International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d
International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d
International Journal of Canadian Studies / Revue internationale d
Create successful ePaper yourself
Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.
Editorial Board / Comité de rédaction<br />
Editor-in-Chief Rédacteur en chef<br />
Kenneth McRoberts, York University, Canada<br />
Associate Editors Rédacteurs adjoints<br />
Isabel Carrera Suarez, Universidad de Oviedo, Spain<br />
Carolle Simard, Université du Québec à Montréal, Canada<br />
Robert S. Schwartzwald, University <strong>of</strong> Massachusetts, U.S.A.<br />
Managing Editor Secrétaire de rédaction<br />
Guy Leclair, ICCS/CIEC, Ottawa, Canada<br />
Advisory Board / Comité consultatif<br />
Irene J.J. Burgers, University <strong>of</strong> Groningen, The Netherlands<br />
Patrick Coleman, University <strong>of</strong> California/Los Angeles, U.S.A.<br />
Enric Fossas, Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona, España<br />
Lois Foster, La Trobe University, Australia<br />
Fabrizio Ghilardi, Università di Pisa, Italia<br />
Teresa Gutiérrez-Haces, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Mexico<br />
Eugenia Issraelian, Russian Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences, Russia<br />
James Jackson, Trinity College, Republic <strong>of</strong> Ireland<br />
Jean-Michel Lacroix, Université de Paris III/Sorbonne Nouvelle, France<br />
Denise Gurgel Lavallée, Universidade do Estado da Bahia, Brésil<br />
Eugene Lee, Sookmyung University, Korea<br />
Erling Lindström, Uppsala University, Sweden<br />
Ursula Mathis, Universität Innsbruck, Autriche<br />
Amarjit S. Narang, Indira Gandhi National Open University, India<br />
Heather Norris Nicholson, University College <strong>of</strong> Ripon and York St. John,<br />
United Kingdom<br />
Satoru Osanai, Chuo University, Japan<br />
Vilma Petrash, Universidad Central de Venezuela-Caracas, Venezuela<br />
Danielle Schaub, University <strong>of</strong> Haifa, Israel<br />
Sherry Simon, Concordia University, Canada<br />
Wang Tongfu, Shanghai <strong>International</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> University, China<br />
2
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong><br />
<strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d’études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996<br />
Citizenship and Rights<br />
La citoyenneté et les droits<br />
Table <strong>of</strong> Contents/Table des matières<br />
Kenneth McRoberts<br />
Introduction/Présentation ..........................5<br />
Claude Denis<br />
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society: A Syewen Case Study. ..13<br />
David Schneiderman<br />
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty<br />
Rights ...................................35<br />
Richard Sigurdson<br />
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada ..........53<br />
Gilles Bourque et Jules Duchastel<br />
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société canadienne et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques ................77<br />
Francisco Colom-González<br />
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship: Canada in Comparative Perspective .....95<br />
Jane Jenson and Susan D. Phillips<br />
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada ...........111<br />
Martin J. Morris and Nadine Changfoot<br />
The Solidarity Deficit: The Rise <strong>of</strong> Neo-liberalism and the Crisis <strong>of</strong><br />
National Unity ..............................137<br />
Fraser Valentine and Jill Vickers<br />
“Released from the Yoke <strong>of</strong> Paternalism and ‘Charity’”: ‘Citizenship<br />
and the Rights <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong>s with Disabilities ..............155<br />
Robert C. Vipond<br />
Citizenship and the Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights: The Two Sides <strong>of</strong><br />
Pierre Trudeau ..............................179<br />
C. Michael MacMillan<br />
Rights In Conflict: Contemporary Disputes Over Language Policy in<br />
Quebec ..................................193
Donald A. Desserud<br />
The Exercise <strong>of</strong> Community Rights in the Liberal-Federal State:<br />
Language Rights and New Brunswick’s Bill 88 .............215<br />
Open topic / Article hors-thème<br />
Michael Lusztig and Patrick James<br />
Constitutional Reform and the Free Trade Agreement in Canada:<br />
Political Entrepreneurship and the Quest for Realignment. .......239<br />
Review Essays / Essais critiques<br />
Samuel V. LaSelva<br />
Three Encounters with Trudeau’s Canada ................259<br />
Frank Davey<br />
Destabilizing the Anthology .......................265<br />
Pierre L’Hérault<br />
Figures de l’immigrant et de l’Amérindien dans le théâtre québécois<br />
moderne .................................273
Introduction<br />
In recent decades, <strong>Canadian</strong>s have<br />
engaged in an increasingly heated<br />
debate over rights and the meaning<br />
<strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship. At the<br />
heart <strong>of</strong> this debate is an argument<br />
over whether <strong>Canadian</strong>s can and<br />
should share a common set <strong>of</strong><br />
rights and a single,<br />
undifferentiated notion <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship. Beyond that, should<br />
rights be conceived in social and<br />
economic terms as well as along<br />
more conventional legal and<br />
political lines? What status should<br />
be accorded to linguistic rights?<br />
And should rights be exercised by<br />
communities as well as<br />
individuals? These and other<br />
issues are elucidated and debated<br />
in the rich inventory <strong>of</strong> articles<br />
that follows.<br />
The first two articles focus on the<br />
rights <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples<br />
insisting that they are distinctive<br />
from those <strong>of</strong> other <strong>Canadian</strong>s, and<br />
must be recognized accordingly. In<br />
reconstructing a British Columbia<br />
court case, Claude Denis shows<br />
how the <strong>Canadian</strong> judicial system<br />
and conceptions <strong>of</strong> justice can<br />
overwhelm distinctive Aboriginal<br />
practices and, in the process,<br />
collide with Aboriginal rights.<br />
David Schneiderman argues that<br />
Aboriginal claims to justice and<br />
self-government cannot be<br />
fathomed by theories <strong>of</strong> difference<br />
since they are not equivalent to the<br />
claims <strong>of</strong> other subordinate<br />
groups, nor can they be resolved<br />
within the framework <strong>of</strong> common<br />
law.<br />
Présentation<br />
Au cours des dernières décennies, les<br />
Canadiennes et les Canadiens ont été<br />
de plus en plus absorbés par le débat<br />
qui porte sur les droits et la<br />
signification de la citoyenneté<br />
canadienne. Au cœur de ce débat se<br />
trouve un point en litige : les<br />
Canadiennes et les Canadiens<br />
peuvent-ils et doivent-ils partager un<br />
ensemble commun de droits et une<br />
notion unique et indifférenciée de la<br />
citoyenneté? En outre, doit-on<br />
concevoir les droits en termes socioéconomiques<br />
en plus de les concevoir<br />
en termes plus conventionnels, c’està-dire<br />
juridiques et politiques? Quel<br />
statut devraient avoir les droits<br />
linguistiques? Et les droits devraientils<br />
être exercés à la fois par les<br />
communautés et par les individus?<br />
Ces questions et d’autres encore sont<br />
éclaircies et débattues dans le riche<br />
inventaire d’articles qui suit.<br />
Les deux premiers articles portent sur<br />
les droits des peuples autochtones et<br />
insistent sur le fait que ces droits<br />
doivent être perçus de façon distincte<br />
de ceux des autres Canadiennes et<br />
Canadiens et reconnus comme tels.<br />
Dans sa reconstruction d’un cas de<br />
jurisprudence de la Colombie-<br />
Britannique, M. Claude Denis<br />
démontre comment le système<br />
judiciaire canadien et les concepts de<br />
justice au pays peuvent submerger les<br />
pratiques distinctes des autochtones<br />
et, par le fait même, entrer en conflit<br />
avec les droits de ces derniers. Pour<br />
sa part, M. David Schneiderman<br />
démontre que les revendications des<br />
Autochtones à leur propre système de<br />
justice et à leur autonomie<br />
gouvernementale ne peuvent être<br />
comprises dans le cadre des théories<br />
de la différence étant donné qu’elles<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d’études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Turning to the question <strong>of</strong> citizenship<br />
and the possibility <strong>of</strong> a universalist<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship, Richard<br />
Sigurdson explores the implications<br />
<strong>of</strong> First Peoples’ conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />
identity. He draws a parallel between<br />
their demands for a differentiated<br />
notion <strong>of</strong> citizenship and those <strong>of</strong><br />
“New Peoples.” At the same time, he<br />
fears that recognition <strong>of</strong> group claims<br />
could subvert the idea <strong>of</strong> civic<br />
community. Nonetheless, based on<br />
their historical survey <strong>of</strong> identities in<br />
Canada, Gilles Bourque and Jules<br />
Duchastel argue for outright<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> the Quebec and<br />
Aboriginal nations. Only through the<br />
construction <strong>of</strong> a multinational state<br />
can Canada escape the consequences<br />
they perceive in the notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />
multicultural Canada, such as an<br />
undue stress upon ethnicity and<br />
society’s fragmentation into a<br />
multiplicity <strong>of</strong> groups. Finally, by<br />
comparing Canada’s conception <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship to that <strong>of</strong> other countries,<br />
Francisco Colom-González<br />
highlights the distinctiveness <strong>of</strong> its<br />
focus on multiculturalism. After<br />
tracing the nation-building objectives<br />
that produced multiculturalism, he<br />
argues that the results are<br />
“inconclusive” and notes the<br />
continued growth <strong>of</strong> identification<br />
with Quebec.<br />
Beyond the recognition (or denial) <strong>of</strong><br />
national and cultural differences<br />
within the population, notions <strong>of</strong><br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship have entailed<br />
the recognition <strong>of</strong> political and social<br />
rights commonly held by all citizens.<br />
Jane Jenson and Susan Phillips show<br />
how the postwar federal government<br />
elaborated a concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizenship that emphasized<br />
democratic rights and a commitment<br />
to social justice. The variety <strong>of</strong><br />
measures it adopted culminated in the<br />
6<br />
n’équivalent pas aux revendications<br />
des autres groupes subordonnés et<br />
qu’elles ne peuvent non plus être<br />
résolues dans le contexte de la<br />
common law.<br />
Intéressé à la question de la<br />
citoyenneté, et surtout de savoir s’il<br />
peut y avoir une citoyenneté<br />
canadienne universelle, M. Richard<br />
Sigurdson explore les répercussions<br />
du concept de « Premières<br />
nations » en matière d’identité. Il<br />
trace un parallèle entre leur<br />
réclamation d’une notion de<br />
citoyenneté distincte et celle des<br />
« néo-Canadiens ». Par la même<br />
occasion, il s’inquiète du fait que la<br />
reconnaissance des revendications<br />
collectives puisse miner le concept<br />
de communauté civique. Par<br />
ailleurs, à la lumière de leur<br />
enquête historique sur les identités<br />
au Canada, MM. Gilles Bourque et<br />
Jules Duchastel insistent sur la<br />
reconnaissance illico des nations<br />
québécoise et autochtones. C’est<br />
seulement par la construction d’un<br />
État multinational que le Canada<br />
peut échapper aux conséquences<br />
qu’ils attribuent à la notion de<br />
multiculturalisme canadien,<br />
notamment un stress indu sur<br />
l’ethnicité et une fragmentation de<br />
la société en une multiplicité de<br />
groupes. Enfin, en comparant le<br />
concept de citoyenneté du Canada à<br />
celui d’autres pays, M. Francisco<br />
Colom-González illustre à quel<br />
point l’accent canadien sur le<br />
multiculturalisme est distinctif.<br />
Après avoir retracé les objectifs de<br />
développement d’une nation qui<br />
ont mené au multiculturalisme, il<br />
allègue que cette démarche a eu des<br />
résultats « inconcluants » et note la<br />
croissance continue de<br />
l’identification au Québec.
Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms.<br />
Yet, this “citizenship regime” now<br />
conflicts with the federal<br />
government’s conversion to neoconservatism.<br />
Citizenship can no<br />
longer protect <strong>Canadian</strong>s against<br />
life’s hardships and groups that<br />
once received formal state<br />
support, such as women’s<br />
organizations, are redefined as<br />
“special interests.”<br />
By the same token, Martin Morris<br />
and Nadine Changfoot<br />
demonstrate how the federal<br />
government, in abandoning the<br />
notion <strong>of</strong> social citizenship, left<br />
federalist forces ill-equipped to<br />
combat sovereignty during the<br />
1995 Quebec referendum. At the<br />
same time, they speculate on the<br />
possible impact <strong>of</strong> neo-liberalism<br />
upon the PQ government’s<br />
capacity to articulate an attractive<br />
sovereigntist project.<br />
Still, even the expansive notions<br />
<strong>of</strong> social citizenship were slow to<br />
respond to the claims <strong>of</strong> one<br />
specific category <strong>of</strong><br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s—the disabled. Fraser<br />
Valentine and Jill Vickers trace<br />
the federal government’s halting<br />
steps in responding to the claims<br />
<strong>of</strong> the disabled, as citizens, and<br />
explore the likely impact <strong>of</strong><br />
current cutbacks in state spending.<br />
Returning to the question <strong>of</strong> rights,<br />
three articles address a type <strong>of</strong><br />
right largely absent from debate in<br />
many countries yet very prominent<br />
in contemporary recent <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
politics: language rights. Robert<br />
Vipond shows how Pierre Trudeau<br />
sought to make language rights an<br />
important component <strong>of</strong> the rights<br />
<strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizens, partly to<br />
strengthen citizenship as a sense<br />
<strong>of</strong> belonging. Yet, as he<br />
Citizenship and Rights<br />
La citoyenneté et les droits<br />
Au-delà de la reconnaissance (ou du<br />
refus) des différences nationales et<br />
culturelles au sein de la population,<br />
les notions de citoyenneté canadienne<br />
ont nécessité la reconnaissance des<br />
droits politiques et sociaux qu’ont en<br />
commun l’ensemble des citoyens et<br />
des citoyennes. M mes Jane Jenson et<br />
Susan Phillips démontrent comment,<br />
durant les années d’après-guerre, le<br />
gouvernement fédéral a élaboré un<br />
concept de citoyenneté canadienne<br />
qui insistait sur les droits démocratiques<br />
et sur un engagement envers la<br />
justice sociale. Il a adopté tout un<br />
train de mesures, aboutissant à la<br />
Charte des droits et libertés. Pourtant,<br />
ce « régime de la citoyenneté » est<br />
maintenant contredit par le virage<br />
néo-conservateur du gouvernement<br />
fédéral. La citoyenneté ne peut plus<br />
<strong>of</strong>frir de protection contre les<br />
difficultés de la vie et les groupes qui<br />
bénéficiaient auparavant de l’appui<br />
de l’État, notamment les<br />
organisations féministes, sont<br />
redéfinis comme des « groupes<br />
d’intérêts spéciaux ».<br />
Incidemment, M. Martin Morris et<br />
M me Nadine Changfoot démontrent<br />
comment en abandonnant la notion<br />
de citoyenneté sociale le<br />
gouvernement fédéral a laissé les<br />
forces fédéralistes mal équipées pour<br />
lutter contre la souveraineté durant la<br />
campagne référendaire québécoise de<br />
1995. En même temps, les auteurs<br />
émettent des hypothèses quant aux<br />
répercussions possibles du néolibéralisme<br />
sur la capacité du<br />
gouvernement québécois d’articuler<br />
un projet de souveraineté attrayant.<br />
Cependant, même une notion élargie<br />
de la citoyenneté sociale ne<br />
comprenait pas d’emblée les<br />
revendications d’une catégorie<br />
particulière de la population<br />
canadienne : les personnes<br />
7
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
demonstrates, most <strong>Canadian</strong>s were<br />
not prepared to include language<br />
rights among fundamental individual<br />
rights. Indeed, some <strong>Canadian</strong>s reject<br />
them in the name <strong>of</strong> individual<br />
rights. In the process, the Trudeau<br />
project to reinforce <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizenship, both as bearer <strong>of</strong> rights<br />
and as sense <strong>of</strong> belonging, was<br />
compromised.<br />
C. Michael MacMillan explores the<br />
debate in Quebec over the regulation<br />
<strong>of</strong> languages in commercial signs.<br />
He critically analyzes approaches to<br />
the question framed in terms <strong>of</strong><br />
collective rights, as well as ones<br />
framed in terms <strong>of</strong> individual rights.<br />
At the same time, he shows how<br />
Francophone public opinion was<br />
prepared to accept the amendment <strong>of</strong><br />
Bill 101’s original, stringent<br />
provisions to accommodate the more<br />
moderate provisions <strong>of</strong> Bill 86. Still,<br />
he cautions, dispute over language<br />
policy is bound to continue.<br />
Finally, Donald Desserud examines<br />
issues raised by New Brunswick’s<br />
Bill 88, which formally recognized<br />
the province’s two linguistic<br />
communities. He shows how the<br />
measure constitutes recognition <strong>of</strong><br />
community rights, potentially<br />
conflicting with individual rights. At<br />
the same time, he argues that this<br />
community right is compromised by<br />
the absence <strong>of</strong> mechanisms through<br />
which the community might exercise<br />
it.<br />
Supplementing these articles on our<br />
theme <strong>of</strong> “Rights and Citizenship” is<br />
a new section <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Journal</strong> for<br />
articles outside the issue’s theme.<br />
Michael Luztig and Patrick James<br />
explore the calculations that led the<br />
Mulroney government to adopt its<br />
proposal <strong>of</strong> U.S.-Canada Free Trade.<br />
They show that free trade was part <strong>of</strong><br />
a dramatic manoeuvre <strong>of</strong> political<br />
8<br />
handicapées. M. Fraser Valentine<br />
et M me Jill Vickers retracent les<br />
méthodes étapistes par lesquelles le<br />
gouvernement fédéral a répondu<br />
aux demandes que lui ont adressées<br />
les personnes handicapées, à titre<br />
de citoyennes et de citoyens à part<br />
entière, et étudient les répercussions<br />
possibles de la réduction actuelle<br />
des dépenses de l’État.<br />
De retour à la question des droits,<br />
trois articles abordent un type de<br />
droits qui n’a pas été au cœur du<br />
débat dans de nombreux pays mais<br />
qui a occupé une place prépondérante<br />
sur la scène politique<br />
canadienne contemporaine : les<br />
droits linguistiques. M. Robert<br />
Vipond démontre comment Pierre<br />
E. Trudeau a cherché à faire des<br />
droits linguistiques un volet<br />
important des droits des citoyennes<br />
et citoyens du Canada, en partie<br />
dans le but de consolider la<br />
citoyenneté comme sentiment<br />
d’appartenance. Pourtant, comme<br />
le démontre l’auteur, la plupart des<br />
Canadiennes et Canadiens n’étaient<br />
pas prêts à inclure les droits<br />
linguistiques dans les droits<br />
humains fondamentaux. De fait,<br />
certaines personnes au pays ont<br />
rejeté ces droits au nom des droits<br />
individuels. En cours de route, le<br />
projet de M. Trudeau visant à<br />
consolider la citoyenneté<br />
canadienne, comme garante des<br />
droits et sentiment d’appartenance,<br />
a été compromis.<br />
Pour sa part, M. C. Michael<br />
MacMillan explore le débat au<br />
Québec portant sur la<br />
réglementation de la langue<br />
d’affichage. Il affirme que les deux<br />
pôles dans le débat (les<br />
Francophones et les Anglophones)<br />
ne peuvent être ramenés à un<br />
simple conflit entre les droits
entrepreneurship in which the<br />
Mulroney Conservatives sought to<br />
construct a new electoral<br />
alignment comprising Western<br />
Canada and Quebec. Ultimately,<br />
Western <strong>Canadian</strong> objections to<br />
the measure designed to secure<br />
Quebec’s loyalty—the ill-fated<br />
Meech Lake Accord—robbed the<br />
Conservatives <strong>of</strong> the electoral<br />
benefits <strong>of</strong> free trade.<br />
In the first <strong>of</strong> three review essays,<br />
Samuel LaSelva draws upon three<br />
recent studies to assess the impact<br />
upon <strong>Canadian</strong> politics <strong>of</strong> Pierre<br />
Trudeau’s concerted effort to<br />
strengthen the sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizenship, most notably through<br />
the Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and<br />
Freedoms. He observes that the<br />
resulting intensification <strong>of</strong> debate<br />
over competing conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />
rights worked against Trudeau’s<br />
“nation-building” purpose. Indeed,<br />
LaSelva concludes that Canada’s<br />
survival may well depend on<br />
transcending the liberal paradigm<br />
in which Trudeau’s project was<br />
conceived.<br />
In the next essay, Frank Davey<br />
explores the continuing debate<br />
over multiculturalism by<br />
examining a recently published<br />
anthology <strong>of</strong> “multicultural<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> literature.” All<br />
inclusions in the volume are<br />
presented as falling outside the<br />
dominant “Anglo-Celtic” literary<br />
establishment. (Francophone<br />
writers, one might add, are<br />
apparently not even considered<br />
part <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> literature.) He<br />
wonders whether Canada’s<br />
multiculturality can be properly<br />
comprehended in such restrictive<br />
terms. Indeed, he opines that this<br />
may be among the last <strong>of</strong> such<br />
Citizenship and Rights<br />
La citoyenneté et les droits<br />
collectifs et les droits individuels. Il<br />
démontre du même coup à quel point<br />
l’opinion publique francophone était<br />
prête à appuyer le remplacement de la<br />
disposition initiale et intransigeante de<br />
la Loi 101 par les dispositions plus<br />
modérées de la Loi 86. Il formule<br />
toutefois une mise en garde : le conflit<br />
au sujet des politiques linguistiques est<br />
appelé à se poursuivre.<br />
Enfin, M. Donald A. Desserud<br />
examine les préoccupations que<br />
soulève la Loi 88 du Nouveau-<br />
Brunswick, qui reconnaît<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficiellement les deux communautés<br />
linguistiques de cette province. Il<br />
démontre à quel point cette mesure<br />
constitue une reconnaissance des<br />
droits des communautés, avec<br />
l’éventualité de conflits par rapport<br />
aux droits individuels. De plus, il<br />
avance que les droits des<br />
communautés sont compromis par<br />
l’absence de mécanismes qui<br />
permettent aux communautés en<br />
question d’exercer pareils droits.<br />
Pour compléter cette série d’articles<br />
sous le thème « Les droits et la<br />
citoyenneté », la RIÉC <strong>of</strong>fre une<br />
nouvelle section consacrée à des<br />
articles qui ne portent pas sur le<br />
thème du numéro. MM. Michael<br />
Luztig et Patrick James explorent les<br />
démarches calculées qui ont mené le<br />
gouvernement Mulroney à adopter<br />
son projet d’Accord de libre-échange<br />
entre le Canada et les États-Unis<br />
(ALE). Les auteurs démontrent que le<br />
principe de libre-échange s’inscrivait<br />
dans une entreprise politique<br />
particulièrement audacieuse par<br />
laquelle les troupes conservatrices de<br />
M. Mulroney cherchaient à instaurer<br />
une nouvelle orientation électorale<br />
ralliant l’Ouest canadien et le<br />
Québec. En bout de ligne, les<br />
objections des provinces de l’Ouest à<br />
la mesure visant à assurer la loyauté<br />
9
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
“<strong>Canadian</strong> multicultural<br />
anthologies.”<br />
In the final article, Pierre<br />
L’Hérault explores how Quebec<br />
drama has sought to come to terms<br />
with the immigrant and Aboriginal<br />
populations <strong>of</strong> Quebec. In the case<br />
<strong>of</strong> immigrants, 1977 was a crucial<br />
juncture: Bill 101 forced Quebec<br />
writers to confront the increased<br />
integration <strong>of</strong> immigrants within<br />
the Québécois collectivity. In the<br />
case <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal Peoples,<br />
Quebec writers have tended to<br />
portray them as distinct from the<br />
Québécois, partly because <strong>of</strong> their<br />
particular relationship with the<br />
federal government.<br />
In sum, with eleven articles and<br />
three review essays on different<br />
aspects <strong>of</strong> rights and citizenship,<br />
along with an innovative analysis<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Mulroney government’s<br />
historic adoption <strong>of</strong> free trade, this<br />
issue <strong>of</strong>fers an especially rich and<br />
stimulating overview <strong>of</strong> crucial<br />
debates in contemporary Canada.<br />
Kenneth McRoberts<br />
Editor-in-Chief<br />
10<br />
du Québec, l’infortuné Accord du<br />
lac Meech, ont miné les avantages<br />
électoraux du libre-échange pour<br />
les Conservateurs.<br />
Dans le premier de trois essais<br />
critiques, M. Samuel LaSelva se<br />
base sur trois études récentes pour<br />
évaluer les répercussions sur la<br />
scène politique canadienne des<br />
efforts déployés par Pierre E.<br />
Trudeau pour consolider le<br />
sentiment de citoyenneté<br />
canadienne, en particulier la Charte<br />
des droits et libertés. Il souligne<br />
qu’il en résulta une intensification<br />
de ce débat qui, alimenté par une<br />
concurrence afin de faire prévaloir<br />
divers concepts de droits, a peu<br />
contribué à la réalisation de<br />
l’objectif visé par M. Trudeau,<br />
c’est-à-dire la construction de la<br />
nation. En fait, M. LaSelva conclut<br />
que la survie du Canada pourrait<br />
bien dépendre de la capacité du<br />
pays de transcender le paradigme<br />
libéral qui a donné lieu au projet de<br />
M. Trudeau.<br />
Dans le second essai critique, M.<br />
Frank Davey explore le débat<br />
continuel en matière de<br />
multiculturalisme en examinant une<br />
anthologie publiée récemment et<br />
portant sur la « littérature<br />
canadienne multiculturelle ». En<br />
effet, tous les éléments inclus dans<br />
le volume sont présentés comme ne<br />
faisant pas partie de la culture<br />
littéraire « anglo-celtique »<br />
dominante. (Quant aux écrivains<br />
francophones, pourrait-on ajouter,<br />
ils ne sont apparemment pas<br />
réputés faire partie de la littérature<br />
canadienne.) L’auteur s’interroge à<br />
savoir si le phénomène<br />
multiculturel du Canada peut être<br />
adéquatement envisagé en ces<br />
termes. En fait, il affirme qu’il<br />
pourrait s’agir là de la dernière
Citizenship and Rights<br />
La citoyenneté et les droits<br />
« anthologie multiculturelle<br />
canadienne ».<br />
Dans le troisième et dernier essai<br />
critique, M. Pierre L’Hérault<br />
explore quant à lui comment le<br />
Québec, malgré sa situation<br />
dramatique, a cherché à négocier<br />
une entente avec ses populations<br />
immigrantes et autochtones. Dans<br />
le cas des immigrants, l’année 1977<br />
a constitué une année-charnière : la<br />
Loi 101 a confronté les écrivains<br />
québécois à l’insertion croissante<br />
d’immigrants dans la collectivité<br />
québécoise. Dans le cas des peuples<br />
autochtones, les écrivains<br />
québécois ont eu tendance à les<br />
dépeindre comme une entité<br />
distincte des Québécoises et des<br />
Québécois, en partie à cause des<br />
liens particuliers entre les<br />
autochtones et le gouvernement<br />
fédéral.<br />
En somme, avec onze articles et<br />
trois essais critiques sur divers<br />
aspects des droits et de la<br />
citoyenneté, ainsi qu’une analyse<br />
novatrice de l’adoption historique<br />
de l’Accord de libre-échange par le<br />
gouvernement Mulroney, le présent<br />
numéro <strong>of</strong>fre un survol<br />
particulièrement riche et stimulant<br />
des débats cruciaux qui touchent le<br />
Canada contemporain.<br />
Kenneth McRoberts<br />
Rédacteur en chef<br />
11
Claude Denis<br />
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society: A<br />
Syewen Case Study 1<br />
Abstract<br />
This paper analyzes the relationship between the <strong>Canadian</strong> state and<br />
Aboriginal peoples, as evidenced by a little-known British Columbian court<br />
case, and in light <strong>of</strong> the Nisga’a treaty signed in 1996. A modern court room is<br />
a place where individual situations are redescribed in the discursive context<br />
<strong>of</strong> occidental justice. When analyzed as a social practice, judicial decisionmaking<br />
can be seen to effect a merging <strong>of</strong> the individual and the collective,<br />
such that the individual case addresses the social relations <strong>of</strong> the collectivity.<br />
In the case studied here, Aboriginal discursive practices were overwhelmed<br />
by <strong>Canadian</strong> judicial / cultural authority, both through the court system and<br />
media coverage. What resulted is a remarkably explicit expression <strong>of</strong> the still<br />
colonial relationship between Canada and First Nations. Aboriginal rights<br />
are thereby trampled. The paper also shows that for these rights to be<br />
substantially recognized, whitestream society will have to reevaluate some <strong>of</strong><br />
its own conceptions <strong>of</strong> justice.<br />
Résumé<br />
Cet article présente une analyse du rapport entre l’État canadien et les<br />
peuples autochtones, tel qu’il est exprimé par un procès peu connu qui a eu<br />
lieu en Colombie-Britannique, et à la lumière du traité signé en 1996 par la<br />
Nation Nisga’a. Un tribunal moderne est un lieu où des situations<br />
individuelles sont redécrites dans le contexte discursif de la justice<br />
occidentale. Le processus décisionnel judiciaire, lorsque analysé en tant que<br />
pratique sociale, peut être compris comme réalisant une fusion de l’individuel<br />
et du collectif; le cas individuel exprime alors les rapports sociaux de la<br />
collectivité. Dans le cas étudié ici, les pratiques discursives autochtones ont<br />
été submergées par l’autorité culturelle / judiciaire canadienne, tant dans le<br />
processus judiciaire que dans la couverture médiatique; c’est ainsi qu’a été<br />
produite une expression remarquablement explicite du colonialisme toujours<br />
présent dans le rapport entre le Canada et les Premières Nations. Les droits<br />
autochtones, dans un tel contexte, sont bafoués. L’article montre aussi que<br />
ces droits ne seront substantiellement reconnus que si la société (à<br />
dominante) blanche est prête à réévaluer certaines de ses conceptions de la<br />
justice.<br />
Now you try and say what is involved in<br />
seeing something as something. It is not<br />
easy.<br />
Ludwig Wittgenstein 2<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d’études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Introducing the “Ordeal” <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters<br />
One February day in 1988, on Vancouver Island, Joseph Peters was coming out<br />
<strong>of</strong> the shower when a group <strong>of</strong> men burst into the house, grabbed him and drove<br />
him away. Over a period <strong>of</strong> four days, they put him through what would later be<br />
described as an ordeal. He escaped, hired a lawyer and launched a civil suit for<br />
assault, battery and false imprisonment. No criminal charges were laid. Four<br />
years later, in February 1992, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> British Columbia<br />
(S.C.B.C.) found in his favour, and awarded him $12,000 “for nonpecuniary<br />
damages, including exemplary damages” (139), but not including punitive<br />
damages. 3<br />
What makes this case interesting is that Joseph Peters and the men who grabbed<br />
him are members <strong>of</strong> the Coast Salish Aboriginal nation, and that the four-day<br />
“ordeal” was an Aboriginal ritual: the initiation into the tradition <strong>of</strong> “syewen.” 4<br />
Joseph Peters, not having consented to the initiation ritual, decided to sue his<br />
initiators. Before Justice Sherman Hood <strong>of</strong> the S.C.B.C., the defendants<br />
claimed an Aboriginal right to conduct such initiations, and in any case denied<br />
that they had either assaulted, battered and falsely imprisoned the plaintiff, or<br />
even intended to do such things.<br />
A modern court room is a place where individual situations are redescribed in<br />
the discursive context <strong>of</strong> whitestream5 justice. When analyzed as a social<br />
practice, judicial decision-making can be seen to effect a merging <strong>of</strong> the<br />
individual and the collective, such that the individual case addresses the social<br />
relations <strong>of</strong> the collectivity. In the case studied here, 6 we will see that<br />
Aboriginal discursive practices were overwhelmed by <strong>Canadian</strong> judicial /<br />
cultural authority, resulting in the remarkably explicit expression <strong>of</strong> the still<br />
colonial relationship between Canada and First Nations. More specifically, the<br />
presentation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal practices in whitestream discourse invents a binary<br />
opposition between “our” civilization and “their” savagery, that contributes not<br />
only to continued whitestream domination but also to the erasure <strong>of</strong> gender as a<br />
significant pole <strong>of</strong> power relations.<br />
Peters v. Campbell, a case pitting Aboriginal men against each other and to be<br />
adjudicated by a “white” court, occurred at a time when relations between<br />
Aboriginals and whitestream Canada are at a turning point. <strong>Canadian</strong>s are<br />
increasingly aware that “Indians” are the victims <strong>of</strong> severe injustice, and that<br />
this should be corrected; constitutional negotiations proposed the recognition<br />
that Aboriginal peoples have an “inherent right to selfgovernment”—although<br />
this proposal eventually unraveled with the failure <strong>of</strong><br />
the Charlottetown process <strong>of</strong> constitutional change. And Canada’s justice<br />
systemfindsitselfanimportanttarget<strong>of</strong>criticismand<strong>of</strong>reform,bigandsmall.<br />
Towards Aboriginal Self-Government?<br />
“For natives, the system shoots first and asks questions later,” writes Ralph<br />
Akiwenzie, 7 chief <strong>of</strong> an Ojibway band that lives on the Bruce Peninsula<br />
between Georgian Bay and Lake Huron. That bay, incidentally, was named<br />
after the English King George IV; and “Huron” is an archaic French word that<br />
refers to a hirsute hairstyle or to an ill-mannered person, a “ruffian,” and was<br />
14
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
used as a nickname by French colonists in reference to members <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Aboriginal Wendat confederacy. 8 The words <strong>of</strong> our everyday language still<br />
carry colonial and derogatory content; one might ask in what ways this is<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> content. Sometimes, as in the shooting death <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal leader J.J.<br />
Harper by a Winnipeg police <strong>of</strong>ficer, Chief Akiwenzie’s statement is literally<br />
true. More generally, his point is that the treatment <strong>of</strong> Aboriginals by Canada’s<br />
legal system is deeply unfair. Aboriginal people are still treated as ruffians.<br />
The killing <strong>of</strong> Harper and the miscarriage <strong>of</strong> justice in the case <strong>of</strong> Donald<br />
Marshall led to provincial commissions <strong>of</strong> inquiry. In the recent past, other<br />
(eventually) well-publicized cases <strong>of</strong> judicial bias against Aboriginals<br />
included the murder <strong>of</strong> Helen Betty Osbourne in Manitoba and, more recently,<br />
the abusive charging, conviction and imprisonment <strong>of</strong> Wilson Nepoose in<br />
Alberta. Cases like these, and the many less publicized cases that result in<br />
Aboriginals being grossly overrepresented in Canada’s jails, prompted<br />
Manitoba’s Aboriginal Justice Inquiry to recommend the development <strong>of</strong> a<br />
separate Aboriginal justice system. Riding on the support acquired for the<br />
principle <strong>of</strong> an inherent right to self-government, an Aboriginal justice system<br />
now seems like a distinct possibility. 9<br />
What would such a system look like? Chief Akiwenzie, in his plea in favour <strong>of</strong> a<br />
separate system, writes that “...tobeequal, native people must be different.”<br />
That is, an Aboriginal administration <strong>of</strong> justice would function in ways<br />
different from “white” justice. But what kind <strong>of</strong> difference is involved? In what<br />
ways and to what extent would it reshape the operation and conception <strong>of</strong> law in<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> society? There are already local attempts to accommodate the needs<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal people, from hiring more native police <strong>of</strong>ficers and prison<br />
guards, to setting up autonomous band police forces, to altering the functioning<br />
<strong>of</strong> courts and involving elders in sentencing. 10 The experiments, among others,<br />
described by crown attorney Rupert Ross in his book Dancing with a Ghost<br />
show that the changes are liable to go far deeper than mere staff replacements.<br />
But with the possible development <strong>of</strong> an Aboriginal justice system and <strong>of</strong> selfgovernment,<br />
this could be just a beginning.<br />
The settlement, in early 1996, <strong>of</strong> the long-standing Nisga’a land claim provides<br />
answers as to what may be ahead—it is, at the least, expected to serve as the<br />
model for settling dozens <strong>of</strong> other claims in British Columbia alone. Up until<br />
1991, the B.C. government always refused to negotiate treaties with any native<br />
people. 11 Since the late 19th century, north-western B.C.’s Nisga’a people had<br />
been trying to obtain recognition <strong>of</strong> their title to roughly 25,000 square<br />
kilometers <strong>of</strong> land. They had gotten nowhere until 1973, when a court decision<br />
that went against them was written in such a way as to provide a political<br />
victory. 12 The resulting instability prompted the federal government to start<br />
negotiations,whichwereblockedbytheB.C.governmentuntiltheearly1990s.<br />
In the Fall <strong>of</strong> 1995, the federal and B.C. governments finally proposed a<br />
settlement to the Nisga’a. Treaty negotiations led in February 1996 to an<br />
Agreement-in-Principle13 in which the Nisga’a obtained title to about 8% <strong>of</strong><br />
the land in their original claim, logging rights over some further land, financial<br />
compensation, and political autonomy amounting to a form <strong>of</strong> municipal<br />
government. They also agreed to surrender their exemption from income taxes<br />
15
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
and gave up an important demand to fishing rights in return for a limited sidedeal<br />
with the federal government. Finally, they agreed to be bound by the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms, and by federal and provincial laws<br />
<strong>of</strong> general application—all <strong>of</strong> which had been strongly resisted by the<br />
Assembly <strong>of</strong> First Nations (A.F.N.) and other native groups during the 1992<br />
Charlottetown constitutional negotiations. 14 The Nisga’a, then, obtained a<br />
very small part <strong>of</strong> what they (along with many other First Nations) had claimed,<br />
not only in terms <strong>of</strong> amounts <strong>of</strong> land, resources and autonomy but also in terms<br />
<strong>of</strong> the kind <strong>of</strong> autonomy and right to self-government.<br />
What concrete impact, one may ask, will all <strong>of</strong> these changes—from the<br />
judicial process to Nisga’a-type treaties—have on Aboriginal peoples in<br />
Canada? Will colonial domination by the <strong>Canadian</strong> state come to an end,<br />
allowing them to live and grow according to their own cultural priorities? Or<br />
will they remain subordinated to the <strong>Canadian</strong> way? In either case, what can we<br />
expect for the relationship between whitestream <strong>Canadian</strong>s and Aboriginal<br />
people?<br />
These are the questions that this paper wants to probe through an analysis <strong>of</strong><br />
Peters v. Campbell. The first (and main) order <strong>of</strong> business will be to “unpack”<br />
the cultural-political coordinates <strong>of</strong> the situation in which the Court found<br />
itself, along with Joseph Peters and his initiators. This will go a long way toward<br />
understanding the extent to which changes such as the Nisga’a treaty are likely<br />
to transform the lives <strong>of</strong> First Nations and their members. Indeed, we will ask<br />
what would have happened if the conflict between Joseph Peters and his<br />
initiators had taken place under a Nisga’a-type jurisdiction.<br />
The object <strong>of</strong> my analysis will be principally constituted by two texts emerging<br />
from Joseph Peters’ lawsuit: a newspaper report on the Court’s decision, and<br />
the decision itself. The decision may or may not turn out to be an important one,<br />
except for the parties in that particular case; but it is extremely revealing <strong>of</strong> how<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> courts are wont to think about Aboriginal rights. It also allows,<br />
despite itself, for a glimpse <strong>of</strong> just how destructive “our” judicial process is <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal ways <strong>of</strong> life and <strong>of</strong> thinking.<br />
In this paper, I have endeavoured to participate in the process <strong>of</strong> reading the<br />
relationship between Aboriginal peoples and whitestream Canada, in the<br />
knowledge that I can only do so from an occidental perspective: such a<br />
perspective is vastly different from Aboriginal ways, to a degree rarely<br />
acknowledged or even grasped by people reared in the white stream. Indeed,<br />
these differences are so deeply ingrained as to involve “irreconcilable or<br />
irreducible elements <strong>of</strong> human relations.” 15 For many years now, this issue <strong>of</strong><br />
difference has provided the social sciences and humanities with large amounts<br />
<strong>of</strong> thinking material, feeding in particular the running feud over relativism<br />
between self-styled modernists and postmodernists. It goes without saying<br />
that, while the debate is germane to this paper, there is no room here to engage it<br />
explicitly. 16<br />
This paper begins by attending to one <strong>of</strong> whitestream culture’s readings <strong>of</strong> the<br />
relationship: that <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> courts’ take on Aboriginal rights. From there, the<br />
paper aims beyond the courts’ perspective with a view to emulating Michel<br />
16
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
Foucault’s yearning to: “penser autrement qu’on ne pense et percevoir<br />
autrement qu’on ne voit.” For Foucault, this is a quest that defines<br />
philosophical practice today: “. ..aulieu de légitimer ce qu’on sait déjà, (la<br />
philosophie aujourd’hui ne consiste-t-elle pas) à entreprendre de savoir<br />
comment et jusqu’où il serait possible de penser autrement?” 17<br />
The Supremacy <strong>of</strong> English Law<br />
In February 1992, The Globe and Mail reported the decision <strong>of</strong> the S.C.B.C. in<br />
Peters v. Campbell. It described syewen as follows:<br />
Spirit dancing, which was illegal in Canada from 1880 to 1951, is a<br />
native ritual involving fasting and confinement until an individual<br />
hears “the song <strong>of</strong> his guardian spirit,” which leads to the initiate<br />
dancing and singing a song. Individuals are grabbed for the ceremony<br />
with or without their consent, the court was told. (Emphasis added)<br />
The issue, beyond the facts <strong>of</strong> the Peters v. Campbell case, was put thusly by the<br />
defendant’s counsel to Judge Hood, who duly noted it in his decision: “Are the<br />
individual rights <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal persons subject to the collective rights <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Aboriginal nation to which he belongs?” (160) The defense answered its own<br />
question, in favour <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal collective rights, by appealing to section<br />
35(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Act 1982, which states: “The existing aboriginal and<br />
treaty rights <strong>of</strong> the aboriginal peoples <strong>of</strong> Canada are hereby recognized and<br />
affirmed.”<br />
As we shall see below, this defense was, in essence, a challenge to the rules <strong>of</strong><br />
the game that allowed a law suit to proceed between these parties, and that give<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> courts the authority to adjudicate it. But Judge Hood missed this basic<br />
point, not seeing that his very jurisdiction was at issue. He did rule on the<br />
defense’s contention that the individual rights <strong>of</strong> an Aboriginal person are<br />
subject to Aboriginal collective rights. He disagreed:<br />
Assuming that spirit dancing was an Aboriginal right, and that it<br />
existed and was practised prior to the assertion <strong>of</strong> British sovereignty<br />
over Vancouver Island, and the imposition <strong>of</strong> English law, in my<br />
opinion those aspects <strong>of</strong> it which were contrary to English common<br />
law, such as the use <strong>of</strong> force, assault, battery and wrongful<br />
imprisonment, did not survive the coming into force <strong>of</strong> that law. . .<br />
(160)<br />
There is no ambiguity in the Court’s decision to affirm “the supremacy <strong>of</strong><br />
English law to the exclusion <strong>of</strong> all others,” and thus the “paramountcy <strong>of</strong><br />
common law to the alleged aboriginal right” (160) 18: Judge Hood found for the<br />
plaintiff. In doing so, the Court exercised cultural authority at its most selfassured,<br />
where cultural authority is defined as:<br />
. . . the authority which one culture is seen to possess to create law and<br />
legal language to resolve disputes involving other cultures and the<br />
manner in which it explains (or fails to explain) and sustains its<br />
authority over different peoples. 19<br />
The Globe and Mail paraphrased the ruling in these terms, which are partly a<br />
quote from Judge Hood, himself quoting the defense’s key question: “The<br />
17
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
freedoms and civil rights <strong>of</strong> an Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong> are not subject to the<br />
collective rights <strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal nation to which he belongs” (emphasis<br />
added). By referring to the plaintiff as an “Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong>,” the reporter<br />
(unwittingly) caught very well the problematic logic <strong>of</strong> the ruling. In the<br />
introduction to his decision, Judge Hood had identified the plaintiff, Joseph<br />
Peters, as “an ‘Indian’ within the meaning <strong>of</strong> the Indian Act, R.S.C. (1985), c. 1-<br />
5, and [. . .] <strong>of</strong> course, a <strong>Canadian</strong> citizen” (140, emphasis added). This “<strong>of</strong><br />
course” had been a good indication that the court would consider the plaintiff as<br />
a <strong>Canadian</strong> first and foremost. Aboriginal rights, whatever they may be or<br />
amount to, must function within that framework:<br />
Placing the Aboriginal right at its highest level it does not include civil<br />
immunity for coercion, force, assault, unlawful confinement, or any<br />
other unlawful tortious conduct on the part <strong>of</strong> the defendants, in<br />
forcing the plaintiff to participate in their tradition. While the plaintiff<br />
may have special rights and status in Canada as an Indian, the<br />
“original” rights and freedoms he enjoys can be no less than those<br />
enjoyed by fellow citizens, Indian and non-Indian alike. He lives in a<br />
free society and his rights are inviolable. [. . .] His freedoms and rights<br />
are not “subject to the collective rights <strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal nation to<br />
which he belongs.” (162. Emphasis added)<br />
The central conflict narrated in the court’s decision was indeed that between<br />
“Aboriginal rights” and “individual civil rights.” The presence <strong>of</strong> this polarity<br />
in Peters v. Campbell was made possible by the existence in <strong>Canadian</strong> law <strong>of</strong><br />
dispositions relating to both these rights: on the one hand, the Charter and a<br />
whole body <strong>of</strong> common law address individual rights; on the other hand,<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> law also has much to say about Aboriginals—in sections 25, 35 and<br />
37(2) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act 1982, in treaties and court decisions, and in the<br />
Indian Act. Had there been no mention <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal rights in at least one area<br />
<strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> law, no defense in front <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Canadian</strong> court challenging the rules<br />
<strong>of</strong> the game would have been thinkable. The defense would have been reduced<br />
to arguing about facts: Was there assault, battery and false imprisonment? Was<br />
there consent?<br />
If a law suit was to be fought over Joseph Peters’ misadventure, there existed a<br />
whole set <strong>of</strong> textual-legal resources for it to be fought over the issue <strong>of</strong> Indian v.<br />
White, Aboriginal right v. civil right, on terms defined and dictated by the<br />
“white” side <strong>of</strong> the relationship. Within the current <strong>Canadian</strong> legal framework,<br />
it was easy to bring a suit <strong>of</strong> civil wrong, it was possible to mount a<br />
constitutional defense based on s. 35, and it was easy for the Court to proclaim<br />
the supremacy <strong>of</strong> English law—to assert the cultural authority <strong>of</strong> the occident<br />
over Aboriginal peoples, thereby reaffirming the colonial character <strong>of</strong> the<br />
relationship. 20 More specifically, it was easy and natural for the Court to<br />
consider (at least certain aspects <strong>of</strong>) syewen as a tort, and even as a crime<br />
although this was a civil proceeding. Judge Hood is worth quoting at length<br />
here:<br />
I am not satisfied that even an ancient tradition or activity carried on<br />
by the defendants and their ancestors, which involves force, assault,<br />
injury and confinement, all against the will <strong>of</strong> the initiate, can be said<br />
to be a continuing Aboriginal right. If spirit dancing includes criminal<br />
18
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
conduct as an integral part <strong>of</strong> it, it could not be said to be an Aboriginal<br />
right which survived the introduction <strong>of</strong> English law into the colonies.<br />
In this regard I note that under the Criminal Code both assault and<br />
confinement <strong>of</strong> a person are criminal <strong>of</strong>fenses in certain<br />
circumstances. [. . .] In my opinion, conduct amounting to civil<br />
wrongs (rights from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the person wronged) should<br />
stand on the same footing as criminal conduct. If such conduct cannot<br />
be separated from the spirit dancing, and thus is an integral part <strong>of</strong> it,<br />
then in my opinion spirit dancing is not an Aboriginal right recognized<br />
or protected by the law. (156. Emphasis added)<br />
But for all the Indian v. White legal-textual apparatus that underlies the Peters<br />
v. Campbell suit, we must not stay within this framework if we are to understand<br />
the battle that was waged here. In order to expand our perspective, it will be<br />
useful to look at how the issue <strong>of</strong> difference between Indian and White is being<br />
constructed in the suit’s narration. With this, I am not trying to dismiss the<br />
Indian v. White framework, nor am I suggesting that some real conflict in this<br />
story lay elsewhere. Rather, I am trying to get at how the conflict is constructed<br />
in discourse as this cultural binary opposition; at what it is that we are given to<br />
understand <strong>of</strong> the suit by its various storytellers; and at what additional issues<br />
may be embedded in the Indian v. White framework.<br />
A Clash <strong>of</strong> Cultures?<br />
After outlining the decision’s affirmation <strong>of</strong> the supremacy <strong>of</strong> British law, the<br />
Globe and Mail article presents two more narratives. First, a description <strong>of</strong> the<br />
circumstances that led to the suit, recounting testimony documenting (a) the<br />
initiate’s lack <strong>of</strong> consent to the initiation and (b) the physical injuries and<br />
humiliations that he sustained:<br />
(a) he was “forcibly taken” to the Long House, “imprisoned,” “forced to<br />
undergo the initiation ceremonies;” he “did not authorize anyone to have<br />
him initiated as a spirit dancer and was not interested in learning about his<br />
people’s culture;”<br />
(b) the initiators “took turns digging their fingers into his stomach area and<br />
biting him on his sides,” causing superficial injuries whose existence was<br />
confirmed by the physician who treated Joseph Peters upon his escape; “...<br />
he was stripped naked, forced to walk backwards into the water and<br />
submerge himself three times, he told the court. He said he was then<br />
beaten with cedar branches;” during these four days, he was given no food<br />
and very little water.<br />
Other features <strong>of</strong> the initiation’s circumstances could have been identified by<br />
the reporter in his attempt to provide readers <strong>of</strong> The Globe with an<br />
understanding <strong>of</strong> the events. But the features he did highlight anchor firmly<br />
Joseph Peters’s claim to have been wronged in one <strong>of</strong> modernity’s fundamental<br />
tenets, at least as it relates to men: the autonomy <strong>of</strong> the self.<br />
In whitestream society, it is taken for granted that men are autonomous selves,<br />
with control over the integrity <strong>of</strong> their body. As such, the fact that Joseph Peters<br />
is a man is certainly not unrelated to this other fact that his forced initiation<br />
became an affair—an event that quickly acquired the public pr<strong>of</strong>ile <strong>of</strong><br />
19
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
something outrageous, requiring and receiving both media and judicial<br />
attention. To him, the override <strong>of</strong> his consent appeared outrageous, as did the<br />
“ordeal”—to quote Judge Hood—he was subjected to. To the court too. And to<br />
The Globe and Mail. Indeed, nobody thought to tell Joseph Peters that his “no”<br />
really meant “yes.” Now, this underscores the fact that the extent to which<br />
women are autonomous selves in whitestream societies remains an issue, and<br />
especially so when it comes to control over the integrity <strong>of</strong> their body—this, in<br />
fact, is a very important, and obscured, part <strong>of</strong> the story, to which we will return<br />
below. Thus, any modernist account <strong>of</strong> these events would have to focus on the<br />
“facts” that Joseph Peters was denied the exercise <strong>of</strong> his free will, and that the<br />
autonomy and integrity <strong>of</strong> his body were violated. But women, and Aboriginal<br />
women more than others, see their consent routinely violated as they are<br />
subjected to treatments far worse than what Joseph Peters experienced. And,<br />
routinely also, these other “ordeals” do not make their way to court.<br />
There are some circumstances in which modernity will allow such denials and<br />
violations <strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> men, such as with convicted criminals (who,<br />
axiomatically, are rightfully imprisoned) and individuals who are deemed<br />
mentally incompetent to make their own decisions. 21 It is a familiar trope <strong>of</strong><br />
liberal discourse that modernity has placed a severe restriction on the infliction<br />
<strong>of</strong> pain and suffering for socially normative purposes. 22 One would not expect<br />
that the authoritative, modern culture would tolerate it coming from the<br />
oppressed culture. 23 As Judge Hood put it, Joseph Peters “did suffer injuries,<br />
both physical and mental” and he “did experience pain and suffering during his<br />
ordeal and for sometime thereafter” (162). Hence the award <strong>of</strong> compensatory<br />
damages.<br />
In assessing damages, the Court easily came to the conclusion that the<br />
intentions <strong>of</strong> the defendants were good, that “they honestly and sincerely<br />
believe in the Dancing Tradition, that they were helping the plaintiff. . .” (162).<br />
As a result, they were not assessed punitive damages. But these good intentions<br />
were <strong>of</strong> no help in getting the suit dismissed. In deciding the case, as far as the<br />
Court was concerned, “the motives <strong>of</strong> the defendants are irrelevant.” (159)<br />
So far as we can tell from The Globe’s article (and also from the Court decision<br />
itself), Joseph Peters had done nothing to deserve such treatment. But, on this<br />
issue <strong>of</strong> initiators’ reasons (why did they do this?), the reporter’s account turns<br />
bizarre: almost as an afterthought, he writes that Peters’s then common-law<br />
wife, Pat Michaels, “had requested that he be initiated as a way <strong>of</strong> dealing with<br />
marital and other problems,” according to the testimony <strong>of</strong> an elder, who was<br />
also a defendant. The initiation, a four-day ritual involving fasting and injuries,<br />
none <strong>of</strong> which Joseph Peters consented to, is to be justified on the grounds <strong>of</strong><br />
“marital and other problems?!” Could any modern reader <strong>of</strong> The Globe and<br />
Mail feel anything but solidarity with Joseph Peters? Could any such reader<br />
conclude anything other than that he was assaulted, battered and wrongfully<br />
imprisoned?<br />
There was no inevitability in the writer presenting the story in this way. But it is<br />
not so simple as to call for “the other side” to be heard—for, indeed, “the other<br />
side” is heard in the report, through the (interviewed) voice <strong>of</strong> the defendant’s<br />
lawyer, Lara Skye. In fact, presenting two sides in this way, constructing binary<br />
20
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
oppositions, is part <strong>of</strong> the difficulty, inasmuch as it is a forceful invitation to<br />
take sides. We will come back to the lawyer’s comments below, but for now the<br />
point is this: in order to provide us with an alternative story, the reporter would<br />
have had not to present the claims <strong>of</strong> “the two sides” but, rather, to do something<br />
that the Court would not: take seriously the reasons <strong>of</strong> the initiators. 24<br />
In the story <strong>of</strong> the initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters as told by The Globe and Mail,<br />
there is no doubt where the sympathies <strong>of</strong> the reader are meant to reside: with<br />
Joseph Peters, against his initiators and, most importantly, against a culture that<br />
would allow a man to be subjected to such an “ordeal.” We will see below that<br />
there were alternatives to this way <strong>of</strong> telling the story. But, as it is, the<br />
newspaper reader is placed in a position where s-he has to choose sides; and<br />
where the party to be sided with is us, “civilized,” modern society, against a<br />
“primitive,” “barbarian” practice. This is a morality tale, then, which makes us<br />
moderns feel good about ourselves, about our respect for human rights, and<br />
which at the same time undermines our ability to respect Aboriginal cultures.<br />
Most <strong>of</strong> all, it allows us, when we hear the word “Indian” or “aboriginal” to<br />
displace concerns from our domination <strong>of</strong> them to their “barbarity.” At work<br />
here is what Dominick LaCapra calls “the scapegoat mechanism—a<br />
mechanism that generates purity for an in-group by projecting all corruption or<br />
pollution onto an out-group.” 25<br />
Such a dramatic slant in a news report would seem to go against the rules <strong>of</strong><br />
reporting to which the prestigious Globe and Mail subscribes: balance, readers<br />
are routinely told, is required. Now, how does one obtain “balance?” In 1977,<br />
the <strong>Canadian</strong> Daily Newspaper Publishers Association adopted a “Statement<br />
<strong>of</strong> Principles” which requires that the news be presented “comprehensively,<br />
accurately and fairly;” it defines fairness as “a balanced presentation <strong>of</strong> the<br />
relevant facts in a news report, and <strong>of</strong> all substantial opinions in a matter <strong>of</strong><br />
controversy. It precludes distortion <strong>of</strong> meaning by over-or under-emphasis, by<br />
placing facts or quotations out <strong>of</strong> context. . .” 26 The question here is: what<br />
counts as “the news?” Is it the initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters? Or the judgement by<br />
the Superior Court <strong>of</strong> British Columbia? Depending on how one answers “the<br />
relevant facts” and context will change.<br />
The initiators’ motivations, clearly, are part <strong>of</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the initiation <strong>of</strong><br />
Joseph Peters; in neglecting them, and thereby presenting the initiation without<br />
an important element <strong>of</strong> its context, the reporter could be said to have breached<br />
the “Statement <strong>of</strong> Principles.” But it is very unclear whether the motivations are<br />
part <strong>of</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the judgement: if we believe the judge, they are irrelevant.<br />
The reporter had to report on the news (and its context); the news, here, was the<br />
Court’s decision—not the initiation itself. And the decision was that the<br />
individual rights <strong>of</strong> Peters were upheld against Aboriginal collective rights; and<br />
that the motivation <strong>of</strong> the initiators were irrelevant.<br />
To go beyond this, the reporter would have needed to expend extra time and<br />
energy todigformoreinformation; inthebusiness <strong>of</strong>dailynewsreporting, time<br />
to dig is rarely forthcoming, such that reporters keep a narrow focus on the<br />
obvious principals <strong>of</strong> the story. Blaming the individual reporter would be to<br />
miss the forest for a tree: it is how the media generally operate that led the<br />
reporter to construct the story as he did. Thus, contrary to appearances, in<br />
21
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
writing his story on Peters v. Campbell, the Globe and Mail reporter was acting<br />
not as a “Native Affairs Reporter” 27 but rather as a legal affairs reporter: more<br />
than anything else, his story was about how the <strong>Canadian</strong> state, through the<br />
Court, was arbitrating conflicts <strong>of</strong> rights. Functioning within these strict limits<br />
is one important mechanism through which the news media contribute mightily<br />
to “the ability <strong>of</strong> authorities to make convincing claims.” 28 In particular, “news<br />
<strong>of</strong> law serves as an influential vehicle through which the authority system can<br />
instruct people on what to be as well as what to do.” 29<br />
It is now time to look at the final narrative in the article, consisting <strong>of</strong> excerpts<br />
from an interview with the defendants’ lawyer, herself an Aboriginal. These<br />
excerpts provide the article with the “balance” that the rules <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />
reporting call for, in this case outlining an Aboriginal cultural and political<br />
critique <strong>of</strong> the judgment. The first excerpt immediately follows the account <strong>of</strong><br />
the Court’s decision:<br />
Native leaders on Vancouver Island greeted the judgement with a<br />
great deal <strong>of</strong> anger, lawyer Lara Skye said yesterday in an interview.<br />
“They see it as a complete denial <strong>of</strong> their constitutionally protected<br />
rights.”<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> judges, who have been indoctrinated in the Western<br />
European tradition <strong>of</strong> individual rights, have difficulty conceptually<br />
in putting collective Aboriginal rights in the proper perspective, Ms.<br />
Skye said.<br />
This Aboriginal narrative is then interrupted by several paragraphs describing<br />
the contentious syewen initiation. Then, the article concludes with a<br />
comparatively long excerpt from the lawyer’s interview:<br />
Ms. Skye maintained that Mr. Peters’ civil rights against assault,<br />
battery and false imprisonment are subordinate to the collective rights<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal nation, protected by Section 35(1) <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Constitution, which confirms Aboriginal and treaty rights.<br />
She said in an interview that most ceremonies involve voluntary<br />
participants because they consider the ritual to be an honour. But<br />
according to tradition, members <strong>of</strong> a family may request that a relative<br />
beinitiatedinvoluntarilyinordertohelpwithpersonalproblems,such<br />
as drinking, drug abuse or other social illnesses.<br />
The native people do not believe an individual is an island in this<br />
world, she said; an individual is part <strong>of</strong> a family and the family is<br />
responsible for the welfare <strong>of</strong> its members.<br />
Contrary to the reporter’s own construction <strong>of</strong> the suit, which is based on Judge<br />
Hood’s narration <strong>of</strong> testimony, Lara Skye places herself30 and her people<br />
outside modernity, and finds it cold and unappealing. She first presents it as<br />
oppressive <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal rights specifically; secondly, she portrays it as<br />
obsessed with the isolated individual and his or her rights, and<br />
uncomprehending <strong>of</strong> collective rights in general. This broad outline <strong>of</strong> a<br />
critique <strong>of</strong> “white” society sounds some familiar complaints about<br />
contemporary occidental societies: there is an excess <strong>of</strong> individualism, the<br />
family is in crisis. But whereas whitestream critics <strong>of</strong> our times target excesses<br />
or specific ills <strong>of</strong> our societies (e.g. individualism is good, but too much <strong>of</strong> it is<br />
22
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
bad), 31 this Aboriginal critique takes aim at the whole “Western European<br />
tradition <strong>of</strong> individual rights.” 32 On the other hand, Skye presents the syewen<br />
ritual as an honour, and the native family as caring and nurturing. This echoes<br />
the defense’s submission to Judge Hood, which he quoted in his decision: “. . .<br />
the primary reason for a Coast Salish family to request that one <strong>of</strong> their<br />
members be initiated is to enhance the quality <strong>of</strong> the life <strong>of</strong> the initiate and to<br />
honour him.” (158)<br />
Problems <strong>of</strong> the individual that may warrant intervention by the family, says the<br />
defense lawyer as quoted in The Globe, are such things as “drinking, drug abuse<br />
and other social illnesses”—problems, by the way, which are strongly<br />
associated with the oppression <strong>of</strong> Aboriginals by “white” society. Two things<br />
are remarkable here: first, whereas the circumstances <strong>of</strong> the Peters initiation are<br />
narrated specifically (this thing happened to this man), the justification for<br />
initiating without consent is presented as a general statement, which may or<br />
may not apply to this case; second, this statement <strong>of</strong> justification comes at the<br />
very end <strong>of</strong> the article, well after reader sympathies have been<br />
established—and, indeed, after many readers will have moved on to some other<br />
article, for few newspaper articles are read to the end. 33<br />
In reporting as it did, even as it followed accepted rules <strong>of</strong> “balance,” The Globe<br />
and Mail made itself an auxiliary to the Court, and contributed to the<br />
reproduction <strong>of</strong> the domination <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal cultures by whitestream<br />
practices. This is best seen in the reporter’s neglect <strong>of</strong> the initiators’<br />
motivations, in conformity to the court finding them irrelevant. There may be<br />
reasons <strong>of</strong> law that would lead the court to take this stance, but these are not<br />
binding on newspaper reporting. The notion that the initiation without consent<br />
was justified by vague marital problems was not only surrealist enough to raise<br />
further questions, but it was also undermined by contradictions in testimony<br />
(more on this below). The narration <strong>of</strong> the two sides, then, was utterly unequal:<br />
readers were presented with those facts <strong>of</strong> the Peters’ initiation which the Court<br />
judged relevant, and they were to make sense <strong>of</strong> those facts either on the basis <strong>of</strong><br />
the modern cultural context with which they are utterly familiar (as water is<br />
familiar to fish), or <strong>of</strong> an Aboriginal context which appeared not even as a<br />
cipher but as a void.<br />
Culture, Gender and Justice<br />
The first line <strong>of</strong> defense for the initiators <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters was stated thusly by<br />
Judge Hood: “The defendants deny that they assaulted, battered or falsely<br />
imprisoned the plaintiff.” Three more lines <strong>of</strong> defense follow: “first, lack <strong>of</strong><br />
intention on their part to inflict harm on the plaintiff, second, consent or<br />
acquiescence on the part <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff, and third, a constitutional defense”<br />
based on their Aboriginal rights (141). Given what we know about the<br />
uncontested facts <strong>of</strong> the initiation, the first defense can seem incomprehensible.<br />
The same goes for the second defense, about the lack <strong>of</strong> intent. And both<br />
certainly were quickly dispatched by Judge Hood: “I do not propose to deal at<br />
length with [. . .] the tort issues. [. . .] The plaintiff has proven, beyond any<br />
question, almost continuous assault, battery and wrongful or false<br />
imprisonment during his ordeal” (150).<br />
23
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
But it is crucial to realize that these defenses do not merely assert statements <strong>of</strong><br />
facts (no assault occurred, etc.). Rather, they assert an Aboriginal perspective<br />
on the facts: to put it in a nutshell, the dancers did not intend to “assault,”<br />
“batter” and “imprison,” they intended to initiate and help. From their point <strong>of</strong><br />
view, which is not idiosyncratic or merely self-exculpatory but rather culturally<br />
constructed, they did not “assault.” They initiated. The point here is that assault<br />
and initiation are not natural facts which are directly grasped as such by<br />
dancers, judges and newspaper readers; they are, rather, particular descriptions<br />
<strong>of</strong> the world, expressing particular cultures.<br />
In claiming that no assault occurred and that there was no intent to assault, the<br />
defense was saying that even the most basic tools (such as acts defined in law as<br />
assault, battery, etc.) <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> legal system are inadequate for dealing<br />
with the events surrounding the initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters. The defense was<br />
inviting the court to declare itself incompetent. But Judge Hood did not quite<br />
grasp this. He did not, that is, understand that in a situation such as the Peters<br />
initiation, the Aboriginal right claimed makes “assault, battery and false<br />
imprisonment” irrelevant descriptions <strong>of</strong> the world and therefore renders<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> courts incompetent. This incomprehension is well indicated by his<br />
puzzlement at why the defendants chose to appeal to s.35(1) <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Constitution, on Aboriginal rights, rather than to s.25 and common law rights<br />
on freedom <strong>of</strong> religion (157).<br />
In the end, Judge Hood could afford to not understand because his description<br />
<strong>of</strong> the world rules over that <strong>of</strong> the Coast Salish people. It is <strong>of</strong> no importance to<br />
him that, within this latter description, it is indeed quite possible that nothing<br />
other than a proper initiation occurred, and that it was done for perfectly good<br />
reasons. This fact, that the propriety <strong>of</strong> the initiation is (necessarily) ruled<br />
irrelevant by a <strong>Canadian</strong> court exposes its constitutive inability to do justice to<br />
Aboriginal life.<br />
One <strong>of</strong> the very peculiar features <strong>of</strong> the Peters v. Campbell decision, as should<br />
be clear by now, is its account <strong>of</strong> the reasons for the Joseph Peters initiation.<br />
Although it is clear how Judge Hood’s cultural and institutional blinkers would<br />
lead him to think these reasons irrelevant, the marginality <strong>of</strong> the discussion <strong>of</strong><br />
reasons remains startling. It is almost as though the initiation had been a<br />
gratuitous act: in narrating testimony, Judge Hood refers (1) to “marital and<br />
other problems;” (2) to Pat Michaels, whom he quotes as saying that “for us, it<br />
was the right thing to do—I thought it would help our relationship;” and (3) to<br />
an elder who, on being told by Pat Michaels that Joseph Peters was drinking,<br />
replied that they needed “more reason than that” (145-147).<br />
The question becomes: viewed from an Aboriginal perspective, was the<br />
initiation justified? Did Joseph Peters need the “help” <strong>of</strong> his family and <strong>of</strong> other<br />
members <strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal community?<br />
Here we may restate that our attempt to “think otherwise,” while aiming at<br />
approaching an Aboriginal perspective, remains firmly anchored within an<br />
occidental description <strong>of</strong> the world. Attempts to use whitestream language to<br />
make some sense <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal ways, may translate some <strong>of</strong> their cultural<br />
24
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
language, but it does not produce one single language, one single description <strong>of</strong><br />
theworld.Thereremainstwocultures,twodescriptions<strong>of</strong>theworld,notone.<br />
If the issue <strong>of</strong> cultural translation is not a problem in and <strong>of</strong> itself, our attempt at<br />
approaching an Aboriginal perspective faces an important impediment: we<br />
must tease out the reasons <strong>of</strong> the initiators from the hints and silences <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Court’s decision and <strong>of</strong> the newspaper account. Thus, the Court tells us that the<br />
initiators had good intentions and that they thought that Joseph Peters needed<br />
help. We remain uncertain as to what actually took place that led to the<br />
initiation, including the specific nature <strong>of</strong> the “marital and other problems” that<br />
moved Pat Michaels to request a forced initiation. But, as we will see, there is<br />
nothing arbitrary about the way in which the elders decided to do it. Thus, if we<br />
are to take seriously Aboriginal cultures, we should be prepared to respect their<br />
decision-making process and their decisions themselves. (This is, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />
what <strong>Canadian</strong> courts are generally not prepared to do.) In other words, we<br />
should be prepared to assume that they would not engage in the gratuitous,<br />
disproportionate or wanton infliction <strong>of</strong> pain and suffering—the contrary<br />
assumption being nothing short <strong>of</strong> racist.<br />
We now return to the comments <strong>of</strong> the defendants’ lawyer in The Globe and<br />
Mail. As typical reasons for a family to request an initiation, she mentioned<br />
“alcohol, drugs and other social illnesses.” And we also have Pat Michaels’<br />
claim that there were “marital problems.” But one elder involved in the<br />
initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters thought alcohol to be insufficient. Which leaves us<br />
some other unspecified, but fairly serious one would think, “social illness.” It is<br />
clear, in any case, that (a) Pat Michaels thought that her problems with her<br />
partner were sufficiently serious that she needed the help <strong>of</strong> the community and<br />
for which he bore enough responsibility that he should be initiated against his<br />
will; and (b) the elders needed what they thought <strong>of</strong> as good and compelling<br />
reasons to carry out an initiation without the consent <strong>of</strong> the initiate.<br />
We have noted earlier that, within the whitestream description <strong>of</strong> the world,<br />
there are circumstances where the suspension <strong>of</strong> individual rights is deemed<br />
legitimate; and this suspension may extend to the infliction <strong>of</strong> pain and<br />
suffering. Presumably, this is also the case within the Coast Salish description<br />
for the world. We can expect, then, that initiation ceremonies will be<br />
undertaken without the consent <strong>of</strong> the initiate only in such cases where there are<br />
good and compelling reasons, and after due consideration <strong>of</strong> whether or not an<br />
initiation should proceed. Clearly, the two cultures have different ways <strong>of</strong><br />
making decisions and <strong>of</strong> suspending rights. But there obviously are situations<br />
where both cultures identify the same social practice as unacceptable and<br />
subject to some community action upon the individual (think for example, <strong>of</strong><br />
something that does not apply in this case: murder).<br />
It could be that if Pat Michaels had chosen to go to the whitestream community<br />
with her claims, she would have obtained “our” version <strong>of</strong> help; or perhaps not,<br />
depending on the specifics <strong>of</strong> her story. But she chose to appeal to the Coast<br />
Salish community, and to bring into play Aboriginal cultural practices. The<br />
Coast Salish community responded to her appeal, and was later told by the B.C.<br />
Supreme Court that it had no right to do so in the way it did.<br />
25
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Two more general propositions can be advanced from this attempt to approach<br />
an Aboriginal perspective in understanding Peters v. Campbell . First, this is<br />
not a conflict between valuing individual or collective rights—contrary to the<br />
standard accounts <strong>of</strong> the cultural difference between the occidental and<br />
Aboriginal worlds, including the comments <strong>of</strong> lawyer Lara Skye published in<br />
The Globe and Mail. Indeed, some features <strong>of</strong> syewen make it very clear that a<br />
strong individualist streak exists in Coast Salish culture—as is argued, it turns<br />
out, in the book that the defendants submitted to the court as a “learned treatise”<br />
whose facts should be treated as prima facie true (154). 34 Which is not to say, <strong>of</strong><br />
course, that the Coast Salish people see the individual as an island, isolated<br />
from family and community. The relationship between individualism and<br />
collectivism in Coast Salish culture is apparently dialectical: they feed on each<br />
other. Now, this is also the case in whitestream culture—at least as<br />
individualism is constructed in philosophical and ethical systems. This<br />
dialectic <strong>of</strong> individual, family and community is, for instance, at the heart <strong>of</strong><br />
hellenistic individualism. 35 It is also crucial in the genesis <strong>of</strong> modern<br />
individualism. 36<br />
Some things are thus shared by the Aboriginal and occidental perspectives,<br />
‘meta-cultural’ features perhaps, constructed and expressed in ways specific to<br />
each. Because <strong>of</strong> this phenomenological depth, the simple “two sides”<br />
structure—us and them, irreconcilably opposed—<strong>of</strong> the newspaper report, and<br />
<strong>of</strong> lawyer Lara Skye’s comments, is enormously misleading. More<br />
importantly, it induces readers, the audience, to take the dominant’s side on the<br />
basis <strong>of</strong> a binary opposition that need not exist, but that covers the weak’s side<br />
with a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance. 37<br />
Secondly, attending to gender relations is crucial in making sense <strong>of</strong> the events<br />
surrounding the initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters. The gender nexus in the story is, in<br />
fact, the key that allows us to unlock the riddle <strong>of</strong> the initiators’ motivations.<br />
But, for this unlocking to happen, it is necessary to respect Pat Michaels as an<br />
autonomous agent just as much as we are clearly prepared to respect Joseph<br />
Peters’ autonomy. In the Court’s decision and in the newspaper report,<br />
however, Pat Michaels gets no such respect—indeed, she was alone among<br />
several reluctant witnesses with failing memories to be targeted for derogatory<br />
comments by Judge Hood: losing patience with her, he portrayed her as an<br />
unintelligent non-entity.<br />
We should never forget or underestimate the fact that, after all, it is Pat Michaels<br />
who set the events in motion. She thought that she and her husband needed help,<br />
and so she went to the elders <strong>of</strong> the Long House to ask that he be initiated. Two<br />
elders and defendants testified that they required Pat Michaels to “have the<br />
consent <strong>of</strong> the plaintiff’s family,” and that she may go to either his brother or his<br />
aunt (147). This is odd and interesting: wasn’t Pat Michaels herself a close<br />
family member? Why should someone else’s permission be needed? It seems<br />
that, because they did not know her at the time (according to the testimony <strong>of</strong><br />
one elder), the elders dismissed the possibility that she may grant<br />
authorization—a family member known to them, then, had to authorize the<br />
initiation.<br />
26
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
So, Pat Michaels sought Joanne Pelkey’s authorization. Ms. Pelkey, herself a<br />
member <strong>of</strong> the Long House, made her authorization conditional on that <strong>of</strong><br />
Joseph Peters’ brother, Gary. In doing this, she removed herself from the events<br />
by making her authorization redundant. Pat Michaels did not, apparently,<br />
obtain Gary Peters’s authorization. But she went back to the elders claiming<br />
that she did and they evidently believed her. There is no account in the<br />
judgement <strong>of</strong> why Michaels did not go to her brother-in-law. In any case: the<br />
elders, after evaluating the case and armed (they thought) with proper<br />
authorization, went ahead with the initiation.<br />
The gender dynamic in this colonial story is striking. To begin with, the coerced<br />
initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters was a response to Pat Michaels’s appeal for help.<br />
After this starting point, however, women disappear from the story. First, being<br />
(apparently) unknown to the elders, Michaels was not considered a proper<br />
family member for the purpose <strong>of</strong> authorizing the initiation; and Joanne Pelkey,<br />
a proper authority, wanted nothing to do with her nephew’s problems—she<br />
would testify in Court that she did not associate much with the family. 38<br />
Secondly, when the initiation was brought to the Superior Court <strong>of</strong> British<br />
Columbia, where the initiators’ reasons are considered irrelevant, the story<br />
focussed exclusively on the violation <strong>of</strong> Peters’s rights; and Michaels was the<br />
only witness to be portrayed in an unfavourable light. Third, when the Court’s<br />
take on the conflict was reported in the media, the erasure <strong>of</strong> women was<br />
repeated—producing a narrative where native culture displays a gross<br />
disrespect for the rights <strong>of</strong> this man, Joseph Peters.<br />
This male-centered, racist narrative is very much an expression <strong>of</strong> dominant<br />
Eurocentric practice in which the bodily autonomy <strong>of</strong> self is strongly genderdependent.<br />
Within the Coast Salish community, a group <strong>of</strong> men acted on behalf<br />
<strong>of</strong> Pat Michaels (and, despite himself, <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters). Once the conflict is<br />
captured by colonialist discourse, in Court and in the media, however, women<br />
and their concerns are pushed into demeaning irrelevance, leaving visible only<br />
the suspension <strong>of</strong> a man’s rights.<br />
The imbalance between our concern for Joseph Peters and the invisibility <strong>of</strong> Pat<br />
Michaels makes the actions <strong>of</strong> the initiators appear almost unmotivated—a<br />
narrative gap that feeds whitestream notions <strong>of</strong> savagery among natives, and<br />
that is a shining example <strong>of</strong> the intertwining <strong>of</strong> “race” and gender in the colonial<br />
enterprise. That is to say, the positioning <strong>of</strong> native women in colonial discourse<br />
contributes to the destructuring <strong>of</strong> the colonized’s culture and society—the<br />
mechanism <strong>of</strong> oppression in Peters v. Campbell combines race and gender: for<br />
the Court and media to be able to narrate the superiority <strong>of</strong> Western culture (in<br />
its concern for individual rights), they have to push the concerns <strong>of</strong> Pat<br />
Michaels outside the frame <strong>of</strong> narrative relevance. And they are able to dismiss<br />
Pat Michaels because <strong>of</strong> the pre-established authority <strong>of</strong> the whitestream over<br />
Aboriginal peoples. Colonialism is reinforced through the erasure <strong>of</strong> women, at<br />
the same time that gender oppression is bolstered by whitestream cultural<br />
authority.<br />
There is also, perhaps, a lesson in this story about the controversy surrounding<br />
the eventual application to Aboriginal self-government <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms, as requested by some Aboriginal women’s<br />
27
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
groups: here is a woman who asks for and obtains her Aboriginal community’s<br />
help in her relationship with her partner, only to find that a <strong>Canadian</strong> court<br />
disallows that help on the grounds <strong>of</strong> the common law, which is consistent with<br />
the Charter.<br />
The Nisga’a Model and Aboriginal Justice<br />
However one evaluates what happened to Joseph Peters, he was not punished.<br />
In the ritual <strong>of</strong> initiation to syewen, the override <strong>of</strong> the individual’s consent<br />
bears an analogy not to the imprisonment <strong>of</strong> a criminal, but rather to the<br />
“involuntary civil confinement” <strong>of</strong> a mentally incompetent person (see note 21<br />
above) which, under the best <strong>of</strong> assumptions, has a therapeutic rationale.<br />
Described in whitestream terms, syewen clearly aims partly at therapy39; it also<br />
has a religious dimension. Its goal, then, is at once religious and therapeutic,<br />
and is far better understood as an attempt to heal a wounded spirit than to punish<br />
a criminal. Further to the point: the theme <strong>of</strong> healing is central in the accounts<br />
given by Aboriginals <strong>of</strong> their attempts to overcome the devastation wrought on<br />
their lives by whitestream domination, <strong>of</strong>ten expressed itself in alcohol and/or<br />
drug addiction, prostitution, suicide and violence against women—“social<br />
illnesses” several <strong>of</strong> which are also defined as crimes under current<br />
whitestream laws. It would therefore be a serious and unnecessary<br />
misunderstanding to portray the initiation process as an instance <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
“justice,” where the initiation ritual would be a trial, conviction and sentence<br />
rolled into one.<br />
Issues <strong>of</strong> justice remain, however, central to this story: was it justified for the<br />
initiation to take place without Joseph Peters’ consent? On this issue,<br />
whitestream sensibilities may hasten to claim that due process was denied<br />
Joseph Peters. But what we call due process is a culturally specific practice, and<br />
the circumstances that led to the initiation may be said to represent a Coast<br />
Salish version <strong>of</strong> due process: the initiation would not be undertaken without<br />
consent, unless the elders in charge <strong>of</strong> the ritual were satisfied that there were<br />
good reasons to do so, as guaranteed by at least one member <strong>of</strong> the prospective<br />
initiate’s family. In such a situation, due process is not dependent on a court <strong>of</strong><br />
law and the adversarial system, but on the trust that a community puts in certain<br />
men and women, endowing them with the status <strong>of</strong> elders. Thus, both in<br />
substantive terms and in procedural terms, an initiation without consent is not<br />
an arbitrarily conducted event.<br />
In the case <strong>of</strong> the initiation <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters, his lack <strong>of</strong> consent may have been<br />
the truly irrelevant issue. Whether or not it was irrelevant is beyond the reach <strong>of</strong><br />
this paper. The point is that the eventual irrelevance <strong>of</strong> Joseph Peters’s lack <strong>of</strong><br />
consent could not be established by a <strong>Canadian</strong> court as currently constituted.<br />
We have seen that such a court is, by definition, incompetent. Assuming a<br />
system <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal justice, instituted in all likelihood in the context <strong>of</strong> treaties<br />
with existing governments, only a Coast Salish process could establish whether<br />
or not this initiation had been gratuitous and unjustified according to<br />
Aboriginal criteria <strong>of</strong> justice.<br />
28
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
What this Coast Salish process may be remains open to question: negotiations<br />
with governments would do much to shape it. What if the Nisga’a treaty were to<br />
serve as the model? Would Joseph Peters have been able to sue, and<br />
successfully so, in front <strong>of</strong> the Superior Court <strong>of</strong> British Columbia? In the<br />
Nisga’a agreement, when non-members <strong>of</strong> the Nisga’a Nation have dealings<br />
with the judiciary, they are given the option <strong>of</strong> either going to the Nisga’a or the<br />
B.C. court systems; and a non-citizen who has agreed to the Nisga’a court’s<br />
authority has to further agree if the penalty is other than “those generally<br />
imposed by provincial or superior courts in Canada.” 40 Finally, when anyone’s<br />
potential sentence is prison, that person may also choose the B.C. court. 41<br />
If this treaty does turn out to be an influential model for future self-government<br />
agreements, the claims <strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal justice system will be highly<br />
dependent on whether the person brought to justice is a First Nation citizen. In<br />
the Nisga’a agreement, a person is entitled to citizenship either through<br />
ancestry or adoption, and may therefore enrol as an <strong>of</strong>ficial member <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Nation; this person has to apply for enrolment and, once a member, may resign<br />
his or her membership. 42 In that context, a person who seriously does not want<br />
to be a member <strong>of</strong> the First Nation would have either not applied for enrolment<br />
or would have resigned his or her membership. But someone who is on the First<br />
Nation’s <strong>of</strong>ficial enrolment register could not claim in court that s/he does not<br />
belong to the Aboriginal community. On the other hand, someone may have<br />
clear links to the community, as Peters did (being the son <strong>of</strong> a prominent Coast<br />
Salish family, and being the spouse <strong>of</strong> a Coast Salish woman who asked the<br />
community that he be initiated), but have chosen to stay <strong>of</strong>f the register. In the<br />
Nisga’a accord, such a person would not be considered a member <strong>of</strong> the Nisga’a<br />
nation, at least for the purpose <strong>of</strong> adjudicating conflicts.<br />
Given all this, what kind <strong>of</strong> help to the Salish community would Nisga’a-type<br />
self-government have been in the case <strong>of</strong> Peters v. Campbell? First, in order to<br />
be treated as an ordinary <strong>Canadian</strong> citizen, Peters would have had to stay <strong>of</strong>f the<br />
register in advance <strong>of</strong> his conflict with his initiators. Had he done so, any action<br />
by his initiators would have been subject to his consent. Had they initiated him<br />
without his consent, he could have sued them in front <strong>of</strong> the B.C. Superior Court<br />
and won—just as he actually did. On the other hand, had he previously applied<br />
for and obtained citizenship in the Coast Salish nation, things get complicated.<br />
We have first to remember that an initiation is not a punishment. So, the Coast<br />
Salish justice system might have become involved only after the initiation, to<br />
deal with Peters’s complaint against his initiators. But remember that in the<br />
Nisga’a accord, self-government remains subject to provincial and federal<br />
laws, as well as to the <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms. So, Peters<br />
could just as well have gone to the B.C. Superior Court and claimed that his<br />
rights under the common law and the Charter had been violated—and he likely<br />
would have won.<br />
Under the Nisga’a regime, then, the integrity <strong>of</strong> such traditional practices as<br />
syewen remains vulnerable to the consent at any time <strong>of</strong> the person who is being<br />
“helped,” and who may well be considered deviant by the community. In other<br />
ords, under the Nisga’a regime, the outcome <strong>of</strong> the Peters initiation could easily<br />
have been the same as what actually happened: a whitestream lawsuit would<br />
29
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
have delegitimated syewen as a means <strong>of</strong> social control, and therefore<br />
destructured the Salish people as a self-governing community.<br />
It follows from this exploration <strong>of</strong> differences between Aboriginal and<br />
occidental ways, and from our evocation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal justice, that we should<br />
not assume that a system <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal justice would merely mirror the current<br />
system, but with a staff <strong>of</strong> Aboriginals: that judges, cops, prison guards, etc.<br />
would do basically the same jobs but would be “Indians.” We have seen that<br />
initiations without consent should be seen as dealing with individuals in need <strong>of</strong><br />
spiritual healing rather than as dealing with criminality. No judges, cops or<br />
prisons are needed for this; which is not to say that they would completely<br />
disappear. Modernity and Aboriginality, then, have different institutional ways<br />
<strong>of</strong> exercising social control over deviance. Because <strong>of</strong> this, if an Aboriginal<br />
justice system is to genuinely function according to Aboriginal criteria, it likely<br />
requires the context <strong>of</strong> wide-ranging Aboriginal self-government—and that<br />
means a degree <strong>of</strong> self-government greater than what the Nisga’a have been<br />
able to obtain.<br />
Social control among Aboriginal peoples would be likely to distribute<br />
normality and deviance in ways different from those <strong>of</strong> modernity: some people<br />
may be labelled deviant in one context but not in the other, and some deviants<br />
whom modernity would allocate to its justice system would, for example, be<br />
subjected to Aboriginal spiritual and/or therapeutic processes. There would<br />
undoubtedly be fewer Aboriginals in jail, among other reasons43 because fewer<br />
would be treated as criminals and more as wounded spirits. The revitalization <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal spiritual traditions in the last several years is a sign that many<br />
Aboriginal communities would be equipped to meet the challenge. Chances are<br />
that this would result in more harmony in Aboriginal communities, and<br />
between Aboriginal people and whitestream <strong>Canadian</strong>s. But if <strong>Canadian</strong> courts<br />
are waiting on the sidelines to trump Aboriginal processes in the name <strong>of</strong> the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Charter, statute and common law, the self-control that First Nations<br />
appear to be gaining will be little other than window dressing.<br />
Responding to a statement by the defendants’ counsel to the effect that “the<br />
application <strong>of</strong> the common law approach to their activity has had a pr<strong>of</strong>ound<br />
negative affect (sic) on the whole <strong>of</strong> the Coast Salish Nation,” Judge Hood<br />
found it “questionable whether in fact the common law does necessarily<br />
infringe on the Aboriginal right” (157). In other words, while syewen itself may<br />
be a right, conducting a forced initiation may not be an integral part <strong>of</strong> that<br />
right—without even having to consider issues <strong>of</strong> common law. This is clearly<br />
absurd, as it ignores the role that syewen obviously plays (at least in some cases)<br />
as a form <strong>of</strong> social control. The only option left, then, is to limit the practice <strong>of</strong><br />
syewen to its consenting (and most frequent) variant by claiming the<br />
paramountcy <strong>of</strong> the common law—which is exactly what Judge Hood ends up<br />
doing. Which means that the defense’s claim that the common law approach is<br />
injurious to the whole Coast Salish Nation, stands—as should be obvious<br />
anyway, since the Nation’s own cultural practices are superseded by foreign<br />
ones.<br />
Judge Hood could have found how culturally important the integrity <strong>of</strong> syewen<br />
is by paying serious attention to Amoss’ Coast Salish Spirit Dancing, which the<br />
30
defense provided him. And he needed not search any further than The <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Encyclopedia to find that syewen is at the core <strong>of</strong> a religious revival among<br />
Northwest Coast peoples; that its practice is accounted for in “institutional<br />
myths,” one <strong>of</strong> the three main types <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal myths in Canada; and that it is<br />
one instance <strong>of</strong> the Guardian Spirit Quest, which “once occurred throughout<br />
most <strong>of</strong> the tribal groups in Canada.”44 The fact that this Quest is largely a thing<br />
<strong>of</strong> the past is the result <strong>of</strong> exactly the type <strong>of</strong> cultural authority which Judge<br />
Hood exercised so serenely.<br />
Not seeing that to subject syewen to the common law is destructive <strong>of</strong> Coast<br />
Salish culture is to display just the kind <strong>of</strong> arrogant ignorance that has come so<br />
close to destroying Aboriginal cultures. If the Nisga’a treaty is any indication,<br />
the time is not over when the <strong>Canadian</strong> state bullied Aboriginal peoples into<br />
subordination. What prospect this <strong>of</strong>fers for First Nations’ future development<br />
in Canada is far from encouraging.<br />
Notes<br />
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
1. I want to thank Danyèle Lacombe, Barbara Marshall, David Schneiderman, the IJCS<br />
Editorial Board and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on various versions <strong>of</strong><br />
the work presented in this paper. In writing this, I benefited from a year’s sabbatical leave<br />
from the Faculté Saint-Jean, University <strong>of</strong> Alberta, and from the hospitality <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Departments <strong>of</strong> Sociology at the Université de Montréal and the University <strong>of</strong> Victoria.<br />
2. Quoted in Ray Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein. The Duty <strong>of</strong> Genius, London, Vintage, 1991,<br />
p.514.<br />
3. Although the events reported here are on the public record, the fact remains that the legal<br />
process robbed a number <strong>of</strong> individuals <strong>of</strong> their privacy, forcing some <strong>of</strong> them to speak <strong>of</strong><br />
cultural practices which they would have preferred to keep quiet. The cultural practices in<br />
question are in fact not a secret—they have been described in the anthropological<br />
literature—but practitioners <strong>of</strong> syewen are <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>of</strong>fended by these descriptions; as well,<br />
these specific individuals were forced into talking. Dealing ethically with such a situation is<br />
not a simple matter, and no one strategy will satisfy all readers. Legal scholars will be<br />
frustrated by a decision to change all names <strong>of</strong> persons, while some members <strong>of</strong> First Nations<br />
may find that too much is being said. I have adopted a strategy consistent with frequent<br />
sociological practice, designed to protect the privacy <strong>of</strong> the people involved while remaining<br />
sufficiently specific to be instructive on the issues at hand. All names <strong>of</strong> persons have been<br />
changed, except that <strong>of</strong> B.C. Superior Court Justice Sherman Hood; I will refer to the case as<br />
Peters v. Campbell. As well, local place names have been changed, while those <strong>of</strong> the region<br />
(Vancouver Island) and people (Coast Salish) have not. I cannot identify either the<br />
judgement’s coordinates or the newspaper article analyzed here. I do provide page numbers<br />
for quotes from the judgement, for those who already know the case, and for those who<br />
would want to study the case further; the latter can write me to ask for full references,<br />
explaining why they need them, and committing to maintaining the privacy <strong>of</strong> those<br />
involved. Should someone be tempted to track down the sources on the basis <strong>of</strong> the fairly<br />
specific information presented in these pages, I can only hope that s-he would also undertake<br />
to respect the participants’ privacy.<br />
4. “Syewen” is generally translated into “spirit dancing,” to the dismay <strong>of</strong> those who practise<br />
it—they consider it a demeaning mistranslation. I will, consequently, leave it untranslated. I<br />
have, however, simplified its spelling somewhat, removing the diacritical marks used by<br />
anthropologists (see for instance Pamela Amoss, Coast Salish Spirit Dancing: The Survival<br />
<strong>of</strong> an Ancient Religion, Seattle and London, University <strong>of</strong> Washington Press, 1978; and<br />
Wayne Suttles, Coast Salish Essays, Vancouver and Seattle, Talon Books and University <strong>of</strong><br />
Washington Press, 1987) but retaining—to my ear, anyway—much <strong>of</strong> the resemblance to<br />
31
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
the spoken word as I have heard it from members <strong>of</strong> the Longhouse, the practitioners <strong>of</strong><br />
syewen.<br />
5. By “whitestream” I am referring to the overwhelming majority <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong>s, who identify<br />
primarily with the dominant values <strong>of</strong> modernity, <strong>of</strong> liberal democratic societies. Especially<br />
in the context <strong>of</strong> discussions <strong>of</strong> their relations with Aboriginals, those <strong>Canadian</strong>s are<br />
typically labelled “white;” and the dominant values <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> society are clearly<br />
European in origin, and as such “white.” But there is now a sizeable number <strong>of</strong> people <strong>of</strong><br />
colour in Canada, such that to speak <strong>of</strong> “white society” is abusive. Hence “whitestream,” a<br />
term which I am adapting somewhat freely from feminist scholarship’s concept <strong>of</strong> “malestream.”<br />
6. This paper presents elements <strong>of</strong> an analysis is more fully developed in my forthcoming We<br />
Are Not You. First Nations and <strong>Canadian</strong> Modernity, Peterborough (On.), Broadview Press,<br />
Series “Terra Incognita”, 1997.<br />
7. Ralph Akiwenzie, “We want to do it our way,” The Globe and Mail (G&M), 6 March 1992.<br />
8. See “Georgian Bay” and “Huron” in The <strong>Canadian</strong> Encyclopedia, Volume 2, Edmonton,<br />
Hurtig Publishers, 1985; also, “huron” in Le Petit Robert 1, Paris, S.N.L.—Dictionnaire Le<br />
Robert, 1978.<br />
9. It is not, however, a sure thing, and not only because constitutional recognition <strong>of</strong> “inherent<br />
right” has not been forthcoming: the government <strong>of</strong> Manitoba rejected the recommendation<br />
<strong>of</strong> its Aboriginal Justice inquiry, and the then-federal justice minister also rejected a separate<br />
system, describing it as “a copout,” a virtual admission that Aboriginals “are people that<br />
cannot be served by the so-called, hypothetical mainstream system. . .” On the other hand,<br />
the Saskatchewan government, relying on the Manitoba inquiry’s report, promised to<br />
implement a parallel justice system for Aboriginals. See “Separate native justice rejected for<br />
Manitoba,” G&M, 29 January 1992; “Separate native justice system would be ‘copout’”<br />
G&M, 31 January 1992; “Saskatchewan moves toward native justice,” G&M, 1 February<br />
1992.<br />
10. See for instance “Blood tribe puts own mark on justice system” and “New police grads take<br />
posts on reserve,” The Edmonton <strong>Journal</strong>, 14 March 1992; a report by Holly Doan on CBC’s<br />
Sunday Report, 19 July 1992; and Rupert Ross, Dancing with a Ghost. Exploring Indian<br />
Reality, Markham (On.), Octopus Publishing Group, 1992.<br />
11. There are a few minor exceptions, but approximately one hundred native bands have been<br />
unable to obtain any kind <strong>of</strong> settlement with the B.C. government for claims that cover a<br />
large majority <strong>of</strong> the province’s territory. Settlement <strong>of</strong> the Nisga’a claim is seen as marking<br />
the beginning <strong>of</strong> the end <strong>of</strong> this situation. On the history <strong>of</strong> the Nisga’a claim, see Olive<br />
Patricia Dickason, Canada’s First Nations. A History <strong>of</strong> Founding Peoples from Earliest<br />
Times, Toronto, McClelland & Stewart, 1992.<br />
12. Indeed, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s decision in Calder v. Attorney General led Prime<br />
Minister Pierre Trudeau to agree that “there was a legal case for Aboriginal rights, in spite <strong>of</strong><br />
his earlier rejection <strong>of</strong> the concept. Conceding that Amerindians have more rights than he<br />
had recognized in the White Paper <strong>of</strong> 1969, he entrenched them without definition in the<br />
Constitution <strong>of</strong> 1982, despite a determined assault by the provincial premiers to prevent it.”<br />
(Dickason, Canada’s First Nations. . ., 349-50)<br />
13. Government <strong>of</strong> Canada, Province <strong>of</strong> British Columbia and Nisga’a Tribal Council, Nisga’a<br />
Treaty Negotiations. Agreement-in-Principle, 15 February, 1996. After this Agreement-in-<br />
Principle is ratified by the three parties, a variety <strong>of</strong> details will remain to negotiate in order to<br />
produce a Final Agreement. Consequently, the Nisga’a do not as yet have a Treaty; for the<br />
sake <strong>of</strong> brevity, however, I will refer to the Nisga’a Treaty, herein, to designate the<br />
Agreement-in-Principle which is highly likely to be the core <strong>of</strong> the future treaty.<br />
14. The A.F.N. model <strong>of</strong> self-government was itself considered overly moderate by the Alberta<br />
Treaty Chiefs and the Mohawk Nation, among others, who boycotted the Charlottetown<br />
process and referendum.<br />
15. Mary Ellen Turpel, “Aboriginal Peoples and the <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter: Interpretive<br />
Monopolies, Cultural Differences,” <strong>Canadian</strong> Human Rights Yearbook 1989-1990, Ottawa,<br />
University <strong>of</strong> Ottawa Human Rights and Education Centre, 1990, 13.<br />
16. For an important take on the issue <strong>of</strong> justice and otherness, however, see Drucilla Cornell,<br />
The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> the Limit, New York and London, Routledge, 1992.<br />
32
Aboriginal Rights In / And <strong>Canadian</strong> Society<br />
17. Michel Foucault, L’usage des plaisirs. Histoire de la sexualité, volume 2, Paris, Gallimard,<br />
1984, 14,15.<br />
18. The reasoning underpinning the decision is less clear. Relying mainly on three historic<br />
decisions (Delgamuukw v. The Queen (1989), 38 B.C.L.R. (2d); Regina v. Sparrow [1990]<br />
70 D.L.R. (4th); Saumur v. City <strong>of</strong> Quebec [1953] 2 S.C.R.), Judge Hood noted that “just as<br />
rights guaranteed under the Charter are not absolute, those guaranteed under s. 35 are not<br />
absolute;” he then affirmed, contradictorily it seems to me, that the plaintiff “lives in a free<br />
society and his rights are inviolable” (161, 162; emphasis added). My purpose here is not,<br />
however, to evaluate the internal consistency <strong>of</strong> the court’s legal reasoning; it is, rather, to<br />
situate it in its inter-cultural context.<br />
19. Turpel, “Aboriginal Peoples and the <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter”, 4.<br />
20. Lest one thinks Judge Hood’s is a rogue, outdated judgement, it should be realized that he<br />
relied on recent precedent (Delgamuukw v. The Queen) which, in articulating the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
legal tradition on such issues, was no less colonial in its reasoning. See Frank Cassidy (Ed.),<br />
Aboriginal Title in British Columbia. Delgamuukw v. The Queen, Lantzville (B.C.) and<br />
Montreal, Oolichan Books and The Institute for Research on Public Policy, 1992.<br />
21. Thus, it is possible under <strong>Canadian</strong> law for family members to have an individual declared<br />
mentally incompetent and institutionalized without his or her consent; and ‘treatment’—say,<br />
electroshocks—has <strong>of</strong>ten included the infliction <strong>of</strong> pain and suffering (see A. Alan Borovoy,<br />
When Freedoms Collide: The Case for Our Civil Liberties, Toronto, Lester & Orpen<br />
Dennys, 1988; in particular, Ch. 9 on “Involuntary Civil Confinement”). I hope it is clear that<br />
I am not endorsing, here, any such “treatment;” rather, I am outlining some <strong>of</strong> the<br />
suspensions <strong>of</strong> rights that are deemed acceptable by the dominant occidental criteria.<br />
22. See Michel Foucault, Surveiller et punir. Naissance de la prison, Paris, Gallimard,<br />
Bibliothèque des Histoires, 1975.<br />
23. On the difficulties <strong>of</strong> liberal democracy in dealing with Aboriginal rights, see Michael Asch,<br />
Home and Native Land. Aboriginal Rights and the <strong>Canadian</strong> Constitution, Scarborough<br />
(On.), Nelson Canada, 1988.<br />
24. Not that reasons, motivations or intentions, should provide the final word to any analysis,<br />
especially one informed by poststructuralist theory. The point, rather, is that an action as<br />
drastic as a syewen initiation is not (as we will see) undertaken lightly, spontaneously or<br />
gratuitously: a forced initiation is part <strong>of</strong> a complex social process in which participants<br />
deliberate as to what constitutes proper conduct. That such deliberations and reasons are<br />
ruled irrelevant by Judge Hood is part <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> cultural / judicial authority.<br />
25. Quoted in Arnold Krupat, Ethnocriticism. Ethnography, History,Literature, Berkeley and<br />
Los Angeles, University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1992, 19.<br />
26. See <strong>Canadian</strong> Daily Newspaper Publishers Association, “A Statement <strong>of</strong> Principles for<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Daily Newspapers,” April 1977; reproduced in Peter Desbarats, Guide to<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> News Media, Toronto, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Canada, 1990, 231-2.<br />
27. This is how his by-line <strong>of</strong>ten identified him, but not for that particular article. On this day, he<br />
was merely presented as part <strong>of</strong> the “British Columbia Bureau.”<br />
28. Richard V. Ericson, Patricia M. Baranek and Janet B.L. Chan, 1991, Representing Order.<br />
Crime, Law, and Justice in the News Media, Toronto, University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1991, 8.<br />
29. Ericson, Baranek and Chan, Representing Order. . ., 7.<br />
30. Although <strong>of</strong> course she, a practicing lawyer in British Columbia, lives very much within<br />
modernity. Or, perhaps more accurately, modernity lives within her—as it does for all those<br />
whose lives it has been shaping. It is hard to imagine that anyone in Canada, as in much <strong>of</strong> the<br />
world, escapes this fate.<br />
31. In the <strong>Canadian</strong> context, see for example the quite popular (and conservative) sociological<br />
essay Mosaic Madness. The Poverty and Potential <strong>of</strong> Life in Canada, by Reginald W. Bibby,<br />
Toronto, Stoddard, 1990.<br />
32. This indictment, only hinted at in The Globe and Mail, is developed much more fully by<br />
Mary Ellen Turpel in her article “Aboriginal Peoples and the <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter.”<br />
33. This is partly why, as I have learned from some limited personal experience in reporting,<br />
news articles are written following an “inverted pyramid” model: articles should begin from<br />
the most important news elements and end with the least important. Not only does this allow<br />
editors to cut easily by chopping <strong>of</strong>f the end when space is scarce, but it is a model built on the<br />
assumption that readers <strong>of</strong>ten do not finish an article. It is significant in this respect that the<br />
33
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Aboriginal rationale for the initiation comes at the end <strong>of</strong> an article that begins with news <strong>of</strong> a<br />
judicial decision.<br />
34. The book is: Pamela Amoss, Coast Salish Spirit Dancing. . . .<br />
35. Michel Foucault, Le souci de soi. Volume 3: Histoire de la sexualité, Paris, Gallimard,<br />
Bibliothèque des Histoires, 1984.<br />
36. Among a multitude <strong>of</strong> discussions <strong>of</strong> this issue, see Charles Taylor’s highly readable and<br />
concise The Malaise <strong>of</strong> Modernity, Concord (On.), Anansi Press, 1991.<br />
37. “Veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance,” many readers will know, is a key concept in John Rawls’s liberal A<br />
Theory <strong>of</strong> Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972. Need I say that I am twisting the<br />
phrase beyond <strong>of</strong> all recognition?<br />
38. On this issue, more below.<br />
39. On this issue, see Amoss, Coast Salish Spirit Dancing; and Wolfgang Jilek, Salish Mental<br />
Health and Culture Change, Toronto and Montreal, Holt, Rinehart and Winston <strong>of</strong> Canada,<br />
1974. Both Amoss and Jilek indicate that the efficacy <strong>of</strong> this “therapy” is uneven; but the<br />
issue <strong>of</strong> whether or not it works is irrelevant here. Besides, although Canada’s justice system,<br />
like that <strong>of</strong> other liberal democracies, claims to try to rehabilitate convicted criminals, its<br />
actual “redeeming” abilities are—to say the least—limited.<br />
40. Government <strong>of</strong> Canada et al., Nisga’a Treaty Negotiations. Agreement-in-Principle, 88.<br />
41. See Government <strong>of</strong> Canada et al., Nisga’a Treaty Negotiations. Agreement-in-Principle.In<br />
the Chapter on “Administration <strong>of</strong> Justice,” paragraphs 32c and 33 limit the Nisga’a Court’s<br />
jurisdiction to Nisga’a citizens except when the person accepts its authority; and paragraph<br />
36 limits the type <strong>of</strong> penalties the Nisga’a Court may impose on non-citizens to whitestream<br />
practices. Further, paragraph 35 <strong>of</strong>fers any accused person the option <strong>of</strong> going to the<br />
Provincial Court <strong>of</strong> British Columbia if the penalty may be imprisonment.<br />
42. See Nisga’a Treaty Negotiations. Agreement-in-Principle, “Eligibility and Enrolment,”<br />
paragraphs 2, 5 and 10.<br />
43. On the Louis Bull reserve in central Alberta, since a fully autonomous Aboriginal police<br />
force was created seven years ago, the crime rate is reported to have dropped by 60%. Asked<br />
to account for this improvement, a local cop suggested that there was now more respect for<br />
the law among band members. CBC’s Sunday Report, 19 July 1992.<br />
44. The <strong>Canadian</strong> Encyclopedia, Edmonton, Hurtig Publishers, 1985; articles on “Native<br />
People, Northwest Coast” and “Native People, Religion.”<br />
34
David Schneiderman*<br />
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
Abstract<br />
Judicial recognition <strong>of</strong> constitutional claims to Aboriginal self-government<br />
can be facilitated, it has been argued, by turning to theories <strong>of</strong> “difference.”<br />
Difference theory suggests that politics can become more democratic and<br />
inclusive if the perspectives <strong>of</strong> cultural and political groups marginalized by<br />
dominant political discourse are taken into account. This paper examines the<br />
work <strong>of</strong> two such theorists and their misplaced faith in judicial<br />
reconstruction. By equating Aboriginal claims to justice with other claims <strong>of</strong><br />
subordinated groups, or by attempting to reconstruct common law<br />
interpretations based on Eurocentric formulations, these theorists undermine<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> the very difference they seek to promote.<br />
Résumé<br />
Selon certains, il est possible de faciliter la reconnaissance juridique des<br />
revendications constitutionnelles au sujet de l’autodétermination des peuples<br />
autochtones en se tournant vers les théories fondées sur la « différence ».<br />
Pareilles théories laissent entendre qu’on peut mettre en place une politique<br />
plus démocratique et plus englobante quand on tient compte des perspectives<br />
des groupes culturels et politiques marginalisés par le discours politique<br />
dominant. Le présent article examine le travail de deux spécialistes de ces<br />
théories ainsi que leur confiance mal placée dans ce projet de reconstruction<br />
juridique. En mettant en parallèle les revendications des peuples autochtones<br />
et celles de groupes subordonnés ou en tentant de réinterpréter la « common<br />
law»àlalumière des formulations eurocentriques, ces théoriciens minent le<br />
processus de reconnaissance de la différence même qu’ils tentent de<br />
promouvoir.<br />
This paper addresses recent attempts by Anglo-<strong>Canadian</strong> scholars to redirect<br />
the majority society’s discussion <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples away from its colonial<br />
suppositions. 1 These scholars have realized that the majority’s approach to<br />
Aboriginal peoples is largely based on Eurocentric characterizations derived<br />
from our colonial heritage. 2 Such suppositions, which portray Aboriginal<br />
peoples as “brutes,” “savages,” having no organized political society or legally<br />
recognizable relationship to the land, constitute the contemporary foundations<br />
for Canada’s sovereignty over Aboriginal peoples and underlying title to their<br />
lands. 3 In other words, the historical fact <strong>of</strong> these Eurocentric suppositions<br />
provide the continuing bases for justifying Canada’s complete sovereignty<br />
over Aboriginal peoples, made manifest in s.91(24) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act,<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d'études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
1867. Recognition <strong>of</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> this past requires reflexive scholarly<br />
production.<br />
Some theorists argue that by acting self-consciously and checking the<br />
continuing operation <strong>of</strong> this heritage in constitutional law, the majority can<br />
work towards achieving justice for Aboriginal peoples in their claims to<br />
cultural recognition and self-government. This aim is pursued in the scholarly<br />
work <strong>of</strong> those characterized in this paper as “theorists <strong>of</strong> difference.” Theorists<br />
<strong>of</strong> difference critique the universalistic premises <strong>of</strong> liberalism and abstract<br />
individualism. 4 They argue compellingly that these premises portray only a<br />
partial view <strong>of</strong> society, ideological in its operation and masking relationships <strong>of</strong><br />
domination and subordination. The politics <strong>of</strong> difference attempts to<br />
reconstruct political and legal theory by accounting for the perspectives <strong>of</strong><br />
those who have been oppressed by liberal societies’ penchant for difference<br />
blindness. It resists the false unity <strong>of</strong> America’s e pluribus unum and its<br />
“colour- blind constitution.” 5<br />
The idea <strong>of</strong> “difference” is invoked in political and legal theory “to cultivate a<br />
sensitivity towards perspectives that derive from membership in or association<br />
with different cultures, religions, genders and other groups.” 6 Reconceiving a<br />
democratic politics which accounts for difference, according to Iris Marion<br />
Young, would “provide mechanisms for the effective representation and<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> the distinct voices and perspectives <strong>of</strong> its constituent groups that<br />
are oppressed or disadvantaged within it.” 7<br />
Applied to Aboriginal-<strong>Canadian</strong> state relations, the politics <strong>of</strong> difference calls<br />
for a recognition <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal identity and a reorientation <strong>of</strong> the legal/<br />
institutional mechanisms which mediate those relations. Two theorists, whose<br />
work is reviewed here, look to legal institutions and the judiciary, in particular,<br />
as trailblazers in this reconstruction. 8 This paper aims to interrogate the work <strong>of</strong><br />
these theorists <strong>of</strong> difference who view judicial institutions as the vehicle for<br />
recognizing and mediating differences between the dominant society and<br />
Aboriginal peoples. Although sympathetic to the intellectual projects <strong>of</strong> both<br />
writers, this author suggests that these theorists <strong>of</strong> difference either: 1) devalue<br />
Aboriginal claims to sovereignty or title as claims to cultural difference or 2)<br />
misread the crucial judicial pronouncements on which they rely. As a<br />
consequence, their reliance on a judicial interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and treaty<br />
rights reinforces the very problems which they seek to resolve: the Eurocentric<br />
suppositions <strong>of</strong> our colonial heritage which continue to justify <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
sovereignty over Aboriginal peoples. 9<br />
In the Courts <strong>of</strong> the Colonizers<br />
The supposition <strong>of</strong> colonial sovereignty and its enduring heritage in<br />
Eurocentric <strong>Canadian</strong> constitutional law can be traced back, at the very least, to<br />
the contractarian fictions <strong>of</strong> European thought, exemplified by John Locke. 10<br />
For Locke, human productivity was a morally commendable act. Both God and<br />
reason commanded man “to subdue the Earth, i.e. to improve it for the benefit <strong>of</strong><br />
Life, and therein lay out something upon it that was his own, his labour.” 11 It<br />
was through productive labour—the appropriation <strong>of</strong> nature through<br />
work—that property came to be vested in individuals. In the state <strong>of</strong> nature,<br />
36
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
consent <strong>of</strong> others was not mandated by Locke, for “[i]f such consent as that was<br />
necessary, Man had starved, notwithstanding the Plenty God had given him.” 12<br />
Appropriation in the state <strong>of</strong> nature was subject to at least one important<br />
proviso: that one appropriate only as much as leaves “enough, and as good left<br />
in common for others.” 13 For the purpose <strong>of</strong> preserving and protecting property<br />
(in the large sense <strong>of</strong> their “Lives, Liberties and Estates”), 14 men subsequently<br />
joined together into political societies. 15<br />
Ignoring all evidence to the contrary, 16 Locke characterized the North<br />
American civilizations as living in that pre-political state <strong>of</strong> nature he described<br />
in his chapter on property: “in the beginning,” he writes, “all the World was<br />
America.” 17 Aboriginal peoples in America, unaware <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> their<br />
wealth and indifferent to property, 18 eschewed the productive life and the value<br />
which productive labour generated. There was no better evidence <strong>of</strong> this, Locke<br />
claimed, than the fact that they, “who are rich in land...having [been] furnished<br />
as liberally as any other people with the materials <strong>of</strong> plenty...yetforwant <strong>of</strong><br />
improving it by labour hav[e] not one hundredth part <strong>of</strong> the Conveniences we<br />
enjoy.” 19 Thus, a “King <strong>of</strong> a large and fruitful territory there feeds, lodges, and<br />
is clad worse than a day labourer in England.” 20 These “great tracts <strong>of</strong><br />
ground”—the “waste” land <strong>of</strong> America 21—still lay in “common” and were<br />
available to European powers to appropriate through the productive labour <strong>of</strong><br />
European agriculture. 22 What about the proviso on appropriation in the state <strong>of</strong><br />
nature that “enough and as good” be left in common for others to appropriate,<br />
which, if not satisfied, then requires the consent <strong>of</strong> others? As Tully shows,<br />
Locke bypasses this requirement by arguing that the introduction <strong>of</strong> European<br />
methods <strong>of</strong> productivity would improve the lives <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples. 23<br />
Seventeenth-century thought, then, was defined only in relation to an “other,”<br />
which was beyond the capacity for thought and reason and incapable <strong>of</strong> making<br />
use <strong>of</strong> the riches available. As Peter Fitzpatrick argues, Aboriginal peoples<br />
became “negative exemplars” <strong>of</strong> European thought, the definitive example <strong>of</strong> a<br />
“savage” human nature beyond the ordering capacity <strong>of</strong> the common law. 24<br />
Locke’s exegeses on productivity and property were incorporated expressly<br />
into the common law by William Blackstone in his Commentaries on the Law <strong>of</strong><br />
England. 25 It is unnecessary to recount here the influence <strong>of</strong> Locke on<br />
Blackstone, or his valorization <strong>of</strong> labour as the source <strong>of</strong> property rights and the<br />
rationale for political society. Suffice it to note that Blackstone also turned to<br />
America for the state <strong>of</strong> nature, where “American nations” lived in their<br />
“primaeval simplicity” until “discovered” by the Europeans. 26 It was<br />
ultimately to the benefit <strong>of</strong> all mankind that the English common law<br />
“universally promoted the grand ends <strong>of</strong> civil society ...bysteadily pursuing<br />
that wise and orderly maxim, <strong>of</strong> assigning to every thing capable <strong>of</strong> ownership a<br />
legal and determinate owner.” 27 The Lockean heritage ruled Aboriginal<br />
peoples incapable, outright, <strong>of</strong> being legal and determinate owners.<br />
English colonial policy pursued this grand end by requiring the orderly<br />
settlement <strong>of</strong> America. The Royal Proclamation <strong>of</strong> 1763 forbade colonists from<br />
purchasing or settling Aboriginal lands to the west without “special leave and<br />
licence” <strong>of</strong> the Crown. Rob Williams describes how the American colonists,<br />
hostile to the aims <strong>of</strong> the Royal Proclamation, seized on Locke’s discourse <strong>of</strong><br />
37
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
productivity to claim their “natural rights to acquire and labour upon American<br />
land, thereby converting that land into valuable property.” 28<br />
The orderly disposal <strong>of</strong> “public lands,” according to Lord Durham, was “the<br />
object <strong>of</strong> the deepest moment to all, and the first business <strong>of</strong> government” in the<br />
early part <strong>of</strong> the nineteenth century. 29 Edward Wakefield, together with<br />
Durham, advocated a system <strong>of</strong> settlement to relieve the stress <strong>of</strong> population<br />
growth on Britain, and saw in the new colonies “plenty <strong>of</strong> room” for colonial<br />
settlers and a means <strong>of</strong> financing further emigration through the sale <strong>of</strong> “public<br />
lands.” 30 John Stuart Mill in the Principles <strong>of</strong> Political Economy endorsed<br />
Wakefield’s plan for raising revenue by emigration. But it had other “greater<br />
recommendations”: “It is a beneficial check upon the tendency <strong>of</strong> a population<br />
<strong>of</strong> colonists to adopt the tastes and inclinations <strong>of</strong> savage life . . .” 31<br />
Chief Justice John Marshall assimilated this common law legacy into colonial<br />
state-Aboriginal relations. He was the first to articulate the legal relationship <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal peoples residing within the territorial boundaries <strong>of</strong> the new United<br />
States to the settlers’ new government. In Johnson v. M’Intosh, 32 Marshall<br />
invoked the concept <strong>of</strong> discovery to impose United States sovereignty and to<br />
disinherit Aboriginal peoples <strong>of</strong> their lands. In a dispute between two settlers,<br />
one who had inherited title from the Piankeshaw Indians and another who had<br />
purchased a parcel <strong>of</strong> surrendered land from the United States government, the<br />
Court confirmed that the United States alone had legal authority to authorize<br />
the sale <strong>of</strong> Indian territory.<br />
The European powers, all in pursuit <strong>of</strong> lands in the new world, established a<br />
principle “as between themselves”: “This principle was that discovery gave<br />
title to the government by whose subjects, or by whose authority, it was made,<br />
against all other European governments, which title might be consummated by<br />
possession.” 33 This entitled the European nation making the discovery “the<br />
sole right <strong>of</strong> acquiring the soil from the natives and establishing settlements<br />
upon it.” 34 Marshall proceeded to collapse the doctrine <strong>of</strong> discovery—a<br />
principle agreed upon between the “great nations <strong>of</strong> Europe”—into a right <strong>of</strong><br />
the Europeans to the title <strong>of</strong> the lands they discovered. Aboriginal peoples were<br />
“admitted to be the rightful occupants <strong>of</strong> the soil, with a legal as well as a just<br />
claim to retain possession <strong>of</strong> it but their rights to complete sovereignty, as<br />
independent nations, were necessarily diminished.” 35 This was because “their<br />
power to dispose <strong>of</strong> the soil at their own will, to whomsoever they pleased, was<br />
denied by the original fundamental principle that discovery gave exclusive title<br />
to those who made it.” It was universally recognized that the Europeans could<br />
assert “ultimate dominion” over the soil though it was still in possession <strong>of</strong> its<br />
original inhabitants. 36<br />
Some excuse, “if not justification,” for these principles could be found for<br />
Marshall “in the character and habits <strong>of</strong> the people whose rights have been<br />
wrested from them.” 37 When the Europeans arrived, the land was inhabited by<br />
“fierce savages.” Leaving the country in their hands was to “leave the country<br />
as a wilderness.” 38 Resistant to the arrival <strong>of</strong> the settlers, fierce and bloody wars<br />
ensued. The law which regulated relationships between conqueror and<br />
conquered—requiring the assimilation <strong>of</strong> the latter into the former’s political<br />
and legal society—was “incapable <strong>of</strong> application to a people under such<br />
38
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
circumstances.” Consequently, a “new and different rule” had to be developed<br />
which was “better adapted to the actual state <strong>of</strong> things.” 39<br />
That rule required that the Indians’ inferior title give way to European-derived<br />
settler states. 40 “Conquest gives title which the courts <strong>of</strong> the conqueror cannot<br />
deny,” wrote Marshall, the validity <strong>of</strong> which “has never been questioned by our<br />
courts.” 41 “However extravagant the pretension <strong>of</strong> converting the discovery <strong>of</strong><br />
an inhabited country into conquest may appear ...ifacountry has been<br />
acquired and held under it; if the property <strong>of</strong> the great mass <strong>of</strong> the community<br />
originates in it, it becomes the law <strong>of</strong> the land and cannot be questioned.” 42 Title<br />
was consummated by the United States in accordance with a principle adhered<br />
to by all <strong>of</strong> the European powers, while Aboriginal title was limited to<br />
“occupancy” by virtue <strong>of</strong> the same principle.<br />
In the Cherokee cases, Marshall had the opportunity to revisit the question <strong>of</strong><br />
Indian title. In the first case <strong>of</strong> Cherokee Nation v. Georgia, 43 the Cherokee<br />
sought injunctive relief from the federal court from the oppressive “Indian<br />
laws” enacted by the Georgia legislature which extended the application <strong>of</strong><br />
state laws to Cherokee territory in contravention <strong>of</strong> treaty obligations. Suing as<br />
independent foreign nations, Marshall denied the Cherokee relief on the basis<br />
that they were “domestic dependent nations ...their relation to the United<br />
States resembles that <strong>of</strong> a ward to his guardian.” 44 Even though the treaties and<br />
acts <strong>of</strong> congress “plainly recognized the Cherokee nation as a state,” they were<br />
not a foreign state for the purposes <strong>of</strong> the constitution. 45<br />
Cherokee claims against the oppressive laws <strong>of</strong> Georgia were vindicated one<br />
year later in the case <strong>of</strong> Worcester v. Georgia. 46 Worcester was convicted<br />
under one <strong>of</strong> Georgia’s “Indian laws” that required state permission to be on a<br />
reservation. Finding for Worcester, Marshall held that the state laws were<br />
“repugnant to the constitution, laws, and treaties <strong>of</strong> the United States.” 47 The<br />
constitution allocated the power to “regulate commerce ...with the Indian<br />
tribes.” Thus, “[t]he whole intercourse between the United States and this<br />
nation is, by our constitution and laws, vested in the government <strong>of</strong> the United<br />
States.” 48 It was beyond the jurisdiction <strong>of</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> Georgia, then, to regulate<br />
relations writ large between American settlers and Aboriginal peoples.<br />
A second branch <strong>of</strong> the judgment revisited Marshall’s earlier characterization<br />
<strong>of</strong> tribal sovereignty articulated in Johnson. Here, he more carefully<br />
distinguished between the right <strong>of</strong> discovery, as the operating principle for the<br />
allocation <strong>of</strong> rights to land in the “new” world, and the rights <strong>of</strong> the inhabitants<br />
<strong>of</strong> those lands. 49 The right <strong>of</strong> discovery, “could not affect the rights <strong>of</strong> those<br />
already in possession,” rather, discovery only granted an “exclusive right to<br />
purchase” from the original inhabitants. 50 The members <strong>of</strong> the Cherokee<br />
nation, in agreeing to the protection <strong>of</strong> the United States through treaty, did not<br />
abandon “their national character” nor did they submit “as subjects to the laws<br />
<strong>of</strong> a master.” 51 This second branch <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s judgment is <strong>of</strong>ten cited in<br />
support <strong>of</strong> the continuing inherent rights <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal communities to selfgovernment.<br />
But it must not be forgotten that Marshall found for the Cherokee<br />
on the basis <strong>of</strong> an exclusive federal power (being a strong nationalist himself),<br />
confirming the ward-like status he had described in Cherokee Nation.<br />
39
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
The Marshall legacy has influenced the Anglo-<strong>Canadian</strong> law <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and<br />
treaty rights—particularly that part which deprived Aboriginal peoples <strong>of</strong><br />
sovereignty and underlying title to their traditional lands. 52 Aboriginal peoples<br />
havebeentreatedassubjecttotheexclusivepower<strong>of</strong>thefederalgovernment. 53<br />
Authority to legislate in regard to “Indians and lands reserved for Indians” is<br />
assigned exclusively to the federal government, appearing as an enumerated<br />
head <strong>of</strong> power in s. 91(24). The threads <strong>of</strong> colonial continuity can be followed<br />
from the Privy Council’s ruling in St. Catherines Milling 54 to Justice<br />
MacEachern’s trial ruling in Delgamuukw. 55 Lord Watson declared in St.<br />
Catherines Milling, a federal-provincial dispute concerning interest in<br />
surrendered land, that “the Crown has all along had a present proprietary estate<br />
in the land, upon which Indian title was a mere burden.” 56 Chief Justice<br />
MacEachern <strong>of</strong> the British Columbia Supreme Court (now <strong>of</strong> the Court <strong>of</strong><br />
Appeal) denied the claim <strong>of</strong> the Gitksan and Wet’suwet’en peoples to the<br />
ownership and possession <strong>of</strong> and jurisdiction over their territories, a claim<br />
which they conceded would amount to a burden on the Crown’s underlying<br />
title. Characterizing their pre-contact existence as a Hobbesian war <strong>of</strong> all<br />
against all—“Aboriginal life in the territory was, at best, ‘nasty, brutish and<br />
short’”—MacEachern found only an entitlement to occupancy for use <strong>of</strong><br />
certain vacant crown land. 57 The British Columbia Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal reversed<br />
this ruling and was careful to distance itself from MacEachern’s Eurocentric<br />
discourse. The majority <strong>of</strong> the Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal found that the Gitksan and<br />
Wet’suwet’en peoples had an “organized society, and that the use and<br />
occupation <strong>of</strong> land and certain products <strong>of</strong> the lands and waters were integral to<br />
that society.” 58 The Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal was also prepared to find that they had “an<br />
unextinguished non-exclusive right, other than a right <strong>of</strong> ownership or property<br />
right...<strong>of</strong>asui generis nature.” 59 It was not prepared to find, however, that<br />
self-government jurisdiction survived beyond the establishment <strong>of</strong> either the<br />
colonial government in the mid-nineteenth century or the joining <strong>of</strong> B.C. in<br />
confederation in 1871. 60<br />
As the plaintiffs in Delgamuukw recognized, the judiciary has resisted<br />
Marshall’s discussion <strong>of</strong> discovery in Worcester, preferring to maintain the<br />
myth that discovery gave title not only against other European governments but<br />
against the original inhabitants themselves. 61 Nevertheless, some openings<br />
have emerged, beginning with the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s split decision in<br />
Calder. 62 The Court was divided over whether general legislation had<br />
extinguished the Nisga’a Nation’s right to use and occupy its traditional lands.<br />
Only after this 1970 decision did the nature <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal title surviving<br />
European contact become a contestable component <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal rights<br />
litigation. The Court’s 1984 decision in Guerin disrupted dominant judicial<br />
suppositions by finding that the Musqueam Indian Band had an interest in<br />
surrendered lands that was sui generis but subject to the overriding power <strong>of</strong> the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> state when it acted in its fiduciary (or “trust-like”) capacity. 63 The<br />
language <strong>of</strong> Justice Hall in Calder, 64 that pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a “clear and plain intention”<br />
was required to extinguish Aboriginal rights, emerged as the requisite judicial<br />
standard after the recognition and affirmation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and treaty rights in<br />
s.35(1) <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act, 1982. 65 Together with the recognition <strong>of</strong> the<br />
fiduciary or “trust-like” relationship between the state and Aboriginal<br />
40
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
peoples, 66 the judicial approach to Aboriginal and treaty rights has taken a<br />
significant turn towards “accommodating” Aboriginal difference.<br />
Yet, the unquestioned validity <strong>of</strong> the Crown’s underlying title survived even<br />
the constitutional entrenchment <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and treaty rights. In Sparrow,<br />
Chief Justice Dickson and Justice La Forest writing for the Supreme Court held<br />
that, from the outset <strong>of</strong> colonization, there never was “any doubt that<br />
sovereignty and legislative power, and indeed, underlying title, to such<br />
[Aboriginal] lands was vested in the Crown.” 67 Conscripted by the Court in<br />
support <strong>of</strong> this proposition is Justice Marshall’s ruling in Johnson. As Michael<br />
Asch and Patrick Macklem have shown, this conclusion, founded upon<br />
ethnocentric Lockean roots, rests upon “unacceptable notions about the<br />
inherent superiority <strong>of</strong> European nations.” 68<br />
Devaluing Aboriginal title to pave the way for the emigration <strong>of</strong> “productive”<br />
settlers, judicial reasoning has remained largely static on questions <strong>of</strong><br />
sovereignty and underlying title, and unceasing in its support <strong>of</strong> the settler<br />
states’ superior claims. Despite whatever openings Chief Justice Marshall<br />
furnished to Aboriginal sovereignty in Worcester, the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong><br />
Canada, in Calder and Guerin, or the Australian Supreme Court, in Mabo—<br />
what have been called “moments <strong>of</strong> accommodation” 69—the judiciary has not<br />
moved much beyond traditional common law understandings <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
title which justified the basis for colonial sovereignty. Despite these failings,<br />
the theorists <strong>of</strong> difference curiously portray the judiciary—the Courts <strong>of</strong> the<br />
colonizer—as a vehicle for challenging these dominant understandings.<br />
The False Equation: Aboriginal Claims as Identity Politics<br />
In response to this Eurocentric legacy, some non-Aboriginal scholars have<br />
turned to the oppositional discourse <strong>of</strong> difference. This discourse is hoped to<br />
yield radically different understandings in judicial interpretation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
rights and in the political responses <strong>of</strong> post-settler governments to Aboriginal<br />
claims to sovereignty. Avigail Eisenberg argues that this perspective<br />
“celebrates” difference and aims to protect identity-related differences. 70 The<br />
difference perspective may unsettle colonial-derived understandings and even<br />
banish “judicial bias” from the constitutional landscape. 71<br />
Eisenberg <strong>of</strong>fers just this thesis in her paper on identity and group difference in<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> jurisprudence. She rejects the dominant characterization <strong>of</strong> rights<br />
claims—the zero-sum game <strong>of</strong> pitting individual against collective<br />
rights—arguing that it clashes with recent <strong>Canadian</strong> jurisprudence. Rather than<br />
disputes between individuals and communities, recent <strong>Canadian</strong> jurisprudence<br />
reflects the judicial goal <strong>of</strong> protecting differences closely connected to<br />
individual and group identity. As an example <strong>of</strong> this reconstruction <strong>of</strong> rights<br />
claims,Eisenberg lookstotheSupreme Court<strong>of</strong>Canada’sdecision in Sparrow.<br />
The difference approach, she claims, is more faithful to the Court’s response to<br />
the Musqueam’s claim <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal fishing rights.<br />
The Court in Sparrow identified the integral role salmon fishing played in<br />
providing sustenance for the Musqueam people, even before the arrival <strong>of</strong><br />
European settlers. The Court then had to decide whether Musqueam fishing<br />
41
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
rights survived their constitutional recognition and affirmation in s.35(1). As<br />
the sovereignty <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> state over Aboriginal peoples was complete<br />
prior to 1982, Aboriginal rights could be extinguished if the Court discerned a<br />
clear and plain intention on the part <strong>of</strong> the state to do so. Mere “regulation” <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal fisheries being insufficient, the Court went on to consider the<br />
impact <strong>of</strong> s.35(1) on post-1982 limitations on fishing rights. Here, according to<br />
Eisenberg, the Court “sanctioned for the Musqueam band different and more<br />
advantageous fishing rights” than those available to other individuals. 72 This<br />
was because their constitutional recognition and affirmation required that any<br />
conservation measures grant priority to Indian food fishing. Even though this<br />
entailed “discrimination” for those engaged in the commercial and sport<br />
fisheries, they would have to bear the brunt <strong>of</strong> the province’s conservation<br />
measures. The Musqueam won, writes Eisenberg, because s.35(1) was<br />
interpreted as protecting Aboriginal identity and because the Musqueam<br />
argued convincingly that their “identity was threatened” by B.C.’s fishery<br />
regulations.<br />
Reading the decision as a victory <strong>of</strong> collective over individual rights would be<br />
“inaccurate” writes Eisenberg. An identity-based reading is more correct<br />
because what the Musqueam won was the protection <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal identity, not<br />
the vindication <strong>of</strong> a collective right. Consequently, “only identity-related<br />
difference[s] <strong>of</strong> sufficient significance” would qualify for constitutional<br />
protection. 73 One should agree with Eisenberg that a proper understanding <strong>of</strong><br />
this case is critical to future Aboriginal and treaty rights litigation, as it was the<br />
Court’s first interpretation <strong>of</strong> the constitutional recognition and affirmation <strong>of</strong><br />
Aboriginal and treaty rights in s.35(1). One would be inclined, therefore, to<br />
eagerly welcome Eisenberg’s sympathetic reconstruction <strong>of</strong> that case.<br />
Unfortunately, her interpretation fails on a number <strong>of</strong> counts.<br />
First, Eisenberg does not speak <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada’s reading <strong>of</strong><br />
s.35(1) which condones the unilateral extinguishment <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal treaties<br />
and rights prior to 1982 if done with “clear and plain intent.” She does admit that<br />
the decision is by no means “immune from criticism,” but does not distinguish<br />
her analysis <strong>of</strong> the decision from the criticisms it has generated. 74 In this way,<br />
she accepts, perhaps unwittingly, the continuing colonial justifications for<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> state sovereignty over Aboriginal peoples.<br />
Second, she appears to endorse the Supreme Court’s test <strong>of</strong> justification for<br />
post-1982 limitations on Aboriginal and treaty rights. The Court accepted that<br />
such limitations, even denials, could occur if they met a test <strong>of</strong> reasonableness<br />
similar to the one the Court has adopted for infringements <strong>of</strong> Charter rights. 75<br />
The state may limit or extinguish rights where there is a valid legislative<br />
objective, the rights limitation is as consistent as possible with their recognition<br />
and affirmation in the constitution, and rights are infringed as little as possible.<br />
The Court also indicated that further questions could be addressed, “depending<br />
on the circumstances”—for example, whether compensation in the case <strong>of</strong><br />
appropriation is fair and whether consultation with the Aboriginal peoples in<br />
question has occurred. Thus, the Court affirmed <strong>Canadian</strong> sovereignty and<br />
Parliamentary and legislative supremacy over Aboriginal peoples without also<br />
requiring the consent (or even consultation with) Aboriginal peoples. 76<br />
42
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
Eisenberg, by celebrating the Court’s analysis, which prioritized Musqueum<br />
food fishing rights over commercial and recreational fishing, also implicitly<br />
affirms the Court’s method <strong>of</strong> obtaining that result.<br />
Third, and perhaps more significantly, Eisenberg devalues the solemn<br />
agreements and understandings reached between European-derived settler<br />
states and Aboriginal peoples. Although no written treaties have existed (until<br />
recently) in B.C., Aboriginal peoples believe that their traditional rights<br />
survived the establishment <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> state. That is, these express and oral<br />
understandings <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal-<strong>Canadian</strong> state relations are not merely<br />
“expressions <strong>of</strong> difference,” but solemn agreements, tantamount, as the Court<br />
has said elsewhere, to “nation-nation relations.” 77 They are not simply<br />
identity-related differences, but claims founded in the legal text <strong>of</strong> the treaties<br />
and oral understandings, manifesting the sovereign rights <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
peoples. 78<br />
Eisenberg’s failure in this regard is confirmed in a footnote, where she writes<br />
that the Sparrow decision “does not preclude the hypothetical possibility <strong>of</strong><br />
other groups securing similar fishing rights in the area if they can make the<br />
same sort <strong>of</strong> argument that the Musqueam made.” 79 This “logic <strong>of</strong><br />
equivalence” between oppressed minorities hardly does justice to Aboriginal<br />
rights claims. 80 Eisenberg conflates Aboriginal claims with those made by<br />
other groups distinguished by their “difference” to the dominant society. This<br />
equivalency undermines the very essence <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal “difference” and,<br />
hence, the very objective <strong>of</strong> her analysis.<br />
Lastly, Eisenberg fails to take into account the tainted basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
sovereignty over Aboriginal peoples and their lands founded on the<br />
Eurocentric discourse <strong>of</strong> Lockean productivity. As mentioned above, the Court<br />
expressly states that the Crown’s underlying title is beyond doubt. The abject<br />
legacy <strong>of</strong> colonialism remains intact. Yet Eisenberg seems unphased by this<br />
admission. The decision, for her, simply represents the virtue <strong>of</strong> the difference<br />
perspective as a means <strong>of</strong> preserving Musqueam identity within the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
state. 81<br />
The Misplaced Faith: Aboriginal Claims and the Hidden Constitution<br />
An engaging account <strong>of</strong> the conflict between settler states and Aboriginal<br />
peoples can be found in James Tully’s Strange Multiplicity. Tully provides a<br />
trenchant critique <strong>of</strong> what he calls “modern constitutionalism,” rooted in the<br />
contractarian tradition and exemplified by the writings <strong>of</strong> John Locke. Modern<br />
constitutionalism masquerades as a universal norm when, in fact, it defines<br />
sovereignty according to European standards, thereby dispossessing<br />
Aboriginal peoples <strong>of</strong> both their sovereignty and their property.<br />
Tully argues that an alternative understanding <strong>of</strong> constitutionalism, one that<br />
recognizes and accommodates cultural diversity, can be gleaned from the<br />
“hidden [or ancient] constitutions <strong>of</strong> contemporary societies.” 82 These “hidden<br />
constitutions” can be found in two different sites: (1) “in the writings and<br />
constitutional arrangements <strong>of</strong> agents <strong>of</strong> justice who have sought to come to<br />
terms with powerful, non-European cultures, immigrants, women and<br />
43
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
linguistic and national minorities fighting for cultural survival”; and (2) “in the<br />
applications <strong>of</strong> constitutional law in particular cases, particularly in the<br />
common law, where the language <strong>of</strong> constitutionalism has been shaped to fit the<br />
reality <strong>of</strong> cultural diversity.” 83 Hidden constitutions disclose three conventions<br />
which Tully wishes to retrieve: mutual recognition, continuity and consent. For<br />
Tully, one “agent <strong>of</strong> justice” who confronted the problems posed by the three<br />
conventions was Chief Justice John Marshall, who “classically formulated” the<br />
problem by recognizing Aboriginal peoples as self-governing nations. 84<br />
In Worcester, Tully writes, Marshall delved deep into the sources <strong>of</strong> common<br />
law constitutionalism, the Royal Proclamation, and the written and oral<br />
Aboriginal accounts <strong>of</strong> the treaties which, together, reflect the “ancient<br />
constitution” and form part <strong>of</strong> US constitutional law and commonwealth<br />
common law. 85Tully argues that Marshall rejected Lockean arguments that the<br />
consent <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples was unnecessary for the Europeans to settle in<br />
North America, or that Aboriginal peoples could simply be treated as<br />
individuals or cultural minorities within sovereign European institutions.86<br />
Drawing on only one <strong>of</strong> the branches <strong>of</strong> the Worcester opinion, Tully praises<br />
Marshall’s reformulation <strong>of</strong> the doctrine <strong>of</strong> discovery as simply a principle<br />
agreed to among the European powers themselves. The doctrine did not give<br />
the Europeans the right to settle and acquire lands without Aboriginal consent.<br />
Tully concludes that Marshall “repudiat[ed] his earlier judgment in Johnson ...<br />
that the Crown gained title by conquest...[and] states that the wars against the<br />
Indians were defensive and did not convey title.” 87 Marshall’s argument<br />
provides the foundation for the treaty system, which was a vehicle <strong>of</strong> mutual<br />
consent and recognition, and provides for the continuity <strong>of</strong> that relationship<br />
between equal and self-governing nations. Rather than being disrupted by<br />
modern notions <strong>of</strong> discontinuity by conquest, consent or extinguishment, the<br />
convention <strong>of</strong> continuity carries the ancient constitutions into the modern<br />
world, “thereby rendering the constitutions <strong>of</strong> contemporary societies different<br />
from constitutional representations <strong>of</strong> them.” 88<br />
It is correct to argue that one branch <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s argument narrowed the<br />
doctrine <strong>of</strong> discovery and recognized the sovereign-to-sovereign relations that<br />
existed between the treaty-making nations. Marshall noted, after all, that the<br />
words “treaty” and “nation” were our words “having a definite and well<br />
understood meaning.” 89 It also is true that Marshall was genuinely sympathetic<br />
to the plight <strong>of</strong> the Cherokee. 90 But it is incorrect to claim, as does Tully, that<br />
Marshall “repudiated” his earlier judgment in Johnson.<br />
The other branch <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s opinion, evidently the decisive reason for<br />
finding in favour <strong>of</strong> Worcester, was the federal government’s exclusive power<br />
to regulate the affairs <strong>of</strong> Indians in the United States. 91 That federal power<br />
formed the central basis for Marshall’s decision is confirmed by his approving<br />
reference to an 1819 act <strong>of</strong> Congress which made “provision for the civilization<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Indian Tribes,” designed to “introduce among them the habits and arts <strong>of</strong><br />
civilization.” 92 The Act enabled the regulation <strong>of</strong> tribes so as to “instruct them<br />
in the mode <strong>of</strong> agriculture ...teaching their children reading, writing and<br />
arithmetic” with the object, according to Marshall, <strong>of</strong> “civilizing and<br />
converting them from hunters into agriculturalists.” 93<br />
44
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
Cumulatively, Marshall’s decisions in Johnson, Cherokee Nation and<br />
Worcester, simply left Aboriginal peoples at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the federal<br />
government which, under the presidency <strong>of</strong> Andrew Jackson in 1832, had only<br />
two alternatives in mind: either Indians were to be civilized or dispossessed. 94<br />
As Edward White concludes:<br />
The <strong>of</strong>ficials <strong>of</strong> that [federal] government were acknowledged to have<br />
the power to do what Georgia had done: place Indians in the position<br />
<strong>of</strong> abandoning their cultural heritage—becoming “civilized”—or<br />
being dispossessed <strong>of</strong> their land and forced to emigrate. 95<br />
While the decision was beneficial for the Cherokee, 96 jurisprudentially, things<br />
remained exactly the same. 97 Marshall virtually acknowledged that justice<br />
could not be obtained by the Cherokee in the “courts <strong>of</strong> the conqueror.” After<br />
all, the Cherokee were denied standing to sue in federal court against the actions<br />
<strong>of</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> Georgia. While Marshall’s treaty-based analysis “qualified many<br />
<strong>of</strong> the extreme applications <strong>of</strong> the doctrine <strong>of</strong> discovery that his earlier opinions<br />
appeared to sanction” writes Rob Williams Jr., “the Marshall Court decisions<br />
failed to establish meaningful legal protections for Indian cultural survival<br />
from the white majority society.” 98 Worcester, according to Jill Norgen, was<br />
both a “lifeline and a hollow hope,” in large part due to the equivocating<br />
language <strong>of</strong> Justice Marshall.<br />
The Marshall model, with its legacy <strong>of</strong> qualified Indian title, domesticdependent<br />
nationhood status, guardian-ward analogy and exclusive federal<br />
authority in Indian affairs, continues to be relied upon in U.S. courts as the<br />
defining basis for federal-tribal relations. Indeed, all <strong>of</strong> the English-derived<br />
settler states, including Canada, have incorporated one or more <strong>of</strong> these<br />
principles into their own framework <strong>of</strong> indigenous “rights.” 99 As we have seen<br />
in Sparrow, all that is required for the state to interfere with Aboriginal and<br />
treaty rights is that it satisfy a test <strong>of</strong> justification.<br />
It is significant, then, that Tully looks to the judicial architect <strong>of</strong> the subservient<br />
status <strong>of</strong> Indian tribes in the United States as the model <strong>of</strong> his “agent <strong>of</strong> justice.”<br />
Despite the well-meaning intentions <strong>of</strong> Tully, and other theorists <strong>of</strong> difference,<br />
their working within the framework <strong>of</strong> the colonial legal legacy does neither<br />
justice to their objectives nor to the claims <strong>of</strong> those who have been dispossessed<br />
by that legacy.<br />
Conclusion<br />
These two Anglo-<strong>Canadian</strong> theorists <strong>of</strong> difference, then, fail to rise above the<br />
colonial premises they wish to expel from legal and political theory. On the one<br />
hand, Eisenberg creates a false equivalency between Aboriginal claims to<br />
fishing and respect for cultural difference, without distinguishing between<br />
these latter claims and Aboriginal claims to sovereignty and title. Tully, on the<br />
other hand, with a much richer understanding <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal claims to<br />
sovereignty, misreads the legal opinions which emerge from, and thereby<br />
misplaces his faith in, the courts <strong>of</strong> the colonizer. Both fail to take fully into<br />
account the unwillingness <strong>of</strong> courts to invalidate the root assumptions <strong>of</strong><br />
colonization that continue to operate in the jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Aboriginal law. 100<br />
45
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Relying on a traditional model <strong>of</strong> judicial review, in which the courts act as a<br />
check on majoritarian excesses, is perhaps the habitual mistake by these<br />
theorists <strong>of</strong> difference. Scholars seeking to vindicate the claims <strong>of</strong> subordinate<br />
groups frequently understate the structural constraints which impede the courts<br />
<strong>of</strong> law from “doing the right thing.” Examining the U.S. experience in this<br />
regard, Girardeau Spann has written that, despite the operational safeguards <strong>of</strong><br />
life tenure and salary protection, the judiciary even at its highest levels, is<br />
“better understood as serving the veiled majoritarian function <strong>of</strong> promoting<br />
popular preferences at the expense <strong>of</strong> minority interests.” 101 Understood in this<br />
way, there is no “meaningful difference between Supreme Court adjudication<br />
and ordinary politics.” 102<br />
This is not to say that Aboriginal peoples should not be expected to litigate<br />
claims in the courts. Those parts <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s opinion in Worcester, Hall’s<br />
judgment in Calder, or Lamer’s ruling in Sioui that affirm the qualified<br />
sovereignty <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples serve to lessen the heaviness <strong>of</strong> the earlier<br />
Marshall, the Watsons and the MacEacherns. Yet, as Paul Patton writes about<br />
the Australian High Court decision in Mabo, “the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> cultures and<br />
powers established at colonization remain essentially intact.” 103 Clearly, the<br />
perceived role <strong>of</strong> an insurgent judiciary as vanguard <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal rights must<br />
be understood as misplaced, and the role <strong>of</strong> the Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> Canada<br />
considered less significant than it has been to date. Instead, Anglo-<strong>Canadian</strong><br />
scholars should undertake, with vigour, the dual challenge <strong>of</strong> both discrediting<br />
and radically reconstructing the constitutional common law <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
rights.<br />
Although not entirely in accord with the view taken here, the Report <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples suggests the direction <strong>of</strong> such a<br />
reconstruction. Despite the colonial remnants in contemporary Aboriginal and<br />
treaty rights jurisprudence, the Commission adopted an optimistic view <strong>of</strong> the<br />
judiciary’s potential to be a partner in that enterprise. After reviewing the role <strong>of</strong><br />
the courts in generating an ambiguous legacy <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal rights<br />
jurisprudence, the Commission asked whether “<strong>Canadian</strong> courts and the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> government” can “change gears” and abandon the remnants <strong>of</strong><br />
colonialism. The Commission indicated “there is reason for optimism” as the<br />
courts “have come a long way” from St. Catherines Milling to Guerin and<br />
Sparrow. 104 The tenor <strong>of</strong> the five-volume report, however, is directed at<br />
political “reconciliation and regeneration” achievable by federal, provincial<br />
and Aboriginal governments working together rather than via the unsteady<br />
hands <strong>of</strong> judicial interpretation.<br />
The Royal Commission’s emphasis on political-legal reconciliation<br />
underscores the need to distinguish between Aboriginal peoples fight for<br />
decolonization and other struggles. The Commission directed itself to this<br />
point in its discussion <strong>of</strong> the elements necessary for the renewal <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal-<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> state relations. One <strong>of</strong> the requisite elements is the need for<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s to come to a “better understanding” <strong>of</strong> the place <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
peoples in <strong>Canadian</strong> society. According to the final report, “<strong>Canadian</strong>s need to<br />
understand that ...equating Aboriginal peoples with racial and cultural<br />
46
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
minorities is a fundamentally flawed conception.” 105 The Commission<br />
observed that it is:<br />
the continuing nation-nation character <strong>of</strong> the Aboriginal/Canada<br />
relationship that differentiates the status <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples from<br />
that <strong>of</strong> other people in Canada. Because <strong>of</strong> this, Aboriginal peoples are<br />
not cultural minorities in the sense that <strong>Canadian</strong>s have come to<br />
understand theterm. Neither arethey citizens with aslightly expanded<br />
set <strong>of</strong> rights based on their descent from the original inhabitants.<br />
Aboriginal people have historical rights. They form distinct political<br />
communities, collectives with a continuing political relationship with<br />
the <strong>Canadian</strong> state. This is the central reality that <strong>Canadian</strong>s must<br />
recognize if we are to reconstruct that relationship. 106<br />
It is particularly ironic that some “theorists <strong>of</strong> difference” would generate<br />
equivalencies across social movements that negate the very difference they<br />
assert. This move may be justified on the basis <strong>of</strong> its “strategic” effect: it<br />
presents an appearance <strong>of</strong> theoretical unity and social solidarity in the face <strong>of</strong> a<br />
larger hegemonic system <strong>of</strong> social domination. The move amounts to a form <strong>of</strong><br />
“strategic essentialism” familiar to feminist theorists who acknowledge that<br />
gender differences are “contingently formed” yet can be deployed strategically<br />
to “unsettle existing inequities.” 107<br />
Much can be gained politically by searching for common ground between<br />
Aboriginal claims for justice and the demands <strong>of</strong> other equality-seeking<br />
groups. Coalition-building and joint political action are strategies which no<br />
subordinated group should abandon. But this must be done with an<br />
understanding that the aspirations <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples are not simply to be<br />
treated as vestiges <strong>of</strong> cultural differences, but those <strong>of</strong> nations disinherited by<br />
the unquestioned operation <strong>of</strong> the colonizer’s constitutional law.<br />
Notes<br />
* Executive Director, Centre for Constitutional <strong>Studies</strong>, University <strong>of</strong> Alberta. This paper was<br />
presented as part <strong>of</strong> the 1996 Richard Frucht Memorial Lecture Series, Association <strong>of</strong><br />
Graduate Anthropology Students, University <strong>of</strong> Alberta. Many thanks to Michael Asch,<br />
Joyce Green and Bruce Ziff for support, to Catherine Bell for last-minute advice, and to<br />
Shirleen Smith for the invitation to present this paper. I am particularly grateful for the<br />
comments <strong>of</strong> an anonymous reader. All errors remain my own, despite all <strong>of</strong> their good<br />
advice.<br />
1. I use the term “Aboriginal peoples” to mean First Nations, Métis and Inuit as they are<br />
referred to in s.35 <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act, 1982.<br />
2. Eurocentrism, in this account, refers to the sanitizing “Western history while patronizing and<br />
even demonizing the non-West; it thinks <strong>of</strong> itself in terms <strong>of</strong> its noblest achievements—<br />
science, progress, humanism—but <strong>of</strong> the non-West in terms <strong>of</strong> its deficiencies, real or<br />
imagined.” See Ella Shohat and Robert Stam, Unthinking Eurocentrism: Multiculturalism<br />
and the Media (London: Routledge, 1994), 3.<br />
3. It might be argued that the treaties conferred sovereignty on the <strong>Canadian</strong> state<br />
(notwithstanding the fact that in a number <strong>of</strong> provinces and territories, no treaties exist). On<br />
this see James [sákéj] Younglood Henderson, “Empowering Treaty Federalism,”<br />
Saskatchewan Law Review 58 (1994), 241-329.<br />
4. And its Aristotelian conception <strong>of</strong> equality (“treating like cases alike”).<br />
5. See generally Christine Sypnowich, “Some Disquiet About Difference” in J. Hart and R.<br />
Bauman, eds., Explorations in Difference: Law, Culture and Politics (Toronto: University<br />
<strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1996), 117-134.<br />
47
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
6. Avigail Eisenberg, “The Politics <strong>of</strong> Individual and Group Difference in <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Jurisprudence,” <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> Political Science 27 (1994), 1-21, 9.<br />
7. Such representation implies institutional mechanisms such as ...“having veto power<br />
regarding specific policies that affect a group directly, for example, reproductive rights for<br />
women, or use <strong>of</strong> reservation lands for Native Americans.” See Iris Marion Young, “Polity<br />
and Group Difference: A Critique <strong>of</strong> the Ideal <strong>of</strong> Universal Citizenship,” Ethics 99 (1989),<br />
250-274, 261-262.<br />
8. Although not admittedly the exclusive vehicle.<br />
9. As Patrick Macklem argues, the fact <strong>of</strong> prior sovereignty provides a normative basis for<br />
Aboriginal claims to distributive justice and equality. See Macklem, “Distributing<br />
Sovereignty: Indian Nations and Equality <strong>of</strong> Peoples,” Stanford Law Review 45 (1993),<br />
1311-1367.<br />
10. See James Tully, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age <strong>of</strong> Diversity<br />
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995); Tully, “Aboriginal Property and Western<br />
Theory: Recovering a Middle Ground” in Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey<br />
Paul, eds., Property Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 153-180;<br />
Tully, “Placing the ‘Two Treatises’” in Nicholas Phillipson and Quentin Skinner, eds.,<br />
Political Discourse in Early Modern Britain (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />
1993), 253-280. I discuss Locke’s treatment <strong>of</strong> property and productivity and its reception<br />
into the common law <strong>of</strong> the constitution in David Schneiderman, “Constitutional<br />
Interpretation in an Age <strong>of</strong> Anxiety: A Reconsideration <strong>of</strong> the Local Prohibition Case,”<br />
McGill Law <strong>Journal</strong> 41 (1996), 411-460.<br />
11. John Locke, Two Treatises <strong>of</strong> Government, ed. by Peter Laslett (Cambridge University<br />
Press, 1988), §2:26, 286 (all further references are to paragraph and page numbers in this<br />
edition).<br />
12. §2:28, 288.<br />
13. §2:27, 288; §2:33, 291. This has been called the “sufficiency” limitation. The other proviso<br />
was that we take no more property than that which will not spoil or be destroyed—the<br />
“spoilage” limitation (§2:31, 290). Jeremy Waldron argues that the sufficiency limitation is<br />
subsumed (being merely an affect <strong>of</strong>) the spoilage limitation. See Waldron, The Right to<br />
Private Property (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 210-211. With the introduction <strong>of</strong><br />
money, these limitations are overcome as all that is required to fulfill the sufficiency proviso<br />
is that people be able to work, guaranteeing the satisfaction <strong>of</strong>, at least, subsistence levels in<br />
the case <strong>of</strong> wage-labourers. See Ian Shapiro, The Evolution <strong>of</strong> Rights in Liberal Theory<br />
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 93.<br />
14. §2:123, 250.<br />
15. §2:124, 350-351.<br />
16. Peter Fitzpatrick, The Mythology <strong>of</strong> the Modern Law (London and New York: Routledge,<br />
1992), 69.<br />
17. §2:49, 301.<br />
18. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. by J.P. Mayer (New York: Harper & Row<br />
Publishers, 1969), 281.<br />
19. §2:41, 296-97.<br />
20. Ibid.<br />
21. §2:45, 299.<br />
22. Tilling, planting, improving and cultivating, for example. See 2:32, 332.<br />
23. §2:37, §2:41. See Tully, Strange Multiplicity, 74-75; Tully, “Aboriginal Property and<br />
Western Theory,” 160-161.<br />
24. Fitzpatrick, The Mythology <strong>of</strong> Modern Law, 63, 80.<br />
25. Introduction by S.N. Katz (Chicago & London: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1979)<br />
[facsimile <strong>of</strong> the first edition 1765-1769]. See Schneiderman, “Constitutional Interpretation<br />
in an Age <strong>of</strong> Anxiety,” 419-421.<br />
26. Bk.II, c.1, 3.<br />
27. Bk.II, c.1, 15.<br />
28. Robert A. Williams, Jr., The American Indian in Western Legal Thought: The Discourses <strong>of</strong><br />
Conquest (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 247.<br />
29. Lord Durham’s Report, ed. by G.M. Craig (Toronto: McLelland & Stewart, 1963), 110.<br />
48
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
30. Edward Gibbon Wakefield, A View <strong>of</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Colonization (Oxford: Clarendon Press,<br />
1914), 79.<br />
31. John Stuart Mill, Principles <strong>of</strong> Political Economy, ed. by Donald Winch (London: Penguin<br />
Books, 1970), 339.<br />
32. 21 U.S. (8 Wheat.) 543 (1823).<br />
33. Ibid., 573.<br />
34. Ibid.<br />
35. Ibid., 574.<br />
36. Ibid.<br />
37. Ibid., 589.<br />
38. Ibid., 590.<br />
39. Ibid., 591.<br />
40. See Williams, The American Indian in Western Legal Thought, 312-316.<br />
41. Johnson, 587-588.<br />
42. Ibid., 591.<br />
43. 30 U.S. (5 Pet.) 1 (1831).<br />
44. Ibid., 17.<br />
45. Ibid., 16.<br />
46. 31 U.S. (6 Pet.) 515 (1832).<br />
47. Ibid., 561.<br />
48. Ibid., 561.<br />
49. Ibid., 543-544.<br />
50. Ibid., 544.<br />
51. Ibid., 555.<br />
52. According to Brian Slattery, the “Marshall decisions are as relevant to Canada as they are to<br />
the United States, and have <strong>of</strong>ten been cited in <strong>Canadian</strong> courts.” See “Understanding<br />
Aboriginal Rights,” <strong>Canadian</strong> Bar Review 66 (1987), 727-789, 739.<br />
53. Aboriginal peoples also are subject to provincial laws <strong>of</strong> general application. See section 88<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Indian Act, R.S.C. 1970, c.I-6 and discussion in Slattery, “Understanding Aboriginal<br />
Rights,” 776-780.<br />
54. St. Catherine’s Milling and Lumber Co. v. The Queen, [1888] 14 AC 46.<br />
55. (1991) 79 D.L.R. (4th) 185 (BCSC), reversed (1993), 104 D.L.R. (4th) 470 (BCCA).<br />
56. St. Catherine’s Milling, 58.<br />
57. Delgamuukw, 451.<br />
58. Delgamuukw (1993), 543.<br />
59. Delgamuukw (1993), 547.<br />
60. See Delgamuukw (1993), 519 and the discussion in Bruce Ryder, “Aboriginal Rights and<br />
Delgamuukw v. The Queen” (1995) 5 Constitutional Forum 43-48.<br />
61. See Patrick Macklem, “First Nations Self-Government and the Borders <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Legal<br />
Imagination,” McGill Law <strong>Journal</strong> 36 (1991), 382-456.<br />
62. Calder et al. v. A.-G. <strong>of</strong> B.C., [1973] 34 DLR (3d) 145 (SCC).<br />
63. Guerin v. The Queen (1984), 13 D.L.R. (4th) 321 (SCC).<br />
64. Calder, 210.<br />
65. R. v. Sparrow (1990), 70 D.L.R. (4th) 385, 401 (S.C.C.).<br />
66. Guerin.<br />
67. R. v. Sparrow, (1990) 70 D.L.R. (4th) 385, 404 (SCC).<br />
68. Michael Asch and Patrick Macklem, “Aboriginal Rights and <strong>Canadian</strong> Sovereignty: An<br />
essay on R. v. Sparrow,” Alberta Law Review 29 (1991), 498-517, 510.<br />
69. Macklem, “First Nations Self-Government and the Borders <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Legal<br />
Imagination,” 452.<br />
70. Eisenberg, “The Politics <strong>of</strong> Individual and Group Difference in <strong>Canadian</strong> Jurisprudence,”<br />
10.<br />
71. Ibid., 14.<br />
72. Ibid., 15.<br />
73. Ibid., 17.<br />
74. Eisenberg cites Menno Boldt, Surviving as Indians: The Challenge <strong>of</strong> Self-Government<br />
(Toronto: University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1993), 32-38.<br />
49
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
75. See R.v.Gladstone (1996) 137 D.L.R. (4th) 648 and Kent McNeil, “How Can Infringements<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Constitutional Rights <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal Peoples Be Justifed?” Constitutional Forum 8<br />
(1997), 33-39.<br />
76. Moreover, the Court built into the constitutional recognition <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal treaty rights an<br />
implied limitations clause where no such clause existed. Note that such a clause was<br />
included expressly in the Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms (s.1) and that this is found in a<br />
different part <strong>of</strong> the Constitution Act, 1982 than s.35(1). See Kent McNeil, “Envisaging<br />
Constitutional Space for Aboriginal Governments,” Queen’s Law <strong>Journal</strong> 19 (1993), 95-<br />
136, 103, 105.<br />
77. See Quebec (A.G.) v. Sioui (1990), 70 D.L.R. (4th) 427 (SCC).<br />
78. Tully makes this complaint in “Aboriginal Property and Western Theory,” 169.<br />
79. Eisenberg, “The Politics <strong>of</strong> Individual and Group Difference in <strong>Canadian</strong> Jurisprudence,”<br />
15, fn.36 (emphasis added).<br />
80. See Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a<br />
Radical Democratic Politics (London: Verso, 1985), 182.<br />
81. Eisenberg, “The Politics <strong>of</strong> Individual and Group Difference in <strong>Canadian</strong> Jurisprudence,”<br />
16. As Macklem writes, “Indian government involves more than the conferral <strong>of</strong> special<br />
rights to engage in particular activities.” See Macklem, “Distributing Sovereignty: Indian<br />
Nations and Equality <strong>of</strong> Peoples,” 1355.<br />
82. Tully, Strange Multiplicity, 99.<br />
83. Ibid., 100.<br />
84. Ibid., 117.<br />
85. Ibid., 119.<br />
86. Ibid., 123.<br />
87. Ibid., 123.<br />
88. Ibid., 127.<br />
89. Worcester, 559.<br />
90. See G. Edward White, The Marshall Court and Cultural Change, 1815-35 (History <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Supreme Court <strong>of</strong> the United States. Volumes III-IV) (New York: Macmillan Publishing<br />
Company, 1988), 729 and Albert J. Beveridge, The Life <strong>of</strong> John Marshall, Bk. IV (Boston<br />
and New York: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1929), 539ff.<br />
91. Worcester, 561.<br />
92. Chapter 85, 3 Stat. 516.<br />
93. Worcester, 557. For Marshall, “[t]his Act furnishes strong additional evidence <strong>of</strong> a settled<br />
purpose to fix the Indians in their country by giving them security at home” (ibid.). Passage<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Act was given impetus by the new President James Munroe’s state <strong>of</strong> the union<br />
address, that provision be made for the Indians’ “improvement in the arts <strong>of</strong> civilized life”<br />
(quoted in Herman J. Viola, Thomas L. McKenney: Architect <strong>of</strong> America’s Early Indian<br />
Policy, 1816-1830 (Chicago: The Swallow Press, 1974), 37-38). For discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />
civilization program see Francis Paul Prucha, American Indian Policy in the Formative<br />
years (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1962), 219-224 and Prucha, The Great<br />
Father: The United States Government and the American Indians, vol.1 (Lincoln:<br />
University <strong>of</strong> Nebraska Press, 1984), 151-154.<br />
94. White, The Marshall Court and Cultural Change, 1815-35, 704.<br />
95. Ibid., 736.<br />
96. Phillip P. Frickey, “Marshalling Past and Present: Colonialism, Constitutionalism, and<br />
Interpretation in Federal Indian Law,” Harvard Law Review 107 (1993), 381-440, 405.<br />
97. White, The Marshall Court and Cultural Change, 1815-35, 732. After all, the Cherokee<br />
were not even a party to the Worcester suit. As Nell Newton describes it, Worcester “was<br />
really a defense <strong>of</strong> federal power over state power, not a defense <strong>of</strong> Indian tribal<br />
sovereignty.” See Nell Jessup Newton, “Federal Power Over Indians: Its Sources, Scope,<br />
and Limitations,” University <strong>of</strong> Pennsylvania Law Review 132 (1984), 195-288, 202.<br />
98. Robert A. Williams, Jr., “Sovereignty, Racism, Human Rights: Indian Self-Determination<br />
and the Postmodern World Legal System,” Review <strong>of</strong> Constitutional <strong>Studies</strong> 2 (1995), 146-<br />
202, 167.<br />
99. Williams, ibid., 168.<br />
100. See Claude Denis, who writes that the Courts are likely to view with hostility any claim to<br />
authority independent <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> state in “Rights and Spirit Dancing: Aboriginal<br />
50
Theorists <strong>of</strong> Difference and the Interpretation<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal and Treaty Rights<br />
Peoples Versus the <strong>Canadian</strong> State” in Hart and Bauman, Explorations in Difference, 199-<br />
226, 222.<br />
101. Girardeau A. Spann, Race Against the Court: The Supreme Court and Minorities in<br />
Contemporary America (New York: New York University Press, 1993), 3.<br />
102. Ibid., 2.<br />
103. Paul Patton, “Sovereignty, Law, and Difference in Australia: After the Mabo Case,”<br />
Alternatives 21 (1996), 149-170, 159.<br />
104. Canada, Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, Report <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission on<br />
Aboriginal Peoples, Looking Forward, Looking Back, volume 1 (Ottawa: Minister <strong>of</strong><br />
Supply and Services Canada, 1996), 229.<br />
105. Report <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, volume 1, 611.<br />
106. Report <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, volume 1, 612.<br />
107. Mary Joe Frug, “Progressive Feminist Legal Scholarship,” Harvard Women’s Law <strong>Journal</strong><br />
(1992), 37, 52 and “A Postmodern Legal Manifesto (An Unfinished Draft),” Harvard Law<br />
Review 105 (1992), 1045.<br />
51
Richard Sigurdson<br />
First Peoples, New Peoples and<br />
Citizenship in Canada*<br />
Abstract<br />
While French-English dualism and regionalism have long been treated as the<br />
primary political cleavages in Canada, many <strong>Canadian</strong>s regard race,<br />
ethnicity and culture as equally important dividing lines. Especially pressing<br />
are the political issues stemming from the divisions between Aboriginal and<br />
non-Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong>s and between ethnic-cultural minority groups and<br />
the cultural majority. This paper examines the issues raised by First Peoples<br />
and New Peoples as they challenge the <strong>Canadian</strong> political system to make<br />
room for their distinct aspirations and requirements. This exploration leads<br />
to an analysis <strong>of</strong> two alternative conceptions <strong>of</strong> citizenship in Canada: the<br />
liberal-individualist notion <strong>of</strong> universalist citizenship and the culturalpluralist<br />
notion <strong>of</strong> differentiated citizenship. Unfortunately, neither <strong>of</strong> these<br />
alternatives provides a satisfactory model for <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship. Hence,<br />
there is a need to look for a third option. Sadly, this third option appears to be<br />
elusive at this time, either as a theoretical ideal or as a practical solution to<br />
the country’s problems.<br />
Résumé<br />
Bien que la dualité linguistique et le régionalisme soient perçus depuis<br />
longtemps comme les principaux clivages politiques au Canada, un grand<br />
nombre de Canadiens et de Canadiennes voient dans la race, l’origine<br />
ethnique et la culture des lignes de démarcation tout aussi importantes. Un<br />
dossier particulièrement pressant est celui des questions politiques découlant<br />
des divisions entre les personnes autochtones et les personnes non<br />
autochtones et entre les groupes appartenant à des minorités ethnoculturelles<br />
et la majorité culturelle. Le présent article examine les<br />
revendications des Premières nations et des nouveaux arrivants qui<br />
contestent le régime politique canadien pour faire place à leurs aspirations et<br />
à leurs exigences distinctes. Cette étude mène à une analyse de deux concepts<br />
de rechange en matière de citoyenneté canadienne : la notion individuelle et<br />
libérale de la citoyenneté universelle et la notion pluraliste et culturelle de la<br />
citoyenneté différenciée. Malheureusement, aucune de ces solutions de<br />
rechange ne fournit de modèle satisfaisant en matière de citoyenneté<br />
canadienne. Par conséquent, il faut trouver une troisième solution. Toutefois,<br />
cette troisième solution demeure insaisissable en tant que concept théorique<br />
ou en tant que solution concrète aux problèmes auxquels est confronté le<br />
Canada.<br />
Every day in Canada, we are reminded <strong>of</strong> the extent to which the facts <strong>of</strong><br />
linguistic duality and regional diversity divide this country in politically<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d'études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
significant ways. Indeed, these two cleavages—duality and<br />
regionalism—have virtually defined <strong>Canadian</strong> politics since Confederation.<br />
Yet for many <strong>Canadian</strong>s, the most salient political fact stems not from duality or<br />
regionalism, but from the division between the cultural majorities—either<br />
English- or French-speaking—and the minorities whose culture and identity<br />
are “different” than the dominant ones. This category includes both those<br />
whose ancestors were the original inhabitants <strong>of</strong> the land and those having<br />
arrived recently from distant shores. (It could be extended, as well, to include<br />
other types <strong>of</strong> difference—such as gender or sexual orientation—but for the<br />
purposes <strong>of</strong> this paper we will focus only on ethnic and cultural diversity.) The<br />
overriding problem arising from this cleavage is how these minority cultures<br />
can integrate into a comprehensive <strong>Canadian</strong> (or Québécois) political<br />
nationality without losing their distinct cultural identities.<br />
This question involves complex issues <strong>of</strong> citizenship, identity and<br />
difference—themes which spark a firestorm <strong>of</strong> competing interpretations from<br />
a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> disciplinary viewpoints. There has been an explosion in<br />
citizenship theory lately, 1 partly as a result <strong>of</strong> the momentous international<br />
events which have toppled nation-states, changed borders, revived nationalism<br />
and globalized economic and political life. Equally important is the rapidly<br />
increased pace <strong>of</strong> multicultural and multiracial migration and its effect on the<br />
populations <strong>of</strong> North America and Western Europe. A huge recent literature<br />
has sprung up dealing with all sorts <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism and diversity issues.<br />
Historians, philosophers, sociologists, political scientists and legal scholars<br />
have all turned their attention to the relationships between citizenship,<br />
pluralism, ethnicity, liberalism, democracy, constitutionalism and so forth. In<br />
Canada, interest in these topics has always been high, largely because <strong>of</strong> the<br />
long cohabitation <strong>of</strong> an English-speaking majority and a French-speaking<br />
minority and partly because twentieth-century Canada has been constructed by<br />
successive waves <strong>of</strong> immigrants from all corners <strong>of</strong> the globe. As a result,<br />
Canada is among a group <strong>of</strong> a few countries in the vanguard <strong>of</strong> creative attempts<br />
to manage ethnic and racial diversity. <strong>Canadian</strong>s are rightfully proud <strong>of</strong> their<br />
country’s accomplishments in this area, and a common national ambition is to<br />
“show the world how to manage ethnic conflict, so as to avoid the horrors <strong>of</strong> the<br />
past century.” 2 It is no accident, then, that this country is home to some <strong>of</strong> the<br />
world’s leading philosophical authorities on how the institutions <strong>of</strong> liberal<br />
democracy might make room for the recognition <strong>of</strong> distinctive cultural<br />
traditions. 3<br />
In spite <strong>of</strong> its reputation for appreciating the aspirations <strong>of</strong> ethnic and national<br />
minorities and for the recognition <strong>of</strong> cultural diversity, Canada has hardly<br />
escaped conflict and turmoil. Along with the never-ending problem <strong>of</strong> settling<br />
jurisdictional battles between Ottawa and Quebec, the country faces the<br />
challenge <strong>of</strong> sorting out the jurisdictions and entitlements <strong>of</strong> its other major<br />
subnational forces—the First Peoples who demand a greater degree <strong>of</strong> selfgovernment<br />
within Canada and the New Peoples (especially New <strong>Canadian</strong>s <strong>of</strong><br />
non-European origin) who expect not only the protection <strong>of</strong> their individual<br />
rights but also some recognition <strong>of</strong> their distinctive collective rights. The<br />
challenge <strong>of</strong> finding ways to allow for greater cultural diversity within an<br />
essentially liberal constitutional and institutional framework is proving to be<br />
54
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
just as daunting as the task <strong>of</strong> finding a means to accommodate Quebec’s<br />
nationalist aspirations within aunited Canada. Indeed, even if the latter solution<br />
is unattainable, even if Quebec separates and the deux nations quickly become<br />
deux états, both societies will still have to come to terms with the challenges <strong>of</strong><br />
aboriginality and cultural pluralism.<br />
The debates over the extent <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal or multicultural entitlements<br />
highlight a larger intellectual and cultural dispute between proponents <strong>of</strong> a<br />
liberal individualist idea <strong>of</strong> universal citizenship and those preferring a cultural<br />
particularist notion <strong>of</strong> differentiated citizenship. Each <strong>of</strong> these conceptions,<br />
taken to its logical conclusion, undermines the credibility and integrity <strong>of</strong><br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship. The challenge, therefore, is to find a “third way” between<br />
these two mutually exclusive (and equally unattractive) perspectives. 4 Yet<br />
unfortunately, in Canada today, such a third way appears to be elusive, either as<br />
a theoretical ideal or a practical solution.<br />
Liberal Individualism, Cultural Pluralism, Citizenship<br />
Virtually everyone in the mainstream <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> society today recognizes and<br />
applauds Canada’s ethnic diversity and cultural pluralism. Canada, we all<br />
proudly declare, is a land <strong>of</strong> immigrants, a “mosaic” <strong>of</strong> different colours and<br />
textures in which the descendants <strong>of</strong> the founding peoples (the French and the<br />
English), along with newer immigrants from a wide variety <strong>of</strong> racial and ethnic<br />
backgrounds, peacefully share the good life with the descendants <strong>of</strong> the land’s<br />
original inhabitants. What is more, we like to say, Canada is a model for<br />
contemporary liberal-democratic polities—a place where freedom, equality<br />
and individual rights are sacred principles, but where difference is tolerated and<br />
even celebrated.<br />
Mind you, it was not until after World War II that these values became<br />
engrained in our ways <strong>of</strong> life and thought. Historically, government policy<br />
reflected the opinion <strong>of</strong> the majority that its values and institutions were<br />
superior to all others. At the federal level, government-minority relations were<br />
structured along lines <strong>of</strong> assimilation and absorption into the British North<br />
American/Anglo-<strong>Canadian</strong> identity. Indeed, only since 1947, with the passage<br />
<strong>of</strong> the Citizenship Act, was there such a thing as a <strong>Canadian</strong> citizen apart from<br />
the British Commonwealth context. Moreover, Canada’s depressing record <strong>of</strong><br />
displacement, racial exclusion and forced assimilation <strong>of</strong> Natives is now well<br />
known, as is the story <strong>of</strong> the government’s racially-based immigration and<br />
naturalization policies. In addition, the French-speaking minority outside <strong>of</strong><br />
Quebec was subject to discrimination and abandonment, while within Quebec<br />
ethnic and religious minorities were excluded from the dominant French<br />
Catholic culture and <strong>of</strong>ten faced racism and harassment from traditionalist<br />
French-speaking politicians, priests and community leaders.<br />
It was only in the postwar period that diversity emerged as a meaningful<br />
concept within Canada’s political discourse. A new generation <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
leaders successfully attacked the racist assumptions and objectives underlying<br />
the government’s Indian Act and won many positive concessions. Ethnic and<br />
racial minority groups began to make successful demands on the <strong>Canadian</strong> state<br />
for recognition both <strong>of</strong> their equality with other <strong>Canadian</strong> citizens and <strong>of</strong> their<br />
55
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
need to preserve and promote what makes them different than the majority.<br />
Explicitly assimilationist strategies were slowly replaced by those promoting<br />
racial tolerance, accommodation, equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity and the flourishing <strong>of</strong><br />
ethnic cultures. What was once regarded as a “problem” to be<br />
eliminated—namely, the existence <strong>of</strong> people who did not fit in and whose<br />
deficiencies had to be dealt with through education and cultural<br />
rehabilitation—was turned into a national resource. Today our multicultural<br />
heritage is a virtue to be flaunted at every international opportunity; and the idea<br />
<strong>of</strong> a cultural “mosaic” is an invaluable component <strong>of</strong> our national identity,<br />
especially to the extent that it helps us feel different from (and superior to) the<br />
Americans with their cultural “melting pot.”<br />
But the story does not end there (although some wish it did). In more recent<br />
years, Aboriginal demands for greater recognition coalesced around demands<br />
for differentiated group rights, particularly the right to self-government. Over<br />
the years, a limited degree <strong>of</strong> differential entitlement was sought and won in the<br />
form <strong>of</strong> affirmative action programs and public funding to enable Aboriginal<br />
groups to carry out such activities as advocating Aboriginal rights in the courts<br />
or lobbying governments and their departments. Some separate Aboriginal<br />
service agencies have been established, and a certain degree <strong>of</strong> selfgovernment<br />
has been made possible under a few new agreements (most notably<br />
for the Inuit in Nunuvat and the Nisga’a in British Columbia). Today, action is<br />
furious both within the corridors <strong>of</strong> established state power—e.g., First Nations<br />
groups negotiate directly with first ministers, while treaty rights and land<br />
claims cases flood the courts—and outside on the streets and in<br />
communities—e.g., radical native protesters set up barricades and Indian bands<br />
openly defy the laws <strong>of</strong> white society by selling tax-free cigarettes or by<br />
otherwise engaging in acts <strong>of</strong> community autonomy.<br />
Meanwhile, changing immigration patterns and demographic trends have<br />
altered the nature <strong>of</strong> the multicultural experience in Canada. There are now far<br />
fewer immigrants <strong>of</strong> European origin and many more from Asian, African,<br />
Middle Eastern, Central American and South American countries. 5 This has<br />
produced a new, more dynamic social environment—especially in Canada’s<br />
largest urban centres. In an effort to deal with this new situation, governments<br />
have come up with a variety <strong>of</strong> policy initiatives. Most prominent is the federal<br />
policy, dating from 1971, that <strong>of</strong>ficially recognizes multiculturalism within a<br />
bilingual framework. This policy, updated in 1988, recognizes the diverse and<br />
pluralistic character <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> society; encourages new <strong>Canadian</strong>s to<br />
preserve various forms <strong>of</strong> their traditional and ethnic culture, including<br />
heritage languages; and promotes racial and ethnic equality and cultural<br />
diversity, in part through an anti-racism educational strategy. One aspect <strong>of</strong> this<br />
regime involves state funding for ethno-cultural groups involved in carrying<br />
out the mandate <strong>of</strong> the multiculturalism policy.<br />
In recent years, though, ethnic groups and their representatives have been<br />
increasingly concerned with the issues <strong>of</strong> “difference” and “identity.” While<br />
the traditional equality model <strong>of</strong> citizenship subtly encourages immigrants to<br />
fit into the mainstream, advocates <strong>of</strong> the new “identity politics” argue that<br />
recognition and acceptance <strong>of</strong> difference are the crucial requirements <strong>of</strong> an<br />
56
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
inclusive citizenship. Hence, equality means more than treating everyone in the<br />
same way, regardless <strong>of</strong> difference. Indeed, it requires one to treat different<br />
groups differently when circumstances warrant. Not surprisingly, this new<br />
attitude raises confusion and leads to misunderstandings and tensions among<br />
those who believe firmly in the traditional ideal <strong>of</strong> equality for everyone. To<br />
them, it seems that the accepted rules for dealing with such matters as colour or<br />
religious affiliation were not in need <strong>of</strong> change. Yet these rules are indeed<br />
changing. For instance, the idea that institutions should be “colour-blind” was<br />
strongly endorsed in the post-war era and considered a vast improvement over<br />
the previous regime <strong>of</strong> colour-conscious discrimination. Yet today, such a<br />
colour-blind commitment is likely to be condemned as a subtle form <strong>of</strong><br />
systemic racism and white privilege. In its place should be a colour-conscious<br />
policy according to which colour-coded differentiation can be an “attribute”<br />
allowing certain individuals to compete more equitably in society. 6<br />
This new politicization <strong>of</strong> difference raises the stakes in the attempt to manage<br />
diversity. Matters are further complicated by the rise in Canada and throughout<br />
the Western world <strong>of</strong> a political movement dedicated to the promotion <strong>of</strong><br />
individual liberty (this program sometimes goes under the name <strong>of</strong> “neoconservatism,”<br />
other times “neo-liberalism,” and is also manifest in what has<br />
been dubbed the “new populism”). One <strong>of</strong> its key tasks is to countervail the<br />
demands <strong>of</strong> ethnic and racial minorities (as well as those <strong>of</strong> feminists, gay and<br />
lesbian rights activists and environmentalists). Opposed to “special rights” for<br />
racial or cultural groups, these ideologues tend to position themselves on the<br />
right <strong>of</strong> the political spectrum and insist upon the priority <strong>of</strong> the individual. Of<br />
course, not all opponents <strong>of</strong> differential rights for minority cultures fit this<br />
pr<strong>of</strong>ile—many are traditional “small-l” liberals and regard themselves as<br />
politically progressive. Still, the ascendency <strong>of</strong> this brashly ideological<br />
movement has helped focus critical attention on the polarized politics <strong>of</strong><br />
multiculturalism and the competing claims about the proper balance between<br />
individual rights and collective entitlements, between liberal individualism<br />
and cultural groupism, and between Kantian universalism and postmodern<br />
particularism.<br />
While it would be an over-simplification to suggest that these are the only<br />
alternatives on <strong>of</strong>fer today, there is nevertheless a significant polarization <strong>of</strong><br />
theoretical and practical preferences which can be expressed as two opposing<br />
understandings <strong>of</strong> citizenship:<br />
1) The Liberal Individualist Notion <strong>of</strong> Universalist Citizenship. There is a<br />
proud tradition in Canada which proclaims the principles <strong>of</strong> liberal<br />
individualism and universal citizenship. This view stresses the individual,<br />
including the individual’s ability to transcend group or collective identity.<br />
In this scenario, the individual is free to choose her identity and is not<br />
defined by her station in life, ethnic background, religious affiliation, etc.<br />
This version <strong>of</strong> citizenship treats everyone equally, regardless <strong>of</strong> race,<br />
colour or creed. Formal equality <strong>of</strong> right and equality before the law are<br />
the cornerstones <strong>of</strong> this approach. Rejected as illiberal and unfair is any<br />
type <strong>of</strong> preferential treatment based on one’s racial identity or ethnocultural<br />
heritage. Such policies, the argument runs, would “particularize”<br />
57
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
human beings, thus perpetuating exclusion and ghettoization rather than<br />
inclusion and participation. Of course, liberals agree that inequality and<br />
discrimination should be stamped out, but this must be done by means <strong>of</strong><br />
an active promotion <strong>of</strong> the equality <strong>of</strong> opportunity and not by the<br />
imposition <strong>of</strong> policies premised upon the equality <strong>of</strong> results. Thus,<br />
barriers to free and equal participation by minority groups should be torn<br />
down, but in a way that does not involve privileging minority individuals<br />
in societal competition. Finally, the individualist-universalist view <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship in no way denies minority group members the right to freely<br />
express their cultural differences. In fact, such free expression <strong>of</strong> diversity<br />
is promoted and encouraged. Yet, as an individual, and not a collective<br />
right, this right is qualified by the prohibition against impinging upon the<br />
rights <strong>of</strong> others (either outside <strong>of</strong> the group or within it).<br />
2) The Cultural Pluralist Notion <strong>of</strong> Differentiated Citizenship. An opposing<br />
argument is made by theorists like Iris Marion Young who promote a<br />
“politics <strong>of</strong> difference” and champion a model <strong>of</strong> “differentiated<br />
citizenship.” 7 The theoretical underpinning <strong>of</strong> this viewpoint is a critique<br />
<strong>of</strong> liberal impartiality, according to which we would all be treated as equal<br />
citizens regardless <strong>of</strong> sex, race, creed or class. While abstract equality may<br />
appear to be an attractive ideal, cultural pluralists argue that equal<br />
treatment in practice merely perpetuates oppression and the exclusion <strong>of</strong><br />
socially or economically disadvantaged groups. True equality therefore<br />
demands some sort <strong>of</strong> institutionalized group representation. This politics<br />
<strong>of</strong> difference would replace the liberal priority <strong>of</strong> the abstract individual<br />
with an emphasis on one’s cultural or ethnic group, for it is the group<br />
which is the source <strong>of</strong> identity and meaning in an otherwise atomizing<br />
world. Solidarity and group cohesion must be preserved among those<br />
sharing a history, a language, a culture, a set <strong>of</strong> common aspirations,<br />
goals, or a way <strong>of</strong> life. In this view, a group’s ability to confer identity<br />
upon those who are members is a primary good. Such a standpoint need<br />
not be regarded as entirely illiberal, however, since it is premised, as<br />
Charles Taylor notes, on the original liberal notion <strong>of</strong> universal equality<br />
(the “politics <strong>of</strong> equal dignity”). That is, the politics <strong>of</strong> difference assumes<br />
that humans are equally worthy <strong>of</strong> respect and is thus very much “full <strong>of</strong><br />
denunciations <strong>of</strong> discrimination and refusal <strong>of</strong> second-class citizenship.”<br />
But beyond the mere protection <strong>of</strong> individual rights must be a respect for<br />
persons as members <strong>of</strong> identity-conferring groups. Hence, as Taylor puts<br />
it, the “politics <strong>of</strong> difference grows organically out <strong>of</strong> the politics <strong>of</strong><br />
universal dignity through one <strong>of</strong> those shifts with which we are all<br />
familiar, where a new understanding <strong>of</strong> the human social condition<br />
imparts a radically new meaning to an old principle.” 8 Nevertheless, the<br />
new politics <strong>of</strong> difference, and the cultural pluralist notion <strong>of</strong> citizenship<br />
which it supports, is in direct conflict with individualistic liberalism.<br />
Unfortunately, each <strong>of</strong> these alternatives, taken to their logical conclusions,<br />
undermines democratic <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship and national unity. Liberal<br />
universalism is dedicated to the interests <strong>of</strong> the individual and not the collective<br />
whole. Its first loyalty is to the individual as an abstract representation <strong>of</strong><br />
universal humanity. Ties <strong>of</strong> civic or national loyalty cannot be granted special<br />
58
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
moral status according to such a philosophy. 9 And when this liberalism is<br />
coupled with capitalism, then citizenship and political nationality are undercut<br />
even further. Liberal universalism respects no collective identity, even<br />
nationality; capitalism respects no boundaries, including national ones.<br />
Cultural pluralism, on the other hand, poses an equally serious challenge to<br />
citizenship and national identity. To the extent that individuals identify with<br />
their own ethnic or cultural groups, there will be a tendency to withdraw into the<br />
confines <strong>of</strong> that group. The result is a sort <strong>of</strong> cultural ghettoization, with each<br />
group retreating into its own territory and tending to its own parochial interests,<br />
without much attention to the cultivation <strong>of</strong> a larger societal culture. When it<br />
comes to Aboriginal peoples or ethno-cultural minorities, then, the<br />
individualist emphasis <strong>of</strong> liberalism would deny the importance <strong>of</strong> the<br />
collective identities through which First Peoples and New Peoples participate<br />
in the larger <strong>Canadian</strong> society; at the same time, a narrow focus on the group<br />
diminishes the significance <strong>of</strong> the ways that minority communities are<br />
connected to the <strong>Canadian</strong> polity. We will have more to say about this dilemma<br />
later in the essay, but for now, suffice it to say that the two major alternatives are<br />
equally problematic. Thus the desire to strive toward a “third way” between<br />
excessive individualism and illiberal groupism.<br />
Aboriginal and Racial-Ethnic Dynamics<br />
Before examining the implications <strong>of</strong> these alternative conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship as they relate to First Nations and ethnic minority experiences, we<br />
need to clarify our choice <strong>of</strong> examples. Indeed, the difference between the<br />
experiences <strong>of</strong> First Peoples and New Peoples in Canada are so sharp that it may<br />
strike one as odd that they can be treated together. It might make more sense,<br />
under the circumstances, to compare the First Nations with Quebeckers and<br />
contrast both with ethnic minority communities. The key issues would be (1)<br />
that while immigrants freely choose to come to Canada, Aboriginals were here<br />
prior to European settlement and never volunteered to become subject to the<br />
political rule <strong>of</strong> the non-Aboriginal majority; (2) that the First Nations, like the<br />
Québécois but unlike ethno-cultural minorities, constitute a distinct “people”<br />
or “nation”; and (3) that the demands made on the <strong>Canadian</strong> state by Aboriginal<br />
activists and Québécois nationalists go well beyond cultural identity matters to<br />
include the control over land and resources, the right to self-government and<br />
jurisdictional autonomy, and the transfer <strong>of</strong> taxing and spending powers.<br />
Issues such as these are raised by Will Kymlicka, who distinguishes between<br />
“nations” and “ethnic groups” and between “multinational” and “polyethnic”<br />
states. 10 As he explains it, a multinational state is characterized by “the<br />
coexistence within a given state <strong>of</strong> more than one nation, where ‘nation’ means<br />
a historical community, more or less institutionally complete, occupying a<br />
given territory or homeland, sharing a distinct language and culture.” 11 A<br />
nation, in this sense, is hardly distinguishable from the sociological categories<br />
<strong>of</strong> a “people” or a “culture.” Polyethnic states, on the other hand, accept large<br />
numbers <strong>of</strong> individuals and families from other cultures as immigrants and<br />
allow them to retain some <strong>of</strong> their ethno-cultural particularity. But it is<br />
important, as Kymlicka sees it, “to distinguish this sort <strong>of</strong> cultural diversity<br />
from that <strong>of</strong> national minorities. Immigrant groups are not ‘nations,’ and do not<br />
59
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
occupy homelands. Their distinctiveness is manifested primarily in their<br />
family lives and in voluntary associations, and is not inconsistent with their<br />
institutional integration.” 12 Some countries, like Canada, are both<br />
multinational and polyethnic states. That is, they house both national<br />
minorities—e.g., Mohawks and Québécois—as well as numerous immigrant<br />
groups. Behind this set <strong>of</strong> distinctions, as one reviewer puts it, is the assumption<br />
that “nations deserve more rights than ethnic groups.” 13 Kymlicka’s work<br />
implies that while national minorities can only be dealt with fairly if they are<br />
granted some concrete powers to govern themselves, ethnic minorities can be<br />
satisfied with anti-racism initiatives, government grants, affirmative action<br />
programs and heritage language classes.<br />
A similar argument is advanced by Charles Taylor who, in an effort to<br />
demonstrate that recognition <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound cultural difference is the only<br />
formula on which a united federal Canada can be rebuilt, distinguishes between<br />
two levels <strong>of</strong> diversity. 14 In what he calls “first-level diversity” there may be<br />
great differences in outlook or background in a population that “nevertheless<br />
shares the same idea <strong>of</strong> what it means to belong to Canada.” 15 Immigrants to<br />
Canada fall into this category, since “their manner <strong>of</strong> belonging is uniform,<br />
whatever their differences, and this is felt to be a necessity if the country is to be<br />
held together.” The key for Taylor is that a member <strong>of</strong> an ethno-cultural<br />
minority feels <strong>Canadian</strong> as a “bearer <strong>of</strong> individual rights in a multicultural<br />
mosaic” but her belonging does not “pass through” some other community. The<br />
same is not the case for Francophone Quebeckers or Aboriginal<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s—their way <strong>of</strong> being <strong>Canadian</strong> cannot be accommodated by firstlevel<br />
diversity but requires a second-level or “deep” diversity, in which “a<br />
plurality <strong>of</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> belonging would be acknowledged and accepted.” 16<br />
Such reasoning does not please all commentators. Daiva Stasiulis objects that<br />
Taylor’s portrait <strong>of</strong> the multicultural experience is contradicted by the<br />
sociological reality <strong>of</strong> large, institutionally-complete ethnic communities in<br />
Canada’s large urban centres. And the notion that immigrants share a common<br />
sense <strong>of</strong> belonging with all <strong>Canadian</strong>s cannot take into account, for instance,<br />
the new patterns <strong>of</strong> ethnic and racial pluralism where new and wealthy<br />
immigrants, many <strong>of</strong> whom regard themselves mainly as “global citizens,” are<br />
setting their own terms for integration into Canada. Finally, Taylor is taken to<br />
task for resuscitating the exclusionary concept <strong>of</strong> the “two founding nations”<br />
(albeit revamped to include a third “founding nation”). 17 The major complaint,<br />
then, is that Taylor’s concept <strong>of</strong> deep diversity relegates all “others”—those <strong>of</strong><br />
non-Anglophone, non-French, and non-Aboriginal origin—to the status <strong>of</strong><br />
second-class citizens, just as it ranks representation questions for ethnocultural<br />
minorities below those <strong>of</strong> the “three nations”—Quebec, Canada<br />
outside Quebec, and the First Nations.<br />
Still, it is doubtless the case that the Québécois and Aboriginal peoples can both<br />
be thought <strong>of</strong> as distinct “nations” in the sociological sense. Much is made <strong>of</strong><br />
these similarities, lending credence to recent proposals for a three nations view<br />
<strong>of</strong> Canada. 18 Yet ways <strong>of</strong> being nations differ radically. Francophone<br />
Québécois share a single language, culture and set <strong>of</strong> historical experiences<br />
within a contained territory. As a province within a very decentralized federal<br />
60
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
system, Quebec already enjoys a good deal <strong>of</strong> autonomous selfgovernance—the<br />
kind <strong>of</strong> authority that First Nations can only dream about.<br />
And after decades <strong>of</strong> province-building, the primary institutions and structures<br />
<strong>of</strong> government are largely in place for Quebec to become a sovereign country<br />
according to the model <strong>of</strong> the contemporary nation-state. On the other hand, the<br />
First Nations are spread out across the continent in non-contiguous reserve<br />
lands, and many <strong>of</strong> their members reside <strong>of</strong>f-reserve in towns and cities. Indeed,<br />
many Aboriginal nations have no land base at all. In addition, each Native<br />
community in North America possesses a distinct culture and historical<br />
background. Collective identity for most Aboriginal peoples is associated with<br />
their own particular culture—Git’san, Nisga’a, Mohawk, Cree, Ojibway,<br />
Déné, Métis, Inuit, etc. The very multiplicity <strong>of</strong> languages, cultures, territories,<br />
values and forms <strong>of</strong> social and political organization among Canada’s First<br />
Nations makes the idea <strong>of</strong> a single affiliation impossible.<br />
At the same time, there is a shared sense <strong>of</strong> identity related to racial affiliation<br />
and membership among North America’s indigenous peoples. This sense <strong>of</strong><br />
identity depends largely on being “different” from the cultural majority, and in<br />
this way resembles the feelings <strong>of</strong> solidarity that may arise among disparate<br />
multiracial collectivities <strong>of</strong> New <strong>Canadian</strong>s. Aboriginal politics, like<br />
multicultural politics, are largely a politics <strong>of</strong> difference, a politics <strong>of</strong> identity.<br />
As one observer explains, “the concern is to ensure that Aboriginal ways <strong>of</strong><br />
life—which include ties to a land-based subsistence economy as well as to<br />
languages, spiritualities and cultures—continue to have relevance in the lives<br />
<strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples. This means that Aboriginal politics are cultural<br />
politics.” 19 For both Aboriginal and multicultural politicians, the danger <strong>of</strong><br />
assimilation into White North American society is a threat to their peoples’<br />
survival. Assimilation means making unique cultures irrelevant in the lives <strong>of</strong><br />
people. There is a very keen awareness <strong>of</strong> this problem among both Aboriginal<br />
and ethnic/racial minorities. For instance, the expression “apple”—red on the<br />
outside, white on the inside—is used in a derogatory manner by some<br />
Aboriginals to designate someone who accepts the values and practices <strong>of</strong> the<br />
dominant culture, thus betraying the essential features <strong>of</strong> one’s cultural<br />
identity. Similar expressions exist among racial immigrant groups—“banana”<br />
in the Asian community, “coconut” among Afro-<strong>Canadian</strong>s. Resistance to<br />
assimilation is thus a common theme within both Aboriginal and multicultural<br />
political discourse.<br />
It is <strong>of</strong>ten pointed out that unlike Québécois or Aboriginal nationalism, the<br />
discourse on multiculturalism is not about separation; rather it connotes a<br />
willingness to work within the system in search <strong>of</strong> a degree <strong>of</strong> integration.<br />
Multicultural groups seek to maintain the cultural integrity <strong>of</strong> the group, yet<br />
they accept and take for granted the authority <strong>of</strong> the larger society. At bottom,<br />
ethno-cultural groups are not nationalist in the sense that they do not aspire to a<br />
separate power base with parallel state institutions. Again, this is a valid<br />
distinction to make. Still, not all types <strong>of</strong> nationalism involve nation-state<br />
aspirations. As Gerald Alfred points out, there are different forms <strong>of</strong> nationalist<br />
ideology in the world today—even different forms <strong>of</strong> ethnic nationalism. 20<br />
One variant, more appropriate in the Quebec case than in Aboriginal<br />
communities, is a state-based ethnic nationalism “oriented towards the<br />
61
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
achievement <strong>of</strong> political independence and the promotion <strong>of</strong> cultural<br />
distinctiveness among a group within a state.” Another form, more appropriate<br />
to Native politics, is a community-based ethnic nationalism “which seeks to<br />
achieve self-determination not through the creation <strong>of</strong> a new state, but through<br />
the achievement <strong>of</strong> a cultural sovereignty and a political relationship based on<br />
group autonomy reflected in formal self-government arrangements in<br />
cooperation with existing state institutions.” Thus, state-based and community<br />
sovereignty movements have essentially different natures: “Where the statebased<br />
nationalist project is geared towards displacing the existing state in the<br />
creation <strong>of</strong> a new one, community sovereignty nationalism accepts the state’s<br />
present existence and attempts an accommodation that preserves the integrity<br />
<strong>of</strong> both the challenging ethnic group and the state itself.” 21 The prevalence <strong>of</strong><br />
this integrationist attitude within Canada’s Aboriginal communities appears to<br />
be supported by empirical research demonstrating that the clear preference<br />
among Aboriginal respondents was to develop as Aboriginal peoples while<br />
integrating with, and within, the larger <strong>Canadian</strong> society. 22 This would parallel<br />
desires among ethno-cultural groups to maintain their cultural distinctiveness<br />
within a multicultural society.<br />
Aboriginals and immigrants are in a minority cultural position vis à vis the<br />
dominant and well-entrenched majority populations in both Canada and<br />
Quebec. What is more, both groups <strong>of</strong> minorities have suffered oppression,<br />
racism, marginalization and paternalism at the hands <strong>of</strong> both the English- and<br />
French-speaking charter groups. Native <strong>Canadian</strong>s are descendants <strong>of</strong> the<br />
original inhabitants <strong>of</strong> this land yet find themselves subjected, largely<br />
unwillingly, to “foreign” customs, rules and institutions. New <strong>Canadian</strong>s<br />
voluntarily immigrated to Canada, bringing with them widely diverse national,<br />
ethnic, racial and religious ways <strong>of</strong> life, yet face an <strong>of</strong>ten difficult<br />
acclimatization in an unfamiliar and sometimes outright hostile socio-cultural<br />
atmosphere. For Native <strong>Canadian</strong>s, the task is to maintain, or more <strong>of</strong>ten to<br />
retrieve, cultural traditions that are contrary to the dominant patterns <strong>of</strong> White<br />
North America. For many New <strong>Canadian</strong>s, on the other hand, the problem is to<br />
preserve unique sets <strong>of</strong> habits and customs against the homogenizing influence<br />
<strong>of</strong> North American popular and political culture. In both cases, problems <strong>of</strong><br />
cultural and racial pluralism in Canada indicate a need to push beyond the<br />
traditional <strong>Canadian</strong> political science emphasis on the French-English and<br />
regional divisions in this country. Race and ethnicity need to be acknowledged<br />
as constitutive features <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> political experience. Such a<br />
recognition helps expand the typical social science notion <strong>of</strong> Canada as a<br />
“white settler colony.” 23<br />
To conclude this section, let it be clear that to consider diversity and<br />
multiculturalism matters in Canada and Quebec by looking at both the First<br />
Nations and ethnic/racial minority experiences is not in any way to undermine<br />
the specificity <strong>of</strong> either case. In particular, the First Nations can claim rights as<br />
indigenous peoples that cannot be claimed by any other group. In terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />
adjudication <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> Constitution or in the eyes <strong>of</strong> international law,<br />
First Nations enjoy a special legal and moral status as indigenous peoples. Yet<br />
in terms <strong>of</strong> the cultural aspect <strong>of</strong> integration by distinct cultural minorities into a<br />
62
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
larger society, we can pr<strong>of</strong>it from examining the dynamics <strong>of</strong> both Aboriginal<br />
and multicultural politics in Canada.<br />
Liberal Individualist/Universal Citizenship<br />
Until recently, as already mentioned, Aboriginal and multicultural policy was<br />
determined by proponents <strong>of</strong> a liberal individualist world view. This<br />
philosophy is most splendidly personified by former Prime Minister Pierre<br />
Trudeau, who did more than anyone else in the last 50 years to institutionalize<br />
the theoretical principles <strong>of</strong> liberalism. Among his achievements were the<br />
inauguration <strong>of</strong> the policy <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial multiculturalism and the patriation <strong>of</strong> the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Constitution with an entrenched Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms.<br />
Among his failures was an attempt in 1969 to desegregate Aboriginal peoples<br />
through integration into the <strong>Canadian</strong> mainstream. In each <strong>of</strong> these policies, we<br />
can detect the nature and observe the logic <strong>of</strong> the liberal individualist view <strong>of</strong><br />
ethno-cultural diversity.<br />
Multiculturalism first appeared in the context <strong>of</strong> the hearings for the Royal<br />
Commission on Bilingualism and Biculturalism, which was mandated to<br />
investigate current levels <strong>of</strong> bilingualism and propose ways <strong>of</strong> encouraging<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> Canada’s basic cultural dualism. Yet to many <strong>Canadian</strong>s,<br />
especially those from non-charter groups (e.g., to Ukrainian-<strong>Canadian</strong>s on the<br />
prairies), the use <strong>of</strong> the term “biculturalism” to express the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
experience was <strong>of</strong>fensive. So in 1971, the federal government <strong>of</strong>ficially<br />
implemented a policy <strong>of</strong> “multiculturalism within a bilingual framework.” As<br />
Trudeau explained in his address to the House <strong>of</strong> Commons, “although there are<br />
two <strong>of</strong>ficial languages, there is no <strong>of</strong>ficial culture, nor does any ethnic group<br />
take precedence over any other.” 24 A lot has been said about Trudeau and<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficial multiculturalism, and much <strong>of</strong> it is negative. 25 In particular, cynicism<br />
abounds concerning the purity <strong>of</strong> its designer’s intentions. The policy has been<br />
criticized as a sop to the ethnic vote, as an affront to Francophone Quebeckers,<br />
and as an unwarranted government intrusion into the lives <strong>of</strong> ordinary<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s. Nevertheless, <strong>of</strong>ficial multiculturalism has become, at least for<br />
most English <strong>Canadian</strong>s, a shibboleth. 26 And in spite <strong>of</strong> its provisions for<br />
government action to aid full participation by ethnic and cultural groups, the<br />
ideology underlying this policy is clearly liberal and individualist. A policy <strong>of</strong><br />
multiculturalism, as Trudeau put it in his 1971 Commons speech, “is basically<br />
the conscious support <strong>of</strong> individual freedom <strong>of</strong> choice. We are free to be<br />
ourselves. But this cannot be left to chance. It must be fostered and pursued<br />
actively. If freedom <strong>of</strong> choice is in danger for some ethnic groups, it is in danger<br />
for all. It is the policy <strong>of</strong> the government to eliminate any such danger and to<br />
‘safeguard’ this freedom.” 27<br />
For Trudeau, moreover, multiculturalism went hand in hand with <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />
bilingualism. Both policies were intended to promote the rights <strong>of</strong> individuals,<br />
not groups. In each case, the state legislated protection against the elimination<br />
<strong>of</strong> individual choice. Behind this was the traditional liberal concern that a<br />
person’s identity should be something that one works out for oneself, reflecting<br />
personal choices as to what is really valuable. 28 Multiculturalism was thus a<br />
“safeguard” against any threats to the liberal freedom to express one’s own<br />
63
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
identity and still participate equally in <strong>Canadian</strong> society. This would ensure that<br />
the institutions <strong>of</strong> government and society were truly representative <strong>of</strong> the full<br />
body <strong>of</strong> citizens. In spite <strong>of</strong> what its critics may now say, multiculturalism was<br />
never expected to separate one group <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong>s from another, granting<br />
“special rights” to disadvantaged groups; rather, it was meant to help all<br />
cultural and ethnic groups integrate more successfully into the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
political nationality. 29<br />
While the primary goal <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism was the promotion <strong>of</strong> pluralism and<br />
tolerance, its secondary objective was the fostering <strong>of</strong> a new and inclusive<br />
national <strong>Canadian</strong> identity appropriate for all <strong>Canadian</strong> citizens, regardless <strong>of</strong><br />
ethnic heritage. A similar goal guided Trudeau’s push to protect individual<br />
rights and freedoms with an entrenched charter. Again, much has been written<br />
about the 1982 <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms and its effect on the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> body politic; again, much <strong>of</strong> this literature is negative. 30 One line <strong>of</strong><br />
criticism sees the Charter as an attack on Canada’s conservative tradition <strong>of</strong><br />
parliamentary supremacy and a benign judiciary31; another line zeroes in on the<br />
Americanizing effects <strong>of</strong> the Charter and its entrenchment <strong>of</strong> individual rather<br />
than collective rights. 32 Either way, the Charter is reviled as a liberal<br />
document, as an institutionalization <strong>of</strong> Trudeau’s faith in universal rights and<br />
his distrust <strong>of</strong> collective entitlements. As regards ethnic and cultural minorities,<br />
the key feature in the Charter is the sweeping anti-discrimination provision in<br />
section 15. This section speaks to what Taylor calls the “politics <strong>of</strong> equal<br />
dignity” and protects individuals from discrimination based on such grounds as<br />
race, national or ethnic origin, colour and religion. There is only a nod towards<br />
the incipient politics <strong>of</strong> difference in the enigmatic section 27, which dictates<br />
that the Charter be interpreted in such a way as to preserve and enhance the<br />
“multicultural heritage <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong>s.” This section is mainly <strong>of</strong> symbolic value<br />
and enjoys little attention from litigators.<br />
For Aboriginal peoples, as well as for people <strong>of</strong> colour in Canada, the Charter’s<br />
anti-discrimination clause was intended as an affirmation <strong>of</strong> the country’s<br />
commitment to equal rights. Yet the imposition <strong>of</strong> the Charter, without First<br />
Nations input or consent, is resented by many since the values it reflects are not<br />
always shared by First Nations peoples or implemented in ways that would be<br />
appropriate for Aboriginal communities. For example, as Mary Ellen Turpel<br />
explains, “many First Nations peoples are not comfortable with the Charter’s<br />
adversarial approach <strong>of</strong> dealing with conflicts in the court system. Others<br />
challenge the Charter’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> rights as weapons to be used against<br />
governments; we tend to see rights as collective responsibilities instead <strong>of</strong><br />
individual rights—or at least see the strong link between the two.” 33 And even<br />
though the Constitution Act, 1982 entrenched, for the first time in <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
law, Aboriginal and treaty rights, these rights were left unclarified—even after<br />
a series <strong>of</strong> First Ministers Conferences (1983-87) convened specifically to<br />
resolve the issue.<br />
Vague though they are, however, the 1982 provisions for Aboriginal and treaty<br />
rights mark a departure from the earlier attempts by the Trudeau government to<br />
desegregate Aboriginal peoples through a policy <strong>of</strong> assimilation. In the aptly<br />
named “White Paper” <strong>of</strong> 1969, the Liberal government proposed legislation<br />
64
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
that would terminate the existing relationship between the First Nations and the<br />
federal government, foreclosing future possibilities <strong>of</strong> a special status for<br />
Aboriginal peoples. The White Paper, as Alan Cairns put it, “was a late<br />
twentieth-century version <strong>of</strong> the Durham Report <strong>of</strong> the previous century, with<br />
Indians substituted for the backward, unprogressive Quebec peasantry.” 34 The<br />
Indian Act was to be repealed, the Department <strong>of</strong> Indian Affairs dismantled,<br />
and the reserve lands divided up and distributed on a per capita basis as personal<br />
private property. Even the abolition <strong>of</strong> treaty privilege was envisioned as a goal<br />
to be reached as Natives assimilated into the larger society. Under this plan,<br />
Indians would be granted full citizenship rights—no more nor less than other<br />
citizens <strong>of</strong> Canada. As Trudeau said at the time, “We can go on treating the<br />
Indians as having a special status...adding bricks <strong>of</strong> discrimination around the<br />
ghetto in which they live....Orwecansayyou’re at a crossroads—the time is<br />
now to decide whether the Indians will be a race apart in Canada or whether<br />
[they] will be <strong>Canadian</strong>s <strong>of</strong> full status.” 35 Eventually the whole plan was<br />
shelved, due to its hostile reaction from the Aboriginal community; but<br />
Trudeau continued to interpret Aboriginal issues in terms <strong>of</strong> the desirability <strong>of</strong><br />
the absolute equality <strong>of</strong> citizenship rights.<br />
Instead <strong>of</strong> this equal citizenship model (or the equally problematical groupdifferentiation<br />
paradigm) there are ways to imagine the role <strong>of</strong> First Nations as<br />
culturally separate groups who are still tied to the whole. An example is the old<br />
“citizens plus” idea that emerged from the Hawthorn-Trembley Report <strong>of</strong><br />
1966. 36 By “citizens plus” it was meant that Aboriginal people would have all<br />
<strong>of</strong> the normal entitlements <strong>of</strong> citizenship, plus certain benefits or special status<br />
that would flow from their historical claims and contemporary needs. What<br />
might constitute the contents <strong>of</strong> the “plus” package would look different now<br />
than it would have in the 1960s, but the basic idea may still be workable as a<br />
middle route between the insistence upon absolute equality <strong>of</strong> citizenship and<br />
widely differentiated citizenship. Under such a framework <strong>of</strong> understanding,<br />
Aboriginal peoples could claim the right to be different (the right to<br />
recognition) as well as a right to be the same (the right to equal dignity); they<br />
could be granted special concessions (equality <strong>of</strong> results) and still enjoy the<br />
equal treatment that befits any citizen (formal equality <strong>of</strong> right). This model<br />
may even be used to accommodate ethnic and cultural minorities (though their<br />
package <strong>of</strong> “plus” rights would differ significantly from the package <strong>of</strong> special<br />
Aboriginal rights).<br />
Yet opposition to any form <strong>of</strong> “special status” for First Nations or multicultural<br />
groups persists within the larger <strong>Canadian</strong> community. Mel Smith, a prominent<br />
constitutional expert and former deputy minister in several British Columbia<br />
governments, has recently argued for a new Aboriginal policy based on the two<br />
principles <strong>of</strong> Native self-reliance and equality under the law. In support <strong>of</strong> the<br />
latter, Smith writes: “It is contrary to all that Canada stands for to support a<br />
policy that extends special privileges based on race or ethnicity. This is a<br />
principle so fundamental to liberal democratic societies that it should not even<br />
be necessary to state it.” 37 These theoretical issues quickly become practical<br />
problems when Aboriginal rights, based on the notion <strong>of</strong> the preservation <strong>of</strong><br />
distinct cultural practices, collide with non-Aboriginal livelihoods—e.g.,<br />
disputes between Native and non-Native commercial fishers on the West Coast<br />
65
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
and conflicts over energy or mineral resource exploitation. In these cases, the<br />
demand for “special rights” for First Nations groups <strong>of</strong>ten meets with a great<br />
deal <strong>of</strong> hostility from the non-Aboriginal population. For instance, the Reform<br />
Party <strong>of</strong> Canada (which also opposes <strong>of</strong>ficial multiculturalism) is consistently<br />
critical <strong>of</strong> programs which would confer special status to Aboriginal<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s. The language used by Reformers is reminiscent <strong>of</strong> Prime Minister<br />
John Diefenbaker’s famous avowal <strong>of</strong> “unhyphenated <strong>Canadian</strong>ism” within<br />
what he called “One Canada.” 38 This notion, in Diefenbaker’s words, stood for<br />
“prejudice toward none and freedom for all. There were to be no second-class<br />
citizens.” 39<br />
To summarize: the liberal individualist view rests on the conferral <strong>of</strong> universal<br />
citizenship with entitlements derived from formal individual rights. For ethnic<br />
and cultural communities, this means protection for their members as<br />
individuals against racial, religious or ethnic discrimination. It may also mean<br />
that the state will take some positive steps to endorse pluralism and tolerance,<br />
ensuring that the ideals <strong>of</strong> liberalism are approximated in social reality. But the<br />
liberal view sees political community as the servant <strong>of</strong> individual identity and<br />
not communal identity. Thus, there can be no room for differential group rights,<br />
no matter how distinct the group may be. Yet many members <strong>of</strong> ethnic or<br />
cultural communities, like Canada’s Aboriginal peoples or members <strong>of</strong><br />
multicultural groups, regard themselves not just as isolated, rights-bearing<br />
individuals but as parts <strong>of</strong> larger communities from which they draw their<br />
inspiration and sense <strong>of</strong> identity. Hence, there is a bitter resentment <strong>of</strong> the<br />
liberal tendency to downplay the importance <strong>of</strong> a person’s connection to a<br />
racial group or ethno-cultural community.<br />
Cultural Pluralist/Differentiated Citizenship<br />
For liberals, democratic progress has always entailed a tendency away from<br />
group privilege and toward an ideal <strong>of</strong> citizenship in which each individual<br />
counts equally as one. Liberal, progressive and radical thinkers have<br />
traditionally strived to achieve a politics in which people transcend their<br />
localized and particularist concerns and participate freely in the open space <strong>of</strong><br />
public life. 40 The politics <strong>of</strong> group identity and representation, now very much<br />
in vogue among today’s progressive and radical thinkers, conflicts with what<br />
has been the main movement <strong>of</strong> universalist liberal-democracy. To cultural<br />
pluralists, as we have seen, the accommodation <strong>of</strong> differences and the<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> group-based special needs is a prerequisite for social justice and<br />
national unity.<br />
The challenge <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism in a country such as Canada is to<br />
accommodate cultural, racial and ethnic differences in an effective and morally<br />
justifiable manner. The way to do this, say the cultural pluralists, is to grant<br />
cultural minorities certain group-specific rights. While this need not entail a<br />
renunciation <strong>of</strong> liberal ideals <strong>of</strong> individual freedom and fairness, 41 it does<br />
involve the abandonment <strong>of</strong> liberal universalism. Will Kymlicka enumerates<br />
three common forms <strong>of</strong> group-differentiated rights which national or ethnic<br />
minorities might legitimately demand: 42<br />
66
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
1) Self-government rights. These would involve some form <strong>of</strong> political<br />
autonomy for the component groups, either within a federal structure or a<br />
loose confederation. Typically this would entail the devolution <strong>of</strong> power<br />
to a political unit substantially controlled by a national minority and<br />
roughly corresponding to its historical homeland or territory.<br />
2) Polyethnic rights. Here minority groups expect not only freedom from<br />
discrimination but demand that positive steps be taken to allow them to<br />
express their cultural particularity. Measures intended for this purpose<br />
commonly include public funding <strong>of</strong> ethno-cultural groups, financial<br />
support for their cultural practices, and legal exemptions from rules that<br />
disadvantage members <strong>of</strong> particular ethnic or religious minorities.<br />
3) Special representation rights. This type <strong>of</strong> group-differentiated measure<br />
is aimed at alleviating situations <strong>of</strong> under-representation within positions<br />
<strong>of</strong> political power and influence <strong>of</strong> disadvantaged minority groups. Means<br />
such as affirmative action programs or guaranteed seats for ethnic or<br />
national groups within the institutions <strong>of</strong> the larger state are commonly<br />
advocated.<br />
Given these observations, Aboriginal peoples might legitimately qualify for all<br />
three types <strong>of</strong> group-differentiated rights. They might receive both special<br />
representation and polyethnic rights due to their disadvantaged circumstances,<br />
aswellasself-governmentrightsduetotheirstatusasa“people”or“nation.”<br />
First, Aboriginal peoples have a good case for winning special representation<br />
rights. As a socially and economically disadvantaged group, Natives would be<br />
entitled under section 15(2) <strong>of</strong> the Charter to benefit from affirmative action<br />
programs even without the further constitutional support for such differential<br />
treatment provided in the Aboriginal and treaty rights provisions. In fact, many<br />
such programs already exist—they provide for special placements in education<br />
and training courses, or for equity hiring <strong>of</strong> First Nations applicants. When it<br />
comes to improved institutional access and representation in the political<br />
domain, however, not much has been done, though many ideas have been<br />
circulated. It is sometimes argued that Aboriginal candidates are disadvantaged<br />
in the political process—in part because <strong>of</strong> the thin distribution <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal<br />
peoples across the country—and therefore require a means <strong>of</strong> explicit<br />
representation. This might take the form <strong>of</strong> separate Aboriginal representation<br />
in the House <strong>of</strong> Commons or a certain number <strong>of</strong> guaranteed seats in provincial<br />
legislatures and the <strong>Canadian</strong> Senate. First Nations representation may also be<br />
mandated for federally-appointed agencies, boards and commissions. And<br />
Aboriginal organizations could be called upon to play an institutionalized role<br />
in the appointment procedure for designated federal positions, such as Supreme<br />
Court Justices.<br />
Second, Aboriginal groups enjoy certain polyethnic rights at present, mainly<br />
under the rubric <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism and the promotion <strong>of</strong> Native awareness and<br />
education. Aboriginal organizations receive various forms <strong>of</strong> funding for their<br />
political and cultural activities. A related set <strong>of</strong> programs has been funded by<br />
governments to allow Aboriginal communities to take control <strong>of</strong> certain social<br />
services, such as community health or child protection services. Limited<br />
67
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
experiments with Native-only schools in inner cities and with Aboriginal<br />
heritage classes are now up and running. More controversial are steps to<br />
institutionalize a separate Aboriginal justice system or to exempt Native<br />
persons from laws and regulations that might disadvantage them. Unlike<br />
affirmative action plans, these sorts <strong>of</strong> group-specific measures are not<br />
intended to be temporary, since the cultural differences they protect are not<br />
something that we seek to eliminate. As a result <strong>of</strong> their successful<br />
implementation, however, these programs would loosen the ties between<br />
Aboriginal peoples and the traditional federal and provincial governments.<br />
While this has been the stated goal <strong>of</strong> many Aboriginal activists, the risks<br />
implicit in this strategy are <strong>of</strong>ten overlooked. For example, there should be<br />
concern that the “removal <strong>of</strong> Aboriginal peoples from the ‘we’ group <strong>of</strong> the<br />
non-Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong> majority will tend to reduce the degree <strong>of</strong> concern<br />
and civic obligation held by the latter to the former. Simultaneously, it will tend<br />
toweakenthemoralpowertheclaims<strong>of</strong>theformercanmakeonthelatter.” 43<br />
Finally, and most controversially, Aboriginal leaders demand some form <strong>of</strong><br />
political or jurisdictional autonomy in order to ensure the full and free<br />
development <strong>of</strong> their culture and to achieve what is in the best interests <strong>of</strong> their<br />
people. At the heart <strong>of</strong> the drive by Canada’s First Nations to regain control <strong>of</strong><br />
their lives and destinies is the concept <strong>of</strong> self-determination, <strong>of</strong>ten expressed in<br />
terms <strong>of</strong> an inherent right to Aboriginal self-government. Unfortunately,<br />
Aboriginal self-government is a notoriously enigmatic concept. No clear<br />
definitions exist, and the attempts at clarification have <strong>of</strong>ten raised more<br />
questions than they have answered. In any event, we know that models <strong>of</strong> selfgovernment<br />
will vary tremendously according to community needs and<br />
resources. Aboriginal peoples will wield a wide-range <strong>of</strong> jurisdictional<br />
power—from near-provincial status in Nunavut, for instance, to quasimunicipal<br />
roles elsewhere. However, there is every reason to believe that<br />
Aboriginal entitlement will derive from constitutionally entrenched rights,<br />
making it different in kind from other forms <strong>of</strong> group rights. In this sense, First<br />
Nations peoples will almost certainly exercise significant degrees <strong>of</strong><br />
differential citizenship rights within Canada. 44<br />
The story is different for multicultural groups. Members <strong>of</strong> ethno-cultural<br />
minorities in Canada do not aspire to self-government and, depending upon<br />
how you read the situation, they may be entitled only to polyethnic rights,<br />
especially if the minority group in question is an economically successful one.<br />
But the demands <strong>of</strong> at least some multiculturalists in Canada would see a<br />
conferral <strong>of</strong> significant group-specific rights on minority ethnic communities.<br />
These would include provisions for public funding <strong>of</strong> separate schools for<br />
particular religious or racial/ethnic minorities. In addition, a wide range <strong>of</strong><br />
cultural exemptions would have to be recognized. These might pertain to such<br />
things as religious holidays, forms <strong>of</strong> dress, access to the media and other forms<br />
<strong>of</strong> communication, restrictions on certain types <strong>of</strong> public discourse, cultural<br />
censorship <strong>of</strong> teaching materials, etc. In addition, ethnic and cultural minorities<br />
sometimes make strong claims for affirmative action and equitable<br />
representation policies.<br />
68
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
To be sure, the emergence <strong>of</strong> new ethno-cultural issues has proved volatile in<br />
several quarters <strong>of</strong> society, and <strong>of</strong>ficials are not unaware <strong>of</strong> this phenomenon. 45<br />
Immigration policy has been the source <strong>of</strong> much political controversy, with<br />
vocal interests demanding reductions in the numbers <strong>of</strong> immigrants and<br />
changes to current immigration procedures. At the extreme, there have been<br />
calls for an end to so-called “non-traditional” immigration (i.e., immigrants <strong>of</strong><br />
non-European origin) and the deportation <strong>of</strong> all immigrants convicted <strong>of</strong><br />
criminal behaviour while in Canada (this hot-button issue raises the<br />
controversial link between certain groups <strong>of</strong> immigrants and increased crime<br />
rates). Of course, the policy <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial multiculturalism has long been a target<br />
for heated criticism and debate. Some critics feel that the multiculturalism<br />
policy lacks substance, that it is only about funding ethnic dance troupes or<br />
international food festivals. Others charge that it does little to encourage racial<br />
and ethnic harmony but has the converse effect <strong>of</strong> hardening racial and ethnic<br />
prejudice by stressing the differences between groups rather than the shared<br />
ideals and values <strong>of</strong> all <strong>Canadian</strong>s. Multiculturalism, according to this view, is a<br />
regressive policy, that ghettoizes minorities and keeps in their own ethnic<br />
enclaves. These points have been forcefully advanced recently in Neil<br />
Bissoondath’s critical book on the subject. 46<br />
In addition, there is much concern that policies designed to accommodate racial<br />
or ethnic minorities have undermined the traditions and symbols that are unique<br />
to Canada, leaving the nation without a clear identity cemented by unifying<br />
cultural institutions and customs. The decision to allow Sikh RCMP <strong>of</strong>ficers to<br />
wear turbans, for instance, led to an <strong>of</strong>ten acrimonious national debate, as did<br />
the decree by some branches <strong>of</strong> the Royal <strong>Canadian</strong> Legion to forbid entry to<br />
anyone sporting headgear, such as turbans or yarmulkes. Another controversy<br />
arose when some school boards in Quebec banned the wearing <strong>of</strong> the hijab,a<br />
form <strong>of</strong> head covering worn by many Muslim women, on the basis that it is a<br />
religious symbol and reflects female oppression and Islamic fanaticism.<br />
Equally controversial are plans for segregated, “black-focused” schools in<br />
Toronto, under the auspices <strong>of</strong> what is called “empowerment multicultural<br />
education.” Advocates <strong>of</strong> the proposal see it as a way to reverse the trend among<br />
black students to drop out at rates two or three times higher than other students;<br />
opponents see it as a return to the bad old days <strong>of</strong> racial segregation and fear it<br />
willleadtoapatchwork<strong>of</strong>separateschoolsystemsbasedonraceandethnicity.<br />
These are just a few <strong>of</strong> the flashpoints in a larger cultural war over the very<br />
meaning <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> political nationality. As we have seen, Canada has<br />
recently fancied itself as a cultural mosaic, in which each ethnic or racial group<br />
preserves its heritage with the help and sympathy <strong>of</strong> government. The crucial<br />
role played by the state (rather than the ethno-cultural communities<br />
themselves) harmonizes with the general <strong>Canadian</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> positive<br />
government and the use <strong>of</strong> state power to effect larger public purposes. But<br />
times are changing, including attitudes about the proper depth and scope <strong>of</strong><br />
government involvement in social affairs. In a time <strong>of</strong> fiscal restraint, many<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s now feel that their governments, pressured by self-interested<br />
multicultural leaders, have gone too far in their attempts to accommodate<br />
diversity. Many <strong>Canadian</strong>s feel uncomfortable with the social changes<br />
characteristic <strong>of</strong> a highly multiracial and multicultural society; as a result, they<br />
69
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
would rather see Canada as more <strong>of</strong> a cultural melting pot—like in the US,<br />
where immigrants are expected to assimilate into the homogenous American<br />
way <strong>of</strong> life—than as an unwieldy mosaic. 47 Other <strong>Canadian</strong>s are mainly<br />
concerned with their own economic futures, and this sometimes boils over as a<br />
resentment against recent immigrants (predominantly now visible minorities).<br />
To the extent, for instance, that employment equity programs are perceived to<br />
privilege such minorities over the majority in a shrinking job market, populist<br />
reaction can be harsh.<br />
First Peoples, New Peoples and Quebec<br />
Throughout this paper there has been an eery absence <strong>of</strong> any specific discussion<br />
<strong>of</strong> Quebec. For the most part, my observations apply to controversies and<br />
debates pertinent to the English half <strong>of</strong> the duality. This saves a lot <strong>of</strong> trouble, to<br />
be sure, but also makes some logistical sense. Relations between First Nations<br />
and the Quebec government are in fact minimal. That is, most Aboriginal<br />
peoples in Quebec have few structural ties with the provincial state—the<br />
exceptions being in the health care and social services sectors. 48 Quebec’s<br />
Aboriginal peoples relate mainly to the federal authorities. And in matters <strong>of</strong><br />
identity and goal formation, the larger community with which First Nations in<br />
Quebec want to remain affiliated is the broadly-defined <strong>Canadian</strong> one, and not<br />
the particularist society <strong>of</strong> French Quebec. If anything, the Quebec government<br />
is viewed by Quebec’s First Nations as a source <strong>of</strong> conflict and hostility.<br />
Quebec’s Native bands have <strong>of</strong>ten rejected the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> Quebec’s<br />
institutions and exerted their own autonomy. What is more, specific irritants<br />
persist, such as the bad relations between Mohawks and the provincial police<br />
force since the crisis at Oka several years ago.<br />
At the root <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> the tension is language, and this puts Aboriginal groups<br />
in Quebec in the same camp as the province’s Anglophones and allophones.<br />
Québécois nationalism is constructed around the French language and a<br />
distinctive Québécois cultural identity. Most First Nations people in Quebec do<br />
not speak French and few participate actively in Québécois culture. Not<br />
surprisingly, Quebec’s Aboriginal peoples, along with most Anglophones and<br />
allophones, perceive great dangers in the movement toward Quebec<br />
sovereignty, while the majority <strong>of</strong> Francophone Quebeckers believe that<br />
Quebec’s natural destiny is estrangement from Canada. The competing ethnic<br />
nationalisms <strong>of</strong> the First Nations and the Québécois complicate matters further<br />
since both rely upon the assumption that “nations” have an inherent right to<br />
self-determination. This leads Quebec’s First Nations to argue either for<br />
outright sovereignty or for the right to stay in Canada if Quebec decides to<br />
separate. Increasingly, Anglophone and allophone Quebeckers, especially in<br />
Montreal, make similar arguments for remaining with Canada, leading to talk<br />
<strong>of</strong> Quebec’s partition which understandably raises the ire <strong>of</strong> Francophone<br />
Quebeckers. None <strong>of</strong> this makes it any easier, at the federal level, to<br />
accommodate either First Peoples or New Peoples when their demands are<br />
resisted by the Quebec government.<br />
In one sense, <strong>of</strong> course, the cultural position <strong>of</strong> First Peoples and New Peoples<br />
in Quebec is equivalent to their station in the rest <strong>of</strong> Canada. That is, they are<br />
70
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
minorities attempting to hang on to their racial or ethno-cultural differences in<br />
the face <strong>of</strong> a dominant majority culture. Without doubt, however, the politics <strong>of</strong><br />
the French-English dualism in Quebec affects minority-majority relations to<br />
the extent that Aboriginal peoples and immigrant ethnic communities in the<br />
province face situations not shared by their counterparts elsewhere in Canada.<br />
In the 1970s and 1980s, for example, Francophone sympathy for Native<br />
peoples in Canada was higher than that <strong>of</strong> Anglophones; but this pattern<br />
changed significantly in the 1990s. Today, Quebeckers tend to take a harder<br />
line than other <strong>Canadian</strong>s on Aboriginal issues. In addition, studies show that<br />
French-speaking <strong>Canadian</strong>s display a less favourable attitude towards non-<br />
English and non-French ethnic origin groups than English-speakers, and that<br />
they also prefer more strongly than other <strong>Canadian</strong>s an atmosphere <strong>of</strong> “cultural<br />
uniformity” rather than “cultural diversity.” Quebeckers and Francophones<br />
also score lower than other <strong>Canadian</strong>s on questionnaires measuring relative<br />
levels <strong>of</strong> comfort with immigrants. Thus, survey research indicates that<br />
Aboriginal and ethno-cultural minorities in Quebec have to define themselves<br />
as Quebec minorities distinct from their counterparts in the rest <strong>of</strong> the<br />
country. 49<br />
Ideologically, moreover, the circumstances faced by Aboriginal and ethnocultural<br />
minority groups are quite different outside and inside <strong>of</strong> Quebec.<br />
Outside <strong>of</strong> Quebec, as we have suggested, the major vision <strong>of</strong> citizenship is a<br />
liberal-individualistic one which sees political community as instrumental for<br />
the betterment <strong>of</strong> individual happiness and flourishing. This is the “Pierre<br />
Trudeau” vision <strong>of</strong> citizenship with its uncompromising appeal to individual<br />
rights and with all <strong>of</strong> its problems for group identity and representation already<br />
outlined. Inside Quebec, on the other hand, a more communitarian notion <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship holds sway which emphasizes solidarity among a given people<br />
(understood as a linguistic/ethnic category as well as a territorial one) and<br />
which sees political community as instrumental to the elaboration and<br />
promotion <strong>of</strong> a collective identity. Following Ronald Beiner, we might call this<br />
the “Jacques Parizeau” vision <strong>of</strong> citizenship with its invocation <strong>of</strong> “old stock”<br />
Québécois. 50 Yet many Quebeckers base their nationalism on territorial<br />
imperatives and reject adamantly any linkage <strong>of</strong> nationalism with race or<br />
ethnicity. But whether ethnic-based or territorial, nationalism in Quebec<br />
collides with the aspirations <strong>of</strong> Quebec’s First Peoples. For the Cree or Inuit,<br />
territorial nationalism is still a threat since it extends the sovereignty <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Francophone population into what they see as their own territory.<br />
Thus, many questions are raised about how the two types <strong>of</strong> diversity under<br />
scrutiny in this paper can be accommodated within a nationalist Quebec. Are<br />
allegiances to Quebec’s national interest to come at the cost <strong>of</strong> suppressing the<br />
more specific identities <strong>of</strong> individuals and groups within Quebec’s boundaries?<br />
How far is it justifiable to restrict individual liberty in the name <strong>of</strong> a collective<br />
identity? To what extent may cultural minorities be forced to conform to the<br />
values and ways <strong>of</strong> life <strong>of</strong> the national majority? How far may immigration or<br />
education policy be legitimately shaped by the demands <strong>of</strong> nationality? These<br />
sorts <strong>of</strong> questions would dominate a more detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> First Peoples and<br />
New Peoples in Quebec. And they would be as inescapable in an independent<br />
Quebec as they are for Quebec as a <strong>Canadian</strong> province.<br />
71
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Conclusion: The Elusive “Third Way”<br />
Our survey <strong>of</strong> the alternative conceptions <strong>of</strong> citizenship and their relation to<br />
Aboriginal and multicultural politics leads to the disquieting conclusion that<br />
neither model can <strong>of</strong>fer a satisfactory means <strong>of</strong> managing diversity. The liberal<br />
model <strong>of</strong> universal citizenship cannot be attractive to First Peoples or New<br />
Peoples because it emphasizes their members’ individual identities and urges<br />
them to transcend their attachment to the group or collectivity for the purposes<br />
<strong>of</strong> enjoying full and equal participation rights in the larger society. The pluralist<br />
model is <strong>of</strong>ten more attractive, especially to Aboriginal leaders and ethnocultural<br />
group representatives, but it may have adverse consequences both for<br />
the groups themselves and for the larger society to which they wish to remain<br />
affiliated. There is real doubt that a single state could maintain a sense <strong>of</strong><br />
nationhood and provide truly multinational rights and/or polyethnic rights to its<br />
subnational communities without inevitably moving in the direction <strong>of</strong><br />
separation or disintegration. Moreover, serious theoretical problems exist<br />
within the cultural pluralist framework. In a powerful recent article, Katherine<br />
Fierlbeck questions the claim that cultural identity can confer sufficient<br />
“normative force” upon which to base differentiated political rights for distinct<br />
cultural groups. 51 She also raises the troubling issue <strong>of</strong> the dangers inherent in<br />
placing so much political value upon cultural identity. For one thing, this can be<br />
used to justify the persecution <strong>of</strong> individuals on the basis <strong>of</strong> difference, since the<br />
very emphasis on cultural identity as a force binding people together can be<br />
seen as a force for keeping different peoples apart. Second, the focus on the<br />
distinct rights <strong>of</strong> cultural groups may “reinforce the marginalization <strong>of</strong> those<br />
who are already disadvantaged within the group.” 52 Thus, the practice <strong>of</strong><br />
establishing group rights on the basis <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> cultural identity alone may<br />
be philosophically unconvincing and possibly dangerous in practice.<br />
So we are faced with a frustrating theoretical conundrum. On the one hand,<br />
various versions <strong>of</strong> liberal universalism glorify the ideal <strong>of</strong> an abstract<br />
individual above any collective or communal identity. Yet this ideology, with<br />
its vision <strong>of</strong> society as an agglomeration <strong>of</strong> competing individuals, cannot<br />
tolerate the privileging <strong>of</strong> an “exclusive and particularist” identity, such as<br />
national citizenship requires. On the other hand, we have the forces <strong>of</strong><br />
exclusivity and particularism that affirm group differences, emphasizing that<br />
which distinguishes some people from others. This philosophy also tends to<br />
subvert, from the opposite direction, the idea <strong>of</strong> civic community. This leaves<br />
us with a dilemma expressed nicely by Ronald Beiner in his reflections on<br />
current citizenship theory:<br />
To opt wholeheartedly for universalism implies deracination—<br />
rootlessness. To opt wholeheartedly for particularism implies<br />
parochialism, exclusivity, and narrow-minded closure <strong>of</strong> horizons.<br />
Yet it is by no means clear that a viable synthesis <strong>of</strong> particularist<br />
rootedness and universalistic openness is philosophically or<br />
practically available. In practice, and perhaps in theory, we always<br />
seem to get drawn to one unsatisfactory extreme or the other. This<br />
elusive synthesis <strong>of</strong> liberal cosmopolitanism and illiberal<br />
particularism, to the extent that it is attainable is what I want to call<br />
“citizenship.” 53<br />
72
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
Under this category <strong>of</strong> “citizenship,” Beiner has in mind a third possibility that<br />
is neither strictly liberal individualist nor strictly particularist. There would<br />
have to be a requirement that citizens consent to a common political culture, but<br />
this culture would be one in which individuals and groups were attached to a<br />
“civic” identity and not an ethnic one. The ties that would bind, then, would be<br />
political-constitutional, not ethno-cultural. Beiner refers to Jürgen Habermas’s<br />
notion <strong>of</strong> “constitutional patriotism” as a possible opening. 54 The hope is that<br />
there might be some way to get people to form an allegiance to a political<br />
community that avoids, on the one hand, an uncompromising appeal to<br />
individual rights with an insistence upon absolute equality <strong>of</strong> citizenship or, on<br />
the other hand, an unbending conformity to a stifling parochialism.<br />
Such a third way is also envisioned by those who draw upon Friedrich<br />
Meinecke’s distinction between “images <strong>of</strong> the state as a Staatsnation,<br />
focusing on the legal forms and Kulturnation which emphasizes the common<br />
values, heritage and symbols.” 55 According to Thomas Courchene, there is no<br />
shared vision in Canada in Kulturnation terms; but there is a basis (at least in<br />
Canada outside <strong>of</strong> Quebec) for an understanding <strong>of</strong> the country in terms <strong>of</strong><br />
Staatsnation. He therefore suggests that we forget about trying to base our<br />
notion <strong>of</strong> citizenship on any kind <strong>of</strong> shared socio-cultural identity and focus<br />
instead on the construction <strong>of</strong> a few agreed-upon processes, institutional<br />
arrangements and so on, “through which we can individually and collectively<br />
filter our conceptions <strong>of</strong> who we are and who we might be.” 56 Presumably, the<br />
basis <strong>of</strong> this agreement would be a form <strong>of</strong> what sociologist Anthony Smith<br />
calls “civic-territorial” nationalism as opposed to “ethnic-genealogical”<br />
nationalism. 57 The same idea underlies what Donald Smiley once called the<br />
“<strong>Canadian</strong> political nationality,” the development <strong>of</strong> which requires simply<br />
that <strong>Canadian</strong>s “find and commit themselves to a group <strong>of</strong> common objectives<br />
which they pursue in equal partnership together.” 58 Pointing out that Smiley’s<br />
phrase derives originally from George-Étienne Cartier, Samuel LaSelva<br />
recently argued that we need not invent some new constitutional order to<br />
achieve this goal, but must instead attempt to recover the “moral foundations”<br />
<strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> federalism, which have always involved the idea that Canada is a<br />
nation in which multiple loyalties and multiple identities may flourish. 59<br />
The problem with this and other recent attempts to “reimagine Canada” (to<br />
borrow Jeremy Webber’s phrase 60) is that even aside from the national identity<br />
issue there appears to be little concrete underpinning for any agreement about<br />
the common rules and objectives <strong>of</strong> our nation (let alone for a “constitutional<br />
patriotism” <strong>of</strong> any sort). After the Meech Lake and Charlottetown fiascos, the<br />
prevailing wisdom is to stay away from constitutional reform. Yet since current<br />
constitutional arrangements are pr<strong>of</strong>oundly unacceptable to many key players,<br />
these unresolved disputes continue to grind away at the foundations <strong>of</strong> the<br />
country. In the absence <strong>of</strong> mutually constructive discourse on the issues, we are<br />
left to muddle through with a hodgepodge <strong>of</strong> initiatives which satisfy no one.<br />
Frustration and anger mount on all sides as attempts to find means to<br />
accommodate across the cleavage between Canada’s cultural majority and its<br />
Aboriginal and ethno-cultural minorities are left to wait until the problems <strong>of</strong><br />
French-English dualism and regionalism are sorted out, which might not be<br />
until the final separation <strong>of</strong> Quebec from the rest <strong>of</strong> Canada. In the meantime,<br />
73
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
the polarization widens between proponents <strong>of</strong> liberal-individualistic<br />
conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship and advocates <strong>of</strong> a cultural pluralist<br />
conception <strong>of</strong> differentiated group rights. As both sides dig in their heels, and<br />
perceive each utterance from the other camp as a threat to their very way <strong>of</strong> life,<br />
the much-desired third way remains as elusive as ever.<br />
Notes<br />
* An early version <strong>of</strong> this paper was delivered at the Annual Meeting <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> Political<br />
Science Association, Brock University, St. Catherine’s, Ontario, June 1996. I would like to<br />
thank participants in that session—Alan Cairns, Yasmeen Abu-Laban and Christopher<br />
McKee—as well as the anonymous readers for this journal.<br />
1. E.g., the University <strong>of</strong> Toronto’s Ronald Beiner edited an important collection <strong>of</strong> such<br />
essays by leading Anglo-American and continental European political theorists—including<br />
Habermas, Walzer, Taylor, Young and Ignatieff. This book, Theorizing Citizenship<br />
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1995), includes a particularly helpful literature review article by Will<br />
Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, 283-322. Another collection <strong>of</strong> essays, spanning a wide<br />
spectrum <strong>of</strong> disciplines and pr<strong>of</strong>essions, is found in William Kaplan (ed.), Belonging: The<br />
Meaning and Future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s<br />
University Press, 1993).<br />
2. Hugh Donald Forbes, “Canada: From Bilingualism to Multiculturalism,” <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />
Democracy 4 (October 1993), 69-84 at 69.<br />
3. E.g., much <strong>of</strong> the theoretical agenda concerning differential rights claims has been set by<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> philosophers Charles Taylor and Will Kymlicka. The Taylor essay, “The Politics<br />
<strong>of</strong> Recognition,” has been particularly influential. See Amy Gutman (ed.), Multiculturalism:<br />
Examining the Politics <strong>of</strong> Recognition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994).<br />
Kymlicka, meanwhile, has informed much <strong>of</strong> the recent literature on the politics <strong>of</strong><br />
difference. See his Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: OUP, 1989) and<br />
Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: OUP, 1995). Both Taylor and Kymlicka encourage a<br />
sympathetic understanding <strong>of</strong> the deep sources <strong>of</strong> identity and the desire for recognition<br />
experienced by minority groups.<br />
4. Here I must acknowledge my debt to Ronald Beiner’s discussions <strong>of</strong> the problems <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship, especially in his introduction to Theorizing Citizenship, “Why Citizenship<br />
Constitutes a Theoretical Problem in the Last Decades <strong>of</strong> the Twentieth Century,” 1-28.<br />
Throughout this essay, Beiner lays out variants <strong>of</strong> the “universalist-particularist” dichotomy<br />
(sometimes portrayed as “nationalism-multiculturalism” and sometimes as “liberalismcommunitarianism”),<br />
pinpoints the shortcomings <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> the alternatives, and then<br />
searches for an elusive middle term which might capture the essence <strong>of</strong> citizenship.<br />
5. According to the 1991 <strong>Canadian</strong> Census, only 25 percent <strong>of</strong> the immigrants who arrived in<br />
Canada between 1981 and 1991 were born in Europe. In contrast, European-born<br />
immigrants represented 90 percent <strong>of</strong> those who arrived in Canada before 1961. See Jane<br />
Badets, “Canada’s Immigrants: Recent Trends,” <strong>Canadian</strong> Social Trends (Toronto:<br />
Thompson Educational Publishing, 1994), 27-30 at 29.<br />
6. This example comes from Augie Fleras and Jean Leonard Elliott, Unequal Relations: An<br />
Introduction to Race, Ethnic and Aboriginal Dynamics in Canada, 2nd. Ed. (Scarborough:<br />
Prentice Hall, 1996), 403-4.<br />
7. Justice and the Politics <strong>of</strong> Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990).<br />
8. Taylor, “The Politics <strong>of</strong> Recognition,” 39.<br />
9. Beiner, “Introduction,” 2.<br />
10. Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, 11-26.<br />
11. Ibid., 11.<br />
12. Ibid., 14.<br />
13. H.D. Forbes, “Affirm or Neglect: Contrasting Views on the Life <strong>of</strong> Groups,” Books in<br />
Canada (April 1996), 26-29 at 27.<br />
14. Charles Taylor, “Shared and Divergent Values,” in Reconciling the Solitudes: Essays on<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Federalism and Nationalism (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University<br />
Press, 1993), 155-86.<br />
74
First Peoples, New Peoples and Citizenship in Canada<br />
15. Ibid., 182.<br />
16. Ibid., 183.<br />
17. “‘Deep Diversity’: Race and Ethnicity in <strong>Canadian</strong> Politics, in Michael S. Whittington and<br />
Glen Williams (eds.), <strong>Canadian</strong> Politics in the 1990s, 4th ed. (Toronto: Nelson, 1995), 191-<br />
217.<br />
18. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this trend, see Alan C. Cairns, “The Fragmentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Citizenship,” in Douglas E. Williams (ed.), Reconfigurations: <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship &<br />
Constitutional Change (Toronto: McClelland & Stewart, 1995), 157-85.<br />
19. Peter Kulchyski, “Aboriginal Peoples and Hegemony in Canada,” <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
<strong>Studies</strong> 30 (Spring 1995), 60-68 at 61.<br />
20. Gerald R. Alfred, Heeding the Voices <strong>of</strong> Our Ancestors: Kahnawake Mohawk Politics and<br />
the Rise <strong>of</strong> Native Nationalism (Toronto: OUP, 1995), 14.<br />
21. Ibid., 15.<br />
22. J.W. Berry and M. Wells, “Attitudes Toward Aboriginal Peoples and Aboriginal Self-<br />
Government in Canada,” in John Hylton (ed.), Aboriginal Self-Government in Canada:<br />
Current Trends and Issues (Saskatoon: Purich Publishing, 1994), 215-34 at 225.<br />
23. Frances Abele and Daiva Stasiulis, “Canada as a ‘White Settler Colony’: What about<br />
Natives and Immigrants?,” in Wallace Clement and Glen Williams (eds.), The New<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> Political Economy (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press,<br />
1989), 240-77.<br />
24. Trudeau cited in H.D. Forbes, “Trudeau’s Moral Vision,” in Anthony A. Peacock,<br />
Rethinking the Constitution: Perspectives <strong>Canadian</strong> Constitutional Reform, Interpretation,<br />
and Theory (Toronto: OUP, 1996), 17-39 at 27.<br />
25. For a description and analysis <strong>of</strong> the main criticisms <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism, see Yasmeen Abu-<br />
Laban and Daiva Stasiulis, “Ethnic Pluralism Under Siege: Popular and Partisan Opposition<br />
to Multiculturalism,” <strong>Canadian</strong> Public Policy 18 (1992), 365-86.<br />
26. Harold Fallding, “Multiculturalism: A Great Shibboleth,” in Policy Options (March 1995),<br />
42.<br />
27. Trudeau cited in Forbes, “Trudeau’s Moral Vision,” 28.<br />
28. David Miller, On Nationality (Oxford: OUP, 1995), 43.<br />
29. See, for instance, the booklet released by the Department <strong>of</strong> Multiculturalism and<br />
Citizenship, Multiculturalism: What is it Really About? (Ottawa: Minister <strong>of</strong> Supply and<br />
Services, 1991).<br />
30. For an overview <strong>of</strong> the Charter’s critics, see Richard Sigurdson, “Left- and Right-Wing<br />
Charterphobia in Canada: A Critique <strong>of</strong> the Critics,” <strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
<strong>Studies</strong>/<strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d’études canadiennes, 7-8 (Spring/Fall, 1993), 95-115.<br />
31. E.g., Rainer Knopff and F.L. Morton, Charter Politics (Scarborough: Nelson, 1992) or<br />
Christopher P. Manfredi, Judicial Power and the Charter: Canada and the Paradox <strong>of</strong><br />
Liberal Constitutionalism (Toronto: McClelland & Stewart, 1993).<br />
32. E.g., Michael Mandel, The Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and the Legalization <strong>of</strong> Politics in Canada<br />
(Toronto: Thompson Educational Publishing, 1994) or Allan C. Hutchinson, Waiting for<br />
Coraf: A Critique <strong>of</strong> Law and Rights (Toronto: University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1995).<br />
33. Ovide Mercredi and Mary Ellen Turpel, In the Rapids: Navigating the Future <strong>of</strong> First<br />
Nations (Toronto: Viking, 1993), 96-97.<br />
34. “Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong>s, Citizenship, and the Constitution,” in Reconfigurations, 238-60 at<br />
244.<br />
35. Trudeau cited in Melvin H. Smith, Our Home or Native Land? What Governments’<br />
Aboriginal Policy is doing to Canada (Victoria: Crown Western, 1995), 1.<br />
36. Cairns, “Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong>s,” 242-5.<br />
37. Smith, Our Home or Native Land?, 263.<br />
38. My thanks to François Rocher and Miriam Smith for pointing this out; see their paper “The<br />
New Boundaries <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> Political Culture,” delivered at the Conference organized<br />
by the Centre for <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong>, University <strong>of</strong> Edinburgh, UK, May 1996, 9.<br />
39. One Canada: Memoirs <strong>of</strong> the Rt. Hon. John G. Diefenbaker, Vol. 2 (Scarborough:<br />
Macmillan, 1976), 27.<br />
40. Anne Phillips, Democracy and Difference (Philadelphia: Pennsylvania State University<br />
Press, 1993), 92.<br />
75
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
41. It is worth mentioning here that Will Kymlicka’s main burden in Liberalism, Community,<br />
and Culture and in Multicultural Citizenship is a sophisticated demonstration that the<br />
granting <strong>of</strong> collective rights to minority cultures can be consistent with liberal democratic<br />
principles, and that the objections <strong>of</strong> traditional liberals to such group rights can be countered<br />
from within a liberal paradigm.<br />
42. Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, 26-33.<br />
43. Cairns, “Aboriginal <strong>Canadian</strong>s,” 258.<br />
44. Cairns, “The Fragmentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship,” 172-3.<br />
45. As Abu-Laban and Stasiulis point out, the government’s own Spicer Commission reported a<br />
high degree <strong>of</strong> concern about the extent to which multiculturalism destabilized and<br />
weakened citizens’ feelings <strong>of</strong> national unity (371). See the Citizens’ Forum on Canada’s<br />
Future, Report to the People and Government <strong>of</strong> Canada (Ottawa: Minister <strong>of</strong> Supply and<br />
Services, 1991).<br />
46. Selling Illusions: The Cult <strong>of</strong> Multiculturalism in Canada (Toronto: Penguin, 1994).<br />
47. Stasiulis cites a 1993 national survey in which 72 per cent <strong>of</strong> respondents agreed that “the<br />
long-standing image <strong>of</strong> Canada as a nation <strong>of</strong> communities, each ethnic and racial group<br />
preserving its own identity with the help <strong>of</strong> government policy, must give way to the US style<br />
<strong>of</strong> cultural absorption” (“Deep Diversity,” 210). See also Reginald W. Bibby, Mosaic<br />
Madness (Toronto: Stoddart, 1990), especially 5-15.<br />
48. Alfred, Heeding the Voices, 17.<br />
49. This overview summarizes research findings presented in Leslie S. Laczco, Pluralism and<br />
Inequality in Quebec (Toronto: University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press, 1995), Chapter 8, 159-70.<br />
50. Beiner, “Introduction,” 15.<br />
51. “The Ambivalent Potential <strong>of</strong> Cultural Identity,” The <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> Political Science<br />
29 (March 1996), 3-22.<br />
52. Ibid., 21.<br />
53. Beiner, “Introduction,” 12-13.<br />
54. See Habermas, “Historical Consciousness and the Post-Traditional Identity,” in Habermas,<br />
The New Conservatism, ed., Shierry Weber Nicholson (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1989), 249-<br />
67.<br />
55. C. Michael Lanphier and Anthony H. Richmond, “Multiculturalism and Identity in ‘Canada<br />
outside <strong>of</strong> Quebec,’” in Kenneth McRoberts (ed.), Beyond Quebec: Taking Stock <strong>of</strong> Canada<br />
(Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1995), 313-32 at 313.<br />
56. “Staatsnation vs. Kulturnation: The Future <strong>of</strong> ROC,” in McRoberts, Beyond Quebec, 388-<br />
99 at 396.<br />
57. National Identity (Reno: University <strong>of</strong> Nevada Press, 1991), ch. 1.<br />
58. The <strong>Canadian</strong> Political Nationality (London & Toronto: Methuen, 1967), 129.<br />
59. The Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Federalism: Paradoxes, Achievements, and Tragedies<br />
<strong>of</strong> Nationhood (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1996).<br />
60. Reimagining Canada (Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1994).<br />
76
Gilles Bourque et Jules Duchastel<br />
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société<br />
canadienne et la constitutionnalisation des enjeux<br />
politiques<br />
Résumé<br />
Cet article porte sur la production des identités politiques au Canada. Les<br />
auteurs soutiennent que l’expérience canadienne qui se caractérise par une<br />
propension à la constitutionnalisation des débats et des enjeux politiques<br />
constitue une sorte de laboratoire des mutations de l’espace public qui<br />
surviennent dans la plupart des sociétés occidentales. Dans ce contexte, la<br />
réitération des revendications québécoises et autochtones, ainsi que<br />
l’affirmation des intérêts catégoriels caractéristiques de l’État-providence,<br />
ont favorisé une véritable fragmentation de la société. Les auteurs signalent<br />
que le rapatriement de la Constitution en 1982 a consolidé la construction<br />
d’un État multiculturel plutôt que d’un État multinational, ce qui a impliqué<br />
une institutionnalisation juridico-culturelle qui divise la société en une<br />
multiplicité de groupes d’ayants droit aux rapports conflictuels. Les auteurs<br />
concluent qu’un État fondé sur la reconnaissance des droits politiques liés à<br />
l’existence de communautés nationales différentes permettrait une sortie de<br />
la crise du régime politique canadien.<br />
Abstract<br />
This article examines the creation <strong>of</strong> political identities in Canada. The<br />
authors argue that the <strong>Canadian</strong> experience, which is characterized by a<br />
propensity to constitutionalize political debates and issues, acts as a breeding<br />
ground involving various transformations <strong>of</strong> the public space, a phenomenon<br />
which is taking place in most western societies. In this context, the repeated<br />
demands from Québécois and Aboriginals, as well as those from numerous<br />
interest groups, have fostered divisions within society. The authors point out<br />
that the repatriation <strong>of</strong> the Constitution in 1982 has helped establish a<br />
multicultural state as opposed to a multinational one. This development has<br />
resulted in a legal and cultural institutionalization which has splintered<br />
society in various groups <strong>of</strong> rights bearer <strong>of</strong>ten in conflict with each other.<br />
The authors conclude that a state based on the recognition <strong>of</strong> political rights<br />
linked to different national communities would allow a way out <strong>of</strong> the crisis<br />
which is troubling the <strong>Canadian</strong> political regime.<br />
La montée du multiculturalisme et des revendications catégorielles, ainsi que<br />
l’affirmation d’une citoyenneté particulariste, comptent parmi les traits les plus<br />
frappants de l’évolution récente des démocraties occidentales (Taylor, 1994 ;<br />
Kymlicka, 1995 ; Pal, 1993 ; Jenson, 1996). Ces phénomènes témoignent d’une<br />
crise pr<strong>of</strong>onde de l’institutionnalisation politique qui avait caractérisé jusqu’ici<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d'études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
la reproduction de la société moderne. On peut parler, à ce titre, d’une triple<br />
dérive : une crise d’abord de l’espace public considéré comme le lieu central de<br />
la discussion du pouvoir et de la production des compromis sociaux<br />
(Habermas, 1978) ; une crise ensuite de la régulation politique, c’est-à-dire de<br />
la capacité des institutions de la démocratie représentative de réaliser ces<br />
compromis (Wieviorka et Dubet, 1996); une crise, enfin, de la communauté<br />
politique (Webber, 1994), cette « source de reconnaissance et de confiance<br />
mutuelle » (Kymlicka, 1995 : 105-106), susceptible de produire un horizon<br />
moral commun (Taylor, 1992) auquel pourrait se rallier l’ensemble des<br />
citoyens.<br />
Les ratés de l’institutionnalisation politique sont intimement liés à ce qu’il est<br />
maintenant convenu d’appeler l’érosion de l’État-nation, mis en péril par un<br />
double mouvement qui mine sa capacité de demeurer l’instance principale de la<br />
reproduction des rapports sociaux. À l’externe, d’une part, la mondialisation et<br />
le libre marché tendent à désaisir l’État-nation d’une très large partie de ses<br />
pouvoirs dans le domaine de la régulation économique (Deblock et Brunelle,<br />
1993 ; Sanderson, 1995 ; Boyer et Hollingsworth, à paraître). À l’interne, on<br />
assiste, d’autre part, à une tendance à l’éclatement et à la fragmentation des<br />
communautés politiques nationales qui se manifeste par la formation de trois<br />
fissures qui menacent de s’élargir sous le poids des luttes sociales. Les<br />
revendications nationales, en premier lieu, qu’elles soient québécoise,<br />
autochtone, catalane, irlandaise ou écossaise, remettent en question, dans<br />
plusieurs pays, l’intégrité du régime politique (Keating, 1997). Les<br />
revendications catégorielles (Jenson, 1996), en second lieu, issues des<br />
nouveaux mouvements sociaux, des groupes d’âge ou des communautés<br />
culturelles provoquent une redéfinition d’inspiration particulariste de la<br />
citoyenneté qui interroge l’universalisme jusqu’ici à la source des cultures<br />
politiques modernes. L’impasse enfin de la société salariale, sous l’effet de la<br />
mondialisation, de la révolution technologique et du néolibéralisme, prend<br />
dans la très vaste majorité des pays le visage du chômage, de l’exclusion et de la<br />
dualisation de la société.<br />
En nous centrant sur la question de la production des identités politiques<br />
(nationales et catégorielles) au Canada, nous tenterons de montrer dans cet<br />
article que ce pays peut être considéré comme une sorte de laboratoire des<br />
mutations de l’espace public qui surviennent actuellement au sein de la plupart<br />
des sociétés occidentales1. Les débats politiques au Canada se caractérisent, en<br />
effet, par la conjugaison contradictoire de l’ensemble des phénomènes et des<br />
types de luttes que nous avons évoqués ci-dessus. Mais l’intérêt de l’analyse<br />
réside principalement dans le fait que l’expérience canadienne se distingue par<br />
l’existence d’une propension à la constitutionnalisation des débats et des<br />
enjeux politiques, c’est-à-dire par le fait qu’un très large éventail des<br />
revendications des groupes sociaux ont pris ou prennent, positivement ou<br />
négativement, la Constitution pour cible (Russell, 1993). Ce que nous appelons<br />
la propension à la constitutionnalisation des débats vient ainsi renforcer au<br />
Canada cette tendance à la fragmentation de la communauté politique qui, nous<br />
l’avons souligné, traverse à des degrés divers la plupart des sociétés<br />
démocratiquesdetraditionlibérale(Cairns,1991;CairnsetDouglas,1991).<br />
78
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
Prolégomènes : La Constitution comme texte fondateur de la<br />
communauté politique<br />
L’importance des débats et des enjeux constitutionnels dans l’histoire politique<br />
canadienne, depuis 1867, impose de nous interroger au moins sommairement<br />
sur le rôle et la place de la Constitution dans la formation et la reproduction de<br />
l’État moderne et de la communauté politique nationale. En tant que texte<br />
fondateur, la Constitution fixe les règles de fonctionnement des institutions de<br />
la démocratie représentative (Parsons, 1969). Bien que la formule ne soit guère<br />
élégante, on peut parler ici d’une institutionnalisation de l’institutionnalisation<br />
ou si l’on préfère d’une régulation de la régulation politique qui caractérise<br />
l’État moderne (Freitag, 1986).<br />
La Constitution fixe, en effet, les règles qui permettent aux acteurs de se<br />
constituer en sujets de droit aptes à l’exercice de la démocratie représentative<br />
(liberté d’expression, droits politiques et juridiques). Elle détermine aussi les<br />
règles de la forme du régime politique, c’est-à-dire de l’organisation et de la<br />
distribution des pouvoirs entre différents paliers de gouvernement. Mais la<br />
fixation de telles règles, loin de se limiter à un exercice purement technique,<br />
implique la construction d’un horizon commun qui contribue à la production<br />
symbolique de la communauté politique elle-même, c’est-à-dire de la nation,<br />
cette communauté de citoyens (Schnapper, 1994 ; Gellner, 1989) au nom de<br />
laquelle s’exercera le pouvoir au sein de l’État de droit.<br />
En somme, toute constitution et tout débat constitutionnel s’appuient sur une<br />
référence identitaire qui permet de définir et de représenter une communauté<br />
politique particulière. Or, cette communauté n’est pas simple addition des<br />
individus-citoyens. Elle s’affirme comme une culture politique nationale ou,<br />
comme l’écrit Will Kymlicka, comme une culture sociétale spécifique : « Le<br />
monde moderne, écrit-il, est divisé entre ce que j’appellerai des «cultures<br />
sociétales» dont les pratiques et les institutions couvrent toutes les facettes de<br />
l’activité humaine relevant aussi bien de la sphère publique que de la sphère<br />
privée. Ces cultures sociétales sont associées de façon typique aux groupes<br />
nationaux » (Kymlicka, 1995 : 75-76, traduction). La communauté nationale se<br />
nourrit ainsi d’une culture politique nationale particulière (culture sociétale au<br />
sens de Kymlicka) qui se forme en chaque pays dans le processus<br />
d’institutionnalisation politique caractéristique de la modernité. Cette culture<br />
est constituée de pratiques et d’institutions qui s’organisent sur la base des<br />
rapports entre les sphères publique et privée. La communauté politique<br />
nationale permet ainsi une discussion du pouvoir susceptible de résoudre les<br />
conflits entre les acteurs et les groupes sociaux. La culture issue du commun<br />
partage d’un seul et même espace public fait apparaître la communauté<br />
politique comme une totalité qui transcende la simple somme des interactions<br />
entre les individus-citoyens. En ce sens, écrit encore Kymlicka, « les<br />
regroupements nationaux fournissent un domaine de liberté et d’égalité, ainsi<br />
qu’une source de reconnaissance et de confiance mutuelle qui peuvent<br />
concilier les différends et les dissensions qui portent sur les conceptions du bien<br />
dans les sociétés modernes » (Kymlicka, 1995 : 105-106, traduction).<br />
Nous entendons le concept de culture politique nationale dans un sens<br />
beaucoup plus large que ne le fait généralement la science politique. Nous<br />
79
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
visons ici le fait que, dans la modernité, cette culture permet de produire la<br />
société comme totalité. C’est précisément la perspective qui conduit Kymlicka<br />
à proposer le concept de culture sociétale. Nous préférons retenir le concept de<br />
culture politique nationale parce qu’il nous permet de faire ressortir que, dans<br />
l’État moderne, la production de la société comme totalité résulte en dernière<br />
analyse d’un procès d’institutionnalisation politique qui organise les rapports<br />
sociaux sur la base de la relation entre deux sphères : la sphère privée et la<br />
sphère publique. Nous qualifions, par ailleurs, celle-ci de culture politique<br />
nationale parce que, dans l’État-nation, comme le souligne ci-dessus<br />
Kymlicka, ces cultures « sont associées de façon typique aux groupes<br />
nationaux » (traduction). Est-il besoin de souligner que nous refusons toute<br />
lecture ethnique ou ethniciste d’un tel concept ? Si, au point de départ, dans le<br />
processus de construction de l’État-nation, la formation d’une culture politique<br />
particulière se réalise à partir de l’univers symbolique de l’une des ethnies<br />
réunies au sein du nouvel État, une telle culture politique vise l’intégration de<br />
l’ensemble des individus de toutes les origines au sein d’une seule et même<br />
citoyenneté nationale. C’est cette tendance à l’affirmation d’une seule culture<br />
politique nationale (ou d’une seule culture sociétale au sens de Kymlicka) qui<br />
rend si difficile l’analyse des conflits nationaux au sein de l’État-nation. Bien<br />
qu’une dérive ethniciste guette toujours les acteurs impliqués dans de tels<br />
conflits, l’enjeu de ces luttes, quand du moins elles respectent les règles de la<br />
démocratie, porte sur la reconnaissance d’une pluralité de cultures politiques<br />
nationales différentes au sein d’un même État (à moins, bien sûr, qu’elles ne se<br />
résolvent par la création d’un nouvel État-nation). Ainsi l’affrontement actuel<br />
entre le Québec et le reste du Canada n’oppose pas les Canadiens anglais et les<br />
Québécois francophones sur une base ethnique (bien que, encore une fois, une<br />
dérive ethniciste soit toujours possible). Nous sommes plutôt face à un conflit<br />
d’intégration de la citoyenneté sur la base de deux cultures politiques nationales<br />
différentes qui devra se résoudre soit à l’intérieur d’un État canadien<br />
transformé, soit par la création d’un État québécois séparé.<br />
Dans la plupart des pays, et même aux États-Unis et en France, la construction<br />
de la communauté nationale est l’objet de luttes qui conduisent à l’affirmation<br />
de contre-nationalismes qui posent l’existence de cultures politiques<br />
nationales différentes au sein de l’État-nation. Dans certains cas, comme la<br />
Suisse et la Belgique, la reconnaissance de la pluralité des cultures politiques<br />
nationales a conduit à la formation d’une communauté politique<br />
multinationale. Dans beaucoup d’autres cas, et particulièrement en cette<br />
période d’érosion de l’État-nation, les revendications nationalitaires se<br />
multiplient. En ce sens, l’exacerbation des luttes nationales au Canada ne fait<br />
pas exception à la règle et ne constitue pas en elle-même la particularité de<br />
l’expérience canadienne. Bien que les questions nationales québécoises et<br />
autochtones jouent un rôle important dans la crise politique actuelle au Canada,<br />
c’est l’éclatement de la communauté politique elle-même, sous l’effet de la<br />
conjugaison de luttes multiformes et de la tendance à la constitutionnalisation<br />
des conflits sociaux, qui constitue ce pays en un laboratoire de la fragmentation<br />
sociétale qui s’affirme en cette fin de siècle.<br />
Nous soutiendrons dans cet article que deux éléments de l’expérience<br />
canadienne, qui se manifestent à long terme (depuis 1867), ont contribué de<br />
80
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
façon décisive à l’affirmation plus récente (1960-1996) de ce que nous avons<br />
appelé la conjugaison des luttes sociales et la constitutionnalisation des enjeux<br />
politiques. La récurrence de problèmes nationaux non résolus depuis 1867 (les<br />
questions du Québec et des Autochtones) et l’inachèvement de la construction<br />
de l’État national jusqu’en 1982 ont en effet contribué à l’exacerbation d’une<br />
saga constitutionnelle qui met en péril l’État canadien. La réitération des<br />
revendications québécoises et autochtones, dans un contexte où s’impose le<br />
rapatriement d’une Constitution — toujours à Londres jusqu’en 1982 — et où<br />
s’affirment les revendications catégorielles caractéristiques de l’Étatprovidence<br />
a favorisé une véritable constitutionnalisation de la fragmentation<br />
de la société canadienne qui rend problématique l’existence même d’une<br />
culture politique nationale canadienne commune. Nous tenterons de montrer<br />
que l’histoire constitutionnelle récente a ainsi suscité l’émergence d’une<br />
institutionnalisation juridico-culturelle des règles de fonctionnement de la<br />
démocratie représentative qui a été caractérisé par l’affirmation d’une<br />
citoyenneté particulariste et multiculturelle. Ce choix, loin de la résoudre,<br />
favorise l’appr<strong>of</strong>ondissement de la crise du régime politique canadien. Seules<br />
des solutions constitutionnelles visant une institutionnalisation juridicopolitique<br />
fondée sur la reconnaissance de la pluralité des cultures politiques<br />
nationales et assurant la promotion d’une citoyenneté universaliste<br />
supranationale, nous paraissent susceptibles de préserver l’unité de l’État<br />
canadien.<br />
De 1867 aux années 1930 : Un État national « inachevé », un problème<br />
national non résolu<br />
La Constitution de 1867, l’Acte de l’Amérique du Nord Britannique,<br />
sanctionne l’existence d’un régime politique fédératif qui apparaît durant cette<br />
deuxième phase de la création des États nationaux au cours de la deuxième<br />
moitié du dix-neuvième siècle. Ces nouveaux pays, ne mentionnons que<br />
l’Allemagne, l’Italie, l’Autriche-Hongrie, l’Argentine et le Canada, durent<br />
faire face à des forces hégémoniques à l’échelle mondiale (l’Angleterre, les<br />
États-Unis, la France), alors même que la construction nationale restait à faire<br />
dans les domaines économique, politique et culturel. Or, les architectes de la<br />
Constitution canadienne de 1867 héritent d’un double problème qu’ils ne<br />
pourront résoudre que fort partiellement et qui marquera décisivement<br />
l’histoire politique canadienne jusqu’en cette fin du vingtième siècle.<br />
La forme du régime politique canadien, le fédéralisme, résulte d’abord d’un<br />
compromis entre les élites des différentes colonies du British North America<br />
(Ryerson, 1972). Ce compromis témoigne déjà de la précarité de ce projet de<br />
construction d’une nouvelle communauté politique à partir de la réunion de<br />
sociétés coloniales qui entretenaient auparavant peu de rapports entre elles (au<br />
point de départ, le Canada-Uni, le Nouveau-Brunswick et la Nouvelle-Écosse)<br />
et au sein desquelles subsistaient des questions nationales non résolues : le<br />
nationalisme canadien-français et les réalités autochtones. À l’encontre du<br />
projet initial d’union législative, les promoteurs du projet de fusion des<br />
colonies britanniques doivent se rallier à la solution de créer un État fédéral qui<br />
favorisera, dans la suite de l’histoire politique canadienne, l’affirmation du<br />
81
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
régionalisme, du nationalisme francophone (canadien-français, puis québécois<br />
et acadien) et, à partir des années 1960, des revendications autochtones.<br />
S’il faudra attendre jusqu’aux années 1960 pour que le régionalisme et les<br />
questions autochtones s’affirment pleinement au cœur des débats<br />
constitutionnels canadiens, la réalité nationale canadienne-française deviendra<br />
dès le début un obstacle à la construction d’une communauté politique<br />
pleinement unifiée. Même si les revendications autonomistes canadiennesfrançaises<br />
ont pesé d’un poids très lourd dans l’adoption d’une union fédérative<br />
qui conduisit à la création de la province de Québec, la Constitution canadienne<br />
ne reconnaît pas l’existence d’une communauté politique distincte, c’est-à-dire<br />
l’existence d’une nation canadienne-française2. Ce problème non résolu<br />
perdurera jusqu’à nos jours au moment où le nationalisme canadien-français<br />
devenu québécois menace l’intégrité de l’État canadien.<br />
La Constitution de 1867 pose en même temps le problème de l’inachèvement<br />
de l’État national qui, tout comme celui de la question du nationalisme<br />
francophone, marquera l’histoire politique canadienne durant tout le vingtième<br />
siècle. L’État canadien de 1867 demeure soumis à l’Empire dans le domaine<br />
des relations <strong>internationale</strong>s. Il apparaît ainsi comme un État national inachevé,<br />
et il faudra attendre 1931 et le Statut de Westminster pour qu’il obtienne<br />
l’autonomie dans le domaine des relations <strong>internationale</strong>s. Jusqu’aux années<br />
trente, le rattachement à l’Empire empêchera l’affirmation d’une identité<br />
politique pleinement canadienne. Mais le Statut de Westminster ne résoudra<br />
pas complètement le problème de l’inachèvement de l’État national canadien.<br />
La Constitution demeurait toujours à Londres et bien que l’on adopta la loi de la<br />
citoyenneté canadienne en 1946 et que l’on cessa de faire appel au Conseil privé<br />
en matière constitutionnelle en 1949, le texte fondateur de la démocratie<br />
canadienne, l’Acte de l’Amérique du Nord Britannique, n’était toujours pas<br />
rapatrié (Rémillard, 1985). Ce fait, qui demeurait un symbole de<br />
l’inachèvement de l’État national canadien, devint alors l’un des plus<br />
importants problèmes politiques au Canada. Les débats constitutionnels furent<br />
désormais hantés par la nécessité, proclamait-on, de rapatrier la Constitution.<br />
Or, cette volonté de rapatriement liée aussi bien au conflit de compétence<br />
impliqué par le passage à l’État-providence qu’aux revendications nationales<br />
québécoise et autochtone contribua à la constitutionnalisation des luttes<br />
politiques évoquées plus haut.<br />
Si l’on s’en tient provisoirement à la période qui va de 1867 aux années 30, la<br />
conjugaison des deux problèmes que nous venons d’évoquer se traduira par<br />
l’affirmation de deux nationalismes ethniques en grande partie antithétiques<br />
qui empêcheront l’éclosion d’une identité politique posant l’existence d’une<br />
communauté politique pan-canadienne. Une identité canado-britannique,<br />
soutenant le rattachement à l’Empire, se développera au Canada anglais et<br />
célébrera l’idée de la race anglo-saxonne et protestante (Breton, 1988 ;<br />
Lacombe, 1993). En milieu francophone s’affirmera à l’opposé un<br />
nationalisme tout aussi ethniciste centré sur la promotion de la race canadiennefrançaise<br />
et catholique. En somme, à la fin des années 1930, bien que l’État<br />
canadien, sauf en matière constitutionnelle, soit devenu pleinement autonome,<br />
82
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
la construction d’une communauté nationale (pan-étatique) n’a pas encore été<br />
réalisée.<br />
De 1940 à 1960 : L’émergence d’une culture politique nationale et<br />
d’une identité canadiennes problématiques<br />
Une série d’événements, les uns témoignant de la transformation de la forme du<br />
régime, les autres de la forme de l’État, favoriseront l’éclosion d’une identité<br />
pleinement canadienne, dans les faits une identité canadienne-anglaise qui<br />
rompt avec la Mère patrie. Ces mutations significatives du régime politique<br />
provoquées par le Statut de Westminster en 1931, la loi sur la citoyenneté<br />
canadienne en 1946 et la cessation des appels au Conseil privé en matière<br />
constitutionnelle en 1949 impulseront, en milieu anglophone, la centration de<br />
l’identité politique dans l’espace canadien. Cependant en nous référant aux<br />
débats constitutionnels et aux luttes politiques qu’ont impliqué le passage à<br />
l’État-providence l’on pourra mieux comprendre la nature de la nouvelle<br />
identité canadienne. La centralisation des pouvoirs rendue nécessaire pour la<br />
mise en œuvre des interventions du gouvernement fédéral dans plusieurs<br />
domaines jusque-là de compétences provinciales a permis à ce dernier de se<br />
poser comme le seul véritable « gouvernement national » au Canada. De même,<br />
la philosophie d’inspiration universaliste du providentialisme a suscité<br />
l’émergence d’une conception pan-canadienne des rapports sociaux.<br />
On assiste ainsi à l’émergence d’un nationalisme civique qui rompt avec<br />
l’ethnicisme lié à l’idée de la race anglo-saxonne et protestante. Centré sur la<br />
notion de citoyen, ce nouveau nationalisme est intimement lié au passage à<br />
l’État-providence. Il promeut, en effet, l’affirmation d’une citoyenneté<br />
universaliste d’inspiration clairement providentialiste. Au nom de l’égalité des<br />
chances, tous les citoyens partout au Canada, soutient-on, doivent avoir accès<br />
aux mêmes services, jouir des mêmes droits et pr<strong>of</strong>iter des mêmes politiques<br />
sociales universelles.<br />
Ce nationalisme civique universaliste et providentialiste se présente en même<br />
temps comme un nationalisme institutionnaliste. Se retrouve ici la véritable<br />
particularité de ce nouveau nationalisme canadien qui n’est pas centré sur la<br />
notion de nation. C’est plutôt autour de l’idée du national, de la « norme »<br />
nationale d’inspiration providentialiste, que se construit l’idéologie nationale<br />
de la citoyenneté canadienne. Le gouvernement fédéral devient l’ultime garant<br />
d’un espace national au sein duquel se déploie la socialité providentialiste. On<br />
peut parler à ce titre d’un nationalisme stato-civique qui pose l’existence d’une<br />
communauté de citoyens partageant les mêmes services, au sein des mêmes<br />
institutions politiques nationales.<br />
Le fait que l’idée de nation (de la nation canadienne) qui, bien que présente dans<br />
le discours politique, n’intervienne pas de façon significative dans la<br />
construction de l’idéologie nationale de la citoyenneté est le principal indice du<br />
caractère problématique de ce nouveau nationalisme. Il faut, en effet, constater<br />
que le nationalisme stato-civique canadien se construit dans un interdiscours<br />
qui l’oppose au nationalisme canadien-français. Le gouvernement du Québec<br />
dirigé par Maurice Duplessis s’opposera aussi bien à la centralisation qu’au<br />
passage à l’État-providence en appelant au respect de la division des pouvoirs<br />
83
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
inscrits dans la Constitution de 1867, texte qu’il présente comme un pacte sacré<br />
entre les deux races fondatrices de l’État canadien (Bourque, Duchastel et<br />
Beauchemin, 1994). Le premier ministre québécois continue donc à s’inspirer<br />
du vieux nationalisme ethnique canadien-français. Sa défense de l’autonomie<br />
provinciale s’inscrit ainsi dans le cadre d’une double lutte marquée par le triple<br />
refus du nouveau nationalisme canadien, de la redéfinition des pouvoirs au sein<br />
du fédéralisme et du passage à l’État-providence.<br />
On constate ainsi comment le problème national canadien-français, non résolu<br />
en 1867, bloque l’affirmation d’une identité nationale pan-étatique, en même<br />
temps qu’il favorise la résistance au passage à l’État-providence au Québec. De<br />
même, il faut le souligner, les questions constitutionnelles deviennent l’un des<br />
principaux enjeux de l’histoire politique canadienne à partir de la deuxième<br />
guerre mondiale. Le projet du passage à l’État-providence implique déjà la<br />
multiplication des conférences fédérale-provinciales et le foisonnement des<br />
débats constitutionnels. La cessation des appels au Conseil privé en matière<br />
constitutionnelle en 1949 et la nécessité consécutive de rapatrier la<br />
Constitution, tout en trouvant une formule d’amendement agréable à tous les<br />
gouvernements canadiens, achèveront de créer les conditions qui feront de la<br />
Constitution le lieu central des luttes politiques.<br />
1960-1970 : La Constitution comme ferment de la division<br />
Les années 1960 peuvent être considérées comme des années charnières au<br />
cours desquelles se mettent en place quelques-uns des principaux éléments<br />
d’une dynamique qui débouchera, durant les années 1980, sur un véritable culde-sac.<br />
Il faut d’abord noter l’importance que prendra la question du<br />
rapatriement de la Constitution, à la suite de la cessation des appels au Conseil<br />
privé en 1949. Bien que Londres cessa depuis lors de rendre jugement en<br />
matière constitutionnelle canadienne, la Constitution ne pouvait être rapatriée<br />
(c’était du moins la démarche que toutes les parties considéraient légitime3) sans que l’on adopta une formule d’amendement faisant l’unanimité des<br />
gouvernements canadiens. Durant les années 1960 et au début des années 1970,<br />
deux formules d’amendement furent discutées, la formule Fulton-Favreau et la<br />
Charte de Victoria. Elles furent cependant rejetées à cause du désaccord du<br />
Québec. Il n’en reste pas moins que l’obsession constitutionnelle était plus que<br />
jamais au cœur des débats politiques canadiens.<br />
C’est aussi durant les années 1960 que se manifestent les principaux problèmes<br />
occasionés par l’affirmation du nationalisme stato-civique canadien. Ce<br />
nationalisme qui, nous l’avons vu, se construit sans qu’il ne fasse référence de<br />
façon significative à la notion de nation canadienne, ne reconnaît pas, a fortiori,<br />
l’existence d’autres nations ou d’autres cultures politiques au Canada (du<br />
moins jusqu’en 1982, dans le cas des Autochtones). Il aura pourtant à affronter<br />
l’affirmation des nationalismes québécois et autochtone. Les solutions<br />
adoptées ou rejetées face aux revendications nationalitaires durant les années<br />
1960 marqueront décisivement aussi bien l’évolution ultérieure du<br />
nationalismecanadienlui-mêmequelanaturedesdébatspolitiquesauCanada.<br />
Il faut d’abord noter la transformation du nationalisme canadien-français qui,<br />
du moins au Québec, sera liée à l’affirmation de l’État-providence durant la<br />
84
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
Révolution tranquille, au début des années 1960. Un nationalisme civique qui<br />
rompt avec l’ethnicisme canadien-français s’affirme alors, que l’on peut saisir<br />
comme un nationalisme politico-culturaliste. Le nationalisme québécois se<br />
présente, en effet, comme un nationalisme politique qui se définit dans son<br />
rapport à l’espace Québec et à l’État du Québec. Il s’agit d’autre part d’un<br />
nationalisme culturaliste en ce qu’il vise l’intégration des citoyens du Québec<br />
au sein d’une culture politique francophone commune.<br />
Or, la question du Québec constituera la question centrale des débats<br />
constitutionnels canadiens durant les années 1960. Un choix fondamental pour<br />
l’avenir sera fait durant cette période. Plutôt que de satisfaire aux exigences du<br />
Québec qui réclamait un statut particulier au sein de la fédération canadienne, le<br />
gouvernement fédéral reconnaîtra par voie législative, la Loi des langues<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficielles, l’existence de droits linguistiques particuliers aux Canadiens<br />
français et par conséquent aux Canadiens anglais, partout au Canada.<br />
Il importe de prendre ici la pleine mesure d’un tel choix. Plutôt que de<br />
reconnaître au sein de la forme de régime des droits politiques liés à l’existence<br />
d’une minorité nationale, plutôt donc que d’assigner un statut particulier au<br />
Québec au sein du système fédéral canadien, on légifère pour conférer des<br />
droits d’appartenance culturelle aux citoyens de langue française et, par<br />
extension, de langue anglaise au Canada. Contrairement à ce que l’on pourrait<br />
penser spontanément, nous ne sommes pas ici face à une simple opposition<br />
entre la promotion de droits collectifs ou de droits individuels. Certes le rejet<br />
d’un statut particulier signifie le refus de reconnaître l’existence d’une minorité<br />
nationale ou, si l’on préfère, d’une culture politique différente. Mais il faut<br />
constater que par le ciblage des droits linguistiques de certains individuscitoyens,onassisteàlaconstitutiondedeuxgroupesd’ayantsdroitauCanada.<br />
Il s’agit là d’un choix décisif qui marquera l’évolution de la vie politique<br />
canadienne jusqu’en cette fin de siècle. La politique linguistique fédérale,<br />
représentant une réponse indirecte à des débats constitutionnels qui<br />
n’aboutissent pas dans le cadre des conférences fédérale-provinciales, marque<br />
un tournant majeur aussi bien au niveau de l’identité nationale canadienne que<br />
de l’institutionnalisation politique au Canada. Une citoyenneté particulariste<br />
reconnaissant l’existence de groupes de citoyens particuliers s’affirme dès lors<br />
au cœur même d’un nationalisme civique qui s’était constitué, nous l’avons vu,<br />
sur la base de l’universalisme providentialiste. Plusieurs autres groupes se<br />
poseront, à partir de là, comme des postulants aux droits et plusieurs autres<br />
types de revendications viendront s’agglomérer autour d’une solution qui<br />
visait au point de départ une question nationale.<br />
La politique linguistique sera le premier moment, d’autre part, de cette autre<br />
transformation majeure qui consistera en la mutation de l’institutionnalisation<br />
politique au Canada. Durant les années 1940 et 1950, nous l’avons vu, s’était<br />
affirmée une institutionnalisation politique caractérisée par la promotion d’une<br />
citoyenneté universaliste centrée sur la reconnaissance des droits politiques,<br />
juridiques et sociaux de l’ensemble des citoyens. On peut parler ici d’une<br />
institutionnalisation juridico-politique en ce qu’elle reconnaît par voie<br />
législative ou constitutionnelle une citoyenneté d’inspiration universaliste<br />
classique (droits politiques et juridiques) et providentialiste (droits sociaux).<br />
85
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Le politique devient ainsi le lieu de la défense et de la promotion des droits de la<br />
personne et des droits sociaux qu’incarnent tous et chacun des citoyens.<br />
Or, sans que ne soit complètement rejetée cette perspective, la législation<br />
linguistique y introduit un principe contradictoire qui marque un glissement de<br />
l’universalisme au particularisme, du politique au culturel. La législation<br />
linguistique instaure, en effet, une nouvelle pratique d’institutionnalisation que<br />
l’on saisira comme une institutionnalisation juridico-culturelle. Les citoyens<br />
ne sont plus saisis seulement à titre de sujets politiques universels, égaux en<br />
droit et potentiellement égaux en fait (le thème de l’égalité des chances). De<br />
plus, certains d’entre eux sont identifiés à partir de leur langue (française ou<br />
anglaise) et reçoivent en conséquence des droits d’appartenance culturelle. Il<br />
nous faudra revenir sur ce choix qui manifeste la volonté de construire au<br />
Canada un État multiculturel plutôt qu’un État multinational.<br />
L’analyse des années 1960 permet aussi de repérer les premières traces de ce<br />
que nous avons appelé la tendance à la conjugaison des luttes sociales et à la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques. Les revendications<br />
constitutionnelles du Québec, surdéterminées par la nécessité du rapatriement<br />
de la Constitution, contribueront à transformer en questions constitutionnelles<br />
une multiplicité d’enjeux politiques équivalents ou disparates qui ne<br />
manqueront pas de devenir contradictoires. Les années 1960 susciteront<br />
d’abord la montée des revendications régionalistes, rien n’est plus clair durant<br />
les débats qui se tiennent aux conférences fédérale-provinciales. Plusieurs<br />
premiers ministres provinciaux ne manqueront pas d’y faire remarquer que la<br />
question du Québec ne représente pas le seul problème politique au Canada.<br />
L’aliénation de l’ouest, l’inégalité du développement économique régional<br />
leur paraissent, par exemple, des enjeux tout aussi importants. La question de<br />
l’égalité régionale, qui deviendra bientôt celle de l’égalité des provinces, se<br />
dresse déjà contre celle de l’égalité nationale.<br />
De la même manière, mais cette fois par le biais de l’émergence d’une autre<br />
question nationale, celle des peuples autochtones, les années 1960 préparent la<br />
très nette conflictualisation des luttes sociales. Il s’agit cette fois d’une solution<br />
politique ratée qui vise les Premières nations. Les peuples autochtones,<br />
rappelons-le, obtiennent le droit de vote en 1960 et sont ainsi, pour la première<br />
fois, partiellement intégrés au sein de la citoyenneté canadienne. Dans cette<br />
foulée, le Livre blanc sur les Indiens de 1969 propose d’intégrer pleinement les<br />
citoyens autochtones (Weaver, 1981). Au nom de l’égalité des chances et d’une<br />
lutte à la non-discrimination d’inspiration résolument providentialiste, le Livre<br />
blanc suggère de fondre les réalités autochtones au sein de la citoyenneté<br />
universaliste canadienne. L’Autochtone devient un citoyen pleinement égal<br />
aux autres Canadiens sans que ne soit posée la question de son rapport à sa<br />
propre communauté nationale. En d’autres termes, la pleine intégration des<br />
citoyens amérindiens et inuits serait réalisée au prix de l’oubli ou de la négation<br />
de leurs cultures nationales. Devant le refus des Premières nations et<br />
l’affirmationdunationalismeautochtone,legouvernementfédéraldutreculer.<br />
À la fin des années 1960, on a donc déjà assisté à la montée des régionalismes et<br />
du nationalisme autochtone, sans que la question du Québec ne soit<br />
véritablement résolue. Les principaux ferments de la division sont déjà à<br />
86
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
l’œuvre dans le cadre d’une course multiforme à la constitutionnalisation des<br />
droits.<br />
1970-1982 : La constitutionnalisation d’une société fragmentée<br />
Durant les années 1970-1982 aboutira le processus de transformation de<br />
l’identité canadienne qui s’était affirmé durant les années 1940 et 1950 et qui<br />
fut largement marqué par la non-résolution de ces problèmes constitutifs à la<br />
Confédération canadienne depuis 1867 : la question nationale canadiennefrançaise,<br />
puis québécoise, et l’inachèvement de l’État national. Ces deux<br />
problèmes, cela devient on ne peut plus manifeste, contribuent à la conjugaison<br />
et à la conflictualisation de luttes sociales qui prennent la Constitution comme<br />
la cible de la réalisation (par voie judiciaire) d’une pluralité d’identités<br />
fragmentées.<br />
Dans la voie ouverte par la solution apportée aux revendications nationalitaires<br />
du Québec, c’est-à-dire la loi fédérale sur le bilinguisme, les multiples<br />
communautés culturelles canadiennes exigeront leur part de reconnaissance.<br />
Ainsi, dès le début des années 70, la loi fédérale sur le multiculturalisme<br />
viendra constituer juridiquement une multitude de nouveaux groupes d’ayants<br />
droit qui s’ajouteront aux deux groupes de langue <strong>of</strong>ficielle. Les droits<br />
d’appartenanceculturellefoisonnentdorénavantdetoushorizonsauCanada.<br />
Comme partout ailleurs on assistera, d’autre part, à l’affirmation des<br />
revendications des nouveaux mouvements sociaux dans la foulée des<br />
transformations de la société salariale providentialiste. Ainsi qu’il est coutume,<br />
le gouvernement canadien, par l’intermédiaire du Secrétariat d’État, tout en<br />
essayant de les contrôler, soutiendra l’organisation d’une multiplicité de<br />
groupes voués à la protection et à la promotion des droits revendiqués par les<br />
nouveaux mouvements sociaux, comme d’ailleurs par les minorités de langue<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficielle et par les communautés culturelles (Pal, 1993). La particularité du<br />
Canada tient au fait que ce type de revendications sera avalé par l’aspirateur<br />
constitutionnel. Les leaders des mouvements sociaux viseront, en effet, la<br />
constitutionnalisation de droits catégoriels tout aussi particularistes que les<br />
droits d’appartenance culturelle déjà fort prolixes. Durant les épisodes qui<br />
conduiront au rapatriement de la Constitution, le gouvernement Trudeau<br />
s’appuiera d’ailleurs sur les nouveaux mouvements sociaux dans sa lutte contre<br />
les législatures provinciales. Il faut prendre garde ici de laisser entendre que le<br />
Secrétariat d’État et le gouvernement Trudeau créent d’eux-mêmes et<br />
manipulent les mouvements sociaux, ni d’ailleurs que les revendications de ces<br />
derniers soient irrecevables. Nous voulons seulement souligner que la<br />
mouvance de l’État-providence canadien, les solutions apportées ou formulées<br />
aux revendications des minorités nationales durant les années 1960 et la<br />
nécessité du rapatriement de la Constitution mèneront, sous l’effet de luttes<br />
sociales multiformes, à la constitutionnalisation d’une citoyenneté<br />
particulariste dans la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982.<br />
La Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 et la Charte des droits qui s’y trouve enchâssée<br />
se présentent, en effet, comme un amalgame de droits potentiellement<br />
contradictoires. On y reconnaît d’abord des droits universalistes classiques<br />
comme la liberté d’expression et les droits politiques et juridiques du citoyen<br />
87
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
(articles 2 à 14), ainsi que des droits universalistes d’inspiration<br />
providentialiste (l’article 34, hors charte, confie aux législatures le devoir de<br />
promouvoir l’égalité des chances au Canada). Ces parties de la Loi<br />
constitutionnelle de 1982 reconduisent l’idéologie nationale de la citoyenneté<br />
universaliste qui s’était construite durant les années 1940 et 1950. Cependant,<br />
la Constitution de 1982 introduit en même temps une conception toute<br />
différente axée sur la promotion et la défense d’une citoyenneté particulariste :<br />
une citoyenneté d’ayants droit culturel, d’une part, visant les groupes de langue<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficielle et le multiculturalisme (respectivement les articles 16 à 22 et l’article<br />
27) et une citoyenneté d’ayants droit catégoriels qui reconnaît des droits à la<br />
non-discrimination et à l’égalité et qui cible des groupes spécifiques, comme<br />
par exemple les femmes et les handicapés (articles 28 et 15). Il faut insister ici<br />
sur la nouveauté de cette conception de la citoyenneté. Commençons par<br />
souligner, paradoxalement, que la plupart de ces droits particularistes sont<br />
défendus, par exemple dans le discours des premiers ministres aux conférences<br />
fédérale-provinciales, sur la base de ce thème cher au providentialisme qu’est<br />
l’égalité des chances. Ils naissent donc très clairement dans le giron de l’Étatprovidence.<br />
Il n’en reste pas moins que leur constitutionnalisation<br />
systématique finit par rompre avec l’universalisme caractéristique du<br />
providentialisme. Pour le comprendre, il faut rappeler que les politiques<br />
sociales de l’État-providence rompaient elles-mêmes avec le libéralisme et<br />
l’universalisme classiques. Elles visaient implicitement une partie de la<br />
population, c’est-à-dire la classe ouvrière et les plus démunis. Il n’en reste pas<br />
moins que, dans les faits, ces politiques étaient universelles et ciblaient tous les<br />
citoyens. Elles conservaient ainsi l’horizon commun de la citoyenneté ou, si<br />
l’on préfère, elles posaient la communauté politique comme totalité<br />
symbolique redevable envers chacun de ses membres à travers, par exemple, le<br />
thème de la solidarité sociale. Certes il y avait là transformation de<br />
l’universalisme classique, mais en même temps reformulation d’un horizon<br />
moral commun. Au contraire, la citoyenneté particulariste, dès lors qu’elle<br />
prend la Constitution pour cible, finit par scinder symboliquement la<br />
communauté politique en une multiplicité de groupes d’ayants droit qui n’ont<br />
d’autre univers que celui de la reconnaissance judiciaire de leur particularité et<br />
de leurs droits. Il n’est donc pas étonnant que l’idéologie nationale adopte<br />
depuis lors le visage de la citoyenneté particulariste.<br />
En plus d’adjoindre le particularisme aux universalismes classique et<br />
providentialiste, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 s’ouvre enfin à la<br />
reconnaissance des droits nationaux des peuples autochtones (article 25), alors<br />
même qu’elle reconduit le refus d’admettre l’existence de la nation québécoise<br />
comme le réclame le mouvement souverainiste du Québec.<br />
1982-1996 : Une société divisée et une Constitution figée<br />
Le rapatriement de la Constitution et la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 n’allaient<br />
cependant pas résoudre tous les problèmes. Le gouvernement du Québec refusa<br />
de signer l’accord intervenu entre les autres premiers ministres. De même, la<br />
reconnaissance des peuples autochtones demeurait en très large partie une<br />
pétition de principes, puisque leur inscription dans la forme du régime, en<br />
particulier le droit à l’autonomie gouvernementale, restait à définir dans des<br />
88
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
conférences constitutionnelles ultérieures. Loin de briser cette tendance à la<br />
constitutionnalisation des problèmes et des luttes politiques, le rapatriement<br />
mènera à la conflictualisation des rapports sociaux dans le contexte d’une<br />
judiciarisation des enjeux politiques qui contribuera à bloquer toute réforme<br />
(Lusztig, 1994). Nous visons bien davantage que la complexité technique<br />
d’une formule d’amendement qui, sur certaines questions, exige l’unanimité et,<br />
sur d’autres, l’accord de sept provinces représentant 50 p. 100 de la population<br />
canadienne. Nous soutenons que la nature même de l’institutionnalisation<br />
juridico-culturelle, que la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 consacre, contribue<br />
dorénavant à la fragmentation d’une société dorénavant construite et<br />
représentée sur la base des rapports judiciarisée entre ses groupes d’ayants<br />
droit.<br />
Même si le rapatriement de la Constitution marque l’achèvement de l’État<br />
national canadien, la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 n’en contribuera pas moins<br />
à l’appr<strong>of</strong>ondissement d’une crise de la forme du régime. Loin de résoudre les<br />
problèmes déjà signalés par la tenue du référendum québécois de 1980 sur la<br />
souveraineté-association, la Constitution de 1982 favorisera le développement<br />
d’un processus de conflictualisation des rapports sociaux marquée par la<br />
défense et la promotion de droits particuliers qui sont posés comme étant<br />
réellement, conjoncturellement ou potentiellement contradictoires (Laforest,<br />
1992). Les différents acteurs et groupes d’acteurs qui s’opposent dans le cours<br />
de ce processus se fondent sur une conception antagonique des droits qui<br />
conduit à les rendre objectivement contradictoires. Les droits des uns finissent<br />
ainsi le plus souvent par s’opposer à ceux des autres au nom de leur primauté, de<br />
leur antériorité ou de la nécessité de leur coréalisation.<br />
Sous le primat de la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982 est ainsi apparue une<br />
multiplicité de conflits des droits que l’on peut distinguer de plusieurs points de<br />
vue. Il nous suffira ici de sérier deux grands types de conflits. L’opposition<br />
entre les droits constitutionnalisés dans la Constitution de 1982 représente déjà<br />
un terreau des plus fertiles. Elle suscitera des conflits issus de l’inégalité de<br />
traitement entre la question du Québec et celle des peuples autochtones (le<br />
gouvernement du Québec rappelle que la nation québécoise n’est pas reconnue<br />
alors que le sont les Premières nations) ou encore liés à l’antériorité ou la<br />
nécessité de la corésolution des questions nationales québécoise et autochtones<br />
(un député amérindien bloquera sur cette base l’Accord de Meech au<br />
Manitoba) 4. L’antagonisme entre les droits particularistes (droits<br />
d’appartenance culturelle et droits sociaux catégoriels) et les droits nationaux<br />
seront eux-mêmes sources de conflit : le mouvement féministe et les<br />
représentants des communautés culturelles s’opposeront, au nom de leurs<br />
droits, à la reconnaissance de la société distincte (ou à une définition extensive<br />
de celle-ci) lors des débats sur l’Accord du Lac Meech et l’entente de<br />
Charlottetown5 ; le mouvement féministe voudra soumettre la reconnaissance<br />
de l’autonomie gouvernementale autochtone à la primauté des droits à la nondiscrimination<br />
et à l’égalité inscrite dans la Charte des droits et libertés (Pal,<br />
1993).<br />
L’obsession constitutionnelle conduira d’autre part à la conflictualisation entre<br />
des droits potentiellement constitutionnalisables. Ainsi la mouvance<br />
89
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
régionaliste dressera le projet du Sénat triple E et le principe de l’égalité des<br />
provinces devant les revendications du Québec, alors que le mouvement des<br />
homosexuels exigera l’égalité et la constitutionnalisation des droits des gays et<br />
lesbiennes.<br />
Cette conflictualisation des revendications sociales qui conduit à la crise du<br />
régime politique est évidemment liée à la judiciarisation des rapports sociaux<br />
provoquée par l’obsession constitutionnelle. La constitutionnalisation des<br />
droits dans la Constitution de 1982 est apparue dans une très large partie comme<br />
une arme contre les législatures provinciales. Elle tend ainsi à privilégier les<br />
institutions judiciaires aux dépens des institutions de la démocratie<br />
représentative y compris le parlement fédéral. Il est inutile de multiplier les<br />
exemples. Ne mentionnons que cette curieuse clause nonobstant, fort ambiguë<br />
à tous égards, qui finit par poser les législatures comme des violatrices<br />
potentielles des droits plutôt que comme des productrices du droit. Soulignons<br />
d’autre part que la Loi constitutionnelle de 1982, comme on a pu le constater<br />
dans la suite des débats, paraît l’inspiratrice sinon l’instigatrice d’un<br />
mouvement de mise en tutelle des législatures. Citons par exemple la<br />
proposition du gouvernement fédéral durant les discussions qui ont mené à<br />
l’entente de Charlottetown de créer « un organisme indépendant chargé de<br />
surveiller et d’évaluer les politiques macroéconomiques des gouvernements<br />
fédéral et provinciaux » (Gouvernement du Canada, 1991).<br />
Les échecs répétés des réformes constitutionnelles depuis 1982 apparaissent<br />
ainsi comme le symptôme d’une crise pr<strong>of</strong>onde du politique au Canada. La<br />
non-résolution des questions autochtones malgré les conférences fédéraleprovinciales<br />
tenues de 1983 à 1987, l’échec de l’Accord du Lac Meech en 1990,<br />
le refus de l’entente de Charlottetown de 1992, l’incapacité évidente de<br />
construire un compromis acceptable suite au référendum québécois de 1996,<br />
qui a failli diviser le pays, tout cela témoigne du fait que la négativité paraît<br />
dorénavant le principe qui guide les rapports politiques au Canada.<br />
La société canadienne arrive moins que jamais à se représenter comme une<br />
véritable communauté politique, c’est-à-dire comme une communauté<br />
susceptible de résoudre ses conflits en regard d’un horizon moral commun<br />
permettant une discussion des pouvoirs qui peut déboucher sur des compromis.<br />
Rien n’est plus remarquable à ce propos, comme en témoigne le discours des<br />
premiers ministres dans les débats constitutionnels depuis 1982, que le<br />
fonctionnement de l’idéologie nationale de la citoyenneté particulariste qui<br />
tient lieu dorénavant de doxa au Canada.<br />
Conclusion<br />
Nous avons soutenu, dans cet article, que les transformations politiques qui<br />
surviennent au Canada depuis les années soixante sont largement déterminées<br />
par un double phénomène qui opère en longue durée, depuis 1867 : le<br />
nationalisme canadien-français puis québécois et l’inachèvement de l’État<br />
national canadien. Nous voudrions insister en terminant sur le fait que, au-delà<br />
de ces déterminations et de bien d’autres qui sont reliées aux mutations de<br />
toutes les sociétés démocratiques occidentales durant la seconde moitié du<br />
vingtième siècle, les transformations que nous évoquons résultent d’un choix<br />
90
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
politique dont il faut mesurer pleinement les conséquences. Ce choix a consisté<br />
à parachever la construction de l’État national canadien par le rapatriement de<br />
la Constitution, tout en continuant à ne pas reconnaître l’existence d’une<br />
culture politique nationale différente au Québec. Cette démarche a poussé à la<br />
construction d’un État multiculturel plutôt que d’un État multinational. Or, ce<br />
choix n’est pas neutre et plus encore ses effets ont des conséquences beaucoup<br />
pluslargesquedansleseuldomainedesrelationsentrelesnationsauCanada.<br />
Ce que nous appelons l’État multiculturel implique en effet une<br />
institutionnalisation juridico-culturelle qui divise la société en une multiplicité<br />
de groupes d’ayants droit aux rapports conflictuels. Mais plus encore, une telle<br />
institutionnalisation oriente l’action politique dans le sens de la réalisation, par<br />
la voie constitutionnelle, de droits qui découlent d’une conception bioculturelle<br />
du lien social. Elle signifie donc, au niveau de la représentation du<br />
monde, une ethnicisation des cultures puisque ces dernières sont conçues<br />
comme simple émanation de chaque communauté culturelle posée comme<br />
groupe ethnique. Elle présuppose aussi une biologisation de la représentation<br />
des groupes sociaux, chacun d’entre eux étant saisi à partir d’un trait biologique<br />
ou comportemental, inné ou constitutif (ne serait-ce que par accident) : les<br />
hommes, les femmes, les handicapés, les jeunes, les personnes âgées, les<br />
homosexuels, etc. L’institutionnalisation juridico-culturelle est enfin<br />
caractérisée par une juridicisation-constitutionnalisation des rapports sociaux<br />
qui, nous l’avons souligné, tend à la mise en veilleuse des institutions de la<br />
démocratie représentative. Elle est ainsi fondée sur cette utopie qui consiste à<br />
vouloir figer une fois pour toute les rapports sociaux dans un texte fondateur qui<br />
assurerait définitivement la réalisation des droits de chaque groupe social. Elle<br />
oppose finalement « l’éternité » du droit aux risques d’une temporalité<br />
politique soumise à la libre discussion du pouvoir dans les instances de la<br />
démocratie représentative. L’État multiculturel fait du temps son ennemi, il<br />
instaure une primauté du judiciaire qui vise à soumettre la temporalité<br />
politique, celle du libre développement de la discussion du pouvoir et des<br />
risques que la posture démocratique suppose nécessairement, à la surveillance<br />
soupçonneuse de la Constitution et du Tribunal. Quand, dans sa lutte aux<br />
promoteurs du Lac Meech, Pierre-Elliott Trudeau écrivit qu’il avait espéré que<br />
la Constitution de 1982 dura mille ans, il faisait bien davantage qu’une boutade.<br />
L’institutionnalisation multiculturelle est hantée par la peur de l’avenir et elle<br />
rompt l’équilibre entre le judiciaire et le législatif, le Droit et le Parlement sur<br />
lequel s’étaient construits et transformés l’État moderne et la démocratie<br />
libérale.<br />
Un autre choix était cependant possible qui aurait permis de résoudre en même<br />
temps les problèmes des questions nationales (québécoise et autochtones) et de<br />
l’inachèvement de l’État national canadien. Un tel choix, encore réalisable,<br />
nécessiterait la construction d’un État multinational et l’instauration d’une<br />
institutionnalisation juridico-politique fondée sur la reconnaissance de la<br />
pluralité des cultures politiques nationales au Canada. Nous entendons par un<br />
État multinational, un État qui reconnaît juridiquement dans sa constitution, et<br />
donc dans les institutions du régime, des droits politiques liés à l’existence de<br />
communautés nationales différentes. Au Canada, un tel projet signifierait sans<br />
doute la transformation du régime fédéral actuel en une union confédérale dont<br />
91
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
les composantes seraient constituées du Québec, du reste du Canada (les neuf<br />
autres provinces) et d’un gouvernement autochtone (comme le proposait<br />
d’ailleurs récemment, dans ce dernier cas, le rapport de la Commission royale<br />
sur les peuples autochtones [1996]). Dans le cadre de cet article, nous ne<br />
pouvons évidemment nous engager dans une description détaillée de la<br />
répartition des compétences qu’impliquerait une souveraineté partagée entre<br />
les gouvernements d’une telle union confédérale. Soulignons seulement que<br />
l’on pourrait s’inspirer ici de l’expérience européenne.<br />
Nous voudrions surtout insister sur le fait qu’un tel régime permettrait enfin à la<br />
communauté canadienne de se reconnaître pour ce qu’elle est : une<br />
communauté politique supranationale. Cette communauté trouverait sa<br />
légitimité pleine et entière dans l’existence d’un Parlement commun élu<br />
directement au suffrage universel par les citoyens de toutes les composantes de<br />
l’Union. Les membres élus de ce Parlement auraient pleins pouvoirs<br />
d’initiative dans le domaine des compétences qui lui seraient confiées dans le<br />
cadre de l’Union confédérale. Cette dernière s’appuierait sur une constitution<br />
qui proclamerait les droits universalistes (politiques, juridiques, économiques<br />
et sociaux) de la personne et du citoyen, droits devant être reconnus aussi bien<br />
au niveau confédéral que par tous les autres gouvernements de l’Union. Quant<br />
aux droits culturels et catégoriels, leur reconnaissance et leur promotion<br />
seraient d’autant plus facilitées qu’ils n’entreraient plus en conflit avec les<br />
revendications nationales québécoise et autochtone d’ores et déjà satisfaites<br />
dans les institutions politiques de l’Union confédérale.<br />
Un tel régime politique permettrait aussi bien la reconnaissance de la pluralité<br />
des cultures politiques nationales que la construction d’une citoyenneté et<br />
d’une communauté politique supranationale. Ainsi le fait d’être Canadien et<br />
Québécois ou Canadien et Autochtone ne serait plus conçu comme une<br />
antinomie ou comme un problème par plusieurs citoyens de ce pays, mais, au<br />
contraire, comme la reconnaissance politique de la complexité des identités qui<br />
partout dans le monde s’affirment en cette fin de siècle. Un tel régime politique<br />
permettrait, croyons-nous, de dépasser au Canada l’âge des contrenationalismes<br />
canadien, québécois et autochtone.<br />
Notes<br />
1. Dans un livre intitulé L’Identité fragmentée (1996), nous avons analysé la production des<br />
références identitaires dans les débats constitutionnels canadiens de 1941 à 1992. Le lecteur<br />
pourra consulter cet ouvrage s’il s’intéresse à la démonstration empirique de bon nombre des<br />
thèses que nous développons dans le présent article.<br />
2. John A. Macdonald, l’un des « pères » de la Confédération canadienne écrivit à ce propos :<br />
« Je n’ai jamais hésité à dire que si la chose était praticable, une union législative eût été<br />
préférable. [. . .] Si nous pouvions avoir un gouvernement et un parlement pour toutes les<br />
provinces, nous aurions eu le gouvernement le meilleur, le moins dispendieux, le plus<br />
vigoureux et le plus fort. [. . .] J’ai trouvé que ce système était impraticable. Et, d’abord, il ne<br />
saurait rencontrer l’assentiment du peuple du Bas-Canada, qui sent que, dans la position<br />
particulière où il se trouve comme minorité, parlant un langage différent, et pr<strong>of</strong>essant une<br />
foi différente de la majorité du peuple sous la confédération, ses institutions, ses lois, ses<br />
associations nationales, qu’il estime hautement, pourraient avoir à en souffrir. C’est<br />
pourquoi il a été compris que toute proposition qui impliquerait l’absorption de<br />
l’individualité du Bas-Canada, ne serait pas reçue avec faveur par le peuple de cette section.<br />
Nous avons trouvé, en outre, que quoique le peuple des provinces inférieures parle la même<br />
92
langue que celui du Haut-Canada et soit régit par la même loi — loi basée sur le droit anglais<br />
— il n’y avait, de la part de ces provinces, aucun désir de perdre leur individualité comme<br />
nation, et qu’elles partageaient à cet égard, les mêmes dispositions que le Bas-Canada »<br />
(Canada, Assemblée législative, 1865).<br />
3. Le gouvernement Trudeau passa finalement outre au début des années 1980 et la<br />
Constitution fut rapatriée sans l’accord de toutes les parties. La Cour Suprême du Canada<br />
avait pourtant émis l’avis quelques temps plus tôt que la démarche était légale à défaut d’être<br />
légitime.<br />
4. En 1986, Gil Rémillard, ministre de la Justice du gouvernement Bourassa, énonça cinq<br />
conditions « minimales » pour que le Québec s’insère « avec honneur et dignité » dans le<br />
nouvel ordre constitutionnel : (1) la reconnaissance explicite du caractère distinct du<br />
Québec, (2) des pouvoirs élargis en matière d’immigration, (3) une limitation au pouvoir de<br />
dépenser d’Ottawa, (4) un droit de veto sur les amendements constitutionnels et (5) la<br />
participation du Québec à la nomination des juges de la Cour suprême. Dans une conférence<br />
tenue au Lac Meech, le 30 avril 1987, tous les premiers ministres se montrèrent favorables<br />
aux demandes du Québec et signèrent un document conjoint. Cet accord devait être entériné<br />
par tous les gouvernements canadiens dans un délai de trois ans. L’aspect le plus important<br />
de « l’Accord du Lac Meech » était la « clause de la société distincte », un énoncé dont<br />
l’objectif était d’imposer aux tribunaux, pour interpréter la Constitution, de tenir compte du<br />
rôle particulier du Québec dans la protection et la promotion de la langue et de la culture<br />
françaises. Cette clause suscita beaucoup de réticences au Canada anglais, car l’on<br />
considérait qu’elle pouvait mettre en cause le principe de l’égalité des provinces au sein de la<br />
Confédération. En outre, plusieurs groupes d’intérêt (dont les féministes) exprimèrent leurs<br />
craintes concernant une éventuelle prédominance des droits collectifs sur les droits<br />
individuels au Québec, alors que les Premières nations s’opposèrent fermement à cette<br />
entente dont elles se sentaient complètement exclues. Lorsque, en 1990, vint le moment de<br />
faire ratifier l’Accord du Lac Meech par les parlements provinciaux, Elijah Harper, un<br />
député autochtone à l’Assemblée législative du Manitoba, vota contre le traitement accéléré<br />
de l’amendement constitutionnel (il fallait le consentement unanime pour suspendre les<br />
procédures normales de l’Assemblée pour la tenue de débats et d’audiences publiques), ce<br />
qui eut pour effet d’empêcher la ratification de l’accord avant l’expiration du terme de trois<br />
ans. L’Accord du Lac Meech n’a donc pu être inscrit dans la Constitution.<br />
5. Après l’échec de l’Accord du Lac Meech, le gouvernement québécois exigea à nouveau une<br />
réponse du reste du Canada à ses demandes constitutionnelles, faute de quoi un référendum<br />
sur la souveraineté du Québec serait tenu, au plus tard, en octobre 1992. Les premiers<br />
ministres, cette fois accompagnés des représentants des peuples autochtones, s’affairèrent à<br />
élaborer une nouvelle proposition de réforme constitutionnelle. Le 28 août 1992 fut adoptée<br />
« l’entente de Charlottetown ». Elle refléta la grande diversité des positions et des enjeux qui<br />
traversaient le débat politique canadien depuis l’échec de l’Accord du Lac Meech. Entre<br />
autres, l’entente cherchait à concilier les « conditions minimales » posées par le Québec, le<br />
droit à l’autonomie gouvernementale des Autochtones, la réforme du Sénat exigée par les<br />
provinces de l’Ouest, une Charte de droits sociaux et certaines mesures souhaitées par<br />
Ottawa qui visaient le renforcement de l’union économique du Canada. Chaque groupe<br />
d’intérêts tâcha d’inscrire ses revendications à l’ordre du jour, donnant ainsi lieu à une sorte<br />
de « patchwork » sans cohérence véritable. Ratifiée par tous les premiers ministres<br />
canadiens, l’entente de Charlottetown fut néanmoins rejetée lors du seul référendum à avoir<br />
été tenu sur la question constitutionnelle dans l’ensemble du Canada. Le référendum (qui<br />
était en fait un plébiscite consultatif) fut tenu le 26 octobre 1992. 54 p. 100 de la population<br />
canadienne vota contre la proposition.<br />
Bibliographie<br />
Les identités, la fragmentation de la société et la<br />
constitutionnalisation des enjeux politiques<br />
Bourque, Gilles et Jules Duchastel (avec la collaboration de Victor Armony). 1996. L’Identité<br />
fragmentée : Nation et citoyenneté dans les débats constitutionnels canadiens, 1941-1992.<br />
Montréal : Fides.<br />
Bourque, Gilles, Jules Duchastel et Jacques Beauchemin. 1994. La société libérale duplessiste.<br />
Montréal : Presses de l’Université de Montréal.<br />
93
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Boyer, Robert et Rogers Hollingsworth. « From National Embeddedness to Spatial and<br />
Institutional Nestedness ». Chapitre in The Embeddedness <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Institutions. À<br />
paraître.<br />
Breton, Raymond. 1988. « From Ethnic to Civic Nationalism : English Canada and Québec ».<br />
Ethnic and Racial <strong>Studies</strong>, vol. II, n o 1, p. 85-102.<br />
Cairns, Alan C. 1991. « The Charter, Interest Groups, Executive Federalism, and Constitutional<br />
Reform ». In After Meech Lake : Lessons for the Future, sous la dir. de David E. Smith, Peter<br />
MacKinnon et John C. Courtney. Saskatoon : Fifth House, p. 13-31.<br />
Cairns, Alan C. et William Douglas E. 1991. Disruptions, Constitutional Struggles, from the<br />
Charter to Meech Lake. Toronto: McClelland and Stewart Inc.<br />
Canada, Commission royale sur les peuples autochtones. 1996. Rapport de la Commission royale<br />
sur les peuples autochtones. Ottawa : Commission royale sur les peuples autochtones.<br />
Canada, Assemblée législative. 1865. Débats parlementaires sur la question de la confédération<br />
des provinces de l’Amérique Britannique du Nord : 3 e Session, 8 e Parlement provincial du<br />
Canada. Québec : Hunter, Rose et Lemieux.<br />
Deblock, Christian et Dorval Brunelle. 1993. « Une intégration régionale stratégique : Le cas nordaméricain<br />
». Études <strong>internationale</strong>s, vol. XXIV, n o 3, p. 595-629.<br />
Freitag, Michel. 1986. Dialectique et société. Tome 2 : Culture, pouvoir, contrôle. Les modes<br />
formels de reproduction de la société. Montréal : Éditions Saint-Martin.<br />
Gellner, Ernest. 1989. Nations et nationalisme. Paris : Payot.<br />
Gouvernement du Canada. 1991. Le fédéralisme canadien et l’union économique : partenariat<br />
pour la prospérité. Ministère des approvisionnements et services, Canada.<br />
Habermas, Jürgen. 1978. Raison et legitimité : problèmes de légitimation dans le capitalisme<br />
avancé. Paris : Payot.<br />
Jenson, Jane. 1996. « Regime shift : New Citizenship Practices in Canada ». <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong><br />
d’études canadiennes, n o 14.<br />
Keating, Michael. Les nations contre l’État. Le nouveau nationalisme au Québec, en Catalogne et<br />
en Écosse. Montréal : Presses de l’Université de Montréal, à paraître.<br />
Kymlicka, Will. 1995. Multicultural Citizenship. New York : Oxford University Press.<br />
Lacombe, Sylvie. 1993. « Race et liberté : l’individualisme politique au Canada, 1896-1920 ».<br />
Thèse de doctorat, Paris : Université de Paris V.<br />
Laforest, Guy. 1992. Trudeau et la fin d’un rêve canadien. Sillery : Septentrion.<br />
Lusztig, Michael. 1994. « Constitutional Paralysis : Why <strong>Canadian</strong> Constitutional Initiatives are<br />
Doomed to Fail ». <strong>Revue</strong> canadienne de science politique, XXVII : 4, p. 747-771.<br />
Pal, Leslie A. 1993. Interests <strong>of</strong> State. The Politics <strong>of</strong> Language, Multiculturalism, and Feminism<br />
in Canada. Montréal : McGill-Queen’s University Press.<br />
Parsons, Talcott. 1969. Politics and Social Structure. New York : Free Press.<br />
Rémillard, Gil. 1985. Le fédéralisme canadien. Tome 2:Lerapatriement de la constitution.<br />
Montréal : Québec/Amérique.<br />
Russell, Peter H. 1993. Constitutional Odyssey : Can <strong>Canadian</strong>s Become a Sovereign People?<br />
Toronto : University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press.<br />
Ryerson, Stanley B. 1972. Le capitalisme et la confédération : aux sources du conflit Canada-<br />
Québec (1760-1873). Montréal : Parti pris.<br />
Schnapper, Dominique. 1994. La communauté des citoyens : Sur l’idée moderne de nation. Paris :<br />
Gallimard.<br />
Stephen K. Sanderson (éd.). 1995. Civilizations and World Systems : Studying World-Historical<br />
Change. Altamira Press : Walnut Creek.<br />
Taylor, Charles. 1992. Grandeur et misère de la modernité. Montréal : Bellarmin.<br />
Taylor, Charles. 1994. Multiculturalisme. Différence et démocratie. Paris : Aubier.<br />
Weaver, Sally Mae. 1981. Making <strong>Canadian</strong> Indian Policy : The Hidden Agenda : 1968-70.<br />
Toronto : University <strong>of</strong> Toronto press.<br />
Webber, Jeremy. 1994. Reimagining Canada : Language, Culture, Community and the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Constitution. Kingston : McGill-Queen’s University Press.<br />
Wieviorka, Michel et Dubet, Francois. 1996. Une société fragmentée? : le multiculturalisme en<br />
débat. Paris : La Découverte.<br />
94
Francisco Colom-González<br />
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship: Canada in<br />
Comparative Perspective<br />
Abstract<br />
Civil, political and social rights have usually been considered distinct<br />
dimensions <strong>of</strong> citizenship. Because <strong>of</strong> its particular history, Canada was one<br />
<strong>of</strong> the first countries to include cultural rights in its constitutional and nationbuilding<br />
agenda. Whereas multicultural policies are a type <strong>of</strong> social rights,<br />
the linguistic rights <strong>of</strong> national minorities reflect a commitment to the basic<br />
identities that comprise the polity. Depending on the particular junction <strong>of</strong><br />
ethnic and political elements, four patterns <strong>of</strong> citizenship are distinguished:<br />
republican, liberal, ethnocultural and multicultural. <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship is<br />
considered from this perspective. It is concluded that the future evolution <strong>of</strong><br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship mainly depends on its skill in balancing the opposing<br />
social cleavages within it.<br />
Résumé<br />
Dans l’ensemble, les droits civils, politiques et sociaux ont été perçus<br />
jusqu’ici comme des aspects distincts de la citoyenneté. Étant donné ses<br />
antécédents historiques particuliers, le Canada a été l’un des premiers États<br />
à inclure les droits culturels dans son programme constitutionnel et son projet<br />
de développement d’un pays. Bien que les politiques multiculturelles soient<br />
une forme de droits sociaux, les droits linguistiques des minorités au pays<br />
témoignent d’un engagement à l’égard des diverses entités fondamentales de<br />
la constitution politique. Selon l’agencement particulier des éléments<br />
ethniques et politiques, quatre modèles de citoyenneté se démarquent : le<br />
modèle républicain, le modèle libéral, le modèle ethnoculturel et le modèle<br />
multiculturel. C’est selon cette perspective que le présent article envisage la<br />
citoyenneté canadienne. L’auteur conclut que son évolution dépendra<br />
principalement de son habileté à équilibrer les forces sociales qui s’affrontent<br />
en son sein.<br />
Citizenship Rights: Civil, Political and Social<br />
Citizenship is an egalitarian and multidimensional condition enjoyed by full<br />
members <strong>of</strong> a political community. On one hand, it is both a legal and an<br />
emotional concept that defines the rights, obligations and allegiances <strong>of</strong> the<br />
individuals to a nation (Morton 1993). Citizenship also has a historical<br />
dimension, since the rights and duties borne by the citizens <strong>of</strong> a country result<br />
from particular political experiences and social interactions. T. H. Marshall’s<br />
classic account <strong>of</strong> modern citizenship was based on this view. According to<br />
him, citizenship rights can be conceptually divided into three different groups<br />
(civil, political and social rights) all <strong>of</strong> which are embedded in the institutions <strong>of</strong><br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d'études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
the present liberal state. Civil citizenship mainly embodies the rights that<br />
secure individual freedom, that is, “liberty <strong>of</strong> the person, freedom <strong>of</strong> speech,<br />
thought and faith, the right to own property, to conclude valid contracts and the<br />
right to justice” (Marshall 1950: 10). On a different level, political rights and<br />
social entitlements channel citizen participation in the exercise <strong>of</strong> power and<br />
allow the state to grant a modicum <strong>of</strong> welfare and economic security. In<br />
Marshall’s view, each <strong>of</strong> these dimensions <strong>of</strong> citizenship emerged during a<br />
process <strong>of</strong> national integration and mobilization that stirred a “sense <strong>of</strong><br />
community membership and common heritage” among the citizens <strong>of</strong> modern<br />
states.<br />
Several years after Marshall, Stein Rokkan, a leading theorist <strong>of</strong> the<br />
functionalist school in sociology, depicted social citizenship as the last step in<br />
the process <strong>of</strong> nation-building. The advance <strong>of</strong> formal democracy in the West<br />
could be therefore described as:<br />
a process <strong>of</strong> institutional innovation leading to the imposition <strong>of</strong><br />
formally equal obligations and the granting <strong>of</strong> formally equal rights to<br />
all adults independently <strong>of</strong> differences in their established influence<br />
through roles in the kinship system, the local community or other<br />
corporate bodies. Direct taxation, military conscription and<br />
compulsory education would be major examples <strong>of</strong> formally<br />
universalized obligations to the nation-state, while equality before the<br />
courts, social security provisions and universal suffrage would be the<br />
principal examples <strong>of</strong> national citizen rights (Rokkan 1970: 27).<br />
Marshall’s account <strong>of</strong> citizenship drew heavily on British history. However, its<br />
conclusions were too specific and value-ridden to apply as a general model. In<br />
each country, the pursuit <strong>of</strong> political freedom and social equality has taken<br />
different routes. In Canada, the term citizenship did not appear in the 1867<br />
Constitution. The decline <strong>of</strong> the British Empire after the Second World War and<br />
the specific political needs <strong>of</strong> the Commonwealth states led to an array <strong>of</strong><br />
different national citizenships within it. <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship was thus<br />
formally created in 1946 through the Citizenship Act. Nevertheless, its<br />
evolution both as a legal status and a political idea must be understood within<br />
the wider context <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> nation-building. Together with the institution <strong>of</strong><br />
the Supreme Court as Canada’s final court <strong>of</strong> appeal in 1949 and with the<br />
adoption <strong>of</strong> a national flag and anthem in 1965 and 1975, the Citizenship Act is<br />
undoubtedly one <strong>of</strong> the main symbolic landmarks <strong>of</strong> that process.<br />
At best, a comparative approach renders Marshall’s sketch <strong>of</strong> rights as a<br />
political narrative providing a time reference and normative criteria for<br />
analyzing citizenship rights, rather than an actual account <strong>of</strong> their historical<br />
development. The political and intellectual roots <strong>of</strong> citizenship differ<br />
significantly in each country. For instance, the idea <strong>of</strong> citizenship as<br />
membership in a legal and political community was entirely alien to British<br />
thinking and history (Brubaker 1989: 10). Only recently has Britain attempted<br />
to define itself as a nation-state, since the idea <strong>of</strong> “imperial subjecthood” had<br />
long pervaded both its own and its colonies’ self-definition (Bothwell 1993). In<br />
fact, British national citizenship did not exist until 1981, although its normative<br />
core developed through an inclusive process involving the consecutive<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> different sets <strong>of</strong> rights, starting with civil rights in the eighteenth<br />
96
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
century and continuing with full political rights and social entitlements in this<br />
century.<br />
Citizenship rights in France, Germany and the United States have a very<br />
different history altogether. Suffrage was extended in each country at a<br />
different pace. French and American political rights were the product <strong>of</strong><br />
revolution and, like civil rights in Britain, were originally linked to property.<br />
Marshall’s imagined sequence <strong>of</strong> rights was also inverted by the German<br />
experience, since social rights were granted under Bismarck’s rule as a means<br />
to block democratic reforms. As for Canada, only after status Indians and Inuit<br />
were allowed to vote in 1960 could it be said to have had a universal franchise<br />
(Ungerleider 1992). Unlike France, with its Proclamation <strong>of</strong> the Rights <strong>of</strong> Man<br />
and Citizen in 1789, no revolutionary moment inaugurated <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizenship rights. Their constitutional entrenchment actually clashed with the<br />
longstanding British tradition <strong>of</strong> parliamentary supremacy. Nevertheless,<br />
citizenship rights have developed a particular legal and political culture in<br />
Canada since Prime Ministers John Diefenbaker had his Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights passed in<br />
1960 and since Pierre E. Trudeau’s Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms was<br />
included in the constitutional package <strong>of</strong> 1982 (Williams 1985). Although<br />
clearly a product <strong>of</strong> Canada’s particular ethno-political cleavage, the inclusion<br />
<strong>of</strong> cultural rights in the agenda <strong>of</strong> citizenship must be considered a valuable and<br />
specific <strong>Canadian</strong> contribution to modern constitutionalism.<br />
Cultural Rights and the Idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship<br />
The idea <strong>of</strong> citizenship draws its normative core from ancient Greece, the<br />
Roman Republic and the city-states <strong>of</strong> northern Italy during the Middle Ages.<br />
Originally, this term referred to those possessing all the rights and duties<br />
enjoyed under the constitution <strong>of</strong> a jural society (Kaplan 1993: 247). Citizens<br />
were reciprocally bound by their right to participate in governing their city and<br />
by their obligation to defend it against alien enemies (Baron 1988). Citizenship<br />
in modern states has inherited some <strong>of</strong> the moral gist <strong>of</strong> its classical counterpart:<br />
it should be egalitarian, democratic and unique in order to induce the citizens to<br />
make any necessary sacrifices for the state. Nation-states emerging since the<br />
nineteenth century, however, imposed a further condition on state<br />
membership: it should be based on a community <strong>of</strong> language and culture.<br />
According to John Stuart Mill’s classical statement, representative government<br />
could only take root with a “sufficient amount <strong>of</strong> mutual sympathy among the<br />
populations” based on affinity <strong>of</strong> “race, language, religion and, above all, <strong>of</strong><br />
political institutions, as conducing most to a feeling <strong>of</strong> identity <strong>of</strong> political<br />
interest” (Mill 1991). Whenever possible, nation-building was carried out<br />
under the dictates <strong>of</strong> cultural assimilation, viewed as the only way a nation-state<br />
could fulfil the romantic dictum and become a nation’s state (Brubaker 1989:<br />
4).<br />
Canada obviously deviates from this pattern. State-making and nation-building<br />
have not merged to produce a homogeneous nation-state. Canada is neither the<br />
product <strong>of</strong> the “national principle” nor <strong>of</strong> a political revolution, but <strong>of</strong> the<br />
particular fate <strong>of</strong> the British Empire in North America: the eventual union <strong>of</strong> the<br />
possessions <strong>of</strong> the British Crown which did not revolt in 1776 (Srebnik 1992).<br />
97
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Assimilationist attempts following the classic nation-building model, as<br />
encouraged by Lord Durham, ostensibly failed when confronting la<br />
survivance, the determination <strong>of</strong> French-<strong>Canadian</strong>s to preserve their distinct<br />
culture. The development <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> state since the British North America<br />
Act <strong>of</strong> 1867 has therefore followed a cultural pattern whose inner hierarchy has<br />
had to adjust to the surmounting political demands <strong>of</strong> different minorities.<br />
Because it lacked an ethnocultural cohesion and a foundational political myth<br />
from the beginning, <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship has traditionally coexisted with<br />
multiple loyalties: to the British Empire, to what many French-<strong>Canadian</strong>s and<br />
Aboriginals consider their own nations, to the provinces and to old homelands<br />
in the case <strong>of</strong> the immigrants. All <strong>of</strong> these cultural cleavages have made their<br />
way into the <strong>Canadian</strong> political language, which granted them a specific<br />
terminology: Founding Peoples, First Nations, Quebeckers, New <strong>Canadian</strong>s.<br />
The absence <strong>of</strong> a common sense <strong>of</strong> nationhood and the recurrent metaphor <strong>of</strong><br />
the “two solitudes” have also become an inevitable topic whenever <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
identity and political unity are discussed. Defining <strong>Canadian</strong>ness has become a<br />
favoured issue in post-modern political approaches, which describe <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizenship as “fragmented,” “layered” or “non-centered” (Fulford 1993,<br />
Cairns 1993, Lanphier and Richmond 1995).<br />
Taking into account Canada’s social complexity, the recognition <strong>of</strong> citizenship<br />
rights, and <strong>of</strong> cultural rights in particular, has played a major role in its<br />
contemporary attempts at nation-building (Breton 1986). This is particularly<br />
obvious if we regard the Charter proposals during the period <strong>of</strong> constitutional<br />
reform as an attempt to locate the citizen at the centre <strong>of</strong> the governmental<br />
process. The constitutional entrenchment <strong>of</strong> citizen rights aimed to curtail the<br />
strength <strong>of</strong> both provincialism and Quebec nationalism (Cairns 1992: 4,<br />
Williams 1985: 112, Colom 1996). Judicially enforceable rights were to help<br />
erode the dominant role <strong>of</strong> executive federalism in the policy-making process,<br />
whereas the constitutional status <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial language educational rights was<br />
expected to reduce the political appeal <strong>of</strong> Quebec nationalism. The ideology <strong>of</strong><br />
multiculturalism appeared later in this context as an alternative to the twonation<br />
approach to <strong>Canadian</strong> identity. As Prime Minister Pierre Elliott Trudeau<br />
stressed in his address on multiculturalism to the House <strong>of</strong> Commons in 1971,<br />
Canada had two languages, albeit no <strong>of</strong>ficial culture (House <strong>of</strong> Commons<br />
Debates, 8545-46). Politically and ideologically, cultural rights can be said to<br />
constitute an essential element <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> citizenship.<br />
With the appointment <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission on Bilingualism and<br />
Biculturalism in 1963, language rights took the lead in the politics <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship. In 1969, English and French were given the status <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />
languages at the federal level, but linguistic rights were soon to open the way for<br />
the recognition <strong>of</strong> a wider set <strong>of</strong> cultural rights. Two years later, Canada became<br />
the first country in the world to adopt multiculturalism as a public policy, and in<br />
1982, Section 27 <strong>of</strong> the Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms further guaranteed<br />
Canada’s multiculturalism by proclaiming a constitutional commitment to<br />
preserve the cultural heritage <strong>of</strong> its citizens. Under this clause, the promotion <strong>of</strong><br />
cultural rights eventually extended to recognize the equal standing <strong>of</strong> all<br />
religions and to allow public funding for heritage language schools. Having<br />
started as “a conscious support <strong>of</strong> individual freedom <strong>of</strong> choice” concerning<br />
98
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
cultural allegiance, multiculturalism would become “a policy to preserve and<br />
enhance the multicultural heritage <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong>s” and “a fundamental<br />
characteristic <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> heritage and identity.” The Multiculturalism Act<br />
<strong>of</strong> 1988 reasserted the federal will to preserve cultural diversity as the new core<br />
<strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>ficial discourse on <strong>Canadian</strong> identity. By establishing a nationwide<br />
code <strong>of</strong> linguistic rights, the Charter provided the framework for a nonterritorial<br />
approach to language issues in Canada and a platform for Trudeau’s<br />
dream <strong>of</strong> reshaping <strong>Canadian</strong> identity along citizenship lines.<br />
The position <strong>of</strong> cultural rights in a developmental theory <strong>of</strong> citizenship like the<br />
one sketched by Marshall is rather ambiguous. Unlike civil and political<br />
liberties, cultural rights are not rights in the traditional liberal sense. The good<br />
they protect is not individual autonomy against state power, but ways <strong>of</strong><br />
belonging to a given cultural and political community. Cultural rights like those<br />
granted by <strong>Canadian</strong> multicultural agencies can be viewed as a special<br />
immigration-focused kind <strong>of</strong> right among a wider array <strong>of</strong> social rights<br />
provided to all citizens under welfare state schemes. In this perspective,<br />
multiculturalism appears as a particular sort <strong>of</strong> integration policy. The case <strong>of</strong><br />
linguistic rights for national minorities is significantly different. Their <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />
status in the Charter reflects the basic collective identities which comprise the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> political community. In other words, “they represent a cultural<br />
compromise designed to enable two linguistic communities to coexist in one<br />
federal country” (Greene 1989: 186).<br />
Canada has made a remarkable attempt to integrate both sorts <strong>of</strong> rights in<br />
forging a common identity out <strong>of</strong> an ethno-racially complex society. However,<br />
the political results <strong>of</strong> this agenda since its launch by the Royal Commission on<br />
Bilingualism and Biculturalism have been at least ambiguous. Though the<br />
language and educational rights included in the Charter proposals during the<br />
1960s were mainly intended to address the English/French cleavage, they soon<br />
penetrated the political rhetoric <strong>of</strong> other cultural groups. Multiculturalism<br />
eventually consolidated as a state-sponsored ideology, and evolved from<br />
folkloric celebration <strong>of</strong> diversity into a set <strong>of</strong> anti-discriminatory and race<br />
relations policies (Fleras and Elliot 1992).<br />
However, the agenda <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism as a federal policy has not proceeded<br />
without problems. A persisting fear exists in Canada that it slides dangerously<br />
close to interest-group politics and that the language <strong>of</strong> cultural rights is used to<br />
dress up political demands. Multiculturalism, therefore, has at best been<br />
perceived as a civic philosophy <strong>of</strong>fering new legitimacy to the <strong>Canadian</strong> state<br />
and, at worst, as an Anglophone strategy to either outdo the French minority or<br />
control the other ethnic groups (Paquet 1994: 67, Fleras and Elliot 1992: 67,<br />
Helly 1996). Supporters <strong>of</strong> a strong pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> identity have traditionally<br />
criticized it as a dispensable source <strong>of</strong> social division. Meanwhile, some voices<br />
among ethnic minorities have recently joined the choir <strong>of</strong> critics denouncing<br />
multiculturalpoliciesasineffectiveorevenasstigmatizingfortheirmembers.<br />
Multicultural policies did not run smoothly among Francophone political and<br />
intellectual circles either. In the beginning, they were warily perceived as an<br />
attempt to reduce the French factor in Canada to the condition <strong>of</strong> other<br />
immigrant ethno-cultural minorities. When multiculturalism was inaugurated<br />
99
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
as a federal policy in 1971, Quebec sovereignists clearly rejected it. However,<br />
the necessity <strong>of</strong> confronting the demographic and linguistic pressures <strong>of</strong><br />
immigration in a predominantly Anglophone environment finally enticed the<br />
Quebec government to develop its own policy for managing cultural pluralism<br />
in1981. Themuchdebated Loi101 notonlyinaugurated anaggressive policyto<br />
ensure the dominant status <strong>of</strong> French language in Quebec, but also marked a<br />
significant departure from the ethnic self-definition <strong>of</strong> French-<strong>Canadian</strong><br />
identity. Interculturalisme became the brand for a new scheme <strong>of</strong> provincial<br />
cultural policies, meaning that the French language and culture would<br />
thereafter be differentiated so that immigrants could be included in the<br />
Francophone political community. This policy was inspired by the perception<br />
<strong>of</strong> an intrinsic contradiction between the bilingualism and multiculturalism<br />
policies. Quebec’s interculturalisme openly recognizes the existence <strong>of</strong> a<br />
hierarchy <strong>of</strong> cultures and an asymmetry favouring the French language as an<br />
instrument for integration (Paquet 1994). However, since federal multicultural<br />
policies have never questioned the integrative role <strong>of</strong> English language in the<br />
rest <strong>of</strong> Canada, its difference with Quebec’s interculturalisme is probably more<br />
practical than theoretical. It has been noticed, for instance, that Quebec’s<br />
government is more inclined to finance multi-ethnic associations than monoethnical<br />
ones (Helly 1996), thus enhancing the role <strong>of</strong> Quebec’s <strong>of</strong>ficial<br />
language and institutions as means for cultural communication.<br />
Regardless <strong>of</strong> the difficulties inherent in its implementation as a public policy,<br />
the ideological core <strong>of</strong> multiculturalism has gained importance as the <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
unity crisis has worsened. Immigration and multiculturalism have indeed been<br />
crucial elements in <strong>Canadian</strong> nation-building (Breton 1986, Tepper 1994). As<br />
in the case <strong>of</strong> the United States or Australia, immigration has played a major<br />
role in shaping the <strong>Canadian</strong> experience and historical narrative. Although<br />
national narratives are undoubtedly fictitious to a great extent, they play a<br />
crucial role in providing the symbols, cultural meanings and political values<br />
that inspire collective identities. The immigration epics implied in the<br />
“American dream,” for instance, have no equivalent in Europe, where national<br />
identities are deeply rooted in history and the need to redefine them to<br />
accommodate the immigrant communities is rarely perceived.<br />
In Canada, the Anglo-French cleavage and enduring ties with the British<br />
Empire prevented the emergence <strong>of</strong> a unified historical narrative. In fact, no<br />
English-<strong>Canadian</strong> equivalent to la survivance exists. In this context<br />
multiculturalism policies have not only assisted in managing social diversity,<br />
but have also provided the symbolic discourse for accommodating it and<br />
<strong>of</strong>fered a self-image <strong>of</strong> Canada as being a “mosaic” as opposed to its “meltingpot”<br />
neighbour to the south. The social and cultural rights comprised in the<br />
Charter were part <strong>of</strong> a wider nation-building agenda intended to produce a<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> identity and civic culture distinct from the individualist and<br />
assimilationist features that predominate in its American counterpart. The<br />
crisis <strong>of</strong> the welfare state and the uncertain future <strong>of</strong> Quebec in the federation<br />
have placed this project on a rather shaky footing.<br />
It is now obvious that the constitutional entrenchment <strong>of</strong> linguistic rights has<br />
not eroded support for Quebec nationalism, whose roots are more complex than<br />
100
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
just language. It also seems clear that multiculturalism is unsuited to<br />
reconciling Canada’s ethno-territorial cleavage by <strong>of</strong>fering a renewed basis <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship. In the long term, multicultural policies can only serve to dignify the<br />
immigrants’ identities and therefore to facilitate their social integration.<br />
However, the political narrative <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> multiculturalism is quite unique:<br />
while clearly a political response to the demands <strong>of</strong> inclusion by immigrant<br />
communities, it also constitutes the ideological platform <strong>of</strong> a liberal state<br />
committed to the tenet <strong>of</strong> cultural pluralism based on individual rights<br />
(Kymlicka 1995b: paper 4). In this respect, Taylor has distinguished two kinds<br />
<strong>of</strong> liberalism: one that advocates the cultural and religious neutrality <strong>of</strong> the state<br />
and is strictly devoted to protecting individual rights; and another that, allows<br />
for a state dedicated to the promotion <strong>of</strong> a particular cultural, religious or<br />
national project (Taylor 1994). The first typically corresponds to the self-image<br />
bolstered by the United States as a society <strong>of</strong> immigrants with no significant<br />
ethno-territorial identities. On the contrary, societies with strong collective<br />
goals, such as Quebec, clearly fit into the second category.<br />
American-style liberalism allows little space for state-run cultural matters.<br />
Inescapable cultural choices, like the language <strong>of</strong> instruction or bureaucracy,<br />
are presented as simply instrumental. Allegiance to the constitution is viewed<br />
as the primary source <strong>of</strong> collective identity. Although not devoid <strong>of</strong> cultural or<br />
religious projects, this model belongs to civil society and the cultural market<br />
place. State institutions are thought and designed to protect the individual’s<br />
autonomy, not to achieve communal goals. Provided that fundamental liberties<br />
and respect for diversity are granted, Taylor sustains that liberal societies can<br />
also be organized around a certain definition <strong>of</strong> the “good life.” Shared<br />
definitions <strong>of</strong> the good life are nevertheless difficult in modern, complex<br />
societies: political self-government, and not only cultural survival, are the<br />
declared goals <strong>of</strong> Quebec nationalism, and views on how to define and relate<br />
both differ. In any event, as far as cultural pluralism is concerned, Quebec’s<br />
policy clearly subordinates the demands for cultural recognition made by its<br />
minorities to the affirmation <strong>of</strong> its own national project.<br />
Canada’s federal multicultural policy probably accommodates both kinds <strong>of</strong><br />
liberalism. Unlike the United States, the <strong>Canadian</strong> commitment to citizenship<br />
rights is particularly sensitive to the cultural background <strong>of</strong> individual<br />
identities as a condition for proper social integration. Cultural policies are<br />
therefore publicly funded and constitutionally recognized. On the other hand,<br />
the <strong>Canadian</strong> state does not endorse, like Quebec, a strong cultural narrative as<br />
the core for the organization <strong>of</strong> political life. Rather, its confessed aim is to<br />
manage cultural diversity within a politically recognizable framework <strong>of</strong><br />
solidarity. Ethno-territorial groups competing for autonomy within the same<br />
state boundaries can hardly be reconciled to this sort <strong>of</strong> arrangement. The<br />
difficulty here lies in the institutions that articulate the exercise <strong>of</strong> this<br />
autonomy: they are mainly expressed as political and territorial demands for<br />
self-government, not just for cultural autonomy. Liberal theory was<br />
constructed around the limits <strong>of</strong> state power in relation to the citizens, their<br />
rights and duties, but it gives no clue about their cultural identity. Citizens and<br />
nations were to be created so that liberal democracy could work.<br />
101
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Patterns <strong>of</strong> Belonging: Culture, Nationhood and Citizenship<br />
The regulation <strong>of</strong> national membership is one <strong>of</strong> the last realms <strong>of</strong> sovereignty<br />
<strong>of</strong> the nation-state. The status <strong>of</strong> citizenship not only regulates physical access<br />
to the state territory, but also allows access to its social services, political<br />
liberties and legal duties. Citizenship is hence a group-specific concept as much<br />
as a closure device (Brubaker 1992: 22). From this perspective, the link<br />
between social rights and nation-building as described by Marshall and Rokkan<br />
has proved true, if not as an historical sequence, certainly as the political<br />
framework that has made those rights possible. Whereas the principles <strong>of</strong><br />
distributive justice embodied in welfare state schemes do not respond to freemarket<br />
standards, they cannot necessarily be universally applied. Indeed, they<br />
are sustainable only on a membership basis: a distinction between those who<br />
belong to a common social framework and those who do not. Sheer utilitarian<br />
strategies alone cannot explain how welfare states have been possible (Baldwin<br />
1990). Welfare policies must be rooted in a general expectation <strong>of</strong> mutual<br />
advantage and in a reasonable commitment to reciprocal sacrifice. Such<br />
expectations are more likely to grow out <strong>of</strong> a sense <strong>of</strong> common belonging. So<br />
far, this particular sense <strong>of</strong> belonging has been mainly understood in terms <strong>of</strong><br />
national membership. The attendant sense <strong>of</strong> belonging has been described by<br />
functionalist sociology as the diffuse enduring solidarity that pervades a<br />
societal community:<br />
The social community presumes a relatively definable population <strong>of</strong><br />
membership which at this level we ordinarily call citizens for the<br />
modern case. [It] presumes as well that the collective organization <strong>of</strong><br />
reference is politically organized on a territorial basis and...atsome<br />
level it is characterized by a common cultural tradition (Parsons 1975:<br />
59).<br />
Solidarity in this sense does not suggest a moral virtue possessed by all<br />
members <strong>of</strong> a community. According to Parsons, diffuse solidarity relies less<br />
on individual attitudes than on a “cultural structure” entailing a common<br />
language, a cultural history and the perception <strong>of</strong> a shared future (Parsons 1975:<br />
60). However, the political relevance <strong>of</strong> ethnocultural identity as we currently<br />
know it is a specific product <strong>of</strong> modern history. Unlike feudalism, modern<br />
territorially-centered political models involve a significant degree <strong>of</strong> state<br />
intervention in society. The present pressure for cultural homogeneity arises<br />
from the bureaucratic, legal and military instruments required by the modern<br />
state and from the long-reaching effects <strong>of</strong> a market economy based on labour<br />
mobility, communication networks and technological change (Gellner 1983).<br />
As is known, the historical relation between state-making and nation-building<br />
is a debated one (Connor 1972). The crucial issue is whether the first process<br />
requires the latter, particularly when it means creating a unified territorial<br />
nation out <strong>of</strong> the multiple existing ethnies and their homelands. This is precisely<br />
the thesis <strong>of</strong> Anthony D. Smith, an outspoken defender <strong>of</strong> the ethnic origin <strong>of</strong><br />
modern nations:<br />
If political leaders wish to create states and form nations under the<br />
appropriate social and technological conditions, they can only do so if<br />
the ethnic conditions are similarly favourable; and the more<br />
appropriate those ethnic conditions are, the more likely are they to<br />
102
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
succeed in creating both states and nations. Conversely, the absence<br />
<strong>of</strong> such conditions creates a serious barrier to state-and-nationformation.<br />
Not only does it remove the basis <strong>of</strong> cohesion for political<br />
unities, it also creates visual bases for alternative unities and the<br />
chances <strong>of</strong> breakdowns <strong>of</strong> ethnically divided polities (Smith 1986:<br />
244-45).<br />
Following this assumption, three state schemes can be brought into<br />
consideration. In the first place, we have what Smith has labelled the immigrant<br />
state model (Smith 1986: 258). This is the case <strong>of</strong> immigration countries built<br />
upon a weak ethnic core. Their basic cultural patterns were originally defined<br />
by the oldest ethnic group in the country, since it held political control <strong>of</strong> the<br />
territory at the moment <strong>of</strong> independence. Examples include the United States,<br />
Australia, Brazil or Argentina. The British conquest <strong>of</strong> Nouvelle France<br />
probably prevented the French settlers in North America from creating a<br />
similar state <strong>of</strong> their own. What Smith calls the autonomist state model <strong>of</strong>fers a<br />
different response to ethnic complexity. This model seeks to create a dual<br />
regional- national identity within a unitary sovereign state by granting a limited<br />
degree <strong>of</strong> institutional autonomy to ethnic groups that demand it. Spain would<br />
fit well into this model, since its political decentralization during the<br />
democratic transition was mainly a reaction to Basque and Catalan<br />
nationalism. Finally, the granting <strong>of</strong> territorial and cultural autonomy is sought<br />
by the federal- national state in a more radical way. This model confers explicit<br />
constitutional and political recognition <strong>of</strong> nationhood on the different ethnoterritorial<br />
groups comprised in its domain. Stability here, however, seems to be<br />
a difficult goal to achieve. Ironically, Smith considered Yugoslavia as a<br />
“promising model” for the resolution <strong>of</strong> national conflicts when he wrote his<br />
book. Belgium and the former Soviet Union, with their tortuous though<br />
radically different experiences, seem to be making headway toward this model.<br />
Canada, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as the issue <strong>of</strong> asymmetric federalism and Quebec’s “distinct<br />
society” status are unresolved, can be considered to sway unstably between the<br />
second and the third alternatives.<br />
This sketch by no means pretends to exhaust the variety <strong>of</strong> possible political<br />
responses to ethnic complexity. Instead, it <strong>of</strong>fers an overview <strong>of</strong> the different<br />
ways in which cultural and political identities can be assembled into a common<br />
polity. Citizenship, both as a status and as the set <strong>of</strong> rights attached to it, is one <strong>of</strong><br />
the main principles regulating ethnic affiliation and state membership in every<br />
country. It is probably true that citizenship has lost part <strong>of</strong> its former value as<br />
social and civil rights have been extended to immigrant populations in many<br />
Western states (Schuck 1989, Hammar 1990). The more extended a social good<br />
is, the more difficult it seems to legitimize the exclusion <strong>of</strong> a part <strong>of</strong> the people<br />
from it. The <strong>Canadian</strong> Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights, for instance, deliberately left as<br />
citizens’ privileges the right to vote, to receive diplomatic protection abroad<br />
and to choose the linguistic-educational model for their children.<br />
This circumstance has led some authors to announce the emergence <strong>of</strong> a new<br />
post-national pattern <strong>of</strong> state membership in which individual rights are<br />
legitimized on the basis <strong>of</strong> personhood, not <strong>of</strong> citizenship (Soysal 1994). Even<br />
if it is true that legal residence has partially displaced the role <strong>of</strong> citizenship in<br />
regulating social membership and that state sovereignty has been notably<br />
103
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
eroded, the nation-state still rules over admission to the country, the granting <strong>of</strong><br />
permanent residence and the naturalization procedures. Unless dual citizenship<br />
is permitted, immigrants usually have to prove somewhat stronger allegiance to<br />
their new country than to their country <strong>of</strong> origin. Under these conditions<br />
naturalization is not always an easy decision:<br />
Changing citizenship is the final stage in the migration process. It<br />
means giving up plans or dreams to return to the country <strong>of</strong> origin. It<br />
involves abandoning the loyalties <strong>of</strong> one’s formative years and<br />
showing that one’s loyalties lie with the new country (Layton-Henry<br />
1991: 117).<br />
Integration models are an increasingly politicized issue in Western societies.<br />
Whereas in former periods, one-directional assimilation was expected <strong>of</strong><br />
immigrants, demands for multiculturalism or for pluralistic integration are now<br />
growing stronger. These demands are <strong>of</strong>ten censured as evidence <strong>of</strong> their<br />
disaffection for their host country. Hence, the fate <strong>of</strong> multicultural policies<br />
largely depends on the political ability <strong>of</strong> the immigrant groups to defend their<br />
specific interests. Exclusively concerned at the beginning with housing and<br />
working conditions, their demands have gradually adopted the language <strong>of</strong><br />
identity politics. However, identity claims here need not be simply understood<br />
in culturalistic terms. They are <strong>of</strong>ten a way <strong>of</strong> expressing their specific social<br />
needs and a means to enter the political sphere <strong>of</strong> their host countries. The<br />
integration <strong>of</strong> immigrants partially reverses once more Marshall’s imagined<br />
sequence: civil rights were in this case the first to be granted; economic and<br />
social rights were generally conferred to immigrants and citizens at the same<br />
time; and although political rights are still an open question, some European<br />
countries already allow immigrants to vote in local elections.<br />
The immigrant condition and the circumstances surrounding the acquisition <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship may help to illuminate the different incorporation strategies and<br />
organizational designs deployed by the states in order to regulate societal life.<br />
Multicultural policies in particular make sense only if the host state is clearly<br />
willing to incorporate immigrants as permanent members <strong>of</strong> the polity. As long<br />
as they continue to be regarded as “guest workers,” integration policies are out<br />
<strong>of</strong> the question. Ethnicity plays a different role in the way every country<br />
understands the meaning <strong>of</strong> its own citizenship. In fact, cultural and political<br />
elements can probably combine in as many models <strong>of</strong> citizenship as there are<br />
states. Considering that relationship in abstract terms, as “ideal types” in the<br />
sense <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, we can distinguish at least four patterns <strong>of</strong> citizenship.<br />
French citizenship has been traditionally presented as a paradigm <strong>of</strong> cultural<br />
assimilation. It corresponds to a pattern that we could call republican<br />
citizenship, since the French patriots stressed the egalitarian, universalist and<br />
unitary character <strong>of</strong> citizenship during the revolution mainly for political<br />
reasons. They strove to build a homogeneous and solidary community <strong>of</strong><br />
citizens around the myth <strong>of</strong> a general will, not to promote a particular ethnic<br />
affiliation. Since French statehood was a consolidated reality at the moment <strong>of</strong><br />
revolution, the proclamation <strong>of</strong> national sovereignty as unitary and indivisible<br />
could be interpreted at once as a political feat and as the basis <strong>of</strong> French national<br />
identity. Hence, the cultural dimension <strong>of</strong> this identity reflected a common<br />
104
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
political commitment toward the future. Local dialects and regional diversity<br />
subsisted under the republican surface. Cultural assimilation only took place<br />
during the Third Republic, due to the wave <strong>of</strong> nationalism prompted by the<br />
defeat in the Franco-Prussian war. Army conscription and public schooling<br />
worked hand in hand as a formidable social agency that set out to transform both<br />
the peasantry and the children <strong>of</strong> immigrants into Frenchmen (Weber 1976).<br />
American statehood and citizenship are unfamiliar with the myth <strong>of</strong> a unitary<br />
and indivisible national sovereignty. Its constitutional structure is built upon<br />
the opposite principle: the dispersal <strong>of</strong> political power. American civic culture<br />
is also considered to rely on the values <strong>of</strong> individualism, egalitarianism,<br />
democracy, nationalism and tolerance for diversity (Karst 1989: 31). Its idea <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship can be best defined as a liberal one. These views are largely a<br />
product <strong>of</strong> the American revolution. In the aftermath <strong>of</strong> the War <strong>of</strong><br />
Independence, American patriots opted for a voluntary, conditional and<br />
institutional concept <strong>of</strong> citizenship. American national ideology included,<br />
however, other values that are nowadays unacceptable, like Protestant<br />
domination and white supremacy. For instance, the Dred Scott judicial decision<br />
in 1857 stated that freed slaves did not qualify for citizenship, while Black<br />
segregation has traditionally coexisted with <strong>of</strong>ficial discourse on the<br />
universalist character <strong>of</strong> American identity. The self-image <strong>of</strong> American<br />
citizenship was nonetheless built upon the idea that it exclusively consists <strong>of</strong> an<br />
act <strong>of</strong> political allegiance:<br />
To be or become an American [at the time <strong>of</strong> Independence], a person<br />
did not have to be <strong>of</strong> any particular national, linguistic, religious, or<br />
ethnic background. All he had to do was to commit himself to the<br />
political ideology centered on the abstract ideals <strong>of</strong> liberty, equality,<br />
and republicanism (Gleason 1982: 62).<br />
American national citizenship did not consolidate until the Fourteenth<br />
Amendment was issued after the War <strong>of</strong> Secession. Since then, American<br />
society has had to develop an internal differentiation between the diverging<br />
characteristics <strong>of</strong> its political institutions and its civic organizations. American<br />
civil society is a collection <strong>of</strong> interest-groups, many <strong>of</strong> them defined by<br />
ethnocultural patterns. On the contrary, the American state is a neutral<br />
institution for the protection <strong>of</strong> the citizens individual rights (Walzer 1992).<br />
Given that the state institutions are universalist by constitutional mandate, they<br />
cannot assume the ethnic or cultural character <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> these groups. Ethnic<br />
and religious affiliations in the United States belong to the private sphere or to<br />
the civil society, not to the state.<br />
Ethnocultural citizenship presents altogether a different case. Ethnic affiliation<br />
and state membership are here one and the same thing. The German idea <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship fits well into this category. German national consciousness was first<br />
imagined in a romantic sense, as Volksgeist, by a literary elite. Politically it<br />
emerged as a reaction against Napoleonic expansionism at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the<br />
nineteenth century. Unlike French or American national identities, German<br />
identity did not dispose <strong>of</strong> the state instruments required to assemble its<br />
political and cultural dimensions into a single national citizenship. German<br />
national union, as proposed by the German Assembly at the Paulskirche in<br />
105
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Frankfurt in 1848, was compelled to choose between the Austrian and the<br />
Prussian alternatives, both <strong>of</strong> which were incomplete. Either some German<br />
territories were left out <strong>of</strong> the German nation-state (the Kleindeutsche option)<br />
or foreign peoples had to be included in it (the Grossdeutsche option). The idea<br />
<strong>of</strong> a German citizenship therefore had to undergo a difficult process <strong>of</strong> change<br />
during which it assumed a clear ethnocultural affiliation.<br />
The first code <strong>of</strong> German state membership dates back from 1842 (Brubaker<br />
1992). This was rather a regulation <strong>of</strong> Prussian subjecthood, not <strong>of</strong> German<br />
citizenship. The latter would be the result <strong>of</strong> Prussia’s efforts to become a<br />
nation-state. Jus sanguinis only consolidated as the chief principle <strong>of</strong> German<br />
citizenship law in 1913, under the influence <strong>of</strong> the pan-germanic nationalism<br />
pervading the Reich. This idea <strong>of</strong> citizenship was intended to protect the<br />
Auslandsdeutsche in Eastern Europe and in the Baltic region and to seclude<br />
German identity within the Reich against the Volksfremde, Jewish and Polish<br />
immigrants mainly. As a result, German citizenship and nationhood have<br />
merged ever since in an ethnocultural pattern which constructs the German<br />
nation as a community <strong>of</strong> descent. This view is also common to Jewish identity,<br />
particularly since the state <strong>of</strong> Israel was created (Kraines 1976), and embodies<br />
the kind <strong>of</strong> political narrative that has traditionally appealed to the imagination<br />
<strong>of</strong> the “stateless nations.”<br />
The attempt to reconcile the ideas <strong>of</strong> cultural autonomy and political<br />
community into a single membership status introduces a new variety <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship that, for our purpose, we can call multicultural (Kymlicka 1995a).<br />
This sort <strong>of</strong> citizenship tries to detach itself from any single ethnocultural<br />
affiliation while promoting the individual’s freedom to choose his/her own<br />
cultural allegiances. The <strong>Canadian</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> citizenship, though unstable and<br />
subject to constant revision, can be said to reflect some <strong>of</strong> these features.<br />
Canada is not the only country to have embraced the multicultural ideology as<br />
an <strong>of</strong>ficial doctrine and policy. Australia, and to a lesser extent, New Zealand<br />
and Sweden, have done the same (Hawkins 1982, Foster and Stockley 1984,<br />
Castles 1988, Alund and Schierup 1991). Multiculturalism here does not imply<br />
an accomplished social and political reality, but a public discourse and a moral<br />
commitment with cultural autonomy as a legitimate goal for integration<br />
policies:<br />
Multiculturalism is now an integral part <strong>of</strong> contemporary...politics.<br />
In some places it has become the legitimate <strong>of</strong>ficial political ideology,<br />
acknowledging the cultural heritage and permanence <strong>of</strong> ethnic<br />
groups. Elsewhere multiculturalism has become an oppositional<br />
position claiming the immigrants’ and ethnic minorities’ rights to<br />
cultural autonomy (Alund and Schierup 1991: 1).<br />
The doctrine <strong>of</strong> cultural pluralism, as vindicated by Horace Kallen for America,<br />
“postulates the parity <strong>of</strong> the different and their free and friendly communication<br />
with one another as both co-operators and competitors; it postulates that every<br />
individual, every society, thus realizes its own being more freely and<br />
abundantly than it can by segregation and isolation and struggle to go it alone”<br />
(Kallen 1956: 98). Of course, this postulation must not be naively assumed. The<br />
effect <strong>of</strong> any multicultural ideology in a given society depends on its power<br />
106
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
structure and on the terms <strong>of</strong> exchange between the different social groupings.<br />
Whereas cultural heterogeneity as such in a free-market, liberal society can<br />
develop a “vertical mosaic” (Porter 1968), i.e., an ethnocultural hierarchy in the<br />
social division <strong>of</strong> labour, state management <strong>of</strong> ethnocultural categories can<br />
confine immigrant cultures to the status <strong>of</strong> preserved and controlled<br />
reservations. An unavoidable by-product <strong>of</strong> multicultural policies is the<br />
culturalization <strong>of</strong> political language. Strategies <strong>of</strong> domination and conflicts <strong>of</strong><br />
interest can be worded in ethnic terms and can displace or disguise more general<br />
social cleavages.<br />
Conclusion<br />
All <strong>of</strong> the citizenship patterns considered are compatible with the democratic<br />
ideal. Each has its own basis <strong>of</strong> legitimacy and reflects a different historical<br />
experience. Though exhibiting a distinctive relationship between their ethnic<br />
and political dimensions, their inner stability depends mainly on their skill in<br />
balancing the opposing social forces around them. Because <strong>of</strong> its particular<br />
history, Canada was one <strong>of</strong> the first democratic countries to include cultural<br />
rights in its constitutional and nation-building agenda. As is now obvious, its<br />
results have been inconclusive. The last thirty years have witnessed the<br />
evolution <strong>of</strong> the old French-<strong>Canadian</strong> identity into a new territorial Québécois<br />
identity that threatens to break the political community. On the other hand, the<br />
so-called “English Canada” seems trapped in an existential identity crisis that<br />
may last as long as the Quebec issue remains unresolved.<br />
Obviously, the future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship depends on the outcome <strong>of</strong> this<br />
crisis. The ethnocultural cleavage that once prompted the emergence <strong>of</strong><br />
multicultural policies will most probably work against them if this cleavage<br />
finally breaks. It is disputable that multicultural citizenship would survive the<br />
splitting up <strong>of</strong> the country. An independent Quebec would most probably adopt<br />
a decidedly ethnolinguistic approach to its new citizenship. While Angloconformity<br />
might be difficult to restore in the rest <strong>of</strong> Canada, a temptation<br />
might arise to switch to an American-inspired form <strong>of</strong> liberal citizenship. After<br />
all, surveys show that immigrant ethnic identity usually dissolves in the third<br />
generation (Helly 1996). What certainly seems to be fading is the dream <strong>of</strong><br />
using multicultural citizenship as a lever for reshaping Canada into a culturally<br />
plural nation-state endowed with symmetric federal structures. The reason is<br />
not only to be found in the challenge <strong>of</strong> Quebec’s national ambitions to a pan-<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> multicultural citizenship, but in the growing disaffection facing<br />
multiculturalism itself in the rest <strong>of</strong> Canada. Not only are the major <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
parties reviewing their attitude toward this issue, but popular platforms like the<br />
Citizens’ Forum have also expressed their concern for the effect <strong>of</strong><br />
multiculturalism on <strong>Canadian</strong> social unity. Last but not least, it is significant<br />
that the Charlottetown agreement did not even mention the multicultural issue<br />
(Helly 1996).<br />
Some authors have suggested that Canada’s reformulation as a multi-nation<br />
federal state is a possible way out <strong>of</strong> the present stalemate (Kymlicka 1995b:<br />
paper 5). This would imply introducing some sort <strong>of</strong> asymmetry into the federal<br />
and constitutional designs. The concept <strong>of</strong> political equality should be detached<br />
107
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
then from the idea <strong>of</strong> a multicultural, pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship and <strong>of</strong> a<br />
procedural constitution neutral to the issue <strong>of</strong> national identities. In order to<br />
make this alternative feasible, English-speaking <strong>Canadian</strong>s should be<br />
convinced <strong>of</strong> their common interests as a linguistic community and that some<br />
sort <strong>of</strong> asymmetry would more fairly accommodate those interests. Not an easy<br />
task to fulfil, since the absence <strong>of</strong> a real threat to their cultural survival has<br />
prevented Anglophone <strong>Canadian</strong>s from viewing language as a reference for<br />
their political identity. In any event, the multi-nation option would bring<br />
Canada to a new stage in the tortuous process <strong>of</strong> soul-searching to define the<br />
nature <strong>of</strong> its citizenship: multicultural citizenship should be probably replaced<br />
by some sort <strong>of</strong> multi-nation federal citizenship and cultural rights readjusted to<br />
a more territorially-centered scheme.<br />
Bibliography<br />
Alund, A., and Schierup, C.U., 1991. Paradoxes <strong>of</strong> Multiculturalism: Essays on Swedish Society.<br />
Aldershot, Avebury.<br />
Baldwin, P., 1990. The Politics <strong>of</strong> Social Solidarity. Class Bases <strong>of</strong> the European Welfare State<br />
(1875-1975). Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.<br />
Baron, H., 1988. In Search <strong>of</strong> Florentine Civic Humanism. Princeton, Princeton University Press.<br />
Bothwell, R., 1993. “Something <strong>of</strong> Value? Subjects and Citizens in <strong>Canadian</strong> History,” in W.<br />
Kaplan (ed.) Belonging: The Meaning and Future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship. Montreal-<br />
Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press: 25-35.<br />
Breton, R., 1986. “Multiculturalism and <strong>Canadian</strong> Nation-Building,” in A. Cairns and C. Williams<br />
(ed) The Politics <strong>of</strong> Gender, Ethnicity and Language in Canada. Toronto, University <strong>of</strong><br />
Toronto Press: 27-66.<br />
Brubaker, W. R., 1992. Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge Mass.,<br />
Harvard University Press.<br />
Brubaker, W. R. (ed.), 1989. Immigration and the Politics <strong>of</strong> Citizenship in Europe and North<br />
America. Lanham, University Press <strong>of</strong> America.<br />
Cairns, A., 1993. “The Fragmentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship,” in W. K. Kaplan Belonging: The<br />
Meaning and Future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship: 181-220.<br />
Cairns, A., 1992. “Citizenship and the New Constitutional Order.” <strong>Canadian</strong> Parliamentary<br />
Review 15 (3): 2-6.<br />
Castles, S. et. al., 1988. Mistaken Identities: Multiculturalism and the Demise <strong>of</strong> Nationalism in<br />
Australia. Sidney, Pluto Press.<br />
Colom, F., 1996. “Las políticas constitucionales y los avatares del federalismo: Canadá y España<br />
ante la cuestión nacional.” Debats 55 (Agosto): 4-16.<br />
Connor, W., 1972. “Nation-building or Nation-destroying?” World Politics 24 (April): 319-355.<br />
Fleras, A. and Elliott, J.L., 1992. Multiculturalism in Canada. Scarborough, Nelson Canada.<br />
Foster, L. and Stockley, D., 1984. Multiculturalism: The Changing Australian Paradigm.<br />
Clevendon, Multilingual Matters.<br />
Fulford, R., 1993. “A Post-Modern Dominion: The Changing Nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship,” in<br />
W.K. Kaplan Belonging: The Meaning and Future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship: 104-122.<br />
Gellner, E., 1983. Nations and Nationalism. Oxford, Blackwell.<br />
Gleason, P., 1982. “American Identity and Americanization,” in W. Petersen et. al. (eds.)<br />
Concepts <strong>of</strong> Ethnicity. Cambridge, Harvard University Press.<br />
Greene, I., 1989. The Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights. Toronto, Lorimer & Co.<br />
Hammar, T., 1990. Democracy and the Nation-State. Avebury, Aldershot.<br />
Hawkins, F., 1982. “Multiculturalism in Two Countries: The <strong>Canadian</strong> and Australian<br />
Experience.” <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> 17 (1): 64-80.<br />
Helly, D., 1994. “Politique québécoise face au ‘pluralisme culturel’ et pistes de recherche: 1977-<br />
1990,” in J.W. Berry and J.A. Laponce (eds.) Ethnicity and Culture in Canada. Toronto,<br />
University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press: 81-123.<br />
———, 1996. “Le multiculturalisme canadien: 1971-1995,” in Hommes et Migrations, 1200<br />
(juillet): 25-34.<br />
House <strong>of</strong> Commons Debates (October 8, 1971) 8545-46.<br />
Kallen, H., 1956. Cultural Pluralism and the American Idea. Philadelphia, University <strong>of</strong><br />
Philadelphia Press.<br />
Kallen, E., 1982. “Multiculturalism: Ideology, Policy and Reality.” <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong><br />
17 (1): 51-80.<br />
108
Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Citizenship<br />
Kaplan, W.K. (ed.), 1993. Belonging: The Meaning and Future <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> Citizenship.<br />
Montreal-Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press.<br />
Karst, L. K., 1989. Belonging to America. New Haven, Yale University Press.<br />
Kraines, O., 1976. The Impossible Dilemma: Who is a Jew in the State <strong>of</strong> Israel? New York, Bloch.<br />
Kymlicka, W., 1995. Multicultural Citizenship. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995.<br />
———. Accommodating Ethnocultural Diversity in Canada. Forthcoming.<br />
Lanphier, C.M. and Richmond, A.H., 1995. “Multiculturalism and Identity in ‘Canada outside<br />
Quebec’,” in K. McRoberts (ed.) Beyond Quebec: Taking Stock <strong>of</strong> Canada. Montreal-<br />
Kingston, McGill-Queen’s University Press: 313-332.<br />
Layton-Henry, Z., 1991. “Citizenship and Migrant Workers in Western Europe,” in U. Vogel and<br />
M. Moran (eds.) The Frontier <strong>of</strong> Citizenship. New York, St. Martin’s Press: 107-124.<br />
Marshall, T.H., 1950. Citizenship and Social Class. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.<br />
Mill, J.S., 1991. Considerations on Representative Government. Collected Works, XIX. Toronto-<br />
Buffalo, University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press: 371-578.<br />
Morton, D., 1993. “Divided Loyalties? Divided Country?,” in W. Kaplan Op. cit.: 50-63.<br />
Paquet, G., 1994. Political Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Multiculturalism, in J.W. Berry and J.A. Laponce (eds.)<br />
Ethnicity and Culture in Canada: 60-80.<br />
Parsons, T., 1975. “Change <strong>of</strong> Ethnicity,” in N. Glazer-Moynihan (ed.) Ethnicity: Theory and<br />
Experience. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press: 53-83.<br />
Porter, J., 1968. The Vertical Mosaic: An Analysis <strong>of</strong> Social Class and Power in Canada. Toronto,<br />
University <strong>of</strong> Toronto Press.<br />
Rokkan, S., 1970. Citizens, Elections, Parties: Approaches to the Comparative Study <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Process <strong>of</strong> Development. Oslo, Universitaetsforlaget: 13-45.<br />
Schuck, P. H., 1989. “Membership in the Liberal Polity: The Devaluation <strong>of</strong> American<br />
Citizenship,” in W.R. Brubaker (ed.) Immigration and the Politics <strong>of</strong> Citizenship in Europe<br />
and North America: 51-66.<br />
Smith, A. D., 1986. “State-Making and Nation-Building,” in J. A. Hall (ed.) States in History.<br />
Oxford, Blackwell: 228-263.<br />
Soysal, Y. N., 1994. Limits <strong>of</strong> Citizenship. Chicago, University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.<br />
Srebnik, H., 1992. “Canada’s Constitution: a New Austria-Hungary in the Making?” <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
Parliamentary Review 15 (1): 2-5.<br />
Taylor, C., 1994. Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics <strong>of</strong> Recognition. Princeton, Princeton<br />
University Press.<br />
Tepper, E.L., 1994. “Immigration Policy and Multiculturalism,” in J.W. Berry and J.A. Laponce<br />
(eds.) Ethnicity and Culture in Canada: 95-123.<br />
Ungerleider, C. S., 1992. “Immigration, Multiculturalism and Citizenship: The Development <strong>of</strong><br />
the <strong>Canadian</strong> Social Justice Infrastructure.” <strong>Canadian</strong> Ethnic <strong>Studies</strong> 24 (3): 7-22.<br />
Walzer, M., 1992. What it Means to be an American. New York, Marsilio.<br />
Weber, M., 1976. Peasants into Frenchmen. Stanford, Stanford University Press.<br />
Weinfield, M., 1994. “Ethnic Assimilation and the Retention <strong>of</strong> Ethnic Cultures,” in J.W. Berry<br />
and J.A. Laponce (eds.) Ethnicity and Culture in Canada: 238-266.<br />
Williams, C., 1985. “The Changing Nature <strong>of</strong> Citizen Rights”, in A. Cairns and C. Williams (eds)<br />
Constitutionalism, Citizenship and Society in Canada. Toronto, University <strong>of</strong> Toronto<br />
Press: 99-131.<br />
109
Jane Jenson and Susan D. Phillips<br />
Regime Shift: New Citizenship<br />
Practices in Canada*<br />
Abstract<br />
As Canada restructures its economy and redefines the relationships between<br />
state and market, it is also restructuring citizens’ relationship with the state.<br />
This paper analyses the transformation <strong>of</strong> the citizenship regime, with<br />
particular attention to changes in access to and representation within the<br />
state. It begins by outlining the principles that underpinned the postwar<br />
citizenship regime and how they were constructed. It then examines the major<br />
manifestations <strong>of</strong> the regime shift, including: institutional changes that have<br />
removed advocates for certain categories <strong>of</strong> citizens, especially women, from<br />
within the state; the diminished capacity and credibility <strong>of</strong> public interest<br />
groups in gaining access to the state; and the definition <strong>of</strong> government<br />
through service delivery partnerships.<br />
Résumé<br />
Au moment même où le Canada réorganise son économie et redéfinit les<br />
relations entre l’État et le marché, il revoit du même coup les liens entre les<br />
citoyens et le gouvernement fédéral. Le présent article analyse la<br />
transformation que subit le régime de citoyenneté, particulièrement les<br />
modifications touchant l’accès aux programmes fédéraux et la représentation<br />
au sein de ces programmes. Les auteures y résument d’abord les principes de<br />
base du régime de citoyenneté né après la guerre et la façon dont ces<br />
principes ont été établis. Elles examinent ensuite les principales<br />
manifestations de la transformation du régime, à savoir : les changements au<br />
sein des établissements qui ont éliminé de la fonction publique les porteparole<br />
de certaines catégories de citoyens (en particulier les femmes); la<br />
diminution de la capacité et de la crédibilité des groupes d’intérêt public au<br />
chapitre de l’accès à l’État; et la nouvelle définition du gouvernement par<br />
l’intermédiaire de partenariats de prestation des services.<br />
[T]here are times in the progress <strong>of</strong> a people when<br />
fundamental challenges must be faced, fundamental<br />
choices made—a new course charted.<br />
For Canada, this is one <strong>of</strong> those times. 1<br />
So began the 1995 budget speech by Canada’s Minister <strong>of</strong> Finance who<br />
promised that his budget would achieve “the very redefinition <strong>of</strong> government<br />
itself.” 2 While such rhetoric is not uncommon among politicians, the Liberal<br />
<strong>International</strong> <strong>Journal</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> <strong>Studies</strong> / <strong>Revue</strong> <strong>internationale</strong> d'études canadiennes<br />
14, Fall/Automne 1996
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
government—following the course charted by its Conservative predecessors<br />
and aided by other forces in <strong>Canadian</strong> society—may achieve more fundamental<br />
reform than even the Minister <strong>of</strong> Finance envisaged in his speech. A series <strong>of</strong><br />
major changes have already been initiated. Institutions, including cabinet, have<br />
been restructured and reduced in size. Parapublic bodies that once provided<br />
external advice or represented the concerns <strong>of</strong> vitally important categories <strong>of</strong><br />
citizens have been eliminated. Government’s relationship with the third sector<br />
has been rethought and interest group funding reduced substantially. While all<br />
<strong>of</strong> these measures could be understood in the context <strong>of</strong> fiscal restraint as<br />
independentattemptsatcost-cutting,suchanexplanationwouldbetoosimple.<br />
These recent reform measures are neither isolated events nor merely budget<br />
reduction exercises. Rather, they form a pattern that marks a major effort by the<br />
state to reconfigure Canada’s postwar citizenship regime. As Canada<br />
restructures its economy as well as the basic relationships between the state and<br />
the market, between the national and the international, and among parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />
state, it is also restructuring citizenship. In essence, the relationship between<br />
the state and civil society, and in particular, the forms <strong>of</strong> legitimate<br />
representation, are being reformulated.<br />
By the mid-1970s Canada’s postwar citizenship regime had evolved to include<br />
both country-wide institutions which addressed citizens as individuals and<br />
programmatic acknowledgement <strong>of</strong> intermediary groups which recognized<br />
and represented particular categories <strong>of</strong> citizens. This regime recognized both<br />
individual and collective rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship. It accepted the legitimacy <strong>of</strong><br />
participation by the intermediary associations <strong>of</strong> civil society in the<br />
representation <strong>of</strong> interests. The construction <strong>of</strong> this regime was a long-term<br />
project, beginning in the war years and reaching its most elaborate form in the<br />
Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms which was embedded in the Constitution<br />
during the 1982 round <strong>of</strong> reforms. 3 The regime was institutionalized in a variety<br />
<strong>of</strong> ways, most obviously in the Constitution and attendant documents such as<br />
the Citizenship Act. But the state bureaucracy, parapublic advisory bodies,<br />
federalism and institutions <strong>of</strong> representation, especially the federal party<br />
system, all made important discursive and practical contributions to this<br />
regime.<br />
In the 1990s, this old regime is being dismantled piece by piece and the<br />
scaffolding <strong>of</strong> what might replace it gradually emerges, although its eventual<br />
form is not yet completely identifiable. What is evident is that forms <strong>of</strong> access to<br />
and representation <strong>of</strong> interests within the state are changing fundamentally.<br />
Who qualifies and is recognized as a model citizen is under challenge. The<br />
legitimacy <strong>of</strong> group action and the desire for social justice are losing ground to<br />
the notion that citizens and interests can compete equally in the political<br />
marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas. In the process, a new, individualized identity for citizens<br />
is emerging. Support for this emerging identity exists within civil society as<br />
well as the state, although, <strong>of</strong> course, the social forces to which it appeals differ<br />
from those which still support the terms <strong>of</strong> the postwar regime.<br />
This paper examines the transformation <strong>of</strong> the citizenship regime, with<br />
particular attention to the shifts in thinking about social justice which<br />
underpinned the postwar social and economic rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship, and about<br />
112
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
access to the state, which has always been a fundamental manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />
political rights to representation.<br />
Citizenship Regimes: Construction and Dismantling<br />
The work <strong>of</strong> historical sociologists, from Marshall’s writings at the end <strong>of</strong><br />
World War II to the recent “explosion <strong>of</strong> interest” described by Kymlicka and<br />
Norman (1994: p. 352), teaches that citizenship is a social construction. As<br />
such, it varies across not only in space but also time. New rights are won, new<br />
groups gain access and definitions <strong>of</strong> community alter over time. Organizing<br />
and legitimizing principles can break with one model and give rise to a quite<br />
different conceptualization. 4 The question remains why and when does<br />
citizenship change.<br />
This paper argues that citizenship regimes exist as the concretization in a<br />
particular place <strong>of</strong> a general model <strong>of</strong> citizenship. Each regime is forged out <strong>of</strong><br />
the political circumstances <strong>of</strong> a national state. 5 Being a regime, citizenship does<br />
not alter quickly or even easily. Nonetheless, it does change at moments <strong>of</strong><br />
economic and political turbulence. In such moments <strong>of</strong> fundamental<br />
restructuring <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> the state, the division <strong>of</strong> labour between state and<br />
market, between public and “private,” and between civil society and the state<br />
are re-opened for discussion. Citizenship regimes also come under pressure at<br />
such times precisely because they are a crucial component <strong>of</strong> the model <strong>of</strong><br />
development which, prior to the turbulent moment, had ordered social<br />
relations. When the model <strong>of</strong> development enters crisis, so does the citizenship<br />
regime embedded within it. 6<br />
A stable regime is one in which the status pr<strong>of</strong>fered matches the status<br />
anticipated, so that the representation <strong>of</strong> citizens by the state accommodates<br />
citizens’ representations <strong>of</strong> themselves. In the post-1945 regimes <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong><br />
Western Europe, for example, such a match existed. The model <strong>of</strong> development<br />
was “social democratized.” Representation was organized around and by classbased<br />
and class-identified actors. The politics <strong>of</strong> production ordered the<br />
meaning and practices <strong>of</strong> the social democratic Nordic countries as well as the<br />
corporatist countries <strong>of</strong> continental Europe. Social rights accrued to the model<br />
citizen who was in most countries the waged male worker, and the rights <strong>of</strong><br />
other categories existed as a declension <strong>of</strong> the primary form. Thus, for example,<br />
pensions were for “old” workers; unemployment benefits went to the “out <strong>of</strong><br />
work;” education and training was directed to “young and potential workers.”<br />
Activities unrelated to paid labour (childbearing and rearing, for example)<br />
were either dealt with in a separate—and inferior—program or treated as<br />
benefits for “families <strong>of</strong> workers.” This regime reached a crisis when it could no<br />
longer accommodate all <strong>of</strong> the contradictions which arose as it became<br />
increasingly difficult to defend the waged male worker as a citizenship norm.<br />
Both economic restructuring and the claims <strong>of</strong> new groups for recognition<br />
contributed to the appearance <strong>of</strong> a mismatch between representations to the<br />
state and representations by the state. The citizenship regime was caught up in<br />
the fundamental restructuring <strong>of</strong> the last two decades, and, in turn, has been<br />
fundamentally altered.<br />
113
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
The outcome <strong>of</strong> these struggles for new rights, identities and access are never<br />
given in advance, <strong>of</strong> course. 7 Only the cumulation <strong>of</strong> case study material can<br />
inform us about the solidification <strong>of</strong> likely general patterns. As a contribution to<br />
this enterprise, this paper presents an analysis <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Canadian</strong> experience in<br />
deconstructing postwar routes <strong>of</strong> representation. The result is not only new<br />
forms <strong>of</strong> access but also new forms <strong>of</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> citizens.<br />
Recognizing Citizens<br />
At its most general, citizenship establishes a system <strong>of</strong> inclusion and exclusion.<br />
It defines boundaries, recognizing the citizenship status <strong>of</strong> the included and<br />
denying the same to the excluded. This notion <strong>of</strong> inside/outside leads directly to<br />
a further specification <strong>of</strong> two dimensions <strong>of</strong> the concept: citizenship as the<br />
conferring <strong>of</strong> rights and citizenship as grounding for feelings <strong>of</strong> identification<br />
with a particular community (Kymlicka and Norman, 1994: 352). Some studies<br />
<strong>of</strong> citizenship have made inclusion and exclusion correspond to the political<br />
border <strong>of</strong> nationality (the citizen <strong>of</strong> a country). 8 But boundaries have never been<br />
confined to national frontiers; internal borders have always separated the full<br />
citizen—the person entitled to full rights—from the national with limited<br />
rights—a sort <strong>of</strong> “second-class citizen.” 9 Attention to internal distinctions<br />
clearly shows that schemas <strong>of</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> citizens are important.<br />
Much analysis <strong>of</strong> the identity dimension <strong>of</strong> citizenship proceeds from the<br />
relatively unproblematized assumption that citizenship practice generates a<br />
sense <strong>of</strong> community loyalty among those grateful to be included. Indeed, since<br />
the 19th century many have assumed that an extension <strong>of</strong> the political<br />
rights—and even more so the social rights—<strong>of</strong> citizenship would calm the<br />
revolutionary fervour <strong>of</strong> the working class. In this conceptualization we see that<br />
the arrow <strong>of</strong> causality points from rights to identity: having access to rights will<br />
create a feeling <strong>of</strong> belonging. 10<br />
Such a formulation fails to address the content <strong>of</strong> citizens’ identity. How does<br />
one recognize a citizen? What does a model citizen look like under each<br />
citizenship regime? What is the model relationship between citizens and the<br />
state? The silence around such questions undoubtedly results from three<br />
tendencies: to see citizenship as part <strong>of</strong> nation-building, and therefore to<br />
assume that a “national” identity results from the extension <strong>of</strong> rights; to take the<br />
“universalist” claims <strong>of</strong> citizenship discourse for reality, without realizing that<br />
“second-class” citizens may exist; and to have a “society-centric” theory <strong>of</strong> the<br />
state, which does not attribute an “interest <strong>of</strong> state” to particular representations<br />
<strong>of</strong> citizens’ identities. 11 Once we realize that citizenship involves a lot more<br />
than the boundary between nationals and non-nationals, that distinctions<br />
among citizens may exist, and that state institutions engage in the politics <strong>of</strong><br />
recognition, then we must begin to ask when the state will alter its<br />
representation <strong>of</strong> its citizens and when citizens’ claims-making will change.<br />
This paper proceeds from this perspective. It demonstrates that state<br />
institutions consciously as well as inadvertently engage in politics <strong>of</strong><br />
recognition which contribute to stabilizing or altering the citizenship regime.<br />
Some roots <strong>of</strong> these politics can be found within the state by assessing its<br />
discourses and practices related to citizens’ rights and access. As it defines<br />
114
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
rights or grants access, the state simultaneously engages in representing<br />
citizens to themselves.<br />
State institutions never have the power to establish these identities, however.<br />
Claims for recognition arise within civil society, <strong>of</strong>ten in the form <strong>of</strong> demands<br />
to change power relations. The state may choose to recognize some claims, and<br />
thereby to shore up some identities, but the identity remains the property <strong>of</strong> the<br />
claimant, a creation <strong>of</strong> collective action. 12<br />
In Canada, and in many other countries, the citizenship regime is in crisis, being<br />
restructured under pressure, as state and non-state actors seek to make sense <strong>of</strong><br />
the world conditions now confronting them, far removed from T.H. Marshall’s<br />
world <strong>of</strong> the completion <strong>of</strong> the tryptic <strong>of</strong> rights or from the world <strong>of</strong> social<br />
movement politics seeking differentiated citizenship. More than a decade <strong>of</strong><br />
politics driven by a neo-conservative agenda has resulted in new definitions <strong>of</strong><br />
marketized and individualized citizenship.<br />
Canada’s Postwar Citizenship Regime<br />
The <strong>Canadian</strong> postwar citizenship regime was an integral part <strong>of</strong> the postwar<br />
model <strong>of</strong> development. Like those <strong>of</strong> many other industrialized countries,<br />
Canada’s model was unusually permeable and open to the effects <strong>of</strong> the<br />
international economy, and less social-democratized than many European<br />
citizenship regimes (Jenson, 1989). Its form was owed to a shift in power<br />
relations between the federal and provincial governments. The fiscal crises<br />
which struck the provinces in the 1930s as well as the needs <strong>of</strong> wartime<br />
mobilization enabled the federal level to accumulate much more authority to<br />
direct the <strong>Canadian</strong> economy and society than it had previously. This<br />
governmenmt shaped Canada’s welfare state, extending the citizenship regime<br />
and incorporating new social rights in two waves: one at its beginnings in the<br />
1940s and the other in the 1960s. 13<br />
The legal concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship established in the 1946 Citizenship<br />
Act coincided with the first years <strong>of</strong> the postwar model <strong>of</strong> development. In all<br />
countries, the economic, political and social elements <strong>of</strong> this general model <strong>of</strong><br />
evelopment <strong>of</strong>ten began to emerge and certainly to solidify during World War<br />
II. As Charles Tilly (1992) has documented, state-building and war have<br />
historically gone hand-in-hand. Canada in the 1940s was no exception. The<br />
turbulence <strong>of</strong> wartime political and economic conditions gave impetus to the<br />
creation <strong>of</strong> a citizenship discourse which would inform the citizenship regime<br />
for the next four decades (Bourque and Duchastel, 1996, Chapter 1).<br />
Wartime fears about the loyalty <strong>of</strong> immigrants from combattant countries as<br />
well as the need to mobilize support for the war effort among those not in the<br />
armed forces laid the groundwork for the state institution that became the<br />
citizenship branch. This branch was housed in various departments, but came<br />
eventually to reside in Secretary <strong>of</strong> State. In 1944, the new citizenship branch<br />
was given a grab-bag <strong>of</strong> responsibilities, including the promotion <strong>of</strong> women’s<br />
participation in the war effort and “fitness programs, incorporating folk<br />
dancing.” The keystone, however, was a citizenship training program (Pal,<br />
1993: 75-76).<br />
115
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
In the postwar years, concerns about identity replaced concerns about loyalty.<br />
In introducing the Citizenship Act, the Secretary <strong>of</strong> State said that the bill would<br />
“provide an underlying community <strong>of</strong> status for all our people in this country<br />
that will bind them together as <strong>Canadian</strong>s” (Pal, 1993: 79). But the state did not<br />
have exclusive responsibility for fostering this identity or even organizing<br />
training for citizenship. It was to be shared, indeed, “contracted out.” As early<br />
as 1951, the branch was providing funds to voluntary organizations for<br />
programs in the area <strong>of</strong> citizenship (Pal, 1993: 85).<br />
Such sharing <strong>of</strong> responsibility was a logical outcome <strong>of</strong> the branch’s vision <strong>of</strong><br />
society. Pal’s (1993: 85-86) description is noteworthy:<br />
The [Citizenship] branch repeatedly made it clear that its concept <strong>of</strong><br />
citizenship hinged on a pan-<strong>Canadian</strong>ism that treasured some<br />
common “<strong>Canadian</strong>” history, had expunged any lingering prejudices,<br />
and was soberly aware <strong>of</strong> its responsibilities. ...thebranch in fact<br />
operated with a quaintly organic view <strong>of</strong> society: its mission was to<br />
help groups weld together individuals in a common community<br />
cognizant<strong>of</strong>itsdutytosupportresponsible,democraticgovernment.<br />
Thus, the principles underpinning the postwar citizenship regime were not<br />
simply liberal, although liberalism was clearly important. Accompanying<br />
Canada’s liberalism was a notion <strong>of</strong> collective responsibility, and the state was<br />
the expression and guarantor <strong>of</strong> this collectivity. 14 The citizen identity being<br />
nurtured was also clearly a national one, and accordingly matched that fostered<br />
by other institutions. Indeed, the societal vision <strong>of</strong> citizenship informed many<br />
more state institutions than simply one branch. A pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> party system<br />
was being created for the first time (Smith, 1988). The notion <strong>of</strong> a “national”<br />
culture, distinguished from that <strong>of</strong> the imperial centre(s) and defensible in its<br />
own right, was identified in the Massey Commission on the Arts in the early<br />
1950s. Economic institutions were creating a country-wide labour market and<br />
consumer society. And, the state was extending pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> social and<br />
economic rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship, several <strong>of</strong> which established a direct link<br />
between individuals and the federal government.<br />
That government entered into a relationship with each <strong>Canadian</strong> via several<br />
important new social programs. Cheques came from the federal government<br />
for family allowances and pensions. Unemployment Insurance was a countrywide<br />
program; the unemployed picked up their benefits at a federal <strong>of</strong>fice,<br />
whether they stayed home in the Maritimes or “went down the road” to<br />
Ontario. 15 Thus, for the first time, the vision <strong>of</strong> individual <strong>Canadian</strong>s linked by<br />
a set <strong>of</strong> national institutions made everyday sense. 16 Pan-<strong>Canadian</strong>ism also<br />
underpinned the equalization payments instituted in the 1950s as<br />
intergovernmental transfers. They set national standards for the provinces’ per<br />
capita incomes. 17 The notion grew that all <strong>Canadian</strong>s should have basic<br />
services, whether they lived in wealthy Toronto or poverty-stricken<br />
Newfoundland.<br />
The 1960s brought a second-wave <strong>of</strong> social program expansion. While<br />
Canada’s welfare state was never very generous and remained firmly in<br />
Esping-Andersen’s (1990) liberal category, the social benefits <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong><br />
citizens became even more distinct from those available in the USA in these<br />
116
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
years (Noël et al., 1993: pp. 185-86). Equity and social justice discourse<br />
influenced proposals for everything from party financing reform to health care<br />
(Maioni, 1994).<br />
A wide variety <strong>of</strong> institutions also shared a conceptualization <strong>of</strong> how citizens<br />
should gain access to the state. Individuals were not the primary actors in this<br />
vision; organizations were. In the 1940s and again in the 1960s, trade unions<br />
grew in size and gained collective bargaining rights to represent their members<br />
in dealings with bosses and the state. Parties changed shape, developing more<br />
elaborate internal machinery for selecting leaders and discussing policy.<br />
Indeed, the New Democratic Party was created in the 1960s partly to represent<br />
workers’ organizations as well as individuals, an undertaking its predecessor<br />
had never managed. The Québécois nationalist movement spawned parties and<br />
associations beginning in the early 1960s and was soon joined by organizations<br />
<strong>of</strong> the English-<strong>Canadian</strong> nationalist movement and then the Aboriginal<br />
nationalist movement, all designed to represent a political position to the state.<br />
Women in Quebec established a large umbrella federation in 1964 and both<br />
Anglophone and Francophone women founded the Voice <strong>of</strong> Women early in<br />
the 1960s to work for peace and oppose nuclear weapons.<br />
Concerns about “<strong>Canadian</strong>” identity flowered. In part, but only in part, this was<br />
because Québécois nationalists challenged the rest <strong>of</strong> Canada to decide what<br />
difference the presence <strong>of</strong> two language groups made to the country’s<br />
definition <strong>of</strong> self. Obviously, one effect <strong>of</strong> this challenge was to produce both<br />
the Official Languages Act (1969) and the multiculturalism policy (1971), and<br />
to breathe new life into the citizenship branch <strong>of</strong> Secretary <strong>of</strong> State, which<br />
gained responsibility for multicultural programs and for <strong>of</strong>ficial language<br />
minority groups.<br />
The challenge extended beyond language, however. The strategy <strong>of</strong> Quebec<br />
nationalists was to use the state to achieve their development project, in<br />
particular to build a sophisticated, secular and above all activist state with the<br />
capacity to catapult Québécois society into modernity. A central element <strong>of</strong> this<br />
construction was to withdraw responsibility for health and education from<br />
religious institutions and to develop an array <strong>of</strong> social programs with which<br />
French-speaking Québécois could identify. Thus, the completion <strong>of</strong> the<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> welfare state became both a response to the initiatives coming from<br />
Quebec and a reflection <strong>of</strong> strengthened social justice discourse overlaid with<br />
nation-building motives. Matters <strong>of</strong> equity were now also matters <strong>of</strong> national<br />
identity.<br />
A similar blending <strong>of</strong> themes <strong>of</strong> fairness and national identity characterized the<br />
English-<strong>Canadian</strong> nationalist movement which arose in the 1960s. Warnings<br />
came from both left and right that Canada risked losing its sovereignty and its<br />
identity because <strong>of</strong> the growing influence <strong>of</strong> the US in the country’s economic<br />
and cultural affairs (Grant, 1963; Taylor, 1970). Only a state actively pursuing<br />
an economic strategy to promote <strong>Canadian</strong> culture, <strong>Canadian</strong> ownership and<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong> distinctiveness, including its social programs could fend <strong>of</strong>f the<br />
threat to its cultural, economic and political autonomy.<br />
117
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Nationalist movements promoted these themes in civil society. But this<br />
discourse also permeated the state. One entry point was the various<br />
commissions studying Canada’s future. Here the Royal Commission on<br />
Bilingualism and Biculturalism was an important source <strong>of</strong> new ideas not only<br />
about relations between English and French, but also multiculturalism. The<br />
Watkins Report in the 1960s—a founding document for economic nationalists<br />
—was the direct heir <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission headed by Walter Gordon<br />
which, in the mid-1950s, had sounded the alarm about foreign investment. The<br />
revival <strong>of</strong> social democracy in the founding <strong>of</strong> the NDP in 1961 pushed the<br />
Liberals to think about their political flank. The progressive discourse <strong>of</strong> social<br />
justice and social engineering gained a foothold in the Liberal party.<br />
This discourse <strong>of</strong> social justice accompanied a boom in state support for<br />
intermediary organizations which might represent citizens to and in the state.<br />
Reform <strong>of</strong> the electoral system and party financing was prompted by the goal <strong>of</strong><br />
assuring equitable treatment <strong>of</strong> parties by the media and by the recognition that<br />
resources were not evenly distributed among social groups. Therefore, the<br />
electoral law <strong>of</strong> 1974 recognized political parties, then proceeded to regulate<br />
their access to the media, limit their campaign expenditures to prevent the<br />
richest parties and candidates from overwhelming the less well-endowed, and<br />
provide public funding for their campaigns (Paltiel, 1970). From 1969 to 1985,<br />
a succession <strong>of</strong> parliamentarians from both sides <strong>of</strong> the House <strong>of</strong> Commons<br />
presented private members bills designed to regulate the conduct <strong>of</strong><br />
pr<strong>of</strong>essional lobbyists, ultimately succeeding in the enactment <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Registration <strong>of</strong> Lobbyists Act in 1987 (Pross and Stewart, 1993: 112-14).<br />
The practice <strong>of</strong> supplying public funding to advocacy groups was common<br />
among federal government departments, providing recognition to groups<br />
which the state deemed worthy. Indeed, this may comprise one <strong>of</strong> the<br />
distinctive characteristics <strong>of</strong> Canada’s citizenship regime (Phillips, 1991: pp.<br />
196-97). The activities <strong>of</strong> the citizenship branch <strong>of</strong> the Secretary <strong>of</strong> State<br />
provide one example here. That agency amplified its activities in the early years<br />
<strong>of</strong> the 1970s. It extended its funding <strong>of</strong> associations which organized groups<br />
whose identity the state sought to affirm, particularly multicultural groups and<br />
<strong>of</strong>ficial language minorities. But the Department also provided support in the<br />
form <strong>of</strong> both core and project funding to groups representing the socially<br />
disadvantaged, with women and Aboriginal groups, as well as certain social<br />
action groups, being prime examples. As Bernard Ostry, a former Assistant<br />
Under Secretary in charge <strong>of</strong> citizenship said, the goal <strong>of</strong> the branch was to<br />
“develop and strengthen a sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship, chiefly through<br />
programs that would aid participation and assuage feelings <strong>of</strong> social injustice”<br />
(quoted in Pal, 1993: p. 109).<br />
To summarize the postwar citizenship regime, we could say the following.<br />
Democracy and the realization <strong>of</strong> the political rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship seemed to<br />
require both the regulation <strong>of</strong> and state support for basic institutions that were<br />
supposed to provide citizens with access to elites. Some efforts aimed to foster<br />
more equitable access to political power and the state via public funding for<br />
electoral and lobbying activity, and some limits were set on the political power<br />
<strong>of</strong> those most endowed with political resources. Achieving social justice and<br />
118
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
equity were legitimate goals, and therefore groups which made claims, and<br />
programs which responded to such claims, were in the political mainstream.<br />
The regime’s discourse linked the solidification <strong>of</strong> Canada’s national identity<br />
to the realization <strong>of</strong> equitable treatment <strong>of</strong> the disadvantaged. As a result, it<br />
gave advocacy groups, whose goal was the achievement <strong>of</strong> social justice for<br />
women, the disabled, Aboriginal peoples, and minorities <strong>of</strong> all sorts the<br />
discursive space to make their claims for “categorical equity” (Jenson, 1991).<br />
To say that the citizenship regime gave legitimacy to such claims and claimants<br />
does not mean that everyone had equal or even fair access. What it does mean is<br />
that claims for access and claims on behalf <strong>of</strong> groups to redress past wrongs<br />
could be heard. Recognition <strong>of</strong> the particular needs <strong>of</strong> disadvantaged groups for<br />
accesstothestateprovidedaprotectedinstitutionalspaceforclaims-making.<br />
The culmination <strong>of</strong> this regime was the Charter <strong>of</strong> Rights and Freedoms. On the<br />
one hand, the Charter endows citizens with pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> rights, thereby again<br />
affirming that provincial differences must be minimized. The federal<br />
government had tried to do as much in 1960 with a Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights, but had failed<br />
to overcome provincial opposition (Cairns, 1995: p. 189; 198). It took until<br />
1982 to negotiate the constitutionalization <strong>of</strong> pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> citizenship rights,<br />
and then only at the cost <strong>of</strong> excluding Quebec. At the same time, the Charter<br />
entrenched collective rights and their protection, recognizing both the<br />
multinational composition <strong>of</strong> Canada, and the responsibility <strong>of</strong> the state for<br />
overcoming past inequities. In all this, the Charter gave constitutional<br />
recognition to many <strong>of</strong> the same groups that had already been recognized via<br />
government funding in previous decades.<br />
The Charter was simultaneously the culmination <strong>of</strong> the postwar citizenship<br />
regime and the beginning <strong>of</strong> its destabilization. The constitutionalization <strong>of</strong> the<br />
regime was occurring just as the policy-makers were realizing that the postwar<br />
model <strong>of</strong> development had reached its limits and as the neo-conservative<br />
agenda began to take hold in government and business circles.<br />
One obvious mismatch was the state’s continued funding <strong>of</strong> equity-seekers<br />
despite its lost enthusiasm for attempts to foster social and economic equity. As<br />
the state started to cut back social programs, it encountered government-funded<br />
groups critical <strong>of</strong> its intentions to cut pensions, to renege on promised childcare<br />
programs and to reduce funding to women’s centres. When it moved from<br />
cutbacks to redefining the basic principles <strong>of</strong> social and economic citizenship<br />
via social policy reform, it also encountered opposition from advocacy groups<br />
<strong>of</strong> all sorts. 18<br />
By the 1990s, the state had begun to reconsider the wisdom <strong>of</strong> funding its<br />
critics. Nonetheless, the cutbacks in support for intermediary institutions<br />
cannot be explained only as a consequence <strong>of</strong> the state “coming to its senses,” or<br />
as an effort to rid itself <strong>of</strong> irritating criticisms. A much larger change was going<br />
on. The citizenship regime was being reconstructed. Citizen recognition would<br />
no longer occur through intermediary institutions. Individualization <strong>of</strong><br />
responsibility for life’s hardships, from which <strong>Canadian</strong>s had previously been<br />
protected by the economic and social rights <strong>of</strong> citizenship, was the new model.<br />
119
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
The discourse on access changed similarly, bringing marketization <strong>of</strong><br />
representation.<br />
Shifting the Relationship between State and Society<br />
How is “the redefinition <strong>of</strong> government itself,” promised by the Minister <strong>of</strong><br />
Finance in his 1995 Budget Speech, linked to shifts in the citizenship regime?<br />
An answer to that question begins with an appreciation <strong>of</strong> the economic crisis<br />
which struck all advanced industrial countries in the mid-1970s, and the<br />
specific responses it generated in Canada. As both a highly industrialized<br />
economy and resource producer, the economic effects <strong>of</strong> the oil shock and<br />
shifts in patterns <strong>of</strong> trade affected Canada differently than countries whose<br />
economies relied more exclusively on industrial production. In particular,<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> the seriousness <strong>of</strong> crisis and the mobilization <strong>of</strong> a political<br />
strategy in response was delayed until well into the 1980s (Noël et al., 1993).<br />
Moreover, because the political regulation <strong>of</strong> the postwar model had implicated<br />
the institutions <strong>of</strong> federalism more than partisan politics, the crisis was<br />
manifested politically as a constitutional crisis (Jenson, 1989a). Constitutional<br />
politics was the terrain where much actual debate on economic restructuring<br />
occurred. As a result, implementing change was <strong>of</strong>ten difficult because it<br />
involved moving eleven governments and because constitutional reform is a<br />
cumbersome route to economic and social policy change. Not surprisingly, to<br />
the extent that changes were made, those affecting individuals were <strong>of</strong>ten done<br />
“by stealth,” involving arcane and poorly understood technical changes to<br />
programs, such as de-indexing and clawbacks in the tax system (Gray, 1990;<br />
Rice and Prince, 1993). Those affecting federalism <strong>of</strong>ten involved changes<br />
imposed on the provinces by the federal government. Thus, concerns about the<br />
restructured economic future were expressed not only in economic terms;<br />
demands for democracy and openness also began to resonate. 19<br />
Demands to be heard in the matter <strong>of</strong> restructuring rose in a loud chorus from<br />
groups in civil society who interpreted the two crucial events <strong>of</strong> the 1980s—the<br />
Meech Lake Accord on the constitution and the Free Trade Agreement with the<br />
USA—as two signs that the state refused to listen to citizens. 20 One result <strong>of</strong><br />
such demands has been an increase in public “consultation” mechanisms as a<br />
standard part <strong>of</strong> the policy process and new forms <strong>of</strong> “partnerships” in program<br />
delivery (Phillips, 1991). While both <strong>of</strong> these might be seen as efforts to allow<br />
more room for democratic citizenship, it is important to place them in context.<br />
That is, they were accompanied by activities <strong>of</strong> the state, parties and other<br />
institutions which both delegitimated the representational role <strong>of</strong> organized<br />
interests and made it more difficult for them to engage in advocacy. 21<br />
The withdrawal <strong>of</strong> support has come in a number <strong>of</strong> ways as part <strong>of</strong> a reconfiguration<br />
<strong>of</strong> the relationship between state and society. First, many<br />
institutions have been reorganized to lower the visibility <strong>of</strong> certain categories <strong>of</strong><br />
citizens and to remove their means <strong>of</strong> advocacy from within the state. The most<br />
obvious <strong>of</strong> these attempts is the swift dismantling <strong>of</strong> the “Women’s State” in<br />
1995. 22 Secondly, the credibility <strong>of</strong> advocacy groups is under attack and their<br />
capacity to represent citizens to the state is being diminished. In the process, the<br />
120
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
nature <strong>of</strong> public consultation is shifting direction. Thirdly, modes <strong>of</strong> service<br />
delivery are being recast under a rubric <strong>of</strong> partnerships.<br />
Removing Advocates from Within the State<br />
Institutional change within the federal government has reduced the internal<br />
recognition <strong>of</strong> many group interests and has shed centres promoting potentially<br />
critical policy perspectives. One step was simply to dismantle the government<br />
department which had been most visibly involved in promoting citizenship<br />
through social development. In a major reorganization after Kim Campbell<br />
became Prime Minister in 1993, the Secretary <strong>of</strong> State Department closed down<br />
and its programs were either cancelled or placed in a variety <strong>of</strong> other<br />
departments. Such reassignments and the breaking <strong>of</strong> bureaucratic linkages<br />
would obviously have effects on civil servants’ capacity to continue to deliver<br />
programs according to the long-standing philosophical principles. In addition,<br />
political representation <strong>of</strong> many societal interests at the cabinet table was<br />
eliminated. In implementing the rhetoric <strong>of</strong> the campaign to reduce waste<br />
within government, the size <strong>of</strong> the cabinet was reduced to 25 under Campbell<br />
and 23 under the Liberal government <strong>of</strong> Jean Chrétien from a peak <strong>of</strong> 40 under<br />
Mulroney, which at various times had included representatives for youth,<br />
seniors and small business, among other interests (Swimmer et al., 1994: 192-<br />
93). 23<br />
Restructuring was also designed to eliminate parapublic bodies which had<br />
stood at the interface <strong>of</strong> civil society and the state, providing access for ideas via<br />
policy research. In 1992, both the Economic Council <strong>of</strong> Canada and the Science<br />
Council, bodies that had been created to advise the government by bringing the<br />
expertise <strong>of</strong> non-governmental sources “into the loop,” were eliminated. The<br />
rationale given was that private-sector research institutes were more<br />
appropriate sources <strong>of</strong> advice as well as recipients <strong>of</strong> state monies for specific<br />
programs. 24 In 1995, the <strong>Canadian</strong> Advisory Council on the Status <strong>of</strong> Women<br />
(CACSW) was also quietly wound down, apparently to avoid duplication with<br />
the activities <strong>of</strong> Status <strong>of</strong> Women Canada and thus improve services to the<br />
public. As we will see below, however, this justification is less convincing than<br />
it might appear.<br />
Women were one category <strong>of</strong> citizens that attained significant recognition in<br />
the postwar regime, and one whose state institutions <strong>of</strong> representation have<br />
been extensively altered in the 1990s. The Women’s State was created in the<br />
1970s in response to women’s claims that they were variously disadvantaged<br />
and that some <strong>of</strong> their citizenship rights were more formal than real. In different<br />
ways, the three institutions collectively called the Women’s State—the<br />
Women’s Program, CACSW and Status <strong>of</strong> Women—became advocates for<br />
women within the state and were therefore important routes to representation<br />
and for making citizenship claims.<br />
In 1974, the Women’s Program was created as a separate branch within the<br />
Department <strong>of</strong> Secretary <strong>of</strong> State. Its goal was to foster the capacity for political<br />
action and organization among women by providing core and project funding<br />
to support women’s advocacy groups. 25 As the Secretary <strong>of</strong> State’s own<br />
evaluation <strong>of</strong> the Program (1985, p. 19) said, “The philosophy behind the<br />
121
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Women’s Program is not one <strong>of</strong> compensation to individuals. Rather it<br />
assumed that weak and disadvantaged segments <strong>of</strong> a population can only begin<br />
to overcome their position through organizing and through collective action.”<br />
From the beginning, the feminists who ran the Program defined their job as<br />
being advocates for women within the state and accountable to the women’s<br />
movement. They developed close ties with women’s groups and sought ways to<br />
use state resources to support the development <strong>of</strong> the movement (Findlay,<br />
1987: pp. 39-40).<br />
The second major state institution representing women, the CACSW, was<br />
created in 1973 as an independent advisory council reporting to the Minister<br />
Responsible for the Status <strong>of</strong> Women, and mandated to conduct research and<br />
advise government on matters pertaining to women. Its structure consisted <strong>of</strong> a<br />
politically appointed board and a full-time pr<strong>of</strong>essional staff. The Council’s<br />
greatest strength was its independent research capacity, although it operated on<br />
a shoe-string budget (Burt, 1995: p. 375). From the early 1980s, however, the<br />
Council was <strong>of</strong>ten seen as little more than an advocate for the women’s<br />
movement by those within the state, especially among the movement’s<br />
detractors or those who considered the CACSW a thorn in their side. Nor did it<br />
have the full support <strong>of</strong> the movement, which saw the Council engaged in selfcensorship,<br />
reluctant to develop close ties with national women’s groups and<br />
extremely limited in its access to political decision-makers (Findlay, 1988: 90;<br />
Burt, 1995). 26<br />
The third part <strong>of</strong> the Women’s State was the tiny (its 1994-95 budget was only<br />
$4.7 million) transversal department assigned to coordinate and provide liaison<br />
on women’s issues and to develop and monitor policy initiatives. Status <strong>of</strong><br />
Women Canada reports to the Minister Responsible for the Status <strong>of</strong> Women,<br />
who has usually also headed a major line department. Of the three parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />
Women’s State, Status <strong>of</strong> Women came under the most direct control <strong>of</strong> a<br />
Minister. Through the 1980s, observers recount that it increasingly became the<br />
instrument <strong>of</strong> the Minister, who closely followed the party’s agenda. 27 In<br />
addition, the Department’s influence has been limited by its inability to<br />
perform the research required to develop policy initiatives. Nor is there any<br />
mechanism to make the line departments accountable to Status for their<br />
programs. It can only exercise vigilance and exert moral suasion.<br />
The Women’s State was dismantled with little publicity in two quick actions in<br />
1995. First, the Budget amalgamated the Women’s Program (which since 1993<br />
had resided in the Human Resources Development Department) with Status <strong>of</strong><br />
Women. Two weeks later, CACSW was eliminated completely, reducing from<br />
three to one the institutionalized points <strong>of</strong> access for women to the federal<br />
government. The government explained these decisions in a variety <strong>of</strong> ways. A<br />
primary justification from the Department <strong>of</strong> Finance concerned an efficiency<br />
argument: “the ‘single window’ approach will result in a streamlining <strong>of</strong><br />
resources and costs, the elimination <strong>of</strong> duplication, and an improvement <strong>of</strong><br />
service to the public.” 28 This logic is less convincing than it might appear<br />
because there was, in fact, very little duplication <strong>of</strong> functions, other than the fact<br />
that all three agencies had “women” in their title .29 Not much money was going<br />
122
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
to be saved by all this reorganization, nor in the larger scheme <strong>of</strong> things did they<br />
spend much to begin with.<br />
Sheila Finestone, the Secretary <strong>of</strong> State for the Status <strong>of</strong> Women, provided a<br />
different—and seemingly contrary—justification. “Our goal is to ensure that<br />
women become full and equal partners in society and this initiative will focus<br />
our efforts more effectively.” 30 The amalgamation was intended to “provide<br />
the government with a critical mass <strong>of</strong> expertise on women’s issues, enhance its<br />
capacity to identify and target key policy issues for actions, and increase the<br />
focus and effectiveness <strong>of</strong> the government’s effort to promote women’s<br />
equality in collaboration with the voluntary and other sectors <strong>of</strong> society.” 31<br />
These statements give no clear indication, however, <strong>of</strong> how women are to<br />
become equal partners and or the envisaged relationship between women and<br />
the state. While such statements might be interpreted to mean that the Minister<br />
is still interested in hearing from women, initial signs point to another process.<br />
The new structure is designed to allow women to hear from the state.<br />
The Minister was reported to be particularly keen on acquiring control over two<br />
structures <strong>of</strong> the Women’s State. The first is the regional <strong>of</strong>fices which the<br />
Women’s Program had developed. These were used by the Program as an “ear<br />
to the ground,” moving information upward as well as providing support and<br />
funds directly to communities. It appears that Status <strong>of</strong> Women intends to use<br />
the <strong>of</strong>fices as a way <strong>of</strong> “informing” citizens about the activities <strong>of</strong> the<br />
department and its Minister. 32 Secondly, Status <strong>of</strong> Women was interested in<br />
absorbing the research budget <strong>of</strong> CACSW but with little intention <strong>of</strong> supporting<br />
independent research as CACSW did. The in-house component is minuscule<br />
and will be used primarily for policy-oriented research into government<br />
priorities, as directed by the Minister. Some “independent” research, under $1<br />
million worth, will be contracted out. 33 Thus the surviving institution <strong>of</strong> the<br />
former Women’s State can be most easily controlled by its “political masters”<br />
with less capacity to act as an internal advocate for women. The signal is clear.<br />
Groups should be self-supporting and voluntary. The state experiment to<br />
facilitate and even promote the collective voice <strong>of</strong> women and its<br />
representation within the state is gone.<br />
Reducing Interest Group Capacity and Credibility<br />
A related manifestation <strong>of</strong> the shift in the citizenship regime has been a direct<br />
attack on the credibility and organizational base <strong>of</strong> groups and their role in<br />
policy consultation. A first step involved reducing direct funding to public<br />
interest groups. The Tory government began to cut grants and contributions to<br />
groups selectively in 1986-87. Often, there was a sort <strong>of</strong> “testing <strong>of</strong> the waters”<br />
to see what reactions would be. The funding practices <strong>of</strong> the Women’s Program<br />
was only one target. 34 Moreover, the cuts were sensitive to political opposition.<br />
For example, the 1990 Budget made cuts to three women’s magazines, five<br />
feminist groups (a 20 percent reduction) and 80 women’s centres. The National<br />
Action Committee on the Status <strong>of</strong> Women (NAC) was spared at first, however.<br />
The government feared an uproar if it were touched and widespread<br />
demonstrations did succeed in restoring some funding to the women’s shelters.<br />
Nonetheless, the pressure for reductions was relentless on both the Secretary <strong>of</strong><br />
123
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
State and the other departments which fund groups. Each year, further cuts<br />
were announced. Nor did a change in government alter the situation. The<br />
Liberals’ first budget in 1994 made a five percent cut and the 1995 budget<br />
imposed further and more selective cuts, specifically targeting advocacy<br />
groups. 35 Finance Minister Martin also promised a major review <strong>of</strong> interest<br />
group funding with a view to reducing overall spending levels and promoting<br />
reliance on other sources. 36<br />
The high-level taskforce appointed by the Liberal government to develop this<br />
new funding strategy identified a number <strong>of</strong> criteria clearly intended to stress<br />
the role <strong>of</strong> groups as service providers, rather than as advocates. One criterion is<br />
to test funding against the organization’s benefit to the public. Another is its<br />
ability to access other funds. Groups which spend more time on service delivery<br />
and less on advocacy are much preferred. Finally, the “fit” between the groups’<br />
activities and government priorities is important. Overall, as the task force<br />
realized, these criteria constituted a test <strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> particular<br />
programs, not just groups, to the departments. For those that need groups to<br />
deliver their programs and support their policies, they could fund them. The<br />
result <strong>of</strong> using these criteria, rather than ones <strong>of</strong> justice or equity in access,<br />
releases the state from many obligations. But in other cases, it will take a strong<br />
hand in setting direction and policy, using groups as its clients and occasional<br />
allies.<br />
Such reductions in funding, then, are not merely a consequence <strong>of</strong> overall costcutting,<br />
but the symptom <strong>of</strong> a full-scale assault on the legitimacy and credibility<br />
<strong>of</strong> advocacy groups. The Conservatives started the drive which accelerated<br />
under the Liberals. The initiative is popular among politicians in both the<br />
government party and the opposition Reform party who argue that the only<br />
legitimate representational form is a direct link between individuals and their<br />
MPs. In addition to calling for more use <strong>of</strong> referenda and recall, they have taken<br />
on advocacy groups, which they prefer to call “special interests.” The debate is<br />
focussed squarely on public interest groups, rather than “lobbyists” in general<br />
or economic associations. 37 According to the discourse <strong>of</strong> right wing populism,<br />
organized public interest groups are not legitimate because they are not “real<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s.” The first line <strong>of</strong> attack concerns the groups’ sources <strong>of</strong> funding.<br />
The second concerns representation itself and the determination <strong>of</strong> legitimacy:<br />
Have they proven themselves worthy <strong>of</strong> the claim that they represent someone?<br />
A common statement is that “group X doesn’t represent me/all women/all<br />
<strong>Canadian</strong>s.” Thus, even if a group is self-supporting, it may still be branded a<br />
“special interest.” Failure to represent only some, and not everyone, makes a<br />
group “special” and therefore lacking legitimacy. 38<br />
One <strong>of</strong> the most vocal critics is John Bryden, a backbench Liberal MP from<br />
Hamilton-Wentworth. His crusade derives from his personal experience as a<br />
new MP when he reports to have been shocked to learn that groups had more<br />
power than parliamentarians. “When I got up here, I was amazed to find that<br />
senior politicians deferred to them so much....Asabackbench MP, I was in<br />
severe competition to be heard.” 39 Bryden produced his own report on interest<br />
group funding and presented it to the House <strong>of</strong> Commons Finance Committee<br />
in November 1994. He looked only at public groups that took money from<br />
124
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
government, but made no mention <strong>of</strong> economic associations or pr<strong>of</strong>essional<br />
lobbyists. 40 He paid particular attention to salaries <strong>of</strong> staff and use <strong>of</strong> charitable<br />
status under the tax system and called for a parliamentary committee to<br />
investigate the finances, tax breaks and funding <strong>of</strong> groups. Thus, he wrote that<br />
the practice <strong>of</strong> using general tax revenues to support advocacy groups:<br />
has created a government-dependent industry where misrepresentation<br />
is a common business practice, where semantics and twisted<br />
definitions enable the spirit <strong>of</strong> laws to be ignored, where individuals<br />
award themselves huge salaries, hire pr<strong>of</strong>essional lobbyists to get<br />
more money, and attack critics with name-calling and noisy<br />
demonstrations. 41<br />
The problem for Bryden is not simply the misuse <strong>of</strong> funds, however. The<br />
fundamental issue is that the groups do not represent the truth, either. As he<br />
said,<br />
Indeed, as paid consultants to government special interest advocacy<br />
groups are truly an Alice-in-Wonderland phenomenon. They are a<br />
kind <strong>of</strong> non-governmental ministry <strong>of</strong> non-experts. They are a world<br />
where non-scientists do scientific research, where non-health care<br />
pr<strong>of</strong>essionals give expert opinions on health, where non-sociologists<br />
do opinion-polling and questionnaires. There are even governmentfunded<br />
information centres to collect and distribute the resulting nonexpert<br />
publications and issue non-expert press releases (Bryden,<br />
1994, p. 13).<br />
The language <strong>of</strong> “special interests” has resonated far beyond Bryden and the<br />
Reform MPs. Indeed, the conflict between groups and elected MPs seems to be<br />
boiling down to an “us or them” mentality. One reason for this divide stems<br />
from a decline in recent decades in the representational capacity <strong>of</strong> Canada’s<br />
brokerage parties. The public’s distrust <strong>of</strong> politicians is another manifestation.<br />
As part <strong>of</strong> the dissatisfaction, many people turned to interest groups to<br />
campaign around the great issues <strong>of</strong> the day. Two defining moments were the<br />
campaigns for the 1988 election and the 1992 constitutional debates. In both<br />
cases, opposition to the government’s proposals was mobilized by groups; the<br />
parties were effectively sidelined from framing the debate (Clarke, Jenson,<br />
LeDuc and Pammett, 1996: Chapter 1). In the 1988 election, the Pro-Canada<br />
Network faced <strong>of</strong>f against the Business Council on National Issues, and a huge<br />
“parallel campaign” emerged (Hiebert, 1991). In the referendum campaign on<br />
the Charlottetown Accord in 1992, the document negotiated by the federal<br />
government, the ten provinces, two territories and four Aboriginal associations<br />
met defeat after a campaign in which advocacy groups, and especially NAC,<br />
were very visible (Pal and Seidle, 1993). The referendum defeat was widely<br />
interpreted as a defeat <strong>of</strong> “elites.”<br />
The line now seems to be that parties and Parliament must monopolize<br />
representation, sharing legitimacy only with individual voters. Thus, the 1992<br />
Report <strong>of</strong> the Royal Commission on Electoral Reform and Party Financing<br />
(RCERPF), whose major goal was to strengthen and shore up the<br />
representational capacity <strong>of</strong> political parties, also adopted the language <strong>of</strong><br />
special interests. The RCERPF was a strong advocate <strong>of</strong> the legitimacy <strong>of</strong><br />
public funding for political parties and state support for ensuring what the<br />
125
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
Report called fair and equitable representation. Despite pressure from some<br />
members <strong>of</strong> the government party to eliminate the current system <strong>of</strong><br />
expenditure limits, and despite the anti-public funding discourse <strong>of</strong> the Reform<br />
and other right-wing parties, the Report <strong>of</strong> the Commission lauded the current<br />
philosophy and even recommended more public funding to induce an increase<br />
in the number <strong>of</strong> women in the House. 42 Nonetheless, it insisted on maintaining<br />
a distinction between the “good” representation provided by strong parties, and<br />
the representation <strong>of</strong> “special interests” by advocacy groups (Dobrowolsky and<br />
Jenson, 1993).<br />
The backlash against public interest groups has also been reflected in subtle<br />
changes to the format <strong>of</strong> public consultations organized by federal<br />
departments, parliamentary committees and independent commissions. This<br />
shift began in 1990 with the Citizens’ Forum on Canada’s Future which used<br />
the opportunity <strong>of</strong> a national consultation exercise to hear individuals as<br />
individuals, not as members <strong>of</strong> interest groups and which judged its success by<br />
the number <strong>of</strong> participants involved, no matter how minimally these<br />
individuals participated: a phone call to a 1-800 number was sufficient to be<br />
counted. This approach has become the norm <strong>of</strong> national consultations. For<br />
example, in 1992 the <strong>Canadian</strong> Panel on Violence against Women used a<br />
substantial part <strong>of</strong> its $10 million budget to travel to 139 communities across the<br />
country. It heard from 4,000 individuals who were encouraged to recall their<br />
personal experiences with violence. At the same time, it severely limited<br />
opportunities for representatives <strong>of</strong> groups from the shelter and women’s<br />
movements to engage in discussions <strong>of</strong> policy alternatives (Phillips, 1995).<br />
Similarly, the Liberal government’s major consultation on the social security<br />
review took great pains to ensure that representation by interest groups was<br />
counter-balanced by participation by individuals. While the parliamentary<br />
standing committee that led the consultation heard from a wide variety <strong>of</strong><br />
interest groups, the Department <strong>of</strong> Human Resources Development ran a series<br />
<strong>of</strong> supplementary exercises, including focus groups, 1-800 phone lines, public<br />
opinion surveys and policy “workbooks” that were designed to provide input<br />
from individual citizens. For Reform party members <strong>of</strong> the parliamentary<br />
committee, however, special interests still dominated the process. In their<br />
dissent from the Committee’s 1995 report, the Reform members complained<br />
about the consultation process and objected to any public funding <strong>of</strong><br />
intervenors (Standing Committee Report, 1995, p. 295):<br />
Reform MPs believe that a way must be found for parliamentarians to<br />
hear the opinions <strong>of</strong> real <strong>Canadian</strong>s. Reformers believe that many <strong>of</strong><br />
the problems experienced by the Standing Committee during the<br />
public hearings could be avoided. The Liberal-dominated committee<br />
gave 159 special interest groups $4 million to appear before the<br />
committee and called it “consultation.” We call it “tales from the<br />
trough.”<br />
The Department <strong>of</strong> Finance has also changed how it conducts its pre-budget<br />
consultations. From consultations on a sector by sector basis it has moved to<br />
more broadly based meetings that involve not only group representatives, but<br />
representative citizens. 43 The trend is to bring together “multi-stakeholder”<br />
126
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
sessions <strong>of</strong> divergent, <strong>of</strong>ten opposing groups, so that they can educate each<br />
other. The implication is that the Minister may no longer hear a strong, coordinated<br />
voice from any particular sector in these consultations. While<br />
consultations with individuals might provide useful additional points <strong>of</strong> access<br />
for citizens, the government’s motive is less one <strong>of</strong> civic education or<br />
participatory democracy than an attempt to countervail the groups, especially<br />
those most likely to oppose the retrenchment <strong>of</strong> the welfare state.<br />
Redefining Government through Partnerships<br />
The language <strong>of</strong> “partnership” became the buzzword for a new form <strong>of</strong><br />
governance in the early 1990s under the Conservatives; it has been maintained<br />
under the Liberals. Indeed, one <strong>of</strong> the six tests used under the 1994 Program<br />
Review <strong>of</strong> the federal government’s future roles and responsibilities is the<br />
scope for public-private partnership as an alternative for the delivery <strong>of</strong><br />
programs or services. 44 The intent is to encourage a wide array <strong>of</strong> partnering<br />
arrangements with both the private and third sectors. While reducing costs is an<br />
important goal <strong>of</strong> public-private partnerships in the current environment <strong>of</strong><br />
economic restraint, it is not the only one. The claim is also made that<br />
partnerships have the potential to improve the quality <strong>of</strong> service delivery and<br />
program design because the partnering organizations <strong>of</strong>ten have a better<br />
awareness <strong>of</strong> the needs <strong>of</strong> their regular clients and more flexibility in<br />
responding to these needs. 45 In addition, partnerships permit differences in the<br />
types <strong>of</strong> services provided and facilitate local control, in keeping with the<br />
retreat from national standards.<br />
Despite the potential <strong>of</strong> partnerships, the current approach in Canada detracts<br />
from, rather than enhances, the maintenance <strong>of</strong> a vibrant third sector. First, true<br />
partnerships involve power-sharing. Initial indications <strong>of</strong> experimentation<br />
with partnerships by <strong>Canadian</strong> governments, however, suggest that they have<br />
not invested whole-heartedly in such relationships and have been unwilling to<br />
share power with the partners, preferring instead to maintain a traditional topdown<br />
approach. Many <strong>of</strong> the so-called partnerships are, in fact, merely<br />
contracts in which the state, as the contracting party, sets all the rules.<br />
Regardless <strong>of</strong> the constraints <strong>of</strong> these contracts, many third sector<br />
organizations enter into them either because they need the project money to<br />
replace the lost core funding or because the state has withdrawn from direct<br />
provision<strong>of</strong>theservicesandtheirconstituencieswillnotbeservedotherwise.<br />
Secondly, partnerships may alter the nature <strong>of</strong> third sector partners, especially<br />
social movements. The originality <strong>of</strong> the new social movements established<br />
since the late 1960s is that they are not tied to specific places, but represent<br />
broader, <strong>of</strong>ten quite diverse, social communities and are dynamic, fluid<br />
networks, rather than conventional, institutionalized organizations. The<br />
sometimes elaborate rules <strong>of</strong> contract partnerships, however, may force them to<br />
become more place bound (by delivering services to specific geographic<br />
communities) and may transform the informality <strong>of</strong> movements into<br />
formalized, pr<strong>of</strong>essionalised organizations (Mendell, 1994: 79).<br />
Thirdly, the current approach is creating a hierarchy <strong>of</strong> groups, with those<br />
focussed exclusively on service delivery at the top, and those focussed on<br />
127
IJCS / RIÉC<br />
advocacy deemed irrelevant. For the partnering organization, opportunities for<br />
“civic engagement” (Putnam, 1995: 66) may be diminished because <strong>of</strong> the<br />
difficulty in advocating for policy changes within a partnership arrangement,<br />
especially if the state holds the power cords. From the outside, it is more<br />
difficult to lobby multiple partnerships than a single government body.<br />
In the face <strong>of</strong> economic restraint, an even more difficult problem arises.<br />
Frequently, once a partnership arrangement has been established and a<br />
clientele has become dependent upon it, the state’s contribution to the contract<br />
is cut significantly. Contrary to the popular myth that such cuts enliven a sense<br />
<strong>of</strong> voluntarism to fill the gap left by state funding, experience from the United<br />
States indicates that the common response by third-sector partners is not a<br />
growth in voluntary activity, but a rise in commercialism. Voluntary<br />
organizations turn to user fees and other sources <strong>of</strong> market income, thereby<br />
becoming more business-like and more integrated into the private market<br />
economy. In addition, for-pr<strong>of</strong>it firms begin to seek out this niche, <strong>of</strong>ten<br />
gradually crowding out the voluntary organizations (Salamon, 1995: 240).<br />
So far, <strong>Canadian</strong> governments have assumed that voluntary organizations not<br />
only have the infrastructure, but would welcome participation in governmentinitiated<br />
partnerships. In reality, the bulk <strong>of</strong> voluntary organizations in Canada<br />
have limited budgets and staff: 50 percent have annual revenues <strong>of</strong> less than<br />
$50,000 and 60 percent employ either no or only one full-time person. 46 And,<br />
given the sustained attacks on their credibility, many organizations which do<br />
have the infrastructure toenter into such partnerships may be unwilling todo so,<br />
at least on the terms demanded by the state.<br />
Finally, the principles that can be substantiated under arrangements <strong>of</strong> service<br />
delivery by public-private partnerships are quite different from those <strong>of</strong> direct<br />
state delivery. This can have both positive and negative consequences. While<br />
governments are expected to provide standardized services on an equitable<br />
basis across wide geographic regions, and are best at it, most voluntary<br />
organizations are particularistic, providing services tailored to their target<br />
constituencies, and are unevenly distributed geographically. 47 Whereas<br />
governments usually stress access to all qualified beneficiaries, voluntary<br />
organizations usually operate on a first-come, first-served basis. Thus, even if<br />
partnerships do prove to be an effective means <strong>of</strong> program delivery, they are<br />
further accelerating the abandonment <strong>of</strong> the pan-<strong>Canadian</strong>ism <strong>of</strong> national<br />
standards and fairness that was a feature <strong>of</strong> the postwar citizenship regime.<br />
One clear message from all this is that the state, within its neo-conservative<br />
thrust to reconfigure state-society relations, has abandoned what Pal labelled<br />
the “quaintly organic view <strong>of</strong> society” in which the state’s mission was to help<br />
groups weld together individuals. That responsibility for fostering solidarity<br />
and guaranteeing the collective access <strong>of</strong> the disadvantaged has been<br />
amputated from the citizenship regime. Individuals are charged with<br />
representing themselves, through referenda and petitions and during public<br />
consultation, in addition to elections. Any expression <strong>of</strong> collective interests<br />
must be the product <strong>of</strong> a hardy competitive capacity to organize and generate<br />
resources in the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas. Both the government and populist social<br />
128
Regime Shift: New Citizenship Practices in Canada<br />
forces advance this position, appropriating the discourse <strong>of</strong> marketization and<br />
cost- effectiveness from the purveyors <strong>of</strong> neo-conservative ideas.<br />
Does this mean, then, the end <strong>of</strong> a “thick” civil society and a new era <strong>of</strong><br />
atomized individualism? Is there no place for organized interests in the<br />
citizenship-regime-in-becoming? The answer to this question is “No.” They do<br />
have a place, albeit different than the one they occupied in the postwar regime.<br />
In the era <strong>of</strong> less interventionary states, organized groups are being pressed into<br />
service to represent the state in civil society. Advocates may be out but service<br />
providers are in.<br />
Redesigning the Citizenship Regime: Contradictory Tendencies?<br />
The final results are not in and the period <strong>of</strong> reconfiguration has not brought a<br />
smooth transition. Rather, it is beset by a number <strong>of</strong> basic contradictions. The<br />
shrinking presence <strong>of</strong> the state means that many <strong>of</strong> the services it once provided<br />
directly will devolve to the voluntary sector. And, with the recent changes in<br />
federal-provincial financing, these services are being <strong>of</strong>f-loaded to the<br />
provinces. The era <strong>of</strong> national standards and pan-<strong>Canadian</strong> services is waning,<br />
as the federal government reduces its participation in the programs and<br />
institutions which underpinned the postwar model <strong>of</strong> development. Provincial<br />
governments, in their own pursuit <strong>of</strong> deficit reduction, are further <strong>of</strong>f-loading<br />
responsibility for many <strong>of</strong> these services to local communities.<br />
The devolution <strong>of</strong> service delivery means that the state will need the third se