03.07.2013 Views

Eberhard Karls Universität Tübingen

Eberhard Karls Universität Tübingen

Eberhard Karls Universität Tübingen

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

with regard to it” it seems to be clear that he thinks of judgment-sensitive attitudes in the first place.<br />

One may then schematize his account as follows:<br />

X is valuable. ↔ X has other natural (or evaluative) properties that provide reasons (of the<br />

relevant kind) for certain judgment-sensitive attitudes.<br />

Scanlon thus offers an intra-normative reduction: the evaluative is analysed in terms of the deontic.<br />

And he can be understood as not only offering a conceptual analysis but as making a metaphysical<br />

claim as well.<br />

It is not the aim of this essay to examine if this intra-normative reduction is especially helpful or<br />

reasonable, but Scanlon’s proposal shall be made as strong as possible and therefore it is necessary to<br />

defend it against the most common objection, the Wrong Kind of Reasons Problem (WKR).<br />

2. The Wrong Kind of Reasons Problem (WKR)<br />

The main point of the WKR is that there may be reasons for a certain (judgment-sensitive) attitude 5<br />

towards an object X which would not be called valuable. 6 The paradigmatic example of the debate is<br />

the evil demon which will inflict a severe pain on me unless I prefer this saucer of mud. 7 Intuitively, a<br />

saucer of mud is not preferable or valuable but the example suggests that I do have a reason to prefer<br />

it, namely the threat of the evil demon. However, this reason seems to be of the wrong kind.<br />

Scanlon seems to have anticipated this objection by sometimes using the careful formulation<br />

“providing reasons of the relevant kind”, but he never explains what “reasons of the relevant kind” are<br />

and so he offers no real solution to the problem.<br />

There have been several proposals how to distinguish between the right kind of reasons and the wrong<br />

kind of reasons, but none of them has been fully convincing. By modifying the example “the evil<br />

demon always strikes back.”<br />

3. A “Brentano style” Solution to the WKR 8<br />

Danielsson and Olson introduce the distinction between two kinds of epistemic reasons for an attitude<br />

(whether cognitive or conative): there are reasons which justify having the attitude, so called holdingreasons<br />

and there are reasons which justify the correctness of the attitude, so called content-reasons. 9<br />

5<br />

The whole debate focuses on attitudes or pro-attitudes and thereby ignores Scanlons specific concept of<br />

judgment-sensitive attitudes.<br />

6<br />

Justin D’Arms and Daniel Jacobson call it the Conflation Problem. See Justin D’Arms/Daniel Jacobson:<br />

Sentiment and Value; The Moralistic Fallacy; Sensibility Theory and Projectivism.<br />

7<br />

It was introduced by Roger Crisp and it has been modified several times to show that the proposed solutions all<br />

fail.<br />

8<br />

The following remarks refer to Danielsson/Olson: Brentano and the Buck-Passers.<br />

9<br />

The term “content-reason” and especially the analogy between correctness and truth may suggest that we are<br />

dealing with ontological reasons, which means facts that render the representational content of a belief or attitude<br />

true or correct (truth-makers or “correctness-makers”). However, this is not how Danielsson and Olson<br />

2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!