21.09.2013 Views

Syntactic Structures

Syntactic Structures

Syntactic Structures

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SYNTACTIC STRUCTURES<br />

The fact that correspondences between formal and semantic<br />

features exist, however, cannot be ignored. These correspondences<br />

should be studied in some more general theory of language that will<br />

include a theory of linguistic form and a theory of the use of<br />

language as subparts. In § 8 we found that there are, apparently,<br />

fairly general types of relations between these two domains that<br />

deserve more intensive study. Having determined the syntactic<br />

structure of the language, we can study the way in which this<br />

syntactic structure is put to use in the actual functioning of language.<br />

An investigation of the semantic function of level structure,<br />

as suggested briefly in § 8, might be a reasonable step towards a<br />

theory of the interconnections between syntax and semantics. In<br />

fact, we pointed out in § 8 that the correlations between the form<br />

and use of language can even provide certain rough criteria of<br />

adequacy for a linguistic theory and the grammars to which it leads.<br />

We can judge formal theories in terms of their ability to explain and<br />

clarify a variety of facts about the way in which sentences are used<br />

and understood. In other words, we should like the syntactic<br />

framework of the language that is isolated and exhibited by the<br />

grammar to be able to support semantic description, and we shall<br />

naturally rate more highly a theory of formal structure that leads<br />

to grammars that meet this requirement more fully.<br />

Phrase structure and transformational structure appear to provide<br />

the major syntactic devices available in language for organization<br />

and expression of content. The grammar of a given language must<br />

show how these abstract structures are actually realized in the case<br />

of the language in question, while linguistic theory must seek to<br />

clarify these foundations for grammar and the methods for<br />

evaluating and choosing between proposed grammars.<br />

It is important to recognize that by introducing such considerations<br />

as those of § 8 into the metatheory that deals with grammar<br />

and semantics and their points of connection, we have not altered<br />

the purely formal character of the theory of grammatical structure<br />

itself. In §§ 3-7 we outlined the development of some fundamental<br />

linguistic concepts in purely formal terms. We considered the<br />

problem of syntactic research to be that of constructing a device<br />

SYNTAX AND SEMANTICS<br />

for producing a given set of grammatical sentences and of studying<br />

the properties of grammars that do this effectively. Such semantic<br />

notions as reference, significance, and synonymity played no role in<br />

the discussion. The outlined theory, of course, had serious gaps in<br />

it — in particular, the assumption that the set of grammatical<br />

sentences is given in advance is clearly too strong, and the notion of<br />

"simplicity" to which appeal was made explicitly or tacitly was left<br />

unanalyzed. However, neither these nor other gaps in this development<br />

of grammatical theory can be filled in or narrowed, to my<br />

knowledge. by constructing this theory on a partially semantic<br />

basis.<br />

In §§ 3-7, then, we were studying language as an instrument or a<br />

tool, attempting to describe its structure with no explicit reference<br />

to the way in which this instrument is put to use. The motivation<br />

for this self-imposed formality requirement for grammars is quite<br />

simple — there seems to be po other basis that will yield a rigorous.<br />

effective, and 'revealing' theory of linguistic structure. The requirement<br />

that this theory shall be a completely formal discipline is<br />

perfectly compatible with the desire to formulate it in such a way as<br />

to have suggestive and significant interconnections with a parallel<br />

semantic theory. What we have pointed out in § 8 is that this formal<br />

study of the structure of language as an instrument may be expected<br />

to provide insight into the actual use of language, i.e., into the<br />

process of understanding sentences.<br />

9.4 To understand a sentence we must know much more than the<br />

analysis of this sentence on each linguistic level. We must also<br />

know the reference and meaning" of the morphemes or words of<br />

10 Goodman has argued—to my mind, quite convincingly—that the notion<br />

of meaning of words can at least in part be reduced to that of reference of<br />

expressions containing these words. See N. Goodman, "On likeness of meaning,"<br />

Analysis, vol. 10, no. 1 (1949); idem, "On some differences about meaning,"<br />

Analysis, vol. 13, no. 4 (1953). Goodman's approach amounts to reformulating<br />

a part of the theory of meaning in the much clearer terms of the theory of<br />

reference, just as much of our discussion can be understood as suggesting a<br />

reformulation of parts of the theory of meaning that deal with so-called "structural<br />

meaning" in terms of the completely nonsemantic theory of grammatical<br />

structure. Part of the difficulty with the theory of meaning is that "meaning"

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!