24.10.2012 Views

The Chimney Sweeper

The Chimney Sweeper

The Chimney Sweeper

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Transform your PDFs into Flipbooks and boost your revenue!

Leverage SEO-optimized Flipbooks, powerful backlinks, and multimedia content to professionally showcase your products and significantly increase your reach.

Comparative Literature 250<br />

English 242 G<br />

Literature & Culture<br />

Professor Leroy Searle<br />

University of Washington<br />

Autumn, 2012


Comparative Literature 250 & English 242G<br />

Course Reader<br />

TABLE OF CONTENTS:<br />

POEMS<br />

William Blake: From Songs of Innocence and Of Experience 1<br />

<strong>The</strong> Book of <strong>The</strong>l 7<br />

Visions of the Daughters of Albion 11<br />

Wallace Stevens: “Not Ideas about the Thing but the Thing Itself” 19<br />

Rainer Maria Rilke: “Archaic Torso of Apollo” 20<br />

William Butler Yeats: “<strong>The</strong> Second Coming” 21<br />

ESSAYS<br />

Ezra Pound: “How to Read” 22<br />

Charles Sanders Peirce: “A Neglected Argument for 48<br />

the Existence of God”<br />

Short FICTION<br />

Nathaniel Hawthorne: “Ethan Brand” 71<br />

Zakaria Tamer: #19: Huda & the Hanged Man 83<br />

from Breaking Knees


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 1<br />

For all Blake’s engravings: http://www.blakearchive.org<br />

Frontispiece: Songs of Innocence<br />

Introduction<br />

Piping down the valleys wild<br />

Piping songs of pleasant glee<br />

On a cloud I saw a child.<br />

And he laughing said to me.<br />

Pipe a song about a Lamb;<br />

So I piped with merry chear,<br />

Piper pipe that song again--<br />

So I piped, he wept to hear.<br />

Drop thy pipe thy happy pipe<br />

Sing thy songs of happy chear,<br />

So I sung the same again<br />

While he wept with joy to hear<br />

Piper sit thee down and write<br />

In a book that all may read--<br />

So he vanish'd from my sight.<br />

And I pluck'd a hollow reed.<br />

And I made a rural pen,<br />

And I stain'd the water clear,<br />

And I wrote my happy songs<br />

Every child may joy to hear


<strong>The</strong> Lamb<br />

Little Lamb who made thee<br />

Dost thou know who made thee<br />

Gave thee life & bid thee feed.<br />

By the stream & o'er the mead;<br />

Gave thee clothing of delight,<br />

Softest clothing wooly bright;<br />

Gave thee such a tender voice,<br />

Making all the vales rejoice!<br />

Little Lamb who made thee<br />

Dost thou know who made thee<br />

Little Lamb I'll tell thee,<br />

Little Lamb I'll tell thee!<br />

He is called by thy name,<br />

For he calls himself a Lamb:<br />

He is meek & he is mild,<br />

He became a little child:<br />

I a child & thou a lamb,<br />

We are called by his name.<br />

Little Lamb God bless thee.<br />

Little Lamb God bless thee.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 2


Frontispiece: Songs of Experience<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 3


Introduction. (Experience)<br />

Hear the voice of the Bard!<br />

Who Present, Past, & Future sees<br />

Whose ears have heard,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Holy Word,<br />

That walk'd among the ancient trees.<br />

Calling the lapsed Soul<br />

And weeping in the evening dew:<br />

That might controll,<br />

<strong>The</strong> starry pole;<br />

And fallen fallen light renew!<br />

O Earth O Earth return!<br />

Arise from out the dewy grass;<br />

Night is worn,<br />

And the morn<br />

Rises from the slumberous mass,<br />

Turn away no more:<br />

Why wilt thou turn away<br />

<strong>The</strong> starry floor<br />

<strong>The</strong> watry shore<br />

Is giv'n thee till the break of day.<br />

EARTH'S Answer.<br />

Earth rais'd up her head,<br />

From the darkness dread & drear.<br />

Her light fled:<br />

Stony dread!<br />

And her locks cover'd with grey despair.<br />

Prison'd on watry shore<br />

Starry jealousy does keep my tent<br />

Cold and hoar<br />

Weeping o'er<br />

I hear the Father of the ancient men<br />

Selfish father of men<br />

Cruel jealous selfish fear<br />

Can delight<br />

Chain'd in night<br />

<strong>The</strong> virgins of youth and morning bear.<br />

Does spring hide its joy<br />

When buds and blossoms grow?<br />

Does the sower?<br />

Sow by night?<br />

Or the plowman in darkness plow?<br />

Break this heavy chain,<br />

That does freeze my bones around<br />

Selfish! vain!<br />

Eternal bane!<br />

That free Love with bondage bound.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 4


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 5<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Chimney</strong> <strong>Sweeper</strong>: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Chimney</strong> <strong>Sweeper</strong>:<br />

Innocence Experience<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Chimney</strong> <strong>Sweeper</strong> THE <strong>Chimney</strong> <strong>Sweeper</strong><br />

When my mother died I was very young, A little black thing among the snow:<br />

And my father sold me while yet my tongue, Crying weep, weep, in notes of woe!<br />

Could scarcely cry weep weep weep weep. Where are thy father & mother? say?<br />

So your chimneys I sweep & in soot I sleep, <strong>The</strong>y are both gone up to the church to pray.<br />

<strong>The</strong>res little Tom Dacre, who cried when his head Because I was happy upon the heath,<br />

That curl'd like a lambs back, was shav'd, so I said. And smil'd among the winter's snow:<br />

Hush Tom never mind it, for when your head's bare, <strong>The</strong>y clothed me in the clothes of death,<br />

You know that the soot cannot spoil your white hair. And taught me to sing the notes of woe.<br />

And so he was quiet, & that very night, And because I am happy, & dance & sing,<br />

As Tom was a sleeping he had such a sight, <strong>The</strong>y think they have done me no injury:<br />

That thousands of sweepers Dick, Joe, Ned & Jack And are gone to praise God & his Priest & King<br />

Were all of them lock'd up in coffins of black, Who make up a heaven of our misery.<br />

And by came an Angel who had a bright key,<br />

And he open'd the coffins & set them all free.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n down a green plain leaping laughing they run<br />

And wash in a river and shine in the Sun.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n naked & white, all their bags left behind,<br />

<strong>The</strong>y rise upon clouds, and sport in the wind.<br />

And the Angel told Tom if he'd be a good boy,<br />

He'd have God for his father & never want joy.<br />

And so Tom awoke and we rose in the dark<br />

And got with our bags & our brushes to work.<br />

Tho' the morning was cold, Tom was happy & warm,<br />

So if all do their duty, they need not fear harm.


Nurses Song: Innocence Nurses Song: Experience<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 6<br />

Nurse's Song (Innocence) NURSES Song (Experience)<br />

When the voices of children are heard on the green When the voices of children, are heard on the green<br />

And laughing is heard on the hill, And whisprings are in the dale:<br />

My heart is at rest within my breast <strong>The</strong> days of my youth rise fresh in my mind,<br />

And every thing else is still My face turns green and pale.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n come home my children, the sun is gone down <strong>The</strong>n come home my children, the sun is gone down<br />

And the dews of night arise And the dews of night arise<br />

Come come leave off play, and let us away Your spring & your day, are wasted in play<br />

Till the morning appears in the skies And your winter and night in disguise.<br />

No no let us play, for it is yet day<br />

And we cannot go to sleep<br />

Besides in the sky, the little birds fly<br />

And the hills are all coverd with sheep<br />

Well well go & play till the light fades away<br />

And then go home to bed<br />

<strong>The</strong> little ones leaped & shouted & laugh'd<br />

And all the hills ecchoed


<strong>The</strong> Book of <strong>The</strong>l (1789) William Blake<br />

<strong>The</strong>l's Motto<br />

Does the Eagle know what is in the pit,<br />

Or wilt thou go ask the Mole?<br />

Can Wisdom be put in a silver rod,<br />

Or Love in a golden bowl?<br />

<strong>The</strong> daughters of Mne Seraphim led round their sunny flocks,<br />

All but the youngest. She in paleness sought the secret air,<br />

To fade away like morning beauty from her mortal day.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 7


Down by the river of Adona her soft voice is heard,<br />

And thus her gentle lamentation falls like the morning dew;<br />

'O life of this our spring! why fades the lotus of the water?<br />

Why fade these children of the spring, born but to smile & fall?<br />

Ah! <strong>The</strong>l is like a wat'ry bow, and like a parting cloud,<br />

Like a reflection in a glass, like shadows in the water,<br />

Like dreams of infants, like a smile upon an infant's face,<br />

Like the dove's voice, like transient day, like music in the air.<br />

Ah! gentle may I lay me down and gentle rest my head,<br />

And gentle sleep the sleep of death, and gentle hear the voice<br />

Of him that walketh in the garden of the evening time.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> Lilly of the Valley, breathing in the humble grass,<br />

Answer'd the lovely maid and said: 'I am a wat'ry weed,<br />

And I am very small and love to dwell in lowly vales;<br />

So weak the gilded butterfly scarce perches on my head;<br />

Yet I am visited from heaven, and he that smiles on all<br />

Walks in the valley, and each morn over me spreads his hand<br />

Saying, "Rejoice, thou humble grass, thou new-born lilly flower,<br />

Thou gentle maid of silent valleys and of modest brooks;<br />

For thou shalt be clothed in light, and fed with morning manna,<br />

Till summer's heat melts thee beside the fountains and the springs<br />

To flourish in eternal vales". <strong>The</strong>n why should <strong>The</strong>l complain?<br />

Why should the mistress of the vales of Har utter a sigh?<br />

She ceas'd & smil'd in tears, then sat down in her silver shrine.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 8<br />

<strong>The</strong>l answer'd: 'O thou little virgin of the peaceful valley,<br />

Giving to those that cannot crave, the voiceless, the o'erfired;<br />

Thy breath doth nourish the innocent lamb, he smells thy milky garments,<br />

He crops thy flowers while thou sittest smiling in his face,<br />

Wiping his mild and meekin mouth from all contagious taints.<br />

Thy wine doth purify the golden honey; thy perfume,<br />

Which thou dost scatter on every little blade of grass that springs,<br />

revives the milked cow, & tames the fire-breathing steed.<br />

But <strong>The</strong>l is like a faint cloud kindled at the rising sun:<br />

I vanish from my pearly throne, and who shall find my place?'<br />

'Queen of the vales,' the Lilly answer'd, 'ask the tender cloud,<br />

And it shall tell thee why it glitters in the morning sky,<br />

And why it scatters its bright beauty thro' the humid air.<br />

Descend, O little cloud, & hover before the eyes of <strong>The</strong>l.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> Cloud descended, and the Lilly bow'd her modest head,<br />

And went to mind her numerous charge among the verdant grass.


II<br />

'O little cloud,' the virgin said, 'I charge thee to tell to me<br />

Why thou complainest not when in one hour thou fade away;<br />

<strong>The</strong>n we shall seek thee, but not find. Ah! <strong>The</strong>l is like to thee:<br />

I pass away; yet I complain, and no one hears my voice.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> Cloud then shew'd his golden head, & his bright form emerg'd,<br />

Hovering and glittering on the air before the face of <strong>The</strong>l:<br />

'O virgin, know'st thou not? Our steeds drink of the golden springs<br />

Where Luvah doth renew his horses. Look'st thou onmy youth,<br />

And fearest thou, because I vanish and am seen no more,<br />

Nothing remains? O maid, I tell thee, when I pass away,<br />

It is to tenfold life, to love, to peace and raptures holy.<br />

Unseen descending, weigh my light wings upon balmy flowers,<br />

And court the fair eyed dew to take me to her shining tent.<br />

<strong>The</strong> weeping virgin trembling kneels before the riding sun,<br />

Till we arise link'd in a golden band, and never part,<br />

But walk united, bearing food to our tender flowers.'<br />

'Dost thou, O little Cloud? I fear that I am not like thee;<br />

For I walk thro' the vales of Har, and smell the sweetest flowers,<br />

But I feed not the little flowers. I hear the warbling birds,<br />

but i feed not the warbling birds; they fly and seek their food.<br />

But <strong>The</strong>l delights in these no more, because I fade away;<br />

And all shall say, "Without a use this shining woman liv'd,<br />

Or did she only live to be at death the food of worms?" '<br />

<strong>The</strong> Cloud reclin'd upon his airy throne and answer'd thus:<br />

'<strong>The</strong>n if thou art the food of worms, O virgin of the skies,<br />

How great thy use, how great thy blessing! Everything that lives<br />

Lives not alone, nor for itself. Fear not, and I will call<br />

<strong>The</strong> weak worm from its lowly bed, and thou shalt hear its voice.<br />

Come forth, worm of the silent valley, to thy pensive queen.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> helpless worm arose, and sat upon the Lilly's leaf,<br />

And the bright Cloud sail'd on, to find his partner in the vale.<br />

III<br />

<strong>The</strong>n <strong>The</strong>l astonish'd view'd the Worm upon its dewy bed:<br />

'Art thou a Worm? image of weakness, art thou but a Worm?<br />

I see thee like an infant wrapped in the Lilly's leaf.<br />

Ah weep not, little voice, thou canst not speak, but thou can weep.<br />

Is this a worm? I see thee lay helpless & naked, weeping,<br />

And none to answer, none to cherish thee with mother's smiles.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> Clod of Clay heard the Worm's voice, & rais'd her pitying head;<br />

She bow'd over the weeping infant, and her life exhal'd<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 9


In milky fondness; then on <strong>The</strong>l she fix'd her humble eyes;<br />

'O beauty of the vales of Har, we live not for ourselves.<br />

Thou seest me the meanest thing, and so I am indeed:<br />

My bosom of itself is cold, and of itself is dark,<br />

But he that loves the lowly pours his oil upon my head,<br />

And kisses me, and binds his nuptial bands around my breast,<br />

And says: "Thou mother of my children, I have loved thee,<br />

And I have given thee a crown that none can take away."<br />

But how this is, sweet maid, I know not, and I cannot know;<br />

I ponder, and I cannot ponder, yet I live and love.'<br />

<strong>The</strong> daughter of beauty wip'd her pitying tears with her white veil,<br />

And said: Alas! I knew not this, and therefore did I weep.<br />

That God would love a Worm I knew, and therefore did I weep;<br />

And I complain'd in the mild air, because i fade away,<br />

And lay me down in thy cold bed, and leave my shining lot.'<br />

'Queen of the vales,' the matron Clay answer'd, 'I heard thy sighs,<br />

And all thy moans flew o'er my roof, but I have call'd them down.<br />

Wilt thou, O Queen, enter my house? 'Tis given thee to enter<br />

And to return; fear nothing; enter with thy virgin feet.'<br />

IV<br />

<strong>The</strong> eternal gates' terrific porter lifted the northern bar.<br />

<strong>The</strong>l enter'd in & saw the secrets of the land unknown.<br />

She saw the couches of the dead, & where the fibrous roots<br />

Of every heart on earth infixes deep its restless twists:<br />

A land of sorrows & of tears where never smile was seen.<br />

She wander'd in the land of clouds thro' valleys dark, list'ning<br />

Dolours and lamentations; waiting oft beside a dewy grave<br />

She stood in silence, list'ning to the voices of the ground,<br />

Till to her own grave plot she came, & there she sat down,<br />

And heard this voice of sorrow breathed from the hollow pit:<br />

'Why cannot the Ear be closed to its own destruction?<br />

Or the glist'ning Eye to the poison of a smile?<br />

Why are Eyelids stor'd with arrows ready drawn,<br />

Where a thousand fighting men in ambush lie?<br />

Or an Eye of gifts & graces, show'ring fruits and coined gold?<br />

Why a Tongue impress'd with honey from every wind?<br />

Why an Ear a whirlpool fierce to draw creations in?<br />

Why a Nostril wide inhaling terror, trembling & affright?<br />

Why a tender curb upon the youthful burning boy?<br />

Why a little curtain of flesh on the bed of our desire?'<br />

<strong>The</strong> Virgin started from her seat, & with a shriek<br />

Fled back unhinder'd till she came into the vales of Har.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 10


Visions of the Daughters of Albion<br />

William Blake (1793)<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 11


VISIONS of the Daughters of Albion<br />

<strong>The</strong> Eye sees more than the Heart knows.<br />

Printed by William Blake: 1793.<br />

PLATE iii<br />

<strong>The</strong> Argument<br />

I loved <strong>The</strong>otormon<br />

And I was not ashamed<br />

I trembled in my virgin fears<br />

And I hid in Leutha's vale!<br />

I plucked Leutha's flower,<br />

And I rose up from the vale;<br />

But the terrible thunders tore<br />

My virgin mantle in twain.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 12


PLATE 1 Visions<br />

ENSLAV'D, the Daughters of Albion weep: a trembling lamentation<br />

Upon their mountains; in their valleys. sighs toward America.<br />

For the soft soul of America, Oothoon wanderd in woe,<br />

Along the vales of Leutha seeking flowers to comfort her;<br />

And thus she spoke to the bright Marygold of Leutha's vale<br />

Art thou a flower! art thou a nymph! I see thee now a flower;<br />

Now a nymph! I dare not pluck thee from thy dewy bed!<br />

<strong>The</strong> Golden nymph replied; pluck thou my flower Oothoon the mild<br />

Another flower shall spring, because the soul of sweet delight<br />

Can never pass away. she ceas'd & closd her golden shrine.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n Oothoon pluck'd the flower saying, I pluck thee from thy bed<br />

Sweet flower. and put thee here to glow between my breasts<br />

And thus I turn my face to where my whole soul seeks.<br />

Over the waves she went in wing'd exulting swift delight;<br />

And over <strong>The</strong>otormons reign, took her impetuous course.<br />

Bromion rent her with his thunders. on his stormy bed<br />

Lay the faint maid, and soon her woes appalld his thunders hoarse<br />

Bromion spoke. behold this harlot here on Bromions bed,<br />

And let the jealous dolphins sport around the lovely maid;<br />

Thy soft American plains are mine, and mine thy north & south:<br />

Stampt with my signet are the swarthy children of the sun:<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are obedient, they resist not, they obey the scourge:<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir daughters worship terrors and obey the violent:<br />

PLATE 2<br />

Now thou maist marry Bromions harlot, and protect the child<br />

Of Bromions rage, that Oothoon shall put forth in nine moons time<br />

<strong>The</strong>n storms rent <strong>The</strong>otormons limbs; he rolld his waves around.<br />

And folded his black jealous waters round the adulterate pair<br />

Bound back to back in Bromions caves terror & meekness dwell<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 13<br />

At entrance <strong>The</strong>otormon sits wearing the threshold hard<br />

With secret tears; beneath him sound like waves on a desart shore<br />

<strong>The</strong> voice of slaves beneath the sun, and children bought with money.<br />

That shiver in religious caves beneath the burning fires<br />

Of lust, that belch incessant from the summits of the earth<br />

Oothoon weeps not: she cannot weep! her tears are locked up;<br />

But she can howl incessant writhing her soft snowy limbs.<br />

And calling <strong>The</strong>otormons Eagles to prey upon her flesh.<br />

I call with holy voice! kings of the sounding air,


Rend away this defiled bosom that I may reflect.<br />

<strong>The</strong> image of <strong>The</strong>otormon on my pure transparent breast.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Eagles at her call descend & rend their bleeding prey;<br />

<strong>The</strong>otormon severely smiles. her soul reflects the smile;<br />

As the clear spring mudded with feet of beasts grows pure & smiles.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Daughters of Albion hear her woes. & eccho back her sighs.<br />

Why does my <strong>The</strong>otormon sit weeping upon the threshold;<br />

And Oothoon hovers by his side, perswading him in vain:<br />

I cry arise O <strong>The</strong>otormon for the village dog<br />

Barks at the breaking day. the nightingale has done lamenting.<br />

<strong>The</strong> lark does rustle in the ripe corn, and the Eagle returns<br />

From nightly prey, and lifts his golden beak to the pure east;<br />

Shaking the dust from his immortal pinions to awake<br />

<strong>The</strong> sun that sleeps too long. Arise my <strong>The</strong>otormon I am pure.<br />

Because the night is gone that clos'd me in its deadly black.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y told me that the night & day were all that I could see;<br />

<strong>The</strong>y told me that I had five senses to inclose me up.<br />

And they inclos'd my infinite brain into a narrow circle,<br />

And sunk my heart into the Abyss, a red round globe hot burning<br />

Till all from life I was obliterated and erased.<br />

Instead of morn arises a bright shadow, like an eye<br />

In the eastern cloud: instead of night a sickly charnel house;<br />

That <strong>The</strong>otormon hears me not! to him the night and morn<br />

Are both alike: a night of sighs, a morning of fresh tears;<br />

PLATE 3<br />

And none but Bromion can hear my lamentations.<br />

With what sense is it that the chicken shuns the ravenous hawk?<br />

With what sense does the tame pigeon measure out the expanse?<br />

With what sense does the bee form cells? have not the mouse & frog<br />

Eyes and ears and sense of touch? yet are their habitations.<br />

And their pursuits, as different as their forms and as their joys:<br />

Ask the wild ass why he refuses burdens: and the meek camel<br />

Why he loves man: is it because of eye ear mouth or skin<br />

Or breathing nostrils? No. for these the wolf and tyger have.<br />

Ask the blind worm the secrets of the grave, and why her spires<br />

Love to curl round the bones of death; and ask the rav'nous snake<br />

Where she gets poison: & the wing'd eagle why he loves the sun<br />

And then tell me the thoughts of man, that have been hid of old.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 14<br />

Silent I hover all the night, and all day could be silent.<br />

If <strong>The</strong>otormon once would turn his loved eyes upon me;<br />

How can I be defild when I reflect thy image pure?<br />

Sweetest the fruit that the worm feeds on. & the soul prey'd on by woe<br />

<strong>The</strong> new wash'd lamb ting'd with the village smoke & the bright swan<br />

By the red earth of our immortal river: I bathe my wings.<br />

And I am white and pure to hover round <strong>The</strong>otormons breast.


<strong>The</strong>n <strong>The</strong>otormon broke his silence. and he answered.<br />

Tell me what is the night or day to one o'erflowd with woe?<br />

Tell me what is a thought? & of what substance is it made?<br />

Tell me what is a joy? & in what gardens do joys grow?<br />

And in what rivers swim the sorrows? and upon what mountains<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 15<br />

PLATE 4<br />

Wave shadows of discontent? and in what houses dwell the wretched<br />

Drunken with woe forgotten. and shut up from cold despair.<br />

Tell me where dwell the thoughts forgotten till thou call them forth<br />

Tell me where dwell the joys of old! & where the ancient loves?<br />

And when will they renew again & the night of oblivion past?<br />

That I might traverse times & spaces far remote and bring<br />

Comforts into a present sorrow and a night of pain<br />

Where goest thou O thought? to what remote land is thy flight?<br />

If thou returnest to the present moment of affliction<br />

Wilt thou bring comforts on thy wings. and dews and honey and balm;<br />

Or poison from the desart wilds, from the eyes of the envier.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n Bromion said: and shook the cavern with his lamentation<br />

Thou knowest that the ancient trees seen by thine eyes have fruit;<br />

But knowest thou that trees and fruits flourish upon the earth<br />

To gratify senses unknown? trees beasts and birds unknown:<br />

Unknown, not unpercievd, spread in the infinite microscope,<br />

In places yet unvisited by the voyager. and in worlds<br />

Over another kind of seas, and in atmospheres unknown:<br />

Ah! are there other wars, beside the wars of sword and fire!<br />

And are there other sorrows, beside the sorrows of poverty!<br />

And are there other joys, beside the joys of riches and ease?<br />

And is there not one law for both the lion and the ox?<br />

And is there not eternal fire, and eternal chains?<br />

To bind the phantoms of existence from eternal life?<br />

<strong>The</strong>n Oothoon waited silent all the day. and all the night,<br />

PLATE 5<br />

But when the morn arose, her lamentation renewd,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Daughters of Albion hear her woes, & eccho back her sighs.<br />

O Urizen! Creator of men! Mistaken Demon of heaven:<br />

Thy joys are tears! thy labour vain, to form men to thine image.<br />

How can one joy absorb another? are not different joys<br />

Holy, eternal, infinite! and each joy is a Love.<br />

Does not the great mouth laugh at a gift? & the narrow eyelids mock<br />

At the labour that is above payment, and wilt thou take the ape<br />

For thy councellor? or the dog, for a schoolmaster to thy children?<br />

Does he who contemns poverty, and he who turns with abhorrence<br />

From usury: feel the same passion or are they moved alike?


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 16<br />

How can the giver of gifts experience the delights of the merchant?<br />

How the industrious citizen the pains of the husbandman.<br />

How different far the fat fed hireling with hollow drum;<br />

Who buys whole corn fields into wastes, and sings upon the heath:<br />

How different their eye and ear! how different the world to them!<br />

With what sense does the parson claim the labour of the farmer?<br />

What are his nets & gins & traps. & how does he surround him<br />

With cold floods of abstraction, and with forests of solitude,<br />

To build him castles and high spires. where kings & priests may dwell.<br />

Till she who burns with youth. and knows no fixed lot; is bound<br />

In spells of law to one she loaths: and must she drag the chain<br />

Of life, in weary lust! must chilling murderous thoughts. obscure<br />

<strong>The</strong> clear heaven of her eternal spring? to bear the wintry rage<br />

Of a harsh terror driv'n to madness, bound to hold a rod<br />

Over her shrinking shoulders all the day; & all the night<br />

To turn the wheel of false desire: and longings that wake her womb<br />

To the abhorred birth of cherubs in the human form<br />

That live a pestilence & die a meteor & are no more.<br />

Till the child dwell with one he hates. and do the deed he loaths<br />

And the impure scourge force his seed into its unripe birth<br />

E'er yet his eyelids can behold the arrows of the day.<br />

Does the whale worship at thy footsteps as the hungry dog?<br />

Or does he scent the mountain prey, because his nostrils wide<br />

Draw in the ocean? does his eye discern the flying cloud<br />

As the ravens eye? or does he measure the expanse like the vulture?<br />

Does the still spider view the cliffs where eagles hide their young?<br />

Or does the fly rejoice. because the harvest is brought in?<br />

Does not the eagle scorn the earth & despise the treasures beneath?<br />

But the mole knoweth what is there, & the worm shall tell it thee.<br />

Does not the worm erect a pillar in the mouldering church yard?<br />

PLATE 6<br />

And a palace of eternity in the jaws of the hungry grave<br />

Over his porch these words are written. Take thy bliss O Man!<br />

And sweet shall be thy taste & sweet thy infant joys renew!<br />

Infancy, fearless, lustful, happy! nestling for delight<br />

In laps of pleasure; Innocence! honest, open, seeking<br />

<strong>The</strong> vigorous joys of morning light; open to virgin bliss.<br />

Who taught thee modesty, subtil modesty! child of night & sleep<br />

When thou awakest, wilt thou dissemble all thy secret joys<br />

Or wert thou not awake when all this mystery was disclos'd!<br />

<strong>The</strong>n com'st thou forth a modest virgin knowing to dissemble<br />

With nets found under thy night pillow, to catch virgin joy,<br />

And brand it with the name of whore; & sell it in the night,<br />

In silence. ev'n without a whisper, and in seeming sleep:<br />

Religious dreams and holy vespers, light thy smoky fires:<br />

Once were thy fires lighted by the eyes of honest morn<br />

And does my <strong>The</strong>otormon seek this hypocrite modesty!


This knowing, artful, secret, fearful, cautious, trembling hypocrite.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n is Oothoon a whore indeed! and all the virgin joys<br />

Of life are harlots: and <strong>The</strong>otormon is a sick mans dream<br />

And Oothoon is the crafty slave of selfish holiness.<br />

But Oothoon is not so, a virgin fill'd with virgin fancies<br />

Open to joy and to delight where ever beauty appears<br />

If in the morning sun I find it: there my eyes are fix'd<br />

PLATE 7<br />

In happy copulation; if in evening mild. wearied with work;<br />

Sit on a bank and draw the pleasures of this free born joy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> moment of desire! the moment of desire! <strong>The</strong> virgin<br />

That pines for man; shall awaken her womb to enormous joys<br />

In the secret shadows of her chamber; the youth shut up from<br />

<strong>The</strong> lustful joy. shall forget to generate. & create an amorous image<br />

In the shadows of his curtains and in the folds of his silent pillow.<br />

Are not these the places of religion? the rewards of continence?<br />

<strong>The</strong> self enjoyings of self denial? Why dost thou seek religion?<br />

Is it because acts are not lovely, that thou seekest solitude,<br />

Where the horrible darkness is impressed with reflections of desire.<br />

Father of jealousy. be thou accursed from the earth!<br />

Why hast thou taught my <strong>The</strong>otormon this accursed thing?<br />

Till beauty fades from off my shoulders darken'd and cast out,<br />

A solitary shadow wailing on the margin of non-entity.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 17<br />

I cry, Love! Love! Love! happy happy Love! free as the mountain wind!<br />

Can that be Love, that drinks another as a sponge drinks water?<br />

That clouds with jealousy his nights, with weepings all the day:<br />

To spin a web of age around him. grey and hoary! dark!<br />

Till his eyes sicken at the fruit that hangs before his sight.<br />

Such is self-love that envies all! a creeping skeleton<br />

With lamplike eyes watching around the frozen marriage bed.<br />

But silken nets and traps of adamant will Oothoon spread,<br />

And catch for thee girls of mild silver, or of furious gold;<br />

I'll lie beside thee on a bank & view their wanton play<br />

In lovely copulation bliss on bliss with <strong>The</strong>otormon:<br />

Red as the rosy morning, lustful as the first born beam,<br />

Oothoon shall view his dear delight, nor e'er with jealous cloud<br />

Come in the heaven of generous love; nor selfish blightings bring.<br />

Does the sun walk in glorious raiment. on the secret floor<br />

PLATE 8<br />

Where the cold miser spreads his gold? or does the bright cloud drop<br />

On his stone threshold? does his eye behold the beam that brings<br />

Expansion to the eye of pity? or will he bind himself<br />

Beside the ox to thy hard furrow? does not that mild beam blot


<strong>The</strong> bat, the owl, the glowing tyger, and the king of night.<br />

<strong>The</strong> sea fowl takes the wintry blast. for a cov'ring to her limbs:<br />

And the wild snake, the pestilence to adorn him with gems & gold.<br />

And trees. & birds. & beasts. & men. behold their eternal joy.<br />

Arise you little glancing wings, and sing your infant joy!<br />

Arise and drink your bliss, for every thing that lives is holy!<br />

Thus every morning wails Oothoon. but <strong>The</strong>otormon sits<br />

Upon the margind ocean conversing with shadows dire.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Daughters of Albion hear her woes, & eccho back her sighs.<br />

<strong>The</strong> End<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 18


Wallace Stevens (1879-1955)<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 19<br />

Not Ideas About the Thing But the Thing Itself<br />

At the earliest ending of winter,<br />

In March, a scrawny cry from outside<br />

Seemed like a sound in his mind.<br />

He knew that he heard it,<br />

A bird's cry, at daylight or before,<br />

In the early March wind.<br />

<strong>The</strong> sun was rising at six,<br />

No longer a battered panache above snow...<br />

It would have been outside.<br />

It was not from the vast ventriloquism<br />

Of sleep's faded papier-mache...<br />

<strong>The</strong> sun was coming from the outside.<br />

That scrawny cry--It was<br />

A chorister whose c preceded the choir.<br />

It was part of the colossal sun,<br />

Surrounded by its choral rings,<br />

Still far away. It was like<br />

A new knowledge of reality.


Rainer Maria Rilke (1875-1926)<br />

Archaischer Torso Apollos<br />

Wir kannten nicht sein unerhörtes Haupt,<br />

darin die Augenäpfel reiften. Aber<br />

sein Torso glüht noch wie ein Kandelaber,<br />

in dem sein Schauen, nur zurückgeschraubt,<br />

sich hält und glänzt. Sonst könnte nicht der Bug<br />

der Brust dich blenden, und im leisen Drehen<br />

der Lenden könnte nicht ein Lächeln gehen<br />

zu jener Mitte, die die Zeugung trug.<br />

Sonst stünde dieser Stein enstellt und kurz<br />

unter der Shultern durchsichtigem Sturz<br />

und flimmerte nicht so wie Raubtierfelle;<br />

und brächte nicht aus allen seinen Rändern<br />

aus wie ein Stern: denn da ist keine Stelle,<br />

die dich nicht sieht. Du mußt dein Leben ändern.<br />

Archaic Torso of Apollo * trans. Leroy Searle<br />

We did not know his fabulous head<br />

Wherein the apples of his eyes ripened. But<br />

his torso glows like a candelabra<br />

in which his gaze, now covertly burning<br />

holds and shines. How else could the curve<br />

of the breast so blind you, or in the slight turn<br />

of the loins, how could that smile slide<br />

to the middle, where procreation starts?<br />

Otherwise this stone would stand maimed, cut off<br />

under the translucent plunge of the shoulders,<br />

not shimmering like a tiger's pelt<br />

Nor breaking out of all its borders<br />

like a star: there is no place<br />

that does not see you. You must change your life.<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 20


William Butler Yeats (1865-1939)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Second Coming<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 21<br />

From Michael Robartes and the Dancer (Churchtown, Dundrum: <strong>The</strong> Cuala Press,<br />

1920))<br />

Turning and turning in the widening gyre<br />

<strong>The</strong> falcon cannot hear the falconer;<br />

Things fall apart; the centre cannot hold;<br />

Mere anarchy is loosed upon the world,<br />

<strong>The</strong> blood-dimmed tide is loosed, and everywhere<br />

<strong>The</strong> ceremony of innocence is drowned;<br />

<strong>The</strong> best lack all conviction, while the worst<br />

Are full of passionate intensity.<br />

Surely some revelation is at hand;<br />

Surely the Second Coming is at hand.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Second Coming! Hardly are those words out<br />

When a vast image out of Spiritus Mundi<br />

Troubles my sight: somewhere in sands of the desert<br />

A shape with lion body and the head of a man,<br />

A gaze blank and pitiless as the sun,<br />

Is moving its slow thighs, while all about it<br />

Reel shadows of the indignant desert birds.<br />

<strong>The</strong> darkness drops again; but now I know<br />

That twenty centuries of stony sleep<br />

Were vexed to nightmare by a rocking cradle,<br />

And what rough beast, its hour come round at last,<br />

Slouches towards Bethlehem to be born?


HOW TO READ'<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 22<br />

PART ONE: INTRODUCTION<br />

Largely Autobiographical, Touching the Present, and More or Less<br />

Immediately Past,'State ofAffairs'.<br />

Literary instruction in our 'institutions of learning'2 was, at the<br />

beginning of this century, cumbrous and inefficient. I dare say it still is. Certain more<br />

or less mildly exceptional professors were affected by the `beauties' of various authors<br />

(usually deceased), but the system, as a whole, lacked sense and co-ordination. I dare<br />

say it still does. When studying physics we are not asked to investigate the biographies of<br />

all the disciples of Newton who showed interest in science, but who failed to make<br />

any discovery. Neither are their unrewarded gropings, hopes, passions, laundry bills,<br />

or erotic experiences thrust on the hurried student or considered germane to the<br />

subject.<br />

<strong>The</strong> general contempt of `scholarship', especially any part of it connected with<br />

subjects included in university `Arts' courses; the shrinking of people in general from<br />

any book supposed to be `good'; and, in another mode, the flamboyant advertisements<br />

telling 'how to seem to know it when you don't', might long since have indicated to the<br />

sensitive that there is something defective in the contemporary methods of purveying<br />

letters.<br />

As the general reader has but a vague idea of what these methods are at the<br />

`centre', i.e. for the specialist who is expected to serve the general reader, I shall<br />

lapse or plunge into autobiography.<br />

In my university I found various men interested (or uninterested) in their subjects,<br />

but, I think, no man with a view of literature as a whole, or with any idea whatsoever<br />

of the relation of the part he himself taught to any other part.<br />

Those professors who regarded their `subject' as a drill manual rose most<br />

rapidly to positions of executive responsibility (one case<br />

1 New York Herald Tribune, 'Books', 1929. [Literary Essays of E P. 1935]<br />

2 Foot-note a few decades later: <strong>The</strong> proper definition would be 'Institutions for the<br />

obstruction of learning.'<br />

15<br />

:


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 23<br />

is now a provost). Those professors who had some natural aptitude for comprehending<br />

their authors and for communicating a general sense of comfort in the presence of<br />

literary masterwork remained obscurely in their less exalted positions.<br />

A professor of Romanics admitted that the Chanson de Roland was inferior to the<br />

Odyssey, but then the Middle Ages were expected to present themselves with<br />

apologies, and this was, if I remember rightly, an isolated exception. English novelists<br />

were not compared with the French. 'Sources' were discussed; forty versions of a<br />

Chaucerian anecdote were 'compared', but not on points of respective literary merit.<br />

<strong>The</strong> whole field was full of redundance. I mean that what one had learned in one class,<br />

in the study of one literature, one was told again in some other.<br />

One was asked to remember what some critic (deceased) had said, scarcely to consider<br />

whether his views were still valid, or ever had been very intelligent.<br />

In defence of this dead and uncorrelated system, it may be urged that authors like<br />

Spengler, who attempt a synthesis, often do so before they have attained sufficient<br />

knowledge of detail: that they stuff expandable and compressible objects into rubber-bag<br />

categories, and that they limit their reference and interest by supposing that the pedagogic<br />

follies which they have themselves encountered, constitute an error universally<br />

distributed, and encountered by every one else. In extenuation of their miscalculations<br />

we may admit that any error or clumsiness of method that has sunk into, or been<br />

hammered into one man, over a period of years, probably continues as an error-- not<br />

merely passively, but as an error still being propagated, consciously or unconsciously,<br />

by a number of educators, from laziness, from habits, or from natural cussedness.<br />

`Comparative literature' sometimes figures in university curricula, but very few people<br />

know what they mean by the term, or approach it with a considered conscious method.<br />

To tranquillize the low-brow reader, let me say at once that I do not wish to muddle<br />

him by making him read more books, but to allow him to read fewer with greater result.<br />

(I am willing to discuss this privately with the book trade.) I have been accused of<br />

wanting to make people read all the classics; which is not so. I have been accused of<br />

wishing to provide a 'portable substitute for the British Museum', which I would do, like<br />

a shot, were it possible. It isn't.<br />

16


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 24<br />

American 'taste' is less official than English taste, but more derivative. When I<br />

arrived in England (A.D. 1908), I found a greater darkness in the British 'serious press' than<br />

had obtained on the banks of the Schuylkill. Already in my young and ignorant years<br />

they considered me 'learned'. It was impossible, at first, to see why and whence the current<br />

opinion of British weeklies. It was incredible that literate men—men literate enough, that<br />

is, to write the orderly paragraphs that they did write constantly in their papers-believed<br />

the stupidities that appeared there with such regularity. (Later,, for two years, we ran<br />

fortnightly in the Egoist, the sort of fool-column that the French call a sottisier, needing<br />

nothing for it but quotations from the Times Literary Supplement. Two issues of the<br />

Supplement yielding, easily, one page of the Egoist.) For years I awaited<br />

enlightenment. One winter I had lodgings in Sussex. On the mantelpiece of the humble<br />

country cottage I found books of an earlier era, among them an anthology printed in 183o,<br />

and yet another dated 1795, and there, there by the sox of Jehosaphat was the British<br />

taste of this century, 191o, 1915, and even the present, A.D. 1931.<br />

I had read Stendhal's remark that it takes eighty years for anything to reach the<br />

general public, and looking out on the waste heath, under the December drizzle, I believed<br />

him. But that is not all of the story. Embedded in that naive innocence that does, to their<br />

credit, pervade our universities, I ascribed the delay to mere time. I still thought: With<br />

the attrition of decades, ah, yes, in another seventy, in another, perhaps, ninety years,<br />

they will admit that . . . etc.<br />

I mean that I thought they wanted to, but were hindered.<br />

Later it struck me that the best history of painting in London was the National Gallery,<br />

and that the best history of literature, more particularly of poetry, would be a twelvevolume<br />

anthology in which each poem was chosen not merely because it was a nice<br />

poem or a poem Aunt Hepsy liked, but because it contained an invention, a definite<br />

contribution to the art of verbal expression. With this in mind, I approached a<br />

respected agent. He was courteous, he was even openly amazed at the list of three<br />

hundred items which I offered as an indication of outline. No autochthonous Briton<br />

had ever, to his professed belief, displayed such familiarity with so vast a tinge, but he was<br />

too indolent to recast my introductory letter into a form suited to commerce. He, as they<br />

say, 'repaired' to an equally august and long-established publishing house (which had<br />

already<br />

17


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 25<br />

served his and my interest). In two days came a hasty summons: would I see<br />

him in person. I found him awed, as if one had killed a cat in the sacristy. Did I<br />

know what I had said in my letter? I did. Yes, but about Palgrave? I did. I had said:<br />

'It is time we had something to replace that doddard Palgrave.' But don't you<br />

know', came the awstruck tones, 'that the whole fortune of X & Co. is founded on<br />

Palgrave's Golden Treasury?'<br />

From that day onward no book of mine received a British imprimatur until<br />

the appearance of Eliot's castrated edition of my poems.<br />

I perceived that there were thousands of pounds sterling invested in electro-plate,<br />

and the least change in the public taste, let alone swift, catastrophic changes,<br />

would depreciate the value of those electros (of Hemans, let us say, or of Collins,<br />

Cowper, and of Churchill, who wrote the satiric verses, and of later less blatant cases,<br />

touched with a slighter flavour of mustiness).<br />

I sought the banks of the Seine. Against ignorance one might struggle, and even<br />

against organic stupidity, but against a so vast vested interest the lone odds were too<br />

heavy.<br />

Two years later a still more august academic press reopened the question. <strong>The</strong>y had<br />

ventured to challenge Palgrave: they had been Interested'—would I send back my<br />

prospectus? I did. <strong>The</strong>y found the plan 'too ambitious'. <strong>The</strong>y said they might do<br />

'something', but that if they did it would be 'more in the nature of gems'.<br />

FOR A METHOD<br />

Nevertheless, the method I had proposed was simple, it is perhaps the only one that<br />

can give a man an orderly arrangement of his perception in the matter of letters. In<br />

opposition to it, there are the forces of superstition, of hang-over. People regard<br />

literature as something vastly more flabby and floating and complicated and<br />

indefinite than, let us say, mathematics. Its subject-matter, the human consciousness, is<br />

more complicated than are number and space. It is not, however, more complicated<br />

than biology, and no one ever supposed that it was. We apply a loose-leaf system to<br />

book-keeping so as to have the live items separated from the dead ones. In the<br />

study of physics we begin with simple mechanism; wedge, lever and fulcrum,<br />

pulley and inclined plane, all of them still as useful as when they were first invented.<br />

We proceed by a study of discoveries.<br />

{18}


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 26<br />

We are not asked to memorize a list of the parts of a side-wheeler engine.<br />

And we could, presumably, apply to the study of literature a little of the<br />

common sense that we currently apply to physics or to biology. In poetry there are<br />

simple procedures, and there are known discoveries, clearly marked. As I have said in<br />

various places in my unorganized and fragmentary volumes: in each age one or two<br />

men of genius find something, and express it. It may be in only a line or in two lines,<br />

or in some quality of a cadence; and thereafter two dozen, or two hundred, or two<br />

or more thousand followers repeat and dilute and modify.<br />

And if the instructor would select his specimens from works that contain these<br />

discoveries and solely on the basis of discovery—which may lie in the dimension<br />

of depth, not merely of some novelty on the surface—he would aid his student far<br />

more than by presenting his authors at random, and talking about them in tow.<br />

Needless to say, this presentation would be entirely independent of consideration<br />

as to whether the given passages tended to make the student a better republican,<br />

monarchist, monist, dualist, rotarian, or other sectarian. To avoid confusion, one<br />

should state at once that such method has nothing to do with those allegedly<br />

scientific methods which approach literature as if it were something not literature,<br />

or with scientists' attempts to sub-divide the elements in literature according to some<br />

non-literary categoric division.<br />

You do not divide physics or chemistry according to racial or religious categories.<br />

You do not put discoveries by Methodists and Germans into one category, and<br />

discoveries by Episcopalians or Americans or Italians into another.<br />

DEFECTIVE RELATIVITIES<br />

It is said that in America nothing is ever consciously related to anything else. I<br />

have cited as an exception the forty versions of the Chaucerian anecdote; they and<br />

the great edition of Horace with the careful list and parallel display of Greek sources for<br />

such line or such paragraph, show how the associative faculty can be side-tracked. Or<br />

at any rate they indicate the first gropings of association. Let us grant that some<br />

bits of literature have been, in special cases, displayed in relation to some other bits;<br />

usually some verbose gentleman<br />

19


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 27<br />

writes a trilogy of essays, on three grandiose figures, comparing their `philosophy' or<br />

personal habits.<br />

Let us by all means glance at 'philology' and the `germanic system'. Speaking as<br />

an historian, `we' may say that this system was designed to inhibit thought. After 1848 it<br />

was, in Germany, observed that some people thought. It was necessary to curtail this<br />

pernicious activity, the thinkists were given a china egg labelled scholarship, and were<br />

gradually unfitted for active life, or for any contact with life in general. Literature was<br />

permitted as a subject of study. And its study was so designed as to draw the mind of the<br />

student away from literature into inanity.<br />

WHY BOOKS?<br />

This simple first question was never asked.<br />

<strong>The</strong> study of literature, or more probably of morphology, verb-roots, etc., was<br />

permitted the German professor in, let us say, x 88o-- 1905, to keep his mind off life<br />

in general, and off public life in particular.<br />

In America it was permitted from precedent; it was known to be permitted in<br />

Germany; Germany had a `great university tradition', which it behoved America to equal<br />

and perhaps to surpass.<br />

This study, or some weaker variety of it, was also known to be permitted at Oxford,<br />

and supposed to have a refining influence on the student.<br />

II<br />

<strong>The</strong> practice of literary composition in private has been permitted since `age<br />

immemorial', like knitting, crocheting, etc. It occupies the practitioner, and, so long as<br />

he keeps it to himself, ne suit pas aux wares, it does not transgress the definition of<br />

liberty which we find in the declaration of the Droits de l'Homme: Liberty is the right to<br />

do anything which harms not others. All of which is rather negative and unsatisfactory.<br />

III<br />

It appears to me quite tenable that the function of literature as a generated prizeworthy<br />

force is precisely that it does incite humanity to continue living; that it eases the<br />

mind of strain, and feeds it, I mean definitely as nutrition of impulse.<br />

20<br />

I


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 28<br />

This idea may worry lovers of order. Just as good literature does often worry them. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

regard it as dangerous, chaotic, subversive. <strong>The</strong>y try every idiotic and degrading wheeze to<br />

tame it down. <strong>The</strong>y try to make a bog, a marasmus, a great putridity in place of a sane and<br />

active ebullience. And they do this from sheer simian and pig-like stupidity, and from<br />

their failure to understand the function of letters.<br />

IV<br />

Has literature a function in the state, in the aggregation of humans, in the republic,<br />

in the rat publica, which ought to mean the public convenience (despite the slime of<br />

bureaucracy, and the execrable taste of the populace in selecting its rulers)? It has.<br />

And this function is not the coercing or emotionally persuading, or bullying or<br />

suppressing people into the acceptance of any one set or any six sets of opinions as<br />

opposed to any other one set or half-dozen sets of opinions.<br />

It has to do with the clarity and vigour of 'any and every' thought and opinion. It has to<br />

do with maintaining the very cleanliness of the tools, the health of the very matter of<br />

thought itself. Save in the rare and limited instances of invention in the plastic arts,<br />

or in mathematics, the individual cannot think and communicate his thought, the<br />

governor and legislator cannot act effectively or frame his laws, without words, and the<br />

solidity and validity of these words is in the care of the damned and despised litterati.<br />

When their work goes rotten—by that I do not mean when they express indecorous<br />

thoughts—but when their very medium, the very essence of their work, the application<br />

of word to thing goes rotten, i.e. becomes slushy and inexact, or excessive or bloated, the<br />

whole machinery of social and of individual thought and order goes to pot. This is a<br />

lesson of history, and a lesson not yet half learned.<br />

<strong>The</strong> great writers need no debunking.<br />

<strong>The</strong> pap is not in them, and doesn't need to be squeezed out. <strong>The</strong>y do not lend<br />

themselves to imperial and sentimental exploitations. A civilization was founded on Homer,<br />

civilization not a mere bloated empire. <strong>The</strong> Macedonian domination rose and grew<br />

after the sophists. It also subsided.<br />

It is not only a question of rhetoric, of loose expression, but also of the loose<br />

use of individual words. What, the renaissance<br />

21


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 29<br />

gained in direct examination of natural phenomena, it in part lost in losing the feel<br />

and desire for exact descriptive terms. I mean that the medieval mind had little but<br />

words to deal with, and it was more careful in its definitions and verbiage. It did<br />

not define a gun in terms that would just as well define an explosion, nor<br />

explosions in terms that would define triggers.<br />

Misquoting Confucius, one might say: It does not matter whether the author<br />

desire the good of the race or acts merely from personal vanity. <strong>The</strong> thing is<br />

mechanical in action. In proportion as his work is exact, i.e., true to human<br />

consciouness and to the nature of man, as it is exact in formulation of desire, so<br />

is it durable and so is it `useful'; I mean it maintains the precision and clarity of<br />

thought, not merely for the benefit of a few dilettantes and 'lovers of literature', but<br />

maintains the health of thought outside literary circles and in non-literary<br />

existence, in general individual and communal life.<br />

Or ce genre on n'emeut que par la clarté. One 'moves' the reader only by<br />

clarity. In depicting the motions of the 'human heart' the durability of the writing<br />

depends on the exactitude. It , is the thing that is true and stays true that keeps<br />

fresh for the new reader.<br />

With this general view in mind, and subsequent to the events already set<br />

forth in this narrative, I proposed (from the left bank of the Seine, and to an<br />

American publishing house), not the twelve-volume anthology, but a short guide to<br />

the subject. That was after a few years of 'pause and reflection'. <strong>The</strong> subject was<br />

pleasantly received and considered with amity, but the house finally decided that<br />

it would pay neither them to print nor me to write the book, because we 'weren't in<br />

the text-book ring'. For the thing would have been a text-book, its circulation would<br />

have depended on educators, and educators have been defined as 'men with no<br />

intellectual interests'.<br />

Hence, after a lapse of four years, this essay, dedicated to Mr Glenn Frank,<br />

and other starters of ideal universities, though not with any great hope that it will<br />

rouse them.<br />

PART II: OR WHAT MAY BE AN INTRODUCTION<br />

TO METHOD<br />

It is as important for the purpose of thought to keep language<br />

efficient as it is in surgery to keep tetanus bacilli out of one's bandages.<br />

22


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 30<br />

In introducing a person to literature one would do well to have<br />

him examine works where language is efficiently used; to devise a system for getting<br />

directly and expeditiously at such works, despite the smokescreens erected by halfknowing<br />

and half-thinking critics. To get at them, despite the mass of dead matter<br />

that these people have heaped up and conserved round about them in the proportion:<br />

one barrel of sawdust to each half-bunch of grapes.<br />

Great literature is simply language charged with meaning to the utmost possible<br />

degree.<br />

When we set about examining it we find that this charging has been done by<br />

several clearly definable sorts of people, and by a periphery of less determinate sorts.<br />

(a) <strong>The</strong> inventors, discoverers of a particular process or of more than one mode<br />

and process. Sometimes these people are known, or discoverable for example, we know,<br />

with reasonable certitude, that Arnaut Daniel introduced certain methods of rhyming,<br />

and we know that certain finenesses of perception appeared first in such a troubadour<br />

or in G. Cavalcanti. We do not know, and are not likely to know, anything definite<br />

about the precursors of Homer.<br />

(6) <strong>The</strong> masters. This is a very small class, and there are very few real ones.<br />

<strong>The</strong> term is properly applied to inventors who, apart from their own inventions, are<br />

able to assimilate and co-ordinate a large number of preceding inventions. I mean<br />

to say they either start with a core of their own and accumulate adjuncts, or they<br />

digest a vast mass of subject-matter, apply a number of known modes of expression,<br />

and succeed in pervading the whole with some special quality or some special<br />

character of their own, and bring the whole to a state of homogeneous fullness.<br />

(c) <strong>The</strong> diluters, these who follow either the inventors or the `great writers', and<br />

who produce something of lower intensity, some flabbier variant, some diffuseness or<br />

tumidity in the wake of the valid.<br />

(d) (And this class produces the great bulk of all writing.) <strong>The</strong> men who do more<br />

or less good work in the more or less good style of a period. Of these the delightful<br />

anthologies, the song books, are full, and choice among them is the matter of taste,<br />

for you prefer Wyatt to Donne, Donne to Herrick, Drummond of Hawthornden to<br />

Browne, in response to some purely personal sympathy, these people add but some<br />

slight personal flavour, some minor variant of a mode, without affecting the main course<br />

of the story. {23}


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 31<br />

(e)<br />

At their faintest `Ifs n'existent pas, leur ambiance fear confert tine existence.' <strong>The</strong>y do<br />

not exist: their ambience confers existence upon them. When they are most prolific they<br />

produce dubious cases like Virgil and Petrarch, who probably pass, among the less<br />

exigeant, for colossi.<br />

(e) Belles Lewes. Longus, Prevost, Benjamin Constant, who are not exactly 'great<br />

masters', who can hardly be said to have originated a form, but who have nevertheless<br />

brought some mode to a very high development.<br />

(f) And there is a supplementary or sixth class of writers, the starters of crazes,<br />

the Ossianic McPhee sons, the Gongorasi whose wave of fashion flows over writing<br />

for a few centuries or a few decades, and then subsides, leaving things as they were.<br />

It will be seen that the first two classes are the more sharply defined: that the<br />

difficulty of classification for particular lesser authors increases as one descends<br />

the list, save for the last class, which is again fairly clear.<br />

<strong>The</strong> point is, that if a man knows the facts about the first two categories, he can<br />

evaluate almost any unfamiliar book at first sight. I mean he can form a just estimate<br />

of its worth, and see how and where it belongs in this schema.<br />

As to crazes, the number of possible diseases in literature is perhaps not very<br />

great, the same afflictions crop up in widely separated countries without any previous<br />

communication. <strong>The</strong> good physician will recognize a known malady, even if the<br />

manifestation be superficially different.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that six different critics will each have a different view concerning what<br />

author belongs in which of the categories here given, does not in the least invalidate<br />

the categories. When a man knows the facts about the first two categories, the reading<br />

of work in the other categories will not greatly change his opinion about those in the<br />

first two.<br />

LANGUAGE<br />

Obviously this knowledge cannot be acquired without knowledge of<br />

various tongues. <strong>The</strong> same discoveries have served a number of<br />

races. If a man has not time to learn different languages he can at<br />

1 One should perhaps apologize, or express a doubt as to the origin of Gon-<br />

gorism, or redefine it or start blaming it on some other Spaniard.<br />

24


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 32<br />

least, and with very little delay, be told what the discoveries were. If he wish to be<br />

a good critic he will have to look for himself.<br />

Bad critics have prolonged the use of demoded terminology, usually a<br />

terminology originally invented to describe what had been done before 300 B.C., and to<br />

describe it in a rather exterior fashion. Writers of second order have often tried to<br />

produce works to fit some category or term not yet occupied in their own local<br />

literature. If we chuck out the classifications which apply to the outer shape of the<br />

work, or to its occasion, and if we look at what actually happens, in, let us say, poetry,<br />

we will find that the language is charged or energized in various manners.<br />

That is to say, there are three 'kinds of poetry':<br />

MELOPOELIA, wherein the words are charged, over and above their plain meaning,<br />

with some musical property, which directs the bearing or trend of that meaning.<br />

PHANOPOEIA, which is a casting of images upon the visual imagination.<br />

LOGOPOEIA 'the dance of the intellect among words', that is to say, it employs<br />

words not only for their direct meaning, but it takes count in a special way of habits of<br />

usage, of the context we expect to find with the word, its usual concomitants, of its<br />

known acceptances, and of ironical play. It holds the aesthetic content which is<br />

peculiarly the domain of verbal manifestation, and cannot possibly be contained in<br />

plastic or in music. It is the latest come, and perhaps most tricky and undependable<br />

mode.<br />

<strong>The</strong> melopoeia can be appreciated by a foreigner with a sensitive ear, even though<br />

he be ignorant of the language in which the poem is written. It is practically impossible<br />

to transfer or translate it from one language to another, save perhaps by divine<br />

accident, and for half a line at a time.<br />

Phanopceia can, on the other hand, be translated almost, or wholly, intact. When it is<br />

good enough, it is practically impossible for the translator to destroy it save by very<br />

crass bungling, and the neglect of perfectly well-known and formulative rules.<br />

Logopoeia does not translate; though the attitude of mind it expresses may<br />

pass through a paraphrase. Or one might say, you can not translate it 'locally', but<br />

having determined the original author's state of mind, you may or may not be able to<br />

find a derivative or an equivalent.<br />

25


PROSE<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 33<br />

<strong>The</strong> language of prose is much less highly charged, that is perhaps the only<br />

availing distinction between prose and poesy. Prose permits greater factual<br />

presentation, explicitness, but a much greater amount of language is needed. During<br />

the last century or century and a half, prose has, perhaps for the first time, perhaps<br />

for the second or third time, arisen to challenge the poetic pre-eminence. That is<br />

to say, Coeur Simple, by Flaubert, is probably more important than<br />

<strong>The</strong>ophile Gautier's Carmen, etc.<br />

<strong>The</strong> total charge in certain nineteenth-century prose works possibly<br />

surpasses the total charge found in individual poems of that period; but that merely<br />

indicates that the author has been able to get his effect cumulatively, by a greater<br />

heaping up of factual data; imagined fact, if you will, but nevertheless<br />

expressed in factual manner.<br />

By using several hundred pages of prose, Flaubert, by force of architectonics,<br />

manages to attain an intensity comparable to that in Villon's Heaulmiere, or his<br />

prayer for his mother. This does not invalidate my dissociation of the two<br />

terms: poetry, prose.<br />

In Phanopoeia we find the greatest drive toward utter precision of word; this<br />

art exists almost exclusively by it.<br />

In melopoeia we find a contrary current, a force tending often to lull, or to<br />

distract the reader from the exact sense of the language. It is poetry on the<br />

borders of music and music is perhaps the bridge between consciousness and the<br />

unthinking sentient or even insentient universe.<br />

All writing is built up of these three elements, plus 'architectonics' or 'the form of<br />

the whole', and to know anything about the relative efficiency of various works one<br />

must have some knowledge of the maximum already attained by various authors,<br />

irrespective of where and when.'<br />

It is not enough to know that the Greeks attained to the greatest skill in<br />

melopoeia, or even that the Provençaux added certain diverse developments and<br />

that some quite minor, nineteenth-century Frenchmen achieved certain<br />

elaborations.<br />

It is not quite enough to have the general idea that the Chinese<br />

2 Lacuna at this point to be corrected in criticism of Hindemith's<br />

Schwanendreher'. E.P. Sept. 1938.<br />

26


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 34<br />

(more particularly Rihaku and Omakitsu) attained the known maximum of<br />

phanopoeia, due perhaps to the nature of their written ideograph, or to wonder whether<br />

Rimbaud is, at rare moments, their equal. One wants one's knowledge in more definite<br />

terms.<br />

It is an error to think that vast reading will automatically produce any such<br />

knowledge or understanding. Neither Chaucer with his forty books, nor Shakespeare<br />

with perhaps half a dozen, in folio, can be considered illiterate. A man can learn more<br />

music by working on a Bach fugue until he can take it apart and put it together, than<br />

by playing through ten dozen heterogeneous albums.<br />

You may say that for twenty-seven years I have thought consciously about this<br />

particular matter, and read or read at a great many books,<br />

4and that with the subject never really out of my mind, I don't yet know half<br />

there is to know about melopoeia.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are, on the other hand, a few books that I still keep on my desk, and a great<br />

number that I shall never open again. But the books that a man needs to know in order<br />

to 'get his bearings', in order to have a sound judgement of any bit of writing that may<br />

come before him, are very few. <strong>The</strong> list is so short, indeed, that one wonders that people,<br />

professional writers in particular, are willing to leave them ignored and to continue<br />

dangling in mid-chaos emitting the most imbecile estimates, and often vitiating their<br />

whole lifetime's production.<br />

Limiting ourselves to the authors who actually invented something, or who are<br />

the 'first known examples' of the process in working order, we find:<br />

OF THE GREEK& Homer, Sappho. (<strong>The</strong> 'great dramatists' decline from Homer,<br />

and depend immensely on him for their effects; their `charge’, at its highest potential,<br />

depends so often, and so greatly on their being able to count on their audience's<br />

knowledge of the Iliad. Even Aeschylus is rhetorical.) 1<br />

OF THE ROMANS: As we have lost Philetas, and most of Callimachus, we may<br />

suppose that the Romans added a certain sophistication; at any rate, Catullus, Ovid,<br />

Propertius, all give us some-<br />

' thing we cannot find now in Greek authors.<br />

A specialist may read Horace if he is interested in learning the precise<br />

demarcation between what can be learned about writing, and<br />

2 E.P.'s later and unpublished notes, revise all this in so far as they demand<br />

much greater recognition of Sophokles.<br />

27


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 35<br />

what cannot. I mean that Horace is the perfect example of a man who acquired all that is<br />

acquirable, without having the root. I beg the reader to observe that I am being<br />

exceedingly iconoclastic, that I am omitting thirty established names for every two I<br />

include. I am chucking out Pindar, and Virgil, without the slightest compunction. I<br />

do not suggest a 'course' in Greek or Latin literature, I name a few isolated writers; five<br />

or six pages of Sappho. One can throw out at least one-third of Ovid. That is to say,<br />

I am omitting the authors who can teach us no new or no more effective method of<br />

`charging words.<br />

OF THE MIDDLE AGES: <strong>The</strong> Anglo-Saxon Seafarer, and some more cursory<br />

notice of some medieval narrative, it does not so greatly matter what narrative,<br />

possibly the Beowulf, the Poema del Cid, and the sagas of Grettir and Burnt Nial.<br />

And then, in contrast, troubadours, perhaps thirty poems in Provençal, and for<br />

comparison with them a few songs by Von Morungen, or Wolfram von Essenbach,<br />

and von der Vogelweide; and then Bion's Death. of Adonis.<br />

From which mixture, taken in this order, the reader will get his bearings on the<br />

art of poetry made to be sung; for there are three kinds of melopoeia; ( 1) that made<br />

to be sung to a tune; (2) that made to be intoned or sung to a sort of chant; and (3)<br />

that made to be spoken; and the art of joining words in each of these kinds is different,<br />

and cannot be clearly understood until the reader knows that there are three<br />

different objectives.<br />

OF THE ITALIANS: Guido Cavalcanti and Dante; perhaps a dozen and a half poems of<br />

Guido's, and a dozen poems by his contemporaries, and the Divine Commedia.<br />

In Italy, around the year 1300, there were new values established, things said that<br />

had not been said in Greece, or in Rome or elsewhere.<br />

VILLON: After Villon and for several centuries, poetry can, be considered as fioritura, as<br />

an efflorescence, almost an effervescence, and without any new roots. Chaucer is an<br />

enrichment, one might say ,a more creamy version of the 'matter of France', and he in<br />

some measure preceded the verbal richness of the classic revival, but beginning with<br />

the Italians after Dante, coming through the Latin writers of the Renaissance, French,<br />

Spanish, English, Tasso, Ariosto, etc., the Italians always a little in the lead, the<br />

whole is elaboration, medieval basis, and wash after wash of Roman or Hellenic<br />

influence. I mean<br />

28


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 36<br />

one need not read any particular part of it for purpose of learning one's comparative<br />

values.<br />

If one were studying history and not poetry, one might discover the medieval<br />

mind more directly in the opening of Mussato's Ecerinus than even in Dante. <strong>The</strong><br />

culture of Chaucer is the same as that which went contemporaneously into<br />

Ferrara, with the tongue called' francoveneto'<br />

One must emphasize one's contrasts in the quattrocento. One can take Vilion as pivot<br />

for understanding them. After Villon, and having begun before his time, we find this foritura,<br />

and for centuries we find little else, Even in Marlowe and Shakespeare there is this<br />

embroidery of language, this talk about the matter, rather than presentation. I doubt if<br />

anyone ever acquired discrimination in studying `<strong>The</strong> Elizabethan?. You have grace,<br />

richness of language, abundance, but you have probably nothing that isn't replaceable<br />

by something else, no ornament that wouldn't have done just as well in some other<br />

connection, or for which some other figure of rhetoric couldn't have served, or which<br />

couldn't have been distilled from literary antecedents.<br />

<strong>The</strong> `language' had not been heard on the London stage, but it had been heard in the<br />

Italian law courts, etc.; there were local attempts, all over Europe, to teach the public (in<br />

Spain, Italy, England) Latin<br />

diction. 'Poetry' was considered to be (as it still is considered by a great number of<br />

drivelling imbeciles) synonymous with 'lofty and flowery language'.<br />

One Elizabethan specialist has suggested that Shakespeare, disgusted with his<br />

efforts, or at least despairing of success, as a poet, took to the stage. <strong>The</strong> drama is a mixed<br />

art; it does not rely on the charge that can be put into the word, but calls on gesture<br />

and mimicry and 'impersonation' for assistance. <strong>The</strong> actor must do a good half of the<br />

work. One does no favour to drama by muddling the two sets of problems.<br />

Apologists for the drama are continually telling us in one way or another that drama<br />

either cannot use at all, or can make but a very limited use of words charged to their<br />

highest potential. This is perfectly true. Let us try to keep our minds on the problem<br />

we started with, i.e., the art of writing, the art of 'charging' language with meaning.<br />

After 1450 we have the age of fioritura; after Marlowe and<br />

29


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 37<br />

Shakespeare came what was called a 'classic' movement, a movement that<br />

restrained without inventing. Anything that happens to mind in England has<br />

usually happened somewhere else first. Someone invents something, then someone<br />

develops, or some dozens develop a frothy or at any rate creamy enthusiasm or overabundance,<br />

then someone tries to tidy things up. For example, the estimable<br />

Pleiad emasculating the French tongue, and the French classicists, and the English<br />

classicists, etc., all of which things should be relegated to the subsidiary zone: period<br />

interest, historical interest, bric-a-brac for museums.<br />

At this point someone says: '0, but the ballads'. All right, I will allow the<br />

voracious peruser a half-hour for ballads (English and Spanish, or Scottish, Border,<br />

and Spanish). <strong>The</strong>re is nothing easier than to be distracted from one's point, or from<br />

the main drive of one's subject by a desire for utterly flawless equity and omniscience.<br />

Let us say, but directly in parenthesis, that there was a very limited sort of<br />

logopoeia in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century satire. And that Rochester and Dorset<br />

may have introduced a new note, or more probably re-introduced an old one, that<br />

reappears later in Heine.<br />

Let us also cut loose from minor details and minor exceptions: the main fact is that<br />

we 'have come' or that 'humanity came' to a point where verse-writing can or could no<br />

longer be clearly understood without the study of prose-writing.<br />

Say, for the sake of argument, that after the slump of the Middle Ages, prose 'came<br />

to' again in Machiavelli; admit that various sorts of prose had existed, in fact nearly all<br />

sorts had existed. Herodotus wrote history that is literature. Thucydides was a<br />

journalist. (It is a modern folly to suppose that vulgarity and cheapness have the<br />

merit of novelty; they have always existed, and are of no interest in themselves.)<br />

<strong>The</strong>re have been bombast, oratory, legal speech, balanced sentences, Ciceronian<br />

impressiveness; Petronius had written a satiric novel, Longus had written a delicate<br />

nouvelle. <strong>The</strong> prose of the Renaissance leaves us Rabelais, Brantôme, Montaigne. A<br />

determined specialist can dig interesting passages, or sumptuous passages, or even<br />

subtle passages out of Pico, the medieval mystics, scholastics, platonists, none of<br />

which will be the least use to a man trying to learn the art of 'changing language'.<br />

30


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 38<br />

I mean to say mat from the beginning of literature up to A.D. 1750 poetry was the<br />

superior art, and was so considered to be, and if we read books written before that<br />

date we find the number of interesting books in verse at least equal to the number<br />

of prose books still readable; and the poetry contains the quintessence. When<br />

we want<br />

to know what people were like before 1750, when we want to know that they had<br />

blood and bones like ourselves, we go to the poetry of the period.<br />

But, as I have said, the 'fioritura business' set in. And one morning Monsieur<br />

Stendhal, not thinking of Homer, or Villon, or Catullus, but having a very keen<br />

sense of actuality, noticed that 'poetry', la poesie, as the term was then understood,<br />

the stuff written by his French contemporaries, or sonorously rolled at him from the<br />

French stage, was a damn nuisance. And he remarked that poetry, with its bagwigs<br />

and its bobwigs, and its padded calves and its periwigs, its `fustian a la Louis XIV',<br />

was greatly inferior to prose for conveying a clear idea of the diverse states of our<br />

consciousness (les mouvements du cceur').<br />

And at that moment the serious art of writing `went over to prose', and for some<br />

time the important developments of language as means of expression were the<br />

developments of prose. And a man cannot clearly understand or justly judge the<br />

value of verse, modern verse, any verse, unless he has grasped this.<br />

PART III: CONCLUSIONS, EXCEPTIONS,<br />

CURRICULA<br />

Before Stendhal there is probably nothing in prose that does not also exist in<br />

verse or that can't be done by verse just as well as by prose. Even the method of<br />

annihilating imbecility employed by Voltaire, Bayle, and Lorenzo Valla can be<br />

managed quite as well in rhymed couplets.<br />

Beginning with the Renaissance, or perhaps with Boccaccio, we have prose<br />

that is quite necessary to the clear comprehension of things in general: with<br />

Rabelais, Brantome, Montaigne, Fielding, Sterne, we begin to find prose recording<br />

states of consciouness that their verse-writing contemporaries scamp. And this<br />

fuller consciousness, in more delicate modes, appears in l'Abbe Prevost,<br />

Benjamin Constant, Jane Austen. So that Stendhal had already<br />

31


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 39<br />

`something back of him' when he made his remarks about the inferiority of `La<br />

Poesie'.<br />

During the nineteenth century the superiority, if temporary, is at any rate<br />

obvious, and to such degree that I believe no man can now write really good verse<br />

unless he knows Stendhal and Flaubert. Or, let us say, Le Rouge et le Noir, the first<br />

half of La Chartreuse, Madame Bovary, L'Education, Les Trois Contes, Bouvard et<br />

Pecuchet. To put it per-haps more strongly, he will learn more about the art of charging<br />

words from Flaubert than he will from the floribund sixteenth-century dramatists.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main expression of nineteenth-century consciousness is in prose. <strong>The</strong> art<br />

continues in Maupassant, who slicked up the Flaubertian mode. <strong>The</strong> art of popular<br />

success lies simply in never putting more on any one page than the most ordinary<br />

reader can lick off it in his normally rapid, half-attentive skim-over. <strong>The</strong><br />

Goncourts strug-gled with praiseworthy sobriety, noble, but sometimes dull.<br />

Henry James was the first person to add anything to the art of the nineteenthcentury<br />

novel not already known to the French.<br />

Thought was churned up by Darwin, by science, by industrial machines,<br />

Nietzsche made a temporary commotion, but these things are extraneous to our subject,<br />

which is the art of getting meaning into words. <strong>The</strong>re is an 'influence of Ibsen', all for the<br />

good, but now exploited by cheap-jacks. Fabre and Frazer are both essential to<br />

contemporary clear thinking. I am not talking about the books that have poured<br />

something into the general consciousness, but of books that show how the pouring is<br />

done or display the implements, newly discovered, by which one can pour.<br />

<strong>The</strong> nineteenth-century novel is such an implement. <strong>The</strong> Ibsen play is, or<br />

perhaps we must say was, such an implement.<br />

It is for us to think whether these implements are more effective than poetry: (a)<br />

as known before 1800; (b) as known during the nineteenth century and up to the<br />

present.<br />

FRANCE<br />

<strong>The</strong> decline of England began on the day when Landor packed his trunks and<br />

departed to Tuscany. Up till then England had been able to contain her best authors;<br />

after that we see Shelley, Keats, Byron, Beddoes on the Continent, and still later<br />

observe the edifying spectacle of Browning in Italy and Tennyson in Buckingham<br />

Palace.<br />

{32}


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 40<br />

In France, as the novel developed, spurred on, shall we say, by the activity in<br />

the prose-media, the versifiers were not idle.<br />

Departing from Albertus, Gautier developed the medium we find in the Emaux<br />

et Camées. England in the 'nineties had got no further than the method of the<br />

Albertus. If Corbière invented no process he at any rate restored French verse to the<br />

vigour of Villon and to an intensity that no Frenchman had touched during the<br />

intervening four centuries.<br />

Unless I am right in discovering logopoeia in Propertius (which means unless<br />

the academic teaching of Latin displays crass insensitivity as it probably does), we<br />

must almost say that Laforgue invented logopoeia observing that there had<br />

been a very limited range of logopoeia in all satire, and that Heine occasionally<br />

employs something like it, together with a dash of bitters, such as can (though he<br />

may not have known it) be found in a few verses of Dorset and Rochester. At<br />

any rate Laforgue found or refound logopoeia. And Rimbaud brought back to<br />

phanopoeia its clarity and directness.<br />

All four of these poets, Gautier, Corbière, Laforgue, Rimbaud, redeem poetry<br />

from Stendhal's condemnation. <strong>The</strong>re is in Corbière something one finds nowhere<br />

before him, unless in Villon.<br />

Laforgue is not like any preceding poet. He is not ubiquitously like Propertius.<br />

In Rimbaud the image stands clean, unencumbered by nonfunctioning<br />

words; to get anything like this directness of presentation one must go back to<br />

Catullus, perhaps to the poem which contains dentes habet.<br />

If a man is too lazy to read the brief works of these poets, he cannot hope to<br />

understand writing, verse writing, prose writing, any writing.<br />

ENGLAND<br />

Against this serious action England can offer only Robert Browning. He has no<br />

French or European parallel. He has, indubitably, grave limitations, but <strong>The</strong> Ring<br />

and the Book is serious experimentation. He is a better poet than Landor, who<br />

was perhaps the only complete and serious man of letters ever born in these islands.<br />

We are so encumbered by having British literature in our foreground that even<br />

in this brief survey one must speak of it in disproportion. It was kept alive during<br />

the last century by a series of<br />

33


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 41<br />

exotic injections. Swinburne read Greek and took English metric in hand; Rossetti<br />

brought in the Italian primitives; FitzGerald made the only good poem of the time that<br />

has gone to the people; it is called, and is to a great extent, a trans- or mistranslation.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re was a faint waft of early French influence. Morris translated sagas, the<br />

Irish took over the business for a few years; Henry James led, or rather preceded,<br />

the novelists, and then the Britons resigned en bloc; the language is now in the<br />

keeping of the Irish (Yeats and Joyce); apart from Yeats, since the death of Hardy,<br />

poetry is being written by Americans. All the developments in English verse since<br />

1910 are due almost wholly to Americans. In fact, there is no longer any reason to<br />

call it English verse, and there is no present reason to think of England at all.<br />

We speak a language that was English. When Richard Coeur de Lion first heard<br />

Turkish he said: 'He spik lak a fole Britain.’ From which orthography one judges that<br />

Richard himself probably spoke like a French-Canadian.<br />

It is a magnificent language, and there is no need of, or advantage in, minimizing<br />

the debt we owe to Englishmen who died before 1620. Neither is there any point in<br />

studying the 'History of English Literature' as taught. Curiously enough, the<br />

histories of Spanish and Italian literature always take count of translators. Histories of<br />

English literature always slide over translation—I suppose it is inferiority complex—<br />

yet some of the best books in English are translations. This is important for two<br />

reasons. First, the reader who has been appalled by the preceding parts and said,<br />

'Oh, but I can't learn all these languages', may in some measure be comforted. He<br />

can learn the art of writing precisely where so many great local lights learned it if<br />

not from the definite poems I have listed, at least from the men who learned it from<br />

those poems in the first place.<br />

We may count the Seafarer, the Beowulf, and the remaining Anglo-Saxon fragments<br />

as indigenous art; at least, they dealt with a native subject, and by an art not newly<br />

borrowed. Whether alliterative metre owes anything to Latin hexameter is a<br />

question open to debate; we have no present means of tracing the debt. Landor<br />

suggests the problem in his dialogue of Ovid and the Prince of the Gaetae.<br />

After this period English literature lives on translation, it is fed by<br />

translation; every new exuberance, every new heave is stimu-<br />

{34}


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 42<br />

lated by translation, every allegedly great age is an age of translations, beginning with<br />

Geoffrey Chaucer, Le Grand Translateur, translator of the Romaunt of the Rose,<br />

paraphraser of Virgil and Ovid, condenser of old stories he had found in Latin,<br />

French, and Italian.<br />

After him even the ballads that tell a local tale tell it in art indebted to Europe. It<br />

is the natural spreading ripple that moves from the civilized Mediterranean centre<br />

out through the half-civilized and into the barbarous peoples.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Britons never have shed barbarism; they are proud to tell you that Tacitus<br />

said the last word about Germans. When Mary Queen of Scots went to Edinburgh<br />

she bewailed going out among savages, and she herself went from a sixteenthcentury<br />

court that held but a barbarous, or rather a drivelling and idiotic and<br />

superficial travesty of the Italian culture as it had been before the debacle of 1527. <strong>The</strong><br />

men who tried to civilize these shaggy and uncouth marginalians by bringing<br />

them news of civilization have left a certain number of translations that are better<br />

reading today than are the works of the ignorant islanders who were too proud to<br />

translate. After Chaucer we have Gavin Douglas's Eneados, better than the<br />

original, as Douglas had heard the sea. Golding's Metamorphoses, from which<br />

Shakespeare learned so much of his trade. Marlowe's translation of Ovid's Amores.<br />

We have no satisfactory translation of any Greek author. Chapman and Pope have<br />

left Iliads that are of interest to specialists; so far as I know, the only translation of<br />

Homer that one can read with continued pleasure is in early French by Hugues Salel;<br />

he, at least, was intent on telling the story, and not wholly muddled with accessories.<br />

I have discussed the merits of these translators elsewhere. I am now trying to tell the<br />

reader what he can learn of comparative literature through translations that are in<br />

themselves better reading than the 'original verse' of their periods. He can study the<br />

whole local development, or, we had better say, the sequence of local fashion in<br />

British verse by studying the translations of Horace that have poured in<br />

uninterrupted sequence from the British Press since 165o. That is work for a<br />

specialist, an historian, not for a man who wants simply to establish his axes of<br />

reference by knowing the best of each kind of written thing; as he would establish<br />

his axes of reference for painting by knowing a few pictures by Cimabue, Giotto,<br />

Piero della Francesca, Ambrogio de Predis, etc.; Velasquez, Goya, etc.<br />

{35}


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 43<br />

It is one thing to be able to spot the best painting and quite another and far<br />

less vital thing to know just where some secondary or tertiary painter learned certain<br />

defects.<br />

Apart from these early translations, a man may enlarge his view of international<br />

poetry by looking at Swinburne's Greek adaptations. <strong>The</strong> Greeks stimulated<br />

Swinburne; if he had defects, let us remember that, apart from Homer, the Greeks often<br />

were rather Swinburnian. Catullus wasn't, or was but seldom. From which one may<br />

learn the nature of the Latin, non-Greek contribution to the art of expression.'<br />

Swinburne's Villon is not Villon very exactly, but it is perhaps the best Swinburne<br />

we have. Rossetti's translations were perhaps better than Rossetti, and his Pita Nuova<br />

and early Italian poets guide one to originals, which he has now and again<br />

improved. Our contact with Oriental poetry begins with FitzGerald's Rubáiyát.<br />

Fenollosa's essay on the Chinese written character opens a door that the earlier<br />

students had, if not 'howled without', at least been unable to open.<br />

In mentioning these translations, I don't in the least admit or imply that any<br />

man in our time can think with only one language. He may be able to invent a new<br />

carburettor, or even work effectively in a biological laboratory, but he probably won't even<br />

try to do the latter without study of at least one foreign tongue. Modern science has<br />

always been multilingual. A good scientist simply would not be bothered to limit<br />

himself to one language and be held up for news of discoveries. <strong>The</strong> writer or reader<br />

who is content with such ignorance simplyadmits that his particularmind is of less<br />

importance than his kidneys or his automobile. <strong>The</strong> French who know no English<br />

are as fragmentary as. the Americans who know. no French. One simply leaves half<br />

of one's thought untouched in their company.<br />

Different languages --I mean the actual vocabularies, the idioms—have worked out<br />

certain mechanisms of communication and registration. No one language is complete.<br />

A master may be continually expanding his own tongue, rendering it fit to bear<br />

some charge hitherto borne only by some other alien tongue, but the process does not<br />

stop with any one man. While Proust is learning Henry James, preparatory to<br />

breaking through certain French paste-board partitions, the whole American speech<br />

is churning and chugging, and every other tongue doing likewise.<br />

To be 'possible' in mentally active company the American has to<br />

1 To be measured against the Sophoklean economy.<br />

36


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 44<br />

learn French, the Frenchman has to learn English or American. <strong>The</strong> Italian has for some<br />

time learned French. <strong>The</strong> man who does not know the Italian of the duocento and<br />

trecento has in him a painful lacuna, not necessarily painful to himself, but there<br />

are simply certain things he don't know, and can't; it is as if he were blind to<br />

some part of the spectrum. Because of the determined attempt of the patriotic<br />

Latinists of Italy in the renaissance to 'conquer' Greek by putting every Greek<br />

author effectively into Latin it is now possible to get a good deal of Greek through<br />

Latin cribs. <strong>The</strong> disuse of Latin cribs in Greek study, beginning, I suppose, about<br />

1820, has caused no end of damage to the general distribution of 'classic<br />

culture'.<br />

Another point miscomprehended by people who are clumsy at<br />

languages is that one does not need to learn a whole language in order to<br />

understand some one or some dozen poems. It is often enough to<br />

understand thoroughly the poem, and every one of the few dozen or few hundred<br />

words that compose it.<br />

This is what we start to do as small children when we memorize some lyric of<br />

Goethe or Heine. Incidentally, this process leaves us for life with a measuring rod (a)<br />

for a certain type of lyric, (6) for the German language, so that, however bored we<br />

may be by the Grundriss von Groeber, we never wholly forget the feel of the language.<br />

VACCINE<br />

Do I suggest a remedy? I do. I suggest several remedies. I suggest that we throw<br />

out all critics who use vague general terms. Not merely those who use vague terms<br />

because they are too ignorant to have a meaning; but the critics who use vague terms to<br />

conceal their meaning, and all critics who use terms so vaguely that the reader can think<br />

he agrees with them or assents to their statements when he doesn't.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first credential we should demand of a critic is his ideograph of the good; of<br />

what he considers valid writing, and indeed of all his general terms. <strong>The</strong>n we know<br />

where he is. He cannot simply stay in London writing of French pictures that his readers<br />

have not seen. He must begin by stating that such and such particular works seem to him<br />

`good', 'best', 'indifferent', 'valid', 'non-valid'. I suggest a definite curriculum in place of<br />

the present emiettements, of breaking the<br />

37


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 45<br />

subject up into crumbs quickly dryable. A curriculum for instructors, for<br />

obstreperous students who wish to annoy dull instructors, for men who<br />

haven't had time for systematized college courses. Call it the minimum basis for<br />

a sound and liberal education in letters (with French and English 'aids' in<br />

parenthesis).<br />

CONFUCIUS—In full (there being no complete and intelligent English version,<br />

one would have either to learn Chinese or make use of the French version by<br />

Pauthier).<br />

HOMER—in full (Latin cribs, Hugues Salel in French, no satisfactory English,<br />

though Chapman can be used as reference).<br />

Ovid—And the Latin 'personal' poets, Catullus and Propertius. (Golding's<br />

Metamorphoses, Marlowe's Amores. <strong>The</strong>re is no useful English version of Catullus.)<br />

A PROVENCAL SONG Book—With cross reference to Minnesingers, and to Bion,<br />

perhaps thirty poems in all.<br />

DANTE—`And his circle'; that is to say Dante, and thirty poems by his<br />

contemporaries, mostly by Guido Cavalcanti.<br />

VILLON-<br />

PARENTHETICALLY—Some other medieval matter might be added, and some<br />

general outline of history of thought through the Renaissance.<br />

VOLTAIRE—That is to say, some incursion into his critical writings,<br />

not into his attempts at fiction and drama, and some dip into his<br />

contemporaries (prose).<br />

STENDHAL—(At least a book and half).<br />

FLAUBERT (omitting Salambo and the Tentation)—And the Goncourts.<br />

GAUTIER, CORBIERE, RIMBAUD.<br />

This would not overburden the three- or four-year student. After this<br />

inoculation he could be `with safety exposed' to modernity or anything else in<br />

literature. I mean he wouldn't lose his head or ascribe ridiculous values to<br />

works of secondary intensity. He would have axes of reference and, would I think,<br />

find them dependable.<br />

For the purposes of general education we could omit all study of monistic<br />

totemism and voodoo for at least fifty years and study of Shakespeare for thirty on<br />

the ground that acquaintance with these subjects is already very widely diffused,<br />

and that one absorbs quite enough knowledge of them from boring circumjacent<br />

conversation.<br />

This list does not, obviously, contain the names of every author<br />

38


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 46<br />

who has ever written a good poem or a good octave or sestet. It is the result of twentyseven<br />

years' thought on the subject and a resume of conclusions. That may be a<br />

reason for giving it some consideration. It is not a reason for accepting it as a finality.<br />

Swallowed whole it is useless. For practical class work the instructor should try,<br />

and incite his students to try, to pry out some element that I have included and to<br />

substitute for it something more valid. <strong>The</strong> intelligent lay reader will instinctively try<br />

to do this for himself.<br />

I merely insist that without this minimum the critic has almost no chance of sound<br />

judgment. Judgment will gain one more chance of soundness if he can be persuaded<br />

to consider Fenollosa's essay or some other, and to me unknown but equally effective,<br />

elucidation of the Chinese written character.<br />

Before I die I hope to see at least a. few of the best Chinese works printed<br />

bilingually, in the form. that Mori and Ariga prepared certain texts for Fenollosa, a 'crib',<br />

the picture of each letter accompanied ' by a full explanation.<br />

For practical contact with all past poetry that was actually sung in its own day I<br />

suggest that each dozen universities combine in employing a couple of singers who<br />

understand the meaning of words. Men like Yves Tinayre and Robert Maitland are<br />

available. A half-dozen hours spent in listening to the lyrics actually performed would<br />

give the student more knowledge of that sort of melopoeia than a year's work in<br />

philology. <strong>The</strong> Kennedy-Frasers have dug up music that fits the Beowulf. It was being<br />

used for heroic song in the Hebrides. <strong>The</strong>re is other available music, plenty of it, from at<br />

least the time of Faidit A.D. 1190).<br />

I cannot repeat too often or too forcibly my caution against so-called critics who<br />

talk 'all around the matter', and who do hot define their terms, and who won't say<br />

frankly that certain authors are demnition bores. Make a man tell you first and<br />

specially what writers he thinks are good writers, after that you can listen to his<br />

explanation.<br />

Naturally, certain professors who have invested all their intellectual capital, i.e.,<br />

spent a lot of time on some perfectly dead period, don't like to admit they've been<br />

sold, and they haven't often the courage to cut a loss. <strong>The</strong>re is no use in following<br />

them into the shadows.<br />

In the above list I take full responsibility for my omissions. I<br />

39


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 47<br />

have omitted `the Rhooshuns'. All right. Let a man judge them after he has encountered<br />

Charles Bovary; he will read them with better balance. I have omitted practically all<br />

the fustian included in curricula of French literature in American universities<br />

(Bossuet, Corneille, etc.) and in so doing I have not committed an oversight. I have<br />

touched German in what most of you will consider an insufficient degree. All right. I have<br />

done it. I rest my case.<br />

If one finds it convenient to think in chronological cycles, and wants to 'relate<br />

literature to history', I suggest the three convenient `breaks' or collapses. <strong>The</strong> fall of<br />

Alexander's Macedonian empire; the fall of the Roman empire; the collapse of Italy after i<br />

Soo, the fall of Lodovico Moro, and the sack of Rome. That is to say, human lucidity<br />

appears to have approached several times a sort of maximum, and then suffered a set-back.<br />

<strong>The</strong> great break in the use of language occurs, however, with the change from<br />

inflected to uninflected speech. It can't be too clearly understood that certain procedures<br />

are good for a language in which every word has a little final tag telling what part of<br />

speech it is, and what case if is in, and whether it is a subject, or an object or an<br />

accessory; and that these procedures are not good in English or French. Milton got<br />

into a mess trying to write English as if it were Latin. Lack of this dissociation is<br />

largely responsible for late renaissance floridity. One cannot at this point study all the<br />

maladies and all their variations. <strong>The</strong> study of misguided Latinization needs a treatise to<br />

itself.'<br />

1 Argument of this essay is elaborated in the author's ABC of Reading<br />

40


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 48<br />

From Charles Sanders Peirce, Collected Papers, ed by Charles Hartshorne<br />

and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1935), vol. 6.<br />

<strong>The</strong> numbers refer to paragraphs, following the now standard protocol for<br />

citation. Each number should be prefaced by 6.?e.g. 6.452- 6.493.<br />

CHAPTER 3<br />

A NEGLECTED ARGUMENT FOR THE REALITY OF GODn1<br />

n1. MUSEMENT<br />

452. <strong>The</strong> word "God," so "capitalized" (as we Americans say), is the<br />

definable proper name, signifying Ens necessarium; in my belief Really<br />

creator of all three Universes of Experience.<br />

Some words shall herein be capitalized when used, not as<br />

vernacular, but as terms defined. Thus an "idea" is the substance of an<br />

actual unitary thought or fancy; but "Idea," nearer Plato's idea of {idea},<br />

denotes anything whose Being consists in its mere capacity for getting<br />

fully represented, regardless of any person's faculty or impotence to<br />

represent it.<br />

453. "Real" is a word invented in the thirteenth century to signify having<br />

Properties, i.e. characters sufficing to identify their subject, and<br />

possessing these whether they be anywise attributed to it by any single<br />

man or group of men, or not. Thus, the substance of a dream is not Real,<br />

since it was such as it was, merely in that a dreamer so dreamed it; but<br />

the fact of the dream is Real, if it was dreamed; since if so, its date, the<br />

name of the dreamer, etc. make up a set of circumstances sufficient to<br />

distinguish it from all other events; and these belong to it, i.e. would be<br />

true if predicated of it, whether A, B, or C Actually ascertains them or not.<br />

<strong>The</strong> "Actual" is that which is met with in the past, present, or future.<br />

454. An "Experience" is a brutally produced conscious effect that<br />

contributes to a habit, self-controlled, yet so satisfying, on deliberation, as<br />

to be destructible by no positive exercise of internal vigour. I use the word<br />

"self-controlled" for "controlled by the thinker's self," and not for<br />

"uncontrolled" except in its own spontaneous, i.e. automatic, selfdevelopment,<br />

as Professor J. M. Baldwin n2 uses the word. Take for<br />

illustration the sensation undergone by a child that puts its forefinger into<br />

a flame with the acquisition of a habit of keeping all its members out of all<br />

flames. A compulsion is "Brute," whose immediate efficacy nowise consists<br />

in conformity to rule or reason.<br />

455. Of the three Universes of Experience familiar to us all n1, the first<br />

comprises all mere Ideas, those airy nothings to which the mind of poet,<br />

pure mathematician, or another might give local habitation and a name<br />

within that mind. <strong>The</strong>ir very airy-nothingness, the fact that their Being


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 49<br />

consists in mere capability of getting thought, not in anybody's Actually<br />

thinking them, saves their Reality. <strong>The</strong> second Universe is that of the<br />

Brute Actuality of things and facts. I am confident that their Being<br />

consists in reactions against Brute forces, notwithstanding objections<br />

redoubtable until they are closely and fairly examined. <strong>The</strong> third Universe<br />

comprises everything whose being consists in active power to establish<br />

connections between different objects, especially between objects in<br />

different Universes. Such is everything which is essentially a Sign -- not<br />

the mere body of the Sign, which is not essentially such, but, so to speak,<br />

the Sign's Soul, which has its Being in its power of serving as intermediary<br />

between its Object and a Mind. Such, too, is a living consciousness, and<br />

such the life, the power of growth, of a plant. Such is a living constitution -<br />

- a daily newspaper, a great fortune, a social "movement."<br />

456. An "Argument" is any process of thought reasonably tending to<br />

produce a definite belief.n2 An "Argumentation" is an Argument<br />

proceeding upon definitely formulated premisses.<br />

457. If God Really be, and be benign, then, in view of the generally<br />

conceded truth that religion, were it but proved, would be a good<br />

outweighing all others, we should naturally expect that there would be<br />

some Argument for His Reality that should be obvious to all minds, high<br />

and low alike, that should earnestly strive to find the truth of the matter;<br />

and further, that this Argument should present its conclusion, not as a<br />

proposition of metaphysical theology, but in a form directly applicable to<br />

the conduct of life, and full of nutrition for man's highest growth. What I<br />

shall refer to as the N.A. -- the Neglected Argument -- seems to me best to<br />

fulfill this condition, and I should not wonder if the majority of those<br />

whose own reflections have harvested belief in God must bless the<br />

radiance of the N.A. for that wealth. Its persuasiveness is no less than<br />

extraordinary; while it is not unknown to anybody. Nevertheless, of all<br />

those theologians (within my little range of reading) who, with<br />

commendable assiduity, scrape together all the sound reasons they can<br />

find or concoct to prove the first proposition of theology, few mention this<br />

one, and they most briefly. <strong>The</strong>y probably share those current notions of<br />

logic which recognize no other Arguments than Argumentations.<br />

458. <strong>The</strong>re is a certain agreeable occupation of mind which, from its<br />

having no distinctive name, I infer is not as commonly practiced as it<br />

deserves to be; for indulged in moderately -- say through some five to six<br />

per cent of one's waking time, perhaps during a stroll -- it is refreshing<br />

enough more than to repay the expenditure. Because it involves no<br />

purpose save that of casting aside all serious purpose, I have sometimes<br />

been half-inclined to call it reverie with some qualification; but for a frame<br />

of mind so antipodal to vacancy and dreaminess such a designation would<br />

be too excruciating a misfit. In fact, it is Pure Play. Now, Play, we all know,<br />

is a lively exercise of one's powers. Pure Play has no rules, except this very


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 50<br />

law of liberty. It bloweth where it listeth. It has no purpose, unless<br />

recreation. <strong>The</strong> particular occupation I mean -- a petite bouch?e with the<br />

Universes -- may take either the form of aesthetic contemplation, or that of<br />

distant castle-building (whether in Spain or within one's own moral<br />

training), or that of considering some wonder in one of the Universes, or<br />

some connection between two of the three, with speculation concerning its<br />

cause. It is this last kind -- I will call it "Musement" on the whole -- that I<br />

particularly recommend, because it will in time flower into the N.A. One<br />

who sits down with the purpose of becoming convinced of the truth of<br />

religion is plainly not inquiring in scientific singleness of heart, and must<br />

aways suspect himself of reasoning unfairly. So he can never attain the<br />

entirety even of a physicist's belief in electrons, although this is avowedly<br />

but provisional. But let religious meditation be allowed to grow up<br />

spontaneously out of Pure Play without any breach of continuity, and the<br />

Muser will retain the perfect candour proper to Musement.<br />

459. If one who had determined to make trial of Musement as a favorite<br />

recreation were to ask me for advice, I should reply as follows: <strong>The</strong> dawn<br />

and the gloaming most invite one to Musement; but I have found no watch<br />

of the nychthemeron that has not its own advantages for the pursuit. It<br />

begins passively enough with drinking in the impression of some nook in<br />

one of the three Universes. But impression soon passes into attentive<br />

observation, observation into musing, musing into a lively give and take of<br />

communion between self and self. If one's observations and reflections are<br />

allowed to specialize themselves too much, the Play will be converted into<br />

scientific study; and that cannot be pursued in odd half hours.<br />

460. I should add: Adhere to the one ordinance of Play, the law of liberty. I<br />

can testify that the last half century, at least, has never lacked tribes of Sir<br />

Oracles, colporting brocards to bar off one or another roadway of inquiry;<br />

and a Rabelais would be needed to bring out all the fun that has been<br />

packed in their airs of infallibility. Auguste Comte, notwithstanding his<br />

having apparently produced some unquestionably genuine thinking, was<br />

long the chief of such a band. <strong>The</strong> vogue of each particular maxim of theirs<br />

was necessarily brief. For what distinction can be gained by repeating<br />

saws heard from all mouths? No bygone fashion seems more grotesque<br />

than a panache of obsolete wisdom. I remember the days when a<br />

pronouncement all the rage was that no science must borrow the methods<br />

of another; the geologist must not use a microscope, nor the astronomer a<br />

spectroscope. Optics must not meddle with electricity, nor logic with<br />

algebra. But twenty years later, if you aspired to pass for a commanding<br />

intellect, you would have to pull a long face and declare that "It is not the<br />

business of science to search for origins." This maxim was a masterpiece,<br />

since no timid soul, in dread of being thought naive, would dare inquire<br />

what "origins" were, albeit the secret confessor within his breast compelled<br />

the awful self-acknowledgment of his having no idea into what else than<br />

"origins" of phenomena (in some sense of that indefinite word) man can


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 51<br />

inquire. That human reason can comprehend some causes is past denial,<br />

and once we are forced to recognize a given element in experience, it is<br />

reasonable to await positive evidence before we complicate our<br />

acknowledgment with qualifications. Otherwise, why venture beyond direct<br />

observation? Illustrations of this principle abound in physical science.<br />

Since, then, it is certain that man is able to understand the laws and the<br />

causes of some phenomena, it is reasonable to assume, in regard to any<br />

given problem, that it would get rightly solved by man, if a sufficiency of<br />

time and attention were devoted to it. Moreover, those problems that at<br />

first blush appear utterly insoluble receive, in that very circumstance, as<br />

Edgar Poe remarked n1 in his "<strong>The</strong> Murders in the Rue Morgue," their<br />

smoothly-fitting keys. This particularly adapts them to the Play of<br />

Musement.<br />

461. Forty or fifty minutes of vigorous and unslackened analytic thought<br />

bestowed upon one of them usually suffices to educe from it all there is to<br />

educe, its general solution. <strong>The</strong>re is no kind of reasoning that I should<br />

wish to discourage in Musement; and I should lament to find anybody<br />

confining it to a method of such moderate fertility as logical analysis. Only,<br />

the Player should bear in mind that the higher weapons in the arsenal of<br />

thought are not playthings but edge-tools. In any mere Play they can be<br />

used by way of exercise alone; while logical analysis can be put to its full<br />

efficiency in Musement. So, continuing the counsels that had been asked<br />

of me, I should say, "Enter your skiff of Musement, push off into the lake<br />

of thought, and leave the breath of heaven to swell your sail. With your<br />

eyes open, awake to what is about or within you, and open conversation<br />

with yourself; for such is all meditation." It is, however, not a conversation<br />

in words alone, but is illustrated, like a lecture, with diagrams and with<br />

experiments.<br />

462. Different people have such wonderfully different ways of thinking that<br />

it would be far beyond my competence to say what courses Musements<br />

might not take; but a brain endowed with automatic control, as man's<br />

indirectly is, is so naturally and rightly interested in its own faculties that<br />

some psychological and semi-psychological questions would doubtless get<br />

touched; such, in the latter class, as this: Darwinians, with truly<br />

surprising ingenuity, have concocted, and with still more astonishing<br />

confidence have accepted as proved, one explanation for the diverse and<br />

delicate beauties of flowers, another for those of butterflies, and so on; but<br />

why is all nature -- the forms of trees, the compositions of sunsets --<br />

suffused with such beauties throughout, and not nature only, but the<br />

other two Universes as well? Among more purely psychological questions,<br />

the nature of pleasure and pain will be likely to attract attention. Are they<br />

mere qualities of feeling, or are they rather motor instincts attracting us to<br />

some feelings and repelling others? Have pleasure and pain the same sort<br />

of constitution, or are they contrasted in this respect, pleasure arising


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 52<br />

upon the forming or strengthening of an association by resemblance, and<br />

pain upon the weakening or disruption of such a habit or conception?n1<br />

463. Psychological speculations will naturally lead on to musings upon<br />

metaphysical problems proper, good exercise for a mind with a turn for<br />

exact thought. It is here that one finds those questions that at first seem<br />

to offer no handle for reason's clutch, but which readily yield to logical<br />

analysis. But problems of metaphysics will inevitably present themselves<br />

that logical analysis will not suffice to solve. Some of the best will be<br />

motived by a desire to comprehend universe-wide aggregates of<br />

unformulated but partly experienced phenomena. I would suggest that the<br />

Muser be not too impatient to analyze these, lest some significant<br />

ingredient be lost in the process; but that he begin by pondering them<br />

from every point of view, until he seems to read some truth beneath the<br />

phenomena.<br />

464. At this point a trained mind will demand that an examination be<br />

made of the truth of the interpretation; and the first step in such<br />

examination must be a logical analysis of the theory. But strict<br />

examination would be a task a little too serious for the Musement of hour<br />

fractions, and if it is postponed there will be ample remuneration even in<br />

the suggestions that there is not time to examine; especially since a few of<br />

them will appeal to reason as all but certain.<br />

Let the Muser, for example, after well appreciating, in its breadth<br />

and depth, the unspeakable variety of each Universe, turn to those<br />

phenomena that are of the nature of homogeneities of connectedness in<br />

each; and what a spectacle will unroll itself! As a mere hint of them I may<br />

point out that every small part of space, however remote, is bounded by<br />

just such neighbouring parts as every other, without a single exception<br />

throughout immensity. <strong>The</strong> matter of Nature is in every star of the same<br />

elementary kinds, and (except for variations of circumstance), what is<br />

more wonderful still, throughout the whole visible universe, about the<br />

same proportions of the different chemical elements prevail. Though the<br />

mere catalogue of known carbon-compounds alone would fill an unwieldy<br />

volume, and perhaps, if the truth were known, the number of amino-acids<br />

alone is greater, yet it is unlikely that there are in all more than about 600<br />

elements, of which 500 dart through space too swiftly to be held down by<br />

the earth's gravitation, coronium being the slowest-moving of these. This<br />

small number bespeaks comparative simplicity of structure. Yet no<br />

mathematician but will confess the present hopelessness of attempting to<br />

comprehend the constitution of the hydrogen-atom, the simplest of the<br />

elements that can be held to earth.<br />

465. From speculations on the homogeneities of each Universe, the Muser<br />

will naturally pass to the consideration of homogeneities and connections<br />

between two different Universes, or all three. Especially in them all we find


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 53<br />

one type of occurrence, that of growth, itself consisting in the<br />

homogeneities of small parts. This is evident in the growth of motion into<br />

displacement, and the growth of force into motion. In growth, too, we find<br />

that the three Universes conspire; and a universal feature of it is provision<br />

for later stages in earlier ones. This is a specimen of certain lines of<br />

reflection which will inevitably suggest the hypothesis of God's Reality. It is<br />

not that such phenomena might not be capable of being accounted for, in<br />

one sense, by the action of chance with the smallest conceivable dose of a<br />

higher element; for if by God be meant the Ens necessarium, that very<br />

hypothesis requires that such should be the case. But the point is that<br />

that sort of explanation leaves a mental explanation just as needful as<br />

before. Tell me, upon sufficient authority, that all cerebration depends<br />

upon movements of neurites that strictly obey certain physical laws, and<br />

that thus all expressions of thought, both external and internal, receive a<br />

physical explanation, and I shall be ready to believe you. But if you go on<br />

to say that this explodes the theory that my neighbour and myself are<br />

governed by reason, and are thinking beings, I must frankly say that it will<br />

not give me a high opinion of your intelligence. But however that may be,<br />

in the Pure Play of Musement the idea of God's Reality will be sure sooner<br />

or later to be found an attractive fancy, which the Muser will develop in<br />

various ways. <strong>The</strong> more he ponders it, the more it will find response in<br />

every part of his mind, for its beauty, for its supplying an ideal of life, and<br />

for its thoroughly satisfactory explanation of his whole threefold<br />

environment.<br />

n2. THE HYPOTHESIS OF GOD E<br />

466. <strong>The</strong> hypothesis of God is a peculiar one, in that it supposes an<br />

infinitely incomprehensible object, although every hypothesis, as such,<br />

supposes its object to be truly conceived in the hypothesis. This leaves the<br />

hypothesis but one way of understanding itself; namely, as vague yet as<br />

true so far as it is definite, and as continually tending to define itself more<br />

and more, and without limit. <strong>The</strong> hypothesis, being thus itself inevitably<br />

subject to the law of growth, appears in its vagueness to represent God as<br />

so, albeit this is directly contradicted in the hypothesis from its very first<br />

phase. But this apparent attribution of growth to God, since it is<br />

ineradicable from the hypothesis, cannot, according to the hypothesis, be<br />

flatly false. Its implications concerning the Universes will be maintained in<br />

the hypothesis, while its implications concerning God will be partly<br />

disavowed, and yet held to be less false than their denial would be. Thus<br />

the hypothesis will lead to our thinking of features of each Universe as<br />

purposed; and this will stand or fall with the hypothesis. Yet a purpose<br />

essentially involves growth, and so cannot be attributed to God. Still it will,<br />

according to the hypothesis, be less false to speak so than to represent<br />

God as purposeless.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 54<br />

467. Assured as I am from my own personal experience that every man<br />

capable of so controlling his attention as to perform a little exact thinking<br />

will, if he examines Zeno's argument about Achilles and the tortoise, come<br />

to think, as I do, that it is nothing but a contemptible catch,n1 I do not<br />

think that I either am or ought to be less assured, from what I know of the<br />

effects of Musement on myself and others, that any normal man who<br />

considers the three Universes in the light of the hypothesis of God's Reality,<br />

and pursues that line of reflection in scientific singleness of heart, will<br />

come to be stirred to the depths of his nature by the beauty of the idea<br />

and by its august practicality, even to the point of earnestly loving and<br />

adoring his strictly hypothetical God, and to that of desiring above all<br />

things to shape the whole conduct of life and all the springs of action into<br />

conformity with that hypothesis. Now to be deliberately and thoroughly<br />

prepared to shape one's conduct into conformity with a proposition is<br />

neither more nor less than the state of mind called Believing that<br />

proposition, however long the conscious classification of it under that head<br />

be postponed.n2<br />

n3. THE THREE STAGES OF INQUIRYE<br />

468. <strong>The</strong>re is my poor sketch of the Neglected Argument, greatly cut down<br />

to bring it within the limits assigned to this article. Next should come the<br />

discussion of its logicality; but nothing readable at a sitting could possibly<br />

bring home to readers my full proof of the principal points of such an<br />

examination. I can only hope to make the residue of this paper a sort of<br />

table of contents, from which some may possibly guess what I have to say;<br />

or to lay down a series of plausible points through which the reader will<br />

have to construct the continuous line of reasoning for himself. In my own<br />

mind the proof is elaborated, and I am exerting my energies to getting it<br />

submitted to public censure. My present abstract will divide itself into<br />

three unequal parts. <strong>The</strong> first shall give the headings of the different steps<br />

of every well-conducted and complete inquiry, without noticing possible<br />

divergencies from the norm. I shall have to mention some steps which<br />

have nothing to do with the Neglected Argument in order to show that they<br />

add no jot nor tittle to the truth which is invariably brought just as the<br />

Neglected Argument brings it. <strong>The</strong> second part shall very briefly state,<br />

without argument (for which there is no room), just wherein lies the logical<br />

validity of the reasoning characteristic of each of the main stages of<br />

inquiry. <strong>The</strong> third part shall indicate the place of the Neglected Argument<br />

in a complete inquiry into the Reality of God, and shall show how well it<br />

would fill that place, and what its logical value is supposing the inquiry to<br />

be limited to this; and I shall add a few words to show how it might be<br />

supplemented.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 55<br />

469. Every inquiry whatsoever takes its rise in the observation, in one or<br />

another of the three Universes, of some surprising phenomenon, some<br />

experience which either disappoints an expectation, or breaks in upon<br />

some habit of expectation of the inquisiturus; and each apparent<br />

exception to this rule only confirms it. <strong>The</strong>re are obvious distinctions<br />

between the objects of surprise in different cases; but throughout this<br />

slight sketch of inquiry such details will be unnoticed, especially since it is<br />

upon such that the logic-books descant. <strong>The</strong> inquiry begins with<br />

pondering these phenomena in all their aspects, in the search of some<br />

point of view whence the wonder shall be resolved. At length a conjecture<br />

arises that furnishes a possible Explanation, by which I mean a syllogism<br />

exhibiting the surprising fact as necessarily consequent upon the<br />

circumstances of its occurrence together with the truth of the credible<br />

conjecture, as premisses.n1 On account of this Explanation, the inquirer<br />

is led to regard his conjecture, or hypothesis, with favor. As I phrase it, he<br />

provisionally holds it to be "Plausible"; this acceptance ranges in different<br />

cases -- and reasonably so -- from a mere expression of it in the<br />

interrogative mood, as a question meriting attention and reply, up through<br />

all appraisals of Plausibility, to uncontrollable inclination to believe. <strong>The</strong><br />

whole series of mental performances between the notice of the wonderful<br />

phenomenon and the acceptance of the hypothesis, during which the<br />

usually docile understanding seems to hold the bit between its teeth and<br />

to have us at its mercy, the search for pertinent circumstances and the<br />

laying hold of them, sometimes without our cognizance, the scrutiny of<br />

them, the dark laboring, the bursting out of the startling conjecture, the<br />

remarking of its smooth fitting to the anomaly, as it is turned back and<br />

forth like a key in a lock, and the final estimation of its Plausibility, I<br />

reckon as composing the First Stage of Inquiry. Its characteristic formula<br />

of reasoning I term Retroduction,n1 i.e. reasoning from consequent to<br />

antecedent. In one respect the designation seems inappropriate; for in<br />

most instances where conjecture mounts the high peaks of Plausibility --<br />

and is really most worthy of confidence -- the inquirer is unable definitely<br />

to formulate just what the explained wonder is; or can only do so in the<br />

light of the hypothesis. In short, it is a form of Argument rather than of<br />

Argumentation.<br />

470. Retroduction does not afford security. <strong>The</strong> hypothesis must be tested.<br />

This testing, to be logically valid, must honestly start, not as<br />

Retroduction starts, with scrutiny of the phenomena, but with<br />

examination of the hypothesis, and a muster of all sorts of conditional<br />

experiential consequences which would follow from its truth. This<br />

constitutes the Second Stage of Inquiry. For its characteristic form of<br />

reasoning our language has, for two centuries, been happily provided with<br />

the name Deduction.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 56<br />

471. Deduction has two parts. For its first step must be by logical analysis<br />

to Explicate the hypothesis, i.e. to render it as perfectly distinct as possible.<br />

This process, like Retroduction, is Argument that is not Argumentation.<br />

But unlike Retroduction, it cannot go wrong from lack of experience, but<br />

so long as it proceeds rightly must reach a true conclusion. Explication is<br />

followed by Demonstration, or Deductive Argumentation. Its procedure is<br />

best learned from Book I of Euclid's Elements, a masterpiece which in real<br />

insight is far superior to Aristotle's Analytics; and its numerous fallacies<br />

render it all the more instructive to a close student. It invariably requires<br />

something of the nature of a diagram; that is, an "Icon," or Sign that<br />

represents its Object in resembling it. It usually, too, needs "Indices," or<br />

Signs that represent their Objects by being actually connected with them.<br />

But it is mainly composed of "Symbols," or Signs that represent their<br />

Objects essentially because they will be so interpreted. Demonstration<br />

should be Corollarial when it can. An accurate definition of Corollarial<br />

Demonstration would require a long explanation; but it will suffice to say<br />

that it limits itself to considerations already introduced or else involved in<br />

the Explication of its conclusion; while <strong>The</strong>orematic Demonstration resorts<br />

to a more complicated process of thought.n1<br />

472. <strong>The</strong> purpose of Deduction, that of collecting consequents of the<br />

hypothesis, having been sufficiently carried out, the inquiry enters upon<br />

its Third Stage, that of ascertaining how far those consequents accord with<br />

Experience, and of judging accordingly whether the hypothesis is sensibly<br />

correct, or requires some inessential modification, or must be entirely<br />

rejected. Its characteristic way of reasoning is Induction. This stage has<br />

three parts. For it must begin with Classification, which is an Inductive<br />

Non-argumentational kind of Argument, by which general Ideas are<br />

attached to objects of Experience; or rather by which the latter are<br />

subordinated to the former. Following this will come the testingargumentations,<br />

the Probations; and the whole inquiry will be wound up<br />

with the Sentential part of the Third Stage, which, by Inductive reasonings,<br />

appraises the different Probations singly, then their combinations, then<br />

makes self-appraisal of these very appraisals themselves, and passes final<br />

judgment on the whole result.<br />

473. <strong>The</strong> Probations, or direct Inductive Argumentations, are of two kinds.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first is that which Bacon ill described as "inductio illa qu? procedit per<br />

enumerationem simplicem." So at least he has been understood. For an<br />

enumeration of instances is not essential to the argument that, for<br />

example, there are no such beings as fairies, or no such events as miracles.<br />

<strong>The</strong> point is that there is no well-established instance of such a thing. I<br />

call this Crude Induction.n2 It is the only Induction which concludes a<br />

logically Universal Proposition. It is the weakest of arguments, being liable<br />

to be demolished in a moment, as happened toward the end of the<br />

eighteenth century to the opinion of the scientific world that no stones fall<br />

from the sky. <strong>The</strong> other kind is Gradual Induction,n1 which makes a new


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 57<br />

estimate of the proportion of truth in the hypothesis with every new<br />

instance; and given any degree of error there will sometime be an estimate<br />

(or would be, if the probation were persisted in) which will be absolutely<br />

the last to be infected with so much falsity. Gradual Induction is either<br />

Qualitative or Quantitative and the latter either depends on measurements,<br />

or on statistics, or on countings.<br />

n4. THE VALIDITY OF THE THREE STAGES<br />

474. Concerning the question of the nature of the logical validity<br />

possessed by Deduction, Induction, and Retroduction, which is still an<br />

arena of controversy, I shall confine myself to stating the opinions which I<br />

am prepared to defend by positive proofs. <strong>The</strong> validity of Deduction was<br />

correctly, if not very clearly, analyzed by Kant.n2 This kind of reasoning<br />

deals exclusively with Pure Ideas attaching primarily to Symbols and<br />

derivatively to other Signs of our own creation; and the fact that man has<br />

a power of Explicating his own meaning renders Deduction valid.<br />

Induction is a kind of reasoning that may lead us into error; but that it<br />

follows a method which, sufficiently persisted in, will be Inductively<br />

Certain (the sort of certainty we have that a perfect coin, pitched up often<br />

enough, will sometime turn up heads) to diminish the error below any<br />

predesignate degree, is assured by man's power of perceiving Inductive<br />

Certainty. In all this I am inviting the reader to peep through the big end<br />

of the telescope; there is a wealth of pertinent detail that must here be<br />

passed over.<br />

475. Finally comes the bottom question of logical Critic,n3 What sort of<br />

validity can be attributed to the First Stage of inquiry? Observe that<br />

neither Deduction nor Induction contributes the smallest positive item to<br />

the final conclusion of the inquiry. <strong>The</strong>y render the indefinite definite;<br />

Deduction Explicates; Induction evaluates: that is all. Over the chasm that<br />

yawns between the ultimate goal of science and such ideas of Man's<br />

environment as, coming over him during his primeval wanderings in the<br />

forest, while yet his very notion of error was of the vaguest, he managed to<br />

communicate to some fellow, we are building a cantilever bridge of<br />

induction, held together by scientific struts and ties. Yet every plank of its<br />

advance is first laid by Retroduction alone, that is to say, by the<br />

spontaneous conjectures of instinctive reason; and neither Deduction nor<br />

Induction contributes a single new concept to the structure. Nor is this<br />

less true or less important for those inquiries that self-interest prompts.<br />

476. <strong>The</strong> first answer we naturally give to this question is that we cannot<br />

help accepting the conjecture at such a valuation as that at which we do<br />

accept it; whether as a simple interrogation, or as more or less Plausible,<br />

or, occasionally, as an irresistible belief. But far from constituting, by itself,<br />

a logical justification such as it becomes a rational being to put forth, this


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 58<br />

pleading, that we cannot help yielding to the suggestion, amounts to<br />

nothing more than a confession of having failed to train ourselves to<br />

control our thoughts. It is more to the purpose, however, to urge that the<br />

strength of the impulse is a symptom of its being instinctive. Animals of all<br />

races rise far above the general level of their intelligence in those<br />

performances that are their proper function, such as flying and nestbuilding<br />

for ordinary birds; and what is man's proper function if it be not<br />

to embody general ideas in art-creations, in utilities, and above all in<br />

theoretical cognition? To give the lie to his own consciousness of divining<br />

the reasons of phenomena would be as silly in a man as it would be in a<br />

fledgling bird to refuse to trust to its wings and leave the nest, because the<br />

poor little thing had read Babinet,n1 and judged aerostation to be<br />

impossible on hydrodynamical grounds. Yes; it must be confessed that if<br />

we knew that the impulse to prefer one hypothesis to another really were<br />

analogous to the instincts of birds and wasps, it would be foolish not to<br />

give it play, within the bounds of reason; especially since we must<br />

entertain some hypothesis, or else forego all further knowledge than that<br />

which we have already gained by that very means. But is it a fact that man<br />

possesses this magical faculty? Not, I reply, to the extent of guessing right<br />

the first time, nor perhaps the second; but that the well-prepared mind<br />

has wonderfully soon guessed each secret of nature is historical truth. All<br />

the theories of science have been so obtained. But may they not have come<br />

fortuitously, or by some such modification of chance as the Darwinian<br />

supposes? I answer that three or four independent methods of<br />

computation show that it would be ridiculous to suppose our science to<br />

have so come to pass. Nevertheless, suppose that it can be so "explained,"<br />

just as that any purposed act of mine is supposed by materialistic<br />

necessitarians to have come about. Still, what of it? Does that materialistic<br />

explanation, supposing it granted, show that reason has nothing to do<br />

with my actions? Even the parallelists will admit that the one explanation<br />

leaves the same need of the other that there was before it was given; and<br />

this is certainly sound logic. <strong>The</strong>re is a reason, an interpretation, a logic,<br />

in the course of scientific advance, and this indisputably proves to him<br />

who has perceptions of rational or significant relations, that man's mind<br />

must have been attuned to the truth of things in order to discover what he<br />

has discovered. It is the very bedrock of logical truth.<br />

477. Modern science has been builded after the model of Galileo, who<br />

founded it, on il lume naturale. That truly inspired prophet had said that,<br />

of two hypotheses, the simpler is to be preferred;n1 but I was formerly one<br />

of those who, in our dull self-conceit fancying ourselves more sly than he,<br />

twisted the maxim to mean the logically simpler, the one that adds the<br />

least to what has been observed, in spite of three obvious objections: first,<br />

that so there was no support for any hypothesis; secondly, that by the<br />

same token we ought to content ourselves with simply formulating the<br />

special observations actually made; and thirdly, that every advance of<br />

science that further opens the truth to our view discloses a world of<br />

unexpected complications. It was not until long experience forced me to


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 59<br />

realize that subsequent discoveries were every time showing I had been<br />

wrong, while those who understood the maxim as Galileo had done, early<br />

unlocked the secret, that the scales fell from my eyes and my mind awoke<br />

to the broad and flaming daylight that it is the simpler Hypothesis in the<br />

sense of the more facile and natural, the one that instinct suggests, that<br />

must be preferred; for the reason that, unless man have a natural bent in<br />

accordance with nature's, he has no chance of understanding nature at all.<br />

Many tests of this principal and positive fact, relating as well to my own<br />

studies as to the researches of others, have confirmed me in this opinion;<br />

and when I shall come to set them forth in a book, their array will<br />

convince everybody. Oh, no! I am forgetting that armour, impenetrable by<br />

accurate thought, in which the rank and file of minds are clad! <strong>The</strong>y may,<br />

for example, get the notion that my proposition involves a denial of the<br />

rigidity of the laws of association: it would be quite on a par with much<br />

that is current. I do not mean that logical simplicity is a consideration of<br />

no value at all, but only that its value is badly secondary to that of<br />

simplicity in the other sense.<br />

If, however, the maxim is correct in Galileo's sense, whence it follows<br />

that man has, in some degree, a divinatory power, primary or derived, like<br />

that of a wasp or a bird, then instances swarm to show that a certain<br />

altogether peculiar confidence in a hypothesis, not to be confounded with<br />

rash cocksureness, has a very appreciable value as a sign of the truth of<br />

the hypothesis. I regret I cannot give an account of certain interesting and<br />

almost convincing cases. <strong>The</strong> N.A. excites this peculiar confidence in the<br />

very highest degree.<br />

n5. PRAGMATICISM n1<br />

478. We have now to apply these principles to the evaluation of the N.A.<br />

Had I space I would put this into the shape of imagining how it is likely to<br />

be esteemed by three types of men: the first of small instruction with<br />

corresponding natural breadth, intimately acquainted with the N.A., but to<br />

whom logic is all Greek; the second, inflated with current notions of logic,<br />

but prodigiously informed about the N.A.; the third, a trained man of<br />

science who, in the modern spirit, has added to his specialty an exact<br />

theoretical and practical study of reasoning and the elements of thought,<br />

so that psychologists account him a sort of psychologist, and<br />

mathematicians a sort of mathematician.<br />

479. I should, then, show how the first would have learned that nothing<br />

has any kind of value in itself -- whether ?sthetic, moral, or scientific --<br />

but only in its place in the whole production to which it appertains; and<br />

that an individual soul with its petty agitations and calamities is a zero<br />

except as filling its infinitesimal place, and accepting his little futility as<br />

his entire treasure. He will see that though his God would not really (in a


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 60<br />

certain sense) adapt means to ends, it is nevertheless quite true that there<br />

are relations among phenomena which finite intelligence must interpret,<br />

and truly interpret, as such adaptations; and he will macarize himself for<br />

his own bitterest griefs, and bless God for the law of growth with all the<br />

fighting it imposes upon him -- Evil, i.e. what it is man's duty to fight,<br />

being one of the major perfections of the Universe. In that fight he will<br />

endeavour to perform just the duty laid upon him and no more. Though<br />

his desperate struggles should issue in the horrors of his rout, and he<br />

should see the innocents who are dearest to his heart exposed to torments,<br />

frenzy and despair, destined to be smirched with filth, and stunted in their<br />

intelligence, still he may hope that it be best for them, and will tell himself<br />

that in any case the secret design of God will be perfected through their<br />

agency; and even while still hot from the battle, will submit with adoration<br />

to His Holy will. He will not worry because the Universes were not<br />

constructed to suit the scheme of some silly scold.<br />

480. <strong>The</strong> context of this I must leave the reader to imagine. I will only add<br />

that the third man, considering the complex process of self-control, will<br />

see that the hypothesis, irresistible though it be to first intention, yet<br />

needs Probation; and that though an infinite being is not tied down to any<br />

consistency, yet man, like any other animal, is gifted with power of<br />

understanding sufficient for the conduct of life. This brings him, for testing<br />

the hypothesis, to taking his stand upon Pragmaticism, which implies<br />

faith in common sense and in instinct, though only as they issue from the<br />

cupel-furnace of measured criticism. In short, he will say that the N.A. is<br />

the First Stage of a scientific inquiry, resulting in a hypothesis of the very<br />

highest Plausibility, whose ultimate test must lie in its value in the selfcontrolled<br />

growth of man's conduct of life.<br />

481.n1 Since I have employed the word Pragmaticism, and shall have<br />

occasion to use it once more, it may perhaps be well to explain it. About<br />

forty years ago, my studies of Berkeley, Kant, and others led me, after<br />

convincing myself that all thinking is performed in Signs, and that<br />

meditation takes the form of a dialogue, so that it is proper to speak of the<br />

"meaning" of a concept, to conclude that to acquire full mastery of that<br />

meaning it is requisite, in the first place, to learn to recognize the concept<br />

under every disguise, through extensive familiarity with instances of it.<br />

But this, after all, does not imply any true understanding of it; so that it is<br />

further requisite that we should make an abstract logical analysis of it into<br />

its ultimate elements, or as complete an analysis as we can compass. But,<br />

even so, we may still be without any living comprehension of it; and the<br />

only way to complete our knowledge of its nature is to discover and<br />

recognize just what general habits of conduct a belief in the truth of the<br />

concept (of any conceivable subject, and under any conceivable<br />

circumstances) would reasonably develop; that is to say, what habits<br />

would ultimately result from a sufficient consideration of such truth. It is<br />

necessary to understand the word "conduct," here, in the broadest sense.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 61<br />

If, for example, the predication of a given concept were to lead to our<br />

admitting that a given form of reasoning concerning the subject of which it<br />

was affirmed was valid, when it would not otherwise be valid, the<br />

recognition of that effect in our reasoning would decidedly be a habit of<br />

conduct.<br />

482. In 1871, in a Metaphysical Club in Cambridge, Massachusetts, I used<br />

to preach this principle as a sort of logical gospel, representing the<br />

unformulated method followed by Berkeley, and in conversation about it I<br />

called it "Pragmatism."n2 In December [November] 1877 and January<br />

1878 I set forth the doctrine in the Popular Science Monthly; and the two<br />

parts of my essay were printed in French in the Revue Philosophique,<br />

volumes vi and vii.n1 Of course, the doctrine attracted no particular<br />

attention, for, as I had remarked in my opening sentence, very few people<br />

care for logic. But in 1897 Professor James remodelled the matter, and<br />

transmogrified it into a doctrine of philosophy,n2 some parts of which I<br />

highly approved, while other and more prominent parts I regarded, and<br />

still regard, as opposed to sound logic. About the time Professor Papini n3<br />

discovered, to the delight of the Pragmatist school, that this doctrine was<br />

incapable of definition, which would certainly seem to distinguish it from<br />

every other doctrine in whatever branch of science, I was coming to the<br />

conclusion that my poor little maxim should be called by another name;<br />

and accordingly, in April, 1905 I renamed it Pragmaticism.n4 I had never<br />

before dignified it by any name in print, except that, at Professor Baldwin's<br />

request, I wrote a definition of it for his Dictionary of Psychology and<br />

Philosophy.n5 I did not insert the word in the Century Dictionary, though<br />

I had charge of the philosophical definitions of that work;n6 for I have a<br />

perhaps exaggerated dislike of r?clame.<br />

483. It is that course of meditation upon the three Universes which gives<br />

birth to the hypothesis and ultimately to the belief that they, or at any rate<br />

two of the three, have a Creator independent of them, that I have<br />

throughout this article called the N.A., because I think the theologians<br />

ought to have recognized it as a line of thought reasonably productive of<br />

belief. This is the "humble" argument, the innermost of the nest.n7 In the<br />

mind of a metaphysician it will have a metaphysical tinge; but that seems<br />

to me rather to detract from its force than to add anything to it. It is just<br />

as good an argument, if not better, in the form it takes in the mind of the<br />

clodhopper.<br />

484. <strong>The</strong> theologians could not have presented the N.A.; because that is a<br />

living course of thought of very various forms. But they might and ought to<br />

have described it, and should have defended it, too, as far as they could,<br />

without going into original logical researches, which could not be justly<br />

expected of them. <strong>The</strong>y are accustomed to make use of the principle that<br />

that which convinces a normal man must be presumed to be sound<br />

reasoning; and therefore they ought to say whatever can truly be advanced


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 62<br />

to show that the N.A., if sufficiently developed, will convince any normal<br />

man. Unfortunately, it happens that there is very little established fact to<br />

show that this is the case. I have not pretended to have any other ground<br />

for my belief that it is so than my assumption, which each one of us<br />

makes, that my own intellectual disposition is normal. I am forced to<br />

confess that no pessimist will agree with me. I do not admit that<br />

pessimists are, at the same time, thoroughly sane, and in addition are<br />

endowed in normal measure with intellectual vigour; and my reasons for<br />

thinking so are two. <strong>The</strong> first is, that the difference between a pessimistic<br />

and an optimistic mind is of such controlling importance in regard to every<br />

intellectual function, and especially for the conduct of life, that it is out of<br />

the question to admit that both are normal, and the great majority of<br />

mankind are naturally optimistic. Now, the majority of every race depart<br />

but little from the norm of that race. In order to present my other reason, I<br />

am obliged to recognize three types of pessimists. <strong>The</strong> first type is often<br />

found in exquisite and noble natures of great force of original intellect<br />

whose own lives are dreadful histories of torment due to some physical<br />

malady. Leopardi is a famous example. We cannot but believe, against<br />

their earnest protests, that if such men had had ordinary health, life<br />

would have worn for them the same colour as for the rest of us. Meantime,<br />

one meets too few pessimists of this type to affect the present question.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second is the misanthropical type, the type that makes itself heard. It<br />

suffices to call to mind the conduct of the famous pessimists of this kind,<br />

Diogenes the Cynic, Schopenhauer, Carlyle, and their kin with<br />

Shakespeare's Timon of Athens, to recognize them as diseased minds. <strong>The</strong><br />

third is the philanthropical type, people whose lively sympathies, easily<br />

excited, become roused to anger at what they consider the stupid<br />

injustices of life. Being easily interested in everything, without being<br />

overloaded with exact thought of any kind, they are excellent raw material<br />

for litt?rateurs: witness Voltaire. No individual remotely approaching the<br />

calibre of a Leibnitz is to be found among them.<br />

485. <strong>The</strong> third argument, enclosing and defending the other two, consists<br />

in the development of those principles of logic according to which the<br />

humble argument is the first stage of a scientific inquiry into the origin of<br />

the three Universes, but of an inquiry which produces, not merely<br />

scientific belief, which is always provisional, but also a living, practical<br />

belief, logically justified in crossing the Rubicon with all the freightage of<br />

eternity. <strong>The</strong> presentation of this argument would require the<br />

establishment of several principles of logic that the logicians have hardly<br />

dreamed of, and particularly a strict proof of the correctness of the maxim<br />

of Pragmaticism. My original essay, having been written for a popular<br />

monthly, assumes, for no better reason than that real inquiry cannot<br />

begin until a state of real doubt arises and ends as soon as Belief is<br />

attained, that "a settlement of Belief," or, in other words, a state of<br />

satisfaction, is all that Truth, or the aim of inquiry, consists in.n1 <strong>The</strong><br />

reason I gave for this was so flimsy, while the inference was so nearly the<br />

gist of Pragmaticism, that I must confess the argument of that essay might


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 63<br />

with some justice be said to beg the question. <strong>The</strong> first part of the essay,n2<br />

however, is occupied with showing that, if Truth consists in satisfaction, it<br />

cannot be any actual satisfaction, but must be the satisfaction which<br />

would ultimately be found if the inquiry were pushed to its ultimate and<br />

indefeasible issue. This, I beg to point out, is a very different position from<br />

that of Mr. Schiller and the pragmatists of today.n3 I trust I shall be<br />

believed when I say that it is only a desire to avoid being misunderstood in<br />

consequence of my relations with pragmatism, and by no means as<br />

arrogating any superior immunity from error which I have too good reason<br />

to know that I do not enjoy, that leads me to express my personal<br />

sentiments about their tenets. <strong>The</strong>ir avowedly undefinable position, if it be<br />

not capable of logical characterization, seems to me to be characterized by<br />

an angry hatred of strict logic, and even some disposition to rate any exact<br />

thought which interferes with their doctrines as all humbug. At the same<br />

time, it seems to me clear that their approximate acceptance of the<br />

Pragmaticist principle, and even that very casting aside of difficult<br />

distinctions (although I cannot approve of it), has helped them to a<br />

mightily clear discernment of some fundamental truths that other<br />

philosophers have seen but through a mist, and most of them not at all.<br />

Among such truths -- all of them old, of course, yet acknowledged by few -<br />

- I reckon their denial of necessitarianism; their rejection of any<br />

"consciousness" different from a visceral or other external sensation; their<br />

acknowledgment that there are, in a Pragmatistical sense, Real habits<br />

(which Really would produce effects, under circumstances that may not<br />

happen to get actualized, and are thus Real generals); and their insistence<br />

upon interpreting all hypos<br />

tatic abstractions in terms of what they would or might (not actually will)<br />

come to in the concrete. It seems to me a pity they should allow a<br />

philosophy so instinct with life to become infected with seeds of death in<br />

such notions as that of the unreality of all ideas of infinity n1 and that of<br />

the mutability of truth,n2 and in such confusions of thought as that of<br />

active willing (willing to control thought, to doubt, and to weigh reasons)<br />

with willing not to exert the will (willing to believe).n3Peirce: CP 6.486<br />

Cross-Ref:??<br />

n6. ADDITAMENT n4<br />

486. A nest of three arguments for the Reality of God has now been<br />

sketched, though none of them could, in the limits of a single article, be<br />

fairly presented. <strong>The</strong> first is that entirely honest, sincere and unaffected,<br />

because unprepense, meditation upon the Idea of God, into which the Play<br />

of Musement will inevitably sooner or later lead, and which, by developing<br />

a deep sense of the adorability of that Idea, will produce a truly religious<br />

Belief in His Reality and His nearness. It is a reasonable argument,<br />

because it naturally results in the most intense and living determination<br />

(Bestimmung) of the soul toward shaping the Muser's whole conduct into<br />

conformity with the Hypothesis that God is Real and very near; and such a


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 64<br />

determination of the soul in regard to any proposition is the very essence<br />

of a living Belief in such proposition. This is that "humble argument," open<br />

to every honest man, which I surmise to have made more worshippers of<br />

God than any other.<br />

487. <strong>The</strong> second of the nest is the argument which seems to me to have<br />

been "neglected" by writers upon natural theology, consisting in showing<br />

that the humble argument is the natural fruit of free meditation, since<br />

every heart will be ravished by the beauty and adorability of the Idea,<br />

when it is so pursued. Were the theologians able to perceive the force of<br />

this argument, they would make it such a presentation of universal<br />

human nature as to show that a latent tendency toward belief in God is a<br />

fundamental ingredient of the soul, and that, far from being a vicious or<br />

superstitious ingredient, it is simply the natural precipitate of meditation<br />

upon the origin of the Three Universes. Of course, it could not, any more<br />

than any other theological argumentation, have the value or the religious<br />

vitality of the "Humble Argument"; for it would only be an apology -- a<br />

vindicatory description -- of the mental operations which the Humble<br />

Argument actually and actively lives out. Though this is properly the<br />

neglected argument, yet I have sometimes used the abbreviation "the N.A."<br />

for the whole nest of three.<br />

488. <strong>The</strong> third argument of the nest consists in a study of logical<br />

methodeutic, illuminated by the light of a first-hand acquaintance with<br />

genuine scientific thought -- the sort of thought whose tools literally<br />

comprise not merely Ideas of mathematical exactitude, but also the<br />

apparatus of the skilled manipulator, actually in use. <strong>The</strong> student,<br />

applying to his own trained habits of research the art of logical analysis --<br />

an art as elaborate and methodical as that of the chemical analyst,<br />

compares the process of thought of the Muser upon the Three Universes<br />

with certain parts of the work of scientific discovery, and finds that the<br />

"Humble Argument" is nothing but an instance of the first stage of all such<br />

work, the stage of observing the facts, or variously rearranging them, and<br />

of pondering them until, by their reactions with the results of previous<br />

scientific experience, there is "evolved" (as the chemists word it) an<br />

explanatory hypothesis. He will note, however, that this instance of<br />

Retroduction, undeniable as this character is, departs widely from the<br />

ordinary run of instances, especially in three respects. In the first place,<br />

the Plausibility of the hypothesis reaches an almost unparalleled height<br />

among deliberately formed hypotheses. So hard is it to doubt God's Reality,<br />

when the Idea has sprung from Musements, that there is great danger that<br />

the investigation will stop at this first stage, owing to the indifference of<br />

the Muser to any further proof of it. At the same time, this very Plausibility<br />

is undoubtedly an argument of no small weight in favor of the truth of the<br />

hypothesis.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 65<br />

489. In the second place, although it is a chief function of an explanatory<br />

hypothesis (and some philosophers say the only one) to excite a clear<br />

image in the mind by means of which experiential consequences of<br />

ascertainable conditions may be predicted, yet in this instance the<br />

hypothesis can only be apprehended so very obscurely that in exceptional<br />

cases alone can any definite and direct deduction from its ordinary<br />

abstract interpretation be made. How, for example, can we ever expect to<br />

be able to predict what the conduct would be, even of [an] omniscient<br />

being, governing no more than one poor solar system for only a million<br />

years or so? How much less if, being also omnipotent, he be thereby freed<br />

from all experience, all desire, all intention! Since God, in His essential<br />

character of Ens necessarium, is a disembodied spirit, and since there is<br />

strong reason to hold that what we call consciousness is either merely the<br />

general sensation of the brain or some part of it, or at all events some<br />

visceral or bodily sensation, God probably has no consciousness. Most of<br />

us are in the habit of thinking that consciousness and psychic life are the<br />

same thing and otherwise greatly to overrate the functions of<br />

consciousness. (See James's paper "Does 'Consciousness' Exist?" in Jour.<br />

Phil., Psy., and Sci. Meth. I, 477; 1904, Sep. 1. But the negative reply is, in<br />

itself, no novelty.)<br />

490. <strong>The</strong> effects of the second peculiarity of the hypothesis are<br />

counteracted by a third, which consists in its commanding influence over<br />

the whole conduct of life of its believers. According to that logical doctrine<br />

which the present writer first formulated in 1873n1 and named<br />

Pragmatism, the true meaning of any product of the intellect lies in<br />

whatever unitary determination it would impart to practical conduct under<br />

any and every conceivable circumstance, supposing such conduct to be<br />

guided by reflexion carried to an ultimate limit. It appears to have been<br />

virtually the philosophy of Socrates. But although it is "an old way of<br />

thinking," in the sense that it was practiced by Spinoza, Berkeley, and<br />

Kant, I am not aware of its having been definitely formulated, whether as a<br />

maxim of logical analysis or otherwise, by anybody before my publication<br />

of it in 1878. Naturally, nobody ever heard of pragmatism. People don't<br />

care for methods! they want results. Give them all the diamonds you make,<br />

and you may have the method of making them for your own. So it was not<br />

until in 1898n2 -- Professor James took hold of the old thing, dignified it<br />

by calling it by its name in print (which I had never done even when I was<br />

in charge of the philosophical part of the Century Dictionary), furbished it<br />

up, and turned it into a philosophical doctrine -- that it had any vogue at<br />

all. It did not, however, shine with its present effulgence until Professor<br />

Papini n3 made the discovery that it cannot be defined -- a circumstance<br />

which, I believe, distinguishes it from all other doctrines, of whatsoever<br />

natures they may be, that were ever promulgated. <strong>The</strong>reupon I thought it<br />

high time to give my method a less distinguished designation; and I<br />

rechristened it pragmaticism.n4 Pragmaticism, then, is a theory of logical<br />

analysis, or true definition; and its merits are greatest in its application to<br />

the highest metaphysical conceptions. At the same time, these merits can


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 66<br />

only be appreciated as the result of long training. A full exposition of the<br />

pragmaticistic definition of Ens necessarium would require many pages;<br />

but some hints toward it may be given. A disembodied spirit, or pure mind,<br />

has its being out of time, since all that it is destined to think is fully in its<br />

being at any and every previous time. But in endless time it is destined to<br />

think all that it is capable of thinking. Order is simply thought embodied<br />

in arrangement; and thought embodied in any other way appears<br />

objectively as a character that is a generalization of order, and that, in the<br />

lack of any word for it, we may call for the nonce, "Super-order." It is<br />

something like uniformity. <strong>The</strong> idea may be caught if it is described as that<br />

of which order and uniformity are particular varieties. Pure mind, as<br />

creative of thought, must, so far as it is manifested in time, appear as<br />

having a character related to the habit-taking capacity, just as super-order<br />

is related to uniformity. Now imagine, in such vague way as such a thing<br />

can be imagined, a perfect cosmology of the three universes. It would<br />

prove all in relation to that subject that reason could desiderate; and of<br />

course all that it would prove must, in actual fact, now be true. But reason<br />

would desiderate that that should be proved from which would follow all<br />

that is in fact true of the three universes; and the postulate from which all<br />

this would follow must not state any matter of fact, since such fact would<br />

thereby be left unexplained. That perfect cosmology must therefore show<br />

that the whole history of the three universes, as it has been and is to be,<br />

would follow from a premiss which would not suppose them to exist at all.<br />

Moreover, such premiss must in actual fact be true. But that premiss<br />

must represent a state of things in which the three universes were<br />

completely nil. Consequently, whether in time or not, the three universes<br />

must actually be absolutely necessary results of a state of utter<br />

nothingness. We cannot ourselves conceive of such a state of nility; but we<br />

can easily conceive that there should be a mind that could conceive it,<br />

since, after all, no contradiction can be involved in mere non-existence. A<br />

state in which there should be absolutely no super-order whatsoever<br />

would be such a state of nility. For all Being involves some kind of superorder.<br />

For example, to suppose a thing to have any particular character is<br />

to suppose a conditional proposition to be true of it, which proposition<br />

would express some kind of super-order, as any formulation of a general<br />

fact does. To suppose it to have elasticity of volume is to suppose that if it<br />

were subjected to pressure its volume would diminish until at a certain<br />

point the full pressure was attained within and without its periphery. This<br />

is a super-order, a law expressible by a differential equation. Any such<br />

super-order would be a super-habit. Any general state of things<br />

whatsoever would be a super-order and a super-habit. In that state of<br />

absolute nility, in or out of time, that is, before or after the evolution of<br />

time, there must then have been a tohu bohu of which nothing whatever<br />

affirmative or negative was true universally. <strong>The</strong>re must have been,<br />

therefore, a little of everything conceivable. <strong>The</strong>re must have been here<br />

and there a little undifferentiated tendency to take super-habits. But such<br />

a state must tend to increase itself. For a tendency to act in any way,<br />

combined with a tendency to take habits, must increase the tendency to


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 67<br />

act in that way. Now substitute in this general statement for "tendency to<br />

act in any way" a tendency to take habits, and we see that that tendency<br />

would grow. It would also become differentiated in various ways. But there<br />

are some habits that carried beyond a certain point eliminate their<br />

subjects from the universe. <strong>The</strong>re are many ways in which this may<br />

happen. Thus a tendency to lose mass will end in a total loss of mass. A<br />

tendency to lose energy will end in removing its subject from perceptible<br />

existence. A tendency to gain energy will end in the body's shooting<br />

through the universe too rapidly to produce any effect, etc.<br />

491. Among the many pertinent considerations which have been crowded<br />

out of this article, I may just mention that it could have been shown that<br />

the hypothesis of God's Reality is logically not so isolated a conclusion as<br />

it may seem. On the contrary, it is connected so with a theory of the<br />

nature of thinking that if this be proved so is that. Now there is no such<br />

difficulty in tracing experiential consequences of this theory of thinking as<br />

there are in attempting directly to trace out other consequences of God's<br />

reality. In so short an article, it could not be expected that I should take<br />

notice of objections. Yet objections, such as they are, are obvious enough,<br />

and a few of them wear at first sight a redoubtable aspect. For example, it<br />

may be said that since I compare man's power of guessing at the truth<br />

with the instincts of animals, I ought to have noticed that these are<br />

entirely explained by the action of natural selection in endowing animals<br />

with such powers as contribute to the preservation of their different stocks;<br />

and that there is evidence that man's power of penetrating the secrets of<br />

nature depends upon this, in the fact that all the successful sciences have<br />

been either mechanical in respect to their theories or psychological. Now,<br />

some notions of mechanics are needed by all animals to enable them to get<br />

food, and are needed most by man; while correct ideas of what passes in<br />

his neighbours' minds are needed for the existence of society, and<br />

therefore for the propagation of his kind.n1 Metaphysics, however, cannot<br />

adapt the human race to maintaining itself, and therefore the presumption<br />

[is] that man has no such genius for discoveries about God, Freedom, and<br />

Immortality, as he has for physical and psychical science.<br />

n7. KNOWLEDGE OF GOD n2<br />

492. [We] can know nothing except what we directly experience. So all that<br />

we can anyway know relates to experience. All the creations of our mind<br />

are but patchworks from experience. So that all our ideas are but ideas of<br />

real or transposed experiences. A word can mean nothing except the idea<br />

it calls up. So that we cannot even talk about anything but a knowable<br />

object. <strong>The</strong> unknowable about which Hamilton and the agnostics talk can<br />

be nothing but an Unknowable Knowable. <strong>The</strong> absolutely unknowable is a<br />

non-existent existence.n3 <strong>The</strong> Unknowable is a nominalistic heresy. <strong>The</strong><br />

nominalists in giving their adherence to that doctrine which is really held


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 68<br />

by all philosophers of all stripes, namely, that experience is all we know,<br />

understand experience in their nominalistic sense as the mere first<br />

impressions of sense. <strong>The</strong>se "first impressions of sense" are hypothetical<br />

creations of nominalistic metaphysics: I for one deny their existence. But<br />

anyway even if they exist, it is not in them that experience consists. By<br />

experience must be understood the entire mental product. Some<br />

psychologists whom I hold in respect will stop me here to say that, while<br />

they admit that experience is more than mere sensation, they cannot<br />

extend it to the whole mental product, since that would include<br />

hallucinations, delusions, superstitious imaginations and fallacies of all<br />

kinds; and that they would limit experience to sense-perceptions. But I<br />

reply that my statement is the logical one. Hallucinations, delusions,<br />

superstitious imaginations, and fallacies of all kinds are experiences, but<br />

experiences misunderstood; while to say that all our knowledge relates<br />

merely to sense perception is to say that we can know nothing -- not even<br />

mistakenly -- about higher matters, as honor, aspirations, and love.<br />

493. Where would such an idea, say as that of God, come from, if<br />

not from direct experience? Would you make it a result of some kind of<br />

reasoning, good or bad? Why, reasoning can supply the mind with nothing<br />

in the world except an estimate of the value of a statistical ratio, that is,<br />

how often certain kinds of things are found in certain combinations in the<br />

ordinary course of experience. And scepticism, in the sense of doubt of the<br />

validity of elementary ideas -- which is really a proposal to turn an idea<br />

out of court and permit no inquiry into its applicability -- is doubly<br />

condemned by the fundamental principle of scientific method --<br />

condemned first as obstructing inquiry, and condemned second because it<br />

is treating some other than a statistical ratio as a thing to be argued about.<br />

No: as to God, open your eyes -- and your heart, which is also a perceptive<br />

organ -- and you see him. But you may ask, Don't you admit there are any<br />

delusions? Yes: I may think a thing is black, and on close examination it<br />

may turn out to be bottle-green. But I cannot think a thing is black if there<br />

is no such thing to be seen as black. Neither can I think that a certain<br />

action is self-sacrificing, if no such thing as self-sacrifice exists, although<br />

it may be very rare. It is the nominalists, and the nominalists alone, who<br />

indulge in such scepticism, which the scientific method utterly condemns.<br />

NOTES:<br />

n1 Hibbert Journal, vol. 7, pp. 90-112 (1908).<br />

n2 See his Thought and Things, p. 261, London (1906).<br />

n1 Cf. 4.545ff.<br />

n2 Cf. 2.266ff, 3.160.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 69<br />

n1 "It appears to me that this mystery is considered insoluble for the<br />

very reason which should cause it to be regarded as easy of solution. I<br />

mean the outr? character of its features."<br />

n1 Cf. 1.333.<br />

n1 See 177ff.<br />

n2 See 5.397ff.<br />

n1 Cf. 2.622ff.<br />

n1 Or Abduction. See 2.708ff, 2.755 and vol. 5, bk. I, ch. 7.<br />

n1 Cf. 2.267.<br />

n2 Cf. 2.756ff.<br />

n1 Cf. 2.758f.<br />

n2 Kritik der Reinen Vernunft, A154-158; B193-197.<br />

n3 See 2.93.<br />

n1 Jacques Babinet (1794-1872), a popular writer on<br />

hydrodynamics and many other scientific subjects.<br />

n1 See "Dialogues Concerning the Two Great Systems of the World,"<br />

in Mathematical Collections and Translations of Thomas Salisbury, vol. 1,<br />

p. 301, London (1661).<br />

n1 In a letter to William James, November 17, 1908, Peirce says, "I<br />

had never contemplated the possibility of the last section's being<br />

published."<br />

n1 Cf. 3.457, 5.388ff.<br />

n2 See 5.12f.<br />

n1 See note to vol. 5, bk. II, Paper No. IV.<br />

n2 See <strong>The</strong> Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy<br />

(1897).<br />

n3 See "What Pragmatism is Like," Popular Science Monthly, vol. 71,<br />

p. 351 (1907).<br />

n4 See 5.414.<br />

n5 See 5.1f.<br />

n6 See 1.106n, 5.13n.<br />

n7 See 486.<br />

n1 See 5.375.<br />

n2 See 5.365ff.<br />

n3 See 5.552, 5.555f.<br />

n1 F. C. S. Schiller, Humanism, p. 314, note, London (1903);<br />

Studies in Humanism, p. 295, London (1907).<br />

n2 William James, Pragmatism, p. 59ff, New York (1908).<br />

n3 William James, <strong>The</strong> Will to Believe, p. 11, New York (1899).<br />

n4 c. 1910; 491 is from an alternative draft.<br />

n1 See 482 and p. v of the Preface to vol. 5.


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 70<br />

n2 "Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results," <strong>The</strong> University<br />

of California Chronicle, pp. 24ff (1898); reprinted in Collected Essays and<br />

Reviews, pp. 406-437 (1920).<br />

n3 "What Pragmatism is Like," Popular Science Monthly, p. 351, vol.<br />

71 (1907).<br />

n4 See 5.414.<br />

n1 See 418.<br />

n2 From an unpaginated fragment, c. 1896.<br />

n3 See 5.255f.


From <strong>The</strong> Snow-Image, and Other Twice-told Tales, 1850, 1852<br />

By Nathaniel Hawthorne, 1804-1864<br />

________________________________________<br />

Ethan Brand<br />

A Chapter from an Abortive Romance<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 71<br />

BARTRAM the lime-burner, a rough, heavy-looking man, begrimed with<br />

charcoal, sat watching his kiln, at nightfall, while his little son played at<br />

building houses with the scattered fragments of marble, when, on the hillside<br />

below them, they heard a roar of laughter, not mirthful, but slow, and<br />

even solemn, like a wind shaking the boughs of the forest.<br />

"Father, what is that?" asked the little boy, leaving his play, and<br />

pressing betwixt his father's knees.<br />

"O, some drunken man, I suppose," answered the lime-burner; "some<br />

merry fellow from the bar-room in the village, who dared not laugh loud<br />

enough within doors, lest he should blow the roof of the house off. So here<br />

he is, shaking his jolly sides at the foot of Gray-lock."<br />

"But, father," said the child, more sensitive than the obtuse, middleaged<br />

clown, "he does not laugh like a man that is glad. So the noise<br />

frightens me!"<br />

"Don't be a fool, child!" cried his father, gruffly. "You will never make a<br />

man, I do believe; there is too much of your mother in you. I have known<br />

the rustling of a leaf startle you. Hark! Here comes the merry fellow, now.<br />

You shall see that there is no harm in him."<br />

Bartram and his little son, while they were talking thus, sat watching<br />

the same lime-kiln that had been the scene of Ethan Brand's solitary and<br />

meditative life, before he began his search for the Unpardonable Sin. Many<br />

years, as we have seen, had now elapsed, since that portentous night<br />

when the IDEA was first developed. <strong>The</strong> kiln, however, on the mountainside,<br />

stood unimpaired, and was in nothing changed since he had thrown<br />

his dark thoughts into the intense glow of its furnace, and melted them, as<br />

it were, into the one thought that took possession of his life. It was a rude,<br />

round, tower-like structure, about twenty feet high, heavily built of rough<br />

stones, and with a hillock of earth heaped about the larger part of its<br />

circumference; so that the blocks and fragments of marble might be drawn<br />

by cart-loads, and thrown in at the top. <strong>The</strong>re was an opening at the<br />

bottom of the tower, like an oven-mouth, but large enough to admit a man<br />

in a stooping posture, and provided with a massive iron door. With the<br />

smoke and jets of flame issuing from the chinks and crevices of this door,<br />

which seemed to give admittance into the hill-side, it resembled nothing so<br />

much as the private entrance to the infernal regions, which the shepherds<br />

of the Delectable Mountains were accustomed to show to pilgrims.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are many such lime-kilns in that tract of country, for the purpose<br />

of burning the white marble which composes a large part of the substance<br />

of the hills. Some of them, built years ago, and long deserted, with weeds<br />

growing in the vacant round of the interior, which is open to the sky, and<br />

grass and wild-flowers rooting themselves into the chinks of the stones,


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 72<br />

look already like relics of antiquity, and may yet be overspread with the<br />

lichens of centuries to come. Others, where the lime-burner still feeds his<br />

daily and nightlong fire, afford points of interest to the wanderer among<br />

the hills, who seats himself on a log of wood or a fragment of marble, to<br />

hold a chat with the solitary man. It is a lonesome, and, when the<br />

character is inclined to thought, may be an intensely thoughtful<br />

occupation; as it proved in the case of Ethan Brand, who had mused to<br />

such strange purpose, in days gone by, while the fire in this very kiln was<br />

burning.<br />

<strong>The</strong> man who now watched the fire was of a different order, and<br />

troubled himself with no thoughts save the very few that were requisite to<br />

his business. At frequent intervals, he flung back the clashing weight of<br />

the iron door, and, turning his face from the insufferable glare, thrust in<br />

huge logs of oak, or stirred the immense brands with a long pole. Within<br />

the furnace were seen the curling and riotous flames, and the burning<br />

marble, almost molten with the intensity of heat; while without, the<br />

reflection of the fire quivered on the dark intricacy of the surrounding<br />

forest, and showed in the foreground a bright and ruddy little picture of<br />

the hut, the spring beside its door, the athletic and coal-begrimed figure of<br />

the lime-burner, and the half-frightened child, shrinking into the<br />

protection of his father's shadow. And when again the iron door was closed,<br />

then reappeared the tender light of the half-full moon, which vainly strove<br />

to trace out the indistinct shapes of the neighboring mountains; and, in<br />

the upper sky, there was a flitting congregation of clouds, still faintly<br />

tinged with the rosy sunset, though thus far down into the valley the<br />

sunshine had vanished long and long ago.<br />

<strong>The</strong> little boy now crept still closer to his father, as footsteps were heard<br />

ascending the hill-side, and a human form thrust aside the bushes that<br />

clustered beneath the trees.<br />

"Halloo! who is it?" cried the lime-burner, vexed at his son's timidity,<br />

yet half infected by it. "Come forward, and show yourself, like a man, or I'll<br />

fling this chunk of marble at your head!"<br />

"You offer me a rough welcome," said a gloomy voice, as the unknown<br />

man drew nigh. "Yet I neither claim nor desire a kinder one, even at my<br />

own fireside."<br />

To obtain a distincter view, Bartram threw open the iron door of the<br />

kiln, whence immediately issued a gush of fierce light, that smote full<br />

upon the stranger's face and figure. To a careless eye there appeared<br />

nothing very remarkable in his aspect, which was that of a man in a<br />

coarse, brown, country-made suit of clothes, tall and thin, with the staff<br />

and heavy shoes of a wayfarer. As he advanced, he fixed his eyes--which<br />

were very bright--intently upon the brightness of the furnace, as if he<br />

beheld, or expected to behold, some object worthy of note within it.<br />

"Good evening, stranger," said the lime-burner; "whence come you, so<br />

late in the day?"<br />

"I come from my search," answered the wayfarer; "for, at last, it is<br />

finished."


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 73<br />

"Drunk!--or crazy!" muttered Bartram to himself. "I shall have trouble<br />

with the fellow. <strong>The</strong> sooner I drive him away, the better."<br />

<strong>The</strong> little boy, all in a tremble, whispered to his father, and begged him<br />

to shut the door of the kiln, so that there might not be so much light; for<br />

that there was something in the man's face which he was afraid to look at,<br />

yet could not look away from. And, indeed, even the lime-burner's dull and<br />

torpid sense began to be impressed by an indescribable something in that<br />

thin, rugged, thoughtful visage, with the grizzled hair hanging wildly about<br />

it, and those deeply-sunken eyes, which gleamed like fires within the<br />

entrance of a mysterious cavern. But, as he closed the door, the stranger<br />

turned towards him, and spoke in a quiet, familiar way, that made<br />

Bartram feel as if he were a sane and sensible man, after all.<br />

"Your task draws to an end, I see," said he. "This marble has already<br />

been burning three days. A few hours more will convert the stone to lime."<br />

"Why, who are you?" exclaimed the lime-burner. "You seem as well<br />

acquainted with my business as I am myself."<br />

"And well I may be," said the stranger; "for I followed the same craft<br />

many a long year, and here, too, on this very spot. But you are a<br />

newcomer in these parts. Did you never hear of Ethan Brand?"<br />

"<strong>The</strong> man that went in search of the Unpardonable Sin?" asked<br />

Bartram, with a laugh.<br />

"<strong>The</strong> same," answered the stranger. "He has found what he sought, and<br />

therefore he comes back again."<br />

"What! then you are Ethan Brand himself?" cried the lime-burner, in<br />

amazement. "I am a newcomer here, as you say, and they call it eighteen<br />

years since you left the foot of Gray-lock. But, I can tell you, the good folks<br />

still talk about Ethan Brand, in the village yonder, and what a strange<br />

errand took him away from his lime-kiln. Well, and so you have found the<br />

Unpardonable Sin?"<br />

"Even so!" said the stranger, calmly.<br />

"If the question is a fair one," proceeded Bartram, "where might it be?"<br />

Ethan Brand laid his finger on his own heart.<br />

"Here!" replied he.<br />

And then, without mirth in his countenance, but as if moved by an<br />

involuntary recognition of the infinite absurdity of seeking throughout the<br />

world for what was the closest of all things to himself, and looking into<br />

every heart, save his own, for what was hidden in no other breast, he<br />

broke into a laugh of scorn. It was the same slow, heavy laugh, that had<br />

almost appalled the lime-burner when it heralded the wayfarer's approach.<br />

<strong>The</strong> solitary mountain-side was made dismal by it. Laughter, when out<br />

of place, mistimed, or bursting forth from a disordered state of feeling, may<br />

be the most terrible modulation of the human voice. <strong>The</strong> laughter of one<br />

asleep, even if it be a little child--the madman's laugh--the wild, screaming<br />

laugh of a born idiot--are sounds that we sometimes tremble to hear, and<br />

would always willingly forget. Poets have imagined no utterance of fiends<br />

or hobgoblins so fearfully appropriate as a laugh. And even the obtuse<br />

lime-burner felt his nerves shaken, as this strange man looked inward at


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 74<br />

his own heart, and burst into laughter that rolled away into the night, and<br />

was indistinctly reverberated among the hills.<br />

"Joe," said he to his little son, "scamper down to the tavern in the<br />

village, and tell the jolly fellows there that Ethan Brand has come back,<br />

and that he has found the Unpardonable Sin!"<br />

<strong>The</strong> boy darted away on his errand, to which Ethan Brand made no<br />

objection, nor seemed hardly to notice it. He sat on a log of wood, looking<br />

steadfastly at the iron door of the kiln. When the child was out of sight,<br />

and his swift and light footsteps ceased to be heard treading first on the<br />

fallen leaves and then on the rocky mountain path, the lime-burner began<br />

to regret his departure. He felt that the little fellow's presence had been a<br />

barrier between his guest and himself, and that he must now deal, heart<br />

to heart, with a man who, on his own confession, had committed the one<br />

only crime for which Heaven could afford no mercy. That crime, in its<br />

indistinct blackness, seemed to overshadow him. <strong>The</strong> lime-burner's own<br />

sins rose up within him, and made his memory riotous with a throng of<br />

evil shapes that asserted their kindred with the Master Sin, whatever it<br />

might be, which it was within the scope of man's corrupted nature to<br />

conceive and cherish. <strong>The</strong>y were all of one family; they went to and fro<br />

between his breast and Ethan Brand's, and carried dark greetings from<br />

one to the other.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n Bartram remembered the stories which had grown traditionary in<br />

reference to this strange man, who had come upon him like a shadow of<br />

the night, and was making himself at home in his old place, after so long<br />

absence that the dead people, dead and buried for years, would have had<br />

more right to be at home, in any familiar spot, than he. Ethan Brand, it<br />

was said, had conversed with Satan himself in the lurid blaze of this very<br />

kiln. <strong>The</strong> legend had been matter of mirth heretofore but looked grisly now.<br />

According to this tale, before Ethan Brand departed on his search, he had<br />

been accustomed to evoke a fiend from the hot furnace of the lime-kiln,<br />

night after night, in order to confer with him about the Unpardonable Sin;<br />

the man and the fiend each laboring to frame the image of some mode of<br />

guilt which could neither be atoned for nor forgiven. And, with the first<br />

gleam of light upon the mountain-top, the fiend crept in at the iron door,<br />

there to abide the intensest element of fire, until again summoned forth to<br />

share in the dreadful task of extending man's possible guilt beyond the<br />

scope of Heaven's else infinite mercy.<br />

While the lime-burner was struggling with the horror of these thoughts,<br />

Ethan Brand rose from the log, and flung open the door of the kiln. <strong>The</strong><br />

action was in such accordance with the idea in Bartram's mind, that he<br />

almost expected to see the Evil One issue forth, red-hot from the raging<br />

furnace.<br />

"Hold! hold!" cried he, with a tremulous attempt to laugh; for he was<br />

ashamed of his fears, although they overmastered him. "Don't, for mercy's<br />

sake, bring out your devil now!"<br />

"Man!" sternly replied Ethan Brand, "what need have I of the devil? I<br />

have left him behind me, on my track. It is with such halfway sinners as<br />

you that he busies himself. Fear not because I open the door. I do but act


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 75<br />

by old custom, and am going to trim your fire, like a lime-burner, as I was<br />

once."<br />

He stirred the vast coals, thrust in more wood, and bent forward to gaze<br />

into the hollow prison-house of the fire, regardless of the fierce glow that<br />

reddened upon his face. <strong>The</strong> lime-burner sat watching him, and half<br />

suspected his strange guest of a purpose, if not to evoke a fiend, at least to<br />

plunge bodily into the flames, and thus vanish from the sight of man.<br />

Ethan Brand, however, drew quietly back, and closed the door of the kiln.<br />

"I have looked, said he, "into many a human heart that was seven times<br />

hotter with sinful passions than yonder furnace is with fire. But I found<br />

not there what I sought. No, not the Unpardonable Sin!"<br />

"What is the Unpardonable Sin?" asked the lime-burner; and then he<br />

shrank further from his companion, trembling lest his question should be<br />

answered.<br />

"It is a sin that grew within my own breast," replied Ethan Brand,<br />

standing erect, with a pride that distinguishes all enthusiasts of his stamp.<br />

"A sin that grew nowhere else! <strong>The</strong> sin of an intellect that triumphed over<br />

the sense of brotherhood with man and reverence for God, and sacrificed<br />

everything to its own mighty claims! <strong>The</strong> only sin that deserves a<br />

recompense of immortal agony! Freely, were it to do again, would I incur<br />

the guilt. Unshrinkingly I accept the retribution!"<br />

"<strong>The</strong> man's head is turned," muttered the lime-burner to himself. "He<br />

may be a sinner, like the rest of us--nothing more likely--but, I'll be sworn,<br />

he is a madman too."<br />

Nevertheless he felt uncomfortable at his situation, alone with Ethan<br />

Brand on the wild mountain-side, and was right glad to hear the rough<br />

murmur of tongues, and the footsteps of what seemed a pretty numerous<br />

party, stumbling over the stones and rustling through the underbrush.<br />

Soon appeared the whole lazy regiment that was wont to infest the village<br />

tavern comprehending three or four individuals who had drunk flip beside<br />

the bar-room fire through all the winters, and smoked their pipes beneath<br />

the stoop through all the summers, since Ethan Brand's departure.<br />

Laughing boisterously, and mingling all their voices together in<br />

unceremonious talk, they now burst into the moonshine and narrow<br />

streaks of fire-light that illuminated the open space before the lime-kiln.<br />

Bartram set the door ajar again, flooding the spot with light, that the<br />

whole company might get a fair view of Ethan Brand, and he of them.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re, among other old acquaintances, was a once ubiquitous man,<br />

now almost extinct, but whom we were formerly sure to encounter at the<br />

hotel of every thriving village throughout the country. It was the stageagent.<br />

<strong>The</strong> present specimen of the genus was a wilted and smoke-dried<br />

man, wrinkled and red-nosed, in a smartly cut, brown, bob-tailed coat,<br />

with brass buttons, who, for a length of time unknown, had kept his desk<br />

and corner in the bar-room, and was still puffing what seemed to be the<br />

same cigar that he had lighted twenty years before. He had great fame as a<br />

dry joker, though, perhaps, less on account of any intrinsic humor than<br />

from a certain flavor of brandy-toddy and tobacco-smoke, which<br />

impregnated all his ideas and expressions, as well as his person. Another


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 76<br />

well-remembered though strangely altered face was that of Lawyer Giles,<br />

as people still called him in courtesy; an elderly ragamuffin, in his soiled<br />

shirt-sleeves and tow-cloth trousers. This poor fellow had been an attorney,<br />

in what he called his better days, a sharp practitioner, and in great vogue<br />

among the village litigants; but flip, and sling, and toddy, and cocktails,<br />

imbibed at all hours, morning, noon, and night, had caused him to slide<br />

from intellectual to various kinds and degrees of bodily labor, till, at last,<br />

to adopt his own phrase, he slid into a soap-vat. In other words, Giles was<br />

now a soap-boiler, in a small way. He had come to be but the fragment of a<br />

human being, a part of one foot having been chopped off by an axe, and an<br />

entire hand torn away by the devilish grip of a steam-engine. Yet, though<br />

the corporeal hand was gone, a spiritual member remained; for, stretching<br />

forth the stump, Giles steadfastly averred that he felt an invisible thumb<br />

and fingers with as vivid a sensation as before the real ones were<br />

amputated. A maimed and miserable wretch he was; but one, nevertheless,<br />

whom the world could not trample on, and had no right to scorn, either in<br />

this or any previous stage of his misfortunes, since he had still kept up the<br />

courage and spirit of a man, asked nothing in charity, and with his one<br />

hand--and that the left one--fought a stern battle against want and hostile<br />

circumstances.<br />

Among the throng, too, came another personage, who, with certain<br />

points of similarity to Lawyer Giles, had many more of difference. It was<br />

the village doctor; a man of some fifty years, whom, at an earlier period of<br />

his life, we introduced as paying a professional visit to Ethan Brand<br />

during the latter's supposed insanity. He was now a purple-visaged, rude,<br />

and brutal, yet half-gentlemanly figure, with something wild, ruined, and<br />

desperate in his talk, and in all the details of his gesture and manners.<br />

Brandy possessed this man like an evil spirit, and made him as surly and<br />

savage as a wild beast, and as miserable as a lost soul; but there was<br />

supposed to be in him such wonderful skill, such native gifts of healing,<br />

beyond any which medical science could impart, that society caught hold<br />

of him, and would not let him sink out of its reach. So, swaying to and fro<br />

upon his horse, and grumbling thick accents at the bedside, he visited all<br />

the sick chambers for miles about among the mountain towns, and<br />

sometimes raised a dying man, as it were, by miracle, or quite as often, no<br />

doubt, sent his patient to a grave that was dug many a year too soon. <strong>The</strong><br />

doctor had an everlasting pipe in his mouth, and, as somebody said, in<br />

allusion to his habit of swearing, it was always alight with hell-fire.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se three worthies pressed forward, and greeted Ethan Brand each<br />

after his own fashion, earnestly inviting him to partake of the contents of a<br />

certain black bottle, in which, as they averred, he would find something<br />

far better worth seeking for than the Unpardonable Sin. No mind, which<br />

has wrought itself by intense and solitary meditation into a high state of<br />

enthusiasm, can endure the kind of contact with low and vulgar modes of<br />

thought and feeling to which Ethan Brand was now subjected. It made<br />

him doubt--and, strange to say, it was a painful doubt--whether he had<br />

indeed found the Unpardonable Sin, and found it within himself. <strong>The</strong>


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 77<br />

whole question on which he had exhausted life, and more than life, looked<br />

like a delusion.<br />

"Leave me," he said, bitterly, "ye brute beasts, that have made<br />

yourselves so, shrivelling up your souls with fiery liquors! I have done with<br />

you. Years and years ago, I groped into your hearts, and found nothing<br />

there for my purpose. Get ye gone!"<br />

"Why, you uncivil scoundrel," cried the fierce doctor, "is that the way<br />

you respond to the kindness of your best friends? <strong>The</strong>n let me tell you the<br />

truth. You have no more found the Unpardonable Sin than yonder boy Joe<br />

has. You are but a crazy fellow--I told you so twenty years ago--neither<br />

better nor worse than a crazy fellow, and the fit companion of old<br />

Humphrey, here!"<br />

He pointed to an old man, shabbily dressed, with long white hair, thin<br />

visage, and unsteady eyes. For some years past this aged person had been<br />

wandering about among the hills, inquiring of all travellers whom he met<br />

for his daughter. <strong>The</strong> girl, it seemed, had gone off with a company of<br />

circus-performers; and occasionally tidings of her came to the village, and<br />

fine stories were told of her glittering appearance as she rode on horseback<br />

in the ring, or performed marvellous feats on the tight-rope.<br />

<strong>The</strong> white-haired father now approached Ethan Brand, and gazed<br />

unsteadily into his face.<br />

"<strong>The</strong>y tell me you have been all over the earth," said he, wringing his<br />

hands with earnestness. "You must have seen my daughter, for she makes<br />

a grand figure in the world, and everybody goes to see her. Did she send<br />

any word to her old father, or say when she was coming back?"<br />

Ethan Brand's eye quailed beneath the old man's. That daughter, from<br />

whom he so earnestly desired a word of greeting, was the Esther of our<br />

tale, the very girl whom, with such cold and remorseless purpose, Ethan<br />

Brand had made the subject of a psychological experiment, and wasted,<br />

absorbed, and perhaps annihilated her soul, in the process.<br />

"Yes," murmured he, turning away from the hoary wanderer; "it is no<br />

delusion. <strong>The</strong>re is an Unpardonable Sin!"<br />

While these things were passing, a merry scene was going forward in<br />

the area of cheerful light, beside the spring and before the door of the hut.<br />

A number of the youth of the village, young men and girls, had hurried up<br />

the hill-side, impelled by curiosity to see Ethan Brand, the hero of so<br />

many a legend familiar to their childhood. Finding nothing, however, very<br />

remarkable in his aspect--nothing but a sun-burnt wayfarer, in plain garb<br />

and dusty shoes, who sat looking into the fire, as if he fancied pictures<br />

among the coals--these young people speedily grew tired of observing him.<br />

As it happened, there was other amusement at hand. An old German Jew,<br />

travelling with a diorama on his back, was passing down the mountainroad<br />

towards the village just as the party turned aside from it, and, in<br />

hopes of eking out the profits of the day, the showman had kept them<br />

company to the lime-kiln.<br />

"Come, old Dutchman," cried one of the young men, "let us see your<br />

pictures, if you can swear they are worth looking at!"


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 78<br />

"O, yes, Captain," answered the Jew--whether as a matter of courtesy<br />

or craft, he styled everybody Captain--"I shall show you, indeed, some very<br />

superb pictures!"<br />

So, placing his box in a proper position, he invited the young men and<br />

girls to look through the glass orifices of the machine, and proceeded to<br />

exhibit a series of the most outrageous scratchings and daubings, as<br />

specimens of the fine arts, that ever an itinerant showman had the face to<br />

impose upon his circle of spectators. <strong>The</strong> pictures were worn out,<br />

moreover, tattered, full of cracks and wrinkles, dingy with tobacco-smoke,<br />

and otherwise in a most pitiable condition. Some purported to be cities,<br />

public edifices, and ruined castles in Europe; others represented<br />

Napoleon's battles and Nelson's sea-fights; and in the midst of these would<br />

be seen a gigantic, brown, hairy hand--which might have been mistaken<br />

for the Hand of Destiny, though, in truth, it was only the showman's-pointing<br />

its forefinger to various scenes of the conflict, while its owner gave<br />

historical illustrations. When, with much merriment at its abominable<br />

deficiency of merit, the exhibition was concluded, the German bade little<br />

Joe put his head into the box. Viewed through the magnifying glasses, the<br />

boy's round, rosy visage assumed the strangest imaginable aspect of an<br />

immense Titanic child, the mouth grinning broadly, and the eyes and<br />

every other feature overflowing with fun at the joke. Suddenly, however,<br />

that merry face turned pale, and its expression changed to horror, for this<br />

easily impressed and excitable child had become sensible that the eye of<br />

Ethan Brand was fixed upon him through the glass.<br />

"You make the little man to be afraid, Captain," said the German Jew,<br />

turning up the dark and strong outline of his visage, from his stooping<br />

posture. "But look again, and, by chance, I shall cause you to see<br />

somewhat that is very fine, upon my word!"<br />

Ethan Brand gazed into the box for an instant, and then starting back,<br />

looked fixedly at the German. What had he seen? Nothing, apparently; for<br />

a curious youth, who had peeped in almost at the same moment, beheld<br />

only a vacant space of canvas.<br />

"I remember you now," muttered Ethan Brand to the showman.<br />

"Ah, Captain," whispered the Jew of Nuremberg, with a dark smile, "I<br />

find it to be a heavy matter in my show-box--this Unpardonable Sin! By<br />

my faith, Captain, it has wearied my shoulders, this long day, to carry it<br />

over the mountain."<br />

"Peace," answered Ethan Brand, sternly, "or get thee into the furnace<br />

yonder!"<br />

<strong>The</strong> Jew's exhibition had scarcely concluded, when a great, elderly dog-<br />

-who seemed to be his own master, as no person in the company laid<br />

claim to him--saw fit to render himself the object of public notice. Hitherto,<br />

he had shown himself a very quiet, well disposed old dog, going round<br />

from one to another, and, by way of being sociable, offering his rough head<br />

to be patted by any kindly hand that would take so much trouble. But now,<br />

all of a sudden, this grave and venerable quadruped, of his own mere<br />

motion, and without the slightest suggestion from anybody else, began to<br />

run round after his tail, which, to heighten the absurdity of the proceeding,


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 79<br />

was a great deal shorter than it should have been. Never was seen such<br />

headlong eagerness in pursuit of an object that could not possibly be<br />

attained; never was heard such a tremendous outbreak of growling,<br />

snarling, barking, and snapping--as if one end of the ridiculous brute's<br />

body were at deadly and most unforgivable enmity with the other. Faster<br />

and faster, round about went the cur; and faster and still faster fled the<br />

unapproachable brevity of his tail; and louder and fiercer grew his yells of<br />

rage and animosity; until, utterly exhausted, and as far from the goal as<br />

ever, the foolish old dog ceased his performance as suddenly as he had<br />

begun it. <strong>The</strong> next moment he was as mild, quiet, sensible, and<br />

respectable in his deportment, as when he first scraped acquaintance with<br />

the company.<br />

As may be supposed, the exhibition was greeted with universal laughter,<br />

clapping of hands, and shouts of encore, to which the canine performer<br />

responded by wagging all that there was to wag of his tail, but appeared<br />

totally unable to repeat his very successful effort to amuse the spectators.<br />

Meanwhile, Ethan Brand had resumed his seat upon the log, and<br />

moved, it might be, by a perception of some remote analogy between his<br />

own case and that of this self-pursuing cur, he broke into the awful laugh,<br />

which, more than any other token, expressed the condition of his inward<br />

being. From that moment, the merriment of the party was at an end; they<br />

stood aghast, dreading lest the inauspicious sound should be reverberated<br />

around the horizon, and that mountain would thunder it to mountain, and<br />

so the horror be prolonged upon their ears. <strong>The</strong>n, whispering one to<br />

another that it was late--that the moon was almost down--that the August<br />

night was growing chill--they hurried homewards leaving the lime-burner<br />

and little Joe to deal as they might with their unwelcome guest. Save for<br />

these three human beings, the open space on the hill-side was a solitude,<br />

set in a vast gloom of forest. Beyond that darksome verge, the fire-light<br />

glimmered on the stately trunks and almost black foliage of pines,<br />

intermixed with the lighter verdure of sapling oaks, maples, and poplars,<br />

while here and there lay the gigantic corpses of dead trees, decaying on the<br />

leaf-strewn soil. And it seemed to little Joe--a timorous and imaginative<br />

child--that the silent forest was holding its breath, until some fearful thing<br />

should happen.<br />

Ethan Brand thrust more wood into the fire, and closed the door of the<br />

kiln; then looking over his shoulder at the lime-burner and his son, he<br />

bade, rather than advised, them to retire to rest.<br />

"For myself, I cannot sleep," said he. "I have matters that it concerns<br />

me to meditate upon. I will watch the fire, as I used to do in the old time."<br />

"And call the devil out of the furnace to keep you company, I suppose,"<br />

muttered Bartram, who had been making intimate acquaintance with the<br />

black bottle above-mentioned. "But watch, if you like, and call as many<br />

devils as you like! For my part, I shall be all the better for a snooze. Come,<br />

Joe!"<br />

As the boy followed his father into the hut, he looked back at the<br />

wayfarer, and the tears came into his eyes, for his tender spirit had an


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 80<br />

intuition of the bleak and terrible loneliness in which this man had<br />

enveloped himself.<br />

When they had gone, Ethan Brand sat listening to the crackling of the<br />

kindled wood, and looking at the little spirts of fire that issued through the<br />

chinks of the door. <strong>The</strong>se trifles, however, once so familiar, had but the<br />

slightest hold of his attention, while deep within his mind he was<br />

reviewing the gradual but marvellous change that had been wrought upon<br />

him by the search to which he had devoted himself. He remembered how<br />

the night dew had fallen upon him--how the dark forest had whispered to<br />

him--how the stars had gleamed upon him--a simple and loving man,<br />

watching his fire in the years gone by, and ever musing as it burned. He<br />

remembered with what tenderness, with what love and sympathy for<br />

mankind, and what pity for human guilt and woe, he had first begun to<br />

contemplate those ideas which afterwards became the inspiration of his<br />

life; with what reverence he had then looked into the heart of man, viewing<br />

it as a temple originally divine, and, however desecrated, still to be held<br />

sacred by a brother; with what awful fear he had deprecated the success of<br />

his pursuit, and prayed that the Unpardonable Sin might never be<br />

revealed to him. <strong>The</strong>n ensued that vast intellectual development, which, in<br />

its progress, disturbed the counterpoise between his mind and heart. <strong>The</strong><br />

Idea that possessed his life had operated as a means of education; it had<br />

gone on cultivating his powers to the highest point of which they were<br />

susceptible; it had raised him from the level of an unlettered laborer to<br />

stand on a star-lit eminence, whither the philosophers of the earth, laden<br />

with the lore of universities, might vainly strive to clamber after him. So<br />

much for the intellect! But where was the heart? That, indeed, had<br />

withered--had contracted--had hardened--had perished! It had ceased to<br />

partake of the universal throb. He had lost his hold of the magnetic chain<br />

of humanity. He was no longer a brother-man, opening the chambers or<br />

the dungeons of our common nature by the key of holy sympathy, which<br />

gave him a right to share in all its secrets; he was now a cold observer,<br />

looking on mankind as the subject of his experiment, and, at length,<br />

converting man and woman to be his puppets, and pulling the wires that<br />

moved them to such degrees of crime as were demanded for his study.<br />

Thus Ethan Brand became a fiend. He began to be so from the moment<br />

that his moral nature had ceased to keep the pace of improvement with<br />

his intellect. And now, as his highest effort and inevitable development--as<br />

the bright and gorgeous flower, and rich, delicious fruit of his life's labor-he<br />

had produced the Unpardonable Sin!<br />

What more have I to seek? What more to achieve?" said Ethan Brand to<br />

himself. "My task is done, and well done!"<br />

Starting from the log with a certain alacrity in his gait, and ascending<br />

the hillock of earth that was raised against the stone circumference of the<br />

lime-kiln, he thus reached the top of the structure. It was a space of<br />

perhaps ten feet across, from edge to edge, presenting a view of the upper<br />

surface of the immense mass of broken marble with which the kiln was<br />

heaped. All these innumerable blocks and fragments of marble were redhot<br />

and vividly on fire, sending up great spouts of blue flame, which


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 81<br />

quivered aloft and danced madly, as within a magic circle, and sank and<br />

rose again, with continual and multitudinous activity. As the lonely man<br />

bent forward over this terrible body of fire, the blasting heat smote up<br />

against his person with a breath that, it might be scorched and shrivelled<br />

him up in a moment.<br />

Ethan Brand stood erect, and raised his arms on high. <strong>The</strong> blue flames<br />

played upon his face, and imparted the wild and ghastly light which alone<br />

could have suited its expression; it was that of a fiend on the verge of<br />

plunging into his gulf of intensest torment.<br />

"O Mother Earth," cried he, "who art no more my Mother, and into<br />

whose bosom this frame shall never be resolved! O mankind, whose<br />

brotherhood I have cast off, and trampled thy great heart beneath my feet!<br />

O stars of heaven, that shone on me of old, as if to light me onward and<br />

upward!--farewell all, and forever. Come, deadly element of Fire-henceforth<br />

my familiar friend! Embrace me, as I do thee!"<br />

That night the sound of a fearful peal of laughter rolled heavily through<br />

the sleep of the lime-burner and his little son; dim shapes of horror and<br />

anguish haunted their dreams, and seemed still present in the rude hovel,<br />

when they opened their eyes to the daylight.<br />

"Up, boy, up!" cried the lime-burner, staring about him. "Thank Heaven,<br />

the night is gone, at last; and rather than pass such another, I would<br />

watch my lime-kiln, wide awake, for a twelvemonth. This Ethan Brand,<br />

with his humbug of an Unpardonable Sin, has done me no such mighty<br />

favor, in taking my place!"<br />

He issued from the hut, followed by little Joe, who kept fast hold of his<br />

father's hand. <strong>The</strong> early sunshine was already pouring its gold upon the<br />

mountain-tops; and though the valleys were still in shadow, they smiled<br />

cheerfully in the promise of the bright day that was hastening onward. <strong>The</strong><br />

village, completely shut in by hills, which swelled away gently about it,<br />

looked as if it had rested peacefully in the hollow of the great hand of<br />

Providence. Every dwelling was distinctly visible; the little spires of the two<br />

churches pointed upwards, and caught a fore-glimmering of brightness<br />

from the sun-gilt skies upon their gilded weather-cocks. <strong>The</strong> tavern was<br />

astir, and the figure of the old, smoke-dried stage-agent, cigar in mouth,<br />

was seen beneath the stoop. Old Graylock was glorified with a golden<br />

cloud upon his head. Scattered likewise over the breasts of the<br />

surrounding mountains, there were heaps of hoary mist, in fantastic<br />

shapes, some of them far down into the valley, others high up towards the<br />

summits and still others, of the same family of mist or cloud, hovering in<br />

the gold radiance of the upper atmosphere. Stepping from one to another<br />

of the clouds that rested on the hills, and thence to the loftier brotherhood<br />

that sailed in air, it seemed almost as if a mortal man might thus ascend<br />

into the heavenly regions. Earth was so mingled with sky that it was a<br />

day-dream to look at it.<br />

To supply that charm of the familiar and homely, which Nature so<br />

readily adopts into a scene like this, the stage-coach was rattling down the<br />

mountain-road, and the driver sounded his horn, while echo caught up<br />

the notes, and intertwined them into a rich and varied and elaborate


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 82<br />

harmony, of which the original performer could lay claim to little share.<br />

<strong>The</strong> great hills played a concert among themselves, each contributing a<br />

strain of airy sweetness.<br />

Little Joe's face brightened at once.<br />

"Dear father," cried he, skipping cheerily to and fro, "that strange man<br />

is gone, and the sky and the mountains all seem glad of it!"<br />

"Yes," growled the lime-burner, with an oath, "but he has let the fire go<br />

down, and no thanks to him if five hundred bushels of lime are not spoiled.<br />

If I catch the fellow hereabouts again, I shall feel like tossing him into the<br />

furnace!"<br />

With his long pole in his hand, he ascended to the top of the kiln. After<br />

a moment's pause, he called to his son.<br />

"Come up here, Joe!" said he.<br />

So little Joe ran up the hillock, and stood by his father's side. <strong>The</strong><br />

marble was all burnt into perfect, snow-white lime. But on its surface, in<br />

the midst of the circle--snow-white too, and thoroughly converted into<br />

lime--lay a human skeleton, in the attitude of a person who, after long toil,<br />

lies down to long repose. Within the ribs--strange to say--was the shape of<br />

a human heart.<br />

"Was the fellow's heart made of marble?" cried Bartram, in some<br />

perplexity at this phenomenon. "At any rate, it is burnt into what looks<br />

like special good lime; and, taking all the bones together, my kiln is half a<br />

bushel the richer for him."<br />

So saying, the rude lime-burner lifted his pole, and, letting it fall upon<br />

the skeleton, the relics of Ethan Brand were crumbled into fragments.


Zakaria Tamer (1931-)<br />

CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 83<br />

From Breaking Knees: Modern Arabic Short Stories from Syria, trans.<br />

by Ibrahim Muhawi (London: Garnet Publishing, 2008)<br />

-19- (Huda & the Hanged Man—untitled in the original)<br />

Huda took care to wake up early and step quicly out of the house,<br />

leaving her husband sleeping the sleep of the dead. She walked through<br />

streets that were nearly empty, heading for a famous bakery. She bought<br />

fresh, hot bread, which her husband liked more than meat or fruit and<br />

would be very pleased to have for breakfast. Suddenly people started<br />

running as fast as they could in the direction of the main square.<br />

Curiosity got the better of Huda, and she followed without thinking. Once<br />

there, she saw a gallows already in place, soldiers carrying guns, a man<br />

about to be hanged, and a sun about to rise. <strong>The</strong> noose was already<br />

around the condemned man’s neck, and he cast a glance upon the<br />

spectators milling around the scaffold. He heard only the sounds they<br />

made but saw no one except Huda, the woman with dark hair and fair<br />

hands and face, staring at him with eyes as wide open as they could be.<br />

She noticed that he had seen her, and she smiled like a child on whom<br />

snow had fallen for the first time.<br />

When the condemned man became aware that what he was standing<br />

on was about to slip away from under his feet, he gave Huda a look that<br />

appealed for help. She was amazed, for she had never thought that one<br />

day a thin young man with a gentle face and gentle eyes would seek her<br />

hep. For a few fleeing moments she felt he was her younger brother<br />

hanging on to the edge of her dress asking for protection but she did not<br />

know what to do. <strong>The</strong> hubbub and the crowd around the gallows grew<br />

more dense, especially when the young man dangled, a lifeless corpse with<br />

a blue face. Huda felt that she was about to suffocate and walked quickly<br />

away, leaving the people behind and heading home before the bread got<br />

cold. She came into the bedroom ad found her husband awake. “Now<br />

that you’re awake,” she said, “I’ll make your breakfast.”<br />

“<strong>The</strong> world won’t go to pieces,” he said as he reached for her, “if<br />

breakfast is delayed.”<br />

He started pulling at her clothes. She was disgusted and felt like<br />

moving away from his hands, but she did not stir. She smiled, pretending<br />

she could not wait for what was coming next, and her hands began to help<br />

his. She was stunned by what she was doing and became angry at herself<br />

for being so weak. She longed to cry out at the top of her voice, but she<br />

jumped into the bed with a cheerful motion and slipped under the quilt as<br />

she said, “A little while ago, I saw a man being hanged.”


CL 250 / ENGL 242 / 84<br />

“Many are hanged every day,” he said, laughing, “without rope or<br />

spectators.”<br />

She said nothing. “What did he do to deserve hanging?” he asked.<br />

“Disobey the traffic laws?”<br />

“I heard the policemen and other people say he killed an entire<br />

family because one of them had killed his brother,” Huda answered. “He<br />

killed the men and the women, and the boys and the girls. He even killed<br />

their cat, and felt sorry for no one except the cat.”<br />

“This is the state of the world,” he said as he embraced her. “He<br />

who kills only ten people is a criminal to be hanged. But he who kills<br />

hundreds of thousands is a hero among heroes.”<br />

In that silent room with the door bolted and the curtains drawn<br />

Huda saw with half-closed eyes a man moving on top of a woman who had<br />

around her neck a rope that forced her to gasp for breath, and he was<br />

ready to choke her every time she tried to break free of him.<br />

<strong>The</strong> man gave the woman a long, hard look, like a merchant who<br />

had bought a cow and wanted to make sure he had not been cheated. She<br />

felt embarrassed and closed her eyes and wanted to turn into lifeless flesh,<br />

but her body paid no head and set to doing all that pleased it and made<br />

her angry. She heard her husband say jokingly that after all this effort<br />

she would certainly give birth in nine months. She was about to say<br />

something disapproving, as she might to one who would never one day<br />

father any child she would bring into the world, but she chose to say<br />

nothing. She imagined that she had gone back to the gallows at night and<br />

cut the noose surrounding the neck of the hanged man, and that he had<br />

felt his neck with his fingers and with a distracted look had thanked her in<br />

a halting voice and promised he would never kill another cat. At that<br />

moment her husband stretched and yawned and asked about breakfast.<br />

She wanted to tell him to hurry out to the nearest restaurant, but she<br />

quickly put on some clothes and rushed into the kitchen.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!