THE BOOK WAS DRENCHED - OUDL Home
THE BOOK WAS DRENCHED - OUDL Home
THE BOOK WAS DRENCHED - OUDL Home
Create successful ePaper yourself
Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.
PREFACEAMAN is seldom moved to praise what he lovesuntil it has been attacked. The first six essaysin this book, which give it its title, were all in varyingdegrees provoked in this way. The first two defendgreat romantic poets against popular hatred or neglectof Romanticism. The third and fourth defendthe present course of English studies at Oxfordagainst certain criticisms; but so differently (the onehaving been addressed to a joint meeting of theClassical and English Associations and the other toundergraduates) that I hope they do not much overlap.The fifth is partly a defence of the many popularbooks which have, I believe, so greatly increasedmy power of enjoying more serious literature as wellas "real life'; but it is much more a defence of disinterestedliterary enjoyment in general against certaindangerous tendencies in modern education. Iwas afraid lest all the pleasant landscapes wouldscxni be shut out by a wall of blackboards and 'certificates'.The sixth is perhaps a work of attack ratherthan of defence; but probably I should not havewritten it if I had not been stimulated by the contemptsometimes expressed for Anglo-Saxon poetry.It is here reprinted from Lysistrata. 1 In spite of the1 As far as I know this Prrindical did nut survive my coutrilution, andI liavi- been unable to dircover the name and aklres of the- lady whordited it. I hope that if there linn meer her eyes she will firgive me forannuming her peruinion to reprine.
ISHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTTo heanlic me pinceppæt gc mid urum sccattum to scypc gangonunbefohtcnc, nu gc pus feorr hiderin urnc card inn becomonMALDONRead at Bedford College, LondonB
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTFEW poets have suffered more than Shelley fromthe modern dislike of the Romantics. It is naturalthat this should be so. His poetry is, to an unusualdegree, entangled in political thought, and in a kindof political thought now generally unpopular. Hisbelief in the natural perfectibility of man justlystrikes the Christian reader as foolishness; while, onthe other hand, the sort of perfection he has in view istoo ideal for dialectical materialists. His writings arctoo generous for our cynics; his life is loo loose for our'humanist' censors. Almost every recent movementof thought in one way or another serves to discredithim. From some points of view, this reaction cannotbe regarded as wholly unfortunate. There is muchin Shelley's poetry that has been praised to excess;much even that deserves no praise at all. In hismetre, with all its sweetness, there is much ignoblefluidity, much of mere jingle. His use of language issuch that he seldom attains for long to the highestqualities of distinction, and often sinks to a facilityand commonplace almost Byronic. He is not a safepoet; you cannot open his works to refute one of hisenemies with any sense of confidence. But reactionmust not be allowed to carry us too far; and whenMr. Eliot offers up Shelley as a sacrifice to the fameof Dryden it is time to call a halt. To be sure, Mr.Eliot has his own purpose in that comparison: he iscombating the view of the last century that Shelleymust necessarily be a greater poet than Dryden becausehis subjects are more obviously poetical—
4 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTbecause the one writes lyrics and the other satire,because one is in the coffee-house and the other inthe clouds. 1 But we must not fall over, like Luther'sdrunk man, on the other side of the horse. Thosewho prefer Shelley to Dryden need not do so on thegrounds which Mr. Eliot has envisaged; and to provethis I will now maintain that Shelley is to be regarded,on grounds which Mr. Eliot himself will allow, as amore masterly, a more sufficient, and indeed a moreclassical poet than Dryden.The days are, or ought to be, long past in whichany well-informed critic could take the couplet poetsof our 'Augustan' school at their own valuation as'classical' writers. This would be quite as grave anerror as the romantic criticism which denied them tobe men of genius. They arc neither bad poets norclassical poets. Their merits are great, but neithertheir merits nor their limitations are those of ancientliterature or of that modern literature which is trulyclassical. It would be hard to find any excellence inwriting less classical than wit; yet it is in wit thatthese poets admittedly excel. The very forms inwhich the greatest and most characteristic of classicalpoetry is cast—the epic and the tragedy—are theforms which they attempt with least success. Theirfavourite form is Satire, a form not invented by theGreeks, and even in Roman hands not very likeMac Fleknoe or the Dunciad. But it is needless to labourthe point. To any one who still thinks Pope a classicalpoet we can only say 'Open your Sophocles, yourVirgil, your Racine, your Milton'; and if that experi-1 Selected Essays, 1932, p. 295.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 5ment does not convince him, we may safely dismisshim for a blockhead.Of the school in general, then, we may say that itis a good, unclassical school. But when we turn toDryden, we must, I think, say more than this. Wemust admit that we have here a great, flawed poet,in whom the flaws, besides being characteristicallyunclassical, are scarcely forgivable even by the mostromantic or revolutionary standards.I have said 'a great, flawed poet'. Of the greatnessI wish to make no question; and it is a greatness towhich the name of genius is peculiarly applicable.The most abiding impression which Dryden makesupon us is that of exuberant power. He is whatMiddle English critics would have called 'boisteous'.He excels in beginnings. 'A milk white hind immortaland unchanged'—'In pious times ere priestcraft didbegin'—there is no fumbling at the exordium. Heleaps into his first paragraph as an athlete leaps intothe hundred yards' track, and before the fascinationof his ringing couplets gives us leisure to take breathwe have been carried into the heart of his matter.The famous 'magnanimity' of his satire is anotheraspect of this same quality of power. His strength isso great that he never needs—or never gives us theimpression of needing—to use it all. He is justlypraised by Mr. Eliot for 'what he has made of hismaterial', for his 'ability to make the small into thegreat, the prosaic into the poetic' : 1 not that the valueof a literary result is in a direct ratio to its difficulty—a theory with absurd consequences—but that the1 Op. cit., p. 296.
6 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTsheer strength of the poet is more easily judged whenit is thus isolated. Of this transforming power I knowno better example than the resume of the politicalsituation which opens Absalom and Achitophel. Notonly is the prosaic made poetical, but the obscure andcomplicated is made clear and simple. A child canhardly fail to understand the state of Israel as Drydendescribes it; and yet surprisingly little of that situation,as Dryden saw it, has been omitted. If anythingis misrepresented, the misrepresentation isdeliberate.Mr. Eliot himself selects, to illustrate this transformingpower, a passage from Alexander's Feast andanother from Cymon and Iphigenia. The first is that inwhich the tipsy Alexander 'Fought all his battles o'eragain; And thrice he routed all his foes, and thrice heslew the slain 5 . Certainly, if the thing was to be doneat all, this is the way to do it. The sudden irruptionof the country-dancing fourtecner among the nobler,if never very subtle, rhythms of the ode, most happilyexpresses the transition from heroics to a tavernscene. Dryden has brought off his effect—and it isan effect which will be dear to all who hate the heroicand cannot see any civil or religious ceremony withoutwishing that some one may slip. For a critic likeMr. Eliot, however, the question must surely be notonly whether a given effect has been attained, butalso whether, and why, it ought to have been attempted.Certain classicists would resent the intrusionof the comic into the greater ode at all, as anoffence against decorum. I am sure that Mr. Eliotremembers, and almost sure he approves, the deli-
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 7cious reproaches levelled against Racine by Frenchcritics for venturing within the remotest hailing distanceof comedy in certain scenes of Andromaque; andthe greater ode is as lofty a form as tragedy. But evenif we allow the comic note, can we excuse comedy ofquite this hackneyed and heavy-handed type? ThatAlexander in his cups should resemble exactly thefirst drunken braggart whom you may meet in a railwayrefreshment room, appears to Mr. Eliot to add'a delicate flavour'. 1 But what is there delicate aboutit? Indelicacy, in the sense of grossness and crudityof apprehension, is surely the very essenceof it. It docs not seem to have crossed Dryden's mindthat when Alexander got drunk he may have behavedlike a drunk gentleman or a drunk scholar andnot like an 'old soldier'. No: this is not a subtle ordelicate joke. If it is to be defended at all, it must bedefended as a 'good plain joke'. As such, Mr. Eliotapparently likes it, and I do not: and this is of verylittle consequence. What is important is that thepassage raises in our minds a rather disturbing doubtabout Dryden's poetical purity of intention. Thejoke may be good or bad in itself. Let us suppose thatit is good;—the question remains whether even agood joke, of this tavern type, really contributes tothe total effect of the ode. Does Dryden really carewhether it contributes or not? Is he, in fine, a manready, for every ray of accidental beauty that maycome in his way, to sacrifice the integrity of his work—a dabbler in 'good passages'—a man who canproduce good poetry but not good poems?1 Op. cit., p. 297.
8 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTAs regards Alexander's Feast I am content to leavethe question open: when once it has been raised weshall have no difficulty in answering it for the rest ofDryden's more considerable works. What do weenjoy in Absalom and Achitophel? Undoubtedly, theincidental merits. Of the poem taken as a whole, asa Johnson has said the last word.'There is an unpleasing disproportion between thebeginning and the end. We are alarmed by a factionformed of many sects, various in their principles, butagreeing in their purpose of mischief, formidable for theirnumbers, and strong by their supports; while the King'sfriends arc few and weak. The chiefs on either part areset forth to view: but when expectation is at the height,the King makes a speech, andHenceforth a series of new times began.'No doubt, the very nature of the case compelledDryden to this fault; but that excuses the man withoutmending the poem. I do not argue why the workis botched, but that it is. It is even part of my casethat the defect in Absalom was unavoidable. It is aradical defect, consubstantial with Dryden's originalconception. It is no mere accident. The work is notmerely maimed, it is diseased at the heart. Likemany human invalids, it is not lacking in charms andhappy moments; but classicists like Mr. Eliot (andmyself) should not accept any amount of litteredpoetry as a poem. If we turn to the Hind and thePanther we find the same irredeemable defect in anaggravated form. Of course it is full of 'good things';but of the plan itself, the nerve and structure of thepoem, what are we to say if not that the very design
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 9of conducting in verse a theological controversy allegorizedas a beast fable suggests in the author a stateof mind bordering on aesthetic insanity? If the poethad succeeded it would indeed provide a noble exampleof the transforming power which Mr. Eliotclaims for him. But he has not. The Hind and thePanther docs not exist, as Phèdre or Persuasion or TheAlchemist exist. It is not a poem: it is simply a namewhich we give for convenience to a number of piecesof good description, vigorous satire, and 'popular'controversy, which have all been yoked together byexternal violence.It may be objected that I am selecting poemsmerely occasional, specimens at least of 'applied'poetry, which cannot fairly be judged by the higheststandards. But this is dangerous argument for thedefenders of Dryden. The two poems I have quotedare among his most considerable works: they containmuch of his noblest, and much of his most piquant,poetry. If these have to be thrown to the wolves asmere applied poetry for which special indulgence issued, it will be hard, on what remains, to support theplea that Dryden is a poet comparable to Shelley.But I pass over this difficulty. Let us turn to worksmore purely 'poetical', and specially to the Fableswhich no one asked him to write. Here, if anywhere,we may hope to find the real 'maker' at last insteadof the mere fountain of brilliant 'passages'. Here,perhaps, Dryden will become the master, not theslave, of inspiration.It falls out very happily that Mr. Eliot should havechosen from one of these fables a passage in illustra-
10 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTtion of the 'transforming power'. It is the satire onthe militia in Cymon and Iphigenia.The country rings around with loud alarms,And raw in fields the rude militia swarms, &c.Of this, Mr. Eliot observes 'the comic is the material,the result is poetry 5 . 1 Yes, but comic poetry.The passage, if not so lustily comic as the picture ofAlexander's tipsy valour, is a humorous passage; andI do not know why it shows more power to makecomic poetry of comic material than to make idyllicpoetry of idyllic material. Yet it shows power enough,and I will not press the point; but I cannot helpwondering that Mr. Eliot should think it worth whileto quote this amusing description (a 'beauty' surelynot very recondite), and yet not worth while to tellus why it should be in Cymon and Iphigenia at all. Towhat artistic end, precisely, is this satire on militiasinserted in a romantic fable? I am afraid it is thereonly because Dryden wanted to write it. Doubtless,the fault is here much more venial than in Alexander'sFeast. The joke itself is less hackneyed, and the lowertone of the fable admits a laxer kind of relevance thanthe ode. Perhaps, justified as an 'episode' the linesare excusable: and if, in this place, Dryden 'will havehis joke', have it he shall, for me. But there is worsebehind. In Sigismonda and Guiscardo Dryden revealsso much of himself that I question whether any onewho has read it with attention can fail to see, onceand for all, the alte terminus haerens which dividesDryden from the class of great poets. Here he sets out1 Op. cit., p. 297.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 11to tell a tragic and 'heroic' story. It is not a story ofthe highest order. It suffers from that overstrain andtendency to falsetto which is the infallible mark ofthe prosaic mind desperately determined to be'poetical'. You could not make an Oedipus or a Learout of it; you might make a Cid. But it is, at least, astory worth telling. And now mark what Drydcndoes with it. He does not intend to forgo a singlethrill of the tragic ending. He intends to purge ouremotions. We are to see the heroine 'devoutly glue'her lips to the heart of her murdered husband, andour respect is to be demanded for her 'Mute solemnsorrow without female noise'. That is the note onwhich the poem is to end. And yet, with such an endin view, this old poet goes out of his way to insert atthe beginning of his story a ribald picture of hisheroine as the lascivious widow of conventionalcomedy. I will not quote the pitiful lines in whichDryden winks and titters to his readers over thesetime-honoured salacities. The reader may turn tothe passage for himself. And when he has read onto the bitter end of it, to that couplet where evenDryden's skill in language deserts him and we sinkto the scribbled meanness ofOn either side the kisses flew so thickThat neither she nor he had breath to speak,then let him remind himself that all this is the beginningof a tragic story, and that Dryden will presentlytry to make sublime this same woman whom he ishere turning into a Widow Wadman. For such sinagainst the essential principles of all poetry whatever,no excuse can be made. It cannot be accident.
12 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTDryden is the most conscious of writers: he knowswell what he is doing. He destroys, and is content todestroy, the kind of poem he sat down to write, if onlyhe can win in return one guffaw from the youngestand most graceless of his audience. There is in thisa poetic blasphemy, an arrogant contempt for hisown art, which cannot, I think, be paralleled in anyother great writer.It would show a serious misunderstanding if Dryden'spartisans pleaded at this point that I wasenslaved to some Victorian canon of solemnity as theessence of poetry and judging Dryden by an alienstandard. I have no quarrel with comic or cynical oreven ribald poetry. 1 have no quarrel with Wycherlcy,I admire Congrevc, I delight in Prior and stillmore in Don Juan. I delight in Dryden himself whenhe is content to talk bawdy in season and consider'Sylvia the fair in the bloom of fifteen' a very prettypiece. But in these fables—as also in the heroictragedies which arc similarly blemished—it is Dryden,not I, who has chosen that the heroic should betrumps, and has lost the game by rules of his ownchoosing. It was Dryden, not I, who decided towrite Annus Mirabilis as a serious and lofty historicalpoem on what he regarded as the 'successes of a mostjust and necessary war'. If, after that decision, hedescribes the enemy asVast bulks which little souls but ill supply,then we have every right to tell that a nation ofreasonable men, not to say men of courage andhonour, are very ill-celebrated by the insinuationthat their enemies are lubbers. This kind of thing
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 13runs through all Drydcn's attempts at the graver andmore enthusiastic kinds of poetry, and it must beremembered that such attempts make up a large partof his work. The sin is so flagrant that I cannotunderstand how so cultivated a critic as Mr. Eliot hasfailed to sec the truth; which truth had now better bestated quite frankly. Drydcn fails to be a satisfactorypoet because being rather a boor, a gross, vulgar,provincial, misunderstanding mind, he yet constantlyattempts those kinds of poetry which demand thecuor gentil. Like so many men of that age he is deeplyinfluenced by the genuinely aristocratic and heroicpoetry of France. He admires the world of the Frenchtragedians—that exalted tableland where rhetoricand honour grow naturally out of the life lived andthe culture inherited. We in England had had anaristocratic tradition of our own, to be sure; a traditionat once more sober and more tenderly romanticthan the French, obeying a code of honour less dissociatedfrom piety. The Duke and Duchess of Newcastlewere perhaps its last exponents. But Drydenseems to know nothing of it. He and his audienceslook to Versailles, and feel for it that pathetic yetunprofitable yearning which vulgarity so often feelsfor unattainable graces. But the yearning does notteach them the secret. Where their model was brilliantthey are flashy; where the Cid was brave,Almansor swaggers; refinements of amorous casuistryout of the heroic romances are aped by the loves ofgrooms and chambermaids. One is reminded of amodern oriental, who may have the blood of oldpaynim knighthoods in him, but who prefers to
14 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTdress himself up as a cheap imitation of a Europeangentleman.The worst thing about such challenging praise asMr. Eliot offers Drydcn—praise, I believe, withwhich Dryden would be seriously embarrassed—isthat it forces the rest of us to remember Dryden'sfaults. I have dealt with them, as I see them, plainly,not maliciously. The man is irremediably ignorantof that world he chooses so often to write about.When he confines himself to satire, he is at home;but even here, the fatal lack of architectonic powerseldom allows him to make a satisfactory poem.That is the case against Dryden. It would have beenplcasanter to state the case for him—to analyse, inorder to praise, the masculine vigour of his English,the fine breezy, sunshiny weather of the man's mindat its best—his poetical health; the sweetness (unsurpassedin its own way) of nearly all his versification.But we cannot allow him to be used, and soused, as a stick to beat Shelley.I have now to show that Shelley, with all his faultsof execution, is a poet who must rank higher thanDryden with any critic who claims to be classical;that he is superior to Dryden by the greatness of hissubjects and his moral elevation (which are meritsby classical standards), and also by the unity of hisactions, his architectonic power, and his generalobservance of decorum in the Renaissance sense ofthe word; that is, his disciplined production not justof poetry but of the poetry in each case proper tothe theme and the species of composition. But itis hardly possible in the present age to approach
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 15these questions without first removing some popularprejudices.In the first place there is the prejudice which leadsmany people to mutter the word 'Godwin' as soon asShelley is mentioned. They are quite sure that Godwinwrote a very silly book; they arc quite sure thatthe philosophic content of much Shelleyan poetry isGodwinian; and they conclude that the poetry mustbe silly too. Their first premiss I cannot discuss,since a regrettable gap in my education has left mestill the only critic in England who has not thatfamiliar knowledge of Political Justice which alonecan justify confident adverse criticism. But thesecond I can. 1 It is quite clear to any reader ofgeneral education—it must be clear, for example, toMr. Eliot—that the influence of Dante and Plato isat least as dominant in Shelley's thought as that ofGodwin—unless, indeed, Godwin shared the opinionsof Dante and Plato, in which case Godwin cannothave been so very silly. Thus, I do not know whatGodwin says about free love; but I see that thepassage in Epipsychidion beginningTrue love in this differs from gold and claymay well derive from Purgatorio xv. 49, and thus ultimatelyfrom Aristotle's Ethics 1169 A. I do not myselfagree with Shelley's application of the doctrineto sexual promiscuity; but then Plato, and manycommunists, would, and neither Shelley nor Godwin1It will be noticed that even if the premisses were true, the inference isinvalid. A similar paralogism has occurred about Mr. Housman (of course,since his death) in the form, 'Kipling is bad. Some lines of Housman arelike some lines of Kipling. Therefore Housman is bad.'
16 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTneed be made the scapegoat. Thus again, in PrometheusUnbound I see that the main theme—the mythof a universal rebirth, a restoration of all things—isone which may occur in any age and which fallsnaturally into place beside Isaiah or the FourthEclogue, and that to pin it down to Godwin is aprovincialism. Something it may owe to Godwin;but its debts to Aeschylus and, as Mr. Tillyard hasshown, to Plato's Politicus arc at least equally interesting.If Shelley were an ignoramus who had read nobook but Political Justice, or a dullard who couldinvent nothing, we might be driven to suppose thathis Asia was merely a personification of Godwinianbenevolence; but when we know that he had readof divine love and beauty in Plato and rememberthat he wrote the Hymn to Intellectual Beauty, the identificationbecomes merely perverse. And finally,whatever Godwin may really have said, one of thechief tenets attributed to him is explicitly rejectedat the end of Act III. Let us hear no more ofGodwin. 1Another prejudice is harder to combat becauseit is ill-defined. It usually expresses itself by thedamning epithet 'adolescent'; it began with Arnold'sphrase about the 'ineffectual angel'. Shelley is supposedto be not merely seely in the Elizabethan sense,but silly in the modern sense; to believe ludicrouslywell of the human heart in general, and crudely illof a few tyrants; to be, in a word, insufficiently disillusioned.Before removing this misunderstanding,1 That is, nothing more in the usual strain. For a reprint of PoliticalJustice (a book very difficult to find) I am all agog: it is not likely to be sodull as our critical tradition proclaims.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 17I must point out that if it were granted it would notplace him below Drydcn. Dryden is equally ignorantof the world, though in the opposite direction, as hissorry joke about Alexander would be sufficient toshow. Whenever he attempts to be lofty he betrayshimself. There are senile and vulgar illusions no lessthan illusions adolescent and heroical; and of thetwo, I sec no reason for preferring the former. IfI must, in either event, be blindfold, why should Ichoose to have my eyes bandaged with stinkingclouts rather than with cloth of gold ? The fashionindeed is all for the stinking clouts, and it is easy tosee why. Men (and, still more, boys) like to callthemselves disillusioned because the very form of theword suggests that they have had the illusions andemerged from them—have tried both worlds. Theclaim, however, is false in nine cases out of ten. Theworld is full of impostors who claim to be disenchantedand are really unenchanted: mere 'natural' men whohave never risen so high as to be in danger of thegenerous illusions they claim to have escaped from.Mr. Mencken is the perfect example. We need to beon our guard against such people. They talk likesages who have passed through the half-truths ofhumanitarian benevolence, aristocratic honour, orromantic passion, while in fact they are clods whohave never yet advanced so far.is theirdisease; and Dryden himself is not free from it. Hehas not escaped from those enchantments which somefind in Shelley; he has tried desperately to taste thelike, and failed, and the fustian remains in his poetrylike a scar on his face. He indeed deserves pity,c
18 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTsince he has struggled against the disease, unlike ourmodern impostors who glory in it and call it health;but this does not alter the conclusion that he cannotbe set against Shelley as one who knows againstone who is deluded. If we granted the doctrine ofShelley's amiable ignorance of the one half of life,it would still but balance Drydcn's banausic ignoranceof the other.But I do not grant the doctrine, and I do not seehow it can be accepted by any one who has readShelley's poetry with attention. It is simply not trueto say that Shelley conceives the human soul as anaturally innocent and divinely beautiful creature,interfered with by external tyrants. On the contraryno other heathen writer comes nearer to stating anddriving home the doctrine of original sin. In such anearly work as The Revolt of Islam those who come 'frompouring human blood' are told toDisguise it not—we have one human heart—All mortal thoughts confess a common home. (VIII. xix.)and again,Look on your mind—it is the book of fate—Ah! it is dark with many a blazoned nameOf misery—all are mirrors of the same, (xx.)This is weak, exclamatory poetry, I grant you, butmy concern is with the sentens. When Shelley looks atand condemns the oppressor he does so with the fullconsciousness that he also is a man just like that: theevil is within as well as without; all are wicked, andthis of course is the significance of the allegorical
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 19passage in Prometheus Unbound, where the Furies sayto PrometheusWe will live through thee, one by one,Like animal life, and though we can obscure notThe soul which burns within, that we will dwellBeside it, like a vain loud multitudeVexing the self-content of wisest men:That we will be dread thought beneath thy brainAnd foul desire round thine astonished heart,And blood within thy labyrinthine veinsCrawling like agony.Prom.Why ye are thus now.The same doctrine, more briefly and suggestivelyexpressed, occurs in the Triumph of Life, where heexplains the failure of the wise, the great, and theunforgotten by sayingtheir loreTaught them not this, to know themselves; their mightCould not repress the mystery within,And for the morn of truth they feigned, deep nightCaught them ere evening. (211-15.)We mistake Shelley wholly if we do not understandthat for him, as certainly as for St. Paul, humanity inits merely natural or 'given' condition is a body ofdeath. It is true that the conclusion he draws is verydifferent from that of St. Paul. To a Christian, convictionof sin is a good thing because it is the necessarypreliminary to repentance; to Shelley it is an extremelydangerous thing. It begets self-contempt,and self-contempt begets misanthropy and cruelty.In the Revolt of Islam the passage I have alreadyquoted leads up to the statement that it is this selfcontemptwhich arms Hatred with a 'mortal sting'.
20 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTThe man who has once seen the darkness within himselfwill soon seek vengeance on others; and in Prometheusself-contempt is twice mentioned as an evil.I do not think we can seriously doubt that Shelley isright. If a man will not become a Christian, it is veryundesirable that he should become aware of thereptilian inhabitants in his own mind. To know howbad we arc, in the condition of mere nature, is anexcellent recipe for becoming much worse. The processis very accurately described in some of the mostmemorable lines Shelley ever wrote:'Tis a trick of this same familyTo analyse their own and other minds.Such self-anatomy shall teach the willDangerous secrets: for it tempts our powers,Knowing what must be thought and may be done,Into the depth of darkest purposes:So Gcnci fell into the pit; even ISince Beatrice unveiled me to myself,And made me shrink from what I cannot shun,Show a poor figure to my own esteem,To which I grow half reconciled. . . .(Cenci, n. ii. 108 et seq.)The lines which I have italicized provide an excellentshort history of thought and sentiment in theearly twentieth century, and the whole passage is ameasure of the difference between Byron and Shelley.Byron, speaking through his Byronic heroes, is in thevery article of that process which Shelley describes,and rather proud of it. He suffers the predicament;Shelley observes and understands it. He understandsit, I think, a good deal better than most of his moderncritics.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 21Shelley's poetry presents a variety of kinds, mostof them traditional. The elegy and the greater odecome down to him from the exemplaria graeca througheighteenth-century practice; the metrical structureof the latter is indeed rooted in a misunderstandingof Pindar, but a misunderstanding which had becomeitself a precedent by Shelley's time. Swellfoot isalmost an attempt to revive the Old Comedy—anattempt which should interest Mr. Eliot since Shelleyin it faces the cardinal problem of much of Mr. Eliot'spoetry: namely, whether it is possible to distinguishpoetry about squalor and chaos from squalid andchaotic poetry. I do not think it a great success.The lyrical drama is in part Aeschylean; in part, Ithink, Shelley's redemption of a bad eighteenthcenturyform. It derives from, and redeems, thedrama of Mason, just as The Prelude and Excursionderive from, and confer new power upon, the eighteenth-centurytreatise-poem. Shelley's lyric is agreater novelty, but heavily indebted on the metricalside to Dryden himself. The fantastic tale or idyll (asin Alastor or the Witch of Atlas) probably derives fromthe mythological epyllion of the Elizabethans. In allthese kinds Shelley produces works which, thoughnot perfect, are in one way more satisfactory thanany of Dryden's longer pieces: that is to say, theydisplay a harmony between the poet's real and professedintention, they answer the demands of theirforms, and they have unity of spirit. Shelley is athome in his best poems, his clothes, so to speak, fithim, as Dryden's do not. The faults are faults ofexecution, such as over-elaboration, occasional verbo-
22 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTsity, and the like: mere stains on the surface. Thefaults in Dryden are fundamental discrepanciesbetween the real and the assumed poetic character,or radical vices in the design: diseases at the heart.Shelley could almost say with Racine, 'When myplan is made my poem is done'; with Dryden the planitself usually foredooms the poem's failure.Thus Alastor is a poem perfectly true to itself. Thetheme is universally interesting—the quest for ideallove. And both the theme and the treatment arefully suited to Shelley's powers. Hence the poem hasan apparent case, a noble obviousness, which deceivessome readers. Mr. Eliot himself is too experienceda writer to be guilty of the delusion that hecould write like Shelley if he chose; but I think manyof Mr. Eliot's readers may suffer from it. They mistakethe inevitability of Alastor, which really springsfrom the poet's harmony with his subject, for thefacility of commonplace, and condemn the poemprecisely because it is successful. Of course it has itsfaults—some of the scenery is over-written, and theform of line which ends with two long monosyllablescomes too often. But these are not the sort of defectsthat kill a poem: the energy of imagination, whichsupports so lofty, remote, and lonely an emotionalmost without a false note for seven hundred lines,remains; and it deserves to be admired, if in no higherway, at least as we admire a great suspension-bridge.I address myself, of course, only to those who areprepared, by toleration of the theme, to let the poemhave a fair hearing. For those who are not, we canonly say that they may doubtless be very worthy
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 23people, but they have no place in the Europeantradition.Perhaps this muscular sustaining power is evenmore noticeable in the Witch of Atlas, for there Shelleygoes more out of himself. In Alastor the congenialityof the theme was fully given in Shelley's temper; inthe Witch he is going successfully beyond the boundsof his temper—making himself something other thanhe was. For in this poem we have, indeed, Shelley'sordinary romantic love of the fantastical and ideal,but all keyed down, muted, deftly inhibited from itsnative solemnity and intensity in order to produce alighter, more playful effect. The theme, at bottom,is as serious as ever; but the handling 'turns all tofavour and to prettiness'. The lightness and liquidityof this piece, the sensation which we feel in reading itof seeing things distinctly, yet at a vast distance,cannot be paralleled in any poem that I know. Wemust go to another art, namely to music, to find anythingat all similar; and there we shall hardly find itoutside Mozart. It could not, indeed, have beenwritten if Shelley had not read the Italians; but it isa new modification, and in it all the light-hearteddancing perfection of Ariosto is detached fromAriosto's hardness and flippancy (though not fromhis irony) and used with a difference—disturbed byovertones, ethcrialized. The whole poem is a happyreproof to that new Puritanism which has capturedso many critics and taught us to object to pleasurein poetry simply because it is pleasure. It is natural,though regrettable, that such people should beexasperated by this mercurial poem; for to them
24 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTit is miching mallecho (as Shelley said of Peter Bell)and means, as so much of his poetry means, mischief.They know very well that they are being laughed at;and they do not like to be told howHeaven and Earth conspire to foilThe over-busy gardener's blundering toil.If Shelley had written only such poems he wouldhave shown his genius: his artistry, the discipline andpower of obedience which makes genius universal,are better shown elsewhere. Adonais naturally occursto the mind, for here we see Shelley fruitfully submittingto the conventions of a well-established form.It has all the traditional features of the elegy—theopening dirge, the processional allegory, and theconcluding consolation. There is one bad error oftaste. The Muse, lamenting Adonais, is made tolament her own immortality,I would giveAll that I am to be as thou now art!But I am chained to Time, and cannot thence depart.(xxvi.)This is to make a goddess speak like a new-madehuman widow, and to dash the public solemnity ofelegy with the violent passions of a personal lyric. Howmuch more fitting are the words of the Roman poet:Immortalcs mortales flere si foret fas,Flerent divae Camenae Naevium poetam.But it is a slip soon recovered, and not to be comparedwith the prolonged indecorum of Dryden'ssatiric conceits in his elegy for Mrs. Anne Killigrew:To the next realm she stretch'd her swayFor Painture near adjoining lay
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 25A plenteous province, and alluring prey.A chamber of Dependencies was fram'd(As conquerors will never want pretence,When arm'd, to justify th' offence)And the whole fief, in right of poetry, she claim'd.The country open lay without defence, &c.There are eighteen lines of it, and I do not knowwhether any major poet other than Dryden everplayed such silly tricks at a funeral. No one demandsthat every poet should write an elegy: let each manbe a master of his own trade. But the fact remainsthat when Shelley intends to do so, he does so; Dryden,equally intending, does not—nimium amatoringenii sui. I do not now speak of the unexampledrapture of Shelley's close. I might do so if I were toargue with Dryden, for he loves this ecstasy andquotes with approval furentis animi vaticinatio; beingoften a romantic in wish, though seldom happilyromantic in the event. But I do not know whetherMr. Eliot shares Dryden's admiration for 'thoseenthusiastic parts of poetry'; and I would prefer toargue from positions that are, or ought in logic to be,admitted by Mr. Eliot. But I have slipped into thatsentence 'If I were to argue with Dryden' unawares.Let no one suppose I am such a coxcomb as to thinkthat my defence of Shelley could stand against Dryden'shumane and luminous and Olympian dialectic;or, indeed, that it would be required in the presenceof one who would almost certainly shame and anticipateme with such generous praise of Shelley as hehas given to Shakespeare, or Milton, or Tasso, anda frank acknowledgement (he made more than one)
26 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTof his own offences against the laws of poetry. Whoeverelse is a Drydcnian in Mr. Eliot's way, I have nofear lest Dryden himself should be one.Of course Shelley too had his failures. The Revoltof Islam does not really exist much more than theHind and the Panther exists, and the ruin is less redeemedby fine passages. The Letter to Maria Gisborneis little better than a draft—a thing scrawled asquickly as the pen would cover the paper and reallyunfit for the printer. Peter Bell the Third is a moredoubtful case. I am not prepared to endure citherits squalors or its obscurity by any such moderatepromise of enjoyment as it holds out; but perhaps thecreator of Sweeney ought to have more patience bothwith the one and with the other. I do not greatlyadmire—but perhaps some of Mr. Eliot's weakerdisciples should—this little picture:As he was speaking came a spasmAnd wrenched his gnashing teeth asunder:Like one who sees a strange phantasmHe lay—there was a silent chasmBetween his upper jaw and under.Epipsychidion raises in an acute form a problem withwhich Mr. Eliot has been much occupied: I meanthe problem of the relation between our judgementon a poem as critics, and our judgement as men onthe ethics, metaphysics, or theology presupposed orexpressed in the poem. For my own part, I do notbelieve that the poetic value of any poem is identicalwith the philosophic; but I think they can differ onlyto a limited extent, so that every poem whose prosaicor intellectual basis is silly, shallow, perverse, or
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 27illiberal, or even radically erroneous, is in somedegree crippled by that fact. I am thus obliged torate Epipsychidion rather low, because I consider thethought implied in it a dangerous delusion. In itShelley is trying to stand on a particular rung of thePlatonic ladder, and I happen to believe firmly thatthat particular rung docs not exist, and that the manwho thinks he is standing on it is not standing butfalling. But no view that we can adopt will removeEpipsychidion from the slate. There is an element ofspiritual, and also of carnal, passion in it, each expressedwith great energy and sensibility, and thewhole is marred, but not completely, by the falsemode (as Mr. Eliot and I would maintain) in whichthe poet tries to blend them. It is particularly interestingto notice the internal, perhaps unconscious,control which arises amidst the very intensity of theexperience and tightens up the metrical form: thefirst forty lines are almost 'stopped couplets' and thewhole movement is much closer to Drydcn's coupletthan to that of Keats.But we are now rapidly approaching that part ofour subject where the difference between Mr. Eliotand myself ceases. In his essay on Dante, Mr. Eliotsays that he thinks the last canto of the Paradiso 'thehighest point that poetry has ever reached'. 1 I thinkthe same—and since it is so pleasant to agree, let meadd irrelevantly that I think as he docs about theBhagavad-Gita. 2 And a few pages later Mr. Eliotsingles Shelley out as the one English poet of hiscentury (I would have said the one English poet yet1 Op. cit., p. 227.2Op. cit., p. 244.
28 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTrecorded) 'who could even have begun to follow'Dante's footsteps; 1 and he generously allows thatShelley, at the end of his life, was beginning to profitby his knowledge of Dante. I do not know how muchof Shelley's work Mr. Eliot would admit by this concession.I suppose he would admit, at the very least,the Triumph of Life. If any passage in our poetry hasprofited by Dante, it is the unforgettable appearanceof Rousseau in that poem—though admittedly it isonly the Dante of the Inferno. But I am not withouthope that Mr. Eliot might be induced to includemore. In this same essay he speaks of a modern'prejudice against beatitude as material for poetry'. 2Now Dante is eminently the poet of beatitude. Hehas not only no rival, but none second to him. Butif we were asked to name the poet who most nearlydeserved this inaccessible proxime accessit, I shouldname Shelley. Indeed, my claim for Shelley mightbe represented by the proposition that Shelley andMilton arc, each, the half of Dante. I do not knowhow we could describe Dante better to one who hadnot read him, than by some such device as the following:'You know the massive quality of Milton, the sense thatevery word is being held in place by a gigantic pressure,so that there is an architectural sublime in every versewhether the matter be sublime at the moment or not.You know also the air and fire of Shelley, the very antithesisof the Miltonic solidity, the untrammelled, recklessspeed through pellucid spaces which makes us imaginewhile we are reading him that we have somehow left ourbodies behind. If now you can imagine (but you cannot,1 Op. cit., p. 250.2Ibid.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 29for it must seem impossible till you see it done) a poetrywhich combined these two ail-but incompatibles—a poetryas bright and piercing and aereal as the one, yet as weighty,as pregnant and as lapidary as the other, then you willknow what Dante is like.'To be thus half of Dante (Caesar is my authority forsuch a rarefied critical symbolism) is fame enough forany ordinary poet. And Shelley, I contend, reachesthis height in the fourth act of Prometheus.Genetically considered, the fourth act, we know,is an afterthought: teleologically it is that for whichthe poem exists. I do not mean by this that the threepreceding acts are mere means; but that their significanceand beauty are determined by what follows,and that what came last in the writing (as it comeslast in the reading) is 'naturally prior' in the Aristoteliansense. It does not add to, and therefore corrupt,a completed structure; it gives structure to thatwhich, without it, would be imperfect. The resultingwhole is the greatest long poem in the nineteenthcentury, and the only long poem of the highest kindin that century which approaches to perfection.The theme is one of sane, public, and perennialinterest—that of rebirth, regeneration, the new cycle.Like all great myths its primary appeal is to theimagination: its indirect and further appeal to thewill and the understanding can therefore be diverselyinterpreted according as the reader is a Christian, apolitician, a psycho-analyst, or what not. Myth isthus like manna; it is to each man a different dish andto each the dish he needs. It docs not grow old norstick at frontiers racial;, sexual, or philosophic; and
30 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTeven from the same man at the same moment it canelicit different responses at different levels. But greatmyth is rare in a reflective age; the temptation toallegorize, to thrust into the story the consciousdoctrines of the poet, there to fight it out as best theycan with the inherent tendency of the fable, is usuallytoo strong. Faust and the Niblung's Ring—the onlyother great mythical poems of modern times—havein this way been partially spoiled. The excellence ofShelley is that he has avoided this. He has foundwhat is, for him, the one perfect story and re-madeit so well that the ancient version now seems merelyembryonic. In his poem there is no strain betweenthe literal sense and the imaginative significance.The events which are needed to produce theseem to become the symbols of the spiritual processhe is presenting without effort or artifice or evenconsciousness on his part.The problem was not an easy one. We are to startwith the soul chained, aged, suffering; and we arc toend with the soul free, rejuvenated, and blessed. Theselection of the Prometheus story (a selection whichseems obvious only because we did not have to makeit) is the first step to the solution. But nearly everythinghas still to be done. By what steps are we topass from Prometheus in his chains to Prometheusfree? The long years of his agony cannot be dramaticallyrepresented, for they are static. The actualmoment of liberation by Heracles is a mere piece of'business'. Dramatic necessity demands that theTitan himself should do or say something before hisliberation—and if possible something that will have
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 31an effect on the action. Shelley answers this bybeginning with Promethcus's revocation of the curseupon Jupiter. Now mark how everything falls intoplace for the poet who well and truly obeys hisimagination. This revocation at once introduces thephantasm of Jupiter, the original curse on the phantasm'slips, and the despair of Earth and Echoes atwhat seems to be Promethcus's capitulation. Wethus get at one stroke a good opening episode and afine piece of irony, on the dramatic level; but we alsohave suggested the phantasmal or nightmare natureof the incubus under which the soul (or the world) isgroaning, and the prime necessity for a change ofheart in the sufferer, who is in some sort his ownprisoner. Prometheus, we are made to feel, has reallystepped out of prison with the words, 'It doth repentme.' But once again structural and spiritual necessitiesjoin hands to postpone his effective liberation.On the structural side, the play must go on; on theother, we know, and Shelley knows, how long ajourney separates the first resolve, from the finalremaking, of a man, a nation, or a world. The Furieswill return, and the act closes with low-toned melodiesof sadness and of hopes that are as yet remoteand notional.The whole of the next act, in story, is occupied withthe difficult efforts of Asia to apprehend and follow adream dreamed in the shadow of Prometheus: thedifficult journey which it leads her; her difficultdescent to the depths of the earth; and her final reascension,transformed, to the light. Difficulty is, soto speak, the subject of this act. The dramatic advan-
32 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTtage of splitting the sufferer's role into two parts,those of Prometheus and Asia, and of giving thelatter a task to perform in the liberation, is sufficientlyobvious. But we hardly need to notice this. Most ofus, while we read this act, are too absorbed, I fancy,by the new sensation it creates in us. The gradualineluctable approach of the unknown, where theunknown is sinister, is not an uncommon theme inliterature; but where else are we to find this moremedicinable theme—these shy approaches, and suddenrecessions, and returnings beyond hope, andswellings and strengthenings of a far-off, uncertainlyprognosticated good? And again, it is a necessity forShelley, simply because he has placed his fiend in thesky, to make Asia go down, not up, to fetch this good;but how miraculously it all fits in! Does any reader,whether his prepossessions be psychological or theological,question this descent into hell, this return tothe womb, this death, as the proper path for Asiato take? Our imaginations, constrained by deepestnecessities, accept all that imagery of interwoventrees and dew and moss whereby the chorus drenchthe second scene with darkness, and the softness anddamp of growing things: by the same necessity theyaccept the harsher images of the final precipitousdescent to Demogorgon's cave, and the seated darknesswhich we find there. It is out of all this, silveragainst this blackness, that the piercing song of Asia'sreascension comes; and if any one who has read thatsong in its setting still supposes that the poet is talkingabout Godwin or the Revolution, or that Shelley isany other than a very great poet, I cannot help him.
SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOT 33But for my own part I believe that no poet has feltmore keenly, or presented more weightily the necessityfor a complete unmaking and remaking of man,to be endured at the dark bases of his being. I do notknow the book (in profane literature) to which Ishould turn for a like expression of what von Hügelwould have called the 'costingness' of regeneration.The third act is the least successful: Shelley's errorwas not to see that he could shorten it when once hehad conceived the fourth. Yet some leisure and someslackened tension are here allowable. We are certainlynot ready for the fourth act at once. Betweenthe end of torment and the beginning of ecstasy theremust be a pause: peace comes before beatitude. Itwould be ridiculous, in point of achievement, to comparethis weak act in Shelley's play with the triumphantconclusion of the Purgatorio; but structurally itcorresponds to the position of the earthly paradisebetween purgatory and heaven. And in one scene atleast it is worthy of its theme. The dialogue betweenOcean and Apollo (at 'the mouth of a great river inthe island Atlantis') is among his best things: a divineindolence soaks it, and if there are better lines inEnglish poetry there are none that breathe a moreheartfelt peace than Ocean's:It is the unpastured sea hungering for calm:Peace, monster. I come now. Farewell.The fourth act I shall not attempt to analyse. Itis an intoxication, a riot, a complicated and uncontrollablesplendour, long, and yet not too long, sustainedon the note of ecstasy such as no other Englishpoet, perhaps no other poet, has given us. It can beD
34 SHELLEY, DRYDEN, AND MR. ELIOTachieved by more than one artist in music: to do it inwords has been, I think, beyond the reach of nearlyall. It has not, and cannot have, the solemnity andoverwhelming realism of the Paradiso, but it hasall its fire and light. It has not the 'sober certaintyof waking bliss' which makes Milton's paradise soinhabitable—but it sings from regions in our consciousnessthat Milton never entered.Some anti-romantic repudiations of such poetryrest, perhaps, on a misunderstanding. It might betrue, as the materialists must hold, that there is nopossible way by which men can arrive at such felicity;or again, as Mr. Eliot and I believe, that there is oneWay, and only one, and that Shelley has missed it.But while we discuss these things, the romantic poethas added meaning to the word Felicity itself. Whateverthe result of our debate, we had better attend tohis discovery lest we remain more ignorant than weneed have been of the very thing about which wedebated.
IIWILLIAM MORRISIn ordinary life a thousand considerations prohibit for mostof us any complete working out of our responses: ... but inthe 'imaginative experiences' these obstacles are removed.I. A. RICHARDS, Principles of Literary Criticism, cap. xxxi
WILLIAM MORRISIT has been said that if you tell ten people you arereading Thomas Aquinas, nine will reply withsomething about angels dancing on the point of aneedle. The saw is already out of date and Thomismin the ascendant; but it is worth remembering as areminder of the misleading labels which great writersbear during the periods of their obscurity, and alsoof the sudden changes of fashion which strip thoselabels off. In spite of some excellent critics, WilliamMorris is still commonly among the labelled. A mentionof him in many literary circles still produces atorrent of objections which have been learned byheart—he wrote Wardour Street he was a victim tofalse medievalism, his poetry is the poetry of escape,his stories are mere tapestries. It is true that thesecharges have never had any effect on his persistentadmirers. But these are a company ill fitted to defendtheir favourite. They are few—though perhaps notso few as each in his solitude supposes—and they readhumbly for the sake of pleasure, a pleasure so inexhaustiblethat after twenty or fifty years of readingthey find it worked so deeply into all their emotionsas to defy analysis. I knew one who could come nonearer to an explanation of Morris's charm than torepeat 'It's the Northernness—the Northernness';and though I knew very well what he meant, I felt itwas not war. Yet as the lovers of Morris now are, thelovers of Donne once were, and not so very long ago.It is possible that a critical revolution may yet embarrassthese scattered and inoffensive readers with the
38 WILLIAM MORRISdiscovery that what they regard as a private, perhapsa shamefaced, indulgence has all along been a gratifyingproof of their penetration and 'contemporaneity.'The thing is feasible because even the sternesttheories of literature cannot permanently suppressan author who is so obstinately pleasurable. It iscertain that the common cries against Morris, wherethey arc not mere ignorance, are based on a prioridogmatisms that will go down at a touch; and it isarguable that of all the romantics he lies least opento the usual attacks of what we may now, 1 perhaps,begin to call Georgian anti-romanticism.The objection to his language is largely a hangoverfrom the old Wordsworthian theory of diction.It is, of course, perfectly true that Morris invented forhis poems and perfected in his prose-romances alanguage which has never at any period been spokenin England; but I suppose that most instructedpeople are now aware (as Wordsworth was notaware) that what we call 'ordinary' or 'straightforward5 English prose, as we have all tried to writeit since Drydcn's time, is almost equally an artificialspeech—a literary or 'hypothetical 5 language basedon a French conception of elegance and a highlyunphilological ideal of 'correctness'. When we beginto teach boys 'essay-writing' at school we are teachingthem to translate into this language, and if they continueto write as they talk we plough them in SchoolCertificate. The question about Morris's style is notwhether it is an artificial language—all endurablelanguage in longer works must be that—but whether1 Written in the reign of Edward VIII.
WILLIAM MORRIS 39it is a good one. And it is here that sheer ignorancebegins to play its part. I cannot help suspecting thatmost of the detractors when they talk of Morris'sstyle are really thinking of his printing: they expectthe florid and the crowded, and imagine somethinglike Sidney's Arcadia. In fact, however, this styleconsistently departs from that of modern prose in thedirection of simplicity. Except for a few archaicwords—and since the appearance of the S.O.E.D. it isa pleasure to be sent to the dictionary—it is incomparablyeasier and clearer than any 'natural' stylecould possibly be, and the 'dull finish', the carefulavoidance of rhetoric, gloss, and decoration, is of itsvery essence. Those who are really repelled by itafter a fair trial are being repelled not by its romanticismbut by its classicism, for in one sense Morris is asclassical as Johnson. Long ago, Mr. Alfred Noyesnoticed the self-imposed limitation under whichMorris describes nature whether in prose or verse—the birds that are merely 'brown', the sea that isnever anything more remarkable than 'blue' or'green'. Morris, in fact, obeys the doctrine of generality;he does not number the streaks on the tulip but'exhibits in his portraits of nature such prominentand striking features as recall the original to everymind'. That such 'just representations of generalnature' can, as Johnson claims, 'please many andplease long', his own writing, and that of Morris,will equally prove.'I sat down on a bank, such as a writer of romancemight have delighted to feign. I had indeed no trees towhisper over my head, but a clear rivulet streamed at my
40 WILLIAM MORRISfeet. The day was calm, the air was soft, and all was rudeness,silence and solitude.''The road was rough that day and they went not abovea foot pace the more part of the time; and daylong theywere going up and up, and it grew cold as the sun got low,though it was yet summer.'The first sentence is from Johnson and the secondfrom Morris. There arc a dozen differences betweenthem, but there arc two important similarities; bothare content with recording obvious facts in verygeneral language, and both succeed so that we reallytaste the mountain air. It is, indeed, this mattcr-offactness,as Clutton-Brock pointed out, which lendsto all Morris's stories their sober air of conviction.Other stories have only scenery: his have geography.He is not concerned with 'painting' landscapes; hetells you the lie of the land, and then you paint thelandscapes for yourself. To a reader long fed on thealmost botanical and entomological niceties of muchmodern fiction—where, indeed, we mostly skip if thecharacters go through a jungle—the effect is at firstvery pale and cold, but also very fresh and spacious.We begin to relish what my friend called the 'Northernness'.No mountains in literature are as far awayas distant mountains in Morris. The world of hisimagining is as windy, as tangible, as resonant andthree dimensional, as that of Scott or <strong>Home</strong>r.He treats the passions, for the most part, in thesame way. A lover's night of anxiety for his mistresswho is a captive is thus described. 'He could notchoose but make stories of her meeting of the tyrant,and her fear and grief and shame, and the despair of
WILLIAM MORRIS 41her heart.' Morris does not particularize the imagerythat passed through the young man's mind; 'he couldnot choose but make stories', that is all. Later inthe same book Morris has to describe the lover'sbehaviour when alone with his mistress for someweeks in the wilderness. It is a situation about whichalmost any other author, sentimental, sensual, orcynical, would have made what Locke calls a 'pudder'.Morris gives the fact—'All this while, he durstnot kiss or caress her save very mcasurely'—and thereason 'for he deemed that she would not suffer it'.What could be more sensible? And this brings us tothe whole question of Morris's treatment of love; itis in this that he differs most remarkably from themajority of romantics and is most immune from antiromanticcriticism. On the one hand, it is no useinvoking modern psychology to reveal the concealederoticism in his imagination, because the eroticismis not concealed: it is patent, ubiquitous, and unabashed.On the other hand, Morris, except in hisfirst volume and in such an anomalous poem as Loveis Enough, makes no attempt to paint Passion asunderstood by the Romantics. Havelock Ellis'sdefinition of love ('lust plus friendship'), monstrouslyinadequate if applied to the love expressed by Danteor Coventry Patmore or Meredith, is a perfectly gooddefinition of love in Morris's stories—unless, indeed,'lust' is too heavy and breathless a name for anythingso bright and youthful and functional as his kind ofsensuality. The experience of his lovers is at theopposite extreme from the dizzying or swooningstates described in common romantic poetry. The
42 WILLIAM MORRISbeauty of Kcats's Madeline made Porphyro Taint'.But when the young man in the Roots of the Mountainsthought of the young woman's body 'it stirred himup to go swiftlier as he strode on, the day brighteningbehind him'. Morris, in fact, describes the sort oflove that is a function of health; it quickens a man'space. It is not surprising that the hero of the Rootsof the Mountains should soon after be in love with adifferent woman. Morris does not deal much inworld-without-end fidelities, and his heroes are seldomso enamoured of one damsel that they arc quiteindifferent to the beauty of others. When infidelitiesoccur they are, of course, regrettable, as any otherbreach of faith, because they wound the social healthand harmony of the tribe; they are not felt as apostasiesfrom any god of love. Morris's Jason is felt tobe a treacherous and ungrateful man for desertingMedea; but the poet docs not share Chaucer's feelingabout the mere change of love considered in itself.Still less does he understand the Christian and sacramentalview of such things. He is the most irreligiousof all our poets—anima naturaliter pagana.To see this is, of course, to see that his medievalismis a kind of accident. The real interests of the MiddleAges—Christian mysticism, Aristotelian philosophy,Courtly Love—mean nothing to him. The world ofthe sagas, at once homely and heroic, is in some waysmore congenial to him than that of the romances,just as their hard-bitten style with its almost excessiveuse of litotes is of all influences upon his language themost fruitful. That is another aspect of the 'Northcrnness'.But it would be a misunderstanding to inquire
WILLIAM MORRIS 43into the date and place of the society he depicts:you might as well apply historical criticism to Chaucer'sTroy or Sidney's Arcadia or the plays of LordDunsany. Morris chose to build up his imaginaryworld on hints furnished by the Middle and the DarkAges as these existed in the imagination of his own timeand his own circle in particular. With that circle hedoubtless shared many historical errors. But his choicewas poetically right simply because that misconceptionof the Middle Ages (for reasons which go far backinto the time of Percy and the Wartons) already existed,and existed poetically, in the public imagination. Itwas, and to some extent still is, part of our mythology.This is only to repeat that his stories in verse andprose represent an imaginary world. It is a recognitionof this fact which has earned them such epithetsas Taint', 'shadowy', 'decorative', and the like. Nineteenth-centurycriticism was unconsciously dominatedby the novel, and could praise only withreservations work which does not present analysedcharacters ('living men and women' as they calledthem) in a naturalistic setting. Modern Shakespeariancriticism dates from the abandonment ofthe attempt to treat Shakespeare's plays as if theywere novels. The change perhaps began withRaleigh's unemphasized observation that for Shakespeareplot comes first and character has to be fittedinto it. Since then such critics as Miss Spurgeon,Stoll, and Wilson Knight have all, in their severaldirections, moved away from the old conception.We are free to recognize that in the Winter's Tale thePygmalion myth or resurrection myth in the last act
44WILLIAM MORRISis the substance and the characters, motives, andhalf-hearted attempts at explanation which surroundit are the shadow. We may even regret that theconvention in which Shakespeare worked did notallow him to make Paulina frankly a fairy or an angeland thus be rid of his 'improbable possibilities'. Itwill soon, we may hope, be impossible to relegateMorris to the shades because his whole world is aninvention. All we need demand is that this inventedworld should have some intellectual or emotionalrelevance to the world we live in.And it has. The travels of the Argonauts or ofthose more ambitious wanderers in the Earthly Paradise,the quest for the well at the world's end or thewood beyond the world, the politics of Mirkwoodand the sorrow of Odin the Goth—all these areattached in a dozen ways first to Morris's life and thento the lives of us all. They express the author'sdeepest sense of reality, which is much subtler andmore sensitive than we expect—a mass of 'tensions'as von Hügel would have said. It is a pity that somany readers begin with the Earthly Paradise, notonly because it contains much of his dullest work butalso because it can hardly be understood in isolation.The opening stanzas state the theme of mutabilityand mortality, which seems at first a romanticcommonplace, and the author seems himself to invitethat very estimate of his work which I am rejecting,calling himself an idle singer, whosemurmuring rhymeBeats with light wing against the ivory gateTelling a tale not too importunate.
WILLIAM MORRIS 45It is only when we have read the Prologue and all the'links' that we perceive this complaint of mortalityas the recoil from a positive and violent passion forimmortality. The Prologue, in fact, is the breakingof a wave: the whole of the rest of the book is 'themelancholy, long, withdrawing roar', and into itMorris has put all that negative and compensatorypoetry which has earned him his reputation. Thescheme could hardly have escaped monotony and henever tried it again. But even here the first 'tension'becomes visible and redeems the whole thing frommere fin de siècle pessimism. On the one hand we havethe passion for immortality, which in Morris is aswild, as piercing, as orgiastic and heart-breaking ashis presentations of sexual love are simple, sensuous,and unimpassioned; and this in itself is somethingvery different from mere melancholy. But it isbalanced by an opposite feeling which no one hasexpressed quite so forcibly as Morris—the feelingthat such desire is not wholly innocent, that the worldof mortality is more than enough for our allegiance,and that the traitor and apostate who follows awilder possibility will look back too late on theland that might have been to meA kindly giver of wife, child, and friendAnd happy life, or at the worser endA quiet grave till doomsday rend the earth.This poise between two moods must not be mistakenfor a debate about two doctrines. Morris, like a truePagan, does not tell us (because he does not think heknows) the ultimate significance of those moments inwhich we cannot help reaching out for something
46 WILLIAM MORRISbeyond the visible world and so discovering 'at whatunmeasured price man sets his life 5 . He neither seeksto justify them like a Christian nor to repress themlike a materialist. He simply presents the tension.And it is one that cannot be resolved: for that sameimpression of the goodness of mere living which correctsour desire for some Acre of the Undying mustalso aggravate the sting of mortality. As Byron hadsaid, there is no sterner moralist than pleasure; andso for Morris it is not unhappiness but happinesswhich is the real fountain of misgiving, making us'more mindful that the sweet days die'. The idyllic,which admittedly fills so large a place in his work, isnot simply an escape; its temporary exclusion of illluck, disease, and injustice serves to disengage thereal and unalterable trouble about temporal existenceas such. It is as if Morris said to the ordinarypessimists, 'Yes, yes, I know all about the slums, andTess, and Jude. Perhaps we can abolish them in arational society; but it is then that the real problemappears.'No doubt many will be tempted to reply that this'is going far to seek disquietude' in a world wherescarce one per cent, of the population have ever beenso fortunate as to have leisure for those delicate distresses.But Morris has not left himself open to thisreply. No one could be less of 'a cut bono man'; noone more concerned, both in practice and imagination,with 'the people's praise 5 and the 'good of thefolk'. This second tension, between the fundamentalunsatisfactoriness of mortal life and a conviction thatthe vigorous enjoyment and improvement of such
WILLIAM MORRIS 47life is infinitely worth while, now begins to appear.Already in The Life and Death of Jason the hauntingdesire for immortality is opposed—and, again, I donot mean doctrinally opposed—not so much to ordinaryhappiness as to heroic exploit. The Argonautsare teased and solicited over and over again byparadises, gardens, and islands, 'not made for menthat die', and every pause of the action is but asilence to make audible theFormless and wailing thoughts that pressAbout our hour of happiness.But the answer to these is simply to get on with thejob—to mend the sails, or launch the boat, or gatherfirewood. This admirable solution—at times almostas surprising as that in the Bhagavad-Gita, 'Defeat andvictory are the same: therefore fight'—becomes moreand more characteristic of Morris as he proceeds. InSigurd it amounts almost to a complete tramplingunderfoot of the whole ideal of happiness in anyshape or form. It is contemptible to ask 'a littlelonger and a little longer to live'. The gods have notmade the world for happiness but to be 'a tale', andit is good, when they ask us for one deed, to give themtwo. We find even a hint that there may be someultimate justification of all things which will explainWhy the brave man's spear is broken and his war-shieldfails at need.But Morris soon withdraws from these supposals.For one so enamoured of 'the Northernness' thesedoomed Eddaic gods—the very type of Stoical Romanticism—hada strong appeal. But Morris cannot
48 WILLIAM MORRISforget that he does not really know whether anythinglike them exists, and he feels that the whole thing isgetting too like a philosophy or a theology. He willnot hammer his world into any simplified shape.Hence in the great prose romances, which arc thereal crown of his work, we come back to somethingmuch more actual. The answer to the 'formless andwailing thoughts' is found in the daily life, health,and preservation of the community. The 'kindreds','houses', or 'little lands' of the romances are thepoints where Morris's career as a socialist touches hiscareer as a poet. For Morris—let there be no mistakeabout it—is in one sense as good a 'totalitarian' asever came out of Moscow or Berlin; his romanticsocialism, if it be romantic, is at the opposite polefrom the individualism of Shelley or Tom Payne. Heimmerses the individual completely in the society. 'Ifthou diest today, where then shall our love be?'asks the heroine in the House of the Wolfings. 'It shallabide with the soul of the Wolfings', comes theanswer. The good tribesman cannot 'see' the 'gravenight',but rather the 'tale of the Wolfings throughthe coming days' and himself 'amidst it ever rebornand yet reborn'. The opposite state of mind is anenchantment of the dwarfs, when a man becomesseparated in soul from the kindred—'I loved themnot and was not of them, and outside myself there wasnothing: within me was the world.' The last words,which I have ventured to italicize, are Morris'spenetrating analysis of the poison inherent in onetype of romanticism: its dandyism, and subjectivity,and its pitiful war-cry au moins je suis autre. Morris
WILLIAM MORRIS 49has nothing here to learn from our own century.Rather he has something to teach. Many sociologicalwriters are dull because while they talk of a justdistribution of goods they give us no assurance thatthey know what Good means: we remain in doubtlest the gold they would distribute so equitably maybe but fairy gold which will turn by daylight intoballot papers or soup tickets. The great use of theidyllic in literature is to find and illustrate the good—to give a real value to the x about which politicalalgebra can then work. The tribal communitieswhich Morris paints in The House of the Wolfings orThe Roots of the Mountains are such attempts, perhapsthe most successful attempts ever made, to give x avalue. Morris knows as concretely as Burke or Tolstoywhat he wants. A modern poet of the Left, praisingthat same solidarity with the group which Morrispraises, invites a man to be 'one cog in the singinggolden hive'. Morris, on the other hand, paints theactual going on of the communal life, the sowing,planting, begetting, building, ditching, eating, andconversation. And for this reason, where the modernpoet (squeezing two of the commonest journalisticmetaphors together, whether inadvertently or in thevain hope of a lively oxymoron) goes no deeper thanthe excitement of a political meeting, Morris, fromremote Mirkwood and unhistoric Burgstead, bringsback a sentiment that a man could really live by. Hemay seem, in one way, to be as ideal as Shelley, butin another he is as earthy, as rooted, as Aristotle orDr. Johnson. He is everywhere concrete. Comte's'subjective immortality' and Godwin's 'benevolence'E
50 WILLIAM MORRISare mere philosophemes: Morris's life beyond lifewith the soul of the Wolfings, because we know themand indeed arc bone of their bone, is something solid.He tells of what he has tried and found good.I spoke just now of the enchantment which separatedone of Morris's heroes from this unity. Significantly,it came from a 'dwarf-wrought hauberk'which offered him immunity from death. Histemptation to use it and his final rejection of it arcthe main theme of The House of the Wolfings: theconflict between the love of the tribe and the fear ofdeath is here explicit. And if Morris were mainlyconcerned with the fear of death, this romance wouldhave resolved the tension, for on this level life anddeath with the kindred has only to be seen to bepreferred to anything else in the world or out of theworld. But the fear of death was never one of Morris'schief concerns: it is only an aspect of something verydifferent, and much harder to extinguish—the positiveand passionate thirst for immortality. And sothe solution is only momentary: in the romances thatfollow, the rebel passion breaks out again, never moreimpressive than when it is thus expressed by an old,unwearied poet. In the later romances the claims ofthe tribe arc not forgotten, and the young hero whogoes to the end of the world to drink of the well oflife carries thither with him, and carries back, thedetermination to settle down and be a good king inhis own small country. No wanderings are allowedto obliterate our love for 'the little platoon we belongto'. The tension is felt not now between the loveof mortal life and the longing for immortality; it is
WILLIAM MORRIS 51rather discovered within the longing itself. We cannothelp wishing that human life and youth shouldlast for ever: yet is it really to be wished ? Long ago inJason Morris had hinted that life owes all its sweetsto that same death whence rise all its bitters. He hadstumbled unawares on the real dialectic of naturaldesire which cannot help wanting (as philosopherswould say) 'the bad infinite', though that infinite isa horror and a torment. In The Story of the GlitteringPlain the land of the ever-living is reached, but itturns out to be only a gorgeous prison. The herofinds 'the falseness of this unchanging land': amongits 'soft and merry folk' he 'longs for the house of hisfathers and the men of the spear and the plough'.So in The Well at the World's End the Innocent folk,whose name is significant, say that 'the gods havegiven us the gift of death lest we weary of life'.If we were dealing with any author but Morriswe should say that this is the conclusion of the wholematter. But in Morris there arc no conclusions. Theopposed desires change into their opposites and arclulled asleep and reawake; balance is attained andimmediately lost; everything is always beginningover again: it is a dance, not a diagram. It can nomore be seized in an epigram, summed up anddocketed, than experience itself. One feeling alonenever alters, and attains something of the stability ofa doctrine. He is always sure that we must labourfor the kindred and 'love the earth and the worldwith all our souls'. This is the central altar: thedance moves round it. Love of the world and earthmust tempt desire to sail beyond the frontier of that
52 WILLIAM MORRISearth and world. Those who sail must look backfrom shoreless seas to find that they have abandonedtheir sole happiness. Those who return must findthat happiness once more embittered by its mortality,must long again. Even if we found what we wantedit might be the ruin, not the consummation, of desire.But we cannot therefore cease to desire it. This hithcringand thithering is too irregular and shot too full ofcolours to be compared to the sad Buddhist wheel, thecircle too beautiful to be called a vicious circle; theconclusion drawn, wherever a mere luxury of pessimismthreatens, is always practical, heroic, and commonsensible.And as the world of Morris cannotbe summed up, so Morris himself escapes definition.What shall we call him? An imaginative Positivist—an animal man flawed by the longing for acoloured cloud—a potential mystic inhibited by atoo-convinced love of the material world—all theseerr by representing as fixed something which isreally always in solution. It is better to say simplythat he is a good story-teller who has presentedperhaps more faithfully than any other writer thewhole scene of life as it must appear on the naturallevel.The old indeterminate, half-Christian, half-Pantheistic,piety of the last century is gone. The modernliterary world is increasingly divided into two camps,that of the positive and militant Christians and thatof the convinced materialists. It is here that Morrismay be of incalculable value in saving us from 'dissociation'; for both camps can find in him somethingthat they need. The appeal of this Pagan poet to the
WILLIAM MORRIS 53Christian reader is obvious. No one else states quiteso clearly that dilemma in the natural virtues and thenatural desires from which all philosophical religionmust start—the question which all theologies claimto answer. And Morris is the more precious becausehe is content simply to state the question. His workis the fresh fruit of naive experience, uncontaminatedby theorizing. When William Allingham in 1882talked to him 'among other things of believing or notbelieving in a God' he replied, 'It's so unimportant'and 'went on to say that all we can get to, do whatwe will, is a form of words'. This scepticism—a truescepticism with no unacknowledged bias to the negative—leaveshis statement of Pagan experience chemicallypure. If he had started from the concept ofEternity we might suspect his exposure of the dialecticof time to be tendentious: as it is, the exposureis forced upon him by mere obedience to desire andhe remains quite unaware of the doctrines whichhe is supporting. He thus becomes one of the greatestPagan witnesses—a prophet as unconscious, andtherefore as far beyond suspicion, as Balaam's ass.As for the readers of the Left, I do not say that theywill find him directly useful in politics. His conceptionof public good is too deeply rooted in agriculture,handicrafts, and the family to be applied to anymodern Utopia. What will interest the Left willbe those very same qualities that interest the Christians.The Left agrees with Morris that it is an absoluteduty to labour for human happiness in thisworld. But the Left is deceiving itself if it thinks thatany zeal for this object can permanently silence the
54 WILLIAM MORRISreflection that every moment of this happiness mustbe lost as soon as gained, that all who enjoy it will die,that the race and the planet themselves must oneday follow the individual into a state of being whichhas no significance—a universe of inorganic homogeneousmatter moving at uniform speed in a lowtemperature. Hitherto the Left has been content,as far as I know, to pretend that this does not matter.It has perhaps been afraid of the 'formless and wailingthoughts' because these seem to lead inevitably intothe paralysing kind of pessimism—'there be somethat say, who shall shew us any good?' At the sametime, modern psychology does not encourage us tobase a single life, much less a civilization, on sogigantic a repression. It is here, surely, that Morriscan come to their assistance. In Morris they will finda political creed which is, in principle, the same astheir own, combined with an absolute refusal topaint out 'the great bar of black that runs across theshield of man.' Morris will show them how to acknowledgewhat they arc tempted to camouflage and yetnot to draw from it the conclusion they rightly fear.Nay, he will show them how this thirst for immortality,tinglingly alive in the perpetual motion of itsdialectic, will but add a more urgent motive to theirendeavours, an honourable firmness in defeat, and akeener edge to victory.For Morris has 'faced the facts'. This is the paradoxof him. He seems to retire far from the real worldand to build a world out of his wishes; but when hehas finished the result stands out as a picture ofexperience ineluctably true. No full-grown mind
WILLIAM MORRIS 55wants optimism or pessimism—philosophies of thenursery where they are not philosophies of the clinic;but to have presented in one vision the ravishingsweetness and the heart-breaking melancholy of ourexperience, to have shown how the one continuallypasses over into the other, and to have combined allthis with a stirring practical creed, this is to havepresented the datum which all our adventures, worldlyand other-worldly alike, must take into account.There are many writers greater than Morris. Youcan go on from him to all sorts of subtleties, delicacies,and sublimities which he lacks. But you can hardlygo behind him.
Ill<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'Non leve quiddam interest inter humanae mentis idola etdivinae mentis ideas, hoc est inter placita quaedam inania etveras signaturas atque inipressiones facias in creaturis, proutinveniuntur.BACON, Novum Organum, i. 23Read to a joint meeting of the Classical and EnglishAssociations
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL 5<strong>THE</strong> title of this paper is unfortunate in recallingthat of Newman's best book. It is doubly unfortunatein so far as it not only suggests, on my part, anarrogant intention of pitting myself against so greata writer, but also carries with it an omen of failure onthe practical side; for none of the things which Newmanadvised has come to pass. Yet some such title isunavoidable. I intend, it is true, to talk a good dealabout the Final Honour School of English as it actuallyexists at Oxford. But I am concerned with thatSchool not as an historical fact but as an approximationto an ideal. What we arc doing at Oxford is ofuniversal interest only as an indication of what, onmy view, we are trying to do or ought to do. We aredoubtless full of faults and do not shun criticism, providedsuch criticism is based on an understanding ofour aims. You may not agree with these aims—though I hope that you will—but do not blame a manfor making slow progress to the North when he istrying to get to the East.We are under no illusions as to our reputation inthe outer world. What our enemies think of us isvigorously enough, if not always very lucidly, conveyedby the expressions they use—by their referencesto 'the Germanic jungle', 'all this philology', 'Verner'slaw', 'Anglo-Saxon', and (most damning of all)'Gothic'. When we listen attentively to this buzz ofcondemnation, we think that we can distinguish twostrains in it. The confusion between 'Germanic' or'Anglo-Saxon' on the one hand and 'philology' or
60 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL''Verncr's law' on the other, is made, we believe, bytwo classes of people. In the first class we find theman who is still living in the Renaissance, the belatedAscham, who is quite sure that literature he cannottranslate must be bad literature—must be 'Gothic'in the classical sense of the word. He does not like thepoetry of the Dark, and Middle Ages (ignoti nullacupido) and he uses 'philology' simply as a term ofabuse. He is not really thinking of philology at all.In the second class we find a much more respectableopponent, probably a real scholar who knows that hedocs not know any medieval language. His objectionis not to the unknown literatures—in such a man itcould not be—but to comparative philology. He hasin his mind the picture of a promising academicdiscipline, in which the young might have beenguided to a systematic study of our English classics,not without some subsidiary Greek and Latin tosteady their judgement, perverted and thwarted byirrelevant excursions into Germanic philology; hesees the interest which ought to have been concentratedon Shakespeare and Johnson dissipated onmere comparisons between English and cognatelanguages; and he wonders why English should havebeen selected to carry this purely scientific and unliteraryburden which might, with equal proprietyor impropriety, have been bound on the back ofseveral other subjects.To this second, and reasonable, type of critic, ourreply is a simple one. His information is out of date.No undergraduate at Oxford is obliged to know asingle word of Gothic, old High German, or Old
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 61Norse, or to study the relations between these languagesand his own. The English student can choosebetween three alternative courses, all of which canconduct him to the highest honours. One of these isfrankly medieval, and if a student chooses it he docsso because he is interested in early English and itsimmediate relatives. The second is a half-way house—a complicated affair that need not now concern us.The third is the literary course proper, which the vastmajority of our students take.But here comes the rub. This third and literarycourse, I must confess, contains three papers whichthe enemy will be tempted to describe as 'philological'.The first is on Modern English, and dealsmainly with the history of meaning, whether insyntax or vocabulary. The second is on Anglo-Saxontexts, and the third on Middle English texts. I do notimagine that the critic I have in view will object verystrongly to the first of these. If he does, the officialvoice of our English School will reply with the verypertinent question, 'Do you wish students to understandwhat they read or not?' For the fact is thatthose who have had no experience in the teaching ofEnglish are living in a fool's paradise as regards theability of the average undergraduate to construe hismother tongue. Again and again curious statementsin the essays of our pupils can be traced back to anoriginal failure to make out the sense of Milton orJohnson or Coleridge, as a schoolboy fails to makeout the sense of Caesar or Xenophon. And with thisanswer I expect that the critics will be satisfied. Butthe other two papers—the Anglo-Saxon and Middle
62 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'English texts—I fear he will regard as vestigial, asrelics of that philological period in which, admittedly,English studies at Oxford began—ein Theildes Theils,der anfangs dies war. He will be in danger of lookingupon them as a rearguard which has not yet beendefeated but whose defeat may be hourly expected.His hopes are vain; and it is at this point that I mustjoin issue with him. If any of the three papers is reallyvestigial, it is the paper on Modern English. I havejust stated the official defence for it; but it would bedisingenuous not to confess that this paper is a subjectof dispute among ourselves. I am, in fact, one ofthose who disapprove of it. But that is not our presentconcern. I mention it only to emphasize the fact thatthis paper is incomparably the most philological ofthe three, and that the other two, so far from beingvestigial, are essential to the idea of an English schoolas I see it.Before I attempt to explain why, I must removetwo possible misconceptions. One is the belief thatAnglo-Saxon is a language other than English, oreven, as used to be said, that English is a third languageborn from the union of two earlier languages,Anglo-Saxon and French. This is an error so grossthat six weeks' study would remove it from the mindsof the most prejudiced. You might as well say thatLatin was a new language born from the union ofRoman and Greek. Anglo-Saxon is simply earlyEnglish. Norman-French is simply one of the foreignlanguages which, from time to time, have enrichedour vocabulary. Most of the changes which separatewhat we call Anglo-Saxon from what we call Middle
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 63English had begun before the Normans landed, andwould have followed much the same course if noConquest had ever occurred. Brevity compels me tobe dogmatic; but it is not really a subject that admitsof discussion.The second misconception turns on our old friend'philology'. There is no philology in the papers onAnglo-Saxon and Middle English. They are paperson texts, consisting of a core of passages for translationsurrounded by questions on archaeological, textual,cultural, or historical matters relevant to the texts.The student is asked to know about Beowulf or Pearljust those things which the classical examiner demandsthat he should know about Virgil or Sophocles.Philology is absent, unless you call grammar philology.Before some audiences I should feel it my dutyto insist rather strongly on the value of grammar. Iam told that there have been critics of Chaucer whoperpetrated serious blunders in translation, and builtup formidable aesthetic superstructures on a purelyintuitive, and sometimes erroneous, conception oftheir author's meaning. But I presume that everyone present agrees that if you are going to read a bookat all, it is desirable to be able to tell which words arein the Nominative and which are in the Accusative.We are now, at last, in a position to come to gripswith the main question. Granted that these oldbooks arc written in what is unmistakably English,and granted that we do not set philological questionson them, still, it will be asked, why should we readthem? What relevance has the study of Beowulffor the man who wants to read modern English
64 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'literature ? If we arc looking for sheer poetical merit,are there not many poems greater than Beowulf andno more difficult? Why not the Iliad, or the Aeneid? If,on the other hand, we are looking for the origins ofModern literature, shall we not find them in Romeand Greece? None of our great poets could readAnglo-Saxon: nearly all of them could and did readLatin, and some knew Greek.I will take the second question first, and before Iattempt to answer it, let me protest that I am noenemy of the classics. I have read the Aeneid throughmore often than I have read any long poem; I havejust finished re-reading the Iliad; to lose what I oweto Plato and Aristotle would be like the amputationof a limb. Hardly any lawful price would seem to metoo high for what I have gained by being made tolearn Latin and Greek. If any question of the valueof classical studies were before us, you would find meon the extreme right. I do not know where the lastditch in our educational war may be at the moment;but point it out to me on the trench-map and I willgo to it. At present, however, we are only askingwhether it is true that the origins of English literatureare to be found in the classics. And perhaps if 'theorigins' here means 'all the origins' no one, however,ignorant, would answer Yes. At most our critics canonly mean that of the innumerable debts which ourliterary tradition owes, the debt to Rome and Greeceis the greatest and most important. I do not thinkthis is true.The first step in an inquiry into its truth is torule out the greatest Greek poets and philosophers.
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 65Except on a few isolated writers such as Milton andGray, these have no influence worth talking aboutbefore the nineteenth century. Chapman's <strong>Home</strong>r,and even Pope's, might almost have been written toprove that <strong>Home</strong>r was invisible to Englishmen untilthe Romantic Revival had cleared their eyes. Indrama, Seneca is of far more importance than all theGreek tragedians put together. The real Platocounts for less in our tradition than that strangetheosophy which Ficino and others called 'Platonictheology'. Aristotle, I admit, in a slightly Thomizedform, bit deeply into the mind of the Middle Ages;but where are the literary results of this? On seventeenth-centurycriticism we can trace his influence atevery step, but it is an influence almost wholly mischievous.Having got rid of these august but irrelevantnames, it will be well to remind ourselves of theauthors who have really affected us deeply and overlong periods. Of the Romans those naturally comefirst who enjoyed the same degree and nearly thesame kind of prestige both before and after theRenaissance—the great Kings whose reign had begunbefore Beowulf was written and has not ended yet.I mean, of course Boethius, Ovid, and Virgil—and Iwould put them roughly in that order of importance.Immediately below these, in length and security ofreign, we might put Juvenal, the moral works ofCicero and Seneca, Horace, Statius, Claudian, and afew others. Apuleius and the elder Pliny would comea good deal higher than they do in our modern scholastictradition. Of the Greeks, the great gossipingF
66 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'authors, the repositories of anecdote, like Plutarchand Diogenes Laertius, would stand at the top of thelist. Second to these we should find, indistinguishablyblended, the joint influence of Theocritus andthe novelists—Longus, Heliodorus, and the like; andperhaps—but I am doubtful about my facts here—the influence of the Anthology.Having identified the influential authors it remainsto consider what their influence really was. It is clear,in the first place, that our literature is not greatlyindebted to them for its forms. We arc apt to forgetthat Milton's classical epic and classical tragedy arclonely exceptions. Most attempts to transplant anancient form into English literature have failed.Milton is the single survivor in a forlorn hope whereCowley, Blackmore, and Glover fell: Samson lives,but Gorboduc, Cato, and Caractacus do not. A list of ourbest narrative poems would contain Troilus, TheFaerie Queene, the Prelude, Don Juan, and Endymion, andwould leave out all our classical epics save one. A listof our greatest dramas would give an even morestriking result. Our lyric poetry is, no doubt, richlydecorated in certain periods with borrowings fromancient Latin and Greek, though they are not morenumerous than its borrowings from medieval Latin,from Italian, and from old and modern French. Itschief serious attempt to adopt an ancient form, however,has left behind it only one or two successes byGray amidst a ruinous waste of Tindarique Odes';and in the very nature of things formal similaritiesbetween quantitative lyric and rhymed accentuallyric must be very superficial. Already in Summer is
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 67icumen in we are basing our lyrical poetry on discoveriesin music which the Greeks never made.The novel, born from the marriage of the periodicalessay and the romance, or the sonnet, descendingfrom the Provencals, are even farther removed fromancient literature. The Satire and the Pastoral aremore instructive, for in them we can sec side by sidethe unhappy attempts to adhere to the classical formand the happy departures from it. The Romanmodel—the static, rambling diatribe—is preservedby Donne, Hall, Marston, and Churchill, and byPope in his inferior works; our great satires, desertingthis in favour of extravagant satiric fiction and owingsomething, perhaps, to Lucian and the Margites, butmuch more to Rabelais and Cervantes, have givenus Hudibras, Absalom, The Rape, The Dunciad, Gulliver,Don Juan, Erewhon, and Brave New World. In thePastoral we can trace both developments in the samewriter (and that, not only in English) as we gratefullylay aside Sannazaro's tedious Piscatory Eclogues andopen his Arcadia or turn from the fussy futility of theShepherds Calendar to the sixth book of The FaerieQueene. The little drop of Theocritus properly mixedwith northern romance and Provencal love poetryimproves the drink: offer it neat, and our stomachsturn. We can read Sidney and William Browne, butwho, unbribed, would open the pastorals of Mantuan,Barclay, or Googc?But perhaps I have argued too long on a point thatis obvious. No one can really be maintaining that thebest and most characteristic English work is deeplyindebted to the classics for its form. We are more
68 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'likely to be told that something subtler than a form—a spirit or temper or attitude—has been transferred.And, of course, I have no wish to deny that manyindividual English authors have in this way beendeeply affected by their classical reading. We cannoteven imagine Chapman without the Stoics, Burkewithout Cicero, or Tennyson without Virgil. It isequally true, however, that we cannot imagineChaucer without Guillaume de Lorris, or Spenserwithout Ariosto, or Morris without Froissart and theEdda. Of tracing such individual affinities therewould be no end. What the argument requires is toshow that the spirit of our literature, or our best literature,or most of our best literature, is closer to thatof the classics than to that of other cultures. And this,I think, has never been shown.Ovid's erotic poetry, received by our culture, becomesthe poetry of Courtly Love; his mythologicalpoetry becomes the wonder talcs of Chaucer andGower, the allegorical and astrological pantheon ofFulgentius and Lydgate, the gods of Botticelli, Titian,and Tintoretto, the emblematic deities of masque andballet and pantomime, and the capitalized abstractionsof eighteenth-century verse. The tale of Troywears casque and habergeon in the fourteenth, laceand periwig in the eighteenth, century. The Pastoral,snatched from those realistic Sicilian slopes, is carriedinto the depths of an Arcadian golden age and thereenchanted. The change which the classics undergowhen we take them into our own imagination is preciselya change of spirit or temper. Names and mythsremain, but all is romanticized, darkened here and
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 69softened there, filled with new shadows and assimilatedto our needs. There is no question of new winebeing poured into old bottles: rather, a little newwine is poured into a lot of old wine. We were not anemptiness which the classics filled, nor a patient onwhich they acted. We had our own idiosyncrasy.We also were a spirit, an ancient, complex, andintensely active spirit. We let in what we could turnto our own substance, and the process of digestionwas thorough. Quidquid recipitur, recipitur ad modumrecipientis. Of this recipiens, the real English Muse, themother of us all, I shall have more to say in a fewmoments. She is, you will notice, the person who hashitherto been left out of the story.My present duty, however, is to answer the questionI set myself: what did the influence of the classicsreally amount to? And already, I fear, it may seemto you that I have proved too much. If they gave usneither form nor spirit, then what, in heaven's name,is this debt to them which even I acknowledge? Theanswer to that is a very simple one. They gave usMatter: not a new way of writing and feeling, butnew things to write and feel about—theories, histories,facts, myths, anecdotes, people. That is whythe gossiping or encyclopaedic authors, like Plutarch,Pliny, Diogenes Laertius, Aulus Gellius, and Macrobius,are so important. This is the real impress whichclassical education has left on our literature. Youcan read English poetry for days on end withoutcoming across classic form or classic feeling; but youwill have been inundated with references to howActeon died or what birds saved the Capitol, what
70 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'Agesilaus said or Pompey did, the constitution ofSparta, the matrimonial troubles of Socrates, andsome one's witty reply to Alexander. It is this kindof influence that lies on the surface of our literatureand meets every one's gaze; and it is of this that mostpeople are really thinking when they say that ourorigins are in Greece and Rome.But a source of matter is a very different thing froma source of inspiration, a real influence on form andspirit. The difference becomes clear if we comparethe effect of the Classics upon us with the effect of aforce that reached us a few centuries before theRenaissance. I promised, a minute ago, to say somethingmore of our mother, the English Muse—therecipiens who receives everything in her own fashion.It is now time to remind you that long before thismother of ours met with Greek literature, she hadalready had a lover—a much more masterful loverwhom she has never yet been able to forget. I mean,of course, Old French. I have said that you can readEnglish poetry for a long time without coming acrossclassic form. You cannot read one verse, unless it isvers libre, without meeting Old French form. It wasOld French that overthrew our native prosody: wehave been singing an old French tune ever since. Itwas Old French that taught us those species of sentimentand refinement which we still use. Wheneveryou think of a rhyme for a limerick, or accept fictitiousprose narrative as an obvious form of seriousliterature, or offer a chair to a lady, or build a castleinstead of a villa in the air, you are being Old French.You can choose, to some extent, how classical you
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 71will be; you cannot choose how Old French you willbe. The thing is in our system, bred in the bone.This is a real influence. Compared with it the influenceof the classics is recent, superficial, almostnegligible.You will have noticed that this casts a disquietinglight on our educational problem. If we arc to seekthe true sources of our own literature, then the seriousrival to Anglo-Saxon is not the classics, but OldFrench. If we abandon Beowulf we must put in not<strong>Home</strong>r but the Romance of the Rose, and that for tworeasons. In the first place, as I have said, the oldFrench influence is incomparably greater in degree.But secondly, it is of a kind that cannot be studied atsecond hand. A real transfusion of spirit involvesintangibles: to study it is to study things that canonly be known by long and sympathetic reading oforiginals. But the matter, which is what we havemainly borrowed from Greece and Rome can bequite adequately learned from Classical Dictionaries,historical text-books, and translations. Do not misunderstandthe word 'adequately'. I do not meanthat we shall thus have an adequate knowledge ofthe classics, but that we shall have an adequatepreparation for the study of English. We shall havelearned what our authors learned and often in thesame way. A great deal of the classical ornament inEnglish poetry was learned from text-books likeNatalis Comes and Lemprière, and from translationslike North's Plutarch. Pope found that he could verycomfortably make a version of <strong>Home</strong>r without seriouslylearning Greek.
72 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'The real choice, then, is between Anglo-Saxon andOld French (or, perhaps, medieval Latin 1 ), and if Ichoose the former it is again in virtue of the principleQuidquid recipitur. Our mother surrendered more toOld French than to the classics, but she did not surrendercompletely: even in the eleventh century shehad a spirit of her own capable of transforming andassimilating what she received, modifying its gallantrieswith a homelier affection, hardening its heroisms,neglecting its ironies, broadening its humour, deepeningits pathos, shading its marvels with a more aweinspiringobscurity, and acccntualizing its syllabicverse. And so, in the end, I am driven back to ourancient alliterative poetry. There for the first timeI find a prosody based on the same speech rhythmsthat I hear in conversation to-day. I find a sense oflanguage so native to us all that the phrases which hitthe eighth-century audience hard, hit me hard too assoon as I have learned to understand them; I see atonce that words like gold and wolf and heart and bloodand winter and earth, had the same overtones for themas for me. Everything is already unmistakablyEnglish. This mere Englishness is usually calledRomanticism by those who do not know Anglo-Saxon. They are fond of tracing it to the FrenchRevolution or even to the Celtic strain in our blood.They bring far-fetched explanations why the Englishwrote melancholy poems about ruins in the eighteenthcentury, not knowing that the English had1 On further consideration I should regard the claims of medieval Latinas almost equal to those of Old French. It would not, at present, be easyto put the relevant texts in the hands of students, and they arc hard totranslate.
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 73begun to do so in the eighth. When they read ofremote wanderings upon strange seas in Morris orColeridge they think the emotion in which suchthings are steeped by these poets essentially modern,and contrast it with the unambiguous simplicity ofthe Odyssey where the wanderer desires nothing butto get home. The contrast is just; but the Englishmood is not modern. The same thing is to be foundin Anglo-Saxon poetry, associated, too, as Wordsworthmight associate it, with the call of the cuckoo.Indeed the Odyssey is everywhere instructive as acontrast to our oldest poetry; Grendcl and theCyclops, 1 at the very beginning of the two literatures,symbolize their difference—the one so dark, somysterious, so fitted to be the central symbol of evilin a great poem; the other so matter of fact, so accidental,so blasphemously tracing his descent from agod though he is the enemy of man. Virgil, as inspace, so in temper, is the middle point between<strong>Home</strong>r and Beowulf, holding out his left hand to thecolour and clarity of the Greek, his right to ourEnglish poet whom he so resembles in melancholywithout pessimism, in half-articulate piety, and,above all, in his sense of the past. I doubt if <strong>Home</strong>rwould really have appreciated horrendum silvis etreligione parentum or the whole conception of Latiumas Lurkwood (quia his latuisset in oris) as any Englishmanof any period must do.If, then, we are concerned with origins, Anglo-Saxon must keep its place in any English syllabus—1 See, on this point, J. R. R. Tolkien's indispensable Beowulf: the Monstersand the Critics.
74 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'nor is it improper, at this stage, to add that themajority of the students like it. In the old philologicaldays they did not; now they do. But, of course,continuity is not everything, and we have not yetconsidered the man who says: 'The origins of Englishliterature may be as you say. All I know is I hadrather my boy read <strong>Home</strong>r than Beowulf.' This is avery legitimate preference, and of course the mostnatural way of gratifying it is to persuade the youngman to take up classics instead of English. We are tosuppose, however, that this is for some reason impossible: what the father wants is not classics instead ofEnglish but classics somehow included in English.I would like to pass over all the practical difficultiesof such a proposal, great as they arc, because thequestion of principle involved goes right down to theroots of a man's educational theory. The EnglishSchool as it stands has chosen unity and continuity:that is to say, taking a given area of reality, it haschosen, so far as possible, to explore it thoroughly,following the natural structure of that area, andneglecting all the interesting and delightful thingsover the frontier. The alternative school which issuggested, with Greek, Latin, and perhaps Frenchclassics side by side with the greatest English writerswould be based on a different principle—the principleof selection. In the one you turn the young outinto a single, untidy country to make what they canof it; in the other you take them to what their eldersthink the five or six most interesting places in a wholecontinent. It is the difference between knowing, say,Worcestershire inside out, while remaining ignorant
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 75of the rest of the world, and knowing four or liveEuropean capitals while striking no roots in anysingle European soil. The choice is a very difficultone. On the one hand we have Arnold's ideal—'thebest that is known and thought in the world'; on theother Spartam nactus es. Embrace the latter and youmay become insular and provincial; embrace theformer and you may be a mere tourist, glib in allcountries and rooted in none. Which is the moredeeply ignorant, the shepherd who has never left theCotswolds, or the Peripatetic millionaire—the taproomof the 'Red Lion', or the lounge of the PalaceHotel?Where a final choice is so difficult I would recommenda compromise. I think that the high lightschosen by his elders and the wide area of ordinarycountry explored on his own, are both necessaryelements in a man's education. But I feel verystrongly that the place for the selected high lights isthe school, and the place for the other is the University.It is natural and necessary that we should beginby giving a boy the keys to some four or five chambersof knowledge which we think the best, but it is equallynatural to let a man choose which he will to live in.The true nature of this change is obscured if we saythat we believe in 'increasing specialization': forspecialization suggests narrowing and narrowingsuggests confinement. Now there is, of course, anobvious sense in which the specialist is narrower thanthe man reading a selection of 'great literatures'.But is there not a sense in which he is freer? Anybalanced course of English and Classics which we
76 <strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL'could draw up would bear the imprint of culturalideals peculiar to an age and a class much more unmistakablythan a school of mere English need do.'English', including Anglo-Saxon and Middle Englishalong with modern English, including what weordinarily call the 'dull' periods as well as the 'great 5ones, is an object more or less presented to us bynature: the balanced course would be our selection,a selection which, in obedience to our local andmomentary ideals, would cut across the joints, orveins, or grain of reality. The one is given, the othera construction. And it must be our construction, notthe student's. We are doing for him one of the thingshe ought to do for himself. Our wild, rough Englishcourse has already thrown up interesting discoveries:the dull and difficult periods which any one workingon the selective principle twenty years ago wouldhave omitted to make room for foreign dainties, areturning out not to be dull at all, and Anglo-Saxontechnical influences have appeared in the work of ouryounger poets. In other words, having kept our eyeon the object and not on our own preconceptions,we are learning; we know more than we did. Butthis would have been quite impossible if we hadbegun with a syncretism of the 'best 5 in two or threedifferent literatures. 'The best 5 could only havemeant what a committee of four or five dons, broughtup in a particular tradition, happened to think thebest. We should have been dictating the course offuture knowledge and taste on the authority of ourexisting taste and ignorance. A discipline so formedwould be incapable of growth. No more would come
<strong>THE</strong> IDEA OF AN 'ENGLISH SCHOOL' 77out of it than had been put into it; and real advancein our knowledge of English would be made, if at all,by real scholars working privately in country rectoriesand London lodging-houses in contemptuous independenceof us.Such is my idea of an English school, and that iswhy the classics find no place in it. Need I say thatI should like English students to know Greek andLatin? But they must not come to an English schoolto learn them. If they have not learned them beforethey come to me, I should like them to learn themafter they leave me. Any proposal which enablesthem to do so in those postgraduate years which areincreasingly spent at the university will always haveall the support I can give it; and to that end I amready to sacrifice any amount of what is called 'Research'.
IVOUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS'I do not like her name.''There was no thought of pleasing you whenshe was christened.'SHAKESPEARERead to the English Society at Oxford
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSSCHOOLMASTERS in our time are fightinghard in defence of education against vocationaltraining; universities, on the other hand, are fightingagainst education on behalf of learning.Let me explain. The purpose of education hasbeen described by Milton as that of fitting a man 'toperform justly, skilfully, and magnanimously all theoffices both private and public, of peace and war*.Provided we do not ovcrstress 'skilfully' Aristotlewould substantially agree with this, but would addthe conception that it should also be a preparationfor leisure, which according to him is the end of allhuman activity. 'We wage war in order to havepeace; we work in order to have leisure.' Neither ofthem would dispute that the purpose of education isto produce the good man and the good citizen,though it must be remembered that we arc not hereusing the word 'good' in any narrowly ethical sense.The 'good man' here means the man of good tasteand good feeling, the interesting and interested man,and almost the happy man. With such an end inview education in most civilized communities hastaken much the same path; it has taught civil behaviourby direct and indirect discipline, has awakenedthe logical faculty by mathematics or dialectic, andhas endeavoured to produce right sentiments—which are to the passions what right habits are to thebody—by steeping the pupil in the literature bothsacred and profane on which the culture of the communityis based. Vocational training, on the otherG
82 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUShand, prepares the pupil not for leisure, but for work;it aims at making not a good man but a good banker,a good electrician, a good scavenger, or a goodsurgeon. You see at once that education is essentiallyfor freemen and vocational training for slaves. Thatis how they were distributed in the old unequalsocieties; the poor man's son was apprenticed to atrade, the rich man's son went to Eton and Oxfordand then made the grand tour. When societies become,in effort if not in achievement, egalitarian, wearc presented with a difficulty. To give every oneeducation and to give no one vocational training isimpossible, for electricians and surgeons we musthave and they must be trained. Our ideal must beto find time for both education and training: ourdanger is that equality may mean training for all andeducation for none—that every one will learn commercialFrench instead of Latin, book-keeping insteadof geometry, and 'knowledge of the world welive in' instead of great literature. It is against thisdanger that schoolmasters have to fight, for if educationis beaten by training, civilization dies. That is athing very likely to happen. One of the most dangerouserrors instilled into us by nineteenth-centuryprogressive optimism is the idea that civilization isautomatically bound to increase and spread. Thelesson of history is the opposite; civilization is a rarity,attained with difficulty and easily lost. The normalstate of humanity is barbarism, just as the normalsurface of our planet is salt water. Land looms largein our imagination of the planet and civilization inour history books, only because sea and savagery are,
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 83to us, less interesting. And if you press to know whatI mean by civilization, I reply 'Humanity', by whichI do not mean kindness so much as the realization ofthe human idea. Human life means to me the life ofbeings for whom the leisured activities of thought,art, literature, conversation are the end, 1 and thepreservation and propagation of life merely themeans. That is why education seems to me so important:it actualizes that potentiality for leisure, if youlike for amateurishness, which is man's prerogative.You have noticed, I hope, that man is the onlyamateur animal; all the others are professionals.They have no leisure and do not desire it. When thecow has finished eating she chews the cud; when shehas finished chewing she sleeps; when she has finishedsleeping she eats again. She is a machine for turninggrass into calves and milk—in other words, for producingmore cows. The lion cannot stop hunting,nor the beaver building dams, nor the bee makinghoney. When God made the beasts dumb He savedthe world from infinite boredom, for if they couldspeak they would all of them, all day, talk nothingbut shop.That is my idea of education. You see at once thatit implies an immense superiority on the part of theteacher. He is trying to make the pupil a good man,in the sense I have described. The assumption is thatthe master is already human, the pupil a mere candidatefor humanity—an unregenerate little bundle of1 The natural end. It would have been out of place here to say what Ibelieve about Man's supernatural end or to explain why I think the naturalend should be pursued although, in isolation from the supernatural, itcannot be fully realized.
84 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSappetites which is to be kneaded and moulded intohuman shape by one who knows better. In educationthe master is the agent, the pupil, the patient.Now learning, considered in itself, has, on my view,no connexion at all with education. It is an activityfor men—that is for beings who have already beenhumanized by this kneading and moulding process.Among these men—these biologically simian animalswho have been made into men—there arc some whodesire to know. Or rather, all desire to know, butsome desire it more fervently than the majority andare ready to make greater sacrifices for it. The thingsthey want to know may be quite different. One maywant to know what happened a million years ago,another, what happens a million light-years away,a third, what is happening in his own table on themicroscopic level. What is common to them all is thethirst for knowledge. Now it might have happenedthat such people were left in civil societies to gratifytheir taste as best they could without assistance orinterference from their fellows. It has not happened.Such societies have usually held a belief—and it is abelief of a quite transcendental nature—that knowledgeis the natural food of the human mind: thatthose who specially pursue it are being speciallyhuman; and that their activity is good in itself besidesbeing always honourable and sometimes useful tothe whole society. Hence we come to have suchassociations as universities—institutions for the supportand encouragement of men devoted to learning.You have doubtless been told—but it can hardlybe repeated too often—that our colleges at Oxford
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 85were founded not in order to teach the young but inorder to support masters of arts. In their originalinstitution they arc homes not for teaching but forthe pursuit of knowledge; and their original natureis witnessed by the brute fact that hardly any collegein Oxford is financially dependent on the undergraduates'fees, and that most colleges are content ifthey do not lose over the undergraduate. A schoolwithout pupils would cease to be school; a collegewithout undergraduates would be as much a collegeas ever, would perhaps be more a college.It follows that the university student is essentiallya different person from the school pupil. He is not acandidate for humanity, he is, in theory, alreadyhuman. He is not a patient; nor is his tutor anoperator who is doing something to him. The studentis, or ought to be, a young man who is already beginningto follow learning for its own sake, and whoattaches himself to an older student, not precisely tobe taught, but to pick up what he can. From thevery beginning the two ought to be fellow students.And that means they ought not to be thinking abouteach other but about the subject. The schoolmastermust think about the pupil: everything he says is saidto improve the boy's character or open his mind—theschoolmaster is there to make the pupil a 'good' man.And the pupil must think about the master. Obedienceis one of the virtues he has come to him to learn;his motive for reading one book and neglectinganother must constantly be that he was told to. Butthe elder student has no such duties ex officio to theyounger. His business is to pursue knowledge. If his
86 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSpursuit happens to be helpful to the junior partner,he is welcome to be present; if not, he is welcome tostay at home. No doubt the elder, of his charity, maygo a little out of his course to help the younger; but heis then acting as a man, not as a student.Such is the ideal. In fact, of course, Oxford hasbecome in modern times very largely a place of teaching.I spend most of the term teaching and mytutorial stipend is a part of my income no less importantthan my fellowship. Most of you, perhaps, havecome here with the idea of completing your educationrather than with the idea of entering a society devotedto the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake. Whatdo these changes mean? They mean, I think, that atemporary immersion in the life of learning has beenfound to have an educational value. Learning is noteducation; but it can be used educationally by thosewho do not propose to pursue learning all their lives.There is nothing odd in the existence of such a byproduct.Games are essentially for pleasure, but theyhappen to produce health. They are not likely, however,to produce health if they are played for the sakeof it. Play to win and you will find yourself takingviolent exercise; play because it is good for you andyou will not. In the same way, though you may havecome here only to be educated, you will never receivethat precise educational gift which a university hasto give you unless you can at least pretend, so long asyou are with us, that you are concerned not witheducation but with knowledge for its own sake. Andwe, on our part, can do very little for you if we aimdirectly at your education. We assume that you are
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 87already human, already good men; that you havethe specifically human virtues and above all the greatvirtue of curiosity. We arc not going to try to improveyou; we have fulfilled our whole function if wehelp you to see some given tract of reality.I dare say some of you are wondering by now whatall this has to do with the English syllabus. I am justcoming to that. From what I have said, it followsthat on my view a freshman hesitating over the choiceof a Final School is quite on the wrong track if he isasking himself, 'Which gives me the best generaleducation?' He may be compelled to ask, 'Whichqualifies me for the best jobs when I go down?' forunfortunately we have to make our livings. Thenecessity which thus limits his choice is, as it were, anexternal necessity: poverty will prevent one manfrom becoming an astronomer as blindness mayprevent another from becoming a painter. But toask for the best 'general education' is to ask for one'sschooldays over again. The proper question for afreshman is not 'What will do me most good?' but'What do I most want to know?' For nothing that wehave to offer will do him good unless he can be persuadedto forget all about self-improvement for threeor four years, and to absorb himself in getting to knowsome part of reality, as it is in itself.The qualification 'as it is in itself is here important.At first sight it might seem that since the studentcannot study everything he should at least study a bitof everything; that the best Final Honour Schoolwould have a composite syllabus—a little philosophy,a little politics, a little economics, a little science, a
88 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSlittle literature. There arc many objections to sucha discipline, but I will mention that one only which iscentral to my argument. The composite school, asits very name implies, has been composed by someone. Those little bits of various subjects arc not foundlying together in those quantities and in that orderwhich the syllabus shows. They have been puttogether in that way artificially by a committee ofprofessors. That committee cannot have been followingthe grain and joint of reality as reality discoversitself to those actually engaged in the pursuit of learning.For the life of learning knows nothing of thisnicely balanced encyclopaedic arrangement. Everyone of the suggested subjects is infinite and, in its ownway, covers the whole field of reality. The committeewould in fact be guided by their idea of what woulddo the students good—that is, by a purely educationalidea. In reading such a school, therefore, you wouldnot be turned loose on some tract of reality as it is, tomake what you could of it; you would be gettingselections of reality selected by your elders—somethingcooked, expurgated, filtered, and generallytoned down for your edification. You would still bein the leading strings and might as well have stayedat school. Your whole reading in its scope and proportionswould bear the impress neither of reality norof your own mind but of the mind of the committee.The educational ideals of a particular age, class, andphilosophy of life would be stamped on your wholecareer.The objection will naturally be clearest to us if weconsider how the subject we know best would fare in
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 89such a school. There would be a little bit of literature.What would it consist of? Obviously, of great works,for we should have to make up in quality what welacked in quantity. Perhaps a few great 'classics' eachfrom French, German, and English. As a curriculumfor a schoolboy, nothing could be more liberal andedifying. But you see at once that it has very little todo with a knowledge of literature as it really growsand works, with all its ups and downs, in any actualcountry. It may train your mind and make youin the Aristotelian sense a better man; but arcyou not old enough now to cease being trained?Is it not time for you to venture to look on realityin the raw?If this objection to the composite school is accepted,we may summarily reject certain proposals for thereform of the English School. When people ask, 'Whynot a little philosophy?' 'Why not Italian literature?''Why not some psychology?', they are usually hankeringafter the composite school. But they may havebetter motives than that. They may want philosophyand Italian not because these are educational butbecause English writers have in fact been influencedby philosophical speculation and by Italian literature—becausethese things, in fact, are parts of thepiece of reality we have set out to study.They are quite right. So is the history of theRomance and Germanic languages from the earliesttimes, the history of all the literatures that haveaffected us, the history, political, social, and economic,of all Europe, and even the flora, fauna, and geologyof Great Britain. A perfect study of English would
90 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSinvolve all this; nay, as Hegel saw, a perfect study ofanything requires a knowledge of everything. ButThe lyf so short, the craft so long to lcrneforces us to be content with less, and you, who arewith us for only four years, to be content with lessstill. Thus I admit that some limitation is necessary;the whole literary reality cannot be embraced by anyFinal Honour School. But there is a differencebetween arbitrary selection and a curtailment whichobediently follows the joints of the real as they are,not as we choose to pretend they are. Thus if a manhas not time to learn the geography of the world, wemight teach him that of Great Britain, a land massgiven to us by nature. There are facts about Englandwhich he would be unable to understand because hedid not know Europe; we should have to put up withthat. The other, the arbitrary, alternative would beto give him selected high lights from all over theplanet—the Grand Canyon, the Rhine, a glimpse ofa South American forest, the Bay of Biscay, andthe Gobi Desert. The first would give him a realthough limited knowledge of nature—would teachhim how one country smelled, looked, lived, anddied. But the second might make him a mere globetrotter.In this spirit then, we approach our vast subject ofEnglish literature, admitting that we cannot study itwhole, but determined to neglect outlying provincesand remote connexions rather than to break up thecentral unity. The first thing to do, obviously, is tocut off some years from this end. The reasons forchoosing this end are, I suppose, obvious. In the first
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 91place, we naturally wish to help the students in studyingthose parts of the subject where we have most helpto give and they need help most. On recent and contemporaryliterature their need is least and our helpleast. They ought to understand it better than we,and if they do not then there is something radicallywrong either with them or with the literature. ButI need not labour the point. There is an intrinsicabsurdity in making current literature a subject ofacademic study, and the student who wants a tutor'sassistance in reading the works of his own contemporariesmight as well ask for a nurse's assistance inblowing his own nose. Again, things are understoodby what precedes them rather than by what followsthem. It may be disappointing to stop a story in themiddle, but you can understand it as far as you havegone; you cannot understand it if you begin in themiddle. I can indeed imagine a man denying thisand maintaining that the nineteenth century can beunderstood only in the light of the twentieth. But ifthat is so, then the twentieth can be understood onlyin the light of the twenty-first and all succeedingcenturies. We are therefore doomed to an equalmisunderstanding wherever we stop, and may justas well stop where we find it convenient.We begin then by cutting off a hundred, or twohundred, or any reasonable number of years fromthis end, and still we have too much left. If we pictureour subject as a tree we have first of all the soil inwhich it grows: that is, the history of the Englishpeople, social, economic, and intellectual. I imaginethat neither you nor I wish to draw attention to this;
92 OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUSfor if you look in the statutes you will find that examinersare at liberty to set questions on it, and it isalways possible that if we talk much about it theymay wake up and really do so. Let us keep quietabout the soil, and go on to the roots. The greatcentral tap-root is old Germanic developing, as wepass above the ground-level, into Old English. Asecond root, not quite so big and important as this,is Old French. A third, noticeably smaller, strikesfarther away into Latin. But all these are prettytough and more or less essential to the tree. Thencome the little ones—the tiny, much advertised, andattractive Greek root, the modern Spanish, modernItalian, modern French, German, &c. Our problemis to find which of these we can neglect with leastviolence to the nature of the tree.Well—the little ones must go. We have not time,in four years, for Greek, Spanish, Italian, French,and German. If one could be saved, it would have tobe modern French. Of course if we were consideringwhich is the most interesting in itself I should unhesitatinglychoose the Greek; but that would be to fallback from naturalism to arbitrary selection, fromlearning to education. Certainly Greek literature isbetter than French; but certainly English and Frenchlie together in reality as English and Greek do not.But even French we can hardly save, for we have thethree great roots to consider. The tap-root, Anglo-Saxon, can never be abandoned. The man who doesnot know it remains all his life a child among realEnglish students. There we find the speech-rhythmsthat we use every day made the basis of metre; there
OUR ENGLISH SYLLABUS 93we find the origins of that romanticism for which theignorant invent such odd explanations. This is ourown stuff and its life is in every branch of the tree tothe remotest twigs. That we cannot abandon. OldFrench and Latin we have reluctantly given up: ifyou want them, I am the last man to deny you.With these limitations, then, we hand you over ourtract of reality. Do not be deceived by talk about thenarrowness of the specialist. The opposite of thespecialist, as you now see, is the student enslaved tosome one else's selection. In the great rough countrysidewhich we throw open to you, you can choose yourown path. Here's your gun, your spade, your fishingtackle;go and get yourself a dinner. Do not tell methat you would sooner have a nice composite menu ofdishes from half the world drawn up for you. Youare too old for that. It is time you learned to wrestlewith nature for yourself. And whom will you trust todraw up the menu? How do you know that in thatvery river which I would exclude as poisonous thefish you specially want, the undiscovered fish, iswaiting? And you would never find it if you let usselect. Our selection would be an effort to bind thefuture within our present knowledge and taste:nothing more could come out than we had put in. Itwould be worse; it would be a kind of propaganda,concealed, unconscious, and omnipotent. Is it reallytrue that you would prefer that to the run of yourteeth over the whole country? Have you no incredulity,no scepticism, left?
VHIGH AND LOW BROWSQuick, quick.—Fling Peregrine Pickle under the toilet—throwRoderick Random into the closet— put The Innocent Adultery intoThe Whole Duty of Man—cram Ovid behind the bolster—there—put The Alan of Feeling into your porket—so, so—now layMrs. Chapone in sight, and leave Fordyce's Sermons open onthe table.SHERIDANRead to the English Society at Oxford
HIGH AND LOW BROWSARISTOTLE often begins his argument withwhat he calls an Isagoge, a collection of instanceswhich is not, if I understand the matter,intended (like Mill's induction) to prove a generalprinciple, but merely to open our eyes to it. Thefollowing instances are meant to form such an isagoge.1. Not many years ago a lady whose studies I wasattempting to supervise, propounded a literarytheory of general application which I found myselfunable to accept. Applying the clenchus after myfashion I inquired whether her theory would coverThe Tale of Peter Rabbit. After a silence of someminutes, she asked me if I thought there was any usein introducing such an example into a serious literarydiscussion. I replied that Peter Rabbit was a book andcertainly not so bad a book that it could be left outsidethe classification 'literature'. The lady, who isas honest as she is learned (and whom I mention herewith all respect), was not prepared to call Peter Rabbit'bad'. 'Trivial' was the word she finally fixed on.But she was quite sure that doctrines about 'literature'need not apply to it.2. I have heard of a preparatory school where thelibrary regulations divide the contents of the libraryinto two classes: Good Books and Books. The boysare allowed to take out two Good Books for everyone Book. To read a Good Book is meritorious, toread a Book only tolerable. At the same time, thoseresponsible for the regulations have hesitated toH
98 HIGH AND LOW BROWSlabel as 'bad' the books which they thus contrastwith the 'good'.3. I have heard the Head of a great college 1 praisethe novels of Anthony Hope and conclude by declaringwith enthusiasm, 'They are the best "bad" booksI've ever read'. Here, it will be seen, the word 'bad'is actually used but used in a sense which admits,inside the class Bad, distinctions of good, better, andbest.4. I have often heard—and who has not?—a plainman praise even to rapture the delightful merits ofsome favourite story and end with the humblereservation, 'Of course, I know it's not real literature'.I trust that these four instances arc already makingclear to you what it is I want to discuss. In all of themwe sec a distinction made between two kinds of book,to the one of which a certain honour is attached, andto the other a certain note of ignominy. Yet in spiteof this there is a reluctance to identify this distinctionwith the plain distinctions of good from bad or betterfrom worse. Those who uphold the distinction preferto call the inferior class popular, common, commercial,cheap, trashy, or the like, and the superior classliterary, classical, serious, or artistic. In our owntime the two odious adjectives Lowbrow and Highbrowhave been introduced as the names of the two classesand bid fair to oust all their rivals. There will also benoticed in the first, third, and fourth of my instancesa suggestion that the lowbrow works are so different1 I have learned since that I misunderstood him, but as my Isagoge ismeant for pure illustration, not proof, I have thought it no dishonesty to letthe example stand.
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 99in kind from the highbrow that they have a goodnessand badness of their own, a servile virtue and servilevice peculiar to themselves, that they are to be judgedby peculiar standards, and that what is said of literaturesimpliciter is not said of them.Now it seems to me that in this popular distinctionthere is some confusion between degrees and kinds ofmerit. If the lowbrow books are really a special kindof book I do not see how they can be inferior to thehigh. You cannot be beaten by a man unless youenter the same competition with him, nor overtakenby a man (as Chesterton observes) unless you bothrun in the same direction. At present the distinctionis certainly used to allow us the satisfaction of despisingcertain authors and readers without imposingon us the labour of showing that they are bad. It isalso used, I find, to allow people to enjoy lowbrowart without gratitude on the one hand or shame onthe other, and those who would hesitate to say, 'Let'sgo and see something bad' will cheerfully say 'Let'sgo to a lowbrow film'. The whole distinction seems tobe made in order to enable us to have it both ways.In the following paper I propose two questions.(1) Is the class of lowbrow books (or 'books' simplyas at the Preparatory School) really the class of badbooks? (2) If not, is the distinction useful in someother way?As soon as we approach the first question we noticethat even if all the lowbrow books—which I am goingto call Class A—are in fact bad, even so the distinctionbetween lowbrow and highbrow—or between class Aand class B—will not coincide with the distinction
100 HIGH AND LOW BROWSbetween bad books and good books, for the veryobvious reason that class B contains bad books too.Gorboduc and Glover's Leonidas and Dyer's Fleece,Gabriel Harvey's hexameters and Johnson's Irene,Tennyson's tragedies and Southey's epics—all theseare classical enough, serious enough, and literaryenough, in all conscience. If they entered the schoollibrary it would certainly be as Good Books, not asBooks. And it will hardly be denied that some ofthem are bad. In fact, as soon as we look at the questionfrom this point of view, it becomes apparent thatclass A is not simply the class of bad books. Mercfailure docs not infallibly give the right of entry to it.If all the books in it arc bad it must be with somespecial sort of badness—an A badness.But arc they all bad? As I have not read the novelsof Anthony Hope, I cannot, though my third instanceinvites me, select them for analysis; but perhapsRider Haggard will do as well, for his books are certainlyin the A class and, in my opinion, some of themare good—are therefore 'good "bad" books' as theHead of that college would say. And of his books Iselect She. If I ask myself why it is that I have morethan once read She with enjoyment, I find that thereis every reason why I should have done so. In thefirst place the story makes an excellent approach; thecentral theme is suffered, in the first chapters, to woous across great distances of space and time. What weare presently to see at close quarters is seen at first,as it were, through the wrong end of the telescope.This is a fine exercise in the art of alluring—you maysee the same thing at work in the opening of the
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 101Utopia, in the second act of Prometheus Unbound, andin the early books of the Odyssey. In the second placeit is a quest story, which is an attractive thing. Andthe object of the quest combines two strong appeals—it is the 'fountain of youth' theme and the princesselointaine in one. Finally, the withdrawal or conclusion,which is always the difficulty in quest stories, iseffected by unexpected means which arc nevertheless,on the author's suppositions, sufficiently plausible.In the conduct of the story the detail is mostlyconvincing. The characters who are meant to beamiable arc amiable and those who are meant to besinister are sinister. The goodness of She is grounded,as firmly as that of any book whatever, on the fundamentallaws of the imagination. But there is badnessin it as well as goodness. Two things deter us fromregarding it as a quite satisfactory romance. One ofthem is the continuous poverty of the style, by which,of course, I do not mean any failure to conform tocertain a priori rules, but rather a sloth or incompetenceof writing whereby the author is contentalways with a vague approximation to the emotion,the reflection, or the image he intends, so that acertain smudging and banality is spread over all.The other fault is the shallowness and folly of thethings put into the mouth of She herself and offeredus for wisdom. That She, in her secular loneliness,should have become a sage, is very proper, andindeed essential to Haggard's story, but Haggard hasnot himself the wisdom wherewith to supply her. Apoet of Dante's depth could have given her thingsreally wise to say; a poet of Shakespeare's address
102 HIGH AND LOW BROWSwould have made us believe in her wisdom withoutcommitting himself.If my analysis is correct, She is not a "good "bad"book' in the sense of being a good specimen of a badkind; it is simply good and bad, like many otherbooks, in the sense that it is good in some respects andbad in others. And those who have read it withenjoyment have been enjoying real literary merits,and merits which it shares with the Odyssey or TheLife and Death of Jason. Certainly, it is not a very goodbook, but since its vices are not sufficient to overwhelmits virtues (as the experience of many wiserreaders than I has proved) it is better, say, thanLeonidas or the Epic of Hades. In other words, thisbook of the A class is better than some books of theB class. It is better by every test; it shows more skillin the author and produces more pleasure in thereader; it is more in touch with the permanent natureof our imagination; it leaves those who have read itricher. And with this, the attempt to identify theclasses A and B with the classes bad and good orworse and better has surely collapsed.We must now cast about for some other possibledefinition of the two classes; and it comes at once intomy mind that the lady in my first instance ruledPeter Rabbit out as 'trivial'. Perhaps the A class consistsof trivial, and the B class of grave, or weighty, ormomentous books. I think that those who use theA-B antithesis very often have something of this sortin their mind, but it is difficult to fix the exact senseof any of the words they use to express it. It is clearthat the contrast cannot be simply between comic
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 103and serious, for then the stories in our Parish Magazinewould be labelled B and Le Misanthrope, A. Itmight be argued, no doubt, that Molière's play,though comic, is momentous as touching life at manypoints and dealing with the depths of our nature, andthis might furnish the ground for a restatement of thedistinction—B books being 'momentous' in the sensejust suggested, while A books touch us only superficially,or concern only highly specialized areas ofour consciousness. But this would make The Importanceof Being Earnest an A. Nor is it clear that all thebooks already in the A class are thus superficial.They are often accused of being 'sentimental'; andthis charge, on inspection, often conceals an admissionthat their appeal is to emotions very basic and universal—tothe same emotions that are concerned ingreat tragedies. Even Dr. Richards's Boosey Ballad, 1which is not only A but bad simply, has a theme thatPetrarch might not have disdained. Indeed, themore I look into it the more I am convinced that anycontrast of weighty and frivolous, solid and slight,deep and shallow, must cut right across the A and Bdistinction. How many of the most perfect thingsarc, after all, trifles! The weighty and frivolous arekinds of literature, and in each kind we shall findgood A's, bad A's, good B's, and bad B's. This is notwhat we are looking for.Among the lowbrows themselves I find that thedistinction is often based on style. When the plainman confesses that the books he delights in are not'real Literature' he will often, if pressed, explain this1 See his Principles of Literary Criticism, cap. 24.
104 HIGH AND LOW BROWSby saying that they 'haven't got style' or 'style andall that'. And when the plain man has been capturedand made into a pathetically willing and bewildereduniversity student he will sometimes praise the greatworks which he has dutifully read and not enjoyed,for the excellence of their style. He has missed thejokes in the comedy, remained unmoved by thetragedy, failed to respond to the suggestions ofthe lyric, and found the episodes of the romance uninteresting;utterly at a loss to explain the value traditionallyset on what has proved to him so tedious, hehands it over to the thing he knows least about, to amysterious entity called Style, which is to him merelywhat occult forces were to the old scientists—anasylum ignorantiae. He docs so because he has a radicallyfalse conception of style. He thinks of it not asthe linguistic means by which the writer produceswhatever results he desires but as a sort of extra—an uncovenantcd pedantry tacked on to the bookproper, to gratify some specifically 'literary' or 'critical'taste which has nothing to do with the ordinarypleasures of the imagination. It is for him ameaningless addition which, by a convention, givesaccess to a higher rank—like the letters Esq. after aman's name on an envelope. Now it must be confessedthat the highbrows sometimes talk of style ina way which gives their weaker brethren some excusefor such misconceptions; but I think that most ofthem, in a cool hour, would admit that 'Style', in thesense in which the lowbrow uses the word, does notexist. When we say that the descriptions of countryin She arc marred by their deficiency of style, we do
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 105not mean (as the ignorant suppose) that they aregood as descriptions but lacking in some abstractly'literary' and undescriptive grace which might havebeen superadded; we mean that they are imperfectdescriptions; and we call their imperfection 'stylistic'because it is due not to faults in the author's conceptionbut to his careless or insensitive language. Abetter choice of epithets, and those distant mountainswould have stood out sharper on the horizon; a wellchosen metaphor, and the whole picture, now dimlydiscerned through seas of wasteful words, would haveprinted itself for ever on the inner eye; a noblerrhythm, and the sense of space and movement wouldhave been given us, not left, as it now is, for us toinfer. Turn from She to almost any page in Eothen,and you will soon see what style in a descriptivepassage means. There is no class of books which canbe 'good in their own way' without bothering aboutstyle. There arc books in which what the author issaying imperfectly, partly failing to say, is sufficientlyinteresting to keep us reading in spite of his failure.Though he has done only half his work, we are contentto do some of it for him. Such books are booksdefective in style. And they do not come only in classA. Scott, Dickens, Byron, Spenser, Alanus, and Apuleiushave detestable faults of style, but they areusually put in class B. St. Paul, despite some passagesof striking beauty, seems to me to write badly, buthe is hardly an A; and I have found in the style ofDonne, Chapman, Meredith, Saintsbury, and others,obstacles to the enjoyment of what they have to giveme as great as those I find in Rider Haggard. It is
106 HIGH AND LOW BROWSnot important here that any reader should agreewith the instances I am choosing; what matters isthe recognition that badness of style (like triviality)will be found in B books. It cannot be made thebasis of a dichotomy between two kinds of book.Another common way of using the distinctiontends to fix on 'popular' as the best adjective forclass A. 'Popular' art is supposed to aim at mereentertainment, while 'real' or 'serious' art aims at somespecifically 'artistic' or 'aesthetic' or even 'spiritual'satisfaction. This is an attractive view because itwould give those who hold it a ground for maintainingthat popular literature has its own good and bad,according to its own rules, distinct from those ofLiterature proper. The popular novel aiming onlyat passing the reader's time, the popular comedycontent to raise a laugh, and be forgotten, the populartragedy which only wants to give us 'a good cry',would have their low, separate, legitimate places.And since I observe that many of my highest-browedacquaintances spend much of their time in talking ofthe vulgarity of popular art, and therefore must knowit well, and could not have acquired that knowledgeunless they enjoyed it, I must assume that they wouldwelcome a theory which justified them in drinkingfreely of that fountain without forfeiting their superiority.But there is a troublesome difficulty in this formof the distinction. We know, without going to look,that the Good Books in that preparatory school librarywould include the novels of Scott and Dickens. Butthese, in their own day, were popular entertainment,best sellers. Some of the contemporary highbrows
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 107may retort that they ought never to have beenallowed into the B class. I do not agree, but let usconcede it. Let us even concede the same aboutScott's poems, and about Byron, which were alsoonce A's and arc now B's. But what of Fielding, ofMalory, of Shakespeare and all his colleagues? Ofthe metrical romances? Of Ovid, scribbled on thewalls at Pompeii? What of Molière, finding the bestjudge of his work in the old woman who neverfailed to laugh in the same place as the audience—the audience whom he wrote to please? What, inanother art, of Mozart's operas? It is not sufficient tosay that a work designed for the popular market maysometimes, by a happy freak, outshoot its mark. Thething has happened too often to be called a freak.What survives from most ages is chiefly either thework that had some religious or national appeal, orelse the popular, commercial work produced forentertainment. I say 'chiefly' because the work ofthe 'pure' artists is not always ephemeral; a little, avery little, of it survives. But the great mass of literaturewhich now fills class B is the work of men whowrote either piously, to edify their fellows, or commercially,to earn their living by 'giving the publicwhat it wanted'.This leads to the very interesting conclusion thatthe B's of one age have most often been the A's ofanother. We are sometimes warned by the supportersof difficult new movements in literature not to imitateour fathers in stoning the prophets; those who dislikePound or Joyce are told 'so you would have dislikedWordsworth and Shelley if you had lived then'. The
108 HIGH AND LOW BROWSwarning may be useful, but clearly it should besupplemented by another—'Beware how you scornthe best sellers of to-day; they may be classics for theintelligentsia of the Twenty-Third Century.'If our age is known to posterity not as that of Eliotand Auden but as that of Buchan and Wodehouse(and stranger things have come to pass), Buchan andWodehouse will then be B's and little boys will getgood marks for reading them. Shakespeare andScott, once A's, are now B's. If we could find what itis that the mere passage of time does to a book, weshould have found out something about the realnature of the A and B distinction. And surely, it isobvious that what time docs to a book is to make itdifficult. There are indeed other operations of time.It makes a book more widely known or spreads on itthat rich patina we now enjoy in Virgil or Malory;but neither of these would furnish the basis for a Bclass since this is to include contemporary books aswell. We want a quality which some books have atonce but which mere time can confer on books thatoriginally lacked it; and difficulty seems to be thequality required. It would be amusing if difficultyturned out to be the real criterion of Literature,Good Books, or classics—if a comedy which wasmere commercial art as long as every one could seethe jokes became aesthetic and spiritual as soon asyou need commentators to explain them. Yet I thinkthis comes much nearer to the ground of the distinctionactually made than any of the hypotheses wehave yet discussed.A distinction simply between easy and difficult
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 109books is a reasonable one; and it is certainly better tobe able to enjoy both kinds than to be limited to theeasy. A man who has hitherto relished only the easyand now learns to relish the difficult as well, mayproperly be said to have improved his taste, forenlargement, other things being equal, is improvement.But there is a great difference between improvementin this sense—the mere enlargement ofa taste which may already have been perfectly goodwithin its own limits—and improvement in the senseof correction or of conversion from the bad to thegood. There is also a great difference between theeasy and the bad. No book can be bad because it iseasy or good because it is hard: a book may be badbecause it is hard. If case and difficulty is the realantithesis behind the A and B distinction, then thedistinction is being widely misused and from the truepremise 'it is better to advance to the difficult books(without leaving the easy ones) if you can 5 some drawthe false conclusions that the difficult books are betterand that you can advance to them only by leavingthe easy ones behind. We shall see presently thepsychological causes of this error.Closely connected with this form of the distinctionis that other which makes Vulgarity' the criterion ofan A book. It might be sufficient in answer to this toinquire what sense can possibly be given to the wordVulgar which will apply to the work of BeatrixPotter, John Buchan, George Birmingham, P. G.Wodehouse, 'Somcrville and Ross', and a dozen morewriters of the A class. But Vulgar is a word so difficultand, in our days, so ubiquitous that perhaps we
110 HIGH AND LOW BROWSshould examine it more closely. It seems to me tohave two principal meanings. In its first sense it isa purely privative term meaning 'not refined', 'notsubtle or delicate or many sided'. What is vulgar inthis sense (of. 'the vulgar tongue') may be perfectlygood: to lack refinement or subtlety when refinementor subtlety are not required is no blemish.Thus the lineThen come kiss me, sweet and twentyis, in its context, good and yet 'vulgar' because itexpresses a conception of love neither elevated nordiscriminating, and this is all that the song requires.The very same line would be vulgar in a bad sense ifany one were absurd enough to put it into the mouthof Launcelot addressing Guinevere after he hasbroken the bars or Zeus addressing Danae as heemerges from the shower of gold. From this point ofview we might admit that all A literature is and oughtto be irreproachably 'vulgar'. It ought to dealstrongly and simply with strong, simple emotions:the directness, the unelaborate, downright portraitureof easily recognizable realities in their familiaraspects, will not be a fault unless it pretends to besomething else. If it essays, without delicacy, thatwhich demands delicacy, it will then become faultilyvulgar; but the whole art of good A writers standsupon not doing so. But there is a second sense ofVulgar; it may be used to mean something essentiallyand, in the long run, morally, bad: the base, themean, the ignoble. These terms themselves are ambiguous,but perhaps an example will make thematter clear. The best instance I know of Vulgarity
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 111in this evil sense occurs in Chapman's Iliad. <strong>Home</strong>rhas said of the old men on the wall,Chapman translateswhen they saw the powerOf beauty, in the queen, ascend, even those cold-spiritedpeers,Those wise and almost withered men, found this heat intheir yearsThat they were forced (though whispering) to say, &c.I do not mean, of course, that the suggestion of senileeroticism which Chapman has foisted on the originalis in itself and necessarily vulgar; a man might makegood lines, whether comic or tragic, even on this subject.But to have let it creep in here of all places, tobe unaware of gulfs of difference between this andanything <strong>Home</strong>r need be supposed to have meant,argues an ungentle heart and a bestial ignorance ofthe whole hierarchy of human feelings. It is somethingmore than lack of delicacy where delicacy isrequired (though of course it is that too); it is a fatal,unconscious welcome held out to the lower when thelower has offered to usurp the place of the higher, 'adownward appetite to mix with mud'. And we cannothere avoid such words as Lower and Higher, forVulgar, in its deeper sense, is really a term of moralreproof. It has nothing to do with the distinction ofpopular and classic. It is low hearts and not lowbrows that are vulgar. 11Another example, more venial, but perhaps even clearer, of such vulgarity,occurs when Dryden renders Quart agite, o tectis, iuvenes, succedite nostris
112 HIGH AND LOW BROWSWe have now made a fairly determined effort tofind some useful meaning for the separation of literatureinto the two classes of classical and popular,Good Books and Books, literary and commercial,highbrow and lowbrow, and we have failed. In fact,the distinction rests upon a confusion between degreesof merit and differences of kind. Our map of literaturehas been made to look like an examination list—a single column of names with a horizontal linedrawn across it, the honour candidates above thatline, and the pass candidates below it. But we oughtrather to have a whole scries of vertical lines representingdifferent kinds of work, and an almost infinitescries of horizontal lines crossing these to representthe different degrees of goodness in each kind. Thus'Simple Adventure Story' is a vertical line with theOdyssey at the top and Edgar Wallace at the bottom;Rider Haggard, R. L. Stevenson, Scott, WilliamMorris will be placed on horizontal lines crossing'Adventure Story' at such heights as we may decide.'Psychological Story' is a separate column, with itsown top (Tolstoy or another) and its own bottom.With such a picture in our minds we should avoidthe confusion of those who say to a boy, 'You shouldnot read trash like King Solomon's Mines. Try Meredith.'Such an exhortation urges him in two quitedifferent directions. You are asking him at once tomove horizontally, from one kind to another, andvertically, from the less good to the better. But youarc also doing something worse; you are instilling(Aen. i. 627), 'Enter, my noble guest, and you shall find, If not a costlywelcome, yet a kind.' The descent here is to the 'genteel'. Of. GavinDouglas's excellent version of the same line.
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 113into his mind a notion (often henceforward indelible)that the pleasure he already has in not very goodbooks is of a quite different nature from anythinghe is to expect in 'real literature'—that the latter issomething to be read 'in school', an affair of marksand School Certificates and conceit and self-improvement.I believe that this misconception is likely to growand to be one day no longer confined to schoolboys.There are many circumstances which encourage it.Until quite modern times the reading of imaginativeliterature in a man's own tongue was not regarded asmeritorious. The great authors of the past wrote toentertain the leisure of their adult contemporaries,and a man who cared for literature needed no spurand expected no good conduct marks for sitting downto the food provided for him. Boys at school weretaught to read Latin and Greek poetry by the birch,and discovered the English poets as accidentally andnaturally as they now discover the local cinema.Most of my own generation, and many, I hope, ofyours, tumbled into literature in that fashion. Ofeach of us some great poet made a rape when we stillwore Eton collars. Shall we be thought immodest ifwe claim that most of the books we loved from thefirst were good books and our earliest loves arc stillunrepented? If so, that very fact bears witness to thenovelty of the modern situation; to us, the claim thatwe have always liked Keats is no prouder than theclaim that we have always liked bacon and eggs.For there are changes afoot. The growth of EnglishSchools at Universities, the School Certificate, andI
114 HIGH AND LOW BROWSthe Educational Ladder—all excellent things—mayyet produce unexpected results. I foresee the growthof a new race of readers and critics to whom, fromthe very outset, good literature will be an accomplishmentrather than a delight, and who will always feel,beneath the acquired taste, the backward tug ofsomething else which they feel merit in resisting.Such people will not be content to say that somebooks arc bad or not very good; they will make aspecial class of 'lowbrow' art which is to be vilified,mocked, quarantined, and sometimes (when theyarc sick or tired) enjoyed. They will be sure thatwhat is popular must always be bad, thus assumingthat human taste is naturally wrong, that it needs notonly improvement and development but veritableconversion. For them a good critic will be, as thetheologians say, essentially a 'twice-born' critic, onewho is regenerate and washed from his OriginalTaste. They will have no conception, because theyhave had no experience, of spontaneous delight inexcellence. Their 'good' taste will have been acquiredby the sweat of their brows, its acquisitionwill often (and legitimately) have coincided withadvancement in the social and economic scale, andthey will hold it with uneasy intensity. As they willbe contemptuous of popular books, so they will benaively tolerant of dullness and difficulty in anyquack or sloven who comes before them with loftypretensions; all literature having been as hard tothem as that, as much an acquired taste, they will notsee the difference. They will be angry with a truelover of literature who does not take pains to unravel
HIGH AND LOW BROWS 115the latest poetical puzzle, and call him a dilettante.Having obtained the freedom of Parnassus at a greatprice, they will be unable to endure the nonchalanceof those who were free-born.The cure for this is not to remove the EducationalLadder, the English Schools, nor the Certificateexaminations. If the danger is recognized it can becombated by teaching and by criticism at everypoint. Those in the predicament I have describedcan combat it in themselves if they will. A very littleattention will soon discover in any 'lowbrow' bookwhat is really good and really bad, and will show usthe very same kinds of goodness and badness in booksthat are not lowbrow. A little patience, a little humility,and all will be well. It is the vanity of newacquisitions and the lazy desire for over-simplificationwhich threatens to impound a hundred books, someirredeemably bad, some excellently good, in a classwhich can be dismissed from criticism. A man oughtnot to be ashamed of reading a good book because itis simple and popular, and he ought not to condonethe faults of a bad book because it is simple andpopular. He should be able to say (altering the namesto suit his own judgement), 'I read Buchan and Eliotfor the same reason, because I think them good; Ileave Edgar Wallace and Ezra Pound unread for thesame reason, because I think them bad.' It is by nomeans for the protection of bad books that I wish thedistinction of high- and lowbrow abolished. Thatdistinction itself protects bad books. As it robs excellentA books of deserved praise, it teaches its victimsto tolerate bad A books. Why was Dr. Richards
n6HIGH AND LOW BROWSreading a bad book when he had influenza? 1 Was itnot that in his illness he needed an easy book, andhaving lumped all easy books together as contemptible,he made no further distinctions? That is theusual result of having a pariah class. Slavery, whiledepressing the slave of noble character, allows thevile slave liberties never conceded to the free servant.Those who most despise the class from which prostitutesarc recruited are not necessarily those whoabstain from fornication. And indeed, I am oftenshocked at what slips out sometimes about the recreationalreading, the off-duty intellectual amusements,of those who arc sternest in their contempt for popularart and demand least pleasure of the art they approve.21 See Practical Criticism (1929), p. 257. I am sorry to have to mention inthis context an admission whose candour deserves so much imitation and acritic whose works are almost the necessary starting-point for all futureliterary theory. But the point is very important, and magis arnica Veritas.2 A full treatment of the subject broached in this essay would demandconsideration of the historical theory that there is some peculiarity in ourown age really producing an unprecedented cleavage between the Few andthe Many, and imposing on popular taste the need of veritable conversion.My own view is that such a situation exists, but that the Highbrow-Lowbrowdistinction is one of the things that have helped to produce it. If the peoplehave never shown less taste for good books, it is also true that those capableof writing good books have seldom taken less pains to please the people, or,indeed, so freely insulted them. There arc members of the intelligentsia atpresent (some of them socialists) who cannot speak of their cultural inferiorsexcept in accents of passionate hatred and contempt. Certainly it is fatal toapproach this or any other quarrel with the assumption that all the faultsare on one side: and just as certainly, in all quarrels the task of conciliationbelongs jure dicino to the more reasonable of the two disputants.
VI<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE'Tis ignorance that makes a barren wasteOf all beyond itself KEATSReprinted from 'Lysistrata'
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METREIN the general reaction which has set in against thelong reign of foreign, syllabic metres in English, itis a little remarkable that few have yet suggested areturn to our own ancient system, the alliterative line.Mr. Auden, however, has revived some of its stylisticfeatures; Professor Tolkien will soon, I hope, beready to publish an alliterative poem; and the momentseems propitious for expounding the principlesof this metre to a larger public than those Anglo-Saxonand Old Norse specialists who know it already.1. Alliteration is no more the whole secret of thisverse than rhyme is the whole secret of syllabic verse.It has, in addition, a metrical structure, which couldstand alone, and which would then be to this systemas blank verse is to the syllabic.2. Latin verse is based on quantity (= the lengthof time taken to pronounce a syllable). ModernEnglish is based on stress-accent (= the loudnesswith which a syllabic is pronounced). Alliterativeverse involves both.3. In order to write Alliterative verse it is thereforenecessary to learn to distinguish not only accentedfrom unaccented syllables, but also long from shortsyllables. This is rendered difficult by our classicaleducation which allows boys to pronounce ille sothat it rhymes with silly, and nevertheless to call thefirst syllabic long, which, in their pronunciation, it isnot. In dealing with English quantity the reader mustlearn to attend entirely to sounds, and to ignore spelling.
120 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METREDEFINITION. A long syllable is one which containseither a long vowel (as fath(er),fame, seek, pile, home,do); or, a vowel followed by more than one consonant(as punt, wind, helm,pelt). 1[Caution, 1. It is here that the trouble from spellingoccurs. In modern English spelling, for reasonswhich need not be discussed here, such words assilly, pretty, merry, sorrow, attraction, show a doubleconsonant in spelling where there is no shadowof a double consonant in pronunciation. Thereader can convince himself of this by comparingthe pretended double T in pretty with the realdouble T in hot toast: and he will then hear howa real double consonant renders the first syllable ofhot toast long, while that of pretty, though accented,is short. So, in distiller the pretended two L's areone, while in still life we have a real double L, disguisedas a triple L. True double consonants canbe heard in palely (of. Paley), fish-shop (of. bishop),unnamed (of. unaimed), midday (of. middy), solely(of. holy). 22. In modern English many words, chiefly monosyllables,which end in a single consonant are pronounceddifferently according to their position in thesentence. If they come at the end of a sentence orother speech-group—that is, if there is a pause afterthem—the final consonant is so dwelled upon that1 That two or more consonants make the syllable long is not a metricalrule but a phonetic fact; that they make the preceding vowel long, as somesay, is neither a rule nor a fact, but false.2 -NG in English usually represents a single consonant (G nasalized), butsometimes it represents this consonant followed by a pure G in addition.Hence the first syllable is short in singer, ringer: long in linger, finger.
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 121the syllable becomes long. If the reader listens carefullyhe will find that the syllable man is short in'Manifold and great mercies'or 'The man of property',but long in'The Invisible Man'or 'The Descent of Man'.With this caution, the reader will be glad to hear, theserious difficulties in the re-education of our ear areover.]4. Each line consists of two half-lines, which areindependent metrical organisms, connected only bythe alliteration.5. The half-line consists of Lifts and Dips.Definitions.A Lift = either (a) one syllabic both long andaccented (as the first syllable of ogre, mountain,Repton),or (b) Two syllables whereof the first is short butaccented, and the second unaccented (as thefirst two syllables of merrily, vigorous, melancholy,evident).(Thus in vary the first syllable is a Lift: in very thewhole word is a Lift.)A Dip = any reasonable number of unaccented syllableswhether long or short.In the following sentences the syllables printed inCapitals are Lifts, the rest Dips.Of COURSE we aSSUME.When a phiLOLOGist is a FOOL.RhadaMANTHus in his MISERy.
122 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE6. Every half-line must contain neither more norless than two Lifts. (The ancient poetry sometimesintroduces a three-lift type which stands to this metremuch as the Alexandrine stands to decasyllabics: butthe beginner will be wise to neglect it.)The five different types of half-line depend on thefive ways in which Lifts and Dips are combined.Before learning these, however, the reader should'work his car in' with the following:We were TALKing of DRAGONS, | TOLkicn and IIn a BERKshire BAR. | The BIG woRKitianWho had SAT siLcnt | and SUCKED his PIPEALL the EVEning, | from his EMPTY MUGWith GLEAMing EYE | GLANCED tOWARDS US;'I SEEN 'em mysELF', | he SAID FIERCEly.7. The 'A' type of half-line is arranged Lift-dip,Lift-dip.e.g. GREEN and GROwing: MERRY were the MiNSTrels:COME from the couNTry.Licence. One or two unaccented syllables may beadded before the first Lift, forming what is technicallyknown as an Anacrusis.e.g. And green and growing: and so merry were theminstrels: he came from the country.Warning. But this licence should be very seldom usedin the second half-line. In the first half-line (i.e. atthe beginning of the whole line) it may be usedfreely.8. B type = dip-Lift, dip-Lift.e.g. and NUMBED with NIGHT: where MAIDS are MERRY:and to the PALACE of PRIDE.
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 123Warning. The first dip may contain 'any reasonablenumber 5 of unaccented syllables: but the secondshould normally consist of a single unaccentedsyllabic. In all circumstances a predominantly'anapaestic' movement is to be avoided.9. G = dip-Lift, Lift-dip.(Note.—Here we reach a rhythm of daily occurrencein our speech (e.g. 'I can't stand him') whichhas been allowed no metrical recognition for centuries.)e.g. The MERRY MASTer: In the DARK DUNGeon:Through CLOUDS CLEAving: It is EVER-oPen: Andwith GOD'S BENIson.Licence. In this type a single short, accented syllablemay serve as the second Lift, giving us:A cold kipper: but they're hard-headed: a proud palace.10. D = Lift, Lift-dip.Here there is only one dip, whereas A, B, and Chave two. To compensate for this, in D types thedip must be strengthened by a syllable 1 nearly (butnot quite) as strong as the Lifts.(Note.—This again rescues a genuine Englishspeech rhythm from metrical non-existence.)e.g. HARD HAYmaking.1It will be heard that the syllable mak is as long as,but just less accented than, hard and hay.e.g. BRIGHT QUICKsilver: MAD MERRYmaking: SHODDYsmpbuilders: GRIM GLADiator: HELL'S HOUSEkeeper.Or, of course, two syllables whereof the first is short. The rules for'compensating elements' are, in this respect, identical with the rules forLifts.
124 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METREIn all these examples the strengthening elementof the dip stands first in the dip: e.g. in 'Hell'shousekeeper', keep- comes before -er. Obviously thereverse order may be used, giving us:ALL UNDcrclothes: MAD MULTitude: EATS ARTichokes:POOR DESTitute.Licence I. In D, as in C, a single short, accentedsyllable may serve as the second Lift, giving us,instead of Hard haymaking, such forms as:SHEER SHOTover: PURE PALimpsest.Licence 2. The compensating element in the dipmay also be a single short, accented syllable,giving us:MAD MELANCHoly: HEAV'N'S WAR-office: BORN BOOTlegger.Licence 3. The sub-type Mad multitude may be extendedby inserting a single unaccented (and preferablyshort) syllabic between the two Lifts, so asto give:MAD the MULTitude: EATing ARTichokes.11. E = Lift-dip-Lift.Here again we have only one dip, and again thedip must contain a compensating element. E, infact, is a rearrangement of D.e.g. HAYmakers HEARD: SHIPbuilders SHOW: GLADIatorGRIM.Licence. The compensating element in the dip may bea single short, accented syllable, giving us:NEW-College KNOWS.
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 12512. For the reader's convenience, I add a recapitulationof the five types.A. 1. Green and growing.2. (With Anacrusis) The grass is growing.B. And life runs low.G. I. A dark dungeon.2. (With single short for 2nd Lift) The gray gravel.D. I. Hell's housekeeper.2. (With compensating element last in dip) Earth'santidote.3. (With single short for 2nd Lift) East Abingdon.4. (With single short for compensating element indip) Heav'n's war-office.5. (Extended) Evil antidote.E. 1. Shipbuilders show.2. (With single short for compensating element indip) New-College knows.13. In every line both the Lifts of the first half-linemay, and one must, alliterate with the first Lift of thesecond half-line. AsIn a Berkshire Bar; the Big workman(both Lifts in the first half alliterating with the firstof the second) or,We were Talking of dragons, Tolkien and I(one Lift of the first half alliterating with the first ofthe second).An alliteration on all four Lifts as inAnd walks by the waves, as winds warbleis regarded not as an added beauty, but as a deformity.(Its use in Middle English, it will be found,radically alters the character of the metre.)
126 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE14. Where only one Lift in the first half-line alliterates,it should normally be the first.15. All vowels alliterate with one another.Warning. Do not be deceived by spelling. Unionalliterates with yeast, yellow, &c, not with uncle.16. No half-line of any type should end in a puredactyl. Noble Norbury, with trash and trumpery, glancinggloomily, &c, are unmetrical.17. Structure.(1) The medial pause which divides the first fromthe second half of the line must be strictly observed,so that the two halves fall apart as separate speechgroups.[By speech-groups I mean those units—rhythmical,rhetorical, emotional, and to some extent syntactical,units—out of which our actual conversation is builtup. Thus if the reader says 'The big workman whohad sat silent and sucked his pipe all the evening', hewill (I hope) find that the speech-groups coincidewith the half-lines in the example given under para. 6.A good deal of re-education is here necessary, for thechief beauty of syllabic verse lies in a deliberate clashor contradiction between the speech-groups and the'feet', whereas in alliterative verse the speech-groupis both the metrical, and the aesthetic, unit. Seebelow, para. 18.]Examples. Thus, he will staand as a stone till the stars crumble,is metrically good. The laugh of the lovely lady is silent isbad. But Lost is the laugh of the lovely damsel is not a lineat all: for it pretends metrically to be.LOST is the LAUGH of | the LOVEly DAMsel
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 127(A-type+A with anacrusis): and in this the firsthalf is so impossible as a speech-group that a poetcould have written it only because he was really stillthinking in feet and syllables, and not in speechgroupsand half-lines.(2) But while we cannot run across the medialbreak, we can run across the end of a line. In otherwords, the last half of a given line and the first half ofthe next are more intimately connected than the twohalves of a single line. Hence we may writeThere stands a stone. Still'd is the Lady'sPeerless laughter.Corollary. Hence, though the poem begins and endswith a full line, yet within the poem a new paragraphor sentence should usually begin in the second half ofa line.18. Aesthetics.It follows that whereas syllabic poetry primarily usesthe evocative qualities of words (and only secondarilythose of phrases), alliterative poetry reverses the procedure.The phrase, coinciding with the half-line, isthe poetic unit. In any English country tap-room thestudent may hear from the lips of labourers speechgroupswhich have a certain race and resonance inisolation. These are the elements of our native metre.Such are the rules. Where no tradition—at leastno modern tradition—exists it is rash to offer advice,but perhaps two counsels may be given. In the firstplace, if any one is attracted by the metre in general,but disposed to omit the rules of quantity and producea merely accentual adaptation, I would like to savehim disappointment by warning him that he will
128 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METREalmost certainly produce rubbish. Torture the language,or the thought, as he will, the result will bethin. The thing to aim at is richness and fullness ofsound, and this cannot be attained without quantity:with quantity, the metre opens possibilities of resonancewhich have not been exploited for a thousandyears. In the second place, I would advise him to beon his guard against too many B types. His iambictraining will probably be tempting him to them atevery turn: but if he yields his poem will sound likeoctosyllabics. And lastly, I would advocate to all whohave a taste for such things some serious contentionwith the difficulties of this metre. A few successfulspecimens would be an excellent answer to the typeof critic (by no means extinct) who accuses themoderns of choosing vers libre because they are notmen enough for metre. For if syllabic verse is likecarving in wood and vers libre like working with abrush, this is like carving in granite.A man who preaches a metre must sooner or laterrisk his case by showing a specimen: and if the fate ofGabriel Harvey deters me, that of Campion invites.In order to avoid misunderstanding I must say thatthe subject of the following poem was not chosenunder the influence of any antiquarian fancy thata medieval metre demanded medieval matter, butbecause the characters of the planets, as conceived bymedieval astrology, seem to me to have a permanentvalue as spiritual symbols—to provide a Phänomenologiedes Geistes which is specially worth while in our owngeneration. Of Saturn we know more than enough.But who does not need to be reminded of Jove?
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 129<strong>THE</strong> PLANETSLady LUNA, in light canoe,A : BBy friths and shallows of fretted cloudland B : cCruises monthly; with chrism of dewsA : BAnd drench of dream, a drizzling glamour, B : BEnchants us—the cheat! changing sometime B : AA mind to madness, melancholy pale, A 2 : E 2Bleached with gazing on her blank count'nance A : cOrb'd and ageless. In earth's bosom A : c 2The shower of her rays, sharp-feathered light B : E 2Reaching downward, ripens silver,A : AForming and fashioning female brightness, A : A—Metal maidenlike. Her moist circleD 2 : cIs nearest earth. Next beyond herB : AMERCURY marches;—madcap rover,A : APatron of pilf'rers. Pert quicksilverA : DHis gaze begets, goblin mineral,B : AMerry multitude of meeting selves,D 2 : BSame but sundered. From the soul's darkness, A : cWith wreathèd wand, 1 words he marshals, B : AGuides and gathers them—gay bellwether A : D4Of flocking fancies. His flint has struckc : BThe spark of speech from spirit's tinder,B : cLord of language! He leads foreverA : BThe spangle and splendour, sport that mingles A 2 : ASound with senses, in subtle pattern, A : c 2Words in wedlock, and wedding alsoA : cOf thing with thought. In the third region B : cVENUS voyages . . . but my voice falters;A : cRude rime-making wrongs her beauty,D : AWhose breasts and brow, and her breath's sweetnessB : cBewitch the worlds. Wide-spread the reign B : EOf her secret sceptre, in the sea's caverns, A 2 : c 21 Alliteration on second lift of the first half. The orthographic w inwreathed has, of course, no metrical function.K
130 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METREIn grass growing, and grain bursting,c : cFlower unfolding, and flesh longing,A : cAnd shower falling sharp in April.c : AThe metal of copper in the mine reddens B : c 2With muffled brightness, like muted gold, c : BBy her finger form'd. Far beyond herB : AThe heaven's highway hums and trembles, c : ADrums and dindlcs, 1 to the driv'n thunder A : cOf SOL'S chariot, whose sword of lightc : BHurts and humbles; beheld onlyA : cOf eagle's eye. When his arrow glancesB : cThrough mortal mind, mists arc parted B : AAnd mild as morning the mellow wisdom A 2 : cBreathes o'er the breast, broadening eastward E : AClear and cloudless. In a clos'd gardenA : c(Unbound her burden) his beams foster A 2 : cSoul in secret, where the soil puts forthA : BParadisal palm, and pure fountainsE : cTurn and rc-temper, touching coollyA : AThe uncomely common to cordial gold;B : BWhose ore also, in earth's matrix,c : cIs print and pressure of his proud signetB : cOn the wax of the world. He is the worshipp'dmale,B : BThe earth's husband, all-beholding,c : AArch-chcmic eye. But other countryE 2 : cDark with discord dins beyond him,A : AWith noise of nakers, neighing of horses,B : AHammering of harness. A haughty godA : BMARS mercenary, 2 makes there his campD 2 : EAnd flies his flag; flaunts laughinglyB : DThe graceless beauty, grey-eyed and keen, A 2 : E—Blond insolence—of his blithe visage D 2 : c 2Which is hard and happy. He hews the act, B : B1 Of. Malory, v, cap. 8.2 -ARY being the compensating element in the Dip.
<strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRE 131The indifferent deed with dint of his mallet B : BAnd his chisel of choice; achievement comes not B:A2Unhelpcd by him;—hired gladiatorB : DOf evil and good. All's one to Mars,B : EThe wrong righted, rescued meekness,c : AOr trouble in trenches, with trees splintered A : cAnd birds banished, banks fill'd with gold c 2 : EAnd the liar made lord. Like handiwork B : D 2He offers to all—earns his wagesB : AAnd whistles the while. White-featured dread B : EMars has mastered. His metal's ironA : cThat was hammered through hands into holycross,B : BCruel carpentry. He is cold and strong, D5:BNecessity's son. 1 Soft breathes the air B : EMild, and meadowy, as we mount further A : cWhere rippled radiance rolls about usc : AMoved with music—measureless the waves' A : EJoy and jubilee. It is JOVE'S orbit,D 5 : cFilled and festal, faster turningA : AWith arc ampler. From the Isles of Tinc : BTyrian traders, in trouble steeringA : cCame with his cargoes; the Cornish treasure A : BThat his ray ripens. Of wrath endedc : cAnd woes mended, of winter passedc : BAnd guilt forgiven, and good fortuneB : cJove is master; and of jocund revel, A : c 2Laughter of ladies. The lion-hearted,A:A2The myriad-minded, men like the gods, A 2 : EHelps and heroes, helms of nationsA : AJust and gentle, are Jove's children,A : cWork his wonders. On his wide forehead 2 A : c 21 The c in necessity, being an s in pronunciation, carries the first alliteration.2 This is c 2 in my pronunciation because I pronounce forehead so as torhyme with horrid. In the alternative pronunciation (which is now heardeven among educated speakers) it would be c I.
132 <strong>THE</strong> ALLITERATIVE METRECalm and kingly, no care darkensA : cNor wrath wrinkles: but righteous power c : BAnd leisure and largess their loose splendours A 2 : cHave wrapped around him—a rich mantle A 2 : cOf ease and empire. Up far beyondA 2 : EGoes SATURN silent in the seventh region,c : cThe skirts of the sky. Scant grows the light, B : ESickly, uncertain (the Sun's finger A : cDaunted with darkness). Distance hurts us, A : AAnd the vault severe of vast silence;B : cWhere fancy fails us, and fair language, A 2 : cAnd love leaves us, and light fails usc : cAnd Mars fails us, and the mirth of Jove c : BIs as tin tinkling. In tattered garment,c : cWeak with winters, he walks foreverA : BA weary way, wide round the heav'n, B : EStoop'd and stumbling, with staff groping, A : cThe lord of lead. He is the last planet B : c 2Old and ugly. His eye fathersA : cPale pestilence, pain of envy,D 2 : ARemorse and murder. Melancholy drink A : E 2(For bane or blessing) of bitter wisdomB : cHe pours for his people, a perilous draught A 2 : BThat the lip loves not. We leave all things c : cTo reach the rim of the round welkin,B : cHeaven's hermitage, high and lonely.D 2 : A
VIIBLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES: ASEMANTIC NIGHTMAREWe arc often compelled to set up standards we cannot reachourselves and to lay down rules we could not ourselvessatisfy.LORD COLERIDGE, c.J. (Law Reports, Queen's Bench DivisionXIV, p. 288 in Reg. v. Dudley and Stephens).Read at Manchester University
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESPHILOLOGISTS often tell us that our languageis full of dead metaphors. In this sentence, theword 'dead' and the word 'metaphors' may turn outto be ambiguous; but the fact, or group of facts, referredto, is one about which there is no great disagreement.We all know in a rough and ready way,and all admit, these things which arc being called'dead metaphors', and for the moment I do not proposeto debate the propriety of the name. But whiletheir existence is not disputed, their nature, and theirrelation to thought, gives rise to a great deal of controversy.For the benefit of any who happen to haveavoided this controversy hitherto, I had better makeplain what it is, by a concrete example. Bréal in hisSemantics often spoke in metaphorical, that is consciously,rhetorically, metaphorical language, oflanguage itself. Messrs. Ogden and Richards in TheMeaning of Meaning took Bréal to task on the groundthat 'it is impossible thus to handle a scientific subjectin metaphorical terms'. Barfield in his Poetic Dictionretorted that Ogden and Richards were, as a matterof fact, just as metaphorical as Bréal. They had forgotten,he complained, that all language has a figurativeorigin and that the 'scientific' terms on whichthey piqued themselves—words like organism, stimulus,reference—were not miraculously exempt. On thecontrary, he maintained, 'these authors who professedto eschew figurative expressions were reallyconfining themselves to one very old kind of figure;they were rigid under the spell of those verbal ghosts
136 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESof the physical sciences which to-day make up practicallythe whole meaning-system of so many Europeanminds'. 1 Whether Ogden and Richards will see fit,or have seen fit, to reply to this, I do not know; butthe lines on which any reply would run are alreadytraditional. In fact the whole debate may be representedby a very simple dialogue.A. You arc being metaphorical.B. You are just as metaphorical as I am, but youdon't know it.A. No, I'm not. Of course I know all about attendingonce having meant stretching, and the rest of it.But that is not what it means now. It may have beena metaphor to Adam—but I am not using it metaphorically.What I mean is a pure concept with nometaphor about it at all. The fact that it was a metaphoris no more relevant than the fact that my pen ismade of wood. You are simply confusing derivationwith meaning.There is clearly a great deal to be said for bothsides. On the one hand it seems odd to suppose thatwhat we mean is conditioned by a dead metaphor ofwhich we may be quite ignorant. On the other hand,we see from day to day, that when a man uses acurrent and admitted metaphor without knowing it,he usually gets led into nonsense; and when, we aretempted to ask, does a metaphor become so old thatwe can ignore it with impunity? It seems harsh torule that a man must know the whole semantic historyof every word he uses—a history usually undiscoverable—orelse talk without thinking. And yet, on the1 A. O. Barfield, Poetic Diction, 1928, pp. 139, 140.
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 137other hand, an obstinate suspicion creeps in that wecannot entirely jump off our own shadows, and thatwe deceive ourselves if we suppose that a new andpurely conceptual notion of attention has replaced andsuperseded the old metaphor of stretching. Here,then, is the problem which I want to consider. Howfar, if at all, is thinking limited by these dead metaphors?Is Anatole France in any sense right whenhe reduces 'The soul possesses God' to 'the breathsits on the bright sky?' Or is the other party rightwhen it urges 'Derivations arc one thing. Meaningsarc another'? Or is the truth somewhere betweenthem?The first and easiest case to study is that in which weourselves invent a new metaphor. This may happenin one of two ways. It may be that when we arc tryingto express clearly to ourselves or to others a conceptionwhich we have never perfectly understood, anew metaphor simply starts forth, under the pressureof composition or argument. When this happens, theresult is often as surprising and illuminating to us asto our audience; and I am inclined to think that thisis what happens with the great, new metaphors of thepoets. And when it does happen, it is plain that ournew understanding is bound up with the new metaphor.In fact, the situation is for our purpose indistinguishablefrom that which arises when we hear anew metaphor from others; and for that reason, itneed not be separately discussed. One of the ways,then, in which we invent a new metaphor, is byfinding it, as unexpectedly as we might find it in thepages of a book; and whatever is true of the new
138 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESmetaphors that we find in books will also be true ofthose which we reach by a kind of lucky chance, orinspiration. But, of course, there is another way inwhich we invent new metaphors. When we are tryingto explain, to some one younger or less instructedthan ourselves, a matter which is already perfectlyclear in our own minds, we may deliberately, and evenpainfully, pitch about for the metaphor that is likelyto help him. Now when this happens, it is quite plainthat our thought, our power of meaning, is not muchhelped or hindered by the metaphor that we use. Onthe contrary, we are often acutely aware of the discrepancybetween our meaning and our image. Weknow that our metaphor is in some respects misleading;and probably, if we have acquired the tutorialshuffle, we warn our audience that it is 'not to bepressed'. It is apparently possible, in this case atleast, to use metaphor and yet to keep our thinkingindependent of it. But we must observe that it ispossible, only because we have other methods ofexpressing the same idea. We have already our ownway of expressing the thing: we could say it, or wesuppose that we could say it, literally instead. Thisclear conception we owe to other sources—to ourprevious studies. We can adopt the new metaphoras a temporary tool which we dominate and by whichwe are not dominated ourselves, only because wehave other tools in our box.Let us now take the opposite situation—that inwhich it is we ourselves who are being instructed.I am no mathematician; and some one is trying toexplain to me the theory that space is finite. Stated
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 139thus, the new doctrine is, to me, meaningless. Butsuppose he proceeds as follows.'You,' he may say, 'can intuit only three dimensions; you therefore cannot conceive how space shouldbe limited. But I think I can show you how thatwhich must appear infinite in three dimensions,might nevertheless be finite in four. Look at it thisway. Imagine a race of people who knew only twodimensions—like the Flatlandcrs. And suppose theywere living on a globe. They would have no conception,of course, that the globe was curved—for it iscurved round in that third dimension of which theyhave no inkling. They will therefore imagine thatthey are living on a plane; but they will soon findout that it is a plane which nowhere comes to an end;there are no edges to it. Nor would they be ableeven to imagine an edge. For an edge would meanthat, after a certain point, there would be nothing towalk on; nothing below their feet. But that belowand above dimension is just what their minds havenot got; they have only backwards and forwards, andleft and right. They would thus be forced to assertthat their globe, which they could not see as a globe,was infinite. You can see perfectly well that it isfinite. And now, can you not conceive that as theseFlatlandcrs are to you, so you might be to a creaturethat intuited four dimensions? Can you not conceivehow that which seems necessarily infinite toyour three-dimensional consciousness might nonethe less be really finite?' The result of such a metaphoron my mind would be—in fact, has been—thatsomething which before was sheerly meaningless
140 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESacquires at least a faint hint of meaning. And if theparticular example docs not appeal to every one, yetevery one has had experiences of the same sort. Forall of us there arc things which we cannot fully understandat all, but of which we can get a faint inkling bymeans of metaphor. And in such cases the relationbetween the thought and the metaphor is preciselythe opposite of the relation which arises when it is weourselves who understand and then invent the metaphorsto help others. We are here entirely at themercy of the metaphor. If our instructor has chosenit badly, we shall be thinking nonsense. If we havenot got the imagery clearly before us, we shall bethinking nonsense. If we have it before us withoutknowing that it is metaphor—if we forget that ourFlatlanders on their globe arc a copy of the thing andmistake them for the thing itself—then again weshall be thinking nonsense. What truth we canattain in such a situation depends rigidly on threeconditions. First, that the imagery should be originallywell chosen; secondly, that we should apprehendthe exact imagery; and thirdly that we should knowthat the metaphor is a metaphor. (That metaphors,misread as statements of fact, arc the source ofmonstrous errors, need hardly be pointed out.)I have now attempted to show two different kindsof metaphorical situation as they are at their birth.They are the two extremes, and furnish the limitswithin which our inquiry must work. On the onehand, there is the metaphor which we invent toteach by; on the other, the metaphor from whichwe learn. They might be called the Master's meta-
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 141phor, and the Pupil's metaphor. The first is freelychosen; it is one among many possible modes ofexpression; it docs not at all hinder, and only veryslightly helps, the thought of its maker. The secondis not chosen at all; it is the unique expression of ameaning that we cannot have on any other terms; itdominates completely the thought of the recipient;his truth cannot rise above the truth of the originalmetaphor. And between the Master's metaphor andthe Pupil's there comes, of course, an endless numberof types, dotted about in every kind of intermediateposition. Indeed, these Pupil-Teachers' metaphorsare the ordinary stuff of our conversation. To dividethem into a scries of classes and sub-classes and toattempt to discuss these separately would be verylaborious, and, I trust, unnecessary. If we can find atrue doctrine about the two extremes, we shall notbe at a loss to give an account of what falls betweenthem. To find the truth about any given metaphoricalsituation will merely be to plot its position. Inso far as it inclines to the 'magistral' extreme, so farour thought will be independent of it; in so far as ithas a 'pupillary' element, so far it will be the uniqueexpression, and therefore the iron limit of our thinking.To fill in this framework would be, as Aristotleused to say, 'anybody's business'.Our problem, it will be remembered, was theproblem of 'dead' or 'forgotten'metaphors. We havenow gained some light on the relation betweenthought and metaphor as it is at the outset, whenthe metaphor is first made; and we have seen thatthis relation varies greatly according to what I have
142 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFEREScalled the 'metaphorical situation'. There is, infact, one relation in the case of the Master's metaphor,and an almost opposite relation in that of thePupil's metaphor. The next step must clearly be tosee what becomes of these two relations as the metaphorsin question progress to the state of death orfossilization.The question of the Master's Metaphor need notdetain us long. I may attempt to explain the Kantianphilosophy to a pupil by the following metaphor.'Kant answered the question "How do I know thatwhatever comes round the corner will be blue?" bythe supposition "I am wearing blue spectacles."In time I may come to use "the blue spectacles" as akind of shorthand for the whole Kantian machineryof the categories and forms of perception. And let ussuppose, for the sake of analogy with the real historyof language, that I continue to use this expressionlong after I have forgotten the metaphor whichoriginally gave rise to it. And perhaps by this timethe form of the word will have changed. Instead ofthe 'blue spectacles' I may now talk of the bloospel oreven the bluspel. If I live long enough to reach mydotage I may even enter on a philological period inwhich I attempt to find the derivation of this mysteriousword. I may suppose that the second elementis derived from the word spell and look back withinterest on the supposed period when Kant appearedto me to be magical; or else, arguing that thewhole word is clearly formed on the analogy ofgospel, may indulge in unhistorical reminiscences ofthe days when the Critique seemed to me irrefragably
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 143true. But how far, if at all, will my thinking aboutKant be affected by all this linguistic process? Inpractice, no doubt, there will be some subtle influence;the mere continued use of the word bluspelmay have led me to attribute to it a unity and substantialitywhich I should have hesitated to attributeto 'the whole Kantian machinery of the categoriesand forms of perception'. But that is a result ratherof the noun-making than of the death of the metaphor.It is an interesting fact, but hardly relevant toour present inquiry. For the rest, the mere forgettingof the metaphor does not seem to alter my thinkingabout Kant, just as the original metaphor did notlimit my thinking about Kant; provided always—and this is of the last importance—that it was, tobegin with, a genuine Master's metaphor. I had myconception of Kant's philosophy before I ever thoughtof the blue spectacles. If I have continued philosophicalstudies I have it still. The 'blue spectacles'phrase was from the first a temporary dress assumedby my thought for a special purpose, and ready to belaid aside at my pleasure; it did not penetrate thethinking itself, and its subsequent history is irrelevant.To any one who attempts to refute my later views onKant by telling me that I don't know the real meaningof bluspel, I may confidently retort 'Derivationsaren't meanings'. To be sure, if there was any pupillaryelement in its original use, if I received, as wellas gave, new understanding when I used it, then thewhole situation will be different. And it is fair toadmit that in practice very few metaphors can bepurely magistral; only that which to some degree
144 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESenlightens ourselves is likely to enlighten others. Itis hardly possible that when I first used the metaphorof the blue spectacles I did not gain some newawareness of the Kantian philosophy; and, so far,it was not purely magistral. But I am deliberatelyidealizing for the sake of clarity. Purely magistralmetaphor may never occur. What is important forus is to grasp that just in so far as any metaphor beganby being magistral, so far I can continue to use itlong after I have forgotten its metaphorical nature,and my thinking will be neither helped nor hinderedby the fact that it was originally a metaphor, nor yetby my forgctfulncss of that fact. It is a mere accident.Here, derivations arc irrelevant to meanings.Let us now turn to the opposite situation, that ofthe Pupil's Metaphor. And let us continue to use ourold example of the unmathematical man who has hadthe finitude of space suggested to him (we can hardlysay 'explained') by the metaphor of the Flatlandcrson their sphere. The question here is rather morecomplicated. In the case of the Master's metaphor,by hypothesis, the master knew, and would continueto know, what he meant, independently of the metaphor.In the present instance, however, the fossilizationof the metaphor may take place in two differentways. The pupil may himself become a mathematician,or he may remain as ignorant of mathematicsas he was before; and in either case, he may continueto use the metaphor of the Flatlandcrs while forgettingits real content and its metaphorical nature.I will take the second possibility first. From theimagery of the Flatlandcrs' sphere I have got my
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 145first inkling of the new meaning. My thought isentirely conditioned by this imagery. I do not apprehendthe thing at all, except by seeing 'it could besomething like this'. Let us suppose that in myanxiety to docket this new experience, I label theinkling or vague notion, 'the Flatlanders' sphere'.When I next hear the fourth dimension spoken of,I shall say, 'Ah yes—the Flatlandcrs' sphere and allthat'. In a few years (to continue our artificialparallel) I may be talking glibly of the Flalansfereand may even have forgotten the whole of theimagery which this word once represented. And Iam still, according to the hypothesis, profoundlyignorant of mathematics. My situation will thensurely be most ridiculous. The meaning of FlalansfereI never knew except through the imagery. I couldget beyond the imagery, to that whereof the imagerywas a copy, only by learning mathematics; but thisI have neglected to do. Yet I have lost the imagery.Nothing remains, then, but the conclusion that theword Flalansfere is now really meaningless. Mythinking, which could never get beyond the imagery,at once its boundary and its support, has now lostthat support. I mean strictly nothing when I speakof the Flalansfere. I am only talking, not thinking,when I use the word. But this fact will be long concealedfrom me, because Flalansfere, being a noun,can be endlessly fitted into various contexts, so as toconform to syntactical usage and to give an appearanceof meaning. It will even conform to the logicalrules; and I can make many judgements about theFlalansfere; such as it is what it is, and has attributes (forL
146 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESotherwise of course it wouldn't be a thing, and if itwasn't a thing, how could I be talking about it?), andis a substance (for it can be the subject of a sentence).And what affective overtones the word may have takenon by that time, it is dangerous to predict. It had anair of mystery from the first: before the end I shallprobably be building temples to it, and exhorting mycountrymen to fight and die for the Flalansfere. Butthe Flalansfere, when once we have forgotten themetaphor, is only a noise.But how if I proceed, after once having graspedthe metaphor of the Flatlanders, to become a mathematician?In this case, too, I may well continue touse the metaphor, and may corrupt it in form till itbecomes a single noun, the Flalansfere. But I shallhave advanced, by other means, from the originalsymbolism; and I shall be able to study the thingsymbolized without reference to the metaphor thatfirst introduced me to it. It will then be no harmthough I should forget that Flalansfere had ever beenmetaphorical. As the metaphor, even if it survived,would no longer limit my thoughts, so its fossilizationcannot confuse them.The results which emerge may now be summarizedas follows. Our thought is independent of the metaphorswe employ, in so far as these metaphors areoptional: that is, in so far as we arc able to have thesame idea without them. For that is the real characteristicboth of the magistral metaphors and of thosewhich become optional, as the Flatlanders wouldbecome, if the pupil learned mathematics. On theother hand, where the metaphor is our only method
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 147of reaching a given idea at all, there our thinking islimited by the metaphor so long as we retain themetaphor; and when the metaphor becomes fossilized,our 'thinking' is not thinking at all, but meresound or mere incipient movements in the larynx.We arc now in a position to reply to the statementthat 'Derivations arc not meanings', and to the claimthat 'we know what we mean by words withoutknowing the fossilized metaphors they contain'. Wecan sec that such a statement, as it stands, is neitherwholly true nor wholly false. The truth will vary fromword to word, and from speaker to speaker. No ruleof thumb is possible, we must take every case on itsmerits. A word can bear a meaning in the mouth ofa speaker who has forgotten its hidden metaphor,and a meaning independent of that metaphor, butonly on certain conditions. Either the metaphor musthave been optional from the beginning, and haveremained optional through all the generations of itsuse, so that the conception has always used and stilluses the imagery as a mere tool; or else, at someperiod subsequent to its creation, we must have goneon to acquire, independently of the metaphor, suchnew knowledge of the object indicated by it asenables us now, at least, to dispense with it. To putthe same thing in another way, meaning is independentof derivation, only if the metaphor wasoriginally 'magistral'; or if, in the case of an originallypupillary metaphor, some quite new kind of apprehensionhas arisen to replace the metaphorical apprehensionwhich has been lost. The two conditions maybe best illustrated by a concrete example. Let us
148 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFEREStake the word for soul as it exists in the Romancelanguage. How far is a man entitled to say that whathe means by the word âme or anima is quite independentof the image of breathing, and that he meansjust the same (and just as much) whether he happensto know that 'derivation' or not? We can only answerthat it depends on a variety of things. I will enumerateall the formal possibilities for the sake ofclearness: one of them, of course, is too grotesque toappear for any other purpose.1. The metaphor may originally have been magistral.Primitive men, we arc to suppose, were clearlyaware, on the one hand, of an entity called soul; and,on the other, of a process or object called breath.And they used the second figuratively to suggest thefirst—presumably when revealing their wisdom toprimitive women and primitive children. And wemay suppose, further, that this magistral relation tothe metaphor has never been lost: that all generations,from the probably arboreal to the man saying 'Blastyour soul' in a pub this evening, have kept clearlybefore them these two separate entities, and used theone metaphorically to denote the other, while atthe same time being well able to conceive the soulunmctaphorically, and using the metaphor merelyas a colour or trope which adorned but did notinfluence their thought. Now if all this were true,it would unquestionably follow that when a mansays anima his meaning is not affected by the oldimage of breath; and also, it does not matter inthe least whether he knows that the word once sug-
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 149gcsted that image or not. But of course all this isnot true.2. The metaphor may originally have been pupillary.So far from being a voluntary ornament orpacdagogic device, the ideas of breath or something likebreath may have been the only possible inkling thatour parents could gain of the soul. But if this was so,how does the modern user of the word stand ?Clearly, if he has ceased to be aware of the metaphoricalelement in anima, without replacing the metaphoricalapprehension by some new knowledge ofthe soul, borrowed from other sources, then he willmean nothing by it; we must not, on that account,suppose that he will cease to use it, or even to use it(as we say) intelligibly—i.e. to use it in sentencesconstructed according to the laws of grammar, andto insert these sentences into those conversational andliterary contexts where usage demands their insertion.If, on the other hand, he has some independentknowledge of the entity which our ancestors indicatedby their metaphor of breath, then indeed hemay mean something.I take it that it is this last situation in which wecommonly suppose ourselves to be. It doesn't matter,we would claim, what the majestic root GNA reallystood for: we have learned a great deal about knowingsince those days, and it is these more recent acquisitionsthat we use in our thinking. The first name fora thing may easily be determined by some inconsiderableaccident. As we learn more, we mean
150 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESmore; the radical meaning of the old syllables doesnot bind us; what we have learned since has set usfree. Assuredly, the accident which led the Romansto call all Hellenes Graeci did not continue to limittheir power of apprehending Greece. And as long aswe are dealing with sensible objects this view ishardly to be disputed. The difficulty begins withobjects of thought. It may be stated as follows.Our claim to independence of the metaphor is, aswe have seen, a claim to know the object otherwisethan through that metaphor. If we can throw theFlatlanders overboard and still think the fourthdimension, then, and not otherwise, we can forgetwhat Flalansfere once meant and still think coherently.That was what happened, you will remember, to theman who went on and learned mathematics. He cameto apprehend that of which the Flatlanders' spherewas only the image, and consequently was free tothink beyond the metaphor and to forget the metaphoraltogether. In our previous account of him, however,we carefully omitted to draw attention to onevery remarkable fact: namely, that when he desertedmetaphor for mathematics, he did not really passfrom symbol to symbolized, but only from one set ofsymbols to another. The equations and what-notsare as unreal, as metaphorical, if you like, as theFlatlanders' sphere. The mathematical problem Ineed not pursue further; we see at once that it castsa disquieting light on our linguistic problem. Wehave hitherto been speaking as if we had two methodsof thought open to us: the metaphorical, and theliteral. We talked as if the creator of a magistral
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 151metaphor had it always in his power to think thesame concept literally if he chose. We talked as if thepresent-day user of the word anima could prove hisright to neglect that word's buried metaphor byturning round and giving us an account of the soulwhich was not metaphorical at all. That he haspower to dispense with the particular metaphor ofbreath, is of course agreed. But we have not yetinquired what he can substitute for it. If we turn tothose who arc most anxious to tell us about the soul—I mean the psychologists—we shall find that theword anima has simply been replaced by complexes,repressions, censors, engrams, and the like. In otherwords the breath has been exchanged for tyings-up,shovings-back, Roman magistrates, and scratchings. If weinquire what has replaced the metaphorical brightsky of primitive theology, we shall only get a perfectsubstance, that is, a completely made lying-under, or—which is very much better, but equally metaphorical—auniversal Father, or perhaps (in English) aloaf-carver, in Latin a householder, in Romance a personolder than. The point need not be laboured. It isabundantly clear that the freedom from a givenmetaphor which we admittedly enjoy in some casesis often only a freedom to choose between that metaphorand others.Certain reassurances may, indeed, be held out. Inthe first place, our distinction between the differentkinds of metaphorical situation can stand; though itis hardly so important as we had hoped. To have achoice of metaphors (as we have in some cases) is toknow more than we know when we are the slaves of
152 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESa unique metaphor. And, in the second place, alldescription or identification, all direction of ourown thought or another's, is not so metaphorical asdefinition. If, when challenged on the word anima,we proceed to define, we shall only reshuffle theburied metaphors; but if we simply say (or think)'what I am', or 'what is going on in here', we shallhave at least something before us which we do notknow by metaphor. We shall at least be no worse offthan the arboreal psychologists. At the same time,this method will not really carry us far. 'What'sgoing on here' is really the content of haec anima: foranima we want 'The sort of thing that is going onhere', and once we are committed to sorts and kindswe are adrift among metaphors.We have already said that when a man claims tothink independently of the buried metaphor in oneof his words, his claim may sometimes be allowed.But it was allowed only in so far as he could reallysupply the place of that buried metaphor with newand independent apprehension of his own. We nowsee that this new apprehension will usually turn outto be itself metaphorical; or else, what is very muchworse, instead of new apprehension we shall havesimply words—each word enshrining one moreignored metaphor. For if he does not know the historyof anima, how should he know the history of theequally metaphorical words in which he defines it, ifchallenged? And if he does not know their historyand therefore their metaphors, and if he cannot definethem without yet further metaphors, what can hisdiscourse be but an endless ringing of the changes on
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 153such bluspels and Flalansferes as seem to mean, indeed,but do not mean? In reality, the man has played usa very elementary trick. He claimed that he couldthink without metaphor, and in ignorance of themetaphors fossilized in his words. He made good theclaim by pointing to the knowledge of his objectwhich he possessed independently of the metaphor;and the proof of this knowledge was the definition ordescription which he could produce. We did not atfirst observe that where we were promised a freedomfrom metaphor we were given only a power ofchanging the metaphors in rapid succession. Thethings he speaks of he has never apprehendedliterally. Yet only such genuinely literal apprehensioncould enable him to forget the metaphorswhich he was actually using and yet to have ameaning. Either literalness, or else metaphor understood:one or other of these we must have; the thirdalternative is nonsense. But literalness we cannothave. The man who does not consciously use metaphorstalks without meaning. We might even formulatea rule: the meaning in any given composition isin inverse ratio to the author's belief in his ownliteralness.If a man has seen ships and the sea, he may abandonthe metaphor of a sea-stallion and call a boat a boat.But suppose a man who has never seen the sea, orships, yet who knows of them just as much as he canglean, say from the following list of Kenningar—seastallions,winged logs, wave riders, ocean trains. Ifhe keeps all these together in his mind, and knowsthem for the metaphors they are, he will be able to
154 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESthink of ships, very imperfectly indeed, and understrict limits, but not wholly in vain. But if insteadof this he pins his faith on the particular kenningocean-trains, because that kenning, with its comfortableair of machinery, seems to him somehow moresafely prosaic, less flighty and dangerous than itsfellows, and if, contracting that to the form oshtrans,he proceeds to forget that it was a metaphor, then,while he talks grammatically, he has ceased to thinkof anything. It will not avail him to stamp his feetand swear that he is literal; to say 'An oshtran is anoshtran, and there's an end. I mean what I mean.What I mean is what I say.'The remedy lies, indeed, in the opposite direction.When we pass beyond pointing to individual sensibleobjects, when we begin to think of causes, relations,of mental states or acts, we become incurably metaphorical.We apprehend none of these things exceptthrough metaphor: we know of the ships only whatthe Kenningar will tell us. Our only choice is to usethe metaphors and thus to think something, thoughless than we could wish; or else to be driven by unrecognizedmetaphors and so think nothing at all.I myself would prefer to embrace the former choice,as far as my ignorance and laziness allow me.To speak more plainly, he who would increase themeaning and decrease the meaningless verbiage inhis own speech and writing, must do two things.He must become conscious of the fossilized metaphorsin his words; and he must freely use new metaphors,which he creates for himself. The first dependsupon knowledge, and therefore on leisure; the second
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 155on a certain degree of imaginative ability. Thesecond is perhaps the more important of the two:we arc never less the slaves of metaphor than whenwe are making metaphor, or hearing it new made.When we are thinking hard of the Flatlanders, andat the same time fully aware that they are a metaphor,we are in a situation almost infinitely superior tothat of the man who talks of the Flalansfere and thinksthat he is being literal and straightforward.If our argument has been sound, it leads us tocertain rather remarkable conclusions. In the firstplace it would seem that we must be content with avery modest quantity of thinking as the core of allour talking. I do not wish to exaggerate our poverty.Not all our words arc equally metaphorical, not allour metaphors are equally forgotten. And evenwhere the old metaphor is lost there is often a hopethat we may still restore meaning by pointing tosome sensible object, some sensation, or some concretememory. But no man can or will confinehis cognitive efforts to this narrow field. At thevery humblest we must speak of things in theplural; we must point not only to isolated sensations,but to groups and classes of sensations; and theuniversal latent in every group and every plural inflectioncannot be thought without metaphor. Thusfar beyond the security of literal meaning all of us,we may be sure, are going to be driven by our dailyneeds; indeed, not to go thus far would be to abandonreason itself. In practice we all really intend to gomuch farther. Why should we not? We have inour hands the key of metaphor, and it would be
156 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESpusillanimous to abandon its significant use, becausewe have come to realize that its meaningless use isnecessarily prevalent. We must indeed learn to useit more cautiously; and one of the chief benefits tobe derived from our inquiry is the new standard ofcriticism which we must henceforward apply both toour own apparent thought and to that of others.We shall find, too, that real meaning, judged bythis standard, docs not come always where we havelearned to expect. Flalansferes and bluspels will clearlybe most prevalent in certain types of writers. Thepercentage of mere syntax masquerading as meaningmay vary from something like 100 per cent, in politicalwriters, journalists, psychologists, and economists, tosomething like forty per cent, in the writers of children'sstories. Some scientists will fare better thanothers: the historian, the geographer, and sometimesthe biologist will speak significantly more often thantheir colleagues; the mathematician, who seldom forgetsthat his symbols are symbolic, may often rise forshort stretches to ninety per cent, of meaning and tenof verbiage. The philosophers will differ as widelyfrom one another as any of the other groups differamong themselves: for a good metaphysical librarycontains at once some of the most verbal, and someof the most significant literature in the world. Thosewho have prided themselves on being literal, andwho have endeavoured to speak plainly, with no mysticaltomfoolery, about the highest abstractions, willbe found to be among the least significant of writers:I doubt if we shall find more than a beggarly fiveper cent, of meaning in the pages of some celebrated
BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERES 157'tough minded' thinkers, and how the account ofKant or Spinoza stands, none knows but heaven.But open your Plato, and you will find yourselfamong the great creators of metaphor, and thereforeamong the masters of meaning. If we turn toTheology—or rather to the literature of religion—the result will be more surprising still; for unlessour whole argument is wrong, we shall have toadmit that a man who says heaven and thinks ofthe visible sky is pretty sure to mean more thana man who tells us that heaven is a state of mind.It may indeed be otherwise; the second man maybe a mystic who is remembering and pointing toan actual and concrete experience of his own. Butit is long, long odds. Bunyan and Dante standwhere they did; the scale of Bishop Butler, and ofbetter men than he, flies up and kicks the beam.It will have escaped no one that in such a scale ofwriters the poets will take the highest place; andamong the poets those who have at once the tenderestcare for old words and the surest instinct for thecreation of new metaphors. But it must not besupposed that I am in any sense putting forwardthe imagination as the organ of truth. We are nottalking of truth, but of meaning: meaning which isthe antecedent condition both of truth and falsehood,whose antithesis is not error but nonsense.I am a rationalist. For me, reason is the naturalorgan of truth; but imagination is the organ ofmeaning. Imagination, producing new metaphorsor revivifying old, is not the cause of truth, but itscondition. It is, I confess, undeniable that such a
158 BLUSPELS AND FLALANSFERESview indirectly implies a kind of truth or Tightnessin the imagination itself. I said at the outset thatthe truth we won by metaphor could not be greaterthan the truth of the metaphor itself; and we haveseen since that all our truth, or all but a few fragments,is won by metaphor. And thence, I confess, itdocs follow that if our thinking is ever true, then themetaphors by which we think must have been goodmetaphors. It docs follow that if those originalequations, between good and light, or evil and dark,between breath and soul and all the others, werefrom the beginning arbitrary and fanciful—if there isnot, in fact, a kind of psycho-physical parallelism(or more) in the universe—then all our thinking isnonsensical. But we cannot, without contradiction,believe it to be nonsensical. And so, admittedly, theview I have taken has metaphysical implications.But so has every view.
VIIIVARIATION IN SHAKESPEAREAND O<strong>THE</strong>RSSententia cum sitUnica, non uno veniat contenta paratu,Sed variet vestes of mutatoria sumat.Sub verbis aliis praesumpta resume, reponePluribus in clausis unum; multiplier formaDissimuletur idem; varius sis of tamen idem.GEFFROIDE DE VINSAUF, Poetria NOVA, pp. 220 et seq.Read to the Mermaid Club
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE ANDO<strong>THE</strong>RSONE day 1 in March, 1781, Mrs. Thrale and Boswellpresented the Doctor with a problem. HadShakespeare or Milton drawn the more admirablepicture of a man? The passages produced on eitherside were Hamlet's description of his father, andMilton's description of Adam. They run as follows.See what a grace was seated on this brow,Hyperion's curls, the front of Jove himself,An eye like Mars, to threaten and command,A station like the herald MercuryNew lighted on a heaven kissing hill;A combination and a form, indeed,Where every God did seem to set his sealTo give the world assurance of a man.His fair large front and eye sublime declar'dAbsolute rule: and hyacinthine locksRound from his parted forelock manly hungClustering, but not beneath his shoulders broad.It may have seemed a little remarkable that the'wild genius' should so abound in classical allusionswhile the scholar poet was so free from them. Butthis would surprise no one who was familiar with theworks of both; nor is it the most important difference.It is, in the logical sense, an accident that the figureswhich fill Shakespeare's description should comefrom classical mythology. It is their presence andtheir function, not their source, that matters. Thetwo passages illustrate two radically different methodsof poetical description. Milton keeps his eye on the1 It was between the a 21st and the 30th.M
162 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSobject, and builds up his picture in what seems anatural order. It is distinguished from a prosecatalogue largely by the verse, and by the exquisitechoice not of the rarest words but of the words whichwill seem the most nobly obvious when once theyhave been chosen. 'Fair large front'—any one, youwould say, could think of that. And yet how well itdoes its work. Those three monosyllables, heavy yeteasily uttered, with the glorious vowel of large, havealready smuggled into our minds the sense of massive,leisurely dignity: it is Michelangelo's Adam 'in thatmajestic indolence so dear to native man'; we arcprepared for the words 'absolute rule' in the nextline. Shakespeare's method is wholly different.Where Milton marches steadily forward, Shakespearebehaves rather like a swallow. He darts at the subjectand glances away; and then he is back again beforeyour eyes can follow him. It is as if he kept on havingtries at it, and being dissatisfied. He darts imageafter image at you and still seems to think that hehas not done enough. He brings up a whole lightartillery of mythology, and gets tired of each piecealmost before he has fired it. He wants to sec theobject from a dozen different angles; if the undignifiedword is pardonable, he nibbles, like a mantrying a tough biscuit now from this side and nowfrom that. You can find the same sort of contrastalmost anywhere between these two poets. WhenMilton wishes to convey to us the greatness ofBeelzebub he says:and in his rising seemedA pillar of state. Deep on his front engraven
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 163Deliberation sat and public care,And princely counsel in his face yet shoneMajestic, though in ruin. Sage he stoodWith Atlantcan shoulders, fit to bearThe weight of mightiest monarchies. His lookDrew audience and attention still as nightOr summer's noontide air.But when Cleopatra wants to tell of Antony'sgreatness, she talks like this:His legs bestrid the ocean: his rear'd armCrested the world: his voice was propertiedAs all the tuned spheres, and that to friends;But when he meant to quail and shake the orbHe was as rattling thunder. For his bountyThere was no winter in't: an autumn 'twasThat grew the more by reaping. His delightsWere dolphin like: they show'd his back aboveThe clement they lived in, &c.You see again how simple, how all of one piece,like the clean growth of a tulip, the Milton is: howdiversified—more like a chrysanthemum—is theShakespeare. In Milton you have first the visualimpression; then the moral showing through it; theallusion to Atlas, so obvious that any one (we feel)could have guessed it was coming: finally the stillness,compared, so obviously, so un-cleverly, to night ornoon, and yet doing to perfection the work it wasmeant to do. In Shakespeare, as before, you havethe ends of the earth all brought together. Youbegin with the gigantic hyperbole of a man bestridingthe ocean, or an arm cresting the world;you go on to the music of the spheres, to thunder, tothe seasons, to dolphins. Nor does one image grow
164 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSout of another. The arm cresting the world is not adevelopment of the legs bestriding the ocean; it isidem in alio, a second attempt at the very same idea,an alternative. The dolphin idea is not a continuationof the autumn idea. It is a fresh start. He beginsover again in every second line. If you extract thebare logical skeleton, the prose 'meaning' of eachimage, you will find that it is precisely the same inmost of them. That is not so with the Milton: theprose abstract would take nearly as many words asthe poetical expression. 'Beelzebub was very big;he looked wise; he looked wise though broken; hisshoulders were broad; the people were hushed whenthey saw him.' If you do the same to Cleopatra'sspeech you get something like this: 'He was great.He was great. He was great enough to help hisfriends. He was great enough to hurt his enemies.He was generous. He was generous. He was great. 5In short, Milton gives you a theme developing:Shakespeare plays variations on a theme that remainsthe same. In the one, touch after touch is added tothe picture until the whole stands completed; in theother you get rather a series of lightning sketches,each of the same subject, and each tossed asidebefore the sketcher has really finished. We mightdistinguish these as the method of construction andthe method of variation. The first does one thing aswell as it can and then proceeds to the next; thesecond cannot do even one thing except by doing itseveral times, as if even one thing were inexhaustible,and the poet could only go on having shots at ituntil mere necessity forced him to give it up.
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 165It would be a mistake to suppose that what we havehere stumbled on is simply the difference between epicand dramatic poetry. If I could presume on endlesspatience I could show you the opposite. I could takeShakespeare where he is himself handling epic matterand show that the very same difference holds betweenhim and <strong>Home</strong>r as between him and Milton. I wouldput the Prologue to the third Act of Henry V, wherePhoebus is fanning the silken streamers and a city isdancing on the billows beside <strong>Home</strong>r's picture of theGreeks advancing 'in silence with their eyes upontheir captains'. I would put a dozen speeches fromancient tragedy beside a dozen speeches from Shakepeare.Everywhere almost, though not everywhereto the same degree, we should find the same distinction.Nor is the difference that between classical andromantic art. Milton's Beelzebub with his dim vastnessand his ruined splendour is ten times moreromantic than Cleopatra's Antony, whose greatness,under all its metaphorical deck hamper, remainsgreatness of a very mundane and lucrative type.The point can easily be settled by another example.Mr. Yeats says, of the fairies,How shall I name you, immortal, mild, proud shadows?I only know that all we know comes from you.Prospero tackles them more like thisyou demi puppets thatBy moonshine do the green sour ringlets makeWhereof the ewe not bites, and you whose pastimeIs to make midnight mushrooms, that delightTo hear the solemn curfew.
166 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSHere both passages arc utterly romantic; but theyarc as different as any other two that I have cited.Yeats gets his effect by packing as much mystery andlonging as he can into a single phrase, without figures:Shakespeare, as always, flits from point to point, andwill have five or six attempts to make you see thefairies, by catching them in different places. Themethod of variation is not a characteristic either ofdramatic, or of romantic poetry. Still less is it peculiarto Shakespeare. It is shared by all the Elizabethandramatists. It was there before Shakespeare.I will be Paris, and for love of theeInstead of Troy shall Wertenbcrg be sacked,And I will combat with weak MenelausAnd wear thy colours on my plumed crest;Yea, I will wound Achilles in the heelAnd then return to Helen for a kiss.If we reduce the prose content of this to 'I love youwell enough to fight for you, as Paris for Helen,' wehave still not done enough. For the Paris and Helenidea is itself merely illustration, and the whole ofthe rest of the passage is a ringing of the changes onParis and Helen, who themselves but ring the changeson the original theme. The method is used equallyby a poet who piques himself on being different fromthe general, like Ben Jonson. Thus in Every Man inhis Humour 1 I readWho will not judge him worthy to be robbedThat sets his doors wide open to a thiefAnd shews the felon where his treasure lies?Again what earthy spirit but will attempt1 Q.. 1601, III. i.
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 167To taste the fruit of beauty's golden treeWhen leaden sleep seals up the dragon's eyes?Oh beauty is a project of some powerChiefly when opportunity attends her.She will infuse true motion in a stone,Put glowing fire in an icy soul,Stuff peasants' bosoms with proud Caesar's spleen,Pour rich device into an empty brain, &c.The whole passage may very profitably be comparedwith Milton's imitation of it in Comus. The six linesbeginning 'Oh beauty is a project', which containfour distinct metaphorical expressions of preciselythe same idea, he throws out altogether. He keepsthe dragon idea, and the stores spread out in thesight of a thief, but reverses the order. The dragoncomes first and is used for a different purpose. Themarvellous line 'Of dragon watch with unenchantedeye' is the central phrase, and the metaphor as awhole becomes less a rhetorical illustration of thetheme than an escape into pure imagination. Thehoard-and-thicf idea is separated from it by thewords 'You may as well', and has the effect ofsumming up the previous argument. It is not simplyone more point that has occurred to the speaker; itis a return to the person addressed, as if he hadrounded on him.It is the same with the later dramatists. If we everfail to notice it, it is because we are so used to it thatit comes to us merged in the general atmosphere of'Elizabethan play'. 'Gentle father, To you I haveunclasped my burdened soul, Emptied the storehouseof my thoughts and heart, Made myself poor
168 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSof secrets: have not left Another word untold whichhath not spoke All that I ever durst or think orknow.' 1 Here are four variations on the theme 'Ihave confided in you 5 . There is no movement.Unclasping the burdened soul and emptying thestorehouse of one's thoughts are simply alternativemetaphors for the same idea. The one does not growout of the other, nor improve on it. Or again: 'Youdreamt of kingdoms, did ye? how to bosom Thedelicacies of a youngling princess, How with this nodto grace that subtle courtyer, How with that frown tomake this noble tremble.' 2 Here the variation is notby metaphors, but, as we might say, by particularization.You announce the theme of Kingship first andthen go on to ring the changes on particular aspectsof Kingship. It is one of the simplest ways of turningan abstract conception into poetry, and is perhapsthe commonest of all forms of variation in thesedramatists. It does not differ essentially from themetaphorical type. The same choice is before thepoet. Some abstraction is to be presented, say,luxury, servility, folly. Are you to do it by findingthe single most suggestive phrase that you can andthen have done with it? Or are you to try to catcha glimpse of it manifested in as many different modesas you can and fling them all together, varying asmany aspects of the theme as possible? The Elizabethansnearly always chose the latter; often withbeautiful result.So shall the spirits of every elementBe always serviceable to us three;1 TIS Pity She's a Whore, I. i.2 The Broken Heart, iv. iv.
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 169Like lions shall they guard us when we please,Like Almain ruttcrs with their horseman's stavesOr Lapland giants trotting by our sides,Sometimes like women or unwedded maidsShadowing more beauty in their airy browsThan have the white breasts of the queen of love.From Venice shall they drag huge argosiesAnd from America the golden fleece.That is Marlowe's way. The abstraction 'magicalpower' is turned into poetry by the process of variation—byoffering you a handful of specimens. Oneis not enough for him; he tries it from this angle andfrom that. But there are other ways. Wordsworthhas to express a much more abstract conceptionthan that of magical power—the conception, namely,of restraints exercised upon the wiser sort of youngmen by the wrong sort of old men. He writes simplyAnd blind authority beating with his staffThe child that might have led him,and the thing is done. We can all guess how theElizabethans would have dealt with it. We shouldhave begun, perhaps, with a flourish about authorityin the abstract, old and sour as Saturn, but blind asCupid; and then we should certainly have passedinto a series of dissolving views in which we caughtglimpses of authority at work—a man being proggedin one line, and a conversation with a dean in thenext.It will be understood, of course, that variationoccurs to some extent in all poetry whatsoever. Whatis the Hebrew parallelism but a kind of variation?The synonyms in Anglo-Saxon are the same. But
170 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSI think it is not likely to be disputed that the Elizabethandramatists used it more extensively than anyother family of poets. All poets use metaphors; allpoets turn the abstract into the concrete; but if wewant to see multiplication of metaphors about thesame idea, and if we want to see concreteness givennot by a single imaginative phrase but by multiplicationof instances, then we naturally turn to Shakespeareand his neighbours. The faculty whichenabled a man to practise such variation, whichstocked his mind with images and which broughta riot of images tumbing over one another to greetevery single idea was for the Elizabethans theessential faculty of the poet. They called it Wit.Middleton in his Changeling 1 writes:Love has an intellect that runs through allThe scrutinous sciences and like a cunning poetCatches a quantity of every knowledgeYet brings all home into one mystery.This may be taken simply as a description of thatcscmplastic power which is involved in all poetry.But it has a special meaning for the seventeenthcentury. Never were the scrutinous sciences and thequantities of every knowledge expected to lie quiteso ready to the poet's hand; never were poets so eagerto bring them all home (if it were possible) on everyoccasion.It is no part of my purpose to compare this kind ofwriting with others. Whether you prefer the poetrywhich deals chiefly in construction or that whichdeals chiefly in variation is largely a matter of tem-1 III. iii. 131.
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 171perament. Any sane man will want both. In Shirleyyou may see this style in the last stages of its decay;all its peculiar vices—for every method has its vices—are then painfully visible. But it is more interestingto consider what this practice of variation could doat its best. What were the kingdoms of poetry whichit alone could conquer, and whose conquest madeit so dangerously attractive to the weaker poets?To ask this is, of course, equivalent to asking whatShakespeare did with it.If we lay aside all the bardolatrous nonsense ofthose who would have us believe that Shakespearewas God or Nature, and ask what, in a few words,was his distinctive contribution to poetry, I really donot know why we should be afraid of answering thequestion. The largest things ought to be the mosteasily seen. The law of gravity is perhaps simplerthan the Law of Tort. It is the minor poets whosequality is really indefinable, because it is nearlynothing. Thus fortified I venture to submit thatthe mark of Shakespeare (and it is quite enough forone mortal man) is simply this; to have combinedtwo species of excellence which are not, in a remarkabledegree, combined by any other artist, namelythe imaginative splendour of the highest type oflyric and the realistic presentation of human life andcharacter. Pindar and Aeschylus and Keats are quiteas good as he on one side; and Jane Austen, Meredith,and George Eliot can meet him on the other. ButJane Austen could not write stuff like the chorusesin the Agamemnon, and Keats (judging by Cap andBells) would have made a poor show among the
172 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSBennets and the Bingleys—(not such a very poorshow, when you remember some of the passages inthe letters). Now the possibility of combining twosuch diverse qualities depends precisely on the use ofvariation. The problem which Shakespeare solved,perhaps unconsciously, is a very difficult one. If thecharacter speaks as living men speak, how arc we tohave in his language the revealing splendours ofimagination? for real passion is not articulate. Wemust give his poetic metaphors the air of beingthrown off accidentally as he gropes for expressionin the very heat of dialogue. He must have a slightstammer in his thought, and his best things must notcome at the first attempt. For on those rare occasionswhen real life finds the inevitable phrase, that is howit arises. The man fumbles and returns again andagain to his theme, and hardly knows which of hiswords has really hit the mark. Listen to Hamlet:O that this too too solid flesh would melt—Thaw and resolve itself into a dew!Or that the Everlasting had not fixedHis canon 'gainst self slaughter. O God, God!How weary, stale, flat and unprofitableSeem to me all the uses of this world.Fie on't, ah fie! 'Tis an unweeded gardenThat grows to seed: things rank and gross in naturePossess it merely.The flesh resolving itself into a dew, and the unweededgarden are poetical metaphors that, takenalone, might seem to come from the heights of fullywrought lyric, expressing real experience but not aslife expresses it. If Hamlet used either of them he
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 173would speak only as a poet. We should not believethat a man spoke thus. We shall believe them onlyif he seems to stumble upon them by accident, ifthey come, as it were, spat out amid a chaos of othergrumbles as he chews over and over again the cudof the same bitter experience. That is how Shakespeareclaims for naturalistic poetry—the poetry ofthe close up—all the rights of that other poetry whichsees its figures at a mythical distance. See how heballasts his imaginative phases with mere exclamations—'O God, God!' and 'Fie on't, ah fie.' Amagnificent example of the same thing occurs inMacbeth'.Methought I heard a voice cry 'Sleep no more!Macbeth does murder sleep'—the innocent sleep,Sleep that knits up the ravcll'd sleave of care,The death of each day's life, sore labour's bath,Balm of hurt minds, great nature's second course,Chief nourisher in life's feast.Here the metaphors arc perhaps even more highlywrought than Hamlet's. If Macbeth had said only'sleep that knits up the ravell'd sleave of care', hewould have said one of the best things that havebeen said of sleep. But we should not have believedIt is art, not life, that selects from the mind's chaosthe one 'predestined and elected phrase That hadlain bound long nights and days Until it worewhen once set free Immortal pellucidity'. It is thevery fact that Macbeth will not leave it at that whichcarries conviction. Because he is not writing a poembut blurting out the agony of his mind he has noleisure to notice that he has said a good thing. The
174 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSwords come tumbling one after the other, and it is onlywe the spectators, who gather them up and see thatalmost every sentence has been a poem in itself. Weconclude—and this goes to the root of the matter—that Macbeth was a great poet. It is only in Shakespeare'splays that we call the characters, as well asthe author, poets. No one describes Clytemnestra asa poet. The poetry belongs to Aeschylus. We knowthat a real Clytemnestra would not talk like that. Itis the poet, quite legitimately, who puts into hermouth the language she would not, in real life, haveused, and thereby enables us to see her charactermore luminously than real life would have allowedus to sec it. But Shakespeare makes you believe thatOthello and Macbeth really spoke as we hear themspeak. Without sacrificing the splendour, he haskept the lower and more factual reality as well; it isthe very marriage of the mimetic and the creative,and it can hardly be done except by variation.It would be untrue, however, to say that Shakespearealways used variation to such good purpose.Very often, and specially in his earlier work, he usesit as a poetical ornament—to decorate, and not torender more real, the dramatic situation.His rash fierce blase of riot cannot last,For violent fires soon burn out themselves;Small showers last long but sudden storms are short;He tires betimes that spurs too fast betimes;With eager feeding food doth choke the feeder;Light vanity, insatiate cormorant,Consuming means, soon preys upon itself.Here, the not very profound idea hardly requires
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 175such a wealth of illustration, and we hardly believethat it would have received it. The passage comestrippingly off the tongue: it is written, I think, for themere fun of the thing. Such examples arc frequentin the earlier plays, and it is in these passages thatShakespeare reminds us most strongly of Marlowe;Marlowe who of all others used variation with theminimum of dramatic purpose, and the maximum ofmusical and rhetorical effect.Cut is the branch that might have grown full straightAnd burned is Apollo's laurel bough.In Shakespeare the variations arc either ornament,or else, as we have seen, a method of combiningpoetry and realism. In Shirley they arc a recipe forpoetry. I do not mean that he uses the figure moreconstantly than his predecessors; I mean that when heis not using it he has commonly no pretence of poetry.To mark a heightened moment, or to translate anabstract conception into something that looks likepoetry, variation is his unfailing resource. WhenShirley had jotted down what was to be covered ina given scene, the process of converting it into actualdrama consisted either of those purely dramaticarticulations in which he does not differ from theprose dramatist or in variation. Where there ispoetry there is variation; where there is no variationthere is no poetry. Consider the opening scene betweenBornwell and his wife in The Lady of Pleasure.The theme can be stated in a few words. A husbandrebukes his wife for extravagance and is obstinatelyanswered. A real dramatist would have found in
176 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSthis matter for as many pages as Shirley; but thosepages would have been occupied by the developmentin dialogue of the emotional situation betweenthe two characters. Every speech would have leftthem related to each other in a slightly new way.On the other hand a pure poet, of the constructivetype, would have given us in some few unforgettablewords an image clearer than life of the essentialquality of luxury and extravagance. We should haveseen once and for all what prodigality in all itswasteful beauty means to the imagination. A singleline might do it, such as Clytemnestra'sWho shall quench all the purple of the sea?A writer who was both a poet and a dramatist wouldhave given us both together. Every speech wouldhave added a new quality to the relation of thespeakers and at the same time would have donewhat Aeschylus docs. Shirley's method is differentfrom cither. On the strictly dramatic side he hasnothing to say that could not have been said in sixlines. 'Why are you angry?'asks Born well. 'Becauseyou stint me,' retorts the lady. 'I don't. On thecontrary I allow you to spend far too much,' saysBornwell. 'Well, I still think you're mean,' says LadyBornwcll. That is the whole scene, as drama. Whatswells it to its 130 odd lines is pure variation on thetheme 'you spend too much' put into the mouth ofBornwell. During this the dramatic situation standsstill. 'Have you done, Sir?' Lady Bornwell asks at theend of her husband's first speech; at the end of histhird she is still asking, 'Have you concluded your
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 177lecture?' The angry husband and the scornful wiferemain dramatically immobile and the play ceasesto go forward while the waves of variation roll overthe audience. In other words, what Shirley has hereto say as a dramatist is extremely little; and to convertthat little into something that should seem richer hehas to call in variation. The variation consists, ofcourse, simply of an endless string of examples of thelady's extravagance—'this Italian master and thatDutchman', 'superfluous plate', Vanities of tires','petticoats and pearls'. There is no reason why anyone image should stand where it docs rather thanelsewhere. There is no reason why the thing shouldstop where it does: you might just as well turn thetap off twenty lines sooner or twenty lines later.Nor does the beauty of the separate items recompenseus (as it would in Marlowe) for their lack of definitetendency. The best that such writing can do is togive us a vague impression of an angry man who hasa great deal to say; but it docs this only by makinghim as tedious as he would be in real life. No methodcould be easier for the writer; any one who can scana verse and has a memory well stored can producesuch work ad libitum. And as if this were not enoughthe scene between Bornwell and his wife is followedalmost immediately by the similar scene betweenCelestina and her steward. Here, once again, thetheme is extravagance opposed to frugality; onceagain the dramatic development, such as it is, couldbe shown in a few lines; all the rest is variation. Inthe next act we have the arrival of Master Frederickand Lady Bornwell's disgust at his scholarly lack ofN
178 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSfashion. Here is a situation very recalcitrant topoetical treatment, but very tempting to a real comicdramatist. It would go admirably into a prosedialogue of short questions and replies. Everythingought to be on the move. We ought to see LadyBornwell's gradual discovery of her nephew's characterand opinions: the rift ought to widen at everyspeech, and at every speech the audience ought toperceive more exactly just what the rift is and howcomically exasperating. Instead of this, Shirley letsLady Bornwell grasp the whole truth, beyond hopeof error, and express her horror, in the very first line,'Support me, I shall faint'. The suddenness of thisis not without its comic effect; but it is dearly purchasedat the price of the following scene, in which,dramatically speaking, there is nothing left to do.The chasm is filled up as usual by the handy rubbleof variation. Lady Bornwell's long speech is merelya string of variations on the theme 'I wish he wereFrench and fashionable instead of studious and parsonical',which is itself only an unprogrcssive amplificationof the opening words 'I shall faint'. AndFrederick replies :Madam, with your pardon, you have practisedAnother dialect than was taught me whenI was commended to your care and breeding.I understand not this. Latin or GreekAre more familiar to my apprehension.Logic was not so hard in my first lecturesAs your strange language.The whole speech is variation; and even the themewhich it varies, namely the theme 'My ways are
VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RS 179not your ways' has already been given in theopening lines of the scene. Frederick's speech merelyrestates the opposition between the two characters;it docs not show us that opposition alive and growing;it adds new colours to it rhetorically, not dramatically.Shirley's method is the precise opposite of thetrue comic method. Shirley gives us endless changeof language and leaves us exactly where we were;Molièrc, on the other hand, can take the very samewords—as he takes the misanthrope's 'Je ne dis pascela' in his scene with the poet—and use them overand over again and yet, at each repetition, givethem a new force. The repetition is part of the progression; it is not the same thing for the poet to berelentlessly shut up by the words 'je ne dis pas cela'the first time as it is the second time. The funninessconsists in his bobbing up irrestibly after eachsuppression, only to be suppressed again. 1 Theidentical phrase develops a new vis comica in eachnew context. If Shirley had been writing GeorgeDandin he would have taken the theme 'vous l'avczvoulu', variated it into thirty lines of creaking blankverse, put it into the mouth of the husband (probablyas the opening speech of the play) and then,for the remaining five acts, would have turnedround and round on the same spot like a dog thatcannot make up its mind to lie down.The dangers of variation have, perhaps, as muchto do with the decay of the 'Elizabethan' theatreas any other internal cause, and its capabilities,as I have suggested, may be one of the principal1 Of., of course, Bergson's analysis of this scene in Le Rire.
180 VARIATION IN SHAKESPEARE AND O<strong>THE</strong>RSconditions of Shakespeare's peculiar greatness. I donot, however, believe that Shakespeare consciouslyselected the method as a means to that combinationof the dramatic and the poetic in which its greatestpotential virtue lies. His own early use of it is purelyornamental, and this suggests that he began byaccepting it from tradition without much reflection.Its origins, so far as I know, have not been fullyexamined. I suppose them to lie in Medieval Latinliterature of the rhetorical type. A new study ofthat literature with special reference to its influenceon the vernacular poets of what is called the 'Renaissance',and a determined inquiry into the channelsby which that influence reached them, would be avery useful work.
IXCHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURECLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA, Protrepticos, I.The Divine Word, not with harp and lyre, but rather tuningas His instrument, by the Holy Spirit, this whole world andthe little world of man, both soul and body, makes musicbefore God. A sweet and lively instrument Our Lord makesof man, and one like Himself: for certainly He also is God'sinstrument of music, all-harmonious.A pealOf laughter, all the angels crying Ton!Here is a fellow calls himself I.CHARLES WILLIAMSRead to a religious society at Oxford
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREWHEN I was asked to address this society, Iwas at first tempted to refuse because the subjectproposed to me, that of Christianity and Literature,did not seem to admit of any discussion. Iknew, of course, that Christian story and sentimentwere among the things on which literature couldbe written, and, conversely, that literature was oneof the ways in which Christian sentiment could beexpressed and Christian story told; but there seemednothing more to be said of Christianity in this connexionthan of any of the hundred and one otherthings that men made books about. We are familiar,no doubt, with the expression 'Christian Art', bywhich people usually mean Art that represents Biblicalor hagiological scenes, and there is, in this sense, afair amount of 'Christian Literature'. But I questionwhether it has any literary qualities peculiar to itself.The rules for writing a good passion play or a gooddevotional lyric are simply the rules for writingtragedy or lyric in general: success in sacred literaturedepends on the same qualities of structure, suspense,variety, diction, and the like which secure success insecular literature. And if we enlarge the idea ofChristian Literature to include not only literature onsacred themes but all that is written by Christians forChristians to read, then, I think, Christian Literaturecan exist only in the same sense in which Christiancookery might exist. It would be possible, and itmight be edifying, to write a Christian cookery book.Such a book would exclude dishes whose preparation
184 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREinvolves unnecessary human labour or animal suffering,and dishes excessively luxurious. That is to say, itschoice of dishes would be Christian. But there couldbe nothing specifically Christian about the actualcooking of the dishes included. Boiling an egg is thesame process whether you arc a Christian or a Pagan.In the same way, literature written by Christiansfor Christians would have to avoid mendacity,cruelty, blasphemy, pornography, and the like, andit would aim at edification in so far as edificationwas proper to the kind of work in hand. But whateverit chose to do would have to be done by themeans common to all literature; it could succeed orfail only by the same excellences and the same faultsas all literature; and its literary success or failurewould never be the same thing as its obedience ordisobedience to Christian principles.I have been speaking so far of Christian Literatureproprement dite—that is, of writing which is intendedto affect us as literature, by its appeal to imagination.But in the visible arts I think we can make a distinctionbetween sacred art, however sacred in theme,and pure iconography—between that which is intended,in the first instance, to affect the imaginationand the aesthetic appetite, and that which is meantmerely as the starting-point for devotion and meditation.If I were treating the visible arts I shouldhave to work out here a full distinction of the workof art from the icon on the one hand and the toy onthe other. The icon and the toy have this in commonthat their value depends very little on their perfectionas artefacts—a shapeless rag may give as much
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 185pleasure as the costliest doll, and two sticks tiedcrosswise may kindle as much devotion as the workof Leonardo. And to make matters more complicatedthe very same object could often be used in allthree ways. But I do not think the icon and the workof art can be so sharply distinguished in literature.I question whether the badness of a really bad hymncan ordinarily be so irrelevant to devotion as thebadness of a bad devotional picture. Because thehymn uses words, its badness will, to some degree,consist in confused or erroneous thought and unworthysentiment. But I mention this difficult questionhere only to say that I do not propose to treatit. If any literary works exist which have a purelyiconographic value and no literary value, they arcnot what I am talking about. Indeed I could not, forI have not met them.Of Christian Literature, then, in the sense of 'workaiming at literary value and written by Christiansfor Christians', you see that I have really nothing tosay and believe that nothing can be said. But I thinkI have something to say about what may be calledthe Christian approach to literature: about theprinciples, if you will, of Christian literary theory andcriticism. For while I was thinking over the subjectyou gave me I made what seemed to me a discovery.It is not an easy one to put into words. The nearestI can come to it is to say that I found a disquietingcontrast between the whole circle of ideas used inmodern criticism and certain ideas recurrent in theNew Testament. Let me say at once that it is hardlya question of logical contradiction between clearly
186 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREdefined concepts. It is too vague for that. It is morea repugnance of atmospheres, a discordance of notes,an incompatibility of temperaments.What are the key-words of modern criticism?Creative, with its opposite derivative; spontaneity, withits opposite convention; freedom, contrasted with rules.Great authors are innovators, pioneers, explorers;bad authors bunch in schools and follow models. Oragain, great authors are always 'breaking fetters' andc bursting bonds'. They have personality, they 'arethemselves'. I do not know whether we often thinkout the implication of such language into a consistentphilosophy; but we certainly have a general picture ofbad work flowing from conformity and discipleship,and of good work bursting out from certain centres ofexplosive force—apparently self-originating force—which we call men of genius.Now the New Testament has nothing at all to tellus of literature. I know that there are some who liketo think of Our Lord Himself as a poet and cite theparables to support their view. I admit freely thatto believe in the Incarnation at all is to believe thatevery mode of human excellence is implicit in Hishistorical human character: poethood, of course, included.But if all had been developed, the limitationsof a single human life would have been transcendedand He would not have been a man; therefore allexcellences save the spiritual remained in varyingdegrees implicit. If it is claimed that the poeticexcellence is more developed than others—say, theintellectual—I think I deny the claim. Some of theparables do work like poetic similes; but then others
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 187work like philosophic illustrations. Thus the UnjustJudge is not emotionally or imaginatively like God:he corresponds to God as the terms in a proportioncorrespond, because he is to the Widow (in one highlyspecialized respect) as God is to man. In that parableOur Lord, if we may so express it, is much more likeSocrates than Shakespeare. And I dread an overemphasison the poetical element in His words becauseI think it tends to obscure that quality in Hishuman character which is, in fact, so visible in Hisirony, His argumenta ad homines, and His use of thea fortiori, and which I would call the homely, peasantshrewdness. Donne points out that we are never toldHe laughed; it is difficult in reading the Gospels notto believe, and to tremble in believing, that Hesmiled.I repeat, the New Testament has nothing to sayof literature; but what it says on other subjects isquite sufficient to strike that note which I find outof tune with the language of modern criticism. Imust begin with something that is unpopular. St.Paul tells us (1 Cor. xi. 3) that man is the 'head' ofwoman. We may soften this if we like by saying thathe means only man qua man and woman qua womanand that an equality of the sexes as citizens or intellectualbeings is not therefore absolutely repugnantto his thought: indeed, that he himself tells us thatin another respect, that is 'in the Lord', the sexescannot be thus separated (ibid. v. 11). But whatconcerns me here is to find out what he means byHead. Now in verse 3 he has given us a very remarkableproportion sum: that God is to Christ as
188 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREChrist is to man and man is to woman, and the relationbetween each term and the next is that of Head.And in verse 7 we arc told that man is God's imageand glory, and woman is man's glory. He does notrepeat 'image', but I question whether the omission isintentional, and I suggest that we shall have a fairlyPauline picture of this whole scries of Head relationsrunning from God to woman if we picture each termas the 'image and glory' of the preceding term. AndI suppose that of which one is the image and gloryis that which one glorifies by copying or imitating.Let me once again insist that I am not trying to twistSt. Paul's metaphors into a logical system. I knowwell that whatever picture he is building up, he himselfwill be the first to throw it aside when it hasserved its turn and to adopt some quite differentpicture when some new aspect of the truth is presentto his mind. But I want to see clearly the sort ofpicture implied in this passage—to get it clearhowever temporary its use or partial its application.And it seems to me a quite clear picture; we are tothink of some original divine virtue passing downwardsfrom rung to rung of a hierarchical ladder,and the mode in which each lower rung receives itis, quite frankly, imitation.What is perhaps most startling in this picture'isthe apparent equivalence of the woman-man andman-God relation with the relation between Christand God, or, in Trinitarian language, with therelation between the First and Second Persons of theTrinity. As a layman and a comparatively recentlyreclaimed apostate I have, of course, no intention
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 189of building a theological system—still less of settingup a catena of New Testament metaphors as a criticismon the Nicene or the Athanasian creed, documentswhich I wholly accept. But it is legitimate tonotice what kinds of metaphor the New Testamentuses; more especially when what we arc in search ofis not dogma but a kind of flavour or atmosphere.And there is no doubt that this kind of proportionsum—A: B: : B: C—is quite freely used in the NewTestament where A and B represent the First andSecond Persons of the Trinity. Thus St. Paul hasalready told us earlier in the same epistle that we arc'of Christ 5 and Christ is 'of God' (iii. 23). Thusagain in the Fourth Gospel, Our Lord Himself comparesthe relation of the Father to the Son with thatof the Son to His flock, in respect of knowledge (x. 15)and of love (xv. 9).I suggest, therefore, that this picture of a hierarchicalorder in which we are encouraged—though,of course, only from certain points of view and incertain respects—to regard the Second Person Himselfas a step, or stage, or degree, is wholly in accordwith the spirit of the New Testament. And if we askhow the stages are connected the answer always seemsto be something like imitation, reflection, assimilation.Thus in Gal. iv. 19 Christ is to be 'formed' insideeach believer—the verb here used meaningto shape, to figure, or even to draw a sketch. In FirstThessalonians (i. 6) Christians arc told to imitateSt. Paul and the Lord, and elsewhere (1 Cor. x. 33)to imitate St. Paul as he in his turn imitates Christ—thus giving us another stage of progressive imitation.
190 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREChanging the metaphor we find that believers are toacquire the fragrance of Christ, redolere Christum (2Cor. ii. 16): that the glory of God has appeared in theface of Christ as, at the creation, light appeared inthe universe (2 Cor. iv. 6); and, finally, if my readingof a much disputed passage is correct, that a Christianis to Christ as a mirror to an object (2 Cor. iii. 18).These passages, you will notice, arc all Pauline; butthere is a place in the Fourth Gospel which goes muchfarther—so far that if it were not a Dominical utterancewe would not venture to think along such lines.There (v. 19) we arc told that the Son does only whatHe sees the Father doing. He watches the Father'soperations and docs the sameor 'copies'.The Father, because of His love for the Son, showsHim all that He docs. I have already explained thatI am not a theologian. What aspect of the Trinitarianreality Our Lord, as God, saw while He spokethese words, I do not venture to define; but I thinkwe have a right and even a duty to notice carefullythe earthly image by which He expressed it—to seeclearly the picture He puts before us. It is a pictureof a boy learning to do things by watching a man atwork. I think we may even guess what memory,humanly speaking, was in His mind. It is hard notto imagine that He remembered His boyhood, thatHe saw Himself as a boy in a carpenter's shop, a boylearning how to do things by watching while St.Joseph did them. So taken, the passage does notseem to me to conflict with anything I have learnedfrom the creeds, but greatly to enrich my conceptionof the Divine sonship.
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 191Now it may be that there is no absolute logicalcontradiction between the passages I have quotedand the assumptions of modern criticism: but I thinkthere is so great a difference of temper that a manwhose mind was at one with the mind of the NewTestament would not, and indeed could not, fall intothe language which most critics now adopt. In theNew Testament the art of life itself is an art of imitation:can we, believing this, believe that literature,which must derive from real life, is to aim at being'creative', 'original', and 'spontaneous'. 'Originality'in the New Testament is quite plainly the prerogativeof God alone; even within the triune being of God itseems to be confined to the Father. The duty andhappiness of every other being is placed in beingderivative, in reflecting like a mirror. Nothing couldbe more foreign to the tone of scripture than thelanguage of those who describe a saint as a 'moralgenius' or a 'spiritual genius' thus insinuating thathis virtue or spirituality is 'creative' or 'original'.If I have read the New Testament aright, it leaves noroom for 'crcativeness' even in a modified or metaphoricalsense. Our whole destiny seems to lie in theopposite direction, in being as little as possible ourselves,in acquiring a fragrance that is not our ownbut borrowed, in becoming clean mirrors filled withthe image of a face that is not ours. I am not heresupporting the doctrine of total depravity, and I donot say that the New Testament supports it; I am sayingonly that the highest good of a creature must becreaturely—that is, derivative or reflective—good. Inother words, as St. Augustine makes plain (De. Civ.
192 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREDei xii, cap i), pride does not only go before afall but is a fall—a fall of the creature's attentionfrom what is better, God, to what is worse, itself.Applying this principle to literature, in its greatestgenerality, we should get as the basis of all criticaltheory the maxim that an author should never conceivehimself as bringing into existence beauty orwisdom which did not exist before, but simply andsolely as trying to embody in terms of his own artsome reflection of eternal Beauty and Wisdom. Ourcriticism would therefore from the beginning groupitself with some existing theories of poetry againstothers. It would have affinities with the primitiveor <strong>Home</strong>ric theory in which the poet is the merepensioner of the Muse. It would have affinities withthe Platonic doctrine of a transcendent Form partlyimitablc on earth; and remoter affinities with theAristotelian doctrine of and the Augustandoctrine about the imitation of Nature and theAncients. It would be opposed to the theory ofgenius as, perhaps, generally understood; and aboveall it would be opposed to the idea that literatureis self-expression.But here some distinctions must be made. I spokejust now of the ancient idea that the poet was merelythe servant of some god, of Apollo, or the Muse; butlet us not forget the highly paradoxical words inwhich <strong>Home</strong>r's Phemius asserts his claim to be apoet—(Od. xxii. 347.)'I am self-taught; a god has inspired me with all
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 193manner of songs. 5 It sounds like a direct contradiction.How can he be self-taught if the god hastaught him all he knows? Doubtless because thegod's instruction is given internally, not through thesenses, and is therefore regarded as part of the Self,to be contrasted with such external aids as, say, theexample of other poets, And this seems to blur thedistinction I am trying to draw between Christianimitation and the 'originality' praised by moderncritics. Phemius obviously claims to be original, inthe sense of being no other poet's disciple, and in thesame breath admits his complete dependence on asupernatural teacher. Does not this let in 'originality'and 'creativeness' of the only kind that haveever been claimed?If you said 'the only kind that ought to have beenclaimed', I would agree; but as things arc, I thinkthe distinction remains, though it becomes finer thanour first glance suggested. A Christian and an unbelievingpoet may both be equally original in thesense that they neglect the example of their poeticforbears and draw on resources peculiar to themselves,but with this difference. The unbeliever maytake his own temperament and experience, just asthey happen to stand, and consider them worth communicatingsimply because they are facts or, worsestill, because they are his. To the Christian his owntemperament and experience, as mere fact, and asmerely his, are of no value or importance whatsoever: he will deal with them, if at all, only becausethey are the medium through which, or the positionfrom which, something universally profitableo
194 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATUREappeared to him. We can imagine two men seatedin different parts of a church or theatre. Both, whenthey come out, may tell us their experiences, andboth may use the first person. But the one is interestedin his scat only because it was his—'I was most uncomfortable,'he will say. 'You would hardly believe,what a draught comes in from the door in thatcorner. And the people! I had to speak prettysharply to the woman in front of me.' The otherwill tell us what could be seen from his scat, choosingto describe this because this is what he knows, andbecause every scat must give the best view of something.'Do you know', he will begin, 'the moulding onthose pillars goes on round at the back. It looks, too,as if the design on the back were the older of the two.'Here we have the expressionist and the Christianattitudes towards the self or temperament. Thus St.Augustine and Rousseau both write Confessions; butto the one his own temperament is a kind of absolute(au moins je suis autre), to the other it is 'a narrowhouse, too narrow for Thee to enter—oh make itwide. It is in ruins—oh rebuild it.' And Wordsworth,the romantic who made a good end, has a foot incither world and though he practises both, distinguisheswell the two ways in which a man may besaid to write about himself. On the one hand he says:I must tread on shadowy ground, must sinkDeep, and aloft ascending breathe in worldsTo which the heaven of heavens is but a veil.On the other he craves indulgence ifwith thisI mix more lowly mutter; with the thing
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 195Contemplated, describe the Mind and ManContemplating; and who and what he was—The transitory being that beheldThis vision.In this sense, then, the Christian writer may be•self-taught or original. He may base his work on the'transitory being' that he is, not because he thinksit valuable (for he knows that in his flesh dwells nogood thing), but solely because of the 'vision' thatappeared to it. But he will have no preference fordoing this. He will do it if it happens to be the thinghe can do best; but if his talents are such that hecan produce good work by writing in an establishedform and dealing with experiences common to allhis race, he will do so just as gladly. I even think hewill do so more gladly. It is to him an argumentnot of strength but of weakness that he should respondfully to the vision only 'in his own way'. Andalways, of every idea and of every method he will asknot 'Is it mine?', but 'Is it good?'This seems to me the most fundamental differencebetween the Christian and the unbeliever in theirapproach to literature. But I think there is another.The Christian will take literature a little less seriouslythan the cultured Pagan: he will feel less uneasy witha purely hedonistic standard for at least many kindsof work. The unbeliever is always apt to make a kindof religion of his aesthetic experiences; he feelsethically irresponsible, perhaps, but he braces hisstrength to receive- responsibilities of another kindwhich seem to the Christian quite illusory. He hasto be 'creative'; he has to obey a mystical amoral02
196 CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURElaw called his artistic conscience; and he commonlywishes to maintain his superiority to the great massof mankind who turn to books for mere recreation.But the Christian knows from the outset that thesalvation of a single soul is more important than theproduction or preservation of all the epics andtragedies in the world: and as for superiority, heknows that the vulgar since they include most of thepoor probably include most of his superiors. He hasno objection to comedies that merely amuse andtales that merely refresh; for he thinks like ThomasAquinas ipsa ratio hoc habet ut quandoque rationis ususintercipiatur. We can play, as we can cat, to the gloryof God. It thus may come about that Christianviews on literature will strike the world as shallowand flippant; but the world must not misunderstand.When Christian work is done on a serioussubject there is no gravity and no sublimity it cannotattain. But they will belong to the theme. That iswhy they will be real and lasting—mighty nounswith which literature, an adjectival thing, is hereunited, far over-topping the fussy and ridiculousclaims of literature that tries to be important simplyas literature. And a posteriori it is not hard to arguethat all the greatest poems have been made by menwho valued something else much more than poetryevenif that something else were only cutting downenemies in a cattle-raid or tumbling a girl in a bed.The real frivolity, the solemn vacuity, is all withthose who make literature a self-existent thing to bevalued for its own sake. Pater prepared for pleasureas if it were martyrdom. 0
CHRISTIANITY AND LITERATURE 197Now that I see where I have arrived a doubtassails me. It all sounds suspiciously like things I havesaid before, starting from very different premisses.Is it King Charles's Head? Have I mistaken for the'vision' the same old 'transitory being' who, in someways, is not nearly transitory enough? It may be so:or I may, after all, be right. I would rather be rightif I could; but if not, if I have only been once morefollowing my own footprints, it is the sort of tragicomedywhich, on my own principles, I must try toenjoy. I find a beautiful example proposed in theParadiso (xxvIII) where poor Pope Gregory, arrivedin Heaven, discovered that his theory of the hierarchies,on which presumably he had taken pains,was quite wrong. We arc told how the redeemedsoul behaved; 'di sè medesmo rise'. It was the funniestthing he'd ever heard.
PRINTED INGREAT BRITAINAT <strong>THE</strong>UNIVERSITY PRESSOXFORDBYJOHN JOHNSONPRINTERTO <strong>THE</strong>UNIVERSITY