22.12.2012 Views

The Global Water Crisis: Addressing an Urgent Security - Unu-inweh ...

The Global Water Crisis: Addressing an Urgent Security - Unu-inweh ...

The Global Water Crisis: Addressing an Urgent Security - Unu-inweh ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

water per person per day. <strong>The</strong> applic<strong>an</strong>ts maintained that the policy breached Section 27 of the Constitution because 25<br />

litres of water was not sufficient for daily use. <strong>The</strong> trial court agreed, concluding that 50 litres of water per person per day<br />

was the proper amount. <strong>The</strong> appeal court reduced this figure to 42 litres. On final appeal, the Constitutional Court found<br />

that Section 27 did not require more free water th<strong>an</strong> the City’s policy provided, <strong>an</strong>d observed that the constitutional right<br />

to water did not require courts to take over tasks that in a democracy should properly be reserved for the democratic<br />

arms of government (Mazibuko, 2009: para. 161). Constitutional rights to water do not simply guar<strong>an</strong>tee that sufficient<br />

water will be provided to each person, but instead are subject to interpretations <strong>an</strong>d qualifications that me<strong>an</strong> that they<br />

are not as straightforward as they appear.<br />

2.5. Prioritizes regulation at the expense of individual legal rights<br />

Regulation has become the domin<strong>an</strong>t form of water govern<strong>an</strong>ce <strong>an</strong>d, ironically, constitutional water rights confirm state<br />

control of water. <strong>The</strong> hum<strong>an</strong> right to water in the South Afric<strong>an</strong> Constitution provides government with the discretion to<br />

develop policies <strong>an</strong>d allocate resources (Mazibuko, 2009: para. 50). Legislation typically authorizes officials to bal<strong>an</strong>ce<br />

competing interests, <strong>an</strong>d thereby to approve water pollution when its effects are judged to be less import<strong>an</strong>t that the<br />

benefits it produces. M<strong>an</strong>ufacturing facilities, farms, <strong>an</strong>d other private commercial enterprises may receive permission to<br />

extract large volumes of water <strong>an</strong>d to pollute even when the direct or cumulative effects are detrimental to water quality<br />

or qu<strong>an</strong>tity, because the benefits are deemed to outweigh these costs. Moreover, regulatory regimes create potential<br />

conflicts of interest when government installations such as sewage treatment facilities <strong>an</strong>d power pl<strong>an</strong>ts themselves pollute.<br />

<strong>The</strong> alternative to regulation is private legal rights, not of the ‘hum<strong>an</strong> rights’ variety. For example, in some common law<br />

jurisdictions such as in Ontario, C<strong>an</strong>ada, surface water is subject to the interests of ripari<strong>an</strong> l<strong>an</strong>downers, who possess<br />

certain rights to quality <strong>an</strong>d qu<strong>an</strong>tity which may be enforced against upstream owners (Young v. B<strong>an</strong>kier Distillery Comp<strong>an</strong>y,<br />

1893; McKie v. K.V.P. Co., 1948; Gauthier v. N<strong>an</strong>eff, 1971). Also, in some countries, accessing natural sources of water may<br />

be considered <strong>an</strong> incident of l<strong>an</strong>d rights. In Mosetlh<strong>an</strong>y<strong>an</strong>e <strong>an</strong>d Matsip<strong>an</strong>e v Attorney General of Botsw<strong>an</strong>a, the Botsw<strong>an</strong>a<br />

Court of Appeal recognized the right of Bushmen to use <strong>an</strong> old borehole to extract water for domestic purposes, overturning<br />

a government prohibition. <strong>The</strong> court found that the Bushmen had the right not to be interfered with on the l<strong>an</strong>ds that<br />

they rightfully occupied. <strong>The</strong>ir right to use the borehole did not consist of a right to be provided with water, or to have<br />

the government cover the expense of using the borehole. <strong>The</strong> case could be interpreted as a vindication of the concept<br />

of a hum<strong>an</strong> right to water, but that would not be <strong>an</strong> accurate reading of the judgement. Instead, the court states, “... the<br />

appell<strong>an</strong>ts as lawful occupiers of the l<strong>an</strong>d in question merely seek, at their own expense, permission to use water from<br />

a discarded existing borehole for domestic purposes...” (Mosetlh<strong>an</strong>y<strong>an</strong>e, 2011: para. 16).<br />

<strong>The</strong> success of private rights as a me<strong>an</strong>s to protect water resources depends in large measure on citizens’ access to <strong>an</strong><br />

independent judiciary, <strong>an</strong>d on whether their rights are displaced by legislation that creates regulatory regimes in their stead.<br />

2.6. Entrenches <strong>an</strong> ideology<br />

Hum<strong>an</strong> rights to be provided with water are less about water th<strong>an</strong> about ideology. <strong>The</strong>y do not protect water resources from<br />

pollution or depletion. <strong>The</strong>y do not preserve ecosystems or the operation of water cycles. Instead, they are declarations<br />

about who should pay the costs of providing water. <strong>The</strong> case for free water rests on the argument that water is essential<br />

to life, <strong>an</strong>d therefore it should not carry a cost. But providing water is costly, particularly in urb<strong>an</strong> areas – for regulating<br />

<strong>an</strong>d enforcing watershed protection, for treating polluted water, <strong>an</strong>d for infrastructure to deliver cle<strong>an</strong> water <strong>an</strong>d remove<br />

waste. A right to free water does not eliminate the cost of providing the water, but instead dem<strong>an</strong>ds that it be paid by<br />

others, such as through general taxes or fees on some other commodity or service. By so doing, a right to be supplied with<br />

water incorporates <strong>an</strong> ideology: water must be provided by government rather th<strong>an</strong> by private me<strong>an</strong>s (Bluemel, 2004),<br />

<strong>an</strong>d the costs of water systems c<strong>an</strong>not be borne by those who use them. Positive rights to water dem<strong>an</strong>d a socialized<br />

system of water provision, subsidized by some for the benefit of others. A constitutional provision of this nature removes<br />

the democratic right of citizens to determine the ideological premises of the water system they wish to run.<br />

‘Positive’ constitutional rights create entitlements governments must actively provide. Governments have <strong>an</strong> unlimited<br />

capacity to provide negative rights, since they require merely that citizens be left alone, while positive rights require<br />

governments to take from some to give to others (Cross, 2000-2001). Negative rights place limits on the state’s ability to<br />

False P<strong>an</strong>acea: <strong>The</strong> Hum<strong>an</strong> Right to <strong>Water</strong><br />

Part 3<br />

139

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!