24.04.2013 Views

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

The Judgment of Animals in Classical Greece: Animal Sculpture and ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Judgment</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>: <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Concept <strong>of</strong><br />

Lifelikeness<br />

by<br />

Evrydiki Tasopoulou<br />

A dissertation submitted <strong>in</strong> partial fulfillment <strong>of</strong> the requirements for the<br />

degree <strong>of</strong> Doctor <strong>of</strong> Philosophy <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>and</strong> Near Eastern Archaeology<br />

Bryn Mawr College<br />

2008


Abstract<br />

Studies <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek sculpture focus almost exclusively on representations <strong>of</strong><br />

the human form. Despite the considerable number <strong>of</strong> animal representations <strong>in</strong> this<br />

medium, animals are absent from the scholarly debate on art-historical topics, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the major issue <strong>of</strong> naturalism. This study addresses the connection between freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

animal funerary sculpture <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C. <strong>and</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalistic style. It exam<strong>in</strong>es ancient Greek texts from the fifth century B.C. to the sixth<br />

century A.D. that preserve evidence <strong>of</strong> animals as subjects <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong><br />

also as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. <strong>The</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong><br />

non-naturalistic features <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture has long been<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted as problematic because it deviates from the st<strong>and</strong>ard conception <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art as strictly imitative <strong>of</strong> the external world. This study<br />

demonstrates that <strong>Classical</strong> Attic funerary statues <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs show various<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic features that are directly shaped by<br />

contemporary ideas about the animals represented. Further, it emphasizes that the<br />

contradictory style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal funerary sculpture is the material<br />

embodiment <strong>of</strong> contemporary conflict<strong>in</strong>g ideas about animals that manifest themselves <strong>in</strong><br />

the literary record. <strong>Classical</strong> texts <strong>in</strong>dicate that contemporary Greek society was<br />

primarily anthropocentric <strong>and</strong> held a contradictory attitude to animals: on the one h<strong>and</strong>, it<br />

denigrated animals, but, on the other, allowed them to occupy a central position <strong>in</strong><br />

everyday life <strong>and</strong> thought. Additionally, this study <strong>of</strong> the judgment <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> focuses on contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage, which suggests a duality <strong>in</strong>


the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term zw|~on—usually taken to mean simply “animal,” but also “image”<br />

<strong>and</strong> “figure.” By exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g both textual <strong>and</strong> epigraphical evidence from the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period, it demonstrates that—when applied to the visual arts—zw|~on carries multiple<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs such as “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” <strong>and</strong> “figural image” that suggest its<br />

<strong>in</strong>clusion with<strong>in</strong> the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> art criticism <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. Representations <strong>of</strong><br />

animals thus <strong>of</strong>fer value to the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style by provid<strong>in</strong>g useful<br />

<strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek conception <strong>of</strong> this style.


Vita<br />

I was born <strong>in</strong> <strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, <strong>Greece</strong>. I received a Bachelor <strong>of</strong> Arts <strong>in</strong> Archaeology <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Studies from Wilson College <strong>in</strong> 1998. In 2001, I atta<strong>in</strong>ed a Master <strong>of</strong> Arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Near Eastern Archaeology from Bryn Mawr College.<br />

i


Table <strong>of</strong> Contents<br />

Acknowledgments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .vi<br />

Notes to the Reader . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .vii<br />

Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .1<br />

Chapter 1: <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Guides to the Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style <strong>in</strong> Greek Art<br />

1. Modern Attitudes <strong>and</strong> the Neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> Form <strong>in</strong> the Study <strong>of</strong> Greek Art . . . . . . . . 10<br />

a. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Valuable Subjects <strong>in</strong> the Visual Arts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10<br />

b. Scholarly Remarks on the Neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek Art . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14<br />

(<strong>in</strong> Particular <strong>Sculpture</strong>)<br />

2. Why Have Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> Been Neglected? . . . . . . . . .17<br />

3. Ancient Texts on Famous Artists <strong>and</strong> Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek Art . . . . . . .20<br />

4. <strong>The</strong> Study <strong>of</strong> Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28<br />

a. <strong>The</strong> Use <strong>of</strong> “Naturalism” <strong>and</strong> “Realism” <strong>in</strong> the Modern Study <strong>of</strong> Greek Art . . . . . . . 31<br />

b. Modern <strong>The</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> the Development <strong>of</strong> Greek Art <strong>in</strong> Terms <strong>of</strong> Naturalism . . . . . . . 39<br />

Emanuel Löwy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39<br />

Ernst H. Gombrich . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42<br />

John Boardman . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48<br />

William A. P. Childs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .53<br />

5. Not Naturalism <strong>and</strong> Realism. <strong>The</strong> Concept <strong>of</strong> Lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> Greek Art <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> . . 57<br />

a. Ancient Texts on Lifelikeness as a Quality <strong>of</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> . . . . 59<br />

b. Ancient Texts on <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Lifelike Images <strong>and</strong> Judges <strong>of</strong> Lifelike Art . . . . . . . . . .66<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Lifelike Images <strong>in</strong> Art . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67<br />

A. Myron’s Cow . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .67<br />

<strong>The</strong> Conventional Nature <strong>of</strong> the Praise <strong>of</strong> Lifelike Works <strong>of</strong> Art . . . . . . .68<br />

<strong>The</strong> Epigrams <strong>of</strong> Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .72<br />

<strong>The</strong> Statue Acts Fantastically . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73<br />

<strong>The</strong> Statue Acts Naturally . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .76<br />

<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> Herdsmen . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .79<br />

<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> a Calf . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82<br />

ii


<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> a Bull . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84<br />

B. <strong>The</strong> Ox <strong>of</strong> Apelles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 86<br />

C. Funerary Statues <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Judges <strong>of</strong> Lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Art . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .92<br />

Chapter 2: Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Phenomenon<br />

<strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style<br />

Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99<br />

1. Examples <strong>of</strong> the Scholarly Treatment <strong>of</strong> the Problematic Style <strong>of</strong> Representations . . . .100<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

a. <strong>The</strong> Case <strong>of</strong> the Lion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .100<br />

<strong>The</strong> Possibility <strong>of</strong> Influence from Bronze Age Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> . . . 107<br />

Naturalism as Anatomical Accuracy: Two Near-Eastern Types <strong>of</strong> Lions on . . .109<br />

Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian Pottery (<strong>and</strong> Contemporary <strong>Sculpture</strong>)<br />

Literary Evidence for the Availability <strong>of</strong> Lions <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> . . . . . . . . . 111<br />

b. <strong>The</strong> Case <strong>of</strong> the Dog . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .117<br />

2. Two Case Studies: <strong>The</strong> Lion <strong>and</strong> the Dog from the Kerameikos . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125<br />

a. How are <strong>The</strong>se <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Different from Composite <strong>Animal</strong> Figures? . . . . . . . . . . . .125<br />

b. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Question <strong>of</strong> “What Is It Really Represented?” . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126<br />

<strong>The</strong> Lion from the Prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos . . . . . 127<br />

<strong>The</strong> Motif <strong>of</strong> the Lion Hold<strong>in</strong>g the Head <strong>of</strong> Its Prey <strong>in</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . 129<br />

Fourth-Century Attic <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Homer<br />

Anatomy <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos Lion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .131<br />

<strong>The</strong> Dog from the Prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos . . 139<br />

<strong>The</strong> Anatomy <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos Dog . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141<br />

Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .148<br />

Chapter 3: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Contradictory Attitude toward the Dog<br />

Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 151<br />

Section 1<br />

a. Dogs Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the House . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .153<br />

b. Dogs as Guardians <strong>of</strong> the House . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .158<br />

c. Molossian Dogs as Guardians <strong>of</strong> the House: <strong>The</strong>ir Ferocity <strong>and</strong> Value . . . . . . . . . . .169<br />

iii


Section 2<br />

a. Dogs Steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Gobbl<strong>in</strong>g Food . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175<br />

b. Punishment <strong>of</strong> Dogs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 182<br />

c. Food for Dogs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .183<br />

d. Dogs as Scavengers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 189<br />

e. <strong>The</strong> Savage Nature <strong>of</strong> Dogs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193<br />

Section 3<br />

Dogs as Food . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 196<br />

a. Post-<strong>Classical</strong> Attitudes to the Practice <strong>of</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g Dogs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .196<br />

b. Dogs as Food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .200<br />

Comedy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .200<br />

Hippocratic Treatises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 205<br />

<strong>The</strong> Properties <strong>of</strong> Dog Flesh . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .206<br />

<strong>The</strong> Flesh <strong>of</strong> Adult Dogs as Dietary Treatment for Certa<strong>in</strong> Diseases . . . . . . . . .209<br />

1. Erysipelas <strong>of</strong> Lungs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .209<br />

2. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Spleen . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 210<br />

<strong>The</strong> Flesh <strong>of</strong> Puppies as Dietary Treatment for Certa<strong>in</strong> Diseases . . . . . . . . . . . 210<br />

1. Pleurisy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .210<br />

2. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Back . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .211<br />

3. Tubercles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .211<br />

4. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Liver . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 212<br />

5. Gynecological Diseases . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 212<br />

6. Non-Hyperthermic Patients . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213<br />

7. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Kidneys . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .214<br />

Dog Flesh as Non-Indicated Dietary Treatment. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214<br />

Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 215<br />

Chapter 4: <strong>The</strong> Word Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Context <strong>of</strong> the Visual Arts <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong><br />

Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 218<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> Etymology <strong>of</strong> Zw|~on . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 219<br />

2. Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century B.C. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .222<br />

A. Literary Texts<br />

iv


Empedocles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .222<br />

Herodotus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229<br />

a. Zw|~a on Clothes from the Caucasus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229<br />

b. Egyptians: <strong>The</strong> First to Carve Zw|~a on Stones . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .235<br />

c. Zw|~a on Khufu’s Causeway . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . .239<br />

d. Zw|~a on a Pyramid . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 247<br />

e. Zw|~a on the Breastplate <strong>of</strong> Amasis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .253<br />

f. <strong>The</strong> Zw|~on Set-Up by Darius . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . 256<br />

g. <strong>The</strong> Zw|~a <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .263<br />

h. Zw|&dia on a Bronze Krater . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .268<br />

B. Inscriptions<br />

Erechtheion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .276<br />

3. Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Fourth Century B.C. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .294<br />

Plato . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 294<br />

Alcidamas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .312<br />

Aristotle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 316<br />

Philemon . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .324<br />

Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .327<br />

Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .329<br />

Appendix: Testimonia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .337<br />

Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .420<br />

List <strong>of</strong> Figures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 452<br />

Figures<br />

v


Acknowledgements<br />

First <strong>and</strong> foremost, I would like to thank my advisor, A. A. Donohue, for her guidance,<br />

support, patience, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cisive criticism, all <strong>of</strong> which made this dissertation possible. In<br />

addition, I am grateful to the Whit<strong>in</strong>g Foundation for generously fund<strong>in</strong>g my research. F<strong>in</strong>ally, I<br />

owe many thanks to my family <strong>and</strong> friends for their support throughout this process, especially<br />

my husb<strong>and</strong>, Derek Stevens, whose help, patience, <strong>and</strong> good humor were <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>in</strong> the<br />

completion <strong>of</strong> this dissertation.<br />

vi


Notes to the Reader<br />

Numbers <strong>in</strong> brackets <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> boldface <strong>in</strong>dicate references to the literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical<br />

testimonia <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the appendix to this work.<br />

Journal abbreviations follow AJA 104 (2000) 3-24. Abbreviations regard<strong>in</strong>g ancient authors <strong>and</strong><br />

their works follow H. G. Liddell <strong>and</strong> R. Scott, rev. H. S. Jones <strong>and</strong> R. McKenzie, A Greek-<br />

English Lexicon with a Revised Supplement (new n<strong>in</strong>th ed.; Oxford, 1940; repr., 1996; here LSJ 9 )<br />

xvi-xxxviii <strong>and</strong> S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford <strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary (third<br />

ed.; Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) xxix-liv.<br />

vii


Introduction<br />

It is generally thought that the style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek sculpture is problematic because it exhibits a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> contradictory or<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistent traits, specifically naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements. Trudy Kawami<br />

illustrates the idea <strong>in</strong> her discussion <strong>of</strong> a fourth-century B.C. statue <strong>of</strong> a dog found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Athenian Kerameikos (Fig. 1):<br />

This “Hound <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos”…has…powerful, naturalistic forms, heavy<br />

shoulders, thick legs <strong>and</strong> large paws [but it also exhibits] subtle leon<strong>in</strong>e qualities,<br />

[such as] the heavy compact chest, the well-sprung, almost barrel-like rib cage,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the carefully modeled toes with claws….<strong>The</strong> Kerameikos hound is lion-like. 1<br />

<strong>The</strong> contradiction <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos dog does not accord well with<br />

the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalistic style, which, as the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

art <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C., is generally known for its adherence to a strict<br />

imitation <strong>of</strong> the external world. <strong>The</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> oppos<strong>in</strong>g, can<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

stylistic elements <strong>in</strong> this statue has been expla<strong>in</strong>ed as a reflection <strong>of</strong> “the common<br />

apotropaic functions <strong>of</strong> the two species <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> both the Aegean <strong>and</strong> the Near<br />

East.” 2 Other discussions <strong>of</strong> the problematic style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture<br />

have <strong>in</strong>terpreted this phenomenon <strong>in</strong> fundamentally negative terms: as the result <strong>of</strong><br />

artists’ <strong>in</strong>ability, misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, or failure to depict animal anatomy accurately, lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> real models, <strong>and</strong> also as a mix <strong>of</strong> artists’ copy<strong>in</strong>g from Near Eastern <strong>and</strong> Bronze Age<br />

animal models <strong>and</strong> observ<strong>in</strong>g only such comparable animals as were available.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se <strong>in</strong>terpretations do not take <strong>in</strong>to account the conceptual context <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek culture, <strong>of</strong> which these animal sculptures are the products. What is lack<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

1 T. S. Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste: Some <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s from Persepolis,” AJA 90 (1986) 262.<br />

2 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

1


therefore, from exist<strong>in</strong>g scholarship is a study that considers the problematic style <strong>of</strong><br />

these statues <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the contemporary attitude toward animals. Fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth-<br />

century texts reveal the existence <strong>of</strong> conflict<strong>in</strong>g ideas about animals <strong>in</strong> Greek society;<br />

they demonstrate that Greek culture was anthropocentric; on the one h<strong>and</strong> it denigrated<br />

animals, but, on the other, it elevated them to a prom<strong>in</strong>ent position <strong>in</strong> everyday life <strong>and</strong><br />

thought. <strong>The</strong>se conflict<strong>in</strong>g ideas about animals serve as the conceptual basis for the<br />

contradictory style <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> contemporary sculpture.<br />

In contrast, well established <strong>in</strong> the scholarship on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

style <strong>in</strong> Greek art is a number <strong>of</strong> theories that expla<strong>in</strong>s the emergence <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style<br />

<strong>in</strong> Greek art as a conscious attempt to reach absolute naturalism. <strong>The</strong> theories, for<br />

example, <strong>of</strong> Emanuel Löwy, Ernst Gombrich, <strong>and</strong> John Boardman, <strong>and</strong> the respective<br />

conceptions—psychological, historical, <strong>and</strong> technical—that shape them consider the goal<br />

<strong>of</strong> absolute naturalism the driv<strong>in</strong>g force beh<strong>in</strong>d the naturalistic development <strong>of</strong> Greek art.<br />

Boardman’s perceived l<strong>in</strong>k between the progression <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism, <strong>in</strong> particular<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> periods, <strong>and</strong> a parallel progress <strong>in</strong> artistic techniques <strong>and</strong><br />

materials cont<strong>in</strong>ues to hold a strong place <strong>in</strong> modern scholarship as a recent collection <strong>of</strong><br />

essays edited by Olga Palagia <strong>and</strong> entitled Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>: Function, Materials, <strong>and</strong><br />

Techniques <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Periods (2006) <strong>in</strong>dicates. <strong>The</strong> theories<br />

mentioned above do not consider the relation between the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

style <strong>in</strong> Greek art <strong>and</strong> the conceptual context <strong>in</strong> which this phenomenon was formed.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y focus on the human figure at the expense <strong>of</strong> the animal one. In addition, they go<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st literary evidence which shows that the ancient Greeks valued the lifelike quality<br />

2


<strong>of</strong> their art while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g awareness <strong>of</strong> its lifeless status. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> feature<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> ancient discussions <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style, <strong>in</strong> particular<br />

its lifelikeness, which is perceived as accurate representation <strong>and</strong> aliveness. Figures <strong>of</strong><br />

animals are regularly praised for their lifelike quality. When the view<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art<br />

is described, animals tell<strong>in</strong>gly appear as judges <strong>of</strong> their lifelike quality. In fact, when<br />

featur<strong>in</strong>g as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art, animals—as constituents <strong>of</strong> the natural world<br />

<strong>and</strong> separate from human cognition—suggest a specific attitude toward art itself: that it<br />

can surpass its own essence as an artificial construction <strong>and</strong>, consequently, be recognized<br />

as natural even by nature itself. It is clear, therefore, that animals <strong>of</strong>fer an <strong>in</strong>valuable<br />

<strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the judgment <strong>of</strong> representational art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, thus substantiat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Claude Levi-Strauss’s famous dictum (drawn from his structural analysis <strong>in</strong><br />

anthropology) that “animals are good to th<strong>in</strong>k with.” 3<br />

“<strong>The</strong> <strong>Judgment</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>: <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Concept <strong>of</strong> Lifelikeness” is an <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> the significant role <strong>of</strong> animals as guides to<br />

the Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style, <strong>in</strong> particular its lifelike<br />

quality. It explores the problematic style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

funerary sculpture <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the conceptual context <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C.<br />

that produced this style. It argues that the problematic, specifically contradictory, style <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal funerary sculpture is the material <strong>and</strong>, at the same time, visual<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> a contemporary contradictory attitude towards animals that is attested <strong>in</strong><br />

the literary record. <strong>The</strong> study is divided <strong>in</strong>to four chapters.<br />

3 C. Lévi-Strauss, tr. R. Needham, Totemism (London, 1969) 126.<br />

3


Chapter one, “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Guides to the Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek Art,” is concerned with the connection between animals <strong>and</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> Greek art. <strong>The</strong> aim is to establish the significant role <strong>of</strong> animals as<br />

guides to the ancient Greek view <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style, <strong>in</strong> particular its lifelike quality.<br />

<strong>The</strong> chapter beg<strong>in</strong>s with a discussion <strong>of</strong> ancient literary accounts <strong>of</strong> animals as notable<br />

subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art by <strong>Classical</strong> Greek artists, both sculptors <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters. It<br />

presents, next, an overview <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong> modern theories about <strong>and</strong> explanations <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> Greek art; it emphasizes that, <strong>in</strong> regards to this topic, modern<br />

scholarship has paid almost exclusive attention to the human form. <strong>The</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong><br />

this style has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted on the basis <strong>of</strong> the assumption that the ancient Greeks<br />

consciously strove to achieve absolute naturalism <strong>in</strong> artistic representations, a concept<br />

which has further been considered the impetus for the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art. Such<br />

explanation dismisses, however, literary evidence which shows that the ancient Greeks<br />

valued highly the lifelike quality <strong>of</strong> their art, while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a conscious<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its <strong>in</strong>animate status.<br />

In addition to this evidence, the chapter exam<strong>in</strong>es ancient texts rang<strong>in</strong>g from the<br />

fifth century B.C. to the sixth century A.D., which <strong>in</strong>dicate the significant role <strong>of</strong> animals<br />

<strong>in</strong> the ancient view <strong>of</strong> the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Greek art: first, representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art are judged for their lifelikeness, are experienced as if they were alive, <strong>and</strong><br />

lend fame to their creators; second, when works <strong>of</strong> art are viewed, animals judge the<br />

lifelike quality <strong>of</strong> these works, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g that art has surpassed its man-made status<br />

<strong>and</strong> is perceived as nature by even nature itself. In this way, animals emerge as reliable<br />

guides to the Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lifelike quality <strong>of</strong> representational art. <strong>The</strong><br />

4


connection between animals <strong>and</strong> lifelikeness that emerges from the ancient texts is<br />

entirely different from modern scholarly discussions which approach the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art only <strong>in</strong> connection with the human form.<br />

Chapter two, “Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Phenomenon <strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style,” exam<strong>in</strong>es the connection between Greek freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

funerary statues <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period <strong>and</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

style. <strong>The</strong> discussion approaches this connection through the specific case study <strong>of</strong> two<br />

such freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, funerary works dat<strong>in</strong>g to the fourth century B.C.—the statue <strong>of</strong> a lion<br />

from the grave prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from the grave prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai, also <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Kerameikos. Representations <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs abound <strong>in</strong> extant Greek animal funerary<br />

sculpture <strong>of</strong> the fourth century, with those <strong>of</strong> the lion outnumber<strong>in</strong>g by far those <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dog. Regardless <strong>of</strong> this imbalance—which may be <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> archaeological<br />

circumstances rather than <strong>of</strong> fourth-century reality—the picture that emerges from this<br />

evidence suggests that both the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog held an important position <strong>in</strong> the<br />

repertoire <strong>of</strong> contemporary Greek animal funerary sculpture, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g an equally<br />

important position <strong>in</strong> contemporary Greek thought. As noted above, it is a well-<br />

established idea <strong>of</strong> modern scholarship that representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture<br />

are problematic because they display a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic<br />

elements. Although true, this assertion does not consider the conceptual context <strong>in</strong> which<br />

these sculptures were made, especially contemporary ideas about the animals represented.<br />

<strong>The</strong> discussion focuses on the visual assessment <strong>of</strong> two funerary statues <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong><br />

5


light <strong>of</strong> these ideas. It suggests that the elements <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>and</strong> contradictory<br />

styles <strong>of</strong> these statues are directly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by contemporary ideas about the lion <strong>and</strong><br />

the dog, respectively. In this way, animals emerge as guides to the conceptual context<br />

that helped shape the elements <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture.<br />

<strong>The</strong> discussion also provides an overview <strong>of</strong> scholarly works that note the<br />

problematic style not only <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong>, but also <strong>of</strong> some Archaic, sculptures <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong><br />

dogs. <strong>The</strong>se works <strong>in</strong>terpret the problematic style <strong>of</strong> animal sculpture as the result <strong>of</strong> a<br />

lack <strong>of</strong> opportunity for artists to observe directly liv<strong>in</strong>g prototypes, <strong>of</strong> artists’ copy<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from Near Eastern animal art, <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> real animals, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tention to<br />

highlight the apotropaic significance <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog <strong>in</strong> Greek culture. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

treatments fail to recognize that <strong>Classical</strong> Greek, but also Archaic, sculptures <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong><br />

dogs susta<strong>in</strong> the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g elements as the underly<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> their<br />

style. In fact, these sculptures <strong>in</strong>dicate the existence <strong>of</strong> various types <strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong><br />

comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g differ<strong>in</strong>g—naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic—elements <strong>in</strong> their style:<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction. Further, by not<strong>in</strong>g that such comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

extends also to Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> the human form <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

sculpture, the discussion suggests that the <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g elements is the mental<br />

structure upon which the notion <strong>of</strong> style is built <strong>in</strong> Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art. In<br />

view <strong>of</strong> this evidence, <strong>and</strong> by draw<strong>in</strong>g also from the notion that the stylistic elements <strong>of</strong><br />

the Kerameikos lion <strong>and</strong> dog are shaped by contemporary ideas, the discussion suggests<br />

that the change <strong>in</strong> style from the Archaic to <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art could be seen not so<br />

much as a progression or improvement <strong>in</strong> artistic practice as a shift <strong>in</strong> the balance <strong>of</strong><br />

elements <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> turn, <strong>of</strong> the ideas that susta<strong>in</strong> the underly<strong>in</strong>g logic <strong>of</strong> style.<br />

6


Chapter three, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Contradictory Attitude toward the Dog,”<br />

focuses on the specific case study <strong>of</strong> the dog—the animal that features most prom<strong>in</strong>ently<br />

<strong>in</strong> the everyday life <strong>and</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, <strong>and</strong> thus serv<strong>in</strong>g as a representative<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the st<strong>and</strong>ard, contradictory <strong>Classical</strong> Greek attitude toward animals. <strong>The</strong><br />

discussion exam<strong>in</strong>es literary evidence which dates to the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C.<br />

<strong>and</strong> demonstrates the existence <strong>of</strong> an ambiguity <strong>in</strong> the collective conception <strong>of</strong> the dog.<br />

Although considered a typical <strong>in</strong>habitant <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek household who enjoyed<br />

free shelter <strong>and</strong> food, <strong>and</strong> a loyal guardian <strong>of</strong> the premises <strong>and</strong> human members <strong>of</strong> this<br />

household, the dog was also seen as a creature <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>satiable appetite, <strong>of</strong> unpredictable <strong>and</strong><br />

dangerous behavior, such as fawn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> scaveng<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> further suitable for<br />

consumption ow<strong>in</strong>g to the conceived therapeutic value <strong>of</strong> its flesh. It is clear, therefore,<br />

that the picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> that emerges from the literary record is that <strong>of</strong> a<br />

primarily anthropocentric culture, which, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, denigrates the dog, but, on the<br />

other, allows it to occupy a central position <strong>in</strong> everyday life <strong>and</strong> thought. This evidence<br />

suggests the existence <strong>of</strong> an analogical relationship between the contemporary<br />

contradictory attitude toward the dog <strong>and</strong> the contradictory style <strong>of</strong> the dog as evident <strong>in</strong><br />

contemporary sculpture. In this way, animals emerge as guides to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> the problematic style <strong>of</strong> representational art, specifically its contradictory<br />

model, as a direct consequence <strong>of</strong> contemporary conflict<strong>in</strong>g ideas about animals.<br />

Chapter four, “<strong>The</strong> Word Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Context <strong>of</strong> the Visual Arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>,” is concerned with the duality <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term zw|~on —usually taken<br />

to mean simply “animal,” <strong>and</strong> less <strong>of</strong>ten “plant <strong>and</strong> “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g.” It exam<strong>in</strong>es literary<br />

7


<strong>and</strong> epigraphic evidence that dates to the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C. <strong>and</strong> demonstrates<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> different mean<strong>in</strong>gs for the word zw|~on when used <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, sculpture, bronze-work, <strong>and</strong> textiles: “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation taken<br />

from real life,” “decorative element,” “figural work <strong>of</strong> art,” “f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> an<br />

artistic process,” <strong>and</strong> “image held by memory.” Given the multiple, nuanced mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong><br />

the term zw|~on with<strong>in</strong> such a dist<strong>in</strong>ct, artistic context the discussion suggests that zw|~on<br />

should be considered part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the visual arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. In this way, animals, once aga<strong>in</strong>, emerge as useful guides to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> representational art. Although not directly connected to the preced<strong>in</strong>g<br />

chapters, this chapter is conceptually l<strong>in</strong>ked to them <strong>in</strong> that, as a model, the semantic split<br />

<strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek term zw|~on appears to be ak<strong>in</strong> to the split <strong>in</strong>to different types <strong>and</strong><br />

degrees <strong>of</strong> deviation from naturalism that def<strong>in</strong>e the style <strong>of</strong> animal sculpture, <strong>and</strong> also to<br />

the split that def<strong>in</strong>es the contradictory <strong>Classical</strong> Greek attitude toward animals. This<br />

evidence suggests that along with structur<strong>in</strong>g the style <strong>of</strong> contemporary animal sculpture,<br />

<strong>and</strong> thought about animals, the idea <strong>of</strong> a split <strong>in</strong>to different parts also governs the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> the vocabulary about animals.<br />

This study <strong>of</strong> the judgment <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>and</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture stresses the primary significance <strong>of</strong> animals for ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

an <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the Greek conception <strong>of</strong> this style <strong>in</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C. It<br />

suggests a new paradigm for approach<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art as a notion,<br />

whose underly<strong>in</strong>g structure is a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistent, <strong>in</strong>congruous, <strong>and</strong><br />

contradictory traits, specifically naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements that are, <strong>in</strong><br />

8


turn, shaped by contemporary ideas about the represented subjects. <strong>The</strong>re is every<br />

reason, therefore, to th<strong>in</strong>k that the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art is <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> the notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> a development <strong>in</strong> artistic techniques <strong>and</strong> materials. Further, the study argues that the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> a clearly contradictory attitude toward animals comprised the conceptual<br />

model for the adoption <strong>of</strong> an equally contradictory style by contemporary animal<br />

sculpture. This adoption <strong>in</strong>dicates that the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek art was directly related to the conceptual context <strong>in</strong> which it was formulated.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, conflict<strong>in</strong>g ideas about animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek life are responsible for the<br />

contradictory style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> contemporary sculpture. <strong>The</strong><br />

adoption <strong>of</strong> contradiction not as an essentially negative feature but <strong>in</strong>stead as a model for<br />

both render<strong>in</strong>g animals <strong>in</strong> art <strong>and</strong> also th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about them <strong>in</strong> real life is not far removed,<br />

at least conceptually, from the existence <strong>of</strong> a duality <strong>in</strong> contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage<br />

which suggests that along with its usual mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “animal,” the word zw|~on was also a<br />

term <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts. Representations <strong>of</strong> animals thus <strong>of</strong>fer<br />

value to the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style by provid<strong>in</strong>g useful <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to the Greek<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> this style.<br />

9


Chapter 1: <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Guides to the Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style <strong>in</strong> Greek Art<br />

1. Modern Attitudes <strong>and</strong> the Neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> Form <strong>in</strong> the Study <strong>of</strong> Greek Art<br />

a. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Valuable Subjects <strong>in</strong> the Visual Arts<br />

While the human form has occupied a prom<strong>in</strong>ent position <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

Greek art, far less attention has been paid to representations <strong>of</strong> animals, which have<br />

therefore been almost absent from the scholarly debate on art-historical topics such as<br />

naturalism. <strong>The</strong> scholarly neglect accorded representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek art <strong>and</strong><br />

its connection with naturalism contrasts sharply with the statement <strong>of</strong> Johann Joachim<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann, <strong>in</strong> his History <strong>of</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Antiquity (1764)—the first modern historical<br />

treatise <strong>of</strong> ancient art—that representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Egyptian art, for example, are a<br />

key to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the approach <strong>of</strong> this culture to naturalism. 4 It also contrasts with the<br />

frequent treatment <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the visual arts <strong>of</strong> past non-classical societies as<br />

significant tools for <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g these societies, <strong>in</strong> particular, how they saw, <strong>in</strong>terpreted,<br />

used symbolically, observed, <strong>and</strong> rendered naturalistically animals <strong>in</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> depiction<br />

<strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> medieval manuscripts, for example, has been seen as a venue for<br />

reconstruct<strong>in</strong>g the complex relationship—physical, <strong>in</strong>tellectual, symbolical—<strong>of</strong> that era<br />

4 H. F. Mallgrave, tr., Johann Joachim W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann. History <strong>of</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Antiquity (Los Angeles, 2006)<br />

132: “<strong>The</strong> characteristics <strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g features <strong>of</strong> the Egyptian style noted here—both the del<strong>in</strong>eation<br />

<strong>of</strong> forms with nearly straight l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>imal <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> bones <strong>and</strong> muscles—suffer an exception<br />

when it comes to animals <strong>in</strong> Egyptian art. Among the latter, especially to be cited are a large basalt sph<strong>in</strong>x<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Villa Borghese, another large sph<strong>in</strong>x <strong>of</strong> granite among the royal antiquities at Dresden, two lions at<br />

the ramp to the Campidoglio, <strong>and</strong> two others at the Fontana dell’Acqua Felice. <strong>The</strong>se animals are made<br />

with much underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, with an elegant multiplicity <strong>of</strong> s<strong>of</strong>tly chang<strong>in</strong>g outl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> fluid transitions<br />

between separate parts. <strong>The</strong> greater trochanter, which on human figures is ill-def<strong>in</strong>ed, on animals is<br />

executed, along with the thigh <strong>and</strong> other bones, with an elegant emphasis….For this stylistic dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between figures <strong>and</strong> animals, we may conclude that the former represented deities or holy persons whose<br />

appearance had universally been established, whereas the artist was allowed greater freedom <strong>in</strong> depict<strong>in</strong>g<br />

animals.”<br />

10


with the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. 5 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the art <strong>of</strong> the Renaissance, for example, the animal<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Albrecht Dürer (1471-1528) have been considered testimony to this artist’s<br />

close observation <strong>and</strong> rare accuracy <strong>of</strong> animals (e.g., Young Hare, 1502), <strong>and</strong> thus, to his<br />

designation as animalier, that is, an artist skilled <strong>in</strong> portray<strong>in</strong>g animals. 6 In addition,<br />

Leonardo da V<strong>in</strong>ci’s (1452-1519) skillful draw<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> animals (e.g., Studies <strong>of</strong> a Bear<br />

Walk<strong>in</strong>g, 1519) have given rise to the view <strong>of</strong> the latter as a means through which<br />

naturalism was studied, pursued, <strong>and</strong> measured at the time. 7 In a similar ve<strong>in</strong>, both<br />

eighteenth- <strong>and</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century animal art has been s<strong>in</strong>gled out for its careful<br />

observation <strong>of</strong> its subjects <strong>and</strong> also their employment as elements <strong>of</strong> representational<br />

fidelity. It has been noticed, for example, that Jean-Baptiste Oudry’s (1686-1755)<br />

eighteenth-century pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> animals present them as exotic specimens, isolated from<br />

their natural environment, but still “beautifully observed” (e.g., Antelope, 1739), <strong>and</strong> also<br />

as detached items <strong>of</strong> food that exhibit a “stagger<strong>in</strong>g visual realism” (e.g., Hare <strong>and</strong> Leg <strong>of</strong><br />

Lamb, 1742). 8 Similarly, n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century animal pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, such as that <strong>of</strong> a dog <strong>in</strong><br />

5 See E. Morrison, <strong>The</strong> Medieval Imag<strong>in</strong>ation. Beasts. Factual <strong>and</strong> Fantastic (Los Angeles <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

2007); also F. Mezzalira et al., Beasts <strong>and</strong> Bestiaries. <strong>The</strong> Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> from Prehistory to<br />

the Renaissance (Tur<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> London, 2001); N. C. Flores, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Middle Ages (New York, 2000).<br />

6 For Albrecht Dürer’s attention to animals, see F. Koreny, Albrecht Dürer <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>and</strong> Plant<br />

Studies <strong>of</strong> the Renaissance (Boston, 1985); for his designation as animalier, see C. Eisler, Dürer’s <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

(Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C., 1991) 16.<br />

7 For the important position <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sects <strong>in</strong> Leonardo da V<strong>in</strong>ci’s study <strong>of</strong> naturalism as an<br />

empirically based artistic pursuit <strong>and</strong> its impact on subsequent artists, such as Giovanni da Ud<strong>in</strong>e (1487-<br />

1564), see L. Wolk-Simon, “Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Lombard Draw<strong>in</strong>g from Leonardo to Cerano,” <strong>in</strong> A. Bayer, ed.,<br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>of</strong> Reality. <strong>The</strong> Legacy <strong>of</strong> Leonardo <strong>and</strong> Caravaggio <strong>in</strong> Lombardy (exhibition catalogue, Museo<br />

Civico “Ala Ponzone,” Cremona, February 14-May 2, 2004, <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New<br />

York, May 27-August 15, 2004; New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 46-47 <strong>and</strong> 89; also for da V<strong>in</strong>ci’s attention<br />

to horses, see M. Kemp, “Draw<strong>in</strong>gs for Il Cavallo del Duca Francesco di Bronzo,” <strong>in</strong> D. C. Ahl, ed.,<br />

Leonardo da V<strong>in</strong>ci’s Sforza Monument Horse: <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> the Eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g; Bethlehem, Pennsylvania <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1995) 64-78; For a short discussion <strong>of</strong> animals as a useful guide to the concept <strong>of</strong> realism <strong>in</strong><br />

Renaissance pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, see J. H. Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs: Pets <strong>in</strong> the Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Modern Life<br />

(New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2003) 6.<br />

8 L. Lipp<strong>in</strong>cott <strong>and</strong> A. Blühm, eds., Fierce Friends: Artists <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, 1750-1900 (exhibition catalogue,<br />

Van Gogh Museum, Amsterdam <strong>and</strong> Carnegie Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, Pittsburgh; London <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2005)19, <strong>and</strong> 34 <strong>and</strong> 38 respectively for depictions <strong>of</strong> Antelope <strong>and</strong> Hare <strong>and</strong> Leg <strong>of</strong> Lamb; for recent<br />

attention to Oudry’s pa<strong>in</strong>ted animals, see M. Morton, ed., Oudry’s Pa<strong>in</strong>ted Menagerie. Portraits <strong>of</strong> Exotic<br />

11


Edgar Degas’s <strong>The</strong> Bellelli Family (1858-1860), have been thought to use animals as<br />

devices that enhance pictorial realism. 9 In addition, n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century depictions <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> a variety <strong>of</strong> media (pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, sculpture, <strong>and</strong> photography) have been<br />

considered evidence <strong>of</strong> contemporary chang<strong>in</strong>g attitudes toward animals as generated by<br />

Charles Darw<strong>in</strong>’s theories <strong>of</strong> evolution (1859) <strong>and</strong> emotion <strong>in</strong> man <strong>and</strong> animals (1872). 10<br />

It has been suggested, for example, that images <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>and</strong> cats <strong>in</strong> lithographs <strong>and</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs reflect the perception <strong>of</strong> these animals not as mere beasts, but as family<br />

members with their own will <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence, <strong>and</strong> also as symbols <strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong><br />

economic class. 11<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Eighteenth-Century Europe (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> J. Paul Getty Museum <strong>in</strong> association<br />

with the Staatliches Museum Schwer<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts, Houston; Los Angeles, 2007).<br />

9 Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats & Dogs 58, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that Degas’s first portrait <strong>of</strong> a dog is <strong>in</strong> the group portrait<br />

<strong>of</strong> his Italian aunt <strong>and</strong> cous<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Bellelli Family. Rub<strong>in</strong>’s comment on the image <strong>of</strong> this dog runs as<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g: “In discussions <strong>of</strong> this complex image, the dog is rarely mentioned. A black toy-sized animal<br />

like a poodle or a terrier, it exits the space at the lower right, its head already outside the frame. With this<br />

cruel decapitation, Degas created a range <strong>of</strong> possibilities. As a pictorial device, the animal implies<br />

extension <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>ted scene beyond the frame. So the image Degas represented seems like a fragment<br />

cut from a larger world. <strong>The</strong> tactic has a double consequence. First, it enhances the picture’s effectiveness<br />

as an illusion <strong>of</strong> reality. But second, it also calls attention to the artist’s <strong>in</strong>cisive, I would say surgical,<br />

pictorial composition—a characteristic particularly associated with Degas. His strategy <strong>of</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g evokes<br />

photography, a technology believed to produce objective records <strong>of</strong> reality. Through it, Degas implied that<br />

his vision was scrupulously true. He sacrificed the dog to do it.”<br />

10 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> depictions <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> all these media, see Lipp<strong>in</strong>cott<br />

<strong>and</strong> Blühm, Fierce <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. For the impact <strong>of</strong> Darw<strong>in</strong>’s effect on n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century visual culture, <strong>in</strong><br />

general, see L. Nochl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> M. Lucy, eds., “<strong>The</strong> Darw<strong>in</strong> Effect: Evolution <strong>and</strong> N<strong>in</strong>eteenth-Century Visual<br />

Culture,” N<strong>in</strong>eteenth Century Art Worldwide II, 2 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 2003) (www.19thc-artworldwide.org); also L.<br />

Golden, “Science, Darw<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Art History,” <strong>in</strong> L. Golden, ed., Rais<strong>in</strong>g the Eyebrow: John Onians <strong>and</strong><br />

World Art Series. An Album Amicorum <strong>in</strong> His Honour (BAR International Series 996; Oxford, 2001) 79-90.<br />

11 For animals as family members, note Honoré Daumier’s lithograph <strong>of</strong> 1856, which shows a pa<strong>in</strong>ter<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g the portrait <strong>of</strong> a dog seated on his mistress’s lap. Its caption reads: “Now that he’s a member <strong>of</strong> the<br />

family, he has to have his portrait, too”: Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 11, fig. 10; for a depiction <strong>of</strong><br />

cats’ willfulness, <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a sign <strong>of</strong> their <strong>in</strong>dependent nature, see Pierre-Auguste Renoir’s<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Girl with a Cat, c. 1882, which depicts a girl observ<strong>in</strong>g a cat stretched on its h<strong>in</strong>d legs <strong>and</strong><br />

reach<strong>in</strong>g up toward the foliage <strong>of</strong> a large house plant: Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 112, 116, fig.<br />

89; also for the contemporary belief <strong>in</strong> animal <strong>in</strong>telligence, see the wood engrav<strong>in</strong>g by an anonymous artist<br />

<strong>of</strong> two cats try<strong>in</strong>g to open an armoire, <strong>in</strong> E. Menault, L’Intelligence des animaux (Paris, 1869) 267, cited <strong>in</strong><br />

Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 119, fig. 91; for animals as symbols <strong>of</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic class <strong>in</strong><br />

the n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century, see Edouard Manet’s Olympia, 1862-1863, which depicts a prostitute with a cat:<br />

Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 17, fig. 13. <strong>The</strong> image becomes more tell<strong>in</strong>g when seen aga<strong>in</strong>st<br />

Champfleury’s contemporary explanation about “the oriental notion that <strong>of</strong> all female animals, the cat most<br />

resembles woman <strong>in</strong> her cleverness, deceit, seductiveness, <strong>in</strong>constancy, <strong>and</strong> fury”: (Jules Husson called<br />

Champfleury, Les Chats (Paris, 1868) 22; translation Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 18-19, n. 15; also<br />

12


<strong>The</strong> examples just cited show that representations <strong>of</strong> animals have been<br />

considered significant not only for the <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> past attitudes towards animals but<br />

also for the role <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> explor<strong>in</strong>g social as well as art-historical issues. That the<br />

significance <strong>of</strong> animal representations has been realized even further <strong>in</strong> recent years is<br />

evident from their featur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a broad range <strong>of</strong> no less critical issues such as gender,<br />

politics, religion, <strong>and</strong> also ethics. 12<br />

Alphonse Toussenel’s earlier remark that “civilized society can no more dispense with cats than with<br />

prostitution”: A. Toussenel, L’Esprit des bêtes: Zoologie passionelle (Paris, 1855) 228; translation Rub<strong>in</strong>,<br />

Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs 19, n. 16. Contrary to the association <strong>of</strong> cats with prostitutes, little dogs were<br />

considered attributes <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class women <strong>and</strong> their prosperity. For an example, see Renoir’s pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

Luncheon <strong>of</strong> the Boat<strong>in</strong>g Party, 1880-1881; it depicts Al<strong>in</strong>e Charigot, a dressmaker <strong>and</strong> Renoir’s mistress<br />

<strong>and</strong> future wife, play<strong>in</strong>g affectionately with a small <strong>and</strong> long-haired dog: Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong><br />

Dogs 94-95, fig. 73. As for the emotions displayed by little dogs, the story that K<strong>in</strong>g Charles I’s spaniels<br />

had cried as the k<strong>in</strong>g was beheaded was a popular one among French Victorians: J. Robert, Le Chien<br />

d’appartement et d’utilité: Education, dressage, hygiene, maladies (Paris, 1888) 94. <strong>The</strong> story recalls<br />

Homer’s assertion <strong>in</strong> the Iliad (17.437) that Achilles’ horses cried for him. For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century France, see K. Kete, <strong>The</strong> Beast <strong>in</strong> the Boudoir: Petkeep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> N<strong>in</strong>eteenth-<br />

Century Paris (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1994), <strong>and</strong> for that <strong>in</strong> contemporary Engl<strong>and</strong>, H. Ritvo, <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>Animal</strong> Estate: <strong>The</strong> English <strong>and</strong> Other Creatures <strong>in</strong> the Victorian Age (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1987).<br />

12 <strong>The</strong> bibliography on the modern realization <strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> depictions <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong><br />

different societies <strong>and</strong> cultures is not vast, but is constantly grow<strong>in</strong>g. For a general <strong>in</strong>troduction to the<br />

subject rang<strong>in</strong>g from Renaissance to modern case studies, both literary <strong>and</strong> pictorial, see the collection <strong>of</strong><br />

essays by M. S. Pollock <strong>and</strong> C. Ra<strong>in</strong>water, eds., Figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>: Essays on <strong>Animal</strong> Images <strong>in</strong> Art,<br />

Literature, Philosophy, <strong>and</strong> Popular Culture (New York, 2005); for a discussion <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> contemporary visual culture, see the collection <strong>of</strong> essays <strong>in</strong> N. Rothfels, ed., Represent<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton <strong>and</strong> Indianapolis, 2002); also S. Baker, Pictur<strong>in</strong>g the Beast. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Identity, <strong>and</strong><br />

Representation (Urbana <strong>and</strong> Chicago, 2001); <strong>and</strong> J. Burt, “<strong>The</strong> Illum<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gdom: <strong>The</strong><br />

Role <strong>of</strong> Light <strong>and</strong> Electricity <strong>in</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> Representation,” <strong>in</strong> L. Kal<strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> A. Fitzgerald, eds., <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

Reader. <strong>The</strong> Essential Classic <strong>and</strong> Contemporary Writ<strong>in</strong>gs (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 2007) 289-301. As for<br />

the ancient world, see the section on animals <strong>in</strong> art <strong>in</strong> B. J. Coll<strong>in</strong>s, ed., A History <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> World <strong>in</strong><br />

the Ancient Near East (Leiden <strong>and</strong> Boston, 2002) 79-211; For images <strong>of</strong> animals associated with beliefs<br />

about gender <strong>in</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century France—women compared to lionesses <strong>and</strong> pantheresses <strong>and</strong> men<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> as lions <strong>and</strong> tigers—see N. F<strong>in</strong>lay, “Eros <strong>and</strong> Sadism: Delacroix’s Depictions <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

People,” <strong>in</strong> N. H. Bluestone, ed., Double Vision: Perspectives on Gender <strong>and</strong> the Visual Arts (London <strong>and</strong><br />

Toronto, 1995) 21-37, figs. 1.1-1.10; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> images <strong>of</strong> animals enabl<strong>in</strong>g rulers to demonstrate<br />

their political power <strong>and</strong> its reach with examples drawn from ancient Egypt, Ch<strong>in</strong>a, the Hellenistic <strong>and</strong><br />

Roman worlds, <strong>and</strong> also the Renaissance all the way to the eighteenth century, see M. Belozerskaya,<br />

“Menageries as Pr<strong>in</strong>cely Necessities <strong>and</strong> Mirrors <strong>of</strong> their Times,” <strong>in</strong> Morton, ed., Oudry’s Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Menagerie 59-73, figs. 1-9; also for an extension <strong>of</strong> her discussion <strong>in</strong>to modern times, <strong>The</strong> Medici Giraffe:<br />

And Other Tales <strong>of</strong> Exotic <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Power (New York, 2006). For a discussion <strong>of</strong> animal<br />

representations play<strong>in</strong>g an important role as archetypes <strong>in</strong> religion, see C. Manes, Other Creations:<br />

Rediscover<strong>in</strong>g the Spirituality <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (New York, 1997); also for an example <strong>of</strong> a recent study focus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on a specific religious tradition, with reference to both its literary <strong>and</strong> visual animal imagery, see R. C.<br />

Foltz, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Islamic Tradition <strong>and</strong> Muslim Cultures (Oxford, 2006) 65-82. F<strong>in</strong>ally, for pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong><br />

photographs <strong>of</strong> animals depicted along with their owners <strong>and</strong> their children as evidence mirror<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

13


. Scholarly Remarks on the Neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek Art (<strong>in</strong> Particular<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong>)<br />

Despite this evidence, the preferential treatment <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

form at the expense <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the study (<strong>of</strong> the development) <strong>of</strong> Greek art,<br />

particularly sculpture, has dom<strong>in</strong>ated both past <strong>and</strong> recent studies. In her study <strong>of</strong> 1930,<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. A Survey, Gisela Richter, for example, <strong>of</strong>fers the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>troductory observation: “the subject <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture has been strangely<br />

neglected. It is the current belief even among archeologists that the Greek sculptor<br />

concentrated practically his whole attention on the human figure <strong>and</strong> attempted little<br />

else.” 13 Richter’s study presents the first <strong>and</strong> also the latest substantial corpus <strong>of</strong><br />

representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture rang<strong>in</strong>g from Archaic to Hellenistic<br />

examples <strong>and</strong> also Roman copies <strong>of</strong> them. Her discussion is further supplemented with<br />

frequent references to representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> other media such as co<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong>, less<br />

frequently, gems <strong>and</strong> pottery. Richter treats animal sculpture accord<strong>in</strong>g to the same<br />

scheme <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism that has dom<strong>in</strong>ated the study <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek art on the basis <strong>of</strong> the human form, a subject that <strong>and</strong> will be addressed <strong>in</strong> detail<br />

shortly. Consider<strong>in</strong>g its early date <strong>of</strong> publication, Richter’s study st<strong>and</strong>s as an eloquent<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the unpopularity <strong>of</strong> animals as a subject <strong>in</strong> twentieth-century studies <strong>of</strong><br />

ancient Greek sculpture.<br />

<strong>The</strong> persistence <strong>of</strong> this unpopularity is also remarked <strong>in</strong> a subsequent discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> ancient Greek animal sculpture. In an article <strong>of</strong> 1972, exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g “Greek Funerary<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period, Cornelius Vermeule expla<strong>in</strong>s the reasons for his<br />

domestic ethic <strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>dness toward animals <strong>in</strong> n<strong>in</strong>eteenth- <strong>and</strong> early twentieth-century American family<br />

relations, see K. C. Grier, Pets <strong>in</strong> America: A History (Chapel Hill, 2006) 127-181, figs. 3.1-3.13.<br />

13 G. M. A. Richter, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. A Survey (New York, 1930) ix.<br />

14


study<strong>in</strong>g freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g statues <strong>of</strong> lions. In defend<strong>in</strong>g his choice <strong>of</strong> subject, he conveys the<br />

generally dismissive attitude <strong>of</strong> his colleagues towards his engagement with this type <strong>of</strong><br />

material:<br />

Why <strong>of</strong>fer a reappraisal <strong>of</strong> classical Greek funerary animals, chiefly lions, at this<br />

time <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the fashion presented here? For one reason the body <strong>of</strong> material is<br />

large <strong>and</strong>, save the admirable set <strong>of</strong> lists published <strong>in</strong> connection with the dra<strong>in</strong>spouts<br />

from Olympia, really little studied beyond s<strong>in</strong>gle, isolated examples. In<br />

<strong>Greece</strong>, the isl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Asia M<strong>in</strong>or, lions are the it<strong>in</strong>erant archaeologist’s delight.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>evitably tethered <strong>in</strong> the courtyards or gardens <strong>of</strong> museums, or even<br />

outside their entrances. <strong>The</strong>refore there is no complex red tape, no frustrat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

delays or refusals <strong>in</strong> photograph<strong>in</strong>g or otherwise study<strong>in</strong>g them. No one is jealous<br />

or possessive <strong>of</strong> the droits de la publication <strong>of</strong> a marble lion….Pr<strong>of</strong>essional<br />

colleagues, particularly those work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> Turkey, tend to feel that<br />

anyone study<strong>in</strong>g lions is either perpetuat<strong>in</strong>g a big joke or slipp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to second<br />

childhood. Like marble cuirassed statues, lions are everywhere, <strong>and</strong> their pursuit<br />

meets with such success that one is encouraged to travel far <strong>and</strong> wide <strong>in</strong> the<br />

byways <strong>of</strong> classical l<strong>and</strong>s. 14<br />

Vermeule’s open<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> clos<strong>in</strong>g remarks that “the body <strong>of</strong> material is large” <strong>and</strong> that<br />

“lions are everywhere” speaks <strong>of</strong> the abundance, <strong>and</strong> therefore, popularity <strong>of</strong> animal<br />

sculpture <strong>in</strong> antiquity. When contrasted with his colleagues’ scorn <strong>of</strong> his engagement<br />

with this body <strong>of</strong> material, such evidence reveals a scholarly view <strong>of</strong> animal sculpture<br />

that does not correspond to ancient reality. This realization, as well as the prevail<strong>in</strong>g<br />

preoccupation with the human form, are succ<strong>in</strong>ctly summarized <strong>in</strong> a later article (1986)<br />

by Trudy Kawami, which underl<strong>in</strong>es the need for <strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g animal sculpture <strong>in</strong> the<br />

study <strong>of</strong> stylistic change <strong>in</strong> Greek art: “Scholarly research has focused on the human<br />

figure as a characteristic theme <strong>in</strong> Greek art <strong>and</strong> the major <strong>in</strong>dicator <strong>of</strong> stylistic change.<br />

We forget that animal sculpture was also highly valued.” 15<br />

Although divorced from the topic <strong>of</strong> style, further evidence <strong>of</strong> the need to<br />

recognize the significance <strong>of</strong> animal representations for the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art is found <strong>in</strong><br />

14 C. Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, 450-300 B.C.,” AJA 76 (1972) 50.<br />

15 T. S. Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 265.<br />

15


a statement by Herbert H<strong>of</strong>fman (1989). As an assessment <strong>of</strong> his own scholarship on<br />

Greek animal rhyta, H<strong>of</strong>fman corrects his previously dismissive attitude towards the<br />

significance <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> both Greek art <strong>and</strong> religion. In do<strong>in</strong>g so, he considers the<br />

wider <strong>in</strong>tellectual context with<strong>in</strong> which this attitude was <strong>in</strong>itially formed:<br />

This writer once made the follow<strong>in</strong>g overly dogmatic statement concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Greek rhyta: “<strong>The</strong> animal heads seem to have been selected for<br />

their sculptural <strong>and</strong> decorative qualities, rather than for any specific cult<br />

associations.”<br />

My verdict <strong>of</strong> “no significance” reflected the neo-positivist st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t then<br />

current <strong>in</strong> British <strong>and</strong> American archaeology, <strong>and</strong> it was symptomatic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

conservative spirit then prevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> academic establishment that my refusal to<br />

venture a hypothesis concern<strong>in</strong>g the possible function <strong>and</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

artifacts I had assembled should have been s<strong>in</strong>gled out for special approval by no<br />

less an authority than Gisela M. A. Richter.<br />

Reflect<strong>in</strong>g on the same artifacts more than two decades later, I now th<strong>in</strong>k that<br />

this verdict was premature <strong>and</strong>, furthermore, that a position that denies the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g to such a radical extent cannot possibly be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed.” 16<br />

[Also] <strong>in</strong> H<strong>of</strong>fmann 1962 my vision was clouded by [one among four]<br />

fundamental misconceptions: that animals are not very important for the<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Greek religion (Greek gods be<strong>in</strong>g so anthropomorphic).” 17<br />

H<strong>of</strong>fmann’s emphasis on the anthropomorphism <strong>of</strong> Greek gods as supersed<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> animal representations <strong>in</strong> Greek religion is <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> the scholarly<br />

concern with the human form, a situation which, as already seen, susta<strong>in</strong>s the neglected<br />

treatment <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art. Furthermore, his reflection on animals’<br />

<strong>in</strong>significance as a well-grounded presupposition with<strong>in</strong> the field <strong>of</strong> Anglo-American<br />

archaeology is illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, for it underl<strong>in</strong>es the general denigration <strong>of</strong> animals as<br />

scholarly subjects, while highlight<strong>in</strong>g the need for reconsideration <strong>of</strong> this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view.<br />

It is clear from the scholarly op<strong>in</strong>ions reviewed so far that an overall scornful<br />

attitude toward the study <strong>of</strong> animal representations <strong>in</strong> Greek art, <strong>and</strong> sculpture <strong>in</strong><br />

16 H. H<strong>of</strong>fmann, “Rhyta <strong>and</strong> Kantharoi <strong>in</strong> Greek Ritual,” Greek Vases <strong>in</strong> the J. Paul Getty Museum 4;<br />

Occasional Papers on Antiquities 5 (Malibu, 1989) 132.<br />

17 H<strong>of</strong>fmann, “Rhyta <strong>and</strong> Kantharoi,” Greek Vases <strong>in</strong> the Getty Museum 4 (Malibu, 1989) 165.<br />

16


particular, has dom<strong>in</strong>ated twentieth-century scholarship, <strong>and</strong> only lately a call for<br />

reconsideration has been explicitly verbalized. <strong>The</strong> long-term survival <strong>of</strong> such an attitude<br />

is both impressive <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g. For this reason, the follow<strong>in</strong>g section considers two<br />

specific conditions that have allowed for the <strong>in</strong>attention to animal representations <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek sculpture to hold strong: humanism <strong>and</strong> Christianity.<br />

2. Why Have Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> Been Neglected?<br />

Published <strong>in</strong> 1970, the last revised edition <strong>of</strong> Richter’s 1929 study, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks, provides an early example <strong>of</strong> attribut<strong>in</strong>g the prevalence <strong>of</strong><br />

the human over the animal form <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek sculpture to a specific Greek<br />

predilection for athletics:<br />

<strong>The</strong> athletic ideal helped to concentrate <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> the human figure. It<br />

accustomed people to see<strong>in</strong>g the human body <strong>in</strong> all manner <strong>of</strong> postures <strong>and</strong> to<br />

appreciat<strong>in</strong>g its beauty. Moreover, the Greek with his love <strong>of</strong> the normal had a<br />

tendency to humanize everyth<strong>in</strong>g. His gods <strong>and</strong> goddess are no longer monsters,<br />

as <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>in</strong> Near Eastern art, but assume human form; so do the nymphs, satyrs,<br />

centaurs, Tritons, <strong>and</strong> the other personifications <strong>of</strong> nature. Even when these start<br />

with hybrid shapes they soon lose their animal characteristics <strong>and</strong> gradually<br />

become more <strong>and</strong> more human. And so Greek sculpture consists largely <strong>of</strong><br />

figures <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs represent<strong>in</strong>g div<strong>in</strong>ities, heroes, <strong>and</strong> athletes. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> decorative motifs f<strong>in</strong>d a place <strong>and</strong> an important one, but they are nevertheless<br />

secondary. <strong>The</strong> human figure is the theme par excellence. 18<br />

As can be seen, Richter adopts a hierarchical approach to the subjects <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture:<br />

animals are important but secondary to representations <strong>of</strong> the human figure. In<br />

accordance with this belief, animal sculpture occupies a separate, but still very brief<br />

chapter (six pages) when compared to her much lengthier discussion <strong>of</strong> the human figure,<br />

which dom<strong>in</strong>ates all the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g chapters <strong>of</strong> her study.<br />

18<br />

G. M. A. Richter, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1929; fourth rev.<br />

ed., 1970) 25.<br />

17


Richter’s position is neither unique nor accidental. In fact, it is <strong>in</strong> perfect<br />

alignment with both a predom<strong>in</strong>ant view <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek culture, <strong>and</strong> specifically art, as<br />

the embodiment <strong>of</strong> humanism, <strong>and</strong> a Christian attitude to animals as subord<strong>in</strong>ate to<br />

human supremacy. Especially prom<strong>in</strong>ent s<strong>in</strong>ce the Renaissance, the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

humanism views man as the measure <strong>of</strong> all th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> the literature <strong>and</strong> art <strong>of</strong> classical<br />

antiquity as examples <strong>of</strong> exceptional human achievement. 19 In Christian thought, the<br />

powerful hold <strong>of</strong> an equally anthropocentric attitude has led to the prevail<strong>in</strong>g view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world, <strong>in</strong> particular its nonhuman <strong>in</strong>habitants, as serv<strong>in</strong>g or advanc<strong>in</strong>g human needs <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terests. 20<br />

19 For an example <strong>of</strong> the exceptional position <strong>of</strong> man <strong>in</strong> Renaissance thought, see P. F. Grendler, “Man is<br />

Almost a God: Fra Battista Carioni Between Renaissance <strong>and</strong> Catholic Reformation,” <strong>in</strong> J. O’Malley et al.,<br />

eds., Humanity <strong>and</strong> Div<strong>in</strong>ity <strong>in</strong> Renaissance <strong>and</strong> Reformation. Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> Charles Tr<strong>in</strong>kaus<br />

(Leiden <strong>and</strong> New York, 1993) 227-249; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the term “humanism” <strong>and</strong> its use <strong>in</strong> the context<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Renaissance, see A. Campana, “<strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Word “Humanist,” Journal <strong>of</strong> the Warburg <strong>and</strong><br />

Courtauld Institutes 9 (1946) 60-73; for a recent discussion <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong> on the visual<br />

arts <strong>of</strong> the Renaissance, see M. Gregori, ed., In the Light <strong>of</strong> Apollo: Italian Renaissance <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, 22<br />

December 2003-31 March 2004 (exhibition catalogue, National Gallery—Alex<strong>and</strong>ros Soutzos Museum <strong>and</strong><br />

Fondazione di Studi dell’Arte Roberto Longhi; Athens, 2003). It should be mentioned that the Renaissance<br />

view <strong>of</strong> humanism <strong>of</strong> classical art is not without ancient pedigree. In his Natural History, Pl<strong>in</strong>y, for<br />

example, whose <strong>in</strong>fluence on Giorgio Vasari’s Lives <strong>of</strong> the Most Excellent Italian Pa<strong>in</strong>ters, Sculptors <strong>and</strong><br />

Architects (1550) is well established, speaks <strong>of</strong> an artist’s decision to make the statue <strong>of</strong> a bull for Phalaris,<br />

the tyrant <strong>of</strong> Akragas (c. 570-554 B.C.), <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way (34.89): “to this debasement, far removed<br />

from all representations <strong>of</strong> gods <strong>and</strong> men, he had brought the highest human art” or “an art that is most<br />

worthy <strong>of</strong> man” (humanissima ars). This is a clear devaluation <strong>of</strong> animal imagery <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong><br />

anthropomorphic form, <strong>and</strong> runs counter to the fact that Myron’s most renowned statue <strong>in</strong> antiquity was his<br />

cow. It should be kept <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that Pl<strong>in</strong>y, a Roman writer, expresses here his personal op<strong>in</strong>ion about Greek<br />

art <strong>of</strong> the past rather than quot<strong>in</strong>g verbatim an earlier author on the subject. For this observation <strong>and</strong> also<br />

an extensive discussion <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on Vasari, see J. Isager, “Humanissima ars:<br />

Evaluation <strong>and</strong> Devaluation <strong>in</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y, Vasari, <strong>and</strong> Baden,” <strong>in</strong> A. A. Donohue <strong>and</strong> M. D. Fullerton, eds.,<br />

Ancient Art <strong>and</strong> Its Historiography (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2003) 49: “it seems to me that Pl<strong>in</strong>y<br />

condenses <strong>in</strong>to this s<strong>in</strong>gle expression [humanissima ars] what one might call his philosophy <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> the<br />

service <strong>of</strong> man.”<br />

20 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the early Christian attitude to animals, see I. S. Gilhus, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Gods, <strong>and</strong> Humans:<br />

Chang<strong>in</strong>g Attitudes to <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek, Roman, <strong>and</strong> Early Christian Ideas (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2006);<br />

<strong>and</strong> for a more general view, A. L<strong>in</strong>zey <strong>and</strong> T. Regan, eds., <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Christianity. A Book <strong>of</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

(New York, 1988); also the collection <strong>of</strong> essays on animals <strong>in</strong> Christian perspective <strong>in</strong> C. P<strong>in</strong>ches <strong>and</strong> J. B.<br />

McDaniel, eds., Good News for <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>? Christian Approaches to <strong>Animal</strong> Well-Be<strong>in</strong>g (Ecology <strong>and</strong><br />

Justice) (Maryknoll, New York, 1993). See also K. Shevelow, For the Love <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Rise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Animal</strong> Protection Movement (New York, 2008) 90-105 for the prosecution, execution, <strong>and</strong> religious<br />

penalty <strong>of</strong> anathematization <strong>of</strong> animals as practiced <strong>in</strong> Europe, especially <strong>in</strong> France <strong>and</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong>, s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

late Middle Ages, dur<strong>in</strong>g the Renaissance, <strong>and</strong> throughout the next three centuries.<br />

18


Regard<strong>in</strong>g classical antiquity, the cumulative effect <strong>of</strong> these concepts appears <strong>in</strong><br />

John Boardman’s dated idea that ancient Greek culture, <strong>in</strong> particular its art, is viewed as:<br />

the expression <strong>of</strong> a people unsurpassed for their purity <strong>of</strong> thought, behavior, <strong>and</strong><br />

design, democrats, philosophers, poets <strong>and</strong> historians, the true precursors <strong>of</strong> the<br />

modern world <strong>and</strong> all-time successes <strong>in</strong> the pursuit <strong>of</strong> the true <strong>and</strong> the beautiful,<br />

express<strong>in</strong>g a humanity that anticipated or even surpassed all that Christianity has<br />

been able to achieve. 21<br />

This praise <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek culture <strong>and</strong> art places emphasis on human achievement, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, removes attention from non-human animals <strong>and</strong> their roles <strong>in</strong> the respective<br />

society; as a result, it promotes a hierarchical approach to the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art that<br />

places foremost significance on the human form, <strong>and</strong> thus, relegates animal<br />

representations to an <strong>in</strong>visible position. An additional example <strong>of</strong> this way <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

can be seen <strong>in</strong> the foreword to the exhibition catalogue <strong>of</strong> 1992, <strong>The</strong> Greek Miracle:<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Dawn <strong>of</strong> Democracy. <strong>The</strong> Fifth Century B.C.:<br />

Greek art centered on the image <strong>of</strong> man: man who <strong>of</strong> all the wonders <strong>in</strong> the world<br />

was the most wonderful, capable <strong>of</strong> great good, but also <strong>of</strong> great evil; sometimes<br />

fall<strong>in</strong>g back, but <strong>in</strong> the fifth-century Greek view, ultimately ris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong><br />

all odds to take charge <strong>of</strong> his dest<strong>in</strong>y. 22<br />

<strong>The</strong> scholarly assertion that the human form dom<strong>in</strong>ated Greek art, particularly that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fifth century—a period <strong>in</strong>deed known for its anthropocentric view <strong>of</strong> man—is used to<br />

justify the disregard <strong>of</strong> animal representations <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art on the grounds<br />

that it simply reflects ancient Greek reality. 23 Yet not only was that reality quite<br />

different, as will be discussed below, but given the persistence <strong>of</strong> an anthropocentric<br />

approach to Greek art, it is even surpris<strong>in</strong>g that animal representations have been denied<br />

21<br />

J. Boardman, Greek Art (fourth ed.; London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) 11; for a more detailed discussion by<br />

this author on ancient Greek art <strong>and</strong> its reception s<strong>in</strong>ce the Renaissance, see J. Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Late <strong>Classical</strong> Period <strong>and</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> Colonies <strong>and</strong> Overseas (London, 1995) 222-228.<br />

22<br />

D. Oliver-Buitron, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek Miracle. <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Dawn <strong>of</strong> Democracy. <strong>The</strong> Fifth<br />

Century B.C. (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 1992) 9.<br />

23<br />

For the prevail<strong>in</strong>g anthropocentrism <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek society, especially <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period, see R.<br />

Renehan, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Anthropocentric View <strong>of</strong> Man,” HSCP 85 (1981) 239-259.<br />

19


careful consideration s<strong>in</strong>ce, as human creations, they can be primarily seen as part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human achievement <strong>in</strong> the arts <strong>of</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. 24 Such an approach accords well, for<br />

example, with ancient literary evidence <strong>in</strong> which animals not only feature as subjects <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art associated with particular artists, but, <strong>in</strong> some cases, also def<strong>in</strong>e the fame <strong>of</strong><br />

these artists.<br />

3. Ancient Texts on Famous Artists <strong>and</strong> Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek Art<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s account <strong>of</strong> two late Archaic Greek sculptors, Kanachos <strong>and</strong> Menaechmus,<br />

mentions animals as be<strong>in</strong>g featured along with human figures <strong>in</strong> two examples <strong>of</strong> statues<br />

by these artists. 25 <strong>The</strong> animals, ultimately, establish, if not def<strong>in</strong>e, the merit <strong>of</strong> these<br />

artists as noteworthy:<br />

Kanachos [was the sculptor <strong>of</strong>] a nude Apollo, which bears the cognomen<br />

Philesios, <strong>in</strong> the sanctuary at Didyma, made from bronze <strong>of</strong> the Aeg<strong>in</strong>itan<br />

formula; <strong>and</strong> with it a stag which is suspended <strong>in</strong> its tracks <strong>in</strong> such a way that a<br />

str<strong>in</strong>g can be drawn underneath its feet, with the heel <strong>and</strong> toe alternately reta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

24 This observation recalls a central po<strong>in</strong>t with<strong>in</strong> the grow<strong>in</strong>g field <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> animals. As E. Fudge,<br />

“A Left-H<strong>and</strong>ed Blow: Writ<strong>in</strong>g the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> Rothfels, ed., Represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> 6 states:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> emerg<strong>in</strong>g field [history <strong>of</strong> animals]—conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g much absolutely fasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> reward<strong>in</strong>g work—is<br />

clearly there, but it is not the history <strong>of</strong> animals; such a th<strong>in</strong>g is impossible. Rather, it is the history <strong>of</strong><br />

human attitudes toward animals….But if this history <strong>of</strong> animals is <strong>in</strong> reality the history <strong>of</strong> human attitudes<br />

toward animals, we are, perhaps deal<strong>in</strong>g with someth<strong>in</strong>g that is merely part <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> ideas: noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

really new at all. If our only access to animals <strong>in</strong> the past is through written documents written by humans,<br />

then we are never look<strong>in</strong>g at the animals, only ever at the representations <strong>of</strong> the animals by humans.”<br />

25 J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965; second ed., Cambridge, 1990;<br />

repr. 1998) 33-34, considers Kanachos <strong>of</strong> Sikyon an artist <strong>of</strong> the late Archaic phase <strong>of</strong> Greek art.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g Menaechmus, he states (3) that the date <strong>of</strong> this artist <strong>and</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> his writ<strong>in</strong>gs, as mentioned<br />

by Pl<strong>in</strong>y, are uncerta<strong>in</strong>. Pausanias (7.18.8) refers to a sculptor named Menaechmus as the artist <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> Artemis Laphria <strong>in</strong> the homonymous sanctuary at Patras: “On the acropolis at Patras there is a<br />

sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Laphria. <strong>The</strong> name <strong>of</strong> the goddess is foreign, <strong>and</strong> the image too was brought <strong>in</strong> from<br />

the outside….<strong>The</strong> image represents her as a huntress, <strong>and</strong> it is made <strong>of</strong> ivory <strong>and</strong> gold. It is the work <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Naupaktian sculptors, Menaichmos [Menaechmus] <strong>and</strong> Soidas. <strong>The</strong> evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates that these men were<br />

active not much later than the time <strong>of</strong> Kanachos <strong>of</strong> Sikyon <strong>and</strong> Kallon the Aeg<strong>in</strong>etan”; translation: Pollitt<br />

42. This Menaechmus Pollitt (42) dates to the late Archaic period, <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s (42, n. 13) that if he is the<br />

same person as the one referred to by Pl<strong>in</strong>y, then he would be the earliest sculptor known to have written<br />

about his art. Although not discard<strong>in</strong>g the chronological uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty surround<strong>in</strong>g Menaechmus, for the<br />

time be<strong>in</strong>g, this discussion treats Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s Menaechmus <strong>and</strong> Kanachos as roughly contemporaries.<br />

20


their grip, for a “tooth” on each part is so geared that when one is dislodged by<br />

pressure the other <strong>in</strong> its turn spr<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to place. (NH 34.75) [154] 26<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a Bull-calf by Menaechmus, on which a man is press<strong>in</strong>g his knee as he<br />

bends its neck back; Menaechmus has written a treatise about his own work.<br />

(NH 34.80) [155] 27<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> Kanachos, the stag dom<strong>in</strong>ates the description <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> Apollo to<br />

which it belongs, <strong>and</strong> is also the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> an astonish<strong>in</strong>g technical <strong>in</strong>novation. In the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> Menaechmus, the bull-calf seems to be the primary subject <strong>of</strong> the composition, even<br />

though the man also depicted has the advantage over the animal. <strong>The</strong> fact that both<br />

examples focus on animals as notable parts <strong>of</strong> two statues by particular sculptors is an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> animals as representational subjects <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture.<br />

But can Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s account be considered representative <strong>in</strong> any way <strong>of</strong> how animal images<br />

<strong>and</strong> artists were actually considered <strong>in</strong> late Archaic <strong>Greece</strong>? Pollitt has advanced the<br />

view that Pl<strong>in</strong>y was a compiler <strong>of</strong> tradition <strong>in</strong> ancient writ<strong>in</strong>gs on art, mean<strong>in</strong>g that the<br />

relevant section <strong>of</strong> his Natural History encapsulates traditional ideas about earlier art <strong>and</strong><br />

26 Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 34, n. 4, mentions that “[r]eproductions <strong>of</strong> this statue on co<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

small bronzes <strong>and</strong> terracottas suggest that this stag was a small object <strong>in</strong> the Apollo’s outstretched<br />

h<strong>and</strong>….<strong>The</strong> statue was taken away to Ecbatana by the Persian k<strong>in</strong>g Darius (Herodotus 6.19 <strong>and</strong> Pausanias<br />

1.16.3) but was later restored by the Hellenistic k<strong>in</strong>g Seleukos Nikator (312-281 B.C.).”<br />

27 This pose is exemplified by west metope 5 from the early <strong>Classical</strong> temple <strong>of</strong> Zeus at Olympia, which<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to J. Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period. A H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1985) fig. 22.5 depicts Heracles fight<strong>in</strong>g the Kerynitian h<strong>in</strong>d; also by metope 19 (perhaps on the north or<br />

west side) <strong>of</strong> the Athenian Treasury at Delphi, which is thought to depict the same subject: J. Boardman,<br />

Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period. A H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York 1978, repr. 1996) fig. 213.19.<br />

Boardman also notes (159) the debate over the dubious date <strong>of</strong> this build<strong>in</strong>g, whether it pre- or postdates<br />

the battle <strong>of</strong> Marathon (490 B.C.), which accord<strong>in</strong>g to Pausanias (10.11.5) was the reason for its erection.<br />

Boardman states (159) that the “subject matter <strong>of</strong> its metopes, divid<strong>in</strong>g the honor between Heracles <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong>seus, make it a good propag<strong>and</strong>a document <strong>of</strong> the new democracy,” therefore show<strong>in</strong>g his approval <strong>of</strong> a<br />

date after the battle <strong>of</strong> Marathon for the build<strong>in</strong>g. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> the metopes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Athenian treasury at Delphi <strong>and</strong> its architecture <strong>in</strong> connection with its date, see E. C. Partida, <strong>The</strong><br />

Treasuries at Delphi. An Architectural Study (Studies <strong>in</strong> Mediterranean Archaeology <strong>and</strong> Literature 160;<br />

Jonsered, Sweden, 2000) 52-53, 253. For a recent summary <strong>of</strong> studies on the Athenian Treasury, see R.<br />

Neer, “<strong>The</strong> Athenian Treasury at Delphi <strong>and</strong> the Material <strong>of</strong> Politics,” ClAnt 23 (2004) 64, n. 2. Further,<br />

the pose is exemplified by Parthenon south metope 2, where a Lapith presses his left bent knee on the body<br />

<strong>of</strong> a fight<strong>in</strong>g centaur, whose head he tries to hold back while gripp<strong>in</strong>g him with his left h<strong>and</strong> by the throat<br />

<strong>and</strong> beard. For the depiction <strong>of</strong> this scene see, J. Boardman <strong>and</strong> D. F<strong>in</strong>n, <strong>The</strong> Parthenon <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong>s<br />

(Aust<strong>in</strong>, 1985) 44; also I. Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Parthenon <strong>Sculpture</strong>s (Cambridge, Mass., 2007) 70 ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that<br />

“the Lapith’s headlock is a hold observed from real-life wrestl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the gymnasium.”<br />

21


artists to which Pl<strong>in</strong>y ga<strong>in</strong>ed access through his predecessors’ writ<strong>in</strong>gs. 28 This view<br />

suggests that the Pl<strong>in</strong>ian portrayal <strong>of</strong> Kanachos, Menaechmus, <strong>and</strong> their stag <strong>and</strong> bull-calf<br />

could be characterized both as unorig<strong>in</strong>al, <strong>and</strong> specifically as a reflection <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al<br />

Greek view <strong>of</strong> these artists through their sculptures <strong>of</strong> animals.<br />

An additional example <strong>of</strong> animal representations’ shap<strong>in</strong>g the image <strong>of</strong> their<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g artist is furnished by the horses <strong>of</strong> Kalamis, a sculptor whom Pollitt calls<br />

“the Elder” <strong>and</strong> dates to the early <strong>Classical</strong> period. 29 As part <strong>of</strong> his description <strong>of</strong> votive<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs at Olympia, Pausanias refers to a bronze ensemble <strong>of</strong> a chariot, horses, <strong>and</strong><br />

human figures dedicated by the Sicilian De<strong>in</strong>omenes <strong>in</strong> commemoration <strong>of</strong> an Olympic<br />

victory <strong>of</strong> his father, Hieron I (468 B.C.). Pausanias attributes the chariot to Onatas <strong>of</strong><br />

Aig<strong>in</strong>a, <strong>and</strong> the horses <strong>and</strong> human figures to Kalamis:<br />

Nearby is a bronze chariot <strong>and</strong> a man mounted on it; race-horses st<strong>and</strong> by the<br />

chariot, one on each side, <strong>and</strong> there are children seated on the horses. <strong>The</strong>se are<br />

memorials to the Olympic victories <strong>of</strong> Hieron the son <strong>of</strong> De<strong>in</strong>omenes, who ruled<br />

as tyrant over the Syracusans after his brother Gelon. But Hieron did not send<br />

these <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs: rather it was De<strong>in</strong>omenes the son <strong>of</strong> Hieron, who gave them to<br />

the god. <strong>The</strong> chariot was the work <strong>of</strong> Onatas <strong>of</strong> Aig<strong>in</strong>a, while the horses on<br />

either side <strong>of</strong> it <strong>and</strong> the children upon them are the works <strong>of</strong> Kalamis.<br />

(6.12.1) [138]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage states that two artists, Onatas <strong>and</strong> Kalamis, collaborated on the creation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

work <strong>of</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> fact that each <strong>of</strong> them concentrated on specific parts <strong>of</strong> the dedication,<br />

with Kalamis creat<strong>in</strong>g the horses <strong>and</strong> their riders, implies that animals partially def<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

the oeuvre <strong>of</strong> this sculptor. In this way, animals emerge as a shap<strong>in</strong>g constituent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>essional image <strong>of</strong> Kalamis. That animals are not excluded from Pausanias’s<br />

28<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this idea concern<strong>in</strong>g Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s account <strong>of</strong> ancient art, See Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong><br />

Documents 6.<br />

29<br />

For Pollitt’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction between an Elder <strong>and</strong> a Younger Kalamis, the former active <strong>in</strong> the early <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period, <strong>and</strong> the latter <strong>in</strong> the fourth century B.C., see the discussion <strong>in</strong> his Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 46-48, 85,<br />

<strong>and</strong> 94, n. 32.<br />

22


discussion <strong>of</strong> the sculpture to which they belong is an <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> his recognition <strong>of</strong><br />

their significance as subjects <strong>in</strong> the visual repertoire <strong>of</strong> classical Greek art. Also, the fact<br />

that Pausanias, like Pl<strong>in</strong>y, belongs to the compilers <strong>of</strong> tradition regard<strong>in</strong>g ancient art<br />

history may suggest that recogniz<strong>in</strong>g this significance was a traditional rather than a later,<br />

idiosyncratic trait <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g on ancient art. 30 Still, such a suggestion does not prove that<br />

both Pl<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> Pausanias were mere compilers <strong>of</strong> this tradition without actually affect<strong>in</strong>g<br />

it themselves.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> period <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture is additionally important for it provides<br />

the most eloquent example <strong>of</strong> an animal statue’s generat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> perpetuat<strong>in</strong>g the fame <strong>of</strong><br />

its artist. <strong>The</strong> fifth-century sculptor Myron, famed <strong>in</strong> modern scholarship <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

culture for his statue <strong>of</strong> the Discus-Thrower, was mostly known <strong>in</strong> antiquity for his image<br />

<strong>of</strong> a cow. 31 Two epigrams <strong>of</strong> Euenos, very probably dat<strong>in</strong>g to the fifth century B.C.,<br />

praise the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow, <strong>and</strong> are the only contemporary<br />

evidence available. <strong>The</strong> epigrams are given here, but will be discussed <strong>in</strong> detail later.<br />

Either a complete hide <strong>of</strong> bronze clothes here a<br />

real cow, or the bronze has soul <strong>in</strong> it.<br />

(Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.717) [91]<br />

Perhaps Myron himself will say this: “I did not<br />

30<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> Pausanias as a follower <strong>of</strong> the tradition <strong>in</strong> ancient writ<strong>in</strong>gs on art, see Pollitt, Sources<br />

<strong>and</strong> Documents 2.<br />

31<br />

<strong>The</strong> Discus-Thrower owes its present fame to the fact that it is the only statue <strong>of</strong> Myron that has been<br />

identified with certa<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong> extant Roman copies, an identification based on a description <strong>of</strong> one similar<br />

statue <strong>in</strong> Lucian’s Philopseudes 18: “Surely, I said, you do not speak <strong>of</strong> the discus-thrower, who is bent<br />

over <strong>in</strong>to the throw<strong>in</strong>g position, is turned toward the h<strong>and</strong> that holds the discus, <strong>and</strong> has the opposite knee<br />

gently flexed, like one who will straighten up aga<strong>in</strong> after the throw? Not that one, he said, for the<br />

Discobolos <strong>of</strong> which you speak is one <strong>of</strong> the works <strong>of</strong> Myron.” For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> this statue as “the<br />

best known today,” <strong>and</strong> the translation <strong>of</strong> the above passage, see Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 49; for<br />

this statue, <strong>and</strong> also the attempt to match other works <strong>of</strong> Myron known from the literary record (e.g.,<br />

Athena <strong>and</strong> Marsyas: Pl<strong>in</strong>y, NH 34.57) with extant Roman copies, see B. S. Ridgway, <strong>The</strong> Severe Style <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1970) 84-86; also A. Stewart, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. An Exploration (New Haven<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1990) 257, where he po<strong>in</strong>ts out the discrepancy between ancient <strong>and</strong> modern views regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Myron’s fame as an artist: “one must remember that <strong>in</strong> antiquity, though his [Myron’s] statues <strong>of</strong> men were<br />

justly renowned, his most famous work was not the Discobolos but his cow.”<br />

23


mould this heifer, but its image.”<br />

(Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.718) [92]<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g Myron <strong>and</strong> his bronze cow comes from Pl<strong>in</strong>y, who<br />

explicitly connects the fame <strong>of</strong> this artist with this animal statue:<br />

Myron, who was born at Eleutherai, <strong>and</strong> was a pupil <strong>of</strong> Ageladas, was most<br />

renowned for his statue <strong>of</strong> a heifer, a work which is praised <strong>in</strong> well-known<br />

verses—for many people ga<strong>in</strong> their reputations through someone else’s<br />

<strong>in</strong>ventiveness rather than their own. He also made a dog, a Discus-thrower, a<br />

Perseus <strong>and</strong> the sea-monster, a Satyr marvel<strong>in</strong>g at the flutes, <strong>and</strong> an Athena,<br />

contestants <strong>in</strong> the pentathlon at Delphi, pankratiasts, <strong>and</strong> a Herakles which is<br />

now <strong>in</strong> the round temple <strong>of</strong> Pompey the Great <strong>in</strong> the Circus Maximus. He also<br />

made a monument to a cicada <strong>and</strong> a locust, as Er<strong>in</strong>na <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>in</strong> her poem.<br />

(NH 34.57-34.58) [151]<br />

In addition to the celebrated statue <strong>of</strong> the heifer, the passage attributes also to Myron<br />

those <strong>of</strong> a dog <strong>and</strong>, perhaps, a cicada <strong>and</strong> a locust, if the monument mentioned here is to<br />

be equated with images <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>sects themselves. 32 Along with the famous heifer,<br />

reference to all these non-human figures by Myron <strong>in</strong>dicates that such subjects were not<br />

excluded from his oeuvre, but rather considered fundamental components <strong>of</strong> his legacy,<br />

as was the case with Kalamis. In this way, animals aga<strong>in</strong> emerge as valued subjects <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> artists’ em<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> antiquity.<br />

Myron, while the best-known case, is not the only example <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Classical</strong> artist<br />

renowned for animals. Pl<strong>in</strong>y also refers to the sculptor, Amphicrates, whose name he<br />

associates with a statue <strong>of</strong> a lioness:<br />

Amphicrates is praised for his Leaena; she was a harlot admitted to the friendship<br />

<strong>of</strong> Harmodius <strong>and</strong> Aristogeiton because <strong>of</strong> her skill as a harpist, who though put<br />

to the torture by the tyrants till she died refused to betray their plot to assass<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

32 Regard<strong>in</strong>g these <strong>in</strong>sects, Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 49, n. 9 states that “Pl<strong>in</strong>y probably presents<br />

garbled <strong>in</strong>formation here derived from a poem <strong>in</strong> the Greek Anthology (7.190) which refers to a tomb for a<br />

pet locust <strong>and</strong> a pet cicada set up by a girl named Myro.” <strong>The</strong> epigram runs as follows: “For her locust, the<br />

night<strong>in</strong>gale <strong>of</strong> the fields, <strong>and</strong> her cicada that resteth on the trees one tomb hath little Myro made, shedd<strong>in</strong>g<br />

girlish tears; for <strong>in</strong>exorable Hades hath carried <strong>of</strong>f her two pets”; translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong><br />

Greek Anthology II (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1917; repr. 1925) 109.<br />

24


them. Consequently the Athenians wish<strong>in</strong>g to do her honour <strong>and</strong> yet unwill<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

have made a harlot famous, had a statue made <strong>of</strong> a lioness, as that was her name,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to <strong>in</strong>dicate the reason for the honour paid her <strong>in</strong>structed the artist to represent<br />

the animal as hav<strong>in</strong>g no tongue. (NH 34.72) [153]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage clearly states that Amphicrates made a statue <strong>of</strong> a lioness for which he<br />

received laudatory comments. An animal aga<strong>in</strong> emerges as the celebrated subject <strong>of</strong> a<br />

work <strong>of</strong> art by an artist, whose name Pl<strong>in</strong>y considered worth record<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> passage is<br />

also important for it demonstrates the commemorative <strong>and</strong> historical function <strong>of</strong> animal<br />

statues <strong>in</strong> post-Peisistratid Athens. Thus, Amphicrates’ tongue-less lioness stood as an<br />

emblem <strong>of</strong> Leaena’s silence <strong>in</strong> connection with a historical event: the Tyrannicides’<br />

assass<strong>in</strong>ation attempt aga<strong>in</strong>st Hippias <strong>in</strong> 514 B.C.<br />

A similar account <strong>of</strong> the event is provided by Pausanias, who gives a detailed<br />

description <strong>of</strong> the historical circumstances <strong>and</strong> set-up location <strong>of</strong> the statue. Unlike Pl<strong>in</strong>y,<br />

however, Pausanias does not attribute the statue to Amphicrates, but to Kalamis, that is,<br />

an early fifth-century sculptor:<br />

When Hipparchos [the son <strong>of</strong> Peisistratos] died—<strong>and</strong> what I am say<strong>in</strong>g has never<br />

before come to be written down but is generally believed by many Athenians—<br />

Hippias tortured <strong>and</strong> killed [an Athenian woman named] Leaena [“Lioness”],<br />

know<strong>in</strong>g that she was the mistress <strong>of</strong> Aristogeiton <strong>and</strong> believ<strong>in</strong>g that there was no<br />

way <strong>in</strong> which she could have been ignorant <strong>of</strong> the plot. In reaction to this, when<br />

the tyranny <strong>of</strong> the Peisistratids came to an end, the Athenians set up a bronze<br />

lioness as a memorial to the woman, next to the image <strong>of</strong> Aphrodite, which they<br />

say, was a dedication <strong>of</strong> Kallias <strong>and</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> Kalamis. (1.23.2) [135]<br />

Further evidence directly connect<strong>in</strong>g animal subjects to renowned artists is found<br />

<strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> Strongylion, another <strong>Classical</strong> sculptor, whose fame Pausanias associates<br />

with statues <strong>of</strong> cattle <strong>and</strong> horses. Pausanias conveys this association while view<strong>in</strong>g some<br />

statues <strong>of</strong> the Muses made by this artist <strong>and</strong> placed along the road to the grove <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Muses on mount Helicon:<br />

25


<strong>The</strong> first images <strong>of</strong> the Muses are the work <strong>of</strong> Kephisodotos, all <strong>of</strong> them; a little<br />

farther on there are three more aga<strong>in</strong> by Kephisodotos, <strong>and</strong> then three others by<br />

Strongylion, an artist responsible for excellent [images <strong>of</strong>] cattle <strong>and</strong> horses.<br />

(9.30.1) [139] 33<br />

Pausanias attributes Strongylion’s fame to his excellent statues <strong>of</strong> cattle <strong>and</strong> horses, thus<br />

imply<strong>in</strong>g that the artist was exceptionally skilled <strong>in</strong> represent<strong>in</strong>g these animals. In light<br />

<strong>of</strong> this evidence, it is reasonable to assume that the concept <strong>of</strong> animalier, as seen earlier<br />

<strong>in</strong> connection with Albrecht Dürer, was not unknown <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. Further,<br />

Pausanias’s reference to Strongylion’s cattle <strong>and</strong> horses appears to be supplementary to<br />

the focal po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> his account which is the statues <strong>of</strong> the Muses at the homonymous grove<br />

on Helikon. This treatment gives the impression that the designation <strong>of</strong> Strongylion as an<br />

artist <strong>of</strong> excellent animal images was a commonly held view <strong>of</strong> him <strong>in</strong> antiquity. In this<br />

way, animals once aga<strong>in</strong> emerge as criteria <strong>of</strong> fame for ancient artists.<br />

Another equally famous <strong>Classical</strong> sculptor s<strong>in</strong>gled out by the literary record for<br />

his statues <strong>of</strong> animals is the Younger Kalamis, whom Pollitt places <strong>in</strong> the fourth century<br />

B.C. 34 Pl<strong>in</strong>y remarks this artist’s expertise <strong>in</strong> render<strong>in</strong>g horses:<br />

<strong>The</strong> k<strong>in</strong>dness also <strong>of</strong> Praxiteles is represented <strong>in</strong> sculpture, as <strong>in</strong> the Chariot <strong>and</strong><br />

Four <strong>of</strong> Calamis he contributed the charioteer, <strong>in</strong> order that the sculptor might not<br />

be thought to have failed <strong>in</strong> the human figure although more successful <strong>in</strong><br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g horses. Calamis himself also made other chariots, some with four<br />

horses <strong>and</strong> some with two, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> execut<strong>in</strong>g the horses he was <strong>in</strong>variably<br />

unrivalled. (NH 34.71) [152]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage emphasizes the view <strong>of</strong> the Younger Kalamis as an unrivalled artist <strong>of</strong><br />

statues <strong>of</strong> horses, thus strengthen<strong>in</strong>g the case that animals were valued as representational<br />

33 Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 72, n. 32 <strong>in</strong>dicates that “Kephisodotos was ma<strong>in</strong>ly active <strong>in</strong> the early<br />

fourth century B.C.” Strongylion’s career, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, he places <strong>in</strong> the late fifth <strong>and</strong> early fourth<br />

centuries B.C. A base <strong>of</strong> a statue with the signature <strong>of</strong> Strongylion as a sculptor has been found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Brauronia on the Acropolis <strong>of</strong> Athens. <strong>The</strong> base is dated to the last quarter <strong>of</strong> the fifth<br />

century B.C.: A. E. Raubitschek, Dedications from the Athenian Akropolis. A Catalogue <strong>of</strong> the Inscriptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Sixth <strong>and</strong> Fifth Centuries B.C. (Cambridge, Mass., 1949) no. 176, 208-209.<br />

34 For the Younger Kalamis, as a sculptor <strong>and</strong> silversmith active <strong>in</strong> the fourth century B.C., <strong>and</strong> perhaps, the<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>son <strong>of</strong> the Elder Kalamis, see Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents 46, 85, <strong>and</strong> 94, n. 32.<br />

26


subjects on the basis <strong>of</strong> which artistic skill was measured <strong>and</strong> fame was built <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. It also speaks <strong>of</strong> the Younger Kalamis as an animalier, therefore, plac<strong>in</strong>g him on<br />

a similar level with Strongylion. In addition, that Praxiteles contributed the charioteer to<br />

help Kalamis bridge his less exceptional ability to render human figures shows, first,<br />

collaboration between two sculptors, which recalls that <strong>of</strong> Onatas with the Elder Kalamis,<br />

<strong>and</strong> second, places animal figures on the same level <strong>of</strong> importance as human ones <strong>in</strong><br />

terms <strong>of</strong> both execution <strong>and</strong> spectatorship. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, h<strong>in</strong>ts at the prospect <strong>of</strong><br />

animal representations’ hav<strong>in</strong>g much more to <strong>of</strong>fer the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art than has<br />

previously been realized.<br />

To turn next to the realm <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, another passage <strong>of</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y refers to Nikias, a<br />

fourth-century artist, whose well-rendered images <strong>of</strong> dogs contributed to his fame <strong>in</strong><br />

antiquity:<br />

[A]t Ephesos there is a Sepulchre <strong>of</strong> a Megabyzus, the priest <strong>of</strong> Artemis at<br />

Ephesos, <strong>and</strong> at Athens the Nekyomanteia [“Invocation <strong>of</strong> the Dead”] after<br />

Homer. This picture he [Nikias] refused to sell to K<strong>in</strong>g Attalos for 60 talents<br />

<strong>and</strong> gave it rather to his home town, s<strong>in</strong>ce he had plenty <strong>of</strong> money already. He<br />

also did some large pictures, among which are a Calypso, an Io, <strong>and</strong> an<br />

Andromeda; also the very excellent Alex<strong>and</strong>er <strong>in</strong> the porticoes <strong>of</strong> Pompey <strong>and</strong> a<br />

Seated Calypso are ascribed to him. Of four-footed animals he rendered dogs the<br />

best. (NH 35.131-35.133) [159]<br />

Like Strongylion, <strong>and</strong> the Elder <strong>and</strong> Younger Kalamis, Nikias appears here as an artist<br />

known to be skilled <strong>in</strong> depict<strong>in</strong>g animals, particularly dogs. This evidence aga<strong>in</strong><br />

highlights the important role <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g the oeuvre <strong>and</strong> fame <strong>of</strong> an artist <strong>in</strong><br />

antiquity. In addition, the fact that the dog is s<strong>in</strong>gled out from Nikias’s other,<br />

unspecified images <strong>of</strong> animals clearly shows the tendency to match artistic skill with a<br />

specific animal species, as was previously the case with Strongylion (cattle <strong>and</strong> horses)<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Younger Kalamis (horses). Given its frequency, such a tendency h<strong>in</strong>ts at the<br />

27


further use <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> both Greek sculpture <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as a means <strong>of</strong> not only<br />

evaluat<strong>in</strong>g, but also classify<strong>in</strong>g artistic skill.<br />

It is clear from the ancient texts reviewed so far that animals, such as stags, cattle,<br />

horses, lions, dogs, <strong>and</strong> perhaps <strong>in</strong>sects such as locusts <strong>and</strong> cicadas were not dismissed<br />

but rather favored <strong>and</strong> valued as subjects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> both sculpture <strong>and</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. It is also clear that animals, when employed as such, became vehicles through<br />

which artistic skill was recognized, evaluated, classified <strong>and</strong>, subsequently, crystallized<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> the legacy <strong>of</strong> Greek artists <strong>in</strong> antiquity. In this way, animal representations<br />

emerge as an <strong>in</strong>tegral part <strong>of</strong> the human achievement <strong>in</strong> the arts <strong>of</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. When<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the abundance <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g animal sculpture, as remarked above by<br />

Vermeule, this evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates that the well-established, scholarly view <strong>of</strong> the animal<br />

form as secondary to the human one <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art, <strong>and</strong> its consequently justifiable<br />

neglect as a subject <strong>of</strong> modern study do not st<strong>and</strong> on solid ground.<br />

4. <strong>The</strong> Study <strong>of</strong> Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art<br />

As mentioned at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this chapter, the neglect <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> Greek art is particularly evident <strong>in</strong> the scholarly debate on naturalism. This<br />

concept has been central to the stylistic development <strong>of</strong> Greek figural art, which has been<br />

conceived <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> both a progression <strong>and</strong> progress from unsatisfactorily rendered<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the human form to (extremely) accurately rendered ones.<br />

An example <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> progression <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

art can be seen <strong>in</strong> Gisela Richter’s study <strong>of</strong> Korai <strong>of</strong> 1968, where her conclud<strong>in</strong>g remark<br />

28


<strong>of</strong> the later (Hellenistic) development <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> female figures <strong>in</strong> sculpture runs as<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

<strong>The</strong> phenomenal progression from conventionalized to more naturalistic<br />

render<strong>in</strong>gs which was atta<strong>in</strong>ed dur<strong>in</strong>g the almost 200 years that we have<br />

contemplated was to have a long future. For the first time, not only <strong>in</strong> Greek art,<br />

but <strong>in</strong> all other arts, the representation <strong>of</strong> the human figure had been freed from<br />

age-old conventions. <strong>The</strong> evolution which ensued <strong>in</strong> all branches <strong>of</strong> Greek art is<br />

well known. Here we will only, by way <strong>of</strong> an epilogue, recall a few characteristic<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> the st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, draped figure <strong>in</strong> the succeed<strong>in</strong>g periods, <strong>and</strong> watch the<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g freedom <strong>in</strong> the render<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the stance <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the drapery—for they<br />

were made possible by the achievements <strong>of</strong> the sculptors <strong>of</strong> our korai. 35<br />

Similarly, her study <strong>of</strong> 1974, Perspective <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Art, purports to<br />

describe, at least for its Greek part, “the progress made from period to period” as the<br />

Greeks made “grop<strong>in</strong>g attempts…to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> solve the manifold problems<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> “true” representation. 36<br />

<strong>The</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism (also called realism) as <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g over time<br />

until it reached the greatest possible accuracy <strong>in</strong> represent<strong>in</strong>g the human body <strong>in</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> period is l<strong>in</strong>ked to the view <strong>of</strong> the concept as the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal virtue <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

Greek art. A proponent <strong>of</strong> this view is Rhys Carpenter, whose study <strong>of</strong> 1962, Greek Art.<br />

A Study <strong>of</strong> the Formal Evolution <strong>of</strong> Style, starts from the premise that “Greek<br />

representational art <strong>in</strong> all its aspects is subject to unremitt<strong>in</strong>g pressure toward realism.” 37<br />

Later, his idea <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> sculptural (human) form, particularly <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period, is conceived <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> a process which he characterizes as:<br />

[T]horoughly consistent, almost undeviat<strong>in</strong>gly cont<strong>in</strong>uous, <strong>and</strong> is susceptible <strong>of</strong><br />

be<strong>in</strong>g epitomized <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>and</strong> simple formula. Persistent <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly<br />

35 G. M. A. Richter, Korai. Archaic Greek Maidens. A Study <strong>of</strong> the Development <strong>of</strong> the Kore Type <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> (London, 1968) 109; for an additional discussion <strong>of</strong> Richter’s passage <strong>and</strong> its connection to<br />

naturalism, see Donohue, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2005) 22-23, n. 5.<br />

36 G. M. A. Richter, Perspective <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Art (London, 1974) 21.<br />

37 R. Carpenter, Greek Art. A Study <strong>of</strong> the Formal Evolution <strong>of</strong> Style (Philadelphia, 1962) 20.<br />

29


detailed observation <strong>of</strong> natural appearances on the part <strong>of</strong> the practic<strong>in</strong>g artists led<br />

to repeated modification <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>herited tradition <strong>of</strong> the workshops <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g it closer to physical actuality, <strong>and</strong> this is the simple formula to which the<br />

Greek sculptors conformed through the late fourth <strong>and</strong> early third centuries. 38<br />

In his study <strong>of</strong> 1972, Art <strong>and</strong> Experience <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, Pollitt, <strong>in</strong> contrast,<br />

considers naturalism a characteristic <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek art, but not its primary aim:<br />

Many such [general] readers may already have read an <strong>in</strong>troductory text <strong>in</strong> which<br />

the formal development <strong>of</strong> Greek art, particularly its mastery <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly<br />

accurate representation <strong>of</strong> our optical experience <strong>of</strong> nature, is seen as its most<br />

<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> noteworthy achievement. It would be idle to deny that a<br />

development <strong>in</strong> the direction <strong>of</strong> a more naturalistic representation <strong>of</strong> anatomy,<br />

drapery <strong>and</strong> the like, is a fact <strong>of</strong> Greek art; whether it was always its aim is more<br />

doubtful. 39<br />

<strong>The</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g debate on the issue is exemplified by John Boardman’s study <strong>of</strong><br />

1985, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period, where he adheres closely to the view that<br />

naturalism was the aim <strong>of</strong> Greek art:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Archaic sculptor explored its [sc. marble] potential <strong>in</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g threedimensional<br />

patterns which represented the human body. Style evolved slowly,<br />

as technique improved, <strong>and</strong> the changes, which must have been admitted because<br />

the results were more satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the functions <strong>of</strong> the figure were thus better<br />

served, also led to render<strong>in</strong>gs which were closer to life (for the whole body at<br />

least) than any achieved by other ancient cultures. Not that there is anyth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>herently good about realism <strong>in</strong> art, but once the Greeks discovered how much<br />

more it could express than the conventions, symbols <strong>and</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> Archaism,<br />

they made a virtue <strong>of</strong> it. 40<br />

38 Carpenter, Greek Art 190.<br />

39 J. J. Pollitt, Art <strong>and</strong> Experience <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 1972) xiii; for the<br />

suggestion that the “<strong>in</strong>troductory text” referred <strong>in</strong> this statement is actually Carpenter’s Greek Art, see E. A.<br />

Meyer <strong>and</strong> J. E. Lendon, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Culture S<strong>in</strong>ce Art <strong>and</strong> Experience <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> J. M.<br />

Barr<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>and</strong> J. M. Hurwit, eds., Periklean Athens <strong>and</strong> Its Legacy. Problems <strong>and</strong> Perspectives (Aust<strong>in</strong>,<br />

2005) 256, n. 3.<br />

40 Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period 20.<br />

30


<strong>The</strong> theory that naturalism played the crucial role <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>ues to f<strong>in</strong>d place <strong>in</strong> modern scholarship, as the studies <strong>of</strong> Richard Neer (2002), Jás<br />

Elsner (2006), <strong>and</strong> Jeremy Tanner (2006) <strong>in</strong>dicate. 41<br />

With the exception <strong>of</strong> Richter’s study <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>, where, as<br />

mentioned earlier, she treats representations <strong>of</strong> animals accord<strong>in</strong>g to the same scheme <strong>of</strong><br />

advanc<strong>in</strong>g naturalism reserved for the human form, no other study <strong>of</strong> this subject <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek art has given consideration to animals. Thus, the relevant theories <strong>of</strong> Emanuel<br />

Löwy, Ernst Gombrich, John Boardman, <strong>and</strong> William Childs, which will be addressed <strong>in</strong><br />

detail shortly, focus almost exclusively on the human form. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, however, allow us<br />

to see how naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art was perceived <strong>and</strong> evaluated. Before exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this<br />

evidence, it is necessary to see, first, how the concepts <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism—<br />

usually considered a sister term—have been employed <strong>in</strong> the modern study <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

Greek art.<br />

a. <strong>The</strong> Use <strong>of</strong> “Naturalism” <strong>and</strong> “Realism” <strong>in</strong> the Modern Study <strong>of</strong> Greek Art<br />

In scholarly discussions <strong>of</strong> Greek art, the concept <strong>of</strong> naturalism is usually<br />

discussed h<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> h<strong>and</strong> with that <strong>of</strong> realism. 42 An example <strong>of</strong> this tendency is found <strong>in</strong><br />

41 R. T. Neer, Style <strong>and</strong> Politics <strong>in</strong> Athenian Vase-Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> Craft <strong>of</strong> Democracy, ca. 530-460 B.C.E.<br />

(Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2002) tries to expla<strong>in</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art, on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> vase pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> its connection with textual narrative <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>; see the review by J. Boardman<br />

<strong>in</strong> Common Knowledge 10 (2004) 353. J. Elsner, “Reflections on the ‘Greek Revolution’ <strong>in</strong> Art,” <strong>in</strong> S.<br />

Goldhill <strong>and</strong> R. Osborne, eds., Reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Revolutions through Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2006) 68, expla<strong>in</strong>s the rise <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art as: “a specific set <strong>of</strong> transformations <strong>in</strong> the<br />

subjectivity <strong>of</strong> viewers—as constructed through their confrontation with objects—that took place <strong>in</strong><br />

relation to the formal changes between archaic <strong>and</strong> classical image-mak<strong>in</strong>g.” For substantial, both literary<br />

<strong>and</strong> epigraphic, evidence, however, that presents the view<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (i.e., fifth<br />

century B.C. to second-century A.D.) as a consistent process <strong>in</strong> which the viewer created <strong>and</strong> assigned<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g to works <strong>of</strong> art through active discourse, see T. J. Rusnak, Jr., “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator: Art <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Viewer <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>” (diss. Bryn Mawr College, 2001). J. Tanner’s study, <strong>The</strong> Invention <strong>of</strong> Art<br />

History <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Religion, Society <strong>and</strong> Artistic Rationalisation (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2006), is a broad discussion <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> the “Greek Revolution” based on a<br />

sociological approach; for its review, see A. A. Donohue <strong>in</strong> CW 101.1 (2007) 109-110.<br />

31


Pollitt’s work. As noted earlier, Pollitt does not subscribe to the scholarly view <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism as the aim <strong>of</strong> Greek art. <strong>The</strong> rejection <strong>of</strong> this view is also found <strong>in</strong> his study <strong>of</strong><br />

1974, <strong>The</strong> Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Greek Art, where he speaks <strong>of</strong> naturalism as one <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

critical concepts (the other one be<strong>in</strong>g idealism) that have shaped our judgment <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

art s<strong>in</strong>ce the Renaissance. 43 His statement implies that the importance placed upon Greek<br />

naturalism as a st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> qualitative criticism derives from modern rather than ancient<br />

reality. <strong>The</strong> same view is also exemplified by his def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> naturalism as a concept:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> idea that the great achievement <strong>of</strong> Greek art was to represent nature as it really is<br />

(or at least to simulate our optical experience <strong>of</strong> it), rather than to represent it by<br />

schematic formulas, is probably a direct outgrowth <strong>of</strong> the rise <strong>of</strong> scientific archaeology <strong>in</strong><br />

the last one hundred years.” 44<br />

Pollitt’s l<strong>in</strong>k between the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> scientific archaeology is<br />

<strong>in</strong>structive, for it allows a comment on how problematic the <strong>in</strong>terpretative framework <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism is when identified with accurate reproduction <strong>of</strong> natural forms (“nature as it<br />

really is” or appears) as an apparently objective criterion <strong>of</strong> scientific (empirical)<br />

observation. 45 It has been remarked, however, that even scientific papers are not devoid<br />

<strong>of</strong> unbiased observation because “[w]hat we see or otherwise sense is a function <strong>of</strong> what<br />

42<br />

This treatment is not unique to the scholarship on ancient Greek art. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the vagueness <strong>of</strong><br />

the term “naturalism,” how it affects scholarship on art <strong>in</strong> general, <strong>and</strong> its perceived affiliation with<br />

“realism” see F. Novotny, “Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Art,” <strong>in</strong> P. P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas III<br />

(New York, 1973) 339-340.<br />

43<br />

J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Greek Art: Criticism, History, <strong>and</strong> Term<strong>in</strong>ology (New Haven <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1974) 3.<br />

44<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 4-5.<br />

45<br />

For a recent discussion <strong>of</strong> the empirical process as a convention <strong>of</strong> apparently direct <strong>and</strong> neutral<br />

description <strong>of</strong> material <strong>in</strong> archaeological scholarship <strong>and</strong> its consequences, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong><br />

Description 17-18.<br />

32


we have seen or sensed <strong>in</strong> the past,” 46 a realization which, when applied to art history,<br />

br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d He<strong>in</strong>rich Wölffl<strong>in</strong>’s famous dictum that because “men have<br />

always seen what they wished to see,” therefore, “[v]ision itself has its history.” 47 <strong>The</strong><br />

implication <strong>of</strong> such remarks is that objective vision does not exist, <strong>and</strong> therefore, when<br />

we equate the concept <strong>of</strong> naturalism with accurate reproduction <strong>of</strong> our optical experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature, it does not necessarily mean that we have decoded the ancient Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> either the concept or the optical experience it entailed.<br />

Pollitt’s attitude <strong>of</strong> downplay<strong>in</strong>g Greek naturalism is further seen <strong>in</strong> his assertion<br />

that the concept probably had some validity as a basis for judg<strong>in</strong>g Greek art <strong>in</strong> antiquity,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce it was present <strong>in</strong> the critical term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>of</strong> the arts, but, at certa<strong>in</strong> times, it was<br />

surpassed by other concepts (e.g., φαντασία) <strong>in</strong> importance. 48 Pollitt does not, at this<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> his <strong>in</strong>troductory essay, either identify these concepts, or give the ancient Greek<br />

term for naturalism. He does, however, consider “realism,” which he equates with the<br />

ancient concept <strong>of</strong> mimesis, to be one <strong>of</strong> the three popular criteria (the other two be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

miraculous qualities <strong>and</strong> costl<strong>in</strong>ess) for judg<strong>in</strong>g art <strong>in</strong> antiquity. 49 It is difficult to discern<br />

from this treatment how exactly the two concepts are related <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g realism, he states that it “is simply a popular, un<strong>in</strong>tellectual version <strong>of</strong><br />

the mimesis idea <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> philosophy. Its st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> judgment is the feel<strong>in</strong>g that the<br />

best works <strong>of</strong> art are those which simulate the external world with such uncanny<br />

46 Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 18 cit<strong>in</strong>g A. B. Medewar, “Is the Scientific Paper a Fraud?” <strong>The</strong><br />

Listener 70, no. 1798 (September 12, 1963) 377.<br />

47 H. Wölffl<strong>in</strong>, tr. M. D. Hott<strong>in</strong>ger, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Art History. <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> the Development <strong>of</strong> Style <strong>in</strong><br />

Later Art (1932; repr. New York, 1950) viii <strong>and</strong> 11.<br />

48 Pollitt, Ancient View 6.<br />

49 Pollitt, Ancient View 63.<br />

33


exactitude that the boundary between art <strong>and</strong> life breaks down.” 50 <strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> the words<br />

“popular” <strong>and</strong> “un<strong>in</strong>tellectual” <strong>in</strong> his def<strong>in</strong>ition implies that only the lower <strong>and</strong><br />

uneducated strata <strong>of</strong> society were absorbed <strong>in</strong> what he perceives as the realism <strong>of</strong> works<br />

<strong>of</strong> art. 51 Such a suggestion trivializes realism as a criterion <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> antiquity. It<br />

may be <strong>in</strong> accordance with “the ancient assumption that it is the ignorant or naïve viewer<br />

who admires or is deceived by the realism <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art,” 52 but fails to underscore the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> ancient literature that reveals a conscious underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> view<strong>in</strong>g realistic<br />

art <strong>and</strong> identifies only two specific groups <strong>of</strong> viewers—children <strong>and</strong> fools—as be<strong>in</strong>g truly<br />

susceptible to artistic deception <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> thought is illustrated, for<br />

example, <strong>in</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g between Socrates <strong>and</strong> Glaucon <strong>in</strong> Plato’s Republic:<br />

SOCRATES. To which is pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g directed <strong>in</strong> every case, to the imitation <strong>of</strong><br />

reality as it is or <strong>of</strong> appearance as it appears?<br />

GLAUCON. Is it an imitation <strong>of</strong> a phantasm or <strong>of</strong> the truth? “Of a phantasm,” he<br />

said.<br />

SOCRATES. <strong>The</strong>n the mimetic art is far removed from truth, <strong>and</strong> this, it seems, is<br />

the reason why it can produce everyth<strong>in</strong>g, because it touches or lays hold <strong>of</strong> only<br />

a small part <strong>of</strong> the object <strong>and</strong> that a phantom; as, for example, a pa<strong>in</strong>ter, we say,<br />

will pa<strong>in</strong>t us a cobbler, a carpenter, <strong>and</strong> other craftsmen, though he himself has no<br />

expertness <strong>in</strong> any <strong>of</strong> these arts, but nevertheless if he were a good pa<strong>in</strong>ter, by<br />

exhibit<strong>in</strong>g at a distance his picture <strong>of</strong> a carpenter he would deceive children <strong>and</strong><br />

foolish men, <strong>and</strong> make them believe it to be a real carpenter.<br />

(Resp. 598b-598c) [150]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage clearly identifies children <strong>and</strong> fools as two specific categories <strong>of</strong> viewers<br />

easily deceived by a good, that is, realistic pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. It thus suggests that all other<br />

viewers, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Socrates, admired realistic works <strong>of</strong> art, while be<strong>in</strong>g completely aware<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fact that they were look<strong>in</strong>g at art. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, implies that realism was a<br />

50<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 63.<br />

51<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> such an implicit mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Pollitt’s def<strong>in</strong>ition, see Rusnak, “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator”<br />

35.<br />

52<br />

Rusnak, “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator” 36, n. 95, where he mentions Plato, Republic 601a, 602b, Menexenus<br />

234b, <strong>and</strong> Sophist 234b-c as examples.<br />

34


valued criterion <strong>of</strong> judg<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> not necessarily bound to the level <strong>of</strong><br />

education <strong>of</strong> viewers.<br />

As seen above, Pollitt equates realism with mimesis. He also po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the<br />

latter is usually translated as “imitation.” 53 Mimesis, however, is a complex concept <strong>and</strong><br />

its translation as “imitation” has been considered mislead<strong>in</strong>g for reach<strong>in</strong>g a useful<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its ancient mean<strong>in</strong>g. 54 Pollitt ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that, when applied to the visual<br />

arts, mimesis “usually implied someth<strong>in</strong>g beyond the simple process <strong>of</strong> copy<strong>in</strong>g a natural<br />

model.” 55 His discussion focuses on the Platonic <strong>and</strong> Aristotelian uses <strong>of</strong> the term as<br />

“literal imitation” <strong>and</strong> “imitation by psychological association” <strong>and</strong> draws extensively<br />

from Gerald Else’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> early fifth-century<br />

literature. 56<br />

In a more recent discussion (2002) <strong>of</strong> mimesis <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, Stephen<br />

Halliwell considers the possibility, drawn by Aristotle’s emphasis on “th<strong>in</strong>gs that could<br />

occur,” (Poetics 9.1451b5), that works or acts <strong>of</strong> artistic mimesis need not always be<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> as correspond<strong>in</strong>g to specific, empirical “orig<strong>in</strong>als.” He states, therefore, that<br />

“when applied to poetry, visual art, music, dance, <strong>and</strong> the like [<strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>],<br />

mimesis amounts to a concept (or family <strong>of</strong> concepts) <strong>of</strong> representation, which…can be<br />

broadly construed as the use <strong>of</strong> an artistic medium (words, sounds, physical images) to<br />

53<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 37.<br />

54<br />

S. Halliwell, <strong>The</strong> Aesthetics <strong>of</strong> Mimesis. Ancient Texts <strong>and</strong> Modern Problems (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton <strong>and</strong> Oxford,<br />

2002) 6, n. 15, <strong>and</strong> 13, 16.<br />

55<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 37.<br />

56<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 37-38 cit<strong>in</strong>g G. F. Else, ““Imitation” <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century,” CP 53 (1958) 73-90,<br />

who identifies three shades <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g for mimesis <strong>and</strong> its cognates prior to mid-fifth century B.C.: a)<br />

“direct representation <strong>of</strong> the looks, actions <strong>and</strong>/or utterances <strong>of</strong> animals or men through speech, song,<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or danc<strong>in</strong>g,” b) “imitation <strong>of</strong> the actions <strong>of</strong> one person by another, <strong>in</strong> a general sense, without actual<br />

mim<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> c) “replication: an image or effigy <strong>of</strong> a person or th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> material form.” For a subsequent<br />

study <strong>of</strong> mimesis, see G. Sörbom, Mimesis <strong>and</strong> Art. Studies <strong>in</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Early Development <strong>of</strong> an<br />

Aesthetic Vocabulary (Uppsala, 1966). For Pollitt’s discussion <strong>of</strong> Plato’s <strong>and</strong> Aristotle’s use <strong>of</strong> mimesis,<br />

see Ancient View 38-41.<br />

35


signify <strong>and</strong> communicate certa<strong>in</strong> hypothesized realities,” <strong>and</strong> also as the effects that such<br />

works can or should elicit <strong>in</strong> their audiences. 57 This def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>in</strong>dicates that mimesis is a<br />

broad <strong>and</strong> complex concept. As such, it cannot be equated with realism, which Pollitt<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>s as simulation <strong>of</strong> the external world based on “uncanny exactitude.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> conta<strong>in</strong>ed element <strong>of</strong> “uncanny exactitude” which Pollitt attaches to realism<br />

is additionally <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g, for it appears to reflect <strong>in</strong>fluence from the n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> realism <strong>in</strong> French literature: “faithful imitation <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>als <strong>of</strong>fered by<br />

nature with special emphasis on exactitude <strong>of</strong> description.” 58 It also suggests that Pollitt<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>s realism as perhaps a stronger version <strong>of</strong> naturalism, which, as seen earlier, he<br />

considers an attempt to simulate our optical experience <strong>of</strong> nature. Thus, <strong>in</strong> Pollitt’s m<strong>in</strong>d,<br />

it appears that what separates the two concepts from each other is a difference <strong>of</strong> degree.<br />

Such difference also shapes another explanation <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism <strong>in</strong> the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>of</strong>fered by William Childs. In his essay <strong>of</strong> 1988, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as<br />

Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” Childs argues aga<strong>in</strong>st the usual assumption that “idealism” is a<br />

def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g element <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art, <strong>in</strong> particular, sculpture. He states<br />

that the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture “is primarily realistic.” When discuss<strong>in</strong>g<br />

works <strong>of</strong> art belong<strong>in</strong>g to its high phase (450-430 B.C.), however, he argues that they<br />

demonstrate “a more accurate observation <strong>of</strong> real forms, generally speak<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>creased<br />

naturalism.” 59 Such phras<strong>in</strong>g suggests that Childs considers realism <strong>and</strong> naturalism as<br />

two concepts <strong>of</strong> the same mean<strong>in</strong>g but different degree. Thus, naturalism is, to him, a<br />

57<br />

Halliwell, <strong>The</strong> Aesthetics <strong>of</strong> Mimesis 16.<br />

58<br />

R. Wellek, “Realism <strong>in</strong> Literature,” <strong>in</strong> P. P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas IV (New<br />

York, 1973) 51-52.<br />

59<br />

W. A. P. Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” Art Journal 48 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 1988) 10, <strong>and</strong> 11-12 for<br />

respective quotations.<br />

36


more accurate observation <strong>and</strong> render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> real forms, a def<strong>in</strong>ition which qualifies the<br />

concept as a stronger version <strong>of</strong> realism. On the basis <strong>of</strong> this reason<strong>in</strong>g, his designation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> style as “generally realistic” reveals his conception <strong>of</strong> realism as general<br />

conformity to nature. 60 Childs’s limitation <strong>of</strong> realism <strong>and</strong> naturalism to these mean<strong>in</strong>gs is<br />

not idiosyncratic, but rather rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> these terms <strong>in</strong> modern<br />

German. As Fritz Novotny ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>in</strong> this language, realism is used for the more<br />

general mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any sort <strong>of</strong> fidelity to nature—<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the subject matter <strong>of</strong> works<br />

<strong>of</strong> art, whereas naturalism is reserved for works <strong>in</strong> which realism is carried to the<br />

extreme, for example, <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> detail. 61 When juxtaposed to Pollitt’s<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> these concepts, those <strong>of</strong> Childs appear to be the exact reverse.<br />

<strong>The</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> Childs <strong>and</strong> Pollitt reveal that, <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art, the<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism are not always used with consistent mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y also reveal that the perceived difference <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> these terms is one <strong>of</strong><br />

degree identified as an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> exactitude or accuracy. <strong>The</strong> problem here is that no<br />

one wishes to state clearly where exactly this designation <strong>of</strong> degree beg<strong>in</strong>s or ends. As a<br />

result, naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism emerge as two highly ambiguous, <strong>and</strong> thus, problematic<br />

concepts for the study <strong>of</strong> Greek art.<br />

Although not <strong>in</strong> reference to Greek art, current, art-historical discourse highlights<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> still another semantic difference between naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism. David<br />

60 It has to be noted that Childs also po<strong>in</strong>ts to specific visual features (e.g., ve<strong>in</strong>s, muscles) <strong>of</strong><br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the human form <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture; therefore his argument is not simply a<br />

semantic game.<br />

61 Novotny, “Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Art,” <strong>in</strong> Wiener, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas III, 339.<br />

37


Summers, for example, <strong>of</strong>fers the follow<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the two concepts <strong>in</strong> his<br />

study <strong>of</strong> Renaissance pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

“Naturalism” refers to art—the paradigm is really the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as opposed<br />

to sculpture or architecture—the elements <strong>of</strong> which are presumed to co<strong>in</strong>cide with<br />

the elements <strong>of</strong> optical experience. “Naturalism” <strong>and</strong> “realism” are sometimes<br />

used <strong>in</strong>terchangeably, but it is necessary to dist<strong>in</strong>guish carefully between them.<br />

“Realism” is at base a category <strong>of</strong> subject matter, <strong>and</strong> refers to art hav<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

concrete historical reference or an apparent concrete historical reference. 62<br />

Summers’s def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> naturalism rests on representational fidelity to the sensible<br />

world, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> realism on a concrete historical reference. Thus, <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, the<br />

difference between the two concepts is one <strong>of</strong> appearance (style) versus subject matter<br />

(content). When transferred to the realm <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, Pausanias’s<br />

description <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Battle <strong>of</strong> Marathon <strong>in</strong> the Stoa Poikile <strong>in</strong> Athens<br />

(1.15.3), for example, could be seen as a representative example <strong>of</strong> Summers’s perception<br />

<strong>of</strong> realism. Whether ancient audiences made such a dist<strong>in</strong>ction is an issue worth not<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Summers’s def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> naturalism, although not devoid <strong>of</strong> vagueness, has its real<br />

value <strong>in</strong> the fact that, like that <strong>of</strong> Pollitt, it gives central stage to “optical experience,” <strong>and</strong><br />

thus, vision. Equally valuable is his remark that “naturalism <strong>in</strong> any given <strong>in</strong>stance is<br />

culturally specific.” 63 This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g accords well with the previously mentioned<br />

dictum <strong>of</strong> Wölffl<strong>in</strong> that “vision itself has its history.” In this way, both authors signal that<br />

naturalism is not to be seen as bound to a universal law <strong>of</strong> objective vision, s<strong>in</strong>ce such a<br />

th<strong>in</strong>g does not exist, but rather to the specific cultural sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which it is formulated.<br />

This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, gives rise to one question <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> Greek art: How were<br />

the qualities to which we assign terms like naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism <strong>in</strong> art perceived <strong>and</strong><br />

62<br />

D. Summers, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Judgment</strong> <strong>of</strong> Sense. Renaissance Naturalism <strong>and</strong> the Rise <strong>of</strong> Aesthetics (London <strong>and</strong><br />

New York, 1987) 3.<br />

63<br />

Summers, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Judgment</strong> <strong>of</strong> Sense 11.<br />

38


judged by the ancient Greeks? As suggested earlier, extant literary evidence strongly<br />

suggests that animals can <strong>of</strong>fer a valuable <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to this question.<br />

b. Modern <strong>The</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> the Development <strong>of</strong> Greek Art <strong>in</strong> Terms <strong>of</strong> Naturalism<br />

First, however, it is necessary to exam<strong>in</strong>e modern theories <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek art <strong>in</strong> connection with naturalism. Four figures are particularly significant <strong>in</strong> this<br />

connection: Emanuel Löwy, Ernst Gombrich, John Boardman, <strong>and</strong> William Childs. <strong>The</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g section discusses the theories <strong>of</strong> these scholars as well as the different<br />

conceptions—psychological, historical, technical, <strong>and</strong> art-historical—that shaped them.<br />

With the exception <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Childs’s, the common element <strong>of</strong> the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g theories is<br />

that dissatisfaction <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greeks with how <strong>in</strong>sufficiently naturalistic their art<br />

looked provided the impetus for the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art toward naturalism. <strong>The</strong><br />

human figure is the focus <strong>of</strong> all these theories.<br />

Emanuel Löwy<br />

In his study, Die Naturwiedergrabe <strong>in</strong> der älteren griechischen Kunst (1900),<br />

Emanuel Löwy <strong>of</strong>fers an account <strong>of</strong> preclassical Greek art (draw<strong>in</strong>g, sculpture) framed by<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> are marg<strong>in</strong>al to this account, which is<br />

dom<strong>in</strong>ated by the idea that “statuary [is], <strong>in</strong> its pr<strong>in</strong>cipal task, the representation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human form.” 64 Löwy expla<strong>in</strong>s the creation <strong>of</strong> artistic forms <strong>in</strong> early Greek art as the<br />

64 E. Löwy, Die Naturwiedergrabe <strong>in</strong> der älteren griechischen Kunst (Rome, 1900) = E. Loewy, tr. E.<br />

Fothergill, <strong>The</strong> Render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Nature <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art (London, 1907) 45. This statement identifies Löwy<br />

as a possible source for Richter’s previously expressed comment that, <strong>in</strong> her time, exist<strong>in</strong>g scholarship<br />

considered the human figure the sole focus <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek sculpture. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong><br />

Löwy’s lectures <strong>in</strong> Rome to Richter’s scholarly program, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 111-<br />

112, n. 275.<br />

39


esult <strong>of</strong> a psychological process <strong>of</strong> visual perception to which he assigns universal status.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to this process, artistic images are not direct render<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> reality, but rather<br />

reproductions <strong>of</strong> mental images <strong>of</strong> this reality:<br />

<strong>The</strong> process described rules our conception <strong>of</strong> images, <strong>and</strong> the more primitive the<br />

conception the more unlimited its rule. Instances <strong>of</strong> these we can see every day <strong>in</strong><br />

the draw<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> persons artistically untra<strong>in</strong>ed, not merely <strong>in</strong> those <strong>of</strong> children <strong>and</strong><br />

savages. <strong>The</strong>ir draw<strong>in</strong>gs do not copy a given aspect <strong>of</strong> reality. <strong>The</strong>se simple<br />

draughtsmen, when placed <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> the object itself, would be for the most part<br />

quite <strong>in</strong>capable <strong>of</strong> render<strong>in</strong>g it directly. For along with the pictures that reality<br />

presents to the eye, there exists another world <strong>of</strong> images, liv<strong>in</strong>g or com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to life<br />

<strong>in</strong> our m<strong>in</strong>ds alone, which, though <strong>in</strong>deed suggested reality, are nevertheless<br />

metamorphosed. Every primitive artist, when endeavour<strong>in</strong>g to imitate nature,<br />

seeks with the spontaneity <strong>of</strong> a physical function to reproduce merely these<br />

mental images. And so it was with the Greek artist. 65<br />

Löwy proposes that mental images, although “suggested by reality,” are essentially<br />

falsified versions <strong>of</strong> this reality created <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed by the m<strong>in</strong>d. <strong>The</strong>y coexist with<br />

images directly perceived by the eye but override them; as such, mental images guide the<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> reality <strong>in</strong> art. Löwy believes that this psychological process <strong>of</strong> visual<br />

perception accounts for the falsification <strong>of</strong> natural forms <strong>in</strong> all primitive art. On the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the universality <strong>of</strong> this process, he implies next that the <strong>in</strong>sufficiently naturalistic<br />

images <strong>of</strong> early Greek art are the result <strong>of</strong> artists’ subord<strong>in</strong>ation to this process. In this<br />

way, Löwy establishes the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> his approach to Greek art through the lens <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism.<br />

Specific evidence for Löwy’s view <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism not as static, but<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> degree through time is seen <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the subsequent phase <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek figural art—the Archaic. Löwy sees this phase as a step away from the<br />

<strong>in</strong>sufficiently naturalistic images <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>cipient Greek phase. <strong>The</strong> psychology <strong>of</strong> vision<br />

65 Loewy, Render<strong>in</strong>g 17-18. For a more detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> Löwy’s theory <strong>of</strong> the psychology <strong>of</strong> vision,<br />

with special emphasis on his borrow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> the memory image from slightly earlier writ<strong>in</strong>gs on<br />

psychology, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 115-117.<br />

40


is still central to his argument, but a new element is added now: artists’ dissatisfaction<br />

with exist<strong>in</strong>g mental images. This condition, he asserts, led to closer observation <strong>of</strong><br />

nature, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, gave rise to <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly naturalistic images <strong>in</strong> Archaic art:<br />

It is worth while to note the manner <strong>in</strong> which art, when strong enough to observe,<br />

turns to account its observations <strong>of</strong> nature. For this it appears to me specially<br />

significant that <strong>in</strong> the more developed archaic period, as has <strong>of</strong>ten been noticed,<br />

there is a relatively greater conformity to nature <strong>in</strong> the representations <strong>of</strong> objects<br />

less commonly seen, as <strong>of</strong> animals rather than <strong>of</strong> men, particularly those animals<br />

with which men are not daily associated, <strong>of</strong> men <strong>of</strong> foreign races rather than those<br />

<strong>of</strong> their own k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>and</strong> so on. In all these cases the artists had not at once at their<br />

disposal a more or less satisfactory memory-picture, <strong>and</strong> so be<strong>in</strong>g compelled to<br />

observe nature they imitated her closely. But it must not therefore be supposed<br />

that these productions represent pictures made on the spot; judged by their entire<br />

structure, the typical generalization <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e, the exhibition <strong>of</strong> the fullest aspect <strong>and</strong><br />

so on, they too betray themselves as be<strong>in</strong>g memory-pictures assimilated to the<br />

common store although consciously acquired. 66<br />

Löwy expla<strong>in</strong>s the <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Archaic Greek art as a reaction to<br />

dissatisfaction with previous conceptual images. His argument unfolds <strong>in</strong> a circular way.<br />

He starts first by acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g the exp<strong>and</strong>ed repertoire <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism <strong>of</strong><br />

subjects <strong>in</strong> Archaic art, where animals are <strong>in</strong>cluded, but mentioned only fleet<strong>in</strong>gly. Löwy<br />

attributes these new conditions to the unavailability <strong>of</strong> satisfactory mental images, which,<br />

he asserts, exhorted artists to observe nature closely, transformed mental images, <strong>and</strong>, as<br />

such, launched the emergence <strong>of</strong> Archaic images <strong>of</strong> “greater conformity to nature.” This<br />

characterization along with the call<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Archaic period as “more developed”<br />

consolidate Löwy’s view <strong>of</strong> this period as a step beyond <strong>of</strong> the earlier one, <strong>and</strong><br />

consequently, <strong>of</strong> preclassical Greek art as a successive advancement <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism.<br />

66 Translation: Fothergill: Loewy, Render<strong>in</strong>g 26-27.<br />

41


Ernst H. Gombrich<br />

A similar, yet more advanced, account <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism appears <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Ernst Gombrich. His essay <strong>of</strong> 1961,<br />

Reflections on the Greek Revolution, makes use <strong>of</strong> Löwy’s ideas <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism<br />

<strong>and</strong> dissatisfaction. 67 Like Löwy, Gombrich is concerned with the development <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

art as a passage from early, <strong>in</strong>sufficient naturalistic images to “the gradual approximation<br />

<strong>of</strong> images to life.” 68 Unlike Löwy, his discussion extends to encompass <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

art, which, he considers, highly naturalistic. This conviction stems from his view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> period as the p<strong>in</strong>nacle <strong>of</strong> a “revolution,” a “great awaken<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> Greek art—the<br />

advent <strong>of</strong> naturalism—whose beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs he places <strong>in</strong> the Archaic period (ca. 550 B.C.),<br />

<strong>and</strong> reasons he seeks to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> connection with contemporary cultural circumstances<br />

such as the rise <strong>of</strong> philosophy, science, <strong>and</strong> drama; thus, Gombrich’s theory emerges as<br />

clearly historical <strong>in</strong> essence. As was the case with Löwy, animals are not prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> it.<br />

Instead, the idea that, “Greek art <strong>of</strong> the classical period concentrated on the image <strong>of</strong> man<br />

almost to an exclusion <strong>of</strong> other motifs,” 69 dom<strong>in</strong>ates Gombrich’s theory, which unfolds <strong>in</strong><br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g way:<br />

[T]here are few more excit<strong>in</strong>g spectacles <strong>in</strong> the whole history <strong>of</strong> art than<br />

the great awaken<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g between the sixth century<br />

<strong>and</strong> the time <strong>of</strong> Plato’s youth toward the end <strong>of</strong> the fifth century B.C. Its dramatic<br />

phases have <strong>of</strong>ten been told <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the episode from “<strong>The</strong> Sleep<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>in</strong>cess”<br />

when the kiss <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>in</strong>ce breaks the thous<strong>and</strong>-year-old spell <strong>and</strong> the whole court<br />

beg<strong>in</strong>s to stir from the rigors <strong>of</strong> unnatural sleep. We are shown how the stiff <strong>and</strong><br />

frozen figures we call Apoll<strong>in</strong>es, or kouroi, first move one foot forward, then bend<br />

their arms, how their masklike smile s<strong>of</strong>tens, <strong>and</strong> how, at the time <strong>of</strong> the Persian<br />

67 E. H. Gombrich, “Reflections on the Greek Revolution,” <strong>in</strong> E. H. Gombrich, Art <strong>and</strong> Illusion: A Study <strong>in</strong><br />

the Psychology <strong>of</strong> Pictorial Representation (New York, 1961), a study dedicated to his teachers: E. Löwy,<br />

J. von Schlosser, <strong>and</strong> E. Kris. For an additional discussion <strong>of</strong> Löwy’s effect on Gombrich, see Donohue,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 112, n. 276.<br />

68 Gombrich, Reflections 117.<br />

69 Gombrich, Reflections 144.<br />

42


wars, the symmetry <strong>of</strong> their tense posture is f<strong>in</strong>ally broken when their bodies<br />

receive a slight twist, so that life seems to enter the marble…<br />

It is a development which neatly illustrates our formulas <strong>of</strong> schema <strong>and</strong><br />

correction, <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g before match<strong>in</strong>g. Indeed it was <strong>in</strong> this area that Emanuel<br />

Loewy at the turn <strong>of</strong> the century first developed his theories about the render<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature <strong>in</strong> Greek art that stressed the priority <strong>of</strong> conceptual modes <strong>and</strong> their<br />

gradual adjustment to natural appearances. Archaic art starts from the schema,<br />

the symmetrical frontal figure conceived for one aspect only, <strong>and</strong> the conquest <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism may be described as the gradual accumulation <strong>of</strong> corrections due to the<br />

observation <strong>of</strong> reality.<br />

As a description <strong>of</strong> what happened, Loewy’s account still seems to me<br />

unsurpassed. But <strong>in</strong> itself it expla<strong>in</strong>s little. For why was it that this process<br />

started comparatively so late <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> mank<strong>in</strong>d? In this respect our<br />

perspectives have very much changed. To the Greeks the archaic period<br />

represented the dawn <strong>of</strong> history, <strong>and</strong> classical scholarship has not always shaken<br />

<strong>of</strong>f this <strong>in</strong>heritance. From this po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view it appeared quite natural that the<br />

awaken<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> art from primitive modes should have co<strong>in</strong>cided with the rise <strong>of</strong> all<br />

those other activities that, for the humanist, belong to civilization: the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> philosophy, <strong>of</strong> science, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> dramatic poetry. 70<br />

As can be seen, Gombrich is <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g the reasons beh<strong>in</strong>d the transition<br />

from “mak<strong>in</strong>g” to “match<strong>in</strong>g” as a “gradual accumulation <strong>of</strong> corrections” that is, from<br />

Löwy’s unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g conceptual images to <strong>Classical</strong> images that reproduce perfectly the<br />

visible world through its careful observation. Such phraseology sheds lights on<br />

Gombrich’s conception <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> style as strict imitation <strong>of</strong> the visible world. Equally illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

his identification <strong>of</strong> specific circumstances beh<strong>in</strong>d the advent <strong>of</strong> this style: artists’<br />

dissatisfaction with exist<strong>in</strong>g images <strong>and</strong> a change <strong>in</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> Greek art caused by<br />

narrative texts (Homer). Although concurrent with the advent <strong>of</strong> other cultural<br />

phenomena (philosophy, science, drama), these circumstances are <strong>of</strong> foremost importance<br />

<strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

Like Löwy, Gombrich considers dissatisfaction with exist<strong>in</strong>g images the impetus<br />

<strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art toward naturalism. “As soon as the Greeks looked at the<br />

70 Gombrich, Reflections 116-118.<br />

43


Egyptian figure type from the aspect <strong>of</strong> an art which wants to “conv<strong>in</strong>ce,” it undoubtedly<br />

raised the question why it looks unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g,” he says. 71 Thus, discontent with the<br />

unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images they <strong>in</strong>herited from the arts <strong>of</strong> Egypt <strong>and</strong> the Near East, early Greek<br />

artists turned to close observation <strong>of</strong> nature—an idea clearly borrowed from Löwy—but<br />

also to acquire skilled craftsmanship. A detailed account <strong>of</strong> this argument, with special<br />

emphasis on sculpture, appears not <strong>in</strong> the Reflections, but <strong>in</strong> <strong>The</strong> Great Awaken<strong>in</strong>g, which<br />

is part <strong>of</strong> his earlier study, <strong>The</strong> Story <strong>of</strong> Art (1951):<br />

When Greek artists began to make statues <strong>of</strong> stone, they started where the<br />

Egyptians <strong>and</strong> Assyrians had left <strong>of</strong>f…[T]hey studied <strong>and</strong> imitated Egyptian<br />

models, <strong>and</strong>…they learned from them how to make the figure <strong>of</strong> a st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g young<br />

man, how to mark the divisions <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>and</strong> the muscles which hold it<br />

together. But…the artist who made th[ese] statue[s] was not content to follow<br />

any formula, however good, <strong>and</strong> that he began experiment<strong>in</strong>g for himself. He was<br />

obviously <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g out what knees really looked like. Perhaps he did<br />

not quite succeed; perhaps the knees <strong>of</strong> his statue are even less conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g than<br />

those <strong>of</strong> Egyptian statues; but the po<strong>in</strong>t was that he had decided to have a look for<br />

himself <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g the old prescription. It was no longer a question <strong>of</strong><br />

learn<strong>in</strong>g a ready-made formula for represent<strong>in</strong>g the human body. Every Greek<br />

sculptor wanted to know how he was to represent a particular body. <strong>The</strong><br />

Egyptians had based their art on knowledge. <strong>The</strong> Greeks began to use their eyes.<br />

Once this revolution had begun, there was no stopp<strong>in</strong>g it. <strong>The</strong> sculptors <strong>in</strong> their<br />

workshops tried new ideas <strong>and</strong> new ways <strong>of</strong> represent<strong>in</strong>g the human figure, <strong>and</strong><br />

each <strong>in</strong>novation was eagerly taken by others who added to their own discoveries.<br />

One discovered how to chisel the trunk, another found out that a statue many look<br />

much more alive if the feet are not placed too firmly on the ground. Yet another<br />

would discover that he could make a face come alive by simply bend<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

mouth upwards so that it appeared to smile. Of course, the Egyptian method was<br />

<strong>in</strong> many ways safer. <strong>The</strong> experiments <strong>of</strong> the Greek artists sometimes misfired.<br />

<strong>The</strong> smile might look like an embarrassed gr<strong>in</strong>, or the less rigid stance might give<br />

the impression <strong>of</strong> affectation. But the Greek artists were not easily frightened by<br />

these difficulties. <strong>The</strong>y had set out on a road on which there was no turn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

back. 72<br />

That the Greek revolution aga<strong>in</strong>st unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images moved only forward <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

that, <strong>in</strong> Gombrich’s view, the naturalistic development <strong>of</strong> Greek art, throughout its early,<br />

71 Gombrich, Reflections 134.<br />

72 E. H. Gombrich, <strong>The</strong> Story <strong>of</strong> Art (New York, 1951) 52.<br />

44


Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> phases, followed a sequential, progressive, <strong>and</strong> also predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

course. 73 In this way, naturalism emerges, <strong>in</strong> his theory, as the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal goal <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

art. Further, what enabled this goal to be achieved were two specific conditions <strong>in</strong><br />

reference to artists—freedom, <strong>and</strong> acquisition <strong>of</strong> skilled craftsmanship.<br />

Gombrich emphasizes the freedom <strong>of</strong> the artists as important to the rise <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

naturalism—a view, which, as it has been suggested, may be reflective <strong>of</strong> his time—but<br />

recalls also W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s idea <strong>of</strong> political freedom fuel<strong>in</strong>g the development <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

Greek art. 74 Similarly, his highlight<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> artists’ improvement <strong>in</strong> their craft bears clear<br />

73 <strong>The</strong>se characteristics are rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> G. W. F. Hegel’s ideas <strong>of</strong> progression <strong>and</strong> historical determ<strong>in</strong>ism<br />

<strong>in</strong> connection with art history. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these ideas <strong>of</strong> Hegel <strong>and</strong> their trac<strong>in</strong>g back to<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann by Gombrich, see Gombrich’s essay, “‘<strong>The</strong> Father <strong>of</strong> Art History’: A Read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Lectures on Aesthetics <strong>of</strong> G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831),” <strong>in</strong> E. H. Gombrich, Tributes. Interpreters <strong>of</strong><br />

Cultural Tradition (Ithaca, New York, 1984) 51-55 <strong>and</strong> 62-66.<br />

74 Gombrich appears to th<strong>in</strong>k that the freedom <strong>of</strong> the artists to experiment with images was <strong>in</strong>spired by (or<br />

rem<strong>in</strong>ded him <strong>of</strong>) the freedom poets had to narrate epic events, as far back as Homer’s time. It is not<br />

exactly clear what type <strong>of</strong> freedom Gombrich has <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, but his follow<strong>in</strong>g reference to “the <strong>in</strong>ner eye<br />

<strong>of</strong> the poet,” prompts one to suggest that he means <strong>in</strong>ner freedom, or perhaps mental freedom <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

set with<strong>in</strong> cultural freedom, <strong>in</strong> general. He says, for example (Reflections 129-130): “What is the character<br />

<strong>of</strong> Greek narration as we know it from Homer? Briefly, it is concerned not only with the “what” but also<br />

with the “how” <strong>of</strong> mythical events. Obviously this is not a very strict dist<strong>in</strong>ction. <strong>The</strong>re can be no recital<br />

<strong>of</strong> events that does not <strong>in</strong>clude description <strong>of</strong> one k<strong>in</strong>d or another, <strong>and</strong> nobody would claim that the<br />

Gilgamesh Epic or the Old Testament is devoid <strong>of</strong> vivid accounts. But maybe there is still a difference <strong>in</strong><br />

the way Homer presents the <strong>in</strong>cidents <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> Troy, the very thoughts <strong>of</strong> the heroes, or the reaction <strong>of</strong><br />

Hector’s small son, who takes fright from the plumes <strong>of</strong> his father’s helmet. <strong>The</strong> poet is here an eyewitness.<br />

If he were asked how he could know so exactly how it actually happened, he would still <strong>in</strong>voke the<br />

authority <strong>of</strong> the Muse who told him all <strong>and</strong> enabled his <strong>in</strong>ner eye to see across the chasm <strong>of</strong> time. We do<br />

not know whether pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>and</strong> sculptors <strong>in</strong>voked a similar sanction when they first ventured <strong>in</strong>to the realm<br />

<strong>of</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e mythological narrative. But one th<strong>in</strong>g was bound to follow: <strong>in</strong> a narrative illustration, any<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the “what” <strong>and</strong> the “how” is impossible to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the creation will<br />

not tell you, like the Holy Writ, only that “<strong>in</strong> the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g God created the heaven <strong>and</strong> the earth.”<br />

Whether he wants or not, the pictorial artist has to <strong>in</strong>clude un<strong>in</strong>tended <strong>in</strong>formation about the way God<br />

proceeded….It may well have been the same difficulty that restra<strong>in</strong>ed earlier cultures from embark<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

pictorial narrative <strong>of</strong> sacred themes. But where the poet was given license to vary <strong>and</strong> embroider the myth<br />

<strong>and</strong> to dwell on the “how” <strong>in</strong> the recital <strong>of</strong> epic events, the way was open for the visual artist to do the<br />

likewise. It was only this freedom that would enable an artist to tackle a subject such as the judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

Paris, for how could he render it without add<strong>in</strong>g to the bare story?”<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the freedom <strong>of</strong> the artists to which Gombrich refers, J. Elsner, “Reflections on the ‘Greek<br />

Revolution’ <strong>in</strong> Art,” <strong>in</strong> Goldhill <strong>and</strong> Osborne, eds., Reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Revolutions through Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> 81, n.<br />

37, says: “we must note that ‘freedom’ is a polemical term <strong>in</strong> Gombrich’s Cold War anti-totalitarian<br />

libertarianism <strong>and</strong> that (after Foucault, before whom Gombrich was writ<strong>in</strong>g) we may take the fictions<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>fered by naturalism to be themselves conventional <strong>and</strong> socially determ<strong>in</strong>ed.” Although this po<strong>in</strong>t may<br />

hold true, Gombrich’s st<strong>and</strong> cannot fail to recall the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann. For the latter’s idea <strong>of</strong><br />

political freedom <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> enabl<strong>in</strong>g artists to create the most beautiful <strong>and</strong> perfect works <strong>of</strong> art,<br />

45


traces <strong>of</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s ideas. 75 Regardless <strong>of</strong> their possible orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>spiration, these<br />

two conditions support Gombrich’s view <strong>of</strong> Greek art as a product directly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by<br />

preexist<strong>in</strong>g (Homer) <strong>and</strong> contemporary cultural conditions. <strong>The</strong> fact that he perceives the<br />

acquisition <strong>of</strong> skilled craftsmanship not as advancement <strong>in</strong> technique, but as<br />

experimentation with artistic media ow<strong>in</strong>g to new ideas is especially <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g. As<br />

Gombrich marks above, “the sculptors <strong>in</strong> their workshops tried new ideas <strong>and</strong> ways <strong>of</strong><br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g the human figure.” <strong>The</strong> precedence <strong>of</strong> ideas is also stressed <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Reflections, where he declares that “what makes it [Greek revolution] unique is<br />

“precisely the directed efforts, the cont<strong>in</strong>ued <strong>and</strong> systematic modifications <strong>of</strong> the<br />

schemata <strong>of</strong> conceptual art, till mak<strong>in</strong>g was replaced by the match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> reality through<br />

the new skill <strong>of</strong> mimesis.” 76 Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the complexity <strong>of</strong> mimesis, this way <strong>of</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dicates that Gombrich is <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> the revolution <strong>in</strong> Greek art as primarily<br />

an artistic <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual phenomenon <strong>and</strong> secondarily as a technical one.<br />

<strong>The</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g hold <strong>of</strong> this <strong>in</strong>terest may be seen elsewhere <strong>in</strong> his theory. <strong>The</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> improved craftsmanship as the second reason for the advent <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

naturalism—the other reason be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence from narrative texts—holds strong <strong>in</strong><br />

Gombrich’s m<strong>in</strong>d. As he states, “Homeric freedom <strong>of</strong> narration was as necessary as was<br />

<strong>and</strong> his adoption <strong>of</strong> these ideas from ancient discourse on the relationship between Art <strong>and</strong> politics, see A.<br />

A. Donohue, “W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s History <strong>of</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> Polyclitus,” <strong>in</strong> W. G. Moon, ed., Polykleitos, the<br />

Doryphoros, <strong>and</strong> Tradition (Madison, 1995) 335, 339, n. 98; also A. Potts, Flesh <strong>and</strong> the Ideal:<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann <strong>and</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Art History (New Haven, 1994). For the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s<br />

study on modern scholarship, see Donohue, “W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s History <strong>of</strong> Art” 327, <strong>and</strong> Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic<br />

as Realism” 10.<br />

75 See, for example, Donohue, “W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s History <strong>of</strong> Art” 339, n. 98 cit<strong>in</strong>g W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann: “In the age<br />

<strong>of</strong> the highest illum<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> freedom <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, says W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann, “through this improvement [i.e., on<br />

the Older Style] <strong>in</strong> art, Phidias, Polyclitus, Scopas, Alcamenes, <strong>and</strong> Myron made themselves celebrated” as<br />

masters <strong>of</strong> the Gr<strong>and</strong> Style.”<br />

76 Gombrich, Reflections 141.<br />

46


the acquired skill <strong>of</strong> craftsmanship to open the way for the Greek Revolution.” 77 How he<br />

actually underst<strong>and</strong>s the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Homeric texts on the naturalistic development <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek art is seen <strong>in</strong> his statement that “when Greek artists discovered the character <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek narration, they set up a cha<strong>in</strong> reaction which transformed the methods <strong>of</strong><br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g the human body.” 78 He elaborates this view further by pos<strong>in</strong>g the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

question:<br />

Is it not much more likely that the discoveries which <strong>in</strong>fused life <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>gle statue were first made <strong>in</strong> narrative contexts that dem<strong>and</strong>ed a<br />

conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g re-creation <strong>of</strong> a situation—for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> the narrative groups <strong>of</strong><br />

pediments with their dramatic evocation <strong>of</strong> mythical episodes? 79<br />

Gombrich seems to place the <strong>in</strong>tellectual orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> textual<br />

narrative. Thus, he connects the emergence <strong>of</strong> naturalistic images <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture to<br />

narrative contexts, whose aim, he identifies, with “a conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g re-creation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

situation.” This dependence <strong>of</strong> images on texts is not completely divorced from his<br />

broader conviction that “<strong>in</strong> the whole history <strong>of</strong> Western art [there is a] constant<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction between narrative <strong>in</strong>tent <strong>and</strong> pictorial realism.” 80 <strong>The</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k between the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> Greek art to textual narrative aga<strong>in</strong> reveals Gombrich’s<br />

attention to specific cultural circumstances fram<strong>in</strong>g his <strong>in</strong>terpretation. In this way, his<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> the rise <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art aga<strong>in</strong> emerges as historical <strong>in</strong> its conception,<br />

<strong>and</strong> diverges from that <strong>of</strong> Löwy, which, as seen earlier, relied on the psychology <strong>of</strong> vision<br />

as a universal phenomenon.<br />

77 Gombrich, Reflections 133; for a short discussion <strong>of</strong> this aspect <strong>of</strong> Gombrich’s theory, see Stewart, Greek<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> 75.<br />

78 Gombrich, Reflections 129.<br />

79 Gombrich, Reflections 133.<br />

80 Gombrich, Reflections 131.<br />

47


John Boardman<br />

<strong>The</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k between the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong><br />

dissatisfaction with exist<strong>in</strong>g images is also found <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> John Boardman. As was<br />

the case with Löwy <strong>and</strong> Gombrich, the human figure dom<strong>in</strong>ates Boardman’s work.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se characteristics are evident <strong>in</strong> his study <strong>of</strong> 1996, Greek Art, where he summarizes<br />

the history <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> realism—his preferred term—by us<strong>in</strong>g sculpture as a<br />

start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t:<br />

[T]here is little <strong>in</strong> 7 th -century sculpture to suggest that with<strong>in</strong> two centuries Greek<br />

artists were to carve statuary <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>and</strong> appearance that we admire on the<br />

Parthenon. In a way this is the most remarkable lesson <strong>of</strong> any history <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

art: its rapid development from strict geometry admitt<strong>in</strong>g hardly any figure<br />

decoration, to full realism <strong>of</strong> anatomy <strong>and</strong> expression. Perhaps this was the result<br />

<strong>of</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ual dissatisfaction, an unease which the Egyptians, for <strong>in</strong>stance, never<br />

felt with an idiom that served them successfully for millennia. In <strong>Greece</strong> we shall<br />

see how the early geometry broke before the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> foreign arts, <strong>and</strong> how<br />

the Greek artists absorbed these alien techniques <strong>and</strong> forms to weld them <strong>in</strong>to an<br />

art <strong>in</strong> which the best formal qualities <strong>of</strong> a native tradition rema<strong>in</strong>ed dom<strong>in</strong>ant.<br />

And then, about the time <strong>of</strong> the Persian Wars <strong>in</strong> the early 5 th century, a break with<br />

Archaic conventions heralded the <strong>Classical</strong> revolution, achiev<strong>in</strong>g that unparalleled<br />

blend <strong>of</strong> realism <strong>and</strong> the ideal which we recognize as the hallmark <strong>of</strong> the classical,<br />

centred on representation <strong>of</strong> the human body. 81<br />

Boardman expla<strong>in</strong>s the development <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture from the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to the fifth<br />

century B.C. as a progression from hardly figural to fully representational images, thus<br />

reveal<strong>in</strong>g a scheme <strong>of</strong> development based on typology. That this scheme relies also on<br />

the idea <strong>of</strong> progression from simple to accomplished representations is evident from his<br />

comment that, <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> quality <strong>and</strong> appearance, seventh-century sculpture has noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> common with the fifth-century sculptures <strong>of</strong> the Parthenon, which he perceives as<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> “full realism <strong>in</strong> anatomy <strong>and</strong> expression.” 82 <strong>The</strong>se explanations show the<br />

81 Boardman, Greek Art 28.<br />

82 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> typology <strong>and</strong> accomplished representation as elements <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

Greek art mentioned by ancient writers, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 49-50; also her Xoana<br />

48


prevalence <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> his view <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art. In this respect,<br />

they are very much aligned with Löwy’s <strong>and</strong> Gombrich’s theories. In alliance also with<br />

these theories is Boardman’s emphasis on Greek dissatisfaction with exist<strong>in</strong>g images—<br />

implicitly identified here with those <strong>in</strong>herited from Egypt—as the driv<strong>in</strong>g force beh<strong>in</strong>d<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture. His subscription especially to Gombrich’s ideas is<br />

seen <strong>in</strong> his recognition <strong>of</strong> a revolution <strong>in</strong> fifth-century Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> “realism,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the human body as the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal subject <strong>of</strong> representation through which this<br />

revolution was realized. What appears to be firmly stressed now is the idea <strong>of</strong> the Greek<br />

absorption <strong>of</strong> “alien techniques” as fuel<strong>in</strong>g the development <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism, <strong>and</strong> therefore <strong>of</strong> his view <strong>of</strong> this development as a primarily technical<br />

phenomenon.<br />

A more succ<strong>in</strong>ct summary <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> technical improvement appears <strong>in</strong> the<br />

conclusion <strong>of</strong> his Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period, which opens with the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

statement:<br />

<strong>The</strong> pictures <strong>and</strong> text <strong>of</strong> this book <strong>of</strong>fer a view <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

sculpture over nearly three hundred years, from m<strong>in</strong>iaturist works <strong>in</strong> the formal<br />

conceptual style <strong>of</strong> Geometric <strong>Greece</strong>, through periods <strong>in</strong> which the east, then<br />

Egypt, suggested new techniques <strong>and</strong> possibilities, to the sixth century <strong>in</strong> which<br />

the sculptor’s own search for improved expression <strong>of</strong> canonic forms led him to<br />

the po<strong>in</strong>t at which he wished consciously to take life as his model. 83<br />

<strong>The</strong> statement clearly shows the idea that Greek sculpture undergoes technical<br />

improvement as it moves through its course <strong>of</strong> development. It also shows clear traces <strong>of</strong><br />

Gombrich’s ideas. <strong>The</strong>se traces are found <strong>in</strong> the outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

sculpture as a shift from conceptual images to those reproduc<strong>in</strong>g the sensible world, <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Greek Art (American <strong>Classical</strong> Studies 15; Atlanta, 1988) 195-205, for ancient traditions<br />

<strong>and</strong> theories recorded by authors, such as Pausanias (7.22.4; 9.24.3; 30.20.9) <strong>and</strong> Callimachus (Diegesis to<br />

Callimachus, Aetia IV, fr. 100) about the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Greek statuary.<br />

83 Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period 169.<br />

49


the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Near Eastern <strong>and</strong> Egyptian arts, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>in</strong> the emphasis placed on the<br />

role <strong>of</strong> the sculptor as the agent <strong>of</strong> the technical improvement <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture. Also<br />

Boardman’s assertion that the artist consciously strove for images taken from life not<br />

only presents his view <strong>of</strong> naturalism as the desirable goal <strong>of</strong> Greek art, but also recalls,<br />

albeit with heavy alteration, Löwy’s idea <strong>of</strong> consciously acquired memory images by<br />

artists.<br />

Additional evidence for Boardman’s conception <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism as technical<br />

improvement derives from his discussion <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period. Here<br />

he conceives <strong>of</strong> a direct connection between technical progress <strong>and</strong> gradual stylistic<br />

change as open<strong>in</strong>g the road to the <strong>Classical</strong> revolution. At the same time, the challenge<br />

<strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> marble, <strong>and</strong> naturalism as the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal aim <strong>of</strong> Greek art, both seen<br />

previously, emerge as two highly important po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> his theory:<br />

<strong>The</strong> physical turmoil <strong>of</strong> Greek history <strong>in</strong> the early decades <strong>of</strong> the fifth century was<br />

answered <strong>in</strong> Greek art by what appears to be sure <strong>and</strong> steady progress, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

gradual changes <strong>in</strong> style encouraged effortlessly, it seems, a revolution <strong>in</strong> the<br />

sculptor’s approach to his craft.<br />

In less than a hundred <strong>and</strong> fifty years the Greek sculptor had perfected his<br />

technical comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the medium <strong>in</strong> which most <strong>of</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>est Archaic sculpture<br />

was executed—white marble. It is not an easy material, nor, on reflection, can we<br />

judge it an obvious choice for the execution <strong>of</strong> images <strong>in</strong> relief or <strong>in</strong> the<br />

round….It lends itself to clear, sharply def<strong>in</strong>ed masses <strong>and</strong> pattern no less than to<br />

subtlety <strong>of</strong> contour <strong>and</strong> even, as later generations were to discover, to the<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the s<strong>of</strong>t, the vaguely def<strong>in</strong>ed, the sensual. <strong>The</strong> Archaic sculptor<br />

explored its potential <strong>in</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g three-dimensional patterns which represented the<br />

human body. Style evolved slowly, as technique improved, <strong>and</strong> the changes,<br />

which must have been admitted because the results were more satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the<br />

functions <strong>of</strong> the figure were thus better served, also led to render<strong>in</strong>gs which were<br />

closer to life, closer (for the whole body at least) than any achieved by other<br />

ancient cultures. Not that there is anyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>herently good about realism <strong>in</strong> art,<br />

but once the Greeks discovered how much more it could express than the<br />

conventions, symbols <strong>and</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> Archaism, they made a virtue <strong>of</strong> it. 84<br />

84 J. Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period 20.<br />

50


<strong>The</strong> statement shows clearly that Boardman sees realism as the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal aim <strong>of</strong> the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> Greek art. It also expresses the core idea <strong>of</strong> his theory that gradual<br />

progress <strong>in</strong> technique caused stylistic change to occur <strong>and</strong> led ultimately to images <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> period whose appearance was more satisfy<strong>in</strong>g to the eye because it was closer<br />

to life. This idea <strong>of</strong> “closer to life” suggests that images <strong>of</strong> previous periods were, <strong>in</strong> his<br />

view, less naturalistic <strong>in</strong> appearance. This evidence, which accords well with his earlier<br />

statements, specifies now the dom<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism <strong>in</strong> his<br />

theory. At the same time, his consideration <strong>of</strong> marble as a difficult material to work with<br />

<strong>in</strong> sculpture is important, for it reveals his view <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism not<br />

as technical advancement <strong>in</strong> general, but <strong>in</strong> connection with a specifically challeng<strong>in</strong>g<br />

material. Such a connection is additionally important, for, when placed aga<strong>in</strong>st ancient<br />

texts that outl<strong>in</strong>e the evolution <strong>of</strong> sculpture as a “progressive exploitation <strong>of</strong> materials<br />

(easily carved wood to more challeng<strong>in</strong>g stone),” it shows that Boardman’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek naturalism is not devoid <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence from the ancient theories <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong><br />

statuary that shaped post-antique histories <strong>of</strong> art. 85<br />

Further, the fact that Boardman, like Gombrich, speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art as<br />

the product <strong>of</strong> a revolution <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> naturalism is valuable, for it allows one to see<br />

where exactly on representations <strong>of</strong> the human body elements <strong>of</strong> this revolution are to be<br />

sought. Boardman summarizes his view <strong>of</strong> this revolution <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way:<br />

<strong>The</strong> 5 th century <strong>in</strong>troduced to world art the <strong>Classical</strong> revolution <strong>and</strong> an idiom<br />

which was totally at variance with the way <strong>in</strong> which man had hitherto desired to<br />

create images <strong>of</strong> himself, his gods <strong>and</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> even beyond his<br />

experience. It was an idiom based essentially on idealized but realistic<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> the human figure: a counterfeit <strong>of</strong> nature but somewhat more as<br />

85 Quotation: Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 50; also her Xoana 208-218 for specific references to<br />

authors, such as Pl<strong>in</strong>y (NH 12.1), Plutarch (Moralia fr. 158), Pausanias (2.19.3) <strong>and</strong> Porphyry (Abst. 2.18),<br />

<strong>and</strong> their discussion <strong>of</strong> wood as the material that preceded stone <strong>in</strong> the execution <strong>of</strong> statues <strong>in</strong> antiquity.<br />

51


she should be than as she was. <strong>The</strong> idealization was noth<strong>in</strong>g new s<strong>in</strong>ce it is<br />

almost normal <strong>in</strong> stylized <strong>and</strong> unrealistic figures such as the Archaic, but <strong>in</strong> the 5 th<br />

century it <strong>in</strong>volved adjustment <strong>of</strong> realistic anatomy <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> perfect<br />

symmetry, <strong>and</strong> suppress<strong>in</strong>g much expression <strong>of</strong> particulars such as <strong>in</strong>dividuality,<br />

age, emotion. <strong>The</strong> realism was new, <strong>and</strong> for the first time <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> art the<br />

artist shows complete underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how the body is constructed, how to<br />

express nuances <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>and</strong>, even more difficult, repose. 86<br />

Anatomy <strong>and</strong> pose are those aspects <strong>of</strong> the human body that Boardman considers<br />

expressive <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> fifth-century realism which, as can be seen, coexists <strong>in</strong><br />

balance with the antithetical concept <strong>of</strong> idealism. Although his focus on the human<br />

figure cannot be denied, this evidence provides the opportunity to po<strong>in</strong>t out that his<br />

discussions <strong>of</strong> Greek sculpture are not completely devoid <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals.<br />

His study <strong>of</strong> Archaic Greek sculpture, for example, dedicates a chapter—albeit<br />

short (two pages)—to the subjects <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>and</strong> monsters, <strong>and</strong> starts with the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

observation: “Greek artists were hardly less observant <strong>of</strong> the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom than they<br />

were <strong>of</strong> man, <strong>and</strong> the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the Archaic period <strong>in</strong>cludes several sympathetic <strong>and</strong><br />

accurate studies <strong>of</strong> animals at rest or <strong>in</strong> action.” 87 In addition, his view that the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the animal form <strong>in</strong> Greek art followed the same course as that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human one is evident from his commentary on a sixth-century lion from Miletus: “the<br />

artist has excelled <strong>in</strong> render<strong>in</strong>g the rough loose pelt, delighted <strong>in</strong> the languorous sweep <strong>of</strong><br />

the sp<strong>in</strong>e, the pattern <strong>of</strong> mane, as consummate a compromise <strong>of</strong> pattern <strong>and</strong> observation<br />

as <strong>in</strong> any kouros” (Fig. 2). 88 Also his study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture, although it does<br />

not specifically discuss representations <strong>of</strong> animals, does not fail to provide illustrations <strong>of</strong><br />

extant examples such as the bull from the fourth-century funerary prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios<br />

86 Boardman, Greek Art 23.<br />

87 Boardman, Greek Art 167.<br />

88 Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period 168, fig. 267 (Berl<strong>in</strong> 1790); for a discussion <strong>and</strong> further<br />

bibliography on this lion from Miletus, see C. Ratté “Five Lydian Fel<strong>in</strong>es,” AJA 93 (1989) 391, no. A20.<br />

52


<strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos (Fig. 3). 89 In this way, Boardman may not<br />

assign importance to the role <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong><br />

naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art, but he does not, at least, ignore the existence <strong>of</strong> this body <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek sculpture.<br />

William A. P. Childs<br />

A similar <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals cannot be detected <strong>in</strong> William<br />

Childs’s article “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek art,” which provides an analysis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-century style <strong>of</strong> Greek art by focus<strong>in</strong>g explicitly on sculptural<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the human form (e.g., recl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g female figure from the west pediment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Temple <strong>of</strong> Zeus at Olympia [c. 460 B.C.] <strong>and</strong> male figure A from the same<br />

pediment <strong>of</strong> the Parthenon [437-432 B.C.]). Childs argues aga<strong>in</strong>st the usual assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> “idealism” as a def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period.<br />

He suggests that the style <strong>of</strong> this period is “primarily realistic” or more precisely, “vital,<br />

descriptive, <strong>and</strong> em<strong>in</strong>ently real—perhaps the only truly realistic style phase.” 90 He<br />

considers this style reflective <strong>of</strong> a conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism that relies heavily on the<br />

contemporary underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the essential character (phusis) <strong>of</strong> the human subjects <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art, while be<strong>in</strong>g simultaneously concerned with an accurate observation <strong>of</strong> real<br />

forms—two notions that are <strong>of</strong>ten seen as opposites. In other words, he proposes to see a<br />

special k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> naturalism governed by a synthesis <strong>of</strong> a heightened reality (how they<br />

knew th<strong>in</strong>gs to be) <strong>and</strong> the accurate reproduction <strong>of</strong> external appearances.<br />

89 Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Late <strong>Classical</strong> Period 114, 120, fig. 112.3 (no museum number); also<br />

120, figs. 113, 114 for statues <strong>of</strong> a dog <strong>and</strong> a lion from respective grave monuments on Salamis <strong>and</strong><br />

perhaps <strong>in</strong> Athens.<br />

90 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13.<br />

53


Childs starts his article by highlight<strong>in</strong>g the unquestioned, as he says assumption<br />

“that the classical style is def<strong>in</strong>ed by an idealized rendition that is antithetical to<br />

realism.” 91 Instead <strong>of</strong> consider<strong>in</strong>g these two contradictory characteristics <strong>in</strong> balance, as<br />

Boardman did, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Childs lends primacy “to the important development <strong>of</strong><br />

realism throughout the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C.” 92 His discussion follows the<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard division <strong>of</strong> the classical style <strong>in</strong>to four phases: 1) early classical (480-450 B.C.),<br />

2) high classical or severe (450-430 B.C.), 3) late high classical or “Rich Style” (430-380<br />

B.C.), <strong>and</strong> 4) late classical (380-300 B.C.). Although his ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest lies <strong>in</strong> the high<br />

classical phase, all other phases attract his attention <strong>and</strong> are framed, as he says, by a<br />

pattern <strong>of</strong> development, whose ma<strong>in</strong> objective is “to describe fully the complex<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> reality.” 93<br />

Childs <strong>in</strong>terprets the stylistic change accompany<strong>in</strong>g each phase <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ancient Greek concept <strong>of</strong> phusis, which, as he expla<strong>in</strong>s, “is not simply the external reality<br />

such as the word “nature” <strong>in</strong> English implies but a complex term that implies the<br />

character <strong>and</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g, embrac<strong>in</strong>g the regular pattern <strong>of</strong> change <strong>in</strong> it.” 94 On the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> this def<strong>in</strong>ition, he suggests the adoption <strong>of</strong> the idea that:<br />

Each phase <strong>of</strong> Greek monumental sculpture is <strong>in</strong>tent on the representation <strong>of</strong><br />

phusis; that is, the representation <strong>of</strong> the essential character <strong>of</strong> its subject, whatever<br />

that may be. Normally it is the generic “man” or “woman.” Thus the kouros is<br />

the phusis <strong>of</strong> man as it was understood at the time: reality is an almost static<br />

phenomenon broken only by the potential motion implied by the forward-set left<br />

leg. 95<br />

91 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 10.<br />

92 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 10.<br />

93 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13.<br />

94 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 12.<br />

95 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13.<br />

54


Hav<strong>in</strong>g expressed this idea, he presents next his analysis <strong>of</strong> each stylistic phase<br />

separately. In the early classical phase, he says, “naturalistic detail is represented (for<br />

example ve<strong>in</strong>s) but there is no study <strong>of</strong> the real <strong>in</strong>teraction <strong>of</strong> the elements <strong>of</strong> the body at<br />

rest or <strong>in</strong> movement.” 96 Thus, Myron’s Discobolos expresses the idea <strong>of</strong> throw<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

discus, but the artist does not depict how the body actually functions <strong>in</strong> the activity. 97<br />

In the high classical phase, attention shifts to the depiction <strong>of</strong> nuances <strong>in</strong> regard to the<br />

functions <strong>of</strong> the body. As Polykleitos’s Doryphoros demonstrates, a real underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> two different states <strong>of</strong> the muscles—represented on one side <strong>of</strong> the body at rest <strong>and</strong> on<br />

the other flexed—is achieved. 98 Such “a true though theoretical reality <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

characteristics <strong>of</strong> the states <strong>of</strong> the muscles,” Childs states, <strong>in</strong>dicates a new, “precise,<br />

objective <strong>and</strong> even near-scientific realism that is laid over the traditional idealized<br />

form.” 99 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, another novelty <strong>of</strong> the high classical style “is the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

a greater number <strong>of</strong> variations from the strict ideal <strong>and</strong> thus the creation <strong>of</strong> a more<br />

descriptive vocabulary” as evidenced, for example, by the figures K, L, <strong>and</strong> M from the<br />

east pediment <strong>of</strong> the Parthenon (437-432 B.C.), whose cl<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g drapery sets them apart<br />

from earlier statuary. 100 This wish for variety is carried on <strong>in</strong>to the late high classical<br />

phase, when new images, such as the S<strong>and</strong>al-b<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> the Nike parapet on the Athenian<br />

Acropolis, heighten the action depicted by be<strong>in</strong>g explicitly descriptive. As for the late<br />

classical phase <strong>of</strong> Greek art, it renders, Childs says, “the knowable form <strong>of</strong> physical<br />

reality,” <strong>and</strong> also the artists’ impression <strong>of</strong> visible appearances. It st<strong>and</strong>s therefore for the<br />

96 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13<br />

97 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 11.<br />

98 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13. For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> this subject, see also G. V. Leftwich,<br />

“Polykleitos <strong>and</strong> Hippokratic Medic<strong>in</strong>e,” <strong>in</strong> W. G. Moon, ed., Polykleitos, the Doryphoros, <strong>and</strong> Tradition<br />

(Madison, 1995) 38-51.<br />

99 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13.<br />

100 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 13 <strong>and</strong> 12, fig. 4.<br />

55


comb<strong>in</strong>ed render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an objective <strong>and</strong> subjective reality <strong>and</strong> “the <strong>in</strong>dividuality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

artist is def<strong>in</strong>ed by the <strong>in</strong>dividuality <strong>of</strong> his vision,” a characteristic which is exemplified,<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, by works <strong>of</strong> art such as the Apollo Sauroktonos <strong>of</strong> Praxiteles. 101<br />

<strong>The</strong> picture that emerges from Childs’s essay <strong>in</strong>dicates that, <strong>in</strong> his view, the<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>cipal objective <strong>of</strong> the classical style is to describe fully the experience <strong>of</strong> current<br />

reality. In this way, the classical style is clearly realistic <strong>in</strong> essence <strong>and</strong> each <strong>of</strong> its phases<br />

renders reality as it was understood <strong>and</strong> seen at the time. Thus, the development <strong>of</strong><br />

realism <strong>in</strong> classical Greek art should be actually seen as parallel to the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>and</strong> visual conception <strong>of</strong> the human subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art throughout the<br />

fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C.<br />

It is clear from the theories reviewed so far that the human form has dom<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

the study <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art, <strong>in</strong> particular sculpture. It is also<br />

clear that the majority <strong>of</strong> these theories—exclud<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>of</strong> Childs—has considered<br />

dissatisfaction <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greeks with supposedly unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal<br />

reason <strong>of</strong> stylistic change toward <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g naturalism. Both assumptions, however,<br />

dismiss literary evidence, which shows, first, that other-than-human subjects can <strong>of</strong>fer a<br />

useful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> second, that<br />

the ancient Greeks, as seen previously <strong>in</strong> Plato’s Republic, admired images that looked<br />

very much real, while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a conscious underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the fact that they were<br />

look<strong>in</strong>g at art; only children <strong>and</strong> fools were excluded from this general attitude toward<br />

art.<br />

101 Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism” 12 <strong>and</strong> 13.<br />

56


5. Not Naturalism <strong>and</strong> Realism. <strong>The</strong> Concept <strong>of</strong> Lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> Greek Art <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> almost exclusive focus on the human form as a guide to the study <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

naturalism has operated very much like a bl<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g approach to this topic. When turn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to the ancient record, such a focus is contradicted, for example, by Plato’s explicit<br />

statement <strong>in</strong> the Critias that contemporary judgment <strong>of</strong> how conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g artistic<br />

representations were <strong>in</strong> execution was not conf<strong>in</strong>ed to the human form, but extended to<br />

the entire surround<strong>in</strong>g environment, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g its natural features <strong>and</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

exists <strong>and</strong> lives <strong>in</strong> it. In fact, what constituted a satisfactory depiction <strong>of</strong> all non-human<br />

subjects appears to have been governed by a relative degree <strong>of</strong> lenience toward extreme<br />

accuracy <strong>of</strong> representation. For example, <strong>in</strong> a discussion that centers on criticism <strong>of</strong><br />

portraiture, Plato has Critias say:<br />

<strong>The</strong> accounts given by all us must be, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>of</strong> the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> imitations <strong>and</strong> representations; <strong>and</strong> if we look at the portraiture<br />

<strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> human bodies as executed by pa<strong>in</strong>ters, <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ease or difficulty with which they succeed <strong>in</strong> imitat<strong>in</strong>g their subjects <strong>in</strong><br />

the op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> onlookers, we shall notice <strong>in</strong> the first place that as regards<br />

the earth <strong>and</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> rivers <strong>and</strong> woods <strong>and</strong> the whole <strong>of</strong> heaven,<br />

with the th<strong>in</strong>gs that exist <strong>and</strong> move there<strong>in</strong>, we are content if a man is<br />

also able to represent them with even a small degree <strong>of</strong> likeness; <strong>and</strong> further,<br />

that, <strong>in</strong>asmuch as we have no exact knowledge about such subjects, we do<br />

not exam<strong>in</strong>e closely or criticize the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, but tolerate, <strong>in</strong> such cases,<br />

an <strong>in</strong>exact <strong>and</strong> deceptive sketch. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, whenever a pa<strong>in</strong>ter<br />

tries to render a likeness <strong>of</strong> our own bodies, we quickly perceive what is<br />

defective because <strong>of</strong> our constant familiar acqua<strong>in</strong>tance with them, <strong>and</strong><br />

become sever critics <strong>of</strong> him who fails to br<strong>in</strong>g out to the full all the<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> similarity. And precisely the same th<strong>in</strong>g happens, as we should<br />

notice, <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> discourse: <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong> what is celestial <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e<br />

we are satisfied if the account possesses even a small degree <strong>of</strong><br />

likelihood, but we exam<strong>in</strong>e with precision what is mortal <strong>and</strong> human.<br />

To an account given now on the spur <strong>of</strong> the moment <strong>in</strong>dulgence must be<br />

granted, should we fail to make it a wholly fitt<strong>in</strong>g representation; for one<br />

must conceive <strong>of</strong> mortal objects as be<strong>in</strong>g difficult, <strong>and</strong> not easy,<br />

to represent satisfactorily. (Critias 107b-107e) [143]<br />

57


Critias states explicitly that conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images <strong>in</strong> art—about which no one cared—did<br />

not concern only the human form, but equally applied to all other subjects <strong>of</strong> the sensible<br />

world. Such evidence contrasts with the modern <strong>in</strong>sistence on the human form as the<br />

only w<strong>in</strong>dow onto the topic <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>in</strong> Greek art. In addition, Critias reveals the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> two different attitudes towards the conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g representation <strong>of</strong> human <strong>and</strong><br />

other subjects <strong>in</strong> art based on the degree <strong>of</strong> preexist<strong>in</strong>g knowledge <strong>of</strong> them: <strong>in</strong>tolerance <strong>of</strong><br />

any omission <strong>of</strong> “all the po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> similarity” regard<strong>in</strong>g depictions <strong>of</strong> the human figure,<br />

with which all humans are well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted, but satisfaction with “even a small degree <strong>of</strong><br />

likeness” or “an <strong>in</strong>exact <strong>and</strong> deceptive sketch,” <strong>of</strong> all other subjects. <strong>The</strong>se phrases are <strong>of</strong><br />

crucial importance for they suggest that exactitude or accuracy, which, as already seen,<br />

def<strong>in</strong>es the problematic, modern concepts <strong>of</strong> naturalism <strong>and</strong> realism, was not a lead<strong>in</strong>g<br />

concern when it came to judg<strong>in</strong>g conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g artistic representations <strong>of</strong> non-human<br />

subjects <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. Such evidence does not remove the notion <strong>of</strong> accurate<br />

representation from the realm <strong>of</strong> Greek art, but implies that animals, when featured as<br />

subjects <strong>of</strong> art, were not devalued for not be<strong>in</strong>g exact reproductions <strong>of</strong> physical models.<br />

As such, animals can be a useful guide to the ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g not <strong>of</strong><br />

“naturalism” <strong>and</strong> “realism,” but rather <strong>of</strong> “lifelikeness” <strong>in</strong> art, a concept, which the<br />

American Heritage Dictionary def<strong>in</strong>es as accurate representation <strong>of</strong> real life. 102<br />

<strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g essay beg<strong>in</strong>s with a discussion <strong>of</strong> literary sources which show that<br />

lifelikeness was a valued quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. It further presents<br />

literary evidence that refers to ancient discussions <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> picture <strong>of</strong><br />

the discourse on lifelikeness that emerges from the ancient sources does not exclude<br />

102 A. H. Soukhanov, ed., <strong>The</strong> American Heritage Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the English Language (third edition;<br />

Boston <strong>and</strong> New York, 1992) 1039, s.v. lifelike.<br />

58


animals, but rather highlights their significant role as guides to the Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> this quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art; <strong>in</strong> this respect, it is wholly different from the persistence <strong>of</strong><br />

modern scholarship <strong>in</strong> view<strong>in</strong>g the human form as the s<strong>in</strong>gle venue for approach<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

issue <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> Greek art. In fact, animals prove valuable w<strong>in</strong>dows onto the<br />

ancient Greek def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness as accurate representation but also aliveness. 103<br />

<strong>The</strong>y do so by featur<strong>in</strong>g simultaneously as lifelike subjects <strong>of</strong> representational art, <strong>and</strong><br />

also as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art. In the latter case, we also witness animals—a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature—validat<strong>in</strong>g the belief that some works <strong>of</strong> art had surpassed nature <strong>and</strong> were<br />

thus accepted as nature. 104<br />

a. Ancient Texts on Lifelikeness as a Quality <strong>of</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong><br />

A fragment <strong>of</strong> Aeschylus’s play <strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae presents an example <strong>of</strong><br />

lifelikeness be<strong>in</strong>g a valued quality <strong>of</strong> images <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. <strong>The</strong> fragment refers to<br />

a scene that takes place <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> Poseidon at Isthmia. A chorus <strong>of</strong> satyrs carries<br />

images <strong>of</strong> themselves:<br />

I’m very grateful to you for this: you’re most oblig<strong>in</strong>g. Listen, all <strong>of</strong> you, <strong>and</strong>…<strong>in</strong><br />

silence. Look <strong>and</strong> see whether the eidolon could [possibly] be more [like] me,<br />

this mimema by the Skillful One; it can do everyth<strong>in</strong>g but talk! Look at these!<br />

You see? Yes, come! Come! I br<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g to the god to ornament his<br />

house, my lovely votive picture. It would give my mother a bad time! If she<br />

103 Such evidence agrees with the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek given by C. M.<br />

Havelock, “Art as Communication <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> E. A. Havelock <strong>and</strong> J. P. Hershbell, eds.,<br />

Communication Arts <strong>in</strong> the Ancient World (New York, 1978) 99: “[l]ifelikeness” should be <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> a<br />

broad but literal sense, as “hav<strong>in</strong>g similarity to life” or “seem<strong>in</strong>g to be alive.””<br />

104 This employment <strong>of</strong> animals is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Renaissance pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs that<br />

depict supernatural visitations such as those <strong>of</strong> angels <strong>and</strong> sa<strong>in</strong>ts. As it has been remarked, the presence <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> these pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> the concurrent belief <strong>of</strong> animals as creatures def<strong>in</strong>ed by sensation <strong>in</strong>structed<br />

contemporary viewers to perceive the depicted visitations <strong>of</strong> angels as a real occurrence. For a discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> this issue, see W. J. Scheick, “<strong>Animal</strong> Testimony <strong>in</strong> Renaissance Art: Angelic <strong>and</strong> Other Supernatural<br />

Visitations,” <strong>in</strong> Pollock <strong>and</strong> Ra<strong>in</strong>water, eds., Figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> 65-79.<br />

59


could see it, she’d certa<strong>in</strong>ly run shriek<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g it was the son she brought<br />

up: so like me is this fellow.<br />

Ho there! Look upon the house <strong>of</strong> the Lord <strong>of</strong> the Sea, the Shaker <strong>of</strong> Earth! And<br />

let each fasten up the likeness <strong>of</strong> his h<strong>and</strong>some face, a truthful messenger, a<br />

voiceless herald to keep <strong>of</strong>f travelers; he’ll halt strangers on their way by his<br />

terrify<strong>in</strong>g look. Hail, K<strong>in</strong>g, hail Poseidon…protector….<br />

(<strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae, P. Oxy., vol. 18. no 2162, Radt, fr. 78a) [9]<br />

In this scene, satyrs thank someone for images <strong>of</strong> themselves, which they proceed to nail<br />

up upon the temple <strong>of</strong> Poseidon, while stat<strong>in</strong>g that they will serve to frighten away<br />

strangers. One <strong>of</strong> them is astounded by his own image, <strong>in</strong> particular, how strongly it<br />

resembles him. He suspects that the image will have an equally powerful, albeit<br />

frighten<strong>in</strong>g, effect on his mother; it could make her th<strong>in</strong>k that this was her son. 105<br />

Com<strong>in</strong>g from the satyr’s own mother, this reaction implies that the image had received a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> accuracy which was very true to its liv<strong>in</strong>g prototype; it was thus so lifelike that it<br />

could easily deceive a person with <strong>in</strong>timate knowledge <strong>of</strong> the satyr’s appearance as be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the satyr himself. This lifelike impression is further strengthened by the remark that the<br />

image lacks only voice, which implies that the image was also very close to convey<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the sense <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g alive. 106 In addition, the fact that it is called “a truthful messenger”<br />

105 M. Stieber, “Aeschylus’ <strong>The</strong>oroi <strong>and</strong> Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” TAPA 124 (1994) 89-90 argues that the<br />

suggestion <strong>of</strong> a mother be<strong>in</strong>g scared by her own child is comic <strong>and</strong> rests on the contradiction that the satyr<br />

calls the image <strong>of</strong> himself beautiful, whereas <strong>in</strong> the audience’s m<strong>in</strong>d a satyr was an ugly creature. H.<br />

Lloyd-Jones, ed., tr., “<strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae,” <strong>in</strong> H. W. Smith, ed., tr., Aeschylus II. Agamemnon. Libation-<br />

Bearers. Eumenides. Fragments (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1923, repr. 1983) 543 suggests that “the<br />

fright which the portraits are likely to give to the satyr’s mother or to any strangers makes it likely that such<br />

portraits, <strong>and</strong> probably the art <strong>of</strong> portraiture itself, are thought <strong>of</strong> as be<strong>in</strong>g unusual or even new at the time<br />

<strong>in</strong> question.” He also notes (543) the suggestion (by Eduard Fraenkel) that these portraits may be antefixes,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce the latter were customarily shaped like masks, <strong>and</strong> satyr-masks were sometimes used as antefixes.<br />

This scene therefore may be suggestive <strong>of</strong> this practice. Lloyd-Jones argues that the satyrs’ portraits cannot<br />

be antefixes, s<strong>in</strong>ce “antefixes cannot be nailed up or taken down at will,” which is partially the case <strong>in</strong> this<br />

scene. G. Ferrari, “Eye-Cup,” RA (1986) 19-20, suggests that the image (eidolon) to which the passage<br />

refers should be understood to mean “mask.” Accord<strong>in</strong>g to her, “the image <strong>of</strong> the satyr must look just like<br />

a satyr’s mask, <strong>and</strong> it is the mask that protects the performer, as well as the reveler, from the consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> his words <strong>and</strong> actions.”<br />

106 J.-P. Vernant, Myth <strong>and</strong> Thought among the Greeks (London <strong>and</strong> Boston, 1983) 311-312 ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that,<br />

<strong>in</strong> ancient Greek thought, the presence <strong>of</strong> voice was an <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> life: “<strong>in</strong> contrast to the word <strong>of</strong> sound<br />

60


<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> a message highlights the perception <strong>of</strong> the image as the liv<strong>in</strong>g model itself<br />

rather than as a mere object <strong>of</strong> depiction. 107 In this way, first, strong likeness to a<br />

prototype, <strong>and</strong> second, accuracy <strong>and</strong> aliveness emerge as constituent elements <strong>of</strong> a<br />

lifelike image which caused audiences to respond with astonishment to it. This evidence,<br />

<strong>in</strong> turn, <strong>in</strong>dicates that lifelikeness was a valued quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> fifth-century<br />

<strong>Greece</strong>.<br />

Mov<strong>in</strong>g to the fourth century, a famous passage <strong>of</strong> Xenophon from his work<br />

Memorabilia also presents lifelikeness as a valued quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>in</strong> this case,<br />

statuary. Xenophon records an <strong>in</strong>formed discussion between the philosopher Socrates<br />

<strong>and</strong> a practic<strong>in</strong>g artist, the sculptor Cleiton, on the subject <strong>of</strong> mimesis:<br />

“Cleiton, that your statues <strong>of</strong> runners, wrestlers, boxers, <strong>and</strong> fighters are beautiful<br />

I see <strong>and</strong> know. But how do you e0nerga&zh| (produce <strong>in</strong>) them that illusion <strong>of</strong> life<br />

(to_ zwtiko_n fai/nesqai) which is their most allur<strong>in</strong>g charm to the beholder?<br />

As Cleiton was puzzled <strong>and</strong> did not reply at once, “Is it,” he added, “by faithfully<br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g the form <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs that you make your statues look as if they<br />

lived?”<br />

“Undoubtedly.”<br />

“<strong>The</strong>n is it not by accurately represent<strong>in</strong>g the different parts <strong>of</strong> the body as they<br />

affected by the pose—the flesh wr<strong>in</strong>kled or tense, the limbs compressed or<br />

outstretched, the muscles taut or loose—that you make them look more real<br />

members <strong>and</strong> more conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g?”<br />

“Yes, certa<strong>in</strong>ly.”<br />

“Does not the exact imitation (a)pomimei=sqai) <strong>of</strong> the feel<strong>in</strong>gs that affect bodies <strong>in</strong><br />

action also produce a sense <strong>of</strong> satisfaction <strong>in</strong> the spectator?”<br />

“Oh yes, presumably.”<br />

“<strong>The</strong>n must not the threaten<strong>in</strong>g look <strong>in</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> fighters be accurately<br />

represented, <strong>and</strong> the triumphant expression on the face <strong>of</strong> conquerors be imitated<br />

(mimhte/a)?”<br />

with its voices, cries, <strong>and</strong> songs, death is the world <strong>of</strong> silence…To animate a statue, made <strong>of</strong> stone or clay,<br />

<strong>and</strong> breathe life <strong>in</strong>to it after hav<strong>in</strong>g fashion<strong>in</strong>g it—as <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> Hermes mak<strong>in</strong>g P<strong>and</strong>ora come alive, or<br />

<strong>of</strong> the liv<strong>in</strong>g statues <strong>in</strong> the service <strong>of</strong> Hephaestus—is to give it a voice.” Also for a discussion <strong>of</strong> images as<br />

“speak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> therefore, liv<strong>in</strong>g objects” <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, see J. Svenbro, tr. J. Lloyd, Phrasikleia: An<br />

Anthropology <strong>of</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Ithaca <strong>and</strong> London, 1993) 9-25, 49-63.<br />

107 Stieber, “Aeschylus’ <strong>The</strong>oroi” 93, argues that the designation “truthful messenger” suggests that the<br />

visual message conveyed by the image was similarly accurate, detailed, <strong>and</strong> trustworthy as the <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

reported by the character <strong>of</strong> the messenger <strong>in</strong> Greek plays. Thus, the language <strong>of</strong> the fragment, she says,<br />

clearly emphasizes realism.<br />

61


“Most certa<strong>in</strong>ly.”<br />

“It follows, then, that the sculptor must represent <strong>in</strong> his figures the<br />

activities <strong>of</strong> the soul.” (Mem. 3.10.6-3.10.8) [193]<br />

In this passage, the identification <strong>of</strong> Cleiton’s statues with runners, wrestlers, boxers <strong>and</strong><br />

fighters sets a context <strong>of</strong> representational subjects <strong>in</strong> which the human form dom<strong>in</strong>ates.<br />

Next, the technical question, “How do you e0nerga&zh| (produce <strong>in</strong>) them that zwtiko_n<br />

fai/nesqai (illusion <strong>of</strong> life),” that Socrates poses to Cleiton is straightforward evidence<br />

that lifelikeness was an essential quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> which both philosophers <strong>and</strong><br />

artists showed <strong>in</strong>terest. <strong>The</strong> phrase to_ zwtiko_n fai/nesqai is translated by Marchant as<br />

“illusion <strong>of</strong> life.” Although not <strong>in</strong>correct, this translation does not capture the literal<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the phrase. <strong>The</strong> adjective zwtiko_n stems from the noun zwh&, which means<br />

“life.” 108 Henry Liddell <strong>and</strong> Robert Scott translate it as “true to life.” 109 Similarly,<br />

Halliwell suggests that the word “identifies the simulation <strong>of</strong> ‘life’ that might be<br />

experienced <strong>in</strong> an image, the sense <strong>of</strong> what might be called its vividly ‘world-like’<br />

properties.” 110 <strong>The</strong> articular <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itive to_ fai/nesqai means “to appear.” 111 Consider<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that this type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itive “is used like any other noun,” then Halliwell’s explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

to_ fai/nesqai as “appearance” is more accurate than its above translation as “illusion.” 112<br />

In this way, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the entire phrase as “appearance <strong>of</strong> life” br<strong>in</strong>gs the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> sharp focus. In addition, the verb e0nerga&zh|, which derives from<br />

e0nerga&zomai, literally mean<strong>in</strong>g “to produce <strong>in</strong>,” sheds light on lifelikeness as a technical<br />

108<br />

H. G. Liddell <strong>and</strong> R. Scott, rev. H. S. Jones <strong>and</strong> R. McKenzie, A Greek-English Lexicon with a Revised<br />

Supplement (new n<strong>in</strong>th ed.; Oxford, 1940; repr. 1996) 759, s.v. zwh& (henceforth LSJ 9 ).<br />

109 9<br />

LSJ , 761, s.v. zwtiko_n.<br />

110<br />

S. Halliwell, “Plato <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> N. K. Rutter <strong>and</strong> B. A. Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong> (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh, 2000) 102.<br />

111 9<br />

LSJ , 1913, s.v. fai/nesqai.<br />

112<br />

First quotation: H. Hansen <strong>and</strong> G. M. Qu<strong>in</strong>n, Greek. An Intensive Course (New York, 1996) 128; second<br />

quotation: Halliwell, “Plato <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> Rutter <strong>and</strong> Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image 102.<br />

62


quality <strong>of</strong> Cleiton’s statues, or, as Halliwell suggests, a quality that was “work[ed] <strong>in</strong>,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus one that “marks the artefactuality <strong>of</strong> the image.” 113 Further, the explicit<br />

identification <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness as “the most allur<strong>in</strong>g charm to the beholder” suggests that<br />

this was a quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art valued not only by <strong>in</strong>tellectuals <strong>and</strong> artists, like Socrates<br />

<strong>and</strong> Cleiton, but by all viewers <strong>in</strong> general.<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage is additionally important, for it identifies constituent components <strong>of</strong><br />

the ancient Greek perception <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> the visual arts. As Socrates expla<strong>in</strong>s,<br />

faithful <strong>and</strong> accurate representation <strong>of</strong> the human body, even when affected by different<br />

poses, is what Cleiton strove to produce <strong>in</strong> his statues, a characteristic which accords well<br />

with Plato’s comment <strong>in</strong> the Critias on viewers’ low tolerance for <strong>in</strong>accurate<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the human body <strong>in</strong> art [143]. This comb<strong>in</strong>ed evidence establishes that<br />

lifelikeness was a quality that both artists <strong>and</strong> viewers eagerly sought <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

Also important <strong>in</strong> this passage is the fact that Socrates reveals an additional goal <strong>of</strong><br />

lifelikeness as an artistic concept: to represent accurately “the feel<strong>in</strong>gs that affect bodies<br />

<strong>in</strong> action,” such as “the threaten<strong>in</strong>g look <strong>in</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> fighters” <strong>and</strong> “the triumphant<br />

expression on the face <strong>of</strong> conquerors.” Such evidence is crucial, for it extends the<br />

ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the goal <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> the visual arts from accurate<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> the forms <strong>of</strong> the human body to that <strong>of</strong> emotions, <strong>and</strong> more specifically<br />

their facial expressions. Recent research on the psychology <strong>of</strong> emotions has shown that<br />

they <strong>and</strong> their facial displays are culturally determ<strong>in</strong>ed. 114 This notion highlights the need<br />

113 For the verb e0nerga&zomai, see LSJ 9 , 563; for Halliwell’s remarks, see his discussion <strong>in</strong> “Plato <strong>and</strong><br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> Rutter <strong>and</strong> Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image 102.<br />

114 A. Wierzbicka, Emotions across Languages <strong>and</strong> Cultures: Diversity <strong>and</strong> Universals (Cambridge <strong>and</strong><br />

Paris, 1999) 170: “as empirical-l<strong>in</strong>guistic studies show, there are simply no emotional expressions (i.e.,<br />

labels) <strong>in</strong>terpreted the same way across cultures.” For an additional discussion <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> emotions as<br />

culturally constructed on the basis <strong>of</strong> anthropological research, see C. A. Lutz, Unnatural Emotions:<br />

Everyday Sentiments on a Micronesian Atoll <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Challenge to Western <strong>The</strong>ory (Chicago, 1988); for a<br />

63


to consider the concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> Greek art on the basis <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g not only <strong>of</strong> form but also <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner emotional states. At the same time, the<br />

fact that the exact representation <strong>of</strong> emotions <strong>in</strong> art created, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Socrates, “a<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> satisfaction <strong>in</strong> the spectator” is explicit <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> not only what was<br />

considered conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> art, but also how highly conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g ancient Greeks found their<br />

art to be. This evidence contrasts sharply with the idea that dissatisfaction with<br />

unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images fueled the development <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism, as asserted by Löwy,<br />

Gombrich, <strong>and</strong> Boardman.<br />

Of great importance <strong>in</strong> this passage is also the fact that lifelikeness is not<br />

conflated with mimesis, but rather def<strong>in</strong>ed as a quality result<strong>in</strong>g from this process.<br />

Socrates, for example, uses two cognates <strong>of</strong> mimesis: first, the word a)pomimei=sqai,<br />

translated above as “exact imitation,” to talk about the representation <strong>of</strong> emotions that<br />

affect bodies <strong>in</strong> action as lifelike <strong>and</strong> thus satisfy<strong>in</strong>g to the eye; <strong>and</strong> second, mimhte/a,<br />

translated above as “imitated,” to exclaim that <strong>in</strong> order for a victorious figure to be<br />

perceived as lifelike, its facial expression has to convey the emotion <strong>of</strong> victory. In both<br />

cases, lifelikeness emerges as a quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art directly dependent on represented<br />

emotions. It is therefore to be understood as the result <strong>of</strong> a process <strong>of</strong> representation<br />

(mimesis) rather than as the process itself. This evidence serves as a good reason to cast<br />

doubt, for example, on Pollitt’s equation <strong>of</strong> mimesis with realism, <strong>and</strong> further suggests<br />

that such an equation may not be as straightforward as previously thought. This function<br />

along with the aforementioned traits <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness present Xenophon’s passage as a<br />

study <strong>of</strong> emotions <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek culture, see D. Konstan, <strong>The</strong> Emotions <strong>of</strong> the Ancient Greeks: Studies <strong>in</strong><br />

Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Literature (Toronto, 2006).<br />

64


valuable guide to the ancient <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this concept <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek art.<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g ancient <strong>in</strong>terest, <strong>in</strong> this case <strong>of</strong> an ord<strong>in</strong>ary viewer,<br />

<strong>in</strong> the lifelike quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art is seen <strong>in</strong> an anecdote recorded by Pl<strong>in</strong>y. It refers to<br />

the criticism leveled by a shoemaker at the <strong>in</strong>accurate depiction <strong>of</strong> the s<strong>and</strong>als <strong>of</strong> a figure<br />

<strong>in</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g by Apelles, an artist <strong>of</strong> the fourth century B.C.:<br />

Another habit <strong>of</strong> his (Apelles) was when he had f<strong>in</strong>ished his works to place them<br />

<strong>in</strong> a gallery <strong>in</strong> the view <strong>of</strong> passers by, <strong>and</strong> he himself stood out <strong>of</strong> sight beh<strong>in</strong>d the<br />

picture <strong>and</strong> listened to hear what faults were noticed, rat<strong>in</strong>g the public as a more<br />

observant critic than himself. And it is said that he was found fault with by a<br />

shoemaker because <strong>in</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g a subject’s s<strong>and</strong>als he has represented the loops <strong>in</strong><br />

one <strong>of</strong> them as one too few, <strong>and</strong> the next day the same critic was so proud <strong>of</strong> the<br />

artist’s correct<strong>in</strong>g the fault <strong>in</strong>dicated by his previous objection that he found fault<br />

with the leg, but Apelles <strong>in</strong>dignantly looked out from beh<strong>in</strong>d the picture <strong>and</strong><br />

rebuked him, say<strong>in</strong>g that a shoemaker <strong>in</strong> his criticism must not go beyond the<br />

s<strong>and</strong>al—a remark that has also passed <strong>in</strong>to a proverb (Pl<strong>in</strong>y, NH 35.85) [157].<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage shows clearly that a detail such as “one too few” lace-holes <strong>in</strong> the render<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> a figure’s s<strong>and</strong>al was enough <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>accuracy to dim<strong>in</strong>ish the lifelike quality <strong>of</strong><br />

Apelles’ pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> thus cause negative criticism on the side <strong>of</strong> a viewer. 115 <strong>The</strong><br />

mention <strong>of</strong> such a response suggests that lifelikeness was a valued quality expected to be<br />

seen <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. Also the acute attention to detail suggests that lifelikeness was<br />

associated with accurate representation <strong>of</strong> objects from real life.<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the viewer himself, the fact that he is a shoemaker establishes his<br />

status as a layman. Lifelikeness thus emerges as a quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art valued by<br />

ord<strong>in</strong>ary viewers, therefore, disconnected from the idea that only cultivated members <strong>of</strong><br />

society were <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> it. Additional support for this po<strong>in</strong>t derives from Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s<br />

assertion that Apelles—a famous pa<strong>in</strong>ter—“rat[ed] the public as a more observant critic<br />

115 For further discussion <strong>of</strong> this passage <strong>in</strong> connection with the concept <strong>of</strong> representational accountability,<br />

see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Description 199.<br />

65


than himself.” In addition, the fact that the viewer is a shoemaker, who criticizes the<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> a s<strong>and</strong>al, <strong>in</strong>dicates that his detection <strong>of</strong> Apelles’ “fault” was drawn from<br />

good knowledge <strong>of</strong> real s<strong>and</strong>als. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, implies that thorough knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> what an artist was try<strong>in</strong>g to depict at first place was a qualify<strong>in</strong>g prerequisite for good<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> texts considered so far def<strong>in</strong>e lifelikeness as strong likeness to the<br />

representational subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>in</strong> particular accurate representation <strong>of</strong> form but<br />

also emotions as expressed on the face. <strong>The</strong>y also h<strong>in</strong>t at another aspect <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness:<br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> the image as if it were alive. Overall, the picture that emerges from<br />

these texts speaks <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness as an artistic quality <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek representations<br />

<strong>in</strong> both sculpture <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> valued by contemporary philosophers, artists, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

general public. <strong>The</strong>refore, all viewers, regardless <strong>of</strong> their degree <strong>of</strong> sophistication, judged<br />

images by their lifelikeness. This evidence suggests that both <strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

reaction to the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> art was alike <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>.<br />

b. Ancient Texts on <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Lifelike Images <strong>and</strong> Judges <strong>of</strong> Lifelike Art<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> play an important role <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. This role, as featured <strong>in</strong> the literary record, is tw<strong>of</strong>old:<br />

animals appear as lifelike subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> also as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike art.<br />

Through their employment, animals demonstrate the ancient perception <strong>of</strong> artistic<br />

lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> connection with two dist<strong>in</strong>ct notions: aliveness <strong>and</strong> accurate<br />

representation. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g section presents literary evidence that exemplifies the<br />

66


importance <strong>of</strong> these notions <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art,<br />

as well as the centrality <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> convey<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this perception as such.<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Lifelike Images <strong>in</strong> Art<br />

A. Myron’s Cow<br />

Ancient references to the early <strong>Classical</strong> sculptor Myron <strong>and</strong> his bronze cow<br />

provide an example <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> animals as lifelike subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> antiquity.<br />

More specifically, Myron’s cow is an example <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek perception <strong>of</strong><br />

lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art as aliveness. This sense <strong>of</strong> aliveness is consistently highlighted <strong>in</strong> the<br />

31 epigrams from the Greek Anthology (9.713-9.742) focused solely on Myron’s bronze<br />

cow. Two <strong>of</strong> them, attributed to Euenos, a fifth century B.C. philosopher <strong>and</strong> poet, are<br />

the only contemporary evidence relat<strong>in</strong>g to the reception <strong>of</strong> the cow. <strong>The</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

epigrams date from later periods; they underl<strong>in</strong>e the aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue through<br />

conceits <strong>of</strong> different types that are <strong>of</strong>ten conflict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> nature. Thus, <strong>in</strong> some epigrams,<br />

the statue acts fantastically by talk<strong>in</strong>g directly to the viewer, whereas, <strong>in</strong> some others, acts<br />

naturally, by low<strong>in</strong>g, go<strong>in</strong>g to the pasture, <strong>and</strong> even work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the field. <strong>The</strong> picture that<br />

emerges, when comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g these two types <strong>of</strong> conceits, may be seen as <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> a<br />

“magic realism” <strong>in</strong> connection with the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s bronze cow. Further, the<br />

epigrams praise this quality <strong>of</strong> the statue by plac<strong>in</strong>g emphasis on a specific group <strong>of</strong><br />

viewers, who are well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with the appearance <strong>of</strong> a cow, such as herdsmen <strong>and</strong><br />

animals (a calf, a bull), yet they are deceived <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that the statue is alive. This<br />

evidence is crucial, for it provides a picture <strong>of</strong> animals not only as subjects <strong>of</strong> lifelike art,<br />

but also as reliable guides to the judgment <strong>of</strong> lifelike art. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g sections discuss<br />

67


the epigrams <strong>in</strong> the order followed above, but, first, draw attention to another important<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> these poems.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Conventional Nature <strong>of</strong> the Praise <strong>of</strong> Lifelike Works <strong>of</strong> Art<br />

<strong>The</strong> epigrams, while focus<strong>in</strong>g on the aliveness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s bronze cow, are not<br />

only useful for highlight<strong>in</strong>g the centrality <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> connection with artistic<br />

lifelikeness. <strong>The</strong>y also provide evidence for the conventional nature <strong>of</strong> praise <strong>of</strong> lifelike<br />

works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> antiquity. <strong>The</strong> epigrams are not consistent regard<strong>in</strong>g the identity <strong>and</strong><br />

appearance <strong>of</strong> Myron’s famous statue. Some <strong>of</strong> them, for example, identify the statue as<br />

that <strong>of</strong> a cow (bou~j)—a mature female <strong>of</strong> a bov<strong>in</strong>e animal—<strong>and</strong>, some others, as that <strong>of</strong><br />

a heifer, that is, a young cow that has not produced a calf (da&malij; boi/dion). Also, <strong>in</strong><br />

some epigrams, the statue announces that it is equipped with a yoke, whereas, <strong>in</strong> another,<br />

it asks for one. This evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates that the poems are variations <strong>of</strong> a basic theme,<br />

Myron’s lifelike statue <strong>of</strong> a cow, but do not require any experience <strong>of</strong> the statue. All<br />

epigrams, however, focus on plac<strong>in</strong>g high value on the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue, which<br />

they perceive as aliveness. In view <strong>of</strong> this evidence, a cow or a heifer is presented as<br />

utterly real, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g the importance <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> connection with the ancient<br />

Greek experience <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art.<br />

Several epigrams give a sense <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>consistency regard<strong>in</strong>g the identity <strong>of</strong><br />

Myron’s statue. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g five are good examples <strong>of</strong> this situation:<br />

Stranger, it was Myron who moulded this cow (bou~n),<br />

on which this calf fawns as if it were alive, tak<strong>in</strong>g it for<br />

its mother. (Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.733) [24]<br />

<strong>The</strong> horned cow (bou~j) would have spoken, though<br />

68


made <strong>of</strong> bronze, if Myron had worked entrails <strong>in</strong>side it.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.727) [21]<br />

<strong>The</strong> cow (bou~j), its mother, moulded this heifer (bou~n)<br />

giv<strong>in</strong>g birth to it, but the h<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Myron did not mould<br />

it, but gave birth to it.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.726) [20]<br />

Myron pretended this heifer (boi/dion) to be the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> his h<strong>and</strong>s, but it was never formed <strong>in</strong> the mould,<br />

but turned <strong>in</strong>to bronze ow<strong>in</strong>g to old age.<br />

(Anacreon, Anth. Pal. 9.716) [13]<br />

Pass by the heifer (da&mal<strong>in</strong>), cowherd, <strong>and</strong> whistle not<br />

to her from afar. She is expect<strong>in</strong>g her calf to suckle it.<br />

(Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anth. Pal. 9.722) [32]<br />

All five epigrams underl<strong>in</strong>e the exceptional aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue, by address<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

viewer or reader directly. In the first epigram, an anonymous, it is made explicit that the<br />

statue is that <strong>of</strong> a cow (“bou~n”); its lifelikeness is conveyed by stat<strong>in</strong>g that a calf<br />

responded to it as if it were alive. In the second epigram, also anonymous, the statue is<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> identified as a cow (“bou~j”) that is very close to be<strong>in</strong>g alive; it lacks only voice. In<br />

the third anonymous epigram, the statue is aga<strong>in</strong> so alive <strong>and</strong> called “bou~n,” which one<br />

would expect to mean “cow,” but W. R. Paton translates it as “heifer.” <strong>The</strong> poem also<br />

uses the same term, bou~j, to refer to the mother <strong>of</strong> this “heifer,” which Paton rightly<br />

translates as “cow.” 116 It is clear, therefore, that the <strong>in</strong>consistency here refers to the<br />

modern translation rather than the term used for identify<strong>in</strong>g the statue, which once aga<strong>in</strong><br />

is perceived as if it were alive.<br />

In the fourth epigram, perhaps by Anacreon, the statue is identified as a boi/dion.<br />

<strong>The</strong> term is a dim<strong>in</strong>utive <strong>of</strong> bou~j, literally a “little cow” or a “very young cow.” Paton<br />

116 W. R. Paton, ed., tr., Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1915, repr. 1925) 397.<br />

69


translates boi/dion as “heifer.” 117 <strong>The</strong> poet praises the perceived aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue,<br />

by not<strong>in</strong>g that “it was never formed <strong>in</strong> a mould”; but his reference to it as one that has<br />

been “turned <strong>in</strong>to bronze ow<strong>in</strong>g to old age,” although it admits its <strong>in</strong>animate status, does<br />

not fit well with its identification as a heifer, that is, a young cow. Although the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> this phrase rema<strong>in</strong>s unclear, the epigram is important, for it signals the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

the variety <strong>of</strong> terms used for the identification <strong>of</strong> the statue by the poets.<br />

Unlike the previous ones, the fifth epigram, by Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, from the first<br />

century B.C., refers to the statue as da&mal<strong>in</strong>, which translates as “heifer.” <strong>The</strong> poet<br />

<strong>in</strong>structs the viewer, a coward, to treat the heifer as a statue <strong>and</strong> not as a real animal,<br />

while mak<strong>in</strong>g reference to its aliveness. <strong>The</strong> heifer, by def<strong>in</strong>ition a young cow that has<br />

not produced a calf, is described as a mother wait<strong>in</strong>g for her calf to suckle it, thus<br />

suggest<strong>in</strong>g no attention to such a conflict<strong>in</strong>g detail. Taken together, the evidence from<br />

these epigrams <strong>in</strong>dicates that they are different versions <strong>of</strong> a basic theme, <strong>and</strong> do not<br />

depend on direct knowledge <strong>of</strong> the statue. Thus, whether the statue is a cow, a little cow,<br />

or a heifer, is <strong>of</strong> no a concern to the poet; <strong>in</strong>stead, what he focuses on is the praise <strong>of</strong> its<br />

exceptional lifelikeness, which is perceived as aliveness.<br />

Two further epigrams show that <strong>in</strong>consistencies were not conf<strong>in</strong>ed to the identity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue, but extended also to its appearance, without, however, affect<strong>in</strong>g the praise<br />

<strong>of</strong> its conventionally assumed aliveness. Thus, <strong>in</strong> an epigram, by Philippus, dated to the<br />

117 Paton, Greek Anthology III 395. Anacreon was a lyric poet <strong>of</strong> the late sixth <strong>and</strong> early fifth centuries<br />

B.C., that is, earlier that Myron’s floruit. His work is known to have <strong>in</strong>spired a corpus <strong>of</strong> frivolous<br />

imitations <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> after the Hellenistic period (between the first century B.C. or A.D. <strong>and</strong> the fifth or sixth<br />

century A.D.): M. L. West, “Anacreontea,” <strong>in</strong> S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Dictionary (third ed.; Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) 80. <strong>The</strong> epigram may be part <strong>of</strong> this corpus.<br />

70


first century A.D., the statue presents itself with a yoke, whereas <strong>in</strong> another, by an<br />

anonymous poet, asks for one:<br />

Take <strong>of</strong>f from my neck, husb<strong>and</strong>man, the collar,<br />

<strong>and</strong> free me from the iron furrow-cutter; for Myron<br />

did not make my bronze <strong>in</strong>to flesh, but his art gave<br />

me the aspect <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g alive, so that <strong>of</strong>ten I even<br />

wish to low. He did not, however, let me go to<br />

work, but tied me to the base.<br />

(Philippus, Anth. Pal. 9.742) [140]<br />

Let someone attach me to the solid plough <strong>and</strong><br />

put a yoke on my neck, for as far as depends on<br />

thy art, Myron, I will plough.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.729) [22]<br />

In both epigrams, the statue speaks to the viewer directly. In both, the statue presents<br />

itself, as if it were alive, by act<strong>in</strong>g both as a speak<strong>in</strong>g object <strong>and</strong> an animal. In the first,<br />

the statue comm<strong>and</strong>s the viewer or reader, who is a husb<strong>and</strong>man, to free it from its yoke,<br />

emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, an attribute <strong>of</strong> its appearance; it also attributes its aliveness to<br />

Myron, <strong>and</strong> announces its placement on a base, thus admitt<strong>in</strong>g its reality as a work <strong>of</strong> art,<br />

while declar<strong>in</strong>g its wish to act naturally, namely, to low. In this way, the epigram blurs<br />

the l<strong>in</strong>e between image <strong>and</strong> reality. <strong>The</strong> same situation is seen <strong>in</strong> the second epigram,<br />

where the statue identifies itself as a work <strong>of</strong> Myron, while address<strong>in</strong>g him directly, as if<br />

it were alive. <strong>The</strong> statue declares its aliveness by ask<strong>in</strong>g Myron to place a yoke on its<br />

neck. Its image, therefore, contrasts with that <strong>of</strong> the yoked animal it was shown to be <strong>in</strong><br />

the first epigram. This evidence suggests that details, such as the presence or absence <strong>of</strong><br />

a yoke, were variations <strong>of</strong> the basic subject that Myron’s statue was thought to represent,<br />

<strong>and</strong> did not affect the high value placed on the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue, which was<br />

conceived as aliveness. Several epigrams, therefore, that celebrate Myron’s cow <strong>of</strong>fer a<br />

71


useful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the conventional nature <strong>of</strong> the praise <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong><br />

antiquity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Epigrams <strong>of</strong> Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros<br />

As mentioned above, two epigrams by Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros, very probably dat<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

the fifth century B.C., are important because they are the only almost contemporary<br />

evidence for the reception <strong>of</strong> Myron’s bronze statue. <strong>The</strong> epigrams praise the sense <strong>of</strong><br />

aliveness associated with the statue, which is identified as a cow <strong>and</strong> a heifer<br />

respectively:<br />

Either a complete hide <strong>of</strong> bronze clothes here a<br />

real cow (boi6), or the bronze has a soul <strong>in</strong>side it<br />

(yuxh_n e1ndon). (Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.717) [92]<br />

Perhaps Myron himself will say this: “I did not<br />

mould this heifer (ta_n da&mal<strong>in</strong>), but its image."<br />

(Euenos, Anth. Pal. 9.718) [93]<br />

In the first epigram, Myron is not mentioned, but it is made explicit that the lifelikeness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the bronze cow described is astonish<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> viewer or the reader is told that the<br />

bronze is only a cover that hides the real animal underneath, imply<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, the<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> the statue as if it were alive. Similarly, the reference to bronze as a material<br />

with a soul <strong>in</strong>vites the perception <strong>of</strong> the statue as fully animated, <strong>and</strong> thus as if it were<br />

alive, aga<strong>in</strong>. 118 It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to see that another epigram, an anonymous, advertises the<br />

118 This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> thought accords well with Plato’s assertion, <strong>in</strong> the Cratylus (400a), that the soul is a power,<br />

which when present <strong>in</strong> the body, it causes it to live <strong>and</strong> gives it power to breathe the air <strong>and</strong> be revitalized.<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> animated images <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, see also A. Schnapp, “Are Images Animated: <strong>The</strong><br />

Psychology <strong>of</strong> the Statues <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> C. Renfrew <strong>and</strong> E. B. W. Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient<br />

M<strong>in</strong>d: Elements <strong>of</strong> Cognitive Archaeology (Cambridge, 1994) 40-44. Also, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

a)yuxi/a (“absence <strong>of</strong> soul”) <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate images <strong>in</strong> antiquity, <strong>and</strong> as a topos <strong>of</strong> iconoclastic polemic, see<br />

Donohue, Xoana 40-41, 135, 138n, 155, 161.<br />

72


lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue, <strong>in</strong> quite the opposite way: by treat<strong>in</strong>g the absence <strong>of</strong> a soul <strong>in</strong> it,<br />

as the only trait that separates it from a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal:<br />

Alack! Myron, thou didst not have time to<br />

complete thy cast<strong>in</strong>g, but the bronze hardened<br />

before thou couldst put life (yuxh_n) <strong>in</strong>to it.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.736) [26]<br />

In the second epigram by Euenos, which identifies the statue as a heifer, the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> extreme aliveness is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Myron’s hypothetical explanation that this is<br />

not a real animal, but an image <strong>of</strong> it. Myron’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the liv<strong>in</strong>g heifer<br />

(subject) <strong>and</strong> its image is not consistent with fifth-century thought on images <strong>in</strong> art,<br />

which is <strong>of</strong>ten marked by the absence <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between representational subject<br />

<strong>and</strong> image. 119 That he is hypothetically compelled to draw such a dist<strong>in</strong>ction, however,<br />

presents his deviation from an ord<strong>in</strong>ary approach to art as a technique to expla<strong>in</strong> the<br />

extraord<strong>in</strong>ary lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> his statue. Both epigrams are typical examples <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistency regard<strong>in</strong>g the identity <strong>of</strong> Myron’s statue <strong>and</strong> its oscillation between a cow<br />

<strong>and</strong> a heifer; both establish the experience <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>and</strong> its equation with aliveness<br />

as a fifth-century phenomenon <strong>in</strong> Greek animal art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Statue Acts Fantastically<br />

As noted earlier <strong>and</strong> also seen <strong>in</strong> the poem <strong>of</strong> Philippus, some epigrams preserve<br />

<strong>in</strong>stances <strong>in</strong> which the statue acts fantastically by speak<strong>in</strong>g directly to the viewer.<br />

Epigrams <strong>of</strong> this type are explicit <strong>in</strong> their use <strong>of</strong> the first person <strong>and</strong> the presentation <strong>of</strong><br />

the statue as both a “speak<strong>in</strong>g object” <strong>and</strong> a “speak<strong>in</strong>g animal.” <strong>The</strong>y address both<br />

119 See discussion <strong>in</strong> the fourth chapter <strong>of</strong> this study with reference to examples from Herodotus, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion; also Donohue, Xoana , for the absence <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between<br />

image <strong>and</strong> subject, <strong>and</strong> 23, for the importance <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> image as an object; also R. L. Gordon, “<strong>The</strong><br />

Real <strong>and</strong> the Imag<strong>in</strong>ary: Production <strong>and</strong> Religion <strong>in</strong> the Graeco-Roman World,” Art History 2 (1979) 9-10.<br />

73


anonymous <strong>and</strong> specific viewers, such as Myron <strong>and</strong> herdsmen, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicate that the<br />

viewer is aware that this is a speak<strong>in</strong>g image <strong>of</strong> an animal.<br />

In the earliest <strong>of</strong> these epigrams, which is attributed to Leonidas <strong>of</strong> Tarentum <strong>and</strong><br />

dates to the third century B.C., Myron’s statue directly addresses an unidentified viewer:<br />

Myron did not mould me; he lied; but driv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

me from the herd where I was feed<strong>in</strong>g, he fixed me<br />

to a stone base. (Leonidas, Anth. Pal. 9.719) [131]<br />

<strong>The</strong> epigram conta<strong>in</strong>s the fiction <strong>of</strong> the statue speak<strong>in</strong>g as though it were alive. By us<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the voice <strong>of</strong> the viewer, who is simultaneously a reader <strong>of</strong> the epigram, the statue<br />

establishes itself as a speak<strong>in</strong>g object, cross<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, two boundaries at once: that <strong>of</strong><br />

a lifeless object, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> a speechless animal. 120 In this way, it presents itself as if it<br />

were super alive. <strong>The</strong> statue expla<strong>in</strong>s the reason it is alive: Myron took it from its herd,<br />

where it was feed<strong>in</strong>g, thus act<strong>in</strong>g naturally, <strong>and</strong> placed it on a base. <strong>The</strong> statue announces<br />

its aliveness while acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g its status as a work <strong>of</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> boundary between<br />

reality <strong>and</strong> image appears to be freely crossed, <strong>and</strong> the viewer or reader is fully aware <strong>of</strong><br />

it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g statue further announces its aliveness <strong>in</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> five epigrams, <strong>in</strong><br />

which it addresses viewers, among them Myron <strong>and</strong> a herdsman, directly:<br />

If Myron had not fixed my feet to this stone I<br />

would have gone to pasture with the other cows.<br />

(Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anth. Pal. 9.720) [30]<br />

<strong>The</strong> lead <strong>and</strong> stone hold me fast, but, otherwise,<br />

thanks to thee, sculptor Myron, I would be nibbl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

lotus <strong>and</strong> rushes. (Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anth. Pal. 9.723) [33]<br />

Why, Myron, didst thou set me here by the altars?<br />

120 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the metaphor <strong>of</strong> the speak<strong>in</strong>g object through the voice <strong>of</strong> the reader <strong>in</strong> connection<br />

with dedicatory <strong>in</strong>scriptions, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g epigrams, on statues <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, see Svenbro, Phrasikleia 49-<br />

63.<br />

74


Wilt thou not lead me <strong>in</strong>to the house?<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.714) [17]<br />

<strong>The</strong> first epigram, by Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, dates to the first century B.C., <strong>and</strong> conta<strong>in</strong>s an<br />

explanation: the speak<strong>in</strong>g cow is alive, but, at the same time, fixed on a stone, therefore,<br />

motionless. <strong>The</strong> statue, therefore, <strong>in</strong>vites the viewer to experience it as a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal<br />

naturally found among other cows, while mark<strong>in</strong>g its status as a work <strong>of</strong> sculpture made<br />

by Myron. Aga<strong>in</strong>, the poem presents a case <strong>of</strong> dissolution <strong>of</strong> the boundary between<br />

reality <strong>and</strong> image, <strong>and</strong> the viewer’s awareness <strong>of</strong> it. In the second epigram, also by<br />

Antipater, the statue directly addresses Myron by blam<strong>in</strong>g him for its fixed location. <strong>The</strong><br />

statue states that were it not for this condition, it would have been able to feed, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

act as a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal. <strong>The</strong> statue announces its <strong>in</strong>animate status as Myron’s work <strong>of</strong> art,<br />

while highlight<strong>in</strong>g its apparent aliveness. In the third epigram, an anonymous, the statue<br />

questions Myron directly. By specify<strong>in</strong>g its set-up location by the altars, <strong>in</strong> the first<br />

question, the statue identifies itself as a work <strong>of</strong> art, while its compla<strong>in</strong> about not be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>side the house, <strong>in</strong> the second question, implies its wish to be treated as a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal,<br />

thus advertis<strong>in</strong>g its aliveness.<br />

In the fourth epigram, attributed to Marcus Argentarius, <strong>and</strong> dat<strong>in</strong>g from the first<br />

century B.C., the statue aga<strong>in</strong> addresses an unidentified viewer directly, as if it were a<br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g, speak<strong>in</strong>g animal, while p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g its status as a work <strong>of</strong> art:<br />

Stranger, if thou seest my herdsman, give him<br />

this message, that the sculptor Myron tied me up here.<br />

(Marcus Argentarius, Anth. Pal. 9.732) [133]<br />

<strong>The</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g statue declares confidently its aliveness by ask<strong>in</strong>g the viewer a favor: to<br />

<strong>in</strong>form its herdsman about its be<strong>in</strong>g tied up by Myron at a spot. In this way, the statue<br />

implies that it could move as a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal, were it not for its status as a work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

75


Aga<strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>e between reality <strong>and</strong> image is blurred, while the viewer is aware <strong>of</strong> his<br />

view<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>animate work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

Written as though it came from the base <strong>of</strong> the statue, the fifth epigram, an<br />

anonymous, has Myron’s statue say<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

I am Myron’s little heifer, set up on a base. Goad<br />

me, herdsman, <strong>and</strong> drive me <strong>of</strong>f to the herd.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.713) [16]<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue speaks to the viewer, a herdsman, directly by declar<strong>in</strong>g its identity, creator,<br />

<strong>and</strong> status as a lifeless object. By us<strong>in</strong>g the voice <strong>of</strong> the viewer, as was the case earlier,<br />

the statue establishes itself neither as a lifeless object nor as a speechless animal, but,<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead, as if it were alive. <strong>The</strong> impression <strong>of</strong> aliveness is further re<strong>in</strong>forced by the use <strong>of</strong><br />

the first person, which blurs the l<strong>in</strong>e between image <strong>and</strong> reality, <strong>and</strong> also by the fact that<br />

the statue addresses the viewer <strong>in</strong> the imperative <strong>and</strong> urges him to perform two specific<br />

acts: goad it <strong>and</strong> drive it <strong>of</strong>f to the herd. In this way, the viewer is <strong>in</strong>vited to <strong>in</strong>teract with<br />

Myron’s statue as if it were a liv<strong>in</strong>g heifer. This is evidence <strong>of</strong> a play between the viewer<br />

<strong>and</strong> the statue. At the same time, the fact that the statue identifies its placement as “on a<br />

base” serves to demonstrate that the viewer is aware <strong>of</strong> its motionless status as a work <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture. This evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates that animals were lifelike subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art,<br />

which viewers experienced as liv<strong>in</strong>g, while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g awareness <strong>of</strong> the fact that they<br />

were view<strong>in</strong>g art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Statue Acts Naturally<br />

Unlike the epigrams <strong>in</strong> which Myron’s statue acts fantastically by speak<strong>in</strong>g, some<br />

other epigrams preserve <strong>in</strong>stances, <strong>in</strong> which the statue acts “naturally,” that is to say, how<br />

76


a real animal might act <strong>in</strong> the real world. As with the conceit <strong>of</strong> the speak<strong>in</strong>g cow, these<br />

epigrams rely also on conceits <strong>in</strong> order to convey the exceptional or conventionally<br />

assumed lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue.<br />

A set <strong>of</strong> four epigrams, two by Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, one by Gem<strong>in</strong>us, <strong>and</strong> another,<br />

an anonymous, conceive <strong>of</strong> Myron’s bronze cow as be<strong>in</strong>g alive, by not<strong>in</strong>g that the animal<br />

acts or will act naturally. <strong>The</strong> two epigrams, attributed to Antipater, <strong>and</strong> dated to the first<br />

century B.C., address Myron <strong>and</strong> an unidentified viewer respectively:<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k the heifer will low. Of a truth it is not<br />

Prometheus alone who moulds liv<strong>in</strong>g creatures,<br />

but thou too, Myron.<br />

(Antipater, Anth. Pal. 9.724) [34]<br />

<strong>The</strong> heifer, I th<strong>in</strong>k, will low, <strong>and</strong> if its delays it<br />

is the fault <strong>of</strong> the senseless bronze, not Myron’s.<br />

(Antipater, Anth. Pal. 9.728) [35]<br />

In the first epigram, Antipater presents himself as a viewer <strong>of</strong> Myron’s heifer (not cow,<br />

thus <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g another example <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>consistent identity <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>in</strong> the epigrams).<br />

Antipater states, first, that the animal will low, thus convey<strong>in</strong>g his impression <strong>of</strong> it as<br />

behav<strong>in</strong>g naturally, <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> turn, as if it were alive. That the heifer is actually a statue<br />

becomes apparent as the poet proceeds to identify Myron as its creator. By compar<strong>in</strong>g<br />

him to Prometheus, Antipater marks Myron’s skill <strong>in</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g exceptionally lifelike<br />

works <strong>of</strong> art, thus expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g his previous conception <strong>of</strong> the statue as a liv<strong>in</strong>g heifer. By<br />

highlight<strong>in</strong>g the perceived equivalence <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> life, the epigram sheds light onto both<br />

the ancient concept <strong>of</strong> the “artist,” <strong>and</strong> also onto aliveness as the utmost level <strong>of</strong> the<br />

lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> antiquity. In the second epigram, the poet aga<strong>in</strong> conceives<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue as a heifer that acts naturally, by low<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> thus as if it were alive. He<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> underl<strong>in</strong>es Myron’s exceptional skill <strong>in</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art. In fact, he<br />

77


anks this artist’s skill higher than the capacity <strong>of</strong> the bronze used for the creation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statue. <strong>The</strong> poet holds the use <strong>of</strong> bronze responsible for delay<strong>in</strong>g his impression that the<br />

statue will low. 121 His comment reveals a positive attitude towards bronze as a suitable<br />

material for lifelike art perceived as alive. His reference to bronze as “senseless,”<br />

acknowledges the status <strong>of</strong> the heifer as an <strong>in</strong>animate object, <strong>and</strong> further notes his<br />

awareness that he is look<strong>in</strong>g at art <strong>and</strong> not “life.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> third epigram, by Gem<strong>in</strong>us, also from the first century B.C., conta<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

same praise <strong>of</strong> the aliveness the statue as the epigrams attributed to Antipater. <strong>The</strong> poet<br />

addresses the viewer directly, by not<strong>in</strong>g that the heifer acts naturally:<br />

It is the base to which it is attached that keeps<br />

back the heifer, <strong>and</strong> if freed from it will run <strong>of</strong>f<br />

to the herd. For the bronze lows. See how much<br />

alive the artist made it. If you yoke a fellow to it,<br />

perhaps it will plough.<br />

(Gem<strong>in</strong>us, Anth. Pal. 9.740) [95]<br />

<strong>The</strong> heifer is acknowledged as a statue fixed on a base; yet if freed, the heifer will run <strong>of</strong>f<br />

to its herd, <strong>and</strong> if yoked to another animal, will plough. Aga<strong>in</strong>, the boundary between art<br />

<strong>and</strong> reality is freely crossed here, without any concern on the side <strong>of</strong> Gem<strong>in</strong>us, who acts<br />

here as both a viewer <strong>and</strong> a narrator. He further states, like Antipater above, that the<br />

bronze lows. He is aware that this is lifeless art, but allows himself to imag<strong>in</strong>e that the<br />

heifer behaves naturally as if it were alive. His comment reveals a positive attitude<br />

towards bronze as a suitable material for lifelike art that is consciously equated here with<br />

“reality.” Further, his remark that the artist <strong>of</strong> the heifer made it to look alive suggests<br />

that lifelikeness was thought to result from the skill <strong>of</strong> the artist comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the use <strong>of</strong><br />

bronze.<br />

121<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y (NH 34.5.10) states that Myron used Aeg<strong>in</strong>etan bronze, which he ranks second <strong>in</strong> fame after that<br />

<strong>of</strong> Cor<strong>in</strong>th.<br />

78


<strong>The</strong> fourth epigram, an anonymous, also praises the aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue by<br />

draw<strong>in</strong>g attention to its natural behavior. In it, the poet exclaims that:<br />

<strong>The</strong> cow has just returned from plow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong><br />

ow<strong>in</strong>g to that is lazy <strong>and</strong> will not advance.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.721A) [18]<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue is identified as that <strong>of</strong> a cow, <strong>and</strong> is described as act<strong>in</strong>g naturally. <strong>The</strong> viewer<br />

is told that the cow is lazy <strong>and</strong> immobile ow<strong>in</strong>g to its employment <strong>in</strong> plow<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong><br />

implication is that the cow is a tired, labor<strong>in</strong>g animal; as such, it rema<strong>in</strong>s fixed at a spot<br />

like an <strong>in</strong>animate work <strong>of</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> epigram plays with the viewer’s awareness <strong>of</strong> the fact<br />

that he is look<strong>in</strong>g at a lifeless cow.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> Herdsmen<br />

Further evidence for the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s statue <strong>and</strong> its<br />

conception as alive comes from a set <strong>of</strong> epigrams, <strong>in</strong> which the statue is viewed by<br />

herdsmen, that is, persons well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with the appearance <strong>and</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> a cow <strong>in</strong><br />

real life; yet they are deceived <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that the statue is a liv<strong>in</strong>g cow.<br />

In the first epigram, an anonymous, the statue says:<br />

Myron placed me the heifer, here, but the herds-<br />

men throw stones at me th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g I have strayed.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.731) [23]<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue addresses the viewer directly, <strong>and</strong> through the use <strong>of</strong> the first person, identifies<br />

itself as a heifer. <strong>The</strong> statue blames Myron for its placement at a spot, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g its<br />

reality as a fixed object, <strong>and</strong> the viewer’s awareness <strong>of</strong> that fact. <strong>The</strong> statue<br />

communicates to the viewer that herdsmen throw stones at it, a statement which<br />

advertises its treatment as a liv<strong>in</strong>g heifer. <strong>The</strong> conceit <strong>of</strong> the speak<strong>in</strong>g animal urges the<br />

79


viewer to put himself <strong>in</strong> the place <strong>of</strong> a herdsman too young or foolish not to recognize a<br />

statue, yet the identification <strong>of</strong> passersby as herdsmen implies their good knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

the appearance <strong>and</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> real heifers, a fact, which serves to demonstrate the<br />

heightened sense <strong>of</strong> aliveness conveyed by the statue. Like the previous ones, this<br />

epigram shows the centrality <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> viewers’ perceiv<strong>in</strong>g lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art as<br />

aliveness while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g awareness <strong>of</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g at art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second epigram, perhaps by Anacreon, praises the aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue by<br />

urg<strong>in</strong>g a herdsman not to mix its herd with Myron’s heifer. <strong>The</strong> poet fears that, despite<br />

his knowledge <strong>of</strong> cows, not even a herdsman will be able to dist<strong>in</strong>guish the bronze heifer<br />

from a real one:<br />

Herdsman, pasture thy herd far from here, lest<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g Myron’s heifer to be alive thou drive it <strong>of</strong>f<br />

with the rest. (Anacreon (?), Anth. Pal. 9.715) [12]<br />

<strong>The</strong> third epigram, an anonymous, has the poet aga<strong>in</strong> urg<strong>in</strong>g a herdsman to stop<br />

treat<strong>in</strong>g Myron’s bronze heifer as if it were alive:<br />

Thou strikest the bronze heifer. Art deceived<br />

thee much, herdsman: Myron did not add life.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.737) [27]<br />

<strong>The</strong> poet <strong>in</strong>forms a herdsman that he has been deceived <strong>in</strong>to believ<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

Myron’s bronze heifer is alive. <strong>The</strong> poet notes the response <strong>of</strong> the deceived herdsman to<br />

the statue: strik<strong>in</strong>g it as if it were a liv<strong>in</strong>g cow, while stat<strong>in</strong>g, at the same time, that this is<br />

a work <strong>of</strong> art made by Myron. Further, by not<strong>in</strong>g the punishment <strong>of</strong> the bronze statue, the<br />

epigram <strong>in</strong>dicates that animal subjects were parts <strong>of</strong> the general body <strong>of</strong> thought <strong>and</strong><br />

literary conceits <strong>and</strong> practices.<br />

80


In the fourth epigram, also an anonymous, the poet addresses the statue directly<br />

by mark<strong>in</strong>g its treatment by a husb<strong>and</strong>man as if it were a liv<strong>in</strong>g, labor<strong>in</strong>g cow:<br />

Thou wast bronze, deceptive heifer, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

husb<strong>and</strong>man came up to thee dragg<strong>in</strong>g a plough<br />

<strong>and</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g a yoke. He far excels all other artists,<br />

Myron, who by his labour made thee alive, just like<br />

a labour<strong>in</strong>g cow. (Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.741) [28]<br />

<strong>The</strong> poet attributes the perceived aliveness <strong>of</strong> the statue to Myron himself while show<strong>in</strong>g<br />

his awareness that it is a work <strong>of</strong> art made by Myron. <strong>The</strong> poet notes the deception <strong>of</strong> a<br />

husb<strong>and</strong>man by identify<strong>in</strong>g his response to the statue as if it were alive: he carried a<br />

plough <strong>and</strong> a yoke to it.<br />

Another epigram, by Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong> Egypt, dat<strong>in</strong>g probably from the sixth<br />

century A.D., charges not only herdsmen, but also a gadfly with a mistaken reaction to<br />

the statue. <strong>The</strong> poet addresses the gadfly directly:<br />

Myron deceived thee too, gadfly, that thou plungest<br />

thy st<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the hard flanks <strong>of</strong> the bronze cow.<br />

But the gadfly is excusable. What wonder! when<br />

Myron deceived even the eyes <strong>of</strong> the herdsmen.<br />

(Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong> Egypt, Anth. Pal. 9.739). [130]<br />

<strong>The</strong> gadfly tries to st<strong>in</strong>g the bronze cow; it responds to it as if it were alive. <strong>The</strong> behavior<br />

<strong>of</strong> the gadfly speaks <strong>of</strong> the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue while <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that non-human<br />

creatures were used as guides to lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. Of <strong>in</strong>terest is that the poet marks the<br />

gadfly’s perception <strong>of</strong> this cow as a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal as “excusable.” His word<strong>in</strong>g implies<br />

that <strong>in</strong>sects were considered creatures <strong>of</strong> limited cognitive capacity, <strong>and</strong> thus the<br />

deception <strong>of</strong> a gadfly comes as no surprise to him. Such a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g exp<strong>and</strong>s<br />

Plato’s category <strong>of</strong> viewers easily deceived by the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> fact, however,<br />

that Myron “deceived even the eyes <strong>of</strong> the herdsmen,” that is, human be<strong>in</strong>gs with<br />

81


<strong>in</strong>timate knowledge <strong>of</strong> a real cow, therefore twice as difficult to fool, speaks volumes <strong>of</strong><br />

the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> his statue <strong>of</strong> a cow. This impression is further<br />

strengthened by an anonymous epigram, <strong>in</strong> which, Myron himself comes close to be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

fooled by the statue:<br />

Myron was look<strong>in</strong>g for his own cow among the<br />

others, <strong>and</strong> found it with difficulty by driv<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

rest away. (Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.725) [19]<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence from these epigrams <strong>in</strong>dicates the conception <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow as an<br />

exceptionally lifelike statue capable <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g even herdsmen, who know very well how<br />

a real cow looks like, perceive it as if it were alive. In this way, lifelikeness aga<strong>in</strong><br />

emerges as a valued quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, which <strong>in</strong> its extreme form was perceived as<br />

aliveness, <strong>and</strong> one <strong>in</strong> whose expression Myron’s statue played an important role.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> a Calf<br />

Herdsmen <strong>and</strong> a gadfly are not the only viewers whose deception the poems note.<br />

A set <strong>of</strong> three epigrams, one by Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, <strong>and</strong> two other, anonymous, note that a<br />

calf was also deceived <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that Myron’s statue was alive. In the first epigram,<br />

the statue asks the calf:<br />

Calf, why dost thou approach my flanks, <strong>and</strong> why<br />

doast thou low? <strong>The</strong> artist put no milk <strong>in</strong> my udder.<br />

(Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anth. Pal. 9.721) [31]<br />

Through the voice <strong>of</strong> the viewer or the reader, the statue addresses a calf <strong>in</strong> the vocative.<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue asks the calf, a younger fellow animal, why it responds to it as if it were alive:<br />

why it approaches its flanks, <strong>and</strong> lows. <strong>The</strong> calf rema<strong>in</strong>s silent, <strong>and</strong> the statue proceeds to<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> its status as a work <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> its lack <strong>of</strong> milk. <strong>The</strong> calf, therefore, appears to have<br />

82


mistaken a bronze cow for a real one, <strong>and</strong> seem<strong>in</strong>gly for a mature one from which it can<br />

suckle. This evidence heightens the sense <strong>of</strong> aliveness conveyed by the statue; it shows<br />

that animals were subjects <strong>of</strong> lifelike art, while portray<strong>in</strong>g animals, along with the gadfly,<br />

as trustworthy judges <strong>of</strong> the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>in</strong> particular animal sculpture. In addition,<br />

the fact that the viewer is a calf, that is, a young animal, which perceives the statue <strong>of</strong> a<br />

mature fellow animal as liv<strong>in</strong>g, br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d Plato’s earlier remark that<br />

children were among those <strong>in</strong>dividuals easily deceived by the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

In the second epigram, an anonymous, (<strong>and</strong> already discussed for its reference to<br />

the statue as a cow), the poet addresses the viewer directly:<br />

Stranger, it was Myron who moulded this cow, on<br />

which this calf fawns as if it were alive, tak<strong>in</strong>g it for<br />

its mother. (Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.733) [24]<br />

In the epigram, the poet addresses an unidentified viewer. He notes the response <strong>of</strong> a calf<br />

to the statue as if it were a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal explicitly identified here as a cow. <strong>The</strong> viewer is<br />

further told that the calf was deceived <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the statue as its own mother. <strong>The</strong><br />

reader is made aware that this is a work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

In the third epigram, also anonymous, the poet addresses Myron directly:<br />

A calf died beside thy heifer, Myron, deceived<br />

<strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that the bronze had milk <strong>in</strong>side.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 9.735) [25]<br />

<strong>The</strong> poet identifies Myron’s statue as that <strong>of</strong> a heifer. He establishes the deceptive power<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue over the calf, by stat<strong>in</strong>g that the latter died beside the former. Aga<strong>in</strong>, the<br />

reader is made aware that this is a work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

In all three epigrams, an animal identified as a calf mistakes a lifeless cow for a<br />

real one, thus establish<strong>in</strong>g the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue. This evidence<br />

83


<strong>in</strong>dicates that animals did not only serve as lifelike subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, but also as<br />

judges <strong>of</strong> the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Deception <strong>of</strong> a Bull<br />

A calf is not the only example <strong>of</strong> an animal deceived by the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong><br />

Myron’s cow. <strong>The</strong> epigrams also refer to a bull, an adult animal, as be<strong>in</strong>g fooled <strong>in</strong>to<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that this is a real cow. In an epigram by Dioscorides, who was active <strong>in</strong> the third<br />

century B.C., a bull is told that it has been deceived; its behavior towards the statue,<br />

(called here a heifer), as if it were alive is po<strong>in</strong>tless, for this is a work <strong>of</strong> art:<br />

In va<strong>in</strong>, bull, thou rushest up to this heifer, for it<br />

is lifeless. <strong>The</strong> sculptor <strong>of</strong> cows, Myron, deceived thee.<br />

(Dioscorides, Anth. Pal. 9.734) [83]<br />

It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g that, <strong>in</strong> this epigram, a bull reacts to Myron’s heifer as if it were alive. It<br />

seems that the poet wants to stress the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> the statue by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

out that even a mature animal with thorough knowledge <strong>of</strong> a heifer could mistake the<br />

statue for a real animal. This evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates an underly<strong>in</strong>g perception <strong>of</strong> animals on<br />

the side <strong>of</strong> the poet: as guides to lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. Thus, if an animal like a bull can be<br />

deceived <strong>in</strong>to believ<strong>in</strong>g a lifeless heifer to be real, then the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong><br />

Myron’s statue is established beyond doubt.<br />

In another epigram, by Demetrius <strong>of</strong> Bithynia, who may have lived <strong>in</strong> the second<br />

century B.C., a bull aga<strong>in</strong> features as an animal deceived by the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s<br />

statue. <strong>The</strong> later speaks directly to the viewer:<br />

If a calf sees me, it will low; a bull will mount<br />

me, <strong>and</strong> the herdsman drive me to the herd.<br />

(Demetrius <strong>of</strong> Bithynia, Anth. Pal. 9.730) [80]<br />

84


<strong>The</strong> statue proclaims its lifelikeness by identify<strong>in</strong>g its treatment as alive not only by a<br />

bull, but also by a calf <strong>and</strong> a herdsman, thus add<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g new to the already<br />

established categories <strong>of</strong> viewers who have been deceived. Like the previous ones, this<br />

epigram po<strong>in</strong>ts to viewers who share a common element: thorough knowledge <strong>of</strong> a cow’s<br />

appearance. Viewed aga<strong>in</strong>st Plato’s explicit assertion that good knowledge <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

tried to be represented <strong>in</strong> art is a necessary criterion for good judgment <strong>of</strong> art, animals<br />

emerge here as qualified judges <strong>of</strong> art. 122 In fact, by identify<strong>in</strong>g cognition as a visual<br />

(sensory) experience <strong>in</strong> which both animals <strong>and</strong> humans partake alike, the epigrams place<br />

two otherwise dist<strong>in</strong>ct categories <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs on the same qualitative level as<br />

connoisseurs <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. In this way, animals emerge as reliable guides to the<br />

ancient Greek judgment <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. If they can be deceived, however, then,<br />

Myron’s statue has surpassed any st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness, <strong>and</strong> can, therefore, be easily<br />

seen as rival<strong>in</strong>g nature. This idea is exemplified by an epigram, by Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong><br />

Egypt, probably from the sixth century A.D., that states the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

Nature <strong>and</strong> Queen Art strove <strong>in</strong> the matter <strong>of</strong><br />

this cow, <strong>and</strong> Myron gave to each a prize <strong>of</strong> equal<br />

value. When one looks at it Art robs nature <strong>of</strong><br />

her superiority, but when one touches it Nature is nature.<br />

(Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong> Egypt, Anth. Pal. 9.738) [129]<br />

<strong>The</strong> poet refers to Myron’s cow as the balanced outcome <strong>of</strong> a struggle between nature<br />

<strong>and</strong> art, that is, between reality <strong>and</strong> image. His statement, although it may be<br />

exaggerated, <strong>in</strong>dicates belief <strong>in</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> the cow to be real, when view<strong>in</strong>g it, while<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g awareness, through touch<strong>in</strong>g it, <strong>of</strong> its artificiality as an image. Sight <strong>and</strong><br />

122 This evidence fits well with Plato’s, already discussed, remark, <strong>in</strong> the Critias (107b-107e) that <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to be able to judge art well, one needs to have <strong>in</strong>timate knowledge <strong>of</strong> what the artist tried to represent [143].<br />

85


touch are perceived here as rival senses. At the same time, they provide an example <strong>of</strong><br />

the experience <strong>of</strong> lifelike art: it was not only viewed, but also touched.<br />

<strong>The</strong> picture that emerges from the epigrams preserved <strong>in</strong> the Greek Anthology,<br />

stresses the exceptional lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow <strong>and</strong> its effect on viewers. By<br />

imply<strong>in</strong>g an appreciation <strong>of</strong> animal cognition <strong>of</strong> natural forms, the epigrams present the<br />

ancient view <strong>of</strong> animals as reliable judges <strong>of</strong> art that aimed at reproduc<strong>in</strong>g these forms,<br />

therefore, <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness. <strong>The</strong> fact that Myron’s cow was so exceptionally lifelike that<br />

succeeded <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g animals th<strong>in</strong>k it as alive presents animals as a st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> evaluation<br />

<strong>of</strong> images <strong>in</strong> which artistic skill competed with nature <strong>in</strong> its capacity to create life, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

fact, succeeded <strong>in</strong> deceiv<strong>in</strong>g the eye that it did so. Simply put, by assum<strong>in</strong>g the role <strong>of</strong><br />

reliable guides to lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art, animals validate the deceptive capacity <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

B. <strong>The</strong> Ox <strong>of</strong> Apelles<br />

<strong>The</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k between animal representations <strong>and</strong> lifelikeness is also witnessed <strong>in</strong> a<br />

third-century text—the fourth Mime <strong>of</strong> Herodas. In this text, reference to the perception<br />

<strong>of</strong> a statue <strong>of</strong> an ox as if it were alive provides another example <strong>of</strong> the centrality <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> the ancient perception <strong>of</strong> artistic lifelikeness as aliveness. <strong>The</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> characters<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mime are two women, Phile <strong>and</strong> Kynno, who, as visitors to the temple <strong>of</strong><br />

Asklepios at Cos, comment upon the various works <strong>of</strong> art they see:<br />

PHILE. Don’t you see, dear Kynno, what works are here! You would say<br />

that Athene carved these lovely th<strong>in</strong>g—greet<strong>in</strong>gs, Lady. This naked<br />

boy, I scratched him, won’t he have a wound, Kynno? For the flesh is<br />

laid on him <strong>in</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, puls<strong>in</strong>g like warm spr<strong>in</strong>gs. And the silver<br />

fire-tongs, if Myellos or Pataekiskos son <strong>of</strong> Lamprion sees them, won’t<br />

they lose their eyes th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g they are really made <strong>of</strong> silver? And the ox,<br />

86


<strong>and</strong> the man lead<strong>in</strong>g it, <strong>and</strong> the woman follow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> this hook-nosed<br />

man <strong>and</strong> the one with his hair stick<strong>in</strong>g up, don’t they all have the look <strong>of</strong><br />

life <strong>and</strong> day? If I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k I was act<strong>in</strong>g too boldly for a woman, I<br />

should have cried out, <strong>in</strong> case the ox might do some harm: he glances<br />

sideways so, Kynno with the one eye.<br />

KYNNO. Yes, Phile, the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Ephesian Apelles are truthful <strong>in</strong><br />

every l<strong>in</strong>e, nor would you say ‘That man looked at one th<strong>in</strong>g but rejected<br />

another,’ but whatever came <strong>in</strong>to his m<strong>in</strong>d he was quick <strong>and</strong> eager to<br />

attempt; <strong>and</strong> anyone who has looked on him or his works without just<br />

excitement ought to hang by the foot <strong>in</strong> the fuller’s house.<br />

(Herodas, Mime 4, 56-78) [96]<br />

Like the ord<strong>in</strong>ary viewers <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow, the women <strong>in</strong> Herodas Mime view the pa<strong>in</strong>ted<br />

image <strong>of</strong> an ox, among others, as if it were alive, while they are aware <strong>of</strong> the fact that<br />

they are look<strong>in</strong>g at art. <strong>The</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> the image is evidenced <strong>in</strong> Phile’s question to<br />

Kynno: “don’t they have all the look <strong>of</strong> life <strong>and</strong> day?” <strong>The</strong> perceived aliveness <strong>of</strong> the ox<br />

is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Phile’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> its glance sideways, which she <strong>in</strong>terprets as a<br />

harb<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>of</strong> a potentially harmful action on the side <strong>of</strong> the animal. Of particular <strong>in</strong>terest<br />

is also her reference to the specific emotional reaction that such a glance could have<br />

elicited from her: “If I did not th<strong>in</strong>k I was act<strong>in</strong>g too boldly for a woman, I should have<br />

cried out, <strong>in</strong> case the ox might do some harm: he glances sideways so, Kynno with the<br />

one eye.” This statement <strong>in</strong>dicates that, when employed as representational subjects,<br />

animals turned lifelikeness <strong>in</strong>to a quality <strong>of</strong> art that allowed the viewer to dissolve the<br />

boundary between reality <strong>and</strong> image, a characteristic also seen earlier, <strong>and</strong> to also form an<br />

emotional response to art. <strong>Animal</strong> images, therefore, show that artistic lifelikeness was<br />

evaluated on the basis <strong>of</strong> the emotions it elicited from viewers. In this case, what keeps<br />

Phile from cry<strong>in</strong>g out loud, when look<strong>in</strong>g at the ox, is the belief that this is <strong>in</strong>appropriate<br />

behavior for a woman, but otherwise a normal mode <strong>of</strong> respond<strong>in</strong>g to lifelike art.<br />

Although not referr<strong>in</strong>g to animals, the capacity <strong>of</strong> lifelike art to trigger an emotional<br />

87


eaction <strong>in</strong> the viewer is also witnessed <strong>in</strong> Kynno’s identification <strong>of</strong> the artist as Apelles<br />

<strong>and</strong> her statement that: “Anyone who has looked on him or his works without just<br />

excitement ought to hang by the foot <strong>in</strong> the fuller’s house.” In addition, her designation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Apelles as “truthful <strong>in</strong> every l<strong>in</strong>e,” implies that accuracy (fidelity to<br />

natural form) was a constituent element <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art. Overall, the dialogue<br />

between Phile <strong>and</strong> Kynno <strong>in</strong>dicates that animals <strong>of</strong>fer a useful <strong>in</strong>sight onto the Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art as aliveness <strong>and</strong> representational accuracy, <strong>and</strong> also as<br />

a criterion <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art dependent upon the viewers’ emotional response to it.<br />

C. Funerary Statues <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> central role <strong>of</strong> animal images <strong>in</strong> the perception <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art as<br />

aliveness is further demonstrated by funerary epigrams, both <strong>in</strong>scriptional <strong>and</strong> literary, <strong>in</strong><br />

which animal subjects represented <strong>in</strong> funerary statues, are given voice <strong>and</strong> engage <strong>in</strong><br />

direct conversation with the viewer. An early example <strong>of</strong> this form is an <strong>in</strong>scribed<br />

epigram that was found at Demetrias <strong>in</strong> <strong>The</strong>ssaly <strong>and</strong> dates to the early fifth century B.C.<br />

Fragmentary <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>scribed on the base <strong>of</strong> a sph<strong>in</strong>x, the epigram preserves the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

dialogue between the sph<strong>in</strong>x <strong>and</strong> the viewer (Fig. 4):<br />

A: O Sph<strong>in</strong>x, dog <strong>of</strong> Hades, whom do you…watch over,<br />

sitt<strong>in</strong>g [on guard over] the dead?<br />

B: Xe[nocrates’ tomb this is…]. [79] 123<br />

In this epigram, the viewer asks the sph<strong>in</strong>x a question <strong>and</strong> the statue answers as if it were<br />

alive. By read<strong>in</strong>g the epigram, the viewer lends his or her voice to the sph<strong>in</strong>x. <strong>The</strong><br />

viewer is aware <strong>of</strong> the lifeless status <strong>of</strong> the sph<strong>in</strong>x, but as the latter speaks through its<br />

123 P. Friedländer <strong>and</strong> H. B. H<strong>of</strong>fleit, Epigrammata. Greek Inscriptions <strong>in</strong> Verse. From the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs to<br />

the Persian Wars (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1984) 129, no. 139A.<br />

88


orrowed voice, the boundary between art <strong>and</strong> reality dissolves; as a result, lifelikeness <strong>in</strong><br />

art is experienced as aliveness.<br />

<strong>The</strong> same association between animal images <strong>and</strong> aliveness is also found <strong>in</strong> three<br />

literary epigrams from the Greek Anthology which are also composed <strong>in</strong> the dialogue<br />

form. <strong>The</strong> first is an anonymous epigram that records an exchange <strong>of</strong> questions <strong>and</strong><br />

answers between the image <strong>of</strong> an eagle on the tomb <strong>of</strong> Plato <strong>and</strong> the viewer:<br />

A: Eagle, why st<strong>and</strong>est thou on the tomb, <strong>and</strong> on whose, tell me, <strong>and</strong><br />

why gazest thou at the starry home <strong>of</strong> the gods?<br />

B: I am the image <strong>of</strong> the soul <strong>of</strong> Plato that hath flown away to<br />

Olympus, but his earth-born body rests here <strong>in</strong> Attic earth.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 7.62) [14]<br />

As <strong>in</strong> the previous epigram, the eagle speaks through the voice <strong>of</strong> the viewer as if it were<br />

alive. It also expla<strong>in</strong>s its function as an image: a substitute for the soul <strong>of</strong> Plato. Aga<strong>in</strong><br />

the l<strong>in</strong>e between life <strong>and</strong> art is freely crossed, a type <strong>of</strong> action that permits the statue <strong>of</strong><br />

the eagle to be seen as lifelike <strong>and</strong> treated as if it were alive. <strong>The</strong> second epigram by<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon from the first century B.C. conta<strong>in</strong>s a dialogue between a viewer <strong>and</strong> a<br />

sculptured lion:<br />

A: Tell, lion, thou slayer <strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>e, on whose tomb thou st<strong>and</strong>est there<br />

<strong>and</strong> who was worthy <strong>of</strong> thy valour?<br />

B: Teleutias, the son <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>odorus, who was far most valiant <strong>of</strong><br />

men, as I am judged to be <strong>of</strong> beasts. Not <strong>in</strong> va<strong>in</strong> st<strong>and</strong> I here, but<br />

I emblem the prowess <strong>of</strong> the man, for he was <strong>in</strong>deed a lion to his<br />

enemies. (Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anth. Pal. 7.426) [29]<br />

Like the funerary images <strong>of</strong> the sph<strong>in</strong>x <strong>and</strong> the eagle <strong>in</strong> the above epigrams, the lion <strong>of</strong><br />

this epigram engages <strong>in</strong> direct conversation with the viewer by us<strong>in</strong>g his or her voice <strong>and</strong><br />

answers as if it were alive. As such, it blurs the l<strong>in</strong>e between a sculptured <strong>and</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

animal, thus between art <strong>and</strong> “reality.” Like the eagle above, the lion responds to the<br />

89


question <strong>of</strong> the viewer <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>s the reason for its placement on the tomb: as a symbol<br />

<strong>of</strong> the courage <strong>of</strong> the dead. 124 <strong>The</strong> third epigram, which is anonymous, conta<strong>in</strong>s a similar,<br />

but lengthier, conversation between a viewer <strong>and</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> a dog:<br />

A: Tell me, dog, who was the man on whose tomb thou st<strong>and</strong>est<br />

keep<strong>in</strong>g guard?<br />

B: <strong>The</strong> Dog.<br />

A: But what man was that, the Dog?<br />

B: Diogenes.<br />

A: Of what country?<br />

B: Of S<strong>in</strong>ope.<br />

A: He who lived <strong>in</strong> a jar?<br />

B: Yes, <strong>and</strong> now he is dead, the stars are his home.<br />

(Anonymous, Anth. Pal. 7.64) [15]<br />

In this epigram, the dog speaks through the voice <strong>of</strong> the viewer as if it were alive. It<br />

identifies the deceased <strong>in</strong>terred <strong>in</strong> the tomb: the philosopher Diogenes. In this respect, it<br />

is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the epigram with the Sph<strong>in</strong>x on Xenocrates’ tomb.<br />

In these epigraphical <strong>and</strong> literary epigrams, animal representations <strong>and</strong> viewers<br />

participate <strong>in</strong> a form <strong>of</strong> a dialogue that is composed <strong>of</strong> questions <strong>and</strong> answers. <strong>The</strong><br />

viewer poses questions to the animal subject which, <strong>in</strong> turn, uses his or her voice <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to answer back. As a result, the animal speaks to the viewer as if it were alive, while the<br />

latter is aware <strong>of</strong> the fact that he or she is speak<strong>in</strong>g to a work <strong>of</strong> art. In this way, the<br />

124 A lion is also depicted on a grave stele found <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos <strong>and</strong> dated to the third or<br />

second centuries B.C. <strong>The</strong> lion attacks the corpse <strong>of</strong> the diseased, whom a bil<strong>in</strong>gual (Greek, Phoenician)<br />

epitaph identifies as Antipater <strong>of</strong> Ashkelon. A six-l<strong>in</strong>e Greek epigram below the image <strong>of</strong> the attack<strong>in</strong>g<br />

lion, cast <strong>in</strong> the voice <strong>of</strong> the dead man, mentions that “the hateful lion came, wish<strong>in</strong>g to destroy my th<strong>in</strong>gs.”<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these stele, its epitaph, imagery, <strong>and</strong> epigram, see J. M. S. Stager, “‘Let No One<br />

Wonder at This Image,’ A Phoenician Funerary Stele <strong>in</strong> Athens,” Hesperia 74 (2005) 427-449.<br />

90


oundary between lifeless art <strong>and</strong> reality appears to be easily crossed. <strong>The</strong>se <strong>in</strong>scriptions<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicate that what susta<strong>in</strong>ed the perceived aliveness <strong>of</strong> animals, when used as subjects <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art, was their furnish<strong>in</strong>g with a voice through an <strong>in</strong>teractive encounter with the<br />

viewer.<br />

Def<strong>in</strong>ed as aliveness, the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> animal representations <strong>in</strong> art is further<br />

demonstrated by an epigram, by Macedonius the Consul, dated to the first century A.D.<br />

<strong>and</strong> preserved <strong>in</strong> the Greek Anthology:<br />

This dog tra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> every k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> hunt<strong>in</strong>g, was carved by Leucon, <strong>and</strong><br />

dedicated by Alcimenes. Alcimenes had no fault to f<strong>in</strong>d, but when he saw<br />

the statue resembl<strong>in</strong>g the dog <strong>in</strong> every feature he came up to it, with a collar,<br />

bidd<strong>in</strong>g Leucon to order the dog to walk, for as it looked to be bark<strong>in</strong>g, it<br />

persuaded him it could walk too.<br />

(Macedonius the Consul, Anth. Pal. 6.175) [132]<br />

In this epigram, Alcimenes, a viewer, like Herodas’ Phile <strong>and</strong> Kynno, behaves toward the<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> a dog as if it were alive. Like the herdsman <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow who wanted to put<br />

a yoke on his neck, Alcimenes wants to put a collar on Leucon’s dog. Like the viewers<br />

<strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow who thought that the statue was ready to low <strong>and</strong> run <strong>of</strong>f, Alcimenes is<br />

persuaded that this dog is ready to walk <strong>and</strong> bark. It is the visual impression <strong>of</strong> potential<br />

movement that forces Alcimenes to believe that this is a liv<strong>in</strong>g dog, dissolv<strong>in</strong>g therefore<br />

the idea <strong>of</strong> it as a lifeless image <strong>and</strong> allow<strong>in</strong>g its experience as a real animal. This<br />

evidence suggests that lifelikeness was aga<strong>in</strong> perceived as aliveness. <strong>The</strong> fact, however,<br />

that Alcimenes was aware <strong>of</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g at a work <strong>of</strong> art is susta<strong>in</strong>ed by the statements that<br />

he could f<strong>in</strong>d “no fault” <strong>in</strong> the appearance <strong>of</strong> the lifeless statue, <strong>and</strong> that the latter<br />

resembled a liv<strong>in</strong>g dog “<strong>in</strong> every feature.” Both statements suggest that accurate<br />

reproduction <strong>of</strong> (or representational fidelity to) a prototype was another way <strong>in</strong> which<br />

lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art was valued.<br />

91


<strong>The</strong> evidence from the texts cited demonstrates that animals, when featured as<br />

subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art, were <strong>in</strong>timately connected with the concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness. In<br />

fact, animals provide the ancient def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> this concept as accurate reproduction <strong>of</strong><br />

physical form <strong>and</strong> a sense <strong>of</strong> aliveness which allowed the viewer to cross freely the<br />

boundary between art <strong>and</strong> reality <strong>and</strong> created the impression that the animal subject had<br />

the ability to speak <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> some cases even move. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, animals<br />

provide a useful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> works<br />

<strong>of</strong> art. This exceptional role <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the realm <strong>of</strong> artistic lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong> is also found <strong>in</strong> their featur<strong>in</strong>g as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Judges <strong>of</strong> Lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Art<br />

<strong>The</strong> case <strong>of</strong> animals—a part <strong>of</strong> the natural world—as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike works <strong>of</strong><br />

art is <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> a very particular approach to art itself: as an artificial man-made<br />

construction, but, at the same time, one accepted as natural even by nature itself. <strong>The</strong><br />

most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> most familiar attestation to animals as judges <strong>of</strong> artistic lifelikeness<br />

occurs <strong>in</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s account <strong>of</strong> a competition between two fourth-century pa<strong>in</strong>ters, Zeuxis<br />

<strong>and</strong> Parrhasius:<br />

His [Zeuxis’] contemporaries <strong>and</strong> rivals were Timanthes, Androcydes, Eupompus<br />

<strong>and</strong> Parrhasius. This last it, is recorded, entered <strong>in</strong>to a competition with Zeuxis,<br />

who produced a picture <strong>of</strong> grapes so successfully represented that birds flew up to<br />

the stage-build<strong>in</strong>gs; whereupon Parrhasius himself produced such a realistic<br />

picture <strong>of</strong> a curta<strong>in</strong> that Zeuxis, proud <strong>of</strong> the verdict <strong>of</strong> the birds, requested that<br />

the curta<strong>in</strong> should now be drawn <strong>and</strong> the picture displayed; <strong>and</strong> when he realized<br />

his mistake, with a modesty that did him honor he yielded up the prize, say<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that whereas he had deceived birds Parrhasius had deceived him, an artist. It is<br />

said that Zeuxis also subsequently pa<strong>in</strong>ted a Child Carry<strong>in</strong>g Grapes, <strong>and</strong> when<br />

birds flew to the fruit with the same frankness as before he strode up to the picture<br />

<strong>in</strong> anger with it <strong>and</strong> said, “I have pa<strong>in</strong>ted the grapes better than the child, as if I<br />

92


had made a success <strong>of</strong> that as well, the birds would <strong>in</strong>evitably have been afraid <strong>of</strong><br />

it.” (NH 35.65-35.66) [156]<br />

<strong>The</strong> story recorded <strong>in</strong> this passage <strong>in</strong>dicates that ancient art <strong>in</strong>deed aimed at deceiv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

viewers by present<strong>in</strong>g them with highly effective lifelike images. Scholars like<br />

Gombrich, Pollitt, <strong>and</strong> Froma Zeitl<strong>in</strong>, among others, for example, argue <strong>in</strong> favor <strong>of</strong> this<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. 125 Furthermore, W. J. T. Mitchell <strong>in</strong>corporates Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s story <strong>in</strong>to his<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> artistic illusion <strong>and</strong> deception, <strong>and</strong> their effects on animal <strong>and</strong> human<br />

viewers respectively. 126 Of <strong>in</strong>terest is his view <strong>of</strong> illusion <strong>and</strong> deception as exclusively<br />

human faculties that are “deeply <strong>in</strong>terwoven with structures <strong>of</strong> power,” <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> animals as<br />

succumb<strong>in</strong>g to these powers. 127 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the difference <strong>in</strong> judgment between non-<br />

human <strong>and</strong> human viewers, it resides, he says, <strong>in</strong> that the birds are “taken <strong>in</strong>” by the<br />

visible, man-made lure—the grapes—whereas Zeuxis “takes himself <strong>in</strong>” by what rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

hidden beh<strong>in</strong>d the curta<strong>in</strong>—also a man-made lure. In other words, animals respond only<br />

to someth<strong>in</strong>g they can see, as if it were real, whereas humans are consciously drawn to<br />

125 See Rusnak, “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator” 119, n. 310, who cites Gombrich, Art <strong>and</strong> Illusion 11; Pollitt,<br />

Ancient View 63-64, F. J. Zeitl<strong>in</strong>, “<strong>The</strong> Artful Eye: Vision, Ecphrasis <strong>and</strong> Spectacle <strong>in</strong> Euripidean <strong>The</strong>atre,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> S. Goldhill <strong>and</strong> R. Osborne, eds., Art <strong>and</strong> Text <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Culture (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1994) 151-152, <strong>and</strong> also J. Elsner, Art <strong>and</strong> the Roman Viewer: <strong>The</strong> Transformation <strong>of</strong> Art from the Pagan<br />

World to Christianity (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 1995) 47, <strong>and</strong> C. Mango, “Antique Statuary <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Byzant<strong>in</strong>e Beholder,” DOP 17 (1963) 64.<br />

126 W. J. T. Mitchell, “Illusion: Look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Look<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> W. J. T. Mitchell, Picture <strong>The</strong>ory. Essays<br />

on Verbal <strong>and</strong> Visual Representation (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1994) 335.<br />

127 Quotation: Mitchell, “Illusion” 333; also 334, where he expla<strong>in</strong>s that: “Th[e] moment [when the animal<br />

is caught <strong>in</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g at man-made illusions <strong>and</strong> respond<strong>in</strong>g to them as if it were alive <strong>and</strong> natural]<br />

provides humanity with a double revelation <strong>and</strong> reassurance—that human representations are true, accurate,<br />

<strong>and</strong> natural (the animals “agree” <strong>and</strong> “comprehend” them <strong>of</strong> their own accord), <strong>and</strong> that human power over<br />

others is secured by mastery <strong>of</strong> representations (the animals are forced to agree, not <strong>of</strong> their own accord,<br />

but automatically).” It has been a commonplace <strong>of</strong> animal cognitive studies, nowadays, that the ability to<br />

imitate <strong>and</strong> deceive is not exclusively human. Parrots can imitate arbitrary sounds <strong>and</strong> language, for<br />

example, <strong>and</strong> adult ostriches <strong>and</strong> killdeer plovers employ the “broken w<strong>in</strong>g display,” as if <strong>in</strong>jured <strong>and</strong> sick,<br />

<strong>in</strong> order to lure predators away from their nests <strong>and</strong> protect their <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these<br />

examples, see V. Morell, “M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Own: <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Are Smarter Than You Th<strong>in</strong>k,” National<br />

Geographic (March, 2008) 44-45, <strong>and</strong> M. Bright, Intelligence <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (London, 1994; second ed., 1997)<br />

90-91. <strong>Animal</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> this type was not unknown <strong>in</strong> antiquity, but rather the subject <strong>of</strong> meticulous<br />

observation <strong>and</strong> analysis. For an <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek knowledge <strong>of</strong> animals’ deceptive<br />

behavior, see M. Detienne <strong>and</strong> J.-P. Vernant, tr. J. Lloyd, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence <strong>in</strong> Greek Culture <strong>and</strong><br />

Society (Hassocks, Sussex <strong>and</strong> Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, New Jersey, 1978).<br />

93


the <strong>in</strong>visible, perhaps by mere curiosity. Mitchell’s differentiation implicitly suggests an<br />

underly<strong>in</strong>g cognitive difference between animal <strong>and</strong> human judgment <strong>of</strong> illusion. 128<br />

Although he does not seem to be unaware <strong>of</strong> contemporary studies on animal cognition,<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d is the idea that the birds’ behavior is a natural error <strong>of</strong> judgment<br />

due to their <strong>in</strong>ferior cognitive status as non-human be<strong>in</strong>gs. 129 It is important to keep <strong>in</strong><br />

m<strong>in</strong>d, however, that studies on animal cognition, both before <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ce Mitchell<br />

published his work, have been cont<strong>in</strong>ually underl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the sophisticated abilities <strong>of</strong><br />

animals, such as dolph<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> pigeons, to differentiate between the real world <strong>and</strong><br />

representations <strong>of</strong> it, <strong>and</strong> also to recognize <strong>and</strong> remember visual differences. 130 In<br />

128 Mitchell, “Illusion” 334, n. 4: “most accounts <strong>of</strong> aesthetic illusion…<strong>in</strong>sist on the radical difference<br />

between animal <strong>and</strong> human responses to images,” as, for <strong>in</strong>stance, “Jacques Lacan’s discussion [ tr. A.<br />

Sheridan, <strong>The</strong> Four Fundamental Concepts <strong>of</strong> Psychoanalysis (Hammondsworth, 1979) 107] <strong>of</strong> the mirrorstage,<br />

[which] moves from the description <strong>of</strong> the behavior <strong>of</strong> the chimpanzee to that <strong>of</strong> a human child, but<br />

<strong>in</strong>sists on the lack <strong>of</strong> a symbolic system <strong>in</strong> the animal”; also 334, where Mitchell’s vocabulary h<strong>in</strong>ts at the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> a preconceived difference between animal <strong>and</strong> human responses to deceptive art: “there is one<br />

writer I know <strong>of</strong> who is notoriously unembarrassed by the equation <strong>of</strong> animal <strong>and</strong> human responses to<br />

aesthetic illusion, <strong>and</strong> that is the Roman historian Pl<strong>in</strong>y, who recorded probably the s<strong>in</strong>gle most famous<br />

anecdote <strong>of</strong> animals look<strong>in</strong>g at pictures.”<br />

129 Mitchell, “Illusion” 337: “there are animal behaviorists engaged, no doubt, at this very moment <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to ascerta<strong>in</strong> just what sorts <strong>of</strong> pictorial illusions will stimulate responses from various k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> animals, <strong>and</strong><br />

it wouldn’t surprise me to learn that some animals respond to the objects <strong>in</strong> some pictures as if they were<br />

really there.”; also <strong>in</strong> 342, he speaks <strong>of</strong> “decoys,” <strong>and</strong> “lures,” which suggest that what he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d is<br />

perhaps the response <strong>of</strong> real ducks to pa<strong>in</strong>ted wooden ones as part <strong>of</strong> their capture, <strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong>ed birds used to<br />

entice fellow animals <strong>in</strong>to a trap. This latter technique is mentioned by Aristotle as be<strong>in</strong>g used <strong>in</strong> the<br />

capture <strong>of</strong> pigeons (HA 613a) <strong>and</strong> partridges (HA 614a), <strong>and</strong> by Strabo (15.1.40-15.1.43) for the hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

elephants <strong>in</strong> India.<br />

130 Recent studies on animal cognition have shown that dolph<strong>in</strong>s, for example, have the cognitive ability to<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guish between look<strong>in</strong>g at the real world <strong>and</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> it. Morell, “M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Own” 54<br />

reports: “there are many th<strong>in</strong>gs they [dolph<strong>in</strong>s] could do that people have always doubted about animals.<br />

For example, they correctly <strong>in</strong>terpreted, on the very first occasion, gestured <strong>in</strong>structions given by a person<br />

displayed on a TV screen beh<strong>in</strong>d an underwater w<strong>in</strong>dow. <strong>The</strong>y recognized that television images were<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the real world that could be acted on <strong>in</strong> the same way as <strong>in</strong> the real world.” Also, for<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> picture cognition <strong>in</strong> pigeons which suggests that they see photographs <strong>and</strong> still video images,<br />

but not l<strong>in</strong>e draw<strong>in</strong>gs, as representations <strong>of</strong> real objects, see S. Watanabe, “How Do Pigeons See Pictures?<br />

Recognition <strong>of</strong> the Real World from its 2-D Representation,” <strong>in</strong> J. Fagot, ed., Picture Perception <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Philadelphia, 2000) 71-90; also, for the ability <strong>of</strong> pigeons to recognize video images <strong>of</strong><br />

themselves faster than it takes three-year old humans to complete the same task, see “Pigeons Show<br />

Superior Self-Recognition Abilities to Three Year Old Humans,” <strong>in</strong><br />

www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2008/06/080613145535.html; <strong>and</strong> A. C. Danto, “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Art<br />

Historians: Reflections on the Innocent Eye,” <strong>in</strong> A. C. Danto, Beyond the Brillo Box. <strong>The</strong> Visual Arts <strong>in</strong><br />

Post-Historical Perspective (New York, 1992) 24, who, on the basis <strong>of</strong> studies <strong>of</strong> pigeons’ ability to<br />

categorize pictures by subject, <strong>and</strong> hence to appreciate differences between pictures <strong>of</strong> different th<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

94


eference to the error <strong>of</strong> the Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s birds, Mitchell notes “the dignity” afforded to them,<br />

which he associates with “their role as omens <strong>and</strong> prophetic signs <strong>in</strong> Roman culture.” 131<br />

At the same time, he reveals his view <strong>of</strong> the story as sitt<strong>in</strong>g on the boundary between fact<br />

<strong>and</strong> fiction. 132<br />

<strong>The</strong> story, however, shows—regardless <strong>of</strong> its actual or <strong>in</strong>vented pedigree—that<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y acknowledges the role <strong>of</strong> the birds as credible guides to lifelike art. His<br />

employment <strong>of</strong> them as judges is particularly <strong>in</strong>structive; for it appears to be “allowed,” if<br />

not the norm, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> judg<strong>in</strong>g art. <strong>The</strong> birds, as they are conceived by Pl<strong>in</strong>y,<br />

validate the quality <strong>of</strong> Zeuxis’ art <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> its extreme lifelikeness. 133 Twice they fly<br />

to his conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g images <strong>of</strong> grapes. Twice they sense these images to be reality. <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

repeated reaction is not a topos <strong>of</strong> unreliable, erroneous behavior: rather, it is the reliable<br />

test <strong>of</strong> lifelike art. As trustworthy connoisseurs <strong>of</strong> lifelike art ow<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps, to their<br />

sensory perception, these non-human creatures confirm Zeuxis’ extraord<strong>in</strong>ary skill to<br />

states that pictorial competence is omnipresent <strong>in</strong> the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. Danto also refers (24), albeit<br />

fleet<strong>in</strong>gly, to the pictorial competence <strong>of</strong> sheep. It has been recently noted that sheep, a species otherwise<br />

known for its lack <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence, have sophisticated abilities to both recognize <strong>and</strong> remember visual<br />

differences. <strong>The</strong>y “recognize different faces (about 50 other sheep <strong>and</strong> 10 humans <strong>and</strong> still know them two<br />

years later,” <strong>and</strong> marmosets “even have a sense <strong>of</strong> “object permanence”—know<strong>in</strong>g that someth<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong><br />

sight still exists.” For these two references, see Morell, “M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Own” 47 <strong>and</strong> 58, respectively. In<br />

addition, pigeons are able to recognize video images <strong>of</strong> themselves faster than it takes three-year old<br />

humans to complete the same task: “Pigeons Show Superior Self-Recognition Abilities to Three Year Old<br />

Humans,” <strong>in</strong> www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2008/06/080613145535.html.<br />

131<br />

Mitchell, “Illusion” 336.<br />

132<br />

Mitchell, “Illusion” 337.<br />

133<br />

For the <strong>in</strong>fluence that the connection between birds, Zeuxis’ grapes, <strong>and</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness<br />

exerted on later pa<strong>in</strong>ters, see A. Bayer, “Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Lombard Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> A. Bayer, ed.,<br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>of</strong> Reality. <strong>The</strong> Legacy <strong>of</strong> Leonardo <strong>and</strong> Caravaggio <strong>in</strong> Lombardy (exhibition catalogue, Museo<br />

Civico “Ala Ponzone,” Cremona, February 14-May 2, 2004, <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New<br />

York, May 27-August 15, 2004 (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 6, n. 9, where he po<strong>in</strong>ts out that Vasari <strong>in</strong><br />

his account <strong>of</strong> the l<strong>and</strong>scape pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Bernard<strong>in</strong>o Marchiselli, called Bernazano (1492-1522) mentions<br />

that <strong>in</strong> these l<strong>and</strong>scapes, “there was a field <strong>of</strong> strawberry plants—“ripe, green, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> flower”—that were so<br />

attractive to some peacocks that the birds actually tried to peck at them, leav<strong>in</strong>g holes <strong>in</strong> the plaster <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wall”; also the Milanese pa<strong>in</strong>ter <strong>and</strong> author Giovanni Paolo Lomazzo (1538-1592), <strong>in</strong> his Treatise [<strong>of</strong> 1584]<br />

on the Art <strong>of</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>Sculpture</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Architecture speaks <strong>of</strong> the birds depicted <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> Lomazzo’s<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs (Baptism <strong>of</strong> Christ) as “so natural that when the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g was placed outside <strong>in</strong> the sun, some<br />

birds flew around <strong>in</strong> believ<strong>in</strong>g them to be real <strong>and</strong> alive.”<br />

95


create highly effective images that go beyond the norm <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness, <strong>and</strong> can, therefore,<br />

be experienced as “real.” 134 In this way, aesthetic illusion becomes deception only<br />

because exceptional artistic skill is <strong>in</strong>volved. As Gombrich states, “illusion could turn<br />

<strong>in</strong>to deception only when the context <strong>of</strong> action set up an expectation which re<strong>in</strong>forced the<br />

artist’s h<strong>and</strong>iwork.” 135 Like the calf, the bull, <strong>and</strong> the gadfly <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow,<br />

the birds verify Zeuxis’ capacity to create images that dissolve the boundary between art<br />

<strong>and</strong> reality. At the end, it is this underly<strong>in</strong>g realization that makes Zeuxis “proud <strong>of</strong> the<br />

verdict <strong>of</strong> the birds.” In this way, animals emerge as significant guides to <strong>and</strong> judges <strong>of</strong><br />

the ancient underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art.<br />

Further evidence for the notion <strong>of</strong> animals as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike art is found <strong>in</strong><br />

another episode recorded by Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Pl<strong>in</strong>y mentions that Apelles, a fourth-century pa<strong>in</strong>ter,<br />

employed the judgment <strong>of</strong> real horses to verify the lifelikeness <strong>of</strong> his pa<strong>in</strong>ted image <strong>of</strong> a<br />

horse:<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is, or was, a picture <strong>of</strong> a Horse by him [Apelles] pa<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> a competition,<br />

by which he carried his appeal for judgment from mank<strong>in</strong>d to the dumb<br />

quadrupeds; for perceiv<strong>in</strong>g that his rivals were gett<strong>in</strong>g the better <strong>of</strong> him by<br />

<strong>in</strong>trigue, he had some horses brought <strong>and</strong> showed them their pictures one by one;<br />

<strong>and</strong> the horses only began to neigh when they saw the horse pa<strong>in</strong>ted by Apelles;<br />

<strong>and</strong> this always happened subsequently, show<strong>in</strong>g it to be a sound test <strong>in</strong> artistic<br />

skill. (NH 35.95) [158]<br />

Like the previous story, the episode recorded <strong>in</strong> this passage <strong>in</strong>dicates general awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> animals, <strong>in</strong> this case horses, as trustworthy judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike art. Mitchell ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that “this episode illustrates, not the deception <strong>of</strong> the horses, but their good judgment, a<br />

134 For the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek belief that the perceptual ability <strong>of</strong> animals derived not from reason, but the five<br />

senses, see R. Sorabji, <strong>Animal</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> Human Morals. <strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Western Debate (Ithaca <strong>and</strong><br />

New York, 1993) 17-29. For the survival <strong>of</strong> this underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the Renaissance, <strong>and</strong> their<br />

employment <strong>in</strong> contemporary pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs to implicitly <strong>in</strong>struct the viewer to believe <strong>in</strong> the depicted angelic<br />

visitation as a real occurrence, see Scheick, “<strong>Animal</strong> Testimony <strong>in</strong> Renaissance Art,” <strong>in</strong> Pollock <strong>and</strong><br />

Ra<strong>in</strong>water, eds., Figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> 65.<br />

135 Gombrich, Art <strong>and</strong> Illusion 206.<br />

96


form <strong>of</strong> equ<strong>in</strong>e connoisseurship responsive to the dignity <strong>of</strong> the artist’s identity as well as<br />

his skill.” 136 Additional evidence po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to the same direction derives also from Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s<br />

characterization <strong>of</strong> the employment <strong>of</strong> animals as “a sound test <strong>in</strong> artistic skill,” which<br />

speaks not only <strong>of</strong> the trust placed upon animals as good judges <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art, but<br />

also <strong>of</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness as an exceptional skill <strong>of</strong> artists. That Apelles was one<br />

<strong>of</strong> these artists is also evidenced <strong>in</strong> another passage <strong>of</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y which presents him as the<br />

creator <strong>of</strong> exceptionally lifelike images, <strong>in</strong> this case <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs. 137<br />

Both stories recorded by Pl<strong>in</strong>y <strong>in</strong>dicate that non-human animals such as birds <strong>and</strong><br />

horses were considered reliable guides even to extreme cases <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong><br />

art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. Furthermore, the fact that animals, as part <strong>of</strong> the natural world,<br />

consider works <strong>of</strong> art to be so lifelike suggests a specific attitude toward art itself: that it<br />

has surpassed its own essence as a man-made creation <strong>and</strong> is now accepted as nature even<br />

by nature itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> literary sources exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> this essay <strong>in</strong>dicate that animals played a<br />

significant role <strong>in</strong> the perception <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> featured<br />

not only as subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art valued for their lifelikeness, which <strong>in</strong> some cases was<br />

perceived as exceptional, but they were also considered a reliable st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> judg<strong>in</strong>g<br />

equally exceptional lifelike art. This double capacity <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the realm <strong>of</strong><br />

136 Mitchell, “Illusion” 336-337.<br />

137 “He [Apelles] also pa<strong>in</strong>ted portraits so absolutely lifelike that, <strong>in</strong>credible, as it sounds, the grammarian<br />

Apio has left it on record that one <strong>of</strong> those persons called ‘physiognomists,’ who prophesy people’s future<br />

by their countenance, pronounced from their portraits either the year <strong>of</strong> the subjects’ deaths hereafter or the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> years they had already lived” (Pl<strong>in</strong>y, NH 35.88-35.89); translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y.<br />

Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995) 327. For the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> Apelles as the most accomplished pa<strong>in</strong>ter <strong>of</strong> lifelike images <strong>in</strong> antiquity, <strong>and</strong> its <strong>in</strong>fluence on<br />

Renaissance artists, who saw Apelles as a model <strong>of</strong> an artist to be imitated, see D. Cast, <strong>The</strong> Calumny <strong>of</strong><br />

Apelles. A Study <strong>in</strong> the Humanist Tradition (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1981) 161-173.<br />

97


lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art sheds also light on two def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g components that helped<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ed the concept <strong>in</strong> the ancient Greek m<strong>in</strong>d: accurate representation <strong>of</strong> physical<br />

models, but not necessarily uncanny accuracy, <strong>and</strong> also the experience <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art as<br />

if it were alive, while the viewer is consciously aware <strong>of</strong> the fact that s/he is look<strong>in</strong>g at<br />

art. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> also feature <strong>in</strong> ancient literature on art as subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art that<br />

helped create <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> the fame <strong>of</strong> a considerable number <strong>of</strong> artists. <strong>The</strong> picture that<br />

emerges from the literary record <strong>in</strong>dicates that animals <strong>of</strong>fer a valuable <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> art while occupy<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

significant place <strong>in</strong> its judgment.<br />

98


Chapter 2: Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Phenomenon<br />

<strong>of</strong> Naturalistic Style<br />

Introduction<br />

It is generally thought that representations <strong>of</strong> animals, such as lions <strong>and</strong> dogs, <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek sculpture are problematic because they exhibit a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g, that is,<br />

naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements. Many suggestions have been <strong>of</strong>fered to<br />

account for this phenomenon: a) a lack <strong>of</strong> opportunity for artists to observe directly liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

animals, b) a result <strong>of</strong> artists’ copy<strong>in</strong>g from Near Eastern <strong>and</strong> Bronze Age models <strong>of</strong><br />

animals, <strong>and</strong> c) an <strong>in</strong>tention to highlight the apotropaic function <strong>of</strong> statues <strong>of</strong> animals.<br />

<strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g section is a selective account <strong>of</strong> scholarly <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> problematic style <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture, specifically<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs. <strong>The</strong>se are two species <strong>of</strong> animals whose<br />

representations abound <strong>in</strong> extant sculpture, with the lion outnumber<strong>in</strong>g the dog by far. It<br />

is for this reason that the follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion presents an uneven number <strong>of</strong> sculptures<br />

<strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs <strong>and</strong> the scholarly evaluation <strong>of</strong> their problematic style. <strong>The</strong> focus is on<br />

the <strong>Classical</strong> period, but, as will be seen, each animal case beg<strong>in</strong>s with an Archaic<br />

example. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention is to show that various types <strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g differ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

elements <strong>in</strong> the representation <strong>of</strong> animals is not a strictly <strong>Classical</strong> phenomenon that<br />

structures the concept <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture, but rather is one that extends back <strong>in</strong>to<br />

the Archaic period. Figures <strong>of</strong> animals thus suggest that <strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong><br />

contradiction are the underly<strong>in</strong>g models for stylistic change <strong>in</strong> both Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek sculpture. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention here is not to deny that a stylistic change occurs <strong>in</strong><br />

sculpture as the Archaic phase move on to the <strong>Classical</strong>, but, rather, to suggest, through<br />

99


the guidance <strong>of</strong> extant sculptures <strong>of</strong> animals, that what actually happens as one phase<br />

proceeds to the other is only a shift <strong>in</strong> the balance <strong>of</strong> the differ<strong>in</strong>g elements that are mixed<br />

together to form the style <strong>of</strong> an image. In other words, the tendency to comb<strong>in</strong>e differ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

elements whether <strong>in</strong> a mode <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, or contradiction rema<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

solid mental framework <strong>of</strong> style. This proposition is <strong>in</strong> some sense <strong>in</strong> essential agreement<br />

with the approach <strong>of</strong> William Childs, who, as noted earlier, sees the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek art as the comb<strong>in</strong>ed render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an objective <strong>and</strong> subjective reality that is<br />

exemplified by representations <strong>of</strong> the human form <strong>in</strong> contemporary sculpture. In this<br />

way, the fact that, dur<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Classical</strong> period, the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> essentially non-<br />

match<strong>in</strong>g elements also extends to the human form solidifies its position as the<br />

underly<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence,<br />

the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> this style as a strict imitation <strong>of</strong> the external world driven by<br />

advancement <strong>in</strong> artistic techniques—a dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>and</strong> widely accepted view, as noted<br />

earlier—does not appear to rest on firm ground.<br />

1. Examples <strong>of</strong> the Scholarly Treatment <strong>of</strong> the Problematic Style <strong>of</strong> Representations<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

a. <strong>The</strong> Case <strong>of</strong> the Lion<br />

Jeffrey Hurwit, <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>in</strong> relief savag<strong>in</strong>g a bull crumpled<br />

beneath it (Fig. 5) from the mid sixth-century (ca. 560 B.C.), west pediment <strong>of</strong> the temple<br />

<strong>of</strong> Athena on the Athenian acropolis, the so-called Hekatompedon, says that it is “<strong>in</strong><br />

almost every way a very lionlike lion—its ferocity, claws, pose, <strong>and</strong> powerful<br />

musculature are all conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g—except that this lion has both a mane <strong>and</strong> teats, the<br />

100


markers <strong>of</strong> both sexes.” 138 He calls this lion “a Mischwesen—not because it is a<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> different beasts, but because it is a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> different genders. It is<br />

a hermaphrodite—a lion/lioness.” 139 <strong>The</strong>se comments clearly show that Hurwit<br />

conceives <strong>of</strong> naturalism ma<strong>in</strong>ly as anatomical accuracy. That he f<strong>in</strong>ds, however, the pose<br />

<strong>of</strong> the animal conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g also bespeaks a behavioral component to his underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept. Additional examples <strong>of</strong> hermaphroditic lions are found, he notes, on Middle<br />

Cor<strong>in</strong>thian vases, such as those by the Chimaera Pa<strong>in</strong>ter (ca. 600-575 B.C.) that depict<br />

lionesses without teats or have them <strong>in</strong> the wrong place—choices that have been<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted as mistakes stemm<strong>in</strong>g from the artist’s ignorance <strong>of</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy. 140<br />

<strong>The</strong> motif <strong>of</strong> a lioness with both mane <strong>and</strong> teats is also found on Late Bronze Age<br />

Aegean seals; <strong>in</strong> fact, it has been considered an Aegean <strong>in</strong>vention. 141 Apart from<br />

favor<strong>in</strong>g the idea <strong>of</strong> artistic mistake as an <strong>in</strong>terpretation, it has also been noted that<br />

supply<strong>in</strong>g the animal with such an <strong>and</strong>rogynous look does not necessarily mean that<br />

Bronze Age Aegean artists were unfamiliar with its anatomy, but “it is quite possible that<br />

138 J. M. Hurwit, “Lizards, Lions, <strong>and</strong> the Uncanny <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art,” Hesperia 75 (2006) 133; this lion<br />

(Acropolis Museum 4) is jo<strong>in</strong>ed on the left by another one, which does not take part <strong>in</strong> attack<strong>in</strong>g the bull;<br />

for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the Hekatompedon <strong>and</strong> its sculpture, see Hurwit, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Acropolis: History,<br />

Mythology, <strong>and</strong> Archaeology from the Neolithic Era to the Present (Cambridge, 1999) 106-112. For a<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> the motif <strong>of</strong> the lion attack<strong>in</strong>g an animal, such as a bull, stag, goat, <strong>and</strong> boar <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek<br />

art with emphasis on Archaic pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, sculpture, <strong>and</strong> metal objects, see G. E. Markoe, “<strong>The</strong> ‘Lion Attack’<br />

<strong>in</strong> Archaic Greek Art: Heroic Triumph,” ClAnt 8 (1989) 86-115.<br />

139 Hurwit, “Lizards, Lions” 133.<br />

140 Hurwit, “Lizards, Lions” 134, n. 55. <strong>The</strong> vases by the Chimaera Pa<strong>in</strong>ter to which Hurwit refers are<br />

mentioned <strong>in</strong> D. A. Amyx, Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Archaic Period (Berkeley, 1988) 168, nos. A-<br />

14, A-15, <strong>and</strong> 663. <strong>The</strong> first is a plate (Louvre S 1679) depict<strong>in</strong>g a lioness without teats. For a discussion<br />

<strong>and</strong> a picture <strong>of</strong> it, see P. Lawrence, “<strong>The</strong> Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Chimaera Pa<strong>in</strong>ter,” AJA 63 (1959) 350, no. 3, pl. 87,<br />

fig. 3. <strong>The</strong> second (Swiss Market. D. 0.285) is also a plate depict<strong>in</strong>g a seated lioness with her four teats<br />

placed <strong>in</strong>correctly all along her belly. For a short description <strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> this plate, see André<br />

Emmerich Gallery Inc., <strong>Classical</strong> Antiquity: An Exhibition Organized <strong>in</strong> Cooperation with Münzen <strong>and</strong><br />

Medaillen AG, Basle, Switzerl<strong>and</strong> November 22, 1975-January 10, 1976 (Zurich <strong>and</strong> New York, 1975) 3,<br />

no. 4, cover illustration.<br />

141 For specific examples <strong>of</strong> seals depict<strong>in</strong>g this motif, such as one from Knossos (Late Helladic IIIAI<br />

context), see M. Ball<strong>in</strong>tijn, “Lions Depicted on Aegean Seals—How Realistic Are <strong>The</strong>y?” <strong>in</strong> W. Muller,<br />

ed., Sceaux m<strong>in</strong>oens et mycéniens: IVe symposium <strong>in</strong>ternational, 10-12 Septembre 1992, Clermont-Ferr<strong>and</strong><br />

(CMS 5 Beiheft 5; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1995) 26, n. 15, where she also po<strong>in</strong>ts out that “the lioness with mane <strong>and</strong> teats is<br />

an Aegean <strong>in</strong>vention <strong>and</strong>, as far as I know, no parallels are to be found <strong>in</strong> the Near East or Egypt.”<br />

101


they expressly depicted a lioness with a mane—with or without teats—so as to make it<br />

clear that it was a lioness <strong>and</strong> not just some other animal.” 142 While this evidence<br />

underl<strong>in</strong>es the likelihood <strong>of</strong> specific <strong>in</strong>tentions shap<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong><br />

Aegean glyptic art, when placed aga<strong>in</strong>st the Hekatompedon lion, it <strong>in</strong>vites the question <strong>of</strong><br />

animals as examples <strong>of</strong> stylistic cont<strong>in</strong>uity from Late Bronze Age art to that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> periods, particularly <strong>in</strong> sculpture—a topic to which we shall return<br />

shortly.<br />

Hurwit hesitates to <strong>in</strong>terpret the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>congruous elements <strong>in</strong> the<br />

style <strong>of</strong> the Hekatompedon lion as an artistic mistake. Rather, he sees it as an attempt on<br />

the side <strong>of</strong> the sculptor to “make the lion even more “awe-ful,” mysterious, <strong>and</strong> strange<br />

than it otherwise is.” 143 Such strangeness, he says, had the power to avert evil from the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> its surround<strong>in</strong>g territory, therefore, the hermaphroditic lion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Hekatompedon “belongs not to the realm <strong>of</strong> artistic error but to the realm <strong>of</strong> the<br />

uncanny.” 144 Hurwit rightly considers the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>congruous elements <strong>in</strong> the<br />

style <strong>of</strong> the Hekatompedon lion as markers <strong>of</strong> sexual dimorphism with<strong>in</strong> the same<br />

species, but his attribution <strong>of</strong> apotropaic significance to them, although reasonable, <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

142 Ball<strong>in</strong>tijn, “Lions Depicted on Aegean Seals” 26. For the notion <strong>of</strong> Late Bronze Age artists <strong>of</strong> seals<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g mistakes, such as represent<strong>in</strong>g a lioness with mane <strong>and</strong> teats followed by an example <strong>of</strong> it on a<br />

carnelian lentoid seal <strong>in</strong> Oxford (CS 314), see J. Boardman, Greek Gems <strong>and</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ger R<strong>in</strong>gs. Early Bronze<br />

Age to Late <strong>Classical</strong> (London, 1970; new exp. ed., 2001) 59, pl. 91. His explanation (58) <strong>of</strong> these<br />

mistakes (58) as stemm<strong>in</strong>g from the suggestion that Late Bronze Age artists had never seen a liv<strong>in</strong>g lion<br />

was supported <strong>in</strong> 1970—when his study was first published—by the marked absence <strong>of</strong> bones <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong><br />

the archaeological record. S<strong>in</strong>ce then, however, start<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> 1978, bones <strong>and</strong> teeth <strong>of</strong> Panthera leo “have<br />

been found <strong>in</strong> n<strong>in</strong>e locations <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> isl<strong>and</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>in</strong> contexts rang<strong>in</strong>g from Late Neolithic to<br />

Early Iron Age <strong>and</strong> also Archaic date; for this evidence, see N. R. Thomas, “<strong>The</strong> Early Mycenaean Lion Up<br />

to Date,” Hesperia Supplement 33 (2004) 189, <strong>and</strong> 189-191 with a complete list <strong>and</strong> bibliographical<br />

references <strong>of</strong> all Greek sites where bones <strong>of</strong> lions have been discovered. Most notable among those dat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the Bronze Age are Kalapodi (LH IIIC), Kastanas (Late Bronze <strong>and</strong> early Middle Iron Age) <strong>and</strong><br />

Tiryns (LH I; LH IIIB; LHIIIC). For another discussion <strong>of</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> prehistoric <strong>Greece</strong>, see<br />

P. Jesk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Environment <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> World (London, 1998) 16-17.<br />

143 Hurwit “Lizards, Lions” 134.<br />

144 Hurwit, “Lizards, Lions” 134.<br />

102


little <strong>in</strong> the way <strong>of</strong> explanation. In fact, it diverts attention away from other cultural<br />

factors, such as attitudes toward the lion, which might have critically affected its<br />

appearance <strong>in</strong> pedimental sculpture.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problematic style <strong>of</strong> Greek animal sculpture has also been noted <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g statues <strong>of</strong> lions. Richter’s description, for example, <strong>of</strong> a<br />

sixth-century limestone statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Perachora, presumably a funerary<br />

monument, housed now <strong>in</strong> the Boston Museum (Fig. 6), states that “the body is<br />

represented <strong>in</strong> full pr<strong>of</strong>ile, the head <strong>in</strong> full front, without any <strong>of</strong> the twists <strong>and</strong> turn<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

natural to a liv<strong>in</strong>g animal. <strong>The</strong> mane is <strong>in</strong>dicated by ornamental rows <strong>of</strong> flame-like locks;<br />

but there is also a dist<strong>in</strong>ct attempt at represent<strong>in</strong>g the swell<strong>in</strong>g muscles <strong>of</strong> the legs <strong>and</strong><br />

trunk as well as the ribs.” 145 Unlike the Hekatompedon lion, whose style was seen as a<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> different sexes/genders, here it is the animal’s non-naturalistic pose <strong>and</strong><br />

mane comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the naturalistic render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its muscles that def<strong>in</strong>e its <strong>in</strong>consistent<br />

style. In this way, the lion’s well-def<strong>in</strong>ed musculature, along with its unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g<br />

mane, suggests that Richter, like Hurwit, conceives <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical accuracy,<br />

whereas its unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g pose suggests that she also sees behavioral accuracy as part <strong>of</strong><br />

the concept.<br />

Richter supplies us with an additional example <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g animal sculpture. Her discussion <strong>of</strong> a late fifth-century (ca. 400 B.C.)<br />

marble statue <strong>of</strong> a lion (Fig. 7) identified as Greek <strong>and</strong> found <strong>in</strong> or near Rome, accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to the records <strong>of</strong> the Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, where it is now housed, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that<br />

145 Richter, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks 74-75; also <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 4; for the<br />

designation <strong>of</strong> the statue (MFA 97.289) as a funerary monument <strong>and</strong> additional description <strong>of</strong> it, see M. B.<br />

Comstock <strong>and</strong> C. C. Vermeule, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> Stone. <strong>The</strong> Greek, Roman <strong>and</strong> Etruscan Collections <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts Boston (Boston, 1974) 9-10, fig. 15.<br />

103


“the pose, the slender body, the elongated skull, the short hair on the neck resemble those<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dog rather than a lion; only <strong>in</strong> the wide-open mouth has the artist successfully<br />

conveyed the impression <strong>of</strong> a fierce animal <strong>of</strong> prey.” 146 As this statement suggests, the<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>congruous, that is, can<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e elements creates an unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g<br />

image <strong>of</strong> a lion, <strong>and</strong>, thus, one that for its most part does not conform to Richter’s<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical <strong>and</strong> behavioral accuracy.<br />

Richter not only po<strong>in</strong>ts out the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture,<br />

but attempts to expla<strong>in</strong> it as well. Such an attempt is clearly seen, for example, as her<br />

discussion proceeds to fourth-century animal funerary sculpture that orig<strong>in</strong>ates outside<br />

the Greek world, namely, one <strong>of</strong> the freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g lions (ca. 350 B.C.) from the<br />

Mausoleum at Halicarnassus (Fig. 8), a monument whose architecture displays, as has<br />

146 Richter, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks 75, n. 11, figs. 361, 362; also <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

7, 50, fig. 20. <strong>The</strong> precise f<strong>in</strong>dspot <strong>of</strong> the statue (MMA 09.221.3) is not known, but for the idea that it was<br />

found <strong>in</strong> or near Rome, see J. Marshall, “Statue <strong>of</strong> a Lion,” M.M.A. Bullet<strong>in</strong> 5 (1910) 212, who also notes<br />

(210) that its style is so close to that <strong>of</strong> the lions <strong>of</strong> the Nereid Monument (ca. 390-380 B.C.) that “at first<br />

sight there seems a possibility that the statue might have come orig<strong>in</strong>ally from the same source….[but]<br />

there is no place <strong>in</strong> the Nereid monument for more lions than the four <strong>of</strong> which fragments were found.”<br />

This observation expla<strong>in</strong>s why Richter, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks 75, <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> 7, speaks <strong>of</strong> the lion at the Metropolitan Museum as be<strong>in</strong>g “related” to those <strong>of</strong> the Nereid<br />

Monument. In his reference to the lions <strong>of</strong> the Nereid Monument, A. H. Smith, A Catalogue <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> the Department <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Antiquities. British Museum II (London, 1900) 41, states that “parts<br />

were found <strong>of</strong> four lions, <strong>of</strong> which two are fairly complete” (BM 929 a lioness, BM 930 a lion). He also<br />

notes no knowledge regard<strong>in</strong>g the orig<strong>in</strong>al placement <strong>of</strong> these statues on or <strong>in</strong> association with the<br />

monument; also, regard<strong>in</strong>g their style, he says that “it is very archaic compared with the rema<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sculptures—especially the stiff <strong>and</strong> conventional treatment <strong>of</strong> the manes,” a phenomenon which forces him<br />

to suggest that the lions “either derived from an older monument or the archaic conventions have been<br />

consciously reta<strong>in</strong>ed [<strong>in</strong> them].” For a recent discussion reiterat<strong>in</strong>g this view, see Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, Greek<br />

Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Cambridge, Mass., 2006) 200, who po<strong>in</strong>ts out that, <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their style,<br />

the statues “appear somewhat archaiz<strong>in</strong>g by comparison with the high <strong>Classical</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

architectural sculpture [<strong>of</strong> the monument].” Regard<strong>in</strong>g their f<strong>in</strong>d spot, W. A. P. Childs <strong>and</strong> P. Demargne,<br />

Fouilles de Xanthos VIII. Les monument des Néréides. Le décor sculpté (Paris, 1989) 231-233, pls. 156-<br />

158, state that they were found near the north terrace, are certa<strong>in</strong>ly associated with the monument, <strong>and</strong> their<br />

purpose was, most likely, to serve as guardian figures. Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> 201,<br />

fig. 196, echoes this po<strong>in</strong>t, when he says that the statues might have “formed part <strong>of</strong> a pride deployed<br />

around the north terrace or at its approach.” B. S. Ridgway, Fourth-Century Styles <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong><br />

(Madison, 1997) 79, <strong>in</strong> her description <strong>of</strong> the Nereid Monument, suggests that “marble lions guarded the<br />

four corners <strong>of</strong> the podium, probably at ground level”; she also provides the follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation (76, n.<br />

6): “W. A. P. Childs k<strong>in</strong>dly tells me that the location <strong>of</strong> the four (?) lions was never fully resolved, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

position<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the ro<strong>of</strong> slope, two on either side, could also be envisioned, on possible analogy with the<br />

(later) arrangement on the Mausolleion.”<br />

104


een noted, a confluence <strong>of</strong> three different cultures—Lycian, Greek, Egyptian—<strong>and</strong> its<br />

sculpture, a strong Greek component. 147 As with the lion at the Metropolitan Museum,<br />

Richter identifies a blend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e elements <strong>in</strong> the lion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Mausoleum, which does not comply with her conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical <strong>and</strong><br />

behavioral accuracy:<br />

[T]he sculptor has given it the build <strong>of</strong> a dog with straight legs placed wide apart<br />

<strong>and</strong> he has <strong>in</strong> no way conveyed that strange restlessness <strong>of</strong> a lion’s body which<br />

suggests motion even when <strong>in</strong> repose, or the quality <strong>of</strong> his sk<strong>in</strong> as it glides to <strong>and</strong><br />

fro over the powerful muscles. And the detailed model<strong>in</strong>g makes us the more<br />

conscious <strong>of</strong> the misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> such salient features. 148<br />

Wish<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong> further this misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Richter states that “the artist had no<br />

opportunity to study from life.” 149 Consonant with what was seen earlier to have been<br />

said about the Chimaera Pa<strong>in</strong>ter <strong>and</strong> Aegean artists, Richter’s statement re<strong>in</strong>troduces the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> artists’ unfamiliarity with leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy; as such, it reflects her explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

the style <strong>of</strong> the Masoleum lion as deriv<strong>in</strong>g from the sculptor’s observation <strong>of</strong> a dog (while<br />

<strong>in</strong>tended to render a lion), <strong>and</strong> therefore, as shar<strong>in</strong>g the lack <strong>of</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g model <strong>and</strong><br />

subsequent borrow<strong>in</strong>g from the anatomy <strong>of</strong> a familiar species.<br />

Such borrow<strong>in</strong>g is a notion not without merit, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is known to occur also <strong>in</strong><br />

Late Bronze Age Aegean glyptic art as evidenced, for example, by a gold seal from Shaft<br />

Grave III at Mycenae (Fig. 9). Regard<strong>in</strong>g the wounded lion depicted on it, it has been<br />

147 <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventory number <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> the lion housed now <strong>in</strong> the British Museum is 1075. For these<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts regard<strong>in</strong>g the Mausoleum at Halicarnassus, <strong>and</strong> also a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> its architecture <strong>and</strong><br />

sculptures, see Ridgway, Fourth-Century Styles 129, <strong>and</strong> 111-135; also Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> 203-227, <strong>in</strong> particular 211-223, for a good summary <strong>of</strong> the suggested reconstructions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

monument, <strong>and</strong> how they connect to the question <strong>of</strong> the display <strong>of</strong> the surviv<strong>in</strong>g freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g sculptures.<br />

148 Richter, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks 75, fig. 363, <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 8, 51-52,<br />

fig. 28 (BM 1075). For the statues <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g lions from the Mausoleum <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus, thought to be at<br />

least 56, see G. B. Waywell, <strong>The</strong> Free-St<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Mausoleum at Halicarnassus <strong>in</strong> the<br />

British Museum (London, 1978) 68; also 27-34 <strong>and</strong> 180-209 for a detailed catalogue <strong>of</strong> both statues <strong>and</strong><br />

fragments <strong>of</strong> lions from the Mausoleum currently housed <strong>in</strong> the British Museum.<br />

149 Richter, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks 75.<br />

105


observed that both its collaps<strong>in</strong>g posture <strong>and</strong> the non-fel<strong>in</strong>e anatomy <strong>of</strong> its forelegs are<br />

typical <strong>of</strong> those <strong>of</strong> cattle, specifically steer. 150 Appear<strong>in</strong>g also on Late Bronze Age seals<br />

<strong>and</strong> said to have been adopted also from cattle (cows) is “the motif <strong>of</strong> a lion or a lioness<br />

st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, with its head lowered <strong>and</strong> fac<strong>in</strong>g backwards toward a cub who is stretch<strong>in</strong>g up<br />

to dr<strong>in</strong>k,” an apparent departure from reality, s<strong>in</strong>ce “a lioness always suckles her cubs<br />

ly<strong>in</strong>g down.” 151 Detached from be<strong>in</strong>g considered an artistic mistake due to lack <strong>of</strong><br />

zoological knowledge, this non-naturalistic motif has been seen <strong>in</strong>stead as an example <strong>of</strong><br />

the viewpo<strong>in</strong>t that, “Aegean artists deliberately allowed themselves to deviate from<br />

reality where they regarded it as advantageous or necessary.” 152 Although<br />

chronologically distant from this evidence, when seen aga<strong>in</strong>st it, Richter’s judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> the Mausoleum lion as stemm<strong>in</strong>g from the sculptor’s<br />

unfamiliarity with the animal does not seem to rest on firm ground. <strong>The</strong> persistence,<br />

however, with which the aff<strong>in</strong>ity with Late Bronze Age material keeps recurr<strong>in</strong>g provides<br />

the grounds for address<strong>in</strong>g next the scholarly attention to animals as examples <strong>of</strong> stylistic<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>uity from the art <strong>of</strong> the Bronze Age to that <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period, particularly <strong>in</strong><br />

sculpture, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> connection (not with deviation from reality, as was the case so far, but)<br />

with naturalism.<br />

150<br />

A. A. Donohue, “Zum Löwenschieber aus Schachtgrab III <strong>in</strong> Mykene,” AA 93 (1978) 259-262; Athens,<br />

NM 34.<br />

151<br />

Ball<strong>in</strong>tijn, “Lions Depicted on Aegean Seals” 26, n. 14 with specific reference to a hematite seal (CMS<br />

II,3 no. 344) from Gortyna (style LM IIIA), which depicts a lioness <strong>and</strong> her cub <strong>in</strong> the pose described<br />

above, <strong>and</strong> also one from Knossos (CMS II,3 no. 88), <strong>and</strong> another one from Mycenae (CMS I no. 20)<br />

depict<strong>in</strong>g a cow <strong>and</strong> her calf <strong>in</strong> the same pose.<br />

152<br />

Ball<strong>in</strong>tijn, “Lions Depicted on Aegean Seals” 37, where she summarizes additional examples <strong>of</strong> nonnaturalistic<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> lions on seals <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way: “Art is not zoology….<strong>The</strong> fly<strong>in</strong>g gallop,<br />

the fly<strong>in</strong>g leap, probably also the lion which leaps onto the back <strong>of</strong> its prey <strong>and</strong> the animal look<strong>in</strong>g back <strong>in</strong><br />

full flight, are means by which to emphasize the speed, power <strong>and</strong> savagery <strong>of</strong> what Aegean artists actually<br />

saw, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion do not necessarily <strong>in</strong>dicate lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge.” For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the “fly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

gallop,” see H. J. Kantor, <strong>The</strong> Aegean <strong>and</strong> the Orient <strong>in</strong> the Second Millennium B.C. (<strong>The</strong> Archaeological<br />

Institute <strong>of</strong> America Monograph Number 1; Boston, 1947; repr. 1997) 92-97.<br />

106


<strong>The</strong> Possibility <strong>of</strong> Influence from Bronze Age Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> stylistic aff<strong>in</strong>ity between Bronze Age naturalistic representations <strong>of</strong> animals<br />

<strong>and</strong> those <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture is a topic that has not passed unnoticed <strong>in</strong> modern<br />

scholarship. Vermeule, for example, addressed it <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

funerary statues <strong>of</strong> animals. <strong>The</strong>re, he speaks <strong>of</strong> a great aff<strong>in</strong>ity between the naturalism<br />

<strong>of</strong> prehistoric <strong>and</strong> later animals, or more precisely, <strong>of</strong> the last<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Bronze Age<br />

depictions <strong>of</strong> animals, such as lions, dogs, <strong>and</strong> bulls on those <strong>of</strong> the same animals <strong>in</strong><br />

Archaic <strong>and</strong>, especially, <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art, <strong>and</strong> sculpture <strong>in</strong> particular. 153 Focus<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

these three animals, Vermeule says:<br />

<strong>The</strong> lions who leap at bulls <strong>and</strong> who face each other <strong>in</strong> various heraldic poses on<br />

Mycenaean gems are little different from the fel<strong>in</strong>es on co<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> gems from 480<br />

to 375 B.C. <strong>The</strong>y have the same circumscribed manes, the same round, fairly flat<br />

faces, <strong>and</strong> the same long, fel<strong>in</strong>e legs with large paws. <strong>The</strong> aff<strong>in</strong>ity is not<br />

co<strong>in</strong>cidental; prehistoric stones were certa<strong>in</strong>ly excavated <strong>and</strong> circulated <strong>in</strong><br />

classical times, <strong>and</strong> the animals on the gate at Mycenae were not the first or the<br />

only testimonia to prehistoric ability <strong>in</strong> the natural, forceful render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> animals<br />

that was available to archaic <strong>and</strong> classical sculptors. In the <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> bulls one<br />

has only to compare, the large marble creature <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos necropolis….<br />

with the bulls on the Vaphio cups “to realize how little the generations after<br />

Pheidias could improve on the art <strong>of</strong> the mid-second millennium B.C. <strong>The</strong> art <strong>of</strong><br />

render<strong>in</strong>g dogs may even have decl<strong>in</strong>ed, compar<strong>in</strong>g the Kerameikos mastiff with<br />

the whippet-like hounds <strong>in</strong> the Mycenae <strong>and</strong> Tiryns frescoes. In brief, animals<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer the best subjective examples <strong>of</strong> artistic cont<strong>in</strong>uity from the art <strong>of</strong> the Bronze<br />

Age to that <strong>of</strong> Skopas <strong>and</strong> Lysippos.” 154<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> lions, the similarity that Vermeule detects between the naturalistic style <strong>of</strong><br />

those depicted <strong>in</strong> Bronze Age art <strong>and</strong> those <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> sculpture refers to the render<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> anatomical aspects, such as their manes, faces, legs, <strong>and</strong> paws, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

that he is not immune to the conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical accuracy. But, as<br />

noted above, Bronze Age depictions <strong>of</strong> lions were not devoid <strong>of</strong> anatomical <strong>in</strong>accuracies.<br />

153 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 52.<br />

154 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 52.<br />

107


Although this deviation does not feature <strong>in</strong> Vermeule’s discussion <strong>of</strong> the cont<strong>in</strong>uity from<br />

Bronze Age to <strong>Classical</strong> naturalism, he does take notice <strong>of</strong> it when he speaks <strong>of</strong> the<br />

doglike appearance <strong>of</strong> fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-century Attic funerary statues <strong>of</strong> lions. In this<br />

way, his discussion takes us back to examples <strong>of</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> the problematic style <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> sculpture.<br />

Vermeule does not talk about the elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Attic statues <strong>of</strong> lions that are<br />

at home with leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy. His bafflement, however, over their problematic style<br />

becomes evident when he identifies their can<strong>in</strong>e characteristics:<br />

Lions [produced by Greek artists between 420 <strong>and</strong> 320 B.C.] crouch like dogs<br />

over bones. <strong>The</strong>ir bodies are as well-proportioned <strong>and</strong> smoothly ideal as those <strong>of</strong><br />

Hegeso herself <strong>and</strong> her servant girl. Manes are like ruffs, <strong>and</strong> it is only close to<br />

the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Hellenistic Age, around 330 B.C., that they beg<strong>in</strong> to look like<br />

the hair on lions seen nowadays <strong>in</strong> zoos <strong>and</strong> circuses. Round eyes, broad, can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

snouts, <strong>and</strong> ears like those <strong>of</strong> a Doberman p<strong>in</strong>scher add to the image <strong>of</strong> friendly<br />

conceptualism. Toward the end <strong>of</strong> the hundred years <strong>of</strong> Attic funerary lions,<br />

some beasts look like as if they might bite but most <strong>of</strong> them are placid,<br />

occasionally even playful. <strong>The</strong> emotional faces which can be identified with the<br />

style <strong>of</strong> Scopas around 350 B.C. enter the repertory <strong>of</strong> lion sculpture, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

elongation <strong>of</strong> athletes by Lysippos <strong>in</strong> the generation after 340 B.C. 155<br />

Vermeule clearly states that <strong>Classical</strong> Attic funerary statues <strong>of</strong> lions follow the same<br />

development as that <strong>of</strong> the human form <strong>in</strong> Greek art, that is, they become more<br />

conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> appearance at the end <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period. Still, however, what<br />

catches his attention is the presence <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e anatomical characteristics, such as the eyes,<br />

snouts, <strong>and</strong> ears <strong>of</strong> these lions, which “add to the image <strong>of</strong> friendly conceptualism,” as he<br />

says. It is unclear what he means by “friendly conceptualism.” A possible mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

emerges when one looks at his <strong>in</strong>terpretation (especially its second component) <strong>of</strong> the<br />

problematic style <strong>of</strong> these lions as a mixture <strong>of</strong>: a) artists us<strong>in</strong>g Near Eastern models, <strong>and</strong><br />

b) thoughtful observation <strong>of</strong> comparable dogs <strong>and</strong> cats. As he characteristically states:<br />

155 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 51.<br />

108


“<strong>in</strong> the later fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries the artistic conception <strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> beasts was<br />

distilled from generations <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g motifs from Syria <strong>and</strong> Mesopotamia <strong>and</strong> from actual<br />

contemplation <strong>of</strong> large dogs <strong>and</strong> precocious cats.” 156 <strong>The</strong> statement is significant, for it<br />

exposes specific sources, other than Bronze Age art, that Vermeule thought to have been<br />

(or not) available to <strong>Classical</strong> sculptors, <strong>and</strong> thus, he held accountable for the naturalistic<br />

<strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> the appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> funerary lions:<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> lions on Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery, where naturalism is conceived as<br />

anatomical accuracy after copy<strong>in</strong>g Syrian (Neo-Hittite) <strong>and</strong> Mesopotamian (Assyrian)<br />

models, <strong>and</strong> the absence or scarcity <strong>of</strong> real lions dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Classical</strong> times <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, an idea<br />

that is not fully supported by classical texts, yet features prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> modern<br />

scholarship as the reason for <strong>Classical</strong> Greek artists’ observation <strong>of</strong> animals comparable<br />

to lions; it is thus considered responsible for the non-naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong><br />

contemporary statues <strong>of</strong> lions. In this respect, Vermeule is <strong>in</strong> agreement with Richter,<br />

who, as seen earlier, attributed the doglike appearance <strong>of</strong> the Mausoleum lion to the<br />

suggestion that <strong>Classical</strong> artists “had no opportunity to study from life.”<br />

Naturalism as Anatomical Accuracy: Two Near-Eastern Types <strong>of</strong> Lions on<br />

Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian Pottery (<strong>and</strong> Contemporary <strong>Sculpture</strong>)<br />

Representations <strong>of</strong> lions on Orientaliz<strong>in</strong>g Cor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery, also known as<br />

Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian, 157 <strong>in</strong>dicate that the conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical accuracy was<br />

a pre-classical phenomenon, <strong>and</strong> thus one at the service <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> artists. Focus<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

specific anatomical features, Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery clearly dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between two<br />

156 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 59.<br />

157 Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery is divided <strong>in</strong>to three phases: Early (EPC): 720-690 B.C., Middle (MPC): 690-<br />

650 B.C., <strong>and</strong> Late (LPC): 650-630 B.C.: J. Boardman, Early Greek Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. 11 TH -6 TH Centuries<br />

B.C. A H<strong>and</strong>book (New York <strong>and</strong> London, 1998) 85.<br />

109


types <strong>of</strong> lions: Syrian/Neo-Hittite <strong>and</strong> Assyrian. As Boardman states, <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

lions on Middle Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery, early on (690-650 B.C.), “lions copy the [out-<strong>of</strong>-<br />

date] Syrian/Neo-Hittite square-muzzled type,” whereas, near 650 B.C. or later, the<br />

Syrian type <strong>of</strong> lion is replaced by the “po<strong>in</strong>ted-nose Assyrian type.” 158 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

Humphrey Payne, the latter type is also used for representations <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> sixth-century<br />

Cor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery. 159<br />

<strong>The</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the Syrian/Neo-Hittite <strong>and</strong> Assyrian types <strong>of</strong> lions occurs<br />

also <strong>in</strong> seventh-century sculpture, where the former is represented by the lions <strong>of</strong> a<br />

marble perrirhanterion found <strong>in</strong> the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Poseidon at Isthmia (ca. 660-650 B.C.),<br />

<strong>and</strong> the latter by the limestone lion found <strong>in</strong> Olympia <strong>and</strong> thought to have been probably<br />

used as a spout for a founta<strong>in</strong> (ca. 650 B.C.). 160 This evidence reveals “a progression <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek approval,” as Boardman says, 161 from the Neo-Hittite to the Assyrian type <strong>of</strong> a<br />

lion, or the existence <strong>of</strong> two possibilities <strong>of</strong> naturalism conceived as anatomical accuracy<br />

<strong>in</strong> connection with lions <strong>and</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> only one <strong>of</strong> them <strong>in</strong> both pre-classical<br />

pottery <strong>and</strong> sculpture. As such, it may very well be what Vermeule had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when<br />

158 Boardman, Early Greek Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g 86 <strong>and</strong> 87 for respective quotations. For these two types <strong>of</strong> lions<br />

on Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery, see H. Payne, Necrocor<strong>in</strong>thia: A Study <strong>of</strong> Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Art <strong>in</strong> the Archaic Period<br />

(Oxford, 1931) 67-70; also Amyx, Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g 663. For an example <strong>of</strong> the Syrian/Neo-<br />

Hittite type <strong>of</strong> a lion on Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery, see the Middle Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian aryballos by the Sacrifice<br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>ter (Boston 95.511) illustrated <strong>in</strong> Boardman, Early Greek Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g fig. 172. <strong>The</strong> earliest known<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the Assyrian type <strong>of</strong> a lion on Protocor<strong>in</strong>thian pottery is the Chigi vase (Rome, VG 22679):<br />

Boardman, Early Greek Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g figs. 178.1-3; also J. M. Hurwit, “Read<strong>in</strong>g the Chigi Vase,”<br />

Hesperia 71 (2002) 11 <strong>and</strong> 12, where he also mentions Assyrian ivories, metalwork, <strong>and</strong> textiles as possible<br />

carriers <strong>of</strong> images <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>of</strong> this type imported to seventh-century Cor<strong>in</strong>th.<br />

159 Payne, Necrocor<strong>in</strong>thia 69.<br />

160 For the debt <strong>of</strong> these examples <strong>of</strong> sculpture to Neo-Hittite <strong>and</strong> Assyrian models respectively <strong>and</strong><br />

illustrations, see Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period 167, figs. 74 <strong>and</strong> 265; also M. C.<br />

Sturgeon, Isthmia IV: <strong>Sculpture</strong> I: 1952-1967 (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1987) 48-51, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the lions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Isthmia perrirhanterion reflect<strong>in</strong>g Neo-Hittite prototypes; <strong>and</strong> H. Gabelmann, Studien zum frühgriechischen<br />

Löwenbild (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1965) 111, no. 2, pl. 1.2-1.3, 32.1 for the lion from Olympia follow<strong>in</strong>g Assyrian<br />

models; see also Boardman’s review <strong>of</strong> Gabelmann’s study <strong>in</strong> Gnomon 39 (1967) 99-101.<br />

161 Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period 167 uses the phrase while discuss<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong><br />

seventh-century vase pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g on contemporary sculpture as evidenced by the these two types <strong>of</strong> lions.<br />

110


speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> sculpture as “distilled from generations <strong>of</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g<br />

motifs from Syria <strong>and</strong> Mesopotamia.”<br />

Literary Evidence for the Availability <strong>of</strong> Lions <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong><br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g next to Vermeule’s assertion that <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculptors contemplated<br />

large dogs <strong>and</strong> precocious cats ow<strong>in</strong>g to the absence <strong>of</strong> real lions—an idea that, <strong>in</strong> his<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d, accounts for the non-naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> the statues <strong>of</strong> lions—it appears to<br />

overlook ancient literary evidence that attests to the presence <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-<br />

century northern <strong>Greece</strong>. Start<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the fifth century, Herodotus, for example, refers to<br />

lions attack<strong>in</strong>g the camel tra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> Xerxes’ <strong>in</strong>vad<strong>in</strong>g army as it was mak<strong>in</strong>g its way<br />

through northern <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>in</strong> 480 B.C., while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that lions were still present <strong>in</strong><br />

that area <strong>in</strong> his own day (later part <strong>of</strong> the fifth century):<br />

As Xerxes marched along, lions set upon his camels, which were carry<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

corn. <strong>The</strong> lions would come constantly at night, <strong>and</strong> leav<strong>in</strong>g their usual haunts,<br />

would touch noth<strong>in</strong>g else, baggage animal or human; they ravaged the camels<br />

only. I wonder what the cause can be that forced the lions to leave the other<br />

creatures alone <strong>and</strong> attack the camels, s<strong>in</strong>ce this was an animal that they had never<br />

seen before or had any experience <strong>of</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are <strong>in</strong> these parts many lions <strong>and</strong> wild oxen, the enormous horns <strong>of</strong> which<br />

are brought to <strong>Greece</strong>. <strong>The</strong> boundary <strong>of</strong> the lions is the river Nestus, which flows<br />

through Abdera, <strong>and</strong> the Achelous, which flows through Acarnania. To the east<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Nestus, <strong>in</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the nearer part <strong>of</strong> Europe, you will never see a lion, nor<br />

west <strong>of</strong> the Achelous <strong>in</strong> the rest <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong>; but they are found <strong>in</strong> the l<strong>and</strong><br />

between these rivers. (7.125-7.126) [106] 162<br />

162 Hurwit, “Read<strong>in</strong>g the Chigi Vase” 11, n. 36, wonders if Herodotus’ lions were mounta<strong>in</strong> lions. It is<br />

important to keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that if by “mounta<strong>in</strong> lions,” he means the big cats also known today as<br />

“cougars,” “pumas,” panthers,” <strong>and</strong> “catamounts” (Felis Concolor), they are native to the Americas <strong>and</strong> not<br />

to the Old World. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this species <strong>and</strong> its various names, see S. Ew<strong>in</strong>g, E. Grossman, eds.,<br />

Shadow Cat: Encounter<strong>in</strong>g the American Mounta<strong>in</strong> Lion (Seattle, 1999). <strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> camels <strong>in</strong> war is also<br />

mentioned by Aristotle (HA 632a), <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> animals’ castration: “the female<br />

camels too are castrated when they wish to use them for war, so that they should not carry young”;<br />

translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1991) 403.<br />

111


<strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>cident <strong>of</strong> lions maul<strong>in</strong>g Xerxes’ camels is repeated by Pausanias along with<br />

the story <strong>of</strong> Pulydamas, a late fifth-century Olympic victor <strong>in</strong> the pancratium (408 B.C.),<br />

also known to have killed a lion with his bare h<strong>and</strong>s around Mount Olympus <strong>in</strong> northern<br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. While referr<strong>in</strong>g to these stories, Pausanias states that lions were still present <strong>in</strong><br />

this area <strong>in</strong> his own time (A.D. II):<br />

Other have won glorious victories <strong>in</strong> the pancratium, but Pulydamas besides the<br />

prizes for the pancratium, has to his credit the follow<strong>in</strong>g exploits <strong>of</strong> a different<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d. <strong>The</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong>ous part <strong>of</strong> Thrace, on this side the river Nestus, which runs<br />

through the l<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Abdera, breeds among other wild beasts lions, which once<br />

attacked the army <strong>of</strong> Xerxes, <strong>and</strong> mauled the camels carry<strong>in</strong>g the supplies. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

lions <strong>of</strong>ten roam right <strong>in</strong>to the l<strong>and</strong> around Mount Olympus, one side <strong>of</strong> which is<br />

turned towards Macedonia, <strong>and</strong> the other towards <strong>The</strong>ssaly <strong>and</strong> the river Peneius.<br />

Here on Mount Olympus Pulydamas slew a lion, a huge <strong>and</strong> powerful beast,<br />

without the help <strong>of</strong> any weapon. To this exploit he was impelled by an ambition<br />

to rival the labours <strong>of</strong> Heracles, because Heracles also, legend says, overthrew the<br />

lion at Nemea. (6.5.4) [137] 163<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the fourth-century B.C., Xenophon, <strong>in</strong> his treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g, places<br />

the habitat <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> foreign countries with the closest be<strong>in</strong>g Macedonia to the north:<br />

Lions, leopards, lynxes, panthers, bears <strong>and</strong> all similar wild beasts are<br />

captured <strong>in</strong> foreign countries (e0n ce/naij xw&raij), about Mt. Pangaeus<br />

<strong>and</strong> Cittus beyond Macedonia, on Mysian Olympus <strong>and</strong> P<strong>in</strong>dus, on Nysa<br />

beyond Syria, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> other mounta<strong>in</strong> ranges capable <strong>of</strong> support<strong>in</strong>g such<br />

animals. (Cyn. 11.1) [192]<br />

163 For the date <strong>of</strong> Pulydamas’ victory <strong>in</strong> 408 B.C., see Hurwit, “Read<strong>in</strong>g the Chigi Vase” 11, n. 36. For a<br />

statue base (ca. 330 B.C.) at Olympia depict<strong>in</strong>g this feat <strong>in</strong> relief, attributed to Lysippos, <strong>and</strong> thought to be<br />

the base <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> Pulydamas at Olympia mentioned by Pausanias (6.5.4) , see A. Kosmopoulou, <strong>The</strong><br />

Iconography <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>d Statue Bases <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Periods (Madison, 2002) 73-74, 200-<br />

202, figs. 56-57. Pausanias (9.40.1) provides an additional example <strong>of</strong> the association <strong>of</strong> lions with<br />

Olympus <strong>in</strong> his reference to a military confrontation between Caranus, the legendary progenitor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Macedonian royal house, <strong>and</strong> Cisseus, the k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Thrace: “<strong>The</strong> Macedonians say that Caranus, k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

Macedonia, overcame <strong>in</strong> battle Cisseus, a chiefta<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a border<strong>in</strong>g country. For his victory Caranus set up a<br />

trophy after the Argive fashion, but it is said to have been upset by a lion from Olympus, which then<br />

vanished”; translation: W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Pausanias. Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> IV (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1935; repr. 1961) 360-361.<br />

112


It is perhaps Xenophon’s use <strong>of</strong> the phrase “foreign countries” that has led Vermeule to<br />

assert that <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculptors never or at least hardly ever saw lions. 164<br />

Next, Aristotle, although he considers the lion a rare animal, he refers to one that<br />

was captured lame, without, however, specify<strong>in</strong>g where, <strong>and</strong> had many <strong>of</strong> its teeth broken<br />

(HA 629b). 165 Like Herodotus, he places the animal’s habitat <strong>in</strong> northern <strong>Greece</strong>, <strong>in</strong> two<br />

different <strong>in</strong>stances:<br />

It is a fact that the lion is a scarce animal, <strong>and</strong> is not found <strong>in</strong> many places—<br />

<strong>in</strong> the whole <strong>of</strong> Europe it occurs only <strong>in</strong> the tract <strong>of</strong> country between the rivers<br />

Achelous <strong>and</strong> Nessos. (HA 579b) [62]<br />

Whereas lions occur more <strong>in</strong> Europe (only <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>in</strong> that region <strong>of</strong> Europe that lies<br />

between the Achelous <strong>and</strong> Nessos), leopards on the other h<strong>and</strong> occur <strong>in</strong> Asia <strong>and</strong><br />

not <strong>in</strong> Europe. (HA 606b) [64]<br />

Aristotle also dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between two different types <strong>of</strong> lions without, however,<br />

assign<strong>in</strong>g them to specific geographical areas. One type, he says, has a rounded body,<br />

curlier hair, <strong>and</strong> a cowardly disposition, whereas the other is characterized by a longer<br />

body, better hair, <strong>and</strong> a braver character. 166 In sum, Aristotle’s accounts suggest that<br />

164 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 49: “sculptors saw humans but never (at least hardly ever) lions”;<br />

but he also states (51): “like the sculptors work<strong>in</strong>g at Xanthos <strong>in</strong> Lycia, artists <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> could have seen<br />

small mounta<strong>in</strong> lions.” <strong>The</strong> same suggestion is also made by E. F. Rambo, “Lions <strong>in</strong> Greek Art” (diss.<br />

Bryn Mawr College, 1918) 9, who, on the basis <strong>of</strong> the very same passage by Xenophon, suggests that the<br />

lions to which he refers could have been mounta<strong>in</strong> lions.<br />

165 Aristotle also discusses bones <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> two different <strong>in</strong>stances (HA 516b <strong>and</strong> 521b): Some animals<br />

would appear to have no marrow at all <strong>in</strong> their bones, e.g., the lion, on account <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g very little marrow<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>and</strong> that th<strong>in</strong>, an <strong>in</strong> a few bones only; actually, there is marrow <strong>in</strong> the thigh <strong>and</strong> arm-bones. <strong>The</strong><br />

bones <strong>of</strong> the lion are more solid than <strong>in</strong> any other animal; they are so hard that when they are rubbed<br />

together sparks fly out as though from fl<strong>in</strong>t (Aristotle HA 516b; translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle.<br />

Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965) 195; also HA 521b, where he says: “In young<br />

animals the marrow is quite bloodlike; when they are older, <strong>in</strong> the fatty animals it becomes fatty, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the<br />

suety ones suety. Not all the bones conta<strong>in</strong> marrow, but only the hollow ones, <strong>and</strong> some <strong>of</strong> these have<br />

none. Thus, <strong>in</strong> the lion some bones have no marrow at all, some only a little; which expla<strong>in</strong>s why, as stated<br />

already, some writers assert that lions have no marrow”; translation: Peck, Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I,<br />

22). Such statement may be related to the modern zoological observation that a lion’s loud roar is made<br />

possible by the cartilage <strong>in</strong> its throat hav<strong>in</strong>g ossified <strong>in</strong>to bone, also known as the hyoid structure. For a<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> this part <strong>of</strong> a lion’s physiology, see C. A. W. Guggisberg, Simba. <strong>The</strong> Life <strong>of</strong> the Lion<br />

(Philadelphia <strong>and</strong> New York, 1963) 19.<br />

166 Aristotle, History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (629b): “<strong>The</strong>re are two k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> lions; <strong>of</strong> these the one with the more<br />

rounded body <strong>and</strong> curlier hair is more cowardly, while the longer one with good hair is braver. Sometimes<br />

113


good knowledge not only <strong>of</strong> the nearby habitat <strong>of</strong> lions, but also <strong>of</strong> different species <strong>of</strong><br />

them based on dist<strong>in</strong>ct anatomical characteristics was available to him <strong>and</strong> his audience.<br />

Additional evidence for <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society be<strong>in</strong>g well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with real<br />

lions derives from a speech <strong>of</strong> Isocrates, which suggests regular exposure <strong>of</strong> fourth-<br />

century audiences to the animal. Dated to 354/3 B.C., Isocrates’ Antidosis refers to<br />

tra<strong>in</strong>ed lions as parts <strong>of</strong> annual exhibitions <strong>in</strong> contemporary <strong>Greece</strong>. In an attempt to<br />

underl<strong>in</strong>e the benefits <strong>of</strong> education for the human m<strong>in</strong>d, the orator draws an analogy from<br />

the tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> bears:<br />

But most absurd <strong>of</strong> all, they [Isocrates’ detractors] behold <strong>in</strong> the shows (e0n toi=j<br />

qau&mas<strong>in</strong>) which are held year after year lions which are more gentle toward their<br />

tra<strong>in</strong>ers than some people are toward their benefactors, <strong>and</strong> bears which dance<br />

about <strong>and</strong> wrestle <strong>and</strong> imitate our skill, <strong>and</strong> yet they are not able to judge even<br />

from these <strong>in</strong>stances the power which education <strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g have, nor can they<br />

see that human nature will respond more promptly than the animals to the benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> education. (Ant. 213-214) [128] 167<br />

they run away stretch<strong>in</strong>g the tail straight out like hounds”; translation: Balme, Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> 384. Physiology aside, what is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g is that Aristotle’s criteria <strong>of</strong> body length <strong>and</strong> appearance<br />

<strong>of</strong> hair match closely those that, nowadays, set apart two recognized species <strong>of</strong> lions: the Asiatic (Panthera<br />

leo Persicus) <strong>and</strong> African (Panthera leo). As modern zoological studies state, Asiatic lions are smaller <strong>in</strong><br />

size <strong>and</strong> have a shorter <strong>and</strong> sparser mane (that makes their ears visible) when compared to their African<br />

counterparts: www.p<strong>and</strong>a.org/news_facts/education/best_place_species/current_top_10/asiatic_lion_.cfm -<br />

167 Similar evidence, but <strong>in</strong> reference to a third-century, religious context, is attested <strong>in</strong> an idyll by<br />

<strong>The</strong>ocritus that refers to a procession <strong>in</strong> honor <strong>of</strong> Artemis (most likely, <strong>in</strong> Syracuse) with many wild beasts<br />

<strong>in</strong> it, among them a lioness:<br />

Eubolus’ daughter, Anexo, was go<strong>in</strong>g, I knew with her basket<br />

to the enclosure <strong>of</strong> Artemis where on that day many wild beasts<br />

walked <strong>in</strong> procession about her, a lioness one <strong>of</strong> the number<br />

<strong>The</strong>ocritus (II, 66-68);<br />

translation: D. H<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>The</strong>ocritus: Idylls <strong>and</strong> Epigrams (New York, 1982) 10. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek sanctuaries <strong>in</strong> the breed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> animals, such as cattle <strong>and</strong> horses, as<br />

evidenced by <strong>in</strong>scriptions associated, for example, with the <strong>Classical</strong> sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>in</strong> Arkes<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

Amorgos, that <strong>of</strong> Alea Athena <strong>in</strong> Tegea, <strong>in</strong> the fourth-century B.C., <strong>and</strong> also that <strong>of</strong> Apollo at Delphi, <strong>in</strong> the<br />

second century B.C., see S. Isager, “Sacred <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hellenistic <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> T. L<strong>in</strong>ders <strong>and</strong><br />

B. Alroth, eds., Economics <strong>of</strong> Cult <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Greek World. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Uppsala Symposium<br />

1990 (Uppsala, 1992) 15-20. For a short discussion <strong>of</strong> both Isocrates’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong>ocritus’ accounts, see G.<br />

Jennison, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> for Show <strong>and</strong> Pleasure <strong>in</strong> Ancient Rome (Manchester, 1937) 24.<br />

114


William Brown suggests that this passage is an example <strong>of</strong> the importation <strong>of</strong> lions from<br />

Africa or Asia to fourth-century <strong>Greece</strong>. 168 Lawrence Bliquez, while acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g this<br />

suggestion, does not rule out the possibility <strong>of</strong> Isocrates’ lions be<strong>in</strong>g trapped <strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

locally <strong>in</strong> northern <strong>Greece</strong>. 169 Whether imported from Africa, Asia, or captured <strong>in</strong><br />

northern <strong>Greece</strong>, these lions show that, <strong>in</strong> the fourth century, Greek artists did have liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

models if they wished to employ them. As Bliquez has po<strong>in</strong>ted out, this evidence<br />

suggests that Vermeule was too quick to dismiss the availability <strong>of</strong> real lions to Greek<br />

sculptors. 170<br />

Taken together, the literary accounts reviewed so far <strong>in</strong>dicate that lions were<br />

present <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> neighbor<strong>in</strong>g areas. As a result, Vermeule’s idea that<br />

contemporary artists were forced to borrow from the anatomy <strong>of</strong> comparable dogs <strong>and</strong><br />

cats ow<strong>in</strong>g to lack <strong>of</strong> real lions appears not to be an adequate explanation <strong>of</strong> the non-<br />

naturalistic elements <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> contemporary sculpture.<br />

So pervasive is, however, the idea <strong>of</strong> the lack <strong>of</strong> real lions <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> that<br />

features also as an explanation <strong>of</strong> the non-naturalistic elements <strong>of</strong> colossal marble statues<br />

<strong>of</strong> lions erected as commemorative monuments to the dead, such as the one found at the<br />

west bank <strong>of</strong> the river Strymon at Amphipolis (Fig. 10), whose date has been placed <strong>in</strong><br />

the fourth century B.C., although a third-century date has also been proposed. 171<br />

168 W. L. Brown, <strong>The</strong> Etruscan Lion (Oxford, 1960) 167.<br />

169 L. J. Bliquez, “Lions <strong>and</strong> Greek Sculptors,” CW 68 (1975) 382 <strong>and</strong> 383.<br />

170 Bliquez, “Lions <strong>and</strong> Greek Sculptors” 381.<br />

171 For an account <strong>of</strong> the discovery <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis, its reconstruction, <strong>and</strong> fourth-century date,<br />

see O. Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis (Cambridge, Mass., 1941) 48, who places it <strong>in</strong> the last<br />

quarter <strong>of</strong> the fourth-century B.C.; see review <strong>of</strong> this study by G. M. A. Richter, <strong>in</strong> AJA 46 (1942) 294-295,<br />

who agrees with this date; Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 100, dates it also to the fourth century<br />

(340-330 B.C.); Ridgway, Fourth-Century Styles 144, does not specify its date, but mentions its use <strong>in</strong><br />

scholarship as fourth-century compar<strong>and</strong>a for assign<strong>in</strong>g a similar date to the lion from the Lion Tomb at<br />

Knidos, which she considers a post-mid-fourth-century work. For the assignment <strong>of</strong> a late fourth-century<br />

date (325-300 B.C.) to the lion <strong>of</strong> Knidos, see Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> 228 <strong>and</strong> 231.<br />

115


Regard<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> this lion, whose reconstruction has been based on a<br />

fourth- <strong>and</strong> perhaps third-century counterpart from Chaeronea, 172 it has been noted that<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> anatomical details, such as its ve<strong>in</strong>s, rich mane, powerful muzzle, mouth turned<br />

down at the side, <strong>and</strong> eyes set deep <strong>in</strong> their sockets are rendered naturalistically, whereas<br />

its pose—sitt<strong>in</strong>g erect on its haunches like a dog—is unnatural <strong>and</strong> dictated perhaps by its<br />

enormous size (5.30m tall). 173 Comment<strong>in</strong>g on this set <strong>of</strong> stylistic <strong>in</strong>congruities, which<br />

he considers a trademark <strong>of</strong> Greek monumental lions, Oscar Broneer says:<br />

<strong>The</strong> strong trend toward realism, which is a fundamental characteristic <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

art, is evident <strong>in</strong> a much less degree <strong>in</strong> sculpture <strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d. Whether this is due<br />

to the lack <strong>of</strong> opportunity on the part <strong>of</strong> the sculptors to observe liv<strong>in</strong>g models, or<br />

to a conscious striv<strong>in</strong>g toward greater effect <strong>in</strong> symbolism <strong>and</strong> monumentality at<br />

For a slightly later date that extends <strong>in</strong>to the third century (300-250 B.C.), see G. B. Waywell, “<strong>The</strong> Lion<br />

from the Lion Tomb <strong>of</strong> Knidos,” <strong>in</strong> O. Palagia <strong>and</strong> W. Coulson, eds., Regional Schools <strong>in</strong> Hellenistic<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong>. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> an International Conference Held at the American Schools at Athens, March 15-<br />

17 1996 (Oxford, 1998) 235-241. He also assigns (239, n. 26) a late fourth- or early third-century date to<br />

the lion <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis; also for the assignment <strong>of</strong> a date around 200 B.C. to this lion, on the grounds <strong>of</strong> its<br />

humanized face wear<strong>in</strong>g “that Duce look first popularized by the Hellenistic monarchs,” see A. W.<br />

Lawrence, rev. <strong>of</strong> O. Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis (Cambridge, Mass., 1941), <strong>in</strong> JHS 62<br />

(1942) 102. For the existence <strong>of</strong> an engaged Doric order <strong>and</strong> a shield decoration <strong>in</strong> relief <strong>in</strong> association<br />

with this monument, see S. G. Miller <strong>and</strong> S. Miller, “Architectural Blocks from the Strymon,” ADeltion 27<br />

(Meletemata 1972) 140-169.<br />

172 For a late fourth or early-third century date assigned to the lion <strong>of</strong> Chaeronea, see Waywell, “<strong>The</strong> lion<br />

from the Lion Tomb at Knidos,” <strong>in</strong> Palagia <strong>and</strong> Coulson, Regional Schools 239, n. 26. For a summary <strong>of</strong><br />

its discovery at the edge <strong>of</strong> a rectangular enclosure <strong>in</strong> which 254 skeletons were found accompanied by<br />

small vases <strong>and</strong> strigils, see W. R. Lethaby, “Greek Lion Monuments,” JHS 38 (1918) 39-41; <strong>The</strong> lion has<br />

been thought to be have marked the grave <strong>of</strong> the Boeotians that fell <strong>in</strong> the battle <strong>of</strong> Chaeronea <strong>in</strong> 338 B.C.<br />

fight<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st Philip II <strong>of</strong> Macedonia. Crucial to this identification have been the account <strong>of</strong> Pausanias<br />

who says (9.40.10): “As you approach the city [Chaeroneia] you see a common grave <strong>of</strong> the <strong>The</strong>bans who<br />

were killed <strong>in</strong> the struggle aga<strong>in</strong>st Philip. It has no <strong>in</strong>scription, but is surmounted by a lion, probably a<br />

reference to the spirit <strong>of</strong> men. That there is no <strong>in</strong>scription is, <strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion, because their courage was not<br />

favored by appropriate good fortune”; translation: Jones, Pausanias. Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> IV 361. Strabo<br />

(9.2.37) mentions that one can see <strong>in</strong> Chaeronea the tombs <strong>of</strong> those who fell <strong>in</strong> the battle, but other authors,<br />

such as D. Siculus (16.86.6), <strong>and</strong> Plutarch (Alex<strong>and</strong>er 9.2) state respectively that after the battle Philip<br />

raised a trophy <strong>of</strong> victory, <strong>and</strong> that there was a poly<strong>and</strong>rion <strong>of</strong> the Macedonians <strong>in</strong> Chaeronea. On the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> this evidence, Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Late <strong>Classical</strong> Period 118, <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the lion<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chaeronea states that: “it is not altogether clear whether it was for the victorious Macedonians or the<br />

<strong>The</strong>ban Sacred B<strong>and</strong>, which was wiped out.”<br />

173 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the naturalistic render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the anatomical details <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis, see D.<br />

Lazaridis, Amphipolis (M<strong>in</strong>istry <strong>of</strong> Culture. Archaeological Receipts Fund; Athens, 1997) 74, who<br />

considers them impressive; for its unnatural pose, see Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis, 40, figs.<br />

36-37, who actually juxtaposes this pose to illustrations <strong>of</strong> poses <strong>of</strong> real lions. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> colossal<br />

statues <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture, see J.-P. Vernant, “<strong>The</strong> Representation <strong>of</strong> the Invisible <strong>and</strong> the Psychological<br />

Category <strong>of</strong> the Double: <strong>The</strong> Colossos,” <strong>in</strong> J.-P. Vernant, Myth <strong>and</strong> Thought among the Greeks (London<br />

<strong>and</strong> Boston, 1983) 305-320.<br />

116


the expense <strong>of</strong> realism, or to a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> both these factors, the fact rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that the lion at an early period, to a greater extend than other animals developed<br />

<strong>in</strong>to a decorative design like the acanthus, the rosette, the tendril, <strong>and</strong> other<br />

patterns derived from the vegetable k<strong>in</strong>gdom. 174<br />

In this statement, the idea <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> real lions as models for artists aga<strong>in</strong> features as a<br />

possible explanation <strong>of</strong> the non-naturalistic appearance <strong>of</strong> statues <strong>of</strong> lions, <strong>in</strong> this case,<br />

colossal. If this is, however, a po<strong>in</strong>t that l<strong>in</strong>ks Broneer’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation to that <strong>of</strong><br />

Vermeule <strong>and</strong> Richter regard<strong>in</strong>g the problematic style <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture, what<br />

sets it apart is the attention paid to the possibility <strong>of</strong> “a conscious striv<strong>in</strong>g toward<br />

symbolism <strong>and</strong> monumentality.” Such a suggestion is important, for, although it st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

side by side with the underly<strong>in</strong>g view <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> these lions as an artistic mistake, it<br />

actually acknowledges the need to approach the sculptures through the eyes <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek artists <strong>and</strong> spectators.<br />

b. <strong>The</strong> Case <strong>of</strong> the Dog<br />

Lions are not the only animals whose representations <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture have<br />

been considered problematic. Representations <strong>of</strong> dogs dat<strong>in</strong>g to the Archaic <strong>and</strong> mostly<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> periods have been also s<strong>in</strong>gled out for their <strong>in</strong>consistent style. Comment<strong>in</strong>g, for<br />

example, on the late sixth-century (ca. 520 B.C.) marble statue <strong>of</strong> a dog, usually<br />

attributed to the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Brauronia on the Athenian Acropolis (Fig. 11),<br />

Humphrey Payne <strong>and</strong> Gerard Mackworth-Young state that: “the figure is a remarkable<br />

anatomical study; so much emphasis <strong>in</strong>deed has been laid on the frame <strong>and</strong> its slight<br />

cover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ew <strong>and</strong> muscle that one is apt to overlook the strength <strong>of</strong> the stylization—<br />

at least <strong>in</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g at the photograph: <strong>in</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al, the long, flat, sharp-edged surfaces,<br />

174 Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis 42.<br />

117


especially <strong>of</strong> the neck <strong>and</strong> flanks, strike the eye more readily.” 175 With respect to the<br />

same statue, but with emphasis now placed on its execution, Richter says: “we<br />

can…enjoy the keen look <strong>of</strong> the eyes <strong>and</strong> the splendid structure <strong>of</strong> the long, lean body;<br />

the shoulder-blade, humerus, <strong>and</strong> ribs are shown strongly protrud<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> a long ridge<br />

marks the abdom<strong>in</strong>al muscle. <strong>The</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g is still angular <strong>and</strong> harsh.” 176<br />

As can be seen, Payne <strong>and</strong> Mackworth-Young note the <strong>in</strong>consistency <strong>in</strong> the style<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue, but provide no explanation <strong>of</strong> it. Yet it is worth not<strong>in</strong>g that both <strong>in</strong> their<br />

case as well as that <strong>of</strong> Richter, the positive evaluation <strong>of</strong> the dog derives from its<br />

conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g anatomical details, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, reveals a modern conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism<br />

as anatomical accuracy, but, at the same time, fails to consider that this conception may<br />

not be an accurate reflection <strong>of</strong> the evaluation <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>in</strong> the late sixth century B.C.<br />

<strong>The</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>consistent style has been also noted <strong>in</strong> a fifth-century marble<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> a dog that was found <strong>in</strong> the area <strong>of</strong> the eastern cemetery <strong>of</strong> Pella <strong>in</strong> Macedonia<br />

(Fig. 12a-b). 177 <strong>The</strong> dog, which sits upright on its haunches, has been dated to around<br />

460-450 B.C. <strong>and</strong> is thought to have stood on a tomb “much like the grave monuments <strong>in</strong><br />

the Kerameikos or other Greek sites,” a suggestion which has been further <strong>in</strong>terpreted as<br />

evidence that Pella was an important center <strong>of</strong> Greek culture <strong>in</strong> the mid-fifth century<br />

175 Payne <strong>and</strong> G. Mackworth-Young, Archaic Marble <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Acropolis (New York, 1951) 51,<br />

pl. 131, 3. <strong>The</strong> dog (Acropolis Museum 143) is the surviv<strong>in</strong>g half <strong>of</strong> a pair <strong>of</strong> dogs (the other one<br />

[Acropolis Museum, 550] be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> fragmentary condition). For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these dogs, their alleged<br />

discovery south <strong>of</strong> the Parthenon, attribution to the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Brauronia, <strong>and</strong> also date<br />

oscillat<strong>in</strong>g between 540 <strong>and</strong> 520 B.C., with the majority <strong>of</strong> scholars favor<strong>in</strong>g the later one, see B. S.<br />

Ridgway, <strong>The</strong> Archaic Style <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (second ed., Chicago, 1993) 201. She does not preclude<br />

the possibility (201) that these two dogs <strong>and</strong> the Ramp<strong>in</strong> horseman with his companion piece found west <strong>of</strong><br />

the Erechtheion might have formed a s<strong>in</strong>gle group: “two young men, return<strong>in</strong>g perhaps from the hunt (the<br />

Dioskouroi after the Kalydonian boar hunt?) accompanied by their dogs,” but she does note that the<br />

f<strong>in</strong>dspot <strong>of</strong> the riders is different from that <strong>of</strong> the hounds.<br />

176 Richter, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 31.<br />

177 <strong>The</strong> statue was discovered by chance <strong>in</strong> 1954, <strong>in</strong> the area <strong>of</strong> the eastern cemetery <strong>of</strong> Pella, <strong>and</strong> three<br />

years before the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the excavations at the site: P. M. Petsas, Pella. Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great’s Capital<br />

(<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1978) 49. For the date <strong>of</strong> the statue as be<strong>in</strong>g based on style rather than archaeological<br />

context, see Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 263.<br />

118


B.C. 178 Although not described <strong>in</strong> detail, the Pella dog features <strong>in</strong> Vermeule’s discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> Roman copies <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek statues <strong>of</strong> animals, specifically dogs. 179 In fact,<br />

Vermeule considers it one <strong>of</strong> three examples <strong>of</strong> Greek sculptural representations <strong>of</strong> dogs<br />

<strong>and</strong> composite creatures with doglike features (i.e. the sph<strong>in</strong>x) that span the decades from<br />

520 to 450 B.C. <strong>and</strong> “are marked by emphasis on somewhat conceptual muscular <strong>and</strong><br />

bone structures, particularly <strong>in</strong> the presentation <strong>of</strong> lumpy ribs sometimes curved too far<br />

toward the shoulders <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> toward the haunches. (This is a misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g [he<br />

says] <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e movement from a sitt<strong>in</strong>g or st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g to a crouch<strong>in</strong>g position).” 180<br />

Undeniably, the body <strong>of</strong> the Pella dog is muscular, but its ribs are curved toward its<br />

haunches <strong>and</strong> not its shoulders. Nevertheless, Vermeule’s statement reveals its<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> naturalism as anatomical accuracy (<strong>and</strong> also behavioral, s<strong>in</strong>ce pose <strong>and</strong><br />

movement are <strong>in</strong>volved), <strong>and</strong> his subsequent negative evaluation <strong>of</strong> the Pella dog as an<br />

artistic mistake (due to the absence <strong>of</strong> such an accuracy). Such an evaluation is further<br />

supported by his detection <strong>of</strong> another disappo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, aspect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statue, namely, its “massive misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e proportions.” 181 Vermeule<br />

provides no further explanation <strong>of</strong> this observation. Kawami, <strong>in</strong> contrast, elucidates this<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t by contrast<strong>in</strong>g the naturalistic musculature <strong>of</strong> the dog <strong>and</strong> its compact pose with its<br />

178 Petsas, Pella 49-50 (no museum number). Petsas does not specify any examples <strong>of</strong> statues <strong>of</strong> dogs from<br />

the Kerameikos or elsewhere, but for an Attic funerary statue <strong>of</strong> a dog (Copenhagen, Ny Carlsberg<br />

Glyptotek, 2447) that dates, however, to the fourth century (370-360 B.C.), <strong>and</strong> has a pose similar to that <strong>of</strong><br />

the dog from Pella, see F. Poulsen, Catalogue <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Ny Carlsberg Glyptotek<br />

(Copenhagen, 1951) 181-182, no. 238 b., <strong>and</strong> L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di<br />

statuaria tra classicità ed ellenismo (Milan, 1993) no. 182.<br />

179 C. Vermeule, “<strong>The</strong> Basel Dog: A V<strong>in</strong>dication,” AJA 72 (1968) 98, n. 9.<br />

180 Vermeule, “<strong>The</strong> Basel Dog” 98, n. 9, where the other two examples mentioned are the dog depicted on<br />

the late Archaic dog-<strong>and</strong>-cat-fight statue base from the Athenian Kerameikos (Fig. 14), <strong>and</strong> the sph<strong>in</strong>x from<br />

Aeg<strong>in</strong>a. For the last see, Ridgway, <strong>The</strong> Severe Style 35-36, 64, figs. 51-52.<br />

181 Vermeule, “<strong>The</strong> Basel Dog” 98, n. 9.<br />

119


small head <strong>and</strong> its th<strong>in</strong>, sharp muzzle. 182 Kawami does not oppose the mid-fifth century<br />

date <strong>of</strong> the Pella dog. That her overall view <strong>of</strong> this statue is, however, as negative as that<br />

<strong>of</strong> Vermeule is seen <strong>in</strong> her focus on the non-naturalistic details <strong>of</strong> its anatomy, that is,<br />

“the stiff l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> the mouth, the bl<strong>and</strong> model<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the eyes <strong>and</strong> forehead, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

conventionalized ruff <strong>of</strong> hair around the neck.” 183 That these characteristics had been<br />

considered responsible for the early <strong>Classical</strong> date <strong>of</strong> the statue is evident from her<br />

statement that “they may be merely aspects <strong>of</strong> prov<strong>in</strong>cial style rather than <strong>in</strong>dications <strong>of</strong><br />

chronology.” 184 Kawami’s characterization <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> the Pella dog as “prov<strong>in</strong>cial,”<br />

it is not surpris<strong>in</strong>g, s<strong>in</strong>ce this is the term usually employed to describe the style <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture found <strong>in</strong> Macedonia, <strong>and</strong> thought to carry a strong <strong>in</strong>fluence from that <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture made <strong>in</strong> the adjacent Greek world. 185 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, Kawami is<br />

able to establish one <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> her argument, namely, that a statue <strong>of</strong> dog<br />

found at Persepolis <strong>and</strong> display<strong>in</strong>g the same pose as that <strong>of</strong> the dog from Pella is Greek<br />

rather that Persian <strong>in</strong> style. Furthermore, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluence it exerts on Persian<br />

taste, Greek animal sculpture, <strong>and</strong> its style <strong>in</strong> particular, Kawami states, deserve more<br />

than the meager attention they have received so far. 186 Despite this valuable observation,<br />

however, Kawami’s discussion <strong>of</strong> the Pella dog does not <strong>of</strong>fer an explanation <strong>of</strong> its<br />

182 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 263.<br />

183 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 263.<br />

184 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 263.<br />

185 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> Macedonian sculpture <strong>of</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> periods <strong>and</strong> its eclectic<br />

tendencies, <strong>of</strong>ten comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Attic, Ionian, Cycladic, Boeotian, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>The</strong>ssalian features <strong>in</strong> what is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

called a Northern Ionic Style, <strong>and</strong> also further bibliography, see S. G. Miller, <strong>The</strong> Tomb <strong>of</strong> Lyson <strong>and</strong><br />

Kallikles: A Pa<strong>in</strong>ted Macedonian Tomb (Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 1993) 94, n. 4.<br />

186 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 259, for the Greek <strong>and</strong> not Persian style <strong>of</strong> animal sculptures<br />

from Persepolis; 265, for the poor attention <strong>of</strong> modern scholarship to Greek animal sculpture as a major<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicator <strong>of</strong> stylistic change; <strong>and</strong> 260-261, pl. 15, figs. 1-2, for a description <strong>and</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> the dog<br />

found <strong>in</strong> a vestibule <strong>of</strong> the southeast tower <strong>of</strong> the Apadana at Persepolis. For a recent discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> the art <strong>of</strong> ancient Iran, with emphasis placed on those <strong>of</strong> the Persian empire,<br />

see M. C. Root, “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient Iran,” <strong>in</strong> B. J. Coll<strong>in</strong>s, ed., A History <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> World<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Ancient Near East (Leiden <strong>and</strong> Boston, 2002) 167-209.<br />

120


<strong>in</strong>consistent style. That <strong>of</strong> Vermeule, <strong>in</strong> contrast, with its focus on the non-naturalistic<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> the statue, may appear that it does, especially when he calls the non-naturalistic<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> the statue “misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gs,” but, as the previous discussion <strong>of</strong> statues <strong>of</strong><br />

lions has suggested, this is a superficial <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> connection with animal<br />

sculpture.<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the fourth century, a marble statue <strong>of</strong> a dog that was found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

funerary prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos (Fig. 1), <strong>and</strong> will be<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> more detail shortly, has been also considered a representative <strong>of</strong> the<br />

problematic style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture. Kawami, for example, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that the heavy shoulders, thick legs, large paws, <strong>and</strong> tense watchfulness <strong>of</strong> the dog are all<br />

powerful naturalistic details. 187 But the statue also shares, she says, subtle leon<strong>in</strong>e<br />

qualities, such as “the heavy, compact chest, the well-sprung almost barrel-like rib cage,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the carefully modeled toes with prom<strong>in</strong>ent claws.” 188 In an attempt to expla<strong>in</strong> why<br />

the contradictory style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos dog is based on such a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e characteristics, Kawami suggests that:<br />

[It] reflects the common apotropaic functions <strong>of</strong> the two species <strong>in</strong> both the<br />

Aegean <strong>and</strong> the Near East. <strong>The</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e forms <strong>in</strong> a<br />

guardian animal has further parallels <strong>in</strong> Asia, not only <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese guardian<br />

sculpture but <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the shih-tzu-kou (lion dogs) whose<br />

dim<strong>in</strong>utive versions are known to us now as the Pek<strong>in</strong>gese, among other East<br />

Asian dog breeds. 189<br />

In a way that is <strong>in</strong> essence identical with Hurwit’s l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g on the Hekatompedon<br />

lion, Kawami attributes, not unreasonably, apotropaic significance to the contradictory<br />

style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos dog. What is different <strong>in</strong> her case, however, is that she supports<br />

187 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

188 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

189 Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

121


her <strong>in</strong>terpretation by draw<strong>in</strong>g a parallel from a distant cultural context. Although helpful,<br />

such an <strong>in</strong>terpretation is still <strong>in</strong>adequate because by restrict<strong>in</strong>g the stylistic analysis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statue to a specific cultural idea that can very well be possible (avert<strong>in</strong>g evil), it<br />

automatically suppresses the possibility <strong>of</strong> other contemporary ideas about the dog be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

at play here.<br />

It is clear from the scholarly op<strong>in</strong>ions cited so far that they provide a variety <strong>of</strong><br />

suggestions that <strong>in</strong>terpret the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g, that is, naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-<br />

naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> sculptures <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs as: a) an<br />

<strong>in</strong>ability <strong>of</strong> sculptors (due to mistake or misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g) to represent conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong><br />

their works animals to which they had no access <strong>in</strong> real life, or a result <strong>of</strong> sculptors’<br />

observ<strong>in</strong>g animals comparable to those they <strong>in</strong>tended to depict <strong>in</strong> their works, but were<br />

unavailable to them <strong>in</strong> real life; b) a result <strong>of</strong> artists’ be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluenced by a stock reservoir<br />

<strong>of</strong> animal images deriv<strong>in</strong>g from Near Eastern, <strong>and</strong> also Bronze Age Aegean art; <strong>and</strong> c) an<br />

attempt by artists to highlight the apotropaic power <strong>of</strong> the animals depicted.<br />

<strong>The</strong> scholarly works cited above may note the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong><br />

non-naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture, but do not<br />

explicitly verbalize, the existence <strong>of</strong> various types <strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation, namely,<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction that b<strong>in</strong>d together the stylistic elements <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture. Heavily <strong>in</strong>fluenced,<br />

however, by the modern conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art as qu<strong>in</strong>tessentially naturalistic<br />

(or strictly imitative <strong>of</strong> the external world), which, <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> animals, translates as<br />

anatomical (<strong>and</strong> behavioral) accuracy, they fall short <strong>of</strong> recogniz<strong>in</strong>g that the comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

<strong>of</strong> disagree<strong>in</strong>g, that is, naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements <strong>and</strong> the different types<br />

122


<strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>in</strong> which this comb<strong>in</strong>ation occurs is actually the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple on which the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture is based. In fact, these varieties <strong>of</strong><br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation, especially that <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency, as evidenced by the above survey, does not<br />

only def<strong>in</strong>e the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> sculptures <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> dogs, but extends also to those <strong>of</strong><br />

the Archaic period. What representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture <strong>in</strong>dicate,<br />

therefore, is that an <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> conflict<strong>in</strong>g elements persists as the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong><br />

style <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> phases <strong>of</strong> Greek art. One needs to consider that such an<br />

<strong>in</strong>terplay also extends to the human form <strong>in</strong> both the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> periods <strong>of</strong><br />

Greek sculpture. As already noted, Childs has po<strong>in</strong>ted out that a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> similarly<br />

conflict<strong>in</strong>g elements also characterizes representations <strong>of</strong> the human form <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

sculpture whose style is def<strong>in</strong>ed by a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> “knowable reality” <strong>and</strong> the artists’<br />

impressions <strong>of</strong> visible appearances. That preced<strong>in</strong>g—Archaic <strong>and</strong> early <strong>Classical</strong>—<br />

sculpture is not immune to this idea is evidenced, for example, by certa<strong>in</strong> pieces <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture, such as the earliest Attic kouroi, whose clenched h<strong>and</strong> “is actually <strong>in</strong>correct,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>gers have been given one extra jo<strong>in</strong>t…[thus] a total <strong>of</strong> four, rather than the<br />

natural three, phalanges,” as Ridgway notes, <strong>and</strong> also by the early <strong>Classical</strong> sph<strong>in</strong>x from<br />

Aeg<strong>in</strong>a, whose purely human head “is disturb<strong>in</strong>gly naturalistic,” unlike its non-<br />

naturalistic animal body. 190 As can be seen <strong>in</strong> this case, the human form develops <strong>in</strong><br />

contrast to the animal one which does not. This paradigm, therefore, shows an <strong>in</strong>terplay<br />

<strong>of</strong> accuracy <strong>and</strong> stylization; <strong>in</strong> other words, it embraces two essentially conflict<strong>in</strong>g<br />

notions/elements <strong>in</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> style.<br />

This evidence notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, another approach from which the scholarly works<br />

cited so far refra<strong>in</strong> is to take <strong>in</strong>to account the cultural context <strong>in</strong> which the animal<br />

190 Ridgway, <strong>The</strong> Archaic Style 80 <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong> Severe Style 36, figs. 51-52 respectively.<br />

123


sculptures they discuss were made. None considers, for example, contemporary ideas<br />

about the animals depicted <strong>in</strong> them. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion focuses on two <strong>Classical</strong><br />

funerary statues <strong>of</strong> animals, a lion <strong>and</strong> a dog, that were found <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos<br />

<strong>in</strong> the funerary prec<strong>in</strong>cts <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>and</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai<br />

respectively. It exam<strong>in</strong>es the style <strong>of</strong> these statues <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> contemporary ideas about<br />

the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog. Regard<strong>in</strong>g the Kerameikos lion, it suggests that the <strong>in</strong>consistent<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> its style are direct reflections <strong>of</strong> the contemporary manner <strong>in</strong> which the<br />

animal was viewed <strong>and</strong> thought to be <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> both its appearance <strong>and</strong> character <strong>and</strong><br />

also <strong>of</strong> a general attitude towards depictions <strong>of</strong> non-human creatures <strong>in</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

importance placed upon certa<strong>in</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> the body as guides to character. Similarly, about<br />

the Kerameikos dog, it suggests that the contradictory (can<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e) elements <strong>of</strong><br />

its style (<strong>and</strong> the pattern <strong>of</strong> opposition <strong>in</strong> which these elements are arranged) are not<br />

divorced from the contemporary Greek idea <strong>of</strong> the dog <strong>and</strong> the lion as two dist<strong>in</strong>ct animal<br />

species, yet very similar <strong>in</strong> nature <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their biology, anatomy, <strong>and</strong> behavior. <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tention is to show that animals are useful guides to the conceptual context that shapes<br />

the elements <strong>of</strong> style <strong>and</strong> serves their arrangement <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture.<br />

124


2. Two Cases Studies: <strong>The</strong> Lion <strong>and</strong> the Dog from the Kerameikos<br />

a. How Are <strong>The</strong>se <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Different from Composite <strong>Animal</strong> Figures?<br />

Before we proceed to the discussion <strong>of</strong> these case studies, it is important to keep<br />

<strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that, although the style <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog from the Kerameikos is based on<br />

elements l<strong>in</strong>ked together <strong>in</strong> a relationship <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency <strong>and</strong> contradiction respectively,<br />

it is not synonymous with the form or render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> composite creatures (Mischwesen),<br />

like Chimaera, for example, who shared the body <strong>of</strong> a lion with a goat’s head grow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from its back, <strong>and</strong> a serpent’s tail. Chimaera consists <strong>of</strong> anatomical parts <strong>of</strong> different<br />

animal species that do not merge <strong>in</strong>to one another, but are rather fragmented, <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>in</strong> their attempt to form a whole. Chimaera, therefore, gives the<br />

impression <strong>of</strong> a multifarious be<strong>in</strong>g with no concern for anatomical plausibility, evidence<br />

that suggests that she was, most likely, def<strong>in</strong>ed by her separate parts rather than as a<br />

whole.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question <strong>of</strong> the visual identity <strong>of</strong> Chimaera <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek thought is<br />

complex. It <strong>in</strong>volves the issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>spiration won from the arts <strong>of</strong> the Near East <strong>in</strong> the<br />

eighth <strong>and</strong> seventh centuries B.C., as well as the possibility <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g been prompted by<br />

the Greeks’ imag<strong>in</strong>ative response to the natural environment <strong>of</strong> Lycia, the creature’s<br />

homel<strong>and</strong>, or by physical evidence <strong>of</strong> fossils, which could have shaped the way<br />

Chimaera, a creature <strong>of</strong> the past, was envisioned <strong>in</strong> the present. That such a possibility is<br />

not unreasonable is suggested by a recent study <strong>of</strong> the griff<strong>in</strong>, which has stated that<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> the creature <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art might have very well been <strong>in</strong>spired by<br />

125


the discovery <strong>of</strong> fossils <strong>of</strong> ext<strong>in</strong>ct species <strong>of</strong> animals, such as d<strong>in</strong>osaurs with which<br />

nobody was familiar. 191<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the statues <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog from the Kerameikos, the elements<br />

compos<strong>in</strong>g their style are <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>and</strong> contradictory respectively, but merge <strong>in</strong>to each<br />

other (blend <strong>in</strong>to one another) <strong>and</strong> create, <strong>in</strong> each case, an animal whole whose anatomy<br />

is an <strong>in</strong>congruous <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> truthfulness <strong>and</strong> falsehood/deception, but fused <strong>in</strong>to a<br />

cohesive whole. As a result, the animal represented <strong>in</strong> each case has a unified form,<br />

whose stylistic structure depends upon a balance (association) <strong>and</strong> at the same time<br />

tension (opposition) between the poles <strong>of</strong> its compos<strong>in</strong>g elements. Such a situation is<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itely puzzl<strong>in</strong>g to the modern viewer, but does not dim<strong>in</strong>ish the fact that the forms <strong>of</strong><br />

the Kerameikos animals are dist<strong>in</strong>ctly different, both visually <strong>and</strong> conceptually, from the<br />

non-unified forms <strong>of</strong> fantastic composite creatures (Mischwesen) like the Chimera.<br />

b. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Question <strong>of</strong> “What Is It Really Represented?”<br />

<strong>The</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> the identification <strong>of</strong> animals represented <strong>in</strong> Greek art is not new <strong>and</strong><br />

does not refer explicitly to works <strong>of</strong> sculpture. It encompasses representations <strong>in</strong> vase<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g too, while conf<strong>in</strong>ement to a specific chronological period is not the case. For<br />

example, Hurwit, comment<strong>in</strong>g on the depiction <strong>of</strong> an animal battl<strong>in</strong>g a human figure on a<br />

Late Geometric II (ca. 730 B.C.) ceramic st<strong>and</strong> from the Kerameikos (Fig. 13), writes:<br />

<strong>The</strong> beast is usually thought to be a lion, though few lions, I suspect, would be<br />

conv<strong>in</strong>ced <strong>of</strong> that. <strong>The</strong> creature has short bristles down its back <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> a<br />

shaggy mane <strong>and</strong> the legs it st<strong>and</strong>s on have ho<strong>of</strong>s <strong>and</strong> fetlocks <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> claws.<br />

This all makes for an odd lion. But <strong>of</strong> course it could be argued that the warrior is<br />

191 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> the griff<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art <strong>and</strong> narrative as <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the<br />

ancient discoveries <strong>of</strong> d<strong>in</strong>osaur bones, see A. Mayor, <strong>The</strong> First Fossil Hunters. Paleontology <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong><br />

Roman Times (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 2000) 38-53.<br />

126


just as odd a man <strong>and</strong> the beast does have a ferociously gap<strong>in</strong>g, toothy mouth—<br />

perhaps the qu<strong>in</strong>tessential leon<strong>in</strong>e feature—so it is probably a lion after all. 192<br />

As can be seen, the render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the animal on this st<strong>and</strong> is so miscellaneous <strong>and</strong> so<br />

variable <strong>in</strong> appearance as to <strong>of</strong>fer a scanty basis for its identification. Similarly, the style<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fel<strong>in</strong>e creature depicted <strong>in</strong> a relief scene on a late Archaic (ca. 520 B.C.) statue<br />

base found also <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos (Fig. 14), the so-called dog-<strong>and</strong>-cat-fight base,<br />

especially the pear-shaped head <strong>and</strong> hunched curve <strong>of</strong> the animal’s back have posed a<br />

similar problem regard<strong>in</strong>g its identification, which, <strong>in</strong> scholarly literature, has featured as<br />

a cat, a cat-like animal, <strong>and</strong> a marten. 193 Both are cases <strong>of</strong> nondescript animals. Both<br />

lack fully def<strong>in</strong>ed features which might prove diagnostic <strong>in</strong> the identification <strong>of</strong> these<br />

animals.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Lion from the Prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> the lion (Fig. 15) discussed below was discovered <strong>in</strong> 1863 <strong>in</strong> the<br />

fourth-century (345-317 B.C.) grave enclosure <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Athenian<br />

Kerameikos. 194 It is made <strong>of</strong> Pentelic marble <strong>and</strong> believed to be one <strong>of</strong> a pair that<br />

192<br />

Kerameikos Museum 407: J. M. Hurwit, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> Culture <strong>of</strong> Early <strong>Greece</strong>, 1100-480 B.C. (Ithaca<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1985) 113.<br />

193<br />

Athens, NM 3476. <strong>The</strong> scene depicted is that <strong>of</strong> four male figures <strong>and</strong> two animals identified as a dog<br />

<strong>and</strong> a cat, or cat-like animal, or a marten. Two <strong>of</strong> the human figures st<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> watch, while each <strong>of</strong> the<br />

other two holds the respective animals, which have been said to be fight<strong>in</strong>g, by a leash, thus, the scene is<br />

usually referred to as “the cat <strong>and</strong> dog fight.” <strong>The</strong> animal <strong>in</strong> question has been called a cat: A.<br />

Philadelpheus, “Three Statue-Bases Recently Discovered at Athens,” JHS 42 (1922) 104-105; N. E.<br />

Kaltsas, tr. D. Hardy, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the National Archaeological Museum, Athens (Los Angeles, 2002) 96,<br />

no. 95, a cat-like creature: Kosmopoulou, <strong>The</strong> Iconography <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>d Statue Bases, 169, whereas his<br />

identity as a marten has been discussed by S. S. Schipper, “Cat or Marten?” Archaeology 5 (1952) 25-29.<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> cats on <strong>Classical</strong> Greek pottery, see A. H. Ashmead, “Greek Cats.<br />

Exotic Pets Kept by Rich Youths <strong>in</strong> Fifth Century B.C. Athens, as Portrayed on Greek Vases,” Expedition<br />

20 (1978) 38-47; also by the same author “Etruscan Domesticated Cats: <strong>Classical</strong> Conformists or Etruscan<br />

Orig<strong>in</strong>als?” <strong>in</strong> R. D. De Puma <strong>and</strong> J. P. Small, eds., Murlo <strong>and</strong> the Etruscans: Art <strong>and</strong> Society <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

Etruria (Wiscons<strong>in</strong>, 1994) 144-164.<br />

194<br />

<strong>The</strong> grave prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos (A3) is the third <strong>of</strong> six prec<strong>in</strong>cts (A1-A6) l<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the south<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the Street <strong>of</strong> the Tombs on a hill <strong>in</strong> the southwestern corner <strong>of</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos. It is an<br />

127


adorned the west <strong>and</strong> east corners respectively <strong>of</strong> the front wall <strong>of</strong> the enclosure. 195 Its<br />

body (length 1.05 m; height 0.63m) appears <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ile to the left <strong>and</strong> its head turns<br />

slightly sideways. <strong>The</strong> animal st<strong>and</strong>s with its h<strong>in</strong>dquarters upright, its tail curl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

downward, <strong>and</strong> its forequarters crouched low as if ready to spr<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>and</strong> forward. <strong>The</strong><br />

area between its forelegs is occupied by what has been identified as the head <strong>of</strong> a heifer<br />

or a bull. 196 This head, along with the forelegs <strong>of</strong> the lion, rests on a surface—the<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al pl<strong>in</strong>th <strong>of</strong> the statue—that breaks <strong>of</strong>f abruptly at the height <strong>of</strong> the animal’s upper<br />

forelegs. <strong>The</strong> right forepaw <strong>of</strong> the lion turns <strong>in</strong>ward <strong>and</strong> its claws are sunken <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

head <strong>of</strong> the bov<strong>in</strong>e, whereas its left foreleg extends forward with its claws firmly on the<br />

pl<strong>in</strong>th. 197<br />

almost rectangular peribolos enclosed by walls on all four sides. Access to it is ga<strong>in</strong>ed (via A2) through a<br />

gap <strong>in</strong> the east wall. <strong>The</strong> width <strong>of</strong> the enclosure varies between 6.5m (on the east side) <strong>and</strong> 7m (on the west<br />

side). <strong>The</strong> length <strong>of</strong> the front wall is 11.6m; it was built <strong>of</strong> dressed limestone ashlar, which has been now<br />

destroyed. Visible today is only its fill with a modern cement overlay. For this <strong>in</strong>formation on the prec<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

<strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> its position with<strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos, see R. Garl<strong>and</strong>, “A First Catalogue <strong>of</strong> Attic<br />

Peribolos Tombs,” BSA 77 (1982) 138 <strong>and</strong> 137, fig. 2. <strong>The</strong> statue (Athens, NM 804) was found <strong>in</strong> 1863 <strong>in</strong><br />

the terrace <strong>of</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>and</strong> was st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g there until 1870, when it was moved to the National Museum <strong>in</strong><br />

Athens: A. Brückner, Der Friedh<strong>of</strong> am Eridanos (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1909) 79; he also adds that a part <strong>of</strong> the lion’s tail<br />

was discovered <strong>in</strong> 1870 <strong>in</strong> the area across from the monument <strong>of</strong> Dexileos, <strong>in</strong> the homonymous prec<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

(A1), which is situated at the corner <strong>of</strong> the Street <strong>of</strong> the Tombs. Brücker’s 1909 account <strong>of</strong> the statue is a<br />

synthesis <strong>of</strong> the 1863 <strong>and</strong> 1870 excavation reports by A. S. Rhousopoulos (AEphem [1863] 279, 295, 312,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Bull. dell’Inst [1864] 45) <strong>and</strong> S. Koumanoudes (∆ύο γενικές συνελεύσεις τϖν ταίρων τ ς ν<br />

θήναις ρχαιολογικ ς ταιρίας, 1870)—both cited as such <strong>in</strong> his discussion (2) <strong>of</strong> previous literature<br />

on the site. For a summary <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> the excavations before 1913, when the Kerameikos<br />

excavations were turned over to the German Archaeological Institute, <strong>and</strong> a brief reference to the work <strong>of</strong><br />

Rhousopoulos <strong>and</strong> Koumanoudes, see U. Knigge, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Kerameikos. History-Monuments-<br />

Excavations (Athens, 1991) 166; <strong>and</strong> 183-184 for a list <strong>of</strong> Greek excavations reports prior to 1913; also<br />

124, n. 114 for the most recent f<strong>in</strong>ds from the prec<strong>in</strong>ct—a marble sarcophagus, identified as that <strong>of</strong><br />

Dionysios, conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g an iron strigil <strong>and</strong> pottery, along with a burnt <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g deposit conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g large<br />

numbers <strong>of</strong> pottery (100 pieces) <strong>and</strong> bronze arrowheads (80). For a more detailed account <strong>of</strong> these f<strong>in</strong>ds,<br />

see R. H. W. Stichel, “Grabung im Bezirk des Dionysios von Kollytos,” AA 99 (1984) 56-61.<br />

195 <strong>The</strong> other statue <strong>of</strong> a lion (Athens, NM 803) was discovered <strong>in</strong> 1870 <strong>in</strong> the vic<strong>in</strong>ity <strong>of</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct. S.<br />

Karouzou, National Archaeological Museum. Collection <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>. A Catalogue (Athens, 1968) 126,<br />

mentions that both statues were “found <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos <strong>in</strong> 1870.” Kaltsas, <strong>Sculpture</strong> 205, cat. no 411,<br />

identifies Kerameikos as the f<strong>in</strong>d spot <strong>of</strong> the statues, but clarifies that one (NM 803) was found <strong>in</strong> 1870,<br />

whereas the other (NM 804) <strong>in</strong> 1863.<br />

196 Heifer: Brückner, Der Friedh<strong>of</strong> am Eridanos 79; bull: Kaltsas, <strong>Sculpture</strong> 205.<br />

197 In old photographs (Brückner, Der Friedh<strong>of</strong> am Eridanos 80, fig. 47; M. Collignon, Les statues<br />

funéraires dans l’art grec [Paris, 1911] 228, fig. 148) <strong>and</strong> recent reproductions <strong>of</strong> them (Todisco, Scultura<br />

greca del IV secolo fig. 178), the lower h<strong>in</strong>d legs <strong>of</strong> the lion are miss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> modern supports st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> their<br />

128


<strong>The</strong> Motif <strong>of</strong> the Lion Hold<strong>in</strong>g the Head <strong>of</strong> Its Prey <strong>in</strong> Fourth-Century Attic<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Homer<br />

Today, the image <strong>of</strong> a lion hold<strong>in</strong>g the head <strong>of</strong> its victim <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g its claws <strong>in</strong>to<br />

it is an <strong>in</strong>dispensable part <strong>of</strong> studies that aim at document<strong>in</strong>g the life <strong>and</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong><br />

lions. 198 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the use <strong>of</strong> this motif <strong>in</strong> fourth-century Attic sculpture, Vermeule<br />

states that it was popular, <strong>and</strong> places its orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> East <strong>Greece</strong>:<br />

In one feature that comes popular <strong>in</strong> Attica around 325 B.C. <strong>and</strong> widespread <strong>in</strong><br />

Hellenistic <strong>and</strong> Roman times, sculptors <strong>in</strong> southwest Asia M<strong>in</strong>or seem to have<br />

pioneered. This is the motif <strong>of</strong> plac<strong>in</strong>g an animal’s head, a bull or deer, beneath<br />

the lions’ forepaws. Hellenistic art took this motive <strong>and</strong> elaborated on its<br />

opportunities <strong>of</strong> ferocious naturalism. 199<br />

Vermeule does not furnish his statement with specific examples <strong>of</strong> sculpture. 200 <strong>The</strong> act<br />

<strong>of</strong> a lion attack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> kill<strong>in</strong>g its prey, be<strong>in</strong>g cattle, sheep, goats or deer, is described<br />

several times <strong>in</strong> the Iliad <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> similes, which compare it to the act <strong>of</strong> human<br />

warriors attack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> kill<strong>in</strong>g their opponents. 201 In one <strong>of</strong> them, for example, the sight<br />

<strong>of</strong> a lion guard<strong>in</strong>g or be<strong>in</strong>g ready to fight over the carcass <strong>of</strong> a heifer features as part <strong>of</strong><br />

the wider comparison <strong>of</strong> Hector attack<strong>in</strong>g the Achaeans to a lion attack<strong>in</strong>g cattle:<br />

place; also the entire statue rests on a modern pl<strong>in</strong>th. <strong>The</strong> later is still present <strong>in</strong> a more recent photograph<br />

(Kaltsas, <strong>Sculpture</strong> 205 fig. 411 (804)) <strong>in</strong> which the legs <strong>of</strong> the lion appear restored. This <strong>in</strong>formation is<br />

also <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the accompany<strong>in</strong>g commentary on the statue which announces that “the h<strong>in</strong>d legs <strong>and</strong><br />

pl<strong>in</strong>th are restored.”<br />

198 See, for example, the illustration <strong>of</strong> a lion s<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g its claws <strong>in</strong>to the head <strong>of</strong> a zebra <strong>in</strong> D. Joubert <strong>and</strong> B.<br />

Joubert, <strong>The</strong> Lions <strong>of</strong> Savuti. Hunt<strong>in</strong>g with the Moon (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C., 1997) 80.<br />

199 Vermeule, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 52<br />

200 For an example <strong>of</strong> such a statue <strong>of</strong> a lion, seated though, but hold<strong>in</strong>g the head <strong>of</strong> a bull <strong>in</strong> his forepaws,<br />

see Rhodes Museum 211, which Vermeule, “<strong>The</strong> Basel Dog” 101 dates to 300 B.C., whereas F. Willemsen,<br />

Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier vom Dach des Zeustempels (OlForsch 5, Berl<strong>in</strong> 1959) 131, pl. 65, to the third<br />

century B.C.<br />

201 For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> the lion similes <strong>in</strong> the Iliad <strong>and</strong> their connection to warriors’ behavior, see S.<br />

H. Lonsdale, Creatures <strong>of</strong> Speech. Lion, Herd<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g Similes <strong>in</strong> the Iliad (Stuttgart, 1990) 38-47;<br />

<strong>and</strong> appendix D for a list <strong>of</strong> all lion similes <strong>in</strong> the poem. Lonsdale ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s (27) that the relationship<br />

between victor <strong>and</strong> victim <strong>in</strong> the war epic dictates a pair <strong>of</strong> species that are natural enemies on l<strong>and</strong>, such as<br />

lion <strong>and</strong> cattle. He also remarks (40) that these similes place emphasis on the emotional <strong>and</strong> mental stages<br />

shared by the beast <strong>and</strong> man. <strong>The</strong> comparison <strong>of</strong> lions to warriors is a feature <strong>of</strong> speech still prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong><br />

modern accounts <strong>of</strong> lions. In their description, for example, <strong>of</strong> the nocturnal behavior <strong>of</strong> lions <strong>in</strong> the area <strong>of</strong><br />

Savuti, <strong>in</strong> Botswana, Joubert <strong>and</strong> Jourbet, <strong>The</strong> Lions <strong>of</strong> Savuti 68 say: “<strong>in</strong> the dull light <strong>of</strong> the males walk<strong>in</strong>g<br />

side by side was awesome, spark<strong>in</strong>g comparisons to warriors or gallant knights: the most regal <strong>of</strong> animals,<br />

march<strong>in</strong>g shoulder to shoulder, ready to take on whatever the night could <strong>of</strong>fer.”<br />

129


But he [Hector] fell on them [Achaeans] like a lion <strong>of</strong> destructive m<strong>in</strong>d<br />

com<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st cattle that are graz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the bottom <strong>of</strong> a great marsh, <strong>and</strong> there is<br />

no count<strong>in</strong>g them, <strong>and</strong> among them is a herdsman who is yet unskilled to fight<br />

with a wild beast over the carcass <strong>of</strong> a sleek heifer that has been sla<strong>in</strong>: he paces<br />

ever by their side, now abreast <strong>of</strong> the foremost <strong>of</strong> the cattle, <strong>and</strong> now <strong>of</strong> the<br />

h<strong>in</strong>dmost, but the lion leaps on the midmost, <strong>and</strong> devours a heifer, <strong>and</strong> at that they<br />

all flee <strong>in</strong> terror; so wondrously were the Achaeans one <strong>and</strong> all then driven <strong>in</strong> rout<br />

by Hector <strong>and</strong> father Zeus. (Il. 15.630-15.637) [125]<br />

<strong>The</strong> unwill<strong>in</strong>gness <strong>of</strong> a lion to release its kill is also encountered <strong>in</strong> another simile<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Iliad, where the scene <strong>of</strong> Patroclus <strong>and</strong> Hector fight<strong>in</strong>g over the corpse <strong>of</strong><br />

Cebriones, the driver <strong>of</strong> Hector’s chariot, is compared to two lions compet<strong>in</strong>g over a sla<strong>in</strong><br />

h<strong>in</strong>d:<br />

So the two jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> strife for Cebriones like two lions that on the peaks <strong>of</strong> a<br />

mounta<strong>in</strong> fight for a sla<strong>in</strong> h<strong>in</strong>d, both <strong>of</strong> them hunger<strong>in</strong>g, both high <strong>of</strong> heart; so<br />

for Cebriones the two masters <strong>of</strong> the war cry, Patroclus, son <strong>of</strong> Menoetius, <strong>and</strong><br />

glorious Hector, were eager each to cleave the other’s flesh with the pitiless<br />

bronze. Hector, when once he has seized the corpse by the head, would not<br />

loose his hold, <strong>and</strong> Patroclus on the other side held fast hold <strong>of</strong> the foot.<br />

(Il. 16.756-763) [126]<br />

<strong>The</strong> representation <strong>of</strong> Hector <strong>and</strong> Patroclus fight<strong>in</strong>g over Cebriones’ corpse like lions<br />

over prey suggests direct borrow<strong>in</strong>g from leon<strong>in</strong>e behavior, <strong>and</strong> therefore, first-h<strong>and</strong><br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> it. 202 Indeed, such evidence accords well with modern observations <strong>of</strong><br />

lions, which note that competition among these animals over the kill or guard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> it is a<br />

pronounced trait <strong>of</strong> their behavior. 203 Given the overall reliance <strong>of</strong> the simile on leon<strong>in</strong>e<br />

202 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the animal similes <strong>in</strong> the Iliad conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g accurate descriptions <strong>of</strong> animal behavior,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the suggestion that Homeric audiences preferred “naturalistic descriptions <strong>of</strong> animals,” see Lonsdale,<br />

Creatures <strong>of</strong> Speech 12-13; also 53, n. 3, where he cites H. W. Auden’s (“Natural History <strong>in</strong> Homer,” CR<br />

10 (1896) 107) observation that Homer’s description <strong>of</strong> lions seiz<strong>in</strong>g their victims by the muzzle (Il. 5.161;<br />

11.174) is <strong>in</strong>deed an accurate one s<strong>in</strong>ce it parallels contemporary accounts <strong>of</strong> similar lion behavior.<br />

203 In Joubert <strong>and</strong> Joubert, <strong>The</strong> Lions <strong>of</strong> Savuti 71, the caption, for example, <strong>of</strong> a photograph <strong>of</strong> two<br />

lionesses fight<strong>in</strong>g over a carcass reads: “the transition from friendly cooperation dur<strong>in</strong>g hunt to ferocious<br />

competition once the kill has been made is an unforgettable, Jekyll <strong>and</strong> Hyde characteristic <strong>of</strong> lion<br />

behavior.” Also, G. B. Schaller, <strong>The</strong> Serengeti Lion. A Study <strong>of</strong> Predator-Prey Relations (Chicago <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1972) 267, states that lions <strong>of</strong>ten transport small prey after kill<strong>in</strong>g it because they want “to escape<br />

from another lion <strong>in</strong>tent on a share….as if afraid <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g deprived <strong>of</strong> a meal.” Schaller (267) also provides<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g account <strong>of</strong> a lion’s safeguard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the kill: “six nomads, two <strong>of</strong> them males, rest at 1635 near<br />

Naabi Hill when a sick wildebeest stumbles by. One lioness pulls it down, <strong>and</strong> while she suffocates it a<br />

130


ehavior, the description <strong>of</strong> Hector seiz<strong>in</strong>g Cebriones’ corpse by the head <strong>and</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g it<br />

strong appears to be direct reproduction <strong>of</strong> such behavior. It thus br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d the statue <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion, which cradles the head <strong>of</strong> its prey, <strong>and</strong> may<br />

suggest that its conception as an image was perhaps a conscious, fourth-century Greek<br />

attempt to recreate visually or “connect with” the heroic past as recorded by Homer. 204<br />

Anatomy <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos Lion<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g this possible connection, the <strong>in</strong>consistent style <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Kerameikos lion is an aspect that has not escaped scholarly attention. Willemsen, for<br />

example, po<strong>in</strong>ts out that its musculature <strong>and</strong> facial expression are naturalistic, whereas<br />

the absence <strong>of</strong> a neck, lower back, backbone, <strong>and</strong> undevelopedness <strong>of</strong> its legs (die<br />

Unentwickeltheit der Biene) st<strong>and</strong> out as its non-naturalistic features, <strong>and</strong> also as<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> unskilled craftsmanship. 205 To these features, one can add, Willemsen says,<br />

those <strong>of</strong> motionlessness <strong>and</strong> compactness, which strengthen the impression <strong>of</strong> a poorly<br />

male beg<strong>in</strong>s to feed at the gro<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> animal dies after 4 m<strong>in</strong>utes <strong>and</strong> the male eats alone, the others<br />

wait<strong>in</strong>g until he f<strong>in</strong>ishes at 1710. After than the lionesses feed, but 15 m<strong>in</strong>utes later the male suddenly<br />

chases them from the carcass <strong>and</strong> guards it until 1840 when he permits the others to jo<strong>in</strong> him.”<br />

Additionally, he notes (267-268) that, <strong>in</strong> cases where the prey is large <strong>in</strong> size such as adult zebras, lions,<br />

usually two, drag the carcass to a location <strong>and</strong> then feed on it. This report recalls Homer’s description <strong>of</strong><br />

the behavior <strong>of</strong> two lions adorn<strong>in</strong>g the shield <strong>of</strong> Achilles: “But two terrible lions were hold<strong>in</strong>g a loudlow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

bull, <strong>and</strong> he, bellow<strong>in</strong>g mightily, was be<strong>in</strong>g dragged by them, while after him pursued the dogs <strong>and</strong><br />

young men. <strong>The</strong> lions had torn the hide <strong>of</strong> the great bull, <strong>and</strong> were devour<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>ner parts <strong>and</strong> the black<br />

blood” (Homer, Il. 18.579-18.581; translation: A. T. Murray, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad II [Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1999] 331).<br />

204 For a recent discussion <strong>of</strong> how the Greeks “visualized <strong>and</strong> re-created their past, especially the remote<br />

past, <strong>in</strong> images <strong>and</strong> objects,” see J. Boardman, <strong>The</strong> Archaeology <strong>of</strong> Nostalgia. How the Greeks Re-Created<br />

their Mythical Past (London, 2002) 7, <strong>and</strong> also 114 for “special properties attributed to some creatures as a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> their encounter with the heroic past,” for example, the pseudo-Aristotelian account (De<br />

Mirabilibus 70) that frogs are quieter <strong>in</strong> Seriphos because once they had annoyed Heracles.<br />

205 Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier 54.<br />

131


executed figure. 206 In contrast to Willemsen’s comment about motionlessness, the<br />

Kerameikos lion looks as if it is spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>The</strong> statue <strong>in</strong>dicates that the sculptor gave thoughtful consideration to leon<strong>in</strong>e<br />

anatomy. Powerful muscles show, for <strong>in</strong>stance, through the sk<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the areas <strong>of</strong> the thigh,<br />

shoulder, <strong>and</strong> forelegs; an equally powerful ve<strong>in</strong> runs alongside the abdomen, while<br />

another one marks the left foreleg; also, the last two ribs <strong>of</strong> the ribcage are made visible<br />

on the animal’s side; the shoulder is clearly pronounced, <strong>and</strong> the legs, despite<br />

Willemsen’s remark that they are not fully developed, stretch powerfully <strong>and</strong> firmly, thus<br />

emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g the animal’s position on the pl<strong>in</strong>th. Overall, the impression ga<strong>in</strong>ed is one <strong>of</strong><br />

a lean <strong>and</strong> strong animal. <strong>The</strong> attention paid to these qualities accords well with the<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy <strong>in</strong> the pseudo-Aristotelian treatise Physiognomics, which<br />

emphasizes that “the animal has lean haunches <strong>and</strong> thighs; his legs are strong <strong>and</strong><br />

muscular, his walk is vigorous, <strong>and</strong> his whole body is well-jo<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>and</strong> muscular, neither<br />

hard, not very moist” (809b) [173]. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it is reasonable to suggest<br />

that the sculptor <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion was familiar with established knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy <strong>and</strong> followed it closely <strong>in</strong> his render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the statue. Of great <strong>in</strong>terest<br />

here is the fact that the ancient literary context from which this evidence derives is the<br />

Physiognomics—a treatise on determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g character or personal characteristics from the<br />

form or features <strong>of</strong> the body, whether human or animal, falsely attributed to Aristotle,<br />

thus commonly recognized as spurious <strong>and</strong> thought to date from the third-century B.C. 207<br />

206 Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier 54.<br />

207 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics as a treatise frequently <strong>in</strong>cluded among the works <strong>of</strong> Aristotle,<br />

but considered spurious, see M. C. Nussbaum, “Aristotle,” <strong>in</strong> Hornblower <strong>and</strong> Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary 166; also W. S. Hett, ed., tr., Aristotle. M<strong>in</strong>or Works (Cambridge, Mass., <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1936; repr. 2000) 83. Also, with respect to the date <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics, M. M. Sassi, “physiognomy,” <strong>in</strong><br />

Hornblower <strong>and</strong> Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford <strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary 1181, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the treatise has<br />

long been attributed to Aristotle, but is actually “a Peripatetic work <strong>of</strong> the third century B.C.” For the same<br />

132


Despite its unclear authorship <strong>and</strong> post-fourth-century date, the Physiognomics is a clear<br />

example <strong>of</strong> how pervasive physiognomic ideas were <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek culture. 208 In fact,<br />

the author <strong>of</strong> the treatise considers the lion to be the equivalent <strong>of</strong> the perfect human male<br />

(<strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> both appearance <strong>and</strong> character) <strong>in</strong> the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. That certa<strong>in</strong><br />

accentuated bodily features <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion, such as its shoulder, hair, <strong>and</strong> face,<br />

also feature <strong>in</strong> this treatise as clues to leon<strong>in</strong>e character, suggests one specific th<strong>in</strong>g: that<br />

the sculptor <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion was concerned with convey<strong>in</strong>g not only a view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

outward appearance <strong>of</strong> his animal subject; its character, an <strong>in</strong>tangible notion, was also<br />

part <strong>of</strong> his agenda. Such an idea fits well, for example, with the mentioned previously<br />

statement <strong>of</strong> Cleiton, the sculptor <strong>in</strong> Xenophon’s Memorabilia, that a good artist is one,<br />

who can convey successfully both the bodily form <strong>and</strong> character <strong>of</strong> his representational<br />

subject [193].<br />

Evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g either the identity or class <strong>of</strong> the sculptor <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos<br />

lion does not survive, but his decision to communicate exist<strong>in</strong>g beliefs about the animal’s<br />

character through its anatomy can be seen elsewhere <strong>in</strong> his statue. As already noted, the<br />

shoulder <strong>of</strong> the lion is clearly pronounced. In fact, it is the bodily part that marks the<br />

passage from the front to the back <strong>of</strong> its body. In his description <strong>of</strong> the lion, the author <strong>of</strong><br />

the Physiognomics po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the animal has a well-jo<strong>in</strong>ted body (809b) [173], thus<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation, as well as a discussion <strong>of</strong> the pervasiveness <strong>of</strong> physiognomic ideas <strong>in</strong> antiquity, see E. C.<br />

Evans, “Physiognomics <strong>in</strong> the Ancient World,” TAPA 59.5 (1969) 1-101. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

application <strong>of</strong> the ancient discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> physiognomy to art, see M. Amberger-Lahrmann, Anatomie und<br />

Physiognomie <strong>in</strong> der hellenistischen Plastik: Dargestellt am Pergamonaltar (Stuttgart, 1996).<br />

208 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the pervasiveness <strong>of</strong> physiognomic th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek <strong>and</strong> also Roman<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> its draw<strong>in</strong>g from analogies with the animal world, see R. Garl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>The</strong> Eye <strong>of</strong> the Beholder.<br />

Deformity <strong>and</strong> Disability <strong>in</strong> the Graeco-Roman World ((Ithaca, 1995) 87-90; also Gilhus, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Gods<br />

<strong>and</strong> Humans 74-76; <strong>and</strong> T. S. Barton, Power <strong>and</strong> Knowledge. Astrology, Physiognomics, <strong>and</strong> Medic<strong>in</strong>e<br />

under the Roman Empire (Ann Arbor, 1994; repr. 1997) 95-131, esp. 101 for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the idea that<br />

“Hippocrates was credited with found<strong>in</strong>g the discipl<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> the first appearances <strong>of</strong> the verb<br />

φυσιογνοµον ω (physiognomize) are <strong>in</strong> the Hippocratic Epidemics.”<br />

133


shoulders, a characteristic which, later on, <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the male character, both<br />

human <strong>and</strong> animal, he considers a mark <strong>of</strong> strong disposition. As he says: “those whose<br />

shoulders <strong>and</strong> shoulder-blades are well articulated have strong characters; witness the<br />

male” (810b) [176]. On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it is reasonable to suggest that the<br />

pronounced shoulder <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion is the sculptor’s attempt to convey<br />

accurately how such an anatomical detail was viewed or was known to exist, <strong>and</strong> what it<br />

was thought to reveal about the character <strong>of</strong> the animal. In other words, style emerges<br />

here as the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> a visual <strong>and</strong> a mental process.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the hair <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion, Willemsen notes its peculiar thickness<br />

<strong>and</strong> stiffness. 209 His characterizations are correct, but his view <strong>of</strong> them as peculiar does<br />

not even agree with modern discussions <strong>of</strong> the lion, which note both the stiffness <strong>and</strong><br />

thickness <strong>of</strong> the animal’s hair. In the Kerameikos lion, the mane is composed by thick<br />

locks <strong>of</strong> hair that are flame-like <strong>and</strong> curly <strong>in</strong> appearance; they cover its head, are quite<br />

curly around its face, <strong>and</strong> hide completely its neck, while extend<strong>in</strong>g down its chest, <strong>and</strong><br />

over its back. Patches <strong>of</strong> hair also appear on its flank, abdomen, <strong>and</strong> under its foreleg.<br />

As a whole, the hair <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion sticks firmly out <strong>and</strong> away from its sk<strong>in</strong>, thus<br />

appear<strong>in</strong>g stiff <strong>and</strong> unmov<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Such a treatment, however, is consistent with the physiognomic idea that<br />

considered the appearance <strong>of</strong> a lion’s hair an important clue to five specific aspects <strong>of</strong> its<br />

character: bravery, shamelessness, generosity, courage, <strong>and</strong> a sense <strong>of</strong> freedom. In regard<br />

to the lion’s stiff hair, the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics, for example, says:<br />

S<strong>of</strong>t hair shows timidity <strong>and</strong> stiff hair courage. This is based on observation <strong>of</strong> all<br />

the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. For the deer the hare <strong>and</strong> sheep are the most timid <strong>of</strong> all<br />

209 Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier 54.<br />

134


animals <strong>and</strong> have the s<strong>of</strong>test hair; the lion <strong>and</strong> wild boar are the bravest <strong>and</strong> have<br />

very stiff hair. (Phgn. 806b) [167]<br />

It is also <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to see that the author <strong>of</strong> the treatise considers stiff hair a<br />

characteristic <strong>of</strong> the brave man <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>t hair <strong>of</strong> the coward. 210 Such evidence matches his<br />

belief that the lion is among animals what a male is among humans. His view <strong>of</strong> stiff hair<br />

as a bodily sign <strong>of</strong> bravery fits well with the stiffness <strong>of</strong> the hair <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion;<br />

it suggests that a trait that has been considered stylistic was <strong>in</strong>stead iconographic, <strong>and</strong><br />

was determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a specific view <strong>of</strong> a leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomical feature, <strong>and</strong> also by what this<br />

feature was thought to reveal about the character <strong>of</strong> the animal. Similarly, that the statue<br />

has its mane extend<strong>in</strong>g down the back, <strong>and</strong> that it seems to lack a neck, as asserted by<br />

Willemsen—or more accurately, that its neck is <strong>in</strong>visible because it is completely<br />

covered with stiff, curly hair that also extends around its face—are all specific aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

a lion’s hair that were thought to st<strong>and</strong> for the animal’s shamelessness, generosity, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

general sense <strong>of</strong> freedom. As the Physiognomics states:<br />

Those with a hairy back are excessively shameless; witness the wild beasts.<br />

Those whose neck is hairy beh<strong>in</strong>d are generous; witness the lions.<br />

(Phgn. 812b) [180]<br />

Hair which curls at the ends tends towards stout-heartedness; witness the lion<br />

among others. Those <strong>in</strong> whom the hair on the face near the head curls backwards<br />

are liberal; witness the lions. (Phgn. 812b) [181]<br />

On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it appears that the characteristics <strong>of</strong> stiff, curly hair that<br />

characterize the style <strong>in</strong> which the Kerameikos lion was executed were themselves<br />

closely l<strong>in</strong>ked to the way the animal was viewed <strong>and</strong> also thought to be <strong>in</strong> real life. Such<br />

evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, shows that style <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture is shaped by both<br />

vision <strong>and</strong> thought.<br />

210 Aristotle, Physiognomics 807a <strong>and</strong> 807b respectively.<br />

135


Further evidence <strong>in</strong> support <strong>of</strong> this <strong>in</strong>terpretation comes from the facial expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion, which Willemsen, as noted above, considers a naturalistic<br />

element <strong>of</strong> its style. More specifically, he says that the eagerness <strong>of</strong> the facial expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue does not compensate for its overall stiff <strong>and</strong>, thus, non-naturalistic<br />

appearance. 211 A look at the face <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion <strong>in</strong>dicates that its forehead is<br />

broad, triangular <strong>in</strong> shape, <strong>and</strong> marked by a deep depression that separates its forehead <strong>in</strong><br />

two halves as it runs between its eyes <strong>and</strong> all the way down to its partially preserved<br />

nose. 212 <strong>The</strong> eyes are deep set especially at the <strong>in</strong>ner corners, thus rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong><br />

“Skopasian style” <strong>and</strong> marked by slant<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> overhang<strong>in</strong>g brows, which, to judge from<br />

the visible left side <strong>of</strong> the statue’s face, run down the sides <strong>of</strong> the eyes. 213 Its mouth is<br />

large <strong>and</strong> partially open with its jaws separated from each other, th<strong>in</strong> (almost <strong>in</strong>visible)<br />

lips, <strong>and</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ent teeth (both regular <strong>and</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e), all <strong>of</strong> which give the impression that<br />

the animal growls. <strong>The</strong> author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics does not explicitly refer to the<br />

growl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lion, but he does discuss its deep voice, which he <strong>in</strong>terprets as a sign <strong>of</strong><br />

bravery. As he says: “the brave animals have deep voices, <strong>and</strong> the cowardly high-pitched<br />

voices, the lion <strong>and</strong> the bull, the bark<strong>in</strong>g dog, <strong>and</strong> the brave cocks are all deep-voiced”<br />

(807a) [168]. 214 Further, he provides a description <strong>of</strong> the face <strong>of</strong> the lion, which, when<br />

compared to that <strong>of</strong> the lion from the Kerameikos, appears to share common elements<br />

211 Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier 54.<br />

212 <strong>The</strong> triangular shape <strong>of</strong> the lion’s forehead seems to follow the st<strong>and</strong>ard fourth-century shape <strong>of</strong><br />

forehead for humans <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this sculptural trait as fourth-century <strong>in</strong> date,<br />

see Ridgway, Fourth-Century Styles 100.<br />

213 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> “the deep sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the eyes at the <strong>in</strong>ner corner” as a trait <strong>of</strong> the “Skopasian style” <strong>in</strong><br />

fourth-century sculptural representations <strong>of</strong> the human form, see B. S. Ridgway, Hellenistic <strong>Sculpture</strong> I:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Styles <strong>of</strong> ca. 331-200 B.C. (Madison, 1990) 14; also for slant<strong>in</strong>g eyebrows as another fourth-century<br />

facial feature <strong>of</strong> human representations <strong>in</strong> Greek sculpture, which along with the deeply set eyes, conveys<br />

an impression <strong>of</strong> pathos, see her discussion <strong>in</strong> Fourth-Century Styles 17.<br />

214 Also: “<strong>in</strong> the matter <strong>of</strong> voice the deep <strong>and</strong> full voice denotes courage, when high <strong>and</strong> slack it means<br />

cowardice” (Aristotle, Phgn. 806b); translation: Hett, Aristotle. M<strong>in</strong>or Works 95.<br />

136


with it. He provides this description as part <strong>of</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the lion as the ideal male<br />

type <strong>of</strong> the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom:<br />

<strong>The</strong> lion <strong>of</strong> all animals seems to have the most perfect share <strong>of</strong> the male type. Its<br />

mouth is very large, its face is square, not too bony, the upper jaw not<br />

overhang<strong>in</strong>g but equally balanced with the lower jaw, a muzzle rather thick than<br />

f<strong>in</strong>e, bright deep-set eyes, neither very round nor very narrow, <strong>of</strong> moderate size, a<br />

large eyebrow, square forehead, rather hollow from the centre, overhang<strong>in</strong>g<br />

towards the brow <strong>and</strong> nostril below the forehead like a cloud. Above on the<br />

forehead towards the muzzle hair slopp<strong>in</strong>g outwards <strong>and</strong> like bristles, a head <strong>of</strong><br />

moderate size, a long neck, with correspond<strong>in</strong>g thickness, covered with tawny<br />

hairs, neither very bristl<strong>in</strong>g nor too much turned back. (Phgn. 809b) [172]<br />

In this case, he describes certa<strong>in</strong> facial features <strong>of</strong> the lion such as its large mouth, deep-<br />

set eyes, forehead hollow <strong>in</strong> the center <strong>and</strong> overhang<strong>in</strong>g toward the brow, <strong>and</strong> bristl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

hair, all <strong>of</strong> which have their counterparts, as already seen, <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos<br />

lion. He does not expla<strong>in</strong> here what these facial features may reveal about the character<br />

<strong>of</strong> the animal, but <strong>in</strong> three other passages he <strong>in</strong>terprets some <strong>of</strong> them, such as its th<strong>in</strong> lips,<br />

deep-set eyes, <strong>and</strong> overhang<strong>in</strong>g brow as signs <strong>of</strong> its magnanimous <strong>and</strong> overbold<br />

character:<br />

Those who have th<strong>in</strong> lips <strong>and</strong> slack parts at the jo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lips, so that the<br />

upper lip overhangs the lower at the jo<strong>in</strong>, are magnanimous; witness the lions.<br />

(Phgn. 811a) [177]<br />

Those whose eyes are slightly hollow are magnanimous; witness lions.<br />

(Phgn. 811b) [178]<br />

Those with an overhang<strong>in</strong>g brow are overbold; witness the bull <strong>and</strong> the lion.<br />

(Phgn. 811b) [179]<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that these facial features are also present <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos lion suggests that its<br />

render<strong>in</strong>g was already tied to the ancient Greek view <strong>of</strong> the animal as a magnanimous <strong>and</strong><br />

bold creature. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests that the style <strong>of</strong> the statue was determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

not only by how certa<strong>in</strong> anatomical features <strong>of</strong> the lion were perceived visually, but also<br />

137


y what these features were thought to mean it terms <strong>of</strong> its character—an essentially<br />

abstract aspect <strong>of</strong> the animal. It is clear, therefore, that the style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion is<br />

based on a blend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how ancient Greek society saw the lion <strong>and</strong> what it thought about<br />

it.<br />

Further, Willemsen notes that the lion from the Kerameikos lacks a lower back<br />

<strong>and</strong> a backbone, <strong>and</strong> has also his legs undeveloped, characteristics, which, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

him, contribute to the non-naturalistic appearance <strong>of</strong> the statue. 215 <strong>The</strong> author <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Physiognomics states, however, that “those [animals] that are small <strong>in</strong> the waist are<br />

hunters: witness lions <strong>and</strong> dogs” (810b) [174]. Such an ancient Greek view <strong>of</strong> the lion<br />

hav<strong>in</strong>g a small waist may help expla<strong>in</strong> why the Kerameikos lion lacks a lower back, a<br />

feature that would make the statue quite naturalistic <strong>in</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> ancient viewers.<br />

Further, the fact that the statue does not have a visible backbone may be directly related<br />

to the statement <strong>of</strong> Plato <strong>in</strong> the Critias mentioned above, that viewers were tolerant <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>accuracies <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art that depicted non-human subjects, without, however,<br />

dismiss<strong>in</strong>g them as unsuccessful representations [143]. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the legs <strong>of</strong> the statue<br />

have been noted earlier for the overall impression <strong>of</strong> power they convey. That the author<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics speaks <strong>of</strong> powerful extremities <strong>in</strong> humans as a sign <strong>of</strong> bravery<br />

(Phgn. 807a) [169] may be <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> the sculptor’s underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tention to show the<br />

character <strong>of</strong> this animal. Such an application <strong>of</strong> a human characteristic to an animal is<br />

not, however, peculiar, s<strong>in</strong>ce the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics makes extensive use—<br />

throughout the entire treatise—<strong>of</strong> human bodily signs drawn from the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. 216<br />

215 Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier 54.<br />

216 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the presence <strong>of</strong> stiff w<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> birds, for example, the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics (806b) says<br />

that this is a sign <strong>of</strong> bravery, whereas those with s<strong>of</strong>t ones are cowardly. Exactly the same th<strong>in</strong>g occurs, he<br />

says, with races <strong>of</strong> men; thus those liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the north are brave <strong>and</strong> stiff-haired <strong>and</strong> those <strong>in</strong> the south are<br />

138


Further, Willemsen’s observation that the legs <strong>of</strong> the lion are not fully developed may not<br />

be completely divorced from another physiognomic idea that the legs <strong>and</strong> feet <strong>of</strong> both<br />

humans <strong>and</strong> animals are last <strong>in</strong> a list <strong>of</strong> the most important bodily parts <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner<br />

character. As stated <strong>in</strong> the conclusion to the Physiognomics:<br />

<strong>The</strong> most favorable part for exam<strong>in</strong>ation is the region round the eyes, forehead,<br />

head <strong>and</strong> face; secondly, the region <strong>of</strong> the breast <strong>and</strong> shoulders, <strong>and</strong> lastly that <strong>of</strong><br />

the legs <strong>and</strong> feet; the parts about the belly are <strong>of</strong> least importance. Generally<br />

speak<strong>in</strong>g, these regions supply the clearest signs, <strong>in</strong> which there is greatest<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence. (Phgn. 814b) [183]<br />

<strong>The</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>consistent elements <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos lion<br />

suggests that these elements are direct reflections <strong>of</strong> how the animal was viewed <strong>and</strong><br />

thought to be <strong>in</strong> both appearance <strong>and</strong> character, <strong>of</strong> a general attitude toward<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> non-human animals <strong>in</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>of</strong> an idea that placed particular<br />

emphasis on anatomical features considered especially tell<strong>in</strong>g, thus important for<br />

convey<strong>in</strong>g personal characteristics <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests the<br />

crucial role <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g that the coexistence <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-<br />

naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art was not a phenomenon <strong>of</strong> which<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek society disapproved, but rather one directly shaped by its conceptual<br />

categories.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Dog from the Prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos<br />

Made <strong>of</strong> Hymettian marble <strong>and</strong> found <strong>in</strong> 1863 <strong>in</strong> the funerary prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong><br />

Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos, the so-called hound <strong>of</strong><br />

Kerameikos (Fig. 1), recl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>and</strong> faces right; as with the lion <strong>in</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios<br />

cowardly <strong>and</strong> have s<strong>of</strong>t hair. Also <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> toes <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs (Phgn. 810a), he says that those<br />

humans, whose toes are curved are shameless, just like birds that have curved talons.<br />

139


<strong>of</strong> Kollytos, this statue is thought to have been one <strong>of</strong> a pair (the other now lost) that<br />

decorated the front corners <strong>of</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong> which it was found. 217 <strong>The</strong> statue, whose<br />

body (length: 1.78m; height 0.90m) rests on a pl<strong>in</strong>th, has been dated to the last three<br />

decades <strong>of</strong> the fourth century B.C. (ca. 320 B.C.), 218 <strong>and</strong> its identification as a hound <strong>of</strong><br />

the ancient Molossian breed (that referred to excellent guard dogs <strong>and</strong> is discussed <strong>in</strong><br />

detail <strong>in</strong> chapter three) has been proposed as early as 1909 by Otto Keller. 219 Hans<br />

Riemann has remarked that the statue is constantly talked about as a dog, although it<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>es a leon<strong>in</strong>e body <strong>and</strong> the head <strong>of</strong> a dog. 220 Kawami admits that “the Kerameikos<br />

hound is lion-like.” 221 In fact, she identifies, as mentioned earlier, its “heavy compact<br />

chest, well-sprung almost barrel-like rib cage, <strong>and</strong> the carefully modeled toes with<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ent claws as those <strong>of</strong> a lion,” whereas she considers its heavy shoulders, thick<br />

legs, <strong>and</strong> large paws to be those <strong>of</strong> a dog. 222 Although Kawami’s observations are not<br />

without merit, the impression that one ga<strong>in</strong>s by look<strong>in</strong>g at the statue is very much <strong>in</strong><br />

agreement with Rienmann’s op<strong>in</strong>ion that it has the body <strong>of</strong> a lion <strong>and</strong> the head <strong>of</strong> a dog.<br />

217<br />

Kerameikos Museum P 670. <strong>The</strong> grave prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai (A4) is the fourth <strong>of</strong> six<br />

prec<strong>in</strong>cts (A1-A6) that l<strong>in</strong>e the south side <strong>of</strong> the Street <strong>of</strong> the Tombs on a hill <strong>in</strong> the southwestern corner <strong>of</strong><br />

the Kerameikos. It lies east <strong>of</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos. “It is an approximately rectangular<br />

peribolos 16.25m <strong>in</strong> length, whose depth varies between 5.9m, on the east side, <strong>and</strong> 6.85m on the west.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> height <strong>of</strong> its front wall is 3.45m. <strong>The</strong> prec<strong>in</strong>ct has been dated to between 338 <strong>and</strong> 317 B.C. on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> evidence that at the east the façade overlaps what rema<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>of</strong> the front wall <strong>of</strong> the neighbor<strong>in</strong>g<br />

prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios after the destruction <strong>of</strong> 338 B.C.: Garl<strong>and</strong>, “A First Catalogue <strong>of</strong> Attic Peribolos<br />

Tombs” 138 <strong>and</strong> 137, fig. 2, <strong>and</strong> Knigge, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Kerameikos 126. Regard<strong>in</strong>g the statue, which is<br />

placed at the eastern corner <strong>of</strong> the enclosure, Garl<strong>and</strong> says (138) that it was doubtless matched by another<br />

one at the western corner. Knigge (126) agrees with him. For an additional discussion <strong>of</strong> the prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong><br />

Lysimachides, <strong>and</strong> grave stelai found <strong>in</strong> it <strong>and</strong> bear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>scriptions with the name <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides, see<br />

Brückner, Der Friedh<strong>of</strong> am Eridanos 76, fig. 45 <strong>and</strong> 83-85.<br />

218<br />

Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo fig. 178: 330-310 B.C; H. Riemann, Kerameikos II: Die<br />

Skulpturen vom 5. Jahrhundert bis <strong>in</strong> römische Zeit (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1940) 102: 320 B.C.<br />

219<br />

O. Keller, Die antike Tierwelt I (Leipzig, 1909) 104-107, 111-112.<br />

220<br />

H. Riemann, Kerameikos II: 101.<br />

221<br />

Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

222<br />

Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste” 262.<br />

140


<strong>The</strong> body <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos hound appears heavy <strong>and</strong> powerful. It is def<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

strong muscles that are made visible through the haunch, h<strong>in</strong>d leg, <strong>and</strong> also through the<br />

shoulder <strong>and</strong> foreleg. <strong>The</strong> four clearly visible ribs on the side <strong>of</strong> the body give the<br />

impression <strong>of</strong> a lean <strong>and</strong> muscular animal. Below the rib cage, an enlarged ve<strong>in</strong> branches<br />

out <strong>and</strong> runs along the abdomen. <strong>The</strong> h<strong>in</strong>d leg is s<strong>in</strong>ewy with a large paw that term<strong>in</strong>ates<br />

<strong>in</strong> pronounced toes <strong>and</strong> claws. <strong>The</strong> forelegs are long <strong>and</strong> muscular with equally large<br />

paws <strong>and</strong> pronounced toes but with curved claws. Each toe, front <strong>and</strong> h<strong>in</strong>d, is detailed<br />

with patches <strong>of</strong> hair as is the underside <strong>of</strong> the right foreleg, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the ribcage. Hair<br />

accentuates the lower rump as well as the tail, which disappears underneath the body <strong>and</strong><br />

emerges over the h<strong>in</strong>d paw. Locks <strong>of</strong> hair run along the backbone <strong>and</strong> are angled slightly<br />

back <strong>and</strong> down; they connect with detailed hair that runs around the neck <strong>and</strong> down to the<br />

chest resembl<strong>in</strong>g a lion’s mane. <strong>The</strong> chest is broad <strong>and</strong> elongated. <strong>The</strong> face is def<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

muscular cheeks, attentive eyes, a large partially open mouth, <strong>and</strong> a long snout. <strong>The</strong><br />

forehead is flat <strong>and</strong> divided <strong>in</strong> the center by a depression that runs between the eyes <strong>and</strong><br />

stops at the snout. <strong>The</strong> hair encircl<strong>in</strong>g the face is organized <strong>in</strong> short locks that project,<br />

thus fram<strong>in</strong>g the face <strong>and</strong> separat<strong>in</strong>g it from the rest <strong>of</strong> the body.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Anatomy <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos Dog<br />

<strong>The</strong> display <strong>of</strong> musculature on the body <strong>of</strong> the statue accords well with Pseudo-<br />

Aristotle’s discussion <strong>of</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy <strong>in</strong> the Physiognomics, which, as already noted,<br />

calls attention to the muscular body <strong>of</strong> lion, particularly, its strong, muscular legs, <strong>and</strong><br />

lean haunches <strong>and</strong> thighs (809b) [173]. Similarly, the presence <strong>of</strong> curved nails on the<br />

statue is consistent with the <strong>in</strong>formation Aristotle provides <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> that<br />

141


<strong>of</strong> “the animals that possess nails…some have straight ones (e.g., man), others crooked or<br />

curved ones (an example from walk<strong>in</strong>g animals is the lion, from fly<strong>in</strong>g ones, the eagle)”<br />

(517a-517b) [59]. <strong>The</strong> sculptor’s attention to the lion’s nails is <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g, consider<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that the animal can <strong>in</strong> reality retract its claws. Further, the presence <strong>of</strong> hair on the back<br />

<strong>and</strong> neck <strong>of</strong> the statue is consistent with the description <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>in</strong> the Physiognomics<br />

as an animal with a hairy back <strong>and</strong> neck, <strong>and</strong> his <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> these bodily features as<br />

signs <strong>of</strong> shamelessness <strong>and</strong> generosity respectively (812b) [180]. Similarly, the<br />

physiognomic idea that those animals (among them the lion) whose hair near the head<br />

curls backwards are liberal <strong>in</strong> character appears to f<strong>in</strong>d application on the lion-like body<br />

<strong>of</strong> the statue, whose hair around its head is pushed backward (812b) [181]. <strong>The</strong><br />

importance <strong>of</strong> this sign <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics emerges clearly<br />

when he notes what the opposite appearance signifies: “those [animals] whose hair<br />

<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>es to grow down from the head towards the nose are mean; this is appropriate as<br />

this appearance gives a servile look” (812b) [182].<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention to highlight the character <strong>of</strong> the animal represented here may be<br />

also seen <strong>in</strong> its possession <strong>of</strong> a large chest, large <strong>and</strong> powerful extremities, <strong>and</strong> also a<br />

hairy tail. As the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics suggests, all animals with bushy tails are<br />

aggressive (808b) [171], <strong>and</strong> with large chests strong <strong>in</strong> character (810b) [175]. In<br />

addition, this author has human be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when he speaks <strong>of</strong> large <strong>and</strong> powerful<br />

extremities as signs <strong>of</strong> bravery (807a) [169], as noted earlier, but also <strong>of</strong> a passionate<br />

temperament (808a) [170]. That his idea could equally apply to animals is supported by<br />

the fundamental notion <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics, also noted earlier, that similar bodily<br />

features <strong>in</strong> humans <strong>and</strong> animals reveal their comparable <strong>in</strong>ner qualities. <strong>The</strong> connection<br />

142


that the author <strong>of</strong> the Physiognomics sees, therefore, between large, powerful extremities<br />

<strong>and</strong> bravery <strong>in</strong> men may serve as a clue to what the large <strong>and</strong> powerful legs <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Kerameikos statue were <strong>in</strong>tended to convey <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> its subject’s character. A similar<br />

<strong>in</strong>tention can be also found <strong>in</strong> the broad chest <strong>of</strong> the animal, an additional bodily feature<br />

which the Physiognomics associates with bravery <strong>in</strong> both humans <strong>and</strong> animals (807a;<br />

810b) [169; 175]. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it is reasonable to suggest that the sculptor <strong>of</strong><br />

the statue was familiar on some level with leon<strong>in</strong>e anatomy <strong>and</strong> with what it was thought<br />

to reveal <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the character <strong>of</strong> the animal. But the Kerameikos statue, as Riemann<br />

has rightly noted, has the head <strong>of</strong> a dog, a non-naturalistic characteristic that does not<br />

allow it to be classified as a lion. In fact, the render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its head, especially the muscles<br />

<strong>of</strong> the face <strong>and</strong> the depression <strong>in</strong> the middle <strong>of</strong> the forehead, accord well with the<br />

description <strong>of</strong> the head <strong>of</strong> the ideal big hunt<strong>in</strong>g dog that Xenophon advises his audience<br />

to acquire, <strong>in</strong> his treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

First, then, they [hunt<strong>in</strong>g dogs] should be big: Next, the head should be light, flat<br />

<strong>and</strong> muscular; the lower parts <strong>of</strong> the forehead s<strong>in</strong>ewy; the eyes prom<strong>in</strong>ent, black<br />

<strong>and</strong> sparkl<strong>in</strong>g; the forehead broad, with a deep divid<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e. (Cyn. 4.1) [190]<br />

This evidence may suggest that the sculptor <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos animal was familiar not<br />

simply with can<strong>in</strong>e anatomy, but also with how it reflected a dog’s hunt<strong>in</strong>g ability.<br />

Further, the fact that he chose to comb<strong>in</strong>e a leon<strong>in</strong>e body, evidently big, with a can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

head on the Kerameikos statue may be also suggestive <strong>of</strong> the fact that he was additionally<br />

familiar with the well-established idea that saw a close ontological relationship between<br />

the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog. This evidence is crucial for expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> leon<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>and</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e elements <strong>in</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> the Kerameikos animal.<br />

143


<strong>The</strong> proximity <strong>of</strong> the lion to the dog <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their nature is a notable element<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek zoological thought. Aristotle frequently groups both animals together<br />

under the general category <strong>of</strong> viviparous quadrupeds, which conta<strong>in</strong>s no h<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> the<br />

modern differentiation between the biological families Felidae <strong>and</strong> Canidae, to which the<br />

lion <strong>and</strong> the dog belong, but rather extends to encompass man <strong>and</strong> other animals as well,<br />

such as deer <strong>and</strong> horses. 223 As he characteristically says <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>: “there<br />

are many k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the group viviparous quadrupeds; but they are unnamed.<br />

Each constituent, we may say, has been named <strong>in</strong>dividually, as man has, e.g., lion, deer,<br />

horse, dog, <strong>and</strong> the rest <strong>of</strong> them <strong>in</strong> the same way” (490b) [55]. <strong>The</strong> conceived proximity<br />

between the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog is further suggested by Aristotle’s <strong>and</strong> pseudo-Aristotle’s<br />

beliefs that the animals share certa<strong>in</strong> anatomical characteristics <strong>and</strong> behaviors, such as<br />

saw-like teeth, large mouths, same-sized stomachs, small waists, which account for their<br />

aff<strong>in</strong>ity for hunt<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> also th<strong>in</strong> lips, which classify both animals as magnanimous, but<br />

<strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the dog, this quality is only visible on large <strong>and</strong> powerful dogs:<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> them [animals] are saw-toothed, e.g., the lion, the leopard, <strong>and</strong> the dog.<br />

(HA 501a) [56]<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> vary <strong>in</strong> the sizes <strong>of</strong> their mouths. Some have mouths which open wide<br />

(e.g., the dog, the lion, <strong>and</strong> all the saw-toothed animals. (HA 502a) [57]<br />

Some [animals] have a comparatively large stomach (e.g., the pig <strong>and</strong> the bear…);<br />

some have a much smaller one, not much larger than the gut, e.g., the dog, lion,<br />

<strong>and</strong> man. (HA 507b) [58]<br />

Those [animals] that are small <strong>in</strong> the waist are hunters; witness lions <strong>and</strong> dogs.<br />

One can observe that the dogs most fond <strong>of</strong> hunt<strong>in</strong>g are those which are narrow <strong>in</strong><br />

the waist. (Phgn. 810b) [174]<br />

223 Peck, Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I 35, n. 35: “there is <strong>in</strong> Greek no name correspond<strong>in</strong>g to Felidae.”<br />

Felidae or Felids is the term designat<strong>in</strong>g the biological family <strong>of</strong> the cats; a member <strong>of</strong> this family is called<br />

a felid. <strong>The</strong> family is divided <strong>in</strong>to two subfamilies: Panther<strong>in</strong>ae, which <strong>in</strong>cludes the lion, the tiger, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

leopard, <strong>and</strong> Fel<strong>in</strong>ae, which <strong>in</strong>cludes the cougar, the cheetah, lynxes, <strong>and</strong> the caracal, along with the<br />

domestic cat.<br />

144


Those [animals] who have th<strong>in</strong> lips <strong>and</strong> slack parts at the jo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lips, so<br />

that the upper lip overhangs the lower at the jo<strong>in</strong>t, are magnanimous; witness the<br />

lions. One can see the same th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> large <strong>and</strong> powerful dogs. (811a) [177]<br />

<strong>The</strong>se observations <strong>in</strong>dicate that <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> these authors the dog <strong>and</strong> the lion were<br />

two species that shared a common nature, which manifested itself <strong>in</strong> the anatomy,<br />

behavior, <strong>and</strong> character <strong>of</strong> the animals.<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the ontological proximity <strong>of</strong> the lion to the dog can<br />

be found <strong>in</strong> several <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s discussions <strong>of</strong> the lion, <strong>in</strong> particular <strong>of</strong> its bodily<br />

functions <strong>and</strong> behavior, which he describes by compar<strong>in</strong>g them directly to those <strong>of</strong> a dog.<br />

In the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, he says, for example:<br />

<strong>The</strong> lion is a carnivore like all others that are wild <strong>and</strong> saw-toothed. Its manner <strong>of</strong><br />

devour<strong>in</strong>g is violent, <strong>and</strong> it swallows much <strong>of</strong> its food without divid<strong>in</strong>g it up, <strong>and</strong><br />

then goes without food for two or three days: it can do this because it is over-full.<br />

It does not dr<strong>in</strong>k much. It discharges excrement sparsely: it is voided every other<br />

day or at r<strong>and</strong>om <strong>in</strong>tervals, <strong>and</strong> is dry <strong>and</strong> desiccated like a dog’s. Also the w<strong>in</strong>d<br />

that it discharges is very pungent <strong>and</strong> its ur<strong>in</strong>e has a smell; hence the dogs sniff at<br />

the trees, for it ur<strong>in</strong>ates lift<strong>in</strong>g its leg like dogs. (HA 594b) [63]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage clearly states the perceived l<strong>in</strong>k between a lion <strong>and</strong> a dog <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong><br />

bodily functions <strong>and</strong> accompanied behavior. Similarly, a lion not only exhibits dog-like<br />

behavior by runn<strong>in</strong>g like a hound, when it is hunted by humans, but also by stretch<strong>in</strong>g its<br />

tail like a hound, when try<strong>in</strong>g to escape; at the same time, a wound caused by a lion<br />

requires the same treatment as that caused by a dog:<br />

When it [lion] is be<strong>in</strong>g hunted, even if it is <strong>in</strong> view it never runs away nor takes<br />

cover, but if it is compelled to withdraw because <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> hunters it<br />

retreats at a walk, step by step, <strong>and</strong> turn<strong>in</strong>g its head at short <strong>in</strong>tervals; nevertheless<br />

if it reaches thick cover it runs away fast until it has come <strong>in</strong>to full view; then <strong>in</strong><br />

aga<strong>in</strong> withdraws at a walk. In open country if it has been forced by the crowd to<br />

run away <strong>in</strong>to full view, it runs extended <strong>and</strong> does not leap. <strong>The</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g gait is<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>uously extended like a hound’s; when it is pursu<strong>in</strong>g, however, it hurls itself<br />

on the prey when it is near. (HA 629b) [67]<br />

145


Sometimes they [lions] run away stretch<strong>in</strong>g the tail straight out like hounds. A<br />

lion has been seen before now to attack a pig, <strong>and</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g away when it saw it<br />

bristl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> defense. Aga<strong>in</strong>st blows to the flanks it is weak, but it can take many<br />

over the rest <strong>of</strong> its body <strong>and</strong> its head is strong. Whatever it has bitten or wounded<br />

with its claws, the wounds run with ichors which are deep yellow <strong>and</strong> cannot be<br />

washed out <strong>of</strong> the b<strong>and</strong>ages <strong>and</strong> sponges. <strong>The</strong> treatment is the same as for<br />

wounds caused by dogbite. (HA 630a) [68]<br />

Evidence that the closeness <strong>of</strong> the dog <strong>and</strong> the lion extends also to their biology is<br />

found elsewhere <strong>in</strong> the zoological treatises <strong>of</strong> Aristotle. In the Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, he<br />

notes, for example, that the dog is one <strong>of</strong> those animals that mates with species other than<br />

its own, but species with which it is allied <strong>in</strong> nature. Although not directly related to the<br />

lion, this <strong>in</strong>formation is crucial for the context it establishes:<br />

<strong>The</strong> partners <strong>in</strong> copulation are naturally <strong>and</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>arily animals <strong>of</strong> the same k<strong>in</strong>d;<br />

but beside that, animals that are closely allied <strong>in</strong> their nature, <strong>and</strong> are not very<br />

different <strong>in</strong> species, copulate, if they are comparable <strong>in</strong> size <strong>and</strong> if their period<br />

<strong>of</strong> gestation are equal <strong>in</strong> length. Although such cross<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong>frequent among the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> animals, it occurs among dogs, foxes, wolves (<strong>and</strong> jackals); the<br />

Indian dog also is produced from the union <strong>of</strong> a dog with some wild doglike beast.<br />

(GA 746a) [50]<br />

In the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Aristotle expla<strong>in</strong>s further the breed <strong>of</strong> the Indian dog as the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> a mat<strong>in</strong>g between a dog <strong>and</strong> a tiger:<br />

Other animals too are produced from the mix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> different breeds, as <strong>in</strong> Cyrene<br />

the wolves mate with the dogs <strong>and</strong> generate young, <strong>and</strong> from fox <strong>and</strong> dog come<br />

the Laconian hounds. <strong>The</strong>y say too that the Indian hounds come from tiger <strong>and</strong><br />

dog, not immediately, but after the third mat<strong>in</strong>g; for they say the first <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

like a savage beast. <strong>The</strong>y take the bitches to deserted places <strong>and</strong> tie them up; <strong>and</strong><br />

many are devoured, if the wild animal does not happen to be excited for mat<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(HA 607a) [65]<br />

By identify<strong>in</strong>g the Indian hound with the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the third-generation mat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

between a tiger <strong>and</strong> a dog, the passage <strong>in</strong>dicates that Aristotle placed the dog lower than a<br />

tiger <strong>in</strong> the scale <strong>of</strong> animals with savage nature, <strong>and</strong> viewed it therefore as the species<br />

directly affected by cross-breed<strong>in</strong>g. Aristotle is not the only author who records<br />

146


knowledge <strong>of</strong> the dog mat<strong>in</strong>g with other species. Xenophon, for example, <strong>in</strong> his treatise<br />

On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g, states that a breed <strong>of</strong> hounds called “Vulp<strong>in</strong>e is a hybrid between the dog<br />

<strong>and</strong> the fox: hence the name” (Cyn. 3.1) [189].<br />

Specific evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the breed<strong>in</strong>g between a dog <strong>and</strong> a lion does is <strong>of</strong>fered<br />

by Aristotle. In the Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, although he acknowledges that these two are<br />

two different species <strong>of</strong> animals, he does not preclude the idea <strong>of</strong> breed<strong>in</strong>g between them.<br />

In fact, he draws attention to how the sex <strong>of</strong> each species <strong>in</strong> this case affects differently<br />

the species <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

Two animals which differ <strong>in</strong> species produce <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g which differs <strong>in</strong> species;<br />

for <strong>in</strong>stance, a dog differs <strong>in</strong> species from a lion, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a male dog<br />

<strong>and</strong> a female lion is different <strong>in</strong> species; so is the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a male lion <strong>and</strong> a<br />

female dog. (GA 747b) [51]<br />

Aristotle does not specify what the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a lion <strong>and</strong> a dog would be, but his<br />

statement is crucial for establish<strong>in</strong>g cross-breed<strong>in</strong>g between the two animals as a fixed<br />

idea <strong>in</strong> his day. 224 Although he does not identify the types <strong>of</strong> dogs used <strong>in</strong> this practice,<br />

his earlier comment that similar-sized animals is a prerequisite for mat<strong>in</strong>g between<br />

different species suggests that large dogs were most likely used <strong>in</strong> this case. Also that the<br />

lion is, <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, a strong, high-bred animal (HA 488b) [54] suggests that the species<br />

most likely to be altered by cross-breed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this case is the dog. Aristotle’s idea <strong>of</strong> a<br />

lion <strong>and</strong> a dog be<strong>in</strong>g cross-bred is also supported by a later author, Pollux (A.D. II), who<br />

reports that <strong>in</strong> Hycarnia, a region to the south <strong>of</strong> the Caspian Sea, dogs are crossed with<br />

lions (Onom. 5.38) [163].<br />

224 Another <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the well-established idea that the sex <strong>of</strong> each species affects the species <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g is the case <strong>of</strong> the mule, which Aristotle def<strong>in</strong>es as (GA 746b, 747a, 748a) as the sterile <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> a male donkey <strong>and</strong> a female horse <strong>and</strong> also that <strong>of</strong> a h<strong>in</strong>ny, that is, the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a male horse <strong>and</strong> a<br />

female donkey.<br />

147


Although not exactly based on cross-breed<strong>in</strong>g, the biological aff<strong>in</strong>ity between a<br />

lion <strong>and</strong> a dog may be also reflected <strong>in</strong> the mythological idea that one <strong>of</strong> these animals<br />

can be parented by the other. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Hesiod’s <strong>The</strong>ogony (306), for example, the<br />

Nemean lion killed by Heracles is the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Orthus, the dog <strong>of</strong> the titan Geryon,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the monster Echidna. Although not conventional, such l<strong>in</strong>eage reflects the idea that<br />

no great biological distance separated the lion from the dog, but rather, the two were<br />

considered ontologically close to one another.<br />

Taken together, the evidence cited so far <strong>in</strong>dicates that <strong>Classical</strong> Greek zoological<br />

thought considered the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog two animals that were closely allied <strong>in</strong> nature.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y shared certa<strong>in</strong> anatomical, behavioral, <strong>and</strong> personal characteristics, <strong>and</strong> were also<br />

cross-bred. When transferred to the Kerameikos hound, which comb<strong>in</strong>es the body <strong>of</strong> a<br />

lion <strong>and</strong> the head <strong>of</strong> a dog, this evidence suggests that the contradictory elements <strong>in</strong> the<br />

style <strong>of</strong> this statue may be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as the result <strong>of</strong> the contemporary view <strong>of</strong> the lion<br />

<strong>and</strong> the dog as ontologically close to one another. This evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, highlights the<br />

role <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> uncover<strong>in</strong>g the conceptual context that helps shape the elements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> fourth-century statues <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>and</strong> the hound from the Kerameikos suggest<br />

that the presence <strong>of</strong> naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic, elements <strong>in</strong> their <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>and</strong><br />

contradictory styles respectively is a direct reflection <strong>of</strong> the manner <strong>in</strong> which these two<br />

animals were viewed <strong>and</strong> thought to be <strong>in</strong> contemporary life. In this way, animals<br />

emerge as useful guides to the conceptual categories that shape the elements <strong>of</strong> style, <strong>and</strong><br />

148


serve their arrangement <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture. Simply put, animals reveal that an<br />

<strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> apparently differ<strong>in</strong>g elements is the susta<strong>in</strong>ed underly<strong>in</strong>g model <strong>of</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g<br />

style <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period <strong>of</strong> Greek art. As the cases <strong>of</strong> the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog suggest,<br />

these elements prove to express similarities. In the first case, for example, the similarity<br />

refers to that between a male lion <strong>and</strong> a male human, whereas, <strong>in</strong> the second, between a<br />

dog <strong>and</strong> a lion. On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the scholarly <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

problematic style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture as a<br />

reflection <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ability <strong>of</strong> the artists to portray accurately their subjects, lack <strong>of</strong> real<br />

models, copy<strong>in</strong>g from foreign animal models, or attempt<strong>in</strong>g to highlight the apotropaic<br />

function <strong>of</strong> the animals depicted do not appear to st<strong>and</strong> on firm ground. By establish<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that the logic <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art is one <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g elements <strong>in</strong> various<br />

modes <strong>and</strong> degrees, such as <strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction animals suggest<br />

that the generally accepted <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> this style as a strict imitation <strong>of</strong> the external<br />

world does not hold true. More specifically, animals suggest that the underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> style is based on an <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> disagree<strong>in</strong>g elements that are,<br />

<strong>in</strong> turn, directly shaped by contemporary ideas regard<strong>in</strong>g the representational subjects <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> art. Further, s<strong>in</strong>ce animals show that such an <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> apparent<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistencies is not limited to the style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> art, but characterizes also that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

art <strong>of</strong> the Archaic period, <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ce it extends also to the human form dur<strong>in</strong>g these<br />

periods, animals suggest a new example for approach<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Classical</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art:<br />

as a model based on fusion that is marked by a shift <strong>in</strong> the balance <strong>of</strong> its differ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

elements as art moves from one stylistic/chronological phase to another. Representations<br />

149


<strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture <strong>of</strong>fer, therefore, an <strong>in</strong>valuable <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek conception <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> contemporary art.<br />

150


Chapter 3: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Contradictory Attitude toward the Dog<br />

Introduction<br />

This chapter is an <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek attitude towards the dog<br />

based on contemporary literary sources. Although the <strong>Classical</strong> period is especially rich<br />

<strong>in</strong> sources, the present chapter is limited to a selected body <strong>of</strong> texts from which a clear<br />

picture <strong>of</strong> how the dog was viewed <strong>and</strong> treated can be discerned.<br />

<strong>The</strong> attitude towards the dog that emerges from these texts is marked by<br />

contradiction: the dog, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, was <strong>in</strong> some respect, central to the life <strong>and</strong><br />

thought <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society, but, on the other, it was denigrated as a malevolent<br />

creature deserv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> callous <strong>and</strong> cruel treatment. <strong>The</strong> sources show that the dog was an<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegral part <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society, which was anthropocentric to its core. As a<br />

resident <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek household, the dog was cared for by hav<strong>in</strong>g both shelter<br />

<strong>and</strong> food provided for it. Its behavior was so familiar <strong>and</strong> closely observed that its<br />

propensity for steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> gobbl<strong>in</strong>g food served as a figure <strong>of</strong> speech for describ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

similar behavior <strong>in</strong> humans. <strong>The</strong> dog was also highly valued for its ability <strong>in</strong> guard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the house, its residents, <strong>and</strong> their possessions, <strong>and</strong> for its fidelity <strong>and</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>telligence. A certa<strong>in</strong> breed known as the Molossian was esteemed for its exceptional<br />

appearance <strong>and</strong> size. Yet along with this positive reception <strong>of</strong> the dog, the sources also<br />

preserve a str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> evidence that portrays the animal as a malevolent <strong>and</strong> dangerous<br />

creature, <strong>and</strong> one that was beaten <strong>and</strong> actually eaten. For example, because <strong>of</strong> its ability<br />

simultaneously to fawn over <strong>and</strong> bite people, the dog was considered a treacherous <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore untrustworthy animal. Similarly, its behavior as a scavenger <strong>in</strong>spired fear <strong>in</strong><br />

151


humans <strong>and</strong> led to its classification as a dangerous animal. Furthermore, the beat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

the dog as punishment for gobbl<strong>in</strong>g down stolen food exemplified its physical abuse,<br />

whereas the consumption <strong>of</strong> its flesh marked its status as no different from any other<br />

edible animal. Both these types <strong>of</strong> treatment <strong>and</strong> the callous views <strong>of</strong> the dog suggest a<br />

negative attitude that contrasts sharply with the one mentioned above.<br />

<strong>The</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> the texts that convey this contradictory attitude is divided <strong>in</strong>to<br />

three sections: Section 1 surveys the evidence for the presence <strong>of</strong> the animal <strong>in</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek household, its role as a guardian, <strong>and</strong> the contradiction evident <strong>in</strong> its<br />

loyal <strong>and</strong>, at the same time, treacherous behavior. <strong>The</strong> section also discusses the<br />

popularity <strong>of</strong> the Molossian breed <strong>of</strong> guard dogs. Section 2 presents evidence that refers<br />

to the feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog, that is, its propensity for steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g up food,<br />

its cunn<strong>in</strong>g behavior, <strong>and</strong> the punishment correspond<strong>in</strong>g to its <strong>of</strong>fense. In addition, the<br />

section discusses the care that the animal received by hav<strong>in</strong>g its food provided, but also<br />

its behavior as a scavenger, <strong>and</strong> ideas regard<strong>in</strong>g the orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> its savage nature. Section 3<br />

is a survey <strong>of</strong> testimony that refers to the practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs as a marker <strong>of</strong> social<br />

class, <strong>and</strong> also as a dietary treatment for certa<strong>in</strong> diseases. <strong>The</strong> arrangement <strong>of</strong> the texts<br />

with<strong>in</strong> each section is chronological with the exception <strong>of</strong> a few <strong>in</strong>stances where<br />

chronology has given way to other factors to further the cohesion <strong>of</strong> the argument.<br />

152


SECTION 1<br />

a. Dogs Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the House<br />

Evidence that dogs lived <strong>in</strong> the premises <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek house comes from<br />

a passage from Aristophanes’ Plutus (388 B.C.). <strong>The</strong> play opens at the house <strong>of</strong><br />

Chremylus, a poor Athenian citizen, where Plutus, the god <strong>of</strong> wealth, appears as an old,<br />

bl<strong>in</strong>d man. Chremylus takes Plutus to a sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Asclepius, where he has his sight<br />

restored. This newfound ability enables Plutus to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between virtuous but poor<br />

<strong>and</strong> wicked but rich citizens. In an attempt to elim<strong>in</strong>ate these categories, Plutus<br />

establishes a new world where everyone is virtuous <strong>and</strong> rich, but the ma<strong>in</strong> effect <strong>of</strong> this<br />

act is the cessation <strong>of</strong> sacrificial <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs to the gods. Hermes visits the house <strong>of</strong><br />

Chremylus to compla<strong>in</strong> about the situation. He is first met by a slave named Carion:<br />

CARION<br />

Here, you, tell me, was it you that was knock<strong>in</strong>g<br />

so hard on the door just now?<br />

HERMES<br />

No, I didn’t; I was go<strong>in</strong>g to, but you opened the door first.<br />

Now run quickly <strong>and</strong> call out your master, then his wife<br />

<strong>and</strong> children, then the servants, then the dog, then yourself, <strong>and</strong><br />

then the pig. (Plut. 1100-1105) [44]<br />

<strong>The</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Hermes show that a dog was <strong>in</strong>cluded among the residents <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>of</strong><br />

Chremylus. This evidence does not automatically assign to the dog status equal to that <strong>of</strong><br />

a member <strong>of</strong> Chremylus’s family, as it has been previously suggested, 225 but does<br />

225 S. Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry (Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 56; Hels<strong>in</strong>ki, 1976)<br />

78-79, correctly notes that the passage cannot be used as evidence that dogs were considered members <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek family. This po<strong>in</strong>t, she clarifies, is presented <strong>in</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> this passage by J. Löbe,<br />

“Notizen über der Hund aus griechischen und römischen Schriftstellern,” Mitteilungen aus dem Österl<strong>and</strong>e<br />

9 (1900) 33. <strong>The</strong> situation provides the ground for reference to modern notions <strong>of</strong> animals as members <strong>of</strong><br />

the family. A. Katcher <strong>and</strong> A. Beck, Between Pets <strong>and</strong> People: <strong>The</strong> Importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> Companionship<br />

(West Lafayette, 1983; rev. ed., 1996) 41, <strong>in</strong>dicate that, <strong>in</strong> a survey regard<strong>in</strong>g animals <strong>and</strong> the family, 87<br />

percent <strong>of</strong> their subjects considered animals liv<strong>in</strong>g with them as members <strong>of</strong> their family. In addition,<br />

another study focus<strong>in</strong>g on adolescent pony-club members found that more than 80 percent <strong>of</strong> persons asked<br />

153


<strong>in</strong>dicate that the premises <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek house served as shelter for the animal,<br />

which further implies the very real presence <strong>of</strong> the dog <strong>in</strong> everyday domestic life. <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>of</strong> a dog <strong>in</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Chremylus raises the question whether specific space<br />

was reserved for the animal. Archaeological evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

doghouses <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek houses is lack<strong>in</strong>g. Physical evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g doghouses <strong>in</strong><br />

the classical world, however, comes from Pompeii. 226<br />

Of particular <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> the passage is the sequence to which Hermes adheres<br />

when he enumerates the residents <strong>of</strong> Chremylus’s house—master, wife, children,<br />

servants, dog, Carion, pig. 227 As can be seen, Hermes follows a hierarchical order by<br />

considered the horse to be a family member, an <strong>in</strong>dication that the feel<strong>in</strong>g does not depend upon the<br />

animal’s actual liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the house. More recently <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the effects <strong>of</strong> hurricane Katr<strong>in</strong>a on<br />

both people <strong>and</strong> animals on the Gulf Coast <strong>of</strong> the United States, some fifteen thous<strong>and</strong> pets, among them<br />

dogs, cats, parakeets, <strong>and</strong> goats, were str<strong>and</strong>ed, rescued, <strong>and</strong> consequently adopted by new owners. As K.<br />

Boccella, “Tug-<strong>of</strong>-War Erupts Over Katr<strong>in</strong>a Pets—Class <strong>and</strong> Race Shade the Fight Between Those Who<br />

Lost, Those Who Now Have,” <strong>The</strong> Philadelphia Inquirer (July 16, 2006) 1, reports, many evacuees, <strong>in</strong> an<br />

effort to reclaim the pets they were forced to ab<strong>and</strong>on, sued agencies that set up the animals for adoption by<br />

new owners. In defense <strong>of</strong> former owners, lawyers represent<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>in</strong> custody battles have argued that<br />

their clients lost everyth<strong>in</strong>g, but the only th<strong>in</strong>g left to them is their family; <strong>and</strong> these animals are their<br />

family. <strong>The</strong> situation, however, has brought forward the overlooked but well-established contradiction<br />

between the widely held notion that pets are family members <strong>and</strong> their legal status as mere property.<br />

Reflective <strong>of</strong> the attempt to resolve this contradiction is the grow<strong>in</strong>g specialty <strong>of</strong> animal law with<strong>in</strong> the<br />

legal world. Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the objective <strong>of</strong> lawyers specializ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this field, W. St. John, “New Breed <strong>of</strong><br />

Lawyer Gives Every Dog His Day <strong>in</strong> Court,” New York Times (Sept. 3, 2006) 13, states that their primary<br />

goal is: “gett<strong>in</strong>g the legal system to acknowledge that animals have an <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic value beyond mere<br />

property, because <strong>of</strong> the bond between pets <strong>and</strong> their owners.”<br />

226 Two doghouses were found at Pompeii. One is a small masonry doghouse located <strong>in</strong> the southwest<br />

corner <strong>of</strong> the tabl<strong>in</strong>um <strong>of</strong> a house (XI.V.2) on the Via di Nola. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this doghouse, see W. F.<br />

Jashemski, <strong>The</strong> Gardens <strong>of</strong> Pompeii, Herculaneum, <strong>and</strong> the Villas Destroyed by Vesuvius (New York,<br />

1979) 103, n. 65, fig. 163. A second doghouse was excavated <strong>in</strong> the so-called Garden <strong>of</strong> Hercules, which<br />

comprised part <strong>of</strong> a humble house (II.VIII.6) to the west <strong>of</strong> the Great Palaestra. <strong>The</strong> doghouse, which was<br />

found south <strong>of</strong> the tricl<strong>in</strong>ium, was made by mount<strong>in</strong>g on a masonry base half <strong>of</strong> a terracotta jar, dolium, that<br />

was cut lengthwise. For a discussion <strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> this doghouse, see Jashemski, <strong>The</strong> Gardens <strong>of</strong><br />

Pompeii 103, n. 66; 279; 426, fig. 422; Also a mosaic from Carthage (A.D. IV-V) depicts a dog cha<strong>in</strong>ed to<br />

its house: D. Brewer et al., Dogs <strong>in</strong> Antiquity. Anubis to Cerberus. <strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Domestic Dog<br />

(Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 2000) 93, fig. 5.12. Varro (116-27 B.C.) is the first classical author to refer to kennels. In his<br />

discussion on dogs liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> farms (Rust. 2.9.12-2.9.13), he recommends: “on ra<strong>in</strong>y days the kennels should<br />

be bedded with leaves or fodder, <strong>and</strong> this for two purposes: to keep them from be<strong>in</strong>g muddied <strong>and</strong> to keep<br />

them from gett<strong>in</strong>g chilled”; translation: W. D. Hooper, ed., tr., rev. H. B. Ash, Marcus Porcius Cato. On<br />

Agriculture. Marcus Terentius Varro. On Agriculture (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1934; rev. <strong>and</strong> repr.<br />

1935; repr. 1993) 403.<br />

227 Additional evidence, that pigs were kept <strong>in</strong> the courtyards <strong>of</strong> Athenian houses <strong>in</strong> specific pens called<br />

xoirokomei=a, derives from comedy (Vesp. 844; Lys. 1037). As A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wealth (<strong>The</strong><br />

154


eferr<strong>in</strong>g first to the human family members <strong>and</strong> then proceed<strong>in</strong>g to the others liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

the house. 228 This sequence accords well with the contemporary anthropocentric view<br />

that humans were primary <strong>and</strong> central <strong>in</strong> the classification <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs. 229 What<br />

seems to upset this view, however, is the placement <strong>of</strong> Carion, a human slave, between<br />

the dog <strong>and</strong> the pig. This placement, which has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as an attempt to<br />

deride 230 <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>sult 231 the slave, is peripheral to the current discussion <strong>of</strong> the dog, but the<br />

possibility that it is reflective <strong>of</strong> current views on slaves <strong>and</strong> animals, 232 <strong>and</strong> also<br />

Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 11; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 2001) 209, l<strong>in</strong>e 1106, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, keep<strong>in</strong>g pigs <strong>in</strong> pens “was an<br />

efficient recycl<strong>in</strong>g device for dispos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> much household rubbish <strong>and</strong> ultimately convert<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong>to food<br />

for the family.” For a thorough discussion <strong>of</strong> the word xoirokomei=on (pig-pen), see G. V. Lalonde,<br />

“Topographical Notes on Aristophanes,” Hesperia Supplement 20 (1982) 77-81.<br />

228 This evidence is also consistent with the suggestion that speech <strong>and</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g are l<strong>in</strong>ear, hence sequential,<br />

<strong>and</strong>, as such, they allow the listener or the reader to get an idea <strong>of</strong> the whole. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this idea<br />

<strong>and</strong> its possible affect on the spatial arrangement <strong>of</strong> representational subjects <strong>in</strong> Greek art, see J. P. Small,<br />

“Time <strong>in</strong> Space: Narrative <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Art,” <strong>The</strong> Art Bullet<strong>in</strong> 81 (1999) 563, n. 25.<br />

229 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this view, see Renehan, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Anthropocentric View <strong>of</strong> Man” 239-259; also G.<br />

Ste<strong>in</strong>er, Anthropocentrism <strong>and</strong> Its Discontents: <strong>The</strong> Moral Status <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Western<br />

Philosophy (Pittsburgh, 2005) 1.<br />

230 Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry 79, n. 31; <strong>in</strong> susta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g her belief <strong>in</strong> the comic element <strong>in</strong> Carion’s<br />

position between the dog <strong>and</strong> the pig, she follows H. van Daele’s (V. Coulon, ed., <strong>and</strong> H. van Daele, tr.,<br />

Aristophane [Collection de Universités de France 5; Paris, 1930; repr. 1963] 142, n. 2) comment on the<br />

passage: “Dans cette énumération, Hermès cite par plaisanterie l’esclave Carion entre la chienne et la<br />

truie.” In addition, C. Ma<strong>in</strong>oldi, L’image du loup et du chien dans la Grèce ancienne d’Homère à Platon<br />

(Paris, 1984) 153, acknowledges the presence <strong>of</strong> a hierarchical order <strong>in</strong> this passage, <strong>and</strong> states that, apart<br />

from the humor, the dog <strong>of</strong> the “house” does not occupy the last place [<strong>in</strong> it], but it appears before the<br />

slave: “S’il faut reconnaîtrai un ordre hiérarchique dans ce passage, il est evident que la chienne de la<br />

maison n’occupe pas la dernière place, et que notamment, au-delà de las plaisanterie, elle devance<br />

l’esclave.” Maison can be translated as “house, residence; home; household, family”: H. Ferrar, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Concise Oxford French-English Dictionary (Oxford, 1934; second ed., 1980) 326-327, s.v. It is not easy to<br />

decide which mean<strong>in</strong>g the author has decided to give to the term used here. S<strong>in</strong>ce most <strong>of</strong> the additional<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs could alter significantly the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the passage under discussion, the term “house” <strong>in</strong><br />

the sense <strong>of</strong> physical premises has been chosen here as the least troublesome.<br />

231 S. D. Olson, “Cario <strong>and</strong> the New World <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes’ Plutus,” TAPA 119 (1989) 198, n. 19, states<br />

that: “Cario’s position <strong>in</strong> this social hierarchy as Hermes def<strong>in</strong>es it, s<strong>and</strong>wiched <strong>in</strong> between the dog, a semi<strong>in</strong>telligent<br />

figure, halfway between servant <strong>and</strong> animal, <strong>and</strong> the pig, is a calculated <strong>in</strong>sult.”<br />

232 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek tendency easily to associate the slave with the animal is a topic that deserves<br />

separate attention. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this tendency, see K. Bradley, “<strong>Animal</strong>iz<strong>in</strong>g the Slave: <strong>The</strong> Truth <strong>of</strong><br />

Fiction,” JRS 90 (2000) 110. Literary evidence that supports this tendency derives from Aristotle’s Politics<br />

(1254b), where slaves are assimilated to animals: “animals other than man are subservient not to reason, by<br />

apprehend<strong>in</strong>g it, but to feel<strong>in</strong>gs. And also the usefulness <strong>of</strong> slaves diverges little from that <strong>of</strong> animals;<br />

bodily service for the necessities <strong>of</strong> life is forthcom<strong>in</strong>g from both, from slaves <strong>and</strong> from domestic animals<br />

alike”; translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Aristotle. Politics (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1932; repr.<br />

1990) 23. Similarly <strong>in</strong> Xenophon’s Oeconomicus (13.9): “<strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs it is possible to<br />

make them more obedient merely by talk<strong>in</strong>g to them, po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that it is to their advantage to obey. But<br />

for slaves the method <strong>of</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that is accepted for wild animals is very effective <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g obedience”;<br />

155


Aristophanes’s <strong>in</strong>tention to control the attention <strong>of</strong> his audience <strong>in</strong> regard to Carion<br />

rema<strong>in</strong>s strong. 233 This evidence notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, it is the preconceived supremacy <strong>of</strong><br />

the human residents <strong>of</strong> Chremylus’s house over the dog that appears to have determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

the way both these fictional characters <strong>and</strong> the audience they addressed related to the<br />

animal.<br />

Further evidence <strong>of</strong> the anthropocentric attitude that characterized the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek relationship between humans <strong>and</strong> the dog is seen <strong>in</strong> philosophical writ<strong>in</strong>gs. In<br />

translation: S. B. Pomeroy, Xenophon. Oeconomicus. A Social <strong>and</strong> Historical Commentary (Oxford, 1994)<br />

67. Bradley, “<strong>Animal</strong>iz<strong>in</strong>g the Slave” 110, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that this notion <strong>of</strong> assimilation is further susta<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

the fact that one <strong>of</strong> the ancient Greek words for slaves was a)ndra&podon mean<strong>in</strong>g a “man-footed th<strong>in</strong>g”<br />

analogous to tetra&podon “four-footed th<strong>in</strong>g.” For further discussion <strong>of</strong> these terms, see P. Cartledge, <strong>The</strong><br />

Greeks: A Portrait <strong>of</strong> Self <strong>and</strong> Others (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1993; second ed., 2002) 151, who clarifies<br />

that a)ndra&podon appears to have been the technical term for those slaves acquired through capture <strong>in</strong> war.<br />

Additional evidence that slaves <strong>and</strong> animals were closely associated <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> derives from the<br />

epigraphic record. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions record<strong>in</strong>g the sale <strong>of</strong> personal property confiscated from Alcibiades <strong>and</strong><br />

those Athenians who were accused <strong>of</strong> mutilat<strong>in</strong>g the Herms <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>an<strong>in</strong>g the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian mysteries (415/4<br />

B.C.) show that both slaves <strong>and</strong> animals were <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> this property. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the slaves sold,<br />

their names (e.g., Pistos) <strong>and</strong> their prices (e.g., 202 drachmai), see W. K. Pritchett, “<strong>The</strong> Attic Stelai, Part<br />

I,” Hesperia 22 (1953) 246; for the animals referred <strong>in</strong> these <strong>in</strong>scriptions, that is, oxen, goats, sheep, cows,<br />

<strong>and</strong> beehives, see W. K. Pritchett, “<strong>The</strong> Attic Stelai, Part II,” Hesperia 25 (1956) 255-261. <strong>The</strong> treatment<br />

<strong>of</strong> animals as property on the <strong>in</strong>scriptions recalls the similarity with the current status <strong>of</strong> animals with<strong>in</strong><br />

human society. F<strong>in</strong>ally, for the ability to speak as the only criterion that differentiated slaves from animals<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, see J. Heath, <strong>The</strong> Talk<strong>in</strong>g Greeks. Speech, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Other <strong>in</strong> Homer, Aeschylus,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Plato (Cambridge, 2005) 203, n. 113. For evidence that the same idea prevailed also <strong>in</strong> Roman society,<br />

see Gilhus, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Gods <strong>and</strong> Humans 14.<br />

233 As Small, “Time <strong>in</strong> Space” 565, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s: “both the classical literary <strong>and</strong> visual examples can order<br />

their words <strong>and</strong> figures <strong>in</strong> a number <strong>of</strong> different ways to achieve particular effects.” That this may be<br />

Aristophanes’ <strong>in</strong>tention is also supported by the fact that the reference to Carion at this po<strong>in</strong>t seems<br />

redundant, s<strong>in</strong>ce Hermes has already referred to the servants <strong>of</strong> the house. For the exceptional abilities <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristophanes to control <strong>and</strong> direct the attention <strong>of</strong> his audience, see N. W. Slater, “Mak<strong>in</strong>g the Aristophanic<br />

Audience,” AJP 120 (1999) 351-368. Given the overall portrayal <strong>of</strong> Carion <strong>in</strong> the play as an unusually<br />

outspoken <strong>and</strong> proud slave, <strong>and</strong> the fact that <strong>in</strong> both ancient Greek art <strong>and</strong> language the center is the most<br />

important position, it may be suggested that, when placed <strong>in</strong> the center <strong>of</strong> an arrangement that is bordered<br />

by a dog <strong>and</strong> a pig, Carion is associated, but not demoted to the level <strong>of</strong> these animals. On the contrary, he<br />

is dist<strong>in</strong>guished from them, who are presented here as the ends next <strong>in</strong> importance to the center. With<strong>in</strong><br />

this context, Carion’s position can be also seen as a trick that Aristophanes employs <strong>in</strong> order to store <strong>in</strong> his<br />

audience’s m<strong>in</strong>d the non-stereotypical behavior <strong>of</strong> this slave. For the perception <strong>of</strong> order <strong>and</strong> physical<br />

context as mnemonic devices, see J. P. Small, Wax Tablets <strong>of</strong> the M<strong>in</strong>d. Cognitive Studies <strong>of</strong> Memory <strong>and</strong><br />

Literacy <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Antiquity (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1997) esp. 84-85 <strong>and</strong> 227-230.<br />

For the exceptional character <strong>of</strong> Carion, see Olson, “Cario <strong>and</strong> the New World” 193-199. For a discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> the center <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art <strong>and</strong> language, see Small, “Time <strong>in</strong> Space” 564-565,<br />

where references are made to specific artistic examples, such as the Parthenon frieze, <strong>and</strong> also to the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the fact that Greek is an <strong>in</strong>flected language, a characteristic that allows the order <strong>of</strong> words to<br />

reflect the importance <strong>of</strong> each word.<br />

156


Aristotle’s Politics, so pervasive is this attitude that the breed<strong>in</strong>g cycle <strong>of</strong> the animal is<br />

perceived as be<strong>in</strong>g affected by its liv<strong>in</strong>g together with humans:<br />

Human be<strong>in</strong>gs pair <strong>and</strong> breed at any <strong>and</strong> every season, <strong>and</strong> so also do many<br />

domesticated (sunanqrwpeuo&mena) animals ow<strong>in</strong>g to the shelter <strong>and</strong> the plentiful<br />

food they get by their association with man: I refer to those whose gestation<br />

periods are short, such as the sow <strong>and</strong> the bitch, <strong>and</strong> those birds which raise<br />

several broods. (HA 542a) [61]<br />

Aristotle confirms that the dog <strong>and</strong> the pig, as was the case with those <strong>in</strong> the house <strong>of</strong><br />

Chremylus, shared the same space with humans. This proximity is attested not only by<br />

the provisions <strong>of</strong> food <strong>and</strong> shelter that the author attaches to the animals, but also by his<br />

reference to them as “sunanqrwpeuo&mena,” which has been translated as<br />

“domesticated,” but its precise mean<strong>in</strong>g is that <strong>of</strong> “symbiotic with humans.” That<br />

Aristotle perceives this symbiosis as a shap<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>in</strong> the breed<strong>in</strong>g cycle <strong>of</strong> the dog is<br />

significant, for it suggests two ideas <strong>of</strong> his about the animal: that it had adopted a<br />

biological response to the human environment <strong>in</strong> which it lived, <strong>and</strong> that it was <strong>in</strong>ferior to<br />

humans because it had succumbed to their environment. When reversed, this evidence<br />

suggests that an anthropocentric attitude pervaded Aristotle’s view <strong>of</strong> the relationship<br />

between humans <strong>and</strong> the dog. Put simply, even though the dog shared the same space<br />

with humans, its conception with<strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society was shaped by deep-seated<br />

convictions about human dom<strong>in</strong>ion over animals.<br />

157


. Dogs as Guardians <strong>of</strong> the House<br />

Several texts that shed light on the prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> the dog as guardian<br />

<strong>of</strong> the house survive from the <strong>Classical</strong> period. One important source that rema<strong>in</strong>s is<br />

Aeschylus’s Agamemnon (458 B.C.). It tells the story <strong>of</strong> the homonymous Argive k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

who, upon return<strong>in</strong>g victorious from Troy, is murdered by his wife Clytemnestra. <strong>The</strong><br />

play opens at the palace <strong>of</strong> Argos, where a watchman looks out for a signal that Troy has<br />

been captured by the Greeks. It is night, <strong>and</strong> he describes the drawbacks <strong>of</strong> his job <strong>in</strong> the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g manner:<br />

I ask the gods for release from this misery, the<br />

year-long watch I lie awake keep<strong>in</strong>g on the ro<strong>of</strong> (ste/gaij)<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Atreidae, up above (a1gkaqen) here like a dog (kuno&j di/khn);<br />

I am familiar now with the night stars’ assembly,<br />

<strong>and</strong> those brilliant potentates which br<strong>in</strong>g men summer<br />

<strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong>ter, conspicuous <strong>in</strong> the heaven;<br />

I mark them closely as they fade, <strong>and</strong> the ris<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

And now I am on watch for a beacon’s sign, a gleam <strong>of</strong> fire<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g word from Troy <strong>and</strong> report <strong>of</strong> its capture: such is the<br />

power here <strong>of</strong> a woman whose heart <strong>in</strong> its hope plans like a man.<br />

Whenever I f<strong>in</strong>d myself shift<strong>in</strong>g my bed about at night, wet with<br />

dew, unvisited by dreams—because fear <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> sleep st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

at my side to stop my eyes clos<strong>in</strong>g fast <strong>in</strong> slumber—<strong>and</strong> whenever<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k to s<strong>in</strong>g or to hum, dispens<strong>in</strong>g this remedy from music aga<strong>in</strong>st sleep,<br />

then I weep <strong>in</strong> lament for this house’s misfortune;<br />

it is not managed for the best as it was before. Now I wish for a happy<br />

release from misery when the fire <strong>in</strong> the dark has appeared with its good<br />

news. (A. 1-21) [6]<br />

Early <strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> his speech, the watchman compares his post to that <strong>of</strong> a dog. This<br />

simile is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it suggests that Aeschylus’s audience was familiar with the role<br />

<strong>of</strong> the animal as a guardian. <strong>The</strong> simile also demonstrates the use <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior as a<br />

model for describ<strong>in</strong>g human behavior, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g the important position <strong>of</strong> the dog<br />

<strong>in</strong> contemporary thought. Apart from the watchman’s own exclamation that his post is<br />

“like that <strong>of</strong> a dog,” three additional conditions re<strong>in</strong>force the aff<strong>in</strong>ity <strong>of</strong> his behavior to<br />

158


that <strong>of</strong> a dog: his location on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the palace, posture, <strong>and</strong> vigilance. As the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion shows, all these three are essential elements <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

view <strong>of</strong> the dog.<br />

<strong>The</strong> placement <strong>of</strong> the watchman on the ro<strong>of</strong>(s) (ste/gaij, A. 3) <strong>of</strong> the palace 234 is<br />

a locale that <strong>Classical</strong> Greek thought easily associated with the dog. As a passage from<br />

Aristotle’s Great Ethics <strong>in</strong>dicates, the image <strong>of</strong> a dog spend<strong>in</strong>g time on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g was familiar can<strong>in</strong>e behavior. In a discussion regard<strong>in</strong>g the question, whether<br />

friendship flourishes between those alike, one <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terlocutors presents refut<strong>in</strong>g<br />

evidence by cit<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

<strong>The</strong> story <strong>of</strong> a dog that always would sleep upon the same tile ( kerami=doj); 235<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> how Empedocles, when asked why it did so, declared that there was<br />

some aff<strong>in</strong>ity between the dog <strong>and</strong> the [ro<strong>of</strong>-] tile which caused the former<br />

always to seek the latter.” (MM 1208b) [69]<br />

Like the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Argive palace on which the watchman lay, this passage presents the<br />

ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a build<strong>in</strong>g as fitt<strong>in</strong>g place for a dog. In this way, the passage re<strong>in</strong>forces the<br />

similarity between the location <strong>of</strong> the watchman <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the dog, 236 <strong>and</strong>, at the same<br />

time, suggests observation <strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior.<br />

234 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the visual effect <strong>of</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> the watchman on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the palace, A. Shapiro <strong>and</strong> P.<br />

Burian, Aeschylus. <strong>The</strong> Oresteia (Oxford, 2003) 189, note that: “there is no real reason to doubt [that] the<br />

Watchman appeared on the ro<strong>of</strong> as the play began, <strong>and</strong> [that this position] will also have provided a strik<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> probably novel scenic effect.” In support <strong>of</strong> this view is also N. G. L. Hammond, “Dramatic<br />

Production to the Death <strong>of</strong> Aeschylus,” GRBS 13 (1972) 434-435, who ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that it is the first time <strong>in</strong><br />

the Oresteia, that a palace background appears on stage where the ro<strong>of</strong> on which the sentry lies is visible.<br />

For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the oppos<strong>in</strong>g view that the watchman is not on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the stage build<strong>in</strong>g, but<br />

probably on the ground before the palace, see J. C. Hogan, A Commentary on the Complete Greek<br />

Tragedies. Aeschylus (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1984) 30.<br />

235 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to LSJ 9 , 940, s.v. kerami/j refers explicitly to a “ro<strong>of</strong>-tile.”<br />

236 Although this passage cannot be seen as evidence that the dog was specifically a watchdog, it provides<br />

the ground for discuss<strong>in</strong>g modern ethnographic <strong>and</strong> travel<strong>in</strong>g accounts, which <strong>in</strong>dicate that it is not<br />

uncommon for dogs to spend time <strong>and</strong> sleep on the ro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> their owners’ houses <strong>and</strong> also act as watchdogs.<br />

H. Lloyd-Jones, tr., Aeschylus. Oresteia. Agamemnon (Berkeley, 1979) 27, says, for example, that: “<strong>in</strong> the<br />

Middle East watchdogs still sometimes spend the night on the ro<strong>of</strong>”; E. Fraenkel, Aeschylus. Agamemnon II<br />

(Oxford, 1950) 4, suggests, on the basis <strong>of</strong> ethnographic research, that “<strong>in</strong> Egypt <strong>and</strong> the Sudan the village<br />

dogs prefer to lie at night on the ro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the houses or huts even when they are not flat.” Dogs spend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

159


Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the posture <strong>of</strong> the watchman on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the palace, Aeschylus<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that he is ly<strong>in</strong>g a1gkaqen (A. 3) like a dog (kuno&j di/khn, A. 3). In his attempt to<br />

visualize the actual posture to which a1gkaqen corresponds, Eduard Fraenkel recognizes,<br />

first, the etymological connection between this term <strong>and</strong> the word a)gkw&n, which means<br />

not only the elbow, but the crook <strong>of</strong> the arm with<strong>in</strong> the elbow. 237 For this reason, he<br />

suggests that “the watchman (like the watchdog) lies as it were thrust forward ‘<strong>in</strong>to his<br />

arms,’ with the upper part <strong>of</strong> his body between them,” or more precisely, “[he] is ly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

flat on his elbows, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> this position he is like the dog <strong>in</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> watch<strong>in</strong>g some<br />

particular object with his head on his paws. In this position the watchman with the least<br />

trouble has the widest look-out.” 238<br />

time on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> a house is an image that can still be found <strong>in</strong> many places around the world. A recent<br />

article published <strong>in</strong> the local newspaper <strong>of</strong> Goldsboro, North Carol<strong>in</strong>a, features the story <strong>of</strong> a dog that spent<br />

considerable time on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> its owners’ house <strong>and</strong> acted like a sentry for the entire neighborhood. <strong>The</strong><br />

city received compla<strong>in</strong>ts from a neighbor, who expressed concerns regard<strong>in</strong>g the sanitary aspects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dog’s liv<strong>in</strong>g on the ro<strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> wondered if its owners could face legal repercussions for allow<strong>in</strong>g this to<br />

happen. <strong>Animal</strong> control <strong>of</strong>ficers clarified that there is no law aga<strong>in</strong>st dogs on the ro<strong>of</strong>. B. Arntsen, Dog On<br />

<strong>The</strong> Ro<strong>of</strong>…No Law Aga<strong>in</strong>st It. http://www.newsargus.com/news/archives/2004/12/31/<br />

dog_on_the_ro<strong>of</strong>no_law_aga<strong>in</strong>st_it/<strong>in</strong>dex.shtml. Also for the presence <strong>of</strong> dogs on the ro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> houses as a<br />

common phenomenon <strong>in</strong> Mexico, see D. Bower, Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Mexico: <strong>The</strong> Friends <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>.<br />

http://ez<strong>in</strong>earticles.com/?Liv<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>-Mexico:-<strong>The</strong>-Friends-<strong>of</strong>-<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>&id=258240.<br />

237 Fraenkel, Aeschylus. Agamemnon 4.<br />

238 Fraenkel, Aeschylus. Agamemnon 4. He also draws evidence from the material record by suggest<strong>in</strong>g (4-<br />

5) that, the scene <strong>of</strong> “dogs on ro<strong>of</strong>” is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the figures <strong>of</strong> two dogs embellished with ivory <strong>and</strong><br />

depicted on a wooden box found <strong>in</strong> shaft grave V <strong>of</strong> Grave Circle A <strong>in</strong> Mycenae (1580-1500 B.C.). B.<br />

Schweitzer, “Hunde auf dem Dach,” AM 55 (1930) 107-118, pl. XXIX, notes that the box is made <strong>of</strong><br />

sycamore wood found <strong>in</strong> Egypt, <strong>and</strong> that its iconographic theme is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Early Dynastic material.<br />

Schweitzer also proposes that the technique <strong>of</strong> the sides <strong>of</strong> the box be<strong>in</strong>g jo<strong>in</strong>ed together is identical to the<br />

Egyptian technique <strong>of</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g wood <strong>and</strong> ivory. For these reasons, he holds that the box was imported<br />

from Egypt; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> this object, see also A. W. Persson, New Tombs at Dendra near Midea<br />

(Oxford, 1942) 179-181, fig. 131.1. <strong>The</strong> posture that Fraenkel attributes to the watchman, <strong>in</strong> particular the<br />

suggestion that he is ly<strong>in</strong>g flat on his elbows like a watchdog br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d the recl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g dog depicted on<br />

the lid <strong>of</strong> an early M<strong>in</strong>oan II (2400 B.C.) pyxis <strong>in</strong> green steatite that was found <strong>in</strong> Grave I <strong>in</strong> the cemetery at<br />

Mochlos. <strong>The</strong> dog serves as the h<strong>and</strong>le <strong>of</strong> the pyxis: S. Mar<strong>in</strong>atos, Crete <strong>and</strong> Mycenae (New York, 1960)<br />

pl. 6, 116; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the Mochlos cemetery, see J. S. Soles, “<strong>The</strong> Prepalatial Cemeteries at<br />

Mochlos <strong>and</strong> Gournia <strong>and</strong> the House Tombs <strong>of</strong> Bronze Age Crete,” Hesperia Supplement (1992). A<br />

steatite pyxis dat<strong>in</strong>g to the same period <strong>and</strong> depict<strong>in</strong>g the same figure <strong>of</strong> a recl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g dog on its lid was also<br />

found <strong>in</strong> a tomb <strong>in</strong> the Gorge <strong>of</strong> the Dead at Zakros. For this pyxis, <strong>and</strong> the suggestion that both this <strong>and</strong> the<br />

one from Mochlos were made by the same craftsman, see N. Platon, Zakros. <strong>The</strong> Discovery <strong>of</strong> a Lost<br />

Palace on Ancient Crete (New York, 1971) 68-69.<br />

160


In contrast to this suggestion, John Denniston <strong>and</strong> Denys Page ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that<br />

a1gkaqen, which they translate as “up above,” def<strong>in</strong>es ste/gaij (A. 3), which means<br />

“ro<strong>of</strong>s,” <strong>and</strong> the two should be translated together as mean<strong>in</strong>g “on the ro<strong>of</strong>.” 239 <strong>The</strong>y<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that a1gkaqen “could not possibly describe a man rest<strong>in</strong>g on his own arms (or<br />

elbows); moreover a man <strong>in</strong> such an attitude would not noticeably resemble a dog; nor<br />

would it be possible to adopt a more uncomfortable posture for observ<strong>in</strong>g the stars.” 240<br />

Although reasonable, this suggestion does not rule out that <strong>of</strong> Fraenkel.<br />

<strong>The</strong> watchman’s statement that he keeps a look-out like a dog (kuno&j di/khn, A. 3)<br />

suggests that vigilance was a recognized quality <strong>of</strong> the animal. <strong>The</strong> capacity for<br />

vigilance, however, was an essential feature <strong>of</strong> a type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence known as mh~tij <strong>and</strong><br />

thought to be possessed by gods (e.g., Zeus, Il. 8.22; 17.339), exceptional mortals (e.g.,<br />

Nestor, Il. 7.324; 14.107, Odysseus, Il. 11.482; Od. 3.163; 13.293), craftsmen (e.g.,<br />

woodcutters, helmsmen, charioteers, Il. 315-18), l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> sea animals (e.g., fox, Op. Hal.<br />

2.107-118; starfish, urch<strong>in</strong>, Op. Hal. 2.182; 225; octopus, Op. Hal. 2.408), <strong>and</strong> skillful<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals, <strong>in</strong> general. 241 In the Iliad, for example, Nestor advises his son, Antilochus,<br />

who competes <strong>in</strong> a chariot race, that <strong>in</strong> order to outdo his rivals, he should employ the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> mh~tij by keep<strong>in</strong>g his eye (dokeu&ei) on the man who leads him <strong>in</strong> the race (Il.<br />

23.320). In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the fact that Aeschylus refers to the vigilance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dog by the term di/khn (A. 3), which is a derivative <strong>of</strong> the Homeric term dokeu&ei, <strong>in</strong><br />

239 J. D. Denniston <strong>and</strong> D. Page, Aeschylus. Agamemnon (Oxford, 1957) 65-66.<br />

240 Denniston <strong>and</strong> Page, Aeschylus. Agamemnon 65-66.<br />

241 For the discussion <strong>of</strong> vigilance as a fundamental quality <strong>of</strong> mh~tij, see Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Intelligence 27-29; also 29, n. 8, for the ancient Greek belief that “every animal with mh~tij is a liv<strong>in</strong>g eye<br />

which never closes or even bl<strong>in</strong>ks.” Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the authors (2), additional levels on which this type <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>telligence operates are: the skills <strong>of</strong> a basket-maker, <strong>of</strong> a weaver, <strong>of</strong> a carpenter, the mastery <strong>of</strong> a<br />

navigator, the flair <strong>of</strong> a politician, the experienced eye <strong>of</strong> a doctor, <strong>and</strong> also the beguil<strong>in</strong>g rhetorical<br />

illusionism <strong>of</strong> the sophists.<br />

161


comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the view <strong>of</strong> animals as possessors <strong>of</strong> mh~tij suggests that both the<br />

playwright <strong>and</strong> his audience considered the dog an animal endowed with mh~tij.<br />

Vigilance aside, how this concept might have further operated <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

image <strong>of</strong> the watchman to that <strong>of</strong> the dog is not made explicit <strong>in</strong> the text. Rather the<br />

mh~tij <strong>of</strong> the watchman appears hidden <strong>in</strong> practical behavior: the cont<strong>in</strong>uous shift<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

his bed <strong>in</strong> order to avoid fall<strong>in</strong>g asleep. 242 This behavior fits well with the fact that he is a<br />

veteran <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>ession (year-long watch), thus justly one <strong>of</strong> those <strong>in</strong>dividuals endowed<br />

with mh~tij. With<strong>in</strong> this implicit context, Aeschylus highlights next the connection <strong>of</strong> the<br />

watchman to the dog through the use <strong>of</strong> explicit vocabulary. He has the watchman<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to his bed as eu)nh&n (A. 13). 243 As Heath ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, “this word (<strong>and</strong> others with<br />

the same root) had a long tradition <strong>of</strong> metaphorical application to the animal world.<br />

Homer [for example] uses it six times <strong>of</strong> animal beds, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g once <strong>of</strong> a nest.” 244<br />

This reference <strong>of</strong> the watchman to his bed as that <strong>of</strong> an animal, his adoption <strong>of</strong><br />

can<strong>in</strong>e behavior as evidenced by his position on the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the palace, the resemblance <strong>of</strong><br />

his posture to that <strong>of</strong> a dog, <strong>and</strong> also his vigilance <strong>and</strong> possible mh~tij, all underscore<br />

242 Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence 3, emphasize that one <strong>of</strong> the difficulties <strong>in</strong> unlock<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

semantics <strong>of</strong> mh~tij stems from the fact that the concept “is never clearly revealed <strong>in</strong> a theoretical work that<br />

aims to def<strong>in</strong>e it. It always appears more or less below the surface, immersed as it were <strong>in</strong> practical<br />

operations which, even when they use it, show no concern to make its nature explicit or to justify its<br />

procedures.”<br />

243 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek term for “bed” is kli/nh not eu)nh&n; for a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the term kli/nh <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical sources, see D. Andrianou, “Chairs, Beds, <strong>and</strong> Tables: Evidence for<br />

Furnished Interiors <strong>in</strong> Hellenistic <strong>Greece</strong>,” Hesperia 75 (2006) 232-233.<br />

244 Heath, <strong>The</strong> Talk<strong>in</strong>g Greeks 225, no. 26, does not <strong>in</strong>clude this example from the watchman’s speech <strong>in</strong><br />

his discussion <strong>of</strong> the term. He demonstrates his po<strong>in</strong>t, however, by referr<strong>in</strong>g to specific examples from the<br />

Homeric poems. In the Iliad, the term is used especially <strong>of</strong> a deer’s lair (2.115, 15.580, <strong>and</strong> 22.190). In the<br />

Odyssey, the same term denotes the nests <strong>of</strong> owls, falcons, sea crows (5.65), <strong>and</strong> a pig-pen (14.14); also the<br />

places, where Menelaus <strong>and</strong> his men, disguised as seals, wait for Proteus are called eu)na~j (4.438).<br />

Aeschylus’s veer<strong>in</strong>g towards Homeric language should not be surpris<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>ce there is ancient testimony<br />

that he viewed his works as “slices from Homer’s great banquets” (Ath. Deipn. 8.347e) <strong>and</strong> recognized<br />

how beneficial the poets <strong>of</strong> the past like Homer, Hesiod, Orpheus, <strong>and</strong> Musaeus had been (Ar. Frogs 1030-<br />

1036). For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> the tendency <strong>of</strong> Aeschylus to adapt words <strong>and</strong> images to his own<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentions, see M. M. Lee, “<strong>The</strong> Myth <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Peplos” (diss. Bryn Mawr College, 1999) 79.<br />

162


Aeschylus’s <strong>in</strong>tention to liken the watchman to a watchdog. Such <strong>in</strong>tention suggests that<br />

Aeschylus considered his audience not only familiar with the behavior <strong>and</strong> qualities <strong>of</strong> a<br />

watchdog, but also ready to “th<strong>in</strong>k with a watchdog <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d,” 245 evidence that, <strong>in</strong> turn,<br />

suggests the centrality <strong>of</strong> this can<strong>in</strong>e role <strong>in</strong> contemporary thought.<br />

Further evidence <strong>of</strong> this centrality is seen <strong>in</strong> another passage from Aeschylus’s<br />

Agamemnon, which has a reference to the role <strong>and</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog as guardian <strong>of</strong> the<br />

house. Clytemnestra has just found out that Agamemnon is on his way back to Argos<br />

from Troy. While dictat<strong>in</strong>g to a herald a message she wants delivered to him, she relates<br />

her behavior as her husb<strong>and</strong>’s regent:<br />

Take this message away to my husb<strong>and</strong>, to come as soon as possible;<br />

he is the city’s beloved darl<strong>in</strong>g. As to his wife,<br />

I wish he may f<strong>in</strong>d her when he comes just as faithful <strong>in</strong> his home<br />

as the one he left beh<strong>in</strong>d, the house’s watchdog (ku&na) true to him while<br />

hostile to ill-wishers <strong>and</strong> similar <strong>in</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g else,<br />

with no seal broken <strong>in</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> time. (A. 604-610) [7]<br />

Clytemnestra clearly states the contrast<strong>in</strong>g behavior she assumed dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Agamemnon’s absence. She rema<strong>in</strong>ed faithful to her duty <strong>of</strong> guard<strong>in</strong>g the palace <strong>and</strong> its<br />

affairs as a dog is faithful to its master. 246 Like a dog, she also kept enemies at bay by<br />

245 <strong>The</strong> phase is an adaptation <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> Lévi-Strauss, Totemism 126, that “animals are good to th<strong>in</strong>k<br />

with.” For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the marg<strong>in</strong>alization <strong>of</strong> the animals <strong>of</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d, that is, animals <strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

dreams, games, stories, superstitions <strong>and</strong> the language itself, <strong>in</strong> modern society, see J. Berger, About<br />

Look<strong>in</strong>g (New York, 1980) 13.<br />

246 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> Clytemnestra’s loyalty to the affairs <strong>of</strong> the palace, see A. Betensky, “Aeschylus’<br />

Oresteia: <strong>The</strong> Power <strong>of</strong> Clytemnestra,” Ramus 7 (1978) 15. <strong>The</strong> image <strong>of</strong> the loyal dog that Clytemnestra<br />

claims for herself is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Argos, Odysseus’ faithful dog, described <strong>in</strong> the Iliad (1.291-17.327) as<br />

an old character, who has endured discomfort <strong>and</strong> neglect—he is full <strong>of</strong> ticks <strong>and</strong> lies on a heap <strong>of</strong> dung—<br />

but waits patiently for a sight <strong>of</strong> his master. Despite his wretched condition, Argos rema<strong>in</strong>s alert, a<br />

characteristic <strong>in</strong>dicated by his keen sense <strong>of</strong> smell that actually enables him to identify Odysseus after<br />

twenty years <strong>of</strong> absence. Shortly after this episode Argos dies. It is actually the tim<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> his death, which<br />

follows his sight <strong>of</strong> Odysseus, that is presented by Homer as the embodiment <strong>of</strong> this dog’s loyalty to his<br />

master. Argos was also the name <strong>of</strong> the ever-watchful giant with one hundred eyes (hence his epithet<br />

Panoptes, “All-See<strong>in</strong>g”), set by Hera as guardian <strong>of</strong> Io, a priestess <strong>of</strong> Hera <strong>in</strong> Argos, whom Zeus seduced<br />

<strong>and</strong> transformed <strong>in</strong>to a heifer <strong>in</strong> order to escape detection from Hera. Argos was killed by Hermes (hence<br />

his epithet Argeiphontes, “Slayer <strong>of</strong> Argos”). Aeschylus refers to the myth <strong>of</strong> Argos <strong>and</strong> Io <strong>in</strong> his<br />

Prometheus Bound (566-574, 640-680), <strong>and</strong> Suppliant Women (292-315). For the suggestion that the myth<br />

163


e<strong>in</strong>g hostile to them. 247 Her behavior is consistent with the ancient Greek ethical<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that one’s duty is to help one’s friends <strong>and</strong> harm one’s enemies, which is also<br />

based on a contrast. 248 Clytemnestra takes pride <strong>in</strong> her hav<strong>in</strong>g behaved like a guard<br />

dog. 249 Such behavior is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it suggests that loyalty to the house a dog<br />

guarded <strong>and</strong> hostility towards strangers were two oppos<strong>in</strong>g aspects <strong>of</strong> behavior for which<br />

the animal was known. Like the watchman, Clytemnestra uses figurative language to<br />

convey the aff<strong>in</strong>ity between her behavior <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> a dog. In this way, it becomes clear<br />

once aga<strong>in</strong> that fifth-century Athenian society observed the dog carefully <strong>and</strong> used its<br />

behavior as a model for describ<strong>in</strong>g human behavior.<br />

Further evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Classical</strong> Greek knowledge <strong>of</strong> the contrast<strong>in</strong>g<br />

behaviors <strong>of</strong> the guard dog is found <strong>in</strong> a passage from Plato’s Republic. Here, two<br />

persons speak <strong>of</strong> the dog as an exemplar for the guardian <strong>of</strong> the state:<br />

“It may be observed <strong>in</strong> other animals, but especially <strong>in</strong> that which we likened to<br />

the guardian. You surely have observed <strong>in</strong> well-bred hounds that their natural<br />

disposition is to be most gentle to their familiars <strong>and</strong> those whom they recognize,<br />

but the contrary to those whom they do not know.” “I am aware <strong>of</strong> that.” “<strong>The</strong><br />

was known to Homer <strong>and</strong> Hesiod, see W. Burkert, tr. P. B<strong>in</strong>g, Homo Necans: <strong>The</strong> Anthropology <strong>of</strong> Ancient<br />

Greek Sacrificial Ritual <strong>and</strong> Myth (Berkeley, 1983) 164, n. 14.<br />

247 This type <strong>of</strong> behavior is also alluded to <strong>in</strong> a short passage from Hesiod’s Works <strong>and</strong> Days (604-605),<br />

which conta<strong>in</strong>s a recommendation to the farmer <strong>in</strong> regards to his guard dog: the farmer should be k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong><br />

generous with the daily portions <strong>of</strong> food provided to his dog; otherwise the animal will not be able to avail<br />

potential robbers.<br />

248 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this idea be<strong>in</strong>g central to traditional Greek morality, as evidenced by the tragedies <strong>of</strong><br />

Sophocles, see M. W. Blundell, Help<strong>in</strong>g Friends <strong>and</strong> Harm<strong>in</strong>g Enemies. A Study <strong>in</strong> Sophocles <strong>and</strong> Greek<br />

Ethics (New York <strong>and</strong> New Rochelle, 1989); L. G. Mitchell <strong>and</strong> P. J. Rhodes, “Friends <strong>and</strong> Enemies <strong>in</strong><br />

Athenian Politics,” GR 43 (1996) 11-30, for the place <strong>of</strong> friendship <strong>in</strong> fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-century political<br />

activity <strong>in</strong> Athens, <strong>and</strong> also for that <strong>of</strong> enmity <strong>in</strong> politics <strong>of</strong> the classical period; <strong>and</strong> also D. Konstan,<br />

“Anger, Hatred, <strong>and</strong> Genocide <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” Common Knowledge 13 (2007) 170-187, who explores<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> hostile emotions, especially anger <strong>and</strong> hatred, as morally defensible <strong>in</strong> daily life <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> time <strong>of</strong><br />

war <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>.<br />

249 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> Clytemnestra’s reference to herself as a guard dog <strong>and</strong> the wider function <strong>of</strong> this<br />

image <strong>in</strong> the plot, particularly the fact that, by murder<strong>in</strong>g Agamemnon, she actually proved to do the<br />

opposite <strong>of</strong> what a guard dog would do, see R. M. Harriott, “<strong>The</strong> Argive Elders, the Discern<strong>in</strong>g Shepherd<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Fawn<strong>in</strong>g Dog: Mislead<strong>in</strong>g Communication <strong>in</strong> the Agamemnon,” CQ 32 (1982) 15-16.<br />

164


th<strong>in</strong>g is possible then,” said I, “<strong>and</strong> it is not an unnatural requirement that we are<br />

look<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>in</strong> our guardian.” “It seems not.” (Resp. 375d-375e) [147]<br />

Plato’s <strong>in</strong>terlocutors appear to be well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with the behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog as a<br />

guardian: gentle toward familiar faces <strong>and</strong> aggressive toward strangers. 250 <strong>The</strong>y know<br />

that such a contrast<strong>in</strong>g behavior was dictated by circumstance, yet they believe that it was<br />

not unrelated to the natural disposition <strong>of</strong> the animal. <strong>The</strong> discussion therefore sheds<br />

light on the way observation <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> ideas about the dog assisted <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> its<br />

behavior with<strong>in</strong> fourth-century Greek society. What the discussion does not reveal,<br />

however, is whether the contrast <strong>in</strong> this behavior cast the dog <strong>in</strong> a negative light.<br />

We get a sense that it did from an earlier text, a fragment <strong>of</strong> Sophocles that<br />

preserves the follow<strong>in</strong>g exclamation: “You fawn on men as you bite them <strong>and</strong> are a<br />

treacherous dog” (885 Radt) [186]. <strong>The</strong> speaker addresses a dog directly, po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out<br />

the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> two acts <strong>in</strong> its behavior that occur simultaneously <strong>and</strong> are conflict<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

fawn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> bit<strong>in</strong>g. 251 <strong>The</strong> regard <strong>of</strong> this comb<strong>in</strong>ation as <strong>in</strong>appropriate is emphasized by<br />

the characterization <strong>of</strong> the dog as treacherous. <strong>The</strong> term implies that deception,<br />

untrustworth<strong>in</strong>ess, <strong>and</strong> danger were all aspects <strong>of</strong> this dog’s <strong>in</strong>appropriate behavior, but it<br />

does not <strong>in</strong>dicate whether such behavior was considered typical <strong>of</strong> all dogs. What<br />

strengthens the last possibility is the well-known behavior <strong>of</strong> Cerberus, the loyal<br />

250 This type <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior features also <strong>in</strong> the Odyssey (16.4-16.10), where Eumaeus’s watchdogs<br />

fawn on Telemachos, whom they already know, but (14.29-14.30) they are aggressive towards Odysseus,<br />

whom they have never seen before.<br />

251 Modern studies on the behavior <strong>of</strong> dogs guard<strong>in</strong>g livestock also mark the ambiguity <strong>of</strong> their behavior.<br />

As R. Copp<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>and</strong> R. Schneider, “Evolution <strong>of</strong> Work<strong>in</strong>g Dogs,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog: Its<br />

Evolution, Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with People (Cambridge, 1995) state: “guard<strong>in</strong>g dogs protect by<br />

disrupt<strong>in</strong>g predators by means <strong>of</strong> behavior that is ambiguous or contextually <strong>in</strong>appropriate: bark<strong>in</strong>g, tail<br />

wagg<strong>in</strong>g, social greet<strong>in</strong>g, play behavior, <strong>and</strong>, occasionally, aggression.” D. McFarl<strong>and</strong>, ed., <strong>The</strong> Oxford<br />

Companion to <strong>Animal</strong> Behavior (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1982) 15-16, speaks <strong>of</strong> ambivalent behavior <strong>in</strong><br />

animals as “typical <strong>of</strong> a conflict situation <strong>in</strong> which an animal has simultaneous tendencies to perform two<br />

<strong>in</strong>compatible activities,” <strong>and</strong> also “<strong>of</strong> threat situations <strong>in</strong> which there is generally a conflict between attack<br />

<strong>and</strong> escape.”<br />

165


watchdog <strong>of</strong> Hades, whom Hesiod <strong>in</strong> the <strong>The</strong>ogony (769-773) describes as a creature that<br />

accepts all newcomers to the underworld by fawn<strong>in</strong>g his ears <strong>and</strong> tail, but devours anyone<br />

who attempts to escape. Monstrous Cerberus does so, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> merely bit<strong>in</strong>g, thus<br />

show<strong>in</strong>g the extreme to which he takes an aspect <strong>of</strong> what must have been otherwise<br />

known as typical can<strong>in</strong>e behavior.<br />

As mentioned above, by call<strong>in</strong>g this dog treacherous, the speaker <strong>of</strong> the fragment<br />

highlights the animal’s ability to deceive. This ability is important, for it endows the<br />

animal aga<strong>in</strong> with the power <strong>of</strong> mh~tij. As Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant suggest, deceit is a<br />

rul<strong>in</strong>g constituent <strong>of</strong> this ancient Greek concept:<br />

Mh~tij is itself a power <strong>of</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> deceit. It operates through disguise. In<br />

order to dupe its victim it assumes a form which masks, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> reveal<strong>in</strong>g its<br />

true be<strong>in</strong>g. In mh~tij appearance <strong>and</strong> reality no longer correspond to one another<br />

but st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> contrast, produc<strong>in</strong>g an effect <strong>of</strong> illusion, a)pa&th, which beguiles the<br />

adversary <strong>in</strong>to error <strong>and</strong> leaves him as bemused by his defeat as by the spells <strong>of</strong> a<br />

magician. 252<br />

In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the ability <strong>of</strong> the dog to exhibit contrast<strong>in</strong>g behavior, as<br />

evidenced by its simultaneous fawn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> bit<strong>in</strong>g, makes it a liv<strong>in</strong>g trap. It is thus<br />

reasonable to suggest that this fragment is likely the result <strong>of</strong> this apprehension on the<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the speaker.<br />

Evidence from comedy further highlights <strong>Classical</strong> Greek knowledge <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contrast<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the guard dog, particularly its aggression toward strangers. In<br />

Lysistrata (411 B.C.), Aristophanes has the leader <strong>of</strong> the chorus <strong>of</strong> women announce that<br />

poor citizens should feel free to visit her house <strong>and</strong> receive food supplies. <strong>The</strong>y should<br />

be wary, though, <strong>of</strong> the dog by her door:<br />

252 Dietenne <strong>and</strong> Vernant, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence 21.<br />

166


If anyone’s out <strong>of</strong> bread<br />

but has slaves to feed<br />

<strong>and</strong> lots <strong>of</strong> little kids,<br />

you can get flour from my house—<br />

puny gra<strong>in</strong>s, true,<br />

but a pound <strong>of</strong> them grow up to be<br />

a loaf that’s very hearty to see.<br />

And <strong>of</strong> the poor are welcome<br />

to come to my house with sacks<br />

<strong>and</strong> bags to carry the flour away;<br />

my houseboy will pour it <strong>in</strong> for them.<br />

A warn<strong>in</strong>g though:<br />

Don’t come to my door—<br />

beware <strong>of</strong> the watchdog there!<br />

(Lys. 1203-1215) [41]<br />

<strong>The</strong> leader <strong>of</strong> the chorus expects her dog to exhibit aggressive behavior towards<br />

unfamiliar visitors to her house. Thus, she not only warns these visitors, but also advises<br />

them to stay away from the animal. Her warn<strong>in</strong>g suggests observation <strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

can<strong>in</strong>e behavior, <strong>and</strong> as such, it parallels similar knowledge seen previously <strong>in</strong> the works<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aeschylus, Sophocles, Plato, <strong>and</strong> Aristotle. Unlike the watchman <strong>in</strong> the Agamemnon,<br />

who stood on a ro<strong>of</strong> like a dog, <strong>and</strong> the dog <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s Great Ethics that chose a ro<strong>of</strong><br />

as its sleep<strong>in</strong>g place, this dog st<strong>and</strong>s by a door, thus add<strong>in</strong>g to the variety <strong>of</strong> domestic<br />

spots associated with the animal <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> times. 253 It is uncerta<strong>in</strong>, however, whether<br />

253 <strong>The</strong> earliest texts that attest to dogs’ guard<strong>in</strong>g doors <strong>of</strong> houses are the Homeric epics: <strong>in</strong> the Iliad<br />

(22.66-22.66), Priam is afraid that the dogs that he raised to guard the gates <strong>of</strong> his palace, will rip him <strong>in</strong><br />

front <strong>of</strong> his doorway. Also <strong>in</strong> the Odyssey (7.91) Homer describes a pair <strong>of</strong> gold <strong>and</strong> silver dogs as flank<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the door <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Alk<strong>in</strong>oos. Turn<strong>in</strong>g to material evidence, the warn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the speaker <strong>of</strong> the chorus<br />

is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription CAVE CANEM (Beware the Dog) from a threshold mosaic from the<br />

vestibule <strong>of</strong> the House <strong>of</strong> the Tragic Poet <strong>in</strong> Pompeii. <strong>The</strong> mosaic depicts a large black dog attached by a<br />

collar to a cha<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> animal is <strong>in</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> menac<strong>in</strong>g the unwary visitor. <strong>The</strong> depiction is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong><br />

an episode from Petronius’ Satyricon (29) where Encolpius upon enter<strong>in</strong>g the house <strong>of</strong> Trimalchio mistakes<br />

for real a dog tethered by a cha<strong>in</strong>, pa<strong>in</strong>ted on the wall to the left <strong>of</strong> the entrance, <strong>and</strong> accompanied by the<br />

warn<strong>in</strong>g: beware the dog. <strong>The</strong> layout <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>in</strong> Pompeii dates to the second century B.C., but its<br />

decoration is later, that is, shortly after the earthquake <strong>of</strong> A.D. 62: M. Ranieri Panetta, ed., Pompeii. <strong>The</strong><br />

History, Life <strong>and</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> the Buried City (Tur<strong>in</strong>, 2004) 342; Similarly, the entry to another Pompeian House,<br />

that <strong>of</strong> Cuspius Pansa, is decorated with a mosaic that depicts a crouch<strong>in</strong>g guard<strong>in</strong>g dog wear<strong>in</strong>g a collar<br />

that is attached to a cha<strong>in</strong>, additionally attached to one <strong>of</strong> the leaves <strong>of</strong> a half-opened door: Ranieri Panetta,<br />

Pompeii 312; Another mosaic depict<strong>in</strong>g a watchdog comes from the entrance <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> L. Caecilius<br />

Jucundus also <strong>in</strong> Pompeii: Jashemski, <strong>The</strong> Gardens <strong>of</strong> Pompeii 102, fig. 161; F<strong>in</strong>ally, a guard dog wear<strong>in</strong>g<br />

167


the door by which this dog stood belonged to the ma<strong>in</strong> entrance <strong>of</strong> the house or to any <strong>of</strong><br />

the rooms <strong>in</strong>side. 254 As a result, it is not possible to detect where exactly <strong>in</strong> the house this<br />

dog was expected to be found. 255<br />

a jeweled collar is depicted on the wall <strong>of</strong> the front room <strong>of</strong> the shop <strong>of</strong> Sotericus on the Via dell’<br />

Abbondanza <strong>in</strong> Pompeii: A. K<strong>in</strong>g, “Mammals. Evidence from Wall Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>Sculpture</strong>, Mosaics, Faunal<br />

Rema<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> Ancient Literary Sources,” <strong>in</strong> W. F. Jashemski <strong>and</strong> F. G. Meyer, eds., <strong>The</strong> Natural History <strong>of</strong><br />

Pompeii (Cambridge, 2002) 412, fig. 340. For the depiction <strong>of</strong> a dog’s collar on a red-figured aryballos<br />

dated to 490-480 B.C., <strong>and</strong> found <strong>in</strong> a tomb (no. 1099) dur<strong>in</strong>g rescue excavations at the Kerameikos Station<br />

<strong>in</strong> Athens, see E. Baziotopoulou-Valavani, “Red-Figure Aryballos,” <strong>in</strong> L. Parlama <strong>and</strong> N. C. Stampolidis,<br />

eds., Athens: <strong>The</strong> City beneath the City. Antiquities from the Metropolitan Railway Excavations (Athens,<br />

2001) 309, no. 311. Also for the bronze studs <strong>of</strong> a collar found <strong>in</strong> a dog’s grave (no. 82) that was uncovered<br />

<strong>in</strong> rescue excavations at the Parliament Square <strong>in</strong> Athens, <strong>and</strong> dates to the transitional period from the first<br />

to the second centuries A.D., see N. C. Stampolidis, “Bronze Studs from the Collar <strong>of</strong> a Dog,” <strong>in</strong> Parlama<br />

<strong>and</strong> Stampolidis, eds., Athens: <strong>The</strong> City beneath the City 177, no. 164 <strong>and</strong> 157, fig. 10.<br />

254 Archaeological evidence suggests that the spatial arrangement <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek house<br />

corresponded to a structure with a s<strong>in</strong>gle street entrance lead<strong>in</strong>g, sometimes though a lobby (pro&quron)<br />

with a second door, to a court through which access was ga<strong>in</strong>ed to the rema<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> the house. As L. C.<br />

Nevett, “Between Urban <strong>and</strong> Rural: House-Form <strong>and</strong> Social Relations <strong>in</strong> Attic Villages <strong>and</strong> Deme<br />

Centers,” <strong>in</strong> B. A. Aunt <strong>and</strong> L. C. Nevett, eds., Ancient Greek Houses <strong>and</strong> Households. Chronological,<br />

Regional, <strong>and</strong> Social Diversity (Philadelphia, 2005) 84, suggests: “Excavation both at Athens <strong>and</strong> at other<br />

large settlements has revealed high numbers <strong>of</strong> houses follow<strong>in</strong>g a relatively st<strong>and</strong>ardized pattern <strong>of</strong><br />

organization, the s<strong>in</strong>gle entrance, courtyard house. <strong>The</strong> only street door <strong>in</strong> such houses generally opens<br />

onto an open central court, which <strong>in</strong> turn provides access to various rooms, their entrances normally shaded<br />

by a portico (a prostas, pastas, or peristyle). ” Similarly, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> reference to the spatial organization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> houses excavated on the north slope <strong>of</strong> the Areopagus <strong>in</strong> Athens, B. Tsakirgis, “Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

Work<strong>in</strong>g Around the Athenian Agora: A Prelim<strong>in</strong>ary Case Study <strong>of</strong> Three Houses,” <strong>in</strong> Aunt <strong>and</strong> Nevett,<br />

eds., Ancient Greek Houses <strong>and</strong> Households 69, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that a st<strong>and</strong>ard feature <strong>of</strong> these houses is a<br />

roughly centrally placed courtyard usually entered directly from the street, rather than from a vestibule.<br />

<strong>The</strong> same site has also provided an example <strong>of</strong> a fourth-century house with a s<strong>in</strong>gle entrance lead<strong>in</strong>g to a<br />

lobby with an <strong>in</strong>terior door lead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the court: L. C. Nevett, “Gender Relations <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

Household: <strong>The</strong> Archaeological Evidence,” BSA 90 (1995) 376, n. 62.<br />

255 It is reasonable to assume that, when the leader <strong>of</strong> the chorus advises her visitors not to approach the dog<br />

by her door, she does not mean the ma<strong>in</strong> entrance to her house; otherwise her <strong>in</strong>vitation does not make any<br />

sense s<strong>in</strong>ce it presupposes that these persons are welcome to her house, but advised not to approach its<br />

ma<strong>in</strong> entrance. Additional evidence that she is not referr<strong>in</strong>g to the ma<strong>in</strong> entrance derives from the sequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>structions she relates: first, visitors are welcome to her house, second, her slave will assist them <strong>in</strong><br />

pour<strong>in</strong>g flour <strong>in</strong> bags, <strong>and</strong> third, they should be cautious about the dog by her door. <strong>The</strong>se successive<br />

phases <strong>of</strong> their visit, especially their assistance by the slave, presuppose the physical presence <strong>of</strong> visitors<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the house. This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g fits well with the suggestion that the courtyard <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek house was the place to which visitors were admitted first. As L. C. Nevett, House <strong>and</strong> Society <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Ancient Greek World (Cambridge, 1999) 70, states the spatial arrangement <strong>of</strong> the court <strong>in</strong> the middle <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek house marks it as part <strong>of</strong> the “public” part <strong>of</strong> the house, the center <strong>of</strong> domestic life <strong>and</strong> the<br />

place that visitors would see first, s<strong>in</strong>ce it was the only area through which access to the other “public” part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the house—<strong>and</strong>ron—<strong>and</strong> the rema<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> the house could be atta<strong>in</strong>ed. At the <strong>Classical</strong> site <strong>of</strong> Olynthus,<br />

the “public” function <strong>of</strong> the courts <strong>of</strong> the excavated houses is corroborated by the use <strong>of</strong> colored walls,<br />

terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>es, <strong>and</strong> metal ornaments for decoration.<br />

168


c. Molossian Dogs as Guardians <strong>of</strong> the House: <strong>The</strong>ir Ferocity <strong>and</strong> Value<br />

<strong>The</strong> connection between guard dogs <strong>and</strong> aggressive behavior towards strangers is<br />

seen elsewhere <strong>in</strong> the comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes. In Women at the <strong>The</strong>smophoria (411<br />

B.C.) a specific breed—Molossian—is portrayed as exceptionally frighten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>,<br />

therefore, suitable for guard<strong>in</strong>g the house <strong>and</strong> its residents. <strong>The</strong> play opens <strong>in</strong> the middle<br />

day <strong>of</strong> the festival <strong>of</strong> the <strong>The</strong>smophoria. Female participants deliberate the punishment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the tragic poet Euripides, whose plays portray them as wicked <strong>in</strong>dividuals. A woman<br />

called Mica remarks how the behavior <strong>of</strong> men towards women has changed after be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>fluenced by Euripides’ sl<strong>and</strong>er aga<strong>in</strong>st women:<br />

<strong>The</strong>n aga<strong>in</strong>, because <strong>of</strong> him, they now keep close guard on us, putt<strong>in</strong>g seals <strong>and</strong><br />

bars on the doors <strong>of</strong> the women’s quarters, <strong>and</strong> on top <strong>of</strong> that they keep Molossian<br />

dogs to frighten the wits (mormolukei=a) out <strong>of</strong> seducers. (Th. 414-417) [45]<br />

Mica states clearly the use <strong>of</strong> Molossian dogs as guardians <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>in</strong> late fifth-<br />

century Athens. To her, these dogs are exceptionally frighten<strong>in</strong>g. As she says, Athenian<br />

men use these dogs as mormolukei=a <strong>in</strong> order to scare their wives’ lovers away from the<br />

house. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Alan Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, the term “mormolukei=a” means “bogies”; as<br />

such, it implies that the thought <strong>of</strong> a Molossian dog was as scary to an adult as the<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> a bogy was to a child. 256 From this evidence, it seems reasonable to conclude<br />

that Molossian dogs were highly aggressive toward strangers <strong>in</strong> the houses they guarded,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the fear this behavior evoked helped shape their image <strong>in</strong> contemporary thought.<br />

<strong>The</strong> comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes are not the only texts <strong>in</strong> which the aggressiveness<br />

<strong>of</strong> Molossian dogs is cited. An excerpt from Aelian’s On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong><br />

256<br />

A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong>smophoriazusae (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 8; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1994)<br />

184, l<strong>in</strong>e 417.<br />

169


(A.D. II-III) preserves an anecdote from the life <strong>of</strong> the Athenian poet Eupolis (a<br />

contemporary <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes), 257 that notes the death <strong>of</strong> a thief after hav<strong>in</strong>g been<br />

attacked by a Molossian dog:<br />

Augeas <strong>of</strong> Eleusis gave Eupolis, the writer <strong>of</strong> comedies, a hound <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e<br />

appearance, a Molossian, which Eupolis named after the donor. Now Augeas the<br />

hound, pampered <strong>in</strong> its feed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenced by long association with its master,<br />

came to love him. On one occasion a young fellow-slave <strong>of</strong> the name <strong>of</strong> Ephialtes<br />

stole some plays from Eupolis, <strong>and</strong> the theft did not pass unnoticed, for the hound<br />

saw him, fell upon him, <strong>and</strong> bit<strong>in</strong>g him mercilessly, killed him. Some time<br />

afterwards Eupolis ended his days <strong>in</strong> Aeg<strong>in</strong>a <strong>and</strong> was buried there, <strong>and</strong> the hound,<br />

howl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lament<strong>in</strong>g after the manner <strong>of</strong> dogs, let himself p<strong>in</strong>e away through<br />

grief <strong>and</strong> starvation <strong>and</strong>, disgusted with life, died soon after on the grave <strong>of</strong> the<br />

master that had fed it. And <strong>in</strong> memory <strong>of</strong> the sad event the place is named<br />

Hound’s Dirge. (NA 10.41) [5]<br />

<strong>The</strong> story <strong>of</strong> Augeas is a prime example <strong>of</strong> how the ferocity, beauty, <strong>and</strong> devotion <strong>of</strong><br />

Molossian dogs to their owners def<strong>in</strong>ed their image <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> times. Aelian relates that<br />

Augeas killed Ephialtes who dared to steal the plays <strong>of</strong> his owner. 258 To judge from this<br />

257 I. C. Storey, “Dat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Re-Dat<strong>in</strong>g Eupolis,” Phoenix 44 (1990) 7, 29, notes that the plays <strong>of</strong> Eupolis<br />

should be dated to the last quarter <strong>of</strong> the fifth century B.C. (i.e., 429-411 B.C.).<br />

258 That the ferocity <strong>of</strong> Molossian dogs <strong>and</strong> their valor as guards were two traits deeply engraved on the<br />

Roman m<strong>in</strong>d as well, is evident from a passage from Virgil (G. 403-408), where his advice on feed<strong>in</strong>g dogs<br />

conta<strong>in</strong>s the follow<strong>in</strong>g comment about Molossians: “feed swift Spartan whelps <strong>and</strong> fierce Molossians <strong>in</strong><br />

fatten<strong>in</strong>g whey. Never, with them on guard need you fear for your stalls a midnight thief, or onslaught <strong>of</strong><br />

wolves, or restless Spaniards <strong>in</strong> your rear.” A marble statue depict<strong>in</strong>g a Molossian dog, 1.18m tall, also<br />

known as “Alcibiades’ Dog” or “Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs’ Dog” was until recently (2001) <strong>in</strong> the possession <strong>of</strong> the family<br />

<strong>of</strong> Charles Duncombe <strong>of</strong> Duncombe Park <strong>in</strong> Yorkshire, Brita<strong>in</strong>. Considered a Roman copy <strong>of</strong> a Greek<br />

bronze orig<strong>in</strong>al, <strong>and</strong> dated to the middle <strong>of</strong> the third century B.C., the statue was allegedly discovered <strong>in</strong><br />

Rome <strong>in</strong> the 1750s, but, <strong>in</strong> reality, its provenance is unknown. It was restored by Bartolomeo Cavaceppi,<br />

the lead<strong>in</strong>g restorer <strong>of</strong> ancient sculpture <strong>in</strong> eighteenth-century Rome. For the history <strong>of</strong> the provenience <strong>of</strong><br />

the statue, see C. A. Picón, Bartolomeo Cavaceppi: Eighteenth Century Restorations <strong>of</strong> Ancient Marble<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> from English Private Collections. A Loan Exhibition at the Clarendon Gallery LTD (London,<br />

1983) 80-83, cat. no. 22. <strong>The</strong> statue was once on display <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> 1983 <strong>and</strong> as part <strong>of</strong> an exhibit<br />

organized <strong>in</strong> 1985 by the National Gallery <strong>of</strong> Art <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C.: C. A. Picón, “<strong>The</strong> Dog <strong>of</strong><br />

Alcibiades,” <strong>in</strong> G. Jackson-Stops, ed., <strong>The</strong> Treasure Houses <strong>of</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>: Five Hundred Years <strong>of</strong> Private<br />

Patronage <strong>and</strong> Art Collect<strong>in</strong>g (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1985) 318, cat. no. 243. In 2001, it was put up for<br />

sale by its owners, <strong>and</strong> the museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts <strong>in</strong> Houston, Texas expressed <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g it. <strong>The</strong><br />

same year <strong>and</strong> as part <strong>of</strong> a fundrais<strong>in</strong>g campaign to prevent it from be<strong>in</strong>g sold overseas, the British Museum<br />

exhibited the statue <strong>in</strong> its premises <strong>and</strong> managed to raise the required funds ($943,000) for its acquisition:<br />

British Museum, 2001, November. British Museum Acquires Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs Dog.<br />

http://www.thebritishmuseum.ac.uk/newsroom/archive 2001/jenn<strong>in</strong>gsdog.html. Two well-preserved<br />

marble statues, also depict<strong>in</strong>g Molossian dogs <strong>and</strong> thought to be Roman copies <strong>of</strong> Greek orig<strong>in</strong>als <strong>of</strong><br />

Hellenistic date (II B.C.), are currently on display <strong>in</strong> the Uffizi Gallery <strong>in</strong> Florence. G. Di Pasquale <strong>and</strong> F.<br />

Paolucci, Uffizi. <strong>The</strong> Ancient <strong>Sculpture</strong>s (Florence, 2001) 16, 69, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that these statues, whose height<br />

170


<strong>in</strong>cident, Aegeas was a ferocious Molossian dog. His behavior, however, is consistent<br />

with that <strong>of</strong> the watchdog that Clytemnestra claimed to be <strong>in</strong> the Agamemnon: helpful to<br />

his master <strong>and</strong> harmful to his enemies; it is, therefore, to be judged as appropriate <strong>and</strong><br />

worthy <strong>of</strong> praise rather that condemn. Aelian also relates that Aegeas was a beautiful dog<br />

that Eupolis received as a gift, suggest<strong>in</strong>g therefore that Molossian dogs were a highly<br />

esteemed breed <strong>in</strong> fifth-century Athens. Aelian records that the death <strong>of</strong> Aegeas, who<br />

was named after his donor, was a reaction to that <strong>of</strong> Eupolis, <strong>and</strong> thus evidence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

love <strong>and</strong> devotion <strong>of</strong> this dog to his master. Aelian describes Augeas’s grief (howl<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

lament<strong>in</strong>g), self-imposed starvation, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally pass<strong>in</strong>g on his master’s grave <strong>in</strong> Aeg<strong>in</strong>a,<br />

a spot which was named afterwards Hound’s Dirge. His description <strong>of</strong> such details gives<br />

the impression that the story, despite its antiquity, was preserved <strong>in</strong>tact <strong>in</strong> his own time.<br />

Aegeas’s story is similar to the slightly earlier story <strong>of</strong> Xanthippos’s dog that took<br />

place also <strong>in</strong> Athens, but <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> Aeg<strong>in</strong>a <strong>in</strong>volved the adjacent isl<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Salamis.<br />

Plutarch (A.D. I-II) records that <strong>in</strong> fear <strong>of</strong> the Persian <strong>in</strong>vasion (480 B.C.), Xanthippos,<br />

the father <strong>of</strong> Pericles, embarked on a boat to Salamis, leav<strong>in</strong>g his can<strong>in</strong>e companion<br />

beh<strong>in</strong>d. Unable to endure separation from his master, the dog swam along with the boat<br />

to Salamis, where it died <strong>of</strong> exhaustion. <strong>The</strong> spot <strong>of</strong> his death was still called “Dog’s<br />

Mound” <strong>in</strong> his time, Plutarch says (<strong>The</strong>m. 10) [162]. <strong>The</strong> similarity between the two<br />

stories may pose questions regard<strong>in</strong>g their reality or fiction, but it is important to keep <strong>in</strong><br />

is 1.11m each, were found <strong>in</strong> Rome. In their discussion, the authors present also the possibility that these<br />

sculptures may have formed part <strong>of</strong> a group, thought to represent a mythological hunt, consist<strong>in</strong>g also <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> a boar (currently on display <strong>in</strong> a separate location with<strong>in</strong> the gallery) <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> a hunter seriously<br />

destroyed by fire <strong>in</strong> 1762. Another idea favored is that these statues <strong>of</strong> dogs could have been funerary<br />

works guard<strong>in</strong>g a tomb. For a summary <strong>of</strong> their provenience, identification <strong>of</strong> their marble as Pentelic, <strong>and</strong><br />

good illustrations, see G. A. Mansuelli, Galleria degli Uffizi: Le sculture I (Rome, 1958) 77-78, figs. 48-49.<br />

Besides this pair <strong>of</strong> marble dogs, there is also another one housed <strong>in</strong> the Vatican Museums: B. Andreae et<br />

al., Bildkatalog der Skulpturen des vaticanischen Museums (DAI II; Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> New York, 1998) 13-14,<br />

pls. 144-147, figs. 64-65. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a sixth marble statue <strong>of</strong> a dog found at Castel Fusano near Ostia is<br />

housed <strong>in</strong> the Palazzo Chigi <strong>in</strong> Rome: Picón, “<strong>The</strong> Dog <strong>of</strong> Alcibiades” 318.<br />

171


m<strong>in</strong>d that the can<strong>in</strong>e devotion which these stories mark rema<strong>in</strong>s consistent with the image<br />

<strong>of</strong> the loyal dog <strong>in</strong> the fifth century.<br />

Further evidence for the ferocity <strong>of</strong> Molossian dogs is found <strong>in</strong> a letter <strong>of</strong><br />

Alciphron (A.D. II-III) that purports to give a sketch <strong>of</strong> life <strong>in</strong> fourth-century Athens.<br />

Horologius, a parasite, relates to one <strong>of</strong> his friends how Molossian dogs that guarded the<br />

house <strong>of</strong> Phanias attacked him after he appropriated a silver pitcher for himself:<br />

All <strong>of</strong> a sudden watchdogs surrounded <strong>and</strong> attacked me, one on this side, another<br />

on that; they were savage <strong>and</strong> deep-throated, Molossians <strong>and</strong> Cnosians, <strong>and</strong> there<br />

was noth<strong>in</strong>g to h<strong>in</strong>der me from be<strong>in</strong>g rent asunder by their jaws (as if I had<br />

<strong>of</strong>fended Artemis) so thoroughly that not even my h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> feet would rema<strong>in</strong><br />

next day for burial by those who might be prepared to pity <strong>and</strong> commiserate.<br />

(Epistles III. 11) [11]<br />

Like Augeas, Eupolis’s Molossian dog who attacked <strong>and</strong> killed Ephialtes, a thief,<br />

Phanias’s Molossian dogs were ferocious to Horologius, also a thief. Unlike Ephialtes,<br />

who succumbed to his wounds, Horologius lived to tell his story. His encounter with<br />

these dogs was a traumatic experience. <strong>The</strong>y were savage <strong>and</strong> deep-throated, <strong>and</strong> he<br />

vividly recalls the fear <strong>and</strong> despair they caused <strong>in</strong> him: “there was noth<strong>in</strong>g to h<strong>in</strong>der me<br />

from be<strong>in</strong>g rent asunder by their jaws.” As a parasite, Horologius may be a ridiculous<br />

figure, but his experience <strong>of</strong> the ferocity <strong>of</strong> Molossian dogs accords well with<br />

Aristophanes’ portrayal <strong>of</strong> them as <strong>in</strong>timidat<strong>in</strong>g watchdogs.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir ferocity aside, Molossian dogs were also known <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> times for their<br />

exceptional size <strong>and</strong> courage. Aristotle, states, for example, <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>:<br />

<strong>The</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> hounds <strong>in</strong> Molossia is no different from those elsewhere <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong><br />

hunt<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>in</strong> shepherd<strong>in</strong>g it is superior by reason <strong>of</strong> size <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> courage <strong>in</strong><br />

fac<strong>in</strong>g wild animals. (HA 608a) [66]<br />

172


Aristotle <strong>in</strong>dicates that Molossian dogs were employed <strong>in</strong> both hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> shepherd<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

but excelled <strong>in</strong> the latter because their size <strong>and</strong> courage made them a threat to predators<br />

<strong>of</strong> herds. His statement implies that Molossian dogs were exceptionally large <strong>and</strong> bold.<br />

It is <strong>of</strong> great <strong>in</strong>terest that, <strong>in</strong> another passage, he speaks <strong>of</strong> Epeirus, the greater area to<br />

which Molossia belonged, <strong>and</strong> from where these dogs were though to orig<strong>in</strong>ate, (hence<br />

their name), as be<strong>in</strong>g rich <strong>in</strong> large animals, especially cattle <strong>and</strong> dogs. <strong>The</strong> issue <strong>of</strong><br />

geography <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g animal size looms large <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, as he states that:<br />

In Phasis there is a breed <strong>of</strong> small cattle every one <strong>of</strong> which yields a copious<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> milk. In Epeirus there are large cows which yield an amphora <strong>and</strong> half<br />

<strong>of</strong> this from the two teats. <strong>The</strong> milker has to st<strong>and</strong> upright, bend<strong>in</strong>g slightly<br />

forward, because he would not be able to reach far enough if seated. In addition<br />

to the cattle, all the quadrupeds (except the ass) <strong>in</strong> Epeirus are large <strong>in</strong> size, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

proportion the cattle <strong>and</strong> the dogs are the largest. (HA 522b) [60]<br />

Aristotle’s contrast between the small cattle <strong>of</strong> Phasis <strong>and</strong> the large one <strong>of</strong> Epeirus clearly<br />

suggests that, <strong>in</strong> his m<strong>in</strong>d, geography was a determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g cause <strong>of</strong> animal size. 259 Of<br />

importance also is his mention <strong>of</strong> dogs be<strong>in</strong>g among the largest animals <strong>in</strong> Epeirus, for it<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>s well his previous note on Molossian dogs be<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>gled out for their size. His<br />

accounts, therefore, <strong>of</strong>fer a useful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the conception <strong>of</strong> the exceptional size <strong>of</strong><br />

Molossian dogs as be<strong>in</strong>g tied to their physical seat <strong>of</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>.<br />

259 <strong>The</strong> responsibility <strong>of</strong> Molossia <strong>in</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g the exceptional qualities <strong>of</strong> its dogs is also attested <strong>in</strong> later<br />

authors, such as Aelian (A.D. II-III), who sees a strong aff<strong>in</strong>ity between the natural disposition <strong>of</strong><br />

Molossian dogs <strong>and</strong> Molossian men. As he says: “among hounds the Molossian is the most high-spirited,<br />

for the men <strong>of</strong> Molossia are hot-tempered” (NA 3.2) [1]. <strong>The</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> such a l<strong>in</strong>k is further expla<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

Pollux, whose Onomasticon (A.D. II) states a mythological bond between these dogs <strong>and</strong> the Molossians,<br />

the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple tribe <strong>of</strong> rulers <strong>in</strong> Epeirus: “the Chaonians <strong>and</strong> the Molossians are descendants <strong>of</strong> a dog which<br />

Hephaestus forged from Demonesian bronze, put a soul <strong>in</strong>to, <strong>and</strong> gave to Zeus” (Onom. 5.39) [164]. That<br />

the l<strong>in</strong>k between Molossian hounds <strong>and</strong> Zeus held alive as far back as the early fourth century B.C. is<br />

evident from the iconography <strong>of</strong> the silver co<strong>in</strong>age <strong>of</strong> Epeirus that dates from this period, <strong>and</strong> depicts on the<br />

obverse, the local breed <strong>of</strong> hound <strong>and</strong> on the reverse, the thunderbolt <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>of</strong> Dodona: C. M. Kraay,<br />

Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Co<strong>in</strong>s (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1976) 129, pl. 24, fig. 444.<br />

173


Although it does not specify their size, evidence that Molossian dogs were highly<br />

valued as early as the sixth century B.C. comes from a passage from Athenaeus’<br />

Deipnosophists. <strong>The</strong> author cites two late fourth-century authors, Clytus, a disciple <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle, <strong>and</strong> Alexis, a comic poet, who count Molossian dogs among the most special<br />

animals collected by Polycrates, the tyrant <strong>of</strong> Samos (ca. 538-522 B.C.):<br />

Clytus the Aristotelian, <strong>in</strong> his work On Miletus, says <strong>of</strong> Polycrates the tyrant <strong>of</strong><br />

Samos that his <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct for luxury moved him to get together the special products<br />

<strong>of</strong> every country—hounds from Epeirus, goats from Scyros, sheep from Miletus,<br />

<strong>and</strong> sw<strong>in</strong>e from Sicily. Alexis, too, <strong>in</strong> the third book <strong>of</strong> Samian Chronicles says<br />

that Samos was enriched by Polycrates with the products <strong>of</strong> many cities: he<br />

imported Molossian <strong>and</strong> Laconian hounds, goats from Scyros <strong>and</strong> Naxos, <strong>and</strong><br />

sheep from Miletus <strong>and</strong> Attica. (Deipn. 12.540c-12.540d) [76]<br />

Both fragments <strong>in</strong>dicate that Molossian dogs were already known as the special animals<br />

<strong>of</strong> Epeirus <strong>in</strong> the late sixth century B.C. By attest<strong>in</strong>g that Polycrates <strong>in</strong>cluded them<br />

among his luxurious possessions, 260 the fragments also suggest that the exceptional social<br />

status that Molossian dogs signified <strong>in</strong> pre-<strong>Classical</strong> times was still relevant as a topic,<br />

<strong>and</strong> therefore, <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> fourth-century authors.<br />

<strong>The</strong> literary evidence cited so far <strong>in</strong>dicates that <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> the<br />

relationship between humans <strong>and</strong> the dog was governed by an anthropocentric attitude.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dog lived together with humans <strong>in</strong> the same domestic sett<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> served as a<br />

guardian <strong>of</strong> this sett<strong>in</strong>g, its residents, <strong>and</strong> their possessions. Fidelity <strong>and</strong> vigilance—an<br />

essential feature <strong>of</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligence—were two qualities for which the animal was<br />

esteemed, whereas its ability to fawn <strong>and</strong> bite at once marked it as a deceptive <strong>and</strong><br />

260 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the Greek adoption <strong>of</strong> Persian practices as a sign <strong>of</strong> prosperity <strong>and</strong> power, <strong>and</strong><br />

literary evidence (e.g., Klearchos <strong>in</strong> Ath. Deipn. 12.54) that charges Polycrates with the establishment <strong>of</strong><br />

his own animal park (paradeisos) <strong>in</strong> emulation <strong>of</strong> Sardis, see M. C. Miller, Athens <strong>and</strong> Persia <strong>in</strong> the Fifth<br />

Century B.C. A Study <strong>in</strong> Cultural Receptivity (Cambridge, 1997) 188-189.<br />

174


untrustworthy animal. So pervasive was this contradictory behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog that<br />

contemporary language adopted it as a figure <strong>of</strong> speech that marked similar behavior <strong>in</strong><br />

humans. Among guard dogs, the Molossian breed was highly valued for its exceptional<br />

ferocity, size, f<strong>in</strong>e appearance, <strong>and</strong> love <strong>and</strong> devotion to its owners; as such, Molossian<br />

dogs were considered valuable possessions <strong>and</strong> gifts.<br />

SECTION 2<br />

a. Dogs Steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Gobbl<strong>in</strong>g Food<br />

Evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek view <strong>of</strong> the feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog<br />

comes from the comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes. A passage from the Knights, for example,<br />

portrays steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> gobbl<strong>in</strong>g food as two types <strong>of</strong> behavior closely associated with the<br />

animal. Produced <strong>in</strong> 424 B.C., the Knights is a susta<strong>in</strong>ed attack on Cleon, a real-life<br />

politician identified throughout the play with a tanner named Paphlagon, <strong>and</strong> also likened<br />

to a dog that howls on behalf <strong>of</strong> the demos—Athenian assembly (e.g., Eq. 1023-1024).<br />

Nikias <strong>and</strong> Demosthenes, represent<strong>in</strong>g two real-life generals, disapprove <strong>of</strong> Paphlagon’s<br />

behavior as a demagogue, <strong>and</strong>, driven by an oracle, seek to replace him with a sausage<br />

seller. In an attempt to w<strong>in</strong> the support <strong>of</strong> Demos, portrayed here as an old, decrepit man,<br />

the sausage seller <strong>in</strong>vites the audience to see Cleon/Paphlagon as:<br />

<strong>The</strong> dog Cerberus, trafficker <strong>in</strong> bodies,<br />

who wags his tail at you when you’re d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

watches, <strong>and</strong> when you happen to gape <strong>in</strong> another direction,<br />

eats up your entrée, <strong>and</strong> at night steals <strong>in</strong>to your kitchen<br />

all unseen, <strong>and</strong> doglike licks clean the plates <strong>and</strong> the isl<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

(Eq. 1030-1034) [38]<br />

175


In this passage, the conflation <strong>of</strong> Cleon with Cerberus, the deceptive watchdog <strong>of</strong><br />

the underworld, who fawned affectionately at newcomers by wagg<strong>in</strong>g his tail, but traded<br />

their bodies, (or, as noted earlier, devoured them) urges the audience to see Cleon’s<br />

behavior as equally deceptive. Such behavior parallels also that <strong>of</strong> the treacherous dog <strong>in</strong><br />

the fragment <strong>of</strong> Sophocles that fawned at <strong>and</strong> bit people at once. In this way,<br />

Aristophanes’s use <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior as a means for describ<strong>in</strong>g human behavior rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

consistent with the use <strong>of</strong> the same model <strong>in</strong> the texts discussed previously.<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage also conflates the steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> public money by Cleon, an act <strong>of</strong> which<br />

he was accused <strong>in</strong> real life, with a dog that steals food from the kitchen <strong>and</strong> licks the<br />

plates clean. Alan Sommerste<strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>s that Aristophanes alludes to this act when he<br />

refers to Cleon as lick<strong>in</strong>g clean “the isl<strong>and</strong>s.” 261 <strong>The</strong> conflation is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it<br />

reveals that steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g food down to its last morsel were behaviors for which the<br />

dog was known. <strong>The</strong> reference, <strong>in</strong> particular, to Cleon’s lick<strong>in</strong>g clean the isl<strong>and</strong>s <strong>in</strong> a<br />

doglike manner h<strong>in</strong>ts at the exploitation <strong>of</strong> large amounts <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong>, therefore,<br />

implies the ability <strong>of</strong> the dog to consume equally large quantities <strong>of</strong> food. 262 Further, the<br />

fact that the dog goes <strong>in</strong>to the kitchen at night like an undetected thief adds to the<br />

domestic places <strong>in</strong> which the animal has been seen so far (ro<strong>of</strong>, door), <strong>and</strong> suggests its<br />

free roam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> around the house. Along with the kitchen, the passage also places<br />

261 A. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Knights (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 2; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1981) 199, l<strong>in</strong>e 1034,<br />

comments that the term “isl<strong>and</strong>s” denotes “the allied states generally, <strong>of</strong> which the Aegean isl<strong>and</strong>s were the<br />

nearest to Athens….<strong>The</strong> allegation appears to be that Cleon takes bribes from the allied states <strong>in</strong> return for<br />

ensur<strong>in</strong>g that their tribute assessment is lower than it would be otherwise, thus <strong>in</strong> effect divert<strong>in</strong>g the money<br />

from the state to himself.”<br />

262 This evidence accords well with modern observations regard<strong>in</strong>g the feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> dogs. As C.<br />

Thorne, “Feed<strong>in</strong>g Behavior <strong>of</strong> Domestic Dogs <strong>and</strong> the Role <strong>of</strong> Experience,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic<br />

Dog, 106, states: “some breeds <strong>of</strong> domestic dog still demonstrate a remarkable ability to gorge, <strong>and</strong> will eat<br />

exceptionally large quantities <strong>of</strong> food whenever it is available. This behavior is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong><br />

the pack hounds, such as beagles <strong>and</strong> foxhounds, although this may be the result <strong>of</strong> the competitive group<br />

feed<strong>in</strong>g that has been the usual husb<strong>and</strong>ry practice for these breeds.”<br />

176


the dog’s steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> food with<strong>in</strong> a d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g context <strong>and</strong> space, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g the lively<br />

presence <strong>of</strong> the animal <strong>in</strong> the daily rout<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> the household. 263 Equally suggestive is<br />

also the description <strong>of</strong> a specific aspect <strong>of</strong> its behavior—wait<strong>in</strong>g for those moments <strong>of</strong><br />

laxity, when d<strong>in</strong>ers look at another direction, <strong>in</strong> order to steal <strong>and</strong> eat their food. This<br />

behavior implies that vigilance was the quality that enabled the dog to pr<strong>of</strong>it from the<br />

lack <strong>of</strong> vigilance <strong>of</strong> humans, switch from fawn<strong>in</strong>g to steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> thus become a<br />

deceptive creature. <strong>The</strong> scene also suggests awareness <strong>of</strong> the fact that the dog observed<br />

human behavior, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, recognizes a degree <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence <strong>in</strong> the animal. 264<br />

Consider<strong>in</strong>g that vigilance was thought to be an essential feature <strong>of</strong> mh~tij, the cunn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>telligence that the dog was seen previously to hold, then the <strong>in</strong>telligence with which<br />

this passage from the Knights charges the animal can be securely identified as mh~tij.<br />

<strong>The</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e tendency to steal <strong>and</strong> gobble food is also seen <strong>in</strong> the slightly later (422<br />

B.C.) comedy <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes, Wasps. <strong>The</strong> play tells the story <strong>of</strong> an old man,<br />

Philocleon, who believes that serv<strong>in</strong>g as a juror provides him with exceptional power.<br />

Object<strong>in</strong>g to this view is his son Bdelycleon, who tries to keep his father away from the<br />

courts. Conf<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> his son’s house, Philocleon is allowed to have a private court <strong>and</strong> try<br />

263 <strong>The</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>in</strong> a context that refers to d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g appears as early as the Homeric poems. In the<br />

Iliad (22.69) [127], for example, Priam talks <strong>of</strong> the dogs that dwell <strong>in</strong> his house as dogs that he reared at his<br />

table (trapezh~aj qurawrou&j) <strong>in</strong> order to guard his door; also <strong>in</strong> the Iliad (23.173), the two dogs<br />

sacrificed by Achilles as part <strong>of</strong> the funeral <strong>of</strong> Patroclus, belonged to a total <strong>of</strong> n<strong>in</strong>e dogs that had been fed<br />

beneath the table (trapezh~ej ku&nej) <strong>of</strong> their master; f<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> the Odyssey (17.309-17.310) Odysseus,<br />

upon his return to Ithaca, asks Eumaeus, whether his dog Argos is like table dogs (trapezh~ej ku&nej),<br />

which their masters keep for show. Regard<strong>in</strong>g the visual record, an example <strong>of</strong> a dog featur<strong>in</strong>g underneath<br />

a table appears as part <strong>of</strong> a symposium scene on an Attic red-figured crater that dates to c. 475-465 B.C.,<br />

<strong>and</strong> has been attributed to the Pig Pa<strong>in</strong>ter. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this vase, see E. Pottier, CVA (France 5;<br />

Louvre 4) 17, cat. no. G355, pl. 25, fig. 9.<br />

264 For modern accounts <strong>of</strong> dogs’ observation <strong>of</strong> human behavior <strong>and</strong> mannerisms, see E. M. Thomas, <strong>The</strong><br />

Social Life <strong>of</strong> Dogs. <strong>The</strong> Grace <strong>of</strong> Can<strong>in</strong>e Behavior (New York, 2000) 41-48.<br />

177


domestic cases. While Bdelycleon <strong>and</strong> some slaves set up a courtroom, another slave,<br />

Xanthias, compla<strong>in</strong>s about the behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the house:<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

To hell with you! To th<strong>in</strong>k that we keep a dog like that!<br />

BDELYCLEON<br />

Tell me, what’s the matter?<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

If it isn’t that dog Labes! He just dashed through (para|&caj)<br />

<strong>in</strong>to the kitchen, grabbed (a(rpa&saj) a long Sicilian cheese,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he’s eaten it all up.<br />

BDELYCLEON<br />

<strong>The</strong>n that must be the first crime I br<strong>in</strong>g before my father.<br />

You be here to prosecute.<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

No, not me; actually the other dog says he’ll be prosecut<strong>in</strong>g<br />

if a charge is brought <strong>in</strong>to court. (Vesp. 835-843) [46]<br />

<strong>The</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Xanthias <strong>in</strong>dicate that not one, as was the case <strong>in</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Chremylus<br />

(Ar. Plut. 1105), but two dogs lived <strong>in</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Bdelycleon. <strong>The</strong> name <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong><br />

them, Labes, which translates as “Grabber,” 265 even though, is fictitious, appears to be<br />

<strong>in</strong>spired by the dog’s grabb<strong>in</strong>g the cheese. Unlike Augeas, Eupolis’ Molossian dog, who<br />

was named after his donor, the name <strong>of</strong> Labes <strong>in</strong>dicates that dogs were assigned names<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> their behavior. This tendency is also seen <strong>in</strong> Xenophon, whose fourth-<br />

century treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g suggests that Phonax, mean<strong>in</strong>g “<strong>The</strong> Loud One,” is a good<br />

name for a hound (Cyn. 7.5.4). 266 <strong>The</strong> same tendency is also seen <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong><br />

265 A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wasps (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 4; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1983) 208, l<strong>in</strong>e 836.<br />

266 For a comprehensive catalogue <strong>of</strong> names given to dogs <strong>in</strong> classical antiquity, see F. Mentz, “Die<br />

klassischen Hundenamen,” Philologus 88 (1933) 104-129, 181-202, 415-442. For a compilation <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

texts referr<strong>in</strong>g to names <strong>of</strong> dogs, <strong>and</strong> modern scholarship on them, see J. Diggle, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong>ophrastus.<br />

Characters (Cambridge, 2004) 411-412. Regard<strong>in</strong>g material evidence, the <strong>in</strong>scribed name <strong>of</strong> a female dog<br />

called FILOQERA, which translates as “Lover <strong>of</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g” appears on a sixth-century (525-500 B.C.)<br />

Boeotian black-figured skyphos, which depicts women <strong>in</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g bread. For a brief<br />

description <strong>of</strong> this vase, see M. Brouskari, <strong>The</strong> Paul <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>ra Canellopoulos Museum (Athens, 1985)<br />

178


mythological dogs, such as those <strong>of</strong> the huntsman Actaeon, whose names, to mention<br />

only two, are Harpalos (Ov., Met. 3.222; Hyg. Fab.181.11) <strong>and</strong> Harpyia (Hyg.<br />

Fab.181.9; Poll., Onom. 5. 47); they correspond respectively to the mascul<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong><br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e versions <strong>of</strong> “Snatcher.” 267 As seen, the names <strong>of</strong> these dogs are attested <strong>in</strong> later<br />

authors, but their <strong>in</strong>clusion here is relevant <strong>in</strong> that their etymology complies with the<br />

behavior <strong>of</strong> Labes, who “snatched” (a(rpa&saj) the cheese from the kitchen.<br />

Comment<strong>in</strong>g on the term, Douglas McDowell states that it denotes the snatch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> food<br />

by dogs <strong>and</strong> other animals. 268 Douglas Olson clarifies that it refers to the snatch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

50, no. 384; also J.-J. Maffre, “Collection Paul Canellopoulos: Vases Béotiens,” BCH 99 (1975) 467-476,<br />

figs. 29a-b, <strong>and</strong> 30a-b. Although dat<strong>in</strong>g from a later period (A.D. III), the mascul<strong>in</strong>e version <strong>of</strong> the can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

name “Lover <strong>of</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g” appears <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription that accompanies the relief sculpture <strong>of</strong> a dog on a<br />

funerary stele from the grave <strong>of</strong> a dog found at Pergamon. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scription reads: “My name is<br />

FILOKUNHGOS because I hunted ferocious prey with my swift feet”; M. Fränkel, Die Inschriften von<br />

Pergamon (Altertümer von Pergamon vol. 8. pt. 2; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1895) 513, no. 3559. For an illustration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

stele, see S. Georgoudi, “Funeral Epigrams for <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>,” Αρχαιολογíα 11 (1984) 38, fig. 3. Also the<br />

<strong>in</strong>scribed names <strong>of</strong> two dogs, Methepon <strong>and</strong> Ormenos, translated respectively as “Pursuer” <strong>and</strong> “Rusher”<br />

appear <strong>in</strong> the depiction <strong>of</strong> the Calydonian boar hunt on the François Vase dated to ca. 570 B.C. For an<br />

illustration <strong>of</strong> this scene <strong>and</strong> additional discussion <strong>of</strong> the sixth- <strong>and</strong> fifth-century iconography <strong>of</strong> this subject<br />

primarily on pottery, see J. M. Barr<strong>in</strong>ger, <strong>The</strong> Hunt <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Baltimore <strong>and</strong> London, 2001) 147-<br />

161, fig. 82, 172-173.<br />

267 As such, but <strong>in</strong> the plural form, translates also the name <strong>of</strong> Harpies, imag<strong>in</strong>ary be<strong>in</strong>gs who appear <strong>in</strong><br />

myth as w<strong>in</strong>d-storms that snatch the daughters <strong>of</strong> P<strong>and</strong>areus <strong>and</strong> give them as servants to the Er<strong>in</strong>yes (Il.<br />

16.150; Od. 1.241, 14.371, 20.77), <strong>and</strong> also as w<strong>in</strong>ged women who cont<strong>in</strong>uously snatch the food <strong>and</strong> befoul<br />

the table <strong>of</strong> the bl<strong>in</strong>d, Thracian k<strong>in</strong>g Ph<strong>in</strong>eus (Hesiod frs. 150-156 <strong>in</strong> R. Merkelbach <strong>and</strong> M. L. West, eds.,<br />

Fragmenta Hesiodea [London, 1967] 73-77; Apollonius <strong>of</strong> Rhodes [2.234-2.434]). For a thorough<br />

summary <strong>of</strong> ancient literary references to <strong>and</strong> artistic representations <strong>of</strong> Harpies, see L. Kahil <strong>and</strong> A.<br />

Jacquem<strong>in</strong>, “Harpyiai,” LIMC IV.1; IV.2 (Zurich <strong>and</strong> Munich, 1988) 445-450; 266-271. For a discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the susta<strong>in</strong>ed relation <strong>of</strong> Harpies with the realm <strong>of</strong> the dead <strong>and</strong> their equation to demons, see S. I.<br />

Johnston, Restless Dead. Encounters between the Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the Dead <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Berkeley, 1999)<br />

180, n. 52. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> depictions <strong>of</strong> Harpies on ancient Greek pottery, with special reference to<br />

their w<strong>in</strong>gs spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g from the front <strong>of</strong> their shoulders as be<strong>in</strong>g a visual clue <strong>of</strong> their otherworldl<strong>in</strong>ess, see<br />

B. Cohen, “Red-Figure Vases Take W<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> J. Oakley et al., eds., Athenian Potters <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>ters. <strong>The</strong><br />

Conference Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs (Oxbow Monograph 67; Oxford, 1997) 141-155. For the frequent tendency to<br />

confuse artistic representations <strong>of</strong> Harpies with those <strong>of</strong> Sirens, the most famous example be<strong>in</strong>g the socalled<br />

Harpy Tomb <strong>in</strong> Lycia, see D. Tsiafakis, ““PELWRA”: Fabulous Creatures <strong>and</strong>/or Demons <strong>of</strong><br />

Death?,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Padgett, ed., <strong>The</strong> Centaur’s Smile: <strong>The</strong> Human <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art (New Haven<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 99, n. 36; also C. Smith, “Harpies <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” JHS 13 (1892-93) 103-114.<br />

268 D. M. McDowell, ed., Aristophanes. Wasps (Oxford, 1971) 243, l<strong>in</strong>e 837. A quick perusal <strong>of</strong> the<br />

comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes provides us with two additional examples <strong>of</strong> dogs snatch<strong>in</strong>g food (a(rpa&sasa,<br />

Ach. 1160; u(farpa&sei, Nub. 490), 268 <strong>and</strong> one where the culprit is a kite (a(rpa&saj, Av. 892); three<br />

examples were also found where food is snatched by humans as well (a(rpa&somai, Hierocles, Pax 1118; an<br />

anonymous man, Eccl. 866; a(rpa&ze<strong>in</strong>, poor people, Plut. 598).<br />

179


food that belongs to others, 269 hence, steal<strong>in</strong>g. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, Labes’ steal<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the cheese from the kitchen fits perfectly with the image <strong>of</strong> the dog steal<strong>in</strong>g food from the<br />

kitchen, <strong>in</strong> the Knights. 270 In both cases, the dogs eat all the food that they have stolen.<br />

Further, both cases are used to describe the theft <strong>of</strong> public money by political figures <strong>in</strong><br />

real life. Like Cleon’s embezzlement from the isl<strong>and</strong>s that was equated to a dog’s<br />

steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g food, Labes’ steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g the cheese also st<strong>and</strong>s for a similar<br />

episode taken from the political scene <strong>of</strong> the day. In this case, even the identification <strong>of</strong><br />

the stolen food with cheese is <strong>of</strong> particular importance to the <strong>in</strong>tended allusion.<br />

As McDowell expla<strong>in</strong>s, the steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> cheese by Labes is an episode that satirizes<br />

a recent event from real life: Laches, a general who had served (<strong>in</strong> 427/6 <strong>and</strong> 426/5 B.C.)<br />

with the Athenian navy <strong>in</strong> Sicily, a region famous for its cheeses, had been accused by<br />

269 S. D. Olson, ed., Aristophanes. Acharnians (New York, 2002) 351, l<strong>in</strong>es 1159-1161.<br />

270 Iconographic evidence that may attest to the presence <strong>of</strong> a dog <strong>in</strong> a kitchen comes from the sixth <strong>and</strong><br />

fifth centuries B.C. First is a terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e housed <strong>in</strong> the Louvre Museum (CA 634) (Fig. 16). <strong>The</strong><br />

figur<strong>in</strong>e is allegedly from Tanagra, Boeotia, <strong>and</strong> has been dated to the last quarter <strong>of</strong> the sixth century B.C.<br />

Fixed on a plaque is the seated figure <strong>of</strong> a female cook, who stirs with a ladle the contents <strong>of</strong> a pot that is<br />

placed on the ground <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> her. To her right is a dog with his head raised upward towards her <strong>and</strong> its<br />

right foreleg slightly elevated. For a description <strong>of</strong> this figur<strong>in</strong>e, see S. Mollard-Besques, Catalogue<br />

raisonné des figur<strong>in</strong>es et reliefs en terre-cuite grecs étrusques et roma<strong>in</strong>es I (Paris, 1954) 20-21, cat. no. B<br />

118, pl. XV; also A. Vigneau, <strong>The</strong> Photographic Encyclopaedia <strong>of</strong> Art: <strong>The</strong> Louvre Museum II (Paris,<br />

1936) 172-173, fig. D. For the belief that this figur<strong>in</strong>e belongs to the category <strong>of</strong> genre pieces, see E.<br />

Pottier, “Les sujets de genre dans les figur<strong>in</strong>es archaïques de terre cuite,” BCH 24 (1900) 510. For genre<br />

pieces be<strong>in</strong>g terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>es “whose subjects are men <strong>and</strong> women engaged <strong>in</strong> their daily occupations,<br />

treated with almost photographic realism, <strong>and</strong> with the commonest scenes be<strong>in</strong>g taken from the kitchen,”<br />

see R. A. Higg<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Terracottas (London, 1967) 77; for a recent discussion on the notion <strong>of</strong> “genre”<br />

as a still alive, but not safe approach to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> images <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art, see G. Ferrari,<br />

Figures <strong>of</strong> Speech. Men <strong>and</strong> Maidens <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 2002) 6. For the<br />

manufactur<strong>in</strong>g techniques <strong>of</strong> figur<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> this type, see M. Szabó, Archaic Terracottas <strong>of</strong> Boeotia (Rome,<br />

1994) 121-131. For another Boeotian figur<strong>in</strong>e depict<strong>in</strong>g the same subject, dated to the late sixth or early<br />

fifth century B.C., <strong>and</strong> housed <strong>in</strong> the State Museum <strong>in</strong> Kassel (523) (Fig. 17), see U. S<strong>in</strong>n, Antike<br />

Terrakotten. Staatliche Kunstsammlungen Kassel (Kassel, 1977) pl. I, 25. A third terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e<br />

depict<strong>in</strong>g a woman with a quadruped, most likely a dog, by her side comes from Cyprus <strong>and</strong> dates to the<br />

sixth century B.C. (V 1674) (Fig. 18). For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this figur<strong>in</strong>e, see A. Bernhard-Walcher et al.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Collection <strong>of</strong> Cypriote Antiquities <strong>in</strong> the Kunsthistorisches Museum (Vienna, 1999) 139, 143-144, cat.<br />

no. 58. For a recent discussion <strong>of</strong> all these <strong>and</strong> additional terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>es that depict scenes from daily<br />

life, see M. Pisani, “Vita quotidiana nel mondo Greco tra il IV e il V secolo A.C. Un contributo per la<br />

classificazione delle rappresentazioni fittili,” Bollet<strong>in</strong>o d’Arte 123 (2003) 3-24.<br />

180


Cleon <strong>of</strong> embezzl<strong>in</strong>g money while campaign<strong>in</strong>g on the isl<strong>and</strong>. 271 <strong>The</strong> allusion to this<br />

event is also apparent <strong>in</strong> the pun that <strong>in</strong>volves the name <strong>of</strong> the general Laches <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong><br />

the dog Labes, which, as mentioned earlier, means “Grabber.” 272 It is clear, therefore,<br />

that Aristophanes uses the steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> food by Labes as an allusion to the steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

money by a real politician. But the scene with Labes, when seen <strong>in</strong> isolation, is<br />

particularly <strong>in</strong>structive, for it shows that can<strong>in</strong>e behavior was observed <strong>in</strong> real life. When<br />

Xanthias describes Labes’ behavior to Bdelycleon, for example, he ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the dog<br />

dashed through <strong>in</strong>to the kitchen (para|&caj). 273 This is a type <strong>of</strong> behavior that <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

agility <strong>and</strong> swiftness, both <strong>of</strong> which are features essential to cunn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligence known<br />

as mh~tij <strong>and</strong> shown earlier to be a can<strong>in</strong>e quality. 274<br />

Taken together, the <strong>in</strong>cidents <strong>of</strong> dogs’ steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g food that are described<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Knights <strong>and</strong> the Wasps are two identical versions <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>in</strong>tention: to highlight<br />

<strong>and</strong>, at the same time, ridicule the steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> public money by political figures. <strong>The</strong> use<br />

<strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior as a metaphor for describ<strong>in</strong>g human behavior suggests that<br />

271 For this event be<strong>in</strong>g taken from real life, <strong>and</strong> for the prosecution <strong>of</strong> Laches by Cleon, which is<br />

mentioned earlier <strong>in</strong> the play (Vesp. 240-244), see S. D. Olson, “Politics <strong>and</strong> Poetry <strong>in</strong> Aristophanes’<br />

Wasps,” TAPA 126 (1996) 138-139; D. M. McDowell, Aristophanes <strong>and</strong> Athens. An Introduction to the<br />

Plays (Oxford, 1995) 167.<br />

272 For the ways <strong>in</strong> which various characters <strong>in</strong> the comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes are named, <strong>and</strong> the use to<br />

which these names are put with<strong>in</strong> the wider context <strong>of</strong> each play, see S. D. Olson, “Names <strong>and</strong> Nam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

Aristophanic Comedy,” CQ 42 (1992) 304-319.<br />

273 Labes’ behavior br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d the story <strong>of</strong> the dog dash<strong>in</strong>g through the Erechtheion, a story quoted by<br />

Dionysius <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus (On D<strong>in</strong>archus 3) who, <strong>in</strong> turn, attributes it to Philochorus, a fourth-century<br />

B.C. scholar-historian <strong>and</strong> a contemporary <strong>of</strong> D<strong>in</strong>archus, the last <strong>of</strong> the canon <strong>of</strong> ten Attic orators.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to J. G. Frazer, Pausanias’s Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> (London, 1898; second ed., 1913) 338, the<br />

story <strong>of</strong> Philochorus runs as follows: “On the Acropolis the follow<strong>in</strong>g portent took place. A bitch entered<br />

the temple <strong>of</strong> the Polias, <strong>and</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g gone down <strong>in</strong>to the P<strong>and</strong>rosium, ascended the altar <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Courtyard which st<strong>and</strong>s under the olive-tree, <strong>and</strong> there lay down. Now it is an old established custom with<br />

the Athenians that no dog shall ascend the Acropolis.”<br />

274 Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence 30, do not refer to explicit examples <strong>of</strong> animals who are<br />

agile <strong>and</strong> swift, but consider the qualities <strong>of</strong> agility, suppleness, swiftness, <strong>and</strong> mobility as fundamental to<br />

both huntsmen <strong>and</strong> fishermen, who <strong>in</strong> order to be successful need to exhibit mh~tij that surpasses that <strong>of</strong><br />

their prey. Such attitude, they state, accords well with “the one unalterable rule for animals <strong>and</strong> men alike,<br />

be they hunt<strong>in</strong>g or fish<strong>in</strong>g: the only way to get better <strong>of</strong> a polumh~tij one (‘one with a lot <strong>of</strong> mh~tij’) is to<br />

exhibit even more mh~tij.”<br />

181


Aristophanes’s audiences were not only familiar with the feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog, but<br />

also considered it an appropriate means <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> express<strong>in</strong>g themselves <strong>in</strong><br />

everyday life.<br />

b. Punishment <strong>of</strong> Dogs<br />

Comedy also provides <strong>in</strong>formation regard<strong>in</strong>g the punishment <strong>of</strong> dogs for steal<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g food. Cited by Athenaeus, a fragment <strong>of</strong> Anax<strong>and</strong>rides’s lost play Poleis,<br />

(fourth century B.C.), focuses on the cultural differences between <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> Egypt. <strong>The</strong><br />

speaker, a Greek, addresses an Egyptian by tell<strong>in</strong>g him, among other th<strong>in</strong>gs, that he beats<br />

his dog when he catches it eat<strong>in</strong>g stolen food:<br />

I couldn’t br<strong>in</strong>g myself to be an ally <strong>of</strong> yours<br />

For neither our manners not our customs agree, but<br />

st<strong>and</strong> a long distance apart from each other.<br />

You worship the cow, but I sacrifice it to the gods.<br />

You hold the eel to be mighty div<strong>in</strong>ity, we hold it<br />

by far the mightiest <strong>of</strong> da<strong>in</strong>ties.<br />

You eat no pork, but I like it very much.<br />

You worship the bitch, I beat her when I catch her eat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

up my best food. (Deipn. 7.299f) [73]<br />

<strong>The</strong> speaker suggests that catch<strong>in</strong>g his dog eat<strong>in</strong>g stolen food <strong>and</strong> beat<strong>in</strong>g it was a regular<br />

occurrence. <strong>The</strong> physical assault aga<strong>in</strong>st the dog <strong>of</strong> which the speaker boasts suggests<br />

behavior that is <strong>in</strong> alignment with the anthropocentric <strong>Classical</strong> Greek assumption <strong>of</strong><br />

dom<strong>in</strong>ion over animals. <strong>The</strong> speaker also contrasts his beat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the animal with its<br />

worship <strong>in</strong> Egypt, thus reveal<strong>in</strong>g his belief that punish<strong>in</strong>g the dog <strong>in</strong> this way is behavior<br />

that sets him apart from his Egyptian addressee. This contrast demonstrates the treatment<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dog as a marker <strong>of</strong> ethnicity.<br />

182


Although not provoked by the act <strong>of</strong> steal<strong>in</strong>g food, beat<strong>in</strong>g features elsewhere as a<br />

violent treatment <strong>of</strong> the dog. In Aristophanes’ Knights, for example, the sausage seller<br />

launches the follow<strong>in</strong>g threat to Paphlagon: “I’ll beat your back like a dog’s!” (Eq. 289)<br />

[36]. <strong>The</strong> simile is <strong>in</strong>structive <strong>in</strong> show<strong>in</strong>g that beat<strong>in</strong>g was treatment regularly meted out<br />

to the animal. Also by equat<strong>in</strong>g his <strong>in</strong>tended beat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Paphlagon to that <strong>of</strong> a dog, the<br />

sausage seller presents a strong case for want<strong>in</strong>g his threat to come across as severe. In<br />

this way, the simile demonstrates the function <strong>of</strong> a dog’s beat<strong>in</strong>g as a sign <strong>of</strong> severity.<br />

This evidence is further <strong>in</strong>structive, for it confirms the prom<strong>in</strong>ence not simply <strong>of</strong> the<br />

animal, but also <strong>of</strong> its physical suffer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> language <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

society.<br />

c. Food for Dogs<br />

<strong>The</strong> physical assault <strong>of</strong> the dog as exemplified by beat<strong>in</strong>g contrasts sharply with<br />

textual evidence that suggests that a considerable degree <strong>of</strong> care was <strong>in</strong>vested <strong>in</strong><br />

provid<strong>in</strong>g food for the animal. First, however, reference should be made to the prevail<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek belief that the dog did not have specific preferences, but ate any food that<br />

came to its attention. 275 This belief is clearly stated <strong>in</strong> Aristophanes’ Peace (421 B.C.).<br />

<strong>The</strong> play opens <strong>in</strong> the courtyard <strong>of</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Trygaeus, a country man. Two slaves<br />

prepare st<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g food for a greedy dung-beetle located <strong>in</strong>side a room <strong>of</strong> the house. One<br />

slave is knead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to dung-cakes the contents <strong>of</strong> a mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl, while another keeps<br />

dash<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> out <strong>of</strong> the room <strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> feed<strong>in</strong>g these cakes to the dung-beetle.<br />

275 <strong>The</strong> fact that comic texts provide evidence for food for dogs accords well with the scholarly status <strong>of</strong><br />

comedy as the most useful literary genre regard<strong>in</strong>g food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> comedic context as evidence for the consumption <strong>of</strong> food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, see J. Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, “Comic<br />

Cuis<strong>in</strong>e: Food <strong>and</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Comic Polis,” <strong>in</strong> G. W. Dobrov, ed., <strong>The</strong> City as Comedy. Society <strong>and</strong><br />

Representation <strong>in</strong> Athenian Drama (Chapel Hill <strong>and</strong> London, 1997) 250-268.<br />

183


Unable to keep up with the quick pace <strong>of</strong> the creature’s eat<strong>in</strong>g, the slave decides to br<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the entire bowl to it. Released from the unpleasant task <strong>of</strong> knead<strong>in</strong>g foul substances, the<br />

other slave exclaims:<br />

SECOND SLAVE<br />

By heaven, you can take it to hell, <strong>and</strong> yourself with it!<br />

(to the spectators) If any <strong>of</strong> you knows where I can buy an<br />

unperforated nose, please tell me! Because there’s no job<br />

more wretched than knead<strong>in</strong>g food to serve to a beetle. A<br />

pig or a dog will simply gobble up any shit that falls, but<br />

this conceited th<strong>in</strong>g puts on airs <strong>and</strong> won’t deign to eat<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g that I don’t spend the whole day mash<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

serve kneaded <strong>in</strong>to a ball, as for a lady. (Pax 19-28) [42]<br />

As <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the dog <strong>and</strong> the pig liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the house <strong>of</strong> Chremylus (Ar. Plut. 1100-<br />

1105), the passage aga<strong>in</strong> presents these two animals liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a domestic context. Unlike<br />

the dung-beetle, for which specific food was be<strong>in</strong>g prepared, the dog did not require such<br />

<strong>in</strong>vestment because it would eat anyth<strong>in</strong>g. In particular, the slave’s assertion that the<br />

animal would gobble up food suggests hasty consumption, thus recall<strong>in</strong>g Labes, who ate<br />

on the spot the cheese he had stolen from the kitchen. Also by stat<strong>in</strong>g that the food was<br />

to be fall<strong>in</strong>g, most likely from a table, the slave places the dog with<strong>in</strong> a context that<br />

suggests d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or preparation <strong>of</strong> food, thereby confirm<strong>in</strong>g the lively presence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

animal with<strong>in</strong> the house. At the same time, the passage demonstrates that slaves were<br />

residents <strong>of</strong> the house whose <strong>in</strong>teraction with the dog allowed them to observe the animal<br />

closely <strong>and</strong> acquire knowledge <strong>of</strong> its behavior <strong>and</strong> habits. 276<br />

276 Even though it is later <strong>in</strong> date (A.D. II), <strong>and</strong> accord<strong>in</strong>g to D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1964) 49, addresses hunt servants, the follow<strong>in</strong>g passage from Arrian’s<br />

treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g (Cyn. 9.1-9.2) [71] exemplifies the knowledge <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e behavior that servants, most<br />

likely slaves, acquired through their proximity to <strong>and</strong> cohabitation with the animal: “there is noth<strong>in</strong>g like a<br />

good warm bed. <strong>The</strong> best is that with a human be<strong>in</strong>g, because hounds are made fond <strong>of</strong> people this way,<br />

<strong>and</strong> they rejoice <strong>in</strong> human sk<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> love the person they sleep with no less that the one who feeds them.<br />

And you should notice which <strong>of</strong> the hounds was unhappy, so as to provide for one which was thirsty <strong>in</strong> the<br />

night <strong>and</strong> for one urged on by its necessities, <strong>and</strong> you would know also how it rested. For if it were<br />

wakeful or if it dripped frequently <strong>in</strong> its sleep or threw up some <strong>of</strong> its food, tak<strong>in</strong>g it on a hunt would not be<br />

184


Apart from label<strong>in</strong>g dogs as <strong>in</strong>discrim<strong>in</strong>ate eaters, textual evidence shows that<br />

owners <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> fulfilled the nutritional needs <strong>of</strong> the animal by<br />

provid<strong>in</strong>g it with a variety <strong>of</strong> foods. In Aristophanes’ Wasps, for example, Bdelycleon<br />

states that Labes, the dog liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> his house, will eat meat-scraps <strong>and</strong> fish-bones (968-<br />

969) [47]. <strong>The</strong> statement reveals the diverse types <strong>of</strong> food that Labes ate. Although this<br />

food appears to have been a discarded part <strong>of</strong> human diet, still does not fail to make a<br />

strong case for the care that Labes received by hav<strong>in</strong>g his meals provided to him.<br />

Additional <strong>in</strong>formation regard<strong>in</strong>g the food provided to dogs is to be found <strong>in</strong><br />

Xenophon. In his treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g the author advises his audience that milk should be<br />

<strong>in</strong>cluded for a year <strong>in</strong> the diet <strong>of</strong> newborn puppies (Cyn. 7.4) [191]. 277 His advice gives<br />

the impression that it was the owners’ responsibility to provide a diet that met the<br />

nutritional needs <strong>of</strong> puppies. As with the diet <strong>of</strong> Labes, Xenophon’s statement reveals<br />

that supply<strong>in</strong>g food to the dog was part <strong>of</strong> the care that the animal received.<br />

Perhaps the most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g evidence for the type <strong>of</strong> food furnished to the dog<br />

occurs <strong>in</strong> Aristophanes’ Knights. A fierce discussion between the sausage seller <strong>and</strong><br />

Paphlagon shows that h<strong>and</strong>-wipes, which were made <strong>of</strong> edible material, were, <strong>in</strong> turn,<br />

recycled as the food par-excellence for dogs:<br />

safe. <strong>The</strong> man sleep<strong>in</strong>g with it would know these th<strong>in</strong>gs”; translation: Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong> 170.<br />

277 To this evidence should be added a large beef bone found near the nose <strong>of</strong> a dog buried <strong>in</strong> a fourthcentury<br />

round pit unearthed beh<strong>in</strong>d the Stoa <strong>of</strong> Attalos <strong>in</strong> Athens. This bone may be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as<br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g the favorite food <strong>of</strong> this animal, even though the possibility <strong>of</strong> a different mean<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>gent<br />

upon the funerary context should not be ruled out. For the excavation <strong>of</strong> this grave, see H. A. Thompson,<br />

“Excavations <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Agora: 1950,” Hesperia 20 (1951) 52, n. 14. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> beef be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the first choice among food preferred by dogs, see Thorne, “Feed<strong>in</strong>g Behavior <strong>of</strong> the Domestic Dogs,” <strong>in</strong><br />

Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 104.<br />

185


SAUSAGE SELLER<br />

Well, I swear by the fists whose blows I’ve borne many on many<br />

a time from a child up, <strong>and</strong> by the slashes <strong>of</strong> butchers’ knives,<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k I will surpass you <strong>in</strong> that. Otherwise it would be for noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that I’ve grown to such a size on a diet <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>-wipes (a)pomagdalia&j).<br />

PAPHLAGON<br />

H<strong>and</strong>-wipes (a)pomagdalia&j), like a dog? Poor rascal, how on a diet<br />

<strong>of</strong> dog’s food do you expect to fight with a dog-faced baboon?<br />

(Eq. 411-416) [37]<br />

Paphlagon identifies his rival’s diet <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>-wipes with that <strong>of</strong> a dog. This identification<br />

implies that h<strong>and</strong>-wipes were made <strong>of</strong> edible material, a po<strong>in</strong>t that will be discussed<br />

shortly. <strong>The</strong> surprise <strong>and</strong> pity that Paphlagon expresses, when the sausage seller alleges<br />

to have been raised on h<strong>and</strong>-wipes, demonstrates that this was food befitt<strong>in</strong>g only dogs.<br />

This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> thought reveals that the contemporary anthropocentric attitude that viewed<br />

humans as a category separate from <strong>and</strong> superior to that <strong>of</strong> animals extended even to the<br />

doma<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> food. 278 <strong>The</strong> statement <strong>of</strong> the sausage seller, however, that he grew to an<br />

exceptional size ow<strong>in</strong>g to eat<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>and</strong>-wipes, suggests that they were considered<br />

nutritious food. As with the milk for puppies seen above, this evidence suggests that a<br />

criterion for select<strong>in</strong>g food for dogs was its nutritional value, which <strong>in</strong> turn suggests that a<br />

degree <strong>of</strong> care was <strong>in</strong>vested on the well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the animal.<br />

<strong>The</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> the term a)pomagdalia&j as “h<strong>and</strong>-wipes” is based on a note by<br />

a scholiast, who expla<strong>in</strong>s that the objects on which d<strong>in</strong>ers wiped their f<strong>in</strong>gers were made<br />

<strong>of</strong> dough <strong>and</strong>, after d<strong>in</strong>ner was completed, were given to dogs as food. 279 Similarly, a<br />

fragment from the Epistle Concern<strong>in</strong>g Obscure Words, a work ascribed to Polemon (c.<br />

278<br />

For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> this attitude, see Renehan, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Anthropocentric View <strong>of</strong> Man,” 239-<br />

259. Although it refers to food for humans, an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g discussion <strong>of</strong> food as “divisive [<strong>and</strong>] be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

distributed <strong>and</strong> consumed <strong>in</strong> accordance with exist<strong>in</strong>g hierarchies,” can be found <strong>in</strong> P. Garsney, Food <strong>and</strong><br />

Society <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Antiquity (Cambridge, 1999) xi; also 6, where the author also remarks that, “food<br />

separates <strong>and</strong> divides…<strong>in</strong> existential, cultural, social <strong>and</strong> economic terms.”<br />

279<br />

D. M. Jones, ed., Scholia Vetera <strong>in</strong> Aristophanis Equites (Scholia <strong>in</strong> Aristophanem 1.2; Gron<strong>in</strong>gen <strong>and</strong><br />

Amsterdam, 1969) 104, 414a-414c.<br />

186


190 B.C.), <strong>and</strong> cited <strong>in</strong> Athenaeus’s discussion on ancient table manners, clarifies that<br />

“[d<strong>in</strong>ers] used to smear their h<strong>and</strong>s with perfumes, spurn<strong>in</strong>g the crumbs <strong>of</strong> bread<br />

(a)pomagdalia&j) which the Spartans called ‘dog-bits’ (kuna&daj)” (Deipn. 9.409d) [75].<br />

In this case, the etymology <strong>of</strong> the word kuna&daj, which shares the same root with the<br />

ancient Greek term for dog (ku&wn) supports the connection between these items <strong>and</strong> the<br />

animal. 280 Further <strong>in</strong>formation regard<strong>in</strong>g the material <strong>of</strong> which a)pomagdalia&j were<br />

made is related by Pollux, who refers to them as s<strong>of</strong>t pieces <strong>of</strong> dough or bread (Onom.<br />

6.93), 281 <strong>and</strong> also by Hesychius, whose lexicon (A.D. V) also identifies them as pieces <strong>of</strong><br />

dough made <strong>of</strong> flour. 282<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the food provided to dogs comes from a short<br />

fragment <strong>of</strong> Diphilus (born c. 360-350 B.C.). <strong>The</strong> fragment preserves an episode <strong>in</strong><br />

which a mysterious woman attempts to feed a dog: 283<br />

This young miss is one <strong>of</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>d even father never kisses<br />

<strong>and</strong> house-dog won’t take crusts (a1rton) from,<br />

so dark she makes day night. (fr. 91 Kock) [84]<br />

280<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the visual record, a scene on a black-figured Boeotian lekythos (c. 550 B.C.) that depicts a<br />

dog <strong>in</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> women <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g bread has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as an allusion<br />

to the dog’s wait<strong>in</strong>g to receive bits <strong>of</strong> this bread, most likely, <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> discarded napk<strong>in</strong>s; B. A.<br />

Sparkes, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Kitchen,” JHS 82 (1962) 126-127, pl. VII, fig. 2; for additional illustrations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same lekythos without, however, focus<strong>in</strong>g on the dog, see S. Lewis, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Woman: An<br />

Iconographic H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2002) 69, fig. 2.10. To this visual repertoire can also be<br />

added the Boeotian, black-figured skyphos that depicts two dogs, FILOQERA be<strong>in</strong>g one <strong>of</strong> them, <strong>in</strong> the<br />

presence <strong>of</strong> women mak<strong>in</strong>g bread, <strong>and</strong> is slightly later <strong>in</strong> date (525-500 B.C.).<br />

281<br />

E. Bethe, ed., Pollucis Onomasticon (Lexicographi Graeci IX) I (Leipzig, 1900, 1931; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967) 26-27.<br />

282<br />

E. Munksgaard, ed., Hesychii Alex<strong>and</strong>r<strong>in</strong>i Lexicon I (Copenhagen, 1953) 219, s.v. a ) pomagdali/a<br />

283<br />

<strong>The</strong> image <strong>of</strong> a dog be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fered food appears frequently <strong>in</strong> the arts <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period, as, for<br />

example, on a red-figured m<strong>in</strong>iature chous, dated to ca. 420 B.C. <strong>and</strong> housed at the A. M. Sackler Museum,<br />

Harvard University Art Museums. <strong>The</strong> vase depicts a boy hold<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g a treat, perhaps meat or grapes,<br />

to a dog that rises onto its h<strong>in</strong>d legs to reach it. For a discussion <strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> this vase, see J. Neils<br />

<strong>and</strong> J. Oakley eds., Com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Age <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Images <strong>of</strong> Childhood from the <strong>Classical</strong> Past (New<br />

Haven, 2003) 146 <strong>and</strong> 285, no. 95.<br />

187


<strong>The</strong> fragment clearly identifies bread (a1rton) as the food presented to the dog. 284<br />

Consider<strong>in</strong>g that the term a1rtoj designated a leavened wheat loaf, 285 <strong>and</strong> that cereals<br />

like wheat were thought to have high nutritional value <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, 286 it is aga<strong>in</strong><br />

evident that the animal was fed with its well-be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fragment is further illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the can<strong>in</strong>e behavior it describes:<br />

so unsympathetic was the woman who tried to feed the dog that the animal decl<strong>in</strong>ed to<br />

take food from her. 287 This behavior contrasts sharply with that seen earlier: decided<br />

eagerness to steal <strong>and</strong> gobble food. Although such contrasts <strong>in</strong> behavior can be attributed<br />

to a possible difference <strong>in</strong> breeds, 288 what cannot be overlooked is that the dog was aware<br />

<strong>of</strong> the woman’s dark character <strong>and</strong> therefore avoided be<strong>in</strong>g fed by her. Such evidence<br />

grants wisdom <strong>and</strong> foresight to the animal <strong>and</strong> recognizes <strong>in</strong> it a level <strong>of</strong> mental capacity;<br />

it also presupposes can<strong>in</strong>e observation <strong>of</strong> human character <strong>and</strong> behavior, a circumstance<br />

already seen <strong>in</strong> the Knights (1030-1034), where the dog waits for the d<strong>in</strong>ers to look <strong>in</strong><br />

another direction <strong>in</strong> order to steal their food. We have already seen from the analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

284<br />

<strong>The</strong> emphasis on bread as the best food for dogs is also found <strong>in</strong> both Greek <strong>and</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> authors <strong>of</strong> later<br />

periods. Varro (Rust. 2.9.8-2.9.10) [188], for example, recommends that dogs should be fed barley bread.<br />

Similarly, Columella (Rust.7.12.10) [78] recommends barley flour with whey or bread made from the flour<br />

<strong>of</strong> emmer or bread-wheat mixed with the liquid <strong>of</strong> boiled beans. Arrian (Cyn. 8.1-8.2) [70] states that dogs<br />

“enjoy wheat bread or barley bread, for this food is best for a hound <strong>and</strong> there is no fear lest they be filled<br />

too full <strong>of</strong> it. <strong>The</strong>n it is better if they like their food dry, but even if you soak it <strong>in</strong> water <strong>and</strong> they like it, it<br />

is not bad”; translation: D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1964)<br />

170. F<strong>in</strong>ally, Nemesianus (Cyn. 151-156) [134] says that bread should be given to puppies.<br />

285<br />

A. Dalby, Siren Feasts. A History <strong>of</strong> Food <strong>and</strong> Gastronomy <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996)<br />

91.<br />

286<br />

Garsney, Food <strong>and</strong> Society 17-21.<br />

287<br />

Such evidence contrasts with the scene on an Attic red-figured lekythos that dates to 470-460 B.C. <strong>The</strong><br />

scene depicts a woman feed<strong>in</strong>g a dog that sits on its h<strong>in</strong>d legs <strong>and</strong> looks upward toward the food suspended<br />

from her h<strong>and</strong> (Fig. 19). For a short discussion <strong>of</strong> this lekythos, now <strong>in</strong> Rome (Accademia dei L<strong>in</strong>cei<br />

2478), see Lewis, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Woman 70-71, fig. 2.13; <strong>and</strong> 159-166 for further discussion <strong>of</strong> scenes on<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek pottery that depict women be<strong>in</strong>g surrounded by animals (e.g., dogs, hares, tortoises, mice,<br />

<strong>and</strong> birds).<br />

288<br />

Thorne, “Feed<strong>in</strong>g Behavior,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 106, presents a discussion <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

observations regard<strong>in</strong>g the feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>and</strong> how it is manifested <strong>in</strong> different breeds: “the<br />

Labrador retriever shows a tendency to over-eat when given the opportunity, while other breeds,<br />

particularly some <strong>of</strong> the toy <strong>and</strong> giant breeds, are so f<strong>in</strong>icky that it is <strong>of</strong>ten difficult to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> their<br />

optimum body weight.”<br />

188


Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant that wisdom <strong>and</strong> foresight were essential features <strong>of</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>telligence (mh~tij). 289 With the emphasis it places upon the dog’s shunn<strong>in</strong>g the woman,<br />

Diphilus’s fragment confirms the wisdom <strong>and</strong> foresight <strong>of</strong> the animal <strong>and</strong> classifies it,<br />

once aga<strong>in</strong>, among those creatures endowed with mh~tij.<br />

d. Dogs as Scavengers<br />

Unlike the textual evidence just cited, which illum<strong>in</strong>ates the types <strong>of</strong> food<br />

provided to domestic dogs, a passage from Thucydides’ account <strong>of</strong> the Peloponnesian<br />

war sheds lights on the type <strong>of</strong> food to which dogs were reduced when they were<br />

responsible for feed<strong>in</strong>g themselves. <strong>The</strong> context <strong>of</strong> the passage <strong>in</strong>dicates difficult<br />

circumstances, as it refers to the epidemic that decimated Athens dur<strong>in</strong>g the second year<br />

<strong>of</strong> the war (430 B.C.). Thucydides says:<br />

Indeed the character <strong>of</strong> the disease proved such that it baffles description,<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> the attack be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> each case too great for human nature to endure,<br />

while <strong>in</strong> one way <strong>in</strong> particular it showed pla<strong>in</strong>ly that it was different from any <strong>of</strong><br />

the familiar diseases: the birds, namely, <strong>and</strong> the four-footed animals which<br />

usually feed upon human bodies, either would not now come near them, though<br />

man lay unburied, or died if they tasted them. <strong>The</strong> evidence for this is that birds<br />

<strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d became noticeably scarce, <strong>and</strong> they were no longer to be seen either<br />

about the bodies or anywhere else; while the dogs gave a still better opportunity to<br />

observe what happened, because they live with man. (2.50) [187]<br />

Thucydides states clearly that observation <strong>of</strong> dogs’ behavior dur<strong>in</strong>g the outbreak <strong>of</strong> the<br />

disease was part <strong>of</strong> the effort to underst<strong>and</strong> its nature. Regard<strong>in</strong>g this behavior, his<br />

comment is straightforward: dogs either ran away from human corpses ly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the streets<br />

or fed on them <strong>and</strong> died. Thucydides implies that some dogs were able to detect danger<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus absta<strong>in</strong>ed from scaveng<strong>in</strong>g on corpses. On a mental level, the ability to<br />

289 Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence 3; also 27-48 for a discussion <strong>of</strong> sea creatures (e.g., starfish,<br />

octopus) <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong> animals (e.g., fox) as exhibit<strong>in</strong>g wisdom <strong>and</strong> foresight, <strong>and</strong> therefore considered<br />

endowed with this type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence.<br />

189


anticipate forthcom<strong>in</strong>g danger endows these animals with forethought. Consider<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

forethought was seen earlier to be a feature <strong>of</strong> mh~tij, then the abst<strong>in</strong>ence from<br />

scaveng<strong>in</strong>g that Thucydides relates can be identified as behavior aga<strong>in</strong> stemm<strong>in</strong>g from<br />

the dog’s possession <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence. Further, the dogs’ abst<strong>in</strong>ence from<br />

feed<strong>in</strong>g on corpses can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a result <strong>of</strong> their acute sense <strong>of</strong> smell. Ancient<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> this can<strong>in</strong>e quality is attested <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, for<br />

example, where the author ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that track<strong>in</strong>g the scent <strong>of</strong> hares makes dogs aware <strong>of</strong><br />

the presence <strong>of</strong> these animals (EN 3.10.7) [53]. 290 Thucydides states, however, that some<br />

other dogs did feed on human corpses, evidence which implies that their sense <strong>of</strong> smell<br />

may have not been as acute as those who absta<strong>in</strong>ed from scaveng<strong>in</strong>g. If can<strong>in</strong>e sense <strong>of</strong><br />

smell is to be taken as a guide here, then Thucydides’ dist<strong>in</strong>ction between dogs who fed<br />

on corpses <strong>and</strong> those who did not may suggest that he was aware <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g degrees <strong>of</strong><br />

olfaction <strong>in</strong> the animal. 291 To judge from this evidence <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with that<br />

290 This evidence accords well with a much earlier <strong>in</strong>cident: In the Odyssey, Argos was able to recognize<br />

Odysseus ow<strong>in</strong>g to his keen sense <strong>of</strong> smell. This sense is perhaps symbolized by the depiction <strong>of</strong> dogs on<br />

Attic grave stelai with their noses touch<strong>in</strong>g the ground. Consider<strong>in</strong>g that the road to the underworld was<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ed as complicated, twisted <strong>and</strong> therefore, treacherous, a keen sense <strong>of</strong> smell made dogs <strong>in</strong>valuable<br />

companions <strong>in</strong> that they could perceive their surround<strong>in</strong>gs accurately <strong>and</strong> promptly <strong>and</strong> thus elim<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

lurk<strong>in</strong>g dangers. An example <strong>of</strong> a stele depict<strong>in</strong>g a sniff<strong>in</strong>g dog is given <strong>in</strong> Kaltsas, <strong>Sculpture</strong> 153, cat. no.<br />

300 (Athens, NM 2894) where the animal is placed between two male figures who shake h<strong>and</strong>s (Fig. 20).<br />

<strong>The</strong> stele, which was found near the Dipylon gate <strong>in</strong> Athens, is made <strong>of</strong> Pentelic marble <strong>and</strong> has been dated<br />

to ca. 410-400 B.C. For the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek vision <strong>of</strong> the path to the underworld as treacherous, see S. G.<br />

Cole, “L<strong>and</strong>scapes <strong>of</strong> Dionysos <strong>and</strong> Elysian Fields,” <strong>in</strong> M. B. Cosmopoulos, ed., <strong>The</strong> Archaeology <strong>and</strong><br />

Ritual <strong>of</strong> Ancient Greek Secret Cults (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2003) 193-217.<br />

291 This suggestion is exemplified <strong>in</strong> a fragment <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes <strong>of</strong> Byzantium, later <strong>in</strong> date (III-II B.C.),<br />

that classifies female Laconian dogs as cleverer than males because they have a better sense <strong>of</strong> smell. <strong>The</strong><br />

fragment also alleges that the opposite holds true for Molossian dogs. <strong>The</strong>y have such discrim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> smell, it is said, that, even if they are given the flesh <strong>of</strong> another dog as food, they do not touch it. That<br />

dogs were believed to have a keen sense <strong>of</strong> smell, <strong>and</strong> avoided dog flesh as food is also mentioned by<br />

Aelian (HA 4.40) [2]. <strong>The</strong> ancient evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g differences <strong>in</strong> the olfactory acuity <strong>of</strong> dogs accords<br />

well with the results <strong>of</strong> modern studies. As Thorne, “Feed<strong>in</strong>g Behavior,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog<br />

108, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s: “Olfaction is particularly important <strong>in</strong> food selection. Olfactorily <strong>in</strong>tact dogs show a clear<br />

preference rank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> different meats, such as beef, pork, lamb, chicken or horse-meat, but anosmic dogs<br />

are unable to dist<strong>in</strong>guish the meats, although they can still differentiate meat from cereal.”<br />

190


egard<strong>in</strong>g mh~tij, the can<strong>in</strong>e behavior that Thucydides describes may be reflective <strong>of</strong> his<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> the physiological <strong>and</strong> mental abilities <strong>of</strong> the dog.<br />

Thucydides does not dist<strong>in</strong>guish between domestic <strong>and</strong> stray dogs, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> such dist<strong>in</strong>ction, one is left with the assumption that he talks about dogs liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> the streets, where the unburied bodies were ly<strong>in</strong>g. 292 His assertion that dogs would<br />

feed on corpses, although it has been doubted by modern scholarship, is a well-<br />

established idea <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek thought. 293 Homer, for example, <strong>in</strong> the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Iliad, speaks <strong>of</strong> the corpses <strong>of</strong> the Achaeans becom<strong>in</strong>g carrion for dogs <strong>and</strong> birds (1.1-<br />

1.5) [124]; 294 <strong>and</strong> later on, Priam fears the moment when his own trusted dogs will<br />

mutilate his dead body (22.66-22.76) [127]. 295 Also, <strong>in</strong> Aeschylus’ Suppliants, the<br />

Danaids, while contemplat<strong>in</strong>g suicide, th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> how their corpses will become prey to<br />

dogs <strong>and</strong> birds (800-801) [8]. And <strong>in</strong> Sophocles’ Antigone, Creon decrees that the body<br />

292 That animals had a prom<strong>in</strong>ent presence <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek cities, among them Athens, is evident from<br />

the large amounts <strong>of</strong> animal dung that designated servants called koprologoi were assigned to remove from<br />

the streets. Even if this evidence is taken to mean that the dung removed was <strong>of</strong> animals liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the<br />

house, still it does not preclude the possibility that it could also refer to the dung <strong>of</strong> animals, among them<br />

dogs, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the streets. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>ession <strong>of</strong> koprologoi, <strong>and</strong> the literary <strong>and</strong><br />

epigraphical evidence document<strong>in</strong>g their duties, see E. J. Owens, “<strong>The</strong> Koprologoi at Athens <strong>in</strong> the Fifth<br />

<strong>and</strong> Fourth Centuries B.C.,” CQ 33 (1983) 44-50. Pert<strong>in</strong>ent here is also the fact that the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

philosopher, Diogenes the Cynic (“Doggish”), who lived <strong>in</strong> the streets <strong>of</strong> Athens had adopted dog-like<br />

behavior, which <strong>in</strong>cluded public defecation (Dio Crys. Or. 8.36).<br />

293 K. F. Kitchell, Jr., “Man’s Best Friend? <strong>The</strong> Chang<strong>in</strong>g Role <strong>of</strong> the Dog <strong>in</strong> Greek Society,” <strong>in</strong> B. Santillo<br />

Frizell ed., PECUS. Man <strong>and</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>in</strong> Antiquity, Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Conference at the Swedish Institute<br />

<strong>in</strong> Rome, September 9-12, 2002 (<strong>The</strong> Swedish Institute <strong>in</strong> Rome. Projects <strong>and</strong> Sem<strong>in</strong>ars 1; Rome, 2004)<br />

181, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the statement <strong>of</strong> Thucydides presents as normal the behavior <strong>of</strong> dogs feed<strong>in</strong>g on dead<br />

bodies, but does not th<strong>in</strong>k that it provides evidence for this behavior tak<strong>in</strong>g place while the disease plagued<br />

Athens.<br />

294 For an example <strong>of</strong> birds feed<strong>in</strong>g on corpses <strong>in</strong> a battlefield, see the fragmented limestone stele <strong>of</strong><br />

Eannatum or Stele <strong>of</strong> the Vultures that dates to the Early Dynastic period (ca. 2500 B.C.), <strong>and</strong> was found at<br />

the Sumerian site <strong>of</strong> Girsu, <strong>in</strong> Mesopotamia. <strong>The</strong> stele commemorates the victory <strong>of</strong> Eannatum, ruler <strong>of</strong><br />

Lagash, over Enakalle <strong>of</strong> Umma, <strong>and</strong> portrays birds <strong>of</strong> prey <strong>and</strong> lions tear<strong>in</strong>g the flesh <strong>of</strong> the corpses <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dead as the lay <strong>in</strong> the battlefield. For a discussion <strong>and</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> this stele, see I. J. W<strong>in</strong>ter, “After the<br />

Battle is Over: <strong>The</strong> Stele <strong>of</strong> the Vultures <strong>and</strong> the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Pictorial Narrative <strong>in</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> the Ancient<br />

Near East,” <strong>in</strong> H. L. Kessler <strong>and</strong> M. S. Simpson, eds., Pictorial Narrative <strong>in</strong> Antiquity <strong>and</strong> the Middle Ages<br />

(Studies <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Art 16; Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 1985) 11-32.<br />

295 Also <strong>in</strong> the Odyssey (18.85-18.87), Ant<strong>in</strong>oos threatens Irus that he will mutilate his body <strong>and</strong> give his<br />

nose, ears, <strong>and</strong> genitals as raw food for dogs to eat. For a thorough summary <strong>of</strong> all the Homeric passages<br />

where dogs are presented as feed<strong>in</strong>g on dead bodies, see M. Faust, “Die künstlerische Verwendung von<br />

κύων ‘Hund’ <strong>in</strong> den homerischen Epen,” Glotta 48 (1970) 8-29.<br />

191


<strong>of</strong> Polynices shall not be buried, but left for birds <strong>and</strong> dogs to devour <strong>and</strong> savage (198-<br />

206) [185]. 296 Further, <strong>in</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> Persian burial customs, Herodotus ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that<br />

the corpses <strong>of</strong> Persians were not buried before they had been mangled by birds or dogs<br />

(1.140) [98]. That this type <strong>of</strong> behavior was recorded by both theatrical <strong>and</strong> prose writers<br />

<strong>and</strong> noted with reference to different cultures implies widespread comprehension <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wild <strong>and</strong> savage nature <strong>of</strong> the dog. In addition, the context <strong>of</strong> the epidemic <strong>in</strong> which<br />

Thucydides places this behavior suggests that the danger <strong>of</strong> the dog revert<strong>in</strong>g to it was<br />

imm<strong>in</strong>ent only under certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances, 297 or, to turn it around, that the animal had<br />

the ability to adjust its behavior to emerg<strong>in</strong>g circumstances. 298 This evidence, further<br />

suggests that even though the dog was enfolded <strong>in</strong>to <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society, its feral<br />

disposition cont<strong>in</strong>ued to shape its collective perception.<br />

296<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>of</strong> this idea <strong>in</strong> tragedy, see Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry 53-<br />

68.<br />

297<br />

Modern accounts <strong>of</strong> dogs feed<strong>in</strong>g on human corpses feature <strong>in</strong> journalistic literature as shock<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

almost <strong>in</strong>credulous <strong>in</strong>cidents, but always <strong>in</strong> association with extraord<strong>in</strong>ary circumstances, such as<br />

starvation. For an example <strong>of</strong> a pet dog feed<strong>in</strong>g on the corpse <strong>of</strong> its owner, see CNN, 2002, 15 May.<br />

Starv<strong>in</strong>g Dog Eats Its Owner. http://edition.cnn.com/2002/WORLD/europe/05/15/austria.dog/<strong>in</strong>dex.html.<br />

For a similar account <strong>of</strong> dogs gnaw<strong>in</strong>g on human corpses, see O. S. Dewaw, “Army Mechanic is Acquitted<br />

on Desertion Charge,” <strong>The</strong> New York Times (July 29, 2005) 15. What is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> these accounts is that<br />

even though the wild nature <strong>of</strong> dogs is implied as a background, it is always the circumstances that bear<br />

responsibility for dogs resort<strong>in</strong>g to this behavior. Such a condition may stem from the fact that the idea <strong>of</strong><br />

dogs feed<strong>in</strong>g on corpses contrasts sharply with the popular perception <strong>of</strong> the animal nowadays. As L. A.<br />

Hart, “Dogs as Human Companions,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 162, po<strong>in</strong>ts out, the vast majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> dogs resid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> modern households are thought <strong>of</strong> as social companions. Similarly, R. Copp<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>and</strong><br />

R. Schneider, “Evolution <strong>of</strong> Work<strong>in</strong>g Dogs,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 22, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that “when we<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> dogs we tend to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> animals that were selected for behavior performed <strong>in</strong> the service <strong>of</strong><br />

people.” Both statements suggest that the modern conception <strong>of</strong> the dog is based primarily on selected <strong>and</strong><br />

preferred aspects <strong>of</strong> its behavior, <strong>and</strong> when disturb<strong>in</strong>g aspects <strong>of</strong> its behavior emerge, they feature<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> journalistic literature.<br />

298<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to D. W. McDonald <strong>and</strong> G. M. Carr, “Variation <strong>in</strong> Dog Society: Between Resource<br />

Dispersion <strong>and</strong> Social Flux,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 211, a study <strong>of</strong> free-liv<strong>in</strong>g dogs <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong><br />

areas <strong>of</strong> Italy (e.g., Altopiano) showed that these animals adjusted their social behavior to their local<br />

circumstances. Thus, <strong>in</strong> villages, they adopted “a ‘fox-like’ existence <strong>in</strong> which <strong>in</strong>dividuals live <strong>in</strong> loose<br />

social groups that defend a territory, but pursue a relatively solitary existence. In the countryside, sylvatic<br />

dogs adopted a more wolf-like lifestyle, generally operat<strong>in</strong>g as a pack, although <strong>in</strong>dividuals sometimes<br />

travel alone.”<br />

192


e. <strong>The</strong> Savage Nature <strong>of</strong> Dogs<br />

Historical <strong>and</strong> philosophical writ<strong>in</strong>gs provide evidence for the division <strong>of</strong> dogs<br />

<strong>in</strong>to specific breeds as well as the genetic factors that contributed to the rise <strong>of</strong> these<br />

breeds. <strong>The</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g idea <strong>in</strong> these writ<strong>in</strong>gs is that certa<strong>in</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e breeds were the<br />

progeny <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terbreed<strong>in</strong>g between a wild animal <strong>and</strong> the dog. As noted earlier,<br />

Xenophon, for example, <strong>in</strong> his treatise On Hunt<strong>in</strong>g asserts that a particular breed <strong>of</strong><br />

Laconian hounds called Vulp<strong>in</strong>e was a hybrid between a fox <strong>and</strong> a dog (Cyn. 3.1)<br />

[189]. 299 In agreement with him is Aristotle, who refers to additional examples <strong>of</strong><br />

hybrids. After conclud<strong>in</strong>g his discussion on mice, for example, he says:<br />

Other animals too are produced from the mix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> different breeds, as <strong>in</strong> Cyrene<br />

the wolves mate with the dogs <strong>and</strong> generate young, <strong>and</strong> from fox <strong>and</strong> dog come<br />

the Laconian hounds. <strong>The</strong>y say too that the Indian hounds come from tiger <strong>and</strong><br />

dog, not immediately, but after the third mat<strong>in</strong>g; for they say the first <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

like a savage beast. <strong>The</strong>y take the bitches to deserted places <strong>and</strong> tie them up; <strong>and</strong><br />

many are devoured, if the wild animal does not happen to be excited for mat<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(HA 7.607a) [65]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage confirms the idea that crossbreed<strong>in</strong>g between a specific wild animal <strong>and</strong> the<br />

dog produced a specific can<strong>in</strong>e breed. <strong>The</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> the breed <strong>of</strong> Indian hounds,<br />

however, is important, for it sheds light on specific beliefs about the savage nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dog. Aristotle identifies the breed <strong>of</strong> Indian hounds as the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a third-generation<br />

mat<strong>in</strong>g between a dog <strong>and</strong> a tiger. 300 His statement demonstrates that he conceived <strong>of</strong> a<br />

299<br />

In addition, Pollux notes that <strong>in</strong> Hycarnia, a region to the south <strong>of</strong> the Caspian Sea, dogs were crossed<br />

with lions (Onom. 5.38) [163].<br />

300<br />

For the suggestion that the Indian dog that Aristotle describes here was a real dog, see A. Platt, “On the<br />

Indian Dog,” CQ 3 (1909) 241-243; also R. H. A. Merlen, De Canibus. Dog <strong>and</strong> Hound <strong>in</strong> Antiquity<br />

(London, 1971) 31-32. <strong>The</strong> earliest reference to Indian dogs is that <strong>of</strong> Herodotus (7.187), who records that<br />

when Xerxes <strong>in</strong>vaded <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>in</strong> the early fifth century B.C., his army <strong>in</strong>cluded vast numbers <strong>of</strong> “Indian”<br />

dogs. <strong>The</strong> earliest literary evidence for the use <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>in</strong> warfare comes from Polyaenus, a second-century<br />

A.D. author, who refers to a sixth-century B.C. battle between Alyattes, the k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Lydia, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Cimmerians: “When the monstrous <strong>and</strong> the bestial Cimmerians made an expedition aga<strong>in</strong>st him, Alyattes<br />

brought out for battle his strongest dogs along with the rest <strong>of</strong> his force. <strong>The</strong> dogs set upon the barbarians<br />

as if they were wild animals, killed many <strong>and</strong> forced the rest to flee shamefully” (Strategems 7.2.1-7.2.6;<br />

193


eed as the result <strong>of</strong> a successive process <strong>of</strong> hybridization. 301 Further, his explanation<br />

that the progeny <strong>of</strong> the first crossbreed<strong>in</strong>g between a dog <strong>and</strong> a tiger was “like a savage<br />

beast” is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it suggests two ideas: 1) that this savage nature manifested itself<br />

<strong>in</strong> an obvious way, perhaps <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>and</strong>/or behavior, <strong>and</strong> 2) that it was<br />

thought to dim<strong>in</strong>ish as each successive phase <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>breed<strong>in</strong>g occurred. In other words,<br />

until it reached the desirable, subsided stage that marked the breed <strong>of</strong> Indian hounds, the<br />

characteristic <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e wildness underwent an evolutionary process that was each time<br />

spurred by a genetic factor. 302<br />

translation: P. Krentz <strong>and</strong> E. L. Wheeler, eds., trs., Polyaenus. Strategems <strong>of</strong> War II (Chicago, 1994) 625.<br />

Polyaenus mentions a second <strong>in</strong>cident <strong>of</strong> warlike character <strong>in</strong> which dogs are featured. Referr<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

Persian <strong>in</strong>vasion <strong>of</strong> Egypt (525 B.C.) by Cambyses, he says: “Cambyses was besieg<strong>in</strong>g Pelusium. <strong>The</strong><br />

Egyptians stoutly resisted by block<strong>in</strong>g the entries to Egypt, <strong>and</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g up many batteries <strong>of</strong> artillery they<br />

shot quick-fir<strong>in</strong>g catapult bolts, stones, <strong>and</strong> fire. Cambyses drew up <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> his army as many animals<br />

as the Egyptians worshipped—dogs, sheep, cats, ibexes. <strong>The</strong> Egyptians stopped shoot<strong>in</strong>g for fear <strong>of</strong><br />

strik<strong>in</strong>g one <strong>of</strong> the holy animals. Thus Cambyses captured Pelusium <strong>and</strong> entered Egypt” (Strategems 7.9.1-<br />

7.9.9); translation: Krentz <strong>and</strong> Wheeler, Polyaenus. Strategems 639. Evidence that dogs were used <strong>in</strong><br />

warfare <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period, derives from Aelian, who mentions that a dog had served <strong>in</strong> the battle <strong>of</strong><br />

Marathon (490 B.C.):<br />

An Athenian took with him a Dog as fellow-soldier to the battle <strong>of</strong> Marathon, <strong>and</strong> both are figured<br />

<strong>in</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Stoa Poecile, nor was the Dog denied honor but received the reward <strong>of</strong> the<br />

danger it had undergone <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g seen among the companions <strong>of</strong> Cynericus, Epizelus, <strong>and</strong><br />

Callimachus. <strong>The</strong>y <strong>and</strong> the dog were pa<strong>in</strong>ted by Micon, though some say it was not his work but<br />

that <strong>of</strong> Polygnotus <strong>of</strong> Thasos (NA 7.38) [3].<br />

Pausanias’s account <strong>of</strong> this picture (1.15.3), however, does not mention this detail.<br />

301 A passage from Aelian, that cites knowledge <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian reference to Indian hounds, is crucial <strong>in</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g how the particular steps <strong>of</strong> this process <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>breed<strong>in</strong>g were thought to have occurred:<br />

Indian histories teach us the follow<strong>in</strong>g facts also. Huntsmen take thoroughbred bitches<br />

which are good at track<strong>in</strong>g wild animals <strong>and</strong> are very swift <strong>of</strong> foot to places <strong>in</strong>fested by<br />

these animals; they tie them to trees <strong>and</strong> then go away, simply, as the say<strong>in</strong>g is, try<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

throw <strong>of</strong> the dice. And if tigers f<strong>in</strong>d them when they have caught noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> are famished,<br />

they tear them to pieces. If however they arrive on heat <strong>and</strong> full-fed they couple with the<br />

bitches, for tigers too when gorged turn their thoughts to sexual <strong>in</strong>tercourse. From this union,<br />

so it said, a tiger is born, not a hound. And from this tiger <strong>and</strong> a bitch aga<strong>in</strong> a tiger would be<br />

born, although the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this last <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> a bitch takes after its dam, <strong>and</strong> the seed<br />

degenerates <strong>and</strong> a hound is born. Nor will Aristotle contradict this. Now these hounds which<br />

can boast a tiger for sire scorn to pursue a stag or to face a boar, but are glad to rush at lions <strong>and</strong><br />

thereby give pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> their pedigree (NA 8.1) [4].<br />

302 <strong>The</strong> parallel between this process <strong>and</strong> the modern underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> how, for example, the domestication<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dog—thought to be <strong>in</strong>itially a wolf—occurred is strik<strong>in</strong>g. J. Clutton-Brock, “Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Dog:<br />

Domestication <strong>and</strong> Early History,” <strong>in</strong> Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog 15, hypothesizes that, after the wolf<br />

was <strong>in</strong>corporated <strong>in</strong>to the social structure <strong>of</strong> the human community <strong>and</strong> was tamed, it would have become<br />

less <strong>and</strong> less like its wild forbears “because <strong>in</strong>herently variable characters, such as coat color, carriage <strong>of</strong><br />

the ears <strong>and</strong> tail, overall size <strong>and</strong> the proportions <strong>of</strong> the limbs would have been altered by the comb<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

194


<strong>The</strong> textual evidence discussed <strong>in</strong> this section <strong>in</strong>dicates that steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> gobbl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

food were two aspects <strong>of</strong> feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior for which the dog was known <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. This can<strong>in</strong>e behavior served as a metaphor for discuss<strong>in</strong>g similar behavior <strong>in</strong><br />

humans, more specifically, political figures accused <strong>of</strong> appropriat<strong>in</strong>g public money for<br />

themselves. Dur<strong>in</strong>g the process <strong>of</strong> steal<strong>in</strong>g food, the dog was observed to exhibit three<br />

specific characteristics: vigilance, agility, <strong>and</strong> swiftness. That these characteristics were<br />

essential to the type <strong>of</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligence known as mh~tij <strong>in</strong>dicates that the dog was<br />

considered to hold this mental capacity. <strong>The</strong> punishment that the dog received for its<br />

steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> food was beat<strong>in</strong>g, a cruel treatment that features <strong>in</strong> the texts as both a<br />

conscious <strong>and</strong> culturally specific behavior. This physical aggression toward the animal<br />

contrasts sharply with evidence that domestic dogs were provided with a variety <strong>of</strong> foods<br />

selected on the basis <strong>of</strong> their nutritional value. <strong>The</strong> texts also <strong>in</strong>dicate that the savage<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> scaveng<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the dog was <strong>in</strong>tegral parts <strong>of</strong> its collective image.<br />

Such behavior evoked the image <strong>of</strong> human corpses becom<strong>in</strong>g carrion for dogs, an image<br />

that <strong>in</strong>spired fear <strong>and</strong> anxiety, <strong>and</strong> also served as a rem<strong>in</strong>der that dangerous feral traits <strong>of</strong><br />

the animal had not completely died out. Unlike the fear that the thought <strong>of</strong> the dog<br />

feed<strong>in</strong>g on human flesh evoked, however, can<strong>in</strong>e flesh as food does not seem to have<br />

generated human responses <strong>of</strong> the same type. On the contrary, the texts that are<br />

discussed next, present the practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh as one from which <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Greek society did not shy away.<br />

effects <strong>of</strong> artificial <strong>and</strong> natural selection. In this way, the wolf became a dog; that is, it was no longer a wild<br />

carnivore but a part <strong>of</strong> human society with physical <strong>and</strong> behavioral characteristics adapted to its economic,<br />

aesthetic or ritual functions.”<br />

195


SECTION 3<br />

Dogs as Food<br />

<strong>The</strong> practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh features <strong>in</strong> two types <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> texts: comic<br />

accounts <strong>and</strong> medical treatises. In terms <strong>of</strong> frequency, the references to consumption <strong>of</strong><br />

dog flesh conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the treatises outnumber by far those found <strong>in</strong> comedy. Later Greek<br />

authors, however, such as Galen, Sextus Empiricus (both A.D. II), <strong>and</strong> Porphyry (A.D.<br />

III), advocate abst<strong>in</strong>ence from consum<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>Greece</strong> among those<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the world that, <strong>in</strong> their times, shared this attitude. Sextus Empiricus, <strong>in</strong><br />

particular, conveys this <strong>in</strong>formation by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out its sharp contrast with the practice <strong>of</strong><br />

fourth-century B.C. Greek physicians <strong>of</strong> prescrib<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh to their patients as dietary<br />

treatment. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion beg<strong>in</strong>s with the post-<strong>Classical</strong> Greek attitudes to the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> dogs, <strong>and</strong> proceeds to comic <strong>and</strong> medical accounts <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period, which <strong>in</strong>dicate that contemporary Greek society did not absta<strong>in</strong> from eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs.<br />

a. Post-<strong>Classical</strong> Greek Attitudes to the Practice <strong>of</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g Dogs<br />

<strong>The</strong> dietary treatises <strong>of</strong> Galen <strong>of</strong> Pergamon, a philosopher <strong>and</strong> physician who<br />

worked <strong>in</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>ria <strong>and</strong> mostly Rome <strong>in</strong> the second century A.D., provide evidence<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g the practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs <strong>in</strong> that time. In his treatise On the Properties <strong>of</strong><br />

Foodstuffs, Galen notes: “As for dogs, what can I say? In some countries they are <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

eaten when they are young <strong>and</strong> plump, <strong>and</strong> particularly after they have been castrated”<br />

(3.664) [93]. 303 As can be seen, Galen’s statement is quite general <strong>in</strong> its character. He<br />

303 This statement accords well with the results <strong>of</strong> the exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> skeletons <strong>of</strong> puppies found <strong>in</strong> twenty-<br />

six assemblage deposits <strong>in</strong> an area <strong>of</strong> both domestic <strong>and</strong> commercial activity at the site <strong>of</strong> Sardis. Dated<br />

between the late seventh <strong>and</strong> early to mid-fifth century B.C., each <strong>of</strong> these deposits, thought to be part <strong>of</strong> a<br />

196


efers to some countries as consumers <strong>of</strong> dog flesh, which suggests his view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

practice as a cultural <strong>and</strong> perhaps ethnic marker, but does not specify which these<br />

countries are. It may be reasonable to assume that he th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>of</strong> them as distant <strong>and</strong>/or<br />

foreign. Although absent from his statement, evidence that this was most likely the case<br />

comes from the next passage, <strong>in</strong> which Galen clearly states that Asia, <strong>Greece</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Italy,<br />

the immediate world <strong>in</strong> which he lived, worked, <strong>and</strong> traveled, absta<strong>in</strong>ed from eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs.<br />

In his treatise On the Th<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g Diet, he says:<br />

As for dogs <strong>and</strong> foxes—I have never tasted their meat, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not the custom<br />

to eat it either <strong>in</strong> Asia or <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, or <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>in</strong> Italy. But there are apparently<br />

many parts <strong>of</strong> the world where they are eaten, <strong>and</strong> my conjecture would be that<br />

their effects would be similar to those <strong>of</strong> the hare; for hare, dog, <strong>and</strong> fox are all<br />

equally dry. (Vict. Att. 8) [94]<br />

In this passage, Galen po<strong>in</strong>ts out that he never ate dog meat. He also counts <strong>Greece</strong><br />

among the places which absta<strong>in</strong>ed from this practice <strong>in</strong> his day. As was the case above,<br />

Galen reports that many parts <strong>of</strong> the world did not shun eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> his conception <strong>of</strong> the practice as a cultural marker. Galen states that dog meat, like<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the hare <strong>and</strong> fox, would be dry as food. As it will be seen later, the idea <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dryness <strong>of</strong> dog flesh features prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> the Hippocratic treatises, evidence<br />

suggest<strong>in</strong>g that Galen was well acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with his predecessors’ writ<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Greek practice <strong>of</strong> absta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs is also attested <strong>in</strong> the writ<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

<strong>of</strong> Sextus Empiricus, another philosopher <strong>and</strong> physician <strong>of</strong> the second century A.D. In<br />

ritual meal, comprises an one-h<strong>and</strong>led jug, an o<strong>in</strong>ochoe, a skyphos, a shallow dish, an iron knife, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

bones <strong>of</strong> a puppy placed <strong>in</strong> the jug. Regard<strong>in</strong>g these bones, C. H. Greenewalt, Jr., Ritual D<strong>in</strong>ners <strong>in</strong> Early<br />

Historic Sardis (Berkeley, 1978) 24, remarks that: “<strong>in</strong> no case is the baculum (or penis) present, but this<br />

need not imply that the puppies were all females as this bone is rather small <strong>and</strong> fragile <strong>in</strong> male canids as<br />

young as this.”<br />

197


his treatise Outl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> Pyrrhonism, he presents a specific reason for not eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs,<br />

while highlight<strong>in</strong>g both contemporary <strong>and</strong> ancient cases <strong>of</strong> evidence to the contrary:<br />

Eat<strong>in</strong>g dog’s flesh, too, is thought by us [Greeks] to be s<strong>in</strong>ful (a)ni/eron), but some<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Thracians are reported to be dog-eaters. Possibly this practice was<br />

customary also amongst the Greeks; <strong>and</strong> on this account Diocles, too, start<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the practices <strong>of</strong> the Asclepiadae, prescribes that hounds’ flesh should be<br />

given to certa<strong>in</strong> patients. (P. 3.225) [184]<br />

Along with consider<strong>in</strong>g it s<strong>in</strong>ful, the passage associates the consumption <strong>of</strong> dog flesh<br />

with a specific cultural group, the Thracians. In this way, the approach to this practice as<br />

a cultural marker is aga<strong>in</strong> clear. <strong>The</strong> passage also expresses the suspicion that eat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

dogs was a Greek habit <strong>of</strong> the past. 304 <strong>The</strong> reference to Diocles, a physician <strong>of</strong> the fourth<br />

century B.C., <strong>and</strong> his prescription <strong>of</strong> dog flesh as a dietary treatment suggests that<br />

contemporary medic<strong>in</strong>e did not recognize the curative properties that its ancient<br />

counterpart attributed to dog flesh. Like Galen, Sextus Empiricus appears to be well-<br />

acqua<strong>in</strong>ted with ancient medical literature.<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the consumption <strong>of</strong> dog flesh comes from<br />

Porphyry. In his treatise On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, the author categorically<br />

denies <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>in</strong> this practice: “<strong>and</strong> though the war aga<strong>in</strong>st the beasts is just, we<br />

absta<strong>in</strong> from many that live with humans. That is why the Greeks do not eat dogs, or<br />

horses, or donkeys” (1.14) [165]. In this statement, the reference to dogs as animals<br />

304 <strong>The</strong> Early Bronze Age site <strong>of</strong> Lerna is the earliest Greek site that has yielded evidence for the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> dogs <strong>in</strong> levels that date from 2200 to 1900 B.C.; N.-G. Gejwall, Lerna I: A Preclassical<br />

Site <strong>in</strong> the Argolid: <strong>The</strong> Fauna (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton 1969) 17-18. Additional evidence comes from the Bronze<br />

through Iron Age site <strong>of</strong> Kastanas: C. Becker, Kastanas. Ausgrabungen <strong>in</strong> e<strong>in</strong>em Siedlungshügel der<br />

Bronze-und Eisenzeit Makedoniens 1975-1979, die Teirnochenfunde (Prähistorische Archäologie <strong>in</strong><br />

Südosteuropa 5; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1986) 88-97, 276-279; also from the Iron Age though Orientaliz<strong>in</strong>g Period site <strong>of</strong><br />

Kastro <strong>in</strong> East Crete; L. M. Snyder <strong>and</strong> W. E. Klippel, “From Lerna to Kastro: Further Thoughts on Dogs<br />

as Food <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>; Perceptions, Prejudices <strong>and</strong> Re<strong>in</strong>vestigations,” <strong>in</strong> E. Kotjabopoulou et al., eds.,<br />

Zooarchaeology <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>: Recent Advances (London, 2003) 221-231.<br />

198


liv<strong>in</strong>g together with humans br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d Aristotle’s earlier designation <strong>of</strong> dogs as<br />

“symbiotic with humans”[61]. What is strik<strong>in</strong>g, however, is that Porphyry presents this<br />

symbiosis as the ma<strong>in</strong> reason for absta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from eat<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh. This evidence<br />

suggests that spatial closeness <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between humans <strong>and</strong> the dog might have<br />

been responsible for produc<strong>in</strong>g a sympathetic attitude towards the animal. 305<br />

It is clear from the literary evidence cited here that the practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs was<br />

not customary among Greeks <strong>in</strong> the second <strong>and</strong> third centuries A.D. <strong>The</strong> medical <strong>and</strong><br />

philosophical writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Galen, Sextus Empiricus, <strong>and</strong> Porphyry <strong>in</strong>dicate that specific<br />

ideas, such as the one that considered eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs a s<strong>in</strong>, provided the basis for advocat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

abst<strong>in</strong>ence from it. In record<strong>in</strong>g that many cultures, such as the Thracians, practiced<br />

eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs, these authors also <strong>in</strong>dicate their approach to the practice as a sign <strong>of</strong> cultural<br />

otherness. Yet they ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> an awareness that this very same practice was<br />

recommended as treatment by Greek physicians <strong>in</strong> the fourth-century B.C. In their<br />

m<strong>in</strong>ds, therefore, the attitude towards eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs was not a po<strong>in</strong>t where past <strong>and</strong> present<br />

met.<br />

305 <strong>The</strong> emotional dimension <strong>of</strong> the relationship between humans <strong>and</strong> dogs, especially <strong>in</strong> second- <strong>and</strong> thirdcentury<br />

A.D. <strong>Greece</strong>, is a topic that deserves further attention, given the literary <strong>and</strong> material evidence that<br />

exists. As examples are mentioned here Aelian’s reference to dogs as tro&fimoi, which translates as “foster<br />

children,” (NA 11.36; 16.39); also the affection (storgh&) <strong>of</strong> the bitch Parthenope for her owner is recorded<br />

on the <strong>in</strong>scription (I.G. XII. 2, no. 459) on a funerary stele that depicts a dog <strong>in</strong> relief. <strong>The</strong> stele was found<br />

at Mytilene, Lesbos <strong>and</strong> has been dated to the second century A.D. For the suggestion that this <strong>in</strong>scription<br />

marked the grave <strong>of</strong> a dog, see S. Georgoudi, “Funeral Epigrams for <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>” 37. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

specific terms, such as storgh& (affection), used to expressed the emotions that marked the relationship<br />

between animals <strong>and</strong> their owners <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong> dur<strong>in</strong>g this period, see L. Bodson, “Motivation for Pet-<br />

Keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> Rome: A Prelim<strong>in</strong>ary Survey,” <strong>in</strong> A. L. Podberschek et al., eds.,<br />

Companion <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Us: Explor<strong>in</strong>g the Relationships between People <strong>and</strong> Pets (Cambridge, 2000) 35.<br />

199


. Dogs as Food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong><br />

Comedy<br />

A passage from Aristophanes’ Knights that refers to the sell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> sausages made<br />

<strong>of</strong> dog meat constitutes the earliest comic reference to dogs as food. Cleon/Paphlagon<br />

<strong>and</strong> the sausage seller, who seeks to replace the former as representative <strong>of</strong> the Athenian<br />

assembly (demos), rival each other <strong>in</strong> order to w<strong>in</strong> the favor <strong>of</strong> the demos represented<br />

here by a homonymous old man. Demos sides with the sausage seller, who proposes the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g punishment to be <strong>in</strong>flicted on Paphlagon:<br />

DEMOS<br />

And Paphlagon, who behaved this way, tell me how you’ll<br />

punish him.<br />

SAUSAGE SELLER<br />

Noth<strong>in</strong>g severe; he’s merely go<strong>in</strong>g to take my old job. He’ll<br />

have his own sausage st<strong>and</strong> at the city gates, hash<strong>in</strong>g up<br />

dog (ku&neia) <strong>and</strong> ass meat <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> politics (pra&gmas<strong>in</strong>),<br />

gett<strong>in</strong>g drunk <strong>and</strong> trad<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sults with the whores,<br />

<strong>and</strong> dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g the run<strong>of</strong>f from the public baths. (Eq. 1395-1401) [39]<br />

Despite its allusion to dog flesh as food, the proposal <strong>of</strong> the sausage seller that Paphlagon<br />

should be demoted to a person who stuffs the meats <strong>of</strong> dog <strong>and</strong> ass <strong>in</strong>to sausages, 306 <strong>and</strong><br />

sells them at the gates <strong>of</strong> the city, 307 has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as evidence that dog flesh was<br />

not consumed <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. Comment<strong>in</strong>g on the subject, René Merlen, for<br />

306 Dalby, Siren Feasts 60, discusses a passage from Galen’s On the Properties <strong>of</strong> Foods (3.1.9), as<br />

evidence that ass flesh was sometimes eaten <strong>in</strong> historic times <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. Pollux (Onom. 9.47-9.48)<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicates that the place where asses’ flesh was sold <strong>in</strong> the agora was called memno&neia; also Erotian<br />

(Glossarium Hippocraticum 82.8), who cites Aristophanes as his source, says that the place <strong>in</strong> the agora<br />

where carrion was sold was called kene/breion after the word for the flesh <strong>of</strong> carrion. For these testimonia,<br />

see R. E. Wycherley, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Agora III. Literary <strong>and</strong> Epigraphical Testimonia (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1957) 186,<br />

197. J. Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Boastful Chef: <strong>The</strong> Discourse <strong>of</strong> Food <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Comedy (Oxford, 2000) 180,<br />

n. 136, notes that the location <strong>of</strong> these stalls is unknown.<br />

307 Additional evidence that sausages were sold both <strong>in</strong> the agora <strong>and</strong> at the gates derives from another part<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristophanes’ Knights, where Paphlagon asks the sausage seller: “Did you really sell your sausages <strong>in</strong><br />

the agora, or at the gates?”(1245-1247); translation: Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, Knights 126. For further discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

both <strong>of</strong> these areas as the ones were various goods were sold, see Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Boastful Chef 180, ns. 133-<br />

135.<br />

200


example, states that “these l<strong>in</strong>es surely <strong>in</strong>dicate beyond all doubt that meat <strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

never passed the lips <strong>of</strong> the Greeks.” 308 Similarly, Frederick Simoons refers to this<br />

passage as evidence that “seems to confirm the fact that dog flesh was not a usual food”<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. 309 He also suggests that the reference to dog flesh “may have been<br />

an attempt at ridicule by Aristophanes,” but does not expla<strong>in</strong> who the subject <strong>of</strong> this<br />

ridicule may have been. 310 Further, Lilja sees the passage as an <strong>in</strong>dication “that the<br />

Greeks did not normally eat dog’s or ass’s flesh.” 311 In her view, Aristophanes used the<br />

reference to dog flesh as an opportunity to ridicule the learned op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> his great<br />

contemporary, Hippocrates, who prescribed dog’s flesh as a curative food for certa<strong>in</strong><br />

diseases. 312 Ma<strong>in</strong>oldi elucidates the connection between Aristophanes <strong>and</strong> Hippocrates<br />

by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that the term ku&neia, which the former uses to refer to “dog flesh” (Eq.<br />

1398), is also used <strong>in</strong> the Hippocratic treatises, where dog flesh features as therapeutic<br />

food. 313 Furthermore, <strong>in</strong> these treatises, she expla<strong>in</strong>s, the term ku&neia is usually<br />

accompanied by the term kre/ata, which translates as “meats,” <strong>and</strong> which Aristophanes<br />

replaced with the term pra&gmata (Eq. 1399) <strong>in</strong> order to evoke the political affairs <strong>of</strong> the<br />

city. 314 Although these are reasonable arguments, they do not detract from the fact that<br />

308 Merlen, De Canibus 86.<br />

309 F. J. Simoons, Eat Not This Flesh: Food Avoidances from Prehistory to the Present (Madison, 1994)<br />

235.<br />

310 Simoons, Eat Not This Flesh 235.<br />

311 Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry 72.<br />

312 Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry 72.<br />

313 Ma<strong>in</strong>oldi, L’image du loup et du chien 174. For various examples from the Hippocratic Collection<br />

where this term is used, see <strong>in</strong>fra p. 56.<br />

314 Ma<strong>in</strong>oldi, L’image du loup et du chien 174; also for the tendency <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes to draw upon the<br />

medical term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>of</strong> his time, the <strong>in</strong>fluence on <strong>and</strong> the literal or metaphorical use <strong>of</strong> these terms <strong>in</strong> his<br />

plays, see H. W. Miller, “Aristophanes <strong>and</strong> Medical Language,” TAPA 76 (1945) 74-84. This suggestion<br />

should not be taken to mean, however, that the terms ku&neia <strong>and</strong> kre/as<strong>in</strong> constituted medical term<strong>in</strong>ology.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are used frequently by Hippocrates, but fit better <strong>in</strong>to the language <strong>of</strong> butchery <strong>and</strong> process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

animal products. Given this evidence, their alteration to ku&neia pra&gmas<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Knights accords well<br />

with the fact that, <strong>in</strong> this play, both Paphlagon, a tanner, <strong>and</strong> the sausage seller are essentially processors <strong>of</strong><br />

meat products, who sell them <strong>in</strong> the agora, a place also l<strong>in</strong>ked here with the sell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> political favors; for a<br />

201


the passage refers to dog flesh as an <strong>in</strong>gredient <strong>of</strong> sausages, <strong>and</strong> thus <strong>in</strong>dicates the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> this flesh <strong>in</strong> the fifth century B.C. <strong>The</strong> only scholar who has recognized<br />

the importance <strong>of</strong> this evidence is Ge<strong>of</strong>frey Arnott, who states that Aristophanes’s<br />

comment should be taken to mean that dog meat was <strong>in</strong>deed eaten, but only by the<br />

poor. 315 In support <strong>of</strong> his argument, Arnott presents a fragment <strong>of</strong> the comic poet Alexis<br />

(c. 375-275 B.C.) that refers to the consumption <strong>of</strong> dog meat by a poor devotee <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Pythagoreans. <strong>The</strong> fragment, which belongs to Alexis’s comedy Men <strong>of</strong> Tarentum, <strong>and</strong> is<br />

cited by Athenaeus, is a discussion between two persons <strong>of</strong> the types <strong>of</strong> food from which<br />

the Pythagoreans absta<strong>in</strong>ed:<br />

A. <strong>The</strong> devotees <strong>of</strong> Pythagoras, we hear, eat neither fish nor anyth<strong>in</strong>g else<br />

that has life, <strong>and</strong> they are the only ones who dr<strong>in</strong>k no w<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

B. Yes, but Epicharides devours dogs, <strong>and</strong> he is a Pythagorean.<br />

A. Of course, after he has killed one, for then it no longer has life!<br />

(Deipn. 4.161b-4.161c) [72]<br />

This fragment refers directly to the consumption <strong>of</strong> dog flesh. Epicharides, a<br />

Pythagorean, ignored the dietary laws <strong>of</strong> his sect <strong>and</strong> ate dog flesh. His behavior appears<br />

shameful, when seen <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> evidence that Pythagoras considered dogs to be<br />

re<strong>in</strong>carnated human souls, <strong>and</strong> proposed abst<strong>in</strong>ence from eat<strong>in</strong>g them because it was like<br />

eat<strong>in</strong>g deceased friends. 316 Arnott suggests that Epicharides should be considered a poor<br />

man. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, <strong>in</strong> fourth-century comedic contexts, the term “Pythagorean,”<br />

which Alexis applies to Epicharides, signified, usually with contempt, beggarly ascetics,<br />

succ<strong>in</strong>ct discussion <strong>of</strong> these <strong>in</strong>terconnected ideas, see Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, “Comic Cuis<strong>in</strong>e,” <strong>in</strong> Dobrov, ed, <strong>The</strong> City as<br />

Comedy 259.<br />

315 W. G. Arnott, Alexis: <strong>The</strong> Fragments. A Commentary (Cambridge, 1996) 636, n. 1.<br />

316 For the ancient sources for Pythagoras, see C. Osborne, “Boundaries <strong>in</strong> Nature: Eat<strong>in</strong>g with <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

the Fifth Century B.C.,” BICS 37 (1990) 23-24.<br />

202


<strong>and</strong> thus poor men. 317 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, Arnott <strong>in</strong>terprets Epicharides’s<br />

eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> dog meat as evidence that this was food for the low strata <strong>of</strong> fourth-century<br />

Athenian society. <strong>The</strong> consumption <strong>of</strong> dog meat <strong>in</strong> Aristophanes’ Knights implies the<br />

same th<strong>in</strong>g for the fifth century, he argues. 318 His analysis <strong>of</strong>fers an <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

valuation <strong>of</strong> the dog as food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Athens.<br />

Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the consumption <strong>of</strong> dog flesh <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong><br />

comes from two other texts <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes, an extant fragment <strong>of</strong> his lost play<br />

Banqueters (427 B.C.), <strong>and</strong> a passage from Plutus (388 B.C.). <strong>The</strong> fragment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Banqueters, which seems to be part <strong>of</strong> a dialogue between two persons, preserves the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g question:<br />

What does this mean? You’ve bought a little white pup (kuni/dion)<br />

on which the goddess at the cross may sup? (fr. 204 Kock) [40]<br />

By consider<strong>in</strong>g a white puppy as food <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g to the goddess <strong>of</strong> the crossroads, the<br />

fragment alludes to the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> dogs as part <strong>of</strong> a religious observance. 319 Regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

317 Arnott, Alexis: <strong>The</strong> Fragments 581-582, 635, presents the texts <strong>of</strong> Aristophon (e.g., 9.12, 12.3), another<br />

fourth-century comic poet, as additional evidence for this contempt.<br />

318 Arnott, Alexis: <strong>The</strong> Fragments 636, n. 1.<br />

319 Additional evidence rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the situation described <strong>in</strong> the Banqueters comes from Plutarch (A.D.<br />

I-II), whose discussion <strong>of</strong> the dog focuses on the past: “Nor, <strong>in</strong> fact, did the men <strong>of</strong> old th<strong>in</strong>k that this<br />

animal was wholly pure, for it was never sacrificed to any <strong>of</strong> the Olympian gods; <strong>and</strong> when it is sent to the<br />

cross-roads as a supper for the earth-goddess Hekate, it has its due portion among sacrifices that avert <strong>and</strong><br />

expiate evil. In Sparta they immolate puppies to the bloodiest <strong>of</strong> the gods Enyalius; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> Boeotia the<br />

ceremony <strong>of</strong> public purification is to pass between the parts <strong>of</strong> a dog which has been cut <strong>in</strong> twa<strong>in</strong>” (Quaest.<br />

Rom. 290D) [161]. In another <strong>in</strong>stance, he clarifies that the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> a dog was an act <strong>of</strong> purification:<br />

“Nearly all the Greeks used a dog as the sacrificial victim for ceremonies <strong>of</strong> purification; <strong>and</strong> some, at least,<br />

make use <strong>of</strong> it even to this day. <strong>The</strong>y br<strong>in</strong>g forth for Hekate puppies along with the other materials for the<br />

purification, <strong>and</strong> rub round about with puppies such persons as are <strong>in</strong> need <strong>of</strong> cleans<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

purification they call periskylakismos” (Quaest. Rom. 280C) [160]. Pausanias (A.D. II) is also another<br />

author, who presents evidence that l<strong>in</strong>ks dog sacrifices to deities protect<strong>in</strong>g crossroads: “Before the fight<strong>in</strong>g<br />

they sacrifice <strong>in</strong> the Phoebaeum which is outside the city, nor far distant from <strong>The</strong>rapne. Here each<br />

company <strong>of</strong> youths sacrifices a puppy to Enyalius, hold<strong>in</strong>g that the most valiant <strong>of</strong> tame animals is an<br />

acceptable victim to the most valiant <strong>of</strong> the gods. I know <strong>of</strong> no other Greeks who are accustomed to<br />

sacrifice puppies except the people <strong>of</strong> Colophon; these too sacrifice a puppy, a black bitch, to the Wayside<br />

203


the identity <strong>of</strong> the deity honored with this food, Ilmo Von Rudl<strong>of</strong>f suggests that it may be<br />

Hekate. 320 Although he does not expla<strong>in</strong> his suggestion further, support<strong>in</strong>g evidence for<br />

it comes from Sarah Johnston’s study, which ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “Hekate’s role as a goddess<br />

<strong>of</strong> crossroads…is a s<strong>in</strong>gle aspect <strong>of</strong> the broader role that she played from early times—<br />

that <strong>of</strong> guid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals through lim<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>and</strong> dur<strong>in</strong>g transitions <strong>of</strong> many<br />

types.” 321 Although <strong>in</strong>structive, this evidence does not elim<strong>in</strong>ate the fact that there is<br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g explicit <strong>in</strong> the fragment that attests to dog flesh as be<strong>in</strong>g eaten by human be<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

or <strong>in</strong> connection with honor<strong>in</strong>g Hekate.<br />

Evidence that supports these po<strong>in</strong>ts can be found <strong>in</strong> a passage from Aristophanes’<br />

Plutus <strong>in</strong> which the personified character <strong>of</strong> Poverty argues that all good th<strong>in</strong>gs come to<br />

people thanks to poverty <strong>and</strong> not wealth. Chremylus’s reply is this:<br />

CHREMYLUS<br />

You can get the answer from Hekate<br />

as to whether it is better to be rich or to be hungry.<br />

She says that the “haves,” the rich, <strong>of</strong>fer her a d<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

every month, but the poor people snatch it away before<br />

it’s even set down! (Plut. 594-597) [43]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage does not specify what type <strong>of</strong> food was presented to Hekate, but the earlier<br />

reference <strong>of</strong> the Banqueters to a white puppy as food <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g to the goddess at the<br />

crossroad, has been used by Sommerste<strong>in</strong> as auxiliary evidence <strong>in</strong> identify<strong>in</strong>g this food<br />

Goddess (Enodio). Both the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> the Colophonians <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the youths at Sparta are appo<strong>in</strong>ted to<br />

take place at night” (3.14.9) [136].<br />

320 I. R. Von Rudl<strong>of</strong>f, “Hekate <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Religion” (diss. University <strong>of</strong> Victoria, 1992) 119.<br />

321 S. I. Johnston, “Crossroads,” ZPE 88 (1991) 218; she also discusses literary evidence for hekataia, that<br />

is, shr<strong>in</strong>es or statues <strong>of</strong> Hekate at crossroads (219, n.10). For the role <strong>of</strong> Hekate as a guide to the transition<br />

to the underworld, her association with lim<strong>in</strong>al spaces, <strong>and</strong> also her connection with dogs, which <strong>in</strong> later<br />

sources, such as the Chaldean Oracles (A.D. II) are represented as ghostly apparitions, see Johnston,<br />

Restless Dead 203-211, <strong>and</strong> Hekate Soteira. A Study <strong>of</strong> Hekate’s Roles <strong>in</strong> the Chaldean Oracles <strong>and</strong><br />

Related Literature (Atlanta, 1990). For a depiction <strong>of</strong> the dogs <strong>of</strong> Hekate devour<strong>in</strong>g the dead on a blackfigured<br />

lekythos (c. 460-450 B.C.) <strong>of</strong> unknown provenance, but most likely, from a tomb <strong>in</strong> Athens, see S.<br />

Karouzou, “An Underworld Scene on a Black-Figured Lekythos,” JHS 92 (1972) 64-73.<br />

204


with dog flesh. 322 Further, on the basis <strong>of</strong> Chremylus’s explanation that poor people stole<br />

this food, Sommerste<strong>in</strong> suggests that poor Athenians were reduced to eat<strong>in</strong>g dog flesh,<br />

which has, <strong>in</strong> turn, prompted his suggestion that this was food <strong>of</strong> the lowest k<strong>in</strong>d. 323 As<br />

can be seen, this evidence accords well with Arnott’s suggestion that dog meat was eaten<br />

by the poor.<br />

Taken together, the accounts <strong>of</strong> the Banqueters <strong>and</strong> Plutus suggest that dog flesh<br />

was presented as a food <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g to Hekate, <strong>and</strong> served also as the food <strong>of</strong> the poor.<br />

Hippocratic Treatises<br />

Further evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g dogs as food <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> comes from the<br />

Hippocratic treatises <strong>in</strong> which dog flesh is presented as therapeutic food for various<br />

diseases. Underly<strong>in</strong>g these prescriptions is the belief that dog flesh held specific dietetic<br />

properties. <strong>The</strong>se properties are exemplified by the division <strong>of</strong> dog flesh <strong>in</strong>to two k<strong>in</strong>ds:<br />

1) that <strong>of</strong> an adult dog, denoted by the terms ku&wn or ku&neia <strong>and</strong> considered <strong>of</strong> curative<br />

value, but hard to digest, therefore thought <strong>of</strong> as caus<strong>in</strong>g constipation; 2) that <strong>of</strong> a puppy,<br />

designated by the terms sku&lac, skula&kion, or skula&keia, also considered curative<br />

food, but easy to digest, <strong>and</strong> therefore, recommended as a laxative.<br />

322 Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, Wealth 178.<br />

323 For the suggestion that the food referred to <strong>in</strong> the Plutus should be identified with dog flesh, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

subsequent designation <strong>of</strong> this food as <strong>of</strong> a low type, see Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, Wealth 178, l<strong>in</strong>es 594 <strong>and</strong> 597<br />

respectively.<br />

205


<strong>The</strong> Properties <strong>of</strong> Dog Flesh<br />

Evidence that dog flesh was considered medic<strong>in</strong>al food appears <strong>in</strong> the treatise<br />

entitled <strong>The</strong> Sacred Disease (c. 450-400 B.C.), which refers to epilepsy. 324 <strong>The</strong> author,<br />

most likely a physician, is a vehement opponent <strong>of</strong> the popular belief that the disease is<br />

the outcome <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>tervention. He considers responsible for such misconceptions<br />

those magicians <strong>and</strong> charlatans who resorted to treat the disease with the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

procedures:<br />

<strong>The</strong>y [magicians <strong>and</strong> charlatans] used purifications <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cantations; they forbade<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> baths, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> many foods that are unsuitable for sick folk—<strong>of</strong> sea<br />

fishes: red mullet, black-tail, hammer <strong>and</strong> the eel (these are the most harmful<br />

sorts); the flesh <strong>of</strong> (krew~n) goats, deer, pigs, <strong>and</strong> dogs (kuno&j) (meats that disturb<br />

most the digestive organs). (Morb. sacr. 1.28-1.35) [118]<br />

In this passage, the speaker clearly states his negative op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> magicians <strong>and</strong><br />

charlatans. He rejects their view <strong>of</strong> dog meat as an appropriate food for patients, <strong>in</strong><br />

general, <strong>and</strong> epileptics, <strong>in</strong> particular. 325 To the contrary, he associates the consumption <strong>of</strong><br />

dog meat (kuno&j) with caus<strong>in</strong>g problems <strong>in</strong> the digestive system. His rejection <strong>of</strong> dog<br />

324 J. Jouanna, tr. M. B. DeBovoise, Hippocrates (Baltimore <strong>and</strong> London, 1999) 411.<br />

325 <strong>The</strong> belief <strong>in</strong> dog flesh as appropriate food for epilepsy is also attested <strong>in</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y (HN 30.27), who<br />

<strong>in</strong>cludes “a suck<strong>in</strong>g puppy taken <strong>in</strong> w<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> myrrh after the head <strong>and</strong> the feet have been cut <strong>of</strong>f” among<br />

the most suitable diets for the treatment <strong>of</strong> the disease. Pl<strong>in</strong>y’s suggestion regard<strong>in</strong>g the preparation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

carcass br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d the archaeological evidence from the site <strong>of</strong> Kastro <strong>in</strong> Crete, where the can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

skeletons discovered <strong>in</strong>dicated removal <strong>of</strong> the head from the body along with that <strong>of</strong> the front <strong>and</strong> h<strong>in</strong>d<br />

limbs: Snyder <strong>and</strong> Klippel, “From Lerna to Kastro,” <strong>in</strong> Kotjabopoulou et al., eds., Zooarchaeology <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong> 225. For the suggestion that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Athens, “the consumption <strong>of</strong> the head meat <strong>of</strong> a fish or an<br />

animal was sought after for flavor <strong>and</strong> texture by those who had the power to choose,” see Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, “Comic<br />

Cuis<strong>in</strong>e,” <strong>in</strong> Dobrov, ed., <strong>The</strong> City as Comedy 256, n. 11.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek belief <strong>in</strong> the ability <strong>of</strong> the dog to provide a cure for various medical conditions is also<br />

attested <strong>in</strong> two <strong>in</strong>scriptions found at the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Asclepios at Epidaurus <strong>and</strong> dat<strong>in</strong>g to the fourth<br />

century B.C. <strong>The</strong>y recount <strong>in</strong>cidents <strong>of</strong> dogs heal<strong>in</strong>g persons suffer<strong>in</strong>g from bl<strong>in</strong>dness <strong>and</strong> a tumor<br />

respectively: [A 20]: “Lyson <strong>of</strong> Hermione, a bl<strong>in</strong>d boy. <strong>The</strong> boy, while awake, had his eyes treated by one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dogs about the sanctuary, <strong>and</strong> went away well.” Also B 6 (26): A dog cured a boy from Aig<strong>in</strong>a. He<br />

had a growth on his neck. When he had come to the god, a dog from the sanctuary took care <strong>of</strong> him, with<br />

its tongue while he was awake, <strong>and</strong> made him well.” L. R. LiDonnici, <strong>The</strong> Epidaurian Miracle<br />

Inscriptions: Text, Translation <strong>and</strong> Commentary (Text <strong>and</strong> Translations 36, Graeco-Roman Religion Series<br />

11; Atlanta, 1995) 99, 105.<br />

206


flesh as medic<strong>in</strong>al food notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, his statement suggests that, <strong>in</strong> the fifth century,<br />

dog flesh was both eaten <strong>and</strong> observed for its effect on the human body.<br />

<strong>The</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> dog flesh <strong>and</strong> its effect on the human body is seen elsewhere is<br />

the Hippocratic treatises. In the Regimen, (late fifth/early fourth century B.C.), 326 a clear<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction is made between the effects <strong>of</strong> the meat <strong>of</strong> an adult dog <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> a puppy,<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> on the digestive system:<br />

Dogs’ flesh (ku&neia) dries, heats, <strong>and</strong> affords strength, but does not pass by stool.<br />

<strong>The</strong> flesh <strong>of</strong> puppies (skula&keia) moistens <strong>and</strong> passes by stool, still more by<br />

ur<strong>in</strong>e. (Vict. 2.46) [122]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage clearly states that the flesh <strong>of</strong> adult dogs (ku&neia) causes constipation,<br />

whereas that <strong>of</strong> puppies (skula&keia) is a laxative. <strong>The</strong> passage <strong>in</strong>dicates that that the age<br />

<strong>of</strong> the animal had a direct effect on its assessment as medic<strong>in</strong>al food. Also, by not<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

“dogs’ flesh dries” the passage presents itself as a possible source <strong>of</strong> Galen’s previously<br />

seen remark on the dryness <strong>of</strong> dog flesh.<br />

<strong>The</strong> flesh <strong>of</strong> an adult dog was not only thought <strong>of</strong> as caus<strong>in</strong>g constipation; its<br />

curative effect on the human body was also known. In the Internal Affections, (400-390<br />

B.C.), 327 for example, it features as a suitable food for dropsy. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>structions provided<br />

to the physician run as follows:<br />

It benefits the patient if you dry out his cavity (belly) by giv<strong>in</strong>g him fresh warm<br />

dark whole-wheat bread, <strong>and</strong> as ma<strong>in</strong> dish the meat <strong>of</strong> ass, mature dog (kuno_j<br />

telei/ou), sw<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> sheep, these very fat <strong>and</strong> boiled, or meat <strong>of</strong> fowl, roasted<br />

<strong>and</strong> warm.” (Int. 22.10-22.13) [112]<br />

326 Jouanna, Hippocrates 409.<br />

327 Jouanna, Hippocrates 395.<br />

207


<strong>The</strong> passage identifies the meat <strong>of</strong> an adult dog (kuno_j telei/ou) as curative food for<br />

dropsy. <strong>The</strong> age <strong>of</strong> the animal is aga<strong>in</strong> specified, but two additional conditions are now<br />

noted: the meat has to be very fat <strong>and</strong> boiled. 328 <strong>The</strong> passage does not expla<strong>in</strong> the reasons<br />

for these conditions, but a statement <strong>in</strong> the Affections (c. 380 B.C.), 329 sheds light on the<br />

preference for boiled dog flesh, when it clarifies that: “the lightest meats for the body are<br />

well-boiled dog (ku&neia), fowl, <strong>and</strong> hare; heavy are beef <strong>and</strong> pork” (6.17-6.19) [107].<br />

<strong>The</strong> Affections provides further evidence for boil<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g the preferred method <strong>of</strong><br />

prepar<strong>in</strong>g the meat not only <strong>of</strong> an adult dog, but also <strong>of</strong> a puppy. <strong>The</strong> advice probably <strong>of</strong><br />

a physician to another on a general diet for patients states:<br />

When you wish to moisten a patient’s cavity by means <strong>of</strong> foods, give barley-cake<br />

<strong>and</strong>, as ma<strong>in</strong>-dishes slices <strong>of</strong> seafoods <strong>in</strong> a mixed dish, meat <strong>of</strong> a very young<br />

lamb, kid, puppy (sku&lakoj) or fowl, these boiled, <strong>and</strong> beets, blites, docks or<br />

gourd if they are <strong>in</strong> season. (Aff. 43.1-43.4) [109]<br />

As <strong>in</strong> the Regimen, the focus here is on puppy meat as a laxative food. <strong>The</strong> passage<br />

highlights this quality <strong>of</strong> dog meat by <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> a diet that consists <strong>of</strong> items <strong>of</strong><br />

328 <strong>The</strong> emphasis on boil<strong>in</strong>g may be <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> a wider belief regard<strong>in</strong>g the effect that this method <strong>of</strong><br />

cook<strong>in</strong>g had on the human body <strong>and</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. Such belief seems plausible <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes’ Knights<br />

1321<strong>and</strong> 1336, where Demos, the senile <strong>and</strong> decrepit old man who st<strong>and</strong>s for the Athenian public, is<br />

restored to his full powers by boil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the cauldron <strong>of</strong> the sausage seller. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this <strong>and</strong><br />

additional examples from mythology that associate boil<strong>in</strong>g with rejuvenation, see A. M. Bowie,<br />

Aristophanes. Myth, Ritual <strong>and</strong> Comedy (Cambridge, 1993; repr. 1996) 76, n. 136; also <strong>in</strong> reference to the<br />

affect that boiled food was thought to have on the body, Galen <strong>in</strong> his treatise On the Properties <strong>of</strong><br />

Foodstuffs (156) expresses the belief that everyth<strong>in</strong>g pre-boiled <strong>in</strong> water provides a moister food.<br />

<strong>The</strong> advice that dog meat should be very fat <strong>and</strong> boiled when eaten accords well with the results <strong>of</strong><br />

archaeozoological research at the site <strong>of</strong> Kastro <strong>in</strong> Crete. As Snyder <strong>and</strong> Klippel, “From Kastro to Lerna,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> Kotjabopoulou et al., eds., Zooarchaeology <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> 225, observe, the can<strong>in</strong>e bones discovered at the<br />

site show a preference for reduc<strong>in</strong>g the carcass to smaller segments, as <strong>in</strong>dicated by the deliberate breakage<br />

<strong>of</strong> long bone diaphyses. This evidence, along with the absence <strong>of</strong> burn<strong>in</strong>g, suggests that these smaller<br />

segments were then boiled or perhaps placed on a brazier rather than be<strong>in</strong>g roasted on fire. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

the authors, this process <strong>of</strong> cook<strong>in</strong>g maximized retention <strong>of</strong> fats <strong>in</strong> muscle tissue <strong>and</strong> bone marrow cavities.<br />

329 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the suggested date <strong>of</strong> this treatise, see Jouanna, Hippocrates 374. Scholarly op<strong>in</strong>ion is split<br />

on whether it was <strong>in</strong>tended for a lay or specialized audience. Jouanna, Hippocrates 373, for example, states<br />

that the treatise “was <strong>in</strong>tended for lay readers rather than specialists. In contrast, P. Potter, ed., tr.,<br />

Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988) 4-5, n. 2, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “first, <strong>in</strong> every s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance <strong>in</strong> which the reader is addressed <strong>in</strong> the second person, the context dictates that it must be the<br />

physician, <strong>and</strong> not the layman, that is meant. Second, the general level <strong>of</strong> technical sophistication evident<br />

<strong>in</strong> Affections is no different from that <strong>of</strong> other Hippocratic works universally held to be addressed to<br />

physicians.”<br />

208


ord<strong>in</strong>ary food, but is not connected to a specific disease. <strong>The</strong> passage suggests that<br />

puppy meat was an accepted item <strong>of</strong> food <strong>in</strong> the dietary treatment <strong>of</strong> patients <strong>in</strong> general.<br />

Both puppy meat <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> an adult dog are also prescribed as curative food for<br />

diseases that are explicitly identified <strong>in</strong> the Hippocratic treatises. All these prescriptions<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude other accepted items <strong>of</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary food, such as fruits, vegetables, fish, meat, <strong>and</strong><br />

w<strong>in</strong>e. <strong>The</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ance, however, <strong>of</strong> puppy meat over that <strong>of</strong> an adult dog is strik<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Flesh <strong>of</strong> Adult Dogs as Dietary Treatment for Certa<strong>in</strong> Diseases<br />

1. Erysipelas <strong>of</strong> the Lungs<br />

In Internal Affections (c. 400-390 B.C.) the discussion <strong>of</strong> the disease identified as<br />

erysipelas (<strong>in</strong>flammation) <strong>of</strong> the lungs beg<strong>in</strong>s with the description <strong>of</strong> the accompany<strong>in</strong>g<br />

symptoms—expectoration <strong>of</strong> sputum, chills, fever, <strong>and</strong> vomit<strong>in</strong>g. As treatment, the<br />

patient is advised to follow a diet <strong>of</strong> silphium juice, dry w<strong>in</strong>e, garlic, <strong>and</strong> radishes. When<br />

the chills <strong>and</strong> fever subside, the food to be eaten should be switched to cereals <strong>and</strong> the<br />

meats <strong>of</strong> boiled ass or dog (kunei/oisi) (6.26-6.32) [110]. <strong>The</strong> boiled flesh <strong>of</strong> an adult dog<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> features as curative food. Of <strong>in</strong>terest here is the specified time at which the patient<br />

could eat this food: after the chills <strong>and</strong> fever subside. Such evidence seems to be related<br />

to the idea seen previously <strong>in</strong> the Regimen that dogs’ flesh dries [<strong>and</strong>] heats,” an idea,<br />

which automatically makes it an unsuitable food for patients with fever, <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

above recommendation. From this evidence, it seems reasonable to conclude that the<br />

medic<strong>in</strong>al properties <strong>of</strong> dog flesh were so carefully observed that they even determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

the time when dog flesh was adm<strong>in</strong>istered as treatment with<strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> a disease.<br />

209


2. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Spleen<br />

<strong>The</strong> part <strong>of</strong> Internal Affections that discusses a disease <strong>of</strong> the spleen ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that, as the illness progresses, the patient becomes pale yellow, experiences severe pa<strong>in</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> does not accept food. When this po<strong>in</strong>t has been reached, the physician is advised to<br />

prescribe a diet <strong>of</strong> Cnidian berries, lentil-soup, boiled beets, <strong>and</strong> dark dry w<strong>in</strong>e; he should<br />

also have the patient rest, <strong>and</strong> allow only shorts walks <strong>in</strong> the shade. From then on, the<br />

patient’s diet should <strong>in</strong>clude whole-wheat bread, the ground meat <strong>of</strong> an adult dog (kuno_j<br />

me/zonoj), sheep or goat, <strong>and</strong> Cadiz salt-fish or saperdes (30.18-30.22) [114]. Even<br />

though it does not provide any evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the boil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> dog flesh, the passage is<br />

<strong>in</strong>formative <strong>in</strong> show<strong>in</strong>g that gr<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g furnished an additional way <strong>in</strong> which this flesh was<br />

adm<strong>in</strong>istered as curative food.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Flesh <strong>of</strong> Puppies as Dietary Treatment for Certa<strong>in</strong> Diseases<br />

1. Pleurisy<br />

A considerable section (chapters 44-62) <strong>of</strong> the treatise Diseases II, which dates to<br />

the middle <strong>of</strong> the fifth century B.C., 330 focuses on diseases <strong>of</strong> the chest <strong>and</strong> back.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the pa<strong>in</strong> occurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the chest <strong>and</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>e due to pleurisy, advice is provided<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g the diet that could alleviate this pa<strong>in</strong>. Apart from dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g millet-juice mixed<br />

with honey, diluted white w<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g beets, the patient should also eat a little <strong>of</strong> the<br />

meat <strong>of</strong> boiled puppy (sku&laka) or fowl, <strong>and</strong> dr<strong>in</strong>k the sauce <strong>in</strong> which it is cooked<br />

(Diseases II, 44.16-44.19) [115]. As can be seen, the boiled meat <strong>of</strong> a puppy features<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> as medic<strong>in</strong>al, <strong>in</strong> this case, analgesic food.<br />

330 Jouanna, Hippocrates 383, states that this should be a possible date for the treatise, but clarifies that<br />

<strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> rewrit<strong>in</strong>gs detected <strong>in</strong> some cases po<strong>in</strong>t to the fact that not all its sections are contemporaneous.<br />

210


2. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Back<br />

Similar to this diet is also the one recommended for a disease <strong>of</strong> the back.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the <strong>in</strong>structions for treatment, fourteen days after the appearance <strong>of</strong><br />

symptoms, the patient should be allowed to have millet, <strong>and</strong> towards the even<strong>in</strong>g, s/he<br />

should eat the boiled meat <strong>of</strong> a puppy (skulaki/ou) or a fowl, <strong>and</strong> also dr<strong>in</strong>k the sauce <strong>in</strong><br />

which this meat is cooked (Diseases II, 56.11-56.12) [116]. This prescription aga<strong>in</strong><br />

shows that the boiled meat <strong>of</strong> a puppy was considered medic<strong>in</strong>al food. Although left<br />

unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest here is the fact that dog flesh features aga<strong>in</strong> as treatment to be<br />

adm<strong>in</strong>istered at a specific time (fourteen days) with<strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> the disease. In this<br />

respect, the prescription parallels that for erysipelas <strong>of</strong> the lungs.<br />

3. Tubercles<br />

Similar <strong>in</strong> content is also the diet recommended for patients suffer<strong>in</strong>g from<br />

tubercles on their sides, <strong>and</strong> recorded <strong>in</strong> the Internal Affections: While boiled barley-<br />

water with honey, <strong>and</strong> white w<strong>in</strong>e diluted with water should be consumed the first eleven<br />

days <strong>of</strong> the disease, after that, the patient’s diet should be switched to small amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

cereals, <strong>and</strong> the warmed meats <strong>of</strong> a puppy (skulakei/ois<strong>in</strong> qermoi=si) or a fowl boiled<br />

well <strong>in</strong>to a soup (9.4-9.11) [111]. Aga<strong>in</strong> the adm<strong>in</strong>istration <strong>of</strong> the meat <strong>of</strong> a puppy<br />

features here as dietary prescription to be followed only at a certa<strong>in</strong> stage with<strong>in</strong> the<br />

course <strong>of</strong> a disease, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with cereals.<br />

211


4. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Liver<br />

Adher<strong>in</strong>g to the same rules is also the diet recommended for a disease <strong>of</strong> the liver.<br />

As the author <strong>of</strong> Internal Affections states:<br />

After the disease’s crisis, treat by giv<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>e cereals <strong>in</strong> small amounts; if the<br />

patient eats bread, let him take it very hot, if barley-cake, let it be unpounded but<br />

mixed a while before it is baked. As ma<strong>in</strong> dish, let him have boiled puppy<br />

(skulaki/ou), pigeon or chicken, tak<strong>in</strong>g all these boiled, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> fish dogfish,<br />

torpedo, st<strong>in</strong>g-ray <strong>and</strong> small skates, also all boiled. (Int. 27.39-27.43) [113]<br />

As was the case above, the boiled meat <strong>of</strong> a puppy (skulaki/ou) <strong>and</strong> cereals are aga<strong>in</strong><br />

prescribed as dietary treatment for a disease.<br />

5. Gynecological Diseases<br />

<strong>The</strong> consumption <strong>of</strong> boiled puppy flesh features also <strong>in</strong> the discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

gynecological diseases. In the treatise Sterile Women (end <strong>of</strong> fifth/ beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fourth century B.C.), 331 the author proposes as treatment for female sterility the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> fat <strong>and</strong> well-boiled puppies (skula&kia) (217) [119]. <strong>The</strong> prescription is<br />

identical to that for dropsy <strong>in</strong> the Internal Affections, with the exception <strong>of</strong> the flesh <strong>of</strong> an<br />

adult dog be<strong>in</strong>g essential there. Further, another <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the author’s discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

female sterility suggests that apart from puppy meat, equally helpful <strong>in</strong> fight<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

condition were considered its entrails (skula&kion e0ntosqi/dia) <strong>in</strong> fumigations (230)<br />

[120].<br />

Although not directly referr<strong>in</strong>g to can<strong>in</strong>e flesh as curative food, an excerpt from<br />

the treatise Nature <strong>of</strong> Women, which is <strong>of</strong> the same date as Sterile Women, 332 provides<br />

additional evidence for the use <strong>of</strong> the dog as medic<strong>in</strong>al food. <strong>The</strong> author <strong>of</strong> the treatise,<br />

which is a discussion regard<strong>in</strong>g birth, advises that successful delivery <strong>of</strong> the fetus can be<br />

331 Jouanna, Hippocrates 384, 386.<br />

332 Jouanna, Hippocrates 385-386.<br />

212


ensured only if one is will<strong>in</strong>g to “rub well silphium equal to one gra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> vetch, together<br />

with cardamom <strong>and</strong> mix it with w<strong>in</strong>e or the milk <strong>of</strong> dog (kuno_j ga&lakti), <strong>and</strong> give it to<br />

dr<strong>in</strong>k. This should deliver the fetus” (32.48-32.49) [121]. This short passage suggests<br />

that that not only the fleshy part <strong>of</strong> a dog’s body was seen as hold<strong>in</strong>g curative powers, but<br />

also its milk as well.<br />

6. Non-Hyperthermic Patients<br />

Affections, a treatise slightly later (c. 380 B.C.) than the Nature <strong>of</strong> Women, proves<br />

traditional <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the type <strong>of</strong> dog meat it recommends as medic<strong>in</strong>al food. In a<br />

passage which refers to patients, who have skipped or already gone through the stage <strong>of</strong><br />

high body temperature, boiled puppy meat is recommended as the suitable food:<br />

If the patients do not have fever give the <strong>in</strong>ner part <strong>of</strong> a loaf <strong>of</strong> white bread<br />

crumbled <strong>in</strong>to soup, or barley-cake <strong>and</strong> a slice <strong>of</strong> boiled fish, or meat <strong>of</strong> very<br />

young lamb, fowl, or puppy, these boiled or beets or gourd or blites; after the<br />

meal let them dr<strong>in</strong>k dilute fragrant old white w<strong>in</strong>e. (Aff. 41.7-41.11) [108]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage aga<strong>in</strong> presents boiled puppy meat as curative food. Consider<strong>in</strong>g the above<br />

discussion on the dry<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> warm<strong>in</strong>g effects <strong>of</strong> this food on the body, its prescription<br />

here to non-hyperthermic patients makes perfect sense. In this way, the parallel with the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> the erysipelas <strong>of</strong> the lungs, where the flesh <strong>of</strong> an adult dog was to be adm<strong>in</strong>istered<br />

only after the patients’ fever subsided, is clear.<br />

213


7. Disease <strong>of</strong> the Kidneys<br />

Explicit reference to the boiled flesh <strong>of</strong> a puppy as a curative is made <strong>in</strong> a part <strong>of</strong><br />

Epidemics VII (c. 350 B.C.), 333 which discusses the case <strong>of</strong> a person who suffered from<br />

nephritic affections. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the text, the patient absta<strong>in</strong>ed from food for seven<br />

days, <strong>and</strong> drank melicrat <strong>in</strong> a strong mixture. Afterwards, he ate bean broth <strong>and</strong><br />

sometimes pea soup, <strong>and</strong> drank water; later, he ate some boiled young dog (skulaki/ou),<br />

<strong>and</strong> a little barley cake (7.62) [117]. <strong>The</strong> passage aga<strong>in</strong> shows that dog flesh was given to<br />

the patient at a specific, that is, later stage <strong>of</strong> his condition.<br />

Dog Flesh as Non-Indicated Dietary Treatment<br />

Apart from accept<strong>in</strong>g the flesh <strong>of</strong> a puppy as curative food, the Hippocratic<br />

treatises also preserve an <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> a prescription <strong>in</strong> which this food is to be avoided: <strong>in</strong><br />

the treatment <strong>of</strong> surfeit. As the author <strong>of</strong> Regimen III, (end <strong>of</strong> fifth/beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> fourth<br />

century B.C.), 334 suggests, the physician should “use warm, fermented bread, crumbl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

it <strong>in</strong>to dark w<strong>in</strong>e or <strong>in</strong>to pork broth. Also fish boiled <strong>in</strong> acrid br<strong>in</strong>e. Use also fleshy<br />

meats, such as pig’s feet well boiled <strong>and</strong> fat roast pork, but be spar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> suck<strong>in</strong>g-pig, <strong>and</strong><br />

the flesh <strong>of</strong> puppies (skula&kwn) <strong>and</strong> kids” (3.75) [123]. <strong>The</strong> passage clearly states that<br />

the flesh <strong>of</strong> puppies was not considered food that could help elim<strong>in</strong>ate the feel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

excessive fullness. Such advice implies that this food was probably conceived <strong>of</strong> as<br />

hav<strong>in</strong>g the opposite effect, that is, <strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g appetite. This view <strong>of</strong> dog flesh may not be<br />

divorced from the already seen propensity <strong>of</strong> the animal to steal food <strong>and</strong> eat it all up.<br />

333 Jouanna, Hippocrates 390, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that some <strong>of</strong> the passages are later than 358-357 B.C.—the date <strong>of</strong><br />

the siege <strong>of</strong> Datum by Philip II mentioned <strong>in</strong> Epidemics VII, 121—whereas others are prior to 348 B.C.—<br />

the date <strong>of</strong> the destruction <strong>of</strong> Olynthus by Philip II mentioned <strong>in</strong> Epidemics VII.<br />

334 Jouanna, Hippocrates 409.<br />

214


<strong>The</strong> literary evidence conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the Hippocratic treatises reveals that dog flesh<br />

was part <strong>of</strong> the human diet <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> valued for its curative effect on the<br />

human body. <strong>The</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction drawn between the two k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> adult <strong>and</strong> puppy flesh <strong>and</strong><br />

the specific qualities attached to them <strong>in</strong>dicates that age was a determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g factor <strong>in</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the dog as medic<strong>in</strong>al food. <strong>The</strong> prevalence <strong>of</strong> puppy meat as a curative for a<br />

wide variety <strong>of</strong> medical conditions suggests its elevated status when compared to that <strong>of</strong><br />

the flesh <strong>of</strong> an adult dog. Also the use <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e milk <strong>and</strong> entrails <strong>in</strong> prescriptions further<br />

suggests that not only the flesh, but also other bodily parts <strong>and</strong> substances <strong>of</strong> the animal<br />

were thought to hold curative powers. <strong>The</strong> evidence, however, <strong>of</strong> the overall high<br />

curative value <strong>of</strong> dog flesh contrasts with the evidence from comedy that dog flesh was<br />

considered food <strong>of</strong> the lowest k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>and</strong> therefore, eaten only by the poor. In light <strong>of</strong> this<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction, it seems reasonable to conclude that two different contexts existed—one<br />

medical, the other social—which susta<strong>in</strong>ed two completely different views <strong>of</strong> the practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dogs with<strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Taken together, the references <strong>of</strong> tragic, comic, <strong>and</strong> prose writers show that<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed an ambivalent attitude towards the dog. <strong>The</strong> animal<br />

was an <strong>in</strong>tegral part <strong>of</strong> daily life, language, <strong>and</strong> thought, but did not escape unsympathetic<br />

views <strong>and</strong> treatment. Its primary role <strong>in</strong> daily domestic life was that <strong>of</strong> the guardian <strong>of</strong><br />

the house, the family, <strong>and</strong> its possessions. It shared the same space with the human<br />

occupants <strong>of</strong> the house, <strong>and</strong> was provided with food, but it was not considered a member<br />

<strong>of</strong> the family. Molossian dogs were a famous breed <strong>of</strong> guard, hunt<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> shepherd<strong>in</strong>g<br />

215


dogs, highly esteemed for their exceptional ferocity, size, f<strong>in</strong>e appearance, <strong>and</strong> also love<br />

<strong>and</strong> devotion to their owners.<br />

Daily proximity to the dog allowed for its behavior to be closely observed <strong>and</strong> its<br />

loyalty to be seen as its trademark quality. In addition, other characteristics <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e<br />

behavior, such vigilance, agility, <strong>and</strong> swiftness, were <strong>in</strong>terpreted as signs <strong>of</strong> cunn<strong>in</strong>g, thus<br />

recogniz<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong> type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence <strong>in</strong> the animal. It was, however, the ability to<br />

display gentle <strong>and</strong> aggressive behavior at once (fawn<strong>in</strong>g, bit<strong>in</strong>g) that shaped the view <strong>of</strong><br />

the dog as a deceptive <strong>and</strong> untrustworthy animal. This view was further susta<strong>in</strong>ed by the<br />

feed<strong>in</strong>g behavior <strong>of</strong> the animal, identified <strong>in</strong> the sources as steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> gobbl<strong>in</strong>g food.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se two acts constituted mental benchmarks <strong>in</strong> the collective conception <strong>of</strong> the dog that<br />

contrasted sharply with its view as a loyal creature. In fact, so pervasive was this<br />

contradiction <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek thought that it was frequently employed as a metaphor<br />

for describ<strong>in</strong>g human behavior. Further, the dog was punished with beat<strong>in</strong>g for its<br />

steal<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> food. This act <strong>of</strong> physical aggression aga<strong>in</strong>st it was perceived as behavior that<br />

set Greek culture apart from others. <strong>The</strong> dog was also known for its scaveng<strong>in</strong>g<br />

behavior, its ability to exercise forethought, <strong>and</strong> also its acute sense <strong>of</strong> smell. Its<br />

scaveng<strong>in</strong>g behavior was a well-established idea <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek thought. It promoted<br />

the fear <strong>of</strong> human flesh becom<strong>in</strong>g part <strong>of</strong> can<strong>in</strong>e diet, <strong>and</strong> caused the dog to be thought <strong>of</strong><br />

as a dangerous animal. Such views <strong>of</strong> the animal did not, however, deter <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

society from <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g can<strong>in</strong>e flesh <strong>in</strong> its diet. Dog flesh was believed to have a curative<br />

effect on the human body, <strong>and</strong> as such, featured prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> the dietary treatment <strong>of</strong><br />

many diseases. Outside this medical context, dog flesh appears to have served only as<br />

the food <strong>of</strong> the lowest strata <strong>of</strong> society. <strong>The</strong>se circumstances notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, the<br />

216


practice <strong>of</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g dog meat <strong>in</strong>dicates a specific view <strong>and</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> the animal: <strong>in</strong> a<br />

purely anthropocentric sense, <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture placed the dog <strong>in</strong> the same category<br />

with any other k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> animal that could be easily converted to food. It this way, the dog<br />

appears to have been seen as a useful creature <strong>in</strong> service <strong>of</strong> human needs.<br />

217


Chapter 4: <strong>The</strong> Word Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Context <strong>of</strong> the Visual Arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong><br />

Introduction<br />

This chapter is concerned with the duality <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term zw|~on.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Greek-English Lexicon <strong>of</strong> Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott def<strong>in</strong>es zw|~on as a fifth-century term,<br />

whose mean<strong>in</strong>g oscillates between two broad categories: a) “animal,” which is the usual<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g assigned to the word, “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “plant,” <strong>and</strong> 2) “image” <strong>and</strong> “figure.”<br />

335 <strong>The</strong>se categories <strong>in</strong>dicate a semantic split that is directly dependent upon the context<br />

<strong>in</strong> which the term occurs. <strong>The</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> “image,” <strong>and</strong> “figure,” <strong>in</strong> particular, imply a<br />

context directly associated with the visual arts. Although this semantic split has not<br />

passed undetected <strong>in</strong> modern scholarship, no study exists that treats thoroughly the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on when applied to the visual arts. 336 This chapter discusses <strong>in</strong> detail the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> direct association with the visual arts <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries<br />

B.C., that is, the period <strong>in</strong> which the word first appears <strong>in</strong> the extant record. <strong>The</strong><br />

discussion starts with an analysis <strong>of</strong> the etymology <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>and</strong> proceeds to exam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong><br />

chronological order the appearances <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong> both literary texts <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions<br />

directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the visual arts. <strong>The</strong> discussion demonstrates the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

different mean<strong>in</strong>gs for the word zw|~on when used <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, sculpture,<br />

bronze-work, <strong>and</strong> textiles: “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” “representation <strong>of</strong> both<br />

animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from real life, “decorative element,” “f<strong>in</strong>ished<br />

335 LSJ 9 , 143, s.v. zw|~on.<br />

336 For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as “image,” for example, see Gordon, “<strong>The</strong> Real <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Imag<strong>in</strong>ary” 9; also H. P. Cooke, ed., tr., Aristotle I. <strong>The</strong> Categories. On Interpretation (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1938; repr. 1996) 12, n. b, who is more explicit when he states that: “zw|~on <strong>in</strong> Greek had two<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs, that is to say, liv<strong>in</strong>g creature, <strong>and</strong> secondly, a figure or image <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, embroidery,<br />

sculpture.”<br />

218


product <strong>of</strong> an artistic process,” “figural image,” <strong>and</strong> “image held by memory.” <strong>The</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> these mean<strong>in</strong>gs with<strong>in</strong> such an artistic context suggests that zw|~on can be<br />

seen as part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. In this way, a<br />

word usually taken to mean “animal” appears to sit on one side <strong>of</strong> a l<strong>in</strong>guistic duality,<br />

while, on the other side, its completely different mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> connection with the arts<br />

reveal that animals, once aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>of</strong>fer an <strong>in</strong>valuable <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> representational art.<br />

Although not directly connected to the previous chapters, this chapter ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s a<br />

conceptual tie with them <strong>in</strong> that its focus on the semantic split <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term<br />

zw|~on is not far removed from the split <strong>in</strong>to different types <strong>of</strong> deviations from naturalism<br />

(<strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, contradiction) that, as already noted, frame the style <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture, as well as from the dichotomy that characterizes the<br />

contemporary attitude towards animals.<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> Etymology <strong>of</strong> Zw|~on<br />

In his study <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek etymology, Pierre Chantra<strong>in</strong>e considers the term<br />

zw&ion <strong>and</strong> its contracted form—zw|~on—respective derivatives <strong>of</strong> the verb zw&w <strong>and</strong> its<br />

contracted form zw~. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, this verb, which he translates as “to live,”<br />

applies equally to human be<strong>in</strong>gs, animals <strong>and</strong> plants, <strong>and</strong> is employed also for<br />

representations. He further expla<strong>in</strong>s that the uncontracted form—zw&w—is found <strong>in</strong><br />

Homer, whereas the contracted form—zw~—is characteristic <strong>of</strong> the Attic dialect. 337<br />

Chantra<strong>in</strong>e’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>guistic history <strong>of</strong> the verb is <strong>in</strong> agreement with the earlier<br />

337 P. Chantra<strong>in</strong>e, Dictionnaire étymologique (Paris, 1968) 402, s.v. zw&ion <strong>and</strong> zw|~on, v. zw&w, zw~.<br />

219


study <strong>of</strong> Hjalmar Frisk on the same subject. <strong>The</strong> only new <strong>in</strong>formation that Chantra<strong>in</strong>e<br />

adds is that the uncontracted form—zw&w—is found not only <strong>in</strong> epic, but <strong>in</strong> lyric poetry<br />

as well. 338 Hardy Hansen <strong>and</strong> Gerald Qu<strong>in</strong>n, <strong>in</strong> their book on Attic Greek prose, agree<br />

with the above scholars on the translation <strong>of</strong> zw~ as “to live,” but ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that it drives<br />

from the uncontracted ancestral form, za&w. 339 This <strong>in</strong>formation, when comb<strong>in</strong>ed with<br />

their <strong>in</strong>troductory statement that their study focuses on the “dialect <strong>of</strong> Athens, as it<br />

appears <strong>in</strong> prose authors <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries,” implies that za&w is a<br />

grammatical form used before or <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period. 340 Turn<strong>in</strong>g to Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott,<br />

however, one f<strong>in</strong>ds that the uncontracted form za&w is attested only <strong>in</strong> the language <strong>of</strong> the<br />

grammarians (e.g., Etymologicum Magnum 410.38). 341 More specifically, Émile Boisacq<br />

states that za&w is an <strong>in</strong>vention <strong>of</strong> the grammarians. 342 F<strong>in</strong>ally, Carl Buck specifies that<br />

the Attic verb zw~ is by itself an exceptional type <strong>of</strong> contracted verbs. As such, it does not<br />

fall <strong>in</strong>to any <strong>of</strong> the usual types <strong>of</strong> these verbs, mean<strong>in</strong>g those whose uncontracted forms<br />

end <strong>in</strong> -αω, -εω, -οω, but it comes from the uncontracted form, zh&w. In trac<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

etymology <strong>of</strong> the verb zh&w, Buck <strong>in</strong>dicates that it means “to live,” <strong>and</strong> as it is unattested<br />

<strong>in</strong> the extant sources, it is therefore a reconstructed form. It derives from the equally<br />

unattested, but reconstructed zh&-iw, which Buck considers parallel to Homer’s<br />

zw&w; the latter deriv<strong>in</strong>g from the unattested <strong>and</strong> therefore reconstructed zw&-iw. 343 In<br />

agreement with his deriv<strong>in</strong>g zw~ from zh&w, are also Michael Oikonomou <strong>and</strong> Anastasios<br />

338<br />

H. Frisk, Griechisches etymologisches Wörterbuch (Heidelberg, 1954) 618, s.v. zw&i+on, zw|~on, v. zw&w.<br />

339<br />

Hansen <strong>and</strong> Qu<strong>in</strong>n, Greek 594-595.<br />

340<br />

Hansen <strong>and</strong> Qu<strong>in</strong>n, Greek 1.<br />

341 9<br />

LSJ , 758, s.v. zw~.<br />

342<br />

E. Boisacq, Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque (Heidelberg <strong>and</strong> Paris, 1923) 309.<br />

343<br />

C. D. Buck, Comparative Grammar <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> (Chicago, 1933) 265, n. 3.<br />

220


Georgopapadakos. 344 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this reconstruction, it appears that the phenomena<br />

<strong>of</strong> phonetic development <strong>and</strong> contraction 345 are responsible for the different forms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

verb zw~ mean<strong>in</strong>g primarily “to live.” 346 Add<strong>in</strong>g to this is Georgopapadakos’s<br />

suggestion that the <strong>in</strong>itial type <strong>of</strong> the verb zw~ could have been dia&w (a1w, a1hmi) mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

not only “to live,” but also “to breathe.” 347 This idea accords well with Buck’s statement<br />

that <strong>in</strong> most Indo-European languages, the notions <strong>of</strong> “breath<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g” are central to<br />

the word for “animal.” 348<br />

On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it appears that the primary mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on was<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g alive <strong>and</strong> breath<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, animated, <strong>and</strong> as an extension “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g”<br />

<strong>and</strong> “animal.” <strong>The</strong>se explanations do not shed light onto how the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as<br />

“image” <strong>and</strong> “figure” came to be; nevertheless, they are important, for they provide a<br />

glimpse <strong>in</strong>to the mechanics <strong>of</strong> ancient thought <strong>and</strong> language <strong>in</strong> regards to the rise <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~on <strong>and</strong> the notions it was thought to st<strong>and</strong> for. As was mentioned earlier, the<br />

contracted form zw|~on is not attested <strong>in</strong> pre-<strong>Classical</strong> texts. <strong>The</strong>refore, the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

discussion illustrates the use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical sources <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

date. <strong>The</strong> focus is on contexts that are directly associated with the visual arts.<br />

344 M. C. Oikonomou, Γραµµατική της Αρχαίας Ελληνικής—Ancient Greek Grammar (Athens, 1996)<br />

208, 240, 300; A. Georgopapadakos, Λεξικό Ανωµάλων Ρηµάτων της Αρχαίας Ελληνικής Γλώσσης—<br />

Lexicon <strong>of</strong> Irregular Verbs <strong>of</strong> the Ancient Greek Language (<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1964) 88-89. For additional<br />

evidence on this suggestion, see the discussion by L. R. Palmer, <strong>The</strong> Greek Language (New Jersey, 1980)<br />

210-211, who focuses on examples <strong>of</strong> words where ζ is traceable to a palatalized d or g.<br />

345 For an <strong>in</strong>troduction to the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> contraction <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek, <strong>in</strong> particular, its embrace by the<br />

Attic dialect, see Buck, Comparative Grammar 264-265.<br />

346 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> sound development <strong>of</strong> the stems <strong>of</strong> Greek verbs, see Palmer, <strong>The</strong> Greek Language<br />

264 <strong>and</strong> 225 with specific reference to the alteration: zww/zh-. This may be further l<strong>in</strong>ked to Palmer’s<br />

discussion (215-220) on vowel gradation. He def<strong>in</strong>es the latter as “the alternation <strong>of</strong> vowels observed <strong>in</strong><br />

morphological systems such as noun <strong>and</strong> verb formation, noun declension <strong>and</strong> verbal conjugation” (216).<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> zw- <strong>and</strong> zww- as stems <strong>of</strong> personal names <strong>in</strong> Mycenaean documents, see<br />

Chantra<strong>in</strong>e, Dictionnaire étymologique 403.<br />

347 Georgopapadakos, Lexicon <strong>of</strong> Irregular Verbs 89.<br />

348 C. D. Buck, A Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Selected Synonyms <strong>in</strong> the Pr<strong>in</strong>cipal Indo-European Languages (Chicago,<br />

1949) 137; Also <strong>in</strong> Plato’s Cratylus (427b), Socrates, while discuss<strong>in</strong>g etymology, he connects the letter z<br />

with the notion <strong>of</strong> life by stat<strong>in</strong>g that it is a letter pronounced with an expulsion <strong>of</strong> breath.<br />

221


2. Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century B.C.<br />

A. Literary Texts<br />

Two authors <strong>of</strong> the fifth century B.C. use the term zw|~on <strong>and</strong> its derivative<br />

zw|&dion <strong>in</strong> contexts that are directly associated with the visual arts: Empedocles <strong>and</strong><br />

Herodotus. In the works <strong>of</strong> these authors, the terms zw|~on <strong>and</strong> zw|&dion carry the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” “representations <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from real life,” <strong>and</strong> “decorative element.” <strong>The</strong> terms are used <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with a variety <strong>of</strong> media, namely, pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, sculpture, bronze work, <strong>and</strong><br />

textiles. <strong>The</strong> text <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> particular, carries <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> zw|~on st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g for the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject.<br />

Empedocles<br />

<strong>The</strong> earliest fifth-century text <strong>in</strong> which zw|~on appears is a fragment <strong>of</strong><br />

Empedocles. Preserved <strong>in</strong> an extract from <strong>The</strong>ophrastus’ treatise On Piety (IV-III B.C.)<br />

that itself survives <strong>in</strong> Porphyry’s On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (A.D. III), the<br />

fragment po<strong>in</strong>ts to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as an image <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, most likely, a picture:<br />

<strong>The</strong>ophrastus uses examples from many ancestral customs <strong>of</strong> different<br />

peoples to show that the ancient form <strong>of</strong> sacrifice was <strong>of</strong> crops; he says too that<br />

even earlier grass was collected. He also expla<strong>in</strong>s libations, as follows. For most<br />

people, ancient rites were sober: libations <strong>of</strong> water are sober, <strong>and</strong> so are the<br />

libations <strong>of</strong> honey which came after them (for this was the first liquid crop we had<br />

to h<strong>and</strong>, taken from the bees). <strong>The</strong>n there were libations <strong>of</strong> oil, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally, last <strong>of</strong><br />

all, came libations <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

Evidence for this comes not only from the kubreis, which are really a k<strong>in</strong>d<br />

<strong>of</strong> transcription <strong>of</strong> the Corybantic rites from Crete, but also from Empedocles,<br />

who comments on sacrifices <strong>in</strong> expound<strong>in</strong>g his theory:<br />

No Ares was to them a god, no Battle-noise,<br />

No Zeus was k<strong>in</strong>g, no Kronos, no Poseidon:<br />

Kypris was queen—<br />

222


that is Friendship.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y made her k<strong>in</strong>d (i9la&skonto) with pious a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong><br />

With graptoi=j zw|&oisi <strong>and</strong> with subtle scents,<br />

With sacrifice <strong>of</strong> purest myrrh <strong>of</strong> frank<strong>in</strong>cense<br />

Sweet-scented; <strong>and</strong> they poured upon the ground<br />

Libations from the tawny bees.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se practices are still preserved among some peoples, like traces <strong>of</strong><br />

truth:<br />

the altar was not soaked by violent deaths<br />

<strong>of</strong> bulls. (Abst. 2.20-2.21) [166]<br />

Through cit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>The</strong>ophrastus, Porphyry reaches back to a fragment <strong>of</strong> Empedocles to<br />

support his argument <strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> bloodless sacrifice. Ow<strong>in</strong>g to this theme, the fragment<br />

is considered to be part <strong>of</strong> Empedocles’ poem Katharmoi, which, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Hippolytus<br />

<strong>of</strong> Rome (A.D. II-III), discussed, though not exclusively, the affiliated theme <strong>of</strong><br />

prohibition aga<strong>in</strong>st eat<strong>in</strong>g meat. 349 <strong>The</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> ascrib<strong>in</strong>g bloodless sacrifice <strong>and</strong><br />

abst<strong>in</strong>ence from meat to early times is a traditional feature <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> early men as simple, <strong>in</strong>nocent, <strong>and</strong> morally superior be<strong>in</strong>gs. 350 In the<br />

349 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the fragment <strong>of</strong> Empedocles as part <strong>of</strong> his Katharmoi on the basis <strong>of</strong> Hippolytus’s<br />

remark (RH 7.30.3), see M. R. Wright, ed., Empedocles: <strong>The</strong> Extant Fragments (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1981) 81, n. 20. For the division <strong>of</strong> Empedocles’ quotations <strong>in</strong>to two poems, Physics <strong>and</strong> Katharmoi, on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> subject matter (i.e., scientific, religious), <strong>and</strong> the idea that this division is a historiographic<br />

<strong>in</strong>vention <strong>of</strong> post-<strong>Classical</strong>, most likely, second- to third-century A.D. date, see C. Osborne, “Empedocles<br />

Recycled,” CQ 37 (1987) 24-50. For Empedocles as an adamant proponent <strong>of</strong> abst<strong>in</strong>ence from sacrific<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g animals, <strong>and</strong> how this idea <strong>in</strong>fluences his wider philosophical st<strong>and</strong>, see Sorabji, <strong>Animal</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ds<br />

<strong>and</strong> Human Morals 174-175; also Osborne, “Boundaries <strong>in</strong> Nature” 23-24. For Porphyry’s excessive<br />

borrow<strong>in</strong>g from writers, such as <strong>The</strong>ophrastus <strong>and</strong> Empedocles <strong>in</strong> order to strengthen his argument for not<br />

kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g animals, see G. Clark, tr., Porphyry. On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Ithaca, New<br />

York, 2000) 19-20.<br />

350 For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> this idea <strong>and</strong> its prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek thought, see W. K. C. Guthrie,<br />

In the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g: Some Greek Views on the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Life <strong>and</strong> the Early State <strong>of</strong> Man (Ithaca, New York,<br />

1957; repr. 1965) 69-73. A representative advocate <strong>of</strong> the belief that early men did not sacrifice animals is<br />

Plato, who states <strong>in</strong> the Laws (782c): “the custom <strong>of</strong> men sacrific<strong>in</strong>g one another, is, <strong>in</strong> fact, one that<br />

survives even now among many peoples; whereas amongst others we hear <strong>of</strong> how the opposite custom<br />

existed, when they were forbidden so much to eat an ox, <strong>and</strong> their <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs to the gods consisted, not <strong>of</strong><br />

animals, but <strong>of</strong> cakes <strong>of</strong> meal, gra<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> honey, <strong>and</strong> other such bloodless sacrifices, <strong>and</strong> from flesh they<br />

absta<strong>in</strong>ed as though it were unholy to eat it or to sta<strong>in</strong> with blood the altars <strong>of</strong> the gods; <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> that,<br />

those <strong>of</strong> us men who then existed lived what is called an “Orphic life,” keep<strong>in</strong>g wholly to <strong>in</strong>animate food,<br />

223


fragment, these st<strong>and</strong>ards are exalted by the rul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Kypris (Friendship), 351 whom early<br />

men propitiated (i9la&skonto) not with sacrifices <strong>of</strong> animals, but, <strong>in</strong>stead, with<br />

eu)sebe/ess<strong>in</strong> (“pious”) a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> graptoi=j (“pa<strong>in</strong>ted,” “drawn”) zw|&oisi. <strong>The</strong><br />

reference to Kypris <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the terms “propitiated” <strong>and</strong> “pious” establish the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> the fragment as that <strong>of</strong> religious practice. With<strong>in</strong> this context, both<br />

a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> zw|&oisi feature as st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d to Kypris.<br />

0Aga&lmas<strong>in</strong> is the dative plural form <strong>of</strong> a1galma, a word, which, <strong>in</strong> fifth-century<br />

literature, is used “for statues <strong>in</strong> general <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual images <strong>of</strong> gods,” but holds also<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “ornament,” “delight,” <strong>and</strong> “picture.” 352 This evidence suggests that the<br />

term was directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the arts. In this case, the general mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “statues”<br />

has been applied to a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> also the ever-general one <strong>of</strong> “images,” which,<br />

although fitt<strong>in</strong>g, underscores our difficulty <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> consequent tendency to<br />

generalize Greek terms that stood <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> for a broad, yet ref<strong>in</strong>ed, spectrum <strong>of</strong> images. 353<br />

That these “statues” are described as pious (eu)sebe/ess<strong>in</strong>) makes it probably safe to<br />

<strong>and</strong> contrariwise, absta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g wholly from th<strong>in</strong>gs animate”; translation: R. G. Bury, ed., tr., Plato IX. Laws I<br />

[London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1926; repr. 1952] 493).<br />

351 For the identification <strong>of</strong> Kypris with Philia, that is, Friendship, <strong>in</strong> fragments <strong>of</strong> the so-called Physics <strong>of</strong><br />

Empedocles (e.g., 62 [73], 70 [75].2, 83 [98].3, <strong>and</strong> 87 [95]), see Wright, Empedocles 283.<br />

352 Donohue, Xoana 24, n. 59, <strong>and</strong> 25, n. 61 respectively, for examples <strong>of</strong> a1galma as “statue” <strong>in</strong>: a) P<strong>in</strong>dar,<br />

Pyth. 5.40, <strong>and</strong> Nem. 5.1, <strong>and</strong> b) Aeschylus, Sept. 258-265; also 25, n. 61, for a1galma as “statue <strong>of</strong> a god”<br />

<strong>in</strong> Aeschylus, Sept. 258-265, <strong>and</strong> 26, n. 63 for the same word <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Euripides, Hipp. 116, 1399,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Andr. 115, 246; also 25, n. 61 for a1galma as “ornament” be<strong>in</strong>g the most frequent mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

Aeschylus (without citations); 26, n. 63 for a1galma as a “delight” <strong>in</strong> Euripides, Suppl. 632, IT 273, <strong>and</strong><br />

Hel. 262 as a “picture.” For the development <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a1galma from the sixth to the fifth<br />

centuries B.C., see H. Philipp, Tektonon Daidala. Der bildende Künstler und se<strong>in</strong> Werk <strong>in</strong> vorplatonischen<br />

Schrifttum (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1988) 103-108.<br />

353 Statues: W. W. Fortenbaugh et al., eds., trs., <strong>The</strong>ophrastus <strong>of</strong> Eresus. Sources for his Life, Writ<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

Thought <strong>and</strong> Influence II (Leiden <strong>and</strong> New York, 1993) 417; Images: Wright, Empedocles 282; Clark,<br />

Porphyry 63. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the “poorly understood [Greek] vocabulary relat<strong>in</strong>g to images”, see A. A.<br />

Donohue, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Images <strong>of</strong> the Gods: Considerations <strong>of</strong> Term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>and</strong> Methodology,” Hephaistos<br />

15 (1997) 34, ns. 11-18, where, along with a1galma, she also mentions a)ndria&j, a)fi/druma, bre/taj,<br />

e3doj, ei1dwlon, ei0kw&n, <strong>and</strong> kolosso&j; similarly, Schnapp, “Are Images Animated,” <strong>in</strong> Renfrew <strong>and</strong><br />

Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient M<strong>in</strong>d 41, who notes that “the Greek language does not possess a word for<br />

‘statue.’ Instead <strong>of</strong> this, the Greeks used a range <strong>of</strong> very different formulations: bretas, xoanon, agalma,<br />

idruma, kolossos, eidolon, eikon.”<br />

224


assume that they referred to images <strong>of</strong> gods, although the possibility <strong>of</strong> their be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

images <strong>of</strong> animals that were not sacrificed cannot be precluded. At the same time, they<br />

can simply mean “delightful th<strong>in</strong>gs.” Apart from these def<strong>in</strong>itions, the a)ga&lmata <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fragment have been also thought to mean “<strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs” <strong>and</strong> “gifts.” 354 That these<br />

a)ga&lmata were presented to Kypris cannot be denied, but their identification with<br />

“images,” <strong>in</strong> particular, pious “statues,” establishes them as works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

significance, <strong>and</strong> therefore allows a close-up view <strong>of</strong> their mean<strong>in</strong>g. This view comes<br />

from the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a1galma as a “statue, [more precisely], an <strong>in</strong>animate image, which<br />

makes the liv<strong>in</strong>g gods present,” which, despite its attestation <strong>in</strong> a later, but still <strong>Classical</strong><br />

author (Plato), when applied to the a)ga&lmata <strong>of</strong> Kypris’s age, illum<strong>in</strong>ates the particular<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g that these statues might have held for Empedocles <strong>and</strong> his contemporaries. 355 In<br />

addition, the fact that Empedocles associates these pious statues with an early age like<br />

that <strong>of</strong> Kypris is suggestive <strong>of</strong> the centrality <strong>of</strong> the visual arts <strong>in</strong> religious practice as a<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ent feature <strong>of</strong> the Greek conception <strong>of</strong> the past. 356 That the Egyptians—a race<br />

much older than the Greek <strong>in</strong> the Greek imag<strong>in</strong>ation—were credited with <strong>in</strong>vent<strong>in</strong>g this<br />

354 Offer<strong>in</strong>gs: Guthrie, In the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g 73; gifts: W. E. Leonard, tr., <strong>The</strong> Fragments <strong>of</strong> Empedocles<br />

(Chicago, 1908) 59. <strong>The</strong>re is a strong suspicion that these translations may be <strong>in</strong>fluenced, not by the<br />

featur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a)ga&lmata as <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs to Kypris <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the fragment, but by the fact that, the early<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a1galma (e.g., <strong>in</strong> Homer <strong>and</strong> Hesiod) was that <strong>of</strong> a gift to a human be<strong>in</strong>g as well as to a god. It<br />

is only <strong>in</strong> the first half <strong>of</strong> the sixth century, that the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term appears to be conf<strong>in</strong>ed to that <strong>of</strong> an<br />

object dedicated to the gods. For these def<strong>in</strong>itions, see Philipp, Tektonon Daidala 103-104; also A. E.<br />

Raubitschek, rev. <strong>of</strong> “H. Bloesh, Agalma, Kle<strong>in</strong>od, Weihgeschenk, Götterbild, e<strong>in</strong> Beitrag zur<br />

frühgriechischen Kultur und Religionsgeschichte (Bern, 1943),” <strong>in</strong> AJA 50 (1946) 197.<br />

355 Plato (Laws 931a): “some <strong>of</strong> the gods whom we honor we see clearly, but <strong>of</strong> other we set up statues<br />

[a)ga&lmata] as images [ei0ko&naj], <strong>and</strong> we believe that when we worship these, lifeless though they be, the<br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g gods beyond feel great good-will towards us <strong>and</strong> gratitude”; translation: R. G. Bury, ed., tr., Plato<br />

IX. Laws II (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1926; repr. 1952) 449. For the value <strong>of</strong> this passage <strong>in</strong><br />

express<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a1galma as a statue, that is, an <strong>in</strong>animate image that makes the liv<strong>in</strong>g gods<br />

present, see Schnapp, “Are Images Animated,” <strong>in</strong> Renfrew <strong>and</strong> Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient M<strong>in</strong>d 43.<br />

356 Such a connection between the past <strong>and</strong> art contrasts with the Greek idea <strong>of</strong> the past as an age before art.<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> an age before art, its featur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Greek conception <strong>of</strong> the past, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

<strong>in</strong> antiquarian writ<strong>in</strong>gs like those <strong>of</strong> Callimachus, Plutarch, <strong>and</strong> Pausanias on the history <strong>of</strong> art, see<br />

Donohue, Xoana 196-197, <strong>and</strong> more generally, 177-205. This is evidence for the existence <strong>of</strong> several<br />

Greek conceptions <strong>of</strong> the past that cannot be reconciled.<br />

225


practice is an idea <strong>of</strong> Herodotus that implies an age before art <strong>and</strong> will be discussed<br />

later. 357<br />

Along with a)ga&lmata <strong>of</strong>fered to Kypris, Empedocles’ fragment also mentions<br />

zw|~a. In terms <strong>of</strong> spell<strong>in</strong>g, zw|&oisi deviates slightly from the correct spell<strong>in</strong>g zw=oij,<br />

which is the dative plural <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. It seems that for reasons <strong>of</strong> metrical cohesion with<br />

adjacent terms (i.e., eu)sebe/ess<strong>in</strong> a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong>, mu&roisi), zw|&oisi has its last syllable<br />

term<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an additional iota (i). 358 <strong>The</strong> fact that these zw|&oisi are called graptoi=j<br />

(“pa<strong>in</strong>ted” or “drawn”), which derives from gra&fw (“to pa<strong>in</strong>t, “to draw,” “to write”),<br />

<strong>and</strong> are mentioned right after pious a)ga&lmata suggests a context directly <strong>in</strong>volved with<br />

the arts <strong>in</strong> a religious sett<strong>in</strong>g. 359 This context, <strong>in</strong> turn, creates the impression that zw|&oisi<br />

are images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, perhaps pictures, rather than “animals,” as the predom<strong>in</strong>ant<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term would urge one to conclude. Furthermore, the absence <strong>of</strong> additional<br />

description relat<strong>in</strong>g to zw|&oisi implies that, even though this is a term for some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

images, it refers to them <strong>in</strong> a general way.<br />

Modern translations <strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi <strong>of</strong>fer a strik<strong>in</strong>g variety <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs rang<strong>in</strong>g from<br />

“pictures,” <strong>and</strong> “figures” to “animal figures,” “pictured creatures,” <strong>and</strong> “images <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs.” 360 As can be seen, some <strong>of</strong> these def<strong>in</strong>itions provide zw|&oisi with its traditional<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> animal <strong>and</strong> its wider notions, whereas others stress its belong<strong>in</strong>g to the realm<br />

<strong>of</strong> images. More generally, this dichotomy <strong>in</strong>dicates scholarly awareness <strong>of</strong> the split <strong>in</strong><br />

357 For the Greek perspective on Egypt as a l<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> ancient wisdom <strong>and</strong> a culture that preceded the Greek<br />

one, see T. Harrison, “Upside Down <strong>and</strong> Back to Front: Herodotus <strong>and</strong> the Greek Encounter with Egypt,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> R. Matthews <strong>and</strong> C. Roemer, eds., Ancient Perspectives on Egypt (London, 2003) 146.<br />

358 For the use <strong>of</strong> dactylic hexameter verse <strong>in</strong> the writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> Empedocles, see J. P. Hershbell,<br />

“Empedocles’ Oral Style,” CJ 63 (1968) 351-357.<br />

359 LSJ 9 , 359, s.v. grapto&j. <strong>The</strong> word derives from gra&fw (360, s.v.), whose primary mean<strong>in</strong>g is “to<br />

write,” but it means also “to pa<strong>in</strong>t” <strong>and</strong> “to draw.”<br />

360 Pictures: Fortenbaugh et al., <strong>The</strong>ophrastus 417; figures: Guthrie, In the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g 73; animal figures:<br />

Wright, Empedocles 282; pictured creatures: Clark, Porphyry 63; images <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs: Leonard, <strong>The</strong><br />

Fragments 59.<br />

226


the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the fifth century. As stated above, zw|&oisi st<strong>and</strong> for pa<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>and</strong><br />

perhaps drawn images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d rather than animals. A digression to the various<br />

translations, however, provides the opportunity to emphasize how modern def<strong>in</strong>itions,<br />

when applied to zw|&oisi, may complicate rather than assist <strong>in</strong> decipher<strong>in</strong>g its ancient<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> situation starts to become thorny, for example, when seen that some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

modern terms that have been applied to zw|&oisi do not hold a s<strong>in</strong>gle mean<strong>in</strong>g but rather<br />

numerous nuanced ones. <strong>The</strong> primary mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “picture,” for example, is that <strong>of</strong> “an<br />

image or likeness <strong>of</strong> an object, person or scene produced on a flat surface, especially by<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, draw<strong>in</strong>g, or photography.” 361 This mean<strong>in</strong>g seems appropriate for zw|&oisi<br />

consider<strong>in</strong>g that the latter is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the ancient text as graptoi=j (“pa<strong>in</strong>ted” or<br />

“drawn”). But the modern term “picture” carries also the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “perfect likeness,”<br />

“anyth<strong>in</strong>g closely resembl<strong>in</strong>g or strik<strong>in</strong>gly typify<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g else,” <strong>and</strong> also “anyth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

regarded as hav<strong>in</strong>g the compositional beauty <strong>of</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g or a draw<strong>in</strong>g.” 362 Faced with<br />

these nuances <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g it is difficult to determ<strong>in</strong>e which, if any, <strong>of</strong> them the translator<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when decid<strong>in</strong>g on “pictures.”<br />

A similar situation is also detected <strong>in</strong> the correspondence <strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi to “figures.”<br />

For a modern audience, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the visual arts, the term “figure” refers to<br />

the representation <strong>of</strong> a bodily form, especially the human one. 363 Current discussions <strong>of</strong><br />

visual art, however, <strong>in</strong>dicate that “figure” is also used for the description <strong>of</strong> the bodily<br />

361<br />

D. B. Guralnik, ed., Webster’s New World Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the American Language (New York, 1970;<br />

second ed., 1980) 1077, s.v. picture.<br />

362<br />

Guralnik, Webster’s New World Dictionary 1077, s.v. picture.<br />

363<br />

R. Mayer, ed., <strong>The</strong> Harper Coll<strong>in</strong>s Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Art Terms <strong>and</strong> Techniques (New York, 1969; second<br />

ed., 1991) 151, s.v. figure; K. Reynolds <strong>and</strong> R. Seddon, eds., Illustrated Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Art Terms. A<br />

H<strong>and</strong>book for the Artist <strong>and</strong> Art Lover (New York, 1984) 68, s.v. figure; also P. B. Gove, ed., Webster’s<br />

Third New International Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the English Language Unabridged (Spr<strong>in</strong>gfield, Mass., 1961; repr.<br />

1986) 848, s.v. figure.<br />

227


form <strong>of</strong> animals. 364 <strong>The</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>able mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term is also witnessed <strong>in</strong> the Object<br />

Names <strong>The</strong>saurus <strong>of</strong> the British Museum, whose notes regard<strong>in</strong>g the description <strong>of</strong><br />

objects, state that “figure” has been used for all animate subjects, <strong>and</strong> “model” for all<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate ones. 365 This dist<strong>in</strong>ction, however, does not seem to carry on <strong>in</strong> the additional<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “figure.” As glosses <strong>in</strong> modern dictionaries expla<strong>in</strong>, “figure” may also st<strong>and</strong><br />

for “a likeness or representation <strong>of</strong> a person or a th<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>and</strong> for “an object significant or<br />

noticeable only <strong>in</strong> its form.” 366 Such an array <strong>of</strong> semantic possibilities puts <strong>in</strong> question<br />

whether Empedocles’ “figures” should be understood synthetically, that is, as figural<br />

images (representations) <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects, or <strong>in</strong> association with a<br />

particular mean<strong>in</strong>g from the pool <strong>of</strong> those that “figure” has been seen to carry.<br />

Return<strong>in</strong>g to the rema<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> modern def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi, one sees that the<br />

attempts to identify the ancient term with “animal figures,” “pictured creatures,” <strong>and</strong> also<br />

“images <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs” are at home with, <strong>and</strong> decisively affected by, the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as “animal,” “creature” <strong>and</strong> “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g.” A closer view <strong>of</strong> these<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions, however, reveals an <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g common element, namely, their underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi as subjects <strong>of</strong> representation. This treatment, when juxtaposed to the above<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> “pictures,” which makes one to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> images, <strong>in</strong>dicates two different<br />

angles from which the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi has been approached. Although this is<br />

evidence that cannot be overlooked, its value lies <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to the foreground the<br />

modern dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject. As it has been remarked, however, the<br />

364 <strong>The</strong> discussion, for example, <strong>of</strong> the Geometric phase <strong>of</strong> Greek art, <strong>in</strong> A. F. Janson, rev. H. W. Hanson,<br />

History <strong>of</strong> Art I (fourth edition; New York, 1991) 151, opens with the follow<strong>in</strong>g statement: “toward 800<br />

B.C. human <strong>and</strong> animal figures beg<strong>in</strong> to appear with<strong>in</strong> the geometric framework, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the most mature<br />

examples these figures could form elaborate scenes.”<br />

365 British Museum Object Names <strong>The</strong>saurus: http://www.mda.org.uk/bmobj/Obthesf1.htm.<br />

366 First quotation: Guralnik, Webster’s New World Dictionary 521, s.v. figure; Second quotation: Gove,<br />

Webster’s Third New International Dictionary 848, s.v. figure.<br />

228


tendency not to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between these two was an exist<strong>in</strong>g characteristic <strong>of</strong> the Greek<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. 367 That zw|~on constituted a term that did not escape from this<br />

tendency will be shown <strong>in</strong> later parts <strong>of</strong> this discussion.<br />

Herodotus<br />

<strong>The</strong> second fifth-century author who uses the word zw|~on <strong>in</strong> connection with the<br />

visual arts is Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> word appears eight times <strong>in</strong> his Histories, seven <strong>in</strong> its<br />

regular form (zw|~on), <strong>and</strong> one <strong>in</strong> its dim<strong>in</strong>utive (zw|&dion); it is associated with a variety <strong>of</strong><br />

media, namely, clothes, sculpture, pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> bronze work; it carries both the mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

<strong>of</strong> “image” <strong>and</strong> “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g that it was used<br />

<strong>in</strong>terchangeably, <strong>and</strong>, therefore, stood for the absence <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong><br />

subject. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g discussion exam<strong>in</strong>es, first, the occurrences <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, <strong>and</strong> then that<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|&dion <strong>in</strong> the Histories.<br />

a. Zw|~a on Clothes from the Caucasus<br />

<strong>The</strong> first occurrence <strong>of</strong> zw|~on is <strong>in</strong> relation to clothes that feature <strong>in</strong> the first book<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Histories. Like Empedocles, Herodotus uses the term to refer to images <strong>of</strong> some<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d, most likely, pictures. After his conquest <strong>of</strong> Sardis (546 B.C.), the Persian k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Cyrus (reign ca. 557-530 B.C.) campaigned aga<strong>in</strong>st the Massagetae, a group <strong>of</strong> people<br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the area east <strong>of</strong> the Caspian Sea. Before narrat<strong>in</strong>g this encounter, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> an<br />

attempt to be faithful to the concept <strong>of</strong> symmetry, 368 Herodotus describes the customs <strong>of</strong><br />

367 Donohue, Xoana 39, for the absence <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject, <strong>and</strong> 23, for the<br />

unimportance <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> image as an object.<br />

368 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ penchant for geographical symmetry <strong>and</strong> its implementation <strong>in</strong> his<br />

descriptions, see R. Thomas, Herodotus <strong>in</strong> Context. Ethnography, Science <strong>and</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Persuasion<br />

229


the people liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the area west <strong>of</strong> the Caspian Sea, that is, around the mounta<strong>in</strong> range<br />

<strong>of</strong> Caucasus:<br />

Many <strong>and</strong> every sort <strong>of</strong> nation the Caucasus conta<strong>in</strong>s with<strong>in</strong> itself, most <strong>of</strong> them<br />

liv<strong>in</strong>g from the fruit <strong>of</strong> the wild trees. Among them, they say, there are trees with<br />

leaves such that, when they crush them <strong>and</strong> mix them with water, they can pa<strong>in</strong>t<br />

(e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>) on their clothes (e0sqh~ta) zw|~a. <strong>The</strong>se zw|~a do not wash out but<br />

grow old with the wool, as though they were woven <strong>in</strong>to it at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(1.203) [99]<br />

All that can be understood from this passage is that the plural zw|~a are some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

decorative elements on clothes (e0sqh~ta) from a distant place <strong>in</strong> the Caucasus. 369 As was<br />

the case with Empedocles’ fragment, the passage provides no <strong>in</strong>formation about the<br />

appearance <strong>of</strong> zw|~a—a usage that aga<strong>in</strong> suggests the general sense <strong>of</strong> the term. Unlike<br />

those <strong>of</strong> the previous fragment, however, these zw|~a do not appear <strong>in</strong> a religious context.<br />

<strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a is not easy to determ<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> this difficulty is reflected <strong>in</strong> the<br />

variety <strong>of</strong> the modern translations <strong>of</strong> the term. Alfred Godley, for example, translates<br />

zw|~a as “figures.” 370 In agreement with him are Joseph Blakesley, Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott,<br />

George Macaulay <strong>and</strong> David Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>and</strong> Rob<strong>in</strong> Waterfield. 371 Aubrey De Sél<strong>in</strong>court<br />

<strong>and</strong> John Mar<strong>in</strong>cola dist<strong>in</strong>guish between two different mean<strong>in</strong>gs for the twice-mentioned<br />

(Cambridge, 2000) 75-101; for Herodotus’ contribution to a conceptual remodel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the geography, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, picture <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>in</strong> the fifth century B.C., see J. S. Romm, <strong>The</strong> Edges <strong>of</strong> the Earth <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

Thought: Geography, Exploration, <strong>and</strong> Fiction (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1992) 32-41.<br />

369 For e0sqh&j <strong>and</strong> the Lat<strong>in</strong> “vestis” as words that refer primarily to cloth<strong>in</strong>g, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong><br />

Description 181-182, n. 86; also Lee, “<strong>The</strong> Myth <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Peplos” 87, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that, <strong>in</strong><br />

Aeschylus’s Persians (472 B.C.) <strong>and</strong> Seven aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>The</strong>bes (467 B.C.), the term e0sqh&j describes women’s<br />

clothes. That Greek women were familiar with a garment called Kimberikon derives from Aristophanes’<br />

Lysistrata (411 B.C.; l<strong>in</strong>e 45), where Calonike exclaims that she will wear a Kimberikon <strong>in</strong> order to force<br />

men to stop fight<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> ancient scholia expla<strong>in</strong> Kimberikon as a type <strong>of</strong> cloth<strong>in</strong>g, whose name results<br />

from geography; they also give the variant read<strong>in</strong>g kimm-, which may be associated with the Cimmerians, a<br />

group <strong>of</strong> people liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the North Caucasus. For a detailed account <strong>of</strong> these scholia, <strong>and</strong> the suggestion<br />

that the variant read<strong>in</strong>g may be the result <strong>of</strong> confusion with the Cimmerians, see Donohue, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong><br />

Description 185, n. 95.<br />

370 A. Godley, ed., tr., Herodotus I (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1920; repr. 1946) 257.<br />

371 J. W. Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary (London, 1854) 152, n. 685; LSJ 9 760, s.v. zw|~on; G. C.<br />

Macaulay, tr., rev. D. Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus (New York, 2004) 74; R. Waterfield, tr.,<br />

Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1998) 89.<br />

230


zw|~a. Thus, they translate the first zw|~a as “figures,” <strong>and</strong> the second as “designs.” 372<br />

David Grene, <strong>in</strong> contrast, suggests that both zw|~a are “figures <strong>of</strong> animals,” <strong>and</strong> Elizabeth<br />

Barber says simply “animals.” 373 F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> his commentary on the first book <strong>of</strong><br />

Herodotus’ Histories, George Sheets translates the term as “creatures.” 374 <strong>The</strong> variety <strong>of</strong><br />

modern def<strong>in</strong>itions for zw|~a reflects scholarly awareness <strong>of</strong> the split <strong>in</strong> the fifth-century<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, a situation, which is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> zw|&oisi <strong>in</strong><br />

Empedocles’ fragment.<br />

Syntactically, the term zw|~a is the object <strong>of</strong> the word e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, which is a<br />

compound <strong>of</strong> the preposition e0n (“<strong>in</strong>”) <strong>and</strong> the verb gra&fw, whose mean<strong>in</strong>g, as noted<br />

earlier, is “to write,” “to draw,” <strong>and</strong> “to pa<strong>in</strong>t.” Given this evidence, it can be seen why<br />

Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott’s Lexicon def<strong>in</strong>es e0ggra&fw as “to make <strong>in</strong>cisions <strong>in</strong>to,” “to mark <strong>in</strong> or<br />

on,” <strong>and</strong> “to pa<strong>in</strong>t”). 375 Regard<strong>in</strong>g this e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Grene,<br />

Godley, Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>and</strong> Waterfield suggest that it refers to pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. 376 In<br />

her analysis, Barber ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that Herodotus’ e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong> denotes that the <strong>in</strong>habitants <strong>of</strong><br />

the Caucasus pa<strong>in</strong>ted or drew all over their clothes. 377 <strong>The</strong>se suggestions, which rely on<br />

the semantic dependence <strong>of</strong> e0ggra&fw on gra&fw, place zw|~a, the direct object <strong>of</strong><br />

e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong> close proximity with Empedocles’ grapta& (also from gra&fw, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, “pa<strong>in</strong>ted” or “drawn”) zw|~a. As seen earlier, the latter were images <strong>of</strong> some<br />

372<br />

A. De Sél<strong>in</strong>court, tr., rev. J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996; rev.<br />

ed., 2003) 89.<br />

373<br />

D. Grene, tr., <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1987) 126; E. J. W. Barber, Prehistoric<br />

Textiles: <strong>The</strong> Development <strong>of</strong> Cloth <strong>in</strong> the Neolithic <strong>and</strong> Bronze Ages with Special Reference to the Aegean<br />

( Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1991) 226.<br />

374<br />

G. A. Sheets, Herodotus Book 1. Commentary (Bryn Mawr, 1981) 73.<br />

375 9<br />

LSJ , 468, s.v. e0ggra&fw.<br />

376<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 89; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 126; Godley,<br />

Herodotus 257; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 74; Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories<br />

89.<br />

377<br />

Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 206 <strong>and</strong> 226 respectively.<br />

231


k<strong>in</strong>d, most likely pictures, <strong>and</strong> not actual animals. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the same<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g can be applied to Herodotus’ zw|~a; the fact, however that these zw|~a were<br />

applied on clothes raises the question <strong>of</strong> the employment <strong>of</strong> a particular technique.<br />

Barber cautions that e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong>fers no particular clue as far as a particular<br />

technique is concerned, but on the basis <strong>of</strong> material evidence, she suggests that the term<br />

may be connected with resist-dye<strong>in</strong>g. 378 Her discussion <strong>of</strong> archaeological parallels<br />

focuses on two examples <strong>of</strong> clothes that were found <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> tombs at the site <strong>of</strong><br />

Kertch (ancient Pantikapaion) <strong>in</strong> the Black Sea area—the western boundary <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Caucasus Mounta<strong>in</strong>s. <strong>The</strong> first example, which belongs to a tomb dat<strong>in</strong>g from the fifth<br />

century B.C., is “a pla<strong>in</strong>-woven cloth <strong>of</strong> wool that had been pa<strong>in</strong>ted or resist-dyed <strong>in</strong> tan,<br />

dark red, <strong>and</strong> black with waves, me<strong>and</strong>ers, squares, dotted rosettes, braids, <strong>and</strong><br />

checkers.” 379 <strong>The</strong> second example is remnants <strong>of</strong> a woolen cloth that functioned as a pall<br />

for a wooden sarcophagus that was found <strong>in</strong> a tomb dated to the early fourth century (c.<br />

400 B.C.) Regard<strong>in</strong>g the provenience, construction <strong>and</strong> decoration <strong>of</strong> this cloth, Barber<br />

notes that it “was locally made,...sewn together from eleven long strips <strong>and</strong> ‘pa<strong>in</strong>ted’ with<br />

frieze after frieze <strong>of</strong> figures from Greek mythology.” 380 Michael Vickers remarks that<br />

these figures were set aga<strong>in</strong>st a dark background. 381 In some cases, Barber cont<strong>in</strong>ues,<br />

several letters <strong>of</strong> names <strong>in</strong>scribed above these figures have been preserved <strong>and</strong> allow their<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g as Jocasta, Phaidra, Eilemene, Mopsos, Hippomedon, <strong>and</strong> Iolaus. <strong>The</strong> decoration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cloth consists also <strong>of</strong> horses <strong>and</strong> chariots <strong>and</strong> its entire arrangement has been<br />

378<br />

Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 226.<br />

379<br />

Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 206.<br />

380<br />

Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 206, <strong>and</strong> 380, where she states that the cloth was “not new when laid <strong>in</strong>to<br />

the tomb, [as] suggested by the careful mend that it conta<strong>in</strong>[ed].”<br />

381<br />

M. Vickers, Images on Textiles. <strong>The</strong> Weave <strong>of</strong> Fifth-Century Athenian Art <strong>and</strong> Society (Xenia 42;<br />

Konstanz, 1999) 21.<br />

232


econstructed as five consecutive friezes (Fig. 21). 382 Barber refers to the decorative<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> the cloth as “resist-pa<strong>in</strong>ted” <strong>and</strong> provides a succ<strong>in</strong>ct explanation <strong>of</strong> their<br />

technical process, cit<strong>in</strong>g Dora Gerz<strong>in</strong>ger, who equates it with what is today known as hot<br />

batik. 383 <strong>The</strong> latter refers to the process <strong>of</strong> decorat<strong>in</strong>g a woven cloth by “us<strong>in</strong>g a [molten]<br />

wax compound to cover those parts <strong>of</strong> the cloth which are to resist a particular color<br />

dur<strong>in</strong>g the dye<strong>in</strong>g process,” <strong>and</strong> is widely used today <strong>in</strong> Indonesia <strong>and</strong> South-East Asia. 384<br />

Worth mention<strong>in</strong>g, only because it br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d Herodotus’ e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, is<br />

that the word batik orig<strong>in</strong>ates from the Javanese work ambatik, which carries the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” “draw<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>and</strong> “writ<strong>in</strong>g.” 385<br />

<strong>The</strong> surviv<strong>in</strong>g textiles from Kertch place the decoration <strong>of</strong> clothes by means <strong>of</strong><br />

resist-dye<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the vic<strong>in</strong>ity <strong>of</strong> the geographical area mentioned by Herodotus. Rang<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from waves, me<strong>and</strong>ers, <strong>and</strong> checkers to horses, chariots, <strong>and</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs with their<br />

names <strong>in</strong>scribed, the decorative elements on these textiles provide a visual example <strong>of</strong><br />

what Herodotus might have had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when mention<strong>in</strong>g zw|~a. It is impossible to<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e, however, whether his zw|~a refer to all these elements <strong>in</strong> general, or to a<br />

specific k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> them. In view <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the modern def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> zw|~a as<br />

“figures” “designs,” “figures <strong>of</strong> animals,” or simply “animals” <strong>and</strong> “creatures” can be<br />

neither dismissed nor substantiated. If one is to use the etymology <strong>of</strong> zw|~on—<strong>in</strong> its most<br />

general sense <strong>of</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g—as a guide here, then the closest one can come to the<br />

382 Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 206-207, fig. 7.11, <strong>and</strong> 379, fig. 16.15.<br />

383 Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 207, where the caption <strong>of</strong> fig. 7.11 refers to the reconstructed cloth as<br />

“resist-pa<strong>in</strong>ted”; also, 206 for citation <strong>of</strong> D. Gerziger, “E<strong>in</strong>e Decke aus dem sechsten Grab der ‘Sieben<br />

Brüder,’ AK 18 (1975) 51, who identifies the process <strong>of</strong> decoration as hot batik.<br />

384 S. Fraser-Lu, Indonesian Batik. Process, Patterns <strong>and</strong> Places (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1986) 1, <strong>and</strong> 6-11<br />

for a description <strong>of</strong> the application <strong>of</strong> molten wax to clothes as part <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> decoration.<br />

385 Fraser-Lu, Indonesian Batik 1.<br />

233


mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> these zw|~a, whose sense is also very general, is that they are decorative<br />

elements that depict animate subjects.<br />

<strong>The</strong> truth is that Herodotus is silent about this possibility; therefore, it should not<br />

be considered conclusive. What he does talk about, <strong>and</strong> what actually agrees well with<br />

the evidence for resist-dye<strong>in</strong>g, is that these zw|~a cannot be washed out (ta_ de\ zw|~a ou)k<br />

e0kplu&nesqai). In fact, so fasc<strong>in</strong>ated is he by this exceptional quality <strong>of</strong> the zw|~a, that he<br />

attributes it to the use <strong>of</strong> ground-up tree leaves <strong>and</strong> water as a compound for their<br />

application on clothes. With<strong>in</strong> this context, zw|~a ga<strong>in</strong> their mean<strong>in</strong>g as decorative<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>delible quality from the use <strong>of</strong> natural substances. 386 <strong>The</strong>se substances, <strong>in</strong><br />

turn, lend qualitative value to the technical process <strong>of</strong> e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Apart from connect<strong>in</strong>g zw|~a with e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, Herodotus also mentions that they<br />

looked as if they have been woven <strong>in</strong> from the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g (kata& per e0nufanqe/nta<br />

a)rxh&n). This evidence does not rule out Barber’s suggestion that zw|~a were produced by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> resist-dye<strong>in</strong>g, but rather highlights that this was a term for both pa<strong>in</strong>ted, most<br />

likely resist-dyed, <strong>and</strong> woven-<strong>in</strong> decorations <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d on textiles. Although not<br />

mention<strong>in</strong>g zw|~a per se, a passage from Euripides’ Ion is illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, for it suggests that<br />

fifth-century Athenian audiences paid attention to <strong>and</strong> valued greatly elaborate<br />

decorations that were woven <strong>in</strong> textiles from the conceived as adjacent to Caucasus, l<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the Amazons, <strong>and</strong> other foreign places <strong>in</strong> general. 387<br />

386 Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, Fraser-Lu, Indonesian Batik 15, mentions that “traditional batik dyes came from a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural substances,” <strong>and</strong> “the oldest <strong>and</strong> first dye to be applied <strong>in</strong> classical Indonesia batik was blue<br />

made from the leaves <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>digo plant.”<br />

387 In Euripides’ Ion (1145-1165), the leader <strong>of</strong> the chorus describes the sett<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>of</strong> a tent by Ion <strong>in</strong> the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g way: “<strong>The</strong>n he took sacred tapestries from the storerooms <strong>and</strong> draped them for shade over the<br />

frame, a marvelous sight for men to see. First on the top he put a cover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> garments dedicated by<br />

Heracles, garments which the son <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>of</strong>fered the god as spoils from the Amazons. On them were<br />

woven the follow<strong>in</strong>g. Heaven was muster<strong>in</strong>g the stars <strong>in</strong> the circle <strong>of</strong> the sky. Helios was driv<strong>in</strong>g his<br />

horses toward his f<strong>in</strong>al gleam<strong>in</strong>g, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g on the brightness <strong>of</strong> Even<strong>in</strong>gstar. Night, robed <strong>in</strong> black, was<br />

234


To conclude the discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Herodotus, two po<strong>in</strong>ts assur<strong>in</strong>g that the context the<br />

author had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when describ<strong>in</strong>g these zw|~a was that <strong>of</strong> the visual arts are that resist-<br />

dye<strong>in</strong>g is overall a method <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> that weav<strong>in</strong>g was considered part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ancient system <strong>of</strong> the arts. 388 This context, which is <strong>in</strong> good accord with that <strong>of</strong><br />

Empedocles’ grapta& zw|~a, suggests that Herodotus’ zw|~a need not be “animals,” but<br />

could rather be a technical term directly borrowed from the fifth-century vocabulary <strong>of</strong><br />

the visual arts.<br />

b. Egyptians: <strong>The</strong> First to Carve Zw|~a on Stones<br />

<strong>The</strong> next three occurrences <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as applied to the arts are all <strong>in</strong> the second<br />

book <strong>of</strong> the Histories, which is a detailed account <strong>of</strong> Egypt its geography, topography,<br />

flora, fauna, <strong>and</strong> customs. All these occurrences po<strong>in</strong>t to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as a<br />

carved image <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, most likely, <strong>in</strong> relief. <strong>The</strong> first <strong>of</strong> them is <strong>in</strong> direct<br />

connection with the antiquity <strong>of</strong> the nomenclature <strong>of</strong> the Egyptian gods <strong>and</strong> their<br />

worship:<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g her chariot, drawn by a pair with no trace horses, sw<strong>in</strong>g forward, <strong>and</strong> the stars were accompany<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the goddess. <strong>The</strong> Pleiades were pass<strong>in</strong>g through mid heaven <strong>and</strong> so was Orion with his sword, while above<br />

them the Bear turned its golden tail about the Pole. <strong>The</strong> circle <strong>of</strong> the full moon, as at mid month, darted her<br />

beams, <strong>and</strong> there were the Hyades, clearest sign for sailors, <strong>and</strong> Dawn the Daybr<strong>in</strong>ger putt<strong>in</strong>g the stars to<br />

flight. On the walls <strong>of</strong> the tent he spread as a cover<strong>in</strong>g other tapestries, barbarian work: there were f<strong>in</strong>ely<br />

oared ships fac<strong>in</strong>g ships <strong>of</strong> the Greeks, half-beast men, horsemen chas<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>in</strong>ds, <strong>and</strong> the hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> wild<br />

lions. Near the entrance he put Cecrops, w<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g himself <strong>in</strong> coils, st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g next to his daughters, a work<br />

dedicated by an Athenian; translation: D. Kovacs, ed., tr., Euripides IV. Trojan Women. Iphigenia among<br />

the Taurians. Ion (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1999) 455-457. For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> decorated<br />

textiles, both foreign <strong>and</strong> domestic, <strong>and</strong> their position <strong>in</strong> fifth-century Athenian society <strong>and</strong> economy, see<br />

M. Vickers, Images on Textiles 15-28, 37-38.<br />

388 Plato (Resp. 3.400d) <strong>in</strong>cludes weav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> the arts. For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

differences between ancient <strong>and</strong> modern notions <strong>of</strong> Art, see P. O. Kristeller, “<strong>The</strong> Modern System <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Arts: A Study <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Aesthetics Part I,” Journal <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas 12, 4 (Oct., 1951) 498,<br />

who eloquently summarizes this po<strong>in</strong>t when he observes that: “the Greek term for Art (τέχνη) <strong>and</strong> its Lat<strong>in</strong><br />

equivalent (ars) do not specifically denote the ‘f<strong>in</strong>e arts’ <strong>in</strong> the modern sense, but were applied to all k<strong>in</strong>ds<br />

<strong>of</strong> human activities which we would call crafts or sciences.”<br />

235


<strong>The</strong>se authorities also say that the Egyptians were the first to use the names <strong>of</strong> the<br />

twelve gods, <strong>and</strong> that the Greeks took these from them, <strong>and</strong> that the Egyptians<br />

were the first to assign altars <strong>and</strong> a)ga&lmata <strong>and</strong> temples to the gods <strong>and</strong> to carve<br />

(e0gglu&yai) zw|~a on stones (e0n li/qoisi). (2.4) [100]<br />

To judge from the zw|~a that are mentioned, Herodotus applies the word to images <strong>of</strong><br />

some k<strong>in</strong>d, which he counts among the st<strong>and</strong>ard equipment for an Egyptian religious<br />

sett<strong>in</strong>g. As was the case previously, the word aga<strong>in</strong> appears <strong>in</strong> the plural <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with religion, whereas the absence <strong>of</strong> any description <strong>of</strong> how these zw|~a<br />

looked aga<strong>in</strong> highlights that it was a term <strong>of</strong> general description. <strong>The</strong> reference to<br />

Egyptians’ be<strong>in</strong>g the first people to <strong>in</strong>clude zw|~a among their <strong>in</strong>stallations for worship<br />

gives the impression that Herodotus considered zw|~a elements <strong>of</strong> the long-ago practice <strong>of</strong><br />

an activity that was current <strong>and</strong> familiar. 389 Further, that he associates these zw|~a with<br />

the arts is evident from his mention <strong>of</strong> them along with a)ga&lmata, which br<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d the fragment <strong>of</strong> Empedocles. As noted above, this fragment placed<br />

both these k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> artistic images well <strong>in</strong>to a religious context <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> direct association<br />

with the Greek idea <strong>of</strong> the past.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the use <strong>of</strong> the term a1galma <strong>in</strong> the Histories, John Powell states that it<br />

occurs sixty six times. 390 As for its mean<strong>in</strong>g, A. A. Donohue says that it is Herodotus’<br />

usual word for “statue” <strong>and</strong> that he uses it for images <strong>of</strong> both men <strong>and</strong> gods. 391 <strong>The</strong><br />

general reference <strong>of</strong> the passage to a)ga&lmata does not allow specific identification with<br />

either <strong>of</strong> these two types <strong>of</strong> images; therefore, the term can be only broadly def<strong>in</strong>ed as<br />

“statues.”<br />

389 For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the importance <strong>of</strong> “firsts” <strong>in</strong> Herodotus, <strong>and</strong> further bibliography on the subject,<br />

see J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Greek Historians (Oxford, 2001) 30, n. 52. For the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek image <strong>of</strong> Egypt as the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> ancient wisdom <strong>and</strong> Greek practice <strong>and</strong> ideals, see Harrison, “Upside Down <strong>and</strong> Back to Front,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> Matthews <strong>and</strong> Roemer, eds., Ancient Perspectives on Egypt (London, 2003) 145-155.<br />

390 J. E. Powell, A Lexicon to Herodotus (Hildesheim, 1966) 1, s.v. a1galma.<br />

391 Donohue, Xoana 26-27, n. 64.<br />

236


Turn<strong>in</strong>g to zw|~a, one sees that Herodotus is more generous with their description.<br />

<strong>The</strong> phrase “e0n li/qoisi e0gglu&yai,” which accompanies zw|~a, is crucial for ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g an<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term, which once aga<strong>in</strong> appears <strong>in</strong> the plural <strong>and</strong><br />

severed from any description <strong>of</strong> appearance. 0En li/qoisi (“<strong>in</strong> stones”) def<strong>in</strong>es the<br />

material <strong>of</strong> zw|~a as stone <strong>and</strong> therefore po<strong>in</strong>ts to sculpture. To the same direction po<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

also the term e0gglu&yai, which derives from e0gglu&fw. <strong>The</strong> latter is a compound word<br />

formed by the preposition e0n [“<strong>in</strong>”] <strong>and</strong> the verb glu&fw, which means “to carve” <strong>and</strong> “to<br />

engrave.” 392 Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott <strong>and</strong> also Powell translate e0gglu&fw as “to carve.” 393 As<br />

such, e0gglu&yai def<strong>in</strong>es zw|~a, which are its direct object, as carved images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d;<br />

<strong>in</strong> this way the connection <strong>of</strong> the term with sculpture is once aga<strong>in</strong> verified. When<br />

juxtaposed to the previous connection <strong>of</strong> zw|~a with be<strong>in</strong>g pa<strong>in</strong>ted on <strong>and</strong> woven <strong>in</strong>to<br />

clothes, the etymological evidence suggests that it was a term bound to neither a specific<br />

process nor a material <strong>of</strong> manufacture.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dependence <strong>of</strong> e0gglu&yai on glu&fw is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the relationship<br />

between gra&fw <strong>and</strong> e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>, the term that, as seen earlier, Herodotus used <strong>in</strong> direct<br />

connection with zw|~a <strong>and</strong> that suggests their be<strong>in</strong>g pa<strong>in</strong>ted, perhaps resist-dyed, on<br />

clothes. Although the compound verbs e0gglu&yai <strong>and</strong> e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong> connote oppos<strong>in</strong>g<br />

processes (i.e., carv<strong>in</strong>g, pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g), the use <strong>of</strong> the same preposition (i.e., e0n, “<strong>in</strong>,” “at”) <strong>in</strong><br />

conjunction with each one <strong>of</strong> them is strik<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> observation that all ancient Greek<br />

prepositions were orig<strong>in</strong>ally adverbs, <strong>and</strong> Herodotus was among those writers who still<br />

regarded them as such, is crucial here; 394 for it suggests that the author <strong>in</strong>corporated the<br />

392 LSJ 9 , 353, s.v. glu&fw.<br />

393 LSJ 9 , 467, s.v. e0gglu&fw; Powell, Lexicon 96, s.v. e0gglu&fw.<br />

394 A. Kaegi, tr. J. A. Kleist, Kaegi’s Greek Grammar (twenty-first edition; Wauconda, Ill<strong>in</strong>ois, 1995) 123.<br />

237


preposition e0n, whose mean<strong>in</strong>g shows a preoccupation with location, <strong>in</strong>to words <strong>in</strong>tended<br />

to convey both where <strong>and</strong> how zw|~a were produced. <strong>The</strong>refore, <strong>in</strong> a similar way that<br />

zw|~a were images pa<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong>to the surface <strong>of</strong> clothes, they were also images carved <strong>in</strong>to<br />

the surface <strong>of</strong> stones. On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the use <strong>of</strong> e0gglu&yai <strong>in</strong> this passage<br />

may be seen as <strong>in</strong>dicative <strong>of</strong> relief sculpture. A proponent <strong>of</strong> this idea is Alan Lloyd,<br />

who states broadly that e0gglu&yai should be seen here as a clear <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> relief<br />

work. 395<br />

Additional evidence po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to the direction <strong>of</strong> relief sculpture may also derive<br />

from the prepositional phrase e0n li/qoisi. As seen above, the traditional English<br />

translation <strong>of</strong> this phrase is “on stone,” but as po<strong>in</strong>ted out, its literal mean<strong>in</strong>g is “<strong>in</strong><br />

stones.” <strong>The</strong> phrase acquires additional importance <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the observation that “as<br />

adverbial locative particles, the prepositions are frequently jo<strong>in</strong>ed to the oblique cases<br />

[i.e., genitive, dative, accusative] <strong>in</strong> order to br<strong>in</strong>g out more clearly, <strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong>e more<br />

pla<strong>in</strong>ly, their local mean<strong>in</strong>g.” 396 In view <strong>of</strong> this evidence, Herodotus’ e0n li/qoisi, the<br />

latter word be<strong>in</strong>g the dative plural <strong>of</strong> li/qoj (“stone”), suggests that zw|~a were images <strong>of</strong><br />

some k<strong>in</strong>d literally carved <strong>in</strong> stones, therefore not parted from them, as if not separated<br />

from the matrix; <strong>in</strong> concrete terms, that zw|~a were images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d carved <strong>in</strong> relief.<br />

This l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g ga<strong>in</strong>s additional value when seen that Herodotus actually<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guishes zw|~a from, <strong>and</strong> therefore, contrasts them with a)ga&lmata. In view <strong>of</strong> this<br />

contrast, a)ga&lmata, which were seen to <strong>in</strong>dicate statues <strong>in</strong> general, may now be seen to<br />

st<strong>and</strong> for freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g statuary <strong>in</strong> specific.<br />

395 A. B. Lloyd, Herodotus Book II. Commentary 1-98 II (Leiden, 1976) 32-33.<br />

396 Kaegi, Kaegi’s Greek Grammar 123.<br />

238


With regard to the modern def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> zw|~a <strong>in</strong> this passage, the majority <strong>of</strong><br />

translations says “figures.” Grene <strong>and</strong> Waterfield embrace this mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> so do<br />

Godley, Macaulay, <strong>and</strong> also De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola. 397 Similarly, the<br />

commentaries <strong>of</strong> Lloyd, Blakesley, <strong>and</strong> Walter How <strong>and</strong> Joseph Wells accept the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a as “figures.” 398 <strong>The</strong> last two authors, <strong>in</strong> particular, clarify that the word<br />

does not refer to “hieroglyphs (which the Greeks did not borrow) but [to] ‘figures’ <strong>of</strong><br />

animals, men, [<strong>and</strong>] plants.” 399 It should be kept <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, however, that large-scale<br />

hieroglyphs can function as images. As Jeffrey Hurwit po<strong>in</strong>ts out, “the word that means<br />

‘hieroglyph’ or ‘sign’ can also mean ‘representation.’” 400 Also Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott <strong>in</strong>clude<br />

this passage <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> their entry zw|~on, which they def<strong>in</strong>e as “figure” <strong>and</strong><br />

“image.” 401 Despite their disagreement on the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a, these translations<br />

provide the first <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as someth<strong>in</strong>g other than<br />

“animals.” It is important to remember that what enables this scholarly consensus is its<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> the context <strong>in</strong> which zw|~a occurs <strong>and</strong>, more specifically, the direct<br />

connection <strong>of</strong> this context with the visual arts.<br />

c. Zw|~a on Khufu’s Causeway<br />

<strong>The</strong> second occurrence <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> the second book <strong>of</strong> the Histories is <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with architecture. This time zw|~a, which refer aga<strong>in</strong> to carved images <strong>in</strong><br />

397<br />

Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 132; Godley, Herodotus 279; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories.<br />

Herodotus 80; De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 97.<br />

398<br />

Lloyd, Herodotus Book II II 32; Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 170, n. 17; W. W. How <strong>and</strong><br />

J. Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus I (Oxford,1912; repr. 1957) 159.<br />

399<br />

How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus 159, do not expla<strong>in</strong> what type <strong>of</strong> source led them to this<br />

suggestion. Similar obscurity characterizes also their reference to Egyptian scarabs as objects on which<br />

such “figures” were to be found.<br />

400<br />

J. M. Hurwit, “<strong>The</strong> Words <strong>in</strong> the Image: Orality, Literacy, <strong>and</strong> Early Greek Art,” Word <strong>and</strong> Image 6<br />

(1990) 180.<br />

401 9<br />

LSJ , 760, s.v. zw|~on.<br />

239


elief, are mentioned <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the logistics <strong>of</strong> the construction <strong>of</strong> the pyramid<br />

complex <strong>of</strong> Cheops (Khufu; reign c. 2596-2573 B.C.). Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> the<br />

materials, techniques, <strong>and</strong> labor force employed for the construction <strong>of</strong> the causeway <strong>of</strong><br />

this k<strong>in</strong>g’s pyramid complex runs as follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

<strong>The</strong> people worked <strong>in</strong> gangs <strong>of</strong> one hundred thous<strong>and</strong> for each period <strong>of</strong> three<br />

months. <strong>The</strong> people were afflicted for ten years <strong>of</strong> time <strong>in</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g the road along<br />

which they dragged the stones—<strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion a work as great as the pyramid<br />

itself. For the length <strong>of</strong> the road is more than half a mile, <strong>and</strong> its breadth is sixty<br />

feet, <strong>and</strong> its height, at its highest, is forty-eight feet. It is made <strong>of</strong> polished stone<br />

(li/qou te cestou~), <strong>and</strong> there are zw|&wn carved (e0ggeglumme/nwn) on it.<br />

(2.124) [101]<br />

Zw|&wn is the genitive plural form <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. As with all previous examples, Herodotus<br />

does not comment on how these zw|&wn looked. <strong>The</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> specificity <strong>and</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plural aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicate that it was a term <strong>of</strong> general description for images. <strong>The</strong> word<br />

e0ggeglumme/nwn, which def<strong>in</strong>es zw|&wn, derives from the verb e0gglu&fw, which, as was<br />

shown previously, refers to carved material, most likely <strong>in</strong> relief, <strong>and</strong> therefore po<strong>in</strong>ts to<br />

sculpture. To the same process po<strong>in</strong>ts also the reference to zw|~a as be<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>of</strong> stone<br />

(li/qou). In addition, the fact that this stone was polished (cestou~) suggests f<strong>in</strong>e quality,<br />

but more precisely, “f<strong>in</strong>e work <strong>in</strong>tricate <strong>of</strong> process <strong>and</strong> accomplished <strong>of</strong><br />

workmanship.” 402 <strong>The</strong>se aspects <strong>of</strong> zw|~a establish that the context which Herodotus had<br />

<strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d while describ<strong>in</strong>g them was directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the arts. Given that the<br />

causeway to which these zw|~a belonged was part <strong>of</strong> a pyramid complex associated with<br />

the funerary cult <strong>of</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>g, then the term should be seen <strong>in</strong> direct association with an<br />

artistic context set with<strong>in</strong> a funerary/religious one.<br />

402 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the verb ce/w from which cestou~ derives, as carry<strong>in</strong>g these<br />

associations, see Donohue, Xoana 28, n. 66.<br />

240


Regard<strong>in</strong>g modern translations <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn, the majority agrees on the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

“figures,” except for two that <strong>in</strong>terpret zw|&wn as “animals.” 403 To judge from previous<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> zw|~a <strong>in</strong> an artistic context, these zw|&wn can be only generally understood as<br />

images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, but the passage provides no additional clue <strong>in</strong> support <strong>of</strong> a more<br />

precise identification <strong>of</strong> “figures” or “animals.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that Herodotus mentions the polished stone <strong>of</strong> carved zw|&wn as the<br />

material <strong>of</strong> the causeway, immediately after he discusses its dimensions, strongly<br />

suggests that his description centers on the architecture <strong>of</strong> the structure. It is thus<br />

probably safe to assume that, when he speaks <strong>of</strong> li/qou te cestou~ kai zw|&wn<br />

e0ggeglumme/nwn, he means ref<strong>in</strong>ed carved images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, most likely <strong>in</strong> relief<br />

sculpture, that adorned the walls <strong>of</strong> the causeway, rather than freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g sculpture.<br />

What cannot be clarified is whether these were the <strong>in</strong>ternal or external walls <strong>of</strong> the<br />

structure. Additional evidence aga<strong>in</strong>st freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g sculpture is also suggested by the fact<br />

that if Herodotus had this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> sculpture <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, then, given his usual, <strong>and</strong> already<br />

noted, references to statues as a)ga&lmata, it is reasonable to assume that he would have<br />

used this term here <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn. In apparent support <strong>of</strong> this po<strong>in</strong>t, although it can be<br />

mere co<strong>in</strong>cidence, is the picture that emerges from the archaeological record: almost no<br />

statues were found <strong>in</strong> the cult complex <strong>of</strong> Khufu at Giza. 404 <strong>The</strong> picture is no different<br />

403 “Figures”: Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 185; Godley, Herodotus 427; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong><br />

Histories. Herodotus 120; Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 145. “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>”: H. Goedicke, Re-Used<br />

Blocks from the Pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhet I at Lisht (<strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art Egyptian Expedition,<br />

no. 20; New York, 1971) 8, n. 2; De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 124.<br />

404 Z. Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs <strong>of</strong> the Royal Funerary Complexes <strong>of</strong> the Fourth Dynasty,” <strong>in</strong> D. O’Connor<br />

<strong>and</strong> D. P. Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship (Leiden <strong>and</strong> New York, 1995) 236, states that “no<br />

statuary program can be established for Khufu because no statues have yet been found at Giza, except for<br />

the alabaster bases found <strong>in</strong>scribed with the k<strong>in</strong>g’s name.” Such evidence should not be taken to mean that<br />

all causeways <strong>of</strong> Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom pyramid complexes were devoid <strong>of</strong> freest<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g statues. As D. Arnold,<br />

“Royal Cult Complexes <strong>of</strong> the Old <strong>and</strong> Middle K<strong>in</strong>gdoms,” <strong>in</strong> B. E. Shafer, ed., Temples <strong>of</strong> Ancient Egypt<br />

(Ithaca, 1997) 73, n. 128, suggests, the walls <strong>of</strong> causeways <strong>of</strong> pyramid complexes <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> sixth<br />

241


when it comes to the architecture <strong>and</strong> architectural decoration <strong>of</strong> the causeway, which are<br />

central aspects <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> this structure.<br />

Herodotus’ o(do&j has been identified with the causeway that connected the lower<br />

or valley temple to the upper or mortuary temple <strong>of</strong> the pyramid complex <strong>of</strong> Khufu at<br />

Giza (Fig. 22). 405 <strong>The</strong> structure has never been exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> detail, but archaeological<br />

<strong>in</strong>vestigations <strong>of</strong> two different phases (1968 <strong>and</strong> 1990) have traced its course <strong>and</strong> located<br />

a small section <strong>of</strong> its architecture. 406 Start<strong>in</strong>g from the recently discovered valley temple,<br />

the causeway follows a westward course, which (after approximately 125 to 150<br />

meters) 407 turns 32 degrees southwest <strong>and</strong> from thereon cont<strong>in</strong>ues to the mortuary<br />

temple. 408 In scholarly accounts, the overall length <strong>of</strong> this structure oscillates between<br />

658.60 <strong>and</strong> 825 meters. 409 <strong>The</strong>se numbers do not fit Herodotus’ observation that the<br />

dynasties were most likely l<strong>in</strong>ed with limestone statues (about 84 cm high) that depicted kneel<strong>in</strong>g African,<br />

Libyan, Asiatic, <strong>and</strong> perhaps Puntite prisoners <strong>of</strong> war “with their arms drawn back <strong>and</strong> lashed at the<br />

elbows.” For a discussion <strong>of</strong> two <strong>of</strong> these statues dat<strong>in</strong>g from the reign <strong>of</strong> Pepi II (sixth dynasty), <strong>and</strong> their<br />

secondary archaeological context, which obscures their orig<strong>in</strong>al location, see M. Hill, “Kneel<strong>in</strong>g Captive,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> J. P. Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan<br />

Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, September 16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum, Toronto,<br />

February 13-May 22, 2000; New York, 1999) 440-441, nos. 173-174.<br />

405<br />

Lloyd, Herodotus. Book II 64; M. Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids (London, 1997) 109; G. Goyon, “La<br />

chausée monumentale et le temple de la vallée de la pyramide de Khéops,” BIFAO 67 (1969) 49; M. Haase,<br />

E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für die Ewigkeit. Der Pramidenkomplex des Cheops aus baulicher, architektonischer und<br />

kulturhistorischer Sicht (Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 2004) 57, n. 176. Regard<strong>in</strong>g Herodotus’ reference to this road as<br />

one along which stones were dragged, Lloyd, 124, argues that Herodotus had probably confused it with a<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g ramp; otherwise, he states, the risk <strong>of</strong> damag<strong>in</strong>g the stone work <strong>of</strong> the causeway would have been<br />

far too great; also A. B. Lloyd, “Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs: A Test Case,” <strong>in</strong> A. Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Greek World (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1995) 276, n. 5.<br />

406<br />

Goyon, “La chausée” 49-69; Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’ Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient<br />

Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 221-262.<br />

407<br />

Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 226, says 125<br />

meters; Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für die Ewigkeit 57, says 150 meters, <strong>and</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts out, 57, n. 177, the discrepancy<br />

between the 125 meters recorded by Hawass <strong>and</strong> 150 meters, also recorded by Z. Hawass, “Recent<br />

Discoveries at Giza Plateau,” <strong>in</strong> S. Curto et al., eds., Atti Sesto Congresso Internazionale di Egittologia I.<br />

Settembre 1-8, Tor<strong>in</strong>o (Tur<strong>in</strong>, 1992) 242.<br />

408<br />

Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für die Ewigkeit 57.<br />

409<br />

This discrepancy <strong>in</strong> the measured length <strong>of</strong> the causeway may be the result <strong>of</strong> the fact that the <strong>in</strong>itial<br />

excavations <strong>of</strong> 1968 exam<strong>in</strong>ed only the upper part <strong>of</strong> the structure, that is, close to the mortuary temple.<br />

Thus, Goyon, “La chausée,” 63, who was the first excavator, <strong>and</strong> also Lloyd, Herodotus Book II 65, who<br />

cites him, record the known length <strong>of</strong> the causeway to be 658.60 meters. <strong>The</strong> 1990 excavations, however,<br />

focused on the lower rema<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> the causeway <strong>and</strong> its connection to Khufu’s valley temple, which was<br />

242


length <strong>of</strong> the causeway was 5 sta&dioi, that is, somewhere between 891 <strong>and</strong> 1065<br />

meters. 410 <strong>The</strong> only measurement that f<strong>in</strong>ds Herodotus <strong>and</strong> modern excavations <strong>in</strong><br />

agreement is the width <strong>of</strong> the causeway, whose actual figure <strong>of</strong> 18.50 meters is not far<br />

away from Herodotus’ ten o)rguiai/, which lie between 17.80 <strong>and</strong> 21.30 meters. 411 As for<br />

the height <strong>of</strong> the structure, Herodotus’ allegation that its highest po<strong>in</strong>t was eight o)rguiai/<br />

has been translated to mean forty-eight feet (c. 14.5 meters), 412 but as Lloyd remarks, the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> material evidence makes this measurement impossible to establish. 413 <strong>The</strong><br />

foundations <strong>of</strong> the structure have been estimated to have reached more than 40 meters<br />

(131 feet) <strong>in</strong> height, 414 <strong>and</strong> it has been thought to have been ro<strong>of</strong>ed. 415 <strong>The</strong> architectural<br />

evidence that has been excavated so far amounts only to “a fragment <strong>of</strong> the south wall <strong>of</strong><br />

also located dur<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>vestigation. <strong>The</strong> literature follow<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>vestigation, however, records no<br />

consistent measurement <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the causeway. Thus, Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,”<strong>in</strong> O’Connor <strong>and</strong><br />

Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 226, states that the overall length <strong>of</strong> the causeway was<br />

approximately 825 meters; Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 109, says 739.8 meters; Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für<br />

die Ewigkeit 58, estimates that the overall length <strong>of</strong> the causeway was approximately 700 meters, but does<br />

caution that there is no fixed measurement <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>in</strong> the exist<strong>in</strong>g literature.<br />

410 Lloyd, Herodotus. Book II 65, equates Herodotus’ measurement to 925 meters, but the same author,<br />

“Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs,” <strong>in</strong> Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek World 278, says that this measurement<br />

should be somewhere between 891 <strong>and</strong> 1065 meters.<br />

411 For the width <strong>of</strong> the causeway be<strong>in</strong>g 18.50 meters, see Goyon, “Le chausée” 58, <strong>and</strong> also Lloyd,<br />

Herodotus. Book II 65. For the suggestion that this width was 18.35 meters, <strong>and</strong> the further attempt to<br />

decipher Herodotus’ figure, see Lloyd, “Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs,” <strong>in</strong> Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek<br />

World 278.<br />

412 Forty eight feet: De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 146; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 120; eight fathoms: Godley, Herodotus 427; Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong><br />

Histories 145.<br />

413 Lloyd, Herodotus Book II 65.<br />

414 Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 109; also Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für die Ewigkeit, 58, fig. 59a, clarifies that<br />

the difference <strong>in</strong> height <strong>of</strong> the causeway, between the valley <strong>and</strong> mortuary temples, was approximately 40<br />

meters.<br />

415 Z. Hawass <strong>and</strong> M. Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure (Archaeological<br />

Report),” MDAIK 52 (1996) 17; also Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient<br />

Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 226; <strong>and</strong> Z. Hawass, Mounta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Pharaohs. <strong>The</strong> Untold Story <strong>of</strong> the Pyramid<br />

Builders (New York, 2006) 70, where he states that “enough <strong>of</strong> this causeway rema<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the fifth century<br />

B.C. for Herodotus to be able to describe it as a huge ro<strong>of</strong>ed structure decorated with birds <strong>and</strong> stars.” Also<br />

<strong>in</strong> discuss<strong>in</strong>g the causeways <strong>of</strong> Old <strong>and</strong> Middle K<strong>in</strong>gdom pyramid complexes, D. Arnold, “Royal Cult<br />

Complexes <strong>of</strong> the Old <strong>and</strong> Middle K<strong>in</strong>gdoms,” <strong>in</strong> Shafer, ed., Temples <strong>of</strong> Ancient Egypt 54-55, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that as a structure, the causeway was a narrow, ro<strong>of</strong>ed, thus dark <strong>in</strong>side, space; f<strong>in</strong>ally, Lloyd, Herodotus.<br />

Book II 65, rightly po<strong>in</strong>ts out, that it is not clear whether the causeway <strong>of</strong> Khufu “was ro<strong>of</strong>ed like the<br />

causeways <strong>of</strong> Chephren <strong>and</strong> Unas or unro<strong>of</strong>ed like that <strong>of</strong> Sn<strong>of</strong>ru.”<br />

243


the massive limestone revetment constructed to support the causeway east <strong>of</strong> the desert<br />

edge.” 416 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Zahi Hawass, this discovery has afforded the opportunity to draw<br />

<strong>and</strong> photograph a clear view <strong>of</strong> the south side <strong>of</strong> the embankment, although a<br />

considerable part <strong>of</strong> the north side is also exposed. 417<br />

<strong>The</strong> extant evidence relat<strong>in</strong>g to the decoration <strong>of</strong> the causeway is scanty <strong>in</strong><br />

quantity <strong>and</strong> problematic <strong>in</strong> character. Attention should first be drawn to the fact that<br />

Herodotus’ reference to zw|&wn e0ggeglumme/nwn <strong>and</strong> the extant relief sculpture that has<br />

been ascribed to the valley <strong>and</strong> mortuary temples <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s pyramid complex have been<br />

used circularly to expla<strong>in</strong> each other. This treatment has, consequently, given rise to the<br />

suggestion that the <strong>in</strong>ner walls <strong>of</strong> the causeway, which functioned as the corridor l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the two temples was also decorated with relief sculpture. 418 <strong>The</strong> outer walls <strong>of</strong> the<br />

causeway do not feature <strong>in</strong> scholarship as a possible space for relief decoration, on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> archaeological evidence, albeit not extensive, that the outer walls <strong>of</strong> Old<br />

K<strong>in</strong>gdom causeways carried m<strong>in</strong>imum decoration, <strong>in</strong> general. 419<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the architectural decoration <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway consists<br />

<strong>of</strong> two examples <strong>of</strong> sculpture <strong>in</strong> relief. <strong>The</strong> first is a fragment show<strong>in</strong>g Khufu’s cartouche<br />

rest<strong>in</strong>g on a board, <strong>and</strong> the head <strong>of</strong> a female personification <strong>of</strong> a royal estate (Fig. 23).<br />

416 Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’ Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 226.<br />

417 Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’ Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 226.<br />

418 None <strong>of</strong> the carved reliefs ascribed to the valley <strong>and</strong> mortuary temples <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s pyramid complex has<br />

been found <strong>in</strong> situ. <strong>The</strong>y belong to fragments <strong>of</strong> stone blocks <strong>in</strong>scribed with the name <strong>of</strong> Cheops, <strong>and</strong> were<br />

found to be reused as build<strong>in</strong>g material <strong>in</strong> the pyramid <strong>of</strong> the twelfth-dynasty k<strong>in</strong>g Amenmehet I at Lisht.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fragments assigned to the valley temple <strong>of</strong> Khufu at Giza are executed <strong>in</strong> low relief <strong>and</strong> depict a<br />

Libyan prisoner, the titulary <strong>of</strong> Khufu, personifications <strong>of</strong> royal estates br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs to the k<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong><br />

also scenes from the palace. For a discussion <strong>and</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> these fragments, see Goedicke, “Re-used<br />

Blocks,” 11-22. <strong>The</strong> fragments identified as belong<strong>in</strong>g to the mortuary temple <strong>of</strong> Khufu are also <strong>in</strong> low<br />

relief <strong>and</strong> depict ritual aspects <strong>of</strong> the Sed festival <strong>in</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> various deities (e.g., Meret), the k<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

religious personnel, <strong>and</strong> also royal <strong>of</strong>ficials. For a discussion <strong>and</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> these fragments, see also<br />

Goedicke, “Re-used Blocks” 29-47.<br />

419 Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 179, mention, for<br />

example, that the external decoration <strong>of</strong> the causeway <strong>of</strong> the fifth-dynasty k<strong>in</strong>g Nyeserre refers to its side<br />

walls, which were battered, <strong>and</strong> their upper ends, which were decorated only with a cornice.<br />

244


<strong>The</strong> fragment was <strong>in</strong>itially assigned to his valley temple, but it has recently been<br />

discussed as perhaps belong<strong>in</strong>g to the upper part <strong>of</strong> the causeway lead<strong>in</strong>g to the temple. 420<br />

This suggestion has been made on the basis <strong>of</strong> preserved relief decoration from the<br />

causeways <strong>of</strong> two other Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom rulers’ funerary complexes, those <strong>of</strong> fifth-dynasty<br />

Unis <strong>and</strong> sixth-dynasty Pepi II, both at Saqqara. In both cases, the upper parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

causeways preserve representations <strong>of</strong> personifications <strong>of</strong> estates <strong>in</strong> relief sculpture. 421<br />

In addition to this problematic fragment, the decoration <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway has<br />

also been l<strong>in</strong>ked to a number <strong>of</strong> equally problematic relief fragments that were allegedly<br />

discovered <strong>in</strong> debris associated with the structure. 422 <strong>The</strong>se seventeen fragments,<br />

reported to be extremely small poorly preserve parts <strong>of</strong> two human faces, an ox, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

bird. <strong>The</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g depictions defy identification. 423 As such, these fragments contribute<br />

little to our knowledge <strong>of</strong> the decoration <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway. 424<br />

Despite the paucity <strong>of</strong> material evidence, the reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the relief<br />

decoration <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ner walls <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway has been attempted on the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

surviv<strong>in</strong>g reliefs <strong>of</strong> the lower temples <strong>and</strong> causeways <strong>of</strong> three other Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom<br />

420<br />

For a brief, still <strong>in</strong>formative, survey <strong>of</strong> material evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the decorative programs, function,<br />

<strong>and</strong> overall mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> causeways <strong>of</strong> the Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom, see Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered<br />

Blocks <strong>of</strong> the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 177-180; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> the relief fragment, as part <strong>of</strong> the wall<br />

decoration <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s valley temple, see Goedicke, “Re-used Blocks” 16-17; for the possibility that this<br />

block may belong to the causeway, see D. Arnold, “Head <strong>of</strong> a Female Personification <strong>of</strong> an Estate,” <strong>in</strong> J. P.<br />

Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong><br />

Art, New York, September 16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum, Toronto, February<br />

13-May 22, 2000; New York, 1999) 226-227.<br />

421<br />

Arnold, “Head <strong>of</strong> a Female Personification <strong>of</strong> an Estate,” <strong>in</strong> Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Pyramids 227, n. 7.<br />

422<br />

G. A. Reisner <strong>and</strong> W. S. Smith, A History <strong>of</strong> the Giza Necropolis II (Cambridge, Mass., 1955) 4.<br />

423<br />

Reisner <strong>and</strong> Smith, A History <strong>of</strong> the Giza Necropolis 4, refer to them as t<strong>in</strong>y; also their figure 7, which<br />

illustrates these fragments, provides only their <strong>in</strong>ventory numbers, but no dimensions, <strong>and</strong> reduces their<br />

number to seventeen.<br />

424<br />

Re<strong>in</strong>ser <strong>and</strong> Smith, A History <strong>of</strong> the Giza Necropolis 4; also Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered<br />

Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 178.<br />

245


pharaohs: Sneferu at Dahshur, Sahure at Abusir, <strong>and</strong> Pepi II at Saqqara. 425 This scholarly<br />

approach reflects the op<strong>in</strong>ion that Egyptian artists <strong>of</strong> Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom royal reliefs “repeated<br />

a rather circumscribed set <strong>of</strong> iconographic configurations from temple to temple <strong>and</strong> from<br />

wall to wall.” 426 In the case <strong>of</strong> the reliefs <strong>in</strong> the valley temple <strong>of</strong> Sahure, for example,<br />

scenes on the north wall depict large griff<strong>in</strong>s trampl<strong>in</strong>g on enemies while deities lead<br />

bound prisoners toward them. <strong>The</strong> theme <strong>of</strong> prisoners is also repeated on the walls <strong>of</strong> the<br />

causeway just beh<strong>in</strong>d the valley temple, “emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g movement from valley temple to<br />

causeway <strong>and</strong> farther on to the pyramid temple.” 427 Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

decoration <strong>of</strong> Sahure’s causeway derives from four recently discovered blocks <strong>of</strong> low<br />

reliefs (2m <strong>in</strong> length; 2m <strong>in</strong> height), which depict, <strong>in</strong> registers, men bear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs, the<br />

slaughter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> animals, the br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the gilded capstone to the pyramid, <strong>and</strong> also men<br />

identified as Bedou<strong>in</strong>s. 428 <strong>The</strong> workmanship <strong>of</strong> these reliefs is reported to be so ref<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

that it recalls the use <strong>of</strong> the word cestou~ by Herodotus. 429 On the basis <strong>of</strong> these images,<br />

from the causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure, 430 <strong>and</strong> also supplementary evidence from Sneferu’s <strong>and</strong><br />

Pepi’s II causeways, Hawass has suggested that the lower end <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway<br />

would have depicted the k<strong>in</strong>g’s titles, representations <strong>of</strong> Libyan captives, <strong>and</strong> royal<br />

425 Hawass, “<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 230-231.<br />

426 Arnold, “Royal Reliefs,” <strong>in</strong> Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids 83.<br />

427 Arnold, “Royal Reliefs,” <strong>in</strong> Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids 94.<br />

428 Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure,” 181-184.<br />

429 Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 181: “the degree <strong>of</strong><br />

delicacy <strong>of</strong> the relief made the photographic record<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the blocks so difficult that it had to be done at<br />

night with artificial illum<strong>in</strong>ation.”<br />

430 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the variety <strong>of</strong> the subject matter <strong>of</strong> the new scenes from Sahure’s causeway, Hawass <strong>and</strong><br />

Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 185, say that it “surpasses the hithertoheld<br />

ideas about the monothematic decoration <strong>of</strong> the causeways <strong>of</strong> the Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom.” For a discussion<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g the narrative character <strong>of</strong> the reliefs from Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom cult spaces, see Arnold, “Royal<br />

Reliefs,” <strong>in</strong> Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids 84-87.<br />

246


estates, whereas the middle part would have been decorated with a scene <strong>of</strong> a procession<br />

<strong>of</strong> oxen, represent<strong>in</strong>g foreign <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs. 431<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the picture that emerges from this reconstruction, all that can be<br />

said about the extant decoration <strong>of</strong> Khufu’s causeway is that it comprises a h<strong>and</strong>ful <strong>of</strong><br />

relief fragments that depict human <strong>and</strong> animal figures, <strong>and</strong> also objects, such as the board<br />

on which the cartouche <strong>of</strong> Khufu stood. At most, these fragments attest that sculpture <strong>in</strong><br />

relief was used as wall decoration <strong>in</strong> the causeway <strong>of</strong> Khufu, which accords well with the<br />

architectural sculpture, most likely, <strong>in</strong> relief, that Herodotus’ description seems to<br />

suggest. As for the images on these fragments, they provide a glimpse <strong>in</strong>to what<br />

Herodotus’ literary zw|&wn might have meant.<br />

d. Zw|~a on a Pyramid<br />

<strong>The</strong> last occurrence <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the second book <strong>of</strong> the Histories is <strong>in</strong> connection<br />

with the decoration <strong>of</strong> an Egyptian pyramid. <strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term aga<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts to<br />

carved images <strong>in</strong> relief. Herodotus places the pyramid beside a marvelous structure<br />

which he refers to as the labyr<strong>in</strong>th. His account starts with a praise <strong>of</strong> the Egyptian<br />

people for build<strong>in</strong>g such structures <strong>and</strong> proceeds to a detailed description, first, <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labyr<strong>in</strong>th, <strong>and</strong> then <strong>of</strong> the pyramid:<br />

Furthermore, they resolved to leave a memorial <strong>of</strong> themselves <strong>in</strong> common, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

pursuance <strong>of</strong> resolve they made a labyr<strong>in</strong>th, a little above Lake Moeris, <strong>and</strong><br />

situated near what is called the City <strong>of</strong> Crocodiles. I saw it myself, <strong>and</strong> it is<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed a wonder past words; for if one were to collect together all the build<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong><br />

the Greeks <strong>and</strong> their most strik<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong> architecture, they would all clearly be<br />

shown to have cost less labor <strong>and</strong> money than this labyr<strong>in</strong>th. Yet the temple at<br />

Ephesus <strong>and</strong> that <strong>in</strong> Samos are surely remarkable. <strong>The</strong> pyramids, too, were<br />

greater than words could tell, <strong>and</strong> each <strong>of</strong> them is the equivalent <strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> the<br />

431 Hawass <strong>and</strong> Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure” 178, n. 12; also Hawass,<br />

“<strong>The</strong> Programs,” <strong>in</strong> O’Connor <strong>and</strong> Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship 231-232.<br />

247


great works <strong>of</strong> the Greeks; but the labyr<strong>in</strong>th surpasses the pyramids also. It has<br />

twelve ro<strong>of</strong>ed courts, with doors fac<strong>in</strong>g one another, six to the north <strong>and</strong> six to the<br />

south <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> a cont<strong>in</strong>uous l<strong>in</strong>e. One wall on the outside encompasses them all.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are double sets <strong>of</strong> chambers <strong>in</strong> it, some underground <strong>and</strong> some above, <strong>and</strong><br />

their number is three thous<strong>and</strong>; there are fifteen hundred <strong>of</strong> each. We ourselves<br />

saw the aboveground chambers, for we went through them <strong>and</strong> so we can talk <strong>of</strong><br />

them, but the underground chambers we can speak only from hearsay. For the<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials <strong>of</strong> the Egyptians entirely refused to show us these, say<strong>in</strong>g that there are<br />

<strong>in</strong> them the c<strong>of</strong>f<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>gs who had built the labyr<strong>in</strong>th at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

also those <strong>of</strong> the holy crocodiles. So we speak from hearsay <strong>of</strong> these underground<br />

places; but what we saw aboveground was certa<strong>in</strong>ly greater than all human works.<br />

<strong>The</strong> passages through the rooms <strong>and</strong> the w<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g go<strong>in</strong>gs-<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> out through the<br />

courts, <strong>in</strong> their extreme complication, caused us countless marvel<strong>in</strong>gs as we went<br />

through, from the court <strong>in</strong>to the rooms, <strong>and</strong> from the rooms <strong>in</strong>to the pillared<br />

corridors, <strong>and</strong> then from these corridors <strong>in</strong>to other rooms aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> from the<br />

rooms <strong>in</strong>to other courts afterwards. <strong>The</strong> ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the whole is stone, as the walls<br />

are, <strong>and</strong> the walls are full <strong>of</strong> tu&pwn e0ggeglumme/nwn, <strong>and</strong> each court is set round<br />

with pillars <strong>of</strong> white stone, very exactly fitted. At the corner where the labyr<strong>in</strong>th<br />

ends there is, nearby, a pyramid two hundred <strong>and</strong> forty feet high <strong>and</strong> e0n th|~ zw|~a<br />

mega&la e0gge/gluptai. <strong>The</strong> road to this is made underground. (2.148) [102]<br />

<strong>The</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g that Herodotus calls the labyr<strong>in</strong>th has been a topic <strong>of</strong> controversy<br />

among scholars. <strong>The</strong> controversy has arisen from the fact that no securely identified<br />

rema<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>in</strong> fact no rema<strong>in</strong>s exist at all that plausibly fit Herodotus’ description. Both the<br />

labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>and</strong> the pyramid mentioned <strong>in</strong> this passage have been considered elements <strong>of</strong><br />

the pyramid enclosure <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat III constructed <strong>in</strong> the twelfth dynasty (ca. 1842-<br />

1797) at Hawara <strong>in</strong> the central Fayum. <strong>The</strong> labyr<strong>in</strong>th has been equated with a structure,<br />

also called the mortuary temple, located to the south <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>and</strong> thought to be <strong>of</strong><br />

impressive dimensions. 432 What survives today <strong>of</strong> this structure is only a foundation bed<br />

432 Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 183; Lloyd, Herodotus. Book II 121-124 provides a summary <strong>of</strong> all<br />

classical authors, who refer to the labyr<strong>in</strong>th. His fig. 1 is a reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the structure based on<br />

Herodotus’ description supplemented by those <strong>of</strong> Strabo <strong>and</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Follow<strong>in</strong>g the 1890 excavation report<br />

<strong>and</strong> reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the structure by Fl<strong>in</strong>ders Petrie, he also suggests (122) that the labyr<strong>in</strong>th was an<br />

oblong build<strong>in</strong>g (304.5m long; 243.6m wide) “divided across the middle from W. to E. by a cross wall, to<br />

the south <strong>of</strong> which lay the aulai <strong>of</strong> Herodotus.” For a summary <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> the exploration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Hawara labyr<strong>in</strong>th, <strong>and</strong> the issue <strong>of</strong> identification, see E. P. Uphill, Pharaoh’s Gateway to Eternity: <strong>The</strong><br />

Hawara Labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>of</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g Amenemhat III (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2000) 1-9. For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

discrepancy between Herodotus’ chronology (seventh century B.C.) <strong>of</strong> the construction <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>and</strong><br />

248


<strong>of</strong> s<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> limestone chips. <strong>The</strong> poor preservation has been attributed to the heavy<br />

quarry<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the site s<strong>in</strong>ce Roman times. 433 <strong>The</strong> view that Herodotus’ labyr<strong>in</strong>th has been<br />

correctly identified, but is long vanished, has been challenged by the suggestion that the<br />

structure did not really exist at all, but was rather the fabulous product <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’<br />

tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> sixth-century Ionian logographic tradition. 434<br />

What appears to be germane to the current discussion is Herodotus’ assertion that<br />

the walls <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th were full (ple/oi) <strong>of</strong> tu&pwn e0ggeglumme/nwn. Although<br />

Herodotus does not specify whether these were the <strong>in</strong>ternal or external walls <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labyr<strong>in</strong>th, his comment automatically qualifies tu&pwn e0ggeglumme/nwn as mean<strong>in</strong>g wall<br />

decorations <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d. As noted earlier, the word e0ggeglumme/nwn refers to carv<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

most likely, <strong>in</strong> relief; here, too the word br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d the process <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture. Tu&pwn is the genitive plural <strong>of</strong> the neuter noun tu&poj, a highly controversial<br />

term, which is frequently cited as the ancient Greek equivalent <strong>of</strong> relief work, sometimes,<br />

but not exclusively, <strong>in</strong> architectural sett<strong>in</strong>gs. 435 Regard<strong>in</strong>g its usage <strong>in</strong> the Histories, it<br />

has been observed that “tu&poj occurs ten times, <strong>and</strong> seems to be restricted to relief<br />

works <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g reliefs carved from liv<strong>in</strong>g rock <strong>and</strong> mummy cases.” 436<br />

Given this evidence, Pollitt’s suggestion that the phrase tu&pwn e0ggeglumme/nwn ple/oi<br />

the actual date <strong>of</strong> the identified rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Amenmehat’s complex (1842-1797 B.C.), see Lloyd,<br />

“Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs,” <strong>in</strong> Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek World 289.<br />

433<br />

Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 183.<br />

434<br />

O. K. Armayor, Herodotus’ Autopsy <strong>of</strong> the Fayoum: Lake Moeris <strong>and</strong> the Labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>in</strong> Egypt<br />

(Amsterdam, 1985) 8-9, focuses on the circular, <strong>and</strong> accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, misguided method used <strong>in</strong> the<br />

archaeological discussion <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>in</strong> question.<br />

435<br />

For a number <strong>of</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> tu&poj as architectural reliefs <strong>in</strong> the text <strong>of</strong> Herodotus, see Pollitt, Ancient<br />

View 273, <strong>and</strong> 284-292 for a commentary on the dispute among scholars on the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word; also<br />

Donohue, Xoana 22, n. 52 <strong>and</strong> 26, n. 64.<br />

436<br />

Donohue, Xoana 26, n. 64; for the specific passages <strong>of</strong> Herodotus where the word occurs, see Powell,<br />

Lexicon 363, s.v. tu&poj.<br />

249


efers to architectural reliefs appears to be a sound one. 437 Accord<strong>in</strong>g with his suggestion<br />

is also a group <strong>of</strong> 74 fragmentary architectural reliefs deriv<strong>in</strong>g from the material<br />

excavated by Fl<strong>in</strong>ders Petrie at the alleged site <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>in</strong> Hawara, <strong>and</strong> housed<br />

now at the Rijksmuseum van Oudheden <strong>in</strong> Leiden. 438 <strong>The</strong> fragments, which belong to<br />

raised reliefs, are made <strong>of</strong> limestone, which <strong>in</strong> some cases is colored yellow, green,<br />

brown, <strong>and</strong> white, <strong>and</strong> bears hieroglyphic <strong>in</strong>scriptions referr<strong>in</strong>g to “the k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Upper <strong>and</strong><br />

Lower Egypt.” <strong>The</strong> depictions on these fragments <strong>in</strong>clude: the Amun crown, the Amun-<br />

M<strong>in</strong> headdress, sacrificial geese <strong>and</strong> birds, a sky symbol with five-po<strong>in</strong>ted stars, a sun<br />

disc, <strong>and</strong> also parts <strong>of</strong> a st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g human figure, the f<strong>in</strong>gers <strong>of</strong> another, a falcon with<br />

outstretched w<strong>in</strong>gs, birds’ claws, cows’ horns, a royal kilt, an <strong>in</strong>cense burner, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

partially preserved hkr-friezes. 439 This evidence is much more useful <strong>in</strong> shedd<strong>in</strong>g light<br />

onto what Herodotus’ tu&poi e0ggeglumme/noi might have looked like than the usual<br />

render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as “figures” <strong>in</strong> modern translations <strong>of</strong> the Histories. 440<br />

Appended to Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th is that <strong>of</strong> a pyramid, which<br />

archaeological studies have identified with that <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat III at Hawara. <strong>The</strong><br />

exist<strong>in</strong>g structure, which is located on the axis <strong>of</strong> the so-called labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>and</strong> not at its<br />

corner, as ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed by Herodotus, now consists <strong>of</strong> a mud-brick core that lacks its<br />

437 Pollitt, Ancient View 273.<br />

438 I. Blom, “<strong>Sculpture</strong>d Fragments <strong>and</strong> Relief Fragments from the Labyr<strong>in</strong>th at Hawara <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Rijksmuseum van Oudheden, Leiden,” OMRO 69 (1989) 25.<br />

439 Blom, “<strong>Sculpture</strong>d Fragments <strong>and</strong> Relief Fragments” 25-50.<br />

440 Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 196; Godley, Herodotus 457; Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 155;<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 157; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories.<br />

Herodotus 129.<br />

250


limestone mantle. 441 Its poor condition partly accounts for our <strong>in</strong>ability to verify the<br />

statement <strong>of</strong> Herodotus regard<strong>in</strong>g its measurement <strong>of</strong> forty o)rguiai/ (tesserakonto&-<br />

rguioj). Lloyd states that Herodotus never makes clear whether the figure <strong>of</strong> forty<br />

o)rguiai/ refers to the height <strong>of</strong> the pyramid or the length <strong>of</strong> its side. 442<br />

Along with this measurement, Herodotus also mentions zw|~a <strong>in</strong> connection with<br />

the pyramid. All that can be understood from his description is that these zw|~a were<br />

images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d. That their appearance is not described, along with the use <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plural, aga<strong>in</strong> suggests that zw|~a was a term <strong>of</strong> general description. That these zw|~a were<br />

mega&la suggests that they were big <strong>in</strong> size, but the possibility <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g great <strong>in</strong> a<br />

metaphorical way as opposed to actual size cannot be ruled out. 443 In addition, the word<br />

e0gge/gluptai, which def<strong>in</strong>es zw|~a, derives from e0gglu/fw <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> appears to refer to<br />

sculpture, most likely, <strong>in</strong> relief. Thus the context <strong>of</strong> these zw|~a seems aga<strong>in</strong> directly<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved with the arts, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> a funerary/religious build<strong>in</strong>g, as suggested by the<br />

prepositional phrase e0n th|~ (“<strong>in</strong> it”), the dative case referr<strong>in</strong>g to the pyramid. In view <strong>of</strong><br />

Herodotus’ previous preference for prepositional phrases that refer to location, this phrase<br />

should be also understood as def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the exact location <strong>of</strong> zw|~a, that is, <strong>in</strong> or at the<br />

pyramid itself, but not necessarily <strong>in</strong>side it. Aga<strong>in</strong>st the latter possibility is Herodotus’<br />

subsequent comment, which shows change <strong>of</strong> thematic direction by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that<br />

access to the pyramid was through an underground passage. In sum, the picture that<br />

441 For a description <strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> the pyramid, see Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 182; for a<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> its location, see Lloyd, “Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs,” <strong>in</strong> Powell, <strong>The</strong> Greek World 282.<br />

442 Lloyd, “Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs,” <strong>in</strong> Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek World 282, where he also states<br />

that the actual height <strong>of</strong> the exist<strong>in</strong>g structure is c. 58 meters <strong>and</strong> the actual length <strong>of</strong> its side c. 106.6<br />

meters.<br />

443 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the literal <strong>and</strong> metaphorical mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term me&geqoj with which mega&la is<br />

directly associated, <strong>and</strong> the difficulty to determ<strong>in</strong>e which mean<strong>in</strong>g is appropriate <strong>in</strong> connection with the<br />

visual arts, see Pollitt, Ancient View 199-201.<br />

251


emerges from this passage is that zw|~a were big or great images <strong>of</strong> an unspecified k<strong>in</strong>d,<br />

executed <strong>in</strong> relief <strong>and</strong> used as decorations on the surface <strong>of</strong> the pyramid.<br />

Further, the impression that the zw|~a were one with the pyramid is heightened by<br />

the fact that they are mentioned immediately after the reference to the measurement <strong>of</strong><br />

the structure, which implies that the Herodotus had its external view <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. In absence<br />

<strong>of</strong> further details, however, one wonders exactly where on the external surfaces <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pyramid the zw|~a were placed. A possible answer may be found <strong>in</strong> the basalt capstone <strong>of</strong><br />

Amenemhat’s III first pyramid at Dahshur (Fig. 24). 444 All four sides <strong>of</strong> the base <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capstone are decorated with a b<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> hieroglyphs. 445 <strong>The</strong> east side, which faced the<br />

ris<strong>in</strong>g sun, additionally bears <strong>in</strong> low relief a w<strong>in</strong>ged sun disk flanked by two uraeus<br />

serpents. <strong>The</strong> w<strong>in</strong>gs flank a set <strong>of</strong> eyes, which is below a hieroglyphic <strong>in</strong>scription, also <strong>in</strong><br />

low relief that mentions the name <strong>of</strong> the pharaoh Amenemhat <strong>and</strong> the phrase “son <strong>of</strong> Ra,”<br />

both given <strong>in</strong> one cartouche; another conta<strong>in</strong>s the name ‘Nimaatra’ <strong>and</strong> the title ‘k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

Upper <strong>and</strong> Lower Egypt.’ Both cartouches are followed by wishes for eternal life for the<br />

sovereign.” 446 Although the good condition <strong>of</strong> this capstone has raised the question<br />

whether it had ever been set <strong>in</strong> place, its decoration is helpful <strong>in</strong> allow<strong>in</strong>g a glimpse <strong>in</strong>to<br />

what Herodotus might have meant <strong>in</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a. Modern translations equate the<br />

term with “hieroglyphics,” “figures,” “figures <strong>of</strong> animals,” <strong>and</strong> simply “animals.” 447<br />

444 Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 180, mentions that the capstone was found <strong>in</strong> 1900 <strong>in</strong> debris along the<br />

eastern base <strong>of</strong> the pyramid. For a detailed discussion <strong>of</strong> this pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhet III, see D. Arnold,<br />

Die Pyramidenbezirk des Königs Amenemhet III <strong>in</strong> Dahshur 1: Die Pyramide (DAIK-Archäologische<br />

Veröffentlichungen 53; (Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 1987).<br />

445 Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids 180.<br />

446 Quotations from S. E<strong>in</strong>audi, “Pyramidion <strong>of</strong> the Pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat III,” <strong>in</strong> A. Bongioanni et al.,<br />

eds., <strong>The</strong> Illustrated Guide to the Egyptian Museum <strong>in</strong> Cairo (Cairo, 2001) 126.<br />

447 Hieroglyphics: Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 280, n. 452 <strong>and</strong> 52, n. 238; How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A<br />

Commentary on Herodotus 242; figures <strong>in</strong> general: Godley, Herodotus 459; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong><br />

Histories. Herodotus 129; figures <strong>of</strong> animals: De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 157;<br />

animals: Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 197.<br />

252


Undoubtedly, these zw|~a did show someth<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> fact, however, that Herodotus never<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>s what raises the question whether he knew or cared about their content.<br />

e. Zw|~a on the Breastplate <strong>of</strong> Amasis<br />

<strong>The</strong> next occurrence <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> Herodotus is <strong>in</strong> the third book <strong>of</strong> the Histories.<br />

Here zw|~a are mentioned as images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d decorat<strong>in</strong>g a l<strong>in</strong>en breastplate that the<br />

Egyptian k<strong>in</strong>g Amasis (reign c. 570-526 B.C.) sent as a gift to the Spartans, but the<br />

Samians stole from them. Herodotus relates the story, while speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> another conflict<br />

between Sparta <strong>and</strong> Samos. 448 In an attempt to reverse their expulsion from their<br />

homel<strong>and</strong>, a group <strong>of</strong> Samian citizens who had recently returned from Egypt, <strong>and</strong> whom<br />

the Samian tyrant Polycrates (reign 535-522 B.C.) suspected <strong>of</strong> overthrow<strong>in</strong>g him,<br />

appealed to Sparta. Herodotus’ account starts with the Spartan response to their request:<br />

After this, hav<strong>in</strong>g made their preparations, the Lacedaemonians made their<br />

expedition aga<strong>in</strong>st Samos. As the Samians tell the story, this was to repay the<br />

k<strong>in</strong>dness done to the Lacedaemonians by the Samians when they helped them<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st Messenia. However, the Lacedaemonians say that this was not the reason<br />

for their assist<strong>in</strong>g the Samians <strong>in</strong> their need; rather, they themselves wanted to<br />

take revenge for the theft <strong>of</strong> the bowl that the Samians stole from them when they<br />

were tak<strong>in</strong>g it up to Croesus, <strong>and</strong> also to the theft <strong>of</strong> the breastplate that Amasis,<br />

k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Egypt, had sent to them, the Spartans, as a gift. <strong>The</strong> Samians had stolen<br />

the breastplate the year before they took the bowl. <strong>The</strong> breastplate was <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>en<br />

<strong>and</strong> with many (suxnw~n) zw|&wn woven <strong>in</strong>to (e0nufasme/nwn) it, <strong>and</strong> decorated<br />

with gold <strong>and</strong> ei0ri/oisi a)po_ cu&lou embroidery. <strong>The</strong> greatest wonder (qwma&sai<br />

a1cion) <strong>of</strong> it is that each s<strong>in</strong>gle f<strong>in</strong>e thread <strong>of</strong> the fabric has <strong>in</strong> itself three hundred<br />

<strong>and</strong> sixty str<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> they all can be seen to be there. One exactly like it was<br />

dedicated by Amasis, <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>dus, to Athena. (3.47) [103]<br />

Herodotus uses zw|&wn, the genitive plural <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, to refer to the decorative elements <strong>of</strong><br />

a l<strong>in</strong>en breastplate, but, as seen previously, he is not concerned with convey<strong>in</strong>g what<br />

448 For an historical analysis <strong>of</strong> the relationship between Sparta <strong>and</strong> Samos, see L. H. Jeffery <strong>and</strong> P.<br />

Cartledge, “Sparta <strong>and</strong> Samos: A Special Relationship?” CQ 32 (1982) 243-265; <strong>and</strong> for the contribution <strong>of</strong><br />

Herodotus’ text to the modern underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this relationship, see B. M. Mitchell, “Herodotus <strong>and</strong><br />

Samos,” JHS 95 (1975) 77-78.<br />

253


these zw|&wn looked like. This evidence aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicates that the term was one <strong>of</strong> general<br />

description for decorative elements <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d on fabric, a situation that recalls the<br />

zw|~a on the clothes from the Caucasus. <strong>The</strong> word suxnw~n, which modifies zw|&wn <strong>and</strong><br />

translates as “many,” suggests a busy display <strong>of</strong> them on the surface <strong>of</strong> the breastplate.<br />

<strong>The</strong> term e0nufasme/nwn, which also modifies zw|&wn, has been most frequently translated<br />

as “woven <strong>in</strong>.” 449 Stephen Newmyer rightly notes that the term derives from the verb<br />

e0nufai/nw, which he expla<strong>in</strong>s as “to weave <strong>in</strong>,” but his translation <strong>of</strong> e0nufasme/nwn as<br />

“embroidered on” is <strong>in</strong>correct. 450 <strong>The</strong> designation <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn as “woven <strong>in</strong>” makes certa<strong>in</strong><br />

the connection with weav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> therefore recalls Herodotus’ assertion that the pa<strong>in</strong>ted,<br />

possibly resist-dyed zw|~a on the clothes from the Caucasus also looked as if they had<br />

been woven <strong>in</strong> from the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g (e0nufanqe/nta a)rxh&n) [99].<br />

Many translations have been assigned to the zw|~a <strong>of</strong> this passage. Waterfield, for<br />

example, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the term refers to “creatures” 451 <strong>and</strong> Newmyer, to “animals.” 452<br />

In partial agreement with him are also De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, who prefer “figures<br />

<strong>of</strong> animals.” 453 Godley, <strong>in</strong> contrast, <strong>and</strong> also Grene, <strong>and</strong> Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er suggest<br />

that the term should be translated as “figures.” 454<br />

Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> the breastplate <strong>in</strong>dicates that it was an object <strong>of</strong><br />

exquisite materials <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> elaborate workmanship. <strong>The</strong> breastplate, he states, was made<br />

<strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>en <strong>and</strong> presented as a gift <strong>of</strong> the Egyptian k<strong>in</strong>g Amasis to the Lacedaemonians. His<br />

449<br />

Waterfield, Herodotus 189; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 232; Godley, Herodotus 61; De Sél<strong>in</strong>court<br />

<strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 191; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 158; LSJ 9 ,<br />

579 s.v. e0nufai/nw.<br />

450<br />

Newmyer, Herodotus 28.<br />

451<br />

Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 189; for the modern confusion between ancient weav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

embroidery, see A. J. B. Wace, “Weav<strong>in</strong>g or Embroidery?” AJA 52 (1948) 51-55.<br />

452<br />

S. T. Newmyer, Herodotus Book III. Commentary (Bryn Mawr, 1986) 28.<br />

453<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 191.<br />

454<br />

Godley, Herodotus 61; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History Herodotus 232; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories.<br />

Herodotus 158.<br />

254


statement accords well with the prom<strong>in</strong>ent position that ancient Egypt held <strong>in</strong> the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>en, <strong>and</strong> therefore po<strong>in</strong>ts to the high value <strong>and</strong> exotic orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

material used. 455 In addition to the zw|~a, the breastplate was decked with gold <strong>and</strong><br />

ei0ri/oisi a)po_ cu&lou threads—a phrase that is taken to mean “embroidery,” thus po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to elaborate work. 456 Gold threads also po<strong>in</strong>t to valued material. 457 <strong>The</strong> phrase ei0ri/oisi<br />

a)po_ cu&lou, whose literal mean<strong>in</strong>g is “the wool <strong>of</strong> the tree,” has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as<br />

“cotton.” 458 As Barber suggests, <strong>in</strong> Herodotus’ era, cotton was a novelty among textiles<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Mediterranean, <strong>and</strong> so the passage po<strong>in</strong>ts, most likely to another valued material. 459<br />

Elaborate workmanship along with superior quality are also implied by the f<strong>in</strong>eness <strong>of</strong><br />

each thread <strong>of</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>en from which the breastplate was made, <strong>and</strong> also the extraord<strong>in</strong>ary<br />

number <strong>of</strong> 360 str<strong>and</strong>s compris<strong>in</strong>g each thread. 460 All these details justify Herodotus’<br />

455<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the prom<strong>in</strong>ent position <strong>of</strong> ancient Egypt <strong>in</strong> the cultivation <strong>of</strong> flux <strong>and</strong> production <strong>of</strong><br />

l<strong>in</strong>en followed by references to visual evidence <strong>and</strong> archaeological rema<strong>in</strong>s, dat<strong>in</strong>g as early as the first<br />

dynasty, see Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 145-162.<br />

456<br />

Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 232; Godley, Herodotus 61.<br />

457<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> golden garments featur<strong>in</strong>g as valued <strong>and</strong> exceptional pieces <strong>in</strong> the ancient sources,<br />

see Vickers, Images on Textiles 20-22. Gold thread was also used for the production <strong>of</strong> the trapezoidshaped<br />

cloth <strong>in</strong> which were wrapped the cremated rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> a female found <strong>in</strong> a larnax <strong>in</strong> the antechamber<br />

<strong>of</strong> the late fourth-century tomb II at Verg<strong>in</strong>a: M. Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a: <strong>The</strong> Royal Tombs <strong>and</strong> the Ancient<br />

City (Athens, 1984) 192, 195, figs. 156-157; also S. Drougou, “Τό ύφασµα της Βεργίνας: Πρώτες<br />

παρατηρήσεις,” <strong>in</strong> ΑΜΗΤΟΣ: Τιµητικός τόµος για τον καθηγητή Μανώλη Ανδρόνικο<br />

(<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1987) 303-323. <strong>The</strong> same tomb yielded also a breastplate made <strong>of</strong> iron sheets with l<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

that preserves remnants <strong>of</strong> cloth <strong>and</strong> leather, <strong>and</strong> external decoration <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> b<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> lions’ heads<br />

<strong>in</strong> real gold. Its gold decoration may provide a parallel to what the gold embroidery on Herodotus’<br />

breastplate might have looked like. For this breastplate, see Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a 138-139, figs. 95-96, <strong>and</strong><br />

140-144.<br />

458<br />

For the translation <strong>of</strong> the phrase as “cotton,” see Newmyer, Herodotus 28; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History.<br />

Herodotus 232. Reference to trees produc<strong>in</strong>g wool is also made <strong>in</strong> Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> India (3.106):<br />

“<strong>The</strong>re are also wild trees there which produce a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> wool which is more attractive <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> better quality<br />

than sheep’s wool, <strong>and</strong> which is used by the Indians for their cloth<strong>in</strong>g”; translation: Waterfield, Herodotus.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Histories 213.<br />

459<br />

Barber, Prehistoric Textiles 33, where she also mentions that the site <strong>of</strong> Trakhones <strong>in</strong> Attica has yielded<br />

a fifth-century example <strong>of</strong> cotton fabric.<br />

460<br />

A description <strong>of</strong> the breastplate dedicated to Athena <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>dus with emphasis on the destructive results<br />

that the exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> its high quality produced is provided by Pl<strong>in</strong>y, NH 19.12, who says: “this may<br />

surprise people who do not know that <strong>in</strong> a breastplate that belonged to a former k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Egypt named<br />

Amasis, preserved <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> M<strong>in</strong>erva at L<strong>in</strong>dus on the isl<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Rhodes, each thread consisted <strong>of</strong> 365<br />

separate threads, a fact which Mucianus, who held the consulship three times quite lately, stated that he had<br />

proved to be true by <strong>in</strong>vestigation, add<strong>in</strong>g that only remnants <strong>of</strong> the breastplate now survive ow<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

255


designation <strong>of</strong> this breastplate as a wonder (qwma&sai a1cion), which places it <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

category <strong>of</strong> exceptional man-made works. 461 F<strong>in</strong>ally, the fact that these zw|~a existed on a<br />

special breastplate that served as a dedication <strong>in</strong> a sanctuary aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicates the direct<br />

connection <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn with the visual arts <strong>in</strong> a generalized religious context.<br />

f. <strong>The</strong> zw|~on Set-Up by Darius<br />

<strong>The</strong> next occurrence <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> relation to the visual arts is <strong>in</strong> the third book <strong>of</strong><br />

the Histories. Here zw|~on refers to the representational subject <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> sculpture<br />

directly <strong>in</strong>spired by <strong>and</strong> commemorat<strong>in</strong>g a specific event <strong>in</strong> Persian history: Darius’ seize<br />

<strong>of</strong> royal power. Part <strong>of</strong> the third book <strong>of</strong> the Histories (chapters 61-87) focuses on the<br />

aftermath <strong>of</strong> Cambyses’ death <strong>and</strong> the accession <strong>of</strong> Darius to the throne <strong>of</strong> the Persian<br />

Empire. Follow<strong>in</strong>g this section is another (chapters 88-119) that enumerates the people<br />

who succumbed to Darius’ conquest. As a prelude to this part, Herodotus mentions, first,<br />

the trick by which Darius won the throne, <strong>and</strong> second, the act with which this newly<br />

assigned k<strong>in</strong>g commemorated his accession to the throne:<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all he made <strong>and</strong> set up (e1sthse) a tu&pon <strong>of</strong> stone (li/q<strong>in</strong>on). On it<br />

(e0nh~n) was a zw|~on <strong>of</strong> a man on horseback, with an <strong>in</strong>scription: “Darius, son<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hystaspes, with the help <strong>of</strong> his horse’s excellence (he there mentioned the<br />

stallion’s name) “<strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Oebares the groom, won the k<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>of</strong> Persia.”<br />

(3.88) [104]<br />

<strong>The</strong> words tu&pon <strong>and</strong> zw|~on are s<strong>in</strong>gular forms <strong>of</strong> tu&poi <strong>and</strong> zw|~a, both <strong>of</strong> which we<br />

have encountered <strong>in</strong> Herodotus’ description <strong>of</strong> the decoration <strong>of</strong> the labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>and</strong> the<br />

damage done by persons exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this quality”; translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History<br />

V. Books XVII-XIX (Cambridge, Mass., 1950) 429.<br />

461 For a discussion on the use <strong>of</strong> the word qw~ma by Herodotus, see Thomas, Herodotus <strong>in</strong> Context 135-<br />

153; also for qw~ma as a literary parallel <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> otherness <strong>in</strong> Herodotus, <strong>and</strong> the designated word<br />

for a splendid man-made object, see F. Hartog, tr. J. Lloyd, <strong>The</strong> Mirror <strong>of</strong> Herodotus: <strong>The</strong> Representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Other <strong>in</strong> the Writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> History (Berkeley, 1988) 231-237.<br />

256


pyramid <strong>in</strong> Egypt. Tu&pon is the accusative s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>of</strong> tu&poj, whose mean<strong>in</strong>g is thought<br />

to be “relief work.” Pollitt states explicitly that the word refers <strong>in</strong> the passage to<br />

sculpture <strong>in</strong> “relief.” 462 Waterfield, <strong>in</strong> contrast, here translates tu&poj as “statue.” 463<br />

Adher<strong>in</strong>g to a more general mean<strong>in</strong>g, Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>and</strong> also Newmyer th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong><br />

tu&poj as “carv<strong>in</strong>g.” 464 Godley translates it together with li/q<strong>in</strong>on as “carved stone,”<br />

whereas Grene, <strong>and</strong> De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola underst<strong>and</strong> tu&pon itself as a<br />

“monument.” 465 <strong>The</strong> word li/q<strong>in</strong>on, which modifies tu&pon, establishes that its material<br />

was <strong>in</strong>deed stone, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests the artistic process <strong>of</strong> sculpture, <strong>and</strong> its status<br />

as a work <strong>of</strong> art. To def<strong>in</strong>e the action <strong>of</strong> Darius <strong>in</strong> regard to this li/q<strong>in</strong>on tu&pon,<br />

Herodotus uses the term e1sthse, the aorist <strong>of</strong> the verb i#sthmi, whose mean<strong>in</strong>g Liddell<br />

<strong>and</strong> Scott def<strong>in</strong>e as “to set up.” 466 Blakesley ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “e!sthse conveys the notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Greek who had <strong>in</strong> his head the conception <strong>of</strong> a sculptured group ‘set up.’” 467 <strong>The</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> e1sthse is <strong>in</strong>deed “set up,” but it should be remembered that it also carries the<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> “st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g” or more precisely, “mak<strong>in</strong>g to st<strong>and</strong>”; 468 as such, the possibility that<br />

tu&poj refers to statuary cannot be ruled out.<br />

Although it is hard to render <strong>in</strong> English, it cannot not be overlooked that the word<br />

tu&pon is preceded by the phrase prw~ton me/n nun, which forms part <strong>of</strong> an antithetical<br />

scheme answered by the words zw|~on de/. It is a truism that the ancient Greek structure<br />

me/n de/, which calls attention to contrasts <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>ds, is to be rendered by on the one<br />

462 Pollitt, Ancient View 273.<br />

463 Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 208.<br />

464 Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 174; Newmyer, Herodotus Book III 48.<br />

465 A. D. Godley, Herodotus II (Cambridge, Mass., <strong>and</strong> London, 1938; repr. 2000) 117; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History.<br />

Herodotus 251; De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 211.<br />

466 LSJ 9 . 841, s.v. i#sthmi; Powell, Lexicon 174, s.v. i#sthmi.<br />

467 Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 367, n. 241.<br />

468 LSJ 9 , 841, s.v. i#sthmi.<br />

257


h<strong>and</strong> on the other h<strong>and</strong>, or <strong>in</strong>deed but, but is <strong>of</strong>ten left without be<strong>in</strong>g translated. 469 <strong>The</strong><br />

terms tu&pon <strong>and</strong> zw|~on thus emerge here as elements <strong>of</strong> a syntactical phenomenon that<br />

marks a contrast between them.<br />

Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er <strong>and</strong> Newmyer translate zw|~on as “figure.” 470 Similarly,<br />

Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott <strong>in</strong>clude this passage <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> their discussion <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~on as “figure” <strong>and</strong> “image.” 471 De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola underst<strong>and</strong> the word to<br />

mean “carv<strong>in</strong>g,” whereas Grene says “engrav<strong>in</strong>g.” 472 F<strong>in</strong>ally, Waterfield equates it with<br />

“featur<strong>in</strong>g.” 473 Herodotus expla<strong>in</strong>s that this zw|~on was a man on horseback (a)nh_r<br />

i9ppeu&j), thus establish<strong>in</strong>g that zw|~on referred to the subject represented by Darius’<br />

tu&poj. This mean<strong>in</strong>g is further strengthened by the appearance—between zw|~on <strong>and</strong><br />

a)nh_r i9ppeu&j—<strong>of</strong> the word e0nh~n, which Godley translates as “whereon.” 474 )Enh~n<br />

derives from the verb e1neimi, which means “to be <strong>in</strong>” or “to be present <strong>in</strong> a place”; as<br />

such, e0nh~n suggests that zw|~on refers to the image, as content, that is shown on the<br />

tu&poj, a physical th<strong>in</strong>g. This is the first explicit example <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the representational subject <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art. When placed next to the previously<br />

discussed references to zw|~on as an image <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art, this passage suggests that the<br />

term was used to <strong>in</strong>dicate both subject <strong>and</strong> image, evidence which, <strong>in</strong> turn, po<strong>in</strong>ts to the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between these two notions. 475<br />

469<br />

H. W. Smyth, rev. G. M. Mess<strong>in</strong>g, Greek Grammar (Cambridge, 1956) 656.<br />

470<br />

Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 174; Newmyer, Herodotus Book III 48.<br />

471 9<br />

LSJ , 760, s.v. zw|~on.<br />

472<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 211; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 250.<br />

473<br />

Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 208.<br />

474<br />

Godley, Herodotus II 117; similarly, Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 174. Blakesley,<br />

Herodotus, with a Commentary 367, n. 241, considers the use <strong>of</strong> the word crucial without, however,<br />

clarify<strong>in</strong>g any further what this statement means.<br />

475<br />

For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>, see<br />

Gordon, “<strong>The</strong> Real <strong>and</strong> the Imag<strong>in</strong>ary” 7-8.<br />

258


Herodotus provides further <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him,<br />

the <strong>in</strong>scription that accompanied the zw|~on <strong>of</strong> a man on horseback set up by Darius read<br />

as follow<strong>in</strong>g: “Darius, son <strong>of</strong> Hystaspes, with the help <strong>of</strong> his horse’s excellence (he there<br />

mentioned the stallion’s name) “<strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Oebares the groom, won the k<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>of</strong><br />

Persia.” <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scription first implies that the image <strong>of</strong> the rider was a representation <strong>of</strong><br />

Darius or at least one that had some connection to him. Second, when seen <strong>in</strong> the<br />

immediate context <strong>of</strong> the Histories, the <strong>in</strong>scription emerges as a succ<strong>in</strong>ct, shorter version<br />

<strong>of</strong> the story narrated <strong>in</strong> the preced<strong>in</strong>g sections (3.84-3.87), <strong>in</strong> which Herodotus expla<strong>in</strong>s<br />

that the groom Oebares, who rigged a horse race, was <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

royal power <strong>of</strong> Darius. This evidence suggests that Herodotus perceived zw|~on, the man<br />

on horseback represented on the work <strong>of</strong> sculpture set up by Darius as be<strong>in</strong>g directly<br />

<strong>in</strong>spired by a contemporary historical event, or, to put it simply, taken from real life.<br />

<strong>The</strong> authenticity <strong>of</strong> both the image <strong>of</strong> the rider <strong>and</strong> the story <strong>of</strong> the trick has,<br />

however, been repeatedly doubted. <strong>The</strong> doubt arose because <strong>of</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> the rider<br />

<strong>in</strong> monumental Achaemenid art. Thus, How <strong>and</strong> Wells, <strong>and</strong> also De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong><br />

Mar<strong>in</strong>cola state firmly that Achaemenid monumental art supplies no evidence that<br />

matches Herodotus’ account. 476 In agreement with them is Stephanie West, who remarks<br />

that “the extant rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid monumental art provide no parallel for the work<br />

here described, though the material at our disposal is not so abundant that an argument<br />

from silence may be regarded as conclusive.” 477 Margaret Root does not take this lack <strong>of</strong><br />

476 How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus 280: “neither at Behistun nor on his tomb at Nakhsh-I-<br />

Rustam is Darius represented on horseback. But Herodotus may well have seen some ‘relief,’ now<br />

destroyed, resembl<strong>in</strong>g the façade <strong>of</strong> Tagh-I-Bostan”; De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong><br />

Histories 648, n. 30: “no monument <strong>of</strong> this sort has been discovered, nor should we expect that it will,<br />

given the portrait <strong>of</strong> Darius’ rise to power <strong>in</strong> the Behistun <strong>in</strong>scription.”<br />

477 S. West, “Herodotus’ Epigraphical Interests,” CQ 35 (1985) 297.<br />

259


material evidence to mean that Herodotus’ account is unreliable or that Achaemenid<br />

sculpture did not feature this subject. <strong>The</strong>refore, she <strong>in</strong>cludes this passage <strong>of</strong> Herodotus<br />

<strong>in</strong> her discussion <strong>of</strong> ancient texts referr<strong>in</strong>g to royal Achaemenid sculpture, <strong>and</strong> says that<br />

“sculptural representations <strong>of</strong> a man on horseback (<strong>and</strong> perhaps the k<strong>in</strong>g on horseback)<br />

might well have formed an important part <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid repertoire.” 478 That the image<br />

<strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>g as a horseman was not foreign to Achaemenid culture is demonstrated by<br />

Achaemenid royal <strong>in</strong>scriptions, more specifically, the statement <strong>of</strong> Darius <strong>in</strong>scribed on<br />

the façade <strong>of</strong> his tomb at Naqsh-i Rustam: “As a horseman I am a good horseman. As a<br />

bowman I am a good bowman both on foot <strong>and</strong> on horseback. As a spearman I am a<br />

good spearman both on foot <strong>and</strong> on horseback.” 479 <strong>The</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong> horsemanship <strong>in</strong><br />

Achaemenid life is further attested <strong>in</strong> Herodotus, who states that that the Persians “tra<strong>in</strong><br />

their sons from their fifth to their twentieth year <strong>in</strong> three th<strong>in</strong>gs only: horsemanship,<br />

archery <strong>and</strong> truth tell<strong>in</strong>g” (1.136.2). His statement is <strong>in</strong> good accord with the image <strong>of</strong><br />

the Persian horseman, recognized by his dist<strong>in</strong>ct cap <strong>and</strong> the deeply fr<strong>in</strong>ged Persian<br />

saddle cloth that appears on a considerable number <strong>of</strong> seals, gems, co<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> also on<br />

metal vessels <strong>and</strong> swords that have all been dated to the Achaemenid period. 480 To this<br />

478<br />

M. C. Root, <strong>The</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>in</strong> Achaemenid Art. Essays on the Creation <strong>of</strong> an Iconography <strong>of</strong><br />

Empire (Acta Iranica 19; Leiden, 1979) 129-130.<br />

479<br />

R. G. Kent, Old Persian. Grammar. Texts. Lexicon (New Haven, 1950; second rev. ed., 1953) 140<br />

(DNb, l<strong>in</strong>es 40-45).<br />

480<br />

For the image <strong>of</strong> the Persian horseman on seals, see J. Boardman, Persia <strong>and</strong> the West: An<br />

Archaeological Investigation <strong>of</strong> the Genesis <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid Art (London, 2000) 161, fig. 5.11, 172, fig.<br />

5.40, 173, fig. 5.46. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to A. Farkas, “<strong>The</strong> Horse <strong>and</strong> Rider <strong>in</strong> Achaemenid Art,” Persica 4 (1969)<br />

66, n. 34, the co<strong>in</strong>s are those <strong>of</strong> Evagoras II <strong>of</strong> Salamis <strong>in</strong> Cyprus <strong>and</strong> date from his reign as Persian satrap,<br />

351-349 B.C. She also mentions, 66-67, that the image appears on a silver roundel from the Oxus<br />

Treasure, <strong>and</strong> on a gold sword hilt that was found <strong>in</strong> a Scythian late fifth-/early fourth-century tomb at the<br />

site <strong>of</strong> Chertomlyk <strong>in</strong> South Russia. For further bibliography on these objects, see Farkas, 66-67, nos. 35-<br />

36. To this evidence should be added the gold figure <strong>of</strong> a male rider from the Oxus treasure, <strong>and</strong> also a<br />

bronze figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a horse <strong>and</strong> a rider <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid date (fifth-fourth centuries B.C.), both housed<br />

currently at the British museum: J. Curtis <strong>and</strong> N. Tallis, eds., Forgotten Empire: <strong>The</strong> World <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid<br />

Persia (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 2005) 226, ns. 408-409. A Persian horseman is also depicted on each<br />

260


evidence should be also added an Aramaic letter that was found <strong>in</strong> Egypt <strong>and</strong> dates to the<br />

reign <strong>of</strong> Darius II (fifth century B.C.). Although the letter specifies no particular<br />

medium, its content is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it describes the plac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an order by Arsam, the<br />

satrap <strong>of</strong> Egypt, for a representation <strong>of</strong> a horse <strong>and</strong> its rider from a craftsman called<br />

H<strong>in</strong>zani. 481 <strong>The</strong>re is, thus, considerable evidence for the centrality <strong>of</strong> the image <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rider <strong>in</strong> both literary <strong>and</strong> visual material that is directly associated with the Achaemenid<br />

Empire.<br />

With respect to the trick that Herodotus relates, it has been suggested that the<br />

account rests on “an ancient Indo-Iranian folktale that bound together horse rac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

k<strong>in</strong>gship.” 482 This idea has been further susta<strong>in</strong>ed by the silence <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> regard<br />

to the location <strong>of</strong> the image <strong>of</strong> the rider that Darius commissioned. 483 Approach<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

evidence from a different angle, Oswyn Murray suggests that Herodotus’ story <strong>of</strong> the<br />

horse race attests to the Achaemenid practice <strong>of</strong> horse div<strong>in</strong>ation. 484 <strong>The</strong> tril<strong>in</strong>gual text <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>in</strong>scribed rock relief at Bisitun, which records Darius’ proclamation <strong>of</strong> legitimate<br />

k<strong>in</strong>gship, does not mention the <strong>in</strong>cident <strong>of</strong> the horse trick. 485 This evidence does not<br />

<strong>of</strong> the gold plaques that form part <strong>of</strong> a necklace with the head <strong>of</strong> Bes at its center, housed now <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Metropolitan Museum: Boardman, Persia <strong>and</strong> the West 195, figs. 5.77a, b.<br />

481<br />

For the scholarly debate on this letter <strong>and</strong> the possibility that the identification <strong>of</strong> the craftsman as a<br />

sculptor is not secure, see S. A. Paspalas, “On Persian-Type Furniture <strong>in</strong> Macedonia: <strong>The</strong> Recognition <strong>and</strong><br />

Transmission <strong>of</strong> Forms,” AJA 105 (2000) 544, n. 85; also West, “Herodotus’ Epigraphical Interests,” 297,<br />

n. 92, where she states that the identification <strong>of</strong> H<strong>in</strong>zani as a sculptor is an assumption; he could have been<br />

a pa<strong>in</strong>ter or seal-cutter.<br />

482<br />

J. M. Balcer, Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Bisitun: Problems <strong>in</strong> Ancient Persian Historiography (Stuttgart, 1987) 38,<br />

n. 61.<br />

483<br />

West, “Herodotus’ Epigraphical Interests” 297, where she states that “we are given no <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> the<br />

location <strong>of</strong> this monument,” <strong>and</strong> that “it looks as if the story <strong>of</strong> Darius’ ruse (together, no doubt, with much<br />

<strong>of</strong> the immediately preced<strong>in</strong>g narrative) represents a Greek fantasy woven around a conspicuous monument<br />

without regard to its real purport.”<br />

484<br />

O. Murray, “Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Oral History,” <strong>in</strong> H. Sancisi-Weerdenburg <strong>and</strong> A. Kuhrt, eds., Achaemenid<br />

History II. <strong>The</strong> Greek Sources. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Gron<strong>in</strong>gen 1984 Achaemenid History Workshop<br />

(Leiden, 1987) 115.<br />

485<br />

E. A. W. Budge, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Inscription <strong>of</strong> Darius the Great on the Rock <strong>of</strong> Behistun <strong>in</strong> Persia<br />

(London, 1907) 1-207. <strong>The</strong> east pediment <strong>of</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> Zeus at Olympia (460s) shows that a similar<br />

story <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a groom <strong>and</strong> a trick was also current <strong>in</strong> early <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>. <strong>The</strong> pediment shows the<br />

261


automatically rule out Herodotus’ statement that Darius commemorated his royal status<br />

with an <strong>in</strong>scribed work <strong>of</strong> art allud<strong>in</strong>g to a historical event. <strong>The</strong> tendency <strong>of</strong> Darius to<br />

commemorate those <strong>of</strong> his acts that had historical value with works <strong>of</strong> art is further<br />

evidenced <strong>in</strong> a now-headless, granite statue that depicts him <strong>and</strong> was found at Susa. 486<br />

<strong>The</strong> tril<strong>in</strong>gual cuneiform texts (Old Persian, Elamite, Babylonian) <strong>and</strong> Egyptian<br />

hieroglyphs <strong>in</strong>scribed on its base state that Darius had it made <strong>in</strong> Egypt to show that a<br />

Persian man had taken this country. 487 <strong>The</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant scholarly op<strong>in</strong>ion is that the statue<br />

was <strong>in</strong>tended to st<strong>and</strong> at the shr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> god Re <strong>in</strong> Heliopolis. 488 <strong>The</strong> fact that it was found<br />

at Susa along with many other works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>of</strong> many periods <strong>in</strong>dicates a special<br />

circumstance, but, at the same time, highlights that works <strong>of</strong> art could travel throughout<br />

the Achaemenid Empire, or be transported from its fr<strong>in</strong>ges to the center. 489 It is,<br />

therefore, not unreasonable to suggest that the issue <strong>of</strong> location may have not been <strong>of</strong><br />

primary importance for Herodotus. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the fact that Herodotus does<br />

not mention the exact location <strong>of</strong> the monument <strong>of</strong> Darius does not serve to impeach the<br />

reliability <strong>of</strong> his account. As was seen above, the surviv<strong>in</strong>g literary <strong>and</strong> visual evidence<br />

suggests a strong presence <strong>of</strong> the image <strong>and</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> the horseman <strong>in</strong> both Achaemenid<br />

language/narrative <strong>and</strong> m<strong>in</strong>or arts.<br />

preparation for the chariot race between Pelops, a hero (father <strong>of</strong> Atreus) worshipped at Olympia <strong>and</strong><br />

O<strong>in</strong>omaos, the ruler <strong>of</strong> neighbor<strong>in</strong>g Pisa. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the story, Pelops, although skilled <strong>in</strong> horsemanship,<br />

won by brib<strong>in</strong>g O<strong>in</strong>omaos’ charioteer Myrtilos to substitute wax for metal lynch-p<strong>in</strong>s on his chariot.<br />

O<strong>in</strong>omaos was thus killed, but <strong>in</strong> dy<strong>in</strong>g he cursed Pelops; or Pelops killed Myrtilos who, <strong>in</strong> turn, cursed him<br />

<strong>and</strong> his house. For further discussion <strong>of</strong> the story <strong>of</strong> Pelops <strong>and</strong> its association with the east pediment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

temple <strong>of</strong> Zeus at Olympia, see Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period 36-38.<br />

486<br />

D. Stronach, “La statue de Darius découverte à Suse,” CDAFI 4 (1974) 61-72; Root, <strong>The</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

K<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>in</strong> Achaemenid Art 68-72; also, Curtis <strong>and</strong> Tallis, Forgotten Empire 99, no. 88.<br />

487<br />

Curtis <strong>and</strong> Tallis, Forgotten Empire 99.<br />

488<br />

Boardman, Persia <strong>and</strong> the West 115, n. 55.<br />

489<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these ideas on the basis <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>of</strong> Darius, see Paspalas, “ On-Persian Style<br />

Furniture <strong>in</strong> Macedonia” 544, n. 84.<br />

262


g. <strong>The</strong> Zw|~a <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

A further occurrence <strong>of</strong> the term zw|~on as applied to the visual arts appears aga<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> connection with Darius. <strong>The</strong> term occurs <strong>in</strong> the fourth book <strong>of</strong> the Histories <strong>and</strong> has<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the representational subject <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>in</strong> this case a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

depict<strong>in</strong>g one <strong>of</strong> Darius’ military feats. A section <strong>of</strong> the fourth book (chapters 83-98)<br />

narrates this k<strong>in</strong>g’s cross<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Hellespont <strong>and</strong> the Danube as part <strong>of</strong> his campaign<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st the Scythians. When Darius left Susa (c. 513 B.C.), 490 he made his way to<br />

Chalcedon, that part <strong>of</strong> the Bosporus, where a bridge had been built as part <strong>of</strong> his regional<br />

military projects that aimed to facilitate his <strong>in</strong>vasion <strong>of</strong> Scythia. Herodotus reports that<br />

when Darius reached Chalcedon, he wanted to <strong>in</strong>spect the Eux<strong>in</strong>e Sea <strong>and</strong> the Bosporus<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus boarded a boat <strong>and</strong> sailed around the area. Pleased with the construction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

bridge over the strait, Darius <strong>of</strong>fered a reward to its head eng<strong>in</strong>eer, M<strong>and</strong>rocles <strong>of</strong> Samos:<br />

After that, Darius was so delighted with his bridge <strong>of</strong> boats, that he gave<br />

M<strong>and</strong>rocles every sort <strong>of</strong> reward. This man took the first-fruits <strong>of</strong> his honors <strong>and</strong><br />

zw|~a graya&menoj depict<strong>in</strong>g the whole bridg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Bosporus <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Darius sitt<strong>in</strong>g high over it <strong>and</strong> the army cross<strong>in</strong>g; he dedicated it <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong><br />

Hera <strong>and</strong> made this <strong>in</strong>scription:<br />

This is the bridge <strong>of</strong> boats over the fish-haunted Bosporus;<br />

M<strong>and</strong>rocles built it, <strong>and</strong> Hera received it as her memorial;<br />

A crown for himself its builder made it, a glory <strong>of</strong> Samos;<br />

All that he wrought he accomplished by the will <strong>of</strong> the K<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

Darius. (4.88) [105]<br />

<strong>The</strong> word graya&menoj, which def<strong>in</strong>es M<strong>and</strong>rocles, is the aorist participle <strong>of</strong> the verb<br />

gra&fw, which, as seen earlier, means “to pa<strong>in</strong>t”, “to draw” <strong>and</strong> “to write.” <strong>The</strong> object <strong>of</strong><br />

graya&menoj is the plural zw|~a. <strong>The</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> graya&menoj establishes that the<br />

context <strong>of</strong> the passage is directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the arts; therefore, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a<br />

490 C. Dewald, “Introduction; Notes,” <strong>in</strong> R. Waterfield, tr., Herodotus: <strong>The</strong> Histories (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1998) 653 notes that 513 B.C. is an approximate date for Darius’ expedition aga<strong>in</strong>st the Scythians<br />

<strong>and</strong> one that cannot be confirmed from Persian records.<br />

263


here need not be “animals.” All modern render<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> zw|~a <strong>in</strong> this passage follow this<br />

l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, but their approach to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term varies greatly. Thus, some<br />

translations detach zw|~a from its surround<strong>in</strong>g vocabulary, <strong>and</strong> render it as “figures,”<br />

whereas some others recognize its dependence on graya&menoj <strong>and</strong> render it as “a<br />

picture made with figures,” “a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>of</strong> figures,” <strong>and</strong> also “pa<strong>in</strong>ted picture(s).” 491<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, some other translations comb<strong>in</strong>e both zw|~a <strong>and</strong> graya&menoj <strong>in</strong>to one modern<br />

term, which they translate as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “picture.” 492<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that all previous occurrences <strong>of</strong> zw|~a <strong>in</strong> the company <strong>of</strong> some form <strong>of</strong><br />

gra&fw or e0ggra&fw refer to images created by means <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g suggests that these<br />

zw|~a, which are the direct object <strong>of</strong> graya&menoj, should be also understood as such.<br />

Reg<strong>in</strong>ald Macan, however, po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the passage does not clarify whether<br />

these zw|~a referred to “a wall pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g or a pi/nac,” the latter carry<strong>in</strong>g multiple mean<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

among them, a writ<strong>in</strong>g or draw<strong>in</strong>g tablet (e.g., Homer, Il. 6.169), a board for pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

(<strong>The</strong>ophrastus, HP 3.9.7), <strong>and</strong> even the plank(s) <strong>of</strong> a ship (Homer, Od. 12.67). 493 In<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> specific evidence, he f<strong>in</strong>ds it safe to assume that what Herodotus had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d<br />

was, most likely, a wall-pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. 494 Although this suggestion cannot be established with<br />

certa<strong>in</strong>ty, its value lies <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g to the foreground the modern tendency to use the term<br />

“pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g” for both the actual object <strong>and</strong> image produced by means <strong>of</strong> this process.<br />

491 Figures: How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus 334; a picture made with figures: Grene, <strong>The</strong><br />

History. Herodotus 313; a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>of</strong> figures: Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus 224;<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ted picture: De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 270; pa<strong>in</strong>ted pictures: LSJ 9 , 760,<br />

s.v. zw|~on.<br />

492 Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g: Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 264; picture: Godley, Herodotus 2 291; Blakesley,<br />

Herodotus, with a Commentary 491, n. 251; R. W. Macan, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Fouth, Fifth, <strong>and</strong> Sixth Books I<br />

(London, 1895) 63-64, n. 88.<br />

493 Macan, Herodotus 64, n. 88; LSJ 9 , 1405, s.v.pi/nac.<br />

494 Macan, Herodotus 64, n. 88.<br />

264


<strong>The</strong> passage is <strong>in</strong>structive for the sense <strong>in</strong> which it uses zw|~a. As Herodotus<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>s these zw|~a were representations <strong>of</strong> three specific th<strong>in</strong>gs: the bridge built over the<br />

Bosporus, Darius sitt<strong>in</strong>g on a throne, <strong>and</strong> the Persian army cross<strong>in</strong>g the bridge. This<br />

description equates zw|~a with the representational subjects <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

More precisely, the bridge—a physical structure, 495 the throne <strong>of</strong> Darius—an item <strong>of</strong><br />

furniture, Darius himself—a human figure, <strong>and</strong> the Persian army cross<strong>in</strong>g—additional<br />

human figures <strong>in</strong> action, all suggest a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

subjects. <strong>The</strong> fact that all these subjects were taken directly out <strong>of</strong> a contemporary<br />

historical achievement—the construction <strong>of</strong> a bridge mark<strong>in</strong>g the Persian advanc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to<br />

foreign territories—<strong>in</strong>dicates that Herodotus perceived zw|~a as historically exist<strong>in</strong>g<br />

subjects, taken from real life. In this sense, these zw|~a are rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the zw|~on <strong>of</strong> the<br />

rider commemorat<strong>in</strong>g the historical ascension <strong>of</strong> Darius to the throne <strong>of</strong> the Persian<br />

Empire. In addition, the equation <strong>of</strong> these zw|~a with both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects<br />

taken from real life is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it allows an <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to how the etymology <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~on should be perceived when the term is used <strong>in</strong> a context directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the<br />

arts. With<strong>in</strong> such a context, zw|~on does not necessarily denote a liv<strong>in</strong>g or breath<strong>in</strong>g<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g, but rather both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects that exist <strong>in</strong> the real world. Thus,<br />

zw|~on can be both a representation <strong>of</strong> a human figure <strong>and</strong> a chair <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as they are both directly borrowed from the surround<strong>in</strong>g environment. It is important to<br />

495 Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 313, n. 42, suggests that this was “a bridge <strong>of</strong> boats constructed <strong>of</strong> a<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> boats or rafts tied together; [therefore, it can be also understood as] a raft.” Herodotus does<br />

not provide the details <strong>of</strong> the construction <strong>of</strong> this bridge, <strong>and</strong> this treatment runs counter to the one he <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

for the construction <strong>of</strong> Xerxes’ bridge over the Hellespont (7.36). For a modern commentary on the<br />

technical aspects <strong>of</strong> this bridge, see N. G. L. Hammond <strong>and</strong> L. J. Roseman, “<strong>The</strong> Construction <strong>of</strong> Xerxes’<br />

Bridge over the Hellespont,” JHS 116 (1996) 88-107. Both descriptions have been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as <strong>in</strong>stances<br />

<strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ belief <strong>in</strong> a predom<strong>in</strong>antly Persian characteristic: the use <strong>of</strong> technology to dom<strong>in</strong>ate the<br />

natural world, <strong>and</strong>, consequently, create a powerful empire. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this concept, see J. Romm,<br />

“Herodotus <strong>and</strong> the Natural World,” <strong>in</strong> C. Dewald <strong>and</strong> J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, eds., <strong>The</strong> Cambridge Companion to<br />

Herodotus (Cambridge, 2006) 189-190.<br />

265


keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, however, that, as it is, this def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> zw|~on appears to stem from an<br />

“essentialist” conception; no evidence exists to suggest an automatic connection with any<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> realism <strong>in</strong> representation. <strong>The</strong> silence on this aspect, however, may mean that<br />

we have here an aspect <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art that was taken for granted. In sum, this evidence<br />

suggests that zw|~on may be very close to the modern def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> representational or<br />

figural art, which may, <strong>in</strong> turn, expla<strong>in</strong> why the term “figure” has been applied to the<br />

ancient zw|~on <strong>in</strong>discrim<strong>in</strong>ately.<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the fact that M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g centered on a historical subject,<br />

William Childs recognizes an affiliation with Anatolian <strong>and</strong> Near Eastern art rather than<br />

with that <strong>of</strong> the Greek ma<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong>. 496 He sees a distant parallel between the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

M<strong>and</strong>rocles <strong>and</strong> the historical reliefs <strong>of</strong> Lycian tombs, which, <strong>in</strong> accordance with<br />

Assyrian iconographic tradition, depict cities <strong>and</strong> also sieges <strong>of</strong> cities. 497 In the same<br />

way, for example, that representations <strong>of</strong> cities on the smaller frieze <strong>of</strong> the Nereid<br />

Monument from Xanthos (ca. 380 B.C.) <strong>and</strong> the west wall <strong>of</strong> the Heroon from Trysa (ca.<br />

370 B.C.) were parts <strong>of</strong> historical narratives that served to glorify the actual deeds <strong>of</strong> the<br />

local dynasts, the bridge represented <strong>in</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g described by Herodotus can be seen<br />

as glorify<strong>in</strong>g the deed <strong>of</strong> both M<strong>and</strong>rocles <strong>and</strong> Darius. 498 Tonio Hölscher suggests that<br />

496 W. A. P. Childs, <strong>The</strong> City-Reliefs <strong>of</strong> Lycia (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1978) 95, where he f<strong>in</strong>ds it po<strong>in</strong>tless to “discredit<br />

totally the historical bent <strong>of</strong> Greek art <strong>of</strong> the fifth century,” evident, for example, <strong>in</strong> the Attic vases, which<br />

show the kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hipparchos by Harmodios <strong>and</strong> Aristogeiton. He does highlight, however (95) the<br />

Eastern Greek <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> specific illustrations than <strong>in</strong> generic types, which he expla<strong>in</strong>s (95, n. 50) as “the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> Oriental <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong> accordance with the <strong>in</strong>terest, however, rudimentary, <strong>in</strong> historical specificity.”<br />

497 Childs, <strong>The</strong> City-Reliefs <strong>of</strong> Lycia 95. He discusses <strong>in</strong> detail (48-54) parallels between the iconography<br />

<strong>of</strong> the city motif, primarily <strong>in</strong> battle <strong>and</strong> siege contexts, <strong>in</strong> Lycian <strong>and</strong> Assyrian reliefs. As an example, he<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers (52) the city sieges on the bronze gates <strong>of</strong> Shalmaneser from Balawat, where the seated figure <strong>of</strong><br />

Shalmaneser <strong>and</strong> his <strong>of</strong>ficials watch rows <strong>of</strong> soldiers attack<strong>in</strong>g a city, while l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> prisoners are led away<br />

from the city. <strong>The</strong> scene recalls that depicted on slab 878 <strong>of</strong> the Nereid Monument, where a siege mound,<br />

soldiers, <strong>and</strong> figures lead<strong>in</strong>g prisoners away are depicted.<br />

498 Childs, <strong>The</strong> City-Reliefs <strong>of</strong> Lycia 97, presents a tripartite division <strong>of</strong> the reliefs <strong>and</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> the<br />

city motif on them. <strong>The</strong> city <strong>of</strong> Type I (e.g., Merehi Sarcophagus, Xanthos, exterior southeast wall <strong>of</strong><br />

Heroon at Trysa, City Sarcophagos, Telmessos), he states, 95, depicts <strong>in</strong> typical Oriental manner the power<br />

266


the representations <strong>of</strong> enthroned Darius <strong>and</strong> rows <strong>of</strong> march<strong>in</strong>g soldiers were elements<br />

borrowed directly from the Achaemenid artistic tradition; he also states that the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

aimed more at commemorat<strong>in</strong>g the eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g feat <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles rather than the<br />

historical significance <strong>of</strong> Darius’ passage to Europe. 499 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the fact that M<strong>and</strong>rocles dedicated this pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g at the Samian<br />

Heraion, Hölscher attributes votive rather than historical value to it. 500 M<strong>and</strong>rocles’<br />

dedication <strong>of</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g with zw|~a at a sanctuary aga<strong>in</strong> connects the latter with a work <strong>of</strong><br />

art with<strong>in</strong> a religious sett<strong>in</strong>g. Although the dedication may h<strong>in</strong>t that personal glorification<br />

was what M<strong>and</strong>rocles had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, it does not appear to have dictated the choice <strong>of</strong> what<br />

was depicted; Herodotus’ narrative implies <strong>in</strong>stead that the subject <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g was the<br />

direct result <strong>of</strong> the historical circumstances that bound M<strong>and</strong>rocles to Darius. Support for<br />

this view is conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, which identifies the depicted<br />

bridge as M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ achievement <strong>and</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ues: “All that he [M<strong>and</strong>rocles] wrought he<br />

accomplished by the will <strong>of</strong> the K<strong>in</strong>g, Darius.” That the historical value <strong>of</strong> such a<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g concerned not only its representational subject, but extended also to the act <strong>of</strong><br />

dedication itself is a subject that has drawn wide attention recently. As Stavros Paspalas<br />

has noted, it is not unreasonable to see this pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as a medium through which the<br />

relationship between the Persian k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> those, like M<strong>and</strong>rocles, who served him <strong>and</strong><br />

found favor with him, was presented to a wider audience <strong>in</strong> the West; 501 <strong>in</strong> other words,<br />

as a form <strong>of</strong> propag<strong>and</strong>a. This suggestion acquires additional value <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dynast. In type II, represented by the Nereid Monument, <strong>and</strong> the west wall <strong>of</strong> the Heroon at Trysa,<br />

described <strong>in</strong> detail <strong>in</strong> 22-36, the city is part <strong>of</strong> a historical narrative, which aims at highlight<strong>in</strong>g the deeds <strong>of</strong><br />

the local dynasts. <strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the city <strong>of</strong> Type III (e.g., L<strong>and</strong>scape tomb at P<strong>in</strong>ara, <strong>and</strong> stepped<br />

monument <strong>of</strong> Izraza at Tlos) is elusive.<br />

499 T. Hölscher, Griechische Historienbilder des 5. und 4. Jahrhunderts V. Chr. (Würzburg, 1975) 36-37.<br />

500 Hölscher, Griechische Historienbilder 37.<br />

501 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as a representative <strong>of</strong> a medium through which Persian forms reached<br />

audiences <strong>in</strong> the West, see Paspalas, “On Persian-Type Furniture <strong>in</strong> Macedonia” 545.<br />

267


observation that the word e0pigra&yaj, which Herodotus uses for the record<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription, as opposed to the graya&menoj used for the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the zw|~a, <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

that M<strong>and</strong>rokles composed the <strong>in</strong>scription himself. 502 In this way, not only is M<strong>and</strong>rocles<br />

presented as determ<strong>in</strong>ed to show to the visitors <strong>of</strong> the sanctuary his relationship with the<br />

Persian k<strong>in</strong>g, but even the personal act <strong>of</strong> supply<strong>in</strong>g its dedication with an explanatory<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription is highlighted as a historical act <strong>in</strong> itself.<br />

h. Zw|&dia on a Bronze Krater<br />

In addition to zw|~on, Herodotus also uses the term zw|&dion to refer to decorative<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> connection with the visual arts. <strong>The</strong> term, which is the<br />

dim<strong>in</strong>utive <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, appears <strong>in</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> the pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g relations that led to a<br />

sixth-century treaty between the Lacedaemonians <strong>and</strong> the Lydian K<strong>in</strong>g, Croesus. 503<br />

Herodotus describes a bronze krater full <strong>of</strong> zw|&dia around its rim that the former <strong>of</strong>fered<br />

as a token <strong>of</strong> their gratitude to Croesus:<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> that, <strong>and</strong> because he had given them precedence, <strong>in</strong> his choice for<br />

friendship, over all the rest <strong>of</strong> the Greeks, the Lacedaemonians accepted the<br />

alliance. So when he made the <strong>of</strong>fer, they were ready; <strong>and</strong>, moreover, they made<br />

a bronze mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl, fill<strong>in</strong>g (plh&santej) it on the outside, around the rim (peri\<br />

to_ xei=loj), with zw|di/wn (the mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl itself was <strong>of</strong> a capacity <strong>of</strong> three<br />

hundred amphorae) <strong>and</strong> sent it on its way to Croesus, wish<strong>in</strong>g to match Croesus’<br />

gift to them with one <strong>of</strong> their own to him. But this mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl never did reach<br />

Sardis, for which two reasons are given. <strong>The</strong> Lacedaemonians say that when, <strong>in</strong><br />

its transport toward Sardis, it came near Samos, the Samians found out about it,<br />

sailed out with their long ships, <strong>and</strong> captured it; but the Samians themselves say<br />

that the Lacedaemonians who were br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g it came too late, heard that Sardis<br />

<strong>and</strong> Croesus had been captured, <strong>and</strong> sold the mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl <strong>in</strong> Samos, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

some private persons bought it <strong>and</strong> dedicated it <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> Hera. And<br />

probably also those who sold it, when they arrived <strong>in</strong> Sparta, would say that it<br />

had been taken from them by the Samians. That, then, is the story <strong>of</strong> the bowl.<br />

(1.70) [97]<br />

502 West, “Herodotus’ Epigraphical Interests” 282, n. 16.<br />

503 De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 629, n. 31, place this treaty to around 548/7 B.C.<br />

268


Herodotus gives no details about the appearance <strong>of</strong> zw|di/wn, which is the genitive<br />

plural <strong>of</strong> zw|&dion. 504 This treatment suggests that zw|di/wn is used here <strong>in</strong> a general sense.<br />

What can be understood from the passage is that they are decorative elements <strong>of</strong> some<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d on the outer rim <strong>of</strong> the bronze krater. In this sense, they are rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the zw|~a<br />

encountered earlier on the clothes from the Caucasus, the breastplate <strong>of</strong> Amasis, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

those on Egyptian build<strong>in</strong>gs. <strong>The</strong> huge size <strong>of</strong> the krater, <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with its be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

made <strong>of</strong> bronze, a valuable material, suggests accomplished craftsmanship. 505 <strong>The</strong>se two<br />

characteristics justify its use as a diplomatic gift <strong>in</strong>tended for a k<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> its subsequent<br />

dedication at the Samian Heraion, which is consistent with the long tradition <strong>of</strong> rich<br />

votive gifts (e.g., tripods <strong>and</strong> cauldrons) at sanctuaries. Further, the fact that the<br />

commissioners <strong>of</strong> this krater were Lacedaemonians accords well with the prom<strong>in</strong>ent<br />

position that Laconia is thought to have held <strong>in</strong> the production <strong>of</strong> bronze vessels dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the Archaic period. 506 Herodotus uses the word plh&santej, which derives from the verb<br />

pi/mplhmi, mean<strong>in</strong>g “to fill,” to <strong>in</strong>dicate a Laconian preference for cover<strong>in</strong>g the outer rim<br />

with zw|&dia. 507 Plh&santej gives the impression <strong>of</strong> a densely covered surface, thus<br />

suggest<strong>in</strong>g abundant decoration <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricate craftsmanship. <strong>The</strong> plural zw|di/wn, which<br />

504 9<br />

LSJ , 758, s.v. zw|&dion; also for –idion as a st<strong>and</strong>ard suffix <strong>of</strong> neutral dim<strong>in</strong>utives, see Smyth, Greek<br />

Grammar 235.<br />

505<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 31, suggest five hundred gallons; for a detailed<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> calculat<strong>in</strong>g the capacity <strong>of</strong> the krater <strong>and</strong> equated it with 7800 liters, see A. Rumpf, “Krath&r<br />

Lakwniko&j,” <strong>in</strong> K. Schauenburg, ed., Charites. Festschrift für E. Langlotz (Bonn, 1957) 131. For bronze<br />

as a valuable material <strong>of</strong> vessels, among them kraters, see C. Rolley, tr. R. Howell, Greek Bronzes<br />

(London, 1986) 140; for a discussion <strong>of</strong> bronze as a costly material for vessels <strong>in</strong> the fifth century, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

the higher status <strong>of</strong> bronze-smiths <strong>in</strong> comparison to that <strong>of</strong> potters, see M. Vickers <strong>and</strong> D. Gill, Artful<br />

Crafts: Ancient Greek Silverware <strong>and</strong> Pottery (Oxford, 1994) 98-99.<br />

506<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to C. M. Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos: Aspects <strong>of</strong> the Archaic Greek Bronze Industry<br />

(Rome, 2000) XIII, n. 3, Laconia was “the lead<strong>in</strong>g Greek centre for bronze work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the first half <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sixth century.” For a discussion <strong>of</strong> both fictile <strong>and</strong> bronze examples <strong>of</strong> Lakonian mix<strong>in</strong>g bowls, see also his<br />

study, Laconian Mix<strong>in</strong>g Bowls: A History <strong>of</strong> the Krater Lakonikos from the Seventh to the Fifth Century<br />

B.C. (Amsterdam, 1989).<br />

507<br />

Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 52 translates the term as “filled up.” Similarly, Sheets,<br />

Herodotus, Book 1 34, traces plh&santej to the verb pi/mplhmi, which means “to fill.”<br />

269


establishes more than one zw|&dion, <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the fact that they were around the<br />

rim (peri\ to_ xei=loj) suggest a busy, cont<strong>in</strong>uous decoration, perhaps on the order <strong>of</strong> a<br />

frieze. In view <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the association <strong>of</strong> zw|di/wn with the realm <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e crafts<br />

appears to be firmly established.<br />

As stated earlier, the word zw|di/wn is considered to be the dim<strong>in</strong>utive <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. On<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, it is probably safe to assume that the decoration on the outer<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the rim <strong>of</strong> the krater consisted <strong>of</strong> “little zw|~a.” Not all modern translations <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|di/wn, however, take this aspect <strong>in</strong>to account. <strong>The</strong>y all agree on the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

term as someth<strong>in</strong>g other than animals; their majority <strong>in</strong>terprets it as “figures.” To this<br />

group belong How <strong>and</strong> Wells, Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, Sheets, <strong>and</strong> Godley. 508 <strong>The</strong> first<br />

two scholars clarify that these are “figures not <strong>of</strong> animals alone.” 509 In agreement with<br />

this suggestion are Blakesley <strong>and</strong> also Henry Woods, who both state that the word<br />

denotes figures <strong>of</strong> any k<strong>in</strong>d. 510 In susta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g his op<strong>in</strong>ion, Blakesley draws attention to<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> the artistic context <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word, <strong>and</strong> states that <strong>in</strong> the<br />

description <strong>of</strong> plastic or architectural works, zw|&dion means figure <strong>of</strong> any k<strong>in</strong>d. 511 Henry<br />

Woods appears to be more concerned with the dim<strong>in</strong>utive aspect <strong>of</strong> the term, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “the figures were not full size.” 512 Similarly, Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude this passage <strong>of</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> their discussion <strong>of</strong> the entry zw|&dion, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

which they translate as “small figure.” 513 Also the translation <strong>of</strong> the passage by Aubrey<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> John Mar<strong>in</strong>cola def<strong>in</strong>es zw|di/wn as “small figures” <strong>and</strong> so does that <strong>of</strong><br />

508<br />

How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus I 92; Macaulay <strong>and</strong> Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus<br />

26; Sheets, Herodotus Book I 3; Godley, Herodotus I 85.<br />

509<br />

How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus I 92.<br />

510<br />

Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 52; H. G. Woods, Herodotus Book I (London <strong>and</strong> Oxford,<br />

1873) 58.<br />

511<br />

Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary 52.<br />

512<br />

Woods, Herodotus Book 1 58.<br />

513 9<br />

LSJ , 758, s.v. zw|&dion.<br />

270


Grene, who says “little figures.” 514 Powell, <strong>in</strong> contrast, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that zw|&dion means<br />

“picture,” 515 <strong>and</strong> so does Waterfield, who translates these zw|di/wn as “pictures.” 516<br />

<strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|di/wn has not been discussed <strong>in</strong>dependently from speculations<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g the technique <strong>of</strong> their manufacture. In their reference to Herodotus’ passage,<br />

Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott, for example, po<strong>in</strong>t out that zw|di/wn should be def<strong>in</strong>ed as pa<strong>in</strong>ted or<br />

carved figures. 517 In addition, Godley underst<strong>and</strong>s the term to mean figures that were<br />

graven, perhaps carved or engraved, on the rim <strong>of</strong> the krater. 518 <strong>The</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> a specific<br />

term with<strong>in</strong> the passage that supports this technical aspect <strong>of</strong> zw|di/wn, <strong>and</strong> the dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

silence <strong>of</strong> Godley on the matter suggest that he considered this aspect a factor that<br />

partook <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term. Similarly, How <strong>and</strong> Wells, who also underst<strong>and</strong><br />

zw|di/wn to mean figures, draw attention to the technique employed for their manufacture<br />

by suggest<strong>in</strong>g that they are figures <strong>in</strong> relief. 519 As with Godley, however, these authors<br />

provide no correspond<strong>in</strong>g term to this specific technique, which implies that they also<br />

saw the latter as be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>corporated <strong>in</strong>to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term.<br />

Herodotus’ krater <strong>and</strong> its zw|&dia have been at the center <strong>of</strong> a search for<br />

archaeological parallels. Andreas Rumpf was the first scholar (1954; 1957) to identify<br />

this krater as a volute krater <strong>of</strong> the Vix type. 520 <strong>The</strong> latter refers to a bronze volute krater<br />

<strong>of</strong> exceptional size (1.63m high; 1.27m diameter <strong>of</strong> body; 1m. diameter <strong>of</strong> mouth; 208.6<br />

kg weight) <strong>and</strong> craftsmanship that was found <strong>in</strong> 1953 <strong>in</strong> a fifth-century, Celtic tomb at the<br />

514<br />

De Sél<strong>in</strong>court <strong>and</strong> Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories 31; Grene, <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus 65.<br />

515<br />

Powell, A Lexicon to Herodotus 159, s.v. zw|&dion.<br />

516<br />

R. Waterfield, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1997) 31.<br />

517 9<br />

LSJ , 758, s.v. zw|&dion.<br />

518<br />

Godley, Herodotus 1 85.<br />

519<br />

How <strong>and</strong> Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus 92.<br />

520<br />

A. Rumpf, “Zum Krater von Vix,” BABesch 29 (1954) 10-11; also “Krath&r Lakwniko&j,” <strong>in</strong><br />

Schauenburg, ed., Charites 131.<br />

271


village <strong>of</strong> Vix <strong>in</strong> France (Fig. 25). 521 This krater has been considered an imported Greek<br />

product <strong>of</strong> the sixth century B.C., but issues, such as its exact location <strong>of</strong> manufacture<br />

<strong>and</strong> date are still debated. 522 Its neck is decorated with a cont<strong>in</strong>uous frieze <strong>of</strong> appliqué<br />

relief figures, that is, figures with flat reverse sides fastened by rivets to the neck. 523<br />

<strong>The</strong>y depict hoplites on foot, <strong>and</strong> four-horse chariots with their charioteers <strong>in</strong> a<br />

procession. <strong>The</strong> backs <strong>of</strong> these figures are marked with Greek letters, a recognized<br />

method for their correct position<strong>in</strong>g on the vessel. 524 Rumpf considered these decorative<br />

elements partial evidence for suggest<strong>in</strong>g that the krater described by Herodotus was <strong>of</strong><br />

identical appearance. 525 Despite René J<strong>of</strong>froy’s warn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> 1954 that “it would be rash to<br />

see <strong>in</strong> the krater from Vix the present <strong>of</strong> the Lacaedemonians to Croesus,” Rumpf’s<br />

521 For the most recent discussion <strong>and</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> the krater from Vix, see C. Rolley, La tombe pr<strong>in</strong>cière<br />

de Vix (Paris, 2003) 77-90; also 90-106 for a catalogue <strong>of</strong> all the well-preserved bronze volute kraters <strong>and</strong><br />

parts <strong>of</strong> them found <strong>in</strong> Greek sites, such as Olympia, Delphi, <strong>and</strong> Athens. For earlier discussions <strong>of</strong> the Vix<br />

krater, see R. J<strong>of</strong>froy, Le Trésor de Vix (Côte d’Or) (Paris, 1954) 6; also Rolley, Greek Bronzes 146, fig.<br />

129, where he expla<strong>in</strong>s that “the body <strong>and</strong> the neck are hammered <strong>in</strong> one piece; the two parts <strong>of</strong> the rim, the<br />

h<strong>and</strong>les, <strong>and</strong> the appliqué decoration on the neck <strong>and</strong> possibly also the foot are cast”: for a brief discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the complex mathematics <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the design <strong>of</strong> the krater, see Vickers <strong>and</strong> Gill, Artful Crafts 190, n.<br />

223.<br />

522 <strong>The</strong>re are three major theses regard<strong>in</strong>g the place <strong>of</strong> manufacture <strong>of</strong> the Vix krater: 1) Laconia, 2) South<br />

Italy, 3) Cor<strong>in</strong>th, <strong>and</strong> two regard<strong>in</strong>g its date: 1) 570-560 B.C., 2) 530-520 B.C. <strong>The</strong> thesis <strong>of</strong> Laconian<br />

manufacture is advocated by Stibbe, Laconian Mix<strong>in</strong>g Bowls 63-67, who dates the Vix krater to 570-560<br />

B.C. <strong>and</strong> attributes it to a Laconian workshop. He also stresses the close relationship between Laconian<br />

fictile <strong>and</strong> bronze kraters. Rolley, Greek Bronzes 150, dates the krater between 530 <strong>and</strong> 520 B.C.,<br />

considers it “<strong>in</strong>separable from” two hydrias found <strong>in</strong> Paestum <strong>and</strong> Sala Consil<strong>in</strong>a, <strong>and</strong> therefore attributes it<br />

to a South Italian workshop located perhaps <strong>in</strong> Sybaris; also Les vases des bronze de l’ archaïsme recent en<br />

Gr<strong>and</strong>e Grèce (Naples, 1982). For a most recent summary <strong>of</strong> these oppos<strong>in</strong>g theses <strong>and</strong> updated<br />

bibliography on the debate, see C. M. Stibbe, “<strong>The</strong> Krater from Vix Aga<strong>in</strong>: A Review Article,” <strong>in</strong> C. M.<br />

Stibbe, “Agalmata. Studien zur griechisch-archaischen Bronzekunst,” (BABesch Suppl. 11; Dudley, 2006)<br />

310-321. <strong>The</strong> hypothesis <strong>of</strong> a Cor<strong>in</strong>thian orig<strong>in</strong> was advanced by M. Gjødesen, “Greek Bronzes: A Review<br />

Article,” AJA 67 (1963) 333-351. For a list <strong>of</strong> additional scholars, each <strong>of</strong> whom adheres to one or another<br />

thesis, see S. Hodk<strong>in</strong>son, “Laconian Artistic Production <strong>and</strong> the Problem <strong>of</strong> Spartan Austerity,” <strong>in</strong> N.<br />

Fischer <strong>and</strong> H. van Wees, eds., Archaic <strong>Greece</strong>: New Approaches <strong>and</strong> New Evidence (London, 1998) 103,<br />

n. 24.<br />

523 Rolley, La tombe pr<strong>in</strong>cière de Vix 79-83, pls. 8-11, <strong>and</strong> Greek Bronzes 146, fig. 129, where he refers to<br />

the decoration <strong>of</strong> the frieze as “appliqué”; also J<strong>of</strong>froy, Le Trésor de Vix 11, 21.<br />

524 Rolley, La tombe pr<strong>in</strong>cière de Vix 87-88.<br />

525 It has to be mentioned that the decoration <strong>of</strong> the frieze played only a partial, but still supportive, role <strong>in</strong><br />

Rumpf’s identification <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ krater as that <strong>of</strong> the Vix-type. Rumpf, “Krath&r Lakwniko&j,” <strong>in</strong><br />

Schauenburg, ed., Charites 131, went much further, especially <strong>in</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g the hold<strong>in</strong>g capacity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

krater described by Herodotus with that <strong>of</strong> the krater from Vix. <strong>The</strong> latter has a capacity <strong>of</strong> 1200 litres,<br />

whereas that <strong>of</strong> the one described by Herodotus, he estimated to be 7800 litres.<br />

272


theory has dom<strong>in</strong>ated scholarship. 526 As Conrad Stibbe has recently (2006) remarked,<br />

Rumpf’s idea that the krater <strong>of</strong> the Spartans was a volute krater <strong>of</strong> the Vix type, has met<br />

general acceptance “because the [zw|&dia] ‘figures’ <strong>of</strong> Herodotus would correspond to the<br />

[appliqué relief] figures on the neck <strong>of</strong> the krater from Vix.” 527 Although dom<strong>in</strong>ant, this<br />

is not the only <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ zw|&dia. In 1961, Emil Kunze suggested that<br />

they could be figures <strong>in</strong> the round. 528 In 1991, however, Werner Gauer cautioned that on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>formation provided by Herodotus it is impossible to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether<br />

the zw|&dia <strong>of</strong> his krater were produced <strong>in</strong> relief or <strong>in</strong> the round, or if the vessel was<br />

identical to that found <strong>in</strong> the tomb from Vix. 529 Recently (2006), Stibbe revived the<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> Herodotus’ zw|&dia be<strong>in</strong>g appliqué relief figures like those on the Vix krater by<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that the phrase e1cwqen peri\ to_ xei=loj (“outside <strong>and</strong> around the rim,”) that<br />

Herodotus uses to <strong>in</strong>dicate the position <strong>of</strong> the zw|&dia supports their identification as relief<br />

figures. If Herodotus was th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> figures <strong>in</strong> the round, Stibbe asserts, he would have<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead said upon (a1nwqen) the rim. 530<br />

Apart from the krater from Vix, additional evidence <strong>of</strong> bronze kraters with<br />

appliqué relief decoration comes from two sixth-century examples found at the<br />

526<br />

J<strong>of</strong>froy, Le Trésor de Vix 22: “Il serait téméraire de voir dans le cratére de Vix le présent des<br />

Lacédémoniens à Crésus.”<br />

527<br />

Stibbe, “<strong>The</strong> Krater from Vix Aga<strong>in</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> Stibbe, Agalmata 314.<br />

528<br />

E. Kunze, “Kle<strong>in</strong>plastik aus Bronze,” <strong>in</strong> E. Kunze, et al., VII. Bericht über die Ausgrabungen <strong>in</strong><br />

Olympia (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1961) 174, n. 68.<br />

529<br />

W. Gauer, Die Bronzegefässe von Olympia (Olympische Forschungen 20; Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> New York, 1991)<br />

129.<br />

530<br />

C. M. Stibbe, “<strong>The</strong> Krater from Vix Aga<strong>in</strong>” <strong>in</strong> Stibbe, Agalmata 315, n. 43. Although not explicitly<br />

stated by Stibbe, his contrast between the words e1cwqen <strong>and</strong> a1nwqen appears to be <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the<br />

appearance <strong>of</strong> the latter <strong>in</strong> Athenaeus’ description <strong>of</strong> two gold Cor<strong>in</strong>thian craters paraded <strong>in</strong> the gr<strong>and</strong><br />

procession <strong>of</strong> Ptolemy II Philadelphus at Alex<strong>and</strong>ria. Athenaeus, whose description is excerpted from the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> third-century Kallixenos <strong>of</strong> Rhodes entitled About Alex<strong>and</strong>ria, states that the craters had on their<br />

upper part (a1nwqen) zw|~a seated <strong>in</strong> the round <strong>of</strong> beaten metal (kaqh&mena perifanh~ tetoreume/na),<br />

<strong>and</strong> on the necks <strong>and</strong> bellies, carefully executed pro&stupa” (Deipn. 5.199e). E. E. Rice, <strong>The</strong> Gr<strong>and</strong><br />

Procession <strong>of</strong> Ptolemy Philadelphus (Oxford, 1983) 140-15, translates these zw|~a as “figures,” <strong>and</strong><br />

pro&stupa as “figures <strong>in</strong> low relief.”<br />

273


necropolis <strong>of</strong> Trebenishte, but <strong>of</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> manufacture, <strong>and</strong> also from a sixth-<br />

century, bronze appliqué relief figure <strong>of</strong> a man found <strong>in</strong> Edessa <strong>and</strong> thought to have been<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the decoration <strong>of</strong> a Laconian krater. 531 Dated to 560-550 B.C., the first krater<br />

from Trebenishte was found <strong>in</strong> a tomb (no. I) <strong>in</strong> 1918. 532 It is a volute krater similar to<br />

that from Vix, but <strong>of</strong> smaller size (e.g., 68cm high) (Fig. 26). 533 Its neck is decorated<br />

with a cont<strong>in</strong>uous frieze <strong>of</strong> five appliqué relief figures <strong>of</strong> cows that walk to the right. 534<br />

One side <strong>of</strong> the neck bears three cows, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g that the other side, which<br />

currently bears only two, had orig<strong>in</strong>ally three. Like the appliqué figures on the Vix<br />

krater, Greek letter<strong>in</strong>g on the back <strong>of</strong> these cows <strong>in</strong>dicates the same method for correctly<br />

position<strong>in</strong>g them on the neck. 535 Where exactly this krater was orig<strong>in</strong>ally manufactured<br />

is a topic <strong>of</strong> scholarly debate; Cor<strong>in</strong>th, Laconia, <strong>and</strong> South Italy have all been considered<br />

potential c<strong>and</strong>idates. 536<br />

<strong>The</strong> second bronze volute krater from Trebenishte was found <strong>in</strong> a tomb (no.<br />

VIII) <strong>in</strong> 1930 <strong>and</strong> has been dated to around 500 B.C. (Fig. 27). 537 Ow<strong>in</strong>g to its poor state<br />

<strong>of</strong> preservation <strong>and</strong> subsequent heavy restoration, its exact height has not been securely<br />

established, but its size has been thought to be similar to that <strong>of</strong> the previous krater from<br />

Trebenishte. 538 Each side <strong>of</strong> its neck is decorated with two appliqué relief figures <strong>of</strong><br />

531<br />

For a recent account <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> excavations at the necropolis <strong>of</strong> Trebenishte, see M. C. Stibbe,<br />

Trebenishte. <strong>The</strong> Fortunes <strong>of</strong> an Unusual Excavation (Studia Archaeologica 121; Rome, 2003).<br />

532<br />

B. D. Filow, Die archaische Nekropole von Trebenischte am Ochrida-See (Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Leipzig, 1927)<br />

39-47 (S<strong>of</strong>ia, NM no <strong>in</strong>ventory number).<br />

533<br />

Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 59, n. 14.<br />

534<br />

Stibbe, Trebenishte 75-78, figs. 33-37.<br />

535<br />

For both the suggestion that these cows were the work <strong>of</strong> two different artists, <strong>and</strong> also the letter<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

their backs, see Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 59, n. 16.<br />

536<br />

For these suggestions, see Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 63.<br />

537<br />

N. Vulić, “Das neue Grab von Trebenishte,” JdI 45 (1930) 299 (Belgrade, NM 174/1).<br />

538<br />

Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 88, n. 156.<br />

274


iders on horses that gallop to the right. 539 Variations <strong>in</strong> the treatments <strong>of</strong> both horses <strong>and</strong><br />

riders have led to the suggestion that more than one artist was at work. 540 This<br />

suggestion has been, <strong>in</strong> turn, central to the scholarly debate regard<strong>in</strong>g the possible<br />

Laconian or Cor<strong>in</strong>thian orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the second krater from Trebenishte. 541<br />

<strong>The</strong> third example <strong>of</strong> appliqué relief decoration on bronze kraters is a small (18.3<br />

cm tall) bronze relief figure <strong>of</strong> a bearded warrior <strong>in</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> putt<strong>in</strong>g on his greaves<br />

that was found <strong>in</strong> Edessa (Fig. 28). 542 <strong>The</strong> figure has a flat reverse side <strong>and</strong> preserves the<br />

holes used for rivet<strong>in</strong>g it to a background, most likely, the neck <strong>of</strong> a bronze volute<br />

Laconian krater produced around 540 B.C. 543<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence from these examples <strong>and</strong> from the Vix krater <strong>in</strong>dicates that add<strong>in</strong>g<br />

decorative elements <strong>of</strong> various subjects by means <strong>of</strong> rivets to the frieze-like necks <strong>of</strong><br />

bronze kraters was a usual technique favored by sixth-century bronze-smiths. If one<br />

were, therefore, to identify Herodotus’ zw|&dia with these decorative elements, the fact<br />

that the latter refer to humans (hoplites, charioteers, riders, warrior), animals (horses,<br />

cows), <strong>and</strong> also lifeless objects (chariots) suggests that Herodotus’ zw|&dia could be<br />

understood as both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate representational subjects applied to bronze<br />

vessels as relief decoration.<br />

539 Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 89-90, fig. 56, <strong>and</strong> 94, fig. 61, also 122, n. 87.<br />

540 As Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 90, n. 160 po<strong>in</strong>ts out, “the mane <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the horses is pla<strong>in</strong>, whereas<br />

the other horses have vertically notched neck manes.” Also, none <strong>of</strong> the heads <strong>of</strong> the riders is identical to<br />

any other. <strong>The</strong> first has a squarish face with wide eyes, the second has a triangular face with small eyes,<br />

the third has a broad <strong>and</strong> angular head, whereas the fourth one “is dist<strong>in</strong>guished by its broad round head.”<br />

541 Stibbe, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos 90-91.<br />

542 Stibbe, Trebenishte 95, n. 19 (Athens, NM 7550); see, also S. Karouzou, “ΤΕΧΝΟΥΡΓΟΙ<br />

ΚΡΑΤΗΡΩΝ: Fragmente bronzeren Volutenkratere,” AM 94 (1979) 79-80. Its exact provenance <strong>and</strong> date<br />

<strong>of</strong> discovery are uncerta<strong>in</strong>. One <strong>of</strong> the earliest reference to it is G. P. Oikonomos, “Bronzen von Pella,” AM<br />

51 (1926) 87-88, who mentions that the figure was found by M. Dimitsas, <strong>and</strong> cites an earlier reference: A.<br />

De Ridder, Catalogue des bronzes de la société archaeologique d’Athènes (1889) 103.<br />

543 Stibbe, Trebenishte 94-95, 105, fig. 63; also Karouzou, “ΤΕΧΝΟΥΡΓΟΙ ΚΡΑΤΗΡΩΝ” 79-80, pl. 15,<br />

figs. 1-3, where the flatness <strong>of</strong> the reverse side <strong>and</strong> the holes for the rivets are clearly visible.<br />

275


B. Inscriptions<br />

<strong>The</strong> fifth century is also the period when both the words zw|~on <strong>and</strong> its dim<strong>in</strong>utive<br />

zw|&dion appear for the first time <strong>in</strong> the epigraphical record. <strong>The</strong> words occur <strong>in</strong> direct<br />

association with architectural sculpture <strong>and</strong> carry the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> both<br />

animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from the real world. In addition to this mean<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

zw|&dion is used <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions to refer to the dist<strong>in</strong>ct method <strong>of</strong> attach<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture by rivets to a background. As <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the literary texts, the <strong>in</strong>scriptions<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicate that the term zw|~on <strong>in</strong>dicated the absence <strong>of</strong> a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong><br />

subject.<br />

Erechtheion<br />

<strong>The</strong> earliest epigraphical attestation <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the fifth century is <strong>in</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion on the Athenian Acropolis. <strong>The</strong>se accounts, which were<br />

<strong>in</strong>scribed on marble stelai, date from 409/8 to 406/5 B.C., <strong>and</strong> detail the state <strong>of</strong> the<br />

unf<strong>in</strong>ished parts <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> expenditures for their completion. 544<br />

A fragment <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> these stelai—also known as the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele—bears an<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription that identifies its date as that <strong>of</strong> the first prytany <strong>of</strong> the year 409/8 B.C. 545 <strong>The</strong><br />

544<br />

L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum (Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 277-<br />

422; also IG I 3 .474-479.<br />

545<br />

For the date <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele identified as that <strong>of</strong> the archonship <strong>of</strong> Diokles <strong>in</strong> 409/8 B.C., see<br />

Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 283. Caskey (277-321) expla<strong>in</strong>s that the<br />

Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele comprises six different fragments, which <strong>in</strong> his discussion are given the numbers II-VII (IG<br />

I 3 .474.2). Fragments II, III, IV, <strong>and</strong> VA are on the obverse <strong>of</strong> the stele, whereas fragments VB <strong>and</strong> VII are<br />

on the reverse. Fragment II, which is the largest (1.08 m. high, 0.505 m. wide, <strong>and</strong> 0.09 m. thick) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

one discussed here, was found by Richard Ch<strong>and</strong>ler built <strong>in</strong>to the steps <strong>of</strong> a house on the Acropolis <strong>in</strong> 1765.<br />

Ch<strong>and</strong>ler took it to Engl<strong>and</strong> for the Society <strong>of</strong> the Dilettanti <strong>and</strong> later presented it to the British Museum:<br />

Caskey, 283; also Ferrari, “<strong>The</strong> Ancient Temple on the Acropolis at Athens,” AJA 106 (2002) 18, n. 48.<br />

Fragment III was found between the Erechtheion <strong>and</strong> the Parthenon: Caskey, 281; Fragment III was “found<br />

<strong>in</strong> [an] excavation on the Acropolis <strong>in</strong> 1836 (Ross) <strong>and</strong> re-discovered between the Erechtheum <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Parthenon <strong>in</strong> 1838 (Pittakis)”: Caskey, 284; Fragments IV, V, <strong>and</strong> VI are <strong>of</strong> unknown provenance: Caskey,<br />

276


<strong>in</strong>scription is <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> a head<strong>in</strong>g followed by a text arranged <strong>in</strong> two columns. <strong>The</strong><br />

head<strong>in</strong>g (l<strong>in</strong>es 1-7) records the names <strong>of</strong> a board <strong>of</strong> commissioners <strong>and</strong> their appo<strong>in</strong>tment<br />

to compile a report on the state <strong>of</strong> construction <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> columnar text details<br />

the <strong>in</strong>complete parts <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> the materials ly<strong>in</strong>g on the site <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ventoried by<br />

the commissioners. <strong>The</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the first column (l<strong>in</strong>es 8-39) concerns unf<strong>in</strong>ished<br />

parts “<strong>of</strong> the temple” (l<strong>in</strong>e 8), such as the wall blocks, wall-capital, <strong>and</strong> epistyle “at the<br />

corner towards the Cecropium” (l<strong>in</strong>e 9). 546 <strong>The</strong> text cont<strong>in</strong>ues with the follow<strong>in</strong>g four<br />

l<strong>in</strong>es:<br />

All the rest <strong>of</strong> the work round about beg<strong>in</strong>s<br />

with the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone aga<strong>in</strong>st which the<br />

zw~ia (are to be fastened), <strong>and</strong> three blocks <strong>of</strong> it<br />

have been placed under the present commissioners.<br />

(IG I 3 . 474 [fr. II, col. I, 40-43]) [85]<br />

Lacey Caskey translates the term zw~ia, which is the plural nom<strong>in</strong>ative <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, as<br />

“figures.” 547 <strong>The</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone aga<strong>in</strong>st which (pro&j w{i) these zw~ia were to be<br />

placed has been identified with the bluish-black limestone <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> both the cella<br />

<strong>and</strong> the north porch <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion, specifically, its smooth background blocks. 548 Of<br />

284, 285 <strong>and</strong> 319 respectively; Fragment VII was found <strong>in</strong> an excavation east <strong>of</strong> the Propylaea on the<br />

Acropolis <strong>in</strong> 1835: Caskey, 319.<br />

546 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 301, identifies the corner <strong>of</strong> the temple<br />

towards the Cecropium with the southwest corner <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion, on the basis <strong>of</strong> evidence that, <strong>in</strong> other<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription (col. I, 58, 63, 83), the Porch <strong>of</strong> the Maidens, which is built aga<strong>in</strong>st the west end <strong>of</strong><br />

its south wall, is referred to as the prostasis that looks “towards the Cecropium.” On the basis <strong>of</strong> additional<br />

literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical evidence, Ferrari, “<strong>The</strong> Ancient Temple” 21, underst<strong>and</strong>s the reference <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription to the corner <strong>of</strong> the temple towards the Cecropium to mean the northwestern corner <strong>of</strong> the<br />

archaic temple <strong>of</strong> Athena Polias, which has been identified with the poros temple discovered by Wilhelm<br />

Dörpfeld <strong>in</strong> 1885 to the south <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. Central to Ferrari’s thesis is the argument, 17, that the<br />

P<strong>and</strong>roseum, Cecropium, <strong>and</strong> Erechtheion were parts <strong>of</strong> the temenos <strong>of</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> Athena Polias, which<br />

was sacked <strong>in</strong> the Persian attack <strong>of</strong> 480 B.C., but once repaired, cont<strong>in</strong>ued to st<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> function until the<br />

second century A.D., when Pausanias (1.27.1) described it; based on this argument, she suggests, 21, that<br />

the Erechtheion was “an ornate <strong>and</strong> elegant appendage to the temple <strong>of</strong> the Polias.”<br />

547 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 289.<br />

548 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the dark stone used for the blocks that formed the background <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion, see J. M. Paton, “Notes on the Construction <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed, <strong>The</strong><br />

Erechtheum 181, n. 4; L. T. Shoe, “Dark Stone <strong>in</strong> Greek Architecture,” Hesperia Supplement 8 (1949) 347-<br />

348; also B. S. Ridgway, Prayers <strong>in</strong> Stone. Greek Architectural <strong>Sculpture</strong> Ca. 600-100 B.C. (Berkeley,<br />

277


considerable importance is the phrase pro&j w{i, whose translation as “aga<strong>in</strong>st this stone,”<br />

suggests that zw~ia, whose position it def<strong>in</strong>es, were some type <strong>of</strong> decoration separated<br />

from, <strong>and</strong> therefore, not carved out <strong>of</strong> the same blocks that formed the background <strong>of</strong> the<br />

frieze. 549 That this was actually the case is confirmed by the surviv<strong>in</strong>g material, which<br />

refers to the blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze, fragmentary sculpture, <strong>and</strong> also technical details<br />

preserved on both types <strong>of</strong> evidence.<br />

1999) 118 <strong>and</strong> 128, where she states that the use <strong>of</strong> such dark stone “had the primary architectural function<br />

not only <strong>of</strong> connect<strong>in</strong>g prostyle columns <strong>and</strong> cella, but also <strong>of</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g specific levels <strong>in</strong> a build<strong>in</strong>g<br />

unusual for its irregular plan, both <strong>in</strong>ternal <strong>and</strong> external.” For an illustration <strong>of</strong> the position <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong><br />

the Erechtheion that emphasizes the dark color <strong>of</strong> its background blocks, see Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Architecture<br />

<strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Cambridge, Mass., 2006) 122, fig. 109.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to H. N. Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 232, a frieze ran around all<br />

sides <strong>of</strong> the cella, except for a portion <strong>of</strong> the northern wall, where it was <strong>in</strong>terrupted by the ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the north<br />

porch. A frieze covered also all the exterior walls <strong>of</strong> the north portico <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g its peculiar southern side,<br />

which corresponded to a short section that projected to the west <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong>se essentially two<br />

friezes were not identical <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> size. As Fowler, 239, states “the height <strong>of</strong> the blocks <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone which formed the frieze about the cella is 0.617m., that <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the north portico<br />

0.683m.” Regard<strong>in</strong>g the blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze over the cella only small sections <strong>of</strong> them survive today.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Fowler, 240, the most complete section is that <strong>of</strong> the eastern side <strong>and</strong> a short distance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

eastern part <strong>of</strong> the southern side, both <strong>of</strong> which sum up to a total length <strong>of</strong> about 14 m. Similarly, J. M.<br />

Paton et al., “Description <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 54, po<strong>in</strong>t out that only two<br />

blocks are now <strong>in</strong> place at the southeast corner, whereas “the frieze from both [the] north <strong>and</strong> south walls<br />

has wholly disappeared.” As for the orig<strong>in</strong>al blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze at the western end <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g, they<br />

were damaged by fire <strong>in</strong> the first century B.C., <strong>and</strong> subsequently replaced with reused statue bases also<br />

made <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone. As Fowler, 240, n. 1, expla<strong>in</strong>s, these replacements “are old statue bases, with the<br />

tops turned toward the <strong>in</strong>terior <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong>se tops show the foot marks <strong>of</strong> the statues which once<br />

stood on them, but the outer surfaces are pla<strong>in</strong>.” For a recent illustration <strong>of</strong> these bases form<strong>in</strong>g a section <strong>of</strong><br />

the frieze <strong>of</strong> the western wall <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g, see O. Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong> O. Palagia ed., Greek<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong>: Function, Materials, Techniques <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Periods (Cambridge, 2006) 143,<br />

fig. 47. As for the background blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze over the north porch, Fowler, 241, expla<strong>in</strong>s that “the<br />

entire length <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the North Portico was about 25 m., <strong>and</strong> about 21 m. <strong>of</strong> the dark blocks now<br />

exist. Those blocks are now, with the exception <strong>of</strong> a few fragments, secured <strong>in</strong> their proper places on the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g.” He also clarifies, 241, n. 1, that “the place <strong>of</strong> the miss<strong>in</strong>g blocks is supplied by blocks <strong>of</strong> bluish<br />

“upper Pentelic” marble.” Pictures <strong>of</strong> the latest restoration (1976-1986) <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion, which aimed at<br />

a wide-rang<strong>in</strong>g correction <strong>of</strong> an earlier erroneous one (1902-1909), show no changes <strong>in</strong> the arrangement <strong>of</strong><br />

the architectural members <strong>of</strong> the frieze as discussed by Fowler <strong>and</strong> Paton et al. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this<br />

restoration <strong>and</strong> accompany<strong>in</strong>g illustrations, see C. Bouras <strong>and</strong> K. Zambas, <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> the Committee for<br />

the Preservation <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis Monuments on the Acropolis <strong>of</strong> Athens (Athens, 2002) 24-27, figs. 34-41.<br />

549 This technique had been used earlier for the decoration <strong>of</strong> the frieze on the base—made also <strong>of</strong><br />

Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone—<strong>of</strong> the cult statues <strong>of</strong> Athena <strong>and</strong> Hephaistos at the Hephaisteion made by Alkamenes<br />

<strong>and</strong> completed around 415 B.C.: For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this base, see O. Palagia, “Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Narrative<br />

Techniques <strong>in</strong> Statue-Bases <strong>of</strong> the Pheidian Circle,” <strong>in</strong> N. K. Rutter <strong>and</strong> B. A. Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong><br />

Image <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh, 2000) 53 <strong>and</strong> 55, where the similarity with the Erechtheion frieze is<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ted out; also 55, fig. 4.1 for an illustration <strong>of</strong> a block <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian limestone that has been attributed to<br />

the front <strong>of</strong> the base <strong>of</strong> this statue <strong>and</strong> carries five dowel holes for the attachment <strong>of</strong> figures.<br />

278


<strong>The</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g blocks that form the background <strong>of</strong> the frieze rest on a widened<br />

epistyle 550 <strong>and</strong> carry holes <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that someth<strong>in</strong>g was fastened to them by means <strong>of</strong><br />

dowels. 551 In addition, holes exist <strong>in</strong> the top surface <strong>of</strong> the epistyle <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g was fastened there as well. 552 Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the extant sculpture, marble<br />

fragments are all that survive today. 553 Some <strong>of</strong> these fragments have flat bottom sides<br />

550<br />

Paton et al., “Description,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 24: “A scratch l<strong>in</strong>e on the top <strong>of</strong> the epistyle<br />

marks the position <strong>of</strong> the frieze, which was set 0.054 m. back <strong>of</strong> the upper fascia <strong>of</strong> the epistyle”; also<br />

Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 239, fig. 150, presents a reconstructed view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

position <strong>of</strong> the epistyle, frieze, <strong>and</strong> cornice <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> further ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that those portions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

epistyle that were covered with decoration, which he identifies as sculpture, exhibit a lesser degree <strong>of</strong><br />

weather<strong>in</strong>g than those that were not. <strong>The</strong> same idea is also expressed by P. N. Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion,” AP 10 (1970) 7 <strong>and</strong> 20, who mentions that “the architrave was widened somewhat to<br />

accommodate the bases [<strong>of</strong> pieces <strong>of</strong> sculpture].”<br />

551<br />

For an illustration <strong>of</strong> the shape <strong>of</strong> the dowels used, see Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Erechtheum 195, fig. 120, <strong>and</strong> pls. III, IV, V, VI, XXI, <strong>and</strong> LXVI for the positions <strong>of</strong> the dowel holes <strong>in</strong> the<br />

blocks <strong>of</strong> the background. Us<strong>in</strong>g the frieze <strong>of</strong> the north porch as an example, Fowler, 242, pls. VI, XXI,<br />

XLVI, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “<strong>in</strong> the exist<strong>in</strong>g dark blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> this porch (about 21 m. <strong>in</strong> length) there<br />

are 59 dowel holes, not <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g several small round holes which may have served for fasten<strong>in</strong>g<br />

attributes.” He also states, 242, that each piece <strong>of</strong> sculpture “was fastened to the background by a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

dowel,” <strong>and</strong> 243, that “the dowels were fixed <strong>in</strong> the holes with lead.” Regard<strong>in</strong>g the study <strong>of</strong> holes on the<br />

stone blocks, he says, 242, n. 3, that “the average distance between the dowel holes is 0.536 m., <strong>and</strong> the<br />

average number <strong>of</strong> holes per meter is 2.81 m.” On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, he estimates that the frieze <strong>of</strong><br />

the north porch (total length ca. 25 m.) consisted <strong>of</strong> about 70 dowel holes that corresponded to a total <strong>of</strong> 70<br />

pieces <strong>of</strong> sculpture. He does caution, however, that match<strong>in</strong>g the dowel holes <strong>in</strong> the blocks to those <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fragments does not lead to an accurate reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the frieze because exact correspondence <strong>in</strong> the<br />

measurements <strong>of</strong> the holes cannot be expected. Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 8, n. 6, agrees<br />

with Fowler’s conclusion; therefore, she considers his estimate <strong>of</strong> 70 pieces <strong>of</strong> sculpture for the frieze <strong>of</strong><br />

the north porch accurate. As for the overall spac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> these pieces, Fowler, 245, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that “the<br />

positions <strong>of</strong> the dowel holes <strong>in</strong> the background show that the space was well filled without overcrowd<strong>in</strong>g.”<br />

552<br />

Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 243, n. 4; also Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion” 20.<br />

553<br />

Although not everyone is so sure <strong>of</strong> marble identifications, both K. Glowacki, “A New Fragment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion Frieze,” Hesperia 64 (1995) 325, <strong>and</strong> Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 7, identify the<br />

marble <strong>of</strong> these fragments as Pentelic. Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong> Palagia, ed., Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 142, n.<br />

193, clarifies that the fragments “<strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion frieze are usually described as made <strong>of</strong> Pentelic<br />

marble. <strong>The</strong>y are <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> Parian marble with a few exceptionally made <strong>of</strong> Pentelic, such as Acr[opolis]<br />

Mus[eum] 1071,” which depicts two female figures. She attributes this phenomenon to the possibility that<br />

“the contractors ran out <strong>of</strong> Parian marble <strong>and</strong> were obliged to use Pentelic near the end <strong>of</strong> the project.”<br />

None <strong>of</strong> the extant sculpture was discovered <strong>in</strong> its orig<strong>in</strong>al sett<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> as Glowacki, 326, po<strong>in</strong>ts out, one <strong>of</strong><br />

the major problems associated with the study <strong>of</strong> these fragments is the lack <strong>of</strong> their recorded provenience.<br />

Eighteenth-century draw<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion (Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum pls. L-LII) show no sculpture<br />

associated with its frieze, thus provid<strong>in</strong>g the earliest illustrative evidence for the condition <strong>of</strong> this part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g. In addition, it is not clear whether the west side <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the cella, which was destroyed by<br />

fire <strong>in</strong> the first century B.C., was supplied with sculpture after its restoration. As Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 240, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, the replaced blocks on this side bear no evidence <strong>of</strong> dowel<br />

holes for the attachment <strong>of</strong> sculpture. Some <strong>of</strong> the surviv<strong>in</strong>g sculpture, however, has been considered to be<br />

<strong>of</strong> Roman workmanship, despite its close imitation <strong>of</strong> fifth-century style, <strong>and</strong> therefore, features<br />

prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> discussions <strong>of</strong> this side <strong>of</strong> the frieze. For such a discussion, see B. S. Ridgway, Fifth-<br />

279


pierced <strong>in</strong> some cases by dowel holes, while some others have flat backs also pierced by<br />

dowel holes. <strong>The</strong>se technical characteristics suggest that the larger sculptures to which<br />

these fragments <strong>in</strong>itially belonged were placed on <strong>and</strong> attached to a flat surface, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

placed aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>and</strong> attached to a flat background. 554 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this evidence, which<br />

Century Styles <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1981) 93, who is careful not to equate this sculpture with that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the west cella; for two examples <strong>of</strong> the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze, which are thought to be<br />

Roman replacements, ow<strong>in</strong>g to the deeply cut grooves <strong>of</strong> their drapery, <strong>and</strong> the “hard” appearance <strong>of</strong> their<br />

model<strong>in</strong>g, see Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 18-19, figs. 17-20; for the suggestion that “the<br />

restoration <strong>of</strong> the west frieze left it pla<strong>in</strong>,” see Palagia, 142-143, ns. 194-195.<br />

For an assembled bibliography <strong>of</strong> the earliest discussions <strong>of</strong> the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze, see Fowler, “<strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 241, n. 3. Fowler’s discussion, 246-276, although it enumerates<br />

a total <strong>of</strong> 112 fragments <strong>in</strong> addition to 12 uncerta<strong>in</strong> ones, does not state provenience for all <strong>of</strong> them. <strong>The</strong><br />

provenience, for example, <strong>of</strong> a fragment <strong>of</strong> a female figure, 249, no. 11, is conf<strong>in</strong>ed to the statement: “it is<br />

said to have been found <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> the north portico.” For the discovery <strong>of</strong> additional fragments follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Fowler’s publication, see O. Broneer, “Excavations on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis <strong>in</strong> Athens, 1931-<br />

1932,” Hesperia 2 (1933) 349-350, figs. 20-21; “Excavations on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis <strong>in</strong><br />

Athens, 1933-1934,” Hesperia 4 (1935) 138-140, figs. 24-29; “Discoveries on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Acropolis, 1938,” AJA 42 (1938) 445-450; also C. Koukouli, “Νέo Σύµπλεγµα από τη Ζωφόρο<br />

του Ερεχθείου,” ADeltion 22 (1967) 133-148. For discussions <strong>of</strong> selective parts <strong>of</strong> this material <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

some from Fowler’s study, see Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 7-28; also M. S. Brouskari,<br />

“Ζώδια Λαΐνεα. Nouvelles figures de la fries de l’ Erechtheion,” <strong>in</strong> M. Schmidt, ed., Kanon: Festschrift<br />

Ernst Berger zum 60. Geburtstag am 26. Februar 1988 gewidmet (Basel, 1988) 60-68. For a discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

the latest evidence <strong>and</strong> updated bibliography with special reference to studies <strong>of</strong> the reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

frieze, see Glowacki 325-331.<br />

554 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> these characteristics as central to the attribution <strong>of</strong> sculpture to the frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion, see Glowacki, “A New Fragment <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion Frieze” 325; for an example <strong>of</strong> a<br />

fragment whose under <strong>and</strong> back sides are both flat, see Glowacki, 326, AS 196, pl. 65. <strong>The</strong> fragment<br />

“depicts a Cor<strong>in</strong>thian helmet set upon a thick, f<strong>in</strong>ished mass, which was modeled to create a slightly<br />

undulat<strong>in</strong>g surface apparently <strong>in</strong>tended to represent stone.” As Glowacki remarks, 326, “the bottom surface<br />

is f<strong>in</strong>ished completely smooth, while the rear surface is flat <strong>and</strong> bears traces <strong>of</strong> a f<strong>in</strong>e-po<strong>in</strong>ted chisel.” For a<br />

fragment that preserves evidence for holes on its under surface (one 0.01 m. <strong>in</strong> diameter, <strong>and</strong> six smaller<br />

drill holes each 0.005 m. <strong>in</strong> diameter) see Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 257, no.<br />

52. This fragment preserves the feet <strong>and</strong> part <strong>of</strong> the area above them <strong>of</strong> a female figure that is dressed <strong>in</strong> a<br />

chiton <strong>and</strong> a himation <strong>and</strong> appears to walk slowly to her right. As Fowler, 326, <strong>in</strong>dicates, the larger hole<br />

conta<strong>in</strong>ed lead, which functioned as adhesive substance for the iron dowel used to attach the piece to the<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the epistyle. Regard<strong>in</strong>g the flat backs <strong>of</strong> the preserved fragments, Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion” 20, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that they “were all uniformly worked first with a medium po<strong>in</strong>t over the rough<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the block as it came from the quarry. But there is a great variety <strong>in</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> subsequent<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps because the work was left to assistants.” For example, the back <strong>of</strong> the fragmentary torso<br />

<strong>of</strong> a male figure—Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 18, no. AS 158, figs. 15-16—was worked with a<br />

f<strong>in</strong>e po<strong>in</strong>t. On the contrary, the back <strong>of</strong> a fragment preserv<strong>in</strong>g the lower portion <strong>of</strong> a female figure that is<br />

seated on a rock—Boulter 17, no. 12, pl. 28b, fig. 10—appears to have been “first worked with a coarse<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> then smoothed with a claw chisel.” In addition, the back <strong>of</strong> a fragment that depicts a seated<br />

female figure hold<strong>in</strong>g a boy on her lap—Boulter 13, no. 11, pls. 17-18, fig. 3, <strong>and</strong> 20—“was actually<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ished with an abrasive.” Regard<strong>in</strong>g examples <strong>of</strong> fragments that have a flat back <strong>and</strong> carry dowel holes,<br />

246, no. 1 <strong>of</strong> Fowler’s study (246) preserves part <strong>of</strong> the thigh <strong>and</strong> adjacent portions <strong>of</strong> a st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g figure<br />

draped with a himation. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Fowler, 246, “the flat surface at the back is dressed with a po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong><br />

chisel….<strong>and</strong> a dowel hole neatly wrought with a chisel is 0.17 m. from the lower edge.” F<strong>in</strong>ally, it should<br />

be mentioned that the presence <strong>of</strong> flat back <strong>and</strong>/or bottom sides <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> dowel holes are not the only<br />

280


suggests a dist<strong>in</strong>ctive technique <strong>of</strong> attachment—also evident on the holes <strong>in</strong> the<br />

background blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>and</strong> the top <strong>of</strong> the epistyle—these fragments have been<br />

attributed to the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. 555 Because <strong>of</strong> the flatness <strong>of</strong><br />

their bottom <strong>and</strong> back sides, <strong>and</strong> also the dowels used to secure them <strong>in</strong> position aga<strong>in</strong>st a<br />

background, these fragments have been referred to as appliqués, but their designation as<br />

sculptures <strong>in</strong> relief is not absent from scholarly discussions. 556 This po<strong>in</strong>t aside, the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> these fragments is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it constitutes material evidence that can<br />

help decipher the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele.<br />

<strong>The</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion is unknown, but the fragments <strong>of</strong><br />

sculpture attributed to it show a variety <strong>of</strong> representations. 557 <strong>The</strong>y depict men, women<br />

<strong>and</strong> children <strong>in</strong> different poses—runn<strong>in</strong>g, sitt<strong>in</strong>g, st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g— natural features (e.g., rocks,<br />

tree trunks), animals (e.g., horses), <strong>and</strong> objects (e.g., chairs, helmets). 558 In particular, the<br />

characteristics on the basis <strong>of</strong> which discovered fragments <strong>of</strong> sculpture have been assigned to the frieze <strong>of</strong><br />

the Erechtheion. As Glowacki, 325, says, criteria, such as technique, material, style, <strong>and</strong> scale have also<br />

been taken <strong>in</strong>to account.<br />

555 Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 242-243; also Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Erechtheion” 7; Glowacki, “A New Fragment <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion Frieze” 325.<br />

556 Appliqué figures: Ridgway, Prayers <strong>in</strong> Stone 118; Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong> Palagia, ed., Greek<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> 143; sculpture <strong>in</strong> relief: Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 413; Boulter,<br />

“<strong>The</strong> Erechtheion Frieze” 21. Although referr<strong>in</strong>g to images <strong>in</strong> clay or metal made from a mold, the<br />

statement <strong>of</strong> Pollitt, Ancient View 288, that “when attached to a flat background,” these images are reliefs,<br />

is helpful.<br />

557 It is assumed that episodes from the life <strong>of</strong> Erechtheus are depicted, but no def<strong>in</strong>ite subject has been<br />

identified. For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the scholarly attempts to determ<strong>in</strong>e the subject <strong>of</strong> the frieze, see Fowler,<br />

“<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 244, n. 3; also for a recent summary <strong>of</strong> the topic, Jenk<strong>in</strong>s,<br />

Greek Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> 127.<br />

558 <strong>The</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al height <strong>of</strong> each piece <strong>of</strong> sculpture is estimated on the basis <strong>of</strong> the height <strong>of</strong> the frieze; for the<br />

pieces <strong>of</strong> the north portico, where the height <strong>of</strong> the frieze is 0.683m., it has been suggested that the orig<strong>in</strong>al<br />

maximum height <strong>of</strong> each sculpture would have been about 0.65 m., whereas the maximum height <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sculptures <strong>of</strong> the cella, where the height <strong>of</strong> the frieze was 0.617m., would have been slightly shorter, that is,<br />

about 0.58m.: Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 7; also Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong> Palagia, ed.,<br />

Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 141.<br />

For a fragment <strong>of</strong> a female figure runn<strong>in</strong>g to the left, see Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Erechtheum 247, no. 4, pl. XL; also Boulter 8, no. 4, pls. 1-2. Although referr<strong>in</strong>g only to the upper part <strong>of</strong><br />

her body, namely, from the neck to the middle <strong>of</strong> her thighs, evidence that this figure was runn<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

preserved <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> the chiton she wears. As Boulter 8, observes: “the curious fold <strong>of</strong> the chiton<br />

on the right thigh, ly<strong>in</strong>g across the other drapery l<strong>in</strong>es, not only varies the drapery pattern, but re<strong>in</strong>forces the<br />

impression <strong>of</strong> rapid movement.” A now-headless female figure is depicted sitt<strong>in</strong>g on a seat “<strong>of</strong> no def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

281


variety <strong>of</strong> poses, which has been <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a variety <strong>of</strong> action, has led to the<br />

suggestion that the subject <strong>of</strong> the frieze was arranged “<strong>in</strong> separate groups or scenes rather<br />

than <strong>in</strong> a cont<strong>in</strong>uous representation.” 559<br />

Apart from this material, additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion derives from two fragmentary <strong>in</strong>scriptions that form part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g accounts that date to 408/7 B.C. <strong>The</strong>se <strong>in</strong>scriptions record the payment that each<br />

sculptor received for the works <strong>of</strong> sculpture he created. <strong>The</strong> text <strong>of</strong> the first <strong>of</strong> these<br />

<strong>in</strong>scriptions (XVI, col. I; IG I 3 . 476) runs as follows:<br />

- - the youth who is writ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> the man st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g beside him, 120 dr.<br />

- -, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Kollytos<br />

- - <strong>and</strong> the wagon without<br />

the two mules, 90 dr.<br />

Agathanor, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Alopeke,<br />

the two women beside the wagon,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the two mules, 240 dr.<br />

(IG I 3 . 476 [fr. XVI, col I. 150-157]) [87] 560<br />

shape” <strong>and</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g a headless naked boy on her lap: Fowler 263, no. 84, pl. XLIV; also Boulter 15, no. 84,<br />

pls. 22, 23a. For a group <strong>of</strong> two male figures—one st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, the other kneel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> front <strong>of</strong> him—see<br />

Fowler, 259, no. 66, pl. XLIII, who ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the pl<strong>in</strong>th on which the group st<strong>and</strong>s is <strong>in</strong>tended to<br />

imitate rock; also M. Brouskari, <strong>The</strong> Monuments on the Acropolis (Athens, 1997) 199, fig. 133, which<br />

depicts the group aga<strong>in</strong>st a dark, almost black background, probably <strong>in</strong> an attempt to capture the darkness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone <strong>of</strong> the frieze. Also a group <strong>of</strong> two fragments depicts a frontal view <strong>of</strong> a st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

woman from the waist down. Beh<strong>in</strong>d the drapery <strong>of</strong> her garment at her left side is preserved the remnant <strong>of</strong><br />

what has been identified as a tree trunk. For this suggestion <strong>and</strong> an illustration <strong>of</strong> the figure, see Fowler<br />

262, no. 8, pl. XLIV; also Boulter 9, 78, pls. 3-4; <strong>and</strong> Brouskari 188, fig. 130. For a fragment <strong>of</strong> the bodies<br />

<strong>of</strong> a pair <strong>of</strong> horses pull<strong>in</strong>g a chariot, see Fowler 267-268, no. 106, pl. XLVI; <strong>and</strong> also 268, no. 107, pl.<br />

XLVI for a fragment <strong>of</strong> the broken forelegs <strong>and</strong> breast <strong>of</strong> a horse gallop<strong>in</strong>g to the left. As for objects,<br />

chairs appear to be repeatedly represented on the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze. For the depiction <strong>of</strong> an armchair on<br />

which a female sits by lean<strong>in</strong>g back, see Fowler 263, no. 85, pl. XLIV; also Boulter 12, no. 85, pls. 13-14,<br />

16b. A partially preserved chair <strong>of</strong> which only the seat <strong>and</strong> one leg rema<strong>in</strong> is also depicted beside the lower<br />

part <strong>of</strong> a female figure st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g next to it: Fowler 257, no. 56, pl. XLIII, <strong>and</strong> Boulter 14, no. 56, pls. 21,<br />

23b. For a fragment <strong>of</strong> a helmet identified as that <strong>of</strong> Athena <strong>and</strong> set upon a mass that is thought to<br />

represent stone, see Glowacki, “A New Fragment <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion Frieze” 326, pl. 65, figs. a-b.<br />

559 Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 244, who further expla<strong>in</strong>s that “some division<br />

<strong>of</strong> scenes is <strong>in</strong>evitable <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the different heights <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the cella <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the North<br />

Portico.”<br />

560 This text corresponds to l<strong>in</strong>es 1-8 <strong>of</strong> the first column <strong>of</strong> a marble <strong>in</strong>scribed fragment (XVI) that was<br />

discovered <strong>in</strong> excavations southeast <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum <strong>in</strong> 1839: Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 375, 389. <strong>The</strong> fragment is part <strong>of</strong> a larger <strong>in</strong>scription compris<strong>in</strong>g several fragments (XII-<br />

XXV), some <strong>of</strong> which (i.e., XIII-XX) follow a stoichedon arrangement. All fragments deal with the<br />

payments <strong>of</strong> workmen. Fragment XV preserves the name <strong>of</strong> the archon Euktemon, <strong>and</strong>, therefore, dates the<br />

282


<strong>The</strong> same type <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation is recorded by part <strong>of</strong> the text <strong>of</strong> the second <strong>of</strong> these<br />

<strong>in</strong>scriptions (XVII, col. I; IG I 3 . 476), which says:<br />

-- the man hold<strong>in</strong>g the spear, 60 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kephisia,<br />

the youth beside the breast-plate, 60 dr.<br />

Praxias, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Melite,<br />

the horse <strong>and</strong> the man appear<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d it 120 dr.<br />

<strong>and</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> the flank,<br />

Antiphanes <strong>of</strong> Kerameis,<br />

the chariot, <strong>and</strong> the youth,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the two horses be<strong>in</strong>g harnessed, 240 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kiphisia,<br />

the man lead<strong>in</strong>g the horse, 60 dr.<br />

Mynnion, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Argyle,<br />

the horse <strong>and</strong> the man strik<strong>in</strong>g it,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he later added the stele, 127 dr.<br />

Soklos, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Alopeke,<br />

the man hold<strong>in</strong>g the bridle, 60 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kephisia,<br />

the man lean<strong>in</strong>g on a staff<br />

beh<strong>in</strong>d the altar,<br />

Iasos <strong>of</strong> Kollytos, the woman with the<br />

little girl lean<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st her, 80 dr.<br />

sum total <strong>of</strong> payments for sculpture, 3315 dr.<br />

(IG I 3 . 476 [fr. XVII, col. I, 159-181]) [88]<br />

Both <strong>in</strong>scriptions are <strong>in</strong>structive, for they provide an <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to what the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the<br />

frieze represented: human adults <strong>and</strong> children <strong>in</strong> different poses, such as lean<strong>in</strong>g on a<br />

staff or aga<strong>in</strong>st each other, animals, such as mules <strong>and</strong> horses be<strong>in</strong>g harnessed, objects<br />

such as a spear, a breastplate, a wagon, <strong>and</strong> a bridle, <strong>and</strong> also features <strong>of</strong> worship, such as<br />

an altar. What is additionally <strong>in</strong>structive is that these <strong>in</strong>scriptions do not speak <strong>of</strong><br />

sculptors mak<strong>in</strong>g a statue <strong>of</strong> someone or someth<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>in</strong>stead someone or someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

himself or itself. This mode <strong>of</strong> expression is crucial, for it suggests that the idea <strong>of</strong> an<br />

account to 408/7 B.C.: Fowler 371-376. For an additional discussion <strong>of</strong> the payments <strong>of</strong> the workmen, see<br />

R. H. R<strong>and</strong>all, Jr., “<strong>The</strong> Erechtheion Workmen,” AJA 57 (1953) 199-210.<br />

283


image as an object was not important. 561 At the same time, the descriptions on these<br />

<strong>in</strong>scriptions suggest that there was no dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject, which<br />

accords well with previous evidence for zw|~on. In regards to the variety <strong>of</strong> action <strong>and</strong><br />

also animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects, the picture that emerges from these <strong>in</strong>scriptions<br />

appears to be no different from the one formed by the extant sculpture. Given this<br />

evidence, the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele, which were to be placed aga<strong>in</strong>st the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian<br />

stone <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion frieze can be identified with the sculptural representations <strong>of</strong> this<br />

frieze as described <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>and</strong> preserved <strong>in</strong> the extant sculpture.<br />

As noted earlier, Caskey def<strong>in</strong>ed the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele as “figures.”<br />

Although this def<strong>in</strong>ition is true, it does not do justice to all subjects represented by the<br />

sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze. As mentioned earlier, the term figure refers to the representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a bodily form, especially the human one. In this respect, the translation <strong>of</strong> zw~ia as<br />

“figures” is restrictive <strong>in</strong> the sense that it makes one th<strong>in</strong>k that human be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> animals<br />

were represented by the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze. As a result, the application <strong>of</strong> the modern<br />

term “figures” onto zw~ia tends to dismiss the objects, <strong>and</strong> both natural <strong>and</strong> manmade<br />

features that accompanied the human <strong>and</strong> animal figures placed there. It should be<br />

remembered, however, that <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions that record the payments <strong>of</strong> the sculptors,<br />

all objects <strong>and</strong> features seem to be <strong>in</strong>separable elements <strong>of</strong> the human <strong>and</strong> animal figures.<br />

More specifically, objects <strong>and</strong> features not only surround the figures described, but also<br />

mark their specific positions. Two women are described as positioned beside a wagon<br />

<strong>and</strong> two mules (fr. XVI, col. I, 153-154) [87], a boy beh<strong>in</strong>d a breastplate (fr. XVII, col. I,<br />

161) [88], <strong>and</strong> a man as lean<strong>in</strong>g on a staff beside an altar (XVII, col. I, 177-178) [88]. In<br />

561 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> this idea, see Donohue, Xoana 23, n. 54.<br />

284


addition, the <strong>in</strong>scriptions provide <strong>in</strong>stances, <strong>in</strong> which objects function as attributes <strong>of</strong><br />

human figures, <strong>and</strong> as such, they def<strong>in</strong>e the identity <strong>of</strong> these figures. A man is identified<br />

as the one who holds a spear, <strong>and</strong> another as the one who holds a bridle (XVII, col. I,<br />

l<strong>in</strong>es 159, 175 respectively) [88]. <strong>The</strong> view that all objects, features, <strong>and</strong> figures enjoy<br />

equal status as subjects <strong>of</strong> the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze is also supported by the extant<br />

fragments, which, as was mentioned earlier, depict human figures <strong>in</strong> various poses <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

the presence <strong>of</strong> various objects <strong>and</strong> features, such as chairs, helmets, <strong>and</strong> tree trunks, <strong>and</strong><br />

also animal figures, such as horses.<br />

In light <strong>of</strong> this comb<strong>in</strong>ed evidence, the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele should be<br />

understood as representations <strong>of</strong> both human <strong>and</strong> animal figures, objects, <strong>and</strong> natural <strong>and</strong><br />

man-made features, or, more generally, <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects. It may<br />

be more accurate to suggest that zw~ia referred generally to all figural sculpture that<br />

decorated the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. This general sense is re<strong>in</strong>forced by the fact that<br />

the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele does not yield any <strong>in</strong>formation about the appearance <strong>of</strong> zw~ia. In this<br />

way, the term is used <strong>in</strong> a way similar to that seen <strong>in</strong> the texts <strong>of</strong> Empedocles <strong>and</strong><br />

Herodotus. Another similarity with these texts is also witnessed <strong>in</strong> the fact that by<br />

equat<strong>in</strong>g zw~ia with the figural sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> a temple, such as the<br />

Erechtheion, the <strong>in</strong>scription establishes a context for zw~ia that is directly <strong>in</strong>volved with<br />

the arts <strong>and</strong> sits <strong>in</strong> a religious sett<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

In addition, <strong>and</strong> also <strong>in</strong> compliance with previous treatment, if one is to consider<br />

here the centrality <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g as seen <strong>in</strong> the previously discussed etymology<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|~on, then it may be suggested that these zw~ia were perceived as representations <strong>of</strong><br />

both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects borrowed from the surround<strong>in</strong>g (sensible) world.<br />

285


That these subjects were still <strong>in</strong>cluded under the blanket <strong>of</strong> one <strong>and</strong> the same term, further<br />

suggests that they were seen as shar<strong>in</strong>g a common characteristic; therefore, form<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

group <strong>of</strong> similar th<strong>in</strong>gs despite their perceived differences <strong>in</strong> essence.<br />

<strong>The</strong> next appearance <strong>of</strong> zw~ia <strong>in</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g accounts <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion is aga<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong> connection with the frieze <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> term appears on an opisthographic<br />

fragment (VIII= IG I 3 . 475) that like the Ch<strong>and</strong>ler stele, dates to 409/8 B.C., but has been<br />

considered an addition to the report <strong>of</strong> the commissioners appear<strong>in</strong>g on that stele. 562 <strong>The</strong><br />

fragment, which is one <strong>of</strong> five <strong>of</strong> a larger <strong>in</strong>scription (VIII-XII), preserves on its obverse<br />

(VIIIA) a text, now restored, which regards payments for specific operations associated<br />

with the construction <strong>of</strong> the frieze.<br />

[- - - Stone-work. Payments for the sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> place <strong>and</strong> the<br />

dress<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the top surface <strong>of</strong> the blocks <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st which ta& zw~ia (are to be placed) <strong>and</strong> their<br />

back<strong>in</strong>g stones.] (IG I 3 . 475 [fr. VIII A]) [86]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage opens with reference to payments for the sett<strong>in</strong>g (qe/sewj) <strong>and</strong> dress<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(e0pergasi/aj) <strong>of</strong> the blocks <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone, which, as was seen <strong>in</strong> the previous<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription, refers to the background blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. 563 Equally<br />

restored is the phrase “aga<strong>in</strong>st which” (pro&j w{i), which as was also seen previously,<br />

suggests that zw~ia were set aga<strong>in</strong>st the backdrop <strong>of</strong> the frieze. If this restoration is<br />

correct, the repetition <strong>of</strong> the dist<strong>in</strong>ctive method <strong>of</strong> attachment between the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian<br />

562 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 323.<br />

563 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 344, the term qe/sewj does not<br />

simply mean the sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> place <strong>of</strong> the stones, but “it <strong>in</strong>cludes any f<strong>in</strong>al chisel<strong>in</strong>g that might be found<br />

necessary after the block had been hoisted, to secure perfect jo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>and</strong> also “the cutt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the holes for<br />

the clamps <strong>and</strong> dowels, the <strong>in</strong>sertion <strong>of</strong> these, <strong>and</strong> the fasten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> them by means <strong>of</strong> molten lead.” Also,<br />

the objective <strong>of</strong> dress<strong>in</strong>g (e0pergasi/a) “was to secure a perfectly level <strong>and</strong> even bed for the next course to<br />

be laid,” whereas “the preposition e0pi/ [which follows] shows that it was the top surface which received this<br />

dress<strong>in</strong>g.”<br />

286


stone <strong>and</strong> zw~ia suggests a st<strong>and</strong>ard element <strong>of</strong> the stock language <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to the frieze. Additional evidence regard<strong>in</strong>g this part <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion is<br />

witnessed <strong>in</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> the term a)ntiqema&twn, which, on the basis <strong>of</strong> its occurrence <strong>in</strong><br />

other <strong>in</strong>scriptions, is taken to mean the back<strong>in</strong>g blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> a build<strong>in</strong>g. 564 Put<br />

together, all this evidence confirms that the architectural part to which the <strong>in</strong>scription<br />

refers is the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion.<br />

Like the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the previous <strong>in</strong>scription, Caskey translates these zw~ia, which<br />

were also to be placed aga<strong>in</strong>st the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone <strong>of</strong> the background <strong>of</strong> the frieze, as<br />

“figures.” 565 As was the case with the earlier zw~ia, the <strong>in</strong>scription employs aga<strong>in</strong> the<br />

word <strong>in</strong> the plural form, <strong>and</strong> yields no <strong>in</strong>formation regard<strong>in</strong>g their appearance. In this<br />

way, the impression that zw~ia was a term <strong>of</strong> general description is once aga<strong>in</strong> re<strong>in</strong>forced.<br />

In view <strong>of</strong> the association <strong>of</strong> zw~ia with the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion as established <strong>in</strong> the<br />

previous <strong>in</strong>scription, <strong>and</strong> also their mean<strong>in</strong>g as sculptural representations <strong>of</strong> animate <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken, most likely, from the surround<strong>in</strong>g world, the current zw~ia<br />

appear to carry the same mean<strong>in</strong>g. In this way, the use <strong>of</strong> zw~ia <strong>in</strong> a context directly<br />

connected with the visual arts <strong>and</strong> experienced <strong>in</strong> a religious sett<strong>in</strong>g is once aga<strong>in</strong><br />

confirmed.<br />

<strong>The</strong> next two fragmentary <strong>in</strong>scriptions, which belong to the build<strong>in</strong>g accounts <strong>of</strong><br />

the Erechtheion that date to 408/7 B.C., attest to the use <strong>of</strong> the word zw&idia <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong><br />

564 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 343, n. 1, expla<strong>in</strong>s that the term refers to the<br />

non-visible blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze, that is the ones to which the slabs <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone were attached. In<br />

support <strong>of</strong> his po<strong>in</strong>t, he provides a series <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions from: 1) another fragment <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g accounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion (X, col. II, I. 9), 2) Troezen (IG IV, 823, l.69), <strong>and</strong> 3) Didyma (IG II, 834b, l. 21), all <strong>of</strong><br />

which po<strong>in</strong>t to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as the back<strong>in</strong>g stones <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> a build<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

565 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 327.<br />

287


zw~ia. <strong>The</strong> first <strong>of</strong> these fragments (XIII, col. II; IG I 3 . 476), whose text is restored,<br />

records payments<br />

for tak<strong>in</strong>g down <strong>and</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g away the scaffold<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the north wall, from which<br />

the zw&idia were fastened <strong>in</strong> place,<br />

to six men; to Prepon, 3 ob.; to Medos, 3 ob.;<br />

to Apollodoros, 3 ob.; to - - -, 3 ob.;<br />

to - - -, 3 ob.; - - - - - -<br />

(IG I 3 . 476 [fr. XIII, col II, 135-140]) [89]<br />

<strong>The</strong> operation recorded <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>scription refers to the remov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the scaffold<strong>in</strong>g used<br />

for the placement <strong>of</strong> zw&idia on the north wall <strong>of</strong> a build<strong>in</strong>g, which has been identified<br />

with the Erechtheion. 566 Caskey translates zw&idia, which is restored except for its first<br />

letter, as “figures <strong>of</strong> the frieze.” 567 As noted earlier <strong>in</strong> connection with Herodotus’ krater,<br />

zw&idia is considered to be the dim<strong>in</strong>utive <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. 568 On the basis <strong>of</strong> this observation,<br />

Caskey’s translation <strong>of</strong> zw&idia should read “little figures,” but as can be seen, he omits<br />

the association with size. Anastasios Orl<strong>and</strong>os <strong>and</strong> John Travlos, <strong>in</strong> contrast, <strong>in</strong>clude this<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription <strong>in</strong> their discussion <strong>of</strong> the word zw|&dion, which they consider the dim<strong>in</strong>utive<br />

form <strong>of</strong> zw|~on; their translation <strong>of</strong> zw|&dion, however, favors a completely different<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition, that <strong>of</strong> “a small pa<strong>in</strong>ted or sculptured picture.” 569 <strong>The</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription under discussion, however, to support the idea that these zw&idia referred to<br />

small pa<strong>in</strong>ted or sculptured pictures or even figures. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scription makes use <strong>of</strong> the<br />

plural form <strong>of</strong> the word, which <strong>in</strong>dicates more than one item, but does not describe what<br />

these zw&idia looked like. In this respect, zw&idia appears to be a term <strong>of</strong> general<br />

566<br />

Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 416.<br />

567<br />

Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 387, 413.<br />

568 9<br />

LSJ , 758, s.v. zw|&dion; also for –idion as a st<strong>and</strong>ard suffix <strong>of</strong> neuter dim<strong>in</strong>utives, see Smyth, Greek<br />

Grammar 235.<br />

569<br />

A. K. Orl<strong>and</strong>os <strong>and</strong> J. N. Travlos, Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Ancient Architectural Terms (Athens, 1986) 123, s.v.<br />

zw|&dion.<br />

288


description for someth<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> therefore, rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the zw~ia <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

<strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>and</strong> also Herodotus’ zw|&dia. Further, the reference <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription to the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> scaffold<strong>in</strong>g for the placement <strong>of</strong> these zw&idia on the build<strong>in</strong>g suggests that they<br />

were some type <strong>of</strong> architectural or decorative elements added separately to the structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. In this way, zw&idia aga<strong>in</strong> appear to share a common element with<br />

the earlier zw~ia, which were carved separately <strong>and</strong> then pegged to the bottom <strong>and</strong> back<br />

surfaces <strong>of</strong> the frieze. <strong>The</strong> impression <strong>of</strong> zw&idia be<strong>in</strong>g used as architectural <strong>of</strong><br />

decorative elements establishes a context directly associated with the visual arts, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, <strong>in</strong> agreement with that <strong>of</strong> the previously seen zw~ia.<br />

Given this closeness between zw&idia <strong>and</strong> zw~ia, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the earlier<br />

association <strong>of</strong> zw~ia with representations <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken<br />

from the real world, <strong>and</strong> employed <strong>in</strong> the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion, it is<br />

likely that these zw&idia stood for representations <strong>of</strong> the type designated by the earlier<br />

zw~ia, but <strong>of</strong> smaller size. Critical for the notion <strong>of</strong> size as be<strong>in</strong>g central to the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw&idia is the fact that, <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>scription, the location <strong>of</strong> zw&idia is specified as “on<br />

the north wall.” This is the side <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion where the discrepancy <strong>in</strong> size<br />

between the frieze <strong>of</strong> the cella <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the north porch is clearly witnessed. As<br />

recorded, the height <strong>of</strong> the blocks that form the background <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the cella is<br />

0.617m., whereas that <strong>of</strong> the blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the north portico, 0.683m. This<br />

discrepancy applies also to the respective sculpture <strong>of</strong> these essentially two friezes. It has<br />

been estimated that the maximum height <strong>of</strong> the sculptures adorn<strong>in</strong>g the frieze <strong>of</strong> the cella<br />

289


must have been 0.58m., whereas that <strong>of</strong> the north portico 0.65m. 570 When taken this<br />

evidence <strong>in</strong>to account, it is possible to speculate that the zw&idia <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription<br />

referred to the smaller <strong>of</strong> the sculptures that formed the decoration <strong>of</strong> the friezes <strong>of</strong> north<br />

wall <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion. <strong>The</strong>se sculptures would correspond to those <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

cella.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions (XVII; col. II; IG I 3 . 476) that attests to the use <strong>of</strong><br />

the word zw&idia <strong>in</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g accounts <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion (408/7 B.C.), records<br />

purchases <strong>of</strong> specific materials for operations related to the frieze <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

two talents <strong>of</strong> lead were bought<br />

for the fasten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zwidi/wn,<br />

from Sostratos, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Melite. 10 dr.<br />

(IG I 3 . 476 [fr. XVII, col. II, 296-299]) [90]<br />

Zwidi/wn is the genitive plural <strong>of</strong> zw&idia <strong>and</strong> belongs to a restored section <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription. As was mentioned earlier, zw&idia are the dim<strong>in</strong>utive form <strong>of</strong> zw~ia, which<br />

automatically qualifies these zwidi/wn to be read as “<strong>of</strong> little zw~ia.” Like the previous<br />

<strong>in</strong>scription, however, this one does not comment on the appearance <strong>of</strong> zwidi/wn, which<br />

aga<strong>in</strong> makes it difficult to ga<strong>in</strong> an underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> their mean<strong>in</strong>g. This lack <strong>of</strong><br />

description <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the use <strong>of</strong> the plural re<strong>in</strong>forces the impression that<br />

zwidi/wn was a term <strong>of</strong> general description for a group <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs. What helps underst<strong>and</strong><br />

what were these th<strong>in</strong>gs is the clear statement <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription that lead was purchased<br />

<strong>and</strong> used <strong>in</strong> the fasten<strong>in</strong>g (pro&sqes<strong>in</strong>) <strong>of</strong> these zwidi/wn. Judg<strong>in</strong>g from the extant<br />

archaeological evidence, which refers to the widened bottom surface <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

570 For the height <strong>of</strong> the blocks, see Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 239; for the<br />

height <strong>of</strong> the sculptures, see Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 7; Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong><br />

Palagia, ed., Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> 141.<br />

290


Erechtheion, <strong>and</strong> also fragments <strong>of</strong> its sculpture, lead was <strong>in</strong>deed used as adhesive for<br />

fix<strong>in</strong>g dowels <strong>in</strong> the holes cut <strong>in</strong> both the blocks <strong>and</strong> sculpture employed <strong>in</strong> this part <strong>of</strong><br />

the build<strong>in</strong>g. 571 Given this evidence, zwidi/wn can be understood as the sculptures placed<br />

on the bottom <strong>and</strong> aga<strong>in</strong>st the back sides <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the build<strong>in</strong>g. It is probably<br />

because <strong>of</strong> this evidence that, unlike his previous consistent translation <strong>of</strong> both zw&idia<br />

<strong>and</strong> zw~ia as “figures,” Caskey translates these zwidi/wn as “sculptures,” which implies<br />

identification with objects rather than with images or subjects. 572 Although fitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

accordance with the general sense detected <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zwidi/wn, this translation<br />

verifies the artistic context for the use <strong>of</strong> the term, but does not take <strong>in</strong>to account an<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> zwidi/wn that clearly st<strong>and</strong>s out: their fasten<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> word pro&sqes<strong>in</strong>, which<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicates this technical aspect, also carries the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “addition.” 573 As such it<br />

qualifies zw&idia as sculptures added, <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g attached to a surface,<br />

therefore <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g their place <strong>in</strong> relation to the surround<strong>in</strong>g structure. Such evidence<br />

may mean that apart from or along with imply<strong>in</strong>g small size, zw&idia were also<br />

understood as appliqué sculptures. This evidence br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d the bronze works<br />

riveted on the krater from Vix <strong>and</strong> those from Trebenishte, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g that the<br />

material <strong>of</strong> manufacture was not central to the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|&dion <strong>in</strong> the fifth century.<br />

571 <strong>The</strong> bottom blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze should be equated with the top surface <strong>of</strong> the architrave, which<br />

functioned as the floor on which the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze was placed. Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s,” <strong>in</strong> Paton,<br />

ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 243, n. 4, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that remnants <strong>of</strong> lead have been found <strong>in</strong> both the holes <strong>in</strong> the<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the architrave <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> the extant sculpture: “there are also <strong>in</strong> the top <strong>of</strong> the architrave numerous<br />

small round holes, <strong>and</strong> similar holes, some <strong>of</strong> which conta<strong>in</strong> rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> iron p<strong>in</strong>s or plugs <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> lead, are<br />

found <strong>in</strong> a few fragments <strong>of</strong> sculpture.” Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion” 20, states that a pour<br />

channel—generally round <strong>and</strong> rather narrow—was required to allow the lead to flow <strong>in</strong>to the dowel hole.<br />

As an example she <strong>of</strong>fers (20, fig. 23) an unpublished fragment <strong>of</strong> a female figure discovered on the north<br />

slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis.<br />

572 Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum 397.<br />

573 LSJ 9 , 1514, s.v.pro&sqesij.<br />

291


Although dat<strong>in</strong>g to the third century B.C., explicit evidence <strong>in</strong> support <strong>of</strong> this<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t comes from two votive objects which, <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ventory lists from Delos, are called<br />

zw&idia. <strong>The</strong> first is a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> two silver figur<strong>in</strong>es, one <strong>of</strong> Apollo, the other <strong>of</strong><br />

Artemis, mounted on a wooden base, <strong>and</strong> dedicated by a woman called Kle<strong>in</strong>o <strong>in</strong> the<br />

temple <strong>of</strong> Artemis. <strong>The</strong> second is a dedication <strong>of</strong> a man called Apollodoros described as<br />

“two zw&idia on a semi-circular surface” that was kept at the temple <strong>of</strong> Apollo. 574 <strong>The</strong><br />

fact that the third-century Delian zw&idia were made <strong>of</strong> silver, whereas those <strong>of</strong> the fifth-<br />

century frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion were made <strong>of</strong> marble, <strong>in</strong>dicates with certa<strong>in</strong>ty that the<br />

material <strong>of</strong> manufacture was not a determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g factor <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term zw&idia.<br />

In sum, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> usage <strong>of</strong> zw~ia <strong>and</strong> zw&idia <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g accounts <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion can be described <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way: Zw~ia are<br />

figural images (representations) <strong>of</strong> animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from the real<br />

world <strong>and</strong> referr<strong>in</strong>g to the sculptural composition <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion frieze. In this way,<br />

zw~ia appear to be directly connected with the visual arts set <strong>in</strong> a religious context as<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicated by the designation <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion as a temple. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions also refer to<br />

the sculpture <strong>of</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> this build<strong>in</strong>g as zw&idia. This term, which is the dim<strong>in</strong>utive<br />

form <strong>of</strong> zw~ia, designated zw~ia <strong>of</strong> small size that were employed <strong>in</strong> the frieze <strong>of</strong> the<br />

574 On the basis <strong>of</strong> thirteen different surviv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ventories that date from 279 to 145 B.C., E. Kosmetatou,<br />

“Zw&idia <strong>in</strong> the Delian Inventory Lists,” Mnemosyne 57 (2002) 482, provides a composite description <strong>of</strong><br />

the text referr<strong>in</strong>g to the silver figur<strong>in</strong>es as: “Two silver figur<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> Apollo <strong>and</strong> Artemis on a wooden base,<br />

unweighed. Inscription: Kle<strong>in</strong>o, daughter <strong>of</strong> Admetos to Apollo <strong>and</strong> Artemis as fulfillment <strong>of</strong> a vow.” She<br />

does specify, 482, however, that the phrase “on a wooden base” does not start to appear on the lists until<br />

195 B.C. This is also the year, when the term zw&idia for these figur<strong>in</strong>es switches to <strong>and</strong>ria&ntia <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong>rianti&dia. As for the second dedication <strong>and</strong> its reference to a semi-circular surface, she suggests, 483,<br />

that “we know that semi-circular exedrae were <strong>in</strong> vogue as bases for group monuments <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

sanctuaries.” For additional discussion regard<strong>in</strong>g the occurrence <strong>of</strong> zw&idia <strong>in</strong> the Delian <strong>in</strong>ventory lists,<br />

see M. C. Hellmann, Recherches sur le vocabulaire de l’ architecture grecque d’après les <strong>in</strong>scriptions de<br />

Délos (Paris, 1992) 120, n. 9.<br />

292


uild<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> also marked a technical aspect <strong>of</strong> them, namely, their fasten<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

background blocks <strong>of</strong> the frieze by means <strong>of</strong> iron dowels fixed <strong>in</strong> place with lead. <strong>The</strong><br />

extant sculpture attests, first, to this unusual method <strong>of</strong> attachment for the sculptured<br />

pieces <strong>of</strong> the frieze, <strong>and</strong>, second, to the variety <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects<br />

represented by these pieces. <strong>The</strong> translations <strong>of</strong> both zw~ia <strong>and</strong> zw&idia as “figures” <strong>and</strong><br />

“pictures” <strong>in</strong>dicate how entrenched these latter terms are <strong>in</strong> our descriptive vocabulary <strong>of</strong><br />

ancient works <strong>of</strong> art; it should be remembered, however, that such translations do not<br />

capture accurately the mean<strong>in</strong>g that these terms carried when used <strong>in</strong> fifth-century<br />

contexts directly <strong>in</strong>volved with the visual arts.<br />

Taken together, the evidence from the literary texts <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>of</strong> the fifth<br />

century B.C. <strong>in</strong>dicates that the word zw|~on <strong>and</strong> its derivative zw|&dion when used <strong>in</strong> direct<br />

association with the visual arts as def<strong>in</strong>ed by pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g sculpture, bronze-work, <strong>and</strong> textiles<br />

held the mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation” “representation <strong>of</strong> both<br />

animate <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from real life,” <strong>and</strong> “decorative element.” <strong>The</strong><br />

fifth-century use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong>dicates that no importance was placed on the dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between image <strong>and</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> contemporary <strong>Greece</strong>, while that <strong>of</strong> zw|&dion po<strong>in</strong>ts out that<br />

this was a term closely associated with the method <strong>of</strong> fasten<strong>in</strong>g images to a background<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> various media, such as bronze-work <strong>and</strong> sculpture.<br />

Contrary to the idea that fifth-century arguments about images <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> are scarce, the<br />

usage <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong> the literary texts <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>scriptions exam<strong>in</strong>ed here <strong>in</strong>dicates that there<br />

was a dist<strong>in</strong>ct vocabulary about the visual arts <strong>in</strong> fifth-century <strong>Greece</strong>. 575<br />

575 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the idea that “evidence for fifth-century arguments about images is scarce,” see<br />

Halliwell, “Plato <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> Rutter <strong>and</strong> Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> 100.<br />

293


3. Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the Fourth Century B.C.<br />

<strong>The</strong> word zw|~on <strong>in</strong> association with the arts appears <strong>in</strong> four fourth-century<br />

authors: Plato, Alcidamas, Aristotle, <strong>and</strong> Philemon. As was the case <strong>in</strong> the previous<br />

century, the term does not carry a s<strong>in</strong>gle mean<strong>in</strong>g, but rather multiple nuanced ones, such<br />

as “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” “f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> an artistic process,” “figural<br />

image,” <strong>and</strong> also “image held by memory.” <strong>The</strong> majority <strong>of</strong> these mean<strong>in</strong>gs occurs<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> specialized discussions <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sculpture, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that the term was part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts.<br />

Plato<br />

<strong>The</strong> first fourth-century author to use zw|~on <strong>in</strong> a context that directly <strong>in</strong>volved the<br />

visual arts is Plato. <strong>The</strong> word appears ten times <strong>in</strong> four <strong>of</strong> his dialogues <strong>and</strong> demonstrates<br />

its application to the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> both pictures <strong>and</strong> statuary. Zw|~on appears first <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Cratylus, <strong>in</strong> which it carries the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong><br />

Cratylus is a discussion among three persons—Cratylus, Hermogenes, <strong>and</strong> Socrates on<br />

the subjects <strong>of</strong> etymology <strong>and</strong> correctness <strong>of</strong> names. Socrates speaks <strong>of</strong> the processes <strong>of</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g words:<br />

SOCRATES. Just as pa<strong>in</strong>ters (zwgra&foi), when they wish to produce an<br />

imitation, sometimes use only red, sometimes, some other color, <strong>and</strong> sometimes<br />

mix many colors, as when they are mak<strong>in</strong>g a picture <strong>of</strong> a man or someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> that<br />

sort, employ<strong>in</strong>g each color, I suppose, as they th<strong>in</strong>k the particular picture dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

it. In just this way we, too, shall apply letters to th<strong>in</strong>gs, us<strong>in</strong>g one letter for one<br />

th<strong>in</strong>g, when that seems to be required, or many letters together, form<strong>in</strong>g syllables,<br />

as they are called, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> turn comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g syllables, <strong>and</strong> by their comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

form<strong>in</strong>g nouns <strong>and</strong> verbs. And from nouns <strong>and</strong> verbs aga<strong>in</strong> we shall f<strong>in</strong>ally<br />

construct someth<strong>in</strong>g great <strong>and</strong> fair <strong>and</strong> complete. Just as <strong>in</strong> our comparison we<br />

made the zw|~on by the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (grafikh|~), so now we shall make language<br />

by the art <strong>of</strong> nam<strong>in</strong>g, or <strong>of</strong> rhetoric, or whatever it be. (Cra. 424d-425a) [141]<br />

294


Socrates likens the use <strong>of</strong> colors by pa<strong>in</strong>ters to create pictures to the use <strong>of</strong> letters <strong>and</strong><br />

syllables by speakers, like himself <strong>and</strong> his <strong>in</strong>terlocutors, to create words. His l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g suggests a successive process, which, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics, term<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong><br />

language <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> a zw|~on. This evidence def<strong>in</strong>es the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

zw|~on as the f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> the artistic process <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> establishes its direct<br />

connection with the realm <strong>of</strong> the arts. What the passage does not clarify, however, is<br />

whether this zw|~on refers to the object, image, or representational subject created by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. This lack <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between object, image, <strong>and</strong> subject is<br />

rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> the description <strong>of</strong> the zwia on the Erechtheion <strong>in</strong>scriptions. In Plato’s<br />

passage, Socrates conceives <strong>of</strong> both language <strong>and</strong> zw|~on as great, fair, <strong>and</strong> complete. <strong>The</strong><br />

translation <strong>of</strong> the passage <strong>in</strong>troduces a break between the reference to these qualities <strong>and</strong><br />

the terms “language” <strong>and</strong> zw|~on, but the ancient text shows un<strong>in</strong>terrupted speech.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, the epithet “complete” (o3lon) can also apply to zw|~on, a situation, which<br />

strengthens the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as the f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. Similarly, the<br />

epithets “great” (me/ga) <strong>and</strong> “fair” (kalo_n) can also apply to zw|~on, <strong>and</strong> therefore, qualify<br />

it as a splendid construction. Me/ga br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d the mega&la zw|~a <strong>in</strong> Herodotus’<br />

description <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>in</strong> Egypt. As was seen then, the word is a cognate <strong>of</strong> me/geqoj,<br />

whose mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> connection with the visual arts is tw<strong>of</strong>old: a) literal, that is, “size,<br />

stature,” <strong>and</strong> b) metaphorical, that is, “greatness, gr<strong>and</strong>eur, <strong>and</strong> majesty.” 576 That me/ga<br />

is applicable to both language <strong>and</strong> zw|~on—an <strong>in</strong>tangible <strong>and</strong> tangible construct<br />

respectively—suggests that the metaphorical mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word is more apt here.<br />

Kalo_n is affiliated, both etymologically <strong>and</strong> semantically, with the concept <strong>of</strong> ka&lloj,<br />

576 Pollitt, Ancient View 199-200.<br />

295


that is, “beauty.” 577 Both the concepts <strong>of</strong> greatness <strong>and</strong> beauty feature prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> the<br />

critical vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the visual arts <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period to such an extent that their<br />

pair<strong>in</strong>g has been suggested to form an idiomatic phrase: ka&lloj kai/ me/geqoj. 578 In light<br />

<strong>of</strong> this evidence, the connection <strong>of</strong> zw|~on with the visual arts is enhanced not only through<br />

its mean<strong>in</strong>g as the f<strong>in</strong>al product <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, but also through its specific qualities <strong>of</strong><br />

greatness <strong>and</strong> beauty.<br />

Despite the situation, <strong>in</strong>stances where the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this zw|~on has been<br />

considered <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> its context are not absent. David Reeve, for example,<br />

translates the word as “animal.” 579 Harold Fowler, <strong>in</strong> contrast, considers zw|~on along<br />

with grafikh|~ <strong>and</strong> te&xnh; therefore, he translates zw|~on as a “picture,” made by the “art<br />

<strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.” 580 In agreement with him is David Sedley, who notes that zw|~on is not an<br />

“animal,” as suggested by Reeve, but a “picture,” which can be also understood as<br />

“complete scenes.” 581 <strong>The</strong> translations <strong>of</strong> Fowler <strong>and</strong> Sedley suggest that the context <strong>of</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g has been considered crucial <strong>in</strong> their proposed def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as “picture.”<br />

Consider<strong>in</strong>g that modern “picture,” however, is a term with multiple mean<strong>in</strong>gs, it is<br />

difficult to determ<strong>in</strong>e which mean<strong>in</strong>g these translators have applied here. 582 Only when<br />

reduced to its modern def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> “a representation (as <strong>of</strong> a person, l<strong>and</strong>scape, build<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

577<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 191-194.<br />

578<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 193, 200.<br />

579<br />

C. D. C. Reeve, tr., Plato. Cratylus (Indianapolis, 1998) 71.<br />

580<br />

H. N. Fowler, ed., tr., Plato. Cratylus. Parmenides. Greater Hippias. Lesser Hippias (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1963) 141.<br />

581<br />

D. Sedley, Plato’s Cratylus (Cambridge, 2003) 128, n. 10.<br />

582<br />

Gove, Webster’s Third New International Dictionary 1711, s.v. picture: a) the act, process, or art <strong>of</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, b) representation by pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, c) a representation (as <strong>of</strong> a person, l<strong>and</strong>scape, build<strong>in</strong>g) on canvas,<br />

paper, or other surface produced by pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, draw<strong>in</strong>g, engrav<strong>in</strong>g, or photography, d) such representation as<br />

a work <strong>of</strong> art, e) a description so vivid or graphic as to suggest a mental image or give an accurate idea <strong>of</strong><br />

the th<strong>in</strong>g described, f) someth<strong>in</strong>g that by its likeness vividly suggests some other th<strong>in</strong>g, that is, copy, g) a<br />

concrete embodiment <strong>of</strong> an abstraction as illusion or symbol, h) a transitory visible image or reproduction<br />

due to the work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> physical laws or made by utiliz<strong>in</strong>g such laws.<br />

296


on a surface produced by pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” their “picture” appears semantically closer to this<br />

zw|~on. In addition, Sedley’s paraphrase “complete scenes” may be seen as an attempt to<br />

reta<strong>in</strong> the aspect <strong>of</strong> completion <strong>in</strong> zw|~on, <strong>and</strong> is certa<strong>in</strong>ly preferable to Reeve’s “animal,”<br />

but it is still an unsuitable modern equivalent <strong>of</strong> the ancient term.<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the passage, the terms that directly connect zw|~on to<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g are grafikh|~ te&xnh, literally mean<strong>in</strong>g “the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>and</strong> zwgra&foi, that<br />

is, pa<strong>in</strong>ters. <strong>The</strong> first br<strong>in</strong>gs immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d the words graptoi=j, e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

graya&menoj, used by Empedocles <strong>and</strong> Herodotus <strong>in</strong> reference to pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> direct<br />

connection with zw|~a as pa<strong>in</strong>ted images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d, resist-dyed decorations applied on<br />

fabric, <strong>and</strong> also the historical subject <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong>se mean<strong>in</strong>gs do not<br />

fall <strong>in</strong>to the semantic range <strong>of</strong> the present zw|~on, but their shar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a common context<br />

with it—pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g—highlights the dom<strong>in</strong>ance <strong>of</strong> this artistic process <strong>in</strong> dissociat<strong>in</strong>g zw|~on<br />

from the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “animal” <strong>in</strong> fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-century contexts directly associated<br />

with the arts.<br />

Further <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> this dom<strong>in</strong>ance can be seen <strong>in</strong> Plato’s use <strong>of</strong> the word<br />

zwgra&foi for pa<strong>in</strong>ters. <strong>The</strong> word appears numerous times <strong>in</strong> his dialogues, as, for<br />

example, <strong>in</strong> Gorgias, where the status <strong>of</strong> Zeuxis as a pa<strong>in</strong>ter is s<strong>in</strong>gled out <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

as “o( ta_ zw|~a gra&fwn” (453c). Literally mean<strong>in</strong>g “the one who pa<strong>in</strong>ts zw|~a,” this<br />

phrase is <strong>in</strong>formative, for it, first, expla<strong>in</strong>s the etymology <strong>of</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular zwgra&foj—<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ter, <strong>and</strong> second, def<strong>in</strong>es zw|~a as the creations <strong>of</strong> his craft. 583 <strong>The</strong> phrase does not<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guish among object, image <strong>and</strong> subject. As such, it supports the general mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~a as works produced by means <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

583 Also <strong>in</strong> the Sophist, where with<strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, that is, grafikh|~ te&xnh| (234b) the<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ter is co<strong>in</strong>ed poihth&j zw|&wn, that is, “maker <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn” (234a). For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> this term, see<br />

E. C. Keuls, Plato <strong>and</strong> Greek Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (Leiden, 1978) 42.<br />

297


Additional evidence for these mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> zw|~a <strong>and</strong> zwgra&foi <strong>in</strong> Plato is found<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Cratylus, where Socrates describes different categories <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>and</strong> their<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs as analogous to those <strong>of</strong> builders <strong>and</strong> their build<strong>in</strong>gs:<br />

SOCRATES. Some pa<strong>in</strong>ters (zwgra&foi) are better, <strong>and</strong> others worse, are they<br />

not?<br />

CRATYLUS. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly.<br />

SOCRATES. And the better produce better works (kalli/w)—that is, their<br />

zw|~a—<strong>and</strong> the others worse works (faulo&tera)? And likewise some builders<br />

build better houses <strong>and</strong> others worse? (Cra. 429a) [142]<br />

Socrates divides pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>and</strong> builders <strong>in</strong>to good <strong>and</strong> bad on the basis <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

works they produce. He uses the plural zw|~a to refer to the works <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>in</strong> general,<br />

but he does not state whether these zw|~a should be understood as objects or images. Both<br />

Fowler <strong>and</strong> Reeve translate these zw|~a as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs.” 584 <strong>The</strong> general sense <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~a as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs” is also supported by Socrates’ assertion that zw|~a can be<br />

both the f<strong>in</strong>er (kalli/w) <strong>and</strong> worse works (faulo&tera) <strong>of</strong> analogous pa<strong>in</strong>ters. This<br />

evidence shows clearly that, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> fourth-century pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~a as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs” was not bound to any notion <strong>of</strong> quality.<br />

<strong>The</strong> next occurrence <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> connection with pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Plato is <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Republic. Here the word refers to the subject represented by a work <strong>of</strong> sculpture; it is<br />

used <strong>in</strong> a passage, <strong>in</strong> which Socrates expla<strong>in</strong>s to Adeimantus that <strong>in</strong> order to create a<br />

happy state, all citizens <strong>and</strong> not only a small group <strong>of</strong> them, namely, the guardians must<br />

be happy. To support his argument, he starts from the opposite premise, that is, the<br />

584 Fowler, Plato. Cratylus 153; Reeve, Plato. Cratylus 76.<br />

298


outst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g allotment <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess to the guardians. He compares this condition to a<br />

hypothetically unsuited choice <strong>of</strong> color for the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> a statue:<br />

What we are do<strong>in</strong>g at the moment, we believe, is not separat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f a few <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>habitants, <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g them happy, but construct<strong>in</strong>g a complete city, <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that happy. We’ll have a look at its opposite later. Imag<strong>in</strong>e we were putt<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

colors [gra&fontaj] on a[n] a)ndria&nta, <strong>and</strong> someone came along <strong>and</strong> told us<br />

we were do<strong>in</strong>g it wrong, s<strong>in</strong>ce we weren’t us<strong>in</strong>g the most beautiful colors for the<br />

most beautiful parts <strong>of</strong> the zw|&ou. <strong>The</strong> eyes, the most beautiful feature, had been<br />

colored black, not purple. We would regard it as a quite reasonable defense to say<br />

to him: “Hang on a m<strong>in</strong>ute. You surely don’t th<strong>in</strong>k, do you, that we should make<br />

the eyes—or any <strong>of</strong> the other parts <strong>of</strong> the body—so beautiful that they don’t even<br />

look like eyes. <strong>The</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g to ask yourself is whether by giv<strong>in</strong>g the right colors to<br />

everyth<strong>in</strong>g we are mak<strong>in</strong>g the whole th<strong>in</strong>g beautiful.” It’s the same with us. You<br />

mustn’t start forc<strong>in</strong>g us to give the guardians the k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess which will<br />

turn them <strong>in</strong>to anyth<strong>in</strong>g other than guardians. (Resp. 420c) [148]<br />

In this passage, Socrates uses the word gra&fontaj to refer to the application <strong>of</strong> colors<br />

on an a)ndria&nta. <strong>The</strong> latter is the accusative s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&j, a word which,<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to Gloria Ferrari, can be understood as “figure <strong>of</strong> manhood,” <strong>and</strong> its material<br />

equivalent can be found <strong>in</strong> the kouros type <strong>in</strong> sculpture. 585 As she expla<strong>in</strong>s further:<br />

“although from the fifth century B.C. onward, this word is used to mean “statue”—seated<br />

as well as st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g female as well as male—there are <strong>in</strong>dications that it carried special<br />

connotations <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g manl<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>and</strong> Apollo.” 586 Regard<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong><br />

the passage, Reg<strong>in</strong>ald Allen, Tom Griffith, <strong>and</strong> Paul Shorey agree on the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

a)ndria&nta as “statue.” Griffith, <strong>in</strong> particular, translates it as “statue <strong>of</strong> a man.” 587<br />

Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott po<strong>in</strong>t out the etymological connection <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&j with a)nh&r, that is,<br />

585 Ferrari, Figures <strong>of</strong> Speech 125-126, ns. 76-77 where she discusses material <strong>and</strong> literary evidence for the<br />

occurrence <strong>of</strong> the word, such as the colossal Apollo dedicated by the Naxians on Delos which is called<br />

a)ndria&j <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription on its base, <strong>and</strong> also ancient writers, such as Herodotus (6.118.12) <strong>and</strong> Diodorus<br />

Siculus (13.108.4.1), who mention a)ndria&ntej represent<strong>in</strong>g Apollo.<br />

586 Ferrari, Figures <strong>of</strong> Speech 125, n. 75, cit<strong>in</strong>g Philipp, Tektonon Daidala 106-107, for the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

word as a statue <strong>of</strong> both a male <strong>and</strong> female figure.<br />

587 R. E. Allen, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2006) 112; T. Griffith, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong><br />

Republic (Cambridge, 2000) 112; P. Shorey, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic I (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass.,<br />

1930; repr. 1963) 319.<br />

299


“man,” <strong>and</strong> state that the former refers to statues <strong>of</strong> both male <strong>and</strong> female figures, <strong>and</strong><br />

also gods. 588 Given Ferrari’s suggestion, this a)ndria&j can be understood as a statue <strong>of</strong> a<br />

man, most likely, <strong>of</strong> the type known as kouros. <strong>The</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its eyes is the context <strong>of</strong><br />

the passage. <strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> zw|&ou with<strong>in</strong> this context aga<strong>in</strong> highlights the connection <strong>of</strong> this<br />

term with the visual arts, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g its mean<strong>in</strong>g as other than “animal” <strong>and</strong> it allied<br />

notions. Despite this evidence, Griffith translates zw|&ou as “liv<strong>in</strong>g creature.” Allen, on<br />

the other h<strong>and</strong>, takes it to mean “statue” <strong>and</strong> Shorey “image.” 589 <strong>The</strong> latter, although<br />

fitt<strong>in</strong>g, does not help to come closer to the ancient mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word. Allen’s<br />

conflation <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&nta <strong>and</strong> zw|&ou with “statue” gives the impression that both terms<br />

designate one <strong>and</strong> the same th<strong>in</strong>g, but their usage with<strong>in</strong> the same sentence suggests<br />

otherwise. Plato uses a)ndria&j <strong>in</strong> order to <strong>in</strong>troduce the act <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g a statue, <strong>and</strong><br />

zw|~on to refer to the application <strong>of</strong> colors to a specific bodily part: its eyes. <strong>The</strong> shift<br />

from one term to the other occurs with<strong>in</strong> a description, which moves from the designation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a type <strong>of</strong> a statue (kouros) to details <strong>of</strong> its embellishment. This evidence re<strong>in</strong>forces the<br />

impression that zw|&ou was not equal to “statue,” but directly associated with the eyes <strong>of</strong><br />

whom the a)ndria&j represented. <strong>The</strong>refore, this zw|&ou seems to apply to the subject that<br />

is be<strong>in</strong>g represented by a work <strong>of</strong> sculpture. What this mean<strong>in</strong>g br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d is the<br />

similar use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on by Herodotus when referr<strong>in</strong>g to the subject, the rider represented by<br />

the sculpture <strong>of</strong> Darius, <strong>and</strong> also the zw|~a <strong>of</strong> M<strong>and</strong>rocles’ pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g depict<strong>in</strong>g the bridg<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Bosporus by Darius. <strong>The</strong> application <strong>of</strong> the term to both works <strong>of</strong> sculpture <strong>and</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g suggests that the term was not bound to a specific medium or artistic process. In<br />

addition, the fact that no details <strong>of</strong> the appearance <strong>of</strong> this zw|&ou are provided aga<strong>in</strong><br />

588 LSJ 9 , 128, s.v. a)ndria&j.<br />

589 Griffith, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 112; Allen, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 112; Shorey, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 319.<br />

300


<strong>in</strong>dicates that it was a term <strong>of</strong> general description for a subject <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>in</strong><br />

sculpture. This evidence exp<strong>and</strong>s the previously encountered mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> Plato<br />

as the object or image produced by means <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>The</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the company <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&j also appears <strong>in</strong> another<br />

passage from the Republic, <strong>in</strong> which zw|~on is used as a blanket term for images <strong>in</strong><br />

sculpture. Here Socrates asks Glaucon to construct mentally the picture <strong>of</strong> people liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

as cha<strong>in</strong>ed prisoners <strong>in</strong> a subterranean cave. <strong>The</strong>se people are prevented from look<strong>in</strong>g<br />

anywhere other than ahead, but have light from a distant fire burn<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> above<br />

them. In the space between them <strong>and</strong> the fire, but on a higher level, is a road along which<br />

a low wall has been built. In addition to this image, Socrates asks Glaucon to<br />

picture also, along the length <strong>of</strong> the wall, people carry<strong>in</strong>g all sorts <strong>of</strong> implements<br />

which project above it, <strong>and</strong> a)ndria&ntaj <strong>and</strong> a1lla zw|~a made <strong>of</strong> stone <strong>and</strong> wood<br />

<strong>and</strong> all k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> materials (pantoi=a ei0rgasme/na). As you’d expect, some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

people carry<strong>in</strong>g the objects are speak<strong>in</strong>g, while others are silent.<br />

(Resp. 514c-515a) [149]<br />

Regard<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&ntaj <strong>in</strong> the passage, Shorey, suggests that it should be<br />

understood as “human images,” Griffith as “statues <strong>of</strong> people,” <strong>and</strong> Allen as “statues <strong>of</strong><br />

men.” 590 <strong>The</strong> previously seen mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&j as “a figure <strong>of</strong> manhood” <strong>and</strong> its<br />

connection with statuary <strong>of</strong> the kouros type make certa<strong>in</strong> that the context <strong>of</strong> the passage<br />

directly <strong>in</strong>volved the visual arts. As for the term zw|~a, all three translators agree on its<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g as “animals,” with Shorey, <strong>in</strong> particular, suggest<strong>in</strong>g “shapes <strong>of</strong> animals.” 591 It<br />

seems that the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “animals” for zw|~a has been fueled by the belief that this term<br />

contrasts with the perceived mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&ntaj as “statues <strong>of</strong> human figures.”<br />

590 Shorey, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 121; Griffith, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 220; Allen, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 227.<br />

591 Shorey, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 121; Griffith, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 220; Allen, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 227.<br />

301


Consider<strong>in</strong>g that the context <strong>of</strong> the visual arts has been previously seen to dissociate<br />

zw|~on from “animal,” these zw|~a, whose context is suggestive <strong>of</strong> the visual arts, do not<br />

necessarily have to mean “animals” or “shapes <strong>of</strong> animals.” That they were made <strong>of</strong><br />

stone <strong>and</strong> wood <strong>and</strong> existed <strong>in</strong> the company <strong>of</strong> statues suggests that they were<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> two different materials; therefore, their designation as<br />

“shapes,” although <strong>in</strong>accurate, deserves some merit. <strong>The</strong> phrase pantoi=a ei0rgasme/na,<br />

that immediately follows, has been taken to mean that these zw|~a were made <strong>of</strong> “all other<br />

materials” too, but “fashioned <strong>in</strong> all sorts <strong>of</strong> ways” is a more accurate translation. 592<br />

Thus, apart from be<strong>in</strong>g images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> stone <strong>and</strong> wood, these zw|~a were also the<br />

products <strong>of</strong> various processes or techniques. This evidence <strong>in</strong>dicates that the word was<br />

not restricted with respect to the material or mode <strong>of</strong> manufacture <strong>of</strong> the pieces to which<br />

it was applied.<br />

One aspect that deserves further attention is the phras<strong>in</strong>g “a)ndria&ntaj kai\ a1lla<br />

zw|~a.” <strong>The</strong> word “other,” which def<strong>in</strong>es zw|~a, is important for it allows the latter to be<br />

understood as a wider category or images to which a)ndria&ntej belonged. This evidence<br />

qualifies zw|~a as a blanket term for images <strong>in</strong> sculpture, not necessarily for the subject <strong>of</strong><br />

representation <strong>in</strong> sculpture as held by the previous zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the company <strong>of</strong> a)ndria&j.<br />

This nuance <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Plato’s zw|~on with<strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> visual arts is crucial,<br />

for it aga<strong>in</strong> reveals the Greek tendency not to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between image <strong>and</strong> subject.<br />

Additional evidence for this tendency <strong>in</strong> connection with zw|~on derives from a<br />

passage <strong>of</strong> Plato’s Politicus (Statesman), whose topic is expert knowledge <strong>of</strong> the just<br />

592 For the translation “all k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> materials,” see Griffith, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic 220.<br />

302


government <strong>of</strong> the state. Four persons participate <strong>in</strong> this dialogue—Socrates, <strong>The</strong>odorus<br />

<strong>of</strong> Cyrene, a Stranger, <strong>and</strong> Socrates the Younger. <strong>The</strong> word occurs twice <strong>in</strong> a passage <strong>in</strong><br />

which the Stranger highlights the <strong>in</strong>complete state <strong>of</strong> his conversation with the younger<br />

Socrates:<br />

So we have made our discourse too long <strong>and</strong> after all have never made an end <strong>of</strong><br />

the tale, but our talk, just like a zw|~on, seems to have a good enough outl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

(e1cwqen me\n perigrafh_n), but not yet to have received the clearness<br />

[e0na&rgeian] that comes from pigments <strong>and</strong> the blend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> colors. And yet it is<br />

more fitt<strong>in</strong>g to portray (dhlou~n) any zw|~on by speech <strong>and</strong> argument than by<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (grafh~j) or any h<strong>and</strong>icraft (xeirourgi/aj) whatsoever to persons who<br />

are able to follow the argument; but to others it is better to do it by means <strong>of</strong><br />

works <strong>of</strong> craftsmanship (dia_ xeirourgiw~n). (Plt. 277c) [146]<br />

Plato’s Stranger describes the <strong>in</strong>complete state <strong>of</strong> his discussion with the younger<br />

Socrates as analogous to the artistic render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a zw|~on, whose outl<strong>in</strong>e is sketched, but<br />

the application <strong>of</strong> colors to it has not yet been completed. 593 Harold Fowler translates this<br />

zw|~on as a “picture <strong>of</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>and</strong> Christopher Rowe as a “portrait.” 594 With<strong>in</strong><br />

this context, which po<strong>in</strong>ts to pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> thus to the visual arts, the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the first<br />

zw|~on is not easy to determ<strong>in</strong>e. It can be understood both as an <strong>in</strong>complete (just the<br />

outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> an) image or subject <strong>of</strong> representation, underscor<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong> the tendency not to<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guish between image <strong>and</strong> subject. Either way, the aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>completeness that<br />

dom<strong>in</strong>ates both possibilities is essential, for it contrasts with the previously seen mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|~on as the f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. What this contrast reveals is that different<br />

stages <strong>of</strong> the process employed for the production <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art to which zw|~on<br />

referred did not affect the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong> the fourth century.<br />

593 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the connection between the notion <strong>of</strong> “outl<strong>in</strong>e sketchily,” <strong>and</strong> the ancient term<br />

skiagraphia, see Keuls, Plato <strong>and</strong> Greek Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g 75.<br />

594 H. Fowler, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Statesman. Philebus (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925; repr. 1962)<br />

77; C. J. Rowe, tr., Statesman, <strong>in</strong> J. M. Cooper, ed., Plato. Complete Works (Indianapolis <strong>and</strong> Cambridge,<br />

1997) 319.<br />

303


As for the second zw|~on <strong>of</strong> the passage, it has been taken to mean “liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g.” 595 <strong>The</strong> word is mentioned with<strong>in</strong> a context that connects it directly to the art <strong>of</strong><br />

rhetoric as seen <strong>in</strong> speech <strong>and</strong> argument <strong>and</strong> also to that <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g: “it is more fitt<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

portray (dhlou~n) any zw|~on by speech <strong>and</strong> argument than by pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.” 596 <strong>The</strong> word<br />

dhlou~n suggests a direct l<strong>in</strong>k with the notion <strong>of</strong> “show<strong>in</strong>g;” as such, it implies that zw|~on<br />

was shown or presented to listeners <strong>and</strong> spectators, therefore, its mean<strong>in</strong>g is fitt<strong>in</strong>g as that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the subject <strong>of</strong> discussion <strong>and</strong> representation respectively. Such evidence accords well<br />

with Else’s demonstration <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> mimesis as be<strong>in</strong>g rooted <strong>in</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

“mimicry” or the vocal <strong>and</strong> active imitation <strong>of</strong> voices <strong>and</strong> movement, <strong>and</strong> its application<br />

to material “images” <strong>in</strong> Plato’s time 597 ; as such, it suggests that zw|~on carries a direct<br />

connection with mimesis here. <strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this zw|~on as the subject <strong>of</strong><br />

representation, when juxtaposed with the ambivalent mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the first zw|~on, which<br />

oscillated between the notions <strong>of</strong> image <strong>and</strong> subject, suggests that when used <strong>in</strong> an artistic<br />

context, the term did not have a fixed mean<strong>in</strong>g, but rather mirrored the tendency to leave<br />

unmarked the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between image <strong>and</strong> subject.<br />

Further evidence for zw|~on <strong>in</strong> direct association with the arts is found <strong>in</strong> a section<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Laws, <strong>in</strong> which the term refers to the subject <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

Three persons—Kle<strong>in</strong>ias from Crete, Megalus from Sparta, <strong>and</strong> an unnamed Athenian—<br />

595 Fowler, Plato. <strong>The</strong> Statesman 77, <strong>and</strong> Rowe, Statesman, <strong>in</strong> Cooper, ed., Plato Complete Works 319,<br />

translate the second zw|~on <strong>of</strong> this passage as “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs” respectively.<br />

596 For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the analogy between the words <strong>of</strong> sophists <strong>and</strong> the images <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>in</strong> ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong>, see J. P. Vernant, “<strong>The</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> Images,” <strong>in</strong> F. I. Zeitl<strong>in</strong>, ed., Mortals <strong>and</strong> Immortals. Collected<br />

Essays (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1992) 172-173.<br />

597 Else, “‘Imitation’ <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century” 87, where he traces the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> mimesis to the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

mimicry, more specifically, “the render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> characteristic look, action, or sound through human means”<br />

<strong>and</strong> further states that by the time Plato was born, “the concept <strong>of</strong> mimicry was transferred to material<br />

“images”: pictures, statues, <strong>and</strong> the like.”<br />

304


form a group <strong>of</strong> discussants on the subject <strong>of</strong> laws <strong>and</strong> constitutions <strong>of</strong> the ideal state.<br />

<strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on occurs twice <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> a discussion between the Athenian <strong>and</strong><br />

Kle<strong>in</strong>ias on the criticism <strong>of</strong> the arts:<br />

ATHENIAN. <strong>The</strong>re are <strong>of</strong> course myriad images (a)peikasi/ai) which are visible<br />

to our eye.<br />

KLEINIAS. Yes.<br />

ATHENIAN. What then, if someone doesn’t know what each <strong>of</strong> the bodies <strong>of</strong> the<br />

memimhme/nwn is? Would he ever know what is correctly executed <strong>in</strong> them? What<br />

I mean is someth<strong>in</strong>g like this: doesn’t he have to know whether the imitation<br />

captures the number <strong>and</strong> the arrangement <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> the parts, how many there are<br />

<strong>and</strong> how they fit next to one another <strong>in</strong> the appropriate order, <strong>and</strong> also the colors<br />

<strong>and</strong> shapes, or whether all these th<strong>in</strong>gs have been put together <strong>in</strong> a confused way?<br />

Do you th<strong>in</strong>k someone can ever know these th<strong>in</strong>gs if he is completely ignorant <strong>of</strong><br />

what is the memimhme/non zw|~on?<br />

KLEINIAS. How could he?<br />

ATHENIAN. What if we were to know that the gegramme/non <strong>and</strong> peplasme/non<br />

is a human be<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> that all his own parts, colors, <strong>and</strong> shapes have been<br />

captured by the art? Does it follow necessarily that whoever knows about these<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs also readily knows whether the work is beautiful or just where it is<br />

deficient <strong>in</strong> beauty?<br />

KLEINIAS. That would mean, stranger, that all <strong>of</strong> us, so to speak, know what is<br />

beautiful <strong>in</strong> any zw|&wn.<br />

ATHENIAN. What you say is very correct. Isn’t it the case, then, that with<br />

regard to each image (ei0ko&na), <strong>in</strong> grafikh|~ <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> music <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all the rest, the<br />

person who is go<strong>in</strong>g to be a prudent judge must have three k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> knowledge?<br />

He must know first what the th<strong>in</strong>g is, <strong>and</strong> then know how correctly, <strong>and</strong> then—the<br />

third th<strong>in</strong>g—how well, any <strong>of</strong> the images (ei0ko&nwn) <strong>of</strong> it <strong>in</strong> words, tunes, <strong>and</strong><br />

rhythms are produced. (Leg. 668c-669b) [144]<br />

By mark<strong>in</strong>g the abundance <strong>of</strong> images <strong>in</strong> the surround<strong>in</strong>g culture, the open<strong>in</strong>g statement <strong>of</strong><br />

the Athenian expresses a concern with the visual arts. This concern is reiterated next <strong>in</strong><br />

the description <strong>of</strong> a hypothetical viewer, who is confronted with each <strong>of</strong> the bodies <strong>of</strong> the<br />

memimhme/nwn, yet ignorance <strong>of</strong> specific aspects <strong>of</strong> their composition <strong>and</strong> appearance<br />

305


disqualifies him from judg<strong>in</strong>g if they are executed correctly. <strong>The</strong> word memimhme/nwn is<br />

the perfect participle <strong>of</strong> the verb mime&omai, which is connected to mi/mhsij (mimesis), a<br />

term which, as noted above, is critical to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek, particularly Platonic, view<br />

<strong>of</strong> “representation” <strong>in</strong> the arts. Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott translate this memimhme/nwn as “artistic<br />

representations.” 598 Consider<strong>in</strong>g that the Athenian speaks <strong>of</strong> “each <strong>of</strong> the bodies<br />

(swma&twn) <strong>of</strong> the memimhme/nwn,” then, the latter phrase should be understood as each <strong>of</strong><br />

the bodies <strong>of</strong> subjects that have been represented <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. Swma&twn is the<br />

genitive plural <strong>of</strong> sw~ma, a word that Liddell <strong>and</strong> Scott consider to be Plato’s usual term<br />

for the body <strong>of</strong> a human be<strong>in</strong>g or animal. 599 If this observation is correct, then the above<br />

memimhme/nwn should be understood as artistic representations <strong>of</strong> the bodies <strong>of</strong> human<br />

be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong>/or animals. Also <strong>in</strong> the Cratylus (400a-400c), Plato perceives <strong>of</strong> the soul as a<br />

power which, when present <strong>in</strong> the body, “causes it to live <strong>and</strong> gives it the power to<br />

breathe the air <strong>and</strong> be revitalized” (400a); thus, the body is “an enclosure or prison <strong>in</strong><br />

which the soul is securely kept” (400c). 600 This remark is important, for it implies that<br />

for Plato representations <strong>of</strong> bodies were most likely deprived <strong>of</strong> life <strong>and</strong> animation.<br />

To be able to judge artistic representations effectively one needs to be familiar<br />

with specific aspects <strong>of</strong> their composition <strong>and</strong> appearance. To the Athenian, these<br />

aspects correspond to “numbers” (a)riqmou&j), <strong>and</strong> “arrangement” (ta&c<strong>in</strong>), “colors”<br />

(xrw&mata), <strong>and</strong> “shapes, designs, or forms” (sxh&mata). <strong>The</strong>se elements belong to both<br />

the orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>and</strong> the representation. Not surpris<strong>in</strong>gly, these are all terms that feature<br />

598 LSJ 9 , 1134, s.v. mime&omai.<br />

599 LSJ 9 , 1749, s.v. sw~ma, suggest that Plato uses the word to refer to the body <strong>of</strong> a man (Resp. 469d) or<br />

animal (Resp. 564a), as opposed to Herodotus, who uses it for “plant” <strong>and</strong> also “liv<strong>in</strong>g body” (1.139).<br />

600 Translations: Reeve, Plato. Cratylus 30 <strong>and</strong> 31, respectively.<br />

306


prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> Plato’s discussion <strong>of</strong> criticism <strong>of</strong> the arts. 601 In this dialogue, their<br />

importance <strong>in</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g the first steps <strong>of</strong> the evaluat<strong>in</strong>g process for works <strong>of</strong> art culm<strong>in</strong>ates<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Athenian’s question to Kle<strong>in</strong>ias: “do you th<strong>in</strong>k that someone can ever know these<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs (i.e., numbers, order, colors, <strong>and</strong> shapes), if he is completely ignorant <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

the memimhme/non zw|~on?” <strong>The</strong> question is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it establishes that previous<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> what is actually represented <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art is a prerequisite for effective<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> the artistic value <strong>of</strong> this work. <strong>The</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular zw|~on is called memimhme/non,<br />

thus establish<strong>in</strong>g the previously suggested connection between zw|~on <strong>and</strong> mi/mhsij<br />

(mimesis), that is, the notion <strong>of</strong> representation. Robert Bury suggests that this zw|~on<br />

means “animal” <strong>and</strong> Thomas Pangle, “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g.” 602 Neither <strong>of</strong> these translations is<br />

satisfactory. On the basis <strong>of</strong> the above evidence, zw|~on appears to refer mostly to the<br />

subject be<strong>in</strong>g represented <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art, although the possibility <strong>of</strong> it referr<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

artistic image produced cannot be ruled out. As can be seen, zw|~on aga<strong>in</strong> st<strong>and</strong>s for the<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the notions <strong>of</strong> subject <strong>and</strong> image <strong>in</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Athenian’s next hypothesis, that this subject could be a human be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

some <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the question <strong>of</strong> the identity <strong>of</strong> an artistic subject. Although the noun<br />

zw|~on is omitted from the Athenian’s sentence, the neuter adjectives gegramme/non<br />

(“pa<strong>in</strong>ted,” “sketched”) <strong>and</strong> peplasme/non (“sculptured”) agree with it <strong>in</strong> both gender<br />

<strong>and</strong> grammatical case, thus <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that their follow<strong>in</strong>g by zw|~on is certa<strong>in</strong> here. In this<br />

way, memimhme/non zw|~on is to be more closely def<strong>in</strong>ed as a representational subject <strong>in</strong><br />

601 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Pollitt, Ancient View 16-17, Plato considers “numbers” carefully <strong>in</strong> connection with the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> symmetria or commensurability <strong>of</strong> all parts <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art (Phil. 25d-e), <strong>and</strong> Aristotle (Metaph.<br />

1090a) states that, for the Pythagoreans, numbers constituted the first pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> sensible physical bodies.<br />

For the use <strong>of</strong> “color” <strong>and</strong> “shape, design, or form” both for visual appearance <strong>and</strong> for the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> Plato, see Keuls, Plato <strong>and</strong> Greek Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g 37-38; <strong>and</strong> Pollitt, Ancient View 258-262, for the second<br />

term.<br />

602 Bury, Plato. Laws I 143; T. L. Pangle, tr., <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato (New York, 1980) 50.<br />

307


pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, sketch<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> sculpture. <strong>The</strong> comment that this particular zw|~on could<br />

represent a human be<strong>in</strong>g complements previous evidence that zw|~on <strong>in</strong> Plato referred to<br />

animate subjects <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art; whereas its different versions here<br />

confirm that it need not be the product <strong>of</strong> a specific artistic process.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question that the Athenian next poses to Kle<strong>in</strong>ias <strong>in</strong>dicates that the parts,<br />

colors, <strong>and</strong> shapes <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al were, as noted above, parts <strong>of</strong> the representation too.<br />

What we learn here is that they were aspects on the basis <strong>of</strong> which a specific quality <strong>of</strong> a<br />

work <strong>of</strong> art was judged: its beauty. “What if we were to know, [the Athenian asks,] that<br />

all his own [a human be<strong>in</strong>g’s] parts, colors, <strong>and</strong> shapes have been captured by the art?<br />

“Does it follow necessarily that whoever knows about these th<strong>in</strong>gs also readily knows<br />

whether the work is beautiful or just where it is deficient <strong>in</strong> beauty?” Kle<strong>in</strong>ias’ response<br />

that more or less all people are competent <strong>in</strong> judg<strong>in</strong>g the subject a work <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>in</strong><br />

particular, how correctly it is represented recalls the already seen connection between<br />

accurate representation <strong>and</strong> lifelikeness as an artistic criterion for all audiences <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, regardless <strong>of</strong> their degree <strong>of</strong> sophistication. His response further<br />

suggests, however, that knowledge <strong>of</strong> the excellence with which the work was executed<br />

was a specialized criterion that only technical experts <strong>and</strong> connoisseurs possessed. It is<br />

implied, therefore, that average spectators are excluded from this category because<br />

otherwise, as Kle<strong>in</strong>ias asserts: “that would mean, stranger, that all <strong>of</strong> us, so to speak,<br />

know what is beautiful <strong>in</strong> any zw|&wn.” Once aga<strong>in</strong>, the appearance <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn, which is<br />

here <strong>in</strong> the genitive plural form, is not described; therefore, its use <strong>in</strong> a very general sense<br />

is once aga<strong>in</strong> confirmed. Bury suggests that these zw|&wn should be understood as<br />

308


“animals,” <strong>and</strong> Pangle, as “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs.” 603 In view <strong>of</strong> the direct association <strong>of</strong> the<br />

overall discussion with the arts, however, these translations do not appear fitt<strong>in</strong>g; on the<br />

contrary, Kle<strong>in</strong>ias’ use <strong>of</strong> zw|&wn with<strong>in</strong> this context suggests that the term refers to<br />

subjects <strong>and</strong>/or images represented <strong>in</strong> art. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the direct association <strong>of</strong> these zw|&wn<br />

with the concept <strong>of</strong> beauty as a criterion for aesthetic judgment places the term with<strong>in</strong> the<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts. That Plato’s Athenian <strong>in</strong>tended to establish a<br />

firm connection with this context is viewed <strong>in</strong> his clos<strong>in</strong>g statement which summarizes<br />

clearly three k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> knowledge that a qualified judge <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art needed to possess:<br />

a) knowledge <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al, b) knowledge <strong>of</strong> the correctness <strong>of</strong> the copy,<br />

<strong>and</strong> c) knowledge <strong>of</strong> the excellence with which the copy was executed. That these<br />

criteria for judgment concerned “every image <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, music, or any other art,”<br />

establishes the overall concern <strong>of</strong> the dialogue with the realm <strong>of</strong> the arts.<br />

Further mention <strong>of</strong> the zw|~on <strong>in</strong> connection with the arts, <strong>in</strong> particular pa<strong>in</strong>tn<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

occurs <strong>in</strong> another section <strong>of</strong> the Laws, <strong>in</strong> which only the Athenian <strong>and</strong> Kle<strong>in</strong>ias take part.<br />

<strong>The</strong> former compares the processes <strong>of</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> preserv<strong>in</strong>g a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to those <strong>of</strong><br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g a law:<br />

ATHENIAN. You know how the pa<strong>in</strong>ters’ (zwgra&fwn) activity, for example,<br />

never seems to f<strong>in</strong>ish work<strong>in</strong>g on each <strong>of</strong> the zw|&wn, but keeps touch<strong>in</strong>g up<br />

(xrai/ne<strong>in</strong>) or highlight<strong>in</strong>g (a)poxrai/ne<strong>in</strong>)—or whatever the pa<strong>in</strong>ters’<br />

(zwgra&fwn) disciples call such activity? It seems never to cease its adorn<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence never to reach a po<strong>in</strong>t where there can be no further improvement <strong>of</strong><br />

the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs (gegramme/na) as regards beauty <strong>and</strong> clarity.<br />

KLEINIAS. I too know pretty well these th<strong>in</strong>gs you’re talk<strong>in</strong>g about, by<br />

hearsay—for I am not at all practiced, at least, <strong>in</strong> such an art (te/xnh|).<br />

603 Bury, Plato. Laws I 145; Pangle, <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato 51.<br />

309


ATHENIAN. That’s no h<strong>in</strong>drance for you. We’ll still make use <strong>of</strong> this allusion<br />

to it that’s cropped up <strong>in</strong> our discussion now, <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g like the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

way: suppose someone once took it <strong>in</strong>to his head to pa<strong>in</strong>t (gra&yai) the most<br />

ka&lliston zw|~on possible, one that would never get worse but would always<br />

improve as time went by. Don’t you see that s<strong>in</strong>ce he’s mortal, he’ll have to leave<br />

beh<strong>in</strong>d a successor, able to make it right if the zw|~on suffers from decay at the<br />

h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> time, as well as to make future touch-ups that improve the deficiencies<br />

left by his own artistic weaknesses? Otherwise, won’t his very great labor last but<br />

a brief time?<br />

KLEINIAS. That’s true.<br />

ATHENIAN. Well, then, don’t you th<strong>in</strong>k the lawgiver has such a purpose? He<br />

first writes (gra&yai) his laws with as nearly adequate a precision as he can<br />

muster. <strong>The</strong>n, with the passage <strong>of</strong> time, as his op<strong>in</strong>ions are tried out <strong>in</strong> deed, do<br />

you suppose there’s any lawgiver who is so imprudent as to be ignorant <strong>of</strong> the fact<br />

that he must necessarily have left very many such th<strong>in</strong>gs that require be<strong>in</strong>g set<br />

right by some follower, if the regime <strong>and</strong> order <strong>of</strong> the city he has founded are<br />

always to become <strong>in</strong> no way worse but <strong>in</strong>stead better? (Leg. 769a-769d) [145]<br />

In this dialogue, the prom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is strik<strong>in</strong>g. Plato uses three different terms:<br />

zwgra&fwn (“pa<strong>in</strong>ters”), gra&yai (“pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g”), <strong>and</strong> gegramme/na (“pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs”) all <strong>of</strong><br />

which br<strong>in</strong>g to m<strong>in</strong>d the previous connection between gra&fw <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore, establish firmly the context <strong>of</strong> this artistic process. Additional support for this<br />

context derives also from the terms xrai/ne<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> a)poxrai/ne<strong>in</strong>. Although their exact<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g rema<strong>in</strong>s elusive, the suggestions <strong>of</strong> “touch<strong>in</strong>g-up” <strong>and</strong> “highlight<strong>in</strong>g,” as <strong>in</strong> the<br />

above translation, <strong>and</strong> also “color<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “shad<strong>in</strong>g,” show preoccupation with certa<strong>in</strong><br />

technical aspects <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g; as such, these terms enhance the connection with the<br />

technical vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts. 604 With<strong>in</strong> this context, the word zw|~on occurs three<br />

times. <strong>The</strong> first time, the term appears <strong>in</strong> its genitive plural form—zw|&wn. <strong>The</strong> Athenian<br />

states that pa<strong>in</strong>ters never f<strong>in</strong>ish work<strong>in</strong>g on each <strong>of</strong> the zw|~a. Like the good <strong>and</strong> bad<br />

works (zw|~a) <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>in</strong> the Cratylus, these zw|&wn st<strong>and</strong> for the works <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>in</strong><br />

604 For this suggestion <strong>and</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> these terms <strong>and</strong> their translations as “color<strong>in</strong>g”<br />

<strong>and</strong> “shad<strong>in</strong>g,” see Keuls, Plato <strong>and</strong> Greek Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g 115-117.<br />

310


general. Trevor Saunders attempts to capture this general sense by render<strong>in</strong>g the phrase<br />

“each <strong>of</strong> the zw|&wn” as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g a picture <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g.” 605 His translation does not<br />

follow Plato’s text literally, <strong>and</strong> therefore, it qualifies as a paraphrase. Pangle, on the<br />

contrary, underst<strong>and</strong>s zw|&wn as “figures,” <strong>and</strong> Bury as “subjects.” Bury’s equation <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|&wn with “subjects” seems appropriate, especially when seen <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> earlier<br />

evidence that Plato perceived zw|~on as the subject <strong>of</strong> representation <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ted works <strong>of</strong><br />

art.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second zw|~on occurs <strong>in</strong> the part <strong>of</strong> the dialogue <strong>in</strong> which the Athenian asks<br />

Kle<strong>in</strong>ias to consider a hypothetical situation: “suppose someone once took it <strong>in</strong>to his head<br />

(e0p<strong>in</strong>oh&seie) to pa<strong>in</strong>t the most beautiful zw|~on possible.” <strong>The</strong> designation <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as<br />

ka&lliston (“most beautiful”) makes it a construction <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e quality, a characteristic that<br />

accords well with previous evidence from the Laws, which discussed zw|~a <strong>in</strong> conjunction<br />

with the concept <strong>of</strong> beauty. As for the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this zw|~on it is not without difficulties.<br />

Pangle translates the term as “figure,” Bury as “object,” <strong>and</strong> Saunders as “picture.” 606<br />

<strong>The</strong> truth is that it is not possible to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether this zw|~on refers to the subject,<br />

image, or pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as a physical object. Given the situation, Plato appears to be us<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

word <strong>in</strong> a similar manner as the earlier zw|&wn, which blurred the boundary between<br />

subject, image, <strong>and</strong> object. What is worth notic<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this zw|~on, however, is that it is<br />

perceived as the outcome <strong>of</strong> a mental process: “suppose someone took it <strong>in</strong>to his head to<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t the most beautiful zw|~on,” says the Athenian. This comment is <strong>in</strong>structive, for it<br />

l<strong>in</strong>ks zw|~on with the realm <strong>of</strong> fourth-century discourse <strong>of</strong> visual perception.<br />

605<br />

T. Saunders, tr., Laws, <strong>in</strong> J. M. Cooper, ed., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Complete Works (Indianapolis <strong>and</strong> Cambridge,<br />

1997) 1443.<br />

606<br />

Figure: Pangle, <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato 156; Object: Bury, Plato. Laws I 451; Picture: Saunders, Laws, <strong>in</strong><br />

Cooper, ed., Plato. Complete Works 1443.<br />

311


Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the third zw|~on <strong>of</strong> the dialogue, one sees that it is used aga<strong>in</strong> by the<br />

Athenian, who tells Kle<strong>in</strong>ias that if a hypothetical pa<strong>in</strong>ter wants his work to survive time,<br />

he has to assign a successor. <strong>The</strong> latter should be able to preserve the zw|~on from the<br />

destructive effects <strong>of</strong> time, provide touch-ups, <strong>and</strong> remedy any artistic deficiencies <strong>of</strong> the<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al artist/work. This l<strong>in</strong>e suggests that zw|~on was the work <strong>of</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>ter. <strong>The</strong> term<br />

has been translated as “pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “picture,” 607 but aga<strong>in</strong> it is not clear if what is<br />

meant here is the subject, image, or pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as an object. <strong>The</strong> references to decay <strong>and</strong><br />

touch-ups suggest that the Athenian had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d the material aspects <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. An<br />

<strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g aspect <strong>of</strong> this zw|~on, however, is its status as the creation not <strong>of</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ter, but successive generations <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ters. In this respect, zw|~on is not a static artistic<br />

creation, but one that undergoes changes progressively <strong>in</strong> order to reach perfection. This<br />

evidence is <strong>of</strong> considerable importance, for it h<strong>in</strong>ts at the application <strong>of</strong> a teleological<br />

model to the appreciation <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. In this way, zw|~on appears as a term <strong>of</strong> the<br />

vocabulary <strong>of</strong> art criticism. As for the impression ga<strong>in</strong>ed from the three separate<br />

occurrences <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong> this passage all that can be said is that, when connected with<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, zw|~on did not held <strong>in</strong> Plato’s m<strong>in</strong>d a monolithic mean<strong>in</strong>g, but rather a flexible<br />

one, which blurred easily the boundaries among subject, image, <strong>and</strong> physical object.<br />

Alcidamas<br />

<strong>The</strong> second fourth-century author who makes use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> a context that<br />

directly <strong>in</strong>volved the arts is Alcidamas. In his treatise On Those Who Write Written<br />

Speeches or On Sophists (c. 390 B.C.), he uses the word to refer to pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

607<br />

“Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g”: Pangle, <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato 157; “picture”: Bury, Plato. Laws 451; also Saunders, Laws, <strong>in</strong><br />

Cooper, ed., Plato. Complete Works 1443.<br />

312


And I do not th<strong>in</strong>k it is right that speeches written down should even be called<br />

speeches, but should be thought <strong>of</strong> as ei1dwla <strong>and</strong> sxh&mata <strong>and</strong> mimh&mata <strong>of</strong><br />

speeches, <strong>and</strong> we could reasonably have the same op<strong>in</strong>ion about them as we have<br />

about bronze a)ndria&ntwn <strong>and</strong> stone a)galma&twn <strong>and</strong> gegramme/nwn zw|&wn.<br />

For, just as these are mimh&mata <strong>of</strong> a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n swma&twn <strong>and</strong> give delight to the<br />

view, but <strong>of</strong>fer no use <strong>in</strong> human life, <strong>in</strong> the same way the written speech, hav<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle sxh&mati <strong>and</strong> ta&cei, produces certa<strong>in</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g effects when it is conned<br />

from the book, but be<strong>in</strong>g fixedly unable to respond to critical moments, if <strong>of</strong> no<br />

use to those who have got hold <strong>of</strong> it. Just as the real bodies present an appearance<br />

far <strong>in</strong>ferior to that <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e statues but yet as many times more useful for gett<strong>in</strong>g<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs done, so too the speech spoken straight from the heart on the spur <strong>of</strong> the<br />

moment has a soul <strong>in</strong> it <strong>and</strong> is alive <strong>and</strong> follows upon events <strong>and</strong> is like those real<br />

bodies, while the written speech whose nature corresponds to a representation <strong>of</strong><br />

the real th<strong>in</strong>g lacks any k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g power. (Soph. 1.27) [10]<br />

In this passage, Alcidamas argues the importance <strong>of</strong> improvised speeches by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out<br />

the weaknesses <strong>of</strong> the written ones. He ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that the latter should be thought <strong>of</strong> not<br />

as speeches, but as the equivalents <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. That he had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d the context <strong>of</strong><br />

visual arts, more precisely, that <strong>of</strong> sculpture <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, is evident from his explicit<br />

references to bronze a)ndria&ntwn, stone a)galma&twn, <strong>and</strong> gegramme/nwn zw|&wn. As<br />

stated earlier, a)ndria&j is a statue <strong>of</strong> the kouros type, <strong>and</strong> a1galma an ord<strong>in</strong>ary statue <strong>and</strong><br />

also that <strong>of</strong> a god; also zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the company <strong>of</strong> gegramme/non <strong>and</strong> other derivatives <strong>of</strong><br />

the verb gra&fw has been repeatedly seen to carry associations with pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g; therefore,<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> gegramme/nwn zw|&wn should here be def<strong>in</strong>ed as pa<strong>in</strong>ted images <strong>of</strong> some<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d. This def<strong>in</strong>ition does not agree with that <strong>of</strong> “depictions <strong>of</strong> animals,” which has been<br />

recently suggested. 608 Alcidamas’ reference to statues (a)ndria&ntwn, a)galma&twn) <strong>and</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Empedocles’ fragment, which also referred to statues<br />

(a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong>) <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ted images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d (graptoi=j zw|&oisi). 609 Alcidamas’ text<br />

608 J. V. Muir, ed., tr., Alcidamas. <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>and</strong> Fragments (Bristol, 2001) 15, 17.<br />

609 That Alcidamas was familiar with the work <strong>of</strong> Empedocles is a possibility that cannot be ruled out.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Muir, Alcidamas. <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>and</strong> Fragments vi: “there is an <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>in</strong>t [i.e., Diog. Laert.<br />

8.56] that Alcidamas may have written the lives <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the Pre-Socratic philosophers, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Zeno<br />

<strong>and</strong> Empedocles, <strong>in</strong> a book entitled the Physikon.”<br />

313


is, however, more explicit <strong>in</strong> its description. <strong>The</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> bronze a)ndria&ntej, stone<br />

a)ga&lmata, <strong>and</strong> gegramme/na zw|~a to which it refers are all grouped together under the<br />

same label: artistic representations <strong>of</strong> real bodies (mimh&mata tw~n a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n<br />

swma&twn). This word<strong>in</strong>g seems to be <strong>in</strong>fluenced by, if not a direct borrow<strong>in</strong>g from,<br />

Plato’s earlier reference <strong>in</strong> the Laws to the bodies <strong>of</strong> subjects represented <strong>in</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art<br />

(tw~n memimhme/nwn…e3kaston tw~n swma&twn) [144]. 610 This impression is further<br />

re<strong>in</strong>forced by Alcidamas’ use <strong>of</strong> the terms sxh&mati (form) <strong>and</strong> ta&cei (arrangement),<br />

which were also used by Plato <strong>in</strong> the Laws. 611 As mentioned earlier, sw~ma is Plato’s<br />

usual word for the body <strong>of</strong> a human be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> animal. If the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Plato on<br />

Alcidamas is considered here, then Alcidamas’ swma&twn may be perceived as bodies <strong>of</strong><br />

similar entities as well. What needs to be mentioned, however, is the contention that<br />

ancient Greek conflated sw&mata (“bodies”) with images <strong>of</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs, a l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

usage which, <strong>in</strong> turn, reveals an anthropocentric <strong>in</strong>filtration <strong>in</strong> the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the<br />

arts. 612 That Alcidamas calls the bodies to which he refers a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n (“true”) is a detail<br />

that deserves further attention. 0Alhq<strong>in</strong>w~n derives from a)lh&qeia, a word, whose<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard mean<strong>in</strong>g is “truth,” but, when <strong>in</strong> connection with the visual arts, as is the case<br />

here, has many implications <strong>and</strong> connotations. Pollitt identifies four different mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

when a)lh&qeia is used <strong>in</strong> this context: a) “real experience” as opposed to “anticipation or<br />

“imag<strong>in</strong>ed experience,” b) the “real th<strong>in</strong>g,” an external physical reality, as opposed <strong>and</strong><br />

610<br />

On the basis <strong>of</strong> evidence emerg<strong>in</strong>g from On Those Who Write Speeches, Alcidamas is considered a rival<br />

<strong>of</strong> Isocrates (436-338), therefore, a contemporary <strong>of</strong> Plato (429-347 B.C.). For a discussion <strong>of</strong> the rivalry<br />

between Alcidamas <strong>and</strong> Isocrates, see Muir, Alcidamas xii-xv.<br />

611<br />

In his commentary on this treatise <strong>of</strong> Alcidamas, Muir, Alcidamas. <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>and</strong> Fragments xiv,<br />

speaks <strong>of</strong> the familiarity <strong>of</strong> this author with the work <strong>of</strong> Plato <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way: “Perhaps the most<br />

surpris<strong>in</strong>g evidence <strong>of</strong> a connection is with Plato/Socrates: Alcidamas had clearly picked up some notion <strong>of</strong><br />

the theory <strong>of</strong> the Forms <strong>and</strong> had also read at least the last section <strong>of</strong> the Phaedrus where the mythical story<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>uth is taken up by Socrates to exp<strong>and</strong> on the limitations <strong>of</strong> the written word.”<br />

612<br />

Schnapp, “Are Images Animated,” <strong>in</strong> Renfrew <strong>and</strong> Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient M<strong>in</strong>d 42 (without<br />

documentation).<br />

314


contrasted to the representations <strong>of</strong> it, c) “visible reality accurately represented,” as<br />

opposed to “<strong>in</strong>accurate representation,” <strong>and</strong> d) reality or truth as confirmed by<br />

measurement. 613 That a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n swma&twn (“<strong>of</strong> true bodies”) refers to mimh&mata<br />

(“artistic representations”) marks a contrast between the two nouns<br />

(swma&twn <strong>and</strong> mimh&mata). This contrast, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests that a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n def<strong>in</strong>es<br />

bodies as real, <strong>and</strong> physical. In light <strong>of</strong> this evidence, the fact that gegramme/nwn zw|&wn<br />

(pa<strong>in</strong>ted images <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d) were mimh&mata tw~n a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n swma&twn (“artistic<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> real, physical bodies”) suggests that zw|&wn were understood as<br />

representations <strong>of</strong> real bodies or as figural images that lacked life. Alcidamas is explicit<br />

about the lifeless status <strong>of</strong> these images: “[they] give delight to the view, but <strong>of</strong>fer no use<br />

<strong>in</strong> human life,” [<strong>and</strong> unlike real bodies, they are not] “useful for gett<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs done.” In<br />

addition, written speech is like them, <strong>in</strong> the sense that it “corresponds to a representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the real th<strong>in</strong>g, [but] lacks any k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g power.” What is central <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|&wn <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> these remarks is a general preoccupation with bodily form, but also<br />

with convey<strong>in</strong>g how physically <strong>in</strong>ert the content <strong>of</strong> these forms (as images) was. When<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to this equation the etymology <strong>of</strong> zw|~on, which centers on the notions <strong>of</strong><br />

“liv<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “breath<strong>in</strong>g,” one sees its contribution to the realm <strong>of</strong> the arts. It stood for<br />

<strong>and</strong> expressed a conscious underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> two contrast<strong>in</strong>g ideas <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|~on as an image: be<strong>in</strong>g borrowed from real life, but be<strong>in</strong>g deprived <strong>of</strong> all force <strong>of</strong><br />

body, therefore, breath<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> animation. 614 F<strong>in</strong>ally, Alcidamas’ view <strong>of</strong> gegramme/nwn<br />

zw|&wn as pa<strong>in</strong>ted images <strong>of</strong> what is represented may be viewed <strong>in</strong> conjunction with the<br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g objects, that is, <strong>in</strong>scribed statues, stelai, <strong>and</strong> vessels, mostly <strong>of</strong><br />

613<br />

Pollitt, Ancient View 131-133.<br />

614<br />

For a discussion <strong>of</strong> images (ei1dwla) as “deprived <strong>of</strong> all animation, <strong>of</strong> all force <strong>of</strong> body or m<strong>in</strong>d,” see<br />

Donohue, Xoana 41.<br />

315


the Archaic <strong>and</strong> less <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> periods, which address the beholder usually <strong>in</strong><br />

the first, but also third person. This treatment, as seen <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> Myron’s cow, was a<br />

conscious attempt to help the representational subject become alive/ animated by<br />

borrow<strong>in</strong>g the voice <strong>of</strong> the spectator <strong>and</strong> engage <strong>in</strong> conversation with him. 615<br />

Aristotle<br />

<strong>The</strong> next fourth-century author to use zw|~on <strong>in</strong> connection with the arts is<br />

Aristotle. <strong>The</strong> word occurs eight times <strong>in</strong> three <strong>of</strong> his treatises: Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>,<br />

Categories, <strong>and</strong> On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection.<br />

In the Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Aristotle uses the term to refer to the subject <strong>of</strong><br />

representation <strong>in</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. After his description <strong>of</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> sk<strong>in</strong> on an animal<br />

embryo, Aristotle expla<strong>in</strong>s the formation <strong>of</strong> the body as a gradual process <strong>of</strong><br />

development:<br />

Now the upper portion <strong>of</strong> the body is the first to be marked <strong>of</strong>f <strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> the<br />

embryo’s formation; the lower portion receives its growth as time goes on. (This<br />

applies to the blooded animals. In the early stages the parts are all traced out <strong>in</strong><br />

outl<strong>in</strong>e; later on they get their various colors <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>tnesses <strong>and</strong> hardnesses, for all<br />

the world as if a pa<strong>in</strong>ter were at work on them, the pa<strong>in</strong>ter be<strong>in</strong>g Nature. Pa<strong>in</strong>ters,<br />

as we know, first <strong>of</strong> all sketch <strong>in</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> after that go on to apply the<br />

colors. (GA 743b) [49]<br />

615 Svenbro, Phrasikleia 30, clarifies that this phenomenon “does not mean to say that they [the objects] are<br />

their own authors,” but rather the viewers, through read<strong>in</strong>g, are the <strong>in</strong>struments that enable the objects to<br />

speak. As for actual examples <strong>of</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> this type, he mentions (30) the <strong>in</strong>scription on the early<br />

seventh-century bronze statuette <strong>of</strong> a man dedicated by M<strong>and</strong>rokles to Apollo at <strong>The</strong>bes: “M<strong>and</strong>rokles<br />

dedicated me”; the message (30, n. 19) written on a sixth-century amphora: “Kleimachos made me <strong>and</strong> I<br />

am his”; the <strong>in</strong>scription (32, n. 25) written on a funerary monument: “Here I am, the tomb <strong>of</strong> Krites,”<br />

which declares a sema from the pla<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> Marathon dat<strong>in</strong>g from 500 B.C.; <strong>and</strong> also 39, n. 58, “the dedication<br />

by Praxiteles, <strong>in</strong>scribed on a votive base discovered at Olympia <strong>and</strong> dat<strong>in</strong>g from the first half <strong>of</strong> the fifth<br />

century: “Praxiteles, a citizen <strong>of</strong> Syracuse, dedicated this statue…<strong>and</strong> this is the monument commemorat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

his virtue.” For a similar discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>scribed objects <strong>in</strong> Greek culture, with emphasis on the Archaic<br />

period, see Hurwit, “<strong>The</strong> Words <strong>in</strong> the Image” 180-190.<br />

316


Aristotle likens the formation <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>of</strong> an animal embryo to the creation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ted depiction. In his view, nature first forms the parts <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> then<br />

proceeds to add color <strong>and</strong> texture to them. In this respect, nature is like a pa<strong>in</strong>ter, who<br />

first sketches the zw|~on <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> then proceeds to add color to it. <strong>The</strong> word ζw|~on<br />

has been translated as “animal,” but this render<strong>in</strong>g does not seem appropriate. Given the<br />

direct association <strong>of</strong> the context with pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, the term can be better understood as the<br />

image <strong>in</strong> general or the subject <strong>of</strong> representation that the pa<strong>in</strong>ter <strong>in</strong>tended to create. <strong>The</strong><br />

blurr<strong>in</strong>g between image <strong>and</strong> subject is not surpris<strong>in</strong>g here, s<strong>in</strong>ce it conforms to an earlier<br />

tendency already encountered <strong>in</strong> Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Plato. Regard<strong>in</strong>g the sketch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this<br />

zw|~on <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e, two aspects st<strong>and</strong> out clearly: first, it constitutes an early stage <strong>in</strong> the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> second, it exhibits a concern with form. This aspect strengthens<br />

the possibility that what Aristotle had actually <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when us<strong>in</strong>g zw|~on was not so<br />

much the image represented by a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, but rather the representational subject itself.<br />

In addition, Aristotle’s concern with form as expressed <strong>in</strong> his reference to outl<strong>in</strong>e recalls,<br />

<strong>in</strong> general, Alcidamas’ preoccupation with form, <strong>and</strong> more specifically, Plato’s Stranger<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Politicus. As seen earlier, the Stranger resembled the <strong>in</strong>complete stage <strong>of</strong> his<br />

discussion with the younger Socrates to that <strong>of</strong> a sufficiently outl<strong>in</strong>ed, but still colorless<br />

zw|~on produced by means <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g [146]. Given this similarity, Plato’s outl<strong>in</strong>ed, but<br />

still <strong>in</strong>complete zw|~on can be easily merged with Aristotle’s perception <strong>of</strong> an outl<strong>in</strong>ed,<br />

uncolored zw|~on as an early stage <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g process. This evidence aga<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ks<br />

zw|~on to the technical vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts. Explicit evidence that a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary outl<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>of</strong> the subject to be depicted <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g was not a literary <strong>in</strong>vention, but, actually, one <strong>of</strong><br />

the steps <strong>in</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>ter’s procedure derives from the wall-pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the mid-fourth-<br />

317


century tomb <strong>of</strong> Persephone at Verg<strong>in</strong>a. Contemporary with Aristotle, the pa<strong>in</strong>ted<br />

decoration that covers three (north, south, east) <strong>of</strong> the four walls <strong>of</strong> this cist grave has as<br />

its subject the abduction <strong>of</strong> Persephone by Plutus. On the north wall, Hermes leads the<br />

way for a quadriga driven by Plutus, whose right h<strong>and</strong> clasps the re<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> a scepter,<br />

while his left arm clutches the distressed figure <strong>of</strong> Persephone. Left beh<strong>in</strong>d, crouch<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

the ground is the figure <strong>of</strong> a horrified female (Fig. 29). <strong>The</strong> east wall depicts the<br />

perplexed figure <strong>of</strong> Demeter seated on a rock, <strong>and</strong> the south carries three seated female<br />

figures. As has been noted, the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this episode supersedes a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary design<br />

<strong>in</strong>cised on the plastered surface <strong>of</strong> the walls <strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the outl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> the subjects<br />

depicted. 616 It has also been suggested that the existence <strong>of</strong> multiple <strong>in</strong>cisions for the<br />

same member, as is the case with Hermes’ torso, for example, <strong>and</strong> “the deviation from all<br />

the <strong>in</strong>cisions <strong>in</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>al pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, which is observed <strong>in</strong> several places [e.g., Plutus’ face],<br />

confirms that the artist did not have a ready-made design or stencil to be faithfully<br />

reproduced on the wall.” 617 Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g this observation, the evidence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

preparatory sketch underneath the f<strong>in</strong>al pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is crucial here, for it confirms Aristotle’s<br />

contemporary assertion about this step as be<strong>in</strong>g st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g the application <strong>of</strong><br />

colors on a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. That Aristotle actually considered this step <strong>in</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

work <strong>of</strong> art analogous to the early formation <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>of</strong> an animal that eventually<br />

grows out <strong>of</strong> this phase is particularly illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g: it implies that for Aristotle the<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> zw|~on as part <strong>of</strong> it was an evolv<strong>in</strong>g process. In<br />

this sense, his argument is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Plato’s earlier statement <strong>in</strong> the Laws that<br />

616 M. Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a II. <strong>The</strong> Tomb <strong>of</strong> Persephone (Athens, 1994) 92-96.<br />

617 Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a II 93; he also notes, (96-99), that this is not the earliest example <strong>of</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> a<br />

prelim<strong>in</strong>ary sketch <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, (97-98, ns. 51-54), Attic black-figured <strong>and</strong><br />

white-ground vases, as well as the tomb <strong>of</strong> the Diver <strong>in</strong> Paestum present the earliest evidence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

prelim<strong>in</strong>ary design preced<strong>in</strong>g actual pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

318


pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs—also connected with zw&wn—evolved to perfection as time went on <strong>and</strong> the<br />

touches <strong>of</strong> various pa<strong>in</strong>ters were added to them.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second occurrence <strong>of</strong> the word <strong>in</strong> association with the arts <strong>in</strong> Aristotle is <strong>in</strong><br />

the Categories. In the open<strong>in</strong>g statement <strong>of</strong> this treatise Aristotle explicitly refers to the<br />

dual mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on:<br />

Th<strong>in</strong>gs are equivocally named, when they have the name only <strong>in</strong> common, the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition (or statement <strong>of</strong> essence) correspond<strong>in</strong>g with the name be<strong>in</strong>g different.<br />

For <strong>in</strong>stance, while a man <strong>and</strong> a zw|~on gegramme/non can properly both be called<br />

zw|~on these are equivocally named. For they have the name only <strong>in</strong> common, the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>itions (or statements <strong>of</strong> essence) correspond<strong>in</strong>g with the name be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

different. For if you are asked to def<strong>in</strong>e what be<strong>in</strong>g an animal means <strong>in</strong> the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> the man <strong>and</strong> the zw|&w, you give <strong>in</strong> either case a def<strong>in</strong>ition appropriate to that<br />

case alone. Th<strong>in</strong>gs are univocally named, when not only they bear the same name<br />

but the name means the same <strong>in</strong> each case—has the same def<strong>in</strong>ition<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g. Thus a man <strong>and</strong> an ox are called zw|~on. <strong>The</strong> name is the same <strong>in</strong><br />

both cases; so also the statement <strong>of</strong> essence. For if you are asked what is meant<br />

by their both <strong>of</strong> them be<strong>in</strong>g called zw|&w| you give that particular name <strong>in</strong> both<br />

cases the same def<strong>in</strong>ition. (Cat. 1a) [48]<br />

In this passage, Aristotle dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between two categories <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs which he calls<br />

homonymous <strong>and</strong> synonymous respectively. <strong>The</strong> first category <strong>in</strong>cludes th<strong>in</strong>gs that have<br />

only a name <strong>in</strong> common but differ <strong>in</strong> essence, whereas the second, th<strong>in</strong>gs that have both<br />

the name <strong>and</strong> the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> essence <strong>in</strong> common. Aristotle’s employment <strong>of</strong> the word<br />

zw|~on <strong>in</strong> this case as an example that demonstrates the validity <strong>of</strong> his classificatory groups<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers the earliest explicit reference to the dual mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period. In discuss<strong>in</strong>g the category <strong>of</strong> homonymous th<strong>in</strong>gs, Aristotle states clearly that,<br />

although it is widely known that they differ <strong>in</strong> essence, both a man <strong>and</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g, which is<br />

gegramme/non (“pa<strong>in</strong>ted,” “drawn”) can share the same def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>and</strong> be called zw|~on,<br />

319


which <strong>in</strong> this case has been rendered as “animal.” 618 Although the equation <strong>of</strong><br />

a1nqrwpoj (“man”) with zw|~on (“animal”) seems reasonable, the statement does not<br />

clarify how the term zw|~on, when def<strong>in</strong>ed as gegramme/non, should be understood. <strong>The</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the adjective gegramme/non (“pa<strong>in</strong>ted,” “drawn”) shows direct association<br />

with the arts, but does not allow one to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether gegramme/non zw|~on should be<br />

taken to mean the representational subject <strong>of</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> art produced by means <strong>of</strong><br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g/draw<strong>in</strong>g or the image to which this work corresponded. Aga<strong>in</strong> the blurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

the boundary between subject <strong>and</strong> image appears at the center <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on<br />

when <strong>in</strong>volved with the arts. Notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g this situation, Aristotle’s statement is<br />

valuable for it presents the difference <strong>of</strong> essence, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, justifies a difference <strong>in</strong><br />

context, as a crucial factor <strong>in</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g the split <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on. <strong>The</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong><br />

this conception is also seen <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s remark that, if asked, anyone would be able to<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> the nuance <strong>in</strong> these two dist<strong>in</strong>ct def<strong>in</strong>itions <strong>of</strong> zw|~on (ti/ e0st<strong>in</strong> au)tw~n e9kate/rw|<br />

to_ zw|&w| ei]nai). By pay<strong>in</strong>g attention to context, this statement establishes the dual<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as common knowledge <strong>in</strong> the Greek thought <strong>of</strong> the fourth century B.C.<br />

<strong>The</strong> importance placed on context is also found <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the category <strong>of</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs, which he def<strong>in</strong>es as synonymous. As stated above, this def<strong>in</strong>ition applies to<br />

entities that are identical <strong>in</strong> essence, such as a man (a1nqrwpoj) <strong>and</strong> an ox (bou~j), which<br />

are both called animal[s] (zw|&w). This group<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> label<strong>in</strong>g, as Aristotle says, can be<br />

easily understood <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>ed by everyone. His comment aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicates a widespread<br />

comprehension <strong>of</strong> the specific mean<strong>in</strong>g that the term zw|~on could acquire when <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with a specific context.<br />

618 <strong>Animal</strong>: H. P. Cooke, ed., tr., Aristotle. <strong>The</strong> Categories. On Interpretation (Cambridge, Mass., <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1938; repr. 1996) 13; animals: J. K. Ackrill, tr., Aristotle’s Categories <strong>and</strong> De Interpretatione<br />

(Oxford, 1953) 3.<br />

320


<strong>The</strong> third occurrence <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> Aristotle is <strong>in</strong> his treatise Memory <strong>and</strong><br />

Recollection, which considers these two functions products <strong>of</strong> the senses <strong>and</strong> places them<br />

<strong>in</strong> the realm <strong>of</strong> the th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g faculty. Aristotle uses zw|~on to refer to an image held by<br />

memory. He speaks <strong>of</strong> memory <strong>in</strong> clearly visual terms. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to him, memory is a<br />

mental state susta<strong>in</strong>ed by a fa&ntasma, that is, an impression or image <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g that has<br />

been experienced through sense perception (ai1sqhsij) <strong>in</strong> the past, <strong>and</strong> is now stored onto<br />

the soul (<strong>and</strong> the part <strong>of</strong> the body that conta<strong>in</strong>s it) <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> capacity. 619 This capacity,<br />

which is, <strong>in</strong> turn, affected by circumstances, such as the age <strong>of</strong> the percipient subject,<br />

dictates the vigor with which the <strong>in</strong>itial impression or image can be retrieved. Aristotle<br />

perceives <strong>of</strong> this image as hav<strong>in</strong>g a dual essence: it is a present affection, but, at the same<br />

time, it resembles or st<strong>and</strong>s for the absent th<strong>in</strong>g that orig<strong>in</strong>ally stimulated it; therefore, it<br />

is an aid to memory. In order to elucidate this po<strong>in</strong>t, Aristotle draws an analogy from the<br />

realm <strong>of</strong> the arts:<br />

For example, the gegramme/non (picture drawn) on a tablet is both a zw|~o&n <strong>and</strong><br />

a[n] ei0kw&n, <strong>and</strong> one <strong>and</strong> the same th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> both <strong>of</strong> these, although what it is to be<br />

these two th<strong>in</strong>gs is not the same, <strong>and</strong> it is possible to behold it both as a zw|~on <strong>and</strong><br />

as a[n] ei0ko&na, so too one ought to conceive <strong>of</strong> the fa&ntasma that is <strong>in</strong> us as<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g itself someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> its own right, <strong>and</strong> as be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g else. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar,<br />

then, as it is someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> its own right, it is a (qew&rhma) or a fa&ntasma, but<br />

<strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it is <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g else, it is a certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> ei0kw_n <strong>and</strong> rem<strong>in</strong>der.<br />

619 Important for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g what Aristotle means by ai1sqhsij is his clarification (Mem. 450a) that “the<br />

stimulus produced impresses a sort <strong>of</strong> likeness <strong>of</strong> the percept (ai0sqh&matoj), just as when men seal with<br />

signet r<strong>in</strong>gs”; translation: W. S. Hett, ed., tr., Aristotle VIII. On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1936; repr. 1995) 295. Additional evidence for how Aristotle understood<br />

the term derives from his treatise On the Soul (II. 12.424a), where he expla<strong>in</strong>s (ai%sqhsiv) <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

way: “we must underst<strong>and</strong> as true generally <strong>of</strong> every sense that sense is that which is receptive <strong>of</strong> the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> sensible objects without the matter, just as the wax receives the impression <strong>of</strong> the signet-r<strong>in</strong>g without the<br />

iron or the gold, <strong>and</strong> receives the impression <strong>of</strong> the gold or bronze, but not as gold or bronze”; translation:<br />

Hett, Aristotle VIII 135. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to W. J. T., Mitchell, Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology (Chicago,<br />

1986) 14, n. 13, the idea <strong>of</strong> memory images as impressions <strong>in</strong> a wax tablet is also discussed by Plato <strong>in</strong> the<br />

<strong>The</strong>aetatus (without documentation). For a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s theory <strong>of</strong> fanta&smata <strong>and</strong> its<br />

<strong>in</strong>fluence upon philosophers like Hobbes, Hume <strong>and</strong> also modern psychology, see Mitchell, Iconology 10-<br />

11 <strong>and</strong> 14-15, n. 13.<br />

321


And so whenever the motion is at work that belongs to it <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it is someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> its own right, if the soul perceives it by this motion a certa<strong>in</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> thought or<br />

image seems to come before it; but if, <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it is <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g else, the soul<br />

beholds it <strong>in</strong> the same way that one beholds what is <strong>in</strong> a picture as an ei0ko&na <strong>and</strong>,<br />

when one has not been see<strong>in</strong>g Coriscus, as Coriscus, <strong>and</strong> the experience <strong>of</strong> this<br />

behold<strong>in</strong>g then, <strong>and</strong> when one beholds it as a zw|~on gegramme/non, are different,<br />

<strong>in</strong> the soul too it comes about <strong>in</strong> the one way only as a thought but <strong>in</strong> the other<br />

way, because, as <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, it is a likeness, it becomes a rem<strong>in</strong>der.<br />

(Mem. 450b-451a) [52]<br />

<strong>The</strong> passage states clearly the Aristotelian conception <strong>of</strong> fa&ntasma as the active hold<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> memory <strong>and</strong> as equal to someth<strong>in</strong>g that has been gegramme/non (“pa<strong>in</strong>ted,”<br />

“drawn,”) on a tablet. As seen <strong>in</strong> Plato <strong>and</strong> Aristotle’s Categories, the word<br />

gegramme/non, which is a derivative <strong>of</strong> the verb gra&fw (“to pa<strong>in</strong>t,” “draw,” “write”), is<br />

taken to mean the artistic processes <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>/or draw<strong>in</strong>g. That it is not easy to<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e which one <strong>of</strong> these processes is meant here is mirrored <strong>in</strong> the various<br />

translations <strong>of</strong> gegramme/non: Walter Hett, for example, renders it as “pa<strong>in</strong>ted” <strong>and</strong> Joe<br />

Sachs as “drawn.” 620 In agreement with the former is Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as, the thirteenth-<br />

century commentator on the Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection, who also thought that<br />

gegramme/non referred to someth<strong>in</strong>g pa<strong>in</strong>ted. 621 Regardless <strong>of</strong> this ambiguity, what is<br />

important here is that the Aristotelian equation <strong>of</strong> fa&ntasma with gegramme/non <strong>in</strong>vites<br />

an underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the former term as picture or, more generally, image held by<br />

memory.<br />

Aristotle proceeds to expla<strong>in</strong> the tw<strong>of</strong>old essence <strong>of</strong> this image without depart<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the framework <strong>of</strong> the analogy with the arts. As he states, a fa&ntasma can be<br />

perceived <strong>in</strong> two different ways: as an “object <strong>of</strong> speculation <strong>in</strong> its own right” (au)to& ti<br />

620<br />

Hett, Aristotle VIII 295. J. Sachs, tr., Aristotle’s On the Soul <strong>and</strong> On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection (Santa<br />

Fe, New Mexico, 2001) 174.<br />

621<br />

K. White <strong>and</strong> E. M. Macierowski, trs., St. Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as. Commentaries on Aristotle’s “On Sense <strong>and</strong><br />

What Is Sensed” <strong>and</strong> “On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection” (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 2005) 202.<br />

322


kaq' au(to_ ei]nai…qew&rhma), <strong>and</strong>, at the same time, as “an image <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g else”<br />

(fa&ntasma& e0st<strong>in</strong>, h| { d' a1llou) that serves as aid to memory (mnhmo&neuma). When<br />

transferred to the context <strong>of</strong> the arts, these two different ontological statuses correspond<br />

to the two different ways that a pa<strong>in</strong>ted or drawn picture/image (gegramme/non) could be<br />

perceived: as a zw|~on <strong>and</strong> ei0kw&n. Simply put, this correspondence suggests that zw|~on<br />

was, for Aristotle, “an object <strong>of</strong> speculation <strong>in</strong> its own right” <strong>and</strong> ei0kw&n, “an image <strong>of</strong><br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g else.” Hett translates ei0kw&n as “portrait,” which implies a human subject.<br />

Sachs, on the contrary, translates it as “likeness” <strong>and</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>s that: “a ‘likeness’ (ei0kw&n)<br />

means not any <strong>and</strong> every th<strong>in</strong>g that resembles someth<strong>in</strong>g else (o(moi/wma), but someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

derivative that imitates or represents the “orig<strong>in</strong>al.” 622 In agreement with Hett is also<br />

Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as, whose commentary on the passage suggests that he, too, understood<br />

ei0kw&n as “likeness.” 623 Additional evidence that supports this mean<strong>in</strong>g derives from his<br />

statement that ei0kw&n stood for or represented someth<strong>in</strong>g or someone perceived<br />

previously, but out <strong>of</strong> sight now. This belief is exemplified <strong>in</strong> Aristotle’s reference to the<br />

contemplation <strong>of</strong> an ei0ko&na <strong>of</strong> someone called Coriscus, which he def<strong>in</strong>es as an image<br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g this person, <strong>and</strong> therefore, function<strong>in</strong>g as a rem<strong>in</strong>der <strong>of</strong> this person’s<br />

existence to the viewer. Although not identical, this l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> thought is very close to that<br />

<strong>of</strong> Plato, who, as seen earlier, thought <strong>of</strong> a)ga&lmata as substitutes <strong>of</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong><br />

gods. Aristotle’s passage states, however, that the image held <strong>in</strong> memory (fa&ntasma)<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> exhibited these qualities <strong>of</strong> ei0kw&n, but it was also a zw|~on.<br />

As noted above, Aristotle provides an explicit def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> this term as “an object<br />

<strong>of</strong> speculation <strong>in</strong> its own right,” thus, not <strong>in</strong> relation to someth<strong>in</strong>g else, or a fa&ntasma,<br />

622 Sachs, Aristotle’s On the Soul <strong>and</strong> On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection 171, n. 4, where he refers to specific<br />

passages, such as Plato’s Sophist (240b-240c), which carries this mean<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

623 White <strong>and</strong> Macierowski, St. Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as. Commentaries 202, n. 18.<br />

323


that is, an image held by memory. This evidence confirms the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as<br />

image. It also provides a glimpse <strong>in</strong>to how viewers approached this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> image: as an<br />

object <strong>of</strong> speculation. Informative is also Aristotle’s additional comment that when one<br />

contemplates the object merely as a gegramme/non zw|~on, which has been translated as<br />

“pa<strong>in</strong>ted picture,” then this object appears <strong>in</strong> the soul as a mere thought. 624 This<br />

clarification suggests that, apart from be<strong>in</strong>g an image <strong>in</strong> its own right, zw|~on was also<br />

understood as visual material that registered directly <strong>in</strong> the th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g faculty. This<br />

evidence, <strong>in</strong> turn, qualifies zw|~on as an important term <strong>in</strong> the fourth-century discourse on<br />

optical theory.<br />

Philemon<br />

<strong>The</strong> last <strong>Classical</strong> zw|~on to be associated with the arts appears <strong>in</strong> a fragment <strong>of</strong><br />

Philemon, a comic poet <strong>of</strong> the mid-fourth to the mid-third centuries B.C. Athenaeus,<br />

writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the second century A.D., cites a fragment <strong>of</strong> Philemon, which relates the story<br />

<strong>of</strong> a man becom<strong>in</strong>g enamored <strong>of</strong> a stone zw|~on. Athenaeus uses the fragment <strong>of</strong> Philemon<br />

as support<strong>in</strong>g evidence for Alexis’s description <strong>of</strong> similar behavior attributed to someone<br />

whom he identifies as Cleisophus <strong>of</strong> Selymbria:<br />

For he [Cleisophus <strong>of</strong> Selymbria], becom<strong>in</strong>g enamored <strong>of</strong> the statue<br />

[a)ga&lmatoj] <strong>in</strong> Parian marble at Samos, locked himself up <strong>in</strong> the temple,<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g he should be able to have <strong>in</strong>tercourse with it; <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ce he found that<br />

impossible on account <strong>of</strong> the frigidity <strong>and</strong> resistance <strong>of</strong> the stone, he then <strong>and</strong><br />

there desisted from that desire <strong>and</strong> plac<strong>in</strong>g before him a small piece <strong>of</strong> flesh he<br />

consorted with that. This deed is mentioned by the poet Alexis <strong>in</strong> the play entitled<br />

A Picture: “Another case <strong>of</strong> a like sort occurred, they say, <strong>in</strong> Samos. A man<br />

conceived a passion for a stone maiden, <strong>and</strong> locked himself up <strong>in</strong> the temple.”<br />

And Philemon, mention<strong>in</strong>g the same, says, “Why, once on a time, <strong>in</strong> Samos, a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> man fell <strong>in</strong> love with a stone zw|&ou; thereupon he locked himself <strong>in</strong> the<br />

624 Pa<strong>in</strong>ted picture: Hett, Aristotle VIII 293; Sachs, Aristotle’s On the Soul 172; White <strong>and</strong> Macierowski, St.<br />

Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as. Commentaries 202, ns. 17, 19.<br />

324


temple.” Now the statue [a1galma] is the work <strong>of</strong> Ctesicles, as Adaeus <strong>of</strong><br />

Mytilene says <strong>in</strong> his work On Sculptors [ 1Agalma-Makers].<br />

(Deipn. 13.606a13.606b) [77]<br />

<strong>The</strong> fragment gives the impression that the genitive s<strong>in</strong>gular zw|&ou refers to an image <strong>of</strong><br />

some k<strong>in</strong>d. <strong>The</strong> fact that this zw|~on was li/q<strong>in</strong>on (“made <strong>of</strong> stone”) <strong>in</strong>dicates that it was<br />

an image <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> sculpture. In agreement with this suggestion is Charles Gulick,<br />

who translates Philemon’s liqi&nou zw|&ou as “stone image.” 625 In view <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> zw|~on as an “object <strong>of</strong> speculation <strong>in</strong> its own right” this render<strong>in</strong>g seems<br />

appropriate. As for the position <strong>of</strong> the term with<strong>in</strong> the general spectrum <strong>of</strong> its <strong>Classical</strong><br />

usage, we see that once aga<strong>in</strong> zw|~on is used <strong>in</strong> a general sense <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> connection with the<br />

language <strong>of</strong> the arts. What is new <strong>in</strong> this case is the use <strong>of</strong> the term <strong>in</strong> comedy. <strong>The</strong><br />

fragment also shows that the context <strong>in</strong> which this zw|~on existed was a temple <strong>in</strong> Samos,<br />

which <strong>in</strong>dicates a religious sett<strong>in</strong>g. This evidence along with the above reference to stone<br />

as the material <strong>of</strong> manufacture br<strong>in</strong>g immediately to m<strong>in</strong>d Herodotus’ assertion that<br />

temples <strong>and</strong> zw|~a carved on stones were, along with altars <strong>and</strong> a)ga&lmata, the primary<br />

components <strong>of</strong> religious activity first set by the Egyptians [100]. In this sense, the term<br />

zw|~on aga<strong>in</strong> appears to be connected with religion. Unlike Herodotus, who, <strong>in</strong> that case,<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>guished between zw|~a <strong>and</strong> a)ga&lmata, <strong>in</strong> this passage, Athenaeus refers to<br />

Philemon’s stone zw|&ou as a1galma, that is, “statue.” This evidence suggests a second-<br />

century A.D. l<strong>in</strong>guistic treatment, which is not distant, however, from that <strong>of</strong> Plato’s <strong>in</strong><br />

the Republic, who, as seen earlier, perceived <strong>of</strong> an a)ndria&v as a zw|~on [148]. <strong>The</strong><br />

similarity between the two authors h<strong>in</strong>ts at a consistent usage <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the<br />

term zw|~on, which apparently permeated chronological boundaries. This impression is<br />

625<br />

C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus VI. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1937; repr.<br />

1959) 267.<br />

325


further re<strong>in</strong>forced by Athenaeus’ suggestion that his underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Philemon’s<br />

zw|&ou as an a1galma stems from the designation <strong>of</strong> this zw|&ou, <strong>in</strong> the 0Agalmatopoioi&<br />

( @Agalma-Makers) <strong>of</strong> Adaeus <strong>of</strong> Mytilene (perhaps, third-century B.C.), as a work <strong>of</strong><br />

Ctesicles (perhaps, third-century B.C.). 626 <strong>The</strong>se references aside, what is <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about Philemon’s zw|&ou, <strong>and</strong> despite its anecdotal nature, is that it marks a specific<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> reaction to an artistic image at the end <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. As the fragment states: “a certa<strong>in</strong> man fell <strong>in</strong> love with a stone zw|&ou; thereupon<br />

he locked himself <strong>in</strong> the temple.” This statement presents zw|~on as a sculptural image<br />

that had the power to elicit an emotional response on the viewer <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> turn, condition<br />

the viewer’s behavior towards it. In this way, the statement is <strong>in</strong>structive <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

the impact <strong>of</strong> an artistic image on the viewer as depend<strong>in</strong>g upon the <strong>in</strong>teraction between<br />

this image <strong>and</strong> the viewer. 627 That this zw|~on was made <strong>of</strong> stone suggests a lifeless<br />

image, which accords with Plato’s <strong>and</strong> Alcidamas’s perception <strong>of</strong> zw|~a as representations<br />

626 <strong>The</strong> date <strong>of</strong> Adaeus <strong>of</strong> Mytilene is uncerta<strong>in</strong>. Additional evidence about him derives from a sepulchral<br />

epigram <strong>of</strong> the Greek Anthology (7.305), which is <strong>in</strong>scribed “<strong>of</strong> Addaeus <strong>of</strong> Mytilene” <strong>and</strong> refers to the<br />

death <strong>of</strong> a fisherman. Athenaeus (11.471f) refers also to an Adaeus as the author <strong>of</strong> a work called On the<br />

Use <strong>of</strong> Words. Another epigram <strong>of</strong> the Greek Anthology (9. 228) is entitled “<strong>of</strong> Addaeus <strong>of</strong> Macedonia”<br />

<strong>and</strong> refers to a deceased called Alcon. <strong>The</strong>re is also a considerable number <strong>of</strong> epigrams which have been<br />

attributed to Adaeus (7.51, 7.694) <strong>and</strong> Addaeus (6.258, 7.51, 7.238, 7.240, 9.300, 9.303, 9.544, <strong>and</strong> 10.20).<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> these refer to the death <strong>of</strong> Euripides <strong>in</strong> the Macedonian locality <strong>of</strong> Arethusa (i.e., Adaeus, 7.51), to<br />

Philip <strong>of</strong> Macedonia <strong>and</strong> the city <strong>of</strong> Aegae (i.e., Addaeus, 7.238), to the tomb <strong>of</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great<br />

(Addaeus, 7.240), <strong>and</strong> also the city <strong>of</strong> Potidaea (i.e., Adaeus, 7.694). On the basis <strong>of</strong> these references, it has<br />

been suggested that the names Ad(d)aeus <strong>and</strong> Adaeus <strong>of</strong> Macedon referred to the same epigrammatic poet,<br />

who was, most likely from Macedonia, <strong>and</strong> lived dur<strong>in</strong>g the time <strong>of</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great (W. Smith, ed.,<br />

Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Biography <strong>and</strong> Mythology I (Boston, 1870) 18; also<br />

http://www.ancientlibrary.com/smith-bio/0027.html. Whether this Macedonian Ad(d)aeus <strong>and</strong> Ad(d)eus <strong>of</strong><br />

Mytilene were one <strong>and</strong> the same person cannot be established. As for Ctesicles, Pollitt, Sources <strong>and</strong><br />

Documents 177, n. 2, notes that a Hellenistic pa<strong>in</strong>ter called Ctesilas or Ctesicles is mentioned by Pl<strong>in</strong>y (NH<br />

35.140), but “the read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this name <strong>in</strong> the manuscripts is uncerta<strong>in</strong>.” He translates (177) the passage <strong>of</strong><br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y as follow<strong>in</strong>g: “Ktesilas became famous because <strong>of</strong> his <strong>in</strong>sult to Queen Stratonike, for s<strong>in</strong>ce he was<br />

denied honor by her, he pa<strong>in</strong>ted a picture <strong>of</strong> her roll<strong>in</strong>g about with a fisherman, with whom rumor said that<br />

she was <strong>in</strong> love. He put his picture on view <strong>in</strong> the port <strong>of</strong> Ephesos <strong>and</strong> made a hurried escape by ship. But<br />

the Queen, [feel<strong>in</strong>g that] the likeness <strong>of</strong> both figures was marvelously expressed, forbade that the picture be<br />

taken down.”<br />

627 For a concise discussion <strong>of</strong> the active role <strong>of</strong> the viewer <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g various modes <strong>of</strong> view<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong> art, see Rusnak, “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator” esp. 1-27.<br />

326


<strong>of</strong> real bodies. When this mean<strong>in</strong>g is applied to Philemon’s zw|~on, then the latter can be<br />

also seen as a figural image. In sum, what this evidence suggests is that the term zw|~on<br />

was a fundamental component <strong>of</strong> the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts <strong>in</strong> the late fourth century<br />

B.C., whose use was favored not only by prose writers, but comic poets as well.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> evidence for zw|~on <strong>in</strong> the fourth century <strong>in</strong>dicates that authors such as Plato,<br />

Alcidamas, Aristotle, <strong>and</strong> Philemon used it widely <strong>in</strong> their works <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> connection with<br />

the arts. Zw|~on <strong>in</strong> Plato can be understood as “the f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> an artistic process,”<br />

“image,” <strong>and</strong> “subject <strong>of</strong> representation” <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sculpture, thus suggest<strong>in</strong>g no<br />

clear dist<strong>in</strong>ction among object, image, <strong>and</strong> subject <strong>in</strong> the visual arts. Alcidamas’ zw|~on,<br />

carries the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> “image” <strong>in</strong> general, but that <strong>of</strong> “figural image” too. Aristotle<br />

provides the earliest explicit reference to the dual mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term as “animal” when<br />

used <strong>in</strong> a general context, <strong>and</strong> an “image” <strong>and</strong>/or “subject <strong>of</strong> representation” when <strong>in</strong><br />

connection with the visual arts. In addition to these mean<strong>in</strong>gs, Aristotle uses zw|~on as<br />

“image held by memory,” thus exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g its use onto the contemporary discourse on<br />

visual perception. Plato’s <strong>and</strong> Aristotle’s detailed discussions <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sculpture<br />

<strong>in</strong> which zw|~on occurs suggest that this was a term <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the<br />

arts. F<strong>in</strong>ally, Philemon, like Alcidamas, uses the term to refer to “image,” most likely, a<br />

figural one. That he is a comic poet us<strong>in</strong>g the term, unlike all other prose writers<br />

mentioned above, suggests that, by the late fourth century, zw|~on was a st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

component <strong>of</strong> the term<strong>in</strong>ology for the arts.<br />

327


<strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> usage <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>and</strong> its dim<strong>in</strong>utive zw|&dion <strong>in</strong> the previous<br />

century are not different. As the literary texts <strong>of</strong> Empedocles <strong>and</strong> Herodotus, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

build<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>scriptions <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion show the terms zw|~on <strong>and</strong> zw|&dion carry the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> “image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation,” “representation <strong>of</strong> both animate <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate subjects taken from real life,” <strong>and</strong> “decorative element.” Unlike the fourth-<br />

century, here the terms are used <strong>in</strong> connection with a wider variety <strong>of</strong> media, which along<br />

with pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sculpture <strong>in</strong>cludes also bronze-work <strong>and</strong> textiles. This evidence<br />

suggests that the term was an important element <strong>of</strong> the vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts, start<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

the fifth century B.C. Also, Herodotus, like Plato later on, provides <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> which no clear dist<strong>in</strong>ction exists between image <strong>and</strong> subject.<br />

Taken together, the literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical evidence <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth<br />

centuries B.C. <strong>in</strong>dicates that when used <strong>in</strong> direct association with the visual arts, zw|~on<br />

held multiple, nuanced mean<strong>in</strong>gs that set it apart from its usual mean<strong>in</strong>g as “animal.”<br />

From a conceptual po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, this duality <strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage <strong>of</strong> zw|~on is consistent<br />

with the split <strong>in</strong>to different types <strong>of</strong> frameworks (<strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity,<br />

contradiction) that susta<strong>in</strong> the naturalistic style <strong>of</strong> contemporary animal sculpture <strong>and</strong><br />

also with the dichotomy <strong>in</strong> contemporary attitudes toward animals, as this discussion<br />

demonstrated earlier. Such a consistency <strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>guistic, artistic, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual<br />

approach to animals suggests that the latter are reliable sources for sharpen<strong>in</strong>g our<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture.<br />

328


Conclusions<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> are fundamental components <strong>of</strong> the art, thought, <strong>and</strong> language <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture. <strong>The</strong>y are valuable guides to the ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> art. <strong>The</strong>y help account for a range <strong>of</strong> deviations<br />

from naturalism that is tied to the notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction<br />

that hold together the elements <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Greek art, <strong>in</strong> particular sculpture.<br />

Representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek funerary sculpture are especially valuable<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style by reveal<strong>in</strong>g that their contradictory<br />

style is the material manifestation <strong>of</strong> a contemporary contradictory attitude toward<br />

animals that is attested <strong>in</strong> the literary record <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s a conceptual aff<strong>in</strong>ity with the<br />

duality that characterizes contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage concern<strong>in</strong>g animals. In this way,<br />

animals establish that the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g essentially differ<strong>in</strong>g elements, as<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ed by the conceptual context <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture, is the fundamental structure<br />

on which the conception <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> contemporary art rests.<br />

Ancient texts dat<strong>in</strong>g from the fifth century B.C. <strong>and</strong> the first <strong>and</strong> second centuries<br />

A.D. <strong>in</strong>dicate that <strong>in</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries B.C. animals are favored <strong>and</strong> valued as<br />

subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> both sculpture <strong>and</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. As subjects <strong>of</strong> representation,<br />

animals are a means by which artistic skill is measured <strong>and</strong> the fame <strong>of</strong> the artists is<br />

established <strong>in</strong> both <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> throughout classical antiquity. This conclusion<br />

is <strong>in</strong> opposition to the prevail<strong>in</strong>g view <strong>in</strong> scholarship that places the animal form <strong>in</strong> a<br />

position subord<strong>in</strong>ate to that <strong>of</strong> the human one <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art.<br />

329


<strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> naturalism has been central to scholarly <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

stylistic development <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek art. This development has been conceived <strong>in</strong><br />

terms <strong>of</strong> an evolution that moves steadily from <strong>in</strong>adequately rendered representations <strong>of</strong><br />

the human form to extremely accurate ones exemplified by those <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> period.<br />

For example, the theories <strong>of</strong> Emanuel Löwy, Ernst Gombrich, <strong>and</strong> John Boardman about<br />

naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> Greek art, <strong>and</strong> the psychological, historical, <strong>and</strong> technical conceptions<br />

that shape them respectively, focus on the human form <strong>and</strong> rely on the idea <strong>of</strong> a<br />

generalized advancement <strong>of</strong> Greek art toward absolute naturalism. Boardman’s theory <strong>in</strong><br />

particular perceives a l<strong>in</strong>k between the progression <strong>of</strong> Greek naturalism, especially dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> periods, <strong>and</strong> a parallel progress <strong>in</strong> artistic techniques <strong>and</strong><br />

materials.<br />

<strong>The</strong> present study has shown that animals are valuable guides to the ancient Greek<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> art. <strong>The</strong> ancient Greeks valued<br />

naturalism or, more precisely, lifelikeness as a quality <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art. <strong>The</strong>y understood<br />

artistic lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> two dist<strong>in</strong>ct notions: accurate representation <strong>and</strong> aliveness.<br />

Ancient texts rang<strong>in</strong>g from the fifth century B.C. to the sixth century A.D. show that<br />

animals occupied a central position <strong>in</strong> the ancient Greek, particularly <strong>Classical</strong>,<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> artistic lifelikeness as such. In these texts, animals appear <strong>in</strong> two different<br />

roles: as subjects <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> art that are praised for their lifelikeness <strong>and</strong> as judges <strong>of</strong><br />

lifelike art. Through their role as lifelike representational subjects, animals show that<br />

ancient Greek society experienced lifelike art as alive while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a conscious<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its lifeless status. Further, through their role as judges <strong>of</strong> lifelike art,<br />

330


animals—as essential elements <strong>of</strong> the natural world <strong>and</strong> separate from human<br />

cognition—uncover a specific attitude toward art itself: that it can rise above its essence<br />

as an artificial creation <strong>and</strong> be acknowledged <strong>and</strong>, at the same time, experienced as<br />

nature, even by nature itself. It is clear, therefore, that animals <strong>of</strong>fer an <strong>in</strong>valuable <strong>in</strong>sight<br />

<strong>in</strong>to the judgment <strong>of</strong> artistic lifelikeness <strong>in</strong> ancient <strong>Greece</strong>.<br />

Modern scholarship has long considered the style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture problematic ow<strong>in</strong>g to its dist<strong>in</strong>ct comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

<strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic elements. Such realization does not fit well with the general<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style, which, as noted above, def<strong>in</strong>es the art <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong><br />

period, <strong>and</strong> is known for its adherence to a strict imitation <strong>of</strong> the external world.<br />

Scholarly works have variously <strong>in</strong>terpreted the problematic style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

animal sculpture as the result <strong>of</strong> artists’ <strong>in</strong>ability to render correctly animal anatomy<br />

ow<strong>in</strong>g to mistake or misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, as reveal<strong>in</strong>g lack <strong>of</strong> real models, as the result <strong>of</strong> a<br />

direct copy<strong>in</strong>g from Bronze Age animal art, as a mix <strong>of</strong> copy<strong>in</strong>g from Near Eastern<br />

animal art <strong>and</strong> observation <strong>of</strong> only a few available comparable species, <strong>and</strong> also as a<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the apotropaic significance <strong>of</strong> more than one species <strong>of</strong> animals. Despite<br />

these remarks, scholarly works have failed to recognize that the problematic style <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal sculpture is actually based on a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g—<br />

naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic—elements. In fact, this comb<strong>in</strong>ation is characterized by<br />

a variety <strong>of</strong> types <strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terplay between these differ<strong>in</strong>g elements, namely,<br />

<strong>in</strong>consistency, <strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction.<br />

331


What the modern scholar considers to be an artistic mistake or misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

could be as valid a stylistic element as any other to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek viewer <strong>of</strong> animal<br />

art. Plato ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that, <strong>in</strong> his day, artistic representations <strong>of</strong> the human form were<br />

scrut<strong>in</strong>ized for their accuracy, <strong>and</strong>, frequently, considered defective, but he also admits<br />

that non-human representational subjects were tolerated for their <strong>in</strong>accuracies <strong>and</strong><br />

deceptiveness as long as they carried the smallest degree <strong>of</strong> likeness to their prototypes.<br />

Unlike the modern critic, however, the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek viewer was open to <strong>in</strong>consistent,<br />

<strong>in</strong>congruous, <strong>and</strong> contradictory render<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> art as long as s/he could<br />

recognize what was represented on the basis <strong>of</strong> his/her previous knowledge. For Plato,<br />

therefore, <strong>and</strong> his contemporaries, the conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>gness <strong>of</strong> an artistic representation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

animal was not always l<strong>in</strong>ked to accuracy. <strong>The</strong> notions, therefore, <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistency,<br />

<strong>in</strong>congruity, <strong>and</strong> contradiction that shaped <strong>and</strong>, at the same time, bound together the<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> the naturalistic style <strong>of</strong> an animal <strong>in</strong> art were acceptable, expected, <strong>and</strong><br />

dependent upon the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the represented animal available to the viewer.<br />

By focus<strong>in</strong>g on a small number <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek statues <strong>of</strong> animals, this study<br />

has tried to draw attention to the conceptual context <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture with<br />

regard to animals <strong>and</strong> how this context shapes the naturalistic style <strong>of</strong> animals<br />

represented <strong>in</strong> art. As the fourth-century funerary statues <strong>of</strong> the lion from the grave<br />

prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Dionysios <strong>of</strong> Kollytos <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Kerameikos <strong>and</strong> the dog from the grave<br />

prec<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>of</strong> Lysimachides <strong>of</strong> Acharnai, also <strong>in</strong> the Kerameikos, show the naturalistic <strong>and</strong><br />

non-naturalistic elements <strong>in</strong> their <strong>in</strong>consistent <strong>and</strong> contradictory styles respectively are<br />

shaped by contemporary ideas about the lion <strong>and</strong> the dog. This is evidence that exist<strong>in</strong>g<br />

332


scholarly <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the problematic style <strong>of</strong> representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture do not take <strong>in</strong>to account.<br />

<strong>The</strong> present study has also shown that the contradictory style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

animal sculpture, as exemplified by the above statue <strong>of</strong> the dog from the Kerameikos, is<br />

rooted <strong>in</strong> the contradictory attitude toward animals that is reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

literature. Fifth- <strong>and</strong> fourth-century texts demonstrate that Greek culture was primarily<br />

anthropocentric <strong>and</strong> held a contradictory attitude toward animals: on the one h<strong>and</strong>, it<br />

allowed them to occupy an important position <strong>in</strong> everyday life <strong>and</strong> thought, but on the<br />

other, it denigrated them. <strong>The</strong> dog is a case <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t. While regarded as a st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

<strong>in</strong>habitant <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek household who had open access to shelter <strong>and</strong> food, <strong>and</strong><br />

a faithful protector <strong>of</strong> the property <strong>and</strong> human members <strong>of</strong> this household, the dog was, at<br />

the same time, seen <strong>in</strong> a negative light. It was deemed a gluttonous, two-faced creature,<br />

whose behavior was treacherous <strong>and</strong> dangerous as evident from its steal<strong>in</strong>g food,<br />

fawn<strong>in</strong>g, bit<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> also scaveng<strong>in</strong>g on human corpses. <strong>The</strong> dog was beaten for steal<strong>in</strong>g<br />

food <strong>and</strong> eaten because its flesh was considered therapeutic food. This ambiguity <strong>in</strong> the<br />

collective conception <strong>of</strong> the dog is a representative example <strong>of</strong> the generalized<br />

contradictory attitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture toward animals. <strong>The</strong> contradiction<br />

<strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> this attitude serves as the conceptual basis for the contradictory style <strong>of</strong><br />

animals <strong>in</strong> contemporary sculpture.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dual attitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek culture toward animals is also reflected <strong>in</strong><br />

contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistic usage. <strong>The</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g(s) <strong>of</strong> the word zw|~on usually taken to mean<br />

333


simply “animal,” <strong>and</strong> less <strong>of</strong>ten “liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g” <strong>and</strong> “plant” extend(s) well beyond these<br />

notions. By exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g literary <strong>and</strong> epigraphical evidence <strong>of</strong> the fifth <strong>and</strong> fourth centuries<br />

B.C. this study has demonstrated that when used <strong>in</strong> an artistic context, as def<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, sculpture, bronze-work <strong>and</strong> textiles, zw|~on carries the additional mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong><br />

“image,” “subject <strong>of</strong> representation taken from real life,” “decorative element,” “figural<br />

image,” “f<strong>in</strong>ished product <strong>of</strong> an artistic process,” <strong>and</strong> also “image held by memory.” In<br />

some cases, the use <strong>of</strong> zw|~on <strong>in</strong> specialized discussions <strong>of</strong> the arts suggests that the term<br />

deserves to be considered part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essional vocabulary <strong>of</strong> the arts <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong>. From a conceptual po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, therefore, the dual attitude toward animals that<br />

the literary record reveals is not far removed from the semantic split <strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

zw|~on, or even the split <strong>in</strong>to various types <strong>and</strong> degrees <strong>of</strong> deviation from naturalism that<br />

form the conceptual foundation <strong>of</strong> the style <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture. To<br />

turn it around, for <strong>Classical</strong> Greek society, the <strong>in</strong>consistent, <strong>in</strong>congruous, <strong>and</strong><br />

contradictory style <strong>of</strong> contemporary works <strong>of</strong> art that depicted animals was as logical as<br />

its dual attitude toward animals or even the duality characteriz<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the term<br />

zw|~on. Like the comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g, that is, naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic<br />

elements <strong>in</strong> artistic representations <strong>of</strong> animals, everyday thought, language, <strong>and</strong> life with<br />

animals were characterized by a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> equally differ<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>in</strong> some cases,<br />

explicitly identified as positive <strong>and</strong> negative—ideas about these non-human creatures.<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, therefore, prove useful guides to the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek conception <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

style as not necessarily reflective <strong>of</strong> absolute naturalism, but rather <strong>of</strong> conceptual patterns<br />

govern<strong>in</strong>g contemporary mentality <strong>and</strong> language about animals.<br />

334


<strong>The</strong> literary, epigraphical, <strong>and</strong> sculptural evidence gathered <strong>in</strong> this study suggests<br />

a new paradigm for consider<strong>in</strong>g the problematic style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal art as<br />

rooted <strong>in</strong> fundamental sets <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>consistencies, <strong>in</strong>congruities, <strong>and</strong> contradictions that are<br />

reflected <strong>in</strong> other treatments <strong>of</strong> animals throughout Greek culture. <strong>The</strong>re is strong<br />

evidence that <strong>in</strong> ancient Greek art, the notion <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g differ<strong>in</strong>g, specifically<br />

naturalistic <strong>and</strong> non-naturalistic, elements should be understood as the underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> style. <strong>The</strong> study <strong>of</strong> the problematic style <strong>of</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> animal sculpture is only<br />

one part <strong>of</strong> a much larger situation. In acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> essentially further<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

observation <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g scholarly works that the problematic, specifically <strong>in</strong>consistent,<br />

style <strong>of</strong> Greek animal sculpture extends also <strong>in</strong>to the Archaic period, this study considers<br />

the notion <strong>of</strong> mix<strong>in</strong>g traits that are different <strong>in</strong> essence as the b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g element <strong>in</strong> the<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> both Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek animal art. Further by<br />

highlight<strong>in</strong>g that the tendency <strong>of</strong> “non-match<strong>in</strong>g” extends also to representations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human form, this study suggests that there is a cont<strong>in</strong>uum to this tendency as the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

that drove the conception <strong>of</strong> style <strong>in</strong> Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek art. In view <strong>of</strong> this<br />

evidence, this study suggests that the change <strong>in</strong> style from the Archaic to <strong>Classical</strong> Greek<br />

art could be seen not so much as a progression or improvement <strong>in</strong> artistic practice as a<br />

shift <strong>in</strong> the balance <strong>of</strong> elements <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> turn, <strong>of</strong> the ideas that susta<strong>in</strong> the underly<strong>in</strong>g logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> style.<br />

<strong>The</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g differ<strong>in</strong>g elements that eventually shape the style <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Greek art can be best understood not as an isolated phenomenon, but as one<br />

directly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the broad conceptual context <strong>of</strong> the society that formulated it.<br />

335


Representations <strong>of</strong> animals <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek sculpture are able to support an<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> this type. In this way, animals emerge as <strong>in</strong>valuable guides to the<br />

ancient Greek underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> naturalistic style <strong>in</strong> art.<br />

336


APPENDIX: TESTIMONIA<br />

Note to the reader: appendix numbers referr<strong>in</strong>g to the sources below appear <strong>in</strong> text <strong>in</strong><br />

boldface <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> brackets, e.g.: [1]. Inscriptions are listed alphabetically by provenance.<br />

When no translator is named, the render<strong>in</strong>g is my own.<br />

1<br />

Aelian, De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium 3.2 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: R. Hercher, ed., Claudii Aeliani. De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium Libri XVII. Varia Historia<br />

Epistolae Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1864; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: A. F. Scholfield, ed., tr., Aelian. On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> I<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1958).<br />

qumikw&tatoj de\ kunw~n Molosso&j, e0pei\ qumwde/statoi kai\ oi9 a1ndrej.<br />

Among hounds the Molossian is the most high-spirited, for the men <strong>of</strong> Molossia are hottempered.<br />

2<br />

Aelian, De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium 4.40 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: R. Hercher, ed., Claudii Aeliani. De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium Libri XVII. Varia Historia<br />

Epistolae Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1864; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: A. F. Scholfield, ed., tr., Aelian. On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> I<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1958).<br />

Kuno_j krani/on r(afh_n ou)k e1xei. dramw_n de\ e0pi\ple/on la&gnhj gi/netai, fasi/.<br />

kuno_j de\ ghrw~ntoj a)mblei=j oi9 o)do&ntej kai\ melai/nontai. eu1r<strong>in</strong>oj de/ e0st<strong>in</strong><br />

ou3twj w(j mh&pot' a2n o)ptou~ kunei/ou kre/wj mhd' a2n karukei/a| th|~ poikilwta&th|<br />

kai\ dolerwta&th| katagohteuqe/ntoj geu&sasqai.<br />

A dog’s skull has no suture. Runn<strong>in</strong>g, they say, makes a dog more lustful. In old age a<br />

dog’s teeth are blunt <strong>and</strong> turn black. He is so keen-scented that he will never touch the<br />

roasted flesh <strong>of</strong> a dog, be it bewitched by the subtlest <strong>and</strong> craftiest <strong>of</strong> rich sauces.<br />

3<br />

Aelian, De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium 7.38 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: R. Hercher, ed., Claudii Aeliani. De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium Libri XVII. Varia Historia<br />

Epistolae Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1864; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: A. F. Scholfield, ed., tr., Aelian. On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> II<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1959).<br />

An Athenian took with him a Dog as fellow-soldier to the battle <strong>of</strong> Marathon, <strong>and</strong> both<br />

are figured <strong>in</strong> a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Stoa Poecile, nor was the Dog denied honor but received<br />

337


the reward <strong>of</strong> the danger it had undergone <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g seen among the companions <strong>of</strong><br />

Cynegirus, Epizelus, <strong>and</strong> Callimachus. <strong>The</strong>y <strong>and</strong> the Dog were pa<strong>in</strong>ted by Micon, though<br />

some say it was not his work but that <strong>of</strong> Polygnotus <strong>of</strong> Thasos.<br />

4<br />

Aelian, De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium 8.1 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: R. Hercher, ed., Claudii Aeliani. De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium Libri XVII. Varia Historia<br />

Epistolae Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1864; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: A. F. Scholfield, ed., tr., Aelian. On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> II<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1959).<br />

0Indikoi\ lo&goi dida&skous<strong>in</strong> h(ma~j kai\ e0kei=na. ta_j ku&naj a1gous<strong>in</strong> e0j ta_ e1nqhra<br />

xwri/a oi9 qhratikoi\ ta_j eu)genei=j te kai\ i1xnh katagnw~nai qhri/wn a)gaqa_j kai\<br />

w)ki/staj e0j dro&mon, kai\ toi=j de/ndroij prosdh&santej ei]ta me/ntoi<br />

a)palla&ttontai, tou~to dh&pou to_ lego&menon a)texnw~j ku&bon a)narri/yantej. oi9 de\<br />

ti/greij e0ntuxo&ntej au)tai=j, a)qhri/a| me\n kai\ limw|~ sumpeso&ntej diaspw~s<strong>in</strong><br />

au)ta&j: e0a_n de\ o)rgw~ntej a)fi/kwntai kai\ kekoresme/noi, sumple/kontai/ te au)tai=j<br />

kai\ th~j a)frodi/thj e0n plhsmonh|~ kai\ e0kei=noi me/mnhntai. e0k de\ th~j o(mili/aj tau&thj<br />

ou) ku&wn fasi\n a)lla_ ti/grij ti/ktetai. e0k de\ tou&tou kai\ kuno_j qhlei/aj e1ti ti/grij<br />

texqei/h a1n, o( de\ e0k tou&tou kai\ kuno_j e0j th_n mhte/ra a)pokri/netai, kai\ katw&lisqen h(<br />

spora_ pro_j to_ xei=ron, kai\ ku&wn ti/ktetai. pro_j tau~ta 0Aristote/lhj ou)k<br />

a)ntifh&sei. ou{toi de\ a1ra oi9 ku&nej, oi[j pa&resti pate/ra au)xei=n ti/gr<strong>in</strong>, e1lafon me\n<br />

qhra~sai h2 sui\ sumpesei=n a)tima&zousi, xai/rousi de\ e0pi\ tou_j le/ontaj a| 1ttontej kai\<br />

tou_j a1nw tou~ ge/nouj a)podeiknu&ntej e0nteu~qen.<br />

Indian histories teach us the follow<strong>in</strong>g facts also. Huntsment take thoroughbred bitches<br />

which are good at track<strong>in</strong>g wild animals <strong>and</strong> are very swift <strong>of</strong> foot to places <strong>in</strong>fested by<br />

these animals; they tie them to trees <strong>and</strong> then go away, simply, as the say<strong>in</strong>g is, try<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

throw <strong>of</strong> a dice. And if tigers f<strong>in</strong>d them when they have caught noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> are<br />

famished, they tear them to pieces. If however they arrive on heat <strong>and</strong> full-fled they<br />

couple with the bitches, for tigers too when gorged turn their thoughts to sexual<br />

<strong>in</strong>tercourse. From this union, so it said, a tiger is born, not a hound. And from this tiger<br />

<strong>and</strong> a bitch aga<strong>in</strong> a tiger would be born, although the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this last <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> a bitch<br />

takes after its dam, <strong>and</strong> the seed degenerates <strong>and</strong> a hound is born. Nor will Aristotle<br />

contradict this. Now these hounds which can boast a tiger for sire scorn to pursue a stag<br />

or to face a boar, but are glad to rush at lions <strong>and</strong> thereby to give pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> their pedigree.<br />

5<br />

Aelian, De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium 10.41 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: R. Hercher, ed., Claudii Aeliani. De Natura <strong>Animal</strong>ium Libri XVII. Varia Historia<br />

Epistolae Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1864; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: A. F. Scholfield, ed., tr., Aelian. On the Characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> II<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1959).<br />

338


Eu)po&lidi tw|~ th~j kwmw|di/aj poihth|~ di/dwsi dw~ron Au)ge/aj o( 0Eleusi/nioj sku&laka<br />

i0dei=n w(rai=on, Molotto_n to_ ge/noj, kai\ kalei= tou~ton o( Eu1polij o(mwnu&mwj tw|~<br />

dwrhsame/nw| au)to&n. kolakeuqei\j ou}n tai=j tr<strong>of</strong>ai=j, kai\ e0k th~j sunhqei/aj<br />

u(paxqei\j th~j makrote/raj, e0fi/lei to_n despo&thn o( Au)ge/aj o( ku&wn. kai/ pote<br />

o(mo&douloj au)tw|~ neani/aj, o1noma 0Efia&lthj, u(fairei=tai dra&mata& t<strong>in</strong>a tou~<br />

Eu)po&lidoj, kai\ ou)k e1laqe kle/ptwn, a)lla_ ei]den au)to_n o( ku&wn, kai\ e0mpesw_n<br />

a)feide/stata da&knwn a)pe/kte<strong>in</strong>en. xro&nw| de\ u3steron e0n Ai0gi/nh| to_n bi/on o( Eu1polij<br />

kate/streye, kai\ e0ta&fh e0ntau~qa: o( de\ ku&wn w)ruo&meno&j te kai\ qrhnw~n to_n tw~n<br />

kunw~n qrh~non, ei]ta me/ntoi lu&ph| kai\ limw|~ e9auto_n e0kth&caj a)pe/qanen e0pi\ tw|~ tr<strong>of</strong>ei=<br />

kai\ despo&th|, mish&saj to_n bi/on o( ku&wn. kai\ o3 ge to&poj kalei=tai mnh&mh| tou~ to&te<br />

pa&qouj Kuno_j Qrh~noj.<br />

Augeas <strong>of</strong> Eleusis gave Eupolis, the writer <strong>of</strong> comedies, a hound <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e appearance, a<br />

Molossian, which Eupolis named after the donor. Now Augeas the hound, pampered <strong>in</strong><br />

its feed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenced by long association with its master, came to love him. On one<br />

occasion a young fellow-slave <strong>of</strong> the name <strong>of</strong> Ephialtes stole some plays <strong>of</strong> Eupolis, <strong>and</strong><br />

the theft did not pass unnoticed, for the hound saw him, fell upon him, <strong>and</strong> bit<strong>in</strong>g him<br />

mercilessly, killed him. Some time afterwards Eupolis ended his days <strong>in</strong> Aeg<strong>in</strong>a <strong>and</strong> was<br />

buried there, <strong>and</strong> the hound, howl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> lament<strong>in</strong>g after the manner <strong>of</strong> dogs, let himself<br />

p<strong>in</strong>e away through grief <strong>and</strong> starvation <strong>and</strong>, disgusted with life, died soon after on the<br />

grave <strong>of</strong> the master that had fed it. And <strong>in</strong> memory <strong>of</strong> the sad event the place is named<br />

Hound’s Dirge.<br />

6<br />

Aeschylus, Agamemnon 1-21 V B.C.<br />

Text: D. L. Page, ed., Aeschyli. Septem quae supersunt tragoedias (Oxford, 1972).<br />

Translation: C. Collard, tr., Aeschylus. Oresteia (Oxford, 2002).<br />

FULAC<br />

1 qeou_j me\n ai0tw~ tw~nd' a)pallagh_n po&nwn,<br />

froura~j e0tei/aj mh~koj, h4n koimw&menoj<br />

ste/gaij 0Atreidw~n a1gkaqen, kuno_j di/khn,<br />

a1strwn ka&toida nukte/rwn o(mh&gur<strong>in</strong><br />

5 kai\ tou_j fe/rontaj xei=ma kai\ qe/roj brotoi=j<br />

lamprou_j duna&staj, e0mpre/pontaj ai0qe/ri<br />

a)ste/raj, o3tan fqi/nws<strong>in</strong> a)ntolai=j te tw~n:<br />

kai\ nu~n fula&ssw lampa&doj to_ su&mbolon,<br />

au)gh_n puro_j fe/rousan e0k Troi/aj fa&t<strong>in</strong><br />

10 a(lw&simo&n te ba&c<strong>in</strong>: w{de ga_r kratei=<br />

gunaiko_j a)ndro&boulon e0lpi/zon ke/ar:<br />

eu}t' a2n de\ nukti/plagkton e1ndroso&n t' e1xw<br />

eu)nh_n o)nei/roij ou)k e0piskopoume/nhn<br />

e0mh&n: fo&boj ga_r a)nq' u3pnou parastatei=,<br />

15 to_ mh_ bebai/wj ble/fara sumbalei=n u3pnwi:<br />

o3tan d' a)ei/de<strong>in</strong> h2 m<strong>in</strong>u&resqai dokw~,<br />

u3pnou to&d' a)nti/molpon e0nte/mnwn a1koj,<br />

339


klai/w to&t' oi1kou tou~de sumfora_n ste/nwn<br />

ou)x w(j ta_ pro&sq' a1rista diaponoume/nou.<br />

20 nu~n d' eu)tuxh_j ge/noit' a)pallagh_ po&nwn<br />

eu)agge/lou fane/ntoj o)rfnai/ou puro&j.<br />

WATCHMAN<br />

I ask the gods for release from this misery, the<br />

year-long watch I lie awake keep<strong>in</strong>g on the ro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the Atreidae, up above here like a dog;<br />

I am familiar now with the night stars’ assembly,<br />

<strong>and</strong> those brilliant potentates which br<strong>in</strong>g men summer<br />

<strong>and</strong> w<strong>in</strong>ter, conspicuous <strong>in</strong> the heaven;<br />

I mark them closely as they fade, <strong>and</strong> the ris<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

And now I am on watch for a beacon’s sign, a gleam <strong>of</strong> fire<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g word from Troy <strong>and</strong> report <strong>of</strong> its capture: such is the<br />

power here <strong>of</strong> a woman whose heart <strong>in</strong> its hope plans like a man.<br />

Whenever I f<strong>in</strong>d myself shift<strong>in</strong>g my bed about at night, wet with<br />

dew, unvisited by dreams—because fear <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> sleep st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

at my side to stop my eyes clos<strong>in</strong>g fast <strong>in</strong> slumber—<strong>and</strong> whenever<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k to s<strong>in</strong>g or to hum, dispens<strong>in</strong>g this remedy from music aga<strong>in</strong>st sleep,<br />

then I weep <strong>in</strong> lament for this house’s misfortune;<br />

it is not managed for the best as it was before. Now I wish for a happy<br />

release from misery when the fire <strong>in</strong> the dark has appeared with its good<br />

news.<br />

7<br />

Aeschylus, Agamemnon 604-610 V B.C.<br />

Text: D. L. Page, ed., Aeschyli. Septem quae supersunt tragoedias (Oxford, 1972).<br />

Translation: C. Collard, tr., Aeschylus. Oresteia (Oxford, 2002).<br />

KLUTEMNUSTRA<br />

tau~t' a)pa&ggeilon po&sei,<br />

605 h3ke<strong>in</strong> o3pwj ta&xist' e0ra&smion po&lei:<br />

gunai=ka pisth_n d' e0n do&moij eu3roi molw_n<br />

oi3anper ou}n e1leipe, dwma&twn ku&na<br />

e0sqlh_n e0kei/nwi, polemi/an toi=j du&sfros<strong>in</strong>,<br />

kai\ ta1ll' o(moi/an pa&nta, shmanth&rion<br />

610 ou)de\n diafqei/rasan e0n mh&kei xro&nou:<br />

CLYTEMNESTRA<br />

Take this message away to my husb<strong>and</strong>,<br />

to come as soon as possible; he is the city’s beloved darl<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

As to his wife, I wish he may f<strong>in</strong>d her when he comes<br />

just as faithful <strong>in</strong> his home as the one he left beh<strong>in</strong>d, the house’s watchdog<br />

true to him while hostile to ill-wishers<br />

<strong>and</strong> similar <strong>in</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g else,<br />

340


with no seal broken <strong>in</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

8<br />

Aeschylus, Supplices 800-801 V B.C.<br />

Text: D. L. Page, ed., Aeschyli. Septem quae supersunt tragodias (Oxford, 1972).<br />

Translation: P. Burian, tr., Aeschylus. <strong>The</strong> Suppliants (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1991).<br />

XOROS<br />

800 kusi\n d' e1peiq' e3lwra ka)pixwri/oij<br />

o1rnisi dei=pnon ou)k a)nai/nomai pe/le<strong>in</strong>:<br />

CHORUS<br />

<strong>The</strong>n let dogs feast, let birds<br />

tear my flesh, no matter.<br />

9<br />

Aeschylus, <strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae, (P. Oxy., vol. 18. no 2162, Radt, fr. 78a) pap. A.D. II<br />

Text: S. Radt, Tragicorum Graecorum fragmenta vol. 3 (Gött<strong>in</strong>gen, 1985).<br />

Translation: H. Lloyd-Jones, ed., tr., “<strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae,” <strong>in</strong> H. W. Smyth, ed., tr.,<br />

Aeschylus II. Agamemnon. Libation-Bearers. Eumenides. Fragments (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1923; repr. 1983) no. 276.<br />

h} ka&rt' o)fei/lw tw~nde/ soi: pro&frwn g?a_r ei].<br />

a1koue dh_ pa~j si=ga d?eiq?e?l?eid? ?[ ?] ?<br />

a1q?r?h?s?on ei0?<br />

?[ ? ?] ? ?[ ]<br />

ei1dwlon e?i]nai? t?o?u~t' e0mh|~ morfh|~ ple/on<br />

to_ Dai?d?a& ?lou m[i/]m?hma: fw?n?h~j dei= mo&non.<br />

tad[ ? ?] ?ei? ? ?<br />

ora ? [ ?] ? ( ? )r ? [ ]<br />

xwrei ma&la<br />

eu)ktai=a ko&smon tau~ ?t? [a] tw|~ qew|~ fe/rw<br />


I’m very grateful to you for this: you’re most oblig<strong>in</strong>g. Listen, all <strong>of</strong> you, <strong>and</strong>…<strong>in</strong><br />

silence. Look <strong>and</strong> see whether the eidolon could [possibly] be more [like] me, this<br />

mimema by the Skillful One; it can do everyth<strong>in</strong>g but talk! Look at these! You see? Yes,<br />

come! Come! I br<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g to the god to ornament his house, my lovely votive<br />

picture. It would give my mother a bad time! If she could see it, she’d certa<strong>in</strong>ly run<br />

shriek<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g it was the son she brought up: so like me is this fellow.<br />

Ho there! Look upon the house <strong>of</strong> the Lord <strong>of</strong> the Sea, the Shaker <strong>of</strong> Earth! And let each<br />

fasten up the likeness <strong>of</strong> his h<strong>and</strong>some face, a truthful messenger, a voiceless herald to<br />

keep <strong>of</strong>f travelers; he’ll halt strangers on their way by his terrify<strong>in</strong>g look. Hail, K<strong>in</strong>g, hail<br />

Poseidon…protector….<br />

10<br />

Alcidamas, On Those Who Write Written Speeches or On Sophists 1.27 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. V. Muir, ed., tr., Alcidamas. <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>and</strong> Fragments (Bristol,<br />

2001).<br />

h(gou~mai d' ou)de\ lo&gouj di/kaion ei]nai kalei=sqai tou_j gegramme/nouj,<br />

a)ll' w3sper ei1dwla kai\ sxh&mata kai\ mimh&mata lo&gwn, kai\ th_n au)th_n<br />

kat' au)tw~n ei0ko&twj a2n do&can e1xoimen, h3nper kai\ kata_ tw~n xalkw~n a)ndria&ntwn<br />

kai\ liqi/nwn a)galma&twn kai\ gegramme/nwn zw|&wn. w3sper ga_r<br />

tau~ta mimh&mata tw~n a)lhq<strong>in</strong>w~n swma&twn e0sti/, kai\ te/ry<strong>in</strong> me\n e0pi\ th~j<br />

qewri/aj e1xei, xrh~s<strong>in</strong> d' ou)demi/an tw|~ tw~n a)nqrw&pwn bi/w| paradi/dwsi,<br />

to_n au)to_n tro&pon o( gegramme/noj lo&goj, e9ni\ sxh&mati kai\ ta&cei kexrhme/noj,<br />

e0k bibli/ou me\n qewrou&menoj e1xei t<strong>in</strong>a_j e0kplh&ceij, e0pi\ de\ tw~n kairw~n<br />

a)ki/nhtoj w2n ou)demi/an w)fe/leian toi=j kekthme/noij paradi/dws<strong>in</strong>.<br />

And I do not th<strong>in</strong>k it is right that speeches written down should even be called speeches,<br />

but should be thought <strong>of</strong> as images <strong>and</strong> patterns <strong>and</strong> imitations <strong>of</strong> speeches, <strong>and</strong> we could<br />

reasonably have the same op<strong>in</strong>ion about them as we have about bronze statues<br />

<strong>and</strong> stone monuments <strong>and</strong> gegramme/nwn zw|&wn (=depictions <strong>of</strong> animals). For, just as<br />

these are imitations <strong>of</strong> real bodies <strong>and</strong> give delight to the view, but <strong>of</strong>fer no use <strong>in</strong> human<br />

life, <strong>in</strong> the same way the written speech, hav<strong>in</strong>g a s<strong>in</strong>gle form <strong>and</strong> arrangement, produces<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g effects when it is conned from the book, but be<strong>in</strong>g fixedly unable to<br />

respond to critical moments, if <strong>of</strong> no use to those who have got hold <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

11<br />

Alciphron, Epistles III.11 II/III A.D.<br />

Text: M.A. Schepers, ed., Alciphronis Rhetoris Epistularum Libri IV (Leipzig, 1905; repr.<br />

1969).<br />

Translation: A. Rogers Benner <strong>and</strong> F. H. Fobes, eds., trs., <strong>The</strong> Letters <strong>of</strong> Alciphron,<br />

Aelian <strong>and</strong> Philostratus (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1990).<br />

9Wrolo&gioj Laxanoqauma&sw|<br />

342


ku&nej de\ e0cai/fnhj oi0kouroi\ perixuqe/ntej a1lloj a)llaxo&qen xalepoi\ kai\ barei=j<br />

th_n u(lakh_n e0ph|&esan Molottoi\ kai\ Knw&sioi, u(f' w{n ou)de\n e0kw&luse/ me w(j<br />

h)dikhko&ta th_n 1Artem<strong>in</strong> diespa&sqai me/son, w(j mhde\ ta_ a)krwth&ria ei0j th_n<br />

u(sterai/an perileifqh~nai pro_j tafh_n toi=j e9toi/moij ei0j e1leon kai\ sumpa&qeian.<br />

Horologius to Lachanothaumasus<br />

All <strong>of</strong> a sudden watchdogs surrounded <strong>and</strong> attacked me, one on this side, another on that;<br />

they were savage <strong>and</strong> deep-throated, Molossians <strong>and</strong> Cnosians, <strong>and</strong> there was noth<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

h<strong>in</strong>der me from be<strong>in</strong>g rent asunder by their jaws (as if I had <strong>of</strong>fended Artemis) so<br />

thoroughly that not even my h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> feet would rema<strong>in</strong> next day for burial by those<br />

who might be prepared to pity <strong>and</strong> commiserate.<br />

Alexis, fr. 220, 221 Kock (Men <strong>of</strong> Tarentum) IV B.C.<br />

See Athenaeus 4.161b-4.161c [72].<br />

12<br />

Anacreon (?), Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.715 ? I B.C.-A.D. I-VI<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Bouko&le, ta_n a)ge/lan po&rrw ne/me, mh_ to_ Mu&rwnoj<br />

boi/dion w(j e1mpnoun bousi\ sunecela&sh|j.<br />

Herdsman, pasture thy herd far from here, lest<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g Myron’s heifer to be alive thou drive it <strong>of</strong>f<br />

with the rest.<br />

13<br />

Anacreon (?), Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.716 ? I B.C.-A.D. I-VI<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Boi/dion ou) xoa&noij tetupwme/non, a)ll' u(po_ gh&rwj<br />

xalkwqe\n sfete/rh| yeu&sato xeiri\ Mu&rwn.<br />

Myron pretended this heifer to be the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> his h<strong>and</strong>s, but it was never formed <strong>in</strong> the mould,<br />

but turned <strong>in</strong>to bronze ow<strong>in</strong>g to old age.<br />

Anax<strong>and</strong>rides, fr. 39 Kock (Cities) IV B.C.<br />

See Athenaeus 7.299f [73].<br />

343


14<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 7.62 ?<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology II (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1917; repr. 1925).<br />

Ai0ete/, ti/pte be/bhkaj u(pe\r ta&fon h2 ti/noj, ei0pe/,<br />

a)stero&enta qew~n oi]kon a)poskope/eij; —<br />

Yuxh~j ei0mi Pla&twnoj a)poptame/nhj e0j 1Olumpon<br />

ei0kw&n: sw~ma de\ gh~ ghgene\j 0Atqi\j e1xei.<br />

Eagle, why st<strong>and</strong>est thou on the tomb, <strong>and</strong> on whose, tell me, <strong>and</strong><br />

why gazest thou at the starry home <strong>of</strong> the gods?<br />

I am the image <strong>of</strong> the soul <strong>of</strong> Plato that hath flown away to<br />

Olympus, but his earth-born body rests here <strong>in</strong> Attic earth.<br />

15<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 7.64 ?<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology II (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1917; repr. 1925).<br />

a. Ei0pe/, ku&on, ti/noj a)ndro_j e0festw_j sh~ma fula&sseij;<br />

b. Tou~ Kuno&j. a. 0Alla_ ti/j h}n ou{toj a)nh_r o( Ku&wn;<br />

b. Dioge/nhj. a. Ge/noj ei0pe/. b. S<strong>in</strong>wpeu&j. a. 4Oj pi/qon w| 1kei;<br />

b. Kai\ ma&la: nu~n de\ qanw_n a)ste/raj oi]kon e1xei.<br />

A. “Tell me, dog, who was the man on whose tomb thou st<strong>and</strong>est keep<strong>in</strong>g guard?” B.<br />

“<strong>The</strong> Dog.” A. “But what man was that, the Dog?” B. “Diogenes.” A. “Of what<br />

country?” B. “Of S<strong>in</strong>ope.” A. “He who lived <strong>in</strong> a jar?” B. “Yes, <strong>and</strong> how he is dead, the<br />

stars are his home.”<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a<br />

<strong>The</strong> text <strong>and</strong> translations <strong>of</strong> all anonymous epigrams <strong>of</strong> the Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a referr<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to Myron’s cow are taken from the edition <strong>of</strong> W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek<br />

Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

16<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.713 ?<br />

Boi/dio&n ei0mi Mu&rwnoj, e0pi\ sth&lhj d' a)na&keimai.<br />

bouko&le, kenth&saj ei0j a)ge/lhn m' a1page.<br />

I am Myron’s little heifer, set up on a base. Goad<br />

me, herdsman, <strong>and</strong> drive me <strong>of</strong>f to the herd.<br />

344


17<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.714 ?<br />

Ti/pte, Mu&rwn, me to_ boi/dion e0ntauqoi= para_ bwmoi=j<br />

e1stasaj; ou)k e0qe/leij ei0sage/men me/garon;<br />

Why, Myron, didst thou set me here by the altars?<br />

Wilt thou not lead me <strong>in</strong>to the house?<br />

18<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.721A ?<br />

9H bou=v e0c a)ro&tou ne/on h2luqe, kai\ dia_ tou~to<br />

o)knei=, kou)k e0qe9/lei bh~m' e0pi/prosqen a1ge<strong>in</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong> cow has just returned from plow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong><br />

ow<strong>in</strong>g to that is lazy <strong>and</strong> will not advance.<br />

19<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.725 ?<br />

Bou~n i0di/an pote\ bousi\ Mu&rwn mixqei=san e0reu&na:<br />

eu{re mo&lij d' au)th_n ta_j bo&aj e0cela&saj.<br />

Myron was look<strong>in</strong>g for his own cow among the<br />

others, <strong>and</strong> found it with difficulty by driv<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

rest away.<br />

20<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.726 ?<br />

9A bou~j a( ti/ktous' a)po_ gaste/roj e1plase ta_n bou~n:<br />

a( de\ Mu&rwnoj xei\r ou) pla&sen, a)ll' e1teken.<br />

<strong>The</strong> cow, its mother, moulded this heifer<br />

giv<strong>in</strong>g birth to it, but the h<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Myron did not mould<br />

it, but gave birth to it.<br />

21<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.727 ?<br />

345


Kai\ xalkh~ per e0ou~sa la&lhsen a2n a( kerah_ bou~j,<br />

ei1 oi9 spla&gxna Mu&rwn e1ndon e0texna&sato.<br />

<strong>The</strong> horned cow would have spoken, though<br />

made <strong>of</strong> bronze, if Myron had worked entrails <strong>in</strong>side it.<br />

22<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.729 ?<br />

Phkto&n moi/ tij a1rotron e0p' au)xe/ni kai\ zuga_ qe/sqw,<br />

ei3neka ga_r te/xnaj sei=o, Mu&rwn, a)ro&sw.<br />

Let someone attach me to the solid plough <strong>and</strong><br />

put a yoke on my neck, for as far as depends on<br />

thy art, Myron, I will plough.<br />

23<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.731 ?<br />

[Wde Mu&rwn m' e1sthse to_ boi/dion: oi9 de\ nomh~ej<br />

ba&llousi/n me li/qoij w(j a)poleipo&menon.<br />

Myron placed me the heifer, here, but the herds-<br />

men throw stones at me th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g I have strayed.<br />

24<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.733 ?<br />

Ta_n bou~n ta&nde Mu&rwn, cei=n', e1plasen, a4n o3de mo&sxoj<br />

w(j zw~san sai/nei, mate/ra derko&menoj.<br />

Stranger, it was Myron who moulded this cow, on which this calf<br />

fawns as if it were alive, tak<strong>in</strong>g it for its mother.<br />

25<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.735 ?<br />

Sei=o, Mu&rwn, dama&lei paraka&tqane mo&sxoj a)laqei\j<br />

kai\ ga&la pisteu&wn xalko_n e1swqen e1xe<strong>in</strong>.<br />

A calf died beside thy heifer, Myron, deceived<br />

<strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that the bronze had milk <strong>in</strong>side.<br />

346


26<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.736 ?<br />

Feu~ su&, Mu&rwn, pla&ssaj ou)k e1fqasaj: a)lla& se xalko&j,<br />

pri\n yuxh_n bale/e<strong>in</strong>, e1fqase phgnu&menoj.<br />

Alack! Myron, thou didst not have time to<br />

complete thy cast<strong>in</strong>g, but the bronze hardened<br />

before thou couldst put life <strong>in</strong>to it.<br />

27<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.737 ?<br />

Xalkei/an tu&pteij da&mal<strong>in</strong>: me/ga s' h1pafe te/xna,<br />

bouko&le: ta_n yuxa_n ou) prose/qhke Mu&rwn.<br />

Thou strikest the bronze heifer. Art deceived<br />

thee much, herdsman: Myron did not add life.<br />

28<br />

Anonymous, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.741 ?<br />

Xa&lkeoj h}j, e0pi\ soi\ de\ gewto&moj ei[lken a1rotron<br />

kai\ zugo&desma fe/rwn, yeudome/na da&mali.<br />

a)lla_ Mu&rwn te/xna| panupei/roxoj, o3j se di' e1rgwn<br />

e1mpnoun w3j t<strong>in</strong>a bou~n e0rga&t<strong>in</strong> ei0rga&sato.<br />

Thou wast bronze, deceptive heifer, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

husb<strong>and</strong>man came up to thee dragg<strong>in</strong>g a plough<br />

<strong>and</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g a yoke. He far excels all other artists,<br />

Myron, who by his labour made thee alive, just like<br />

a labour<strong>in</strong>g cow.<br />

29<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 7.426 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology II (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1917; repr. 1925).<br />

Ei0pe/, le/on, fqime/noio ti/noj ta&fon a)mfibe/bhkaj,<br />

boufa&ge; ti/j ta~j sa~j a1cioj h}n a)reta~j; —<br />

Ui9o_j Qeudw&roio Teleuti/aj, o4j me/ga pa&ntwn<br />

fe/rteroj h}n, qhrw~n o3sson e0gw_ ke/krimai.<br />

347


ou)xi\ ma&tan e3staka, fe/rw de/ ti su&mbolon a)lka~j<br />

a)ne/roj: h}n ga_r dh_ dusmene/essi le/wn.<br />

Tell, lion, thou slayer <strong>of</strong> k<strong>in</strong>e, on whose tomb thou st<strong>and</strong>est there<br />

<strong>and</strong> who was worthy <strong>of</strong> thy valour?<br />

Teleutias, the son <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>odorus, who was far most valiant <strong>of</strong><br />

men, as I am judged to be <strong>of</strong> beasts. Not <strong>in</strong> va<strong>in</strong> st<strong>and</strong> I here, but<br />

I emblem the prowess <strong>of</strong> the man, for he was <strong>in</strong>deed a lion to his<br />

enemies.<br />

30<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.720 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Ei0 mh& mou poti\ ta|~de Mu&rwn po&daj h3rmose pe/tra|,<br />

a1llaij a2n nemo&man bousi\n o(mou~ da&malij.<br />

If Myron had not fixed my feet to this stone I<br />

would have gone to pasture with the other cows.<br />

31<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.721 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Mo&sxe, ti/ moi lago&nessi prose/rxeai; e0j ti/ de\ muka|~;<br />

a( te/xna mazoi=j ou)k e0ne/qhke ga&la.<br />

Calf, why dost thou approach my flanks, <strong>and</strong> why<br />

doast thou low? <strong>The</strong> artist put no milk <strong>in</strong> my udder.<br />

32<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.722 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Ta_n da&mal<strong>in</strong>, bouforbe/, pare/rxeo mhd' a)pa&neuqe<br />

suri/sdh|j: mastw|~ po&rt<strong>in</strong> u(pekde/xetai.<br />

Pass by the heifer, cowherd, <strong>and</strong> whistle not<br />

to her from afar. She is expect<strong>in</strong>g her calf to suckle it.<br />

348


33<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.723 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

9A mo&liboj kate/xei me kai\ a( li/qoj: ei3neka d' a2n seu~,<br />

pla&sta Mu&rwn, lwto_n kai\ qru&on e0drepo&man.<br />

<strong>The</strong> lead <strong>and</strong> stone hold me fast, but, otherwise,<br />

thanks to thee, sculptor Myron, I would be nibbl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

lotus <strong>and</strong> rushes.<br />

34<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.724 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

9A da&malij, doke/w, mukh&setai: h} r(' o( Promhqeu_j<br />

ou)xi\ mo&noj, pla&tteij e1mpnoa kai\ su&, Mu&rwn.<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k the heifer will low. Of a truth it is not<br />

Prometheus alone who moulds liv<strong>in</strong>g creatures,<br />

but thou too, Myron.<br />

35<br />

Antipater <strong>of</strong> Sidon, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.728 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

9A da&malij, doke/w, mukh&setai: h2n de\ bradu&nh|,<br />

xalko_j o( mh_ noe/wn ai1tioj, ou)xi\ Mu&rwn.<br />

<strong>The</strong> heifer, I th<strong>in</strong>k, will low, <strong>and</strong> if its delays it<br />

is the fault <strong>of</strong> the senseless bronze, not Myron’s.<br />

36<br />

Aristophanes, Equites 289 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Henderson, ed., tr., Aristophanes. Acharnians. Knights<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1998).<br />

ALLANTOPWLHS<br />

kunokoph&sw sou to_ nw~ton.<br />

349


SAUSAGE SELLER<br />

I’ll beat your back like a dog’s!<br />

37<br />

Aristophanes, Equites 411-416 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Knights (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes<br />

2; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1981).<br />

ALLANTOPWLHS<br />

1Egwge, nh_ tou_j kondu&louj, ou4j polla_ dh_ 'pi\ polloi=j<br />

h)nesxo&mhn e0k paidi/ou, maxairi/dwn te plhga&j,<br />

u(perbalei=sqai/ s' oi1omai tou&tois<strong>in</strong>, h2 ma&thn g' a2n<br />

a)pomagdalia_j sitou&menoj tosou~toj e0ktrafei/hn.<br />

PAFLAGWN<br />

415 0Apomagdalia_j w3sper ku&wn; ]W pampo&nhre, pw~j ou}n<br />

kuno_j bora_n sitou&menoj maxei= su_ kunokefa&lw|;<br />

SAUSAGE-SELLER<br />

Well, I swear by the fists whose blows I’ve borne many on many<br />

a time from a child up, <strong>and</strong> by the slashes <strong>of</strong> butchers’ knives,<br />

I th<strong>in</strong>k I will surpass you <strong>in</strong> that. Otherwise it would be for noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that I’ve grown to such a size on a diet <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>-wipes.<br />

PAPHLAGON<br />

H<strong>and</strong>-wipes, like a dog? Poor rascal, how on a diet<br />

<strong>of</strong> dog’s food do you expect to fight with a dog-faced baboon?<br />

38<br />

Aristophanes, Equites 1030-1034 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Henderson, ed., tr., Aristophanes. Acharnians. Knights<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1998).<br />

ALLANTOPWLHS<br />

1030 ku&na Ke/rberon a)ndrapodisth&n,<br />

o4j ke/rkw| sai/nwn s', o(po&tan deipnh|~j, e0pithrw~n<br />

e0ce/detai/ sou tou1yon, o3tan su& poi a1llose xa&skh|j:<br />

e0sfoitw~n t' e0j tou)pta&nion lh&sei se kunhdo_n<br />

nu&ktwr ta_j lopa&daj kai\ ta_j nh&souj dialei/xwn.<br />

SAUSAGE SELLER<br />

<strong>The</strong> dog Cerberus, trafficker <strong>in</strong> bodies,<br />

who wags his tail at you when you’re d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

350


watches, <strong>and</strong> when you happen to gape <strong>in</strong> another direction,<br />

eats up your entrée, <strong>and</strong> at night steals <strong>in</strong>to your kitchen<br />

all unseen, <strong>and</strong> doglike licks clean the plates <strong>and</strong> the isl<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

39<br />

Aristophanes, Equites 1395-1401 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Henderson, ed., tr., Aristophanes. Acharnians. Knights<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1998).<br />

DHMOS<br />

1395 to_n de\ Paflago&na,<br />

o4j tau~t' e1drasen, ei1f' o3 ti poh&seij kako&n.<br />

ALLANTOPWLHS<br />

ou)de\n me/g' a)ll' h2 th_n e0mh_n e3cei te/xnhn:<br />

e0pi\ tai=j pu&laij a)llantopwlh&sei mo&noj,<br />

ta_ ku&neia meignu_j toi=j o)nei/oij pra&gmas<strong>in</strong>,<br />

1400 mequ&wn te tai=j po&rnaisi loidorh&setai,<br />

ka)k tw~n balanei/wn pi/etai to_ lou&trion.<br />

DEMOS<br />

And Paphlagon, who behaved this way, tell me how you’ll<br />

punish him.<br />

SAUSAGE SELLER<br />

Noth<strong>in</strong>g severe; he’s merely go<strong>in</strong>g to take my old job. He’ll<br />

have his own sausage st<strong>and</strong> at the city gates, hash<strong>in</strong>g up<br />

dog <strong>and</strong> ass meat <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> politics, gett<strong>in</strong>g drunk <strong>and</strong><br />

trad<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sults with the whores, <strong>and</strong> dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g the run<strong>of</strong>f<br />

from the public baths.<br />

40<br />

Aristophanes, fr. 204 Kock (Banqueters) V B.C.<br />

Text: Kock, Comicorum Atticorum Fragmenta I (Leipzig, 1880).<br />

Translation: J. M. Edmonds, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Fragments <strong>of</strong> Attic Comedy I (Leiden, 1957).<br />

41<br />

ti/ dai/; kuni/dion lepto_n e0pri/w th|~ qea|~<br />

ei0j ta_j trio&douj;<br />

What does this mean? You’ve bought a little white pup<br />

on which the goddess at the cross may sup?<br />

351


Aristophanes, Lysistrata 1203-1215 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Henderson, ed., tr., Aristophanes. Birds. Lysistrata. Women at the<br />

<strong>The</strong>smophoria (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 2000).<br />

XOROS<br />

ei0 de/ tw| mh_ si=toj u(mw~n<br />

e0sti, bo&skei d' oi0ke/taj kai\<br />

smikra_ polla_ paidi/a,<br />

1205 e1sti par' e0mou~ labei=n<br />

puri/dia lepta_ me/n, o( d'<br />

a1rtoj a)po_ xoi/nikoj i0-<br />

dei=n ma&la neani/aj.<br />

1210 3Ostij ou}n bou&letai tw~n penh&twn i1tw<br />

ei0j e0mou~ sa&kouj e1xwn kai\<br />

kwru&kouj: w(j lh&yetai purou&j. 9O ma-<br />

nh~j d' ou(mo_j au)toi=j e0mbalei=.<br />

pro&j ge me/ntoi th_n qu&ran<br />

proagoreu&w mh_ badi/ze<strong>in</strong> th_n e0mh&n, a)ll'<br />

1215 eu)labei=sqai th_n ku&na.<br />

CHORUS<br />

If anyone’s out <strong>of</strong> bread<br />

but has slaves to feed<br />

<strong>and</strong> lots <strong>of</strong> little kids,<br />

you can get flour from my house—<br />

puny gra<strong>in</strong>s, true,<br />

but a pound <strong>of</strong> them grow up to be<br />

a loaf that’s very hearty to see.<br />

And <strong>of</strong> the poor are welcome<br />

to come to my house with sacks<br />

<strong>and</strong> bags to carry the flour away; my houseboy<br />

will pour it <strong>in</strong> for them.<br />

A warn<strong>in</strong>g though:<br />

Don’t come to my door—<br />

beware <strong>of</strong> the watchdog there!<br />

42<br />

Aristophanes, Pax 19-28 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Henderson, ed., tr., Aristophanes. Clouds. Wasps. Peace<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1998).<br />

OIKETHS B &<br />

nh_ to_n Di/' e0j ko&raka&j ge, kai\ sauto&n ge pro&j.<br />

20 u(mw~n de/ g' ei1 tij oi]de/ moi kateipa&tw<br />

po&qen a2n priai/mhn r(i=na mh_ tetrhme/nhn.<br />

352


ou)de\n ga_r e1rgon h}n a1r' a)qliw&teron<br />

h2 kanqa&rw| ma&ttonta pare/xe<strong>in</strong> e0sqi/e<strong>in</strong>.<br />

u{j me\n ga&r, w3sper a2n xe/sh| tij, h2 ku&wn<br />

25 fau&lwj e0rei/dei tou~q': o( d' u(po_ fronh&matoj<br />

brenqu&etai/ te kai\ fagei=n ou)k a)cioi=,<br />

h2n mh_ paraqw~ tri/yaj di' h(me/raj o3lhj<br />

w3sper gunaiki\ goggu&lhn memagme/nhn.<br />

SECOND SLAVE<br />

By heaven, you can take it to hell, <strong>and</strong> yourself with it!<br />

(to the spectators) If any <strong>of</strong> you knows where I can buy an<br />

unperforated nose, please tell me! Because there’s no job<br />

more wretched than knead<strong>in</strong>g food to serve to a beetle. A<br />

pig or a dog will simply gobble up any shit that falls, but<br />

this conceited th<strong>in</strong>g puts on airs <strong>and</strong> won’t deign to eat<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g that I don’t spend the whole day mash<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

serve kneaded <strong>in</strong>to a ball, as for a lady.<br />

43<br />

Aristophanes, Plutus 594-597<br />

Text: V. Coulon <strong>and</strong> H. van Daele, eds., Aristophane V (Paris, 1930; repr. 1963).<br />

Translation: A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wealth (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 11;<br />

Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 2001).<br />

XREMULOS<br />

Para_ th~j 9Eka&thj e1cest<strong>in</strong> tou~to puqe/sqai,<br />

595 ei1te to_ ploutei=n ei1te to_ pe<strong>in</strong>h~n be/ltion. Fhsi\ ga_r au3th<br />

tou_j me\n e1xontaj kai\ ploutou~ntaj dei=pnon kata_ mh~n' a)pope/mpe<strong>in</strong>,<br />

tou_j de\ pe/nhtaj tw~n a)nqrw&pwn a(rpa&ze<strong>in</strong> pri\n kataqei=nai.<br />

CHREMYLUS<br />

You can get the answer from Hecate<br />

as to whether it is better to be rich or to be hungry.<br />

She says that the “haves,” the rich, <strong>of</strong>fer her a d<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

every month, but the poor people snatch it away before<br />

it’s even set down!<br />

44<br />

Aristophanes, Plutus 1100-1105<br />

Text: V. Coulon <strong>and</strong> H. van Daele, eds., Aristophane V (Paris, 1930; repr. 1963).<br />

Translation: A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wealth (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 11;<br />

Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 2001).<br />

KARIWN<br />

353


1100 ou{toj, ei0pe/ moi,<br />

su_ th_n qu&ran e1koptej ou(twsi\ sfo&dra;<br />

ERMHS<br />

ma_ Di/', a)ll' e1mellon: ei]t' a)ne/w|ca&j me fqa&saj.<br />

0All' e0kka&lei to_n despo&thn tre/xwn taxu&,<br />

e1peita th_n gunai=ka kai\ ta_ paidi/a,<br />

1105 e1peita tou_j qera&pontaj, ei]ta th_n ku&na,<br />

e1peita sauto&n, ei]ta th_n u{n.<br />

CARION<br />

Here, you, tell me,<br />

was it you that was knock<strong>in</strong>g so hard on the door just now?<br />

HERMES<br />

No, I didn’t; I was go<strong>in</strong>g to, but you opened the door first.<br />

Now run quickly <strong>and</strong> call out your master,<br />

then his wife <strong>and</strong> children,<br />

then the servants, then the dog,<br />

then yourself, <strong>and</strong> then the pig.<br />

45<br />

Aristophanes, <strong>The</strong>smophoriazusae 414-417<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong>smophoriazusae (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristophanes 8; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1994).<br />

MIKA<br />

ei]ta dia_ tou~ton tai=j gunaikwni/tis<strong>in</strong><br />

415 sfragi=daj e0piba&llous<strong>in</strong> h1dh kai\ moxlou_j<br />

throu~ntej h(ma~j, kai\ prose/ti Molottikou_j<br />

tre/fousi mormolukei=a toi=j moixoi=j ku&naj.<br />

MICA<br />

<strong>The</strong>n, aga<strong>in</strong>, because <strong>of</strong> him, they now keep close guard on us,<br />

putt<strong>in</strong>g seals <strong>and</strong> bars on the doors <strong>of</strong> the women’s quarters,<br />

<strong>and</strong> on top <strong>of</strong> that they keep Molossian dogs<br />

to frighten the wits out <strong>of</strong> seducers.<br />

46<br />

Aristophanes, Vespae 835-843 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. A. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wasps (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes<br />

4; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1983).<br />

CANQIAS<br />

354


835 ba&ll' e0j ko&rakaj. toioutoni\ tre/fe<strong>in</strong> ku&na.<br />

BDELUKLEWN<br />

ti/ d' e0sti\n e0teo&n;<br />

CANQIAS<br />

ou) ga_r o( La&bhj a)rti/wj,<br />

o( ku&wn, para|&caj ei0j to_n i0pno_n a(rpa&saj<br />

tr<strong>of</strong>ali/da turou~ Sikelikh_n katedh&doken;<br />

BDELUKLEWN<br />

840 tou~t' a}ra prw~ton ta)di/khma tw|~ patri\<br />

ei0sakte/on moi. su_ de\ kathgo&rei parw&n.<br />

CANQIAS<br />

ma_ Di/' ou)k e1gwg', a)ll' a3tero&j fhs<strong>in</strong> ku&wn<br />

kathgorh&se<strong>in</strong>, h1n tij ei0sa&gh| grafh&n.<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

To hell with you! To th<strong>in</strong>k that we keep a dog like that!<br />

BDELYCLEON<br />

Tell me, what’s the matter?<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

If it isn’t that dog Labes! He just dashed through<br />

<strong>in</strong>to the kitchen, grabbed a long Sicilian cheese,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he’s eaten it all up.<br />

BDELYCLEON<br />

<strong>The</strong>n that must be the first crime I br<strong>in</strong>g before my father.<br />

You be here to prosecute.<br />

XANTHIAS<br />

No, not me; actually the other dog says<br />

he’ll be prosecut<strong>in</strong>g if a charge is brought <strong>in</strong>to court.<br />

47<br />

Aristophanes, Vespae 968-969 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. A. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wasps (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes<br />

4; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1983).<br />

BDELUKLEWN<br />

ou{toj ga_r o( La&bhj kai\ traxh&li' e0sqi/ei<br />

kai\ ta_j a)ka&nqaj, kou)de/pot' e0n tau)tw|~ me/nei.<br />

355


BDELYCLEON<br />

This Labes will eat meat-scraps<br />

<strong>and</strong> fish-bones, <strong>and</strong> he never stays <strong>in</strong> one place for long.<br />

48<br />

Aristotle, Categoriae 1a IV B.C.<br />

Text: L. M<strong>in</strong>io-Paluello, ed., Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione (Oxford,<br />

1949; repr. 1966).<br />

Translation: H. P. Cooke, ed., tr., Aristotle I. Categories. On Interpretation. Prior<br />

Analytics (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1938; repr. 1996).<br />

9Omw&numa le/getai w{n o1noma mo&non ko<strong>in</strong>o&n, o( de\ kata_ tou1noma lo&goj th~j ou)si/aj<br />

e3teroj, oi[on zw|~on o3 te a1nqrwpoj kai\ to_ gegramme/non: tou&twn ga_r o1noma mo&non<br />

ko<strong>in</strong>o&n, o( de\ kata_ tou1noma lo&goj th~j ou)si/aj e3teroj: e0a_n ga_r a)podidw|~ tij ti/<br />

e0st<strong>in</strong> au)tw~n e9kate/rw| to_ zw|&w| ei]nai, i1dion e9kate/rou lo&gon a)podw&sei. sunw&numa<br />

de\ le/getai w{n to& te o1noma ko<strong>in</strong>o_n kai\ o( kata_ tou1noma lo&goj th~j ou)si/aj o( au)to&j,<br />

oi[on zw|~on o3 te a1nqrwpoj kai\ o( bou~j: tou&twn ga_r e9ka&teron ko<strong>in</strong>w|~ o)no&mati<br />

prosagoreu&etai zw|~on, kai\ o( lo&goj de\ th~j ou)si/aj o( au)to&j: e0a_n ga_r a)podidw|~ tij<br />

to_n e9kate/rou lo&gon ti/ e0st<strong>in</strong> au)tw~n e9kate/rw| to_ zw|&w| ei]nai, to_n au)to_n<br />

lo&gon a)podw&sei. parw&numa de\ le/getai o3sa a)po& t<strong>in</strong>oj diafe/ronta th|~ ptw&sei<br />

th_n kata_ tou1noma proshgori/an e1xei, oi[on a)po_ th~j grammatikh~j o( grammatiko_j<br />

kai\ a)po_ th~j a)ndrei/aj o( a)ndrei=oj.<br />

Th<strong>in</strong>gs are equivocally named, when they have the name only <strong>in</strong> common, the def<strong>in</strong>ition<br />

(or statement <strong>of</strong> essence) correspond<strong>in</strong>g with the name be<strong>in</strong>g different. For <strong>in</strong>stance,<br />

while a man <strong>and</strong> a portrait can properly both be called ‘animals’ these are equivocally<br />

named. For they have the name only <strong>in</strong> common, the def<strong>in</strong>itions (or statements <strong>of</strong><br />

essence) correspond<strong>in</strong>g with the name be<strong>in</strong>g different. For if you are asked to def<strong>in</strong>e<br />

what the be<strong>in</strong>g an animal means <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the man <strong>and</strong> the portrait, you give <strong>in</strong> either<br />

case a def<strong>in</strong>ition appropriate to that case alone.<br />

Th<strong>in</strong>gs are univocally named, when not only they bear the same name but the name<br />

means the same <strong>in</strong> each case—has the same def<strong>in</strong>ition correspond<strong>in</strong>g. Thus a man <strong>and</strong> an<br />

ox are called ‘animals.’ <strong>The</strong> name is the same <strong>in</strong> both cases; so also the statement <strong>of</strong><br />

essence. For if you are asked what is meant by their both <strong>of</strong> them be<strong>in</strong>g called ‘animals’<br />

you give that particular name <strong>in</strong> both cases the same def<strong>in</strong>ition. Th<strong>in</strong>gs are ‘derivatively’<br />

named that derive their own name form some other, that is given a new verbal form, as,<br />

for <strong>in</strong>stance, ‘grammarian’ from ‘grammar,’ from ‘heroism,’ ‘hero,’ <strong>and</strong> so on.<br />

49<br />

Aristotle, De Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium 743b IV B.C.<br />

Text: H. J. D. Lul<strong>of</strong>s, ed., Aristotelis de Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium (Oxford, 1965; repr.<br />

1972).<br />

Translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1943; repr. 1953).<br />

356


Prw~ton me\n ou}n to_ a1nw ku&toj a)fori/zetai kata_ th_n ge/nes<strong>in</strong>,<br />

to_ de\ ka&tw proi"o&ntoj tou~ xro&nou lamba&nei th_n au1chs<strong>in</strong> e0n toi=j e0nai/moij.<br />

a3panta de\ tai=j perigrafai=j diori/zetai pro&teron, u3steron de\ lamba&nei ta_<br />

xrw&mata kai\ ta_j malako&thtaj kai\ ta_j sklhro&thtaj, a)texnw~j w3sper<br />

a2n u(po_ zwgra&fou th~j fu&sewj dhmiourgou&mena: kai\ ga_r oi9 grafei=j<br />

u(pogra&yantej tai=j grammai=j ou3twj e0nalei/fousi toi=j xrw&masi to_ zw|~on.<br />

Now the upper portion <strong>of</strong> the body is the first to be marked <strong>of</strong>f <strong>in</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> the<br />

embryo’s formation; the lower portion receives its growth as time goes on. (This applies<br />

to the blooded animals). In the early stages the parts are all traced out <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e; later on<br />

they get their various colors <strong>and</strong> s<strong>of</strong>tnesses <strong>and</strong> hardnesses, for all the world as if a<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ter were at work on them, the pa<strong>in</strong>ter be<strong>in</strong>g Nature. Pa<strong>in</strong>ters, as we know, first <strong>of</strong> all<br />

sketch <strong>in</strong> the figure <strong>of</strong> the animal <strong>in</strong> outl<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> after that go on to apply the colors.<br />

50<br />

Aristotle, De Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium 746a IV B.C.<br />

Text: H. J. D. Lul<strong>of</strong>s, ed., Aristotelis de Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium (Oxford, 1965; repr.<br />

1972).<br />

Translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1943; repr. 1953).<br />

Gi/gnetai de\ o( sunduasmo_j toi=j zw|&oij kata_ fu&s<strong>in</strong> me\n toi=j o(mogene/s<strong>in</strong>, ou) mh_n<br />

a)lla_ kai\ toi=j me\n su&negguj th_n fu&s<strong>in</strong> e1xous<strong>in</strong> ou)k a)diafo&roij de\ tw|~ ei1dei, e0a_n<br />

ta& te mege/qh paraplh&sia h|} kai\ oi9 xro&noi i1soi w}si th~j kuh&sewj. spa&nia me\n<br />

ou}n gi/gnetai ta_ toiau~ta e0pi\ tw~n a1llwn, gi/gnetai de\ kai\ e0pi\ kunw~n kai\<br />

a)lwpe/kwn kai\ lu&kwn : kai\ oi9 0Indikoi\ de\ ku&nej e0k qhri/ou t<strong>in</strong>o_j<br />

kunw&douj gennw~ntai kai\ kuno&j.<br />

<strong>The</strong> partners <strong>in</strong> copulation are naturally <strong>and</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>arily animals <strong>of</strong> the same k<strong>in</strong>d; but<br />

beside that, animals that are closely allied <strong>in</strong> their nature, <strong>and</strong> are not very different <strong>in</strong><br />

species, copulate, if they are comparable <strong>in</strong> size <strong>and</strong> if their period <strong>of</strong> gestation are equal<br />

<strong>in</strong> length. Although such cross<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong>frequent among the majority <strong>of</strong> animals, it occurs<br />

among dogs, foxes, wolves (<strong>and</strong> jackals); the Indian dog also is produced from the union<br />

<strong>of</strong> a dog with some wild doglike beast.<br />

51<br />

Aristotle, De Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium 747b IV B.C.<br />

Text: H. J. D. Lul<strong>of</strong>s, ed., Aristotelis de Generatione <strong>Animal</strong>ium (Oxford, 1965; repr.<br />

1972).<br />

Translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Generation <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1943; repr. 1953).<br />

ei0 ga_r e0c o(moeidw~n a1rrenoj kai\ qh&leoj o(moeide\j gi/gnesqai pe/fuke toi=j<br />

gennh&sas<strong>in</strong> a1rren h2 qh~lu, oi[on e0k kuno_j a1rrenoj kai\ qh&leoj ku&wn a1rrhn<br />

h2 qh&leia, kai\ e0c e9te/rwn tw|~ ei1dei e3teron tw|~ ei1dei, oi[on ei0 ku&wn<br />

357


e3teron le/ontoj, kai\ e0k kuno_j a1rrenoj kai\ le/ontoj qh&leoj e3teron<br />

kai\ e0k le/ontoj a1rrenoj kai\ kuno_j qh&leoj e3teron:<br />

Two animals which differ <strong>in</strong> species produce <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g which differs <strong>in</strong> species; for<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance, a dog differs <strong>in</strong> species from a lion, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a male dog <strong>and</strong> a<br />

female lion is different <strong>in</strong> species; so is the <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a male lion <strong>and</strong> a female dog.<br />

52<br />

Aristotle, De Memoria et Rem<strong>in</strong>iscentia 450b-451a IV B.C.<br />

Text: W. D. Ross, ed., Aristotle. Parva Naturalia (Oxford, 1955; repr. 1970).<br />

Translation: W. S. Hett, ed., tr., Aristotle VIII. On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1995).<br />

oi[on ga_r to_ e0n pi/naki gegramme/non zw|~on kai\ zw|~o&n e0sti kai\ ei0kw&n, kai\ to_ au)to_ kai\<br />

e4n tou~t' e0sti\n a1mfw, to_ me/ntoi ei]nai ou) tau)to_n a)mfoi=n, kai\ e1sti qewrei=n kai\ w(j<br />

zw|~on kai\ w(j ei0ko&na, ou3tw kai\ to_ e0n h(mi=n fa&ntasma dei= u(polabei=n kai\<br />

au)to& ti kaq' au(to_ ei]nai kai\ a1llou [fa&ntasma]. h| { me\n ou}n kaq' au(to&, qew&rhma h2<br />

fa&ntasma& e0st<strong>in</strong>, h| { d' a1llou, oi[on ei0kw_n kai\ mnhmo&neuma. w3ste kai\ o3tan e0nergh|~ h(<br />

ki/nhsij au)tou~, a2n me\n h| { kaq' au(to& e0sti, tau&th| ai0sqa&nhtai h( yuxh_ au)tou~, oi[on<br />

no&hma& ti h2 fa&ntasma fai/netai e0pelqei=n: a2n d' h| { a1llou kai\ w3sper e0n th|~ grafh|~ w(j<br />

ei0ko&na qewrei= kai/, mh__<br />

e9wrakw_j to_n Kori/skon, w(j Kori/skou, e0ntau~qa& te a1llo to_<br />

pa&qoj th~j qewri/aj tau&thj kai\ o3tan w(j zw|~on gegramme/non qewrh|~, e1n te th|~ yuxh|~<br />

to_ me\n gi/gnetai w3sper no&hma mo&non, to_ d' w(j e0kei= o3ti ei0kw&n, mnhmo&neuma.<br />

Just as the picture pa<strong>in</strong>ted on the panel is at once a picture <strong>and</strong> a portrait, <strong>and</strong> though one<br />

<strong>and</strong> the same, is both, yet the essence <strong>of</strong> the two is not the same, <strong>and</strong> it is possible to th<strong>in</strong>k<br />

<strong>of</strong> it as a picture <strong>and</strong> as a portrait, so <strong>in</strong> the same way we must regard the mental picture<br />

with<strong>in</strong> us both as an object <strong>of</strong> contemplation <strong>in</strong> itself <strong>and</strong> as a mental picture <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

else. In so far as we consider it <strong>in</strong> itself, it is an object <strong>of</strong> contemplation or a mental<br />

picture, but <strong>in</strong> so far as we consider it <strong>in</strong> relation to someth<strong>in</strong>g else, e.g., as a likeness, it<br />

is also an aid to memory. Hence when the stimulus <strong>of</strong> it is operative, if the soul perceives<br />

the impression as <strong>in</strong>dependent, it appears to occur as a thought, or a mental picture; but if<br />

it is considered <strong>in</strong> relation to someth<strong>in</strong>g else, it is as though one contemplated a figure <strong>in</strong><br />

the picture as a portrait, e.g., <strong>of</strong> Coriscus, although he has not just seen Coriscus. As <strong>in</strong><br />

this case the affection caused by the contemplation differs from that which is caused then<br />

one contemplates the object merely as a pa<strong>in</strong>ted picture, so <strong>in</strong> the soul the one object<br />

appears as a mere thought, but the other, be<strong>in</strong>g (as <strong>in</strong> the former case) a likeness, is an aid<br />

to memory.<br />

53<br />

Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea 3.10.7 IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Aristotle. <strong>The</strong> Nicomachean Ethics<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1926; repr. 1956).<br />

ou)de\ ga_r tai=j o)smai=j tw~n lagww~n ai9 ku&nej<br />

358


xai/rous<strong>in</strong> a)lla_ th|~ brw&sei, th_n d' ai1sqhs<strong>in</strong> h( o)smh_ e0poi/hsen:<br />

Hounds do not take pleasure <strong>in</strong> scent<strong>in</strong>g hares,<br />

but <strong>in</strong> eat<strong>in</strong>g them; the scent merely made them aware <strong>of</strong> the hare.<br />

54<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 488b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

ta_ d' e0leuqe/ria kai\ a)ndrei=a kai\ eu)genh~, oi[on le/wn.<br />

Other [animals] are noble <strong>and</strong> brave <strong>and</strong> high-bred, e.g., the lion.<br />

55<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 490b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

Tou~ de\ ge/nouj tou~ tw~n tetrapo&dwn zw|&wn kai\ zw|oto&kwn ei1dh me/n e0sti polla&,<br />

a)nw&numa de/: a)lla_ kaq' e3kaston au)tw~n w(j ei0pei=n, w3sper a1nqrwpoj ei1rhtai,<br />

le/wn, e1lafoj, i3ppoj, ku&wn kai\ ta}lla tou~ton to_n tro&pon,<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are many k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the group <strong>of</strong> viviparous quadrupeds; but they are<br />

unnamed. Each constituent, we may say, has been named <strong>in</strong>dividually, as man has, e.g.,<br />

lion, deer, horse, dog, <strong>and</strong> the rest <strong>of</strong> them <strong>in</strong> the same way.<br />

56<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 501a IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

1Eti de\ ta_ me/n e0sti karxaro&donta au)tw~n, oi[on le/wn kai\ pa&rdalij kai\ ku&wn.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> them [animals] are saw-toothed, e.g., the lion, the leopard, <strong>and</strong> the dog.<br />

57<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 502a IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

359


1Exousi de\ ta_ zw|~a kai\ ta_ mege/qh diafe/ronta tou~ sto&matoj. Tw~n me\n ga&r e0sti<br />

ta_ sto&mata a)nerrwgo&ta, w3sper kuno_j kai\ le/ontoj kai\ pa&ntwn tw~n<br />

karxarodo&ntwn.<br />

<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> vary <strong>in</strong> the sizes <strong>of</strong> their mouths. Some have mouths which open wide (e.g., the<br />

dog, the lion, <strong>and</strong> all the saw-toothed animals.<br />

58<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 507b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

a)lla_ ta_ me\n e1xei mei/zw th_n koili/an, w3sper u{j kai\ a1rktoj (kai\ h3 ge th~j u(o_j<br />

o)li/gaj e1xei lei/aj pla&kaj), ta_ de\ polu_ e0la&ttw kai\ ou) pollw|~ mei/zw tou~ e0nte/rou,<br />

kaqa&per le/wn kai\ ku&wn kai\ a1nqrwpoj.<br />

Some [animals] have a comparatively large stomach (e.g., the pig <strong>and</strong> the bear; the pig’s<br />

stomach has a few smooth folds <strong>in</strong> it); some have a much smaller one, not much larger<br />

than the gut, e.g., the dog, the lion, <strong>and</strong> the man.<br />

59<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 517a-517b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

tw~n d' e0xo&ntwn ta_ me/n e0st<strong>in</strong> eu)quw&nuxa, w3sper a1nqrwpoj, ta_ de\ gamyw&nuxa,<br />

w3sper kai\ tw~n pezw~n le/wn kai\ tw~n pthnw~n a)eto&j.<br />

Of the animals that possess nails, then, some have straight ones (e.g., man), others<br />

crooked or curved ones (an example from walk<strong>in</strong>g animals is the lion, from fly<strong>in</strong>g ones,<br />

the eagle.<br />

60<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 522b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1965).<br />

e0n Fa&sei me/n e0sti boi5dia mikra_ w{n e3kaston bda&lletai ga&la polu&, ai9 d'<br />

0Hpeirwtikai\ bo&ej ai9 mega&lai bda&llontai e9ka&sth a)mfore/a kai\ tou&tou to_ h3misu<br />

kata_ tou_j du&o mastou&j: o( de\ bda&llwn o)rqo_j e3sthken, mikro_n e0piku&ptwn, dia_ to_<br />

mh_ du&nasqai a2n e0fiknei=sqai kaqh&menoj. Gi/netai d' e1cw o1nou kai\ ta}lla mega&la e0n<br />

th|~ 0Hpei/rw| tetra&poda, me/gistoi d' oi9 bo&ej kai\ oi9 ku&nej.<br />

360


In Phasis there is a breed <strong>of</strong> small cattle every one <strong>of</strong> which yields a copious supply <strong>of</strong><br />

milk. In Epeirus there are large cows which yield an amphoreus <strong>and</strong> half <strong>of</strong> this from the<br />

two teats. <strong>The</strong> milker has to st<strong>and</strong> upright, bend<strong>in</strong>g slightly forward, because he would<br />

not be able to reach far enough if seated. In addition to the cattle, all the quadrupeds<br />

(except the ass) <strong>in</strong> Epeirus are large <strong>in</strong> size, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> proportion the cattle <strong>and</strong> the dogs are<br />

the largest.<br />

61<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 542a IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium II (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1970).<br />

a1nqrwpoj de\ ma&lista pa~san w3ran, kai\ tw~n sunanqrwpeuome/nwn zw|&wn polla_<br />

dia_ th_n a)le/an kai\ eu)tr<strong>of</strong>i/an, o3swn kai\ ai9 kuh&seij o)ligoxro&nioi/ ei0s<strong>in</strong>, oi[on u(o_j<br />

kai\ kuno&j, kai\ tw~n pthnw~n o3sa pleona&kij poiou~ntai tou_j to&kouj.<br />

Human be<strong>in</strong>gs pair <strong>and</strong> breed at any <strong>and</strong> every season, <strong>and</strong> so also do many domesticated<br />

animals ow<strong>in</strong>g to the shelter <strong>and</strong> the plentiful food they get by their association with man:<br />

I refer to those whose gestation periods are short, such as the sow <strong>and</strong> the bitch, <strong>and</strong> those<br />

birds which raise several broods.<br />

62<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 579b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium II (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1970).<br />

spa&nion ga_r to_ ge/noj to_ tw~n leo&ntwn e0sti\ kai\ ou)k e0n pollw|~ gi/netai to&pw|,<br />

a)lla_ th~j Eu)rw&phj a(pa&shj e0n tw|~ metacu_ tou~ 0Axelw|&ou kai\ tou~ Ne/ssou<br />

potamou~.<br />

It is a fact that the lion is a scarce animal, <strong>and</strong> is not found <strong>in</strong> many places—<br />

<strong>in</strong> the whole <strong>of</strong> Europe it occurs only <strong>in</strong> the tract <strong>of</strong> country between the rivers<br />

Acheloös <strong>and</strong> Nessos.<br />

63<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 594b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

9O de\ le/wn sark<strong>of</strong>a&gon me/n e0st<strong>in</strong>, w3sper kai\ ta}lla o3sa a1gria kai\<br />

karxaro&donta, th|~ de\ brw&sei xrh~tai la&brwj, kai\ katapi/nei polla_ o3la ou)<br />

diairw~n, ei]q' h(me/raj du&o h2 trei=j a)sitei=: du&natai ga_r dia_ to_ u(perplhrou~sqai.<br />

0Oligo&poton d' e0sti/n. To_ de\ peri/ttwma proi5etai spani/wj: dia_ tri/thj ga_r h2<br />

o3pwj a2n tu&xh| proxwrei=, kai\ tou~to sklhro_n kai\ e0cikmasme/non, o3moion kuni/.<br />

361


Proi5etai de\ kai\ th_n fu~san sfo&dra drimei=an kai\ to_ ou}ron e1xon o)smh&n, dio_ w3sper<br />

oi9 ku&nej o)sfrai/netai tw~n de/ndrwn: ou)rei= ga_r ai1rwn to_ ske/loj w3sper oi9 ku&nej.<br />

<strong>The</strong> lion is a carnivore like all others that are wild <strong>and</strong> saw-toothed. Its manner <strong>of</strong><br />

devour<strong>in</strong>g is violent, <strong>and</strong> it swallows much <strong>of</strong> its food without divid<strong>in</strong>g it up, <strong>and</strong> then<br />

goes without food for two or three days: it can do this because it is over-full. It does not<br />

dr<strong>in</strong>k much. It discharges excrement sparsely: it is voided every other day or at r<strong>and</strong>om<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervals, <strong>and</strong> is dry <strong>and</strong> desiccated like a dog’s. Also the w<strong>in</strong>d that it discharges is very<br />

pungent <strong>and</strong> its ur<strong>in</strong>e has a smell; hence the dogs sniff at the trees, for it ur<strong>in</strong>ates lift<strong>in</strong>g<br />

its leg like dogs.<br />

64<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 606b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

1Eti de\ le/ontej me\n e0n th|~ Eu)rw&ph ma~llon, kai\ th~j 0Eurw&phj e0n tw|~ metacu_ to&pw|<br />

tou~ 0Axelw|&ou kai\ Ne/ssou potamou~ mo&non:<br />

Whereas lions occur more <strong>in</strong> Europe (only <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>in</strong> that region <strong>of</strong> Europe that lies<br />

between the Achelous <strong>and</strong> Nessus), leopards on the other h<strong>and</strong> occur <strong>in</strong> Asia <strong>and</strong> not <strong>in</strong><br />

Europe.<br />

65<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 607a IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

gi/netai de\ kai\ a1lla e0k mi/cewj mh_ o(m<strong>of</strong>u&lwn, w3sper kai\ e0n Kurh&nh|<br />

oi9 lu&koi mi/sgontai tai=j kusi\ kai\ gennw~si, kai\ e0c a)lw&pekoj kai\ kuno_j oi9<br />

Lakwnikoi/. Fasi\ de\ kai\ e0k tou~ ti/grioj kai\ kuno_j gi/nesqai tou_j 0Indikou&j, ou)k<br />

eu)qu_j d' a)ll' e0pi\ th~j tri/thj mi/cewj: to_ ga_r prw~ton gennhqe\n qhriw~dej gi/nesqai/<br />

fas<strong>in</strong>. 1Agontej de\ desmeu&ous<strong>in</strong> ei0j ta_j e0rhmi/aj ta_j ku&naj: kai\ pollai\<br />

katesqi/ontai, e0a_n mh_ tu&xh| o)rgw~n pro_j th_n o)xei/an to_ qhri/on.<br />

Other animals too are produced from the mix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> different breeds, as <strong>in</strong> Cyrene the<br />

wolves mate with the dogs <strong>and</strong> generate young, <strong>and</strong> from fox <strong>and</strong> dog come the Laconian<br />

hounds. <strong>The</strong>y say too that the Indian hounds come from tiger <strong>and</strong> dog, not immediately,<br />

but after the third mat<strong>in</strong>g; for they say the first <strong>of</strong>fspr<strong>in</strong>g is like a savage beast. <strong>The</strong>y take<br />

the bitches to deserted places <strong>and</strong> tie them up; <strong>and</strong> many are devoured, if the wild animal<br />

does not happen to be excited for mat<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

66<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 608a IV B.C.<br />

362


Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

To_ d' e0n th|~ Molotti/a| ge/noj tw~n kunw~n to_ me\n qhreutiko_n ou)de\n diafe/rei pro_j to_<br />

para_ toi=j a1lloij, to_ d' a)ko&louqon toi=j proba&toij tw|~ mege/qei kai\ th|~<br />

a)ndrei/a| th|~ pro_j ta_ qhri/a.<br />

<strong>The</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> hounds <strong>in</strong> Molossia is no different from those elsewhere <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong><br />

hunt<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>in</strong> shepherd<strong>in</strong>g it is superior by reason <strong>of</strong> size <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> courage <strong>in</strong> fac<strong>in</strong>g wild<br />

animals.<br />

67<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 629b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

0En de\ tai=j qh&raij o(rw&menoj me\n ou)de/pote feu&gei ou)de\ pth&ssei, a)ll' e0a_n kai\ dia_<br />

plh~qoj a)nagkasqh|~ tw~n qhreuo&ntwn u(pagagei=n ba&dhn u(poxwrei= kai\ kata_<br />

ske/loj, kata_ braxu_ e0pistrefo&menoj: e0a_n me/ntoi e0pila&bhtai dase/oj,<br />

feu&gei taxe/wj, e3wj a2n katasth|~ ei0j fanero&n: to&te de\ pa&l<strong>in</strong> u(pa&gei ba&dhn.<br />

0En de\ toi=j yiloi=j e0a&n pot' a)nagkasqh|~ ei0j fanero_n dia_ to_ plh~qoj feu&ge<strong>in</strong>,<br />

tre/xei katatei/naj kai\ ou) phda|~. To_ de\ dro&mhma sunexw~j w3sper kuno&j e0sti<br />

katatetame/non: diw&kwn me/ntoi e0pirri/ptei e9auto&n, o3tan h|} plhsi/on.<br />

When it [lion] is be<strong>in</strong>g hunted, even if it is <strong>in</strong> view it never runs away nor takes cover, but<br />

if it is compelled to withdraw because <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> hunters it retreats at a walk, step<br />

by step, <strong>and</strong> turn<strong>in</strong>g its head at short <strong>in</strong>tervals; nevertheless if it reaches thick cover it<br />

runs away fast until it has come <strong>in</strong>to full view; then <strong>in</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> withdraws at a walk. In<br />

open country if it has been forced by the crowd to run away <strong>in</strong>to full view, it runs<br />

extended <strong>and</strong> does not leap. <strong>The</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g gait is cont<strong>in</strong>uously extended like a hound’s;<br />

when it is pursu<strong>in</strong>g, however, it hurls itself on the prey when it is near.<br />

68<br />

Aristotle, Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium 630a IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: D. M. Balme, ed., tr., Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1991).<br />

Feu&gousi d' e0ni/ote katatei/nantej th_n ke/rkon w3sper ku&nej. 1Hdh d' w}ptai le/wn<br />

kai\ u(i6 e0piti/qesqai me/llwn, kai\ w(j ei]den a)ntifri/canta, feu&gwn. 1Esti de\ pro_j<br />

ta_j plhga_j ei0j me\n ta_ koi=la a)sqenh&j, kata_ de\ to_ a1llo sw~ma de/xetai polla_j kai\<br />

kefalh_n e1xei i0sxura&n. 3Osa d' a2n da&kh| h2 toi=j o1nuc<strong>in</strong> e9lkw&sh|, e0k tw~n e9lkw~n<br />

i0xw~rej r(e/ous<strong>in</strong> w)xroi\ sfo&dra kai\ e0k tw~n e0pide/smwn kai\ spo&ggwn u(p' ou)deno_j<br />

duna&menoi e0kklu&zesqai: h( de\ qerapei/a h( au)th_ kai\ tw~n kunodh&ktwn e9lkw~n.<br />

363


Sometimes they [lions] run away stretch<strong>in</strong>g the tail straight out like hounds. A lion has<br />

been seen before now to attack a pig, <strong>and</strong> runn<strong>in</strong>g away when it saw it bristl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

defence. Agianst blows to the flanks it is weak, but it can take many over the rest <strong>of</strong> its<br />

body <strong>and</strong> its head is strong. Whatever it has bitten or wounded with its claws, the<br />

wounds run with ichors which are deep yellow <strong>and</strong> cannot be washed out <strong>of</strong> the b<strong>and</strong>ages<br />

<strong>and</strong> sponges. <strong>The</strong> treatment is the same as for wounds caused by dogbite.<br />

69<br />

Aristotle, Magna Moralia 1208b IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. C. Armstrong, ed., tr., Aristotle. <strong>The</strong> Oeconomica <strong>and</strong> Magna<br />

Moralia (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1935).<br />

fasi\n de\ kai\ kuno&j pote a)ei\ kaqeudou&shj e0pi\ th~j au)th~j kerami=doj,<br />

e0rwthqe/nta to_n 0Empedokle/a, dia_ ti/ pote h( ku&wn e0pi\ th~j au)th~j kerami=doj<br />

kaqeu&dei,ei0pei=n o3ti e1xei ti th|~ kerami=di o3moion h( ku&wn, w(j dia_ to_ o3moion th_n ku&na<br />

foitw~san.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is also a story <strong>of</strong> a dog that always would sleep upon the same tile; <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> how<br />

Empedocles, when asked why it did so, declared that there was some aff<strong>in</strong>ity between the<br />

dog <strong>and</strong> the tile which caused the former always to seek the latter.<br />

70<br />

Arrian, Cynegeticus 8.1-8.2 A.D. II<br />

Text: A.G. Roos <strong>and</strong> G. Wirth, eds., Flavii Arriani quae Exstant Omnia II. Scripta<br />

M<strong>in</strong>ora et Fragmenta (first corr. ed.; Leipzig, 1968).<br />

Translation: D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1964).<br />

e0sqi/ous<strong>in</strong> de\ ai4 me\n la&brwj ai4 de\ kosmi/wj, kai\ to_ ko&smion gennaio&teron tou~<br />

a)ko&smou. a)gaqai\ de\ o3sai mh_ kako&sitoi, a)ll' a1rtw| h2 ma&zh| xai/rous<strong>in</strong>: kra&tiston<br />

ga_r kuni\ tou~to siti/on, kai\ ou) de/oj mh_ u(peremplhsqei/h a)p' au)tou~. a1me<strong>in</strong>on de\ ei0<br />

kai\ chra|~ th|~ tr<strong>of</strong>h|~ xai/roien. ei0 de\ kai\ u3dati katabre/xoij kai\ tou&tw| xai/roien, ou)<br />

kako&n.<br />

Enjoy wheat bread or barley bread, for this food is best for a hound <strong>and</strong> there is no fear<br />

lest they be filled too full <strong>of</strong> it. <strong>The</strong>n it is better if they like their food dry, but even if you<br />

soak it <strong>in</strong> water <strong>and</strong> they like it, it is not bad.<br />

71<br />

Arrian, Cynegeticus 9.1-9.2 A.D. II<br />

Text: A.G. Roos <strong>and</strong> G. Wirth, eds., Flavii Arriani quae Exstant Omnia II. Scripta<br />

M<strong>in</strong>ora et Fragmenta (first corr. ed.; Leipzig, 1968).<br />

Translation: D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1964).<br />

364


ou)de\n de\ oi[on eu)nh_ malqakh_ kai\ a)llee<strong>in</strong>h&. krati/sth de\ h( met' a)nqrw&pou, o3ti kai\<br />

fila&nqrwpoi a)potelou~ntai, kai\ tw|~ xrwti\ tw|~ a)nqrwpi/nw| xai/rous<strong>in</strong>, kai\<br />

filou~s<strong>in</strong> ou) mei=on to_n sugkaqeu&donta h2 to_n tre/fonta. ka2n tw~n lupou&ntwn th_n<br />

ku&na tij ai0sqa&noito, w(j diyw&sh| te e0n nukti\ e0pikourh~sai kai\ e0peigome/nh| u(po& tou<br />

tw~n a)nagkai/wn: gnoi/h d' a2n kai\ o3pwj a)nepau&sato. ei0 ga_r a)grupnh&seien,<br />

e0ca&ge<strong>in</strong> e0pi\ qh&ran ou)k a)sfale/j, ou)d' ei0 e0pista&ceien qam<strong>in</strong>a_ e0n tw|~ u3pnw|, ou)d' ei1 ti<br />

a)peme/seien tw~n siti/wn: tau~ta de\ gnoi/h a2n o( sunanapauo&menoj.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g like a good warm bed. <strong>The</strong> best is that with a human be<strong>in</strong>g, because<br />

hounds are made fond <strong>of</strong> people this way, <strong>and</strong> they rejoice <strong>in</strong> human sk<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> love the<br />

person they sleep with no less tham the one who feeds them. And you should notice<br />

which <strong>of</strong> the hounds was unhappy, so as to provide for one which was thirsty <strong>in</strong> the night<br />

<strong>and</strong> for one urged on by necessities, <strong>and</strong> you would know also how it rested. For if it<br />

were wakeful or <strong>of</strong> it dripped frequently <strong>in</strong> its sleep or threw up some <strong>of</strong> its food, tak<strong>in</strong>g it<br />

on a hunt would not be safe. <strong>The</strong> man sleep<strong>in</strong>g with it would know these th<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

72<br />

Athenaeus 4.161b-4.161c A.D. II-III<br />

(=Alexis, fr. 220, 221 Kock [Men <strong>of</strong> Tarentum])<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, ed., Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, I (Leipzig, 1887;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1961).<br />

Translation: C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists II (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1928; repr. 1957).<br />

a. oi9 puqagori/zontej ga&r, w(j a)kou&omen, ou1t' o1yon e0sqi/ous<strong>in</strong> ou1t' a1ll' ou)de\ e4n<br />

e1myuxon, oi]no&n t' ou)xi\ pi/nous<strong>in</strong> mo&noi. b. 0Epixari/dhj me/ntoi ku&naj katesqi/ei,<br />

tw~n Puqagorei/wn ei[j. a. a)poktei/naj ge/ pou: ou)k e1ti ga&r e0st' e1myuxon.<br />

A. “<strong>The</strong> devotees <strong>of</strong> Pythagoras, we hear, eat neither fish not anyth<strong>in</strong>g else that has life,<br />

<strong>and</strong> they are the only one who dr<strong>in</strong>k no w<strong>in</strong>e.” B. “Yes, but Epicharides devours dogs,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he is a Pythagorean.” A. “Of course, after he has killed one, for then it no longer has<br />

life!”<br />

73<br />

Athenaeus 7.299f A.D. II-III<br />

(=Anax<strong>and</strong>rides fr. 39 Kock (Cities))<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, ed., Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, II (Leipzig, 1887;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1965).<br />

Translation: C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1929).<br />

ou)k a2n dunai/mhn summaxei=n u(mi=n e0gw&:<br />

ou1q' oi9 tro&poi ga_r o(monoou~s' ou1q' oi9 no&moi<br />

h(mw~n, a)p' a)llh&lwn de\ die/xous<strong>in</strong> polu&.<br />

365


ou~n proskunei=j, e0gw_ de\ qu&w toi=j qeoi=j:<br />

th_n e1gxelun me/giston h(gei= dai/mona,<br />

h(mei=j de\ tw~n o1ywn me/giston para_ polu&.<br />

ou)k e0sqi/eij u3ei', e0gw_ de/ g' h3domai<br />

ma&lista tou&toij: ku&na se/beij, tu&ptw d' e0gw&,<br />

tou1yon katesqi/ousan h(ni/k' a2n la&bw.<br />

I couldn’t br<strong>in</strong>g myself to be an ally <strong>of</strong> yours,<br />

for neither our manners not our customs agree, but<br />

st<strong>and</strong> a long distance apart from each other.<br />

You worship the cow, but I sacrifice it to the gods.<br />

You hold the eel to be mighty div<strong>in</strong>ity, we hold it<br />

by far the mightiest <strong>of</strong> da<strong>in</strong>ties.<br />

You eat no pork, but I like it very much.<br />

You worship the bitch, I beat her when I catch her eat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

up my best food.<br />

74<br />

Athenaeus 7.308c-7.308d A.D. II-III<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, ed., Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, II (Leipzig, 1887;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1965).<br />

Translation: C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1929).<br />

le/cw de\ kai\ mh_ problhqe/ntoj dia_ ti/ oi9 Puqagorikoi\ tw~n me\n a1llwn e0myu&xwn<br />

metri/wj a3ptontai, t<strong>in</strong>a_ de\ kai\ qu&ontej, i0xqu&wn mo&nwn ou) geu&ontai to_<br />

para&pan…. h2 dia_ th_n e0xemuqi/an; qei=on ga_r h(gou~ntai th_n siwph&n. e0pei\ ou}n kai\<br />

u(mei=j, w} Molottikoi\ ku&nej, pa&nta me\n siwpa~te, puqagori/zete de\ ou1, h(mei=j me\n<br />

a1llouj i0xquologh&somen.<br />

I will also expla<strong>in</strong>, even if the question has not been asked, why the Pythagoreans, who<br />

eat moderately <strong>of</strong> other live animals, some <strong>of</strong> which they even sacrifice, nevertheless<br />

utterly refuse to touch fish alone. Is it because <strong>of</strong> their silence? <strong>The</strong>y regard silence, <strong>in</strong><br />

fact, as div<strong>in</strong>e. S<strong>in</strong>ce then you also, Molossian hounds, are altogether silent though you<br />

are no Pythagoreans, we will proceed to the discussion <strong>of</strong> other fish.<br />

75<br />

Athenaeus 9.409d A.D. II-III<br />

(=Polemon fr. 77 Preller [Epistle Concern<strong>in</strong>g Obscure Words])<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, ed., Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, II (Leipzig, 1887;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1965).<br />

Translation: C. G. Gulick, tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists IV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1930; repr. 1957).<br />

366


e1ti de\ kai\ eu)w&desi ta_j xei=raj katexri/onto ta_j a)pomagdali/aj a)tima&santej, a4j<br />

Lakedaimo&nioi e0ka&loun kuna&daj, w3j fhsi Pole/mwn e0n th|~ peri\ o)noma&twn a)do&cwn<br />

e0pistolh|~.<br />

Further, they used to smear their h<strong>and</strong>s with perfumes, spurn<strong>in</strong>g the crumbs <strong>of</strong> bread<br />

which Spartans call “dog-bits,” as Polemon avers <strong>in</strong> his Epistle concern<strong>in</strong>g Obscure<br />

Words.<br />

76<br />

Athenaeus 12.540c-12.540d A.D. II-III<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, III (Leipzig, 1890;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1962).<br />

Translation: C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists V (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1933; repr. 1963).<br />

Klu&toj d' o( 0Aristoteliko_j e0n toi=j peri\ Milh&tou POLUKRATHN fhsi\ to_n<br />

Sami/wn tu&rannon u(po_ trufh~j ta_ pantaxo&qen suna&ge<strong>in</strong>, ku&naj<br />

me\n e0c 0Hpei/rou, ai]gaj de\ e0k Sku&rou, e0k de\ Milh&tou pro&bata, u{j d' e0k Sikeli/aj.<br />

1Alecij d' e0n tri/tw| Sami/wn 3Wrwn e0k pollw~n po&lew&n fhs<strong>in</strong> kosmhqh~nai<br />

th_n Sa&mon u(po_ tou~ Polukra&touj, ku&naj me\n Molottika_j kai\ Lakai/naj<br />

ei0sagago&ntoj, ai]gaj d' e0k Sku&rou kai\ Na&cou, pro&bata d' e0k Milh&tou kai\ th~j<br />

0Attikh~j.<br />

Clytus the Aristotelian, <strong>in</strong> his work On Miletus, says <strong>of</strong> Polycrates the tyrant <strong>of</strong> Samos<br />

that his <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct for luxury moved him to get together the special products <strong>of</strong> every<br />

country—hounds from Epeirus, goats from Scyros, sheep from Miletus, <strong>and</strong> sw<strong>in</strong>e from<br />

Sicily. Alexis, too, <strong>in</strong> the third book <strong>of</strong> Samian Chronicles says that Samos was enriched<br />

by Polycrates with the products <strong>of</strong> many cities: he imported Molossian <strong>and</strong> Laconian<br />

hounds, goats from Scyros <strong>and</strong> Naxos, <strong>and</strong> sheep from Miletus <strong>and</strong> Attica.<br />

77<br />

Athenaeus 13.606a-13.606b A.D. II-III<br />

(= Philemon fr. 139 Kock)<br />

Text: G. Kaibel, ed., Athenaei Naucratitae Dipnosophistarum libri XV, III (Leipzig,<br />

1890; repr. Stuttgart, 1962).<br />

Translation: C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists VI (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1937).<br />

u{toj ga_r tou~ e0n Sa&mw| Pari/ou a)ga&lmatoj e0rasqei\j kate/kleisen<br />

au(to_n e0n tw|~ naw|~, w(j plhsia&sai dunhso&menoj: kai\ w(j h)duna&tei dia& te th_n<br />

yuxro&thta kai\ to_ a)nti/tupon tou~ li/qou, thnikau~ta th~j e0piqumi/aj a)pe/sth kai\<br />

proballo&menoj to_ sarki/on e0plhsi/asen. th~j pra&cewj tau&thj mnhmoneu&ei kai\<br />

1Alecij o( poihth_j e0n tw|~ e0pigrafome/nw| dra&mati Grafh|~ le/gwn w{de:<br />

gege/nhtai d', w(j le/gous<strong>in</strong>, ka)n Sa&mw| toiou~q' e3teron. liqi/nhj e0pequ&mhsen ko&rhj<br />

a1nqrwpoj e0gkate/kleise/ q' au(to_n tw|~ new|~.<br />

367


kai\ Filh&mwn tou~ au)tou~ mnhmoneu&wn fhsi/n:<br />

a)ll' e0n Sa&mw| me\n tou~ liqi/nou zw|&ou pote\ a1nqrwpoj h)ra&sqh tij: ei]t' ei0j to_n<br />

new_n kate/kleisen au(to&n.<br />

Kthsikle/ouj d' e0sti\n e1rgon to_ a1galma, w3j fhs<strong>in</strong> 0Adai=oj o( Mitulhnai=oj e0n tw|~<br />

peri\ 0Agalmatopoiw~n.<br />

For he [Cleisophus <strong>of</strong> Selymbria], becom<strong>in</strong>g enamored <strong>of</strong> the statue <strong>in</strong> Parian marble at<br />

Samos, locked himself up <strong>in</strong> the temple, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g he should be able to have <strong>in</strong>tercourse<br />

with it; <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ce he found that impossible on account <strong>of</strong> the frigidity <strong>and</strong> resistance <strong>of</strong><br />

the stone, he then <strong>and</strong> there desisted from that desire <strong>and</strong> plac<strong>in</strong>g before him a small piece<br />

<strong>of</strong> flesh he consorted with that. This deed is mentioned by the poet Alexis <strong>in</strong> the play<br />

entitled A Picture : “Another case <strong>of</strong> a like sort occurred, they say, <strong>in</strong> Samos. A man<br />

conceived a passion for a stone maiden, <strong>and</strong> locked himself up <strong>in</strong> the temple.” And<br />

Philemon, mention<strong>in</strong>g the same, says: “Why, once on a time, <strong>in</strong> Samos, a certa<strong>in</strong> man fell<br />

<strong>in</strong> love with the stone zw|&ou (image); thereupon he locked himself <strong>in</strong> the temple.” Now<br />

the statue is the work <strong>of</strong> Ctesicles, as Adaeus <strong>of</strong> Mytilene says <strong>in</strong> his work On<br />

Sculptors[ 1Agalma-Makers].<br />

78<br />

Collumella, De Re Rustica 7.12.10 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. S. Foster amd E. H. Heffner, eds., trs., Lucius Junius Moderatus<br />

Columella. On Agriculture. Books V-IX (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1954;<br />

repr. 1997).<br />

Cibaria fere eadem sunt utrique generi praebenda. Nam si tam laxa rura sunt, ut<br />

sust<strong>in</strong>eant pecorum greges, omnes s<strong>in</strong>e discrim<strong>in</strong>e canes hordeacea far<strong>in</strong>a cum sero<br />

commode pascit. S<strong>in</strong> autem surculo consitus ager s<strong>in</strong>e pascuo est, farreo vel triticeo pane<br />

sati<strong>and</strong>i sunt, admixto tamen liquore coctae fabae, sed tepido: nam fervens rabiem creat.<br />

Practically the same food should be given to both types <strong>of</strong> dog. If the farm is extensive<br />

enough to support herds <strong>of</strong> cattle, barley-flour with whey is a suitable food for all dogs<br />

without dist<strong>in</strong>ction; but if the l<strong>and</strong> is closely planted with young shoots <strong>and</strong> affords no<br />

pasture, they must be given their fill <strong>of</strong> bread made with flour <strong>of</strong> emmer or bread-wheat,<br />

mixed, however, with the liquid <strong>of</strong> boiled beans, which must be lukewarm, for, if it is<br />

boil<strong>in</strong>g, it causes madness.<br />

79<br />

Demetrias, <strong>The</strong>ssaly V B.C.<br />

Square marble base for a Sph<strong>in</strong>x<br />

Text: SEG <strong>The</strong>ssaly 23:453. Friedländer <strong>and</strong> H<strong>of</strong>fleit 1948, 139A.<br />

Translation: P. Friedländer <strong>and</strong> H. B. H<strong>of</strong>fleit, Epigrammata: Greek Inscriptions <strong>in</strong> Verse<br />

from the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs to the Persian Wars (Berkeley, 1948).<br />

Sfίξ, ίdao [k]ύoν, τ̣ί̣ν’ [χouσa . . .]opιd[. . fu]lάσ(σ)εις<br />

368


μέν[a έν f]ρo[uρ ί k ]do[ς p]<strong>of</strong>qιμ[ένou];<br />

Ξε[ινokρ tεoς tόdε σ a . . .]<br />

A: O Sph<strong>in</strong>x, dog <strong>of</strong> Hades, whom do you…watch over,<br />

sitt<strong>in</strong>g [on guard over] the dead?<br />

B: Xe[nocrates’ tomb this is…]<br />

80<br />

Demetrius <strong>of</strong> Bithynia, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.730 II B.C. (?)<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

1Hn m' e0si/dh| mo&sxoj, mukh&setai: h2n de/ ge tau~roj,<br />

bh&setai: h2n de\ nomeu&j, ei0j a)ge/lan e0la&sei.<br />

If a calf sees me, it will low; a bull will mount<br />

me, <strong>and</strong> the herdsman drive me to the herd.<br />

81<br />

Diogenes Laertius 4.20 A.D. III<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: R. D. Hicks, ed., tr., Diogenes Laertius. Lives <strong>of</strong> Em<strong>in</strong>ent<br />

Philosophers I (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1925).<br />

h}n de\ kai\ filos<strong>of</strong>oklh~j, kai\ ma&lista e0n e0kei/noij o3pou kata_ to_n<br />

kwmiko_n ta_ poih&mata au)tw|~<br />

ku&wn tij e0do&kei sumpoiei=n Molottiko&j.<br />

He loved Sophocles, particularly <strong>in</strong> those passages where it seemed as if, <strong>in</strong> the phrase <strong>of</strong><br />

the comic poet,<br />

A stout Molossian mastiff lent him aid.<br />

82<br />

Diogenes Laertius 6.55 A.D. III<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: R. D. Hicks, ed., tr., Diogenes Laertius. Lives <strong>of</strong> Em<strong>in</strong>ent<br />

Philosophers II (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1925) 57.<br />

e0rwthqei\j potapo_j ei1h ku&wn, e1fh, pe<strong>in</strong>w~n Melitai=oj, xortasqei\j de\<br />

Molottiko&j, tou&twn ou4j e0pa<strong>in</strong>ou~ntej oi9 polloi\ ou) tolmw~si dia_ to_n po&non<br />

sunecie/nai au)toi=j e0pi\ th_n qh&ran:<br />

369


Be<strong>in</strong>g asked what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> hound he was, he replied, “When hungry, a Maltese; when full,<br />

a Molossian—two breeds which most people praise, though for fear <strong>of</strong> fatigue they do<br />

not venture out hunt<strong>in</strong>g with them.”<br />

83<br />

Dioscorides, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.734 III B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Tau~re, ma&thn e0pi\ mo&sxon e0pei/geai: e1sti ga_r a1pnouj:<br />

a)lla& s' o( boupla&staj e0capa&thse Mu&rwn.<br />

In va<strong>in</strong>, bull, thou rushest up to this heifer, for it<br />

is lifeless. <strong>The</strong> sculptor <strong>of</strong> cows, Myron, deceived thee.<br />

84<br />

Diphylus, fr. 91 Kock IV/III B.C.<br />

Text: T. Kock, Comicorum Atticorum Fragmenta II (Leipzig, 1884).<br />

Translation: J. M. Edmonds, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Fragments <strong>of</strong> Attic Comedy III A (Leiden,<br />

1961).<br />

h4n ou)d' o( path_r e0fi/lhsen ou)depw&pote,<br />

par' h{j to_n a1rton h( ku&wn ou) lamba&nei,<br />

me/la<strong>in</strong>a d' ou3twj w3ste kai\ poiei=n sko&toj.<br />

This young miss is one <strong>of</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>d even father never kisses<br />

And house-dog won’t take crusts from,<br />

So dark she makes day night.<br />

Empedocles, fr. DK128 V B.C.<br />

See Porphyry, De Abst<strong>in</strong>entia 2.20-2.21 [166].<br />

(= <strong>The</strong>ophrastus, fr. 12 Pötscher, [155 Nauck 2 ]<br />

85<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 474 (fr. II, col. I, 40-43)<br />

Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 289.<br />

το̑ δὲ λοιπο̑ ἔργο ℎάπαντος<br />

ἐγ κύκλοι ἄρχει ℎο Ἐλευσινιακὸς<br />

370


λίθος πρὸς ℎο̑ι τὰ ζο̑ια, καὶ ἐτέθε<br />

ἐπὶ το̑ν ἐπιστατο̑ν τούτον.<br />

All the rest <strong>of</strong> the work round about beg<strong>in</strong>s<br />

with the Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone aga<strong>in</strong>st which the<br />

zw~ia (are to be fastened), <strong>and</strong> three blocks <strong>of</strong> it<br />

have been placed under the present commissioners.<br />

86<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 475 (fr. VIII A)<br />

Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 327.<br />

[— — — λιθοργικο̑· θέσεος καὶ ἐπερ-]<br />

[γασίας το̑ Ἐλευσινιακο̑ λίθο πρὸς ℎο̑ι]<br />

[τὰ ζο̑ια καὶ ἀντιθεμάτον·]<br />

[- - - Stone-work. Payments for the sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> place <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Dress<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the top surface <strong>of</strong> the blocks <strong>of</strong> Eleus<strong>in</strong>ian stone<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st which ta& zw~ia (are to be placed) <strong>and</strong> their back<strong>in</strong>g stones.<br />

87<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 476 (fr. XVI, col I, 150-157)<br />

Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 389.<br />

[..]ς τ[ὸγ γρ]άφοντα νεα[νίσ]κον<br />

καὶ τ[ὸμ πρ]ο[σ]ε[στ]ο̑τα ℎαυτο̑ι : Η.<br />

[Μ]υνν[ίον] ἐν Κολλυτο̑ι ℎοικ[ο̑ν]<br />

[…]ο[.. κ]αὶ τὲν ἅμαχσαν πλ̣[ὲν]<br />

[τοῖν ἑμιόν]οιν . .ΔΔΔΔ. Ἀγ[α]θάν-<br />

155 [ορ Ἀλοπεκε̑σι] ℎοικο̑ν τὸ γυνα-<br />

[ῖκε τὸ πρὸς τε̑ι ἁμ]άχσει καὶ τ-<br />

[ὸ ℎεμιόνο ΗΗΔΔΔΔ..6…]ν ἐκ<br />

- - the youth who is writ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>and</strong> the man st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g beside him, 120 dr.<br />

- -, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Kollytos<br />

- - <strong>and</strong> the wagon without<br />

371


the two mules, 90 dr.<br />

Agathanor, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Alopeke,<br />

the two women beside the wagon,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the two mules, 240 dr.<br />

88<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 476 (fr. XVII, col. I, 159-181)<br />

Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 389.<br />

ὸν τὸ δ]όρυ ℎέχοντα, . .Δ. Φυρόμα-<br />

160 [χος Κ]εφισιεύς, τὸν νεανίσκο-<br />

[ν τὸ]ν παρὰ τὸν θόρακα, . .Δ. Πραχ-<br />

[σίας] ἐμ Μελίτει ℎοικο̑ν, τὸν ℎ-<br />

[ίππο]ν καὶ τὸν ℎοπισθοφανε̑ τ-<br />

[ὸν πα]ρακρόοντα, ΗΔΔ. Ἀντιφάν-<br />

165 [ες ℎεκ] Κεραμέον, τὸ ἅρμα καὶ τ-<br />

[ὸν νε]ανίσκον καὶ τὸ ℎίππο τὸ<br />

[ζευγ]νυμένο, ΗΗΔΔΔΔ. Φυρόμαχ-<br />

[ος Κε]φισιεύς, τὸν ℎάγοντα τὸ-<br />

[ν ℎί]ππον, . .Δ: Μυννίον ℎαγρυλε̑-<br />

170 [σι] ℎοικο̑ν, τὸν ℎίππον καὶ τὸν<br />

[ℎά]νδρα τὸν ℎεπικρόοντα καὶ<br />

[τὲ]ν στέλεν ℎύστερον προσέθ-<br />

[εκ]ε :ΗΔΔ. . . . . . . Σο̑κλος ℎαλοπεκε̑-<br />

[σι] ℎοικο̑ν, τὸν τὸν χαλινὸν ℎέ-<br />

175 [χο]ντα, . .Δ: Φυρόμαχος Κεφισιε-<br />

[ύς], τὸν ℎάνδρα τὸν ℎεπὶ τε̑ς βα-<br />

[κτ]ερίας εἱστεκότα τὸν παρὰ<br />

[τὸ]ν βομὸν, . .Δ: ℎίασος Κολλυτε-<br />

[ύς], τὲγ γυναῖκα ἑ̑ι<br />

ἑ παῖς προσ-<br />

180 [πέ]πτοκε, . .ΔΔΔ v κεφάλαιον ℎα-<br />

[γα]λματοποϊκο̑, ΧΧΧΗΗΗΔ. .<br />

-- the man hold<strong>in</strong>g the spear, 60 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kephisia,<br />

the youth beside the breast-plate, 60 dr.<br />

Praxias, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Melite,<br />

372


the horse <strong>and</strong> the man appear<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d it 120 dr.<br />

<strong>and</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> the flank,<br />

Antiphanes <strong>of</strong> Kerameis,<br />

the chariot, <strong>and</strong> the youth,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the two horses be<strong>in</strong>g harnessed, 240 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kiphisia,<br />

the man lead<strong>in</strong>g the horse, 60 dr.<br />

Mynnion, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Argyle,<br />

the horse <strong>and</strong> the man strik<strong>in</strong>g it,<br />

<strong>and</strong> he later added the stele, 127 dr.<br />

Soklos, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Alopeke,<br />

the man hold<strong>in</strong>g the bridle, 60 dr.<br />

Phyromachos <strong>of</strong> Kephisia,<br />

the man lean<strong>in</strong>g on a staff<br />

beh<strong>in</strong>d the altar,<br />

Iasos <strong>of</strong> Kollytos, the woman with the<br />

little girl lean<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st her, 80 dr.<br />

sum total <strong>of</strong> payments for sculpture, 3315 dr.<br />

89<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 476 (fr. XIII, col II, 135-140)<br />

Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 387.<br />

Μαμμάνοι :. .: [. . . .10. . . . :. .: ℎίκ]-<br />

135 ρια καθελο̑[σι καὶ ἀποκομίσα]σι<br />

ℎαπὸ το̑ το[ίχο το̑ πρὸς βορέ]ο<br />

ℎαφ’ ὁ̑ν<br />

τὰ ζ[όιδια ἐτέθε, ℎέχς]<br />

ἀνδράσι, Π[ρέποντι :ΙΙΙ: Μέδοι :ΙΙΙ: Ἀ]πολλοδό[ροι<br />

:ΙΙΙ: . . . . .12. . . . .]<br />

140 αίοι :ΙΙΙ[. . . . . . .17. . . . . . . .]<br />

for tak<strong>in</strong>g down <strong>and</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g away the scaffold<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the north wall, from which<br />

the zw&idia were fastened <strong>in</strong> place,<br />

to six men; to Prepon, 3 ob.; to Medos, 3 ob.;<br />

to Apollodoros, 3 ob.; to - - -, 3 ob.;<br />

to - - -, 3 ob.; - - - - - -<br />

90<br />

Erechtheion, Acropolis, Athens V B.C.<br />

Text: IG I 3 . 476 (fr. XVII, col. II, 296-299)<br />

373


Translation: L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 397.<br />

μόλυβδος ℎεονέθε [δύ]ο<br />

ταλάντο ℎεις πρόσθεσι[ν το̑]ν<br />

ζοιδίον παρὰ Σοστράτ[ο ἐμ Μ]ελίτει<br />

ℎοικο̑ντος : Δ :<br />

two talents <strong>of</strong> lead were bought<br />

for the fasten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> zwidi/wn,<br />

from Sostratos, liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Melite. 10 dr.<br />

91<br />

Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.717 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

2H to_ de/raj xa&lkeion o3lon boi6 ta|~d' e0pi/keitai<br />

e1ktoqen, h2 yuxh_n e1ndon o( xalko_j e1xei.<br />

Either a complete hide <strong>of</strong> bronze clothes here a<br />

real cow, or the bronze has a soul <strong>in</strong>side it.<br />

92<br />

Euenos <strong>of</strong> Paros, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.718 V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Au)to_j e0rei= ta&xa tou~to Mu&rwn: Ou)k e1plasa tau&tan<br />

ta_n da&mal<strong>in</strong>, tau&taj d' ei0ko&n' a)neplasa&mhn.<br />

Perhaps Myron himself will say this: “I did not<br />

mould this heifer, but its image.”<br />

93<br />

Galen, De alimentorum facultatibus libri iii 664 A.D. II<br />

Text: G. Helmreich, Galeni de alimentorum facultatibus libri iii (Corpus medicorum<br />

Graecorum 5.4.2; Leipzig, 1923).<br />

Translation: M. Grant, tr., Galen on Food <strong>and</strong> Diet (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2000).<br />

peri\ de\ kunw~n ti/ dei= kai\ le/ge<strong>in</strong>, w(s tou_s ne/ous te kai\ liparou_s au)tw~n,<br />

kai\ ma&lisq' o3tan eu)nouxisqw~si, kat' e1nia tw~n e0qnw~n e0sqi/ousi pa&mpolloi.<br />

374


As for dogs, what can I say? In some countries they are <strong>of</strong>ten eaten when young <strong>and</strong><br />

plump, <strong>and</strong> particularly after they have been castrated.<br />

94<br />

Galen, De victu attenuante 8 A.D. II<br />

Text: K. Kalbfleisch, Galeni De victu attenuante (Corpus Medicorum Graecorum 5.4.2.<br />

Leipzig, 1923).<br />

Translation: M. Grant, ed., tr., Galen on Food <strong>and</strong> Diet (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2000).<br />

As for dogs <strong>and</strong> foxes—I have never tasted their meat, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not the custom to eat it<br />

either <strong>in</strong> Asia or <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, or <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>in</strong> Italy. But there are apparently many parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world where they are eaten, <strong>and</strong> my conjecture would be that their effects would be<br />

similar to those <strong>of</strong> the hare; for hare, dog, <strong>and</strong> fox are all equally dry.<br />

95<br />

Gem<strong>in</strong>us, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.740 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

9H ba&sij h( kate/xousa to_ boi/dion, h| { pepe/dhtai:<br />

h2n d' a)feqh|~ tau&thj, feu&cetai ei0j a)ge/lhn.<br />

muka~tai ga_r o( xalko&j: i1d', w(j e1mpnoun o( texni/taj<br />

qh&kato: ka2n zeu&ch|j a1llon, i1swj a)ro&sei.<br />

It is the base to which it is attached that keeps<br />

back the heifer, <strong>and</strong> if freed from it will run <strong>of</strong>f<br />

to the herd. For the bronze lows. See how much<br />

alive the artist made it. If you yoke a fellow to it,<br />

perhaps it will plough.<br />

96<br />

Herodas, Mime 4, 56-78 III B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. Rusten, I. C. Cunn<strong>in</strong>gham <strong>and</strong> A. D. Knox, <strong>The</strong>ophrastus:<br />

Characters. Herodas. Mimes. Cercias <strong>and</strong> the Choliambic Poets (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1993).<br />

[FI.] ou)k o)rh~ij, fi/lh Kunnoi=;<br />

oi]' e1rga kei= 'nh~n: tau~t' e0rei=j 0Aqhnai/hn<br />

glu&yai ta_ kala&—xaire/tw de\ de/spo<strong>in</strong>a.<br />

to_n pai=da dh_ gumno_n h2n kni/sw tou~ton<br />

ou)k e1lkoj e1cei, Ku&nna; pro_j ga&r oi0 kei=ntai 60<br />

ai0 sa&rkej oi]a qerma_ qerma_ phdw~sai<br />

375


e0n th~i sani/skhi. tw)rgu&reun de\ pu&raustron<br />

ou)k h2n i1dh Mu&lloj h2 Pataiki/skoj<br />

o) Lampri/wnoj, e0kbaleu~si ta_j kou&raj<br />

dokeu~ntej o1ntwj a)rgu&reun pepoih~sqai; 65<br />

o) bou~j de\ kw) a1gwn au)to_n h1 t' o)marteu~sa<br />

kw) grupo_j ou}toj kw) [a)n]a&silloj a1nqrwpoj<br />

ou)xi\ zoh_n ble/pousi kh)me/rhn pa&ntej;<br />

ei0 mh_ e0do&keun ti me/zon h2 gunh_ prh&sse<strong>in</strong>,<br />

a)nhla&lac' a1n, mh& m' o) bou~j ti phmh&nhi: 70<br />

ou1tw e0pilocoi=, Kunni/, th~i e0te/rhi kou&rhi.<br />

[KU.] a)lhq<strong>in</strong>ai/, Fi/lh, ga_r ai0 0Efesi/ou xei=rej<br />

e0j pa&nt' 0Apelle/w gra&mmat': ou)d' e0rei=j “kei=noj<br />

w1nqrwpoj e2n me\n ei]den, e2n d' a)phrnh&qh”,<br />

a)ll' w}i e0pi\ nou~n ge/noito kai\ qe/wn yau&e<strong>in</strong> 75<br />

h)pei/get'. o2j d' e0kei=non h2 e1rga ta_ e0kei/nou<br />

mh_ pamfalh&saj e0k di/khj o)rw&rhken,<br />

podo_j kre/mait' e0kei=noj e0n gnafe/wj oi1kwi.<br />

PHILE. Don’t you see, dear Kynno, what works are here! You would say<br />

that Athene carved these lovely th<strong>in</strong>g—greet<strong>in</strong>gs, Lady. This naked<br />

boy, I scratched him, won’t he have a wound, Kynno? For the flesh is<br />

laid on him <strong>in</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, puls<strong>in</strong>g like warm spr<strong>in</strong>gs. And the silver<br />

fire-tongs, if Myellos or Pataekiskos son <strong>of</strong> Lamprion sees them, won’t<br />

they lose their eyes th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g they are really made <strong>of</strong> silver? And the ox,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the man lead<strong>in</strong>g it, <strong>and</strong> the woman follow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> this hook-nosed<br />

man <strong>and</strong> the one with his hair stick<strong>in</strong>g up, don’t they all have the look <strong>of</strong><br />

life <strong>and</strong> day? If I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k I was act<strong>in</strong>g too boldly for a woman, I<br />

should have cried out, <strong>in</strong> case the ox might do some harm: he glances<br />

sideways so, Kynno with the one eye.<br />

KYNNO. Yes, Phile, the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Ephesian Apelles are truthful <strong>in</strong><br />

every l<strong>in</strong>e, nor would you say ‘That man looked at one th<strong>in</strong>g but rejected<br />

another,’ but whatever came <strong>in</strong>to his m<strong>in</strong>d he was quick <strong>and</strong> eager to<br />

attempt; <strong>and</strong> anyone who has looked on him or his works without just<br />

excitement ought to hang by the foot <strong>in</strong> the fuller’s house.<br />

Herodotus V B.C.<br />

Text: <strong>The</strong> text <strong>of</strong> all passages <strong>of</strong> Herodotus is taken from the edition <strong>of</strong> C. Hude, ed.,<br />

Herodoti Historiae (Oxford, 1908; repr., 1990).<br />

Translations are taken from the edition <strong>of</strong> D. Grene, tr., <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus (Chicago<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1987).<br />

97<br />

Herodotus 1.70<br />

376


Tou&twn te w}n ei3neken oi9 Lakedaimo&nioi th_n summaxi/hn<br />

e0de/canto, kai\ o3ti e0k pa&ntwn sfe/aj prokri/naj 9Ellh&nwn<br />

ai9re/eto fi/louj. Kai\ tou~to me\n au)toi\ h}san e3toimoi e0paggei/lanti,<br />

tou~to de\ poihsa&menoi krhth~ra xa&lkeon zw|di/wn te<br />

e1cwqen plh&santej peri\ to_ xei=loj kai\ mega&qei" trihkosi/ouj<br />

a)mfore/aj xwre/onta h}gon, dw~ron boulo&menoi a)ntidou~nai<br />

Kroi/sw|. Ou{toj o( krhth_r ou)k a)pi/keto e0j Sa&rdij di' ai0ti/aj<br />

difasi/aj legome/naj ta&sde: oi9 me\n Lakedaimo&nioi le/gousi<br />

w(j, e0pei/te a)go&menoj e0j ta_j Sa&rdij o( krhth_r e0gi/neto kata_<br />

th_n Sami/hn, puqo&menoi Sa&mioi a)peloi/ato au)to_n nhusi\<br />

makrh|~si e0piplw&santej: au)toi\ de\ Sa&mioi le/gousi w(j, e0pei/te<br />

u(ste/rhsan oi9 a1gontej tw~n Lakedaimoni/wn to_n krhth~ra,<br />

e0punqa&nonto de\ Sa&rdij te kai\ Kroi=son h(lwke/nai, a)pe/donto<br />

to_n krhth~ra e0n Sa&mw|, i0diw&taj de\ a1ndraj priame/nouj<br />

a)naqei=nai/ m<strong>in</strong> e0j to_ 3Hraion: ta&xa de\ a2n kai\ oi9 a)podo&menoi<br />

le/goien, a)piko&menoi e0j Spa&rthn, w(j a)paireqei/hsan<br />

u(po_ Sami/wn. Kata_ me/n nun to_n krhth~ra ou3twj e1sxe.<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> that, <strong>and</strong> because he had given them precedence, <strong>in</strong> his choice for friendship,<br />

over all the rest <strong>of</strong> the Greeks, the Lacedaemonians accepted the alliance. So when he<br />

made the <strong>of</strong>fer, they were ready; <strong>and</strong>, moreover, they made a bronze mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl, fill<strong>in</strong>g<br />

it on the outside, around the rim, with little figures [zw|di/wn] (the mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl itself was<br />

<strong>of</strong> a capacity <strong>of</strong> three hundred amphorae) <strong>and</strong> sent it on its way to Croesus, wish<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

match Croesus’ gift to them with one <strong>of</strong> their own to him. But this mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl never<br />

did reach Sardis, for which two reasons are given. <strong>The</strong> Lacedaemonians say that when,<br />

<strong>in</strong> its transport toward Sardis, it came near Samos, the Samians found out about it, sailed<br />

out with their long ships, <strong>and</strong> captured it; but the Samians themselves say that the<br />

Lacedaemonians who were br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g it came too late, heard that Sardis <strong>and</strong> Croesus had<br />

been captured, <strong>and</strong> sold the mix<strong>in</strong>g bowl <strong>in</strong> Samos, <strong>and</strong> that some private persons bought<br />

it <strong>and</strong> dedicated it <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong> Hera. And probably also those who sold it, when they<br />

arrived <strong>in</strong> Sparta, would say that it had been taken from them by the Samians. That, then,<br />

is the story <strong>of</strong> the bowl.<br />

98<br />

Herodotus 1.140<br />

Tau~ta me\n a)treke/wj e1xw peri\ au)tw~n ei0dw_j ei0pei=n. Ta&de me/ntoi w(j krupto&mena<br />

le/getai kai\ ou) safhne/wj peri\ tou~ a)poqano&ntoj, w(j ou) pro&teron qa&ptetai<br />

a)ndro_j Pe/rsew o( ne/kuj pri\n a2n u(p' o1rniqoj h2 kuno_j e9lkusqh|~.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se th<strong>in</strong>gs I know surely about them, for I speak from personal knowledge. But the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g are described as secret <strong>and</strong> obscure <strong>and</strong> have to do with the dead. <strong>The</strong>y say<br />

that the corpse <strong>of</strong> no Persian man is buried until it is dragged <strong>and</strong> torn by bird or dog.<br />

99<br />

377


Herodotus 1.203<br />

1Eqnea de\ a)nqrw&pwn polla_ kai\ pantoi=a e0n e9wutw|~ e1xei o( Kau&kasij, ta_ polla_<br />

pa&nta a)p' u3lhj a)gri/hj zw&onta. 0En toi=si kai\ de/ndrea fu&lla toih~sde i0de/hj<br />

parexo&mena ei]nai le/getai, ta_ tri/bonta&j te kai\ parami/sgontaj u3dwr zw|~a<br />

e9wutoi=si e0j th_n e0sqh~ta e0ggra&fe<strong>in</strong>: ta_ de\ zw|~a ou)k e0kplu&nesqai, a)lla_<br />

sugkataghra&ske<strong>in</strong> tw|~ a1llw| ei0ri/w| kata& per e0nufanqe/nta a)rxh&n.<br />

Many <strong>and</strong> every sort <strong>of</strong> nation the Caucasus conta<strong>in</strong>s with<strong>in</strong> itself, most <strong>of</strong> them liv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from the fruit <strong>of</strong> the wild tress. Among them, they say, there are trees with leaves such<br />

that, when they crush them <strong>and</strong> mix them with water, they can pa<strong>in</strong>t on their clothes<br />

figures <strong>of</strong> animals [zw|~a]. <strong>The</strong>se figures <strong>of</strong> animals [zw|~a] do not wash out but grow old<br />

with the wool, as though they were woven <strong>in</strong>to it at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

100<br />

Herodotus 2.4<br />

Duw&deka te qew~n e0pwnumi/aj e1legon prw&touj Ai0gupti/ouj nomi/sai kai\<br />

3Ellhnaj para_ sfe/wn a)nalabei=n, bwmou&j te kai\ a)ga&lmata kai\ nhou_j qeoi=si<br />

a)ponei=mai sfe/aj prw&touj kai\ zw|~a e0n li/qoisi e0gglu&yai. Kai\ tou&twn me/n nun ta_<br />

ple/w e1rgw| e0dh&loun ou3tw geno&mena.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se authorities also say that the Egyptians were the first to use the names <strong>of</strong> the twelve<br />

gods, <strong>and</strong> that the Greeks took these from them, <strong>and</strong> that the Egyptians were the first to<br />

assign altars <strong>and</strong> images [a)ga&lmata] <strong>and</strong> temples to the gods <strong>and</strong> to carve [e0gglu&yai]<br />

figures [zw|~a] on stone [e0n li/qoisi]. Most <strong>of</strong> these th<strong>in</strong>gs the showed me by clear pro<strong>of</strong>.<br />

101<br />

Herodotus 2.124<br />

0Erga&zonto de\ kata_ de/ka muria&daj a)nqrw&pwn ai0ei\ th_n tri/mhnon e9ka&sthn. Xro&non<br />

de\ e0ggene/sqai tribome/nw| tw|~ lew|~ de/ka e1tea me\n th~j o(dou~ kat' h4n ei[lkon tou_j<br />

li/qouj, th_n e1deiman e1rgon e0o_n ou) pollw|~ tew| e1lasson th~j purami/doj, w(j e0moi\<br />

doke/e<strong>in</strong> (th~j ga_r mh~koj me/n ei0si pe/nte sta&dioi, eu}roj de\ de/ka o)rguiai/, u3yoj de/, th|~<br />

u(yhlota&th e0sti\ au)th_ e9wuth~j, o)ktw_ o)rguiai/), li/qou te cestou~ kai\ zw|&wn<br />

e0ggeglumme/nwn.<br />

<strong>The</strong> people worked <strong>in</strong> gangs <strong>of</strong> one hundred thous<strong>and</strong> for each period <strong>of</strong> three months.<br />

<strong>The</strong> people were afflicted for ten years <strong>of</strong> time <strong>in</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g the road along which they<br />

dragged the stones—<strong>in</strong> my op<strong>in</strong>ion a work as great as the pyramid itself. For the length<br />

<strong>of</strong> the road is more than half a mile, <strong>and</strong> its breadth is sixty feet, <strong>and</strong> its height, at its<br />

highest, is forty-eight feet. It is made <strong>of</strong> polished stone [li/qou te cestou~], <strong>and</strong> there are<br />

figures [zw|&wn] carved [e0ggeglumme/nwn] on it.<br />

102<br />

378


Herodotus 2.148<br />

oi9 ga_r e0pestew~tej tw~n Ai0gupti/wn deiknu&nai au)ta_ ou)damw~j h1qelon, fa&menoi<br />

qh&kaj au)to&qi ei]nai tw~n te a)rxh_n to_n labu&r<strong>in</strong>qon tou~ton oi0kodomhsame/nwn<br />

basile/wn kai\ tw~n i9rw~n krokodei/lwn. Ou3tw tw~n me\n ka&tw pe/ri oi0khma&twn<br />

a)koh|~ paralabo&ntej le/gomen, ta_ de\ a1nw me/zona a)nqrwphi/wn e1rgwn au)toi\<br />

w(rw~men. Ai3 te ga_r e1codoi dia_ tw~n stege/wn kai\ oi9 ei9ligmoi\ dia_ tw~n au)le/wn<br />

e0o&ntej poikilw&tatoi qw~ma muri/on parei/xonto e0c au)lh~j te e0j ta_ oi0kh&mata<br />

dieciou~si kai\ e0k tw~n oi0khma&twn e0j pasta&daj, e0j ste/gaj te a1llaj e0k<br />

tw~n pasta&dwn kai\ e0j au)la_j a1llaj e0k tw~n oi0khma&twn. 0Or<strong>of</strong>h_ de\ pa&ntwn<br />

tou&twn liqi/nh kata& per oi9 toi=xoi, oi9 de\ toi=xoi tu&pwn e0ggeglumme/nwn ple/oi,<br />

au)lh_ de\ e9ka&sth peri/stuloj li/qou leukou~ a(rmosme/nou ta_ ma&lista. Th~j de\ gwni/hj<br />

teleutw~ntoj tou~ laburi/nqou e1xetai purami\j tesserakonto&rguioj, e0n th|~ zw|~a<br />

mega&la e0gge/gluptai: o(do_j d' e0j au)th_n u(po_ gh~n pepoi/htai.<br />

Furthermore, they resolved to leave a memorial <strong>of</strong> themselves <strong>in</strong> common, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

pursuance <strong>of</strong> resolve they made a labyr<strong>in</strong>th, a little above Lake Moeris, <strong>and</strong> situated near<br />

what is called the City <strong>of</strong> Crocodiles. I saw it myself, <strong>and</strong> it is <strong>in</strong>deed a wonder past<br />

words; for if one were to collect together all the build<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Greeks <strong>and</strong> their most<br />

strik<strong>in</strong>g works <strong>of</strong> architecture, they would all clearly be shown to have cost less labor <strong>and</strong><br />

money than this labyr<strong>in</strong>th. Yet the temple at Ephesus <strong>and</strong> that <strong>in</strong> Samos are surely<br />

remarkable. <strong>The</strong> pyramids, too, were greater than words could tell, <strong>and</strong> each <strong>of</strong> them is<br />

the equivalent <strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> the great works <strong>of</strong> the Greeks; but the labyr<strong>in</strong>th surpasses the<br />

pyramids also. It has twelve ro<strong>of</strong>ed courts, with doors fac<strong>in</strong>g one another, six to the north<br />

<strong>and</strong> six to the south <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> a cont<strong>in</strong>uous l<strong>in</strong>e. One wall on the outside encompasses them<br />

all. <strong>The</strong>re are double sets <strong>of</strong> chambers <strong>in</strong> it, some underground <strong>and</strong> some above, <strong>and</strong> their<br />

number is three thous<strong>and</strong>; there are fifteen hundred <strong>of</strong> each. We ourselves saw the<br />

aboveground chambers, for we went through them <strong>and</strong> so we can talk <strong>of</strong> them, but the<br />

underground chambers we can speak only from hearsay. For the <strong>of</strong>ficials <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Egyptians entirely refused to show us these, say<strong>in</strong>g that there are <strong>in</strong> them the c<strong>of</strong>f<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong><br />

the k<strong>in</strong>gs who had builded the labyr<strong>in</strong>th at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> also those <strong>of</strong> the holy<br />

crocodiles. So we speak from hearsay <strong>of</strong> these underground places; but what we saw<br />

aboveground was certa<strong>in</strong>ly greater than all human works. <strong>The</strong> passages through the<br />

rooms <strong>and</strong> the w<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g go<strong>in</strong>gs-<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> out through the courts, <strong>in</strong> their extreme<br />

complication, caused us countless marvel<strong>in</strong>gs as we went through, from the court <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

rooms, <strong>and</strong> from the rooms <strong>in</strong>to the pillared corridors, <strong>and</strong> then from these corridors <strong>in</strong>to<br />

other rooms aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> from the rooms <strong>in</strong>to other courts afterwards. <strong>The</strong> ro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

whole is stone, as the walls are, <strong>and</strong> the walls are full <strong>of</strong> engraved figures [tu&pwn], <strong>and</strong><br />

each court is set round with pillars <strong>of</strong> white stone, very exactly fitted. At the corner<br />

where the labyr<strong>in</strong>th ends there is, nearby, a pyramid two hundred <strong>and</strong> forty feet high <strong>and</strong><br />

engraved with great animals [zw|~a]. <strong>The</strong> road to this is made underground.<br />

103<br />

Herodotus 3.47<br />

379


Kai\ e1peita paraskeuasa&menoi e0strateu&onto Lakedaimo&nioi e0pi\ Sa&mon, w(j me\n<br />

Sa&mioi le/gousi, eu)ergesi/aj e0kti/nontej o3ti sfi pro&teroi au)toi\ nhusi\ e0boh&qhsan<br />

e0pi\ Messhni/ouj, w(j de\ Lakedaimo&nioi le/gousi, ou)k ou3tw timwrh~sai deome/noisi<br />

Sami/oisi e0strateu&onto w(j tei/sasqai boulo&menoi tou~ krhth~roj th~j a(rpagh~j,<br />

to_n h}gon Kroi/sw|, kai\ tou~ qw&rhkoj, to_n au)toi=si 1Amasij o( Ai0gu&ptou basileu_j<br />

e1pemye dw~ron. Kai\ ga_r qw&rhka e0lhi/santo tw|~ prote/rw| e1tei" h2 to_n krhth~ra oi9<br />

Sa&mioi, e0o&nta me\n li/neon kai\ zw|&wn e0nufasme/nwn suxnw~n, kekosmhme/non de\ xrusw|~<br />

kai\ ei0ri/oisi a)po_ cu&lou: tw~n de\ ei3neka qwma&sai a1cion a(rpedo&nh e9ka&sth tou~<br />

qw&rhkoj poie/ei: e0ou~sa ga_r lepth_ e1xei a(rpedo&naj e0n e9wuth|~ trihkosi/aj kai\<br />

e9ch&konta, pa&saj fanera&j. Toiou~toj e3tero&j e0sti kai\ to_n e0n Li/ndw| a)ne/qhke th|~<br />

0Aqhnai/h| 1Amasij.<br />

After this, hav<strong>in</strong>g made their preparations, the Lacedaemonians made their expedition<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st Samos. As the Samians tell the story, this was to repay the k<strong>in</strong>dness done to the<br />

Lacedaemonians by the Samians when they helped them aga<strong>in</strong>st Messenia. However, the<br />

Lacedaemonians say that this was not the reason for their assist<strong>in</strong>g the Samians <strong>in</strong> their<br />

need; rather, they themselves wanted to take revenge for the theft <strong>of</strong> the bowl that the<br />

Samians stole from them when they were tak<strong>in</strong>g it up to Croesus, <strong>and</strong> also to the theft <strong>of</strong><br />

the breastplate that Amasis, k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Egypt, had sent to them, the Spartans, as a gift. <strong>The</strong><br />

Samians had stolen the breastplate the year before they took the bowl. <strong>The</strong> breastplate<br />

was <strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>en <strong>and</strong> with many figures [zw|&wn] woven <strong>in</strong>to it, <strong>and</strong> decorated with gold <strong>and</strong><br />

cotton embroidery. <strong>The</strong> greatest wonder <strong>of</strong> it is that each s<strong>in</strong>gle f<strong>in</strong>e thread <strong>of</strong> the fabric<br />

has <strong>in</strong> itself three hundred <strong>and</strong> sixty str<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> they all can be seen to be there. One<br />

exactly like it was dedicated by Amasis, <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>dus, to Athena.<br />

104<br />

Herodotus 3.88<br />

Prw~ton me/n nun tu&pon poihsa&menoj li/q<strong>in</strong>on e1sthse: zw|~on de/ oi9 e0nh~n a)nh_r i9ppeu&j,<br />

e0pe/graye de/ [oi9] gra&mmata le/gonta ta&de: «Darei=oj o( 9Usta&speoj su&n<br />

te tou~ i3ppou th|~ a)reth|~ (to_ ou1noma le/gwn) kai\ Oi0ba&reoj tou~ i9ppoko&mou e0kth&sato<br />

th_n Perse/wn basilhi/hn.<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all he made <strong>and</strong> set up [e1sthse] a monument [tu&pon] <strong>of</strong> stone [li/q<strong>in</strong>on]. On it<br />

was an engrav<strong>in</strong>g [zw|~on] <strong>of</strong> a man on horseback, with an <strong>in</strong>scription: “Darius, son <strong>of</strong><br />

Hystaspes, with the help <strong>of</strong> his horse’s excellence” (he there mentioned the stallion’s<br />

name) “<strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Oebares the groom, won the k<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>of</strong> Persia.”<br />

105<br />

Herodotus 4.88<br />

Darei=oj de\ meta_ tau~ta h(sqei\j th|~<br />

sxedi/h| to_n a)rxite/ktona au)th~j M<strong>and</strong>rokle/a to_n Sa&mion<br />

e0dwrh&sato pa~si de/ka. 0Ap' w{n dh_ M<strong>and</strong>rokle/hj a)parxh&n,<br />

zw|~a graya&menoj pa~san th_n zeu~c<strong>in</strong> tou~ Bospo&rou kai\<br />

380


asile/a te Darei=on e0n proedri/h| kath&menon kai\ to_n strato_n<br />

au)tou~ diabai/nonta, tau~ta graya&menoj a)ne/qhke e0j to_<br />

3Hraion, e0pigra&yaj ta&de:<br />

Bo&sporon i0xquo&enta gefurw&saj a)ne/qhke<br />

M<strong>and</strong>rokle/hj 3Hrh| mnhmo&sunon sxedi/hj,<br />

au(tw|~ me\n ste/fanon periqei/j, Sami/oisi de\ ku~doj,<br />

Darei/ou basile/oj e0ktele/saj kata_ nou~n.<br />

After that, Darius was so delighted with his bridge <strong>of</strong> boats, that he gave M<strong>and</strong>rocles<br />

every sort <strong>of</strong> reward. This man took the firstfruits <strong>of</strong> his honors <strong>and</strong> had a picture made<br />

with figures depict<strong>in</strong>g [zw|~a graya&menoj] the whole bridg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Bosporus <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

K<strong>in</strong>g Darius sitt<strong>in</strong>g high over it <strong>and</strong> the army cross<strong>in</strong>g; he dedicated it <strong>in</strong> the temple <strong>of</strong><br />

Hera <strong>and</strong> made this <strong>in</strong>scription:<br />

This is the bridge <strong>of</strong> boats over the fish-haunted Bosporus;<br />

M<strong>and</strong>rocles built it, <strong>and</strong> Hera received it as her memorial;<br />

A crown for himself its builder made it, a glory <strong>of</strong> Samos;<br />

All that he wrought he accomplished by the will <strong>of</strong> the K<strong>in</strong>g, Darius.<br />

106<br />

Herodotus 7.125-7.126<br />

Poreuome/nw| de\ tau&th| le/onte/j oi9 e0peqh&kanto th|~si sit<strong>of</strong>o&roisi kamh&loisi: kata-<br />

foitw~ntej ga_r oi9 le/ontej ta_j nu&ktaj kai\ lei/pontej ta_ sfe/tera h1qea a1llou me\n<br />

ou)deno_j a3ptonto ou1te u(pozugi/ou ou1te a)nqrw&pou, oi9 de\ ta_j kamh&louj e0kera&i"zon<br />

mou&naj. Qwma&zw de\ to_ ai1tion, o3 ti kote\ h}n tw~n a1llwn to_ a)nagka&zon<br />

a)pexome/nouj tou_j le/ontaj th|~si kamh&loisi e0piti/qesqai, to_ mh&te pro&teron<br />

o)pw&pesan qhri/on mh&t' e0pepeire/ato au)tou~.<br />

Ei0si\ de\ kata_ tau~ta ta_ xwri/a kai\ le/ontej polloi\ kai\ bo&ej a1grioi, tw~n ta_ ke/rea<br />

u(permega&qea& e0sti ta_ e0j 3Ellhnaj foitw~nta. Ou}roj de\ toi=si le/ousi/ e0sti o3 te di'<br />

0Abdh&rwn r(e/wn potamo_j Ne/stoj kai\ o( di' 0Akarnani/hj r(e/wn 0Axelw|~oj: ou1te ga_r<br />

to_ pro_j th_n h)w~ tou~ Ne/stou ou)damo&qi pa&shj th~j e1mprosqe Eu)rw&phj i1doi tij a2n<br />

le/onta, ou1te pro_j e9spe/rhj tou~ 0Axelw|&ou e0n th|~ e0piloi/pw| h)pei/rw|, a)ll' e0n th|~<br />

metacu_ tou&twn tw~n potamw~n gi/nontai.<br />

As Xerxes marched along, lions set upon his camels, which were carry<strong>in</strong>g the corn. <strong>The</strong><br />

lions would come constantly at night, <strong>and</strong> leav<strong>in</strong>g their usual haunts, would touch noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

else, baggage animal or human; they ravaged the camels only. I wonder what the cause<br />

can be that forced the lions to leave the other creatures alone <strong>and</strong> attack the camels, s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

this was an animal that they had never seen before or had any experience <strong>of</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are <strong>in</strong> these parts many lions <strong>and</strong> wild oxen, the enormous horns <strong>of</strong> which are<br />

brought to <strong>Greece</strong>. <strong>The</strong> boundary <strong>of</strong> the lions is the river Nestus, which flows through<br />

Abdera, <strong>and</strong> the Achelous, which flows through Acarnania. To the east <strong>of</strong> the Nestus, <strong>in</strong><br />

all <strong>of</strong> the nearer part <strong>of</strong> Europe, you will never see a lion, nor west <strong>of</strong> the Achelous <strong>in</strong> the<br />

rest <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>l<strong>and</strong>; but they are found <strong>in</strong> the l<strong>and</strong> between these rivers.<br />

381


107<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus 6.17-6.19 IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

Krew~n koufo&tata e0j to_ sw~ma ku&neia kai\ o)rni/qeia kai\ lagw|~a ta_ di/efqa:<br />

bare/a de\ ta_ bo&eia kai\ ta_ xoi/reia.<br />

<strong>The</strong> lightest meats for the body are well-boiled dog, fowl <strong>and</strong> hare;<br />

heavy are beef <strong>and</strong> pork.<br />

108<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus 41.7-41.11 IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

toi=si de\ a)pu&rois<strong>in</strong> a1rtou kaqarou~ to_ e1swqen e0nqru&yaj e0n zwmw|~, h2 ma~zan<br />

kai\ te/maxoj e9fqo_n, h2 kre/aj o)i"o_j w(j newta&thj, h2 o1rniqoj, h2 sku&lakoj e9fqo_n, h2<br />

teu~tlon h2 koloku&nthn h2 blh~ton, kai\ meta_ to_ siti/on pi/ne<strong>in</strong> oi]non eu)w&dea, palaio_n,<br />

leuko_n, u(dare/a.<br />

If the patients do not have fever give the <strong>in</strong>ner part <strong>of</strong> a loaf <strong>of</strong> white bread crumbled <strong>in</strong>to<br />

soup, or barley-cake <strong>and</strong> a slice <strong>of</strong> boiled fish, or meat <strong>of</strong> very young lamb, fowl, or<br />

puppy, these boiled or beets or gourd or blites; after the meal let them dr<strong>in</strong>k dilute<br />

fragrant old white w<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

109<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus 43.1-43.4 IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

3Otan koili/hn u(grai/ne<strong>in</strong> a)po_ siti/wn a)sqene/ontoj e0qe/lh|j, dido&nai ma~zan kai\ o1ya,<br />

qalassi/wn me\n tema&xea e9fqa_ e0n u(potri/mmati, kre/a de\ o)i"o_j w(j newta&thj, h2<br />

e0ri/fou, h2 sku&lakoj, h2 o1rniqoj e9fqa_, kai\ teu~tla h2 blh~ta h2 la&paqa h2 koloku&nthn,<br />

h2n h( w3rh h|}:<br />

When you wish to moisten a patient’s cavity by means <strong>of</strong> foods, give barley-cake, <strong>and</strong>, as<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>-dishes slices <strong>of</strong> seafoods <strong>in</strong> a mixed dish, meat <strong>of</strong> very young lamb, kid, puppy or<br />

fowl, these boiled, <strong>and</strong> beets, blites docks or gourd if they are <strong>in</strong> season.<br />

382


110<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus <strong>in</strong>terioribus 6.26-6.32 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates VI (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

9Oko&tan de\ ai9 pe/nte h(me/rai pare/lqws<strong>in</strong>, prw&i"oj nh~stij p<strong>in</strong>e/tw e0n melikrh&tw| h2<br />

oi0nome/liti o)po_n silfi/ou o(ko&son o1robon, kai\ sko&rodon trwge/tw kai\<br />

r(afani=daj nh~stij, kai\ a1krhton oi]non e0pir)r(<strong>of</strong>ane/tw me/lana h2 leuko_n<br />

au)sthro&n: p<strong>in</strong>e/tw de\ kai\ e0pi\ si/tw| kai\ meta_ to_ si=ton: siti/oisi de\ chroi=si kai\<br />

kre/as<strong>in</strong> o)nei/ois<strong>in</strong> h2 kunei/oisi xree/sqw e9fqoi=s<strong>in</strong>, h2n to_ r(i=goj kai\ o( pureto_j mh_<br />

e0pilamba&nh|.<br />

When the five days are up, early <strong>in</strong> the morn<strong>in</strong>g let the patient dr<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> the fast<strong>in</strong>g taster<br />

silphium juice, to the amount <strong>of</strong> a vetch, <strong>in</strong> melicrat or <strong>in</strong> w<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> honey, eat garlic <strong>and</strong><br />

radishes, <strong>and</strong> on top <strong>of</strong> that take dry white or dark w<strong>in</strong>e unmixed with water; let him also<br />

take these th<strong>in</strong>gs with his meal <strong>and</strong> after it. If chills <strong>and</strong> fever are not present, give dry<br />

cereals <strong>and</strong> the meat <strong>of</strong> ass or dog boiled.<br />

111<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus <strong>in</strong>terioribus 9.4-9.11 V-VI B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates VI (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

Ou{toj o3tan ou3twj e1xh|, e0n me\n th|~si prw&th|s<strong>in</strong> h(me/rh|s<strong>in</strong> e3ndeka r(<strong>of</strong>h&masi<br />

xree/sqw, ptisa&nhj xulw|~ kaqe/fqw| me/li paraxe/wn, o(ko&tan e9fqo_n to_ r(o&fhma h|}:<br />

oi1nw| de\ xree/sqw leukw|~, glukei= h2 au)sthrw|~ kai\ u(darei=, kai\ r(<strong>of</strong>a&nonta pleona&kij<br />

tou~ oi1nou e0kptu&e<strong>in</strong> keleu&e<strong>in</strong>, kai\ tou~ u3pnou kwlu&e<strong>in</strong>, e1st' a2n ai9 e3ndeka h(me/rai<br />

pare/lqws<strong>in</strong>, meta_ de\ tau&taj ta_j h(me/raj siti/ois<strong>in</strong> o)li/gois<strong>in</strong> w(j ma&lista<br />

xree/sqw, kre/asi skulakei/ois<strong>in</strong> h2 a)lektruonei/oisi qermoi=si: e0zwmeu~sqai de\ xrh_<br />

kalw~j, kai\ to_n zwmo_n r(<strong>of</strong>ane/tw.<br />

When the case is such, for the first eleven days let the patient take as gruel boiled-down<br />

barley-water to which honey has been added after the gruel has been boiled, <strong>and</strong> dr<strong>in</strong>k<br />

white w<strong>in</strong>e—either sweet or dry—diluted with water; after he has had several dr<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>of</strong><br />

w<strong>in</strong>e, order him to expectorate; prevent sleep until the eleven days have passed. After<br />

that, let the patient take ma<strong>in</strong>ly cereals <strong>in</strong> small amounts, <strong>and</strong> meat <strong>of</strong> puppy or fowl<br />

warmed; you must boil these well <strong>in</strong>to a soup, <strong>and</strong> have the patient dr<strong>in</strong>k the soup.<br />

112<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus <strong>in</strong>terioribus 22.10-22.13 V-VI B.C.<br />

383


Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates VI (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

Tou&tw| cumfe/rei th_n koili/hn chrai/ne<strong>in</strong>, dido&nta a1rton me\n au)topuri/thn, qermo_n,<br />

mh_ e3wlon, o1yon de\ o1nou kre/aj kai\ kuno_j telei/ou, kai\ o1i"oj, kai\ u(o_j w(j o)pta_, kai\<br />

a)lektruo&noj o)pta_ qerma_,<br />

It benefits the patient if you dry out his cavity by giv<strong>in</strong>g him fresh warm dark wholewheat<br />

bread, <strong>and</strong> as ma<strong>in</strong> dish the meat <strong>of</strong> ass, mature dog, sw<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> sheep, these very<br />

fat <strong>and</strong> boiled, or meat <strong>of</strong> fowl, roasted <strong>and</strong> warm.<br />

113<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus <strong>in</strong>terioribus 27.39-27.43 V-VI B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates VI (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

Meta_ de\ th~j nou&sou th_n kri/s<strong>in</strong> meleth|~n, siti/a o)li/ga didou_j kaqara&: kh2n me\n<br />

a1rton file/h| e0sqi/e<strong>in</strong>, a1rton qermo_n w(j ma&lista kaqaro_n e0sqie/tw: h2n de\ ma&zhn,<br />

a1tripton e0sqie/tw, pro&teron pr<strong>of</strong>urh&saj: o1yon de\ e0xe/tw kre/a skulaki/ou e9fqa_<br />

h2 peleia&doj h2 a)lektori/doj neossou~, e9fqoi=si pa~s<strong>in</strong>:<br />

After the disease’s crisis, treat by giv<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>e cereals <strong>in</strong> small amounts; if the patient<br />

eats bread, let him take it very hot, if barley-cake, let it be unpounded but mixed a while<br />

before it is baked. As ma<strong>in</strong> dish, let him have boiled puppy, pigeon or chicken, tak<strong>in</strong>g all<br />

these boiled.<br />

114<br />

Hippocrates, De affectionibus <strong>in</strong>terioribus 30.18-30.22 V-VI B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates VI (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

To_n de\ loipo_n xro&non ta&de xrh_ prosfe/resqai: siti/on me\n a1rton au)topuri/thn,<br />

o1yon de\ e0xe/tw kre/aj kuno_j me/zonoj h2 ai0go_j h2 oi0o_j tetrimme/non, kai\ ta&rixoj<br />

Gadeiriko_n h2 sape/rdhn, kai\ ta_ o)ce/a kai\ ta_ a(lmura_ pa&nta prosfere/sqw<br />

kai\ ta_ strufna&:<br />

From then on, the follow<strong>in</strong>g must be adm<strong>in</strong>istered: <strong>of</strong> cereals let the patient have wholewheat<br />

bread, as ma<strong>in</strong> dish ground meat <strong>of</strong> an adult dog, sheep or goat, <strong>and</strong> Cadiz salt-fish<br />

or saperdes; adm<strong>in</strong>ister all the acid <strong>and</strong> salty foods, <strong>and</strong> also the sour ones.<br />

115<br />

384


Hippocrates, De morbis ii 44.16-44.19 V B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

3Otan de\ o( pureto_j a)fh|~, h(me/raj me\n du&o to_n ke/gxron r(<strong>of</strong>ee/tw di\j th~j h(me/rhj,<br />

kai\ teu~tla h(du&tata e0sqie/tw: e1peita meta_ tau~ta sku&laka h2 o)rni/qion ka&qefqon<br />

poih&saj, tou~ zwmou~ r(<strong>of</strong>ee/tw, kai\ tw~n krew~n fage/tw o)li/ga:<br />

When the fever remits, for two days have the patient dr<strong>in</strong>k the millet as gruel twice daily,<br />

<strong>and</strong> eat seasoned beets; after that, make boiled puppy or fowl, <strong>and</strong> have him dr<strong>in</strong>k the<br />

sauce <strong>and</strong> eat a little <strong>of</strong> the meat.<br />

116<br />

Hippocrates, De morbis ii 56.11-56.12 V B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988).<br />

e0j e9spe/rhn de\ kre/a skulaki/ou h2 o)rni/qeia e9fqa_ e0sqi/e<strong>in</strong>, kai\ tou~ zwmou~ r(<strong>of</strong>a&ne<strong>in</strong>:<br />

Towards even<strong>in</strong>g eat boiled meat <strong>of</strong> puppy or fowl, <strong>and</strong> dr<strong>in</strong>k the sauce; on the first days<br />

let him have as little food as possible.<br />

117<br />

Hippocrates, De morbis popularibus (=Epidemiae) 7.62<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate V (Paris, 1846; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: W. D. Smith, ed., tr., Hippocrates VII (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1994).<br />

0Hsi/thsen h(me/raj e9pta_, meli/krhton a)krhte/steron e1pie, meta_ de\, xulo_n fakou~,<br />

o(te\ de\ lepto_n to_ e1tnoj, e0pe/p<strong>in</strong>en u3dwr, meta_ de\, skulaki/ou e9fqou~, ma&zhj mikro_n<br />

o3ti ma&lista pa&lai cugkeime/nhj: proi"o&ntoj de\, h2 bo&eia traxh&lia, h2 kwlh~naj<br />

u(ei/wn krew~n e9fqw~n.<br />

He absta<strong>in</strong>ed from food for seven days, drank melicrat <strong>in</strong> a strong mixture. Afterwards<br />

bean broth <strong>and</strong> sometimes pea soup; he drank water; later some boiled young dog, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

little barley cake which had been made as long before as possible. As time went on either<br />

beef neck-meat or pork leg-bones.<br />

118<br />

Hippocrates, De morbo sacro 1.28-1.35 V B.C.<br />

385


Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Hippocrates II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1923; repr. 1992).<br />

kai\ lo&gouj e0pile/cantej e0pithdei/ouj th_n i1hs<strong>in</strong> katesth&santo e0j to_ a)sfale\j<br />

sfi/s<strong>in</strong> au)toi=si, kaqarmou_j prosfe/rontej kai\ e0paoida_j, loutrw~n te a)pe/xesqai<br />

keleu&ontej kai\ e0desma&twn pollw~n kai\ a)nepithdei/wn a)nqrw&poisi nose/ous<strong>in</strong><br />

e0sqi/e<strong>in</strong>, qalassi/wn me\n tri/glhj, melanou&rou, kestre/oj, e0gxe/luoj (ou{toi ga_r oi9<br />

i0xqu&ej ei0si\n e0pikairo&tatoi), krew~n de\ ai0gei/ou kai\ e0la&fwn kai\ xoiri/wn kai\ kuno_j<br />

(tau~ta ga_r krew~n taraktikw&tata& e0sti th~j koili/hj).<br />

<strong>The</strong>y used purifications <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cantations; they forbade the use <strong>of</strong> baths, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> many<br />

foods that are unsuitable for sick folk—<strong>of</strong> sea fishes: red mullet, black-tail, hammer <strong>and</strong><br />

the eel (these are the most harmful sorts); the flesh <strong>of</strong> goats, deer, pigs, <strong>and</strong> dogs (meats<br />

that disturb most the digestive organs).<br />

119<br />

Hippocrates, De mulierum affectibus i-iii 217<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VIII (Paris, 1853; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

e0sqie/tw skula&kia sialw&dea di/efqa.<br />

Eat well-boiled fattened puppies.<br />

120<br />

Hippocrates, De mulierum affectibus i-iii 230<br />

Text: É. Littré, Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VIII (Paris, 1853; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

ta_ e0ntosqi/dia e0celw_n tou~ skulaki/ou e0mplh~sai kai\ sa&cai o3ti ma&lista tw~n<br />

a)rwma&twn.<br />

After tak<strong>in</strong>g out the entrails <strong>of</strong> the puppy, wash them <strong>and</strong> stuff them with aromatic herbs.<br />

121<br />

Hippocrates, De natura muliebri 32.48-32.49 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d' Hippocrate VII (Paris, 1851; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

o)po_n silfi/ou o3son o1robon, kai\ karda&mou karpo_n tri/yaj lei=a kai\ cummi/caj e0n<br />

oi1nw|, h2 e0n kuno_j ga&lakti, di/dou piei=n. Tou~to kai\ e1mbruon e0celau&nei.<br />

386


Rub well silphium equal to one gra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> vetch, together with cardamom <strong>and</strong> mix it with<br />

w<strong>in</strong>e or the milk <strong>of</strong> dog, <strong>and</strong> give it to dr<strong>in</strong>k. This should deliver the fetus.<br />

122<br />

Hippocrates, De victu 2.46 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Hippocrates IV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1931; repr. 1959).<br />

Ku&neia de\ qermai/nei kai\ chrai/nei kai\ i0sxu_n e0mpoie/ei, ou) me/ntoi diaxwre/ei:<br />

skula&keia de\ u(grai/nei kai\ diaxwre/ei, ou)re/etai de\ ma~llon.<br />

Dogs’ flesh dries, heats, <strong>and</strong> affords strength, but does not pass by stool. <strong>The</strong> flesh <strong>of</strong><br />

puppies moistens <strong>and</strong> passes by stool, still more by ur<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

123<br />

Hippocrates, De victu 3.75 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text: É. Littré, ed., Oeuvres complètes d'Hippocrate VI (Paris, 1849; repr. Amsterdam,<br />

1962).<br />

Translation: W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Hippocrates IV (Cambridge, Mass., <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1931; repr. 1959).<br />

prw~ton me\n ou}n xrh_ a1rtw| qermw|~ xre/esqai zumi/th|, diaqru&ptonta e0j oi]non me/lana<br />

h2 zwmo_n u(ei/wn krew~n: toi=si/ te i0xqu&s<strong>in</strong> e9fqoi=s<strong>in</strong> e0n a3lmh| drimei/h|: xre/esqai me\n kai\<br />

toi=si sarkw&des<strong>in</strong>, oi[on a)krokwli/oisi/ te die/fqoisi toi=s<strong>in</strong> u(ei/oisi, toi=si/ te pi/os<strong>in</strong><br />

u(ei/ois<strong>in</strong> o)ptoi=si, toi=si de\ xoirei/oisi mh_ polloi=si kai\ skula&kwn mhde\ e0ri/fwn:<br />

So first use warm, fermented bread, crumbl<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong>to dark w<strong>in</strong>e or <strong>in</strong>to pork broth. Also<br />

fish boiled <strong>in</strong> acrid br<strong>in</strong>e. Use also fleshy meats, such as pig’s feet well boiled <strong>and</strong> fat<br />

roast pork, but be spar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> suck<strong>in</strong>g-pig, <strong>and</strong> the flesh <strong>of</strong> puppies <strong>and</strong> kids.<br />

124<br />

Homer, Iliad 1.1-1.5 VIII B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. P. Gould, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad I (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1924; second ed., 1999).<br />

Mh~n<strong>in</strong> a1eide qea_ Phlhi"a&dew 0Axilh~oj<br />

ou)lome/nhn, h4 muri/' 0Axaioi=j a1lge' e1qhke,<br />

polla_j d' i0fqi/mouj yuxa_j 1Ai"di proi5ayen<br />

h(rw&wn, au)tou_j de\ e9lw&ria teu~xe ku&ness<strong>in</strong><br />

5 oi0wnoi=si/ te pa~si.<br />

<strong>The</strong> wrath s<strong>in</strong>g, goddess, <strong>of</strong> Peleus’ son Achilles,<br />

387


the accursed wrath which brought countless sorrows upon<br />

the Achaeans, <strong>and</strong> sent down to Hades many valiant souls<br />

<strong>of</strong> warriors, <strong>and</strong> made the men themselves to be the spoil for<br />

dogs <strong>and</strong> birds <strong>of</strong> every k<strong>in</strong>d.<br />

125<br />

Homer, Iliad 15.630-15.637<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. P. Gould, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1925; second ed., 1999).<br />

630 au)ta_r o3 g' w3j te le/wn o)loo&frwn bousi\n e0pelqw&n,<br />

ai3 r(a& t' e0n ei9amenh|~ e3leoj mega&loio ne/montai<br />

muri/ai, e0n de/ te th|~si nomeu_j ou1 pw sa&fa ei0dw_j<br />

qhri\ maxe/ssasqai e3likoj boo_j a)mfi\ fonh|~s<strong>in</strong>:<br />

h1toi o4 me\n prw&th|si kai\ u(stati/h|si bo&ess<strong>in</strong><br />

ai0e\n o(mostixa&ei, o4 de/ t' e0n me/ssh|s<strong>in</strong> o)rou&saj<br />

bou~n e1dei, ai4 de/ te pa~sai u(pe/tresan: w4j to&t' 0Axaioi\<br />

qespesi/wj e0fo&bhqen u(f' 3Ektori kai\ Dii\ patri\<br />

pa&ntej.<br />

But he [Hector] fell on them [Achaeans] like a lion <strong>of</strong> destructive m<strong>in</strong>d<br />

com<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st cattle that are graz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the bottom <strong>of</strong> a great marsh, <strong>and</strong><br />

there is no count<strong>in</strong>g them, <strong>and</strong> among them is a herdsman who is yet<br />

unskilled to fight with a wild beast over the carcase <strong>of</strong> a sleek heifer that<br />

has been sla<strong>in</strong>: he paces ever by their side, now abreast <strong>of</strong> the foremost <strong>of</strong><br />

the cattle, <strong>and</strong> now <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>in</strong>dmost, but the lion leaps on the midmost, <strong>and</strong><br />

devours a heifer, <strong>and</strong> at that they all flee <strong>in</strong> terror; so wondrously were the<br />

Achaeans one <strong>and</strong> all then driven <strong>in</strong> rout by Hector <strong>and</strong> father Zeus.<br />

126<br />

Homer, Iliad 16.756-16.763 VIII B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. P. Gould, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1925; second ed., 1999).<br />

tw_ peri\ Kebrio&nao le/onq' w4j dhr<strong>in</strong>qh&thn,<br />

w3 t' o1reoj korufh|~si peri\ ktame/nhj e0la&foio<br />

a1mfw pe<strong>in</strong>a&onte me/ga frone/onte ma&xesqon:<br />

w4j peri\ Kebrio&nao du&w mh&stwrej a)u+th~j<br />

760 Pa&troklo&j te Menoitia&dhj kai\ fai/dimoj 3Ektwr,<br />

i3ent' a)llh&lwn tame/e<strong>in</strong> xro&a nhle/i" xalkw|~.<br />

3Ektwr me\n kefalh~f<strong>in</strong> e0pei\ la&ben ou)xi\ meqi/ei:<br />

Pa&trokloj d' e9te/rwqen e1xen podo&j:<br />

So the two jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> strife for Cebriones like two lions<br />

388


that on the peaks <strong>of</strong> a mounta<strong>in</strong> fight for a sla<strong>in</strong> h<strong>in</strong>d,<br />

both <strong>of</strong> them hunger<strong>in</strong>g, both high <strong>of</strong> heart; so for Cebriones<br />

the two masters <strong>of</strong> the war cry, Patroclus, son <strong>of</strong> Menoetius,<br />

<strong>and</strong> glorious Hector, were eager each to cleave the other’s flesh<br />

with the pitiless bronze. Hector, when once he has seized the<br />

corpse by the head, would not loose his hold, <strong>and</strong> Patroclus on the<br />

other side held fast hold <strong>of</strong> the foot.<br />

127<br />

Homer, Iliad 22.66-22.76 VIII B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. P. Gould, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1925; second ed., 1999).<br />

au)to_n d' a2n pu&mato&n me ku&nej prw&th|si qu&rh|s<strong>in</strong><br />

w)mhstai\ e0ru&ous<strong>in</strong>, e0pei/ ke/ tij o)ce/i" xalkw|~<br />

tu&yaj h)e\ balw_n r(eqe/wn e0k qumo_n e3lhtai,<br />

ou4j tre/fon e0n mega&roisi trapezh~aj qurawrou&j,<br />

70 oi3 k' e0mo_n ai[ma pio&ntej a)lu&ssontej peri\ qumw|~ ( 0)<br />

kei/sont' e0n proqu&roisi. ne/w| de/ te pa&nt' e0pe/oiken<br />

a1rhi" ktame/nw| dedai"gme/nw| o)ce/i" xalkw|~<br />

kei=sqai: pa&nta de\ kala_ qano&nti per o3tti fanh&h|:<br />

a)ll' o3te dh_ polio&n te ka&rh polio&n te ge/neion<br />

75 ai0dw~ t' ai0sxu&nwsi ku&nej ktame/noio ge/rontoj,<br />

tou~to dh_ oi1ktiston pe/letai deiloi=si brotoi=s<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Myself then last <strong>of</strong> all before my doors will dogs that<br />

eat raw flesh tear apart, when some man by thrust or cast<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sharp bronze has taken the spirit from my limbs—<br />

the dogs that <strong>in</strong> my halls I reared at my table to guard my door—<br />

which then hav<strong>in</strong>g drunk my blood <strong>in</strong> the madness <strong>of</strong> their hearts,<br />

will lie there <strong>in</strong> the gateway. For a young man it is wholly fitt<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

when he is sla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> battle, to lie mangled by the sharp bronze; dead<br />

though he is, all is fair that can be seen. But when dogs work shame<br />

on the gray head <strong>and</strong> gray beard <strong>and</strong> on the nakedness <strong>of</strong> a sla<strong>in</strong> old<br />

man, that is the most piteous th<strong>in</strong>g that falls to wretched mortals.<br />

128<br />

Isocrates, Antidosis 213-214 IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: G. Norl<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Isocrates II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1929; repr. 1992) 305.<br />

4O de\ pa&ntwn de<strong>in</strong>o&taton, o3ti kaq' e3kaston to_n e0niauto_n qewrou~ntej e0n toi=j<br />

qau&mas<strong>in</strong> tou_j me\n le/ontaj prao&teron diakeime/nouj pro_j tou_j qerapeu&ontaj h2<br />

tw~n a)nqrw&pwn e1nioi pro_j tou_j eu} poiou~ntaj, ta_j d' a1rktouj<br />

389


kal<strong>in</strong>doume/naj kai\ palaiou&saj kai\ mimoume/naj ta_j h(mete/raj e0pisth&maj, ou)d' e0k<br />

tou&twn du&nantai gnw~nai th_n paidei/an kai\ th_n e0pime/leian, o3shn e1xei du&nam<strong>in</strong>,<br />

ou)d' o3ti tau~ta polu_ a2n qa~tton th_n h(mete/ran fu&s<strong>in</strong> h2 th_n e0kei/nwn w)felh&seien:<br />

But most absurd <strong>of</strong> all, they [Isocrates’ detractors] behold <strong>in</strong> the shows which are held<br />

year after year lions which are more gentle toward their tra<strong>in</strong>ers than some people are<br />

toward their benefactors, <strong>and</strong> bears which dance about <strong>and</strong> wrestle <strong>and</strong> imitate our skill,<br />

<strong>and</strong> yet they are not able to judge even from these <strong>in</strong>stances the power which education<br />

<strong>and</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g have, nor can they see that human nature will respond more promptly than<br />

the animals to the benefits <strong>of</strong> education.<br />

129<br />

Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong> Egypt, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.738 A.D. VI<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

0En boi6 ta|~d' e0ma&xonto Fu&sij kai\ po&tnia Te/xna:<br />

a)mfote/raij de\ Mu&rwn i]son o1passe ge/raj:<br />

derkome/noij me\n ga_r Fu&sioj kra&toj h3rpase Te/xna:<br />

au)ta_r e0faptome/noij h( Fu&sij e0sti\ fu&sij.<br />

Nature <strong>and</strong> Queen Art strove <strong>in</strong> the matter <strong>of</strong><br />

this cow, <strong>and</strong> Myron gave to each a prize <strong>of</strong> equal<br />

value. When one looks at it Art robs nature <strong>of</strong><br />

her superiority, but when one touches it Nature is nature.<br />

130<br />

Julian, Prefect <strong>of</strong> Egypt, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.739 A.D. VI<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

1Hpafe kai\ se\ mu&wpa Mu&rwn, o3ti ke/ntron e0rei/deij<br />

pleurai=j xalkoxu&toij a)ntitu&poio boo&j.<br />

ou) ne/mesij de\ mu&wpi. ti/ ga_r to&son; ei1 ge kai\ au)tou_j<br />

o)fqalmou_j nome/wn h)pero&peuse Mu&rwn.<br />

Myron deceived thee too, gadfly, that thou plungest<br />

thy st<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the hard flanks <strong>of</strong> the bronze cow.<br />

But the gadfly is excusable. What wonder! when<br />

Myron deceived even the eyes <strong>of</strong> the herdsmen.<br />

131<br />

Leonidas <strong>of</strong> Tarentum, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.719 III B.C.<br />

390


Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Ou)k e1plase/n me Mu&rwn, e0yeu&sato: boskome/nan de\<br />

e0c a)ge/laj e0la&saj dh~se ba&sei liqi/nw|.<br />

Myron did not mould me; he lied; but driv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

me from the herd where I was feed<strong>in</strong>g, he fixed me<br />

to a stone base.<br />

132<br />

Macedonius the Consul, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 6.175 A.D. I (?)<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology I (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1916; repr. 1927).<br />

To_n ku&na, to_n pa&shj kraterh~j e0pii/dmona qh&rhj,<br />

e1cese me\n Leu&kwn, a1nqeto d' 0Alkime/nhj.<br />

0Alkime/nhj d' ou)x eu{re, ti/ me/myetai: w(j d' i1d' o(moi/hn<br />

ei0ko&na pantoi/w| sxh&mati fa<strong>in</strong>ome/nhn,<br />

kloio_n e1xwn pe/laj h}lqe, le/gwn Leu&kwni keleu&e<strong>in</strong><br />

tw|~ kuni\ kai\ bai/ne<strong>in</strong>: pei=qe ga_r w(j u(la&wn.<br />

This dog tra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> every k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> hunt<strong>in</strong>g, was carved by Leucon, <strong>and</strong> dedicated by<br />

Alcimenes. Alcimenes had no fault to f<strong>in</strong>d, but when he saw the statue resembl<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

dog <strong>in</strong> every feature he came up to it, with a collar, bidd<strong>in</strong>g Leucon to order the dog to<br />

walk, for as it looked to be bark<strong>in</strong>g, it persuaded him it could walk too.<br />

133<br />

Marcus Argentarius, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.732 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

Bouko&lon h2n e0si/dh|j to_n e0mo&n, ce/ne, tou~t' e1poj au)tw|~<br />

ei]pon, o3q' o( pla&sthj w{de/ m' e1dhse Mu&rwn.<br />

Stranger, if thou seest my herdsman, give him<br />

this message, that the sculptor Myron tied me up here.<br />

134<br />

Nemesianus, Cynegetica 151-156 A.D. III<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: J. W. Duff <strong>and</strong> A. M. Duff, eds., trs., M<strong>in</strong>or Lat<strong>in</strong> Poets II<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1934; rev. ed. 1935; repr. 1982).<br />

hos igitur genetrice simul iam vere sereno<br />

391


molli pasce sero (passim nam lactis abundans<br />

tempus adest, ablent plenis et ovilia mulctris),<br />

<strong>in</strong>terdumque cibo cererem cum lacte m<strong>in</strong>istra,<br />

155 fortibus ut sucis teneras cnplenere medullas<br />

poss<strong>in</strong>t et validas iam tunc promittere vires.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se then along with their mother, now that it is clear spr<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

you are to feed on s<strong>of</strong>t whey (for everywhere the season that abounds<br />

<strong>in</strong> milk has come, <strong>and</strong> sheepfolds are white with brimmimg milk-pails):<br />

at times, too, add to their food bread with milk, so that they may be<br />

able to fill their young marrows with powerful juices <strong>and</strong> even at that<br />

time give promise <strong>of</strong> vigorous strength.<br />

135<br />

Pausanias 1.23.2 A.D. II<br />

Text: F. Spiro, Pausaniae Graeciae descriptio (3 vols.; Leipzig, 1903; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

tau&thn ga&r, e0pei/ te a)pe/qanen 3Ipparxoj, —le/gw de\ ou)k e0j suggrafh_n pro&teron<br />

h3konta, pista_ de\ a1llwj 0Aqhnai/wn toi=j polloi=j— 9Ippi/aj ei]xen e0n ai0ki/a| e0j o4<br />

die/fqeiren, oi[a e9tai/ran 0Aristogei/tonoj e0pista&menoj ou}san kai\ to_ bou&leuma<br />

ou)damw~j a)gnoh~sai doca&zwn: a)nti\ de\ tou&twn, e0pei\ turanni/doj e0pau&qhsan oi9<br />

Peisistrati/dai, xalkh~ le/a<strong>in</strong>a 0Aqhnai/oij e0sti\n e0j mnh&mhn th~j gunaiko&j, para_ de\<br />

au)th_n a1galma 0Afrodi/thj, o4 Kalli/ou te/fas<strong>in</strong> a) na&qhma ei]nai kai\<br />

e 1 rgon Kala&midoj.<br />

When Hipparchos [the son <strong>of</strong> Peisistratos] died—<strong>and</strong> what I am say<strong>in</strong>g has never before<br />

come to be written down but is generally belied by many Athenians—Hippias tortured<br />

<strong>and</strong> killed [an Athenian woman named] Lea<strong>in</strong>a [“Lioness”], know<strong>in</strong>g that she was the<br />

mistress <strong>of</strong> Aristogeiton <strong>and</strong> believ<strong>in</strong>g that there was no way <strong>in</strong> which she could have<br />

been ignorant <strong>of</strong> the plot. In reaction to this, when the tyranny <strong>of</strong> the Peisistratids came<br />

to an end, the Athenians set up a bronze lioness as a memorial to the woman, next to the<br />

image <strong>of</strong> Aphrodite, which they say, was a dedication <strong>of</strong> Kallias <strong>and</strong> a work <strong>of</strong> Kalamis.<br />

136<br />

Pausanias 3.14.9 A.D. II<br />

Text: F. Spiro, ed., Pausaniae Graeciae descriptio (3 vols.; Leipzig, 1903; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967).<br />

Translation: W. H. Jones <strong>and</strong> H. A. Ormedog, eds., trs., Pausanias. Description <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Greece</strong> II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1926; repr. 1977).<br />

kai\ ta&de a1lla toi=j e0fh&boij drw&mena& e0sti: qu&ousi pro_ th~j ma&xhj e0n tw|~<br />

Foibai/w|: to_ de\ Foibai=o&n e0st<strong>in</strong> e0kto_j th~j po&lewj, Qera&pnhj ou) polu_<br />

392


a)festhko&j. e0ntau~qa e9kate/ra moi=ra tw~n e0fh&bwn sku&laka kuno_j tw|~ 0Enuali/w|<br />

qu&ousi, qew~n tw|~ a)lkimwta&tw| kri/nontej i9erei=on kata_ gnw&mhn ei]nai to_<br />

a)lkimw&taton zw|~on tw~n h(me/rwn. kuno_j de\ sku&lakaj ou)de/naj a1llouj oi]da<br />

9Ellh&nwn nomi/zontaj qu&e<strong>in</strong> o3ti mh_ Kol<strong>of</strong>wni/ouj: qu&ousi ga_r kai\ Kol<strong>of</strong>w&nioi<br />

me/la<strong>in</strong>an th|~ 0Enodi/w| sku&laka. nukter<strong>in</strong>ai\ de\ h3 te Kol<strong>of</strong>wni/wn qusi/a kai\ tw~n<br />

e0n Lakedai/moni e0fh&bwn kaqesth&kas<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Before the fight<strong>in</strong>g they sacrifice <strong>in</strong> the Phoebeum, which is outside the city, not far<br />

distant from <strong>The</strong>rapne. Here each company <strong>of</strong> youths sacrifices a puppy to Enyalius,<br />

hold<strong>in</strong>g that the most valiant <strong>of</strong> tame animals is an acceptable victim to the most valiant<br />

<strong>of</strong> the gods. I know <strong>of</strong> no other Greeks who are accustomed to sacrifice puppies except<br />

the people <strong>of</strong> Colophon; these too sacrifice a puppy, a black bitch, to the Wayside<br />

Goddess. Both the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> the Colophonians <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> the youths at<br />

Sparta are appo<strong>in</strong>ted to take place at night.<br />

137<br />

Pausanias 6.5.4 A.D. II<br />

Text: F. Spiro, ed., Pausaniae Graeciae descriptio (3 vols.; Leipzig, 1903; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967).<br />

Translation: W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Pausanias. Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> III (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1933; repr. 1960).<br />

pagkrati/ou me\n dh_ kai\ a1lloij h1dh gego&nas<strong>in</strong> e0pifanei=j ni=kai: Pouluda&manti de\<br />

ta&de a)lloi=a para_ tou_j e0pi\ tw|~ pagkrati/w| stefa&nouj u(pa&rxonta& e0st<strong>in</strong>. h(<br />

o)re<strong>in</strong>h_ th~j Qra|&khj, h( e1ndon Ne/stou potamou~ tou~ r(e/ontoj dia_<br />

th~j 0Abdhritw~n, kai\ a1lla qhri/a, e0n de\ au)toi=j pare/xetai kai\ le/ontaj, oi4 kai\ tw|~<br />

stratw|~ pote e0piqe/menoi tw|~ Ce/rcou ta_j a)gou&saj kamh&louj ta_ siti/a e0lumh&nanto.<br />

ou{toi polla&kij oi9 le/ontej kai\ e0j th_n peri\ to_n 1Olumpon planw~ntai xw&ran:<br />

tou&tou de\ tou~ o1rouj h( me\n e0j Makedoni/an pleura&, h( de\ e0pi\ Qessalou_j kai\ to_n<br />

potamo_n te/traptai to_n Phneio&n: e0ntau~qa o( Pouluda&maj le/onta e0n tw|~<br />

0Olu&mpw|, me/ga kai\ a1lkimon qhri/on, kateirga&sato ou)deni\ e0skeuasme/noj o3plw|.<br />

proh&xqh de\ e0j to_ to&lmhma filotimi/a| pro_j ta_ 9Hrakle/ouj e1rga, o3ti<br />

kai\ 9Hrakle/a e1xei lo&goj krath~sai tou~ e0n Neme/a| le/ontoj.<br />

Other have won glorious victories <strong>in</strong> the pancratium, but Pulydamas besides the prizes for<br />

the pancratium, has to his credit the follow<strong>in</strong>g exploits <strong>of</strong> a different k<strong>in</strong>d. <strong>The</strong><br />

mounta<strong>in</strong>ous part <strong>of</strong> Thrace, on this side the river Nestus, which runs through the l<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

Abdera, breeds among other wild beasts lions, which once attacked the army <strong>of</strong> Xerxes,<br />

<strong>and</strong> mauled the camels carry<strong>in</strong>g the supplies. <strong>The</strong>se lions <strong>of</strong>ten roam right <strong>in</strong>to the l<strong>and</strong><br />

around Mount Olympus, one side <strong>of</strong> which is turned towards Macedonia, <strong>and</strong> the other<br />

towards <strong>The</strong>ssaly <strong>and</strong> the river Peneius. Here on Mount Olympus Pulydamas slew a lion,<br />

a huge <strong>and</strong> powerful beast, without the help <strong>of</strong> any weapon. To this exploit he was<br />

impelled by an ambition to rival the labours <strong>of</strong> Heracles, because Heracles also, legend<br />

says, overthrew the lion at Nemea.<br />

393


138<br />

Pausanias 6.12.1 A.D. II<br />

Text: F. Spiro, ed., Pausaniae Graeciae descriptio (3 vols.; Leipzig, 1903; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

plhsi/on de\ a3rma te/ e0sti xalkou~n kai\ a)nh_r a)nabebhkw_j e0p' au)to&, ke/lhtej de\<br />

i3ppoi para_ to_ a3rma ei[j e9kate/rwqen e3sthke kai\ e0pi\ tw~n i3ppwn kaqe/zontai<br />

pai=dej: u(pomnh&mata de\ e0pi\ ni/kaij 0Olumpikai=j e0st<strong>in</strong> 9Ie/rwnoj tou~ De<strong>in</strong>ome/nouj<br />

turannh&santoj Surakousi/wn meta_ to_n a)delfo_n Ge/lwna. ta_ de\ a)naqh&mata ou)x<br />

9Ie/rwn a)pe/steilen, a)ll' o( me\n a)podou_j tw|~ qew|~ De<strong>in</strong>ome/nhj e0sti\n o( 9Ie/rwnoj, e1rga<br />

de\ to_ me\n 0 Ona&ta tou~ Ai0g<strong>in</strong>h&tou to_ a3rma, K a l a & m i d o j de\ oi9 i3ppoi te oi9<br />

e9kate/rwqen kai\ e0p' au)tw~n ei0s<strong>in</strong> oi9 pai=dej.<br />

Nearby is a bronze chariot <strong>and</strong> a man mounted on it; race-horses st<strong>and</strong> by the chariot, one<br />

on each side, <strong>and</strong> there are children seated on the horses. <strong>The</strong>se are memorials to the<br />

Olympic victories <strong>of</strong> Hieron the son <strong>of</strong> De<strong>in</strong>omenes, who ruled as tyrant over the<br />

Syracusans after his brother Gelon. But Hieron did not send these <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs: rather it was<br />

De<strong>in</strong>omenes the son <strong>of</strong> Hieron, who gave them to the god. <strong>The</strong> chariot was the work <strong>of</strong><br />

Onatas <strong>of</strong> Aig<strong>in</strong>a, while the horses on either side <strong>of</strong> it <strong>and</strong> the children upon them are the<br />

works <strong>of</strong> Kalamis.<br />

139<br />

Pausanias 9.30.1 A.D. II<br />

Text: F. Spiro, ed., Pausaniae Graeciae descriptio (3 vols.; Leipzig, 1903; repr. Stuttgart,<br />

1967).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

tai=j Mou&saij de\ a)ga&lmata me\n prw~ta& e0sti Khfisodo&tou te/xnh<br />

pa&saij, proelqo&nti de\ ou) polu_ trei=j me/n ei0s<strong>in</strong> au}qij K h f i s o d o & t o u ,<br />

Strogguli/wnoj de\ e3tera tosau~ta, a)ndro_j bou~j kai\ i3ppouj a1rista<br />

ei0rgasme/nou:<br />

<strong>The</strong> first images <strong>of</strong> the Muses are the work <strong>of</strong> Kephisodotos, all <strong>of</strong> them; a little farther<br />

on there are three more aga<strong>in</strong> by Kephisodotos, <strong>and</strong> then three others by Strongylion, an<br />

artist responsible for excellent [images <strong>of</strong>] cattle <strong>and</strong> horses.<br />

Philemon fr. 139 Kock IV-III B.C.<br />

See Athenaeus 13.606a-13.606b [77].<br />

140<br />

Phillipus, Anthologia Palat<strong>in</strong>a 9.742 A.D. I<br />

394


Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1915; repr. 1925).<br />

1Apaire/ mou te/nontoj, w} gewpo&ne,<br />

le/padna kai\ si/daron au)lakerga&tan:<br />

xalko_n ga_r a(mw~n ou)k e0sa&rkwsen Mu&rwn,<br />

te/xna d' e0zwpo&nhsen o1y<strong>in</strong> e1mpnoon,<br />

w(j polla&kij me ka)pomuka~sqai qe/le<strong>in</strong>:<br />

ei0j e1rga d' ou)k ei1ase prosdh&saj ba&sei.<br />

Take <strong>of</strong>f from my neck, husb<strong>and</strong>man, the collar,<br />

<strong>and</strong> free me from the iron furrow-cutter; for Myron<br />

did not make my bronze <strong>in</strong>to flesh, but his art gave<br />

me the aspect <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g alive, so that <strong>of</strong>ten I even<br />

wish to low. He did not, however, let me go to<br />

work, but tied me to the base.<br />

141<br />

Plato, Cratylus 424d-425a IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera I (Oxford, 1900; repr. 1967).<br />

Translation: H. N. Fowler, ed., tr., Plato. Cratylus. Parmenides. Greater Hippias. Lesser<br />

Hippias (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1926; repr. 1963).<br />

[SW.] w3sper oi9 zwgra&foi boulo&menoi a)fomoiou~n e0ni/ote me\n o1streon mo&non<br />

e0ph&negkan, e0ni/ote de\ o(tiou~n a1llo tw~n farma&kwn, e1sti de\ o3te polla_ sugkera&-<br />

santej, oi[on o3tan a)ndrei/kelon skeua&zws<strong>in</strong> h2 a1llo ti tw~n toiou&twn—w(j a2n<br />

oi]mai dokh|~ e9ka&sth h( ei0kw_n dei=sqai e9ka&stou farma&kou—ou3tw dh_ kai\ h(mei=j ta_<br />

stoixei=a e0pi\ ta_ pra&gmata e0poi/somen, kai\ e4n e0pi\ e3n, ou{ a2n dokh|~ dei=n, kai\<br />

su&mpolla, poiou~ntej o4 dh_ sullaba_j kalou~s<strong>in</strong>, kai\ sullaba_j au} suntiqe/ntej, e0c<br />

w{n ta& te o)no&mata kai\ ta_ r(h&mata sunti/qentai: kai\ pa&l<strong>in</strong> e0k tw~n o)noma&twn kai\<br />

r(hma&twn me/ga h1dh ti kai\ kalo_n kai\ o3lon susth&somen, w3sper e0kei= to_ zw|~on th|~<br />

grafikh|~, e0ntau~qa to_n lo&gon th|~ o)nomastikh|~ h2 r(htorikh|~ h2 h3tij e0sti\n h( te/xnh.<br />

SOCRATES. Just as pa<strong>in</strong>ters, when they wish to produce an imitation, sometimes use<br />

only red, sometimes, some other color, <strong>and</strong> sometimes mix many colors, as when they are<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g a picture <strong>of</strong> a man or someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> that sort, employ<strong>in</strong>g each color, I suppose, as<br />

they th<strong>in</strong>k the particular picture dem<strong>and</strong>s it. In just this way we, too, shall apply letters to<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs, us<strong>in</strong>g one letter for one th<strong>in</strong>g, when that seems to be required, or many letters<br />

together, form<strong>in</strong>g syllables, as they are called, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> turn comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g syllables, <strong>and</strong> by<br />

their comb<strong>in</strong>ation form<strong>in</strong>g nouns <strong>and</strong> verbs. And from nouns <strong>and</strong> verbs aga<strong>in</strong> we shall<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ally construct someth<strong>in</strong>g great <strong>and</strong> fair <strong>and</strong> complete. Just as <strong>in</strong> our comparison we<br />

made the zw|~on by the art <strong>of</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, so now we shall make language by the art <strong>of</strong><br />

nam<strong>in</strong>g, or <strong>of</strong> rhetoric, or whatever it be.<br />

142<br />

395


Plato, Cratylus 429a IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera I (Oxford, 1900; repr. 1967).<br />

Translation: H. N. Fowler, ed., tr., Plato. Cratylus. Parmenides. Greater Hippias. Lesser<br />

Hippias (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1926; repr. 1963).<br />

[SW.] zwgra&foi ei0si/n pou oi9 me\n xei/rouj, oi9 de\ a)mei/nouj;<br />

[KR.] Pa&nu ge.<br />

[SW.] Ou)kou~n oi9 me\n a)mei/nouj ta_ au(tw~n e1rga kalli/w pare/xontai, ta_ zw|~a,<br />

oi9 de\ faulo&tera; kai\ oi0kodo&moi w(sau&twj oi9 me\n kalli/ouj ta_j oi0ki/aj<br />

e0rga&zontai, oi9 de\ ai0sxi/ouj;<br />

[KR.] Nai/.<br />

[SW.] ]Ar' ou}n kai\ nomoqe/tai oi9 me\n kalli/w ta_ [e1rga] au(tw~n pare/xontai, oi9 de\<br />

ai0sxi/w;<br />

SOCRATES: Some pa<strong>in</strong>ters are better, <strong>and</strong> others worse, are they not?<br />

CRATYLUS: Certa<strong>in</strong>ly.<br />

SOCRATES: And the better produce better works—that is, their pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs—<strong>and</strong> the<br />

others worse works? And likewise some builders build better houses <strong>and</strong> others worse?<br />

143<br />

Plato, Critias 107b-107e IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: R. Bury, ed., tr., Plato IX (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1960).<br />

mi/mhs<strong>in</strong> me\n ga_r dh_ kai\ a)peikasi/an ta_ para_ pa&ntwn h(mw~n r(hqe/nta<br />

xrew&n pou gene/sqai: th_n de\ tw~n grafe/wn ei0dwlopoii/an<br />

peri\ ta_ qei=a& te kai\ ta_ a)nqrw&p<strong>in</strong>a sw&mata gignome/nhn<br />

i1dwmen r(a|stw&nhj te pe/ri kai\ xalepo&thtoj pro_j to_ toi=j<br />

o(rw~s<strong>in</strong> dokei=n a)poxrw&ntwj memimh~sqai, kai\ katoyo&meqa o3ti<br />

gh~n me\n kai\ o1rh kai\ potamou_j kai\ u3lhn ou)rano&n te su&m-<br />

panta kai\ ta_ peri\ au)to_n o1nta kai\ i0o&nta prw~ton me\n a)gapw~-<br />

men a1n ti/j ti kai\ braxu_ pro_j o(moio&thta au)tw~n a)pomimei=sqai<br />

dunato_j h|}, pro_j de\ tou&toij, a3te ou)de\n ei0do&tej a)kribe\j peri\<br />

tw~n toiou&twn, ou1te e0ceta&zomen ou1te e0le/gxomen ta_ gegram-<br />

me/na, skiagrafi/a| de\ a)safei= kai\ a)pathlw|~ xrw&meqa peri\<br />

au)ta&: ta_ de\ h(me/tera o(po&tan tij e0pixeirh|~ sw&mata a)peika&-<br />

ze<strong>in</strong>, o)ce/wj ai0sqano&menoi to_ paraleipo&menon dia_ th_n a)ei\<br />

su&noikon katano&hs<strong>in</strong> xalepoi\ kritai\ gigno&meqa tw|~ mh_ pa&saj<br />

pa&ntwj ta_j o(moio&thtaj a)podido&nti. tau)to_n dh_ kai\ kata_<br />

tou_j lo&gouj i0dei=n dei= gigno&menon, o3ti ta_ me\n ou)ra&nia kai\<br />

qei=a a)gapw~men kai\ smikrw~j ei0ko&ta lego&mena, ta_ de\ qnhta_<br />

kai\ a)nqrw&p<strong>in</strong>a a)kribw~j e0ceta&zomen. e0k dh_ tou~ paraxrh~ma<br />

(e.) nu~n lego&mena, to_ pre/pon a2n mh_ dunw&meqa pa&ntwj a)podido&-<br />

nai, suggignw&ske<strong>in</strong> xrew&n: ou) ga_r w(j r(a|&dia ta_ qnhta_ a)ll'<br />

w(j xalepa_ pro_j do&can o1nta a)peika&ze<strong>in</strong> dei= dianoei=sqai.<br />

396


<strong>The</strong> accounts given by all us must be, <strong>of</strong> course, <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> imitations <strong>and</strong><br />

representations; <strong>and</strong> if we look at the portraiture <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> human bodies as<br />

executed by pa<strong>in</strong>ters, <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong> the ease or difficulty with which they succeed <strong>in</strong><br />

imitat<strong>in</strong>g their subjects <strong>in</strong> the op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> onlookers, we shall notice <strong>in</strong> the first place that<br />

as regards the earth <strong>and</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>and</strong> rivers <strong>and</strong> woods <strong>and</strong> the whole <strong>of</strong> heaven,<br />

with the th<strong>in</strong>gs that exist <strong>and</strong> move there<strong>in</strong>, we are content if a man is also able to<br />

represent them with even a small degree <strong>of</strong> likeness; <strong>and</strong> further, that, <strong>in</strong>asmuch as we<br />

have no exact knowledge about such subjects, we do not exam<strong>in</strong>e closely or criticize the<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs, but tolerate, <strong>in</strong> such cases, an <strong>in</strong>exact <strong>and</strong> deceptive sketch. On the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

whenever a pa<strong>in</strong>ter tries to render a likeness <strong>of</strong> our own bodies, we quickly perceive what<br />

is defective because <strong>of</strong> our constant familiar acqua<strong>in</strong>tance with them, <strong>and</strong> become sever<br />

critics <strong>of</strong> him who fails to br<strong>in</strong>g out to the full all the po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> similarity. And precisely<br />

the same th<strong>in</strong>g happens, as we should notice, <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> discourse: <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong> what<br />

is celestial <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e we are satisfied if the account possesses even a small degree <strong>of</strong><br />

likelihood, but we exam<strong>in</strong>e with precision what is mortal <strong>and</strong> human. To an account<br />

given now on the spur <strong>of</strong> the moment <strong>in</strong>dulgence must be granted, should we fail to make<br />

it a wholly fitt<strong>in</strong>g representation; for one must conceive <strong>of</strong> mortal objects as be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

difficult, <strong>and</strong> not easy, to represent satisfactorily.<br />

144<br />

Plato, Leges 668c-669b IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera V (Oxford, 1907; repr. 1967).<br />

Translation: T. L. Pangle, tr., <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato (New York, 1980).<br />

[AQ.] Ei0si\n dh&pou kata_ th_n o1y<strong>in</strong> h(mi=n a)peikasi/ai muri/ai.<br />

[KL.] Nai/.<br />

[AQ.] Ti/ ou}n ei1 tij kai\ e0n tou&toij a)gnooi= tw~n memimhme/nwn o3ti pot' e0sti\n<br />

e3kaston tw~n swma&twn; a}r' a1n pote to& ge o)rqw~j au)tw~n ei0rgasme/non gnoi/h;<br />

le/gw de\ to_ toio&nde, oi[on tou_j a)riqmou_j tou~ sw&matoj kai\ e9ka&stwn tw~n merw~n<br />

ta_j qe/seij ei0 e1xei, o3soi te/ ei0s<strong>in</strong> kai\ o(poi=a par' o(poi=a au)tw~n kei/mena th_n<br />

prosh&kousan ta&c<strong>in</strong> a)pei/lhfen—kai\ e1ti dh_ xrw&mata& te kai\ sxh&mata—h2 pa&nta<br />

tau~ta tetaragme/nwj ei1rgastai: mw~n dokei= tau~t' a1n pote diagnw~nai/ tij to_<br />

para&pan a)gnow~n o3ti pot' e0sti\ to_ memimhme/non zw|~on;<br />

[KL.] Kai\ pw~j;<br />

[AQ.] Ti/ d' ei0 gignw&skoimen o3ti to_ gegramme/non h2 to_ peplasme/non e0sti\n<br />

a1nqrwpoj, kai\ ta_ me/rh pa&nta ta_ e9autou~ kai\ xrw&mata a3ma kai\ sxh&mata<br />

a)pei/lhfen u(po_ th~j te/xnhj; a}ra& ge a)nagkai=on h1dh tw|~ tau~ta gno&nti kai\ e0kei=no<br />

e9toi/mwj gignw&ske<strong>in</strong>, ei1te kalo_n ei1te o3ph| pote\ e0llipe\j a2n ei1h ka&llouj;<br />

[KL.] Pa&ntej menta2n w(j e1poj ei0pei=n, w} ce/ne, ta_ kala_ tw~n zw|&wn e0gignw&skomen.<br />

[AQ.] 0Orqo&tata le/geij. a}r' ou}n ou) peri\ e9ka&sthn ei0ko&na, kai\ e0n grafikh|~ kai\ e0n<br />

mousikh|~ kai\ pa&nth|, to_n me/llonta e1mfrona krith_n e1sesqai dei= tau~ta tri/a e1xe<strong>in</strong>, o3<br />

te/ e0sti prw~ton gignw&ske<strong>in</strong>, e1peita w(j o)rqw~j, e1peiq' w(j eu}, to_ tri/ton, ei1rgastai<br />

tw~n ei0ko&nwn h(tisou~n r(h&masi/ te kai\ me/lesi kai\ toi=j r(uqmoi=j;<br />

ATHENIAN. <strong>The</strong>re are <strong>of</strong> course myriad images which are visible to our eye.<br />

397


KLEINIAS. Yes.<br />

ATHENIAN. What then, if someone doesn’t know what each <strong>of</strong> the bodies <strong>of</strong> the th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

imitated is? Would he ever know what is correctly executed <strong>in</strong> them? What I mean is<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g like this: doesn’t he have to know whether the imitation captures the number<br />

<strong>and</strong> the arrangement <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> the parts, how many there are <strong>and</strong> how they fit next to one<br />

another <strong>in</strong> the appropriate order, <strong>and</strong> also the colors <strong>and</strong> shapes, or whether all these<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs have been put together <strong>in</strong> a confused way? Do you th<strong>in</strong>k someone can ever know<br />

these th<strong>in</strong>gs if he is completely ignorant <strong>of</strong> what the liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g is that has been imitated?<br />

KLEINIAS. How could he?<br />

ATHENIAN. What if we were to know that the th<strong>in</strong>g that has been pa<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>and</strong><br />

sculptured is a human be<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> that all his own parts, colors, <strong>and</strong> shapes have been<br />

captured by the art? Does it follow necessarily that whoever knows about these th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

also readily knows whether the work is beautiful or just where it is deficient <strong>in</strong> beauty?<br />

KLEINIAS. That would mean, stranger, that all <strong>of</strong> us, so to speak, know what is beautiful<br />

<strong>in</strong> any pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

ATHENIAN. What you say is very correct. Isn’t it the case, then, that with regard to<br />

each image, <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> music <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> all the rest, the person who is go<strong>in</strong>g to be a<br />

prudent judge must have three k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> knowledge? He must know first what the th<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is, <strong>and</strong> then know how correctly, <strong>and</strong> then—the third th<strong>in</strong>g—how well, any <strong>of</strong> the images<br />

<strong>of</strong> it <strong>in</strong> words, tunes, <strong>and</strong> rhythms are produced.<br />

145<br />

Plato, Leges 769a-769d IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera V (Oxford, 1907; repr. 1967).<br />

Translation: T. L. Pangle, tr., <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato (New York, 1980).<br />

[AQ.] Oi]sq' o3ti kaqa&per zwgra&fwn ou)de\n pe/raj e1xe<strong>in</strong> h( pragmatei/a dokei= peri\<br />

e9ka&stwn tw~n zw|&wn, a)ll' h2 tou~ xrai/ne<strong>in</strong> h2 a)poxrai/ne<strong>in</strong>, h2 o(tidh&pote kalou~si to_<br />

toiou~ton oi9 zwgra&fwn pai=dej, ou)k a1n pote dokei= pau&sasqai kosmou~sa,<br />

w3ste e0pi/dos<strong>in</strong> mhke/t' e1xe<strong>in</strong> ei0j to_ kalli/w te kai\ fanerw&tera gi/gnesqai ta_<br />

gegramme/na.<br />

[KL.] Sxedo_n e0nnow~ a)kou&wn kai\ au)to_j tau~ta a4 le/geij, e0pei\ e0ntribh&j ge<br />

ou)damw~j ge/gona th|~ toiau&th| te/xnh|.<br />

[AQ.] Kai\ ou)de/n ge e0bla&bhj. xrhsw&meqa& ge mh_n tw|~ nu~n paratuxo&nti peri\ au)th~j<br />

h(mi=n lo&gw| to_ toio&nde, w(j ei1 pote/ tij e0p<strong>in</strong>oh&seie gra&yai te w(j ka&lliston zw|~on<br />

kai\ tou~t' au} mhde/pote e0pi\ faulo&teron a)ll' e0pi\ to_ be/ltion i1sxe<strong>in</strong> tou~ e0pio&ntoj<br />

a)ei\ xro&nou, sunnoei=j o3ti qnhto_j w1n, ei0 mh& t<strong>in</strong>a katalei/yei dia&doxon tou~<br />

e0panorqou~n te, e0a&n ti sfa&llhtai to_ zw|~on u(po_ xro&nwn, kai\ to_ paraleifqe\n u(po_<br />

th~j a)sqenei/aj th~j e9autou~ pro_j th_n te/xnhn oi[o&j te ei0j to_ pro&sqen e1stai<br />

faidru&nwn poiei=n e0pidido&nai, smikro&n t<strong>in</strong>a xro&non au)tw|~ po&noj paramenei=<br />

pa&mpoluj;<br />

[KL.] 0Alhqh~.<br />

[AQ.] Ti/ ou}n; a}r' ou) toiou~ton dokei= soi to_ tou~ nomoqe/tou bou&lhm' ei]nai; prw~ton<br />

me\n gra&yai tou_j no&mouj pro_j th_n a)kri/beian kata_ du&nam<strong>in</strong> i9kanw~j: e1peita<br />

proi"o&ntoj tou~ xro&nou kai\ tw~n doca&ntwn e1rgw| peirw&menon, a}r' oi1ei t<strong>in</strong>a_ ou3twj<br />

398


a1frona gegone/nai nomoqe/thn, w3st' a)gnoei=n o3ti pa&mpolla a)na&gkh<br />

paralei/pesqai toiau~ta, a4 dei= t<strong>in</strong>a sunepo&menon e0panorqou~n, i3na mhdamh|~ xei/rwn,<br />

belti/wn de\ h( politei/a kai\ o( ko&smoj a)ei\ gi/gnhtai peri\ th_n w| )kisme/nhn au)tw|~<br />

po&l<strong>in</strong>;<br />

ATHENIAN. You know how the pa<strong>in</strong>ters’ activity, for example, never seems to f<strong>in</strong>ish<br />

work<strong>in</strong>g on each <strong>of</strong> the figures, but keeps touch<strong>in</strong>g up or highlight<strong>in</strong>g—or whatever the<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>ters’ disciples call such activity? It seems never to cease its adorn<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

never to reach a po<strong>in</strong>t where there can be no further improvement <strong>of</strong> the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs as<br />

regards beauty <strong>and</strong> clarity.<br />

KLEINIAS. I too know pretty well these th<strong>in</strong>gs you’re talk<strong>in</strong>g about, by hearsay—for I<br />

am not at all practiced, at least, <strong>in</strong> such an art.<br />

ATHENIAN. That’s no h<strong>in</strong>drance for you. We’ll still make use <strong>of</strong> this allusion to it<br />

that’s cropped up <strong>in</strong> our discussion now, <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g like the follow<strong>in</strong>g way: suppose<br />

someone once took it <strong>in</strong>to his head to pa<strong>in</strong>t the most beautiful figure possible, one that<br />

would never get worse but would always improve as time went by. Don’t you see that<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce he’s mortal, he’ll have to leave beh<strong>in</strong>d a successor, able to make it right if the<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g suffers from decay at the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> time, as well as to make future touch-ups that<br />

improve the deficiencies left by his own artistic weaknesses? Otherwise, won’t his very<br />

great labor last but a brief time?<br />

KLEINIAS. That’s true.<br />

ATHENIAN. Well, then, don’t you th<strong>in</strong>k the lawgiver has such a purpose? He first<br />

writes his laws with as nearly adequate a precision as he can muster. <strong>The</strong>n, with the<br />

passage <strong>of</strong> time, as his op<strong>in</strong>ions are tried out <strong>in</strong> deed, do you suppose there’s any<br />

lawgiver who is so imprudent as to be ignorant <strong>of</strong> the fact that he must necessarily have<br />

left very many such th<strong>in</strong>gs that require be<strong>in</strong>g set right by some follower, if the regime <strong>and</strong><br />

order <strong>of</strong> the city he has founded are always to become <strong>in</strong> no way worse but <strong>in</strong>stead<br />

better?<br />

146<br />

Plato, Politicus 277c IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera I (Oxford, 1900; repr. 1967).<br />

Translation: H. N. Fowler, ed., tr., Plato. Politicus. Philebus (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1962).<br />

dio_ makrote/ran th_n a)po&deic<strong>in</strong> pepoih&kamen kai\ pa&ntwj tw|~ mu&qw| te/loj ou)k<br />

e0pe/qemen, a)ll' a)texnw~j o( lo&goj h(mi=n w3sper zw|~on th_n e1cwqen me\n perigrafh_n<br />

e1oiken i9kanw~j e1xe<strong>in</strong>, th_n de\ oi[on toi=j farma&koij kai\ th|~ sugkra&sei tw~n<br />

xrwma&twn e0na&rgeian ou)k a)peilhfe/nai pw. grafh~j de\ kai\ sumpa&shj<br />

xeirourgi/aj le/cei kai\ lo&gw| dhlou~n pa~n zw|~on ma~llon pre/pei toi=j duname/noij<br />

e3pesqai: toi=j d' a1lloij dia_ xeirourgiw~n.<br />

So we have made our discourse too long <strong>and</strong> after all have never made an end <strong>of</strong> the tale,<br />

but our talk, just like a picture <strong>of</strong> a liv<strong>in</strong>g creature, seems to have a good enough outl<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

but not yet to have received the clearness that comes from pigments <strong>and</strong> the blend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

colors. And yet it is more fitt<strong>in</strong>g to portray any liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g by speech <strong>and</strong> argument than<br />

399


y pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g or any h<strong>and</strong>icraft whatsoever to persons who are able to follow the argument;<br />

but to others it is better to do it by means <strong>of</strong> works <strong>of</strong> craftsmanship.<br />

147<br />

Plato, Respublica 375d-375e IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera IV (Oxford, 1902; repr. 1968).<br />

Translation: P. Shorey, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic I (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass.,<br />

1930; repr. 1963).<br />

1Idoi me\n a1n tij kai\ e0n a1lloij zw|&oij, ou) menta2n h3kista e0n w| { h(mei=j pareba&llomen<br />

tw|~ fu&laki. oi]sqa ga&r pou tw~n gennai/wn kunw~n, o3ti tou~to fu&sei au)tw~n to_ h}qoj,<br />

pro_j me\n tou_j sunh&qeij te kai\ gnwri/mouj w(j oi[o&n te pra|ota&touj ei]nai,<br />

pro_j de\ tou_j a)gnw~taj tou)nanti/on. Oi]da me/ntoi. Tou~to me\n a1ra, h}n d' e0gw&,<br />

dunato&n, kai\ ou) para_ fu&s<strong>in</strong> zhtou~men toiou~ton ei]nai to_n fu&laka. Ou)k e1oiken.<br />

“It may be observed <strong>in</strong> other animals, but especially <strong>in</strong> that which we likened to the<br />

guardian. You surely have observed <strong>in</strong> well-bred hounds that their natural disposition is<br />

to be most gentle to their familiars <strong>and</strong> those whom they recognize, but the contrary to<br />

those whom they do not know.” “I am aware <strong>of</strong> that.” “<strong>The</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g is possible then,” said I,<br />

“<strong>and</strong> it is not an unnatural requirement that we are look<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>in</strong> our guardian.” “It seems<br />

not.”<br />

148<br />

Plato, Respublica 420c IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera IV (Oxford, 1902; repr. 1968).<br />

Translation: G. R. F. Ferrari, ed., <strong>and</strong> T. Griffith, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic (Cambridge,<br />

2000).<br />

nu~n me\n ou}n, w(j oi0o&meqa, th_n eu)dai/mona pla&ttomen ou)k a)polabo&ntej o)li/gouj e0n<br />

au)th|~ toiou&touj t<strong>in</strong>a_j tiqe/ntej, a)ll' o3lhn: au)ti/ka de\ th_n e0nanti/an skeyo&meqa.<br />

#Wsper ou}n a2n ei0 h(ma~j a)ndria&nta gra&fontaj proselqw&n tij e1yege<br />

le/gwn o3ti ou) toi=j kalli/stoij tou~ zw|&ou ta_ ka&llista fa&rmaka prosti/qemen, oi9<br />

ga_r o)fqalmoi\ ka&lliston o2n ou)k o)strei/w| e0nalhlimme/noi ei]en a)lla_ me/lani, metri/wj<br />

a2n e0dokou~men pro_j au)to_n a)pologei=sqai le/gontej: “ ]W qauma&sie,<br />

mh_ oi1ou dei=n h(ma~j ou3tw kalou_j o)fqalmou_j gra&fe<strong>in</strong>, w3ste mhde\ o)fqalmou_j<br />

fai/nesqai, mhd' au} ta}lla me/rh, a)ll' a1qrei ei0 ta_ prosh&konta e9ka&stoij<br />

a)podido&ntej to_ o3lon kalo_n poiou~men.” kai\ dh_ kai\ nu~n mh_ a)na&gkaze h(ma~j<br />

toiau&thn eu)daimoni/an toi=j fu&laci prosa&pte<strong>in</strong>, h4 e0kei/nouj pa~n ma~llon<br />

a)perga&setai h2 fu&lakaj.<br />

What we are do<strong>in</strong>g at the moment, we believe, is not separat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f a few <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>habitants, <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g them happy, but construct<strong>in</strong>g a complete city, <strong>and</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

happy. We’ll have a look at its opposite later. Imag<strong>in</strong>e we were putt<strong>in</strong>g the colours on a<br />

statue <strong>of</strong> a man, <strong>and</strong> someone came along <strong>and</strong> told us we were do<strong>in</strong>g it wrong, s<strong>in</strong>ce we<br />

weren’t us<strong>in</strong>g the most beautiful colors for the most beautiful parts <strong>of</strong> the liv<strong>in</strong>g creature.<br />

400


<strong>The</strong> eyes, the most beautiful feature, had been colored black, not purple. We would<br />

regard it as a quite reasonable defense to say to him: “Hang on a m<strong>in</strong>ute. You surely<br />

don’t th<strong>in</strong>k, do you, that we should make the eyes—or any <strong>of</strong> the other parts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

body—so beautiful that they don’t even look like eyes. <strong>The</strong> th<strong>in</strong>g to ask yourself is<br />

whether by giv<strong>in</strong>g the right colours to everyth<strong>in</strong>g we are mak<strong>in</strong>g the whole th<strong>in</strong>g<br />

beautiful.” It’s the same with us. You mustn’t start forc<strong>in</strong>g us to give the guardians the<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess which will turn them <strong>in</strong>to anyth<strong>in</strong>g other than guardians.<br />

149<br />

Plato, Respublica 514c-515a IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera IV (Oxford, 1902; repr. 1968).<br />

Translation: G. R. F. Ferrari, ed., <strong>and</strong> T. Griffith, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic (Cambridge,<br />

2000).<br />

3Ora toi/nun para_ tou~to to_ teixi/on fe/rontaj a)nqrw&pouj skeu&h te pantodapa_<br />

u(pere/xonta tou~ teixi/ou kai\ a)ndria&ntaj kai\ a1lla zw|~a li/q<strong>in</strong>a& te kai\ cu&l<strong>in</strong>a kai\<br />

pantoi=a ei0rgasme/na,oi[on ei0ko_j tou_j me\n fqeggome/nouj, tou_j de\ sigw~ntaj tw~n<br />

parafero&ntwn.<br />

Picture also, along the length <strong>of</strong> the wall, people carry<strong>in</strong>g all sorts <strong>of</strong> implements which<br />

project above it, <strong>and</strong> statues <strong>of</strong> people <strong>and</strong> animals made <strong>of</strong> stone <strong>and</strong> wood <strong>and</strong> all k<strong>in</strong>ds<br />

<strong>of</strong> materials. As you’d expect, some <strong>of</strong> the people carry<strong>in</strong>g the objects are speak<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

while others are silent.<br />

150<br />

Plato, Respublica 598b-598c IV B.C.<br />

Text: J. Burnet, ed., Platonis opera IV (Oxford, 1902; repr. 1968).<br />

Translation: P. Shorey, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic II (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass.,<br />

1935; repr. 1963).<br />

[SW.] pro_j po&teron h( grafikh_ pepoi/htai peri\ e3kaston; po&tera pro_j to_ o1n, w(j<br />

e1xei, mimh&sasqai, h2 pro_j to_ fa<strong>in</strong>o&menon, w(j fai/netai, fanta&smatoj h2 a)lhqei/aj<br />

ou}sa mi/mhsij;<br />

[GL.] Fanta&smatoj, e1fh.<br />

[SW.] Po&rrw a1ra pou tou~ a)lhqou~j h( mimhtikh& e0st<strong>in</strong> kai/, w(j e1oiken, dia_ tou~to<br />

pa&nta a)perga&zetai, o3ti smikro&n ti e9ka&stou e0fa&ptetai, kai\ tou~to ei1dwlon. oi[on<br />

o( zwgra&foj, fame/n, zwgrafh&sei h(mi=n skutoto&mon, te/ktona, tou_j a1llouj<br />

dhmiourgou&j, peri\ ou)deno_j tou&twn e0pai5wn tw~n texnw~n: a)ll' o3mwj pai=da&j ge<br />

kai\ a1fronaj a)nqrw&pouj, ei0 a)gaqo_j ei1h zwgra&foj, gra&yaj a2n te/ktona kai\<br />

po&rrwqen e0pideiknu_j e0capatw|~ a2n tw|~ dokei=n w(j a)lhqw~j te/ktona ei]nai.<br />

SOCRATES. To which is pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g directed <strong>in</strong> every case, to the imitation <strong>of</strong> reality as it<br />

is or <strong>of</strong> appearance as it appears?<br />

GLAUCON. Is it an imitation <strong>of</strong> a phantasm or <strong>of</strong> the truth? “Of a phantasm,” he said.<br />

SOCRATES. <strong>The</strong>n the mimetic art is far removed from truth, <strong>and</strong> this, it seems, is the<br />

401


eason why it can produce everyth<strong>in</strong>g, because it touches or lays hold <strong>of</strong> only a small part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the object <strong>and</strong> that a phantom; as, for example, a pa<strong>in</strong>ter, we say, will pa<strong>in</strong>t us a<br />

cobbler, a carpenter, <strong>and</strong> other craftsmen, though he himself has no expertness <strong>in</strong> any <strong>of</strong><br />

these arts, but nevertheless if he were a good pa<strong>in</strong>ter, by exhibit<strong>in</strong>g at a distance his<br />

picture <strong>of</strong> a carpenter he would deceive children <strong>and</strong> foolish men, <strong>and</strong> make them believe<br />

it to be a real carpenter.<br />

151<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 34.57-34.58 A.D. I<br />

Text: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-XXXV (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

Myronem Eleutheris natum, Hageladae et ipsum discipulum, bucula maxime nobilitavit<br />

celebratis versibus laudata, qu<strong>and</strong>o alieno plerique <strong>in</strong>genio magis quam suo<br />

commendantur. Fecit et Ladam et discobolon et Perseum et pristas et Satyrum<br />

admirantem tibias et M<strong>in</strong>ervam, Delphicos pentathlos, pancratiastas, Herculem, qui est<br />

apud circum maximum <strong>in</strong> aede Pompei Magni. Fecisse et cicadae monumentum ac<br />

locustae carm<strong>in</strong>ibus suis Er<strong>in</strong>na significant.<br />

Myron, who was born at Eleutherai, <strong>and</strong> was a pupil <strong>of</strong> Ageladas, was most renowned for<br />

his statue <strong>of</strong> a heifer, a work which is praised <strong>in</strong> well-known verses—for many people<br />

ga<strong>in</strong> their reputations through someone else’s <strong>in</strong>ventiveness rather than their own. He<br />

also made a dog, a Discus-thrower, a Perseus <strong>and</strong> the sea-monster, a Satyr marvel<strong>in</strong>g at<br />

the flutes, <strong>and</strong> an Athena, contestants <strong>in</strong> the pentathlon at Delphi, pankratiasts, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

Herakles which is now <strong>in</strong> the round temple <strong>of</strong> Pompey the Great <strong>in</strong> the Circus Maximus.<br />

He also made a monument to a cicada <strong>and</strong> a locust, as Er<strong>in</strong>na <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>in</strong> her poem.<br />

152<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 34.71 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Calamidis enim quadrigae aurigam suum <strong>in</strong>posuit, ne melior <strong>in</strong> equorum effigie defecisse<br />

<strong>in</strong> hom<strong>in</strong>e crederetur. Ipse Calamis et alias quadrigas bigasque fecit equis semper s<strong>in</strong>e<br />

aemulo expressis; sed, ne videatur <strong>in</strong> hom<strong>in</strong>um effigie <strong>in</strong>ferior, Alcmena nullius est<br />

nobilior.<br />

<strong>The</strong> k<strong>in</strong>dness also <strong>of</strong> Praxiteles is represented <strong>in</strong> sculpture, as <strong>in</strong> the Chariot <strong>and</strong> Four <strong>of</strong><br />

Calamis he contributed the charioteer, <strong>in</strong> order that the sculptor might not be thought to<br />

have failed <strong>in</strong> the human figure although more successful <strong>in</strong> represent<strong>in</strong>g horses. Calamis<br />

himself also made other chariots, some with four horses <strong>and</strong> some with two, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

execut<strong>in</strong>g the horses he was <strong>in</strong>variably unrivalled.<br />

402


153<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 34.72 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Amphicrates Leaena laudatur. Scortum haec, lyrae cantu familiaris Harmodio et<br />

Aristogitoni. Consilia eorum de tyrannicidio usque <strong>in</strong> mortem excruciata a tyrannis non<br />

prodidit; quam ob rem Athenienses, et honorem habere ei volentes nec tamen scortum<br />

celebrasse, animal nom<strong>in</strong>is eius fecere atque, ut <strong>in</strong>tellegeretur causa honoris, <strong>in</strong> opere<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guam addi artifice vetuerunt.<br />

Amphicrates is praised for his Leaena; she was a harlot admitted to the friendship <strong>of</strong><br />

Harmodius <strong>and</strong> Aristogeiton because <strong>of</strong> her skill as a harpist, who though put to the<br />

torture by the tyrants till she died refused to betray their plot to assass<strong>in</strong>ate them.<br />

Consequently the Athenians wish<strong>in</strong>g to do her honour <strong>and</strong> yet unwill<strong>in</strong>g to have made a<br />

harlot famous, had a statue made <strong>of</strong> a lioness, as that was her name, <strong>and</strong> to <strong>in</strong>dicate the<br />

reason for the honour paid her <strong>in</strong>structed the artist to represent the animal as hav<strong>in</strong>g no<br />

tongue.<br />

154<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 34.75 A.D. I<br />

Text: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-XXXV (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

Canachus Apoll<strong>in</strong>em nudum, qui Philesius cognom<strong>in</strong>atur, <strong>in</strong> Didymaeo Aeg<strong>in</strong>etica aeris<br />

temperatura, cervumque una ita vestigiis suspendit, ut l<strong>in</strong>um subter pedes trahatur alterno<br />

morsu calce digitisque ret<strong>in</strong>entibus solum, ita vertebrato ungue utrisque <strong>in</strong> partibus, ut a<br />

repulsu per vices resiliat.<br />

Kanachos [was the sculptor <strong>of</strong>] a nude Apollo, which bears the cognomen Philesios, <strong>in</strong><br />

the sanctuary at Didyma, made from bronze <strong>of</strong> the Aeg<strong>in</strong>itan formula; <strong>and</strong> with it a stag<br />

which is suspended <strong>in</strong> its tracks <strong>in</strong> such a way that a str<strong>in</strong>g can be drawn underneath its<br />

feet, with the heel <strong>and</strong> toe alternately reta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g their grip, for a “tooth” on each part is so<br />

geared that when one is dislodged by pressure the other <strong>in</strong> its turn spr<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to place.<br />

155<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 34.80 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

403


Menaechmi vitulus genu premitur replicata cervice. Ipse Menaechmus scripsit de sua<br />

arte.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a Bull-calf by Menaechmus, on which a man is press<strong>in</strong>g his knee as he bends its<br />

neck back; Menaechmus has written a treatise about his own work.<br />

156<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 35.65-35.66 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Aequales eius et aemuli fuere Timanthes, Androcydes, Eupompus, Parrhasius.<br />

Descendisse hic <strong>in</strong> certamen cum Zeuxide traditur et, cum ille detulisset uvas pictas tanto<br />

successu, ut <strong>in</strong> scaenam aves advolarent, ipse detulisse l<strong>in</strong>teum pictum ita veritate<br />

repraesentata, ut Zeuxis alitum iudicio tumens flagitaret t<strong>and</strong>em remoto l<strong>in</strong>teo ostendi<br />

picturam atque <strong>in</strong>tellecto errore concederet palmam <strong>in</strong>genuo pudore, quoniam ipse<br />

volucres fefellisset, Parrhasius autem se artificem. Fertur et postea Zeuxis p<strong>in</strong>xisse<br />

puerum uvas ferentem, ad quas cum advolassent aves, eaden <strong>in</strong>genuitate processit iratus<br />

operi et dixit: ‘uvas melius p<strong>in</strong>xi quam puerum, nam si et hoc consummassem, aves<br />

timere debuerant.’<br />

His contemporaries <strong>and</strong> rivals were Timanthes, Androcydes, Eupompus <strong>and</strong> Parrhasius.<br />

This last, it is recorded, entered <strong>in</strong>to a competition with Zeuxis, who produced a picture<br />

<strong>of</strong> grapes so successfully represented that birds flew up to the stage-build<strong>in</strong>gs; whereupon<br />

Parrhasius himself produced such a realistic picture <strong>of</strong> a curta<strong>in</strong> that Zeuxis, proud <strong>of</strong> the<br />

verdict <strong>of</strong> the birds, requested that the curta<strong>in</strong> should now be drawn <strong>and</strong> the picture<br />

displayed; <strong>and</strong> when he realized his mistake, with a modesty that did him honor he<br />

yielded up the prize, say<strong>in</strong>g that whereas he had deceived birds Parrhasius had deceived<br />

him, an artist. It is said that Zeuxis also subsequently pa<strong>in</strong>ted a Child Carry<strong>in</strong>g Grapes,<br />

<strong>and</strong> when birds flew to the fruit with the same frankness as before he strode up to the<br />

picture <strong>in</strong> anger with it <strong>and</strong> said, “I have pa<strong>in</strong>ted the grapes better than the child, as if I<br />

had made a success <strong>of</strong> that as well, the birds would <strong>in</strong>evitably have been afraid <strong>of</strong> it”<br />

157<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 35.85 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Idem perfecta opera proponebat <strong>in</strong> pergola transeuntibus atque, ipse post tabulam latens,<br />

vitia quae notarentur auscultabat, vulgum diligentiorem iudicem quam se praeferens;<br />

feruntque reprehensum a sutore, quod <strong>in</strong> crepidis una pauciores <strong>in</strong>tus fecisset ansas,<br />

eodem postero die superbo emendatione prist<strong>in</strong>ae admonitionis cavillante circa crus,<br />

<strong>in</strong>dignatum prospexisse denuntiantem, ne supra crepidam sutor iudicaret, quod et ipsum<br />

<strong>in</strong> proverbium abiit.<br />

404


Another habit <strong>of</strong> his was when he had f<strong>in</strong>ished his works to place them <strong>in</strong> a gallery <strong>in</strong> the<br />

view <strong>of</strong> passers by, <strong>and</strong> he himself stood out <strong>of</strong> sight beh<strong>in</strong>d the picture <strong>and</strong> listened to<br />

hear what faults were noticed, rat<strong>in</strong>g the public as a more observant critic than himself.<br />

And it is said that he was found fault with by a shoemaker because <strong>in</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g a subject’s<br />

s<strong>and</strong>als he has represented the loops <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> them as one too few, <strong>and</strong> the next day the<br />

same critic was so proud <strong>of</strong> the artist’s correct<strong>in</strong>g the fault <strong>in</strong>dicated by his previous<br />

objection that he found fault with the leg, but Apelles <strong>in</strong>dignantly looked out from beh<strong>in</strong>d<br />

the picture <strong>and</strong> rebuked him, say<strong>in</strong>g that a shoemaker <strong>in</strong> his criticism must not go beyond<br />

the s<strong>and</strong>al—a remark that has also passed <strong>in</strong>to a proverb.<br />

158<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 35.95 A.D. I<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-<br />

XXXV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Est et equus eius, sive fuit, pictus <strong>in</strong> certam<strong>in</strong>e, quo iudicium ad mutas quadripedes<br />

provocavit ab hom<strong>in</strong>ibus. Namque ambitu praevalere aemulos sentiens s<strong>in</strong>gulorum<br />

pictures <strong>in</strong>ductis equis ostendit: Apellis tantum equo adh<strong>in</strong>nivere, idque et postea simper<br />

evenit, ut experimentum artis illud stentaretur.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is, or was, a picture <strong>of</strong> a Horse by him pa<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> a competition, by which he<br />

carried his appeal for judgment from mank<strong>in</strong>d to the dumb quadrupeds; for perceiv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that his rivals were gett<strong>in</strong>g the better <strong>of</strong> him by <strong>in</strong>trigue, he had some horses brought <strong>and</strong><br />

showed them their pictures one by one; <strong>and</strong> the horses only began to neigh when they<br />

saw the horse pa<strong>in</strong>ted by Apelles; <strong>and</strong> this always happened subsequently, show<strong>in</strong>g it to<br />

be a sound test <strong>in</strong> artistic skill.<br />

159<br />

Pl<strong>in</strong>y 35.131-35.133 A.D. I<br />

Text: H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-XXXV (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995).<br />

Translation: J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965;<br />

second ed., Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998).<br />

Ephesi vero est megabyzi, sacerdotis Ephesiae Dianae, sepulchrum, Athenis necyomantea<br />

Homeri. Hanc vendere Attalo regi noluit talentis LX potiusque patriae suae donavit<br />

abundans opibus. Fecit et gr<strong>and</strong>es picturas, <strong>in</strong> quibus sunt Calypso et Io et Andromeda;<br />

Alex<strong>and</strong>er quoque <strong>in</strong> Pompei porticibus praecellens et Calypso sedens huic eidem<br />

adscribuntur. Quadripedum prosperrime canes expressit.<br />

At Ephesos there is a Sepulchre <strong>of</strong> a Megabyzus, the priest <strong>of</strong> Artemis at Ephesos, <strong>and</strong> at<br />

Athens the Nekyomanteia [“Invocation <strong>of</strong> the Dead”] after Homer. This picture he<br />

[Nikias] refused to sell to K<strong>in</strong>g Attalos for 60 talents <strong>and</strong> gave it rather to his home town,<br />

405


s<strong>in</strong>ce he had plenty <strong>of</strong> money already. He also did some large pictures, among which are<br />

a Calypso, an Io, <strong>and</strong> an Andromeda; also the very excellent Alex<strong>and</strong>er <strong>in</strong> the porticoes <strong>of</strong><br />

Pompey <strong>and</strong> a Seated Calypso are ascribed to him. Of four-footed animals he rendered<br />

dogs the best.<br />

Plutarch, Moralia 280C A.D. I-II<br />

See Plutach, Quaestiones Romanae 280C [160].<br />

Plutarch, Moralia 290D A.D. I-II<br />

See Plutarch, Quaestiones Romanae 290D [161].<br />

160<br />

Plutarch, Quaestiones Romanae 280C A.D. I-II<br />

(=Moralia 280C)<br />

Text: J.B. Titchener, ed., Plutarchi moralia II.I (Leipzig, 1935; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: F. C. Babbitt, ed., tr., Plutarch. Moralia IV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1936; repr. 1993).<br />

tw|~ de\ kuni\ pa&ntej w(j e1poj ei0pei=n 3Ellhnej e0xrw~nto kai\ xrw~ntai/ ge me/xri nu~n<br />

e1nioi sfagi/w| pro_j tou_j kaqarmou&j: kai\ th|~ 9Eka&th| skula&kia meta_ tw~n<br />

a1llwn kaqarsi/wn e0kfe/rousi kai\ perima&ttousi skulaki/oij tou_j a(gnismou~<br />

deome/nouj, periskulakismo_n to_ toiou~to ge/noj tou~ kaqarmou~ kalou~ntej:<br />

Nearly all the Greeks used a dog as the sacrificial victim for ceremonies <strong>of</strong> purification;<br />

<strong>and</strong> some, at least, make use <strong>of</strong> it even to this day. <strong>The</strong>y br<strong>in</strong>g forth for Hecate puppies<br />

along with the other materials for the purification, <strong>and</strong> rub round about with puppies such<br />

persons as are <strong>in</strong> need <strong>of</strong> cleans<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> purification they call periskylakismos<br />

(“purification”).<br />

161<br />

Plutarch, Quaestiones Romanae 290D A.D. I-II<br />

(=Moralia 290D)<br />

Text: J.B. Titchener, ed., Plutarchi moralia II.I (Leipzig, 1935; repr. 1971).<br />

Translation: F. C. Babbitt, ed., tr., Plutarch. Moralia IV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1936; repr. 1993).<br />

ou) mh_n ou)de\ kaqareu&e<strong>in</strong> w| 1onto panta&pas<strong>in</strong> oi9 palaioi\ to_ zw|~on: o)lumpi/wn me\n<br />

ga_r ou)deni\ qew~n kaqie/rwtai, xqoni/a| de\ dei=pnon 9Eka&th| pempo&menoj ei0j trio&douj<br />

a)potropai/wn kai\ kaqarsi/wn e0pe/xei moi=ran. e0n de\ Lakedai/moni tw|~ fonikwta&tw|<br />

qew~n 0Enuali/w| sku&lakaj e0nte/mnousi: Boiwtoi=j de\ dhmosi/a| kaqarmo&j e0sti kuno_j<br />

dixotomhqe/ntoj tw~n merw~n diecelqei=n:<br />

Nor, <strong>in</strong> fact, did the men <strong>of</strong> old th<strong>in</strong>k that this animal was holly pure, for it was never<br />

sacrificed to any <strong>of</strong> the Olympian gods; <strong>and</strong> when it is sent to the cross-roads as a supper<br />

406


for the earth-goddess Hecate, it has its due portion among sacrifices that avert <strong>and</strong> expiate<br />

evil. In Sparta they immolate puppies to the bloodiest <strong>of</strong> the gods Enyalius; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

Boeotia the ceremony <strong>of</strong> public purification is to pass between the parts <strong>of</strong> a dog which<br />

has been cut <strong>in</strong> twa<strong>in</strong>.<br />

162<br />

Plutarch, <strong>The</strong>mistocles 10 A.D. I-II<br />

Text: K. Ziegler, ed., Plutarchi vitae parallelae I.1 (Leipzig, 1969).<br />

Translation: B. Perr<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Plutarch’s Lives II (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1914).<br />

0Ekpleou&shj de\ th~j po&lewj toi=j me\n oi]kton to_ qe/ama, toi=j de\ qau~ma th~j to&lmhj<br />

parei=xe, genea_j me\n a1llh| propempo&ntwn, au)tw~n d' a)ka&mptwn pro_j oi0mwga_j<br />

kai\ da&krua gone/wn kai\ peribola_j diaperw&ntwn ei0j th_n nh~son. kai/toi polu_n me\n<br />

oi9 dia_ gh~raj u(poleipo&menoi tw~n politw~n e1leon ei]xon, h}n de/ tij kai\ a)po_ tw~n<br />

h(me/rwn kai\ suntro&fwn zw|&wn e0piklw~sa glukuqumi/a, met' w)rugh~j kai\<br />

po&qou sumparaqeo&ntwn e0mbai/nousi toi=j e9autw~n tr<strong>of</strong>eu~s<strong>in</strong>. e0n oi[j i9storei=tai<br />

ku&wn Canqi/ppou tou~ Perikle/ouj patro&j, ou)k a)nasxo&menoj th_n a)p' au)tou~<br />

mo&nws<strong>in</strong>, e0nale/sqai th|~ qala&tth| kai\ th|~ trih&rei paranhxo&menoj e0kpesei=n ei0j th_n<br />

Salami=na, kai\ lipoqumh&saj a)poqanei=n eu)qu&j: ou{ kai\ to_ deiknu&menon a1xri nu~n kai\<br />

kalou&menon Kuno_j sh~ma ta&fon ei]nai le/gousi.<br />

When the entire city was thus putt<strong>in</strong>g out to sea, the sight provoked pity <strong>in</strong> some, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

others astonishment at the hardihood <strong>of</strong> the step; for they were send<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>f their families<br />

<strong>in</strong> one direction, while they themselves, unmoved by the lamentations <strong>and</strong> tears <strong>and</strong><br />

embraces <strong>of</strong> their loved ones, were cross<strong>in</strong>g over to the isl<strong>and</strong> where the enemy was to be<br />

fought. Besides, many who were left beh<strong>in</strong>d on account <strong>of</strong> great age <strong>in</strong>vited pity also,<br />

<strong>and</strong> much affect<strong>in</strong>g fondness was shown by the tame domestic animals, which ran along<br />

with yearn<strong>in</strong>g cries <strong>of</strong> distress by the side <strong>of</strong> their masters as they embarked. A story is<br />

told <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> these, the dog <strong>of</strong> Xanthippus the father <strong>of</strong> Pericles, how he could not<br />

endure to be ab<strong>and</strong>oned by his master, <strong>and</strong> so sprang <strong>in</strong>to the sea, swam across the strait<br />

by the side <strong>of</strong> his master’s trireme, <strong>and</strong> staggered out on Salamis, only to fa<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> die<br />

straightway. <strong>The</strong>y say that the spot which is po<strong>in</strong>ted out to this day as “Dog’s Mound” is<br />

his tomb.<br />

Polemon, fr. 77 Preller (Epistle Concern<strong>in</strong>g Obscure Words) II B.C.<br />

See Athenaeus 9.409d [75].<br />

163<br />

Pollux, Onomasticon 5.38 A.D. II<br />

Text: E. Bethe, ed., Pollucis Onomasticon (Lexicographi Graeci IX) I (Leipzig, 1900,<br />

1931; repr. Stuttgart, 1967).<br />

Translation: D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1964).<br />

407


le/gousi de\ ta_j me\n Lakai/naj e0c a)lwpe/kwn to_ a)rxai=on kai\ kunw~n genome/naj<br />

klhqh~nai a)lwpeki/daj, ta_j d' 9Urkana_j e0k kunw~n kai\ leo&ntwn, kai\ klhqh~nai<br />

leontomigei=j.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y say that the Laconians, orig<strong>in</strong>ally bred from foxes <strong>and</strong> dogs, were called<br />

“Vulp<strong>in</strong>es,” <strong>and</strong> the Hyrcanians were bred from dogs <strong>and</strong> lions <strong>and</strong> were called<br />

“Leon<strong>in</strong>es.”<br />

164<br />

Pollux, Onomasticon 5.39 A.D. II<br />

Text: E. Bethe, ed., Pollucis Onomasticon (Lexicographi Graeci IX) I (Leipzig, 1900,<br />

1931; repr. Stuggart, 1967).<br />

Translation: D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1964).<br />

w3sper kai\ ta_j Xaoni/daj kai\ Molotti/daj a)pogo&nouj ei]nai/ fhsi kuno&j, o4n<br />

3Hfaistoj e0k xalkou~ Dhmonhsi/ou xalkeusa&menoj, yuxh_n e0nqei/j, dw~ron e1dwke Dii\.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Chaonians <strong>and</strong> the Molossians are descendants <strong>of</strong> a dog which Hephaestus forged<br />

from Demonesian bronze, put a soul <strong>in</strong>to, <strong>and</strong> gave to Zeus.<br />

165<br />

Porphyry, De Abst<strong>in</strong>entia 1.14 A.D. III<br />

Text: A. Nauck, Porphyrii philosophi Platonici opuscula selecta (second ed.; Leipzig,<br />

1886; repr. Hildesheim, 1963).<br />

Translation: G. Clark, tr., Porphyry. On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Ithaca, New<br />

York, 2000).<br />

dikai/ou d' o1ntoj tou~ pro_j ta_ qhri/a pole/mou pollw~n a)pexo&meqa tw~n<br />

sunanqrwpou&ntwn. o3qen oi9 3Ellhnej ou1te kun<strong>of</strong>agou~s<strong>in</strong> ou1q' i3ppouj e0sqi/ous<strong>in</strong><br />

ou1t' o1nouj.<br />

And though the war aga<strong>in</strong>st the beasts is just, we absta<strong>in</strong> from many that live with<br />

humans. That is why the Greeks do not eat dogs, or horses, or donkeys.<br />

166<br />

Porphyry, De Abst<strong>in</strong>entia 2.20-2.21 A.D. III<br />

(= Empedocles, fr. DK128).<br />

(= <strong>The</strong>ophrastus, fr. 12 Pötscher, [155 Nauck 2 ] (On Piety).<br />

Text: A. Nauck, Porphyrii philosophi Platonici opuscula selecta (second ed.; Leipzig,<br />

1886; repr. Hildesheim, 1963).<br />

Translation: G. Clark, tr., Porphyry. On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Ithaca, New<br />

York, 2000).<br />

408


dia_ pollw~n de\ o( Qeo&frastoj e0k tw~n par' e9ka&stoij patri/wn e0pidei/caj,<br />

o3ti to_ palaio_n tw~n qusiw~n dia_ tw~n karpw~n h}n e1t' ei0pw_n pro&teron th~j po&aj<br />

lambanome/nhj, kai\ ta_ tw~n spondw~n e0chgei=tai tou~ton to_n tro&pon.<br />

ta_ me\n a)rxai=a tw~n i9erw~n nhfa&lia para_ polloi=j h}n, nhfa&lia d' e0sti\n ta_<br />

u(dro&sponda, ta_ de\ meta_ tau~ta meli/sponda: tou~ton ga_r e3toimon para_ melittw~n<br />

prw~ton e0la&bomen to_n u(gro_n karpo&n: ei]t' e0laio&sponda: te/loj d' e0pi\ pa~s<strong>in</strong> ta_<br />

u3steron gegono&ta oi0no&sponda.<br />

marturei=tai de\ tau~ta ou) mo&non u(po_ tw~n ku&rbewn, ai4 tw~n Krh&thqe/n ei0si<br />

Korubantikw~n i9erw~n oi[on a)nti/grafa a1tta pro_j a)lh&qeian, a)lla_ kai\ par'<br />

0Empedokle/ouj, o4j peri\ th~j qeogoni/aj dieciw_n kai\ peri\ tw~n quma&twn<br />

paremfai/nei le/gwn:<br />

ou)de/ tij h}n kei/nois<strong>in</strong> 1Arhj qeo_j ou)de\ Kudoimo_j<br />

ou)de\ Zeu_j basileu_j ou)d' o( Kro&noj ou)d' o( Poseidw~n,<br />

a)lla_ Ku&prij basi/leia,<br />

h3 e0st<strong>in</strong> h( fili/a:<br />

th_n oi3 g' eu)sebe/ess<strong>in</strong> a)ga&lmas<strong>in</strong> i9la&skonto<br />

graptoi=j te zw|&oisi mu&roisi/ te daidaleo&smoij<br />

smu&rnhj t' a)kra&tou qusi/aij liba&nou te quw&douj<br />

couqw~n te sponda_j melittw~n r(iptou~ntej e0j ou}daj,<br />

a3per kai\ nu~n e1ti sw|&zetai par' e0ni/oij oi[on i1xnh t<strong>in</strong>a_ th~j a)lhqei/aj o1nta,<br />

tau&rwn d' a)kri/toisi fo&noij ou) deu&eto bwmo&j.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ophrastus uses examples from many ancestral customs <strong>of</strong> different peoples to<br />

show that the ancient form <strong>of</strong> sacrifice was <strong>of</strong> crops; he says too that even earlier grass<br />

was collected. He also expla<strong>in</strong>s libations, as follows.<br />

For most people, ancient rites were sober: libations <strong>of</strong> water are sober, <strong>and</strong> so are<br />

the libations <strong>of</strong> honey which came after them (for this was the first liquid crop we had to<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, taken from the bees). <strong>The</strong>n there were libations <strong>of</strong> oil, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally, last <strong>of</strong> all, came<br />

libations <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

Evidence for this comes not only from the kubreis, which are really a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

transcription <strong>of</strong> the Corybantic rites from Crete, but also from Empedocles, who<br />

comments on sacrifices <strong>in</strong> expound<strong>in</strong>g his theory:<br />

No Ares was to them a god, no Battle-noise,<br />

No Zeus was k<strong>in</strong>g, no Kronos, no Poseidon:<br />

Kypris was queen—<br />

that is Friendship.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y made her k<strong>in</strong>d with pious images<br />

With <strong>and</strong> with subtle scents,<br />

With sacrifice <strong>of</strong> purest myrrh <strong>of</strong> frank<strong>in</strong>cense<br />

409


Sweet-scented; <strong>and</strong> they poured upon the ground<br />

Libations from the tawny bees.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se practices are still preserved among some peoples, like traces <strong>of</strong> truth:<br />

the altar was not soaked by violent deaths<br />

<strong>of</strong> bulls.<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica III B.C<br />

<strong>The</strong> text <strong>and</strong> translations <strong>of</strong> all passages <strong>of</strong> Pseudo-Aristotle’s Physiognomonica are<br />

taken from the edition <strong>of</strong> W. S. Hett, ed., tr., Aristotle. M<strong>in</strong>or Works (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1936; repr. 2000)<br />

167<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 806b III B.C.<br />

ta_ de\ trixw&mata ta_ me\n malaka_ deilo&n, ta_ de\ sklhra_ a)ndrei=on. tou~to de\ to_<br />

shmei=on ei1lhptai e0c a(pa&ntwn tw~n zw|&wn. deilo&taton me\n ga&r e0st<strong>in</strong> e1lafoj<br />

lagwo_j pro&bata, kai\ th_n tri/xa malakwta&thn e1xei: a)ndreio&taton de\ le/wn,<br />

u{j a1grioj, kai\ tri/xa sklhrota&thn fe/rei.<br />

S<strong>of</strong>t hair shows timidity <strong>and</strong> stiff hair courage. This is based on observation <strong>of</strong> all the<br />

animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom. For the deer the hare <strong>and</strong> sheep are the most timid <strong>of</strong> all animals <strong>and</strong><br />

have the s<strong>of</strong>test hair; the lion <strong>and</strong> wild boar are the bravest <strong>and</strong> have very stiff hair.<br />

168<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 807a III B.C.<br />

tw~n d' au} zw|&wn ta_ me\n a)ndrei=a baru&fwna& e0sti, ta_ de\ deila_ o)cu&fwna, le/wn<br />

me\n kai\ tau~roj, kai\ ku&wn u(laktiko&j, kai\ tw~n a)lektruo&nwn oi9 eu1yuxoi baru&fwnoi<br />

fqe/ggontai:<br />

<strong>The</strong> brave animals have deep voices, <strong>and</strong> the cowardly high-pitched voices, the lion<br />

<strong>and</strong> the bull, the bark<strong>in</strong>g dog, <strong>and</strong> the brave cocks are all deep-voiced.<br />

169<br />

Aristotle, Physiognomonica 807a III B.C.<br />

0 Andrei/ou shmei=a tri/xwma sklhro&n, to_ sxh~ma tou~ sw&matoj o)rqo&n, o)sta~ kai\<br />

pleurai\ kai\ ta_ a)krwth&ria tou~ sw&matoj i0sxura_ kai\ mega&la, kai\ koili/a platei=a<br />

kai\ prosestalme/nh:<br />

410


<strong>The</strong> characteristics <strong>of</strong> the brave man are stiff hair, an erect carriage <strong>of</strong> body, bones, sides<br />

<strong>and</strong> extremities <strong>of</strong> the body strong <strong>and</strong> large, broad <strong>and</strong> flat belly.<br />

170<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 808a III B.C.<br />

qumw&douj shmei=a. o)rqo_j to_ sw~ma, tw|~ sxh&mati eu1pleuroj, eu1qumoj,<br />

e0pi/purroj: w)mopla&tai diesthkui=ai kai\ mega&lai kai\ platei=ai: a)krw-<br />

th&ria mega&la kai\ e0gkrath~: lei=oj kai\ peri\ ta_ sth&qh kai\ peri\ boubw~naj,<br />

eu)pw&gwn: eu)auch_j o( peri/dromoj tw~n trixw~n, ka&tw katelhluqw&j.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se are the marks <strong>of</strong> the passionate temperament. <strong>The</strong> body is erect, <strong>in</strong> appearance it is<br />

broad at the ribs, sangu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> ruddy, the shoulder-blades are wide apart, large <strong>and</strong><br />

broad; the extremities are large <strong>and</strong> powerful; he is smooth about the chest <strong>and</strong> gro<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong><br />

well-bearded; the growth <strong>of</strong> hair is considerable <strong>and</strong> starts low down.<br />

171<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 808b III B.C.<br />

tw~n me\n ou}n l<strong>of</strong>ou&rwn ko<strong>in</strong>o&n e0st<strong>in</strong> u3brij, tw~n de\ o1nwn te kai\ suw~n h( peri\ ta_<br />

a)frodi/sia e3cij.<br />

All animals with bushy tails are aggressive, while asses <strong>and</strong> pigs show sexual excitement.<br />

172<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 809b III B.C.<br />

fai/netai tw~n zw|&wn a(pa&ntwn le/wn telew&tata meteilhfe/nai th~j tou~ a1rrenoj<br />

i0de/aj. e1sti ga_r e1xwn sto&ma eu)me/geqej, to_ de\ pro&swpon tetragwno&teron, ou)k<br />

a1gan o)stw~dej, th_n a1nw te ge/nun ou) proecesthkui=an a)lla_ i0sorropou~san th|~<br />

ka&tw, r(i=na de\ paxute/ran h2 leptote/ran, xaropou_j o)fqalmou_j e0gkoi/louj, ou)<br />

sfo&dra periferei=j ou1te a1gan promh&keij, me/geqoj de\ me/trion, o)fru_n eu)mege/qh,<br />

me/twpon tetra&gwnon, e0k me/sou u(pokoilo&teron, pro_j de\ ta_j o)fru~j kai\ th_n r(i=na<br />

u(po_ tou~ metw&pou oi[on ne/foj e0panesthko&j. a1nwqen de\ tou~ metw&pou kata_ th_n<br />

r(i=na e1xei tri/xaj e0kkl<strong>in</strong>ei=j oi[on a2n a1silon, kefalh_n metri/an, tra&xhlon eu)mh&kh,<br />

pa&xei su&mmetron, qrici\ canqai=j kexrhme/non, ou) fricai=j ou1te a1gan<br />

a)pestramme/naij:<br />

<strong>The</strong> lion <strong>of</strong> all animals seems to have the most perfect share <strong>of</strong> the male type. Its mouth is<br />

very large, its face is square, not too bony, the upper jaw not overhang<strong>in</strong>g but equally<br />

balanced with the lower jaw, a muzzle rather thick than f<strong>in</strong>e, bright deep-set eyes, neither<br />

very round nor very narrow, <strong>of</strong> moderate size, a large eyebrow, square forehead, rather<br />

hollow from the centre, overhang<strong>in</strong>g towards the brow <strong>and</strong> nostril below the forehead like<br />

a cloud. Above on the forehead towards the muzzle hair slopp<strong>in</strong>g outwards <strong>and</strong> like<br />

411


istles, a head <strong>of</strong> moderate size, a long neck, with correspond<strong>in</strong>g thickness, covered with<br />

tawny hairs, neither very bristl<strong>in</strong>g nor too much turned back.<br />

173<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 809b III B.C.<br />

zw|~on a)sarko&teron ta_ i0sxi/a kai\ tou_j mhrou&j: ske/lh e0rrwme/na kai\ neurw&dh,<br />

ba&s<strong>in</strong> te neanikh&n, kai\ o3lon to_ sw~ma a)rqrw~dej kai\ neurw~dej, ou1te li/an sklhro_n<br />

ou1te li/an u(gro&n.<br />

<strong>The</strong> animal [lion] has lean haunches <strong>and</strong> thighs; his legs are strong <strong>and</strong> muscular, his<br />

walk is vigorous, <strong>and</strong> his whole body is well-jo<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>and</strong> muscular, neither very hard nor<br />

very moist.<br />

174<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 810b III B.C.<br />

oi9 zwnoi\ filo&qhroi: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ tou_j le/ontaj kai\ tou_j ku&naj. i1doi d' a1n tij<br />

kai\ tw~n kunw~n tou_j filoqhrota&touj zwnou_j o1ntaj.<br />

Those that are small <strong>in</strong> the waist are hunters; witness lions <strong>and</strong> dogs. One can observe<br />

that the dogs most fond <strong>of</strong> hunt<strong>in</strong>g are those which are narrow <strong>in</strong> the waist.<br />

175<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 810b III B.C.<br />

o3soi de\ ta_ sthqi/a e1xousi mega&la kai\ dihrqrwme/na, eu1rwstoi ta_j yuxa&j:<br />

a)nafe/retai e0pi\ to_ a1rren.<br />

Those who have large chests well jo<strong>in</strong>ted are strong <strong>in</strong> character; witness the male.<br />

176<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 810b III B.C.<br />

o3soij ai9 e 0 pwmi/dej e0chrqrwme/nai kai\ oi9 w}moi, eu1rwstoi ta_j yuxa&j:<br />

a)nafe/retai e0pi\ to_ a1rren.<br />

Those whose shoulders <strong>and</strong> shoulder-blades are well articulated have strong characters;<br />

witness the male.<br />

177<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 811a III B.C.<br />

412


oi[j ta_ xei/lh lepta_ kai\ e0p' a1kraij tai=j sugxeili/aij xalara&, w(j e0pi\ tou~ a1nw<br />

xei/louj pro_j to_ ka&tw e0pibeblh~sqai to_ pro_j ta_j sugxeili/aj, megalo&yuxoi:<br />

a)nafe/retai e0pi\ tou_j le/ontaj. i1doi d' a1n tij tou~to kai\ e0pi\ tw~n mega&lwn<br />

kai\ eu)rw&stwn kunw~n.<br />

Those who have th<strong>in</strong> lips <strong>and</strong> slack parts at the jo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the lips, so that the upper lip<br />

overhangs the lower at the jo<strong>in</strong>, are magnanimous; witness the lions. One can see the<br />

same th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> large <strong>and</strong> powerful dogs.<br />

178<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 811b III B.C.<br />

o3soij o)fqalmoi\ mikro_n e0gkoilo&teroi, megalo&yuxoi: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ tou_j<br />

le/ontaj.<br />

Those whose eyes are slightly hollow are magnanimous; witness lions.<br />

179<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 811b III B.C.<br />

oi9 de\ sunnefe\j e1xontej au)qa&deij: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ tau~ron kai\ le/onta.<br />

Those with an overhang<strong>in</strong>g brow are overbold; witness the bull <strong>and</strong> the lion.<br />

180<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 812b III B.C.<br />

oi9 to_n nw~ton dasu_n e1xontej a1gan a)naidei=j: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ ta_ qhri/a. oi9 de\ to_n<br />

au)xe/na o1pisqen dasu_n e1xontej e0leuqe/rioi: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ tou_j le/ontaj.<br />

Those with a hairy back are excessively shameless; witness the wild beasts.<br />

Those whose neck is hairy beh<strong>in</strong>d are generous; witness the lions.<br />

181<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 812b III B.C.<br />

ai9 a1krouloi a2n ei]en pro_j eu)yuxi/an a1gousai: a)nafe/retai de\ kai\ e0pi\ to_n le/onta. oi9<br />

tou~ metw&pou to_ pro_j th|~ kefalh|~ a)nastei=lon e1xontej e0leuqe/rioi: a)nafe/retai e0pi\<br />

tou_j le/ontaj.<br />

413


Hair which curls at the ends tends towards stout-heartedness; witness the lion among<br />

others. Those <strong>in</strong> whom the hair on the face near the head curls backwards are liberal;<br />

witness the lions.<br />

182<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 812b III B.C.<br />

oi9 e0pi\ th~j kefalh~j prospefukui/aj e1xontej ta_j tri/xaj e0pi\ tou~ metw&pou kata_<br />

th_n r(i=na a)neleu&qeroi: a)nafe/retai e0pi\ th_n e0pipre/peian, o3ti douloprepe\j to_<br />

fa<strong>in</strong>o&menon.<br />

Those [animals] whose hair <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>es to grow down from the head towards the nose are<br />

mean; this is appropriate as this appearance gives a servile look.<br />

183<br />

Pseudo-Aristotle, Physiognomonica 814b III B.C.<br />

e0pikairo&tatoj de\ to&poj o( peri\ ta_ o1mmata& te kai\ to_ me/twpon kai\ kefalh_n kai\<br />

pro&swpon, deu&teroj de\ o( peri\ ta_ sth&qh kai\ w1mouj, e1peita peri\ ta_ ske/lh te<br />

kai\ po&daj: ta_ de\ peri\ th_n koili/an h3kista. o3lwj de\ ei0pei=n ou{toi oi9 to&poi<br />

e0narge/stata shmei=a pare/xontai, e0f' w{n kai\ fronh&sewj plei/sthj e0pipre/peia<br />

gi/netai.<br />

<strong>The</strong> most favorable part for exam<strong>in</strong>ation is the region round the eyes, forehead, head <strong>and</strong><br />

face; secondly, the region <strong>of</strong> the breast <strong>and</strong> shoulders, <strong>and</strong> lastly that <strong>of</strong> the legs <strong>and</strong> feet;<br />

the parts about the belly are <strong>of</strong> least importance. Generally speak<strong>in</strong>g, these regions<br />

supply the clearest signs, <strong>in</strong> which there is greatest evidence <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence.<br />

184<br />

Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrhoniae hypotyposes 3.225 A.D. II-III<br />

Text: H. Mutschmann, ed., Sexti Empirici opera I (Leipzig, 1912).<br />

Translation: R. G. Bury, ed., tr., Sextus Empiricus. Outl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> Pyrrhonism I (London <strong>and</strong><br />

New York, 1933).<br />

kunei/wn te geu&sasqai dokou~men h(mei=j a)ni/eron ei]nai, Qra|kw~n de\ e1nioi kun<strong>of</strong>agei=n<br />

i9storou~ntai. i1swj de\ kai\ par' 3Ellhsi tou~to h}n su&nhqej: dio&per kai\ Dioklh~j a)po_<br />

tw~n kata_ tou_j 0Asklhpia&daj o(rmw&menoj tisi\ tw~n pasxo&ntwn skula&keia<br />

di/dosqai keleu&ei kre/a.<br />

Eat<strong>in</strong>g dog’s flesh, too, is thought by us to be s<strong>in</strong>ful, but some <strong>of</strong> the Thracians are<br />

reported to be do-eaters. Possibly this practice was customary also amongst the Greeks;<br />

<strong>and</strong> on this account, Diocles, too, start<strong>in</strong>g from the practices <strong>of</strong> the Asclepiadae,<br />

prescribed that hounds’ flesh should be given to certa<strong>in</strong> patients.<br />

414


185<br />

Sophocles, Antigone 198-206 V B.C.<br />

Text: H. Lloyd-Jones <strong>and</strong> N.G. Wilson, eds., Sophoclis fabulae (Oxford, 1990; repr.<br />

1992).<br />

Translation: H. Lloyd-Jones, ed., tr., Sophocles. Antigone. <strong>The</strong> Women <strong>of</strong> Trachis.<br />

Philoctetes. Oedipus at Colonus (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1994).<br />

KREWN<br />

to_n d' au} cu&naimon tou~de, Polunei/kh le/gw,<br />

o4j gh~n patrw|&an kai\ qeou_j tou_j e0ggenei=j<br />

200 fuga_j katelqw_n h)qe/lhse me\n puri\<br />

prh~sai kat' a1kraj, h)qe/lhse d' ai3matoj<br />

ko<strong>in</strong>ou~ pa&sasqai, tou_j de\ doulw&saj a1ge<strong>in</strong>,<br />

tou~ton po&lei th|~d' e0kkekh&ruktai ta&fw|<br />

mh&te kteri/ze<strong>in</strong> mh&te kwku~sai/ t<strong>in</strong>a,<br />

205 e0a~n d' a1qapton kai\ pro_j oi0wnw~n de/maj<br />

kai\ pro_j kunw~n e0desto_n ai0kisqe/n t' i0dei=n.<br />

CREON<br />

But his brother, I mean Polynices,<br />

who came back from exile, mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to burn tothe ground his native city <strong>and</strong><br />

the gods <strong>of</strong> his race, <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g to dr<strong>in</strong>k<br />

the people’s blood <strong>and</strong> to enslave its people,<br />

as for him it is proclaimed to this city<br />

that none shall bury or lament,<br />

but they shall leave his body unburied<br />

for birds <strong>and</strong> dogs to devour <strong>and</strong> savage.<br />

186<br />

Sophocles, fr. 885 Radt V B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: H. Lloyd-Jones, ed., tr., Sophocles III. Fragments (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1996).<br />

sai/neij da&knousa kai\ ku&wn lai/qargoj ei]<br />

You fawn on men as you bite them <strong>and</strong> are a treacherous dog.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ophrastus, fr. 12 Pötscher, [155 Nauck 2 ] (On Piety) IV/III B.C.<br />

See Porphyry, De Abst<strong>in</strong>entia 2.20-2.21 [166].<br />

187<br />

Thucydides 2.50 V B.C.<br />

415


Text <strong>and</strong> translation: C. F. Smith, ed., tr., Thucydides I. History <strong>of</strong> the Peloponnesian War<br />

Books I <strong>and</strong> II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1919; rev. <strong>and</strong> repr. 1928; repr.<br />

1980).<br />

Geno&menon ga_r krei=sson lo&gou to_ ei]doj th~j no&sou ta& te a1lla xalepwte/rwj h2<br />

kata_ th_n a)nqrwpei/an fu&s<strong>in</strong> prose/pipten e9ka&stw| kai\ e0n tw|~de e0dh&lwse ma&lista<br />

a1llo ti o2n h2 tw~n cuntro&fwn ti: ta_ ga_r o1rnea kai\ tetra&poda o3sa a)nqrw&pwn<br />

a3ptetai pollw~n a)ta&fwn gignome/nwn h2 ou) prosh|&ei h2 geusa&mena diefqei/reto.<br />

tekmh&rion de/: tw~n me\n toiou&twn o)rni/qwn e0pi/leiyij safh_j e0ge/neto, kai\ ou)x<br />

e9wrw~nto ou1te a1llwj ou1te peri\ toiou~ton ou)de/n: oi9 de\ ku&nej ma~llon ai1sqhs<strong>in</strong><br />

parei=xon tou~ a)pobai/nontoj dia_ to_ cundiaita~sqai.<br />

Indeed the character <strong>of</strong> the disease proved such that it baffles description,<br />

the violence <strong>of</strong> the attack be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> each case too great for human nature to endure, while<br />

<strong>in</strong> one way <strong>in</strong> particular it showed pla<strong>in</strong>ly that it was different from any <strong>of</strong> the familiar<br />

diseases: the birds, namely, <strong>and</strong> the fourfooted animals, which usually feed upon human<br />

bodies, either would not now come near them, though man lay unburied, or died if they<br />

tasted them. <strong>The</strong> evidence for this is that birds <strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d became noticeably scarce, <strong>and</strong><br />

they were no longer to be seen either about the bodies or anywhere else; while the dogs<br />

gave a still better opportunity to observe what happened, because they live with man.<br />

188<br />

Varro, Rustica 2.9.8-2.9.10 I B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: W. D. Hooper, ed., tr., Marcus Porcius Cato. On Agriculture.<br />

Marcus Terentius Varro. On Agriculture; rev. H. B. Ash (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1934; rev. <strong>and</strong> repr. 1935; repr. 1993).<br />

Cibatus cnis proprior hom<strong>in</strong>is quam ovis. Pascitur enim eduliis et ossibus, nn herbis aut<br />

fronde. Diligenter ut habeat cibaria providendum. Fames enim hos ad quaerendum<br />

cibum ducet, si non praebebitur, et a pecore abducet; nisi si, ut quidam putant, etiam illuc<br />

pervener<strong>in</strong>t, proverbium ut tollant anticum vel etiam ut aperiant de Actaeone atque <strong>in</strong><br />

dom<strong>in</strong>um adferant dentes. Nec non ita panem hordeaciim d<strong>and</strong>um, ut non potius eum <strong>in</strong><br />

lacte des <strong>in</strong>tritum, quod eo consueti cibo uti a pecore non cito desciscunt. Mortic<strong>in</strong>ae<br />

ovis non patiuntur vesci carne, ne ducti sapore m<strong>in</strong>us se abst<strong>in</strong>eant. Dant etiam ius ex<br />

ossibus et ea ipsa ossa contuse. Dentes enim facit firmiores et os magis patulum,<br />

propterea quod vehementius diducuntur malae, acrioresque fiunt propter medullarum<br />

saporem. Cibum capere consuescunt <strong>in</strong>terdiu, ubi pascuntur, vesperi, ubi stabulantur.<br />

<strong>The</strong> food <strong>of</strong> dogs is morelike that <strong>of</strong> man than that <strong>of</strong> sheep: they eat scraps <strong>of</strong> meat <strong>and</strong><br />

bones, not grass <strong>and</strong> leaves. Great care must be taen for their supply <strong>of</strong> food; for hunger<br />

wull drive them to hunt for food, if it is not provided, <strong>and</strong> take them away from the<br />

flock—even if they do not, as some th<strong>in</strong>k, come to the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> disprov<strong>in</strong>g the ancient<br />

proverb, or even go so far as to enact the story <strong>of</strong> Actaeon, <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>k their teeth <strong>in</strong> their<br />

master. You should also feed them barley bread, but not without soak<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong> milk; for<br />

when they have become accustomed to eat<strong>in</strong>g that k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> food they will not soon stray<br />

from the flock <strong>The</strong>y are not allowed to feed on the flesh <strong>of</strong> the dead sheep, for fear that<br />

416


the taste will make them less <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to spare the flock. <strong>The</strong>y are also fed on bone soup<br />

<strong>and</strong> even broken bones as well; for these make their teeth stronger <strong>and</strong> their mouths <strong>of</strong><br />

wider stretch, because their jaws are spread with greater force, <strong>and</strong> the savour <strong>of</strong> the<br />

marrow makes them moe keen. <strong>The</strong>ir habit is to eat dur<strong>in</strong>g the day when they are out<br />

with the flocks, <strong>and</strong> at even<strong>in</strong>g when these are folded.<br />

189<br />

Xenophon, Cynegeticus 3.1 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. C. Marchant, ed., tr., Xenophon VII. Scripta M<strong>in</strong>ora (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925; repr. 1984).<br />

Ta_ de\ ge/nh tw~n kunw~n ditta&, ai9 me\n kasto&riai, ai9 de\ a)lwpeki/dej. e1xousi d' ai9 me\n<br />

kasto&riai th_n e0pwnumi/an tau&thn o3ti Ka&stwr h(sqei\j tw|~ e1rgw| ma&lista au)ta_j<br />

diefu&lacen: ai9 d' a)lwpeki/dej dio&ti e0k kunw~n te kai\ a)lwpe/kwn e0ge/nonto: e0n<br />

pollw|~ de\ xro&nw| sugke/kratai au)tw~n h( fu&sij.<br />

<strong>The</strong> hounds used are <strong>of</strong> two k<strong>in</strong>ds, the Castorian <strong>and</strong> the Vulp<strong>in</strong>e. <strong>The</strong> Castorian is so<br />

called because Castor paid special attention to the breed, mak<strong>in</strong>g a hobby <strong>of</strong> the bus<strong>in</strong>ess.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Vulp<strong>in</strong>e is a hybrid between the dog <strong>and</strong> the fox: hence the name. In the course <strong>of</strong><br />

time the nature <strong>of</strong> the parents has become fused.<br />

190<br />

Xenophon, Cynegeticus 4.1 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. C. Marchant, ed., tr., Xenophon VII. Scripta M<strong>in</strong>ora (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925; repr. 1984).<br />

Prw~ton me\n ou}n xrh_ ei]nai mega&laj, ei]ta e0xou&saj ta_j kefala_j e0lafra&j, sima&j,<br />

a)rqrw&deij, i0nw&dh ta_ ka&twqen tw~n metw&pwn, o1mmata mete/wra, me/lana, lampra&,<br />

me/twpa plate/a, ta_j diakri/seij baqei/av.<br />

First, then, they [hunt<strong>in</strong>g dogs] should be big: Next, the head should be light, flat <strong>and</strong><br />

muscular; the lower parts <strong>of</strong> the forehead s<strong>in</strong>ewy; the eyes prom<strong>in</strong>ent, black <strong>and</strong><br />

sparkl<strong>in</strong>g; the forehead broad, with a deep divid<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

191<br />

Xenophon, Cynegeticus 7.4 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. C. Marchant, ed., tr., Xenophon VII. Scripta M<strong>in</strong>ora (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925; repr. 1984).<br />

e0peida_n de\ plana~tai ta_ skula&kia h1dh, dido&nai ga&la me/xri e0niautou~ kai\ oi[j<br />

me/llei to_n a3panta xro&non biw&sesqai, a1llo de\ mhde/n: ai9 ga_r barei=ai plhsmonai\<br />

tw~n skulaki/wn diastre/fousi ta_ ske/lh, toi=j sw&masi no&souj e0mpoiou~si,<br />

kai\ ta_ e0nto_j a1dika gi/gnetai.<br />

417


As soon as the puppies can get about, give them milk for a year, <strong>and</strong> the food that will<br />

form their regular diet, <strong>and</strong> noth<strong>in</strong>g else. For heavy feed<strong>in</strong>g warps the puppies’ legs <strong>and</strong><br />

sows the seeds <strong>of</strong> disease <strong>in</strong> the system, <strong>and</strong> their <strong>in</strong>sides go wrong.<br />

192<br />

Xenophon, Cynegeticus 11.1 V-IV B.C.<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. C. Marchant, ed., tr., Xenophon VII. Scripta M<strong>in</strong>ora (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925; repr. 1984).<br />

Le/ontej de\ kai\ parda&leij, lu&gkej, pa&nqhrej, a1rktoi kai\ ta}lla o3sa e0sti\<br />

toiau~ta qhri/a a(li/sketai e0n ce/naij xw&raij peri\ to_ Pa&ggaion o1roj kai\ to_n<br />

Ki/tton to_n u(pe\r th~j Makedoni/aj, ta_ d' e0n tw|~ 0Olu&mpw| tw|~ Musi/w| kai\ e0n Pi/ndw|,<br />

ta_ d' e0n th|~ Nu&sh| th|~ u(pe\r th~j Suri/aj, kai\ pro_j toi=j a1lloij o1res<strong>in</strong> o3sa oi[a& t' e0sti\<br />

tre/fe<strong>in</strong> toiau~ta.<br />

Lions, leopards, lynxes, panthers, bears <strong>and</strong> all similar wild beasts are captured <strong>in</strong> foreign<br />

countries, about Mt. Pangaeus <strong>and</strong> Cittus beyond Macedonia, on Mysian Olympus <strong>and</strong><br />

P<strong>in</strong>dus, on Nysa beyond Syria, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> other mounta<strong>in</strong> ranges capable <strong>of</strong> support<strong>in</strong>g such<br />

animals.<br />

193<br />

Xenophon, Memorabilia 3.10.6-3.10.8<br />

Text <strong>and</strong> translation: E. C. Marchant, ed., tr., Xenophon. Memorabilian <strong>and</strong> Oeconomicus<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1923; repr. 1965).<br />

3Oti me/n, e1fh, w} Klei/twn, kaloi\ ou4j poiei=j drome/aj te kai\ palaista_j kai\<br />

pu&ktaj kai\ pagkratiasta&j, o(rw~ te kai\ oi]da: o4 de\ ma&lista yuxagwgei= dia_ th~j<br />

o1yewj tou_j a)nqrw&pouj, to_ zwtiko_n fai/nesqai, pw~j tou~to e0nerga&zh| toi=j<br />

a)ndria~s<strong>in</strong>;<br />

e0pei\ de\ a)porw~n o( Klei/twn ou) taxu_ a)pekri/nato, ]Ar', e1fh, toi=j tw~n zw&ntwn<br />

ei1des<strong>in</strong> a)peika&zwn to_ e1rgon zwtikwte/rouj poiei=j fai/nesqai tou_j<br />

a)ndria&ntaj;<br />

Kai\ ma&la, e1fh.<br />

Ou)kou~n ta& te u(po_ tw~n sxhma&twn kataspw&mena kai\ ta)naspw&mena e0n toi=j<br />

sw&masi kai\ ta_ sumpiezo&mena kai\ ta_ dielko&mena kai\ ta_ e0nte<strong>in</strong>o&mena kai\ ta_<br />

a)nie/mena a)peika&zwn o(moio&tera& te toi=j a)lhq<strong>in</strong>oi=j kai\<br />

piqanw&tera poiei=j fai/nesqai;<br />

Pa&nu me\n ou}n, e1fh.<br />

To_ de\ kai\ ta_ pa&qh tw~n poiou&ntwn ti swma&twn a)pomimei=sqai ou) poiei= t<strong>in</strong>a<br />

te/ry<strong>in</strong> toi=j qewme/noij;<br />

Ei0ko_j gou~n, e1fh.<br />

Ou)kou~n kai\ tw~n me\n maxome/nwn a)peilhtika_ ta_ o1mmata a)peikaste/on,<br />

tw~n de\ nenikhko&twn eu)fra<strong>in</strong>ome/nwn h( o1yij mimhte/a;<br />

Sfo&dra g', e1fh.<br />

Dei= a1ra, e1fh, to_n a)ndriantopoio_n ta_ th~j yuxh~j e1rga tw|~ ei1dei proseika&ze<strong>in</strong>.<br />

418


“Cleiton, that your statues <strong>of</strong> runners, wrestlers, boxers, <strong>and</strong> fighters are beautiful I see<br />

<strong>and</strong> know. But how do you e0nerga&zh| (produce <strong>in</strong>) them that illusion <strong>of</strong> life (to_ zwtiko_n<br />

fai/nesqai) which is their most allur<strong>in</strong>g charm to the beholder?”<br />

As Cleiton was puzzled <strong>and</strong> did not reply at once, “Is it,” he added, “by faithfully<br />

represent<strong>in</strong>g the form <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs that you make your statues look as if they lived?”<br />

“Undoubtedly.”<br />

“<strong>The</strong>n is it not by accurately represent<strong>in</strong>g the different parts <strong>of</strong> the body as they affected<br />

by the pose—the flesh wr<strong>in</strong>kled or tense, the limbs compressed or outstretched, the<br />

muscles taut or loose—that you make them look more real members <strong>and</strong> more<br />

conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g?”<br />

“Yes, certa<strong>in</strong>ly.”<br />

“Does not the exact imitation (a)pomimei=sqai) <strong>of</strong> the feel<strong>in</strong>gs that affect bodies <strong>in</strong> action<br />

also produce a sense <strong>of</strong> satisfaction <strong>in</strong> the spectator?”<br />

“Oh yes, presumably.”<br />

“<strong>The</strong>n must not the threaten<strong>in</strong>g look <strong>in</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> fighters be accurately represented, <strong>and</strong><br />

the triumphant expression on the face <strong>of</strong> conquerors be imitated (mimhte/a)?”<br />

“Most certa<strong>in</strong>ly.”<br />

“It follows, then, that the sculptor must represent <strong>in</strong> his figures the<br />

activities <strong>of</strong> the soul.”<br />

419


Bibliography<br />

J. L. Ackrill, tr., Aristotle’s Categories <strong>and</strong> De Interpretatione (Oxford, 1963)<br />

J. P. Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong><br />

Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, September 16, 1999-January 9, 2000<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum, Toronto, February 13-May 22, 2000; New York,<br />

1999)<br />

R. E. Allen, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2006)<br />

M. Amberger-Lahrmann, Anatomie und Physiognomie <strong>in</strong> der hellenistischen Plastik:<br />

Dargestellt am Pergamonaltar (Stuttgart, 1996)<br />

D. A. Amyx, Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Archaic Period (Berkeley, 1986)<br />

B. Andreae et al., Bildkatalog der <strong>Sculpture</strong>n des vaticanischen Museums (DAI II; Berl<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> New York, 1998)<br />

D. Andrianou, “Chairs, Beds, <strong>and</strong> Tables: Evidence for Furnished Interiors <strong>in</strong> Hellenistic<br />

<strong>Greece</strong>,” Hesperia 75 (2006) 219-266<br />

M. Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a II. <strong>The</strong> Tomb <strong>of</strong> Persephone (Athens, 1994)<br />

_____, Verg<strong>in</strong>a: <strong>The</strong> Royal Tombs <strong>and</strong> the Ancient City (Athens, 1984)<br />

O. K. Armayor, Herodotus’ Autopsy <strong>of</strong> the Fayoum: Lake Moeris <strong>and</strong> the Labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>in</strong><br />

Egypt (Amsterdam, 1985)<br />

D. Arnold, “Head <strong>of</strong> a Female Personification <strong>of</strong> an Estate,” <strong>in</strong> J. P. Allen et al., Egyptian<br />

Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum<br />

<strong>of</strong> Art, New York, September 16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario<br />

Museum, Toronto, February 13-May 22, 2000; New York, 1999) 226-227<br />

_____, “Royal Reliefs,” <strong>in</strong> J. P. Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids<br />

(exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, September<br />

16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum, Toronto, February 13-<br />

May 22, 2000; New York, 1999) 83-101<br />

_____, “Royal Cult Complexes <strong>of</strong> the Old <strong>and</strong> Middle K<strong>in</strong>gdoms,” <strong>in</strong> B. E. Shafer, ed.,<br />

Temples <strong>of</strong> Ancient Egypt (Ithaca, 1997) 31-85<br />

_____, Die Pyramidenbezirk des Königs Amenemhet III <strong>in</strong> Dahshur 1: Die Pyramide<br />

(DAIK-Archäologische Veröffentlichungen 53; Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 1987)<br />

W. G. Arnott, Alexis: <strong>The</strong> Fragments: A Commentary (Cambridge, 1996)<br />

420


B. Arntsen, Dog On <strong>The</strong> Ro<strong>of</strong>…No Law Aga<strong>in</strong>st It.<br />

http://www.newsargus.com/news/archives/2004/12/31dog_on_the_ro<strong>of</strong>no_law_<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st_it/<strong>in</strong>dex.shtml<br />

A. H. Ashmead, “Etruscan Domesticated Cats: <strong>Classical</strong> Conformists or Etruscan<br />

Orig<strong>in</strong>als?” <strong>in</strong> R. D. De Puma <strong>and</strong> J. P. Small, eds., Murlo <strong>and</strong> the Etruscans: Art<br />

<strong>and</strong> Society <strong>in</strong> Ancient Etruria (Wiscons<strong>in</strong>, 1994) 144-164<br />

_____, “Greek Cats. Exotic Pets Kept by Rich Youths <strong>in</strong> Fifth Century B.C. Athens, as<br />

Portrayed on Greek Vases,” Expedition 20 (1978) 38-47<br />

H. W. Auden, “Natural History <strong>in</strong> Homer,” CR 10 (1896) 107<br />

S. Baker, Pictur<strong>in</strong>g the Beast. <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Identity, <strong>and</strong> Representation (Urbana <strong>and</strong><br />

Chicago, 2001)<br />

J. M. Balcer, Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Bisitun: Problems <strong>in</strong> Ancient Persian Historiography<br />

(Stuttgart, 1987)<br />

M. Ball<strong>in</strong>tijn, “Lions Depicted on Aegean Seals—How Realistic Are <strong>The</strong>y?” <strong>in</strong> W.<br />

Muller, ed., Sceaux m<strong>in</strong>oens et mycéniens: IVe symposium <strong>in</strong>ternational, 10-12<br />

septembre 1992, Clermont-Ferr<strong>and</strong> (CMS 5 Beiheft 5; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1995) 23-37<br />

D. M. Balme, Aristotle XI. History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. Books VII-X (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1991)<br />

E. J. W. Barber, Prehistoric Textiles. <strong>The</strong> Development <strong>of</strong> Cloth <strong>in</strong> the Neolithic <strong>and</strong><br />

Bronze Ages with Special Reference to the Aegean (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1991)<br />

J. M. Barr<strong>in</strong>ger, <strong>The</strong> Hunt <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Baltimore <strong>and</strong> London, 2001)<br />

T. S. Barton, Power <strong>and</strong> Knowledge. Astrology, Physiognomics, <strong>and</strong> Medic<strong>in</strong>e under the<br />

Roman Empire (Ann Arbor, 1994; repr. 1997)<br />

A. Bayer, “Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Lombard Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> A. Bayer, ed., Pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>of</strong><br />

Reality. <strong>The</strong> Legacy <strong>of</strong> Leonardo <strong>and</strong> Caravaggio <strong>in</strong> Lombardy (exhibition<br />

catalogue, Museo Civico “Ala Ponzone,” Cremona, February 14-May 2, 2004,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, May 27-August 15, 2004 (New<br />

Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 3-21<br />

E. Baziotopoulou-Valavani, “Red-Figured Aryballos,” <strong>in</strong> L. Parlama <strong>and</strong> N. C.<br />

Stampolidis, eds., Athens: <strong>The</strong> City Beneath the City. Antiquities from the<br />

Metropolitan Railway Excavations (Athens, 2001) 309<br />

421


C. Becker, Kastanas. Ausgrabungen <strong>in</strong> e<strong>in</strong>em Siedlungshügel der Bronze-und Eisenzeit<br />

Makedoniens, 1975-1979, die Tierknochenfunde (Prähistorische Archäologie <strong>in</strong><br />

Südosteuropa 5; Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1986)<br />

M. Belozerskaya, “Menageries as Pr<strong>in</strong>cely Necessities <strong>and</strong> Mirrors <strong>of</strong> their Times,” <strong>in</strong> M.<br />

Morton, ed., Oudry’s Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Menagerie. Portraits <strong>of</strong> Exotic <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

Eighteenth-Century Europe (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> J. Paul Getty Museum <strong>in</strong><br />

association with the Staatliches Museum Schwer<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts,<br />

Houston; Los Angeles, 2007) 59-73<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Medici Giraffe: And Other Tales <strong>of</strong> Exotic <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Power (New York,<br />

2006)<br />

J. Berger, About Look<strong>in</strong>g (New York, 1980)<br />

A. Bernhard-Walcher et al., <strong>The</strong> Collection <strong>of</strong> Cypriot Antiquities <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Kunsthistorisches Museum (Vienna, 1999)<br />

A. Betensky, “Aeschylus’ Oresteia: <strong>The</strong> Power <strong>of</strong> Clytemnestra,” Ramus 7 (1978) 11-25<br />

E. Bethe, ed., Pollucis Onomasticon (Lexicographi Graeci IX) I (Leipzig, 1900, 1931;<br />

repr. Stuttgart, 1967)<br />

J. W. Blakesley, Herodotus, with a Commentary (London, 1854)<br />

L. J. Bliquez, “Lions <strong>and</strong> Greek Sculptors,” CW 68 (1975) 381-384<br />

I. Blom, “<strong>Sculpture</strong>d Fragments <strong>and</strong> Relief Fragments from the Labyr<strong>in</strong>th at Hawara <strong>in</strong><br />

the Rijksmseum van Oudheden, Leiden,” OMRO 69 (1989) 25-50<br />

M. W. Blundell, Help<strong>in</strong>g Friends <strong>and</strong> Harm<strong>in</strong>g Enemies. A Study <strong>in</strong> Sophocles <strong>and</strong> Greek<br />

Ethics (New York <strong>and</strong> New Rochelle, 1989)<br />

J. Boardman, rev. <strong>of</strong> R. T. Neer, Style <strong>and</strong> Politics <strong>in</strong> Athenian Vase-Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> Craft<br />

<strong>of</strong> Democracy, ca. 530-460 B.C.E. (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2002), <strong>in</strong> Common<br />

Knowledge 10 (2004) 353<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Archaeology <strong>of</strong> Nostalgia. How the Greeks Re-Created their Mythical Past<br />

(London, 2002)<br />

_____, Greek Gems <strong>and</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ger R<strong>in</strong>gs. Early Bronze Age to Late <strong>Classical</strong> (London<br />

1970; new exp. ed., 2001)<br />

_____, Persia <strong>and</strong> the West: An Archaeological Investigation <strong>of</strong> the Genesis <strong>of</strong><br />

Achaemenid Art (London, 2000)<br />

422


_____, Early Greek Vase Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. 11 TH -6 TH Centuries B.C. A H<strong>and</strong>book (New York <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1998)<br />

_____, Greek Art (fourth ed.; London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996)<br />

_____, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Late <strong>Classical</strong> Period <strong>and</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> Colonies <strong>and</strong><br />

Overseas (London, 1995)<br />

_____, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Period. A H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1985)<br />

_____, Greek Art. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period. A H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1978; repr.<br />

1996)<br />

_____, rev <strong>of</strong> H. Gabelmann, Studien zum frühgriechischen Löwenbild (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1965), <strong>in</strong><br />

Gnomon 39 (1967) 99-101<br />

_____ <strong>and</strong> D. F<strong>in</strong>n, <strong>The</strong> Parthenon <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong>s (Aust<strong>in</strong>, 1985)<br />

K. Boccella, “Tug-<strong>of</strong>-War Erupts over Katr<strong>in</strong>a Pets—Class <strong>and</strong> Race Shade the Fight<br />

between Those Who Lost, Those Who Now Have,” <strong>The</strong> Philadelphia Inquirer<br />

(July 16, 2006) 1<br />

L. Bodson, “Motivation for Pet-Keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> <strong>and</strong> Rome: A Prelim<strong>in</strong>ary<br />

Survey,” <strong>in</strong> A. L. Podberschek et al., eds., Companion <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Us: Explor<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the Relationships between People <strong>and</strong> Pets (Cambridge, 2000) 27-41<br />

E. Boisacq, Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue greque (Heidelberg <strong>and</strong> Paris, 1923)<br />

P. N. Boulter, “<strong>The</strong> Frieze <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion,” AntP 10 (1970) 7-28<br />

C. Bouras <strong>and</strong> K. Zambas, <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> the Committee for the Preservation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Acropolis Monuments on the Acropolis <strong>of</strong> Athens (Athens, 2002)<br />

D. Bower, Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Mexico: <strong>The</strong> Friends <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. http://ez<strong>in</strong>earticles.com/?Liv<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>-<br />

Mexico:-<strong>The</strong>-Friends-<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>&id=258240<br />

M. Bowie, Aristophanes. Myth, Ritual <strong>and</strong> Comedy (Cambridge, 1993; repr. 1996)<br />

K. Bradley, “<strong>Animal</strong>iz<strong>in</strong>g the Slave: <strong>The</strong> Truth <strong>of</strong> Fiction,” JRS 90 (2000) 110-125<br />

D. Brewer et al., Dogs <strong>in</strong> Antiquity. Anubis to Cerberus. <strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Domestic Dog<br />

(Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 2000)<br />

M. Bright, Intelligence <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (London, 1994; second ed., 1997)<br />

423


British Museum, 2001, November. British Museum Acquires Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs Dog.<br />

http://www.thebritishmuseum.ac.uk/newsroom/archive 2001/jenn<strong>in</strong>gsdog.html<br />

British Museum Object Names <strong>The</strong>saurus: http://www.mda.org.uk/bmobj/Obthesf1.htm<br />

O. Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis (Cambridge, Mass., 1941)<br />

_____, “Discoveries on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis, 1938,” AJA 42 (1938) 161-164<br />

_____, “Excavations on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis <strong>in</strong> Athens, 1933-1934,”<br />

Hesperia 4 (1935) 109-188<br />

_____, “Excavations on the North Slope <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis <strong>in</strong> Athens, 1931-1932,”<br />

Hesperia 2 (1933) 329-417<br />

M. Brouskari, <strong>The</strong> Monuments <strong>of</strong> the Acropolis (Athens, 1997)<br />

_____, “Ζώδια Λαΐνεα. Nouvelles figures de la frise de l’ Erechtheion,” <strong>in</strong> M. Schmidt,<br />

ed., Kanon: Festschrift Ernst Berger zum 60. Geburstag am 26. Februar 1988<br />

gewidmet (Basel, 1988) 60-68<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Paul <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>ra Canellopoulos Museum (Athens, 1985)<br />

W. L. Brown, <strong>The</strong> Etruscan Lion (Oxford, 1960)<br />

A. Brückner, Der Friedh<strong>of</strong> am Eridanos (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1909)<br />

C. D. Buck, A Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Selected Synonyms <strong>in</strong> the Pr<strong>in</strong>cipal Indo-European<br />

Languages (Chicago, 1949)<br />

_____, Comparative Grammar <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> (Chicago, 1933)<br />

E. A. W. Budge, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Inscriptions <strong>of</strong> Darius the Great on the Rock <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Behistun <strong>in</strong> Persia (London, 1907)<br />

W. Burkert, tr. P. B<strong>in</strong>g, Homo Necans: <strong>The</strong> Anthropology <strong>of</strong> Ancient Greek Sacrificial<br />

Ritual <strong>and</strong> Myth (Berkeley, 1983)<br />

J. Burt, “<strong>The</strong> Illum<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gdom: <strong>The</strong> Role <strong>of</strong> Light <strong>and</strong> Electricity <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Animal</strong> Representation,” <strong>in</strong> L. Kal<strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> A. Fitzgerald, eds., <strong>The</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Reader.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Essential Classic <strong>and</strong> Contemporary Writ<strong>in</strong>gs (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 2007)<br />

289-301<br />

R. G. Bury, ed., tr., Plato IX. Laws I; II (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1926; repr.<br />

1952)<br />

424


A. Campana, “<strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Word “Humanist,” Journal <strong>of</strong> the Warburg <strong>and</strong><br />

Courtlauld Institutes 9 (1946) 60-73<br />

R. Carpenter, Greek Art. A Study <strong>of</strong> the Formal Evolution <strong>of</strong> Style (Philadelphia, 1962)<br />

P. Cartledge, <strong>The</strong> Greeks: A Portrait <strong>of</strong> Self <strong>and</strong> Others (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1993;<br />

second ed., 2002)<br />

L. D. Caskey, “<strong>The</strong> Inscriptions,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum (Cambridge,<br />

Mass., 1927) 277-422<br />

D. Cast, <strong>The</strong> Calumny <strong>of</strong> Apelles. A Study <strong>in</strong> the Humanist Tradition (New Haven <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1981)<br />

P. Chantra<strong>in</strong>e, Dictionnaire étymologique (Paris, 1968)<br />

W. A. P. Childs, “<strong>The</strong> Classic as Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” Art Journal 48 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 1988)<br />

10-14<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> City-Reliefs <strong>of</strong> Lycia (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1978)<br />

_____. <strong>and</strong> P. Demargne, Fouilles de Xanthos VIII. Les monument des Néréides. Le<br />

décor sculpté (Paris, 1989)<br />

G. Clark, tr., Porphyry. On Abst<strong>in</strong>ence from Kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Ithaca, New York, 2000)<br />

J. Clutton-Brock, “Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Dog: Domestication <strong>and</strong> Early History,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell,<br />

ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog: Its Evolution, Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with People<br />

(Cambridge, 1995) 7-20<br />

CNN, 2002, 15 May. Starv<strong>in</strong>g Dog Eats Its Owner.<br />

http://edition.cnn.com/2002/WORLD/Europe/05/15/Austria.dog/<strong>in</strong>dex.html<br />

B. Cohen, “Red-Figure Vases Take W<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> J. Oakley et al., eds., Athenian Potters <strong>and</strong><br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>ters. <strong>The</strong> Conference Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs (Oxbow Monograph 67; Oxford, 1997)<br />

141-155<br />

S. G. Cole, “L<strong>and</strong>scapes <strong>of</strong> Dionysos <strong>and</strong> Elysian Fields,” <strong>in</strong> M. B. Cosmopoulos, ed.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Archaeology <strong>and</strong> Ritual <strong>of</strong> Ancient Greek Secret Cults (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 2003) 193-217<br />

M. Collignon, Les statues funéraires dans l’art grec (Paris, 1911)<br />

B. J. Coll<strong>in</strong>s, ed., A History <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> World <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Near East (Leiden <strong>and</strong><br />

Boston, 2002)<br />

425


H. P. Cooke, ed., tr., Aristotle I. <strong>The</strong> Categories. On Interpretation (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1938, repr. 1996)<br />

R. Copp<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>and</strong> R. Schneider, “Evolution <strong>of</strong> Work<strong>in</strong>g Dogs,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Domestic Dog: Its Evolution, Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with People (Cambridge,<br />

1995) 21-47<br />

V. Coulon, ed., <strong>and</strong> H. van Daele, tr., Aristophane (Collection de Universités de France<br />

5; Paris, 1930; repr. 1963)<br />

J. Curtis <strong>and</strong> N. Tallis, eds., Forgotten Empire: <strong>The</strong> World <strong>of</strong> Achaemenid Persia<br />

(Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 2005)<br />

A. Dalby, Siren Feasts: A History <strong>of</strong> Food <strong>and</strong> Gastronomy <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1996)<br />

A. C. Danto, “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> as Art Historians. Reflections on the Innocent Eye,” <strong>in</strong> A. C.<br />

Danto, Beyond the Brillo Box. <strong>The</strong> Visual Arts <strong>in</strong> Post-Historical Perspective<br />

(New York, 1992) 15-31<br />

J. D. Denniston <strong>and</strong> D. Page, eds., Aeschylus. Agamemnon (Oxford, 1957)<br />

A. De Ridder, Catalogue des bronzes de la société archaeologique d’Athènes (1889)<br />

A. De Sél<strong>in</strong>court, tr., rev. J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories (London <strong>and</strong> New<br />

York, 1996; rev. ed., 2003)<br />

M. Detienne <strong>and</strong> J.-P. Vernant, tr. J. Lloyd, Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence <strong>in</strong> Greek Culture <strong>and</strong><br />

Society (Hassocks, Sussex <strong>and</strong> Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, New Jersey, 1978)<br />

C. Dewald, “Introduction; Notes” <strong>in</strong> R. Waterfield, tr., Herodotus: <strong>The</strong> Histories (Oxford<br />

<strong>and</strong> New York, 1998) ix-xli; 594-735<br />

O. S. Dewaw, “Army Mechanic is Acquitted on Desertion Charge,” <strong>The</strong> New York Times<br />

(July 29, 2005) 15<br />

G. Di Pasquale <strong>and</strong> F. Paolucci, Uffizi: <strong>The</strong> Ancient <strong>Sculpture</strong>s (Florence, 2001)<br />

J. Diggle, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong>ophrastus. Characters (Cambridge, 2004)<br />

A. A. Donohue, rev. <strong>of</strong> J. Tanner, <strong>The</strong> Invention <strong>of</strong> Art History <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>:<br />

Religion, Society <strong>and</strong> Artistic Rationalisation (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2006),<br />

<strong>in</strong> CW 101.1 (2007) 109-110<br />

_____, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Problem <strong>of</strong> Description (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2005)<br />

426


_____, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Images <strong>of</strong> the Gods: Considerations on Term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>and</strong><br />

Methodology,” Hephaistos 15 (1997) 31-45<br />

_____, “W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann’s History <strong>of</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> Polyclitus,” <strong>in</strong> W. G. Moon, ed., Polykleitos,<br />

the Doryphoros, <strong>and</strong> Tradition (Madison, 1995) 327-353<br />

_____, Xoana <strong>and</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (American <strong>Classical</strong> Studies 15;<br />

Atlanta, 1988)<br />

_____, “Zum Löwenschieber aus Schachtgrab III <strong>in</strong> Mykene,” AA 93 (1978) 259-262<br />

S. Drougou, “Τό ύφασµα της Βεργίνας: Πρώτες παρατηρήσεις,” <strong>in</strong> ΑΜΗΤΟΣ:<br />

Τιµητικός τόµος για τον καθηγητή Μανώλη Ανδρόνικο (<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1987)<br />

303-323<br />

S. E<strong>in</strong>audi, “Pyramidion <strong>of</strong> the Pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat III,” <strong>in</strong> A. Bongioanni et al., eds.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Illustrated Guide to the Egyptian Museum <strong>in</strong> Cairo (Cairo, 2001) 126<br />

C. Eisler, Dürer’s <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C., 1991)<br />

G. F. Else, ““Imitation” <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century,” CP 53 (1958) 73-90<br />

J. Elsner, “Reflections on the ‘Greek Revolution’ <strong>in</strong> Art: From Changes <strong>in</strong> View<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

Transformation <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity,” <strong>in</strong> S. Godhill <strong>and</strong> R. Osborne, eds., Reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Revolutions through Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2006) 68-95<br />

_____, Art <strong>and</strong> the Roman Viewer: <strong>The</strong> Transformation <strong>of</strong> Art from the Pagan World to<br />

Christianity (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 1995)<br />

A. Emmerich Gallery Inc., <strong>Classical</strong> Antiquity: An Exhibition Organized <strong>in</strong> Cooperation<br />

with Münzen <strong>and</strong> Medaillen AG, Basle, Switzerl<strong>and</strong> November 22, 1975-January<br />

10, 1976 (Zurich <strong>and</strong> New York, 1975)<br />

S. Ew<strong>in</strong>g, E. Grossman, eds., Shadow Cat: Encounter<strong>in</strong>g the American Mounta<strong>in</strong> Lion<br />

(Seattle, 1999)<br />

A. Farkas, “<strong>The</strong> Horse <strong>and</strong> Rider <strong>in</strong> Achaemenid Art,” Persica 4 (1969) 57-76<br />

M. Faust, “Die künstlerische Verwendung von κύων ’Hund’ <strong>in</strong> den homerischen Epen,”<br />

Glotta 48 (1970) 8-29<br />

H. Ferrar, ed., <strong>The</strong> Concise Oxford French-English Dictionary (Oxford, 1984; second ed.,<br />

1980)<br />

427


G. Ferrari, Figures <strong>of</strong> Speech. Men <strong>and</strong> Maidens <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 2002)<br />

_____, “<strong>The</strong> Ancient Temple on the Acropolis at Athens,” AJA 106 (2002) 11-35<br />

_____, “Eye-Cup,” RA (1986) 5-20<br />

B. D. Filow, Die archaische Nekropole von Trebenischte am Ochrida-See (Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Leipzig, 1927)<br />

N. F<strong>in</strong>lay, “Eros <strong>and</strong> Sadism: Delacroix’s Depictions <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g People,” <strong>in</strong> N. H.<br />

Bluestone, ed., Double Vision: Perspectives on Gender <strong>and</strong> the Visual Arts<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Toronto, 1995) 21-37<br />

N. C. Flores, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Middle Ages (New York, 2000)<br />

R. C. Foltz, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Islamic Tradition <strong>and</strong> Muslim Cultures (Oxford, 2006)<br />

W. W. Fortenbaugh et al., eds., trs., <strong>The</strong>ophrastus <strong>of</strong> Eresus. Sources for his Life,<br />

Writ<strong>in</strong>gs, Thought <strong>and</strong> Influence II (Leiden <strong>and</strong> New York, 1993)<br />

H. N. Fowler, “<strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 232-276<br />

_____, ed., tr., Plato. Cratylus. Parmenides. Greater Hippias. Lesser Hippias<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1926; repr. 1963)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Statesman. Philebus (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1925;<br />

repr., 1962)<br />

E. Fraenkel, Aeschylus. Agamemnon II (Oxford, 1950)<br />

M. Fränkel, Die Inschriften von Pergamon (Altertümer von Pergamon vol. 8, pt. 2;<br />

Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1895)<br />

J. G. Frazer, Pausanias’s Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> (London, 1898; second ed., 1913)<br />

S. Fraser-Lu, Indonesian Batik. Process, Patterns <strong>and</strong> Places (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1986)<br />

P. Friedländer <strong>and</strong> H. B. H<strong>of</strong>fleit, Epigrammata. Greek Inscriptions <strong>in</strong> Verse. From the<br />

Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs to the Persian Wars (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1948)<br />

H. Frisk, Griechisches etymologisches Wörterbuch (Heidelberg, 1954)<br />

428


E. Fudge, “A Left-H<strong>and</strong>ed Blow: Writ<strong>in</strong>g the History <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> N. Rothfels, ed.,<br />

Represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton <strong>and</strong> Indianapolis, 2002) 3-18<br />

H. Gabelmann, Studien zum frühgriechischen Löwenbild (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1965)<br />

R. Garl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>The</strong> Eye <strong>of</strong> the Beholder. Deformity <strong>and</strong> Disability <strong>in</strong> the Graeco-Roman<br />

World ((Ithaca, 1995)<br />

_____, “A First Catalogue <strong>of</strong> Attic Peribolos Tombs,” BSA 77 (1982) 125-176<br />

P. Garsney, Food <strong>and</strong> Society <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Antiquity (Cambridge, 1999)<br />

W. Gauer, Die Bronzegefässe von Olympia (Olympische Forschungen 20; Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

New York, 1991)<br />

N.-G. Gejwall, Lerna I: A Preclassical Site <strong>in</strong> the Argolid: <strong>The</strong> Fauna (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1969)<br />

A. Georgopapadakos, Λεξικό Ανωµάλων Ρηµάτων της Αρχαίας Ελληνικής<br />

Γλώσσης—Lexicon <strong>of</strong> Irregular Verbs <strong>of</strong> the Ancient Greek Language<br />

(<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1964)<br />

S. Georgoudi, “Funeral Epigrams for <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>,” Αρχαιολογία 11 (1984) 36-41<br />

D. Gerziger, “E<strong>in</strong>e Decke aus dem sechsten Grab der ‘Sieben Brüder,’” AK 18 (1975) 51-<br />

55<br />

I. S. Gilhus, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, Gods <strong>and</strong> Humans: Chang<strong>in</strong>g Attitudes to <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek,<br />

Roman <strong>and</strong> Early Christian Eras (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2006)<br />

M. Gjødesen, “Greek Bronzes: A Review Article,” AJA 67 (1963) 333-351<br />

K. Glowacki, “A New Fragment <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheion Frieze,” Hesperia 64 (1995) 325-331<br />

A. Godley, ed., tr., Herodotus II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1938; repr. 2000)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Herodotus I (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1920; repr. 1946)<br />

H. Goedicke, Re-Used Blocks from the Pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhet I at Lisht (<strong>The</strong><br />

Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art Egyptian Expedition no. 20; New York, 1971)<br />

L. Golden, “Science, Darw<strong>in</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Art History,” <strong>in</strong> L. Golden, ed., Rais<strong>in</strong>g the Eyebrow:<br />

John Onians <strong>and</strong> World Art Series. An Album Amicorum <strong>in</strong> His Honour (BAR<br />

International Series 996; Oxford, 2001) 79-90<br />

429


E. H. Gombrich, “‘<strong>The</strong> Father <strong>of</strong> Art History’: A Read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Lectures on Aesthetics<br />

<strong>of</strong> G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831),” <strong>in</strong> E. H. Gombrich, Tributes. Interpreters <strong>of</strong> Our<br />

Cultural Tradition (Ithaca, New York, 1984) 51-69.<br />

_____, “Reflections on the Greek Revolution,” <strong>in</strong> E. H. Gombrich, Art <strong>and</strong> Illusion. A<br />

Study <strong>in</strong> the Psychology <strong>of</strong> Pictorial Representation (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1961) 116-145<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Story <strong>of</strong> Art (New York, 1951)<br />

R. L. Gordon, “<strong>The</strong> Real <strong>and</strong> the Imag<strong>in</strong>ary: Production <strong>and</strong> Religion <strong>in</strong> the Graeco-<br />

Roman World,” Art History 2 (1979) 5-34<br />

P. B. Gove, ed., Webster’s Third International Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the English Language<br />

Unabridged (Spr<strong>in</strong>gfield, Mass., 1961; 1986)<br />

G. Goyon, “La chausée monumentale et le temple de la vallée de la pyramide de<br />

Khéops,” BIFAO 67 (1969) 7-69<br />

C. H. Greenewalt, Jr., Ritual D<strong>in</strong>ners <strong>in</strong> Early Historic Sardis (Berkeley, 1978)<br />

M. Gregori, ed., In the Light <strong>of</strong> Apollo: Italian Renaissance <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>, 22 December<br />

2003-31 March 2004 (exhibition catalogue, National Gallery-Alex<strong>and</strong>ros Soutzos<br />

Museum <strong>and</strong> Fondazione di Studi dell’Arte Roberto Longhi; Athens, 2003)<br />

P. F. Grendler, “Man is Almost a God: Fra Battista between Renaissance <strong>and</strong> Catholic<br />

Reformation,” <strong>in</strong> J. O’Malley et al., eds., Humanity <strong>and</strong> Div<strong>in</strong>ity <strong>in</strong> Renaissance<br />

<strong>and</strong> Reformation. Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> Charles Tr<strong>in</strong>kaus (Leiden <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1993) 227-249<br />

D. Grene, tr., <strong>The</strong> History. Herodotus (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1987)<br />

K. C. Grier, Pets <strong>in</strong> America: A History (Chapel Hill, 2006)<br />

T. Griffith, tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic (Cambridge, 2000)<br />

C. A. W. Guggisberg, Simba. <strong>The</strong> Life <strong>of</strong> the Lion (Philadelphia <strong>and</strong> New York, 1963)<br />

C. B. Gulick, ed., tr., Athenaeus VI. <strong>The</strong> Deipnosophists (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1937; repr. 1959)<br />

D. B. Guralnik, ed., Webster’s New World Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the American Language (New<br />

York, 1970; second ed., 1980)<br />

W. K. C. Guthrie, In the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g: Some Greek Views on the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Life <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Early State <strong>of</strong> Man (Ithaca, New York, 1957; repr. 1965)<br />

430


M. Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e Stätte für die Ewigkeit. Der Pyramidenkomplex des Cheops aus<br />

baulicher, architektonischer und kulturhistorischer Sicht (Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 2004)<br />

S. Halliwell, <strong>The</strong> Aesthetics <strong>of</strong> Mimesis: Ancient Texts <strong>and</strong> Modern Problems (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton,<br />

2002)<br />

_____, “Plato <strong>and</strong> Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> N. K. Rutter <strong>and</strong> B. A. Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image <strong>in</strong><br />

Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh, 2000) 99-116<br />

N. G. L. Hammond, “Dramatic Production to the Death <strong>of</strong> Aeschylus,” GRBS 13 (1972)<br />

387-450<br />

_____, <strong>and</strong> L. J. Roseman, “<strong>The</strong> Construction <strong>of</strong> Xerxes’ Bridge over the Hellespont,”<br />

JHS 116 (1996) 88-107<br />

H. Hansen <strong>and</strong> G. M. Qu<strong>in</strong>n, Greek. An Intensive Course (New York, 1992)<br />

R. M. Harriott, “<strong>The</strong> Argive Elders, the Discern<strong>in</strong>g Shepherd <strong>and</strong> the Fawn<strong>in</strong>g Dog:<br />

Mislead<strong>in</strong>g Communication <strong>in</strong> the Agamemnon,” CQ 32 (1982) 9-17<br />

T. Harrison, “Upside Down <strong>and</strong> Back to Front: Herodotus <strong>and</strong> the Greek Encounter with<br />

Egypt,” <strong>in</strong> R. Matthews <strong>and</strong> C. Roemer, eds., Ancient Perspectives on Egypt<br />

(London, 2003) 145-155<br />

L. A. Hart, “Dogs as Human Companions: A Review <strong>of</strong> the Relationship,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell,<br />

ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog: Its Evolution, Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with People<br />

(Cambridge, 1995) 161-178<br />

F. Hartog, tr. J. Lloyd, <strong>The</strong> Mirror <strong>of</strong> Herodotus: <strong>The</strong> Representation <strong>of</strong> the Other <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> History (Berkeley, 1988)<br />

C. M. Havelock, “Art as Communication <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> E. A. Havelock <strong>and</strong> J. P.<br />

Hershbell, eds., Communication Arts <strong>in</strong> the Ancient World (New York, 1978) 95-<br />

118<br />

Z. Hawass, Mounta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Pharaohs. <strong>The</strong> Untold Story <strong>of</strong> the Pyramid Builders (New<br />

York, 2006)<br />

_____, “<strong>The</strong> Programs <strong>of</strong> the Royal Funerary Complexes <strong>of</strong> the Fourth Dynasty,” <strong>in</strong> D.<br />

O’Connor <strong>and</strong> D. P. Silverman, eds., Ancient Egyptian K<strong>in</strong>gship (Leiden, New<br />

York, <strong>and</strong> Köln, 1995) 221-262<br />

_____, “Recent Discoveries at Giza Plateau,” <strong>in</strong> S. Curto et al., eds., Atti Sesto Congresso<br />

Internazionale di Egittologia I. Settembre 1-8, Tor<strong>in</strong>o (Tur<strong>in</strong>, 1992) 241-242<br />

431


_____ <strong>and</strong> M. Verner, “Newly Discovered Blocks from the Causeway <strong>of</strong> Sahure<br />

(Archaeological Report),” MDAIK 52 (1996) 177-186<br />

J. Heath, <strong>The</strong> Talk<strong>in</strong>g Greeks. Speech, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Other <strong>in</strong> Homer, Aeschylus, <strong>and</strong><br />

Plato (Cambridge, 2005)<br />

M. C. Hellmann, Recherches sur le vocabulaire de l’ architecture grecque d’ après les<br />

<strong>in</strong>scriptions de Délos (Paris, 1992)<br />

J. P. Hershbell, “Empedocles’ Oral Style,” CJ 63 (1968) 351-357<br />

W. S. Hett, ed., tr., Aristotle. M<strong>in</strong>or Works (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1936; repr.<br />

2000)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Aristotle VIII. On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath (Cambridge,<br />

Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1936; repr. 1995)<br />

R. A. Higg<strong>in</strong>s, Greek Terracottas (London, 1967)<br />

M. Hill, “Kneel<strong>in</strong>g Captive,” <strong>in</strong> J. P. Allen et al., Egyptian Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids<br />

(exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, September<br />

16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum, Toronto, February 13-<br />

May 22, 2000; New York, 1999) 440-441<br />

D. H<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>The</strong>ocritus: Idylls <strong>and</strong> Epigrams (New York, 1982)<br />

S. Hodk<strong>in</strong>son, “Laconian Artistic Production <strong>and</strong> the Problem <strong>of</strong> Spartan Austerity,” <strong>in</strong><br />

N. Fischer <strong>and</strong> H. van Wees, eds., Archaic <strong>Greece</strong>: New Approaches <strong>and</strong> New<br />

Evidence (London, 1998) 93-117<br />

H. H<strong>of</strong>fmann, “Rhyta <strong>and</strong> Kantharoi <strong>in</strong> Greek Ritual,” Greek Vases <strong>in</strong> the J. Paul Getty<br />

Museum 4; Occasional Papers on Antiquities 5 (Malibu, 1989) 131-166<br />

J. C. Hogan, A Commentary on the Complete Greek Tragedies. Aeschylus (Chicago <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1984)<br />

T. Hölscher, Griechische Historienbilder des 5. und 4. Jahrhunderts V. Chr. (Würzburg,<br />

1975)<br />

W. D. Hooper, ed., tr., rev. H. B. Ash, Marcus Porcius Cato. On Argiculture. Marcus<br />

Terentius Varro. On Agriculture (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1934; rev. <strong>and</strong><br />

repr. 1935; repr. 1993)<br />

S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford <strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary (third ed.;<br />

Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996)<br />

432


W. W. How <strong>and</strong> J. Wells, A Commentary on Herodotus I (Oxford, 1912; repr. 1957)<br />

D. B. Hull, Hounds <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1964)<br />

J. M. Hurwit, “Lizards, Lions, <strong>and</strong> the Uncanny <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art,” Hesperia 75 (2006)<br />

121-136<br />

_____, “Read<strong>in</strong>g the Chigi Vase,” Hesperia 71 (2002) 1-22<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Acropolis: History, Mythology, <strong>and</strong> Archaeology from the Neolithic<br />

Era to the Present (Cambridge, 1999)<br />

_____, “<strong>The</strong> Words <strong>in</strong> the Image: Orality, Literacy, <strong>and</strong> Early Greek Art,” Word <strong>and</strong><br />

Image 6 (1990) 180-197<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> Culture <strong>of</strong> Early <strong>Greece</strong>, 1100 -480 B.C. (Ithaca <strong>and</strong> London, 1985)<br />

J. Husson called Champfleury, Les Chats (Paris, 1868)<br />

J. Isager, “Humanissima ars: Evaluation <strong>and</strong> Devaluation <strong>in</strong> Pl<strong>in</strong>y, Vasari, <strong>and</strong> Baden,”<br />

<strong>in</strong> A. A. Donohue <strong>and</strong> M. D. Fullerton, eds., Ancient Art <strong>and</strong> Its Historiography<br />

(Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2003) 48-68<br />

A. F. Janson, rev. H. W. Hanson, History <strong>of</strong> Art I (fourth edition; New York, 1991)<br />

W. F. Jashemski, <strong>The</strong> Gardens <strong>of</strong> Pompeii, Herculaneum, <strong>and</strong> the Villas Destroyed by<br />

Vesuvius (New York, 1979)<br />

L. H. Jeffery <strong>and</strong> P. Cartledge, “Sparta <strong>and</strong> Samos: A Special Relationship?” CQ 32<br />

(1982) 243-265<br />

I. Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Parthenon <strong>Sculpture</strong>s (Cambridge, Mass., 2007)<br />

_____, Greek Architecture <strong>and</strong> Its <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Cambridge, Mass., 2006)<br />

G. Jennison, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> for Show <strong>and</strong> Pleasure <strong>in</strong> Ancient Rome (Manchester, 1937)<br />

P. Jesk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Environment <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> World (London, 1998)<br />

R. J<strong>of</strong>froy, Le trésor de Vix (Côte-d’ Or) (Paris, 1954)<br />

W. St. John, “New Breed <strong>of</strong> Lawyer Gives Every Dog His Day <strong>in</strong> Court,” New York<br />

Times (Sept. 3, 2006) 13<br />

S. I. Johnston, Restless Dead: Encounters between the Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the Dead <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

<strong>Greece</strong> (Berkeley, 1999)<br />

433


_____, “Crossroads,” ZPE 88 (1991) 217-224<br />

_____, Hekate Soteira. A Study <strong>of</strong> Hekate’s Roles <strong>in</strong> the Chaldean Oracles <strong>and</strong> Related<br />

Literature (Atlanta, 1990)<br />

D. M. Jones, ed., Scholia Vetera <strong>in</strong> Aristophanis Equites (Scholia <strong>in</strong> Aristophanem vol. 1,<br />

pt. 2; Gron<strong>in</strong>gen <strong>and</strong> Amsterdam, 1969)<br />

W. H. S. Jones, ed., tr., Pausanias. Description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greece</strong> IV (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1935; repr. 1961)<br />

J. Jouanna, tr. M. B. DeBovoise, Hippocrates (Baltimore <strong>and</strong> London, 1999)<br />

D. Joubert <strong>and</strong> B. Joubert, <strong>The</strong> Lions <strong>of</strong> Savuti. Hunt<strong>in</strong>g with the Moon (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,<br />

D.C., 1997)<br />

A. Kaegi, tr. J. A. Kleist, Kaegi’s Greek Grammar (twenty-first edition; Wauconda,<br />

Ill<strong>in</strong>ois, 1995)<br />

L. Kahil <strong>and</strong> A. Jaquem<strong>in</strong>, “Harpyiai,” LIMC IV.1; IV.2 (Zurich <strong>and</strong> Munich, 1988) 445-<br />

450; 266-271<br />

N. Kaltsas, tr. D. Hardy, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the National Archaeological Museum, Athens (Los<br />

Angeles, 2002)<br />

H. J. Kantor, <strong>The</strong> Aegean <strong>and</strong> the Orient <strong>in</strong> the Second Millenium B.C. (<strong>The</strong><br />

Archaeological Institute <strong>of</strong> America Monograph Number 1; Boston, 1947; repr.<br />

1997)<br />

S. Karouzou, “An Underworld Scene on a Black-Figured Lekythos,” JHS 92 (1972) 64-<br />

73<br />

_____, “ΤΕΧΝΟΥΡΓΟΙ ΚΡΑΤΗΡΩΝ: Fragmente bronzeren Volutenkratere,” AM 94<br />

(1979) 77-91<br />

A. Katcher <strong>and</strong> A. Beck, Between Pets <strong>and</strong> People: <strong>The</strong> Importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Animal</strong><br />

Companionship (West Lafayette, 1983; rev. ed., 1996)<br />

T. S. Kawami, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Persian Taste: Some <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>s from Persepolis,”<br />

AJA 90 (1962) 259-267<br />

O. Keller, Die antike Tierwelt I (Leipzig, 1909)<br />

M. Kemp, “Draw<strong>in</strong>gs for Il Cavallo del Duca Francesco di Bronzo,” <strong>in</strong> D. C. Ahl, ed.,<br />

Leonardo da V<strong>in</strong>ci’s Sforza Monument Horse: <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> the Eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g;<br />

Bethlehem, Pennsylvania <strong>and</strong> London, 1995) 64-78<br />

434


R. G. Kent, Old Persian. Grammar. Texts. Lexicon (New Haven, 1950; second rev. ed.,<br />

1953)<br />

K. Kete, <strong>The</strong> Beast <strong>in</strong> the Boudoir: Petkeep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> N<strong>in</strong>eteenth-Century Paris (Berkeley<br />

<strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1994)<br />

E. C. Keuls, Plato <strong>and</strong> Greek Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (Leiden, 1978)<br />

A. K<strong>in</strong>g, “Mammals. Evidence from Wall Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>Sculpture</strong>, Mosaics, Faunal Rema<strong>in</strong>s,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Ancient Literary Sources,” <strong>in</strong> W. F. Jashemski <strong>and</strong> F. G. Meyer, eds., <strong>The</strong><br />

Natural History <strong>of</strong> Pompeii (Cambridge, 2002) 401-450<br />

K. F. Kitchell, Jr., “Man’s Best Friend? <strong>The</strong> Chang<strong>in</strong>g Role <strong>of</strong> the Dog <strong>in</strong> Greek<br />

Society,” <strong>in</strong> B. Santillo Frizell, ed., PECUS. Man <strong>and</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>in</strong> Antiquity,<br />

Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Conference at the Swedish Institute <strong>in</strong> Rome, September 9-12,<br />

2002 (<strong>The</strong> Swedish Institute <strong>in</strong> Rome. Projects <strong>and</strong> Sem<strong>in</strong>ars 1; Rome, 2004) 177-<br />

182<br />

U. Knigge, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Kerameikos. History-Monuments-Excavations (Athens, 1991)<br />

D. Konstan, “Anger, Hatred, <strong>and</strong> Genocide <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” Common Knowledge 13<br />

(2007) 170-187<br />

____, <strong>The</strong> Emotions <strong>of</strong> the Ancient Greeks: Studies <strong>in</strong> Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Literature<br />

(Toronto, 2006)<br />

F. Koreny, Albrecht Dürer <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>and</strong> Plant Studies <strong>of</strong> the Renaissance (Boston,<br />

1985)<br />

E. Kosmetatou, “Ζώιδια <strong>in</strong> the Delian Inventory Lists,” Mnemosyne 57 (2002) 481-484<br />

A. Kosmopoulou, <strong>The</strong> Iconography <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>d Statue Bases <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Periods (Madison, 2002)<br />

C. Koukouli, “Νέο Σύµπλεγµα από τη Ζωφόρο του Ερεχθείου,” ArchDelt 22 (1967)<br />

133-148<br />

D. Kovacs, ed., tr., Euripides IV. Trojan Women. Iphigeneia among the Taurians. Ion<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1999)<br />

C. M. Kraay, Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Co<strong>in</strong>s (Berkeley <strong>and</strong> Los Angeles, 1976)<br />

P. Krentz <strong>and</strong> E. L. Wheeler, eds., trs., Polyaenus. Strategems <strong>of</strong> War II (Chicago, 1994)<br />

P. O. Kristeller, “<strong>The</strong> Modern System <strong>of</strong> the Arts: A Study <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Aesthetics<br />

Part I,” Journal <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas 12. 4 (Oct., 1951) 496-527<br />

435


E. Kunze, “Kle<strong>in</strong>plastik aus Bronze,” <strong>in</strong> E. Kunze et al., VII. Bericht über die<br />

Ausgrabungen <strong>in</strong> Olympia (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1961)<br />

J. Lacan, tr. A. Sheridan, <strong>The</strong> Four Fundamental Concepts <strong>of</strong> Psychoanalysis<br />

(Hammonsworth, 1979)<br />

G. V. Lalonde, “Topographical Notes on Aristophanes,” Hesperia Supplement 20 (1982)<br />

77-81<br />

A. W. Lawrence, rev. <strong>of</strong> O. Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis (Cambridge,<br />

Mass., 1941), <strong>in</strong> JHS 62 (1942) 101-102<br />

P. Lawrence, “<strong>The</strong> Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Chimaera Pa<strong>in</strong>ter,” AJA 63 (1959) 349-363<br />

D. Lazaridis, Amphipolis (M<strong>in</strong>istry <strong>of</strong> Culture. Archaeological Receipts Fund; Athens,<br />

1997)<br />

M. M. Lee, “<strong>The</strong> Myth <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Peplos” (diss. Bryn Mawr College, 1999)<br />

G. V. Leftwich, “Polykleitos <strong>and</strong> Hippokratic Medic<strong>in</strong>e,” <strong>in</strong> W. G. Moon, ed.,<br />

Polykleitos, the Doryphoros, <strong>and</strong> Tradition (Madison, 1995) 38-51<br />

M. Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids (London, 1997)<br />

W. E. Leonard, tr., <strong>The</strong> Fragments <strong>of</strong> Empedocles (Chicago, 1908)<br />

W. R. Lethaby, “Greek Lion Monuments,” JHS 38 (1918) 37-44<br />

C. Lévi-Strauss, tr. R. Needham, Totemism (London, 1969)<br />

S. Lewis, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Woman: An Iconographic H<strong>and</strong>book (London <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

2002)<br />

H. G. Liddell <strong>and</strong> R. Scott, rev. H. S. Jones <strong>and</strong> R. McKenzie, A Greek-English Lexicon<br />

with a Revised Supplement (new n<strong>in</strong>th ed.; Oxford, 1940; repr., 1996)<br />

L. R. LiDonnici, <strong>The</strong> Epidaurian Miracle Inscriptions: Text, Translation <strong>and</strong><br />

Commentary (Text <strong>and</strong> Translations 36, Graeco-Roman Religion Series 11;<br />

Atlanta, 1995)<br />

S. Lilja, Dogs <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Poetry (Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 56;<br />

Hels<strong>in</strong>ki, 1976)<br />

T. L<strong>in</strong>ders <strong>and</strong> B. Alroth, eds., Economics <strong>of</strong> Cult <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Greek World.<br />

Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Uppsala Symposium 1990 (Uppsala, 1992) 15-20<br />

436


A. L<strong>in</strong>zey <strong>and</strong> T. Regan, eds., <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>and</strong> Christianity. A Book <strong>of</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>gs (New York,<br />

1988)<br />

L. Lipp<strong>in</strong>cott <strong>and</strong> A. Blühm, eds., Fierce Friends: Artists <strong>and</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, 1750-1900<br />

(exhibition catalogue, Van Gogh Museum, Amsterdam <strong>and</strong> Carnegie Museum <strong>of</strong><br />

Art, Pittsburgh; London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2005)<br />

A. B. Lloyd, “Herodotus on Egyptian Build<strong>in</strong>gs: A Test Case,” <strong>in</strong> A. Powell, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Greek World (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1995) 273-300<br />

_____, Herodotus Book II. Commentary 1-98 II (Leiden, 1976)<br />

H. Lloyd-Jones, “<strong>The</strong>ori or Isthmiastae,” <strong>in</strong> H. W. Smith, ed., tr., Aeschylus II.<br />

Agamemnon. Libation-Bearers. Eumenides. Fragments (Cambridge, Mass <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1923; repr. 1983) 541-555<br />

_____, tr., Aeschylus. Oresteia. Agamemnon (Berkeley, 1979)<br />

J. Löbe, “Notizen über der Hund aus griechischen und römischen Schriftstellern,”<br />

Mitteilungen aus dem Österl<strong>and</strong>e 9 (1900) 31-56<br />

E. Loewy, tr. E. Fothergill, <strong>The</strong> Render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Nature <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art (London, 1907)<br />

S. H. Lonsdale, Creatures <strong>of</strong> Speech. Lion, Herd<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> Hunt<strong>in</strong>g Similes <strong>in</strong> the Iliad<br />

(Stuttgart, 1990)<br />

E. Löwy, Die Naturwiedergabe <strong>in</strong> der älteren griechischen Kunst (Rome, 1900)<br />

C. A. Lutz, Unnatural Emotions: Everyday Sentiments on a Micronesian Atoll <strong>and</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

Challenge to Western <strong>The</strong>ory (Chicago, 1988)<br />

R. W. Macan, Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Fourth, Fifth, <strong>and</strong> Sixth Books I (London, 1895)<br />

G. C. Macaulay, tr., rev. D. Late<strong>in</strong>er, <strong>The</strong> Histories. Herodotus (New York, 2004)<br />

J.-J. Maffre, “Collection Paul Canellopoulos: Vases Béotiens,” BCH 99 (1975) 409-520<br />

C. Ma<strong>in</strong>oldi, L’ image du loup et du chien dans la Grèce ancienne d’ Homère à Platon<br />

(Paris, 1984)<br />

H. F. Mallgrave, tr., Johann Joachim W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann. History <strong>of</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Antiquity (Los<br />

Angeles, 2006)<br />

C. Manes, Other Creations: Rediscover<strong>in</strong>g the Spirituality <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (New York, 1997)<br />

C. Mango, “Antique Statuary <strong>and</strong> the Byzant<strong>in</strong>e Beholder,” DOP 17 (1963) 53-75<br />

437


G. A. Mansuelli, Galleria degli Uffizi: Le sculture I (Rome, 1958)<br />

S. Mar<strong>in</strong>atos, Crete <strong>and</strong> Mycenae (New York, 1960)<br />

G. E. Markoe, “<strong>The</strong> ‘Lion Attack’ <strong>in</strong> Archaic Greek Art: Heroic Triumph,” ClAnt 8<br />

(1989) 86-115<br />

J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, Greek Historians (Oxford, 2001)<br />

J. Marshall, “Statue <strong>of</strong> a Lion,” M.M.A. Bullet<strong>in</strong> 5 (1910) 210-213<br />

R. Mayer, ed., <strong>The</strong> Harper Coll<strong>in</strong>s Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Art Terms <strong>and</strong> Techniques (New York,<br />

1969; second ed., 1991)<br />

A. Mayor, <strong>The</strong> First Fossil Hunters. Paleontology <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Times (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton,<br />

2000)<br />

D. W. McDonald <strong>and</strong> G. M. Carr, “Variation <strong>in</strong> Dog Society: Between Resource<br />

Dispersion <strong>and</strong> Social Flux,” <strong>in</strong> J. Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog: Its Evolution,<br />

Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with People (Cambridge, 1995) 199-216<br />

D. M. McDowell, Aristophanes <strong>and</strong> Athens. An Introduction to the Plays (Oxford, 1995)<br />

_____, ed., Aristophanes. Wasps (Oxford, 1971)<br />

D. McFarl<strong>and</strong>, ed., <strong>The</strong> Oxford Companion to <strong>Animal</strong> Behavior (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York,<br />

1982)<br />

P. B. Medewar, “Is the Scientific Paper a Fraud?” <strong>The</strong> Listener 70, no. 1798 (September<br />

12, 1963) 377-378<br />

E. Menault, L’Intelligence des animaux (Paris, 1869)<br />

F. Mentz, “Die klassischen Hundenamen,” Philologus 88 (1933) 104-129, 181-202, 415-<br />

422<br />

R. Merkelbach <strong>and</strong> M. L. West, eds., Fragmenta Hesiodea (London, 1967)<br />

R. H. A. Merlen, De Canibus. Dog <strong>and</strong> Hound <strong>in</strong> Antiquity (London, 1971)<br />

E. A. Meyer <strong>and</strong> J. E. Lendon, “Greek Art <strong>and</strong> Culture S<strong>in</strong>ce Art <strong>and</strong> Experience <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Burr<strong>in</strong>ger <strong>and</strong> J. M. Hurwit, eds., Periklean Athens<br />

<strong>and</strong> Its Legacy. Problems <strong>and</strong> Perspectives (Aust<strong>in</strong>, 2005) 255-276<br />

F. Mezzalira et al., Beasts <strong>and</strong> Bestiaries. <strong>The</strong> Representations <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> from<br />

Prehistory to the Renaissance (Tur<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> London, 2001)<br />

438


H. W. Miller, “Aristophanes <strong>and</strong> Medical Language,” TAPA 76 (1945) 74-84<br />

M. C. Miller, Athens <strong>and</strong> Persia <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century B.C. A Study <strong>in</strong> Cultural Receptivity<br />

(Cambridge, 1997)<br />

S. G. Miller, <strong>The</strong> Tomb <strong>of</strong> Lyson <strong>and</strong> Kallikles: A Pa<strong>in</strong>ted Macedonian Tomb (Ma<strong>in</strong>z am<br />

Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 1993)<br />

S. G. Miller <strong>and</strong> S. Miller, “Architectural Blocks from the Strymon,” ADeltion 27<br />

(Meletemata 1972) 140-169<br />

B. M. Mitchell, “Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Samos,” JHS 95 (1975) 75-91<br />

L. G. Mitchell <strong>and</strong> P. J. Rhodes, “Friends <strong>and</strong> Enemies <strong>in</strong> Athenian Politics,” GR 43<br />

(1996) 11-30<br />

W. J. T. Mitchell, “Illusion: Look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Look<strong>in</strong>g,” <strong>in</strong> W. J. T. Mitchell, Picture<br />

<strong>The</strong>ory. Essays on Verbal <strong>and</strong> Visual Representation (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1994)<br />

329-344<br />

_____, Iconology. Image, Text, Ideology (Chicago <strong>and</strong> London, 1986)<br />

S. Mollard-Besques, Catalogue raisonné des figur<strong>in</strong>es et reliefs en terre-cuite grecs<br />

étrusques et roma<strong>in</strong>es I (Paris, 1954)<br />

V. Morell, “M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ir Own: <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> Are Smarter Than You Th<strong>in</strong>k,” National<br />

Geographic (March, 2008) 37-61<br />

E. Morrison, <strong>The</strong> Medieval Imag<strong>in</strong>ation. Beasts. Factual <strong>and</strong> Fantastic (Los Angeles <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 2007)<br />

M. Morton, ed., Oudry’s Pa<strong>in</strong>ted Menagerie. Portraits <strong>of</strong> Exotic <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Eighteenth-<br />

Century Europe (exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> J. Paul Getty Museum <strong>in</strong> association<br />

with the Staatliches Museum Schwer<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts, Houston;<br />

Los Angeles, 2007)<br />

J. V. Muir, ed., tr., Alcidamas. <strong>The</strong> Works <strong>and</strong> Fragments (Bristol, 2001)<br />

E. Munksgaard, ed., Hesychii Alex<strong>and</strong>r<strong>in</strong>i Lexicon I (Copenhagen, 1953)<br />

A. T. Murray, ed., tr., Homer. Iliad II (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1999)<br />

O. Murray, “Herodotus <strong>and</strong> Oral History,” <strong>in</strong> H. Sancisi-Weerdenburg <strong>and</strong> A. Kuhrt, eds.,<br />

Achaemenid History II. <strong>The</strong> Greek Sources. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the Gron<strong>in</strong>gen 1984<br />

Achaemenid History Workshop (Leiden, 1987) 93-115<br />

439


J. Neils <strong>and</strong> J. H. Oakley, eds., Com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Age <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>. Images <strong>of</strong> Childhood<br />

from the <strong>Classical</strong> Past (Hanover, New Hampshire, 2003)<br />

R. T. Neer, “<strong>The</strong> Athenian Treasury at Delphi <strong>and</strong> the Material <strong>of</strong> Politics,” <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Antiquity 23 (2004) 63-93<br />

_____, Style <strong>and</strong> Politics <strong>in</strong> Athenian Vase-Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> Craft <strong>of</strong> Democracy, ca. 530-<br />

460 B.C.E. (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2002)<br />

L. C. Nevett, “Between Urban <strong>and</strong> Rural: House-Form <strong>and</strong> Social Relations <strong>in</strong> Attic<br />

Villages <strong>and</strong> Deme Centers,” <strong>in</strong> B. A. Aunt <strong>and</strong> L. C. Nevett, eds., Ancient Greek<br />

Houses <strong>and</strong> Households. Chronological, Regional, <strong>and</strong> Social Diversity<br />

(Philadelphia, 2005) 83-98<br />

_____, House <strong>and</strong> Society <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Greek World (Cambridge, 1999)<br />

_____, “Gender Relations <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Classical</strong> Greek Household: <strong>The</strong> Archaeological<br />

Evidence,” BSA 90 (1995) 363-381<br />

S. T. Newmyer, Herodotus Book III. Commentary (Bryn Mawr Greek Commentaries;<br />

Bryn Mawr, 1986)<br />

L. Nochl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> M. Lucy, eds., “<strong>The</strong> Darw<strong>in</strong> Effect: Evolution <strong>and</strong> N<strong>in</strong>eteenth-Century<br />

Visual Culture,” N<strong>in</strong>eteenth Century Art Worldwide II, 2 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 2003),<br />

www.19thc-artworldwide.org<br />

F. Novotny, “Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Art,” <strong>in</strong> P. P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas<br />

III (New York, 1973) 339-346<br />

M. C. Nussbaum, “Aristotle,” <strong>in</strong> S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary (third ed.; Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) 166<br />

G. P. Oikonomos, “Bronzen von Pella,” AM 51 (1926) 87-88<br />

M. C. Oikonomou, Γραµµατική της Αρχαίας Ελληνικής—Ancient Greek Grammar<br />

(Athens, 1996)<br />

D. Oliver-Buitron, ed., <strong>The</strong> Greek Miracle. <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Dawn <strong>of</strong><br />

Democracy. <strong>The</strong> Fifth Century B.C. (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 1992)<br />

S. D. Olson, ed., Aristophanes. Acharnians (Oxford, 2002)<br />

_____, “Politics <strong>and</strong> Poetry <strong>in</strong> Aristophanes’ Wasps,” TAPA 126 (1996) 129-150<br />

_____, “Names <strong>and</strong> Nam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Aristophanic Comedy,” CQ 42 (1992) 304-319<br />

440


_____, “Cario <strong>and</strong> the New World <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes’ Plutus,” TAPA 119 (1989) 193-199<br />

A. K. Orl<strong>and</strong>os <strong>and</strong> J. N. Travlos, Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Ancient Architectural Terms (Athens,<br />

1986)<br />

C. Osborne, “Boundaries <strong>in</strong> Nature: Eat<strong>in</strong>g with <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Fifth Century B.C.,”<br />

BICS 37 (1990) 15-29<br />

_____, “Empedocles Recycled,” CQ 37 (1987) 24-50<br />

E. J. Owens, “<strong>The</strong> Koprologoi at Athens <strong>in</strong> the Fifth <strong>and</strong> Fourth Centuries B.C.,” CQ 33<br />

(1983) 44-50<br />

O. Palagia, “<strong>Classical</strong> Athens,” <strong>in</strong> O. Palagia, ed., Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>: Function, Materials,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Techniques <strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Periods (Cambridge, 2006) 119-162<br />

_____, “Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Narrative Techniques <strong>in</strong> Statue-Bases <strong>of</strong> the Pheidian Circle,” <strong>in</strong> N.<br />

K. Rutter <strong>and</strong> B. A. Sparkes, eds., Word <strong>and</strong> Image <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong><br />

(Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh, 2000) 53-78<br />

L. R. Palmer, <strong>The</strong> Greek Language (New Jersey, 1980)<br />

T. L. Pangle, tr., <strong>The</strong> Laws <strong>of</strong> Plato (New York, 1980)<br />

E. C. Partida, <strong>The</strong> Treasuries at Delphi. An Architectural Study (Studies <strong>in</strong><br />

Mediterranean Archaeology <strong>and</strong> Literature 160; Jonsered, Sweden 2000)<br />

S. A. Paspalas, “On Persian-Type Furniture <strong>in</strong> Macedonia: <strong>The</strong> Recognition <strong>and</strong><br />

Transmission <strong>of</strong> Forms,” AJA 105 (2000) 531-560<br />

J. M. Paton, “Notes on the Construction <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

Erechtheum (Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 181-231<br />

_____ et al., “Description <strong>of</strong> the Erechtheum,” <strong>in</strong> J. M. Paton, ed., <strong>The</strong> Erechtheum<br />

(Cambridge, Mass., 1927) 3-180<br />

W. R. Paton, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology II (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1917; repr., 1925)<br />

_____, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong> Greek Anthology III (London <strong>and</strong> New York 1915; repr. 1925)<br />

H. Payne, Necrocor<strong>in</strong>thia: A Study <strong>of</strong> Cor<strong>in</strong>thian Art <strong>in</strong> the Archaic Period (Oxford,<br />

1931)<br />

_____ <strong>and</strong> G. Mackworth-Young, Archaic Marble <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Acropolis (New<br />

York, 1951)<br />

441


A. L. Peck, ed., tr., Aristotle. Historia <strong>Animal</strong>ium I (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London,<br />

1965)<br />

A. W. Persson, New Tombs at Dendra near Midea (Oxford, 1942)<br />

P. M. Petsas, Pella. Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great’s Capital (<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1978)<br />

A. Philadelpheus, “Three Statue-Bases Recently Discovered at Athens,” JHS 42 (1922)<br />

104-106<br />

H. Philipp, Tektonon Daidala: der bildende Künstler und se<strong>in</strong>e Welt im voplatonischen<br />

Schrifttum (Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1968)<br />

C. A. Picόn, “<strong>The</strong> Dog <strong>of</strong> Alcibiades,” <strong>in</strong> G. Jackson-Stops, ed., <strong>The</strong> Treasure Houses <strong>of</strong><br />

Brita<strong>in</strong>: Five Hundred Years <strong>of</strong> Private Patronagee <strong>and</strong> Art Collect<strong>in</strong>g (New<br />

Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1985) 318-319<br />

_____, Bartolomeo Cavaceppi: Eighteenth Century Restorations <strong>of</strong> Ancient Marble<br />

<strong>Sculpture</strong> from English Private Collections. A Loan Exhibition at the Clarendon<br />

Gallery LTD (London, 1983)<br />

“Pigeons Show Superior Self-Recognition Abilities to Three Year Old Humans,” <strong>in</strong><br />

www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2008/06/080613145535.html<br />

C. P<strong>in</strong>ches <strong>and</strong> J. B. McDaniel, eds., Good News for <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>? Christian Approaches to<br />

<strong>Animal</strong> Well-Be<strong>in</strong>g (Ecology <strong>and</strong> Justice) (Maryknoll, New York, 1993)<br />

M. Pisani, “Vita quotidiana nel mondo Greco tra il IV e il V secolo A.C. Un contributo<br />

per la classificazione delle rappresentazioni fittili,” Bollet<strong>in</strong>o d’Arte 123 (2003) 3-<br />

24<br />

N. Platon, Zakros. <strong>The</strong> Discovery <strong>of</strong> a Lost Palace on Ancient Crete (New York, 1971)<br />

A. Platt, “On the Indian Dog,” CQ 3 (1909) 241-243<br />

J. J. Pollitt, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (1965; second ed.,<br />

Cambridge, 1990; repr. 1998)<br />

_____, Art <strong>and</strong> Experience <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong> (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 1972)<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Ancient View <strong>of</strong> Greek Art: Criticism, History <strong>and</strong> Term<strong>in</strong>ology (New Haven<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1974)<br />

M. S. Pollock <strong>and</strong> C. Ra<strong>in</strong>water, eds., Figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>: Essays on <strong>Animal</strong> Images <strong>in</strong><br />

Art, Literature, Philosophy, <strong>and</strong> Popular Culture (New York, 2005)<br />

442


S. B. Pomeroy, Xenophon. Oeconomicus. A Social <strong>and</strong> Historical Commentary (Oxford,<br />

1994)<br />

E. Pottier, CVA (France 5; Louvre 4) (Paris, 1926)<br />

_____, “Les sujets de genre dans les figur<strong>in</strong>es archaïques de terre cuite,” BCH 24 (1900)<br />

510-523<br />

P. Potter, ed., tr., Hippocrates V (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1988)<br />

A. Potts, Flesh <strong>and</strong> the Ideal: W<strong>in</strong>ckelmann <strong>and</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Art History (New Haven,<br />

1994)<br />

F. Poulsen, Catalogue <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Ny Carlsberg Glyptotek (Copenhagen,<br />

1951)<br />

J. E. Powell, A Lexicon to Herodotus (Hildesheim, 1966)<br />

W. K. Pritchett, “<strong>The</strong> Attic Stelai. Part II,” Hesperia 25 (1956) 178-328<br />

_____. “<strong>The</strong> Attic Stelai. Part I,” Hesperia 22 (1953) 225-299<br />

H. Rackham, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History IX. Books XXXIII-XXXV (Cambridge, Mass.<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, 1952; repr. 1995)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Pl<strong>in</strong>y. Natural History V. Books XVII-XIX (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1950)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Aristotle. Politics (Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1932; repr. 1990)<br />

E. F. Rambo, “Lions <strong>in</strong> Greek Art” (diss. Bryn Mawr College, 1918)<br />

R. H. R<strong>and</strong>all, Jr., “<strong>The</strong> Erechtheion Workmen,” AJA 57 (1953) 199-210<br />

M. Ranieri Panetta, ed., Pompeii. <strong>The</strong> History, Life <strong>and</strong> Art <strong>of</strong> the Buried City (Tur<strong>in</strong>,<br />

2004)<br />

C. Ratté “Five Lydian Fel<strong>in</strong>es,” AJA 93 (1989) 379-393<br />

A. E. Raubitschek, Dedications from the Athenian Akropolis. A Catalogue <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Inscriptions <strong>of</strong> the Sixth <strong>and</strong> Fifth Centuries B.C. (Cambridge, Mass., 1949)<br />

_____, rev. <strong>of</strong> H. Bloesch, Agalma, Kle<strong>in</strong>od, Weihgeschenk, Götterbild, e<strong>in</strong> Beitrag zur<br />

frühgriechischen Kulturund Religionsgesichte (Bern, 1943), <strong>in</strong> AJA 50 (1946)<br />

196-197<br />

443


C. D. C. Reeve, tr., Plato. Cratylus (Indianapolis, 1998)<br />

G. A. Reisner <strong>and</strong> W. S. Smith, A History <strong>of</strong> the Giza Necropolis II (Cambridge, Mass.,<br />

1955)<br />

R. Renehan, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Anthropocentric View <strong>of</strong> Man,” HSCP 85 (1981) 239-259<br />

K. Reynolds <strong>and</strong> R. Seddon, eds., Illustrated Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Art Terms. A H<strong>and</strong>book for<br />

the Artist <strong>and</strong> Art Lover (New York, 1984)<br />

E. E. Rice, <strong>The</strong> Gr<strong>and</strong> Procession <strong>of</strong> Prolemy Philadelphus (Oxford, 1983)<br />

G. M. A. Richter, Perspective <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Art (London, 1974)<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Sculptors <strong>of</strong> the Greeks (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1929; fourth<br />

rev. ed., 1970)<br />

_____, Korai. Archaic Greek Maidens. A Study <strong>of</strong> the Development <strong>of</strong> Kore Type <strong>in</strong><br />

Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (London, 1968)<br />

_____, rev <strong>of</strong> O. Broneer, <strong>The</strong> Lion Monument at Amphipolis (Cambridge, Mass., 1941)<br />

<strong>in</strong> AJA 46 (1942) 294-295<br />

_____, <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. A Survey (New York, 1930)<br />

B. S. Ridgway, Prayers <strong>in</strong> Stone. Greek Architectural <strong>Sculpture</strong> Ca. 600-100 B.C.<br />

(Berkeley, 1999)<br />

_____, Fourth-Century Styles <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Madison, 1997)<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Archaic Style <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (second ed., Chicago, 1993)<br />

_____, Hellenistic <strong>Sculpture</strong> I: <strong>The</strong> Styles <strong>of</strong> ca. 331-200 B.C. (Madison, 1990)<br />

_____, Fifth-Century Styles <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1981)<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Severe Style <strong>in</strong> Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong> (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1970)<br />

H. Riemann, Kerameikos II: Die Skulpturen vom 5. Jahrhundert bis <strong>in</strong> römische Zeit<br />

(Berl<strong>in</strong>, 1940)<br />

H. Ritvo, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Animal</strong> Estate: <strong>The</strong> English <strong>and</strong> Other Creatures <strong>in</strong> the Victorian Age<br />

(Cambridge, Mass. <strong>and</strong> London, 1987)<br />

J. Robert, Le Chien d’appartement et d’utilité: Education, dressage, hygiene, maladies<br />

(Paris, 1888)<br />

444


C. Rolley, La tombe pr<strong>in</strong>cière de Vix (Paris, 2003)<br />

_____, tr. R. Howell, Greek Bronzes (London, 1986)<br />

_____, Les vases des bronze de l’archaïsme recent en Gr<strong>and</strong>e Grèce (Naples, 1982)<br />

J. S. Romm, “Herodotus <strong>and</strong> the Natural World,” <strong>in</strong> C. Dewald <strong>and</strong> J. Mar<strong>in</strong>cola, eds.,<br />

<strong>The</strong> Cambridge Companion to Herodotus (Cambridge, 2006) 178-191<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Edges <strong>of</strong> the Earth <strong>in</strong> Ancient Thought: Geography, Exploration, <strong>and</strong> Fiction<br />

(Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1992)<br />

M. C. Root, “<strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Ancient Iran,” <strong>in</strong> B. J. Coll<strong>in</strong>s, ed., A History <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>Animal</strong> World <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Near East (Leiden <strong>and</strong> Boston, 2002) 167-209<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gship <strong>in</strong> Achaemenid Art. Essays on the Creation <strong>of</strong><br />

Iconography <strong>of</strong> Empire (Acta Iranica 19; Leiden, 1979)<br />

N. Rothfels, ed., Represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton <strong>and</strong> Indianapolis, 2002)<br />

C. J. Rowe, tr., Statesman, <strong>in</strong> J. M. Cooper, ed., Plato. Complete Works (Indianapolis <strong>and</strong><br />

Cambridge, 1997) 294-358<br />

J. H. Rub<strong>in</strong>, Impressionist Cats <strong>and</strong> Dogs: Pets <strong>in</strong> the Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Modern Life (New<br />

Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2003)<br />

A. Rumpf, “Κρατήρ Λακωνικός,” <strong>in</strong> K. Schauenburg, ed., Charites. Festschrift für E.<br />

Langlotz (Bonn, 1957) 127-135<br />

_____, “Zum Krater von Vix,” BABesch 29 (1954) 8-11<br />

T. J. Rusnak, Jr., “<strong>The</strong> Active Spectator: Art <strong>and</strong> the Viewer <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>” (diss.<br />

Bryn Mawr College, 2001)<br />

J. Sachs, tr., Aristotle’s On the Soul <strong>and</strong> On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection (Santa Fe, New<br />

Mexico, 2001)<br />

M. M. Sassi, “physiognomy,” <strong>in</strong> S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary (third ed.; Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) 1181<br />

T. J. Saunders, tr., Laws, <strong>in</strong> J. M. Cooper, ed., Plato. Complete Works (Indianapolis <strong>and</strong><br />

Cambridge, 1997) 1318-1616<br />

G. B. Schaller, <strong>The</strong> Serengeti Lion. A Study <strong>of</strong> Predator-Prey Relations (Chicago <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1972)<br />

445


W. J. Scheick, “<strong>Animal</strong> Testimony <strong>in</strong> Renaissance Art: Angelic <strong>and</strong> Other Supernatural<br />

Visitations,” <strong>in</strong> M. S. Pollock <strong>and</strong> C. Ra<strong>in</strong>water, eds., Figur<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>: Essays<br />

on <strong>Animal</strong> Images <strong>in</strong> Art, Literature, Philosophy, <strong>and</strong> Popular Culture (New<br />

York, 2005) 65-79<br />

S. S. Schipper, “Cat or Marten?” Archaeology 5 (1952) 25-29<br />

A. Schnapp, “Are Images Animated: <strong>The</strong> Psychology <strong>of</strong> Statues <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>,” <strong>in</strong><br />

C. Renfrew <strong>and</strong> E. B. W. Zubrow, eds., <strong>The</strong> Ancient M<strong>in</strong>d. Elements <strong>of</strong> Cognitive<br />

Archaeology (Cambridge, 1994) 40-44<br />

B. Schweitzer, “Hunde auf dem Dach,” AM 55 (1930) 107-118<br />

D. Sedley, Plato’s Cratylus (Cambridge, 2003)<br />

A. Shapiro <strong>and</strong> P. Burian, Aeschylus. <strong>The</strong> Oresteia (Oxford, 2003)<br />

G. A. Sheets, Herodotus. Book I. Commentary (Bryn Mawr, 1981)<br />

K. Shevelow, For the Love <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Rise <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Animal</strong> Protection Movement<br />

(New York, 2008)<br />

L. T. Shoe, “Dark Stone <strong>in</strong> Greek Architecture,” Hesperia Supplement 8 (1949) 341-352,<br />

481-482<br />

P. Shorey, ed., tr., Plato. <strong>The</strong> Republic I (London <strong>and</strong> Cambridge, Mass., 1930; repr.<br />

1963)<br />

F. J. Simoons, Eat Not This Flesh: Food Avoidances from Prehistory to the Present<br />

(Madison, 1994)<br />

U. S<strong>in</strong>n, Antike Terrakotten. Staatliche Kunstsammlungen Kassel (Kassel, 1977)<br />

N. W. Slater, “Mak<strong>in</strong>g the Aristophanic Audience,” AJP 120 (1999) 351-368<br />

J. P. Small, “Time <strong>in</strong> Space: Narrative <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Art,” <strong>The</strong> Art Bullet<strong>in</strong> 81 (1999) 562-<br />

575<br />

_____. Wax Tablets <strong>of</strong> the M<strong>in</strong>d. Cognitive Studies <strong>of</strong> Memory <strong>and</strong> Literacy <strong>in</strong> <strong>Classical</strong><br />

Antiquity (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 1997)<br />

A. H. Smith, A Catalogue <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Department <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman<br />

Antiquities. British Museum II (London, 1941)<br />

C. Smith, “Harpies <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” JHS 13 (1892-1893) 103-114<br />

446


W. Smith, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> Greek <strong>and</strong> Roman Biography <strong>and</strong> Mythology I (Boston,<br />

1870); http://www.ancientlibrary.com/smith-bio/0027.html<br />

H. W. Smyth, rev., G. M. Mess<strong>in</strong>g, Greek Grammar (Cambridge, 1956)<br />

L. M. Snyder <strong>and</strong> W. E. Klippel, “From Lerna to Kastro: Further Thoughts on Dogs as<br />

Food <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Perceptions, Prejudices, <strong>and</strong> Re<strong>in</strong>vestigations,” <strong>in</strong> E.<br />

Kotjabopoulou et al., eds., Zooarchaeology <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greece</strong>: Recent Advances (London,<br />

2003) 221-231<br />

J. S. Soles, “<strong>The</strong> Prepalatial Cemeteries at Mochlos <strong>and</strong> Gournia <strong>and</strong> the House Tombs <strong>of</strong><br />

Bronze Age Crete,” Hesperia Supplement (1992)<br />

A. H. Sommerste<strong>in</strong>, ed., tr., Wealth (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 11; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster,<br />

2001)<br />

_____, ed., tr., <strong>The</strong>smophoriazusae (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 8; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1994)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Wasps (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 4; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1983)<br />

_____, ed., tr., Knights (<strong>The</strong> Comedies <strong>of</strong> Aristophanes 2; Warm<strong>in</strong>ster, 1981)<br />

R. Sorabji, <strong>Animal</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> Human Morals. <strong>The</strong> Orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Western Debate<br />

(Ithaca, New York, 1993)<br />

G. Sörbom, Mimesis <strong>and</strong> Art. Studies <strong>in</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Early Development <strong>of</strong> an<br />

Aesthetic Vocabulary (Uppsala, 1966)<br />

A. H. Soukhanov, ed., <strong>The</strong> American Heritage Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the English Language (third<br />

edition; Boston <strong>and</strong> New York, 1992)<br />

B. A. Sparkes, “<strong>The</strong> Greek Kitchen,” JHS 82 (1962) 121-137<br />

J. M. S. Stager, “‘Let No One Wonder at This Image,’ A Phoenician Funerary Stele <strong>in</strong><br />

Athens,” Hesperia 74 (2005) 427-449<br />

N. C. Stampolidis, “Bronze Studs from the Collar <strong>of</strong> a Dog,” <strong>in</strong> L. Parlama <strong>and</strong> N. C.<br />

Stampolidis, eds., Athens: <strong>The</strong> City Beneath the City. Antiquities from the<br />

Metropolitan Railway Excavations (Athens, 2001) 177<br />

G. Ste<strong>in</strong>er, Anthropocentrism <strong>and</strong> Its Discontents: <strong>The</strong> Moral Status <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> <strong>in</strong> the<br />

History <strong>of</strong> Western Philosophy (Pittsburgh, 2005)<br />

A. Stewart, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. An Exploration (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1990)<br />

447


C. M. Stibbe, “<strong>The</strong> Krater from Vix Aga<strong>in</strong>: A Review Article,” <strong>in</strong> C. M. Stibbe,<br />

“Agalmata. Studien zur griechisch-archaischen Bronzekunst,” (BABesch<br />

Supplement 11; Dudley, 2006) 310-325<br />

_____, Trebenishte. <strong>The</strong> Fortunes <strong>of</strong> an Unusual Excavation (Studia Archaeologica 121;<br />

Rome, 2003)<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Sons <strong>of</strong> Hephaistos: Aspects <strong>of</strong> the Archaic Greek Bronze Industry (Rome,<br />

2000)<br />

_____, Laconian Mix<strong>in</strong>g Bowls: A History <strong>of</strong> the Krater Lakonikos from the Seventh to<br />

the Fifth Century B.C. (Amsterdam, 1989)<br />

R. H. W. Stichel, “Grabung im Bezirk des Dionysios von Kollytos,” AA 99 (1984) 56-61<br />

M. Stieber, “Aeschylus’ <strong>The</strong>oroi <strong>and</strong> Realism <strong>in</strong> Greek Art,” TAPA 124 (1994) 85-119<br />

I. C. Storey, “Dat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Re-Dat<strong>in</strong>g Eupolis,” Phoenix 44 (1990) 1-30<br />

D. Stronach, “La statue de Darius découverte à Suse,” CDAFI 4 (1974) 61-72<br />

M. C. Sturgeon, Isthmia IV: <strong>Sculpture</strong> I: 1952-1967 (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1987)<br />

D. Summers, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Judgment</strong> <strong>of</strong> Sense. Renaissance Naturalism <strong>and</strong> the Rise <strong>of</strong> Aesthetics<br />

(Cambridge <strong>and</strong> London, 1987)<br />

J. Svenbro, tr. J. Lloyd, Phrasikleia: An Anthropology <strong>of</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong><br />

(Ithaca <strong>and</strong> London, 1993)<br />

M. Szabό, Archaic Terracottas <strong>of</strong> Boeotia (Rome, 1994)<br />

J. Tanner, <strong>The</strong> Invention <strong>of</strong> Art History <strong>in</strong> Ancient <strong>Greece</strong>: Religion, Society <strong>and</strong> Artistic<br />

Rationalisation (Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 2006)<br />

E. M. Thomas, <strong>The</strong> Social Life <strong>of</strong> Dogs. <strong>The</strong> Grace <strong>of</strong> Can<strong>in</strong>e Behavior (New York,<br />

2000)<br />

N. R. Thomas, “<strong>The</strong> Early Mycenaean Lion Up to Date,” Hesperia Supplement 33 (2004)<br />

161-206<br />

R. Thomas, Herodotus <strong>in</strong> Context. Ethnography, Science <strong>and</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> Persuasion<br />

(Cambridge, 2000)<br />

H. A. Thompson, “Excavations <strong>in</strong> the Athenian Agora: 1950,” Hesperia 20 (1951) 45-60<br />

448


C. Thorne, “Feed<strong>in</strong>g Behavior <strong>of</strong> Domestic Dogs <strong>and</strong> the Role <strong>of</strong> Experience,” <strong>in</strong> J.<br />

Serpell, ed., <strong>The</strong> Domestic Dog: Its Evolution, Behavior <strong>and</strong> Interactions with<br />

People (Cambridge, 1995) 103-114<br />

L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di statuaria tra classicità ed<br />

ellenismo (Milano, 1993)<br />

A. Toussenel, L’Esprit des bêtes: Zoologie passionelle (Paris, 1855)<br />

B. Tsakirgis, “Liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Work<strong>in</strong>g Around the Athenian Agora: A Prelim<strong>in</strong>ary Case<br />

Study <strong>of</strong> Three Houses,” <strong>in</strong> B. A. Aunt <strong>and</strong> L. C. Nevett, eds., Ancient Greek<br />

Houses <strong>and</strong> Households. Chronological, Regional, <strong>and</strong> Social Diversity<br />

(Philadelphia, 2005) 67-82<br />

D. Tsiafakis, ““ΠΕΛΩΡΑ”: Fabulous Creatures <strong>and</strong>/or Demons <strong>of</strong> Death?,” <strong>in</strong> J. M.<br />

Padgett, ed., <strong>The</strong> Centaur’s Smile: <strong>The</strong> Human <strong>Animal</strong> <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Art (New<br />

Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 73-104<br />

E. P. Uphill, Pharaoh’s Gateway to Eternity: <strong>The</strong> Hawara Labyr<strong>in</strong>th <strong>of</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g Amenemhat<br />

III (London <strong>and</strong> New York, 2000)<br />

C. Vermeule, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> Stone. <strong>The</strong> Greek, Roman <strong>and</strong> Etruscan Collections <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts Boston (Boston, 1974)<br />

_____, “Greek Funerary <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong>, 450-300 B.C.,” AJA 76 (1972) 49-59<br />

_____, “<strong>The</strong> Basel Dog: A V<strong>in</strong>dication,” AJA 72 (1968) 95-101<br />

J.-P. Vernant, “<strong>The</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> Images,” <strong>in</strong> F. I. Zeitl<strong>in</strong>, ed., Mortals <strong>and</strong> Immortals.<br />

Collected Essays (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1992) 164-185<br />

_____, Myth <strong>and</strong> Thought among the Greeks (London <strong>and</strong> Boston, 1983)<br />

_____, “<strong>The</strong> Representation <strong>of</strong> the Invisible <strong>and</strong> the Psychological Category <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Double: <strong>The</strong> Colossos,” <strong>in</strong> J.-P. Vernant, Myth <strong>and</strong> Thought among the Greeks<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> Boston, 1983) 305-320<br />

M. Vickers, Images on Textiles. <strong>The</strong> Weave <strong>of</strong> Fifth-Century Athenian Art <strong>and</strong> Society<br />

(Xenia 42; Konstanz, 1999)<br />

_____ <strong>and</strong> D. Gill, Artful Crafts: Ancient Greek Silverware <strong>and</strong> Pottery (Oxford, 1994)<br />

A. Vigneau, <strong>The</strong> Photographic Encyclopaedia <strong>of</strong> Art: <strong>The</strong> Louvre Museum II (Paris,<br />

1936)<br />

I. R. Von Rudl<strong>of</strong>f, “Hekate <strong>in</strong> Early Greek Religion” (diss. University <strong>of</strong> Victoria, 1992)<br />

449


N. Vulić, “Das neue Grab von Trebenischte,” JdI 45 (1930) 276-299<br />

A. J. B. Wace, “Weav<strong>in</strong>g or Embroidery?” AJA 52 (1948) 51-55<br />

S. Watanabe, “How do Pigeons See Pictures? Recognition <strong>of</strong> the Real World from Its 2-<br />

D Representation,” <strong>in</strong> J. Fagot, ed., Picture Perception <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>Animal</strong>s</strong> (Philadelphia,<br />

2000) 71-90<br />

R. Waterfield, tr., Herodotus. <strong>The</strong> Histories (Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1998)<br />

G. B. Waywell, “<strong>The</strong> Lion from the Lion Tomb <strong>of</strong> Knidos,” <strong>in</strong> O. Palagia <strong>and</strong> W.<br />

Coulson, eds., Regional Schools <strong>in</strong> Hellenistic <strong>Sculpture</strong>. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> an<br />

International Conference Held at the American Schools at Athens, March 15-17<br />

1996 (Oxford, 1998) 235-241<br />

_____, <strong>The</strong> Free-St<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the Mausoleum at Halicarnassus <strong>in</strong> the British<br />

Museum (London, 1978)<br />

R. Wellek, “Realism <strong>in</strong> Literature,” <strong>in</strong> P. P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong><br />

Ideas IV (New York, 1973) 51-56<br />

M. L. West, “Anacreontea,” <strong>in</strong> S. Hornblower <strong>and</strong> A. Spawforth, eds., <strong>The</strong> Oxford<br />

<strong>Classical</strong> Dictionary (third ed.; Oxford <strong>and</strong> New York, 1996) 80<br />

S. West, “Herodotus’ Epigraphical Interests,” CQ 35 (1985) 278-305<br />

K. White <strong>and</strong> E. M. Macierowski, trs., St. Thomas Aqu<strong>in</strong>as. Commentaries on Aristotle’s<br />

“On Sense <strong>and</strong> What is Sensed” <strong>and</strong> “On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection”<br />

(Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 2005)<br />

A. Wierzbicka, Emotions across Languages <strong>and</strong> Cultures: Diversity <strong>and</strong> Universals<br />

(Cambridge <strong>and</strong> Paris, 1999)<br />

J. Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>The</strong> Boastful Chef: <strong>The</strong> Discourse <strong>of</strong> Food <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Comedy (Oxford,<br />

2000)<br />

_____, “Comic Cuis<strong>in</strong>e: Food <strong>and</strong> Eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Comic Polis,” <strong>in</strong> G. W. Dobrov, ed., <strong>The</strong><br />

City as Comedy. Society <strong>and</strong> Representation <strong>in</strong> Athenian Drama (Chapel Hill <strong>and</strong><br />

London, 1997) 250-268<br />

F. Willemsen, Die Löwenkopf-Wasserspeier vom Dach des Zeustempels (OlForsch 5,<br />

Berl<strong>in</strong> 1959)<br />

I. J. W<strong>in</strong>ter, “After the Battle is Over: <strong>The</strong> Stele <strong>of</strong> the Vultures <strong>and</strong> the Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

Pictorial Narrative <strong>in</strong> the Art <strong>of</strong> the Ancient Near East,” <strong>in</strong> H. L. Kessler <strong>and</strong> M.<br />

450


S. Simpson, eds., Pictorial Narrative <strong>in</strong> Antiquity <strong>and</strong> the Middle Ages (Studies <strong>in</strong><br />

the History <strong>of</strong> Art 16; Wash<strong>in</strong>gton D.C., 1985) 11-32<br />

H. Wölffl<strong>in</strong>, tr. M. D. Hott<strong>in</strong>ger, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> Art History. <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Development <strong>of</strong> Style <strong>in</strong> Later Art (1932; repr. New York, 1950)<br />

L. Wolk-Simon, “Naturalism <strong>in</strong> Lombard Draw<strong>in</strong>g from Leonardo to Cerano,” <strong>in</strong> A.<br />

Bayer, ed., Pa<strong>in</strong>ters <strong>of</strong> Reality. <strong>The</strong> Legacy <strong>of</strong> Leonardo <strong>and</strong> Caravaggio <strong>in</strong><br />

Lombardy (exhibition catalogue, Museo Civico “Ala Ponzone,” Cremona,<br />

February 14-May 2, 2004, <strong>and</strong> the Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York, May<br />

27-August 15, 2004; New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 2004) 45-63<br />

H. G. Woods, Herodotus Book I (London <strong>and</strong> Oxford, 1873)<br />

M. R. Wright, ed., Empedocles: <strong>The</strong> Extant Fragments (New Haven <strong>and</strong> London, 1981)<br />

www.p<strong>and</strong>a.org/news_facts/education/best_place_species/current_top_10/asiatic_lion_.cf<br />

m -<br />

R. E. Wycherley, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Agora III. Literary <strong>and</strong> Epigraphical Testimonia<br />

(Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1957)<br />

F. J. Zeitl<strong>in</strong>, “<strong>The</strong> Artful Eye: Vision, Ecphrasis <strong>and</strong> Spectacle <strong>in</strong> Euripidean <strong>The</strong>atre,” <strong>in</strong><br />

S. Godhill <strong>and</strong> R. Osborne, eds., Art <strong>and</strong> Text <strong>in</strong> Ancient Greek Culture<br />

(Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York, 1994) 138-196<br />

451


LIST OF FIGURES<br />

Fig. 1 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from the Kerameikos, Kerameikos Museum P<br />

670 (L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di<br />

statuaria tra classicità ed ellenismo [Milan, 1993] fig. 185)<br />

Fig. 2 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Miletus, Berl<strong>in</strong> 1790<br />

(J. Boardman, Greek <strong>Sculpture</strong>. <strong>The</strong> Archaic Period. A H<strong>and</strong>book<br />

[London <strong>and</strong> New York 1978; repr. 1996] fig. 267)<br />

Fig. 3 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a bull from the Kerameikos, Kerameikos Museum (no<br />

number) (L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di<br />

statuaria tra classicità ed ellenismo [Milan, 1993] fig. 187)<br />

Fig. 4 <strong>Classical</strong> <strong>in</strong>scription from a marble base <strong>of</strong> a statue from Demetrias,<br />

<strong>The</strong>ssaly (L. H. Jeffery, <strong>The</strong> Local Scripts <strong>of</strong> Archaic <strong>Greece</strong>. A Study <strong>of</strong><br />

the Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the Greek Alphabet <strong>and</strong> Its Development from the Eighth to<br />

the Fifth Centuries B.C. [Oxford, 1961] pl. 11, fig. 8)<br />

Fig. 5 Lion savag<strong>in</strong>g a bull, Hekatompedon pediment, Acropolis, Athens,<br />

Acropolis Museum 4 (J. M. Hurwit, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Acropolis: History,<br />

Mythology, <strong>and</strong> Archaeology from the Neolithic Era to the Present<br />

[Cambridge, 1999] 109, fig. 80)<br />

Fig. 6 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Perachora, Cor<strong>in</strong>th, Boston, MFA 97.289<br />

(C. C. Vermeule, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> Stone. <strong>The</strong> Greek, Roman <strong>and</strong> Etruscan<br />

Collections <strong>of</strong> the Museum <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>e Arts Boston [Boston, 1974] 9, fig. 15)<br />

Fig. 7 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Rome (?), New York, MMA 09.221.3<br />

(J. Marshall, “Statue <strong>of</strong> a Lion” M.M.A Bullet<strong>in</strong> 5 (1910) 213)<br />

Fig. 8 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from the Mausoleum <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus, London,<br />

BM 1075 (G. B. Waywell, <strong>The</strong> Free-St<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>Sculpture</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Mausoleum <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus <strong>in</strong> the British Museum [London, 1978] pl.<br />

37, fig. 1)<br />

Fig. 9 Gold seal from Shaft Grave III at Mycenae, Athens, NM 34<br />

(A. A. Donohue, “Zum Löwenschieber aus Schachtgrab III <strong>in</strong> Mykene,”<br />

AA 93 (1978) 261, fig. 1)<br />

Fig. 10 <strong>The</strong> lion <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis (fourth-third c. B.C. ?)<br />

(L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di statuaria tra<br />

classicità ed ellenismo [Milan, 1993] fig. 176)<br />

Fig. 11 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Brauronia (?),<br />

Acropolis, Athens, Acropolis Museum 143 (H. Payne <strong>and</strong> G. Mackworth-<br />

452


Young, Archaic Marble <strong>Sculpture</strong> from the Acropolis [New York, 1951]<br />

pl. 131, 3)<br />

Fig. 12a <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from Pella, Pella Museum (no number)<br />

(P. M. Petsas, Pella. Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great’s Capital [<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1978]<br />

46, fig. 5)<br />

Fig. 12b <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from Pella, Pella Museum (no number)<br />

(P. M. Petsas, Pella. Alex<strong>and</strong>er the Great’s Capital [<strong>The</strong>ssaloniki, 1978]<br />

47, fig. 6)<br />

Fig. 13 Late Geometric II st<strong>and</strong> from the Kerameikos, Kerameikos Museum 407<br />

(J. M. Hurwit, <strong>The</strong> Art <strong>and</strong> Culture <strong>of</strong> Early <strong>Greece</strong>, 1100-480 B.C.<br />

[Ithaca <strong>and</strong> London] 114, fig. 53)<br />

Fig. 14 Archaic marble base <strong>of</strong> a statue (cat-<strong>and</strong>-dog fight), right side, Athens,<br />

NM 3476 (A. Kosmopoulou, <strong>The</strong> Iconography <strong>of</strong> <strong>Sculpture</strong>d Statue Bases<br />

<strong>in</strong> the Archaic <strong>and</strong> <strong>Classical</strong> Periods [Madison, 2002])<br />

Fig. 15 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from the Kerameikos, Athens, NM 804<br />

(L. Todisco, Scultura greca del IV secolo. Maestri e scuole di statuaria tra<br />

classicità ed ellenismo [Milan, 1993] fig. 178)<br />

Fig. 16 Late Archaic Boeotian terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a woman cook<strong>in</strong>g with a dog<br />

by her side, Louvre Museum, CA 634 (A. Vigneau, <strong>The</strong> Photographic<br />

Encyclopaedia <strong>of</strong> Art: <strong>The</strong> Louvre Museum II [Paris, 1936] 172, fig. D)<br />

Fig. 17 Late Archaic Boeotian terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a woman with a dog by her<br />

side, Kassel Museum 523 (U. S<strong>in</strong>n, Antike Terrakotten. Staatliche<br />

Kunstsammlungen Kassel [Kassel, 1977] pl. 1, fig. 25)<br />

Fig. 18 Archaic Cypriot terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a woman bak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> a dog, Vienna,<br />

Kunsthistorisches Museum V 1674 (A. Bernhard-Walcher et al., <strong>The</strong><br />

Collection <strong>of</strong> Cypriote Antiquities <strong>in</strong> the Kunsthistorisches Museum<br />

[Vienna, 1999] 143, fig. 58)<br />

Fig. 19 <strong>Classical</strong> Attic red-figured lekythos depict<strong>in</strong>g a woman feed<strong>in</strong>g a dog,<br />

Rome, Accademia dei L<strong>in</strong>cei 2478, (S. Lewis, <strong>The</strong> Athenian Woman: An<br />

Iconographic H<strong>and</strong>book [London <strong>and</strong> New York 2002] 71, fig. 2.13)<br />

Fig. 20 <strong>Classical</strong> Attic grave stele with a dog between two male figures, Athens<br />

NM 2894 (N. Kaltsas, tr. D. Hardy, <strong>Sculpture</strong> <strong>in</strong> the National<br />

Archaeological Museum, Athens [Los Angeles, 2002] 153, cat. no. <strong>and</strong> fig.<br />

300)<br />

453


Fig. 21 Reconstruction <strong>of</strong> part <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Classical</strong> resist-pa<strong>in</strong>ted cloth from kurgan 6,<br />

Kertch, Crimaea (E. J. W. Barber, Prehistoric Textiles. <strong>The</strong> Development<br />

<strong>of</strong> Cloth <strong>in</strong> the Neolithic <strong>and</strong> Bronze Ages with Special Reference to the<br />

Aegean [Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1991] 207, fig. 7.11)<br />

Fig. 22 Schematic representation <strong>of</strong> the funerary complex <strong>of</strong> Cheops with<br />

causeway connect<strong>in</strong>g the valley to the mortuary temple (M. Haase, E<strong>in</strong>e<br />

Stätte für die Ewigkeit. Der Pyramidenkomplex des Cheops aus Baulicher,<br />

Architektonischer und Kulturhistorischer Sicht [Ma<strong>in</strong>z am Rhe<strong>in</strong>, 2004]<br />

56, fig. 56)<br />

Fig. 23 Limestone fragment <strong>of</strong> an Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom (reign <strong>of</strong> Khufu) block that was<br />

reused <strong>in</strong> the core <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat I at Lisht, New York,<br />

MMA 1922, 22.1.7 (J. P. Allen et al., Art <strong>in</strong> the Age <strong>of</strong> the Pyramids<br />

[exhibition catalogue, <strong>The</strong> Metropolitan Museum <strong>of</strong> Art, New York,<br />

September 16, 1999-January 9, 2000 <strong>and</strong> the Royal Ontario Museum,<br />

Toronto, February 13-May 22, 2000] 226, cat. no <strong>and</strong> fig. 41)<br />

Fig. 24 Capstone <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenemhat III <strong>in</strong> Dahshur, Cairo Museum<br />

35133 <strong>and</strong> 35745 (M. Lehner, <strong>The</strong> Complete Pyramids (London, 1997) 34<br />

Fig. 25 Archaic bronze krater from Vix, Châtillon sur Se<strong>in</strong>e Musée Archélogique<br />

(no number) (C. Rolley, La Tombe pr<strong>in</strong>cière de Vix [Paris, 2003] pl. 4)<br />

Fig. 26 Archaic bronze krater from tomb I, Trebenishte, tomb I, S<strong>of</strong>ia, NM (no<br />

number) (B. D. Filow, Die archaische Nekropole von Trebenischte am<br />

Ochrida-See [Berl<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Leipzig, 1927] pl. VII)<br />

Fig. 27 Archaic bronze krater from tomb VIII, Trebenishte, Belgrade NM 174/1<br />

(C. M. Stibbe, Trebenishte. <strong>The</strong> Fortunes <strong>of</strong> an Unusual Excavation<br />

[Studia Archaeologica 121; Rome, 2002] 85, fig. 48)<br />

Fig. 28 Bronze relief decorative figure <strong>of</strong> a warrior found <strong>in</strong> Edessa <strong>and</strong> presumed<br />

to be from an Archaic bronze krater, Athens, NM 7550 (C. M. Stibbe,<br />

Trebenishte. <strong>The</strong> Fortunes <strong>of</strong> an Unusual Excavation [Studia<br />

archaeologica 121; Rome, 2002] 105, fig. 63)<br />

Fig. 29 Figure <strong>of</strong> a horrified female from the north wall <strong>of</strong> the fourth-century B.C.<br />

tomb <strong>of</strong> Persephone at Verg<strong>in</strong>a (M. Andronikos, Verg<strong>in</strong>a II. <strong>The</strong> Tomb <strong>of</strong><br />

Persephone [Athens, 1994] 25, fig. IX)<br />

454


Fig. 1 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from the Kerameikos.<br />

Fig. 2 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Miletus.


Fig. 3 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a bull from the Kerameikos.


Fig. 4 <strong>Classical</strong> Inscription from a marble base <strong>of</strong> a statue from Demetrias, <strong>The</strong>ssaly.<br />

Fig. 5 Lion savag<strong>in</strong>g a bull, Hekatompedon pediment, Acropolis, Athens.


Fig. 6 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Perachora, Cor<strong>in</strong>th.


Fig. 7 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from Rome (?) .


Fig. 8 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from the Mausoleum <strong>of</strong> Halicarnassus.<br />

Fig. 9 Gold seal from Shaft Grave III at Mycenae.


Fig. 10 <strong>The</strong> lion <strong>of</strong> Amphipolis (fourth-third c. B.C. ?).


Fig. 11 Archaic statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from the sanctuary <strong>of</strong> Artemis Brauronia (?), Acropolis, Athens.<br />

Fig. 12 (a-b) <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a dog from Pella.


Fig. 13 Late Geometric II st<strong>and</strong> from the Kerameikos.<br />

Fig. 14 Archaic marble base <strong>of</strong> a statue (“cat-<strong>and</strong>-dog fight”), right side, Athens.


Fig. 15 <strong>Classical</strong> statue <strong>of</strong> a lion from the Kerameikos.


Fig. 16 Late Archaic Boeotian terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a woman<br />

cook<strong>in</strong>g with a dog by her side, Louvre Museum.<br />

Fig. 17 Late Archaic Boeotian<br />

terracotta figure <strong>of</strong> a woman<br />

with a dog by her side, Kassel<br />

Museum.<br />

Fig. 18 Archaic Cypriot terracotta figur<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> a woman bak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> a dog, Vienna,<br />

Kunsthistorisches Museum.


Fig. 19 <strong>Classical</strong> Attic red-figured lekythos Fig. 20 <strong>Classical</strong> Attic grave stele with a dog between<br />

depict<strong>in</strong>g a woman feed<strong>in</strong>g a dog. two male figures.


Fig. 21 Reconstruction <strong>of</strong> part <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Classical</strong> resist-pa<strong>in</strong>ted cloth from kurgan 6,<br />

Kertch, Crimaea.


Fig. 22 Schematic representation <strong>of</strong> the funerary complex <strong>of</strong> Cheops with causeway connect<strong>in</strong>g the valley to the<br />

mortuary temple.


Fig. 24 Capstone <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>of</strong> Amenenhat III at Dahshur.<br />

Fig. 23 Limestone fragment <strong>of</strong> an Old K<strong>in</strong>gdom (reign <strong>of</strong> Khufu)<br />

block that was reused <strong>in</strong> the core <strong>of</strong> the pyramid <strong>of</strong><br />

Amenemhat I at Lisht.


Fig. 25 Archaic bronze krater from Vix.


Fig. 26 Archaic bronze krater from tomb I, Trebenishte.


Fig. 28 Bronze relief decorative figure <strong>of</strong> a warrior<br />

found <strong>in</strong> Edessa <strong>and</strong> presumed to be from an<br />

Archaic bronze krater.<br />

Fig. 27 Archaic bronze krater from tomb VIII, Trebenishte.


Fig. 29 Figure <strong>of</strong> a horrified female from the north wall <strong>of</strong> the fourth-century B.C. tomb <strong>of</strong><br />

Persephone at Verg<strong>in</strong>a.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!