28.03.2013 Views

105 119 147 171 177 197 - Interpretation: A Journal of Political ...

105 119 147 171 177 197 - Interpretation: A Journal of Political ...

105 119 147 171 177 197 - Interpretation: A Journal of Political ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1 3 0 I n t e r p r e t a t i o n Volume 38 / Issue 2<br />

rational power. This sickness is untreatable. The soul doctor who specializes<br />

in improving the moral habits <strong>of</strong> the appetitive power cannot be in the business<br />

<strong>of</strong> curing what Aristotle calls “the eye <strong>of</strong> the soul.” What would the soul<br />

doctor do with the young who belong potentially to the highest class <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human? To whom would he, as it were, refer them?<br />

The difficulty involved in initiating the soul doctor’s treatment<br />

is significant. Those who are treated must seek treatment voluntarily;<br />

to do so, however, they must recognize the defective character <strong>of</strong> their own<br />

condition. Yet “those with sick souls…do not recognize their illness, but<br />

imagine they are healthy” (66). Maimonides pretends that this is not a universal<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> the sick soul, but if all imagine the bad they pursue to be<br />

good and the good they shun to be bad, it seems that it must be (Lerner and<br />

Mahdi 1963, 39). How is the soul doctor to establish a clientele? Can the soul<br />

doctor come to the aid <strong>of</strong> anyone?<br />

The soul doctor plies his art on the basis <strong>of</strong> the understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> moral virtue articulated in Aristotle’s Ethics. Behind the figure <strong>of</strong><br />

the soul doctor stand Aristotle and his teaching. Above all it is Aristotle’s<br />

teaching regarding the noble or beautiful virtues—courage, moderation,<br />

liberality, great-souledness, and so forth (Ethics 1106b36–1108b10, 1115a25–<br />

b13, 1<strong>119</strong>b15–17, 1120a25–27, 1123a35–b7, 1124a2–4)—that is the basis <strong>of</strong> his<br />

practice. Justice is never referred to as a virtue instilled by the cure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

soul that the soul doctor effects (see Addendum 6). Maimonides, therefore,<br />

is able to represent all moral virtues and virtuous states <strong>of</strong> soul in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

a mean between two extremes, both <strong>of</strong> which are equally species <strong>of</strong> vice.<br />

Maimonides, however, has modified Aristotle’s teaching in certain crucial<br />

respects: he follows Alfarabi and parts company with Aristotle by including<br />

modesty and humility as among the virtuous states <strong>of</strong> character (67). Modesty<br />

is the equivalent <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s “sense <strong>of</strong> shame”—but, says Aristotle, though<br />

a sense <strong>of</strong> shame appears to be a mean between shamelessness and shyness, it<br />

is not a virtue (1108a31–35). Humility seems to have taken the place both <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle’s great-souledness and his virtuous love <strong>of</strong> honor (see Addendum 7).<br />

The inclusion <strong>of</strong> shame or modesty among the virtues and<br />

the substitution <strong>of</strong> humility for a noble pride indicate the pressure that the<br />

Mosaic law exerts on the understanding <strong>of</strong> moral virtue. According to Aristotle’s<br />

account, the great-souled man rightly demands the honors due him,<br />

honors equivalent to those we give the gods (Ethics 1123b3–25). He demands<br />

such honors because he understands himself to embody the completion<br />

<strong>of</strong> moral virtue and understands moral virtue in its completion to be the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!