26.07.2013 Views

stoicism in early christianity - Baker Publishing Group

stoicism in early christianity - Baker Publishing Group

stoicism in early christianity - Baker Publishing Group

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Sett<strong>in</strong>g the Scene: Stoicism and Platonism <strong>in</strong> the Transitional Period <strong>in</strong> Ancient Philosophy 7<br />

<strong>in</strong>g about a “pool<strong>in</strong>g of philosophical resources among what could be seen as<br />

three branches of the Platonist tradition: <strong>early</strong> Platonism, Aristotelianism, and<br />

Stoicism.” 19 Sedley also speaks of this strategy as be<strong>in</strong>g one of “syncretism,” but<br />

what he actually shows is that such syncretism should be understood not as an act<br />

of blend<strong>in</strong>g or br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g ideas together <strong>in</strong> a great melt<strong>in</strong>g pot, but <strong>in</strong> a rather more<br />

specific manner as a strategy of “reclaim<strong>in</strong>g” or “absorb<strong>in</strong>g” ideas from a philosophy<br />

other than one’s own <strong>in</strong>to one’s own philosophy. The syncretism does not erase<br />

the differences between any two philosophies. Nor does it <strong>in</strong> any way imply that a<br />

given philosopher is no longer either a Stoic or a Platonist (or aga<strong>in</strong>, a Christian).<br />

On the contrary, it is precisely while be<strong>in</strong>g either this or that that one may also<br />

“reclaim” or “absorb” foreign ideas <strong>in</strong>to one’s own philosophy.<br />

If Panaetius and Posidonius are <strong>in</strong> this way an example of Stoics who also<br />

“syncretized” certa<strong>in</strong> Platonic ideas <strong>in</strong>to their own Stoicism, Sedley shows how<br />

Posidonius’s contemporary Antiochus of Ascalon, whom I mentioned earlier, fits<br />

the opposite bill of be<strong>in</strong>g a Platonist who <strong>in</strong>corporated a huge amount of Stoicism<br />

<strong>in</strong>to what he himself took to be the authentic form of Platonism. Antiochus’s case<br />

is <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a number of ways. 20 His position constituted a break with the skeptical<br />

New Academy of his teacher Philo of Larissa, a break that Antiochus marked<br />

by speak<strong>in</strong>g of his own position as articulat<strong>in</strong>g that of the “Old Academy.” In itself,<br />

that move is perhaps not so surpris<strong>in</strong>g, s<strong>in</strong>ce epistemological and ontological<br />

skepticism surely does not cover everyth<strong>in</strong>g to be found <strong>in</strong> Plato. What is more<br />

surpris<strong>in</strong>g is that, apparently, Antiochus took over from the Stoics a number of<br />

ideas <strong>in</strong> physics that the Stoics themselves had articulated <strong>in</strong> direct opposition to<br />

Aristotelianism and Platonism. When Antiochus <strong>in</strong>sisted, on the basis of his contention<br />

that “the doctr<strong>in</strong>es of the Stoics were present already <strong>in</strong> Plato,” 21 that talk<br />

of an immaterial substance (like the Platonic ideas) was “un<strong>in</strong>telligible,” and that<br />

he saw “no possibility . . . of anyth<strong>in</strong>g immaterial, transcendent or external to the<br />

material universe,” 22 then certa<strong>in</strong>ly he was tak<strong>in</strong>g up a basically Stoic position. But<br />

how he could also claim that this particular Stoic doctr<strong>in</strong>e was already present <strong>in</strong><br />

Plato rema<strong>in</strong>s a mystery.<br />

It is a very <strong>in</strong>structive mystery, however. For it shows how far it was apparently<br />

possible to go <strong>in</strong> the direction of reclaim<strong>in</strong>g alien material for one’s own<br />

philosophy as long as one was able to conv<strong>in</strong>ce oneself that one rema<strong>in</strong>ed loyal to<br />

the founder of that philosophy—<strong>in</strong> the present case, Plato.<br />

We should conclude that the paradox identified here—philosophers who both<br />

emphasized the differences between the various ma<strong>in</strong> types of philosophy and also<br />

produced philosophies of their own that look like an amalgam of several types—<br />

can be resolved when one sees the whole set of operations as part of a strategy of<br />

creat<strong>in</strong>g a philosophical identity of one’s own. That identity was def<strong>in</strong>ed by the<br />

found<strong>in</strong>g father with whom one identified. But it also allowed one to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

19 Ibid., 22.<br />

20 A prob<strong>in</strong>g account is Barnes 1989.<br />

21 The quotation is from Sextus Empiricus. See Dillon 1996b, 59n3.<br />

22 The quotation is from Cicero, De F<strong>in</strong>ibus. See Dillon 1996b, 84.<br />

Tuomas Rasimus, Troels Engberg-Pedersen and Ismo Dunderberg, Stoicism <strong>in</strong> Early Christianity<br />

<strong>Baker</strong> Academic, a division of <strong>Baker</strong> Publish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Group</strong>, © 2010. Used by permission.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!