12.08.2013 Views

calculus book - Mathematics and Computer Science

calculus book - Mathematics and Computer Science

calculus book - Mathematics and Computer Science

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1.3. LOGIC 15<br />

over A. Wiles’ proof of “Fermat’s Last Theorem”. Wiles used techniques<br />

from “hyperbolic geometry”, which the columnist thought was<br />

self-contradictory because “It is possible to square the circle in hyperbolic<br />

geometry”, while every school student of the columnist’s generation<br />

learned that “It is impossible to square the circle”. The columnist<br />

was, presumably, remembering the conclusion of a celebrated theorem<br />

of 19th Century mathematics:<br />

Theorem 1.2. Let the axioms of Euclidean geometry be assumed. If a<br />

line segment of unit length is given, then it is impossible to construct a<br />

line segment of length π in finitely many steps using only a straightedge<br />

<strong>and</strong> compass. Consequently, it is impossible to construct a segment of<br />

length √ π, that is, to “square the circle”.<br />

As a general lesson, Theorem 1.2 says nothing about the possibility<br />

of constructing such a line segment with tools other than a straightedge<br />

<strong>and</strong> compass, nor about the possibility of obtaining better <strong>and</strong> better<br />

approximations with a straightedge <strong>and</strong> compass, thereby (in a sense)<br />

achieving the construction in infinitely many steps. The relevant shortcoming<br />

in this story is that the theorem says nothing unless the axioms<br />

of Euclidean geometry are assumed. 2<br />

If there is a linguistic lesson to be gleaned from mathematics, it<br />

is that words themselves are merely labels for concepts. While our<br />

minds react strongly to words, 3 it is the underlying concepts that are<br />

central to logic, mathematics, <strong>and</strong> reality. Good terminology is chosen<br />

to reflect meaning, but it is a common, human, mistake to assume an<br />

implication is obvious on the basis of terminology. Mathematicians<br />

remind themselves of this with the red herring principle:<br />

In mathematics, a ‘red herring’ may be neither red nor a<br />

herring.<br />

Theorem 1.2 is remarkable for another reason: It asserts the impossibility<br />

of a procedure that is a priori conceivable (namely, that is not<br />

2 The columnist’s error was not this glaring; they argued that because theorems<br />

of hyperbolic geometry can be interpreted as statements in Euclidean geometry,<br />

a “hyperbolic” proof is self-contradictory. The resolution to this objection is that<br />

while “squaring the circle in hyperbolic geometry” can be interpreted as a statement<br />

about Euclidean geometry, the interpretation is markedly different from “squaring<br />

the circle in Euclidean geometry”, <strong>and</strong> does not contradict Theorem 1.2.<br />

3 To the extent that nonsensical rhetoric can be persuasive, or that it is illegal in<br />

the U.S. to broadcast certain words by radio or television.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!