01.09.2013 Views

Situation Ethics - TERE

Situation Ethics - TERE

Situation Ethics - TERE

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Critique of <strong>Situation</strong> <strong>Ethics</strong><br />

Positive<br />

1 It can be considered as the solution to<br />

two tendencies in ethics – rule-bound<br />

ethics (legalism) and no-rules ethics<br />

(antinomianism). It has one rule: love.<br />

The rule of love is prescriptive, others<br />

rules merely illuminative.<br />

2 It is simple and yet profound. It is not<br />

meant to encourage laxity. Fletcher<br />

has in mind agape, that self-giving,<br />

unconditional willing of another’s good,<br />

when he uses the word love.<br />

3 In grounding his theory in this love<br />

Fletcher seeks to align it with the<br />

gospels and the letters of Paul (cf.<br />

Great Commandment & St Paul’s<br />

hymn to agape in 1 Corinthians).<br />

4 It aims to skirt the problems arising<br />

when a situation brings important rules<br />

into conflict. It simply says: ‘Do the<br />

most loving thing.’ Fletcher, is in book<br />

<strong>Situation</strong> <strong>Ethics</strong>, highlights cases when<br />

the application of rules in itself does<br />

not address the moral problem.<br />

Negative<br />

Fletcher’s theory will share the weaknesses of<br />

utilitarianism, of which it appears to be a form.<br />

1 Fletcher’s theory depends on the<br />

individual’s appraisal of situations. A<br />

person, even with the finest of<br />

intentions, cannot foresee every<br />

consequence of an action, nor realise<br />

the number likely to be affected by it.<br />

2 Add to this the taint on a person’s<br />

decision-making arising from ingrained<br />

self-seeking and from a reluctance to<br />

aim for the high standards of<br />

unconditional love, and we quickly see<br />

the value of a more rule-dependent<br />

moral system - if only to protect others<br />

© 2006 P.J. McHugh 3<br />

from our latent selfishness<br />

masquerading as ‘love’.<br />

3 St Paul wrote not that ‘love is the end<br />

of the law’ but that ‘love is the<br />

fulfilment of the law’. For love and law<br />

need each other. Love needs law for<br />

its direction, while law needs love for<br />

its inspiration. (cf. John Stott)<br />

4 Add to this the impracticality of<br />

attempting a moral calculus when a<br />

quick decision is needed.<br />

5 Fletcher’s ethics stresses the<br />

uniqueness of moral situations. Whilst<br />

no two situations demanding moral<br />

choices can be said to be identical, the<br />

moral problem may be so similar in<br />

each as not to require separate<br />

analysis. In other words, situations<br />

that vary enormously in externals<br />

may be very similar in their moral<br />

tenor.<br />

5 It could be argued that when one acts<br />

lovingly there are certain things one<br />

will always do and certain things one<br />

will never do. Fundamental rules, like<br />

those in the Decalogue, are merely<br />

‘crystallisations of love’.<br />

6 Hence, the rule of love is interpreted<br />

through other rules which should also<br />

be prescriptive. Certainly, the Judeo-<br />

Christian heritage is one wherein rules<br />

have a place - even in the agape<br />

communities of the early Church.<br />

6 The problem of legalism is not brought<br />

on by rules, but by a mindset.<br />

Legalistic minds may abound even<br />

when there are few explicit rules, and<br />

those who are not of a legalistic<br />

mindset will ignore the fussier,<br />

pernickety prescriptions of an<br />

elaborate rule system - they will realise<br />

that certain prescriptions are more<br />

binding than others.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!