30.12.2013 Views

Tearing Apart the Zagreus Myth - Bryn Mawr College

Tearing Apart the Zagreus Myth - Bryn Mawr College

Tearing Apart the Zagreus Myth - Bryn Mawr College

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

RADCLIFFE EDMONDS<br />

<strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong>:<br />

A Few Disparaging Remarks<br />

On Orphism and Original Sin<br />

Pure I come from <strong>the</strong> pure, Queen of those below <strong>the</strong> earth,<br />

and Eukles and Eubouleus and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r gods and daimons;<br />

For I boast that I am of your blessed race.<br />

I have paid <strong>the</strong> penalty on account of deeds not just;<br />

Ei<strong>the</strong>r Fate mastered me or <strong>the</strong> Thunderer, striking with his lightning.<br />

Now I come, a suppliant, to holy Phersephoneia,<br />

that she, gracious, may send me to <strong>the</strong> seats of <strong>the</strong> blessed. 1<br />

So proclaims <strong>the</strong> deceased woman of Thurii on <strong>the</strong> gold tablet buried in her<br />

tomb in Timpone Piccolo. This enigmatic statement, similar to <strong>the</strong> proclamations<br />

on <strong>the</strong> gold tablets found in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two tombs in <strong>the</strong> mound, has piqued <strong>the</strong><br />

interest of scholars ever since its discovery in 1879. Despite <strong>the</strong> protests of<br />

Wilamowitz, Linforth, Zuntz, and, most recently, Luc Brisson, scholars continue,<br />

for <strong>the</strong> most part, to interpret <strong>the</strong>se tablets in terms of what is known as <strong>the</strong><br />

Orphic myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>. This tale, called “<strong>the</strong> cardinal myth of Orphism,” 2 is<br />

typically related as it is in Morford and Lenardon’s introductory textbook on<br />

Greek <strong>Myth</strong>ology (sixth edition, 1999):<br />

I would like to thank Chris Faraone, Hans Dieter Betz, J. Z. Smith, Bruce Lincoln, Fritz Graf, and<br />

<strong>the</strong> editors and readers at Classical Antiquity for <strong>the</strong>ir comments on earlier drafts of this paper. It<br />

need scarcely be said that any infelicities of expression or outright errors that remain are wholly<br />

<strong>the</strong> products of my own ignorance, carelessness, or obstinacy.<br />

1. êrxomai âk kaqarÀn kaqarˆ, xqonÐwn basÐleia, EÎkl¨j kaÈ EÎbouleÔj kaÈ qeoÈ<br />

daÐmonej Šlloi kaÈ g€r âg°n ÍmÀn gènoj îlbion eÖxomai eÚnai. poin€n d' ‚ntapèteis'<br />

êrgwn ének' oÖti dikaÐwn; eÒte me MoØra âdamˆsato eÒte ÇAsterop¨ta kraunÀn. nÜn<br />

d' Ékètij ¡kw par' gn˜n Fersefìneian ¹j me prìfrwn pèmyhi édraj âj eÎagèwn (Tablet<br />

A2, Zuntz 1971:303). The tablet is listed in Kern 1922 as OF 32d. All references to fragments in<br />

Kern will be labeled as OF, <strong>the</strong> testimonies as OT.<br />

2. Nilsson 1935:202.<br />

© 1999 BY THE REGENTS OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA.<br />

ISSN 0278-6656(p); 1067-8344 (e).


36<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

Zeus mated with his daughter Persephone, who bore a son, <strong>Zagreus</strong>,<br />

which is ano<strong>the</strong>r name for Dionysus. Hera in her jealousy aroused <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans to attack <strong>the</strong> child. These monstrous beings, <strong>the</strong>ir faces whitened<br />

with chalk, attacked <strong>the</strong> infant as he was looking in a mirror (in ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

version <strong>the</strong>y beguiled him with toys and cut him to pieces with knives).<br />

After <strong>the</strong> murder, <strong>the</strong> Titans devoured <strong>the</strong> dismembered corpse. But <strong>the</strong><br />

heart of <strong>the</strong> infant god was saved and brought to Zeus by A<strong>the</strong>na, and<br />

Dionysus was born again—swallowed by Zeus and begotten on Semele.<br />

Zeus was angry with <strong>the</strong> Titans and destroyed <strong>the</strong>m with his thunder and<br />

lightning. But from <strong>the</strong>ir ashes mankind was born.<br />

Surely this is one of <strong>the</strong> most significant myths in terms of <strong>the</strong> philosophy<br />

and religious dogma that it provides. By it man is endowed with a dual<br />

nature—a body, gross and evil (since he is sprung from <strong>the</strong> Titans),<br />

and a soul that is pure and divine (for after all <strong>the</strong> Titans had devoured<br />

<strong>the</strong> god). Thus basic religious concepts (which lie at <strong>the</strong> root of all<br />

mystery religions) are accounted for: sin, immortality, resurrection, life<br />

after death, reward, and punishment. 3<br />

Read in <strong>the</strong> light of this <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, <strong>the</strong> tablets’ message seems clear. The<br />

deceased claims kinship with <strong>the</strong> gods by virtue of her descent from <strong>the</strong> Titans.<br />

Like <strong>the</strong> Titans, she claims to have perished by <strong>the</strong> lightning bolt of Zeus. In her<br />

life as an Orphic, she has paid <strong>the</strong> penalty for <strong>the</strong> ancestral crime of <strong>the</strong> Titans<br />

through purificatory rituals. Now, purified of <strong>the</strong> taint of this original sin, she<br />

asks Persephone for favorable treatment in <strong>the</strong> afterlife by virtue of her divine<br />

descent from <strong>the</strong> flesh of Dionysos eaten by <strong>the</strong> Titans.<br />

Although this myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> provides a seductively simple and neat explanation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> cryptic gold tablet, it is unfortunately a modern creation that<br />

could not have been known to <strong>the</strong> “Orphics” of Timpone Piccolo. Indeed, I shall<br />

demonstrate that this <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth is, in fact, a modern fabrication dependent<br />

upon Christian models that reconstruct <strong>the</strong> fragmentary evidence in terms of a unified<br />

“Orphic” church, an almost Christian religion with dogma based on a central<br />

myth—specifically, salvation from original sin through <strong>the</strong> death and resurrection<br />

of <strong>the</strong> suffering god. If <strong>the</strong> evidence is viewed without <strong>the</strong>se assumptions, it can be<br />

put back toge<strong>the</strong>r quite differently.<br />

Ivan Linforth critically reviewed most of this evidence in his 1941 work, The<br />

Arts of Orpheus, but <strong>the</strong> consequences of his analysis have been neglected, in part<br />

because of <strong>the</strong> extreme minimalist stance he took in his definition of Orphism. 4<br />

3. Morford and Lenardon 1999:223–24.<br />

4. Linforth 1941. Despite his overly narrow restriction of <strong>the</strong> evidence for Orphism to things<br />

bearing <strong>the</strong> name of Orpheus (thus omitting all of <strong>the</strong> gold tablets), much of Linforth’s critique of <strong>the</strong><br />

modern construction of Orphism remains valid, even with <strong>the</strong> discovery of new evidence such as <strong>the</strong><br />

Derveni papyrus, <strong>the</strong> Olbia bone tablets, and several new gold tablets with different texts. These<br />

discoveries indeed throw new light on <strong>the</strong> religious phenomena termed “Orphic,” but this makes <strong>the</strong><br />

revival of Linforth’s critiques of <strong>the</strong> monolithic construction of Orphism even more crucial. The<br />

Derveni papyrus shows that <strong>the</strong>ogonies ascribed to Orpheus in <strong>the</strong> fourth century BCE contained


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 37<br />

Recently, Burkert and o<strong>the</strong>rs have shown that Orphism was not a single unified<br />

Church, but is best understood as a collection of diverse counter-cultural religious<br />

movements whose major proponents were itinerant “craftsmen” of purification<br />

who provided services for a wide variety of customers. 5 Viewed in this light, <strong>the</strong><br />

pieces of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth reveal not a single canonical story providing crucial<br />

dogma for <strong>the</strong> “Orphic Church,” but ra<strong>the</strong>r a multitude of tales told about <strong>the</strong><br />

death of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, each with its own meaning<br />

woven out of <strong>the</strong> differing combinations of <strong>the</strong> traditional motifs.<br />

In this paper, I distinguish between <strong>the</strong> ancient tales relating to <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

or sparagmos of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> modern fabrication which I call <strong>the</strong><br />

“<strong>Zagreus</strong> myth.” This myth is put toge<strong>the</strong>r from a number of elements: (1) <strong>the</strong><br />

dismemberment of Dionysos; (2) <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans; (3) <strong>the</strong> creation of<br />

mankind from <strong>the</strong> Titans; and (4) <strong>the</strong> inheritance humans receive from <strong>the</strong> first<br />

three elements—<strong>the</strong> burden of guilt from <strong>the</strong> Titans’ crime and <strong>the</strong> divine spark<br />

from <strong>the</strong> remains of Dionysos. I refer to <strong>the</strong> entire story as <strong>the</strong> “<strong>Zagreus</strong> myth”<br />

to reflect <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> name <strong>Zagreus</strong> for <strong>the</strong> Orphic Dionysos by <strong>the</strong> scholars<br />

who fabricated this myth. 6<br />

Building upon Linforth’s critical review, I first examine <strong>the</strong> pieces of evidence<br />

out of which <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth has been assembled, demonstrating that <strong>the</strong><br />

few pieces of evidence used to construct <strong>the</strong> myth fail to support not only <strong>the</strong><br />

centrality and early date of <strong>the</strong> myth (as Linforth has argued), but even <strong>the</strong><br />

existence of such a story before <strong>the</strong> modern era. While ancient sources provide<br />

testimony for <strong>the</strong> first three components of <strong>the</strong> myth, <strong>the</strong> final component—<br />

some of <strong>the</strong> elements found in later Orphic material, but <strong>the</strong> contrast between <strong>the</strong> Derveni fourgeneration<br />

<strong>the</strong>ogony (which reappears in Neoplatonic testimonia) and <strong>the</strong> six-generation <strong>the</strong>ogony<br />

to which Plato alludes confirms that a variety of “Orphic” <strong>the</strong>ogonies were circulating at <strong>the</strong> time. In<br />

his recent work, West 1983 has reduced all of <strong>the</strong> testimonies to Orphic <strong>the</strong>ogonies to a stemma with<br />

two main branches, on <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> variations in <strong>the</strong> mythic tellings can be charted as<br />

neatly as <strong>the</strong> errors in manuscripts. Even West, however, does not suggest that <strong>the</strong> Derveni <strong>the</strong>ogony<br />

contained <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth. If West’s reconstruction of ORFIK[ on <strong>the</strong> Olbia bone tablets as<br />

“Orphikoi” is correct, it would provide <strong>the</strong> first clear reference to people calling <strong>the</strong>mselves Orphics<br />

(ra<strong>the</strong>r than to rituals and texts called Orphica) before <strong>the</strong> second century CE. Although <strong>the</strong> new gold<br />

tablets from Hipponion and Pelinna finally provide evidence of a link between <strong>the</strong> gold tablets and<br />

Dionysos, an idea vehemently denied by scholars such as Zuntz, <strong>the</strong> presence of Dionysos does not<br />

imply <strong>the</strong> myth of Dionysos <strong>Zagreus</strong>.<br />

5. Burkert 1982. Detienne 1975 refers to Orphism and Pythagoreanism as different chemins<br />

de déviance from mainstream Greek religion, a useful term I would apply to <strong>the</strong> various modes of<br />

Orphism itself.<br />

6. Lobeck 1829 seems to be responsible for <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> name <strong>Zagreus</strong> for <strong>the</strong> Orphic<br />

Dionysos. As Linforth noticed, “It is a curious thing that <strong>the</strong> name <strong>Zagreus</strong> does not appear in<br />

any Orphic poem or fragment, nor is it used by any author who refers to Orpheus” (Linforth<br />

1941:311). In his reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> story, however, Lobeck made extensive use of <strong>the</strong> fifthcentury<br />

CE epic of Nonnos, who does use <strong>the</strong> name <strong>Zagreus</strong>, and later scholars followed his cue. The<br />

association of Dionysos with <strong>Zagreus</strong> appears first explicitly in a fragment of Callimachus preserved<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Etymologicum Magnum (fr. 43.117 P), with a possible earlier precedent in <strong>the</strong> fragment from<br />

Euripides Cretans (fr. 472 Nauck). Earlier evidence, however, (e.g., Alkmaionis fr. 3 PEG; Aeschylus<br />

frr. 5, 228) suggests that <strong>Zagreus</strong> was often identified with o<strong>the</strong>r deities.


38<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

<strong>the</strong> resulting original sin—is an addition of modern scholars. I next show that,<br />

viewed without <strong>the</strong> framework of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, <strong>the</strong> pieces of evidence provide<br />

testimony for a variety of tellings of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment myth, which was not<br />

<strong>the</strong> exclusive property of <strong>the</strong> “Orphics” but ra<strong>the</strong>r a well-known element in <strong>the</strong><br />

Greek mythic tradition. I <strong>the</strong>n explore <strong>the</strong> Christian models of religion within<br />

which <strong>the</strong> myth was mistakenly reconstructed, noting <strong>the</strong> role this reconstruction<br />

of Orphism played in <strong>the</strong> turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-century debates surrounding <strong>the</strong> nature of<br />

<strong>the</strong> early Church. Finally, I conclude that <strong>the</strong> gold tablets and <strong>the</strong>ir religious<br />

contexts have been misunderstood because <strong>the</strong>se texts have been interpreted<br />

in terms of a modern fabrication dependent on Christian models, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

myth. The “Orphic” gold tablets <strong>the</strong>mselves have nothing to do with <strong>the</strong> stories<br />

of sparagmos and anthropogony, but instead supply important evidence for <strong>the</strong><br />

study of Greek eschatological beliefs.<br />

THE PIECES OF THE ZAGREUS MYTH<br />

“All of <strong>the</strong> reconstructions of Orphism have as <strong>the</strong>ir base a very small<br />

number of secure pieces of evidence and a much greater number of texts whose<br />

interpretation seems to me to be quite arbitrary.” 7 Of no part of Orphism is<br />

Festugière’s comment more true than of <strong>the</strong> supposed heart of <strong>the</strong> religion, <strong>the</strong><br />

myth of <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind from <strong>the</strong> dismembered <strong>Zagreus</strong>. All of <strong>the</strong><br />

reconstructions of this myth depend upon only six pieces of evidence, fragments<br />

whose interpretation is indeed disputable. A number of sources mention <strong>the</strong><br />

sparagmos of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans, ranging from mere<br />

allusions as early as <strong>the</strong> third century BCE to fairly detailed narratives in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

several centuries of <strong>the</strong> Christian era. These stories, often attributed to Orpheus,<br />

include various details, with some versions focusing on <strong>the</strong> death or rebirth of<br />

Dionysos and o<strong>the</strong>rs on <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans. The most detailed version<br />

(and one of <strong>the</strong> few sources that actually refers to Dionysos as <strong>Zagreus</strong>) appears in<br />

<strong>the</strong> fifth-century CE Dionysiaca of Nonnos, an antiquarian work that combines as<br />

many stories as possible about Dionysos into a lengthy epic. Even this source,<br />

however, does not add <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind to <strong>the</strong> tale of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment.<br />

The anthropogony, <strong>the</strong> supposedly crucial element in <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, is, in<br />

fact, only found combined with <strong>the</strong> tales of <strong>the</strong> sparagmos and <strong>the</strong> punishment<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Titans in a single Neoplatonic commentary that dates to <strong>the</strong> sixth century of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Christian era.<br />

The interpretation of all <strong>the</strong>se tales about Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> Titans in terms<br />

of original sin passed from <strong>the</strong> Titans to <strong>the</strong> human race by this anthropogony<br />

first appears in 1879, in Comparetti’s analysis of <strong>the</strong> Thurii gold tablets in <strong>the</strong><br />

7. “Toutes les reconstructions de l’orphisme ont pour fondement un très petit nombre de<br />

témoignages sûrs et un plus grand nombre de textes dont l’exégese me paraît arbitraire” (Festugière<br />

1936:310).


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 39<br />

excavation report. 8 The gold tablets, with <strong>the</strong>ir cryptic references to lightning<br />

and unjust deeds, open <strong>the</strong> flood gates for <strong>the</strong> new wave of interpretation of <strong>the</strong><br />

old evidence. Although half a century earlier Lobeck collected <strong>the</strong> evidence for<br />

<strong>the</strong> stories of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos by <strong>the</strong> Titans, <strong>the</strong>ir punishment,<br />

and even <strong>the</strong> subsequent anthropogony, he did not refer to a doctrine of original<br />

sin, nor is it mentioned in scholarly treatments between Lobeck and Comparetti,<br />

such as Zeller’s History of Greek Philosophy or <strong>the</strong> mythological handbooks<br />

of Creuzer, Maury, and Welcker. 9 The scholarship on <strong>the</strong> first gold tablet from<br />

Petelia, published in 1836, contains no reference to <strong>the</strong> Titanic heritage and <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, or even to Orphism, until Comparetti associated it with <strong>the</strong> Thurii<br />

tablets. 10 After Comparetti, however, <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> (<strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

and punishment plus <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and original sin) quickly becomes, through<br />

<strong>the</strong> influence of scholars such as Rohde and Harrison, <strong>the</strong> accepted central dogma<br />

of Orphism. 11<br />

Although Linforth, after his critical examination of <strong>the</strong> evidence for <strong>the</strong><br />

reconstruction, concludes that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth should not be considered <strong>the</strong><br />

central doctrine of Orphism, he does think that <strong>the</strong> myth existed in some form as<br />

early as Pindar. I would take Linforth’s critique of <strong>the</strong> previous scholarship even<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r. Building upon his examination of <strong>the</strong> evidence for <strong>the</strong> various elements of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, I argue that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth is, in fact, not even a peripheral<br />

story for <strong>the</strong> ancient Orphics, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a modern fabrication from a variety of<br />

tales in <strong>the</strong> Greek mythological tradition. In this section, I examine <strong>the</strong> select<br />

few passages on which <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth is based, <strong>the</strong> same<br />

six passages cited by scholars from Comparetti to <strong>the</strong> present day to support<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir addition of <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and <strong>the</strong> doctrine of original sin to <strong>the</strong> tales<br />

of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans. While<br />

those engaged in <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth have construed <strong>the</strong>se<br />

passages in accordance with <strong>the</strong> idea of a central but secret myth of <strong>the</strong> creation of<br />

mankind stained with original sin, only one of <strong>the</strong> passages even mentions <strong>the</strong><br />

anthropogony, and none supports a doctrine of original sin.<br />

8. Comparetti 1879. Comparetti cites no sources for his interpretation of <strong>the</strong> gold tablet in<br />

terms of Orphic original sin, but scholars have noted Comparetti’s part in <strong>the</strong> anticlerical polemic<br />

in <strong>the</strong> debates regarding <strong>the</strong> early Church, which I will discuss below (cf. Ziolkowski 1997, esp.<br />

p. xxvii).<br />

9. Zeller 1881; Creuzer 1822; Maury 1857; Welcker 1860. Comparetti’s interpretation has not<br />

yet penetrated into <strong>the</strong> scholarship of Dieterich 1891, 1893 or even Frazer’s discussion of Dionysos<br />

<strong>Zagreus</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Golden Bough (Frazer 1912).<br />

10. Comparetti 1882:111–18; cf. Comparetti 1910. The earlier publications of <strong>the</strong> Petelia tablet<br />

debated whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> tablet pertained to <strong>the</strong> Trophonios oracle at Lebedeia or was a Pythian oracle<br />

regarding <strong>the</strong> Trophonios oracle. Cf. Franz 1836:149–50; Goettling 1843.<br />

11. The influential first appearances of this interpretation are in Rohde 1925 (German 1st ed. vol.<br />

2 in 1894) and in Harrison 1922 (1st ed. 1903). The interpretation was <strong>the</strong>n built into <strong>the</strong> scholarship<br />

on Orphism by Kern’s arrangement of <strong>the</strong> fragments in his 1922 Orphicorum Fragmenta, which<br />

is still <strong>the</strong> standard reference.


40<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

The central piece of evidence for <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth comes<br />

from <strong>the</strong> late sixth-century CE Neoplatonist Olympiodorus in his commentary on<br />

Plato’s Phaedo. Commenting on <strong>the</strong> prohibition of suicide that Socrates attributes<br />

vaguely to <strong>the</strong> mystery doctrine that our souls are imprisoned in our bodies,<br />

Olympiodorus claims that <strong>the</strong> mythical explanation of <strong>the</strong> prohibition may be<br />

found in a tale told by Orpheus:<br />

Then Dionysus succeeds Zeus. Through <strong>the</strong> scheme of Hera, <strong>the</strong>y say, his<br />

retainers, <strong>the</strong> Titans, tear him to pieces and eat his flesh. Zeus, angered by<br />

<strong>the</strong> deed, blasts <strong>the</strong>m with his thunderbolts, and from <strong>the</strong> sublimate of <strong>the</strong><br />

vapors that rise from <strong>the</strong>m comes <strong>the</strong> matter from which men are created.<br />

Therefore we must not kill ourselves, not because, as <strong>the</strong> text appears<br />

to say, we are in <strong>the</strong> body as a kind of shackle, for that is obvious, and<br />

Socrates would not call this a mystery; but we must not kill ourselves<br />

because our bodies are Dionysiac; we are, in fact, a part of him, if indeed<br />

we come about from <strong>the</strong> sublimate of <strong>the</strong> Titans who ate his flesh. 12<br />

Olympiodorus claims that <strong>the</strong> real reason for <strong>the</strong> prohibition against suicide comes<br />

not from <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> soul is imprisoned in <strong>the</strong> body, since that is obvious<br />

(at least to a good sixth-century Neoplatonist), but ra<strong>the</strong>r comes from <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

our bodies contain <strong>the</strong> fragments of Dionysos eaten by <strong>the</strong> Titans. Guthrie, in<br />

his Orpheus and Greek Religion, sums up <strong>the</strong> predominant interpretation:<br />

From <strong>the</strong> smoking remnants of <strong>the</strong> Titans <strong>the</strong>re arose a race which this<br />

age had not yet known, <strong>the</strong> race of mortal men. Our nature <strong>the</strong>refore is<br />

twofold. We are born from <strong>the</strong> Titans, <strong>the</strong> wicked sons of Earth, but <strong>the</strong>re<br />

is in us something of a heavenly nature too, since <strong>the</strong>re went into our<br />

making fragments of <strong>the</strong> body of Dionysos, son of Olympian Zeus, on<br />

whom <strong>the</strong> Titans had made <strong>the</strong>ir impious feast. . . . Knowing all this, what<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r aim can we have in life but to purge away as far as possible <strong>the</strong><br />

Titanic element in us and exalt and cherish <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac. 13<br />

Although no o<strong>the</strong>r ancient author connects <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong><br />

creation of mankind, many scholars have assumed that this story was <strong>the</strong> central,<br />

secret dogma of Orphism from earliest times. 14 Guthrie interprets this passage of<br />

12. eÚta tän DÐa diedècato å Diìnusoj, ín fasi kat' âpiboul˜n t¨j ‡Hraj toÌj perÈ<br />

aÎtän Tit naj sparˆttein kaÈ tÀn sarkÀn aÎtoÜ ‚pogeÔesqai. kaÈ toÔtouj ærgisqeÈj<br />

å ZeÌj âkeraÔnwse, kaÈ âk t¨j aÊqˆlhj tÀn ‚tmÀn tÀn ‚nadoqèntwn âc aÎtÀn Õlhj<br />

genomènhj genèsqai toÌj ‚nqr¸pouj; oÎ deØ oÞn âcˆgein m j áautoÔj, oÎx íti, ±j<br />

dokeØ lègein lècij, diìti ên tini desmÀú âsmen tÀú s¸mati, toÜto g€r d¨lìn âsti, kaÈ<br />

oÎk “n toÜto ‚pìrrhton êlegen, ‚ll' íti oÎ deØ âcˆgein m j áautoÌj ±j toÜ s¸matoj<br />

mÀn DionusiakoÜ întoj; mèroj g€r aÎtoÜ âsmen, eÒ ge âk t¨j aÊqˆlhj tÀn Titˆnwn<br />

sugkeÐmeqa geusamènwn tÀn sarkÀn toÔtou (Olympiodorus In Phaed. 1.3 = OF 220).<br />

13. Guthrie 1952:83.<br />

14. Proclus does link two of <strong>the</strong> elements, <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans and <strong>the</strong> creation of<br />

mankind. In his commentary on <strong>the</strong> Republic, Proclus cites some Orphic poems to support <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

of reincarnation into both human and animal forms. £ oÎxÈ kaÈ ÇOrfeÌj t€ toiaÜta safÀj


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 41<br />

Olympiodorus as evidence that <strong>the</strong> Orphics had a central dogma of <strong>the</strong> duality<br />

of man’s nature, a belief <strong>the</strong>y based on <strong>the</strong> anthropogonic myth of <strong>the</strong> creation<br />

of man from <strong>the</strong> ashes of <strong>the</strong> Titans filled with <strong>the</strong> fragments of Dionysos.<br />

Linforth, however, has pointed out that Olympiodorus’ interpretation, far<br />

from representing canonical Orphic doctrine, is ra<strong>the</strong>r an idiosyncratic version of<br />

<strong>the</strong> story, created by Olympiodorus in <strong>the</strong> service of his argument against suicide.<br />

Linforth argues, “There can be little doubt that Olympiodorus drew this inference<br />

himself in order to contrive an argument against suicide on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong><br />

myth. . . . He does not say that he found <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> body of man is Dionysiac<br />

in an Orphic poem, nor does he present it as if he had.” 15 Olympiodorus is clearly<br />

and consciously innovating, bringing out <strong>the</strong> previously unnoticed consequences<br />

of a detail of <strong>the</strong> story—<strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> Titans consumed Dionysos means that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y absorbed some of his being.<br />

Brisson, moreover, suggests a particular reason for Olympiodorus’ peculiar<br />

version of <strong>the</strong> story. He notes that Olympiodorus uses contemporary alchemical<br />

terms to describe <strong>the</strong> creation of man from <strong>the</strong> sublimate (aÊqˆlh) produced<br />

from <strong>the</strong> vaporization (å ‚tmìj) of <strong>the</strong> Titans by Zeus’ lightning. 16 The word<br />

tÐtanoj means quicklime, a substance produced by burning limestone, and Brisson<br />

cites two definitions from an alchemical lexicon: titanos is <strong>the</strong> lime of <strong>the</strong><br />

egg (tÐtanìj âsti Šsbestoj ²oÜ) and <strong>the</strong> stone of Dionysos is lime (lÐqoj<br />

DionÔsou âstÈn Šsbestoj). 17 The Titanic and Dionysiac elements, subjected<br />

to <strong>the</strong> fire of Zeus, produce a sublimate, aÊqˆlh, which <strong>the</strong> third-century CE<br />

alchemist Zosimus equates with <strong>the</strong> pneÜma that animates <strong>the</strong> human body. 18 Thus,<br />

Olympiodorus’ way of telling <strong>the</strong> myth makes it a perfect alchemical allegory for<br />

<strong>the</strong> formation of <strong>the</strong> human pneÜma. Olympiodorus refers to both <strong>the</strong> Titanic and<br />

Dionysiac elements that went into <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind because both have<br />

an alchemical significance. He stresses <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac element<br />

in <strong>the</strong> formula because of his argument against suicide. While Olympiodorus<br />

provides an excellent sample of late antique alchemical speculation, nothing in<br />

his telling of <strong>the</strong> myth provides any evidence for an early Orphic doctrine of <strong>the</strong><br />

divinity or salvation of mankind from <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac bits absorbed by <strong>the</strong> Titans. 19<br />

paradÐdwsin, ítan met€ t˜n tÀn Titˆnwn muqik˜n dÐkhn kaÈ t˜n âc âkeÐnwn gènesin tÀn<br />

qnhtÀn toÔtwn z¸úwn . . . (Proclus In Plat. Rempublicam 2.338 = OF 224). Proclus links <strong>the</strong><br />

creation of all living beings with <strong>the</strong> mythic punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, but this tale of punishment<br />

is more likely to be <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> Titanomachy ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos. Moreover,<br />

since all living creatures, not simply humans, are created from <strong>the</strong> Titans in this telling, <strong>the</strong> story<br />

cannot have included an element of an original sin that burdens <strong>the</strong> human race.<br />

15. Linforth 1941:330.<br />

16. “En définitive, en foudroyant les Titans, Zeus aurait procédé àune opération alchimique,<br />

dont aurait résulté l’être humain” (Brisson 1992:493–94, reprinted in Brisson 1995).<br />

17. Ber<strong>the</strong>lot 1888 II:14.2, 10.2.<br />

18. Ibid. II, Les quatres corps, par. 5:151.1: AÊqˆlh dà pneÜma, pneÔmati di€ t€ s¸mata.<br />

19. Cf. Linforth’s assessment, “The belief that this myth transcends in importance all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

things that were contained in <strong>the</strong> poetry of Orpheus or were o<strong>the</strong>rwise associated with his name


42<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

West, whose Orphic Poems is <strong>the</strong> most recent comprehensive treatment of<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject, agrees with Linforth that <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac element in mankind is an<br />

invention of Olympiodorus, but he persists in <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> anthropogony from<br />

<strong>the</strong> blasted Titans is an early element in <strong>the</strong> myth:<br />

Although Olympiodorus’ interpretation of <strong>the</strong> Orphic myth is to be rejected,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no denying that <strong>the</strong> poet may have drawn some conclusion<br />

from it about man’s nature; . . . any such conclusion is likely to have concerned<br />

<strong>the</strong> burdens of our inheritance. The fact that <strong>the</strong> Titans had eaten<br />

Dionysus was merely evidence of <strong>the</strong>ir wickedness, it did not introduce<br />

a saving element into our constitution. It is to <strong>the</strong> living Dionysus that we<br />

must turn for salvation. 20<br />

West still sees original sin and salvation through <strong>the</strong> resurrected Dionysos as<br />

Orphic doctrines for which Olympiodorus’ commentary provides firm evidence.<br />

Even if <strong>the</strong>re is no Dionysiac nature in mankind, <strong>the</strong> Titanic nature still lingers<br />

in humanity, creating <strong>the</strong> need to pay reparation for <strong>the</strong> ancestral crime.<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> fact that nothing in Olympiodorus implies <strong>the</strong> idea of guilt<br />

inherited from <strong>the</strong> Titans, scholars from Comparetti to West have cited several<br />

specific fragments of evidence to support <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> Orphics believed,<br />

from a very early date, in a Titanic nature of man that is a consequence of <strong>the</strong><br />

anthropogony from <strong>the</strong> ashes of <strong>the</strong> Titans. As I examine <strong>the</strong> next few pieces of<br />

evidence, I shall argue, to <strong>the</strong> contrary, that <strong>the</strong> anthropogonic part of <strong>the</strong> myth<br />

of <strong>Zagreus</strong> does not appear to be linked with <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong><br />

punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans in any evidence before <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists, and that <strong>the</strong><br />

doctrine of original sin derived from it is, in fact, an invention of modern scholars.<br />

Those who wish to date <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth derived from Olympiodorus to <strong>the</strong><br />

sixth century BCE instead of CE adduce as evidence <strong>the</strong> statement of Pausanias<br />

that Onomakritos was <strong>the</strong> first to put <strong>the</strong> Titans in <strong>the</strong> myth of Dionysos. “Homer<br />

first introduced <strong>the</strong> Titans into poetry, making <strong>the</strong>m gods down in Tartaros, as it<br />

is called; <strong>the</strong> lines are in <strong>the</strong> oath of Hera. Onomakritos, borrowing <strong>the</strong> name from<br />

Homer, composed <strong>the</strong> rites of Dionysos and made <strong>the</strong> Titans <strong>the</strong> authors of <strong>the</strong><br />

sufferings of Dionysos.” 21 Onomakritos, according to Herodotus (6.7.3), kept <strong>the</strong><br />

oracle collection of <strong>the</strong> Pisistratids in A<strong>the</strong>ns until he was exiled for forging some<br />

oracles of Musaeus, son of Orpheus. As a result, Onomakritos has been described<br />

probably rests in large part on <strong>the</strong> assumption that it formed <strong>the</strong> basis for an Orphic doctrine of <strong>the</strong><br />

divinity of man. The profound significance of such a doctrine, however, is so dazzling and impressive<br />

that scholars have been somewhat uncritical in <strong>the</strong>ir use of <strong>the</strong> testimony which is supposed to supply<br />

a warrant for it in Orphic religion” (Linforth 1941:308).<br />

20. West 1983:166.<br />

21. Tit naj dà prÀtoj âj poÐhsin âs gagen ‡Omhroj, qeoÌj eÚnai sf j Ípä tÀú<br />

kaloumènwú Tartˆrwú; kaÈ êstin ân ‡Hraj írkwú t€ êph. par€ dà ÃOm rou ÇOnomˆkritoj<br />

paralab°n tÀn Titˆnwn tä înoma DionÔswú te sunèqhken îrgia, kaÈ eÚnai toÌj Tit naj<br />

tÀú DionÔswú tÀn paqhmˆtwn âpoÐhsen aÎtourgoÔj (Pausanias 8.37.5 = OT 194). For <strong>the</strong> oath<br />

of Hera passage, see Iliad 14.279 and Hom. Hymn to Apollo 334–36.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 43<br />

according to this argument as an Orphic priest, one of <strong>the</strong> chief formulators of<br />

Orphic dogma and even <strong>the</strong> one responsible for <strong>the</strong> so-called Orphic interpolations<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Odyssey of Homer during <strong>the</strong> Pisistratid recension. 22 If Pausanias is to be<br />

trusted, <strong>the</strong> date of some tale of <strong>the</strong> Titans murdering Dionysos could be fixed<br />

to <strong>the</strong> sixth century BCE. However, as Linforth argues, scholars in <strong>the</strong> Hellenistic<br />

era and later, who were trying to determine <strong>the</strong> real authorship of various poems<br />

attributed to Orpheus, often attributed <strong>the</strong>m to Onomakritos, who was already<br />

famous as a forger:<br />

No one else throughout antiquity quotes from works of Onomacritus<br />

or makes any allusion to <strong>the</strong>m. It is an extremely probable inference<br />

from <strong>the</strong>se considerations that when Pausanias says Onomacritus he<br />

means Ps.-Orpheus, that all his quotations from Onomacritus are really<br />

quotations from Orphic poems, and that <strong>the</strong>re were actually no poems<br />

by Onomacritus and never had been. His words cannot be taken as a<br />

statement of fact, but only as an echo of speculations concerning <strong>the</strong><br />

authorship of Orphic poetry. 23<br />

Pausanias <strong>the</strong>refore only attributes <strong>the</strong> introduction of <strong>the</strong> Titans into <strong>the</strong> story<br />

of <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos to some poem claiming to be by Orpheus and gives<br />

<strong>the</strong> name of <strong>the</strong> famous forger Onomakritos as <strong>the</strong> author of <strong>the</strong> forgery. His<br />

testimony can hardly be used to set <strong>the</strong> date much earlier than his own time, in <strong>the</strong><br />

second century CE. Moreover, while it does establish <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> Titans<br />

in <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> murder before <strong>the</strong> sixth century CE, i.e., a link between <strong>the</strong><br />

first two elements of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, it still furnishes no evidence that <strong>the</strong> third<br />

element, <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind from <strong>the</strong> Titans’ remains, was related before<br />

<strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists.<br />

Many scholars argue that <strong>the</strong> evidence of a reference in Plato’s Laws to a<br />

Titanic nature, Titanik˜n fÔsin, places <strong>the</strong> doctrine of an inherited original sin<br />

(and thus, necessarily, an anthropogony) back into <strong>the</strong> Classical era:<br />

Next on this path to liberty would be <strong>the</strong> wish not to submit to <strong>the</strong> rulers;<br />

and, following this, to flee <strong>the</strong> service and authority of fa<strong>the</strong>r and mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

and <strong>the</strong> elders; and, near <strong>the</strong> end, to seek not to obey <strong>the</strong> laws, and, at<br />

<strong>the</strong> end itself, to pay no mind to oaths and promises and <strong>the</strong> entirety of <strong>the</strong><br />

gods, displaying and imitating <strong>the</strong> fabled ancient Titanic nature, wherein<br />

<strong>the</strong>y return to <strong>the</strong> same things, experiencing a savage time, never to cease<br />

from evils. 24<br />

22. Guthrie emphasizes <strong>the</strong> role of Onomakritos, e.g., Guthrie 1952:13–14. Macchioro holds<br />

that <strong>the</strong> Orphics of Pisistratean A<strong>the</strong>ns were responsible for interpolations in Homer as part of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

“conquest of Greece” (Macchioro 1930:151–56).<br />

23. Linforth 1941:353. Cf. Pausanias’ attribution of poems to Onomakritos: 1.22.7; 8.31.3;<br />

9.35.5. In each case, it seems likely that he is referring to a poem attributed to Orpheus that he<br />

believes is not actually by Orpheus.<br />

24. âfec¨j d˜ taÔthù t¨ù âleuqerÐaø toÜ m˜ âqèlein toØj Šrxousi douleÔein gÐgnoit' Šn,<br />

kaÈ ápomènh taÔthù feÔgein paträj kaÈ mhträj kaÈ presbutèrwn douleÐan kaÈ nomoqèthsin,


44<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

Even if <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac nature in mankind is a modern misunderstanding of an<br />

Olympiodoran innovation, this Titanic nature, it is claimed, can only refer to<br />

<strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> and <strong>the</strong> creation of man from <strong>the</strong> ashes of <strong>the</strong> Titans.<br />

Nilsson claims that this passage is “fully understandable only in <strong>the</strong> light of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir role in Orphism, <strong>the</strong>ir dismembering of <strong>the</strong> Divine Child, and of <strong>the</strong> Orphic<br />

doctrine that human nature had incorporated a part of <strong>the</strong> Titans. Even if it is<br />

not ma<strong>the</strong>matically demonstrable, it is practically certain that this expression<br />

is due to <strong>the</strong> Orphic myth referred to.” 25 Linforth, however, has demonstrated<br />

that this passage does not identify mankind with its Titanic heritage, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

compares <strong>the</strong> behavior of certain degenerate people in Plato’s hypo<strong>the</strong>tical society<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Laws with <strong>the</strong> behavior of <strong>the</strong> Titans. 26 In this passage, Plato describes a<br />

progressive degeneration of society, culminating in <strong>the</strong> disregard of oaths and lack<br />

of respect for <strong>the</strong> gods—in short, behavior just like that of <strong>the</strong> Titans, a return to <strong>the</strong><br />

savage state of those early mythic times. No Orphic tale of <strong>the</strong> murder of <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

need be supposed, since <strong>the</strong> Titans are depicted as violent and opposed to rightful<br />

rule even in Hesiod: this second element of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, <strong>the</strong> chastisement<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Titans, is indeed often included in a story as <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> war of <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans against Zeus and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r gods, an event completely unconnected with <strong>the</strong><br />

tale of <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos. The stories of <strong>the</strong> Titanomachy, moreover, are<br />

well enough known to be referred to without fur<strong>the</strong>r explanation, in contrast to <strong>the</strong><br />

supposedly secret dogma of <strong>the</strong> murder of <strong>Zagreus</strong>. As Linforth has argued, <strong>the</strong>n,<br />

Plato is making a comparison between <strong>the</strong> subversive behavior of certain people<br />

in society and <strong>the</strong> subversive behavior of <strong>the</strong> Titans in <strong>the</strong>ir war against <strong>the</strong> rightful<br />

authority of <strong>the</strong> gods. He is not attributing this behavior to a Titanic element in<br />

<strong>the</strong> subversives. The Titanic nature mentioned in Plato, <strong>the</strong>refore, provides no<br />

evidence for a secret Orphic doctrine of original sin stemming from <strong>the</strong> Titans’<br />

murder of Dionysos.<br />

By contrast, when Plutarch, some five hundred years later, mentions <strong>the</strong><br />

irrational, disorderly, and violent nature in humankind, he clearly is referring<br />

to a tale of <strong>the</strong> Titans’ murder of Dionysos, although he does not include an<br />

anthropogony:<br />

kaÈ âggÌj toÜ tèlouj oÞsin nìmwn zhteØn m˜ Íphkìoij eÚnai, präj aÎtÀú dà ¢dh tÀú tèlei<br />

írkwn kaÈ pÐstewn kaÈ tä parˆpan qeÀn m˜ frontÐzein, t˜n legomènhn palai€n Titanik˜n<br />

fÔsin âpideiknÜsi kaÈ mimoumènoij, âpÈ t€ aÎt€ pˆlin âkeØna ‚fikomènouj, xalepän aÊÀna<br />

diˆgontaj m˜ l¨caÐ pote kakÀn (Plato Laws iii, 701bc = OF 9).<br />

25. Nilsson 1935:203.<br />

26. Linforth 1941:342–44. Alderink agrees that <strong>the</strong> passage sets out a comparison ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

an identification, but still thinks that <strong>the</strong> reference to <strong>the</strong> Titans implies <strong>the</strong> dismemberment story<br />

(Alderink 1981:70–71). Alderink follows Bianchi’s distinction between péché antécédent and péché<br />

originel in that <strong>the</strong> crime of <strong>the</strong> Titans is not a crime by humans for which all mankind bears <strong>the</strong> guilt,<br />

but ra<strong>the</strong>r a crime by mythic creatures that serves as a model or pattern for all <strong>the</strong> crimes of humanity<br />

(Bianchi 1966:119–26). Alderink and Bianchi, however, still see <strong>the</strong> Titans’ péché antécédent as <strong>the</strong><br />

reason for <strong>the</strong> later crimes of humanity ra<strong>the</strong>r than a parallel or analogous case, and <strong>the</strong>y assume too<br />

readily that it is <strong>the</strong> dismemberment and not <strong>the</strong> Titans’ many o<strong>the</strong>r crimes that are alluded to in<br />

Plato.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 45<br />

It would perhaps not be wrong to begin and quote lines of Empedokles as<br />

a preface. . . . For here he says allegorically that souls, paying <strong>the</strong> penalty<br />

for murders and <strong>the</strong> eating of flesh and cannibalism, are imprisoned in<br />

mortal bodies. However, it seems that this account is even older, for<br />

<strong>the</strong> legendary suffering of dismemberment told about Dionysos and <strong>the</strong><br />

outrages of <strong>the</strong> Titans on him, and <strong>the</strong>ir punishment and <strong>the</strong>ir being<br />

blasted with lightning after having tasted of <strong>the</strong> blood, this is all a myth,<br />

in its hidden inner meaning, about reincarnation. For that in us which<br />

is irrational and disorderly and violent and not divine but demonic, <strong>the</strong><br />

ancients used <strong>the</strong> name, “Titans,” and <strong>the</strong> myth is about being punished<br />

and paying <strong>the</strong> penalty. 27<br />

Plutarch knows <strong>the</strong> story much as it appears in Olympiodorus, with <strong>the</strong> Titans first<br />

tearing Dionysos apart and tasting his flesh, <strong>the</strong>n being blasted by <strong>the</strong> lightning bolt<br />

of Zeus, but one cannot simply presume fur<strong>the</strong>r that Plutarch’s story implies <strong>the</strong><br />

conclusion of Olympiodorus, <strong>the</strong> anthropogony from <strong>the</strong> ashes of <strong>the</strong> Titans, much<br />

less an inherited stain upon mankind. Certainly, he does state that <strong>the</strong> myth has to<br />

do with reincarnation (eÊj t˜n paliggenesÐan) and that it is about punishment<br />

and paying of penalties (toÜt' êsti kolazomènou kaÈ dÐkhn didìntoj), but of<br />

a resulting anthropogony <strong>the</strong>re is no mention.<br />

Plutarch, in fact, avoids making <strong>the</strong> connection made by modern interpreters,<br />

namely, that <strong>the</strong> Titans were imprisoned in human form as a result of eating <strong>the</strong><br />

flesh of Dionysos, in <strong>the</strong> same way that daimons, in Empedokles, take on mortal<br />

incarnation as punishment for <strong>the</strong> crime of murder and cannibalism. 28 Plutarch<br />

instead reads <strong>the</strong> chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans as a mythic allegory of <strong>the</strong> punishment<br />

of incarnation for <strong>the</strong> crime of meat-eating, ra<strong>the</strong>r than, as modern scholars have<br />

assumed, as <strong>the</strong> outstanding example of how eating flesh was <strong>the</strong> crime that<br />

led to <strong>the</strong> incarnation of humans in <strong>the</strong> first place. Plutarch’s telling links <strong>the</strong><br />

murder of Dionysos with <strong>the</strong> chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans, but it does not include<br />

<strong>the</strong> element of anthropogony which could <strong>the</strong>n be used to create a causal link<br />

between <strong>the</strong> Titans’ murder and <strong>the</strong> punishment of mankind. Such a causal link<br />

27. oÎ xeØron d' Òswj kaÈ proanakroÔsasqai kaÈ proanafwn¨sai t€ toÜ ÇEmpedoklèouj;<br />

[...] ‚llhgoreØ g€r ântaÜqa t€j yuxˆj, íti fìnwn kaÈ br¸sewj sarkÀn kaÈ<br />

‚llhlofagÐaj dÐkhn tÐnousai s¸masi qnhtoØj ândèdentai. kaÐtoi dokeØ palaiìteroj oÝtoj<br />

å lìgoj eÚnai; t€ g€r d˜ perÈ tän Diìnuson memuqeumèna pˆqh toÜ diamelismoÜ kaÈ t€<br />

Titˆnwn âp' aÎtän tolm mata, kolˆseij te toÔtwn kaÈ keraun¸seij geusamènwn toÜ<br />

fìnou, šùnigmènoj âstÈ mÜqoj eÊj t˜n paliggenesÐan; tä g€r ân mØn Šlogon kaÈ Štakton<br />

kaÈ bÐaion oÎ qeØon ‚ll€ daimonikän oÉ palaioÈ Tit naj ²nìmasan, kaÈ toÜt' êsti kolazomènou<br />

kaÈ dÐkhn didìntoj (Plutarch De Esu Carn. 1.996b-c = OF 210). The ellipsis indicates<br />

<strong>the</strong> place where a quote from Empedokles is presumed to have been but is not present in <strong>the</strong> text.<br />

28. Linforth points out: “Ei<strong>the</strong>r he was unacquainted with <strong>the</strong> version of <strong>the</strong> myth which we first<br />

find unmistakably in Olympiodorus, and according to which <strong>the</strong> birth of men from <strong>the</strong> Titans was<br />

brought into immediate connection with <strong>the</strong> outrage on Dionysus, or for some cause he suppressed<br />

it” (Linforth 1941:337). Linforth, however, fails to separate <strong>the</strong> idea of <strong>the</strong> Titans’ punishment by<br />

lightning and/or imprisonment in Tartaros as an analogy for <strong>the</strong> punishment of humans from <strong>the</strong><br />

idea that <strong>the</strong> Titans’ punishment is actually imprisonment in humans who suffer punishment.


46<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

would transform <strong>the</strong> allegory into an aition, <strong>the</strong> myth with a hidden enigmatic<br />

meaning into a literal tale of cause and effect. The ancients do use <strong>the</strong> Titans as a<br />

symbol of <strong>the</strong> evil impulses in humans; <strong>the</strong>y do not, however, say that <strong>the</strong> evil and<br />

irrational in man is <strong>the</strong> Titan in man. Plutarch’s phrasing is ambiguous, but he is<br />

producing an allegorical interpretation of <strong>the</strong> ancient myth, explaining <strong>the</strong> inner,<br />

moral meaning (i.e., <strong>the</strong> Empedoklean doctrine of reincarnation) that <strong>the</strong> story<br />

reveals enigmatically (šùnigmènoj) ra<strong>the</strong>r than citing <strong>the</strong> myth as an aition, <strong>the</strong><br />

cause of human reincarnation and punishment.<br />

Plutarch’s allegorical interpretation of <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong> Titans’ murder of<br />

Dionysos may have come from Xenokrates, a pupil of Plato who also wrote a<br />

treatise against <strong>the</strong> eating of flesh. A cryptic reference preserved in Damascius’<br />

commentary on <strong>the</strong> Phaedo, which dates to <strong>the</strong> beginning of <strong>the</strong> sixth century CE,<br />

provides this fifth piece of evidence for <strong>the</strong> construction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth. 29<br />

“We are in some kind of custody (froÔra): Using <strong>the</strong>se principles, we shall easily<br />

prove that ‘<strong>the</strong> custody’ is not <strong>the</strong> Good, as some say, nor pleasure, as Noumenios<br />

would have it, nor <strong>the</strong> Demiurge, as Paterios says, but ra<strong>the</strong>r, as Xenokrates has<br />

it, that it is Titanic and culminates in Dionysos.” 30 Xenokrates apparently made<br />

some connection between <strong>the</strong> froÔra of Plato and <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong> Titans and<br />

Dionysos. Damascius’ summary of Xenokrates’ idea gives no clue as to what <strong>the</strong><br />

connection might have been, but it seems likely that Xenokrates, like Plutarch,<br />

was explaining <strong>the</strong> myth as an allegory of <strong>the</strong> punishment of a human soul that<br />

eats meat. Linforth comments, “In any case, <strong>the</strong> idea that men were born from<br />

Titans is clearly avoided by Plutarch; and that it was also avoided by Xenocrates<br />

is made <strong>the</strong> more likely by <strong>the</strong> fact that according to his view (fr. 59 Heinze),<br />

as we learn from Censorinus, <strong>the</strong> human race had existed forever.” 31 Not only<br />

Plutarch, <strong>the</strong>n, but also Xenokrates knew a myth of <strong>the</strong> Titans’ dismembering and<br />

eating of Dionysos. Since <strong>the</strong>y do not connect <strong>the</strong> anthropogony story, such as<br />

it is found in Olympiodorus, with <strong>the</strong> myth <strong>the</strong>y know of <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos<br />

and <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, it seems most probable that <strong>the</strong>y used <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans as a mythic analogy for <strong>the</strong> fate of <strong>the</strong> human soul that consumed meat,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than identifying <strong>the</strong> Titans’ consumption of Dionysos as <strong>the</strong> cause of all<br />

human incarnation. Plutarch and Xenokrates do not include <strong>the</strong> anthropogony<br />

story because that mythic element does not fit with <strong>the</strong> points <strong>the</strong>y are making<br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir telling of <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos.<br />

29. This commentary has also been attributed to Olympiodorus, e.g. by Norvin, but Westerink<br />

argues for <strong>the</strong> attribution to Damascius (Westerink 1977, vol. 2:15–17).<br />

30. ên tini frour ø âsmen (62b): ‡Oti toÔtoij xr¸menoi toØj kanìsi ûaødÐwj dielègcomen,<br />

±j oÖte t‚gaqìn âstin frourˆ, ¹j tinej, oÖte don , ±j Noum nioj, oÖte å<br />

dhmiourgìj, ±j Patèrioj, ‚ll', ±j Cenokrˆthj, Titanik âstin kaÈ eÊj Diìnuson ‚pokorufoÜtai<br />

(Xenokrates fr. 20 = Damascius In Phaed. 1.2).<br />

31. Linforth 1941:339. Brisson 1992:497 concurs: “ Or, la version de la théogonie orphique,<br />

connue par Xénocrate et par Platon, ne se terminait pas sur une anthropogonie, comme semble le<br />

laisser supposer l’analyse du passage de Plutarque qui y fait allusion.”


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 47<br />

Of <strong>the</strong> fragments that are cited as evidence, <strong>the</strong>n, for <strong>the</strong> existence before<br />

Olympiodorus of a tale with all <strong>the</strong> elements of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth—<strong>the</strong> anthropogony<br />

from <strong>the</strong> ashes of <strong>the</strong> Titans punished for <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos<br />

and <strong>the</strong> subsequent Titanic nature in man stained with original sin—not one indicates<br />

that <strong>the</strong> anthropogony was known or that <strong>the</strong> crime of <strong>the</strong> Titans was regarded<br />

as more than an allegory for <strong>the</strong> crimes of mankind, a symbol used by <strong>the</strong> ancients<br />

to convey wise prohibitions and warnings. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, Xenokrates would<br />

have rejected such an anthropogony, while Plutarch, if he had even known of it,<br />

would surely have cited it in his argument. Plutarch knows <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> Titans’<br />

murder of Dionysos and, most likely, Xenokrates does too, but <strong>the</strong> passage from<br />

Plato may not even refer to it. The passage from Pausanias tells us that someone<br />

made <strong>the</strong> Titans <strong>the</strong> murderers in <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> death of Dionysos, linking <strong>the</strong><br />

elements of <strong>the</strong> sparagmos of Dionysos with <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, but<br />

even if this innovation occurred before Xenokrates, <strong>the</strong>re is nothing to indicate<br />

that <strong>the</strong> anthropogony was added at <strong>the</strong> same time, much less that <strong>the</strong> whole tale<br />

was <strong>the</strong> crucial story for <strong>the</strong> Orphics.<br />

Dismemberment Punishment Anthropogony Original Sin<br />

of Dionysos of <strong>the</strong> Titans for Humans<br />

Olympiodorus yes yes yes no<br />

- sixth CE<br />

= OF 220<br />

Pausanias 8.37.5 probably probably no no<br />

- 2nd CE<br />

= OT 194<br />

Plato Laws 701c no yes no no<br />

- 4th BCE<br />

=OF9<br />

Plutarch<br />

yes yes no no<br />

- 2nd CE<br />

= OF 210<br />

Xenokrates fr. 20<br />

- 4th/3rd BCE<br />

probably probably no no<br />

These five pieces of evidence form <strong>the</strong> basis, in <strong>the</strong> scholarship from Comparetti<br />

to West, for <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, with its doctrine of<br />

original sin, stands at <strong>the</strong> center of Orphism from <strong>the</strong> sixth century BCE. One<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r important piece of evidence was added to Comparetti’s original argument: a<br />

fragment, presumably from Pindar, quoted in Plato’s Meno. H. J. Rose introduced<br />

this fragment into <strong>the</strong> debate to prove <strong>the</strong> existence of an Orphic doctrine of<br />

original sin from <strong>the</strong> late Archaic age. 32<br />

32. Rose 1936.


48<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

“Those from whom Persephone receives <strong>the</strong> penalty of ancient grief, in <strong>the</strong><br />

ninth year she sends back <strong>the</strong>ir souls to <strong>the</strong> sun above, and from <strong>the</strong>m grow glorious<br />

kings and men swift with strength and great in wisdom; at <strong>the</strong> last <strong>the</strong>y are called<br />

sacred heroes among men.” 33 Despite all of his doubts about <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth,<br />

even <strong>the</strong> skeptical Linforth accepts (wrongly, as I shall show) <strong>the</strong> explanation of<br />

Rose that this line can only refer to Persephone accepting a recompense from<br />

humans for <strong>the</strong> murder of her son Dionysos by <strong>the</strong> Titans, ancestors of mankind.<br />

He does note, however, “It is a curious thing that nowhere else, early or late, is<br />

it said or even expressly implied that guilt descended to men in consequence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> outrage committed upon Dionysos. Even Olympiodorus does not say so.” 34<br />

Rose argues that poin in Pindar has <strong>the</strong> primary sense of recompense for<br />

blood guilt and, more importantly, that <strong>the</strong> only ancient grief (palaioÜ pènqeoj)<br />

for which Persephone could accept recompense is <strong>the</strong> murder of her son. 35 Indeed,<br />

if <strong>the</strong> grief must be Persephone’s, it might be hard to find an alternate explanation,<br />

but, as Linforth himself suggests, <strong>the</strong> grief may not be Persephone’s at all, but<br />

may refer to <strong>the</strong> souls passing through a series of incarnations. He adds, “Ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

possibility is that <strong>the</strong> pènqoj itself is <strong>the</strong> poin (<strong>the</strong> genitive being appositional), so<br />

that Persephone is said to accept as atonement <strong>the</strong> misery of previous existences.” 36<br />

The syntax may be awkward, but not much more so than in Rose’s reading, and <strong>the</strong><br />

idea of an individual paying a penalty for <strong>the</strong> various crimes committed by <strong>the</strong> self<br />

or an ancestor in a previous existence has parallels throughout Greek literature<br />

from Homer on. 37<br />

More importantly, Rose’s whole argument, as he himself admits, depends<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> idea that mankind has inherited a dual nature from <strong>the</strong> crime of <strong>the</strong> Titans,<br />

an idea that stems from <strong>the</strong> sixth-century CE alchemical allegory of Olympiodorus:<br />

For if men are not <strong>the</strong> descendants of <strong>the</strong> Titans (again it is of little moment<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y were actually called by this name so early), what share have<br />

<strong>the</strong>y in <strong>the</strong> guilt which grieves Persephone and causes her to accept an<br />

atonement at <strong>the</strong>ir hands? Again, if <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors did not devour <strong>the</strong><br />

divine infant, what claim have <strong>the</strong>y, <strong>the</strong>ir satisfaction once made, to such<br />

33. oÙsi g€r “n Fersefìna poin€n palaioÜ pènqeoj dècetai, eÊj tän Õperqen ‰lion<br />

keÐnwn ânˆtwú êtei ‚ndidoØ yux€j pˆlin, âk t n basil¨ej ‚gauoÈ kaÈ sqènei kraipnoÈ<br />

sofÐaø te mègistoi Šndrej aÖcont'; âj dà tän loipän xrìnon ¡rwej gnoÈ präj ‚nqr¸pwn<br />

kalèontai (Pindar fr. 133 from Plato Meno 81bc, not in Kern).<br />

34. Linforth 1941:350. West, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, sees o<strong>the</strong>r possible explanations of <strong>the</strong> fragment<br />

(West 1983:110n. 82). However, despite his acceptance of Linforth’s arguments against all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

evidence used to support an early date for <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> story, he never<strong>the</strong>less includes <strong>the</strong> story, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> basis of its similarity to <strong>the</strong> tale of <strong>the</strong> infancy of Zeus in Crete, in <strong>the</strong> Eudemian <strong>the</strong>ogony, which<br />

he dates to fourth-century A<strong>the</strong>ns.<br />

35. “The one thing which I personally find puzzling about <strong>the</strong> whole phrase is that any one<br />

acquainted with Greek mythology should ever have interpreted it in any o<strong>the</strong>r way” (Rose 1936:86).<br />

36. Linforth 1941:347. Seaford 1986 concurs with this reading and also suggests that <strong>the</strong><br />

Titanomachy is a more likely crime if <strong>the</strong> Titans are considered <strong>the</strong> forebears in question.<br />

37. This element of humans paying <strong>the</strong> penalty for <strong>the</strong> crimes of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors is discussed<br />

below in <strong>the</strong> next section.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 49<br />

especial grace as she shows <strong>the</strong>m? Mere Titan-men might well be content<br />

if <strong>the</strong>y escape Tartaros, with such an inheritance of guilt; <strong>the</strong>se pardoned<br />

sinners are raised to <strong>the</strong> highest rank on earth and afterwards heroized. 38<br />

But even if <strong>the</strong> Titans were thought to be <strong>the</strong> ancestors of mankind, no ancient<br />

author ever suggests that mankind does have a share in <strong>the</strong> guilt for <strong>the</strong>ir murder of<br />

Dionysos, and not even Olympiodorus suggests that <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac pieces absorbed<br />

into <strong>the</strong> sublimate out of which mankind was formed somehow make Persephone<br />

benevolently disposed to mankind. Rose’s argument, plausible if <strong>the</strong> dual nature<br />

of mankind is assumed to be a well-known central doctrine of Orphism, collapses<br />

when <strong>the</strong> evidence is examined carefully. By Rose’s own argument, <strong>the</strong> penalty of<br />

ancient grief makes no sense as <strong>the</strong> recompense paid to Persephone for <strong>the</strong> Titanic<br />

murder of her son Dionysos.<br />

None of <strong>the</strong> evidence, <strong>the</strong>n, that is cited in support of <strong>the</strong> central presence<br />

from earliest times in Orphism of a myth, linking <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos<br />

<strong>Zagreus</strong> and <strong>the</strong> chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans with <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and <strong>the</strong> burden<br />

of Titanic guilt, can withstand serious scrutiny. In <strong>the</strong> next section, I argue that<br />

this evidence points instead to a number of stories about <strong>the</strong> dismemberment, <strong>the</strong><br />

punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, and <strong>the</strong> creation of humans, woven toge<strong>the</strong>r in a variety<br />

of ways that reveal <strong>the</strong> concerns of <strong>the</strong> tellers at different times.<br />

GATHERING THE PIECES OF THE ZAGREUS MYTH<br />

This modern myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, <strong>the</strong>n, has been dismembered, and its pieces<br />

lie strewn about, apparently unconnected with one ano<strong>the</strong>r. The task that now<br />

remains is to ga<strong>the</strong>r anew <strong>the</strong> scattered fragments of <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, to<br />

find places for <strong>the</strong> disparate pieces of evidence for <strong>the</strong> story. The myth of <strong>the</strong><br />

sparagmos of Dionysos, I would argue, was not a single tale containing a timeless<br />

doctrine, but grew and changed over time, being told and retold in different ways<br />

according to <strong>the</strong> interests of <strong>the</strong> teller, who combined this motif with o<strong>the</strong>rs to suit<br />

<strong>the</strong> occasion. 39 This story will naturally remain for us a collection of fragments,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than a neatly unified whole, because of <strong>the</strong> enormous gaps in our evidence<br />

and <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> evidence that does remain, mostly in <strong>the</strong> form of references<br />

and citations by <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists. 40 Never<strong>the</strong>less, this collection of fragments<br />

38. Rose 1936:88. In Rose’s response to Linforth (Rose 1943), he can do no more than reiterate<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that he can think of no o<strong>the</strong>r way to interpret <strong>the</strong> passage.<br />

39. As J. Z. Smith puts it: “The work of comparison, within and without <strong>the</strong> area of Late<br />

Antiquity, requires acceptance of <strong>the</strong> notion that, regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r we are studying myths from<br />

literate or non-literate cultures, we are dealing with historical processes of reinterpretation, with<br />

tradition. That, for a given group at a given time to choose this or that mode of interpreting <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

tradition is to opt for a particular way of relating <strong>the</strong>mselves to <strong>the</strong>ir historical past and social present”<br />

(Smith 1990:106–107, original emphases).<br />

40. The basic problem, as Boyance notes, is that <strong>the</strong> evidence comes in fragmentary form in<br />

Neoplatonic commentators. “Les modernes s’y sont souvent mépris et cru voir dans les my<strong>the</strong>s eux-


50<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

presents a more accurate picture of <strong>the</strong> whole than <strong>the</strong> fabricated <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth,<br />

construed as a tale that always signified <strong>the</strong> sinful nature of mankind and <strong>the</strong> hope<br />

of redemption.<br />

Each individual retelling, examined in its context, sheds light on <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

tradition. However, three important strands must be distinguished in <strong>the</strong> various<br />

myths that appear in <strong>the</strong> evidence, for <strong>the</strong> presence of one strand in a piece of<br />

evidence need not imply <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs:<br />

(1) The first strand contains <strong>the</strong> motifs of dismemberment and cannibalism,<br />

specifically <strong>the</strong> sparagmos associated with Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> eating<br />

of an infant.<br />

(2) The second strand is <strong>the</strong> idea of punishment for past wrongdoings,<br />

both for <strong>the</strong> Titans and for mortals.<br />

(3) The third strand that is woven into <strong>the</strong>se stories is <strong>the</strong> generation of<br />

human beings, <strong>the</strong> anthropogony.<br />

The final element of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, <strong>the</strong> original sin that burdens mankind, is,<br />

as we have seen, not actually present in any of <strong>the</strong> tellings of <strong>the</strong> tale before 1879.<br />

Much of this evidence is reviewed by Linforth, but he fails in <strong>the</strong> final analysis<br />

to separate all <strong>the</strong> elements of <strong>the</strong> myth, which leads him to take evidence for parts<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth as evidence for <strong>the</strong> whole. He reluctantly concludes (p. 350)<br />

that <strong>the</strong> weight of <strong>the</strong> evidence suggests that <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth was probably<br />

known as early as Pindar, although he does argue that it was no more important<br />

than o<strong>the</strong>r versions of <strong>the</strong> sparagmos story. West too fails to separate <strong>the</strong> elements<br />

and assumes that <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> Titans in <strong>the</strong> dismemberment story implies<br />

all of <strong>the</strong> elements of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth. 41 All <strong>the</strong>se motifs can be found woven<br />

into various stories throughout <strong>the</strong> Greek mythic tradition, but <strong>the</strong> significance<br />

of <strong>the</strong>se elements and of <strong>the</strong> whole story that contains <strong>the</strong>m is not <strong>the</strong> same in<br />

all <strong>the</strong> various permutations. 42<br />

The earliest tellings of <strong>the</strong> sparagmos of Dionysos are impossible to trace.<br />

Dionysos and his maenads are associated with deaths through dismemberment<br />

in a number of myths. 43 Perhaps <strong>the</strong> motif of dismemberment and subsequent<br />

mêmes des éléments tardifs qui ne sont que les éléments philosophiques introduits arbitrairement par<br />

l’exégèse. C’est un peu comme si nous ne connnaissons l’Antre des Nymphes de l’Odyssée que par<br />

Porphyre” (Boyancé 1963:11).<br />

41. Accordingly, West locates <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth in his Eudemian <strong>the</strong>ogony, which he dates to <strong>the</strong><br />

fourth century BCE, although not in his earliest Protogonos <strong>the</strong>ogony (of which he sees <strong>the</strong> Derveni<br />

<strong>the</strong>ogony as a truncated variant). For serious critiques of West’s reconstruction, see <strong>the</strong> reviews by<br />

Casadio 1986 (esp. p. 311), Brisson 1985, and Finamore 1987. The failure to separate <strong>the</strong> different<br />

elements of <strong>the</strong> myth also troubles <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise fascinating treatment by Scalera McClintock 1995.<br />

42. Only in Olympiodorus are all three strands combined—<strong>the</strong> rending of <strong>the</strong> infant Dionysos,<br />

<strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans for cannibalism, and <strong>the</strong> birth of humans. Even in Olympiodorus,<br />

however, <strong>the</strong> motifs of punishment and anthropogony do not imply any idea of original sin that<br />

burdens all of mankind.<br />

43. The tale of Pen<strong>the</strong>us is <strong>the</strong> most famous, but <strong>the</strong> stories of Orpheus, Lycurgus, and perhaps<br />

Actaeon, also fall into this type.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 51<br />

rebirth were borrowed from <strong>the</strong> Egyptian story of Osiris; 44 perhaps this element<br />

came from ancient shamanic ritual practices. West, following <strong>the</strong> shamanic model<br />

proposed by Jeanmaire and Dodds, argues that <strong>the</strong> motif of sparagmos and rebirth<br />

is a feature of shamanic initiation in cultures throughout <strong>the</strong> world and that its<br />

presence, both in <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth and in o<strong>the</strong>r Greek myths (e.g., <strong>the</strong> cauldron of<br />

Medea or <strong>the</strong> experience of Pelops), indicates a survival of shamanic initiation<br />

ritual in Greek culture. 45 The notion of survivals is, in itself, not unproblematic,<br />

nor does <strong>the</strong> origin of a myth explain its function, but <strong>the</strong> shamanic model does<br />

give an account for <strong>the</strong> presence of this kind of motif and suggest a scenario for its<br />

function. As West demonstrates, various references in Plato and o<strong>the</strong>r authors of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Classical period to Korybantic initiation rituals, as well as <strong>the</strong> descriptions<br />

from <strong>the</strong> Hellenistic era and even later, all seem to indicate that this kind of<br />

initiation, with its ritual experience of being torn apart and reborn, did not belong<br />

solely to <strong>the</strong> depths of <strong>the</strong> primitive past but had meaning for people living in<br />

<strong>the</strong> historical periods from which <strong>the</strong> evidence comes.<br />

This initiatory scenario, however, is not <strong>the</strong> only (or even <strong>the</strong> most frequent)<br />

context in which <strong>the</strong> myth appears. In <strong>the</strong> first fully extant telling of <strong>the</strong> myth of<br />

<strong>the</strong> sparagmos and rebirth of Dionysos, Diodorus in fact explains it as an allegory<br />

of <strong>the</strong> process of winemaking. Dionysos, who represents <strong>the</strong> grape and <strong>the</strong> vine,<br />

is torn to pieces by <strong>the</strong> workers of <strong>the</strong> earth (gewrgoÐ, who are assimilated to<br />

ghgeneØj, <strong>the</strong> earthborn giants who, in turn, are sometimes assimilated to <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans). 46 However, <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment was retold many times in<br />

different ways by ancient sources who saw <strong>the</strong> myth as something o<strong>the</strong>r than an<br />

allegory of nature. Later thinkers may have used it as an allegory for diakosmesis,<br />

<strong>the</strong> physical process by which <strong>the</strong> original unitary substance of <strong>the</strong> universe was<br />

dispersed. Plutarch tells how Dionysos is <strong>the</strong> name <strong>the</strong> wise use to describe <strong>the</strong><br />

transformation of <strong>the</strong> cosmos from <strong>the</strong> single fire to <strong>the</strong> diverse states of being:<br />

The wiser folk, concealing it from <strong>the</strong> masses, call <strong>the</strong> transformation<br />

into fire by <strong>the</strong> name of Apollo because of <strong>the</strong> oneness of that state, or<br />

by <strong>the</strong> name of Phoebus because of its purity and lack of defilement.<br />

As to <strong>the</strong> manner of his birth and diakosmesis into winds, water, earth,<br />

stars, plants, and animals, <strong>the</strong>y describe this experience and transforma-<br />

44. Herodotus mentions <strong>the</strong> identification of Osiris and Dionysos. (2.42, 47, 123, 144, 156)<br />

The connection with Egypt has been much debated, but, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> dismemberment myth was <strong>the</strong><br />

early cause of <strong>the</strong> identification or <strong>the</strong> late Hellenistic result, <strong>the</strong> connection could not have occurred<br />

had <strong>the</strong> myth not found a significance within <strong>the</strong> Greek religious tradition. Cf. Plutarch De Iside<br />

et Osiride 35.364f-365a.<br />

45. West 1983:143–63. Cf. Dodds, “The Greek Shamans and <strong>the</strong> Origins of Puritanism,” in<br />

Dodds 1951:135–78; Jeanmaire 1939:147–223.<br />

46. Diodorus Siculus 3.62–65 = OF 301. Cornutus seems also to have explained <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

story as an allegory of <strong>the</strong> winemaking process (Cornutus fr. 30). Cf. <strong>the</strong> references to Oinos<br />

in Proclus In Cratyl. p. 108 = OF 216. West cannot work this testimony into his reconstruction,<br />

so he dismisses it as an innovation of <strong>the</strong> compiler of <strong>the</strong> Rhapsodies and <strong>the</strong>n omits it from his<br />

summary of <strong>the</strong> Rhapsodies (West 1983:142, 245–46).


52<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

tion allegorically as “rending” and “dismemberment.” They name him<br />

Dionysus, <strong>Zagreus</strong>, Nyctelius, Isodaites, and <strong>the</strong>y construct allegories<br />

and myths proper to <strong>the</strong> stories of death and destruction followed by life<br />

and rebirth. 47<br />

The Neoplatonists, for <strong>the</strong>ir part, cite <strong>the</strong> myth frequently as a tale about <strong>the</strong><br />

One and <strong>the</strong> Many, <strong>the</strong> diffusion of divine power throughout <strong>the</strong> entire material<br />

universe. Linforth summarizes some of <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonic readings of <strong>the</strong> story.<br />

“Dionysus, who, though he is torn to pieces, is reborn whole and sound, is <strong>the</strong><br />

Soul of <strong>the</strong> universe, which is divided and yet retains its indestructible unity. The<br />

Titans represent <strong>the</strong> evil principle of division.” 48 Even though <strong>the</strong> earliest variants<br />

of <strong>the</strong> tale date centuries earlier, most of <strong>the</strong> references to <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of<br />

Dionysos in fact come from <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists or <strong>the</strong>ir contemporaries, indicating<br />

perhaps that <strong>the</strong> myth became particularly meaningful in this period.<br />

Often entwined with <strong>the</strong> motif of sparagmos is <strong>the</strong> idea of cannibalism,<br />

specifically <strong>the</strong> eating of children. Not only is this a favorite motif in <strong>the</strong> tragic<br />

retellings of myths, but <strong>the</strong> threat to <strong>the</strong> infant god by Titans can be found as early<br />

as <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> infant Zeus and his child-devouring fa<strong>the</strong>r, Kronos, recounted<br />

in Hesiod. 49<br />

When <strong>the</strong> eating of <strong>the</strong> child becomes linked with <strong>the</strong> dismemberment, <strong>the</strong><br />

sparagmos is transformed from a dissolution preceding a rebirth to a brutal and<br />

savage murder. Detienne’s analysis of <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment in Dionysos<br />

Slain highlights this important development in <strong>the</strong> myth. Detienne also points to<br />

<strong>the</strong> language of sacrificial practice in various versions of <strong>the</strong> myth, in particular <strong>the</strong><br />

description of <strong>the</strong> peculiar cooking process mentioned in <strong>the</strong> pseudo-Aristotelian<br />

“Problem.” 50 The Titans pervert <strong>the</strong> normal sacrificial practice by first boiling<br />

<strong>the</strong>n roasting <strong>the</strong>ir victim, who has been cut up with a sacrificial knife, not torn<br />

apart with bare hands. Detienne sees this story as an Orphic protest against <strong>the</strong><br />

sacrifice and <strong>the</strong> eating of meat that play an important role of <strong>the</strong> religion of <strong>the</strong><br />

polis:<br />

47. kruptìmenoi dà toÌj polloÌj oÉ sof¸teroi t˜n màn eÊj pÜr metabol˜n ÇApìllwnˆ<br />

te t¨ù mon¸sei FoØbìn te tÀú kaqarÀú kaÈ ‚miˆntwú kaloÜsi. t¨j d' eÊj pneÔmata kaÈ Õdwr<br />

kaÈ g¨n kaÈ Šstra kaÈ futÀn z¸úwn te genèseij trop¨j aÎtoÜ kaÈ diakosm sewj tä<br />

màn pˆqhma kaÈ t˜n metabol˜n diaspasmìn tina kaÈ diamelismän aÊnÐttontai; Diìnuson<br />

dà kaÈ Zagrèa kaÈ Nuktèlion kaÈ ÇIsodaÐthn aÎtän ænomˆzousi, kaÈ fqorˆj tinaj kaÈ<br />

‚fanismoÌj eÚta d' ‚nabi¸seij kaÈ paliggenesÐaj, oÊkeØa taØj eÊrhmènaij metabolaØj<br />

aÊnÐgmata kaÈ muqeÔmata peraÐnousi (Plutarch De Ei 9.388e).<br />

48. Linforth 1941:320. Cf. e.g., OF 210, 211.<br />

49. West 1983 and Guthrie 1952 both provide imaginative reconstructions of <strong>the</strong> process by<br />

which this story became attached to <strong>the</strong> infant Dionysos and <strong>the</strong>n linked to <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

myth. Guthrie still subscribes to <strong>the</strong> idea of <strong>the</strong> Thracian invasion of Dionysos, and West is<br />

perhaps a bit uncritical in his attribution of certain elements of <strong>the</strong> story to Crete or to Delphi,<br />

but both reconstructions on <strong>the</strong> whole remain fairly plausible. West fails to argue, however, how<br />

<strong>the</strong> anthropogony was attached to <strong>the</strong>se stories.<br />

50. Ps.-Aristotle Problemata 3.43 (Bussemaker). Cf. Iamblichus Vita Pythag. 154; Ath. 656b.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 53<br />

To abstain from eating meat in <strong>the</strong> Greek city-state is a highly subversive<br />

act. Such is <strong>the</strong> cultural and religious backdrop of <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> death of<br />

Dionysos told by <strong>the</strong> disciples of Orpheus. This is a myth about <strong>the</strong> blood<br />

sacrifice, and it stands at <strong>the</strong> center of a system of thought that rejects this<br />

kind of sacrifice and establishes itself in open opposition to <strong>the</strong> official<br />

tradition. 51<br />

By linking <strong>the</strong> sparagmos and cannibalism, <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of<br />

Dionysos becomes an expression of a protest against <strong>the</strong> mainstream religious<br />

tradition, wherein <strong>the</strong> sacrificial ritual which comprises one of <strong>the</strong> fundamental<br />

acts of <strong>the</strong> mainstream religious tradition is depicted as a brutal act of savage<br />

cannibalism. Certainly this reading of <strong>the</strong> myth fits in with <strong>the</strong> doctrines of<br />

Empedokles, and it seems likely that, when Xenokrates and Plutarch related <strong>the</strong><br />

myth in <strong>the</strong>ir condemnations of meat-eating, <strong>the</strong>y had this meaning in mind.<br />

That <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos was interpreted by some as<br />

a condemnation of <strong>the</strong> meat-eating order of <strong>the</strong> polis religion, however, by no<br />

means guarantees that it always had this significance for those relating <strong>the</strong> myth;<br />

this strand was woven into many different kinds of tales. 52<br />

The second strand in <strong>the</strong> tradition is <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, a tale<br />

that goes back to Hesiod and reappears in most of <strong>the</strong> stories about <strong>the</strong> Titans.<br />

Most often <strong>the</strong> Titans are being punished for <strong>the</strong>ir war against Zeus and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

gods, but some stories attribute <strong>the</strong> punishment to <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos. The<br />

chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans may be described as imprisonment in Tartaros, as<br />

in Homer and Hesiod, or in terms of <strong>the</strong> lightning strikes of <strong>the</strong> angry Zeus,<br />

or, in some cases, a combination of <strong>the</strong> lightning bolts and imprisonment, as in<br />

Aeschylus’ Prome<strong>the</strong>us Bound, which ends with Prome<strong>the</strong>us blasted down into<br />

<strong>the</strong> bowels of <strong>the</strong> earth by Zeus’ bolts. 53 In Plutarch (and probably in Xenokrates),<br />

this chastisement of <strong>the</strong> Titans serves as an analogy to <strong>the</strong> punishments that<br />

humans receive for <strong>the</strong> crimes of <strong>the</strong>ir previous existences, a mythic description<br />

of <strong>the</strong> familiar Greek idea of <strong>the</strong> delays of divine vengeance.<br />

51. Detienne 1979:72.<br />

52. Detienne, in his efforts to prove that <strong>the</strong> myth had this meaning, neglects <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

that <strong>the</strong> myth may originally have described <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos as a sparagmos followed by<br />

omophagia and later been revised for <strong>the</strong> purpose of <strong>the</strong> argument against <strong>the</strong> eating of meat. He<br />

dismisses <strong>the</strong> versions that seem to indicate a sparagmos as misleadingly vague or simply mistaken<br />

in <strong>the</strong> details, accepting as accurate only those which indicate a sacrificial ritual. Detienne brilliantly<br />

teases out <strong>the</strong> system of oppositions involving raw and cooked, savage and civilized, primitive and<br />

advanced, but he fails to allow <strong>the</strong> possibility that <strong>the</strong> same tale could have been told with <strong>the</strong> focus<br />

on o<strong>the</strong>r oppositions, such as, e.g., <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists’ Many and One. His insistence that <strong>the</strong> story<br />

must always have been told in fundamentally <strong>the</strong> same way causes him to neglect <strong>the</strong> problems with<br />

<strong>the</strong> chronology of <strong>the</strong> evidence and assume that <strong>the</strong> Titans and <strong>the</strong> anthropogony must always have<br />

been a part of <strong>the</strong> myth. Never<strong>the</strong>less, Detienne’s analysis provides an insight into one of <strong>the</strong> levels<br />

of reinterpretation of <strong>the</strong> myth and explains why many of <strong>the</strong> details found in some versions—<strong>the</strong><br />

boiling and roasting, perhaps even <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> Titans—were added by <strong>the</strong> teller.<br />

53. Cf. Linforth 1941:328–29, contra Rohde 1925:353n. 28, on <strong>the</strong> combination of <strong>the</strong> two<br />

punishments as consistent.


54<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

The motif of paying <strong>the</strong> penalty for <strong>the</strong> crimes of previous lives, which<br />

appears as early as Empedokles and <strong>the</strong> Pindar fragment (fr. 133), seems to be<br />

a development of <strong>the</strong> idea that descendants may have to pay <strong>the</strong> penalty for <strong>the</strong><br />

crimes of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors, an idea which has a long tradition in Greek mythology.<br />

Solon assures <strong>the</strong> wicked that even if <strong>the</strong>y do not pay for <strong>the</strong>ir crimes in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

lifetime, <strong>the</strong>ir descendants will pay (‚naÐtioi êrga tÐnousin £ paØdej toÔtwn £<br />

gènoj âcopÐsw). While <strong>the</strong> affliction of an entire family line for such crimes as<br />

murder and perjury goes back to Homer and Hesiod, <strong>the</strong> myths of <strong>the</strong> punishment<br />

of an entire family as retribution for <strong>the</strong> murder of a family member, incest, or<br />

cannibalism become a favorite subject in tragedy. 54 Nor is <strong>the</strong> family curse, in<br />

which each member must pay for <strong>the</strong> misdeed of an ancestor, confined to tragedy;<br />

this mythical idea was employed in practical politics as well. The prominent<br />

A<strong>the</strong>nian noble family of <strong>the</strong> Alcmaeonids, which boasted such members as<br />

Cleis<strong>the</strong>nes and Pericles, contended constantly with <strong>the</strong>ir political enemies about<br />

<strong>the</strong> stain that <strong>the</strong> murder of Cylon had left upon <strong>the</strong>ir family. 55<br />

Along with <strong>the</strong> idea of paying for an ancestor’s crimes naturally comes <strong>the</strong><br />

idea of somehow evading <strong>the</strong> penalty. Herodotus’ myth of <strong>the</strong> fall of Croesus is<br />

fascinating in this regard: Croesus is doomed to fall, despite his many sacrifices to<br />

Apollo, because his ancestor Gyges murdered King Candaules and took his throne<br />

and his wife. When Croesus rebukes Apollo for ingratitude, Apollo informs him<br />

that his sacrifices were not ignored, but ra<strong>the</strong>r procured for him a three-year delay<br />

of <strong>the</strong> inevitable downfall. 56 The Orpheotelests described in Plato’s Republic<br />

seem to have promised more complete results from <strong>the</strong> sacrifices <strong>the</strong>y advised,<br />

and, in <strong>the</strong> Phaedrus, Plato mentions Dionysiac purifications as bringing relief to<br />

those suffering under <strong>the</strong> burdens of <strong>the</strong> crimes of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors. 57 Olympiodorus<br />

refers to <strong>the</strong> role of Dionysos Lusios and his rites in freeing an individual from <strong>the</strong><br />

penalty of crimes committed by ancestors. 58 But, contrary to Graf’s assertions<br />

54. Solon fr. 1.31, cf. esp. 25–35. Hereditary punishment of perjury: Il. 4.160–62, cf. 3.300ff.;<br />

Hesiod Op. 282–85. For affliction of whole families: Il. 6.200–205; Od. 20.66–78; cf. Od. 11.436. In<br />

tragedy: Aeschylus Sept. 653–55, 699–701, 720–91; Ag. 1090–97, 1186–97, 1309, 1338–42, 1460,<br />

1468–88, 1497–1512, 1565–76, 1600–1602; Sophocles El. 504–15, Ant. 583–603, OC 367–70,<br />

964–65, 1299; Euripides El. 699–746, 1306ff., IT 186–202, 987ff., Or. 811–18, 985–1012, 1546–48,<br />

Phoen. 379–82, 867–88, 1556–59, 1592–94, 1611. See fur<strong>the</strong>r Parker 1983:191–206.<br />

55. Cf. Hdt. 5.70–72; Thucydides 1.126–27. Noble families were not <strong>the</strong> only ones to feel <strong>the</strong><br />

need of purification for <strong>the</strong>ir own crimes and those of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors. Plato’s Orpheotelests and<br />

<strong>the</strong> practices of Theophrastus’ Superstitious Man indicate that individuals and whole cities tried<br />

to relieve <strong>the</strong>ir anxiety about <strong>the</strong> misdeeds of <strong>the</strong>ir forebears (Plato Rep. 364e-365a; Theophrastus<br />

Char. 16.12).<br />

56. Herodotus 1.90–91.<br />

57. Republic 364e-365a; Phaedrus 254de, 265b.<br />

58. íti å Diìnusoj lÔse¸j âstin aÒtioj; diä kaÈ LuseÌj å qeìj, kaÈ å ÇOrfeÔj<br />

fhsin; Šnqrwpoi dà telhèssaj ákatìmbaj pèmpousin pˆshùsi ân ¹raij ‚mfièthùsin îrgia<br />

t' âktelèsousi, lÔsin progìnwn ‚qemÐstwn maÐomenoi; sÌ dà toØsin êxwn krˆtoj, oÕj k'<br />

âqèlhùsqa, lÔseij êk te pìnwn xalepÀn kaÈ ‚peÐronoj oÒstrou. “That Dionysos is responsible<br />

for release and because of this <strong>the</strong> god is called ‘Deliverer.’ And Orpheus says: ‘People send perfect


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 55<br />

regarding <strong>the</strong> Pelinna tablets, <strong>the</strong> lawless ancestors of <strong>the</strong>se passages need not<br />

be <strong>the</strong> Titans. Graf’s hesitation betrays <strong>the</strong> flaw in his own argument: “But <strong>the</strong>se<br />

ancestors are not just ordinary deceased, since Dionysus has power over <strong>the</strong>m:<br />

<strong>the</strong> only ancestors of humans who are closely connected with Dionysus are <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans, who killed <strong>the</strong> god—though it is somewhat unclear what power Dionysus<br />

has over <strong>the</strong>m.” 59 Dionysos actually appears in quite a number of contexts as <strong>the</strong><br />

deity who suspends <strong>the</strong> normal constraints, who bursts <strong>the</strong> bonds that regulate<br />

<strong>the</strong> order of <strong>the</strong> cosmos, providing relief for those constricted or burdened by <strong>the</strong><br />

normal order. 60 His role in freeing <strong>the</strong> initiate, in this life or <strong>the</strong> next, from <strong>the</strong><br />

penalties due for <strong>the</strong> crimes of ancestors is simply an extension of this essential<br />

aspect to eschatology. 61<br />

The idea of a descendant’s paying for an ancestor’s crimes handles two<br />

difficult problems of <strong>the</strong>odicy: why some evil-doers are not visibly punished<br />

by <strong>the</strong> gods and why some apparently innocent folk suffer. In Empedokles and<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs who accepted a system of metempsychosis, <strong>the</strong> workings of justice are even<br />

neater, in that <strong>the</strong> delayed suffering falls not on some extension of <strong>the</strong> criminal<br />

in <strong>the</strong> form of a descendant, but on <strong>the</strong> individual himself in a later incarnation. In<br />

Empedokles, <strong>the</strong> cycle of reincarnations itself, <strong>the</strong> imprisoning of <strong>the</strong> soul in flesh,<br />

is a penalty for some crime of bloodshed committed as a divine being. For <strong>the</strong><br />

prison of Tartaros or <strong>the</strong> waters of <strong>the</strong> Styx found in Hesiod as <strong>the</strong> punishment for<br />

divine beings who violate <strong>the</strong> order of Zeus, he substitutes <strong>the</strong> prison of <strong>the</strong> body. 62<br />

Centuries later, as we saw above, Plutarch explains Empedokles’ adaptation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> tradition as a case of <strong>the</strong> ancient mythmakers concealing in riddling stories<br />

about <strong>the</strong> Titans <strong>the</strong> doctrine of reincarnation that Empedokles was putting forth<br />

as his own. Plutarch, perhaps following Xenokrates, thus links <strong>the</strong> strands of<br />

(1) sparagmos and (2) punishment, but he does not bring in <strong>the</strong> motif of (3)<br />

anthropogony, a general creation of <strong>the</strong> human race.<br />

hecatombs in all seasons throughout <strong>the</strong> year and perform rites, seeking release from unlawful<br />

ancestors. But you, having power over <strong>the</strong>m, you will release whomever you wish from harsh<br />

suffering and boundless frenzy’ ” (OF 232).<br />

59. Graf 1993:244. Dionysos’ power as Lusios, however, depends not on any special relation to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Titans as <strong>the</strong> criminals (or to <strong>the</strong> humans with a divine tidbit of Dionysos in <strong>the</strong>m), but on his<br />

general function as <strong>the</strong> loosener, a trait illustrated even by <strong>the</strong> effects of wine, <strong>the</strong> most widespread<br />

symbol for <strong>the</strong> god.<br />

60. For <strong>the</strong> role of Dionysos within polis-cult as <strong>the</strong> one who provides <strong>the</strong> necessary temporary<br />

relief from <strong>the</strong> normal order, cf. Sabbatucci 1979:51; cf. also Versnel 1991:139, 166, and Casadio<br />

1987:199ff., on <strong>the</strong> functions of Dionysos Lusios.<br />

61. Cf. <strong>the</strong> Pelinna tablets: “Tell Persephone that Bacchios himself has freed you” (eÊpeØn<br />

Fersefìnai s' íti Bxioj aÎtäj êluse). The tablet from Pherai that proclaims, “<strong>the</strong> initiate<br />

is without penalty” (Špoinoj g€r å mÔsthj), probably contains <strong>the</strong> same idea. The Apulian vase in<br />

Toledo that depicts Dionysos greeting Pluto in <strong>the</strong> underworld seems to symbolize Dionysos’ power<br />

to save his worshippers in <strong>the</strong> realm of <strong>the</strong> dead. (See Johnston and McNiven 1996.)<br />

62. Empedokles B115 DK; cf. Seaford 1986, who traces <strong>the</strong> motifs of <strong>the</strong> imprisonment of a<br />

divine being from Hesiod through Empedokles, Herakleitos, and Aeschylus (although he assumes<br />

that <strong>the</strong> gold tablets provide evidence for <strong>the</strong> Titans imprisoned in human bodies).


56<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

The Neoplatonic allegorical interpretation of <strong>the</strong> sparagmos of Dionysos<br />

may provide <strong>the</strong> link between <strong>the</strong> motif of dismemberment and <strong>the</strong> third strand<br />

in <strong>the</strong> tradition, <strong>the</strong> anthropogony. While <strong>the</strong>re are many tales of <strong>the</strong> creation<br />

of certain human families, ei<strong>the</strong>r autochthonously from <strong>the</strong> Earth or through<br />

<strong>the</strong> mating of mortals and gods, no story of <strong>the</strong> creation of <strong>the</strong> whole human<br />

race appears in <strong>the</strong> Greek tradition until <strong>the</strong> first century CE. 63 The idea that<br />

<strong>the</strong> Titans are <strong>the</strong> ancestors of all living creatures, however, is found as early<br />

as <strong>the</strong> Homeric Hymn to Apollo and recurs in a variety of mythical contexts.<br />

The Homeric Hymn to Apollo refers to <strong>the</strong> Titans as <strong>the</strong> ancestors of men and<br />

gods, while <strong>the</strong> Orphic Hymn to <strong>the</strong> Titans praises <strong>the</strong>m as <strong>the</strong> ancestors of all<br />

living things. 64 Dio Chrysostom’s story of <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind from <strong>the</strong><br />

blood of <strong>the</strong> Titans shed in <strong>the</strong>ir war against <strong>the</strong> gods links <strong>the</strong> creation of man<br />

to <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> Titanomachy and thus to <strong>the</strong> idea of punishment. The gods<br />

persecute <strong>the</strong> race of men, Dio says, because men are descended from <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

enemies. 65 Of all <strong>the</strong> testimonies to <strong>the</strong> myth, however, only <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonist<br />

Olympiodorus makes any kind of causal link between <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans<br />

for <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> creation of mortal things from Titanic<br />

stock. 66 Olympiodorus and o<strong>the</strong>r Neoplatonists see <strong>the</strong> myth of dismemberment<br />

as an allegory for <strong>the</strong> creation of <strong>the</strong> manifold material world out of divine unity<br />

by <strong>the</strong> action of <strong>the</strong> Titans, <strong>the</strong> forces of division. Thus, <strong>the</strong>y could connect this<br />

myth with <strong>the</strong> anthropogonic myths, which also, in a fashion, make <strong>the</strong> Titans<br />

responsible for <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> diversity of mortal life. And even though some<br />

Neoplatonists combine all three mythic strands, weaving in <strong>the</strong> anthropogony with<br />

<strong>the</strong> motifs of <strong>the</strong> cannibalistic dismemberment and punishment, <strong>the</strong>y still do not<br />

63. Hesiod’s myth of <strong>the</strong> metallic races (Op.106ff.) details <strong>the</strong> creation of several mortal<br />

races, but <strong>the</strong> myth describes <strong>the</strong> progressively worse conditions of life ra<strong>the</strong>r than providing an<br />

anthropogony for all mankind. The myth of <strong>the</strong> flood and <strong>the</strong> repopulation of <strong>the</strong> world by Deucalion<br />

and Pyrrha occurs first in Pindar (Olympian 9), but only in <strong>the</strong> much later Ovid (Met. 163–312) is it<br />

suggested that this episode begins <strong>the</strong> entire human race anew. Although this flood myth is conflated<br />

with <strong>the</strong> Biblical one by <strong>the</strong> early Christian Fa<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong>re is no reason to suppose it occupied <strong>the</strong><br />

same prominence in Greek thought that Noah’s flood did in <strong>the</strong> Biblical tradition. Plato’s myth in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Protagoras (320–21) implies a creation of mankind, but it only details <strong>the</strong> gifts given to mankind<br />

by Prome<strong>the</strong>us.<br />

64. Homeric Hymn to Apollo 334ff.; Orphic Hymn to <strong>the</strong> Titans (37).<br />

65. íti toÜ tÀn Titˆnwn aÑmatìj âsmen meØj ‰pantej oÉ Šnqrwpoi. ±j oÞn âkeÐnwn<br />

âxqrÀn întwn toØj qeoØj kaÈ polemhsˆntwn oÎdà meØj fÐloi âsmèn, ‚ll€ kolazìmeqˆ<br />

te Íp' aÎtÀn kaÈ âpÈ timwrÐaø gegìnamen, ân frour ø d˜ întej ân tÀú bÐwú tosoÜton<br />

xrìnon íson ékastoi zÀmen ... eÚnai dà tän màn tìpon toÜton, çn kìsmon ænomˆzomen,<br />

desmwtèrion Ípä tÀn qeÀn kateskeuasmènon xalepìn te kaÈ dusˆeron (Dio Chrysostom<br />

Or. 30.10–11). This text from <strong>the</strong> Second Sophistic attributes this gloomy view of life, with its<br />

echoes of <strong>the</strong> Platonic frourˆ, to a morose man who must have suffered much in life. Oppian’s<br />

Halieutica (5.1–10), on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, which attributes <strong>the</strong> creation of man ei<strong>the</strong>r to Prome<strong>the</strong>us<br />

or to <strong>the</strong> blood shed by <strong>the</strong> Titans in <strong>the</strong>ir war with <strong>the</strong> gods, attributes positive ramifications to<br />

<strong>the</strong> connection of humans to <strong>the</strong> Titans. The Orphic Argonautica (17ff.) links <strong>the</strong> race of mortals<br />

to <strong>the</strong> sperm of <strong>the</strong> Earthborn fallen from <strong>the</strong> sky.<br />

66. Olympiodorus OF 220; cf. Proclus’ version, which does not mention <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

and probably implies <strong>the</strong> Titanomachy, OF 224.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 57<br />

produce a doctrine of original sin. Even for <strong>the</strong>se Neoplatonists, <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong><br />

dismembered Dionysos does not become <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> Fall of Man, <strong>the</strong> central<br />

explanation of <strong>the</strong> degenerate state of <strong>the</strong> cosmos, but ra<strong>the</strong>r remains an allegory,<br />

a story told by <strong>the</strong> ancients who were so wise that <strong>the</strong>y encoded Neoplatonic ideas<br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir myths.<br />

Perhaps because <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists too saw <strong>the</strong> myth as an expression of<br />

one of <strong>the</strong> fundamental principles of <strong>the</strong>ir ideology, <strong>the</strong> myth seems almost as<br />

popular among <strong>the</strong>m as it is among modern scholars. However, just because <strong>the</strong><br />

Neoplatonists cite <strong>the</strong> myth as evidence that <strong>the</strong> doctrine of <strong>the</strong> Many and <strong>the</strong><br />

One was known to <strong>the</strong> ancients does not mean that we, like Rohde, should accept<br />

that this was always <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong> myth. Linforth notes, “In <strong>the</strong> age-long<br />

speculations on <strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong> One and <strong>the</strong> Many <strong>the</strong>re is no record of <strong>the</strong><br />

myth of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment before <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists, and we have no right to say<br />

that because this allegorical application of <strong>the</strong> myth could have been made by<br />

its first author, it was so made.” 67 The myth no more referred to <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonic<br />

One and Many before <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists than it referred to original sin before its<br />

interpretation by modern scholars. Although <strong>the</strong> parallel between <strong>the</strong> deaths and<br />

resurrections of Jesus and Dionysos was drawn by early Christian <strong>the</strong>ologians<br />

such as Justinian and Origen, <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> Titans’ murder of Dionysos was<br />

<strong>the</strong> original sin that caused mankind to need redemption does not appear—until<br />

Comparetti in 1879. 68 The myth survived and remained popular precisely because<br />

it was susceptible to so many kinds of retellings and reinterpretations. The various<br />

tellers of <strong>the</strong> story used <strong>the</strong> different pieces of <strong>the</strong> myth—<strong>the</strong> motifs of sparagmos,<br />

punishment by lightning, Dionysos, <strong>the</strong> Titans, etc., etc.—to create versions of<br />

<strong>the</strong> myth that reflected <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>the</strong>y saw in it. Over many centuries, <strong>the</strong>se<br />

bricoleurs assembled <strong>the</strong>se pieces for <strong>the</strong>ir own purposes in numerous ways and<br />

have left a bewildering array of fragments of <strong>the</strong>ir tales behind.<br />

CONSTRUCTING AN ARTIFICIAL FRAME<br />

FOR THE PIECES OF ZAGREUS<br />

From this assortment of fragments, modern scholars constructed a picture of<br />

an “Orphic” religion, centered around <strong>the</strong> dismemberment of Dionysos by <strong>the</strong><br />

Titans and <strong>the</strong> creation of mankind from <strong>the</strong>ir ashes, burdened with a kind of<br />

original sin. This picture remains appealing, even when <strong>the</strong> evidence on which it<br />

rests is shown to be flawed. Many scholars find <strong>the</strong> myth convincing despite <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

acceptance of <strong>the</strong> critique of <strong>the</strong> evidence. As Dodds comments, “Individually,<br />

<strong>the</strong>se apparent references to <strong>the</strong> myth can at a pinch be explained away; but taking<br />

<strong>the</strong>m toge<strong>the</strong>r, I find it hard to resist <strong>the</strong> conclusion that <strong>the</strong> complete story was<br />

67. Linforth 1941:324n. 7. Contra Rohde 1925:354n. 38.<br />

68. Cf. Justin Martyr Tryph 69.2 and Origen Contra Celsum 4.17.


58<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

known to Plato and his public.” 69 Just <strong>the</strong> same six pieces of evidence, discussed<br />

in <strong>the</strong> first section, along with <strong>the</strong> passage from <strong>the</strong> gold tablets, underlie all<br />

of <strong>the</strong> arguments for <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>the</strong> Orphic doctrine of <strong>the</strong> dual nature of<br />

mankind and <strong>the</strong> original sin inherited from <strong>the</strong> Titans, which modern scholars<br />

have seen as <strong>the</strong> natural product of <strong>the</strong> combination of <strong>the</strong> motifs of punishment<br />

and anthropogony. O<strong>the</strong>r fragments provide testimony to o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong> myth<br />

of <strong>Zagreus</strong>—<strong>the</strong> sparagmos of Dionysos, <strong>the</strong> cannibalistic feast, <strong>the</strong> punishment<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Titans, etc.—but <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and inherited guilt rest on <strong>the</strong>se pieces<br />

alone. Why, <strong>the</strong>n, were <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and subsequent doctrine of original sin<br />

made <strong>the</strong> crucial feature of Orphic religion and assumed to be <strong>the</strong> central point<br />

of <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> from its earliest tellings?<br />

The answer, I would argue, lies in <strong>the</strong> role that Orphism played in <strong>the</strong> debates<br />

surrounding early Christianity in <strong>the</strong> scholarship of <strong>the</strong> late nineteenth and early<br />

twentieth centuries. The scholars of this period fit <strong>the</strong> same six pieces of evidence<br />

into <strong>the</strong> familiar models of Christian religious sects and put toge<strong>the</strong>r a picture of<br />

Orphism as a religious sect, with a well-defined set of worshippers and religious<br />

doctrines. They used <strong>the</strong> “Orphic Church” thus created in <strong>the</strong> debates about <strong>the</strong><br />

origin and nature of <strong>the</strong> early Christian church. These scholars were operating<br />

with a paradigm of religion that took as its model <strong>the</strong> familiar structure of <strong>the</strong><br />

Christian religion, and this paradigm shaped <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y all imagined <strong>the</strong> religion<br />

<strong>the</strong>y studied. Even Guthrie, perhaps <strong>the</strong> most careful and self-conscious about<br />

not applying a Christian model to <strong>the</strong> ancient religions he studied, admits, “We<br />

are brought up in an atmosphere of Christianity, and whe<strong>the</strong>r we like it or not,<br />

Christian notions of behaviour have sunk into <strong>the</strong> very marrow of our thought<br />

and expression.” 70 The reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth seems persuasive<br />

to scholars even today, despite <strong>the</strong> lack of evidence, because it resonates so<br />

thoroughly with this familiar paradigm of religion. In this section, I examine<br />

how Orphism was constructed as a kind of spiritual religious reform movement<br />

that foreshadowed <strong>the</strong> rise of Christianity, and I briefly sketch <strong>the</strong> ways in<br />

which this construction was used as a foil in <strong>the</strong> debates over <strong>the</strong> nature of<br />

<strong>the</strong> early church.<br />

Orphism, as it was reconstructed by scholars in <strong>the</strong> late nineteenth and early<br />

twentieth centuries, was seen as a reform movement in Greek religion parallel<br />

to that of Protestantism in Christianity. This putatively purer, more rational, and<br />

more spiritual kind of religion paved <strong>the</strong> way for <strong>the</strong> coming of Christianity.<br />

Thus, Orphism was seen as a source or a parallel for many of <strong>the</strong> features that<br />

69. Dodds 1951:156. The strength of <strong>the</strong> collection of evidence comes from <strong>the</strong> fact that it fits<br />

into <strong>the</strong> familiar paradigm.<br />

70. Guthrie 1952:200. The extent to which he felt compelled to bow to <strong>the</strong> spirit of his times<br />

may be seen from his comment on <strong>the</strong> last page of his study on Orphism: “It is only from a feeling that<br />

a book on <strong>the</strong> Orphics which did not contain some comparison with <strong>the</strong> Christians would probably be<br />

thought intolerable, that I have been persuaded to depart even so far from <strong>the</strong> principle that <strong>the</strong> study<br />

here attempted is not a comparative one” (Guthrie 1952:271).


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 59<br />

distinguished Christianity from o<strong>the</strong>r mystery religions of <strong>the</strong> period. Scholars<br />

constructed Orphism as an advanced, spiritual religion in accordance with <strong>the</strong><br />

dominant paradigm of religion at <strong>the</strong> time, a model shared not only by scholars of<br />

a Protestant bent but also by anticlerical movements within <strong>the</strong> Catholic church.<br />

In this model, a good and advanced religion was characterized by an emphasis<br />

on personal and individual spirituality ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> performance of traditional<br />

ritual, an absence of priestly hierarchy linked with state political control, and<br />

a rational and sophisticated <strong>the</strong>ology grounded in <strong>the</strong> exegesis of sacred texts.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> religious beliefs should focus on <strong>the</strong> fallen nature<br />

of mankind and its redemption through divine action.<br />

As J. Z. Smith has argued in his Drudgery Divine, this model of what a good<br />

religion should be, often expressed in terms of <strong>the</strong> contrast between medieval<br />

Catholicism and <strong>the</strong> Protestant Reformation, influenced <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong><br />

mystery cults that were contemporary with early Christianity. The early Christian<br />

church was seen as pure and spiritual like <strong>the</strong> Protestant church, in contrast to<br />

<strong>the</strong> mystery religions whose ritual and ceremonial focus made <strong>the</strong>m more like<br />

<strong>the</strong> Catholic church:<br />

This is a modulation of <strong>the</strong> Protestant historiographic myth: a “uniquely”<br />

pristine “original” Christianity which suffered later corruptions. In this<br />

construction one is not, in fact, comparing early Christianity and <strong>the</strong><br />

religions of Late Antiquity. The latter have become code-words for<br />

Roman Catholicism and it is <strong>the</strong> Protestant catalogue of <strong>the</strong> central<br />

characteristics of Catholicism, from which it dissents, which provides<br />

<strong>the</strong> categories for comparison with Late Antiquity. 71<br />

To a certain extent, <strong>the</strong> mystery cults were reconstructed by <strong>the</strong>se scholars to fit<br />

<strong>the</strong> arguments, becoming <strong>the</strong> sources of <strong>the</strong> corruption of <strong>the</strong> pure early Church<br />

that led to <strong>the</strong> development of Catholicism. As Smith points out, <strong>the</strong> evidence<br />

for <strong>the</strong>se mystery cults was often distorted in <strong>the</strong> attempt to find <strong>the</strong> sources and<br />

parallels for <strong>the</strong> negative elements in Catholicism, with <strong>the</strong> result that <strong>the</strong> mystery<br />

religions were often depicted as largely focused on ritual and ceremony at <strong>the</strong><br />

expense of spiritual content and dominated by priestly hierarchies ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

personal contact with <strong>the</strong> divine.<br />

A similar distortion of <strong>the</strong> evidence occurred in <strong>the</strong> scholarship on Orphism,<br />

although Orphism was more often cast in <strong>the</strong> mold of <strong>the</strong> “good” type of religion.<br />

Comparetti, whose interpretation of <strong>the</strong> gold tablets in terms of an alleged<br />

Orphism centered around a doctrine of original sin set <strong>the</strong> terms for <strong>the</strong> modern<br />

reconstruction of Orphism, has been noted for his anti-clericalism. As Ziolkowski<br />

describes it, “One aspect of Comparetti’s conflicted outlook on Christianity has<br />

been called ‘rationalist laicism’: a predisposition to accentuate those beliefs and<br />

71. Smith 1990:43.


60<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

practices of medieval Christianity that appeared to be adaptations of paganism.” 72<br />

Comparetti and <strong>the</strong> scholars who followed his interpretation of <strong>the</strong> tablets saw<br />

Orphism as more advanced than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r religions of its time, more like <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

model of a “good” religion. Accordingly, <strong>the</strong>y saw in Orphism <strong>the</strong> familiar<br />

characteristics of religion as <strong>the</strong>y knew it: a founding prophet, a sacred scripture,<br />

and a developed rational <strong>the</strong>ology. At <strong>the</strong> center of such a religion must be a<br />

doctrine of <strong>the</strong> redemption of mankind through <strong>the</strong> suffering and death of <strong>the</strong> divine<br />

savior, for only such a doctrine could provide a truly religious understanding<br />

of <strong>the</strong> world. <strong>Zagreus</strong> was <strong>the</strong> perfect candidate for <strong>the</strong> suffering savior, and<br />

Olympiodorus’ story of <strong>the</strong> birth of mankind from <strong>the</strong> Titans suggested, to<br />

Comparetti and later scholars, an origin for <strong>the</strong> fallen nature of mankind, <strong>the</strong><br />

source of original sin as well as <strong>the</strong> hope of redemption.<br />

Like Protestantism, Orphism was described as, in essence, a reform movement,<br />

although <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> reform depends upon <strong>the</strong> scholar. Harrison saw<br />

Orpheus as <strong>the</strong> prophet of a reform of <strong>the</strong> primitive, ecstatic Dionysiac religion.<br />

She displays her own sympathies in describing a picture of <strong>the</strong> death of Orpheus<br />

at <strong>the</strong> hands of <strong>the</strong> maenads: “Orpheus was a reformer, a protestant; <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

always about him a touch of <strong>the</strong> reformer’s priggishness; it is impossible not<br />

to sympathize a little with <strong>the</strong> determined looking Maenad who is coming up<br />

behind to put a stop to all this sun-watching and lyre-playing.” 73 Macchioro<br />

makes <strong>the</strong> comparison between Orphism and Protestantism explicit: “The links<br />

between <strong>the</strong> Dionysiac religion and Orphism might be aptly compared with <strong>the</strong><br />

links which exist between a religion and its sects; for instance, between Christianity<br />

and Lu<strong>the</strong>ranism. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, I think that Orphism was a particular branch<br />

of Dionysiac religion centering around <strong>the</strong> person and <strong>the</strong> activity of a reformer,<br />

which in time reached <strong>the</strong> importance and <strong>the</strong> diffusion of a really new religion.” 74<br />

O<strong>the</strong>rs see Orphism as a reform of traditional Greek (that is, Homeric)<br />

religion. Watmough’s entire essay is devoted to <strong>the</strong> parallels between Homeric<br />

religion and Orphism on <strong>the</strong> one hand and <strong>the</strong> medieval Catholic Church and<br />

Protestantism on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r:<br />

In <strong>the</strong> ancient world we have <strong>the</strong> religion of Homer, entirely concerned<br />

with sacrifice and ritual, entirely dominated by <strong>the</strong> note of “Confiteor”—<br />

<strong>the</strong> confession of vows duly performed: and over against it <strong>the</strong> religion<br />

of “Orpheus,” which emphasised <strong>the</strong> relation of <strong>the</strong> individual soul<br />

with God, for authority turning not to priests but scriptures. In <strong>the</strong><br />

more modern world we have <strong>the</strong> mediaeval Church, a picturesque and<br />

colourful religious system based on sacerdotalism and ecclesiolatry: over<br />

72. Ziolkowski 1997:xxviii. That <strong>the</strong> Jesuit-educated Comparetti combined his anti-clericalism<br />

with a strong Italian nationalist bent hints at <strong>the</strong> complexities of <strong>the</strong>se debates about <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

early Church.<br />

73. Harrison 1922:461.<br />

74. Macchioro 1930:137.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 61<br />

against it <strong>the</strong> Protestant reformers with <strong>the</strong>ir “justification by faith” and<br />

bibliolatrous attitude to <strong>the</strong> canonical writings. 75<br />

The Orphic reform, according to <strong>the</strong>se scholars, spiritualized <strong>the</strong> meaningless<br />

rituals of traditional religion and gave <strong>the</strong>m a significance for <strong>the</strong> individual in<br />

his relations with <strong>the</strong> divine, just as <strong>the</strong> Protestant Reformation did away with<br />

<strong>the</strong> ritualism of <strong>the</strong> Catholic Church and focused on <strong>the</strong> relation of <strong>the</strong> individual<br />

with God. Of <strong>the</strong> rituals of Homeric religion, Watmough claims, “The important<br />

fact is that <strong>the</strong>y were devoid of moral and spiritual significance. With ‘Orphism’<br />

much of <strong>the</strong> ritualistic and ceremonial element is retained, but behind <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

much more real and much more personal yearning to escape from an abstract<br />

power called Evil.... The parallel in modern Protestantism is clear to <strong>the</strong> most<br />

superficial observer.” 76 Orphism even surpasses <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r mystery religions with<br />

this emphasis on <strong>the</strong> personal and spiritual ra<strong>the</strong>r than ritual and ceremonial<br />

elements. Morford and Lenardon compare Orphism with <strong>the</strong> most famous of <strong>the</strong><br />

mystery cults, <strong>the</strong> Eleusinian Mysteries: “The mysteries of Demeter, with <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

emphasis on participation in certain dramatic rites, lacked <strong>the</strong> spiritual depth of<br />

Orphism with its insistence on <strong>the</strong> good life as well as mere initiation and ritual.” 77<br />

The point of all <strong>the</strong>se comparisons is that Orphism is higher up on <strong>the</strong> scale<br />

of religions than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms of Greek religion (be it Dionysism, Homeric<br />

cult or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r mystery cults), just as, for <strong>the</strong> same reasons, Protestantism (or a<br />

reformed version of modern Catholicism) is higher than medieval Catholicism.<br />

Protestantism was thus mapped onto ano<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> dominant paradigms of <strong>the</strong><br />

day, <strong>the</strong> idea of <strong>the</strong> evolution of mankind in terms of a growing rationality and<br />

individuation. As Orphism represents an advance on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms of Greek<br />

religion, so Christianity represents an advance on <strong>the</strong> earlier Greek religions,<br />

and so too Protestantism represents an advance over medieval Catholicism in<br />

terms of rational <strong>the</strong>ology for <strong>the</strong> individual. Macchioro explicitly posits an<br />

evolutionary scale of religions, progressing from <strong>the</strong> childishly irrational to <strong>the</strong><br />

maturely reasonable and spiritual: “Human spiritual evolution progresses from<br />

a maximum to a minimum of imagination. It seems that <strong>the</strong> path of history<br />

leads mankind from fantasy to reason, from a mythical to a logical condition.<br />

Perhaps progress consists in getting rid of that overwhelming power of fantasy,<br />

which seems to dominate children and primitive people.” 78 Orphism is thus for<br />

Macchioro <strong>the</strong> step on <strong>the</strong> road from pagan myth to Christian religion. 79<br />

This construction of Orphism served in <strong>the</strong> debates about <strong>the</strong> nature of early<br />

Christianity as a foil to <strong>the</strong> mystery cults and o<strong>the</strong>r forms of Greek religion. Just as<br />

75. Watmough 1934:56–57.<br />

76. Watmough 1934:50.<br />

77. Morford and Lenardon 1999:280–81.<br />

78. Macchioro 1930:73.<br />

79. Literally. Macchioro argues, in a number of his books, that St. Paul was directly influenced<br />

by Orphism in his <strong>the</strong>ology.


62<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

early Christianity was being constructed as a kind of pure anticlerical Christianity<br />

that was superior to <strong>the</strong> contemporary mystery cults and <strong>the</strong> later Catholic Church,<br />

so Orphism was constructed as a kind of Protestant reform movement in contrast<br />

with Homeric religion, Dionysism, or o<strong>the</strong>r mystery cults. Orphism thus became<br />

a forerunner of Christianity, a vehicle for <strong>the</strong> best parts of Greek culture—<strong>the</strong><br />

rational, spiritual, philosophical, Apollonian parts. 80<br />

Orphism was depicted as a movement ahead of its time, an enlightened<br />

religious movement in <strong>the</strong> midst of pagan superstitions. As such, Orphism must<br />

be given <strong>the</strong> familiar features of an advanced, enlightened religion. Macchioro<br />

distinguishes between spontaneous religions, in which he includes all “primitive”<br />

religions, and revealed, doctrinal religions. “The spontaneous religions which<br />

do not boast of a founder at all, are <strong>the</strong> outgrowth of primitive, unconscious,<br />

religious needs, which were never shaped into any rigid definite schema. Herein<br />

lies <strong>the</strong> explanation of <strong>the</strong> overwhelming power exerted by <strong>the</strong> imagination in<br />

<strong>the</strong>se religions, and, conversely, of <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>oretical and philosophical poverty.” 81<br />

Orphism he firmly classifies with <strong>the</strong> revealed religions like Judaism, Christianity,<br />

and Islam, since it has all <strong>the</strong> requisite features: a founding prophet, a sacred<br />

scripture, and a developed, rational <strong>the</strong>ology.<br />

According to this reconstruction, <strong>the</strong> founding prophet of Orphism is, of<br />

course, <strong>the</strong> mythical poet Orpheus, who, like a good Biblical prophet, was not<br />

without honor except in his own country of Thrace. In Thrace, he was torn apart<br />

by maenads, a martyr to <strong>the</strong> spiritual religion he came to preach to <strong>the</strong> savage<br />

primitives. The historicity of Orpheus himself was debated among <strong>the</strong>se scholars,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> historical kernel was rarely doubted. As Harrison says, “The blood of some<br />

real martyr may have been <strong>the</strong> seed of <strong>the</strong> new Orphic church.” 82 The prophet set<br />

forth in his poetry <strong>the</strong> doctrines of his new religion, as Morford and Lenardon<br />

tell us: “Orpheus was considered <strong>the</strong> founder of a religion, a prophet (<strong>the</strong>ologos)<br />

who with his priests and disciples committed to writing holy words (hieroi logoi)<br />

that provided a bible for dogma, ritual, and behavior.” 83 In keeping with <strong>the</strong><br />

familiar model of Protestant religion centered around <strong>the</strong> exegesis of <strong>the</strong> sacred<br />

scripture, <strong>the</strong> poetry of Orpheus is seen by <strong>the</strong>se scholars as <strong>the</strong> equivalent of<br />

<strong>the</strong> “Orphic Bible.”<br />

80. The Nietzschean contrast between <strong>the</strong> Dionysian and <strong>the</strong> Apollonian plays a part in this story<br />

of <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, largely because of <strong>the</strong> influence of Nietzsche’s friend Rohde, who described<br />

Orphism as a reform of Dionysiac religion, a movement tending to <strong>the</strong> rational and philosophical<br />

Apollonian facet of Greek culture. The story of Orpheus’ death at <strong>the</strong> hands of Maenads angered by<br />

his devotion to <strong>the</strong> Sun (identified with Apollo), a story extrapolated from a scholiast’s reference to<br />

Aeschylus’ lost Bassarai, became <strong>the</strong> central symbol of <strong>the</strong> Apollonian/Dionysiac tension within<br />

Orphism.<br />

81. Macchioro 1930:123–24.<br />

82. Harrison 1922:468. Cf. Nilsson, contra Kern (Orpheus 26 [Berlin, 1920]): “I should not<br />

dare to say that Orpheus died a martyr to his religion, but his manner of death is <strong>the</strong> mythical<br />

vengeance for his blasphemy according to <strong>the</strong> jus talionis” (Nilsson 1935:204).<br />

83. Morford and Lenardon 1999:278.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 63<br />

This idea of <strong>the</strong> Orphic sacred scriptures played an important part in <strong>the</strong><br />

fabrication of a proto-Protestant Orphism. Numerous titles of works said to be<br />

by Orpheus have been preserved in <strong>the</strong> commentators of late antiquity. In <strong>the</strong><br />

Classical period, Plato and Euripides both refer to collections of writings by<br />

Orpheus. 84 Since mainstream Greek religion had no sacred writings at all, <strong>the</strong><br />

Orphics, defined as those who use works by Orpheus, seem, by contrast, to be<br />

much more like a familiar religion of <strong>the</strong> Book. Guthrie draws an exaggerated<br />

conclusion from this importance of writing in Orphism, “The Orphic did nothing<br />

unless <strong>the</strong>re was a warrant for it in his books.” 85 Of course, <strong>the</strong> reasoning here<br />

is somewhat circular. Since <strong>the</strong> “Orphics” are defined as those who refer to <strong>the</strong><br />

writings of Orpheus, <strong>the</strong> writings become, by definition, <strong>the</strong> central defining<br />

feature of <strong>the</strong> group.<br />

This idea of <strong>the</strong> importance of scripture for <strong>the</strong> Orphics seems to persist<br />

even in West’s recent assumption, never defended, that <strong>the</strong> details from <strong>the</strong> late<br />

Rhapsodic Theogony must come from earlier, complete <strong>the</strong>ogonies, ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

from shorter works that included <strong>the</strong>ogonic material, perhaps, e.g., <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Orphica whose titles are preserved in various sources. West assumes that <strong>the</strong><br />

sources of <strong>the</strong> later Orphica were comprehensive stories of <strong>the</strong> creation of <strong>the</strong><br />

world, <strong>the</strong> gods, and mankind (on <strong>the</strong> scale of Hesiod’s Theogony or perhaps<br />

Genesis) that provided a complete and consistent <strong>the</strong>ological framework for<br />

everything. West gives no argument or evidence for this assumption; indeed,<br />

<strong>the</strong> extant evidence would seem to tell against such an assumption. The only<br />

<strong>the</strong>ogony that actually survives, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ogony commented upon in <strong>the</strong> Derveni<br />

papyrus, is not a comprehensive <strong>the</strong>ogony. Therefore, West claims, it must be<br />

an abridgment of a comprehensive, but not extant, <strong>the</strong>ogony, which he calls<br />

<strong>the</strong> Protogonos Theogony. 86<br />

The assumption that <strong>the</strong> Orphic <strong>the</strong>ogonies must have been comprehensive<br />

accounts seems to rest on <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>se “Orphics” relied on <strong>the</strong>se poems as<br />

sacred scripture from which <strong>the</strong>y derived <strong>the</strong>ir religious doctrine. The reasoning<br />

seems to run something like this: since <strong>the</strong>y derived all <strong>the</strong>ir doctrines from<br />

<strong>the</strong> scriptures, <strong>the</strong> scriptures must be complete and comprehensive, providing a<br />

warrant for every feature of <strong>the</strong>ir religious life. Rohde indeed marks this as a<br />

trait which distinguished <strong>the</strong> Orphics from <strong>the</strong> rest of Greek religion: “The Orphic<br />

sect had a fixed and definite set of doctrines; this alone sufficed to distinguish it<br />

both from <strong>the</strong> official worships of <strong>the</strong> state, and from all o<strong>the</strong>r cult-associations of<br />

<strong>the</strong> time. The reduction of belief to distinct doctrinal formulae may have done<br />

84. Euripides Hippolytus (943–57 = OT 213): Theseus refers to Orphics with <strong>the</strong>ir pollÀn<br />

grammˆtwn ... kapnoÔj. Plato in <strong>the</strong> Republic (364e = OF 3) speaks of a bÐblwn ímadon by<br />

Orpheus and Musaeus (in Dodd’s felicitous translation, “a hubbub of books”). Pausanias (1.37.4<br />

= OT 219) seems to draw a distinction between <strong>the</strong> rites of Eleusis and <strong>the</strong> Orphic writings, but<br />

this does not necessarily imply that Orphism was solely or even primarily a literary tradition.<br />

85. Guthrie 1952:202.<br />

86. West 1983:69, 101.


64<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

more than anything else to make Orphism a society of believers.” 87 The Orphics<br />

were thus characterized as a religious sect that derived a sophisticated <strong>the</strong>ology<br />

from <strong>the</strong>ir comprehensive cosmogonic myths. Or, to look at it from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side,<br />

<strong>the</strong> Orphics developed comprehensive cosmogonies because of <strong>the</strong>ir rationalistic<br />

interest in philosophical <strong>the</strong>ology. Macchioro goes so far as to claim that <strong>the</strong><br />

Orphics really had very little myth, but a great deal of philosophical, <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

speculation:<br />

In <strong>the</strong> last analysis, Orphism had no mythology of its own, with <strong>the</strong> exception<br />

of a few <strong>the</strong>ological accounts and tales, such as <strong>the</strong> description of <strong>the</strong><br />

world of <strong>the</strong> dead, and some cosmogonies; o<strong>the</strong>rwise nothing to compare<br />

with <strong>the</strong> enormous richness of Greek mythology. This lack of mythical<br />

interest is offset by a living interest in <strong>the</strong>ological and cosmological problems,<br />

as is shown by <strong>the</strong> very great antiquity of Orphic <strong>the</strong>ogonies and<br />

cosmogonies, and <strong>the</strong>ir tendency to generate philosophies. 88<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> only myths of <strong>the</strong> Orphics were stories on real <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

concerns, such as creation, eschatology, and soteriology. 89 According to <strong>the</strong>se<br />

turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-century scholars, Orphism—with its founding prophet, sacred scriptures,<br />

and sophisticated <strong>the</strong>ology—was far advanced on <strong>the</strong> road from mythos<br />

to logos, from pagan superstition to enlightened religion.<br />

At <strong>the</strong> center of this proto-Christian Orphism, scholars naturally looked for a<br />

parallel with <strong>the</strong> death and resurrection of Christ, with an attendant doctrine of<br />

redemption from original sin as a consequence of his passion. The myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

seemed to include <strong>the</strong> death and resurrection of a god, and, with <strong>the</strong> anthropogony<br />

in <strong>the</strong> version of Olympiodorus, <strong>the</strong> possibility for a doctrine of original sin. As a<br />

result, scholars made it <strong>the</strong> heart of <strong>the</strong>ir reconstructed Orphism. “We come now,”<br />

Guthrie says, “to what must have been for a worshipper <strong>the</strong> central point of Orphic<br />

story, <strong>the</strong> tales of Dionysos son of Zeus and his sufferings.” 90 “There is no doubt,”<br />

asserts Macchioro, “that <strong>the</strong> death and resurrection of <strong>Zagreus</strong> formed <strong>the</strong> pivot of<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole Orphic mystery.” 91 The myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> is seen by <strong>the</strong>se scholars as<br />

<strong>the</strong> story which provides <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong> whole religion, much as <strong>the</strong> story<br />

of Christ provides <strong>the</strong> religious meaning for Christianity.<br />

But a mere story of death and resurrection would be insufficient, in <strong>the</strong> light<br />

of Frazer and his examples of dying and rising gods all over <strong>the</strong> Mediterranean.<br />

The anthropogony attached to <strong>the</strong> myth provides <strong>the</strong> necessary connection with<br />

mankind to give <strong>the</strong> myth <strong>the</strong> kind of religious significance that <strong>the</strong> resurrection of<br />

87. Rohde 1925:338. For “<strong>the</strong> official worships of <strong>the</strong> state” we may understand “Catholicism”;<br />

for “all o<strong>the</strong>r cult-associations of <strong>the</strong> time” we may understand “<strong>the</strong> mystery cults.”<br />

88. Macchioro 1930:129.<br />

89. Cf. Smith, “In <strong>the</strong> hands of many scholars, both past and present, it is primarily soteriological<br />

notions which supply an evolutionary scale that ranks religions, with Protestant Christianity often<br />

serving as <strong>the</strong> implicit or explicit norm or <strong>the</strong> culmination of <strong>the</strong> exercise” (Smith 1990:119).<br />

90. Guthrie 1952:107.<br />

91. Macchioro 1930:75.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 65<br />

Christ has in Christianity. Only <strong>the</strong> anthropogony could make <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

about sin and redemption, and <strong>the</strong>refore, scholars concluded, it must always have<br />

been part of <strong>the</strong> story central to this religion. Guthrie identifies this story as<br />

<strong>the</strong> crucial feature that permits Orphic poetry, unlike <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>the</strong>ogony of<br />

Hesiod, to become <strong>the</strong> basis for a truly religious life:<br />

There is no Chronos in Hesiod, none of <strong>the</strong> curious second beginning of<br />

all things within <strong>the</strong> body of Zeus, above all none of <strong>the</strong> story of Dionysos<br />

and <strong>the</strong> Titans. From this it follows that <strong>the</strong> human interest with which<br />

<strong>the</strong> Orphic poem ends is entirely lacking in Hesiod, and his <strong>the</strong>ogony<br />

is divorced from ideas of good and evil .... In short, <strong>the</strong> fundamental<br />

difference between <strong>the</strong> two systems lies here: <strong>the</strong> one could never be<br />

made <strong>the</strong> doctrinal basis of a religious life; <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r both could be and<br />

in fact was. 92<br />

Human interest comes from <strong>the</strong> anthropogony, which makes <strong>the</strong> myth about <strong>the</strong><br />

salvation of mankind ra<strong>the</strong>r than simply a tale of long ago. Nilsson explicitly draws<br />

this distinction between myths, which tell fantastic tales without any religious<br />

significance, and <strong>the</strong> anthropogonic myth of <strong>the</strong> Orphics, which, because it is<br />

about sin and redemption, has a truly religious significance: “Beginning with<br />

Chaos and ending with <strong>the</strong> creation of man <strong>the</strong> cosmogony is rounded off into<br />

a systematic whole which has not only a mythical but also a religious meaning.<br />

Its final aim is not to relate tales of <strong>the</strong> world and of <strong>the</strong> gods, but to explain <strong>the</strong><br />

composite nature of man and his fate.” 93 Traditional Greek cult, in o<strong>the</strong>r words,<br />

had only myths; <strong>the</strong> Orphics had a real religion. 94 The crucial significance of<br />

<strong>the</strong> anthropogony to <strong>the</strong> picture of Orphism as a kind of proto-Christian religion<br />

explains why so many scholars insist on its presence from <strong>the</strong> earliest tellings<br />

of <strong>the</strong> story, despite <strong>the</strong> lack of any solid evidence. 95<br />

The placement of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth with its anthropogony at <strong>the</strong> heart of<br />

Orphism from its inception depends, <strong>the</strong>n, on <strong>the</strong> model of Orphism as a kind<br />

92. Guthrie 1952:84.<br />

93. Nilsson 1935:225 (my emphasis).<br />

94. Rohde too makes <strong>the</strong> distinction between myth and real religion. “The myth of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

of <strong>Zagreus</strong> by <strong>the</strong> Titans was already put into verse by Onomakritos; it continued to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> culminating point of <strong>the</strong> doctrinal poetry of <strong>the</strong> Orphics. . . . It is a religious myth in <strong>the</strong> stricter<br />

sense; its aetiological character is most marked” (Rohde 1925:341). Cf.: “This poem must have<br />

been one of <strong>the</strong> basic, and in <strong>the</strong> strictest sense ‘religious’ [im engeren Sinne religiöse] writings<br />

of <strong>the</strong> sect” (Rohde 1925:338).<br />

95. West, in his recent treatment of <strong>the</strong> Orphic poems, places <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth and <strong>the</strong><br />

anthropogony toge<strong>the</strong>r in what he calls <strong>the</strong> Eudemian <strong>the</strong>ogony, <strong>the</strong> second oldest of <strong>the</strong> Orphic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ogonies he identifies (West 1983:140–75). Although he accepts <strong>the</strong> arguments of Linforth 1941<br />

regarding <strong>the</strong> evidence, he never<strong>the</strong>less assumes that <strong>the</strong> anthropogony and doctrine of Titanic guilt<br />

must have been part of <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysos <strong>Zagreus</strong>, which he links to Cretan<br />

initiation rituals. West here seems to ignore <strong>the</strong> consequences of Linforth’s conclusions; he accepts<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctrine of Orphic original sin and salvation left over from <strong>the</strong> turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-century paradigm<br />

of religion without questioning and works it into his reconstruction wherever he can make it fit.


66<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

of proto-Protestantism, a real religion according to <strong>the</strong> paradigm of religion<br />

used by <strong>the</strong> scholars, both Catholic and Protestant, at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> nineteenth<br />

and beginning of <strong>the</strong> twentieth century. This paradigm of religion continues to<br />

be influential, which is why <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth from <strong>the</strong><br />

fragments of evidence continues to be persuasive. Such a model of religion,<br />

however, distorts <strong>the</strong> evidence, taking <strong>the</strong> fragments out of <strong>the</strong>ir proper context<br />

and placing <strong>the</strong>m in an alien and artificial structure. The apparent coherence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> evidence comes only from our familiarity with <strong>the</strong> structure in which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are placed. The myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, which brings toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> ancient tales of <strong>the</strong><br />

dismemberment of Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, <strong>the</strong> later tales of<br />

<strong>the</strong> creation of mankind, and <strong>the</strong> idea of original sin and redemption borrowed<br />

from <strong>the</strong> modern Christian ideas of religion, is a fabrication of <strong>the</strong> scholars of<br />

<strong>the</strong> late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.<br />

REPLACING THE HEART OF THE ZAGREUS MYTH<br />

This modern myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> arose from <strong>the</strong> discovery of <strong>the</strong> gold tablets<br />

at Thurii in 1879, a set of cryptic and fragmentary texts that forced scholars to<br />

reexamine <strong>the</strong> old evidence for Greek religious beliefs. Comparetti’s interpretation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> newly discovered Thurii tablets in terms of an Orphic doctrine of original<br />

sin (based on <strong>the</strong> anthropogony found in Olympiodorus) laid <strong>the</strong> foundation for <strong>the</strong><br />

reconstruction of Orphism in <strong>the</strong> early twentieth century. Although scholars have<br />

begun to discard this outdated model for understanding Orphism as a whole, <strong>the</strong><br />

interpretation of <strong>the</strong> tablets <strong>the</strong>mselves still rests largely on <strong>the</strong> central feature of<br />

this turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-century paradigm, <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>. 96 However, just as I have<br />

shown that <strong>the</strong> various tales of Dionysos’ dismemberment can be understood with<br />

reference to ideas for which <strong>the</strong>re is evidence within <strong>the</strong> Greek religious tradition,<br />

so too <strong>the</strong> Orphic gold tablets must be interpreted apart from this anachronistic<br />

myth. The imagery of <strong>the</strong> gold tablets draws on a variety of mythical elements<br />

familiar from <strong>the</strong> mythic tradition, but <strong>the</strong> resonance of each of <strong>the</strong>se elements<br />

is lost if <strong>the</strong>y are all read as referring to a single myth of anthropogony and<br />

original sin, a myth not told until 1879, thousands of years after <strong>the</strong> tablets were<br />

composed. By examining <strong>the</strong> claims of <strong>the</strong> gold tablets without <strong>the</strong> framework<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, we can make better sense of <strong>the</strong> religious traditions and<br />

96. Burkert is among <strong>the</strong> few moving beyond <strong>the</strong> old paradigm. In Greek Religion he suggests,<br />

“Once again this is not to say that all forms of Bacchic mysteries are built on this foundation. When<br />

<strong>the</strong> dead man of Thurioi introduces himself as <strong>the</strong> ‘son of earth and starry heaven’ [sic], <strong>the</strong> myth<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Titans is not necessarily implied; <strong>the</strong> ‘penance for unjust deeds’ on <strong>the</strong> Thurioi leaves might be<br />

better grouped with Pindar and Plato” (Burkert 1985:298). The fact that even Burkert conflates <strong>the</strong> A<br />

tablets of Thurii (which mention penance and lightning) with <strong>the</strong> reference to <strong>the</strong> “child of earth<br />

and starry heaven” in <strong>the</strong> B series (which mention nei<strong>the</strong>r penance nor lightning) shows <strong>the</strong> lingering<br />

influence of <strong>the</strong> model which lumped all of <strong>the</strong> tablets into a single category that was interpreted<br />

through <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 67<br />

<strong>the</strong> individual groups that produced <strong>the</strong> tablets. A brief analysis of some of <strong>the</strong><br />

statements on <strong>the</strong> tablet from Thurii quoted at <strong>the</strong> beginning of this essay may<br />

serve as a demonstration.<br />

The claim of <strong>the</strong> deceased to be ÍmÀn gènoj îlbion, of your blessed race,<br />

when addressing a deity is by no means impossible for a mortal outside <strong>the</strong><br />

framework of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> anthropogony. As mainstream a poet as Hesiod says he<br />

will tell how <strong>the</strong> gods and man came from <strong>the</strong> same origin, ±j åmìqen gegˆasi<br />

qeoÈ qnhtoÐ t' Šnqrwpoi. 97 By claiming to be of <strong>the</strong> gènoj of <strong>the</strong> gods, <strong>the</strong><br />

deceased is employing a familiar mythic element to make a claim that transcends<br />

<strong>the</strong> clan politics of her contemporary world, where status is based on family<br />

position and <strong>the</strong> confinements of various social hierarchies. The deceased instead<br />

lays claim to kinship with <strong>the</strong> gods, recalling <strong>the</strong> ideal of <strong>the</strong> time before <strong>the</strong><br />

separation of mortals and immortals. Hesiod’s description of <strong>the</strong> unity of men and<br />

gods, which ended with <strong>the</strong> divisive sacrifice at Mekone, is only <strong>the</strong> most obvious<br />

of <strong>the</strong> numerous myths of an idealized primeval communion of men and gods. 98<br />

The deceased also claims to have paid <strong>the</strong> penalty for unjust deeds. These<br />

unjust deeds may ei<strong>the</strong>r be those of <strong>the</strong> deceased herself or those committed by<br />

some ancestor, as Plato’s discussion of purificatory rituals for unjust deeds in <strong>the</strong><br />

Republic shows: “For beggar priests and prophets go to <strong>the</strong> doors of <strong>the</strong> rich and<br />

persuade <strong>the</strong>m that <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong> power from <strong>the</strong> gods to perform sacrifices and<br />

spells. If <strong>the</strong>y or one of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors has done something unjust, <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong><br />

power to heal it with pleasurable things and festivals.” 99 But Plato’s discussion<br />

also shows that <strong>the</strong>se ancestors are unlikely to be <strong>the</strong> Titans as <strong>the</strong> universal<br />

ancestors of mankind, for every mortal has ancestors who were less than perfectly<br />

just. The use of this mythic element in <strong>the</strong> tablets would have evoked a wide<br />

range of traditional stories of individuals paying <strong>the</strong> penalty not only for <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

own crimes, but for those of <strong>the</strong>ir ancestors.<br />

The claim of <strong>the</strong> deceased to have been struck by lightning also admits<br />

of more interpretations than <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong> Titans, for <strong>the</strong> idea has a<br />

number of interesting mythic resonances. The Titans were by no means <strong>the</strong> only<br />

97. Hesiod Op. 108. Closer to <strong>the</strong>se tablets in time and place, Pindar begins <strong>the</strong> Sixth Nemean<br />

Ode by affirming <strong>the</strong> same idea, ën ‚ndrÀn, ën qeÀn gènoj; âk mi j dà pnèomen maträj<br />

‚mfìteroi (1–2). A different formulation of <strong>the</strong> same idea may be found in <strong>the</strong> B tablets’ formula of<br />

self-identification, “I am <strong>the</strong> child of earth and starry heaven,” a Hesiodic phrase that would apply<br />

not only to <strong>the</strong> Titans but to all of <strong>the</strong> later generations of gods (and possibly mortals). Cf., Hesiod<br />

Theog. 105–106.<br />

98. Theog. 535ff.: cunaÈ g€r tìte daØtej êsan, cunoÈ dà qìwkoi ‚qanˆtoisi qeoØsi<br />

kataqnhtoØj t' ‚nqr¸poij. Cf. Eoiae fr. 1.6–7 Merkelbach-West; cf. also <strong>the</strong> feasting of Tantalus<br />

and Ixion with <strong>the</strong> gods.<br />

99. ‚gÔrtai dà kaÈ mˆnteij âpÈ plousÐwn qÔraj Êìntej peÐqousin ±j êsti par€ sfÐsi<br />

dÔnamij âk qeÀn prozomènh qusÐaj te kaÈ âpwúdaØj, eÒte ti ‚dÐkhmˆ tou gègonen aÎtoÜ £<br />

progìnwn, ‚keØsqai meq' donÀn te kaÈ áortÀn (Republic 364bc; cf. 364e-5a, 366ab). The<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r tablets from Thurii, A1 and A4, make no mention of paying a penalty, nor do any of <strong>the</strong> tablets<br />

in <strong>the</strong> B series. The Pelinna tablets refer to Bacchios freeing <strong>the</strong> initiate, perhaps meaning that she,<br />

like <strong>the</strong> initiate of <strong>the</strong> Pherai tablet, need not pay a penalty.


68<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

ones to have felt Zeus’ lightning bolt. <strong>Apart</strong> from o<strong>the</strong>r monstrous enemies of<br />

Zeus, like Typhon, a number of heroes were struck by lightning in a variety of<br />

myths. As Rohde states in his Appendix on <strong>the</strong> “Consecration of Persons Struck<br />

by Lightning,” “In many legends death by lightning makes <strong>the</strong> victim holy and<br />

raises him to godlike (everlasting) life.” 100 In some versions, Herakles’ apo<strong>the</strong>osis<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> pyre at Oeta was accomplished by Zeus’ thunderbolt, and Semele and<br />

Asclepius, for example, were also struck by lightning before <strong>the</strong>ir final apo<strong>the</strong>osis<br />

or heroization. 101<br />

These three examples are particularly interesting because each of <strong>the</strong>se heroes<br />

could better serve as <strong>the</strong> mythic reference for <strong>the</strong> gold tablets than <strong>the</strong> Titans.<br />

Each of <strong>the</strong>m was originally a mortal, but divinely descended or connected; each<br />

committed unjust deeds; and each was described as being hit by <strong>the</strong> lightning<br />

of Zeus. For Herakles, <strong>the</strong> lightning strike was strictly part of <strong>the</strong> apo<strong>the</strong>osis or<br />

heroization process ra<strong>the</strong>r than punishment, but for both Asclepius and Semele <strong>the</strong><br />

lightning bolt served as <strong>the</strong> punishment for <strong>the</strong> unjust deeds, with <strong>the</strong> apo<strong>the</strong>osis<br />

or heroization following. The use of <strong>the</strong> mythic element of <strong>the</strong> lightning strike<br />

in <strong>the</strong> tablets would conjure up <strong>the</strong> tales about <strong>the</strong>se heroes and confer some of<br />

<strong>the</strong> authority of <strong>the</strong>se tales upon <strong>the</strong> deceased’s account of herself, as well as<br />

transferring some of <strong>the</strong> prestige of <strong>the</strong>se figures to <strong>the</strong> deceased. The deceased<br />

did not necessarily see herself as ano<strong>the</strong>r Semele or even ano<strong>the</strong>r Herakles, but<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se figures served as <strong>the</strong> mythic precedents, having undergone <strong>the</strong> same<br />

process of heroization, of purification through <strong>the</strong> fire of <strong>the</strong> lightning bolt, which<br />

simultaneously stripped <strong>the</strong>m of <strong>the</strong>ir mortal impurities and translated <strong>the</strong>m to <strong>the</strong><br />

realm of <strong>the</strong> immortals.<br />

Such explanations of <strong>the</strong> verses on <strong>the</strong> gold tablet may not tidily explain <strong>the</strong><br />

religious ideas behind <strong>the</strong> tablet in terms of a single, central myth that provides<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctrine for <strong>the</strong> cult, but <strong>the</strong>y do point to a kind of bricolage of mythic ideas<br />

drawn from a set of beliefs and ideas found elsewhere in Greek religion. Our<br />

knowledge of <strong>the</strong> rich tradition from which <strong>the</strong>se elements were drawn remains<br />

fragmentary, but <strong>the</strong> careful reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> contexts and meanings of such<br />

fragments as <strong>the</strong> gold tablets deepens our understanding of <strong>the</strong> tradition and how<br />

it was used. Such a reconstruction, whe<strong>the</strong>r it be of <strong>the</strong> religious background of<br />

<strong>the</strong> gold tablets or of <strong>the</strong> various uses of <strong>the</strong> myth of Dionysos’ dismemberment<br />

is, of course, more difficult than simply squeezing <strong>the</strong>m all into <strong>the</strong> framework<br />

of a single myth, and <strong>the</strong> end product is less satisfyingly neat. Alister Cameron,<br />

in his 1942 review of Linforth, complains, “Linforth’s analysis of <strong>the</strong>se texts<br />

100. Rohde 1925:581–82.<br />

101. Herakles: D.S. 4.38.4–5. Semele: Pind. O. 2.27; D.S. 5.52.2; Charax ap. Anon. de Incred.<br />

xvi; Arist. 1, p. 47 Dind.; Philostr. Imag. 1.14; Nonnos Dion. 8.409ff. Asclepius: Hesiod fr. 109<br />

Rz.; Lucian DD. 13. Cf. also figures such as Erec<strong>the</strong>us, Kapaneus, and Amphiaraus. The sacralizing<br />

effect of lightning may been seen from later testimonies in <strong>the</strong> reverence for <strong>the</strong> lightning-struck<br />

tombs of Lycurgus and Euripides in Plut. Lyc. 31 and Pliny’s report that <strong>the</strong> thunderbolting of <strong>the</strong><br />

statues of Olympic victor Euthymos indicated his heroic status (NH 7.152).


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 69<br />

fractures <strong>the</strong>ir unity and gives us back a structure of unsatisfactorily assembled<br />

fragments.” 102 Such a messy picture was unacceptable in Linforth’s day, and, as<br />

a result, Linforth’s analyses have been ignored and <strong>the</strong>ir consequences have not<br />

been pursued. The picture of Orphism and <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> that emerges from<br />

a careful analysis of <strong>the</strong> evidence lacks <strong>the</strong> neat and unified outline presented by<br />

<strong>the</strong> reconstruction in terms of a doctrine of original sin and a proto-Protestant<br />

sect. The evidence is less distorted, however, because it is not all crammed into<br />

a single framework. I have given some tentative suggestions about <strong>the</strong> ways in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> evidence may be seen to reflect <strong>the</strong> retellings of <strong>the</strong> dismemberment<br />

myth over time and <strong>the</strong> ways in which <strong>the</strong> gold tablets might be interpreted, but<br />

such outlines could certainly be fur<strong>the</strong>r fleshed out.<br />

CONCLUSION: BURYING THE REMAINS<br />

I shall have to traverse ground which has been churned to deep and<br />

slippery mud by <strong>the</strong> heavy feet of contending scholars; ground, also,<br />

where those in a hurry are liable to trip over <strong>the</strong> partially decayed remains<br />

of dead <strong>the</strong>ories that have not yet been decently interred. We shall be wise,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, to move slowly, and to pick our steps ra<strong>the</strong>r carefully among <strong>the</strong><br />

litter. 103<br />

Dodds’ warning about <strong>the</strong> perils of research on Orphism remains apt, and since<br />

his time <strong>the</strong> mud has been fur<strong>the</strong>r churned and more <strong>the</strong>ories have slipped into<br />

ruin, leaving behind <strong>the</strong>ir partially decayed remains. One such relic that continues<br />

to trip up <strong>the</strong> passerby is <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong>, left over from <strong>the</strong> proto-Protestant<br />

model of Orphism that dominated <strong>the</strong> scholarship in <strong>the</strong> first half of this century. It<br />

is time that it be decently laid to rest.<br />

Morford and Lenardon’s introductory textbook, with its version of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

myth from “<strong>the</strong> Orphic bible,” 104 is hardly alone in perpetuating this error. The<br />

standard references for <strong>the</strong> professional classicist are no better, and in most cases<br />

worse, since most have not been updated since <strong>the</strong> forties or fifties. The Pauly-<br />

Wissowa article on Orphism and <strong>the</strong> Roscher Lexicon of <strong>Myth</strong>ology on <strong>Zagreus</strong>,<br />

just to name two of <strong>the</strong> most prominent, both contain accounts of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong><br />

myth that place it at <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong> Orphic puritans’ doctrine of original sin. 105<br />

The most recent works by <strong>the</strong> experts on <strong>the</strong> subject are beginning to lean towards<br />

102. Cameron 1942:458.<br />

103. Dodds 1951:136.<br />

104. Morford and Lenardon 1999:280.<br />

105. Ziegler in P-W, cols. 1354, 1381–82; Schmidt in Roscher, vol. VI, col. 535. Cf. Dodds’<br />

assessment of <strong>the</strong> Pauly-Wissowa article: “A spirited counter-attack on this ‘reactionary’ scepticism<br />

was delivered in 1942 by Ziegler, representing <strong>the</strong> Old Guard of pan-Orphists, in <strong>the</strong> guise of an<br />

article in a work of reference” (Dodds 1951:168, n. 79). Even <strong>the</strong> new (1996) Oxford Classical<br />

Dictionary entry by Fritz Graf includes <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth as <strong>the</strong> centerpiece of Orphic literature<br />

(OCD s.v. Orphic literature).


70<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

<strong>the</strong> abolishment of <strong>the</strong> old <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth, but <strong>the</strong> qualified statements of such<br />

scholars as Burkert, Graf, and West do not go far enough. West, for example,<br />

removes <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth from <strong>the</strong> earliest of Orphic <strong>the</strong>ogonies and accepts (in<br />

his footnotes, if not in <strong>the</strong> main text) most of <strong>the</strong> arguments of Linforth regarding<br />

<strong>the</strong> evidence. Never<strong>the</strong>less, he places <strong>the</strong> story in <strong>the</strong> second oldest <strong>the</strong>ogony and<br />

continues to give it pride of place in Orphic doctrine. “According to <strong>the</strong> Eudemian<br />

Theogony, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, mankind came into being from <strong>the</strong> soot deposited by<br />

<strong>the</strong> smoke from <strong>the</strong> blasted Titans. This must have been given as a reason why<br />

we are sinful creatures who must seek salvation through purification.” 106<br />

Burkert, followed by o<strong>the</strong>rs, has begun to reconstruct <strong>the</strong> evidence for Orphism<br />

according to paradigms of religion different from <strong>the</strong> standard Christian<br />

model used at <strong>the</strong> turn of <strong>the</strong> century. These scholars recognize Orphism as a<br />

modern term to describe a range of counter-cultural religious movements which<br />

frequently attributed <strong>the</strong>ir religious ideas to <strong>the</strong> authority of <strong>the</strong> mythical poet<br />

Orpheus. 107 As a result, <strong>the</strong>se scholars have begun to de-emphasize <strong>the</strong> importance<br />

of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth in Orphic and Dionysiac mythology. Burkert cautiously<br />

admits that, “as for Dionysos, <strong>the</strong>re is a rich variety of Bacchic mythology, but<br />

with regard to mysteries one tale has commanded attention, perhaps too exclusively:<br />

<strong>the</strong> story of Chthonian Dionysus born from Persephone and slaughtered<br />

by <strong>the</strong> Titans, ancestors of man.” 108 This relic of an outdated paradigm has done<br />

more than simply command undue attention; it has obstructed <strong>the</strong> understanding<br />

of ancient Greek Orphism, because it was used to define <strong>the</strong> essence of Orphism.<br />

Despite <strong>the</strong> recent shift in <strong>the</strong> scholarship, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> myth persists, particularly<br />

in <strong>the</strong> interpretation of <strong>the</strong> original cornerstone of <strong>the</strong> reconstructed Orphism, <strong>the</strong><br />

“Orphic” gold tablets. This myth of <strong>Zagreus</strong> must be torn apart, and <strong>the</strong> fragments<br />

of evidence collected and restored to <strong>the</strong>ir context so that <strong>the</strong> various uses and<br />

metamorphoses of <strong>the</strong> Greek myth of Dionysos may be recovered.<br />

University of Chicago<br />

rgedmond@midway.uchicago.edu<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY<br />

106. West 1983:246. He lists this myth as one of <strong>the</strong> two major contributions of Orphism to<br />

Greek religion. “Its mythology was not exclusive to it, though it did provide <strong>the</strong> main channel of<br />

transmission for two major myths, <strong>the</strong> Time-cosmogony and <strong>the</strong> murder of Dionysus by <strong>the</strong> Titans”<br />

(West 1983:263).<br />

107. Cf. West, “It is a fallacy to suppose that all ‘Orphic’ poems and rituals are related to each<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r or that <strong>the</strong>y are to be interpreted as different manifestations of a single religious movement. . . .<br />

There was no doctrinal criterion for ascription to Orpheus, and no copyright restriction. It was a<br />

device for conferring antiquity and authority upon a text that stood in need of <strong>the</strong>m” (West 1983:3).<br />

See also: Burkert 1975, 1977, 1982; Detienne 1975; Redfield 1991; Sabbatucci 1975, 1979. The<br />

OCD article by Graf on Orphism follows this trend as well.<br />

108. Burkert 1987:73.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 71<br />

Alderink, L. 1981. Creation and Salvation in Ancient Orphism. American Classical<br />

Studies 8. Chico, Calif.<br />

Ber<strong>the</strong>lot, M. 1888. Collection des anciens alchimistes grecs. Paris.<br />

Bianchi, U. 1966. “Pêché originel et pêché ‘antécédent.’ ” Revue de l’histoire des<br />

religions 170: 119–26.<br />

Boyancé, P. 1963. “Note sur la FROURA platonicienne.” Revue de philologie 37: 7–11.<br />

Brisson, L. 1985. “Les théogonies orphiques et le papyrus de Derveni.” Revue de<br />

l’histoire des religions 202: 389–420.<br />

. 1992. “Le corps ‘dionysiaque.’ L’anthropogonie décrite dans le Commentaire<br />

sur le Phédon de Platon (1, par. 3–6) attribué àOlympiodore est-elle orphique?” In<br />

SOFIHS MAIHTORES / Chercheurs de Sagesse: Hommage à Jean Pepin, Institut<br />

d’Études Augustiniennes, 483–99. Paris.<br />

. 1995. Orphée et l’orphisme dans l’antiquité gréco-romaine. Variorum Collected<br />

Studies Series. Brookfield, Vt.<br />

Burkert, W. 1975. “Le laminette aurée: Da Orfeo a Lampone.” In Orfismo in Magna<br />

Grecia: Atti del quattordicesimo convegno di studi sulla Magna Grecia, 81–104.<br />

Napoli.<br />

. 1977. “Orphism and Bacchic Mysteries: New Evidence and Old Problems of<br />

Interpretation.” In Protocol for <strong>the</strong> Center for Hermeneutical Studies in Hellenistic<br />

and Modern Culture: Colloquy 28: 1–10.<br />

. 1982. “Craft Versus Sect: The Problem of Orphics and Pythagoreans.” In B. F.<br />

Meyer and E. P. Sanders, eds., Jewish and Christian Self-Definition, vol. 3, 1–22.<br />

London.<br />

. 1985. Greek Religion: Archaic and Classical. Trans. J. Raffan. Oxford.<br />

. 1987. Ancient Mystery Cults. Cambridge, Mass.<br />

Cameron, A. 1942. “Review of The Arts of Orpheus by Ivan M. Linforth.” AJA: 455–60.<br />

Casadio, G. 1986. “Adversaria Orphica et Orientalia.” Studi e materiali di storia delle<br />

religioni 52: 291–322.<br />

. 1987. “Antropologia orfico-dionisiaca nel culto di Tebe, Corinto e Sicione.”<br />

In F. Vattioni, ed., Sangue e Antropologia: Riti e Culto, 191–260. Roma.<br />

Comparetti, D. 1879, 1880. In F. S. Cavallari, Notizie degli Scavi, 1879: 156ff., 1880:<br />

152ff.<br />

. 1882. “The Petelia Gold Tablet.” JHS 3: 111–18.<br />

. 1910. Laminette Orfiche. Firenze.<br />

Creuzer, F. 1822. Symbolik und <strong>Myth</strong>ologie der alten Völker besonders der Griechen.<br />

Leipzig and Darmstadt.<br />

Detienne, M. 1975. “Les chemins de la déviance: Orphisme, dionysisme et pythagorisme.”<br />

In Orfismo in Magna Grecia: Atti del quattordicesimo convegno di studi<br />

sulla Magna Grecia, 49–79. Napoli.<br />

. 1979. Dionysos Slain. Trans. M. and L. Muellner. Baltimore.<br />

Dieterich, A. 1891. De hymnis orphicis capitula quinque. Marburg.<br />

. 1893. Nekyia: Beiträge zur Erklärung der Neuentdeckten Petrusapokalypse.<br />

Leipzig.<br />

Dodds, E. R. 1951. The Greeks and <strong>the</strong> Irrational. Berkeley.<br />

Festugière, A. J. 1936. “Comptes rendus bibliographiques: Guthrie (W.K.C.) Orpheus<br />

and Greek Religion.” Rev. Ét. Grec.: 306–10.<br />

Finamore, J. 1987. “The Orphic Labyrinth: The Orphic Poems by M. L. West.” Helios<br />

14: 59–63.


72<br />

CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY Volume 18/No. 1/April 1999<br />

Franz, G. 1836. “Epigrafe greca sopra lamina d’oro spettante al sig. Millingen.”<br />

Bullettino dell’instituto di corrispondenza archeologica, 149–50.<br />

Frazer, J. G. 1912. The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic and Religion, Part 5, vol. 1:<br />

Spirits of <strong>the</strong> Corn and of <strong>the</strong> Wild. 3rd ed. London.<br />

Goettling, C. 1843. Narratio de oraculo Trophonii. Ienae.<br />

Graf, F. 1993. “Dionysian and Orphic Eschatology: New Texts and Old Questions.” In<br />

Faraone and Carpenter, eds., Masks of Dionysos, 239–58. Ithaca.<br />

. 1996. “Orphic Literature.” In Hornblower and Spawforth, eds., The Oxford<br />

Classical Dictionary, 3rd ed., 1078–79. Oxford.<br />

Guthrie, W. K. C. 1952. Orpheus and Greek Religion. 2nd ed. London.<br />

Harrison, J. 1922. Prolegomena to <strong>the</strong> Study of Greek Religion. Princeton.<br />

Jeanmaire, H. 1939. Couroi et Couretes. Lille.<br />

Johnston, S. I., and T. J. McNiven. 1996. “Dionysos and <strong>the</strong> Underworld in Toledo.”<br />

MH 53: 25–34.<br />

Kern, O. 1922. Orphicorum Fragmenta. Berlin.<br />

Linforth, I. 1941. The Arts of Orpheus. Berkeley.<br />

Lobeck, C. A. 1829. Aglaophamus. Darmstadt.<br />

Macchioro, V. 1930. From Orpheus to Paul: A History of Orphism. NewYork.<br />

Maury, L.-F. A. 1857. Histoire des religions de la Grèce antique. Paris.<br />

Morford, M. P. O., and R. J. Lenardon. 1999. Classical <strong>Myth</strong>ology. 6th edition. New<br />

York and London.<br />

Nilsson, M. 1935. “Early Orphism and Kindred Movements.” Harvard Theological<br />

Review 28: 181–230.<br />

Parker, R. 1983. Miasma: Pollution and Purity in Early Greek Religion. Oxford.<br />

Redfield, J. 1991. “The Politics of Immortality.” In Bourgeaud, ed., Orphisme et Orphée:<br />

En l’honneur de Jean Rudhardt. Recherches et rencontres 3: 103–17. Geneva.<br />

Rohde, E. 1925. Psyche: The Cult of Souls and Belief in Immortality among <strong>the</strong> Greeks.<br />

Trans. W. B. Hillis. London.<br />

Rose, H. J. 1936. “A Study of Pindar, Fragment 133 Bergk, 127 Bowra.” In C. Bailey et<br />

al., eds., Greek Poetry and Life: Essays presented to Gilbert Murray, 79–96. Oxford.<br />

. 1943. “The Grief of Persephone.” Harvard Theological Review 36: 247–50.<br />

Sabbatucci, D. 1975. “Criteri per una valutazione scientifica del ‘mistico-orfico’ nella<br />

Magna Grecia.” In Orfismo in Magna Grecia: Atti del quattordicesimo convegno<br />

di studi sulla Magna Grecia, 35–49. Napoli.<br />

. 1979. Saggio sul misticismo greco. 2nd ed. Rome.<br />

Scalera McClintock, G. 1995. “L’antica natura titanic. Variazioni sul mito greco della<br />

colpa.” Filosofia e Teologia 9.2: 307–25.<br />

Schmidt, J. 1884–1937. “<strong>Zagreus</strong>.” In W. H. Roscher, Ausfürliches Lexikon der griechischen<br />

und römischen <strong>Myth</strong>ologie, vol. 6, col. 532–38. Leipzig and Berlin.<br />

Seaford, R. 1986. “Immortality, Salvation, and <strong>the</strong> Elements.” HSCP 90: 1–26.<br />

Smith, J. Z. 1990. Drudgery Divine: On <strong>the</strong> Comparison of Early Christianities and<br />

<strong>the</strong> Religions of Late Antiquity. Chicago.<br />

Versnel, H. S. 1990–1993. Inconsistencies in Greek Religion. Vols. 1 and 2. Leiden.<br />

Watmough, J. R. 1934. Orphism. Cambridge.<br />

Welcker, S. G. 1860. Griechische Götterlehre. Göttingen.<br />

West, M. L. 1983. The Orphic Poems. Oxford.


EDMONDS: <strong>Tearing</strong> <strong>Apart</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Zagreus</strong> <strong>Myth</strong> 73<br />

Westerink, L. G. 1977. The Greek Commentaries on Plato’s Phaedo. 2 vols. Amsterdam,<br />

Oxford, and New York.<br />

Zeller, E. 1881. A History of Greek Philosophy. Trans. S. F. Alleyne from vol. 1, 4th<br />

ed., 1876. London.<br />

Ziegler, K. 1894–1980. “Orphische Dichtung.” In Pauly-Wissowa, Realencyclopäde der<br />

classischen Altertumswissenschaft, cols. 1322–1417. Stuttgart.<br />

Ziolkowski, J. M. 1997. “Introduction: The Making of Domenico Comparetti’s Vergil<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages.” In D. Comparetti, Vergil in <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages, trans. E. F. M.<br />

Benecke. Princeton.<br />

Zuntz, G. 1971. Persephone: Three Essays on Religion and Thought in Magna Graecia.<br />

Oxford.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!