10.05.2014 Views

Yourgrau P. A world without time.. the forgotten legacy of Goedel and Einstein (Basic Books, 2005)(ISBN 0465092934)(176s)_PPop_

Yourgrau P. A world without time.. the forgotten legacy of Goedel and Einstein (Basic Books, 2005)(ISBN 0465092934)(176s)_PPop_

Yourgrau P. A world without time.. the forgotten legacy of Goedel and Einstein (Basic Books, 2005)(ISBN 0465092934)(176s)_PPop_

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

So is G a <strong>the</strong>orem <strong>of</strong> FA? We assume first that FA is consistent. If it were not consistent, it<br />

would obviously be useless for ma<strong>the</strong>matics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> game would be over. Assume next<br />

that G is provable in FA. That means that some sequence <strong>of</strong> formulas S <strong>of</strong> FA is a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

G. Using <strong>the</strong> abbreviation we introduced earlier, that means that Bew(S, G). But we saw<br />

earlier that Godel had shown that <strong>the</strong> function, Bew(x, y), when coded into natural<br />

numbers, yields a recursive function <strong>and</strong> is thus rep-resentable in FA. The representation<br />

occurs via <strong>the</strong> arithmetization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntax <strong>of</strong> FA, so corresponding to a given syntactical<br />

truth Bew(x, y) <strong>of</strong> MFA, <strong>the</strong>re is an arithmetical truth Bew(x, y) <strong>of</strong> IA that corresponds to a<br />

formula Bew(x, y) in FA that can be interpreted as saying that <strong>the</strong> sequence <strong>of</strong> formulas<br />

with Godel number x is a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> formula with Godel number y, <strong>and</strong> this formula,<br />

Bew(x, y), is a <strong>the</strong>orem <strong>of</strong> FA. Thus if G is provable in FA for some s, <strong>the</strong>n Bew(s, g) is a<br />

<strong>the</strong>orem <strong>of</strong> FA (where s is <strong>the</strong> numeral in FA for s, <strong>the</strong> Godel number <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sequence <strong>of</strong><br />

formulas S that constitutes <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> G, <strong>and</strong> g is <strong>the</strong> numeral in FA for g, <strong>the</strong> Godel<br />

number <strong>of</strong> G). But as we saw at <strong>the</strong> beginning, what G states is that formula number g<br />

(i.e., G) is unprovable, that is, for any sequence x, it is not <strong>the</strong> case that Bew(x, g). Using<br />

a little logic, however, it follows from Bew(s, g) that <strong>the</strong>re exists a sequence <strong>of</strong> formulas x<br />

such that Bew(x, g), hence, using a bit more logic, that it is not <strong>the</strong> case that for any<br />

sequence x it is not <strong>the</strong> case that Bew(x, g). That is, if something is a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> formula<br />

number g, it can't be that <strong>the</strong>re is no pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> g. But since G can be interpreted as saying<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re is no pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> g, this last<br />

conclusion is evidently equivalent to not-G, <strong>the</strong> negation <strong>of</strong> G, <strong>and</strong> since it was derived,<br />

logically, from Bew(s, g), which, by hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, is a <strong>the</strong>orem, it too is a <strong>the</strong>orem. That is,<br />

not-G is also a <strong>the</strong>orem. The assumption that G is provable, <strong>the</strong>n, leads to <strong>the</strong> conclusion<br />

that both G <strong>and</strong> not-G are <strong>the</strong>orems, i.e., that both are provable in FA. Hence FA is<br />

inconsistent. But <strong>the</strong> assumption was that FA is consistent. If FA is consistent, <strong>the</strong>n, G is<br />

not provable. That is <strong>the</strong> first part <strong>of</strong> GodePs <strong>the</strong>orem.<br />

How about not-G? Godel assumed for this half <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>orem that FA is not just consistent<br />

but "omega-consistent." (Omega is <strong>the</strong> traditional symbol for <strong>the</strong> natural numbers.) If a<br />

system is omega-consistent, <strong>the</strong> following cannot happen: some statement F( ) is provable<br />

individually <strong>of</strong> each natural number, i.e., F(0), F(l), F(2), etc., but it cannot be proved<br />

that for all x, <strong>the</strong> statement F(x) is true. Clearly, if FA is to represent all <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

numbers via its coordination with IA, omega-consistency if nonnegotiable. If not-G is a<br />

<strong>the</strong>orem, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>of</strong> FA, given what G says, it follows that <strong>the</strong> following is provable: it is not<br />

<strong>the</strong> case that every sequence <strong>of</strong> formulas number x does not constitute a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> formula<br />

number g. But we have already learned that formula number g, i.e., G, is not provable in<br />

FA. Thus, for every individual sequence <strong>of</strong> formulas x, not-Bew(x, g) holds. Given <strong>the</strong><br />

representability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> function Bew(x, y) in FA, it follows that for every natural number x,<br />

it is provable in FA that not-Bew(x, g). Since we are assuming that FA is omega-consistent,<br />

it follows that it cannot also be provable that it is not <strong>the</strong> case that for all sequences <strong>of</strong><br />

formulas x, not-Bew(x, g) holds. But <strong>the</strong> latter is precisely what we assumed when we<br />

agreed for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> argument that not-G is a <strong>the</strong>orem. If FA is omega-consistent, <strong>the</strong>n it<br />

follows that not-G is also not provable. This is <strong>the</strong> second half <strong>of</strong> Godel's <strong>the</strong>orem. Barkley<br />

Rosser later showed that one can construct an unprovable statement assuming only<br />

consistency, not omega-consistency.<br />

But Godel wasn't done yet. He was able to prove, quickly, his second incompleteness<br />

<strong>the</strong>orem, also on <strong>the</strong> assumption that FA is consistent. Using techniques similar to his pro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first <strong>the</strong>orem, Godel proved easily that if FA is consistent, it cannot prove that it is

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!