27.11.2014 Views

Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation

Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation

Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

HORIZONS<br />

appear has been established by conditions or laws which govern appearance. In<br />

Kant, for instance, <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon’s appearance is determined in<br />

advance by “formal conditions,” viz. <strong>the</strong> coupling <strong>of</strong> intuition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept. In<br />

Leibniz, <strong>the</strong> law is Sufficient Reason, or ra<strong>the</strong>r Sufficient Reason is <strong>the</strong> law which<br />

governs phenomena. In both, <strong>the</strong>re are appearances which would be impossible,<br />

realities which cannot measure up to this st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>of</strong> phenomenality <strong>and</strong> thus are<br />

denied <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> phenomena (SP 80–1/103–4). In both cases, <strong>the</strong> phenomenon is<br />

conditioned by <strong>the</strong> finitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> knower: <strong>the</strong> “formal conditions” or “power <strong>of</strong><br />

knowing” (Kant), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> Sufficient Reason (Leibniz). For both Kant <strong>and</strong><br />

Leibniz, <strong>the</strong> “possibility [<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon] does not follow from <strong>the</strong> phenomenon,<br />

but from <strong>the</strong> conditions set for any phenomenon” (SP 81/103). Thus, in such<br />

“metaphysical” systems, “<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> appearing never belongs to what appears,<br />

nor phenomenality to <strong>the</strong> phenomenon” (SP 83/104); ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> appearance<br />

is determined by <strong>the</strong> knowing ego: “Any phenomenon is possible that grants itself to<br />

<strong>the</strong> finitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> knowing <strong>and</strong> its requirements” (SP 81/104, emphasis<br />

added). The object/phenomenon does not appear on its own terms, but under<br />

conditions established by <strong>the</strong> ego.<br />

We can appreciate Marion’s argument if we keep returning to our limit or test<br />

case: <strong>the</strong> religious phenomenon. Within a “metaphysical” system, God must be<br />

conceptualized, made an object (objectified), which can only happen in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

formal conditions <strong>of</strong> knowing determined by <strong>the</strong> experiencing ego. Thus, <strong>the</strong> infinite<br />

is reduced to <strong>the</strong> finite; <strong>the</strong> transcendent is absorbed into <strong>the</strong> immanent; <strong>the</strong><br />

“impossible” is forced to appear within <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> possibility, under certain<br />

conditions <strong>and</strong> laws.<br />

In contrast to such “metaphysical” systems, 57 Marion suggests that phenomenology’s<br />

“principle <strong>of</strong> all principles,” or at least a certain reading <strong>of</strong> it, <strong>of</strong>fers a<br />

phenomenality without condition, providing liberation <strong>and</strong> deliverance (relève) from <strong>the</strong><br />

law (le droit) <strong>of</strong> phenomenality <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time restoring <strong>the</strong> phenomenon’s<br />

rights with its own justification (SP 84/105). This unconditioned giving is signaled in<br />

<strong>the</strong> “principle <strong>of</strong> all principles,” which states<br />

that every originary presentive intuition is a legitimizing source <strong>of</strong> cognition, that<br />

everything originarily (so to speak, in its “personal” actuality) <strong>of</strong>fered to us in<br />

“intuition” is to be accepted simply as what it is presented as being, but also only within<br />

<strong>the</strong> limits in which it is presented <strong>the</strong>re. (Id I 44)<br />

In contrast to external conditions imposed upon <strong>the</strong> phenomenon (as in Kant <strong>and</strong><br />

Leibniz), Marion argues, in phenomenology it is <strong>the</strong> phenomenon itself which sets<br />

<strong>the</strong> rules for appearance, which determines its own appearance <strong>and</strong> is its own source<br />

<strong>of</strong> legitimation or justification. The phenomenon appears on its own terms, “on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis <strong>of</strong> itself [à partir de soi-même] as a pure <strong>and</strong> perfect appearance <strong>of</strong> itself, <strong>and</strong> not on<br />

<strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r than itself which would not appear (a reason)” (SP 84/105). As<br />

such, it appears without horizon or background or presupposition: it is a donation, an<br />

originary giving.<br />

34

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!