07.02.2015 Views

The Expected Utility Model: Its Variants, Purposes, Evidence and ...

The Expected Utility Model: Its Variants, Purposes, Evidence and ...

The Expected Utility Model: Its Variants, Purposes, Evidence and ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Schoemaker: <strong>The</strong> <strong>Expected</strong> <strong>Utility</strong> <strong>Model</strong> 531<br />

of tosses required to get heads. Say this<br />

number is n, the payoff will then be $2",<br />

which means the game has many possible<br />

outcomes, namely: $2, 4, 8, . . . ,2n, with<br />

probabilities Yz, %, %, . . . ,(Yz)n, respectively.<br />

Interestingly, the expected monetary<br />

value (EV) of this gamble is infinite,<br />

m<br />

since Z) ($5) n2n = m.<br />

n =l<br />

To explain why most people value this<br />

infinite EV game below $100, or even $20,<br />

Bernoulli proposed that people maximize<br />

expected utility rather than expected<br />

monetary value. <strong>The</strong> utility function U(x)<br />

he proposed was logarithmic, exhibiting<br />

diminishing increases in utility for equal<br />

increments in ~ealth.~ Bernoulli then proceeded<br />

to show that for a logarithmic<br />

function the game's expected utility, i.e.,<br />

B(Yz) nlog,(2n), is indeed finite.3 However,<br />

he did not address the issue of how to measure<br />

utility, nor why his expectation principle<br />

would be rational. As such, Bernoulli's<br />

theory is mostly a descriptive model,<br />

even though the expectation principle at<br />

the time may have enjoyed much face validity<br />

normatively. It was not until John<br />

von Neumann <strong>and</strong> Oskar Morgenstern<br />

(1944) that expected utility maximization<br />

was formally proved to be a rational<br />

decision criterion, i.e., derivable from<br />

several appealing axioms. In their own<br />

words they "practically defined numerical<br />

utility as being that thing for which<br />

a calculus of expectations is legitimate"<br />

<strong>The</strong> exact function proposed by Bernoulli was<br />

U(x) = blog[(a + x)la]. Note that dU(x)ldx =<br />

bl(a+ x), which is inversely proportional to wealth.<br />

Also, d2U(x)ldxZ < 0. Bernoulli's logarithmic function<br />

was later suggested by Gustav Fechner (1860)<br />

for subjective magnitudes in general.<br />

A proof of the convergence of this infinite series<br />

is offered in my book on expected utility experiments<br />

(1980, p. 12). Note that the certainty equivalence<br />

of this game, i.e., the amount ce for which U(ce)=<br />

H(h)"U(2"),will be finite for many other concave<br />

utility functions as well, although not for all. <strong>The</strong><br />

same holds for the maximum bid (m)one would pay<br />

for the Petersburg game, which is determined from<br />

the equation U(0)= H(%)nU(2n- m).<br />

(1944, p. 28). In this sense, von Neumann-<br />

Morgenstern (NM) utility theory is quite<br />

different from Bernoulli's conceptualization.<br />

Moreover NM utility applies to any<br />

type of outcomes, money being a special<br />

case.<br />

Specifically, von Neumann <strong>and</strong> Morgenstern<br />

proved that five basic axioms imply<br />

the existence of numerical utilities for<br />

outcomes whose expectations for lotteries<br />

preserve the preference order over lotteries:<br />

i.e., greater expected utility corresponds<br />

to higher preference. <strong>The</strong>ir utility<br />

function is unique up to positive linear<br />

transformations, meaning that if the function<br />

U(x) represents a person's risk preferences<br />

then so will U*(x) if <strong>and</strong> only if<br />

U*(x) = aU(x) + b for numbers a > 0<br />

<strong>and</strong> b. Jacob Marschak (1950) reformulated<br />

the NM axioms <strong>and</strong> proof, <strong>and</strong> proposed<br />

them as a definition of rational behavior<br />

under risk. In light of later<br />

discussions, the NM axioms are informally<br />

stated below.<br />

1. Preferences for lotteries L, are <br />

complete <strong>and</strong> transitive. Com-<br />

pleteness means that for any <br />

choice between lotteries L1 <strong>and</strong> L2 <br />

either L1 is preferred to L2 (de- <br />

noted L1 L2), L2 Ll or both are <br />

equally attractive. Transitivity im- <br />

plies that if L1 L2 <strong>and</strong> L2 L3 <br />

then L1 L3 (where denotes "at <br />

least as preferred as"). <br />

2. If xl x2 x3, then there exists <br />

some probability p between zero <br />

<strong>and</strong> one such that the lottery<br />

&:: is as attractive as receiv- <br />

ing x2 for certain.<br />

3. If objects xl <strong>and</strong> x2 (being either <br />

risky or riskless prospects) are <br />

equally attractive, then lottery<br />

eX1eX2<br />

<strong>and</strong> lottery will<br />

P x3 1-P x3 <br />

also be equally attractive (for any <br />

values of p <strong>and</strong> x3).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!