10.07.2015 Views

Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality. - Ancient Philosophy ...

Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality. - Ancient Philosophy ...

Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality. - Ancient Philosophy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

particular kind <strong>of</strong> intermediary <strong>and</strong> relation involved, <strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y canaccount for <strong>the</strong> peculiarities <strong>of</strong> intentionality.Using this triad as a basis, it is easy to show that <strong>Aristotle</strong> was fullyaware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> intentionality <strong>and</strong> attempted to <strong>of</strong>fer his own solutionto it. It is not to be found in his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> sensation, though, asBrentano <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs have thought, but in his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> phantasia. To see this,let us begin briefly with <strong>Aristotle</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> sensation.II. <strong>Aristotle</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> SensationThe passage from Psychology from an Empirical St<strong>and</strong>point where Brentan<strong>of</strong>irst appeals to intentionality is well-known:Every psychical phenomenon is characterized by what <strong>the</strong> scholastics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Middle Ages usedto call <strong>the</strong> intentional (or mental) in-existence <strong>of</strong> an object, <strong>and</strong> which we might call—althoughwith expressions which are not entirely unambiguous—relation to a content, direction upon anobject (which is here not to be understood as something real), or immanent-object-hood. Eachcontains something as an object within itself, although not in <strong>the</strong> same way. In presentation,something is presented; in judgement, something is accepted or rejected; in love, loved; in hate,hated; in desire, desired; <strong>and</strong> so on. 9 (Brentano [1874] 1924–25, 1.124–25)Much less known, however, is a footnote to this very passage, whereBrentano acknowledges his intellectual debts, tracing <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notionthrough <strong>Aristotle</strong>, Philo, <strong>the</strong> Neoplatonists, Augustine, Anselm, <strong>and</strong> ThomasAquinas. He begins with <strong>Aristotle</strong>:<strong>Aristotle</strong> had already spoken <strong>of</strong> this psychical indwelling. In his books On <strong>the</strong> Soul he says thatwhat is experienced, as something experienced, is in <strong>the</strong> experiencing subject; that <strong>the</strong> sensereceives what is experienced without <strong>the</strong> matter; <strong>and</strong> that what is thought is in <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing.(Brentano [1874] 1924–25, 1.125, note *)Here Brentano identifies some <strong>of</strong> <strong>Aristotle</strong>’s most central doctrines in On <strong>the</strong>Soul as precursors <strong>of</strong> his own conception <strong>of</strong> intentionality. Years later, in aletter to one <strong>of</strong> his former students, Brentano would again reflect on <strong>the</strong>sedoctrines <strong>and</strong> conclude: “wasn’t he thinking essentially <strong>the</strong> same way asus?” 10Brentano is not alone. To <strong>the</strong> extent that intentionality is discussed inconnection with <strong>Aristotle</strong> at all, <strong>the</strong> same doctrines are st<strong>and</strong>ardly cited. 11 But<strong>the</strong> evidence is not encouraging when viewed in context. In fact, Brentano9 In what follows, all translations are my own.10 From a letter to Anton Marty, dated 17 March 1905 (reprinted in Brentano 1930, 88–89).11 Geyser 1917, 158–59; Simon 1934, 12–27; Rohmer 1951, 13; Anscombe <strong>and</strong> Geach 1961,55; Oehler 1962, 188–201; Veatch 1974, 83–84; Owens 1963, 31–32, 218–28; [1976]1981, 74–80; 1981, passim; Richardson 1983, 275–79; Basti 1986; Modrak 1987, 32 <strong>and</strong>148; Münch 1993, 42–63; Shields 1995, esp. 322–30. (Properly speaking, we should alsoadd Burnyeat 1992 to this group, even though intentionality is not his principal concern.)A few o<strong>the</strong>r scholars cite a passage from On Memory <strong>and</strong> Recollection we will discussbelow (see pp. 258–60, esp. n. 21).seems to have realized this himself in later years. Although he would continuethroughout his life to credit <strong>Aristotle</strong> for his conception <strong>of</strong> intentionality,as early as 1889 he stops citing On <strong>the</strong> Soul, turning instead to a textfrom <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics (5.15, 1021a26–b3). 12 This is not <strong>the</strong> place to investigatethis fur<strong>the</strong>r claim, but it is equally hopeless as evidence for <strong>the</strong> concept<strong>of</strong> intentionality. 13The first doctrine cited in <strong>the</strong> passage above holds that <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> sensationis in some sense present in <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> sensation. This derives from On<strong>the</strong> Soul 3.2, where <strong>Aristotle</strong> claims that (i) <strong>the</strong> functioning or activity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>sensible object is “one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same” (≤ aÈtØ ka‹ m¤a) as <strong>the</strong> functioning<strong>of</strong> sensation (425b26–27, cf. 426a15); <strong>and</strong> (ii) <strong>the</strong>se occur toge<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> perceiver(426a10-11). It is easy to underst<strong>and</strong> Brentano’s temptation. To saythat sensation, which occurs in <strong>the</strong> perceiver, is <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> functioning<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sensible object seems to make <strong>the</strong> object, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is an object <strong>of</strong>sensation, immanent in <strong>the</strong> act. Indeed, it seems to constitute <strong>the</strong> act <strong>and</strong> soexplain what that act is about.The difficulty is that this doctrine, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole structure <strong>of</strong> act <strong>and</strong>object in <strong>Aristotle</strong>’s psychology, comes straight from his more general viewson causation. A version <strong>of</strong> this doctrine applies to every case <strong>of</strong> causal interaction,whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> an object, <strong>the</strong> digestion <strong>of</strong> a biscuit, or <strong>the</strong>warming <strong>of</strong> a kettle. In fact, in applying it to perception, <strong>Aristotle</strong> explicitlyappeals to this more general principle (426a2-11), developed at length inPhysics 3.3. There <strong>Aristotle</strong> argues that in every causal interaction <strong>the</strong> functioning<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> agent is “one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same” as <strong>the</strong> functioning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> patient<strong>and</strong> present in <strong>the</strong> patient (202a13-16). If this doctrine entailed <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong>intentionality, it would entail it for every case <strong>of</strong> causal interaction across <strong>the</strong>board.More serious still is <strong>the</strong> fact that this doctrine can apply to only a h<strong>and</strong>ful<strong>of</strong> intentional states at most. It may be reasonable to identify <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong>sensation with its cause. But for a wide range <strong>of</strong> mental states that couldnever work. The contents <strong>of</strong> our dreams, desires, wishes, fears, thoughts <strong>and</strong>plans <strong>of</strong>ten do not correspond to anything in reality, much less <strong>the</strong>ir causes.Thus, whatever this doctrine contributes to his <strong>the</strong>ory, it cannot provide amodel for <strong>the</strong> intentionality <strong>of</strong> mental states in general. It is precisely <strong>the</strong> sort<strong>of</strong> doctrine that leads to <strong>the</strong> inconsistent triad above.12 Brentano 1889, 14 <strong>and</strong> 51, n. 19; <strong>the</strong> 1911 appendix <strong>of</strong> [1874] 1924, 2.133–34, 272; 1930,117; 1933, 133–34, 166–69; 1982, 21–22. The one exception I know <strong>of</strong> is in a private letter(1930, 88–89; cited above on p. 254); but <strong>the</strong>re he is trying to explain what he meantwhen he originally wrote his Psychology (1874), where he did appeal to <strong>the</strong> On <strong>the</strong> Soulpassages.13 Briefly, <strong>the</strong> passage makes a point about linguistic redundancy in certain forms <strong>of</strong> relativedescription, not <strong>the</strong> ontological distinction Brentano takes him to make. For a discussion <strong>of</strong><strong>the</strong>se passages, see my The <strong>Problem</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Intentionality</strong> in <strong>Ancient</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> (n. 8 above).254 VICTOR CASTONARISTOTLE AND THE PROBLEM OF INTENTIONALITY 255

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!