11.07.2015 Views

Adorno-The-Essay-As-Form

Adorno-The-Essay-As-Form

Adorno-The-Essay-As-Form

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>T. W. <strong>Adorno</strong>; Bob Hullot-Kentor; Frederic WillNew German Critique, No. 32. (Spring - Summer, 1984), pp. 151-171.Stable URL:http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0094-033X%28198421%2F22%290%3A32%3C151%3ATEAF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-CNew German Critique is currently published by New German Critique.Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content inthe JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/journals/ngc.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.<strong>The</strong> JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around the world. <strong>The</strong> Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.http://www.jstor.orgThu Sep 20 11:02:26 2007


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong> *by T.W. <strong>Adorno</strong>"Destined, to see the illuminated,not the light."Goethe, PandoraThat in Germany the essay is decried as a hybrid; that it is lacking aconvincing tradition; that its strenuous requirements have only rarelybeen met: all this has been often remarked upon and censured. "<strong>The</strong>essay form has not yet, today, travelled the road to independencewhich its sister, poetry, covered long ago; the road of developmentfrom aprimitive, undifferentiated unitywith science, ethics, and art."'But neither discontent with this situation, nor discontent with thementality that reacts to the situation by fencing up art as a preserve forthe irrational, identifying knowledge with organized science and excludingasimpure anything that does not fit this antithesis: neither discontenthas changed anything in the customary national prejudice.<strong>The</strong> bestowal of the garland "writer" still suffices to exclude fromacademia the person one is praising. Despite the weighty perspicacitythat Simmel and the young Lukics, Kassner and Benjamin entrustedto the essay, to the speculative investigation of specific, culturally predeterminedobjects,' the academic guild only has ptience for philosophythat dresses itself up with the nobility oft e universal, theeverlasting, and today -when possible -with the primal; the culturalartifact is of interest only to the degree that it serves to exemplify* <strong>Adorno</strong>'s "Der <strong>Essay</strong> als <strong>Form</strong>" was written between 1954 and 1958 and first publishedas the lead essay of Nota zur Literatur I in 1958. It is now contained in <strong>Adorno</strong>,Gesammelte Schnzen, 11 (~;ankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1974).<strong>The</strong> essay is publishedhere in English with the permission of Suhrkamp Verlag.1. George Lukiics, Soul and <strong>Form</strong>, trans. Anna Bostock (Cambridge: MIT, 1974),p. 13.2. Ibid.,p. 10."<strong>The</strong> essay isalways concerned with something already formed, oratbest, with something that has been; it is part of its essence that it does not draw somethingnew out of an empty vacuum, but only gives a new order to such things as oncelived. And because he only newly orders them, not forming something new out of theformless, he is bound to them; he must always speakg'the truth" about them, find, thatis, the expression for their essence."


152 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>universal categories, or at the very least allows them to shine through- however little the particular is thereby illuminated. <strong>The</strong> stubbornnesswith which this stereotypical thought survives would be as puzzlingas its emotional rootedness if it were not fed by motives that arestronger than the painful recollection of how much cultivation is missingfrom a culture that historically scarcely recognizes the homme de lettres.In Germany the essay provokes resistance because it is reminiscent ofthe intellectual freedom that, from the time of an unsuccessful andlukewarm Enlightenment, since Leibniz's day, all the way to the presenthas never really emerged, not even under the conditions of formalfreedom; the German Enlightenment was always ready to proclaim, asits essential concern, subordination under whatever higher courts.<strong>The</strong> essay, however, does not permit its domain to be prescribed.Instead of achieving something scientifically, or creating somethingartistically, the effort of the essay reflects a childlike freedom thatcatches fire, without scruple, on what others have already done. <strong>The</strong>essay mirrors what is loved and hated instead of presenting the intellect,on the model of a boundless work ethic, as creatio ex nihilo. Luckand play are essential to the essay. It does not begin with Adam and Evebut with what it wants to discuss; it says what is at issue and stops whereit feels itselfcomplete - not where nothing is left to say. <strong>The</strong>refore it isclassed among the oddities. Its concepts are neither deduced from anyfirst principle nor do they come full circle and arrive at afinal principle.Its interpretations are not philologically hardened and sober, rather -according to the predictable verdict of that vigilant calculating reasonthat hires itself out to stupidity as a guard against intelligence - itoverinterprets. Due to a fear of negativityper se, the subject's effort tobreak through what masks itself as objectivity is branded as idleness.Everything is supposedly much simpler. <strong>The</strong> person who interpretsinstead of unquestioningly accepting and categorizing is slapped withthe charge of intellectualizing as if with a yellow star; his misled anddecadent intelligence is said to subtilize and project meaning wherethere is nothing to interpret. Technician or dreamer, those are thealternatives. Once one lets oneself be terrorized by the prohibition ofgoing beyond the intended meaning of a certain text, one becomes thedupe of the false intentionality that men and things harbor of themselves.Understanding then amounts to nothing more than unwrappingwhat the author wanted to say, or, if need by, tracking down theindividual psychological reactions that the phenomenon indicates.Butjust as it is scarcely possible to figure out what someone at a certaintime and place felt and thought, such insights could not hope to gainanything essential. <strong>The</strong> author's impulses are extinguished in theobjective substance they grasp. <strong>The</strong> objective abundance of signifi-


cations encapsulated within each spiritual phenomenon, if it is toreveal itself, requires from the person receiving them precisely thatspontaneity of subjective fantasy that is chastised in the name of objectivediscipline. Nothing can be interpreted out of aworkwithout at thesame time being interpreted into it. <strong>The</strong> criteria of this process are thecompatibility of the interpretation with the text and with itself and itspower to release the object's expression in the unity of its elements.<strong>The</strong> essay thereby acquires an aesthetic autonomy that is easily criticizedas simply borrowed from art, though it distinguishes itself fromart through its conceptual character and its claim to truth free fromaesthetic semblance. Lukscs failed to recognize this when he called theessay an art form in a letter to Leo Popper that serves as the introductionto Soul and <strong>Form</strong>.3 Neither is the positivist maxim superior toLukscs' thesis, namely the maxim which maintains that what is writtenabout art may claim nothing of art's mode of presentation, nothing,that is, of its autonomy of form. <strong>The</strong> positivist tendency to set up everypossible examinable object in rigid opposition to the knowing subjectremains - in this as in every other instance -caught up with the rigidseparation ofform and content: for it is scarcely possible to speakoftheaesthetic unaesthetically, stripped of any similarity with its object,without becoming narrow-minded and a priori losing touch with theaesthetic object. According to a positivist procedure the content, oncerigidly modelled on the protocol sentence, should be indifferent to itspresentation. Presentation should be conventional, not demanded bythe matter itself. Every impulse of expression -as far as the instinct ofscientific purism is concerned - endangers an objectivity that is saidto spring forth after the subtraction of the subject; such expressionwould thus endanger the authenticity of the material, which is said toprove itself all the better the less it relies on form, even though themeasure of form is precisely its ability to render content purely andwithout addition. In its allergy to forms, as pure accidents, the scientificmind approaches the stupidly dogmatic mind. Positivism's irresponsiblybungled language fancies itself to be responsibly objectiveand adaquate to the matter at hand; the reflection on the spiritualbecomes the privilege of the spiritless.None of these offspring of resentment are simply untruth. If theessay disdains to begin by deriving cultural products from somethingunderlying them, it embroils itself only more intently in the cultureindustry and it falls for the conspicuousness, success and prestige ofproductsdesigned for the market place. Fictional biographies and all therelated commercial writing are no mere degeneration but the perma-3. LukPcs, "On the Nature and <strong>Form</strong> of the <strong>Essay</strong>," in Soul and <strong>Form</strong>, pp. 1- 18.


154 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong>as <strong>Form</strong>nent temptation of a form whose suspicion toward false profundity isno defense against its own turning into skillful superficiality. <strong>The</strong>essay's capitulation is already evident in Sainte-Beuve, from whom thegenre of the modern essay really stems. Such works -alongwith productslike the biographical sketches of Herbert E~lenberg,~ the Germanmodel for a flood of cultural trash-literature, all the way to the filmsabout Rembrandt, Toulouse-Lautrec, and the Holy Bible - have promotedthe neutralizing transformation of cultural artifacts into commodities,a transformation which, in recent cultural history, has irresistablyseized up all that which in the eastern bloc is shamelesslycalled "the cultural heritage." This process is perhaps most striking inthe instance of Stefan Zweig, who in his youth wrote several discerningessays, and who finally, in his book on Balzac, stooped so low as to describethe psychology of the creative artist. Such writing does notcriticize basic abstract concepts, mindless dates, worn-out clich6s, butimplicitly and thereby with the greater complicity, it presupposesthem. <strong>The</strong> detritus of an hermeneutic psychology is fused with commoncategories drawn from the Weltanschauung of the cultural philistines,categories like those of personality and the irrational. Such essaysmistake themselves for that kind of feuilleton journalism with whichmistake themselves for that kind of feuilleton journalism withwhich the enemies of form confuse the form of the essay. Tornitself becomes unfree and sets itself to work in the service of the sociallyperformed needs of its customers. <strong>The</strong> moment of irresponsibility, initself an aspect of every truth that does not exhaust itself in responsibilitytoward the status quo, will account for itselfwhen faced with theneeds of the established consciousness; bad essays are no less conformistthan bad dissertations. Responsibility, however, respects notonly authorities and committees but the object itself.<strong>The</strong> bad essay chats about people instead of opening up the matterat hand; in this the essay form is somewhat complicitous. <strong>The</strong>separation of knowledge from art is irreversible. Only the naivetCof the literary entrepreneur takes no notice of this separation; he thinksof himself as at least an organizational genius, and simply chews upgood art-works into bad ones. With the objectification of the world inthe course of progressing demythologization, science and art haveseparated from each other. A consciousness in which perception andconcept, image and sign would be one is not, if it ever existed, to be recreatedwith a wave of the wand; its restitution would be a return tochaos. Only as the completion of the mediating process would such a4. [Herbert Eulenberg (1 876-1949), author of Schattenbilder (Silhouettes), a collectionof biograptlical miniatures of notables published in 1910. Translator's footnote.]


consciousness be thinkable, as a utopia just as that on which idealistphilosophers since Kant had bestowed the name of creative intuition,and which failed them whenever actual knowledge appealed to it.When philosophy supposes that by borrowing from art it can do awaywith objectifying thought and its history -with what is usually termedthe antithesis of subject and object - and indeed expects that beingitselfwould speak out of a poetic montage of Parmenides and Jungnickel,5itonly approximates a washed-out pseudo-culture. With peasantcunning legitimated as primordiality, it refuses to honor the obligationof conceptual thought to which it has subscribed as soon as it hasemployed concepts in statements and judgments. At the same time itsaesthetic element remains a second-hand thinned-out cultural reminiscenceof Holderlin or Expressionism, or possibly of art nouveau,simplybecause no thought can entrust itself to language as boundlessly andblindly as the idea of a primal utterance deceptively suggests. Out ofthe violence that image and concept do to one another in such writingssprings the jargon of authenticity in which words tremble as thoughpossessed, while remaining secretive about that which possesses them.<strong>The</strong> ambitious transcendence of language beyond its meaning resultsin a meaninglessness that can easily be seized upon by a positivism towhich one thinks oneself superior; and yet, one falls victim to positivismprecisely through that meaninglessness that positivism criticizesand which one shares with it. <strong>The</strong> playing chips of both are thesame. Under the spell of such developments, language, where in thesciences it still dares to stir, approximates pseudo-art; and onlythat scientist proves, negatively, his fidelity to the aesthetic who ingeneral resists language and instead of degrading the word to a mereparaphrase of his calculations prefers the charts that uninhibitedlyadmit the reification of consciousness and so produces a sort of formfor reification without resorting to any apologetic borrowing from art.Of course art was always so interwoven with the dominant tendency ofthe Enlightenment that it has, since antiquity, incorporated scientificdiscoveries in its technique. Yet quantity becomes quality. When techniqueis made absolute in the art-work; when construction becomestotal, eliminating what motivates it and what resists it, expression;when art claims to be science and makes scientific criteria its standard,it sanctions a crude preartistic manipulation of raw material as devoidof meaning as all the talk about "Being" (Seyn) in philosophicalseminars. It allies itselfwith that reification against which it is the functionof functionless art, even today, to raise its own however mute and5. [Ludwig Heinrich Jungnickel (b. 1881 in Vienna), painter and handicraft artistwell known for his animal woodcuts. This and the following passage refer toHeidegger. Translator's note.]


1 5 6 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>objectified protest.But although art and science have separated from each other in history,their opposition is not to be hypostatized. <strong>The</strong> disgust for anachronisticeclecticism does not sanctify a culture organized according todepartmental specialization. In all of their necessity these divisionssimply attest institutionally to the renunciation of the whole truth. <strong>The</strong>ideals of purity and cleanliness bear the marks of a repressive order;these ideals are shared by the bustle of authentic philosophy aiming ateternal values, a sealed and flawlessly organized science, and by a conceptless,intuitive art. Spirit must pass a competency test to assure thatit will not overstep the offical culture or cross its officially sanctionedborders. <strong>The</strong> presupposition is that all knowledge can potentially beconverted into science. <strong>The</strong>ories of knowledge that distinguish prescientificfrom scientific consciousness have therefore grasped this distinctionas one of degree only. <strong>The</strong> fact that this convertibility hasremained a mere assertion and that living consciousness has neverreally been transformed into scientific consciousness, points to theprecariousness of the transition itself, to a qualitative difference. <strong>The</strong>simplest reflection on the life of consciousness would reveal just howlittle acts of knowledge, which are notjust arbitrary premonitions, canbe completely caught by the net of science. <strong>The</strong> work of Marcel Proust,no more lacking than Bergson's in scientific-positivistic elements, is asingle effort to express necessary and compelling perceptions aboutmen and their social relations which science can simply not match,while at the same time the claim of these perceptions to objectivitywould be neither lessened nor left up to vague plausibility. <strong>The</strong> measureof such objectivity is not the verification ofasserted theses throughrepeated testing, but individual experience, unified in hope and disillusion.Experience, reminiscing, gives depth to its observations byconfirming or refuting them. But their individually grasped unity, inwhich the whole surely appears, could not be divided up and reorganizedunder the separatedpersonae and apparatuses of psychologyand sociology. Under the pressure of the scientific spirit and of'an everpresentdesire latent in every artist, Proust attempted, by means of ascientifically modelled technique, a sort of experimentation, to save orreproduce a form of knowledge that was still considered valid in thedays of bourgeois individualism when the individual consciousnessstill trusted itself and was not yet worried about organizational censure:the knowledge of an experienced man, that extinct homme de lettres,whom Proust once again conjures up as the highest form of the dilettante.No one would have thought to dismiss as unimportant, accidentalor irrational the observations of an experienced man because theyare only his own and as such do not lend themselves readily to scientific


generalization. Those ofhis discoveries which slip through the meshesof science certainly elude science itself. Science, as cultural science (Geisteswissenschaj?),negates what it promises to culture: to open up itsartifacts from within. <strong>The</strong> young writer who wants to learn at collegewhat an art-work is, what linguistic form, aesthetic quality, even aesthetictechnique are, will only haphazardly learn anything at all aboutthe matter; at best he will pick up information ready culled fromwhatever modish philosophy and more or less arbitrarily slapped onto the content of works currently under discussion. If he turns, however,to philosophical aesthetics he is beleagured with highly abstractpropositions that have neither a connection with the works he wants tounderstand, nor with the content after which he is groping. <strong>The</strong> divisionof labor within the kosmos noetikos (intelligible world) into art andscience is not, however, altogether responsible for this situation; theinternal boundaries between art and science will not be obviated bygood will or over-arching planning. Rather, the spirit irretrievablymodeled on the pattern of the control of nature and material productionforgoes both recollection of any surpassed phase that wouldpromise any other future and any transcendence vis-2-vis the frozenrelations of production; this cripples the technical intelligence's ownspecialized procedure precisely with regard to its specific objects.With regard to scientific procedure and its philosophic grounding asmethod, the essay, in accordance with its idea, draws the fullest consequencesfrom the critique of the system. Even the empiricist doctrinesthat grant priority to open, unanticipated experience over firm, conceptualordering remain systematic to the extent that they investigatewhat they hold to be the more or less constant pre-conditions ofknowledge and develop them in as continuous a context as possible.Since the time of Bacon, who was himselfan essayist, empiricism -noless than rationalism - has been "method." Doubt about the unconditionalpriority of method was raised, in the actual process of thought,almost exclusively by the essay. It does justice to the consciousness ofnon-identity, without needing to say so, radically un-radical in refrainingfrom any reduction to a principle, in accentuating the fragmentary,the partial rather then the total. "Perhaps the great Sieur de Montaignefelt something like this when he gave his writings the wonderfullyelegant and apt title of <strong>Essay</strong>s. <strong>The</strong> simple modesty of this word is anarrogant courtesy. <strong>The</strong> essayist dismisses his own proud hopes whichsometimes lead him to believe that he has come close to the ultimate:he has, after all, no more to offer than explanations of the poems ofothers, or at best of his own ideas. But he ironically adapts himself tothis smallness - the eternal smallness of the most profound work ofthe intellect in face of life -and even emphasizes it with ironic modes-


158 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as Fonnty."6<strong>The</strong>essay does not obey the rules ofthe game of organized scienceand theory that, following Spinoza's principle, the order of things isidentical with that of ideas. Since the airtight order of concepts is notidentical with existence, the essay does not strive for closed, deductiveor inductive, construction. It revolts above all against the doctrine -deeply rooted since Plato - that the changing and ephemeral isunworthy of philosophy; against that ancient injustice toward the transitory,by which it is once more anathematized, conceptually. <strong>The</strong>essay shys away from the violence of dogma, from the notion that theresult of abstraction, the temporally invariable concept indifferent tothe individual phenomenon grasped by it, deserves ontological dignity.<strong>The</strong> delusion that theordo idearum (order of ideas) should be theordorerum (order of things) is based on the insinuation that the mediated isunmediated. Just as little as a simple fact can be thought without a concept,because to think it always already means to conceptualize it, it isequally impossible to think the purest conceptwithout reference to thefactual. Even the creations of phantasy that are supposedly independentof space and time, point toward individual existence - howeverfar they may be removed from it. <strong>The</strong>refore the essay is not intimidatedby the depraved profundity which claims that truth and history areincompatible. If truth has in fact a temporal core, then the full historicalcontent becomes an integral moment in truth; the a posteriori becomesconcretely the apriori, as only generally stipulated by Fichte andhis followers. <strong>The</strong> relation to experience - and from it the essay takesas much substance as does traditional theory from its categories - is arelation to all of history; merely individual experience, in which consciousnessbegins with what is nearest to it, is itself mediated by the allencompassingexperience of historical humanity; the claim that socialhistoricalcontents are nevertheless supposed to be only indirectlyimportant compared with the immediate life of the individual is a simpleself-delusion of an individualistic society and ideology. <strong>The</strong> depreciationof the historically produced, as an object of theory, istherefore corrected by the essay. <strong>The</strong>re is no salvaging the distinctionof a first philosophy from a mere philosophy of culture that assumesthe former and builds on it, a distinction with which the taboo on theessay is rationalized theoretically. <strong>The</strong> intellectual process which canonizesa distinction between the temporal and the timeless is losing itsauthority. Higher levels of abstraction invest thought neither with agreater sanctity nor with metaphysical content; rather, the metaphysicalcontent evaporates with the progress of abstraction, for which the6. Lukics, p. 9.


essay attempts to make reparation. <strong>The</strong> usual reproach against theessay, that it is fragmentary and random, itself assumes the giveness oftotality and thereby the identity of subject and object, and it suggeststhat man is in control of totality. But the desire ofthe essay is not to seekand filter the eternal out of the transitory; it wants, rather, to make thetransitory eternal. Its weakness testifies to the non-identity that it has toexpress, as well as to that excess of intention over its object, andthereby it points to that utopia which is blocked out by the classificationof the world into the eternal and the transitory. In the emphaticessay, thought gets rid of the traditional idea of truth.<strong>The</strong> essay simultaneously suspends the traditional concept of method.Thought acquires its depth from penetrating deeply into a matter,not from referring it back to something else. In this the essay becomespolemical by treating what is normally held to be derived, withouthowever pursuing its ultimate derivation. <strong>The</strong> essay freely associateswhat can be found associated in the freely chosen object. It does notinsist stubbornly on a realm transcending all mediations - and theyare the historical ones in which the whole of society is sedimented -rather the essay seeks truth contents as being historical in themselves.It does not concern itself with any supposed primeval condition inorder to contravene society's false sociality, which, just because ittolerates nothing not stamped by it, ultimately tolerates nothing indicativeof it own omnipresence and necessarily cites, as its ideologicalcomplement, that nature which its own praxis eliminates. <strong>The</strong> essaysilently abandons the illusion that thought can break out of thesis intophysis, out of culture into nature. Spellbound by what is fixed andadmittedly deduced, by artifacts, the essay honors nature by confirmingthat it no longer exists for human beings. <strong>The</strong> essay's Alexandrianismreplies to the fact that by their very existence the lilac and thenightingale, wherever the universal net allows them to survive, onlywant to delude us that life still lives. <strong>The</strong> essay abandons the main roadto the origins, the road leading to the most derivative, to being, theideology that simply doubles that which already exists; at the sametime the essay does not allow the idea of immediacy, postulated by thevery concept of mediation, to disappear entirely. All levels of themediated are immediate to the essay, before its reflection begins.<strong>As</strong> the essay denies any primeval givens, so it refuses any definitionof its concepts. Philosophy has completed the fullest critique of definitionfrom the most diverse perspectives, including those of Kant,Hegel and Nietzsche. But science has never adopted this critique.While the movement beginning with Kant, a movement against thescholastic residues in modern thought, replaces verbal definition withan understanding of concepts as part of the process in which they are


160 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>temporally embodied, the individual sciences insist stubbornly on thepre-critical job of definition - and do so for the sake of the undisturbedsecurity of their operation. In this regard the neopositivists,who identify philosophy with scientific method, agree with Scholasticism.<strong>The</strong> essay, in contrast, takes the anti-systematic impulse into itsown procedure, and introduces concepts directly, "immediately," as itreceives them. <strong>The</strong>y gain their precision only through their relation toone another. In this, however, the essay gets some support from theconcepts themselves. For it is a mere superstition of a science exclusivelyconcerned with the appropriation of raw materials to believethat concepts are in themselves undetermined, that they are first determinedby their definition. Science requires the image of the concept asatabula rasa, in order to secure its claim to domination; the claim to bethe sole power at the head of the table. Actually, all concepts arealready implicitly concretized through the language in which theystand. <strong>The</strong> essay begins with such meanings and, itself being essentiallylanguage, it forces these meanings on farther; it wants to helplanguage, in its relation to concepts, to grasp these concepts reflectivelyin the way that they are already unconsciously named in language. Thateffort is already envisaged by the procedure of meaning-analysis inphenomenology; only there the relation of concepts to language isfetishized. <strong>The</strong> essay remains as skeptical of this as it is of definition.Without apology the essay draws on itself the reproach that it does notknow beyond a doubtjust what is to be understood as the real contentof concepts. For the essay perceives that the longing for strict definitionshas long offered, through fixating manipulations of the meaningsof concepts, to eliminate the irritating and dangerous elements ofthings that live within concepts. Yet the essay can neither do withoutgeneral concepts - even language that does not fetishize the conceptcannot do without concepts - nor does it treat them arbitrarily. Ittherefore takes the matter of presentation more seriously than do thoseprocedures that separate out method from material and are indifferentto the way they represent their objectified contents. <strong>The</strong> how of expressionshould rescue, in precision, what the refusal to outline sacrifices,without, however, betraying the intended matter to the arbitrariness ofpreviously decreed significations. In this Benjamin was an unequaledmaster. Such precision, however, cannot remain atomistic. Not less,but more than the process of defining, the essay urges the reciprocalinteraction of its concepts in the process of intellectual experience. Inthe essay, concepts do not build a continuum of operations, thoughtdoes not advance in a single direction, rather the aspects of the argumentinterweave as in a carpet. <strong>The</strong> fruitfulness of the thoughts dependson the density of this texture. Actually, the thinker does not


T W.Adomo 161think, but rather transforms himself into an arena of intellectual experience,without simplifying it. While even traditional thought drawsits impulses from such experience, such thought by its form eliminatesthe remembrance of these impulses. <strong>The</strong> essay, on the other hand,takes them as its model, without simply imitating them as reflectedform; it mediates them through its own conceptual organization; itproceeds, so to speak, methodically unmethodically.<strong>The</strong> way in which the essay appropriates concepts is most easilycomparable to the behavior of a man who is obliged, in a foreign country,to speak that country's language instead of patching it togetherfrom its elements, as he did in school. He will read without a dictionary.If he has looked at the same word thirty times, in constantlychanging contexts, he has a clearer grasp of it than he would if helooked up all the word's meanings; meanings that are generally toonarrow, considering they change depending on the context, and toovague in view of the nuances that the context establishes in everyindividual case. Just as such learning remains exposed to error, so doesthe essay as form; it must pay for its affinity with open intellectualexperience by the lack of security, a lack which the norm of establishedthought fears like death. It is not so much that the essay ignores indisputablecertainty, as that it abrogates the ideal. <strong>The</strong> essay becomes truein its progress, which drives it beyond itself, and not in a hoardingobsession with fundamentals. Its concepts receive their light from aterminusad quem hidden to the essay itself, and not from an obvious terminusa quo. In this the very method of the essay expresses the utopianintention. All of its concepts are presentable in such a way that theysupport one another, that each one articulates itself according to theconfiguration that it forms with the others. In the essay discreet1separated elements enter into a readable context; it erects no scaftbl ‘?-ing, no edifice. Through their own movement the elements crystallizeinto a configuration. It is a force field, just as under the essay's glanceevery intellectual artifact must transform itself into a force field.<strong>The</strong> essay gently defies the ideals of clara et distinctaperceptio and ofabsolute certainty. On the whole it could be interpreted as a protestagaint the four rules that Descartes' Discourse on Method sets up at thebeginning of modern Western science and its theory. <strong>The</strong> second ofthese rules, the decomposition of the object into "as many parts aspossible and as might be necessary for its adequate ~olution,"~ formulatesthat analysis of elements under whose sign traditional theory7. Ren6 Descartes, A Discourse On Method, trans. John Veitch (New York: E.P. Dutton,1951), p. 15.


162 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>equates a conceptual order with the structure of being. But the objectof the essay, the artifact, refuses any analysis of its elements and canonly be constructed from its specific idea; it is not accidental that Kanttreated art-works and organisms analogously, although at the sametime he insisted, against all romantic obscurantism, on distinguishingthem. <strong>The</strong> whole is to be hypostatized into afirst principlejust as littleas is the product of analysis, the elements. In opposition to both, theessay is informed by the idea of that interaction which in fact toleratesthe question of elements as little as that of the elementary. Neither arethe specific elements to be developed purely out of the whole, nor viceversa. <strong>The</strong> artifact is a monad, yet it is not; its elements, as such ofa conceptualkind, point beyond the specific object in which they gatherthemselves. But the essay does not 'follow these elements to that pointwhere they legitimize themselves, on the far side of the specific object;otherwise it would turn into a bad kind of infinity. Rather, the essavcomes so close to the here and now of the object, up to the point wherethat object, instead of being simply an object, dissociates itself intothose elements in which it has its life.<strong>The</strong> third Cartesian rule, "to conduct my thoughts in such an orderthat, by commencing with the simplest and easiest to know, I mightascend by little and little, step by step, to the knowledge of the more~omplex,"~ is sharply contravened by the form of the essay in that itbegins with the most complex, not the most simple, which is in everyinstance the habitual. <strong>The</strong> essay as form will be a good guide for theperson who is beginning to study philosophy, and before whose eyesthe idea of philosophy somehow stands. He will hardly begin by readingthe easiest writers, whose common senseg will skim the surfacewhere depth is called for; he will rather go for the allegedly difficultwriters, who shed light on what is simple and illuminate it as a "stanceof the mind toward objectivity." <strong>The</strong> naivetC of the student, to whomthe difficult and formidable seems good enough, is wiser than theadult pedantry that admonishes thought with a threatening finger tounderstand the simple before risking that complexity which aloneentices it. Such a postponement of knowledge only prevents knowledge.In opposition to the clich6 of the "understandable," the notionof truth as a network of causes and effects, the essay insists that a matterbe considered, from the verv first, in its whole complexity; it counteractsthat hardened primitiveness that always allies itself with reason'scurrent form. Whereas science treats the difficulties and complexitiesof an antagonistic and monadologically split reality according to the8. Ibid.9. [In English.]


expectation of this society by reducing them to simplifying models andthen belatedly differentiates them with fabricated material, the essayshakes off the illusion of a simple, basically logical world that soperfectly suits the defense of the status quo. Its differentiation is nosupplement, but its medium. Established thought readily ascribes thatdifferentiation to the mere psychology of the author and then thinksthat it has adequately dealt with it. <strong>The</strong> pompous scientific objectionsto over-sophistication actually do not aim at the impertinently unreliablemethod but at the irritating aspects of the object which theessay reveals.<strong>The</strong> fourth Cartesian rule that one "should in every case institutesuch exhaustive enumerations and such general surveys" that one "issure of leaving nothing out" - this ultimate principle of systematicthought - reappears unchanged in Kant's polemic against Aristotle's"rhapsodic" thought. This rule corresponds to the particular objectionto the essay that, in the words of the schoolmaster, it is not exhaustive,while it is clear that every object, and above all a cultural object,encloses endlessly many aspects, the choice among which can only bedetermined by the intention of the knower. <strong>The</strong> "general survey''would only be possible if it were determined in advance that the objectin question can be fully grasped by the concepts which treat it; thatnothing is left over that could not be anticipated by these concepts.Following that assumption, the rule requiring the exhaustive enumerationofthe individual elements claims that the object can be presentedin an airtight deductive system: a supposition of aphilosophy of identity.<strong>As</strong> a practical technique of thought, as for example in its insistenceon definition, the Cartesian rule has outlived the rationalistic theoremon which it was founded: a comprehensive general view and a continuityof presentation is urged even upon empirically open scientificprocedure. In this fashion the intellectual conscience that should, inDescartes' philosophy, keep watch over the necessity of knowledge istransformed into the arbitrariness of a "frame of reference."" In orderto satisfy a methodological need and to support the plausibility of thewhole, it becomes an axiomatic doctrine that is being set up as the gatewayto thought while no longer being able to demonstrate its ownvalidity or proof. Or, in the German version, it becomes a "project"(Entwurf)that, with the pathos-laden claim of reaching into being, simplysuppresses its subjective conditions. <strong>The</strong> insistence on thecontinuity of thought's process tends to prejudice the inner coherenceof the object, its own harmony. A continuous presentationwould contradict material that is full of antogonisms as long as it did10. [In English.]


164 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>not simultaneously define continuity as discontinuity. Unconsciouslyand far from theory, the need arises in the essay as form to annul thetheoretically outmoded claims of totality and continuity, and to do soin the concrete procedure of the intellect. If the essay struggles aestheticallyagainst that narrow-minded method that will leave nothingout, it is obeying an epistemological motive. <strong>The</strong> romantic conceptionof the fragment as an artifact that is not complete in itself but openlystriding into infinity by way of self-reflection, advocates this antiidealistmotive even in the midst of idealism. Even in its manner ofdelivery the essay refuses to behave as though it had deduced its objectand had exhausted the topic. Self-relativization is immanent in itsform; it must be constructed in such a way that it could always, and atany point, break off. It thinks in fragments just as reality is fragmentedand gains its unity only by moving through the fissures, rather than bysmoothing them over. <strong>The</strong> unanimity of the logical order deceives usabout the antagonistic nature of that on which it was jauntily imposed.Discontinuity is essential to the essay; its concern is always a conflictbrought to a standstill. While the essay adjusts concepts to one anotherby virtue of their function in the parallelogram of the forces of thematerials, it shrinks back from the over-arching concept under whichparticular concepts should be subordinated; what the over-archingconcept merely pretends to accomplish, the essay's method recognizesas insoluble while nevertheless attempting to accomplish it. <strong>The</strong>word "essay" - in which thought's utopia of hitting the bull's eyeunites with the consciousness of its own fallibility and provisionalnature - indicates something, like most historically surviving terminologies,about the form, the importance of which is magnified by thefact that it results not programmatically but as a characteristic of theform's groping intention. <strong>The</strong> essay must let the totality light up in oneof its chosen or haphazard features but without asserting that thewhole is present. It corrects the isolated and accidental aspects of itsinsights by allowing them to multiply, confirm, and restrict themselves-whether in the essay's proper progress or in its mosaic-like relationto other essays; and it does so not by abstracting characteristic featuresfrom its insights. "Thus the essay distinguishes itself from a scientifictreatise. He writes essayistically who writes while experimenting, whoturns his object this way and that, who questions it, feels it, tests it,thoroughly reflects on it, attacks it from different angles, and in hismind's eye collects what he sees, and puts into words what the objectallows to be seen under the conditions established in the course ofwriting."" <strong>The</strong> discontent with this procedure, the feeling that it could11. Max Bense, "Cber den <strong>Essay</strong> und seine Prosa," Aferkur 1:3 (1947), 418.


T.W.<strong>Adorno</strong> 165all go on indefinitely, has its truth and untruth. Its truth, because in factthe essay comes to no final conclusions and makes explicit its inabilityto do so by parodying its own apriori; it is then saddled with the guiltthat is actually incurred by those forms that erase every trace of arbitrariness.Yet that discontent with the essay is at the same time untruebecause, as a constellation, the essay is not arbitrary in the way that itseems to a philosophical subjectivism which translates the exigenciesof the object into those of its conceptual organization. <strong>The</strong> essay isdetermined by the unity of its object, together with that of theory andexperience which have migrated into the object. <strong>The</strong> essay's opennessis not vaguely one of feeling and mood, but obtains its contour from itscontent. It resists the idea of the master-work that reflects the idea ofcreation and totality. Its form follows the critical thought that man isno creator, that nothing human is creation. <strong>The</strong> essay, always directedtowards artifacts, does not present itself as a creation; nor does it longfor something all-embracing, the totality of which would resemblecreation. Its totality, the unity of a form thoroughly constructed initself, is that of non-totality; one that even as form does not assert the.thesis of the identity of thought and thing, the thesis which in its owncontent the essay rejects. Freedom from the pressure of identity occasionallyprovides the essay (and this is lacking in official thought) withan aspect of ineffaceability, of inextinguishable color. In Simmel certainforeign words - cachet, attitude - betray this intention, without itbeing treated theoretically as such.<strong>The</strong> essay is both more open and more closed than traditionalthought would like. It is more open in so far as, through its innernature, it negates anything systematic and satisfies itself all the betterthe more strictly it excludes the systematic; residues of the systematicin the essay such as the infiltration of literary studies with ready-made,wide-spread philosophical commonplaces, by which these studies tryto make themselves respectable, are of no morevalue than psychologicalbanalities. On the other hand, the essay is more closed in that itlabors emphatically on the form of its presentation. <strong>The</strong> consciousnessof the non-identity between presentation and presented material forcesthe form to make unlimited efforts. In that respect alone the essayresembles art; otherwise, on account of the concepts which appear in itand which import not only their meaning but also their theoreticalaspects, the essay is necessarily related to theory. To be sure, the essayrelates itselfto theory as cautiously as to the concept. It neither deducesitself rigidly from theory -the cardinal fault of all LukAcs' later essayisticwork - nor is it a down-payment on future syntheses. Disasterthreatens intellectual experience the more strenuously it ossifies intotheory and acts as if it held the philosopher's stone in hand. And yet,


166 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>intellectual experience itself strives by its own nature toward suchobjectification. This antinomy is mirrored by the essay. Just as itabsorbs concepts and experiences, so it absorbs theories. However, itsrelation to them is not that ofa standpoint. If this lackofa standpoint isno longer naive and dependent on the prominence of its objects; if theessay rather uses the relationship to its objects as aweapon against thespell of beginnings, it parodically practices the otherwise only feeblepolemic of thought against mere standpoint philosophy. <strong>The</strong> essayswallows up the theories that are close by; its tendency is always towardthe liquidation of opinion, even that from which it takes its ownimpulse. <strong>The</strong> essay remains what it always was, the critical form parexcellence; specifically, it constructs the immanent criticism of culturalartifacts, and it confronts that which such artifacts are with their concept;it is the critique of ideology. "<strong>The</strong> essay is the form of the criticalcategory of our mind. For whoever criticizes must necessarily experiment;he must create conditions under which an object is newly seen,and he must do so in a fashion different from that of a creative author.Above all the fragility of the object must be probed, tested; this is preciselythe meaning of the small variation that an object undergoes inthe hands of its critic."" If the essay is accused of lacking a standpointand of tending toward relativism because it recognizes no standpointlying outside of itself, then the accusation implicitly contains the conceptionof truth as something "ready-made," a hierarchy of concepts,an image of truth that Hegel destroyed in his dislike of standpoints: inthis the essay touches its polar opposite, the philosophy of absoluteknowledge. <strong>The</strong> essay would like to cure thought of its arbitrariness bytaking arbitrariness reflectively into its own procedure instead ofmaskingit as spontaneity.Hegelian philosophy, to be sure, remained trapped in the inconsistencythat it criticized the abstract, over-arching concept, the mere"result," in the name of an internally discontinuous process, while atthe same time, in the idealist tradition, speaking about dialecticalmethod. <strong>The</strong>refore the essay is more dialectical than the dialectic as itarticulates itself. <strong>The</strong> essay takes Hegelian logic at its word: neither maythe truth of the totality be played off immediately against individualjudgments, nor may truth be reduced to individual judgments; rather,the claim of the particular to truth is taken literally to the point wherethere is evidence of its untruth. <strong>The</strong> risked, anticipatory, and incompletelyredeemed aspect of every essayistic detail draws in other detailsas negation; the untruth in which the essay knowingly entangles itselfis the element of its truth. Untruth certainly also resides in the essay's


asic form, in its relation to what is culturally preformed and derivedas though it were something in-itself. But the more energetically theessay suspends the concept of some first principle, the more it refusesto spin culture out of nature, the more fundamentally it recognizes theunremittingly natural essence of culture itself. Up to the present day, ablind natural interconnectedness, myth, perpetuates itself in culture.It is precisely this upon which the essay reflects: its proper theme is theinterrelation of nature and culture. It is not by coincidence that, ratherthan "reducing" the artifact, the essay immerses itself in culturalphenomena as in a second nature, a second immediacy, in orderthrough persistence to remove the illusion of immediacy. <strong>The</strong> essaydeceives itself as little as the philosophy of origins about the differencebetween culture and that which underlies it. Yet for the essay, culture isnot some epiphenomenon superimposed on being that must be eliminated,but rather what lies underneath is itself artificial (thesei), falsesociety. Thus, for the essay, origins have no priority over the superstructure.<strong>The</strong> essay owes its freedom in its choice of objects, itssovereignty vis-2-vis all prioritiesI3 offact or theory to the circumstancethat for it all objects are equally near the center, to the principle thatcasts a spell over everything. <strong>The</strong> essay refuses to glorify concern for theprimal as something more primal than concern for the mediated,because to the essay primacy itself is an object of reflection, somethingnegative. It corresponds to a situation in which the primal, as a standpointof the mind within the falsely socialized world, becomes a lie. Itcovers a wide territory from the enshrinement as primal words of historicalconcepts extracted from historical languages, to academic instructionin "creative writing;"I4 from craft-shop primitiveness to recordersand finger-painting: '' in every instance the pedagogical necessitysets itself up as a metaphysical virtue. Thought is not exempt fromBaudelaire's rebellion of poetry against nature as a social reservation.Even the paradises of thought are only artificial, and in them the essayindulges. Since, according to Hegel's dictum, there is nothing betweenheaven and earth that is not mediated, thought may only hold true tothe idea of immediacy by way of the mediated, but it becomes the preyof the mediated the instant it grasps directly for the unmediated. Cunningly,the essay settles itself into texts, as though they were simplythere and had authority; without the illusion of the primal, it getsunder its feet a ground, however dubious, comparable to earliertheological exegesis of holy writings. <strong>The</strong> essay's impulse, however, is13. [In English.]14. [In English.]15. [In English.]


I68 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>the exact opposite of the theological; it is critical: through confrontationof texts with their own emphatic concept, with the truth that eachtext intends even in spite of itself, to shatter the claim of culture andmove it to remember its untruth - the untruth of that ideologicalfacade which reveals culture's bondage to nature. Under the glance ofthe essay second nature becomes conscious of itself as first nature.If the truth of the essay gains its momentum by way ofits untruth, itstruth is not to be sought in mere opposition to what is ignoble and proscribedin it, but in these very things: in its mobility, its lack of thatsolidity which science demands, transferring it, as it were, from propertyrelationshipsto the intellect. Those who believe they must defend theintellect against the charge of a lack of solidity are the enemies ofintellect: intellect itself, once emancipated, is mobile. <strong>As</strong> soon as itwants more than simply the administrative repetition and manipulatedpresentation of what already exists, it is somehow exposed; truthabandoned by play would be nothing more than tautology. Thus historicallythe essay is related to rhetoric, which the scientific mentality,since Descartes and Bacon, has always wanted to do away with; that is,until, appropriately in the age of science, rhetoric decayed and becamea science suigeneris, the science of communication. Of course rhetorichas always been a form of thought which accommodated itself to communicativelanguage. It directed itself to the unmediated: thesubstitute-satisfaction of its audience. Yet the essay preserves in thevery autonomy of its presentation, through which it distinguishes itselffrom the scientific mode of communication, traces of the communicativewith which science dispenses. <strong>The</strong> pleasures which rhetoric wantsto provide to its audience are sublimated in the essay into the idea ofthe pleasure of freedom vis-A-vis the object, freedom that gives theobject more of itself than if it were mercilessly incorporated into theorder of ideas. <strong>The</strong> scientific consciousness, which is directed againstany anthropomorphic idea whatsoever, was always closely bound upwith the reality principle and similarly hostile to happiness. While happinessis supposedly the goal of all domination over nature, it alwaysappears to the reality principle as regression to mere nature. This canbe seen even in the highest philosophies, including Kant's and Hegel's.Reason, in whoseabsolute idea these philosophies have their pathos, isdenounced by them as something both pert and disrespectful as soonas it challenges the established system of values. Against this inclinationthe essay rescues a sophistic element. <strong>The</strong> hostility to happiness ofofficial critical thought can be felt particularly in Kant's transcendentaldialectic: it wants to eternalize the boundary between understandingand speculation, and, according to its characteristic metaphor, to preventany "roaming around in intelligible worlds." While self-critical


eason should, according to Kant, keep both feet planted on theground, indeed should ground itself, it follows its innermost principleand seals itself off against anything new as well as against curiosity, thepleasure principle of thought, that is also upbraided by existentialontology. What in the content of his thought Kant projects as the goalof reason, utopia, the production of humanity, is disbarred by theform of his thought, the theory of knowledge; it forbids reason to gobeyond the realm of experience, which, caught in the machinery ofmere material and unchangeable categories, is reduced to that whichalways was. But the object of the essay is the new as something genuinelynew, as something not translatable back into the staleness ofalready existing forms. By reflecting the object without doing violenceto it, the essay silently laments the fact that truth has betrayed happinessand thus itself; this lament incites the rage against the essay. In theessay the persuasive aspect of communication, analogously to thefunctional transformation of many traits in autonomous music, isalienated from its original goal and converted into the pure articulationof presentation in itself; it becomes a compelling construction thatdoes not want to copy the object, but to reconstruct it out of its conceptualmembra disjecta. But the objectionable transitions in rhetoric, inwhich association, ambiguity of words, neglect of logical synthesis allmake it easy for the auditor, yoking him to the speaker's will: all theseare fused ik the essay with its truth-content. Its transitions disavowrigid deduction in the interest of establishing internal cross-connections,something for which discursive logic has no use. It uses equivocationneither out ofslovenliness nor in ignorance of their proscription byscience, but to clarify what usually remains obscure to the critique ofequivocation and its mere discrimination of meanings: whenever aword means avariety of things, the differences are not entirely distinct,for the unity of the word points to some unity, no matter how hidden,in the thing itself; however, it is obviously not the case that this unity, asclaimed by contemporary restorative philosophies, can itself be takensimply as a unity of linguistic affinities. Here as well the essay verges onthe logic of music, the stringent and yet aconceptual art of transition; itaims at appropriating for expressive language something that it forfeitedunder the domination of a discursive logic which cannot be circumvented,but may be outwitted in its own form by the force of anintruding subjective expression. For the essay is not situated in simpleopposition to discursive procedure. It is not unlogical; rather it obeyslogical criteria in so far as the totality of its sentences must fit togethercoherently. Mere contradictions may not remain, unless they aregrounded in the object itself. It is just that the essay develops thoughtsdifferently from discursive logic. <strong>The</strong> essay neither makes deductions


1 70 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Essay</strong> as <strong>Form</strong>from a principle nor does it draw conclusions from coherent individualobsenlations. It co-ordinates elements, rather than subordinatingthem; and only the essence ofits content, not the manner ofitspresentation, is commensurable with logical criteria. If, thanks to the tensionbetween presentation and what is presented, the essay - comparedwith forms which indifferently convey a ready-made content - ismore dynamic than traditional thought, it is at the same time, as a constructedjuxtaposition of elements, more static than traditionalthought. In that alone rests the essay's affinity to the visual image;except that the essay's static quality is itself composed of tensionswhich, as it were, have been brought to a standstill. <strong>The</strong> slightly yieldingquality of the essayist's thought forces him to greater intensity thandiscursive thought can offer; for the essay, unlike discursive thought,does not proceed blindly, automatically, but at every moment it mustreflect on itself. This reflexion, however, does not only extend to theessay's relation to established thought, but also to its relation to rhetoricand communication. Otherwise the essay, while fancying itselfmeta-scientific, would become vainly pre-scientific.<strong>The</strong> relevance of the essay is that of anachronism. <strong>The</strong> hour is moreunfavorable to it than ever. it is being crushed between an organizedscience, on one side, in which everyone presumes to control everyoneand everything else, and which excludes, with the sanctimonious praiseof "intuitive" or "stimulating," anything that does not conform to thestatus quo; and, on the other side, by a philosophy that makes do withthe empty and abstract residues left aside by the scientific apparatus,residues which then become, for philosophy, the objects of seconddegreeoperations. <strong>The</strong> essay, however, has to do with that which isblind in its objects. Conceptually it wants to blow open what cannot beabsorbed by concepts, or what, through contradictions in which conceptsentangle themselves, betrays the fact that the network of theirobjectivity is a purely subjective rigging. It wants to polarize theopaque, to unbind the powers latent in it. It strives to concretize contentas determined by space and time; it constructs the interwovenness ofconcepts in such a way that they can be imagined as themselves interwovenin the object. It frees itself from the stipulation of those attributeswhich since the definition in the S~)mposiumhave been ascribedto ideas; the notion that ideas "exist eternally and neither come intobeing nor pass away, neither change nor wane;" "A being eternallycreated in itself and for itself;" and yet the essay remains idea, in that itdoes not capitulate under the burden of mere being, does not bowdown before what merely is. It does not measure what is by some eternalstandard, rather by an enthusiastic fragment from Nietzsche's laterlife: "Ifwe affirm one single moment, we thus affirm not only ourselves


ut all existence. For nothing is self-sufficient, neither in ourselves norin things: and if our soul has trembled with happiness and soundedlike a harpstring just once, all eternity was needed to produce this oneevent -and in this single moment ofaffirmation all eternity was calledgood, redeemed, justified, and affirmed."16 This with the exceptionthat the essay mistrusts such justification and affirmation. For the happinessthat Nietzsche found holy, the essay has no other name than thenegative. Even the highest manifestations of the intellect that expresshappiness are always at the same time caught in the guilt of thwartinghappiness as long as they remain mere intellect. <strong>The</strong>refore the law ofthe innermost form of the essay is heresy. By transgressing the orthodoxyof thought, something becomes visible in the object which it isorthodoxy's secret purpose to keep invisible.Translated b~ Bob Hullot-Kentor and Frederic Will16. Friedrich Nietzsche, Me Will To Power,trans. W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale(London: Weidenfeeld and Nicolson, 1968), pp. 532-533.A Quarterly Journal of Critical Thought ISTAM E: <strong>The</strong> Crisis of the LeftFRASER: Legal AmnesiaPICARD: New Black Economic StrategyTISMANEANU: Romantan (,'omrnunismOFFE: <strong>The</strong> Future of the Lobor MarketHULLOT-KENTOR: Introduction to <strong>Adorno</strong>ADORNO: <strong>The</strong> Idea of Natural HisloryNotes and Commentary:SIEGEL: <strong>The</strong> Reagan "Revolution"SOLLNER: NPO-Consematism@ Critical <strong>The</strong>olyEISENZWEIC: Zzonism and Delectiue FictionZERZAN: Taylonsm and UnionismLOW ENTHAL: Goethe and False SubjectiuityReview-Symposium on Soviet-Type SocietiesLUKE, ULMEN, SZELENYI, BAUMAN,~RIlTERSPORN AND GILLReviews:D'AMICO: Castoriadis. LabyrinthSICA: Rabinbach, Austrian ~dcialismREED: West, Prophesy Deliz~erance!SIEGEL: Books by Barnet, Hoffman, UlamPOSTER: Dreyfus and Rabinow, Michei FoucaultSTEWART-SWEET: Anderson, On NationalrsmWOLIN: Heller, Luka'cs Revalued- -- -- -Subscriptions cost $22 per year for ind~viduals; $50 for institutions. Foreign orders add 10 per-cent. Checks must bein U.S.funds. NoCanadian checkscan be accepted. Backissues prior to NO. 50 cost 55.50each; No. 50 and subsequent issues are $6.00each. Institutions pay $15.00for all back issues. For a full list of available-back issues and to subscribe, write: Telos, Box 31 11, St. Louis, MO 63130 USA.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!