29.11.2012 Views

THE HUMANISTIC THEORY OF PAINTING - College Art Association

THE HUMANISTIC THEORY OF PAINTING - College Art Association

THE HUMANISTIC THEORY OF PAINTING - College Art Association

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

UT PICTURA POESIS: <strong>HUMANISTIC</strong> <strong>THE</strong>ORY <strong>OF</strong> <strong>PAINTING</strong> 221<br />

And this doctrine in De Piles anticipates, four years before its translation by Boileau, the<br />

enormous influence that would gather momentum in the following century of the treatise of<br />

Longinus on the Sublime. De Piles was definitely influenced in his later writings by Longinus<br />

who had maintained that the sublime in art is the product of genius-of that inward great-<br />

ness of soul that must from time to time inevitably transcend the rules, the correct observ-<br />

ance of which by a lesser artist would result in mediocrity.?09<br />

Some thirty years later when the Longinian temper had grown upon him, De Piles<br />

again showed his skepticism of prescribed rules for expression when he criticized those defi-<br />

nitions of the passions that Le Brun in his treatise on the subject had taken from Descartes'<br />

Traite' des passions de l'dme. De Piles remarks truthfully and, one may hope, a little<br />

caustically, that these definitions are not always accommodated to the capacities of painters,<br />

who are not all philosophers, though in other respects they may not want sense and good<br />

natural parts."10 He adds that Le Brun's definitions are very learned and fine but too<br />

general, and it is perfectly clear from the pages that follow that De Piles found the ancients<br />

who appealed to nature (he has Horace and Quintilian particularly in mind) more valuable<br />

sources of advice for the painters on this important subject than he found Le Brun, even<br />

though the latter's treatise carried with it the impressive sanction of the Cartesian philoso-<br />

phy. The modern reader of Le Brun's treatise will scarcely fail to agree with the opinion of<br />

De Piles, for nowhere did the aesthetic legislation of the Academy display itself in such<br />

absurdly detailed and absurdly abstract categories as in this attempt to specify the minute<br />

changes in facial expression by which each passion manifests itself through the complex<br />

action of those subtle vapors known as the esprits animaux which are the product of certain<br />

refinements of the circulatory system. One need not consider here the details of those<br />

deformations of pupil, eyebrow, nose, and mouth, or of those changes in complexion wrought<br />

by the esprits after sensory or imaginative stimuli have set them in motion. It should be<br />

remembered, however, that the treatise of Descartes, who shared the profound interest of<br />

his age in the perturbationes animae, was largely responsible for the special psycho-physio-<br />

logical character of the theory of expression during the last decades of the seventeenth<br />

century among the painter-theorists of the Academy who, legislating as they were for an<br />

art that would conserve the outward record of the soul's inner activity, were naturally far<br />

more precise in charting the details of expression than the philosopher himself had been.<br />

But behind the categorical exactitude with which they formulated the visible manifesta-<br />

tions of these invisible states of the soul lay not only the rational thoroughness of the<br />

Cartesian method, but also the central concept of the Cartesian physics that the whole<br />

passage in Plato's Phaedrus (245a): "But he who without<br />

the divine madness comes to the doors of the Muses, con-<br />

fident that he will be a good poet by art (K rxv7ns), meets<br />

with no success, and the poetry of the same man vanishes<br />

into nothingness before that of the madman" (trans. H. N.<br />

Fowler, Loeb Classical Library, London and New York,<br />

1928, p. 469). Junius (De pictura veterum, Amsterdam,<br />

1637, I, 4, p. 22) applies the Platonic concept to painters as<br />

well as poets: "Utraque certe sequitur occulta quaedam<br />

naturae semina: unde persaepe videas cum Poetas, tum<br />

Pictores, ad amorem artis non tam provido multum diuque<br />

pensitatae rationis consilio duci, quam coeco quodam avi-<br />

dae mentis impetu trahi atque impelli." Lomazzo (see<br />

note 75) had already remarked that painters are like poets<br />

in sharing "il furor di Apolline." In insisting on the neces-<br />

sity of inspiration in artistic creation as opposed to reason<br />

(even though the latter also be encouraged to make its con-<br />

tribution), the Platonic tradition of the Renaissance prepared<br />

the way for the enthusiastic reception later of the<br />

doctrine of Longinus.<br />

lo9. See note 311 and p. 262.<br />

Iio. Cours de peinture, pp. 164 ff. It should be noted<br />

that after criticizing Le Brun, De Piles turns about and pays<br />

his respects to the famous Academician, remarking that his<br />

demonstrations may be of service to most painters. But<br />

certainly this is said without conviction and is merely a<br />

lukewarm and perfunctory salute to the tradition with<br />

which in this as in other respects, De Piles was often in<br />

disagreement. Descartes' treatise was published first in<br />

1649. Le Brun's Traite des passions, as he called it in<br />

manuscript, was published first in Amsterdam and Paris<br />

in 1698 under the title Confirence de M. Le Brun ... sur<br />

lexpression ginerale et particuliere. The treatise is reprinted<br />

in Jouin, Charles le Brun, Paris, 1889, pp. 371-93.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!