23.02.2013 Views

Seeing with Different Eyes - Cosmology and Divination

Seeing with Different Eyes - Cosmology and Divination

Seeing with Different Eyes - Cosmology and Divination

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

16<br />

Chapter One<br />

the divinity inside itself. The explanations for oracular trance are not as<br />

close to h<strong>and</strong>, but would presumably rely on a similar line of reasoning.<br />

This follows up on <strong>and</strong> deepens an observation made earlier. The Stoics<br />

see the human soul as up to the task of underst<strong>and</strong>ing the world, here<br />

reflected in a true continuity between divine reason <strong>and</strong> human reason.<br />

VI. Concluding Thoughts<br />

If we take a step back from the Stoic evidence for a moment <strong>and</strong> look at<br />

the whole, we can, in my view, find some illumination as to why ancients<br />

<strong>and</strong> moderns might view divination differently, based on certain premises<br />

of ancient <strong>and</strong> modern physics. Most important here is a central idea of<br />

ancient physics that is not mirrored in modern accounts: the idea of<br />

intentionality. In my view, a focus on intentionality as an organizing<br />

principle in the cosmos provides a way around the horns of Fritz Graf’s<br />

dilemma that I mentioned at the beginning of this paper. It holds out a<br />

detour around the problem of belief versus skepticism <strong>and</strong> instead gives us<br />

breadth of view. I’ll explain.<br />

Only a few ancient philosophers deviated from the idea of a purposive<br />

cosmos. It was more often the case that the world unfolded as it did<br />

according to some form of teleological drive. Its processes were not willynilly,<br />

but were part of a larger plan. And more often than not, the ancients<br />

were comfortable enough calling the architect of this plan the divine (<strong>with</strong><br />

all caveats in place against assimilating the various philosophical notions<br />

of the divine <strong>with</strong> traditional Homeric theology). If this is a beginning<br />

point of physics, then the study of the unfolding of physical processes will<br />

be the reading of a purposiveness that is ultimately traceable, even if by a<br />

long <strong>and</strong> circuitous route, to the divine. This starting point makes<br />

divination look a lot less exotic <strong>and</strong> more a practice whose premises are<br />

congruent <strong>with</strong> those of the empirical scientist: both place human beings in<br />

the position of gathering information derived from a more or less remote<br />

cause of causes. Neither Plato, Aristotle, nor of course the Stoics, would<br />

have any objection.<br />

The next step is, then, to think about the gap that separates the process<br />

of reading signs in an intentional cosmos from reading signs in an<br />

unintentional one. Contemporary theorists of signs have already pointed<br />

the way. In his A Theory of Semiotics, Umberto Eco talks of a “lower<br />

threshold” of semiotic activity that takes place around natural “things”<br />

whose status as “signs” is liminal. 32 In his discussion, Eco makes reference<br />

to physical stimuli, neurophysiological phenomena, <strong>and</strong> genetic coding as<br />

signals that exist below the threshold of the sign. In referring in particular

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!