20.03.2013 Views

Old Masters and New Lessons - Grant Kester

Old Masters and New Lessons - Grant Kester

Old Masters and New Lessons - Grant Kester

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Art Journal (Spring 1997)<br />

Learning from Aesthetics: <strong>Old</strong> <strong>Masters</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>Lessons</strong><br />

In the Aesthetic State everything - even the tool which serves - is a free citizen, having equal<br />

rights with the noblest; <strong>and</strong> the mind, which would force the patient mass beneath the yoke of its<br />

purposes, must here first obtain its assent.<br />

Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man, 1792(1)<br />

The essays in this issue of Art Journal explore some of the complex meanings generated by the<br />

concept of the aesthetic within contemporary art <strong>and</strong> culture. The contributors pursue the<br />

aesthetic through a range of sites <strong>and</strong> domains: from the silvered corpse of Joseph Jernigan<br />

floating in the ether of cyberspace, to the multimedia spectacle of the Holocaust Memorial<br />

Museum in Washington, D.C., to the creation of wall-sized digital montages in London's<br />

Dockl<strong>and</strong>s. There is a common interest throughout in exp<strong>and</strong>ing the conceptual scope of the<br />

aesthetic beyond the sanctioned domain of the solitary artist <strong>and</strong> work of art to include a range of<br />

practices <strong>and</strong> conditions that inform everyday life.<br />

The idea for this issue began with my interest in the much heralded "return" to beauty in<br />

art making <strong>and</strong> art criticism a few years ago. This movement was catalyzed by Dave Hickey's<br />

influential book The Invisible Dragon: Four Essays on Beauty (1993) <strong>and</strong> soon grew into a<br />

torrent of interviews, special issues of magazines, <strong>and</strong> assorted commentaries.(2) Hickey's book,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the general interest in beauty that followed from it, did much to refocus the attention of artists,<br />

critics, <strong>and</strong> art historians on the sensual <strong>and</strong> somatic dimension of aesthetic experience, which<br />

had been neglected under the arid regime of the "anti-aesthetic." In responding to this neglect,<br />

however, many of the proponents of beauty seem to have ab<strong>and</strong>oned in turn some of the<br />

valuable insights into the contingency of the aesthetic provided by critical theory <strong>and</strong> postmodern<br />

art practice during the last decade <strong>and</strong> a half. Thus the "ground" of beauty, as Peter Dunn <strong>and</strong><br />

Loraine Leeson have noted, has all too often been ceded to those who speak on behalf of the<br />

body <strong>and</strong> the aesthetic from a highly traditional, <strong>and</strong> in some cases even conservative, point of<br />

view.(3) The essays herein seek a return to the aesthetic that preserves its full complexity as a<br />

cultural, political, <strong>and</strong> sensual form of experience. This has led many of the contributors to


eexamine the origins of the aesthetic in early modern philosophy. What they have found there is<br />

a concept of aesthetic knowledge that is rooted in both the private body <strong>and</strong> the body politic. In<br />

fact, it is in the very nature of the aesthetic that it is located at the intersection between the<br />

experience of subjective autonomy <strong>and</strong> the subject-positions provided by a dominant culture.<br />

Hickey's book did much to reignite interest in the powerful visual experience provided by<br />

the work of art, but his argument loses its focus at precisely the point at which this experience<br />

engages with broader forms of discursive knowledge <strong>and</strong> public subjectivity. Hickey begins his<br />

book by evoking a nightmarishly Orwellian scenario in which a politically correct thought police<br />

dominate a well-funded network of "alternative" art spaces. This liberal elite, painfully out of<br />

touch with the vox populi of good old-fashioned bodily experience, have shackled the<br />

subversively beautiful art object in the basement in order to satisfy their fiendish desire to<br />

improve <strong>and</strong> infantilize the museum-going public. Hickey establishes a curious parallel between<br />

the alternative arts sector <strong>and</strong> the world of private galleries <strong>and</strong> auction houses. Thus, a<br />

"massive civil service" of arts administrators in charge of a vast apparatus of "publicly funded"<br />

exhibition spaces is juxtaposed to a "h<strong>and</strong>ful" of beleaguered dealers <strong>and</strong> gallery owners, who,<br />

if somewhat too ready to "nibble canapes on the Concorde," are at least honest about their<br />

relationship to the market <strong>and</strong> are more than willing to embrace the ambiguous pleasures of<br />

aesthetic desire.(4) The fact that this characterization could be persuasively advanced at a time<br />

when literally dozens of nonprofit exhibition spaces, publications, <strong>and</strong> media centers were being<br />

forced to close owing to drastic funding cuts <strong>and</strong> conservative political attacks suggests the<br />

emotional power of Hickey's underlying message for many in the art world.<br />

Hickey's essays deploy all the accouterments of classic bohemianism; "the street" is a<br />

persistent point of reference, along with sneering references to sc<strong>and</strong>alized "church ladies."(5)<br />

We find him rifling through Mapplethorpe's "X" portfolio in a "coke dealer's penthouse," or<br />

evoking the origins of Mapplethorpe's work in "smoky, crowded rooms with raw brick walls [<strong>and</strong>]<br />

sawhorse bars."(6) Hickey poses as a kind of critic provocateur, hurling his "outrageous" epithets<br />

at the indifferent monolith of the art establishment.(7) At the center of this avant-garde mise en<br />

scene is the artwork that magically eludes any deadening "institutional" mediation to strike up a<br />

direct <strong>and</strong> spontaneous relationship with the viewer. This exchange may take place in a


Manhattan penthouse or in a smoke-filled bar but it certainly can't occur in a glacial "postmodern<br />

ice box."(8) Just what would a work of art outside of some form of institutional mediation look<br />

like? And how would we recognize it? It is the "rhetorical" power of the artwork that marks it off<br />

from other cultural objects, according to Hickey; its suasive ability to bring us into direct contact<br />

with a radically different set of values or model of subjectivity.(9)<br />

On the one h<strong>and</strong>, by embracing "dangerous" or "transgressive" art that is willfully<br />

indifferent to its own cultural responsibilities, Hickey wants to reject what he views as the liberal<br />

do-goodism of an engaged art that treats the viewer as a child to be educated. At the same<br />

moment Hickey cannot entirely ab<strong>and</strong>on the Enlightenment tradition, which insists that the<br />

aesthetic has a moral function, if not necessarily a moral intention. He postulates the experience<br />

of beauty as an unfolding cognitive operation in which we are first drawn in <strong>and</strong> made receptive<br />

by the sensory pleasure of beauty, <strong>and</strong> then confronted with the presence of a radically different<br />

subjectivity (e.g., Mapplethorpe's renegade sexuality).(10) Thus the artwork is an expression of<br />

the artist's own "moral <strong>and</strong> political construction of the visual world" that he communicates to the<br />

viewer through techniques of beauty that excite visual pleasure.(11) Rather than simply<br />

defending the value of a private aesthetic pleasure, Hickey is concerned to identify some<br />

relationship between "private desire" <strong>and</strong> "public virtue."(12) It is not the fact that art might have a<br />

moral/pedagogical function that Hickey objects to, but rather the means by which this function is<br />

exercised on the viewer. Thus aesthetic experience destabilizes our sense of identity <strong>and</strong> leads<br />

us to an "anxious" consciousness that is appropriate to the political condition of contemporary<br />

society. After undergoing an aesthetic experience, the viewer's subjectivity is transformed in<br />

such a way that he or she becomes a more capable participant in "democratic" discourse.(13)<br />

The beautiful artwork induces a kind of therapeutic libertarianism, forcing the viewer to make<br />

"moral decisions" without recourse to cultural or political absolutes.(14) This is, unfortunately, the<br />

point in Hickey's analysis that is most ambiguous. How does he define democracy? What form of<br />

agency do his "anxious" subjects exercise? What is the relationship between the privatized <strong>and</strong><br />

physical aesthetic encounter <strong>and</strong> discursive knowledge?<br />

It is precisely this ambiguity that links Hickey's account of beauty to a nexus of questions


about the aesthetic that stretches back over two centuries to the writings of such figures as Kant,<br />

Lessing, Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, <strong>and</strong> Hume.(15) The following essays seek to build on, <strong>and</strong><br />

also complicate, the questions of aesthetic experience that have been raised by Hickey <strong>and</strong><br />

others during the last few years. At the same time they seek to establish a critical rapprochement<br />

with the "return" to the aesthetic in contemporary philosophy <strong>and</strong> critical theory. Thus we might<br />

consider Hickey's embrace of beauty in relation to recent work by such scholars as Howard<br />

Caygill, David Wellbery, Luc Ferry, D. N. Rodowick, Susan Buck-Morss, <strong>and</strong> Terry Eagleton,<br />

among others.(16) Here the "return" to the aesthetic is precisely an attempt to recapture a<br />

broader underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the term, prior to its specification to the experience of the work of art in<br />

the nineteenth century. For Kant the term "aesthetic" is used in both Critique of Pure Reason, to<br />

refer to a priori sense-based experience, <strong>and</strong> Critique of Judgment, to refer to a disinterested<br />

"reflective judgment" epitomized by the experience of "taste."(17) Although Alex<strong>and</strong>er<br />

Baumgarten, who coined the term "aesthetic" in his Reflections on Poetry (1735), was<br />

concerned with questions of art making (specifically poetics), he also defined the aesthetic in<br />

terms of somatic experience ("the science of sensory cognition") rather than beauty per se.(18)<br />

The aesthetic also functions within Enlightenment philosophy (<strong>and</strong> later in the work of Hegel) as<br />

a political figure for the relationship between the individual subject <strong>and</strong> a social totality, such as<br />

the "state." It is this political dimension of the aesthetic that is examined by Greig Crysler <strong>and</strong><br />

Abidin Kusno in their reading of the Holocaust Memorial Museum <strong>and</strong> its construction of a<br />

national subject on the basis of a process of bodily identification.<br />

We can identify both a politically symbolic aesthetic <strong>and</strong> a somatic aesthetic; an aesthetic<br />

predicated on public discourse <strong>and</strong> an aesthetic predicated on bodily knowledge. Or rather, as I<br />

have suggested above, we might say that the aesthetic is located precisely between these two<br />

points. The complex position of the aesthetic originates in the political <strong>and</strong> epistemological crisis<br />

brought about by the erosion of monarchical <strong>and</strong> religious authority <strong>and</strong> the accession of the<br />

bourgeoisie to political power during the eighteenth century. These two events threatened to<br />

sunder the signifying chain of divine right. The social cohesion provided by the feudal system<br />

(albeit often by force) was dissolved. But what would take its place? What power could hold the<br />

social order together? This question became even more pressing under the impact of the rising


market economy in which traditional forms of social organization were subjected to what Marx<br />

described as the "everlasting uncertainty <strong>and</strong> agitation" created by capitalism.(19) Much of the<br />

philosophy of the Enlightenment can be read simultaneously as a critique of absolutism <strong>and</strong> as a<br />

search for a new epistemological foundation to replace it. From Lord Shaftesbury's je ne sais<br />

quoi to Adam Smith's "invisible h<strong>and</strong>," philosophers were obsessed with uncovering some<br />

principle that could bring harmony <strong>and</strong> coordination to the complex play of interests <strong>and</strong> classes<br />

that made up eighteenth-century European social order.<br />

The aesthetic emerges with such urgency during the eighteenth century because it<br />

promises to reveal a (noncoercive) cognitive ground that can guarantee a universal st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

judgment. It is through this "anthropological ontology"(20) that Kant discovers a prior unity that<br />

can resolve the contradiction between subjective experience <strong>and</strong> objective judgment. As Kant<br />

notes:<br />

The cognitive powers brought into play by [aesthetic] presentation are in free play, because no<br />

determinant concept restricts them to a particular rule of cognition. . . . This state of free play of<br />

the cognitive powers, accompanying a presentation by which the object is given, must be<br />

universally communicable; for cognition, the determination of the object with which given<br />

presentations are to harmonize (in any subject whatever) is the only way of presenting that holds<br />

for everyone.(21)<br />

The feeling of (bodily) pleasure that is produced by the cooperation of the imagination <strong>and</strong> the<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing is a signifier for Kant of the underlying correspondence between the individual<br />

subject <strong>and</strong> the "universal voice" (Kant's variant of Shaftesbury's sensus communis or "common<br />

sense").(22) It provides the calming reassurance that we are, beneath it all (or perhaps, above it<br />

all), rational subjects <strong>and</strong> at least potentially capable of achieving a political consensus by virtue<br />

of that fact that we all experience the world through the same basic cognitive operations. The<br />

"common sense" (Gemeinsinn) achieved by aesthetic reflection evokes a utopian community in<br />

which our most personal <strong>and</strong> intuitive responses to the world around us are immediately<br />

validated by the collective experience of our fellow citizens. This "aesthetic state" further<br />

presupposes the existence of a "public sphere" (premised on what Kant defines as "publicity") in<br />

which free <strong>and</strong> open debate among equals always results in an absolute but non-coercive<br />

consensus because each subject is able to overcome their own petty differences <strong>and</strong> judge from


the vantage point of a transcendent greater good.(23)<br />

Although Kant is concerned to differentiate aesthetic judgment from moral judgment by<br />

virtue of its non-instrumental or disinterested character, the very experience evoked by the<br />

aesthetic, the intuition of a universal voice, clearly has moral <strong>and</strong> political implications about<br />

which one could hardly remain indifferent. It is, after all, the aesthetic that claims to reconcile the<br />

purely subjective experience of beauty with the "objective" conditions necessary for political<br />

discourse <strong>and</strong> will formation. The unresolved relationship between the moral <strong>and</strong> the aesthetic in<br />

Kant's philosophy is marked by his recourse to a poetics of ambiguity. Although there is no<br />

causal relationship or "intrinsic affinity" (innere Affinitat) between morality <strong>and</strong> taste, it is<br />

nevertheless the case that our sense of beauty is provided with a form of moral "guidance"<br />

(geleitet, a word that also has the connotation of a military escort [Ak298]). Thus, despite Kant's<br />

insistence on the neutrality of aesthetic judgment, there is clearly an active moral <strong>and</strong><br />

pedagogical element at work: the aesthetic "teaches us to like even objects of sense freely"<br />

(Ak354), <strong>and</strong> in the act of experiencing beauty we are conscious of the fact that our mind is<br />

"being ennobled" (Veredlung [Ak353]).(24)<br />

This ambiguity between the moral <strong>and</strong> the aesthetic is characteristic of what philosopher<br />

Anthony Cascardi has termed the tradition of "aesthetic liberalism."(25) It also marks Hickey's<br />

account of a "rhetorical" beauty.(26) There are two components of Hickey's analysis that are of<br />

particular relevance here. First is his commitment to the "work of art" as a specifically privileged<br />

vehicle for inducing an "aesthetic" awareness, defined as a mode of cognition that provides a<br />

conduit between somatic experience (the felt pleasure of beauty) <strong>and</strong> a ground for<br />

intersubjective communication. This conduit itself has a highly developed symbolic value, <strong>and</strong>,<br />

although it is often only vaguely defined, it typically makes reference to some form of social or<br />

political consensus (in Hickey's case "democracy"). Second, the experience of the work of art is<br />

understood as a paradigm for the construction of an exemplary subjectivity. This is an essentially<br />

private encounter between the viewer (defined as a monadic subject) <strong>and</strong> the artwork (as the<br />

material expression of another monadic subject), which must remain free of any external<br />

"mediation." It is this belief in an unmediated, <strong>and</strong> essentially private, encounter that allows<br />

Hickey to ignore any contextual distinctions between, for example, the market conditions of the


gallery sector <strong>and</strong> the market conditions of the nonprofit "alternative" arts sector.(27) We might<br />

contrast this with the interest shown by the contributors here in collaborative modes of<br />

production. Jill Casid <strong>and</strong> Maria DeGuzman, for example, organize their projects through<br />

"collaboration agreements" among their friends <strong>and</strong> colleagues. They write: "These agreements<br />

<strong>and</strong> our praxis of collaboration are for us a means to intervene in the persistent myth of<br />

individualism that lies behind so much of U.S. culture's rhetoric of community <strong>and</strong> consensus.<br />

Furthermore, through this process of collaboration we attempt to contest the aesthetic fetish of<br />

the authorial trace central to the institutions of connoisseurship <strong>and</strong> the image market." Peter<br />

Dunn <strong>and</strong> Loraine Leeson describe their practice as the result of "a transformation through<br />

critique, collaboration, <strong>and</strong> communication [in which] . . . social <strong>and</strong> visual processes [are]<br />

inextricably linked. . . . the work forms a lens that creates a focal point in the energies of<br />

transformation. Desire focused is passion, <strong>and</strong> what is socialized passion but aesthetics?"<br />

The political dimension of the aesthetic is explicit in the work of Schiller as well as Hegel.<br />

Their concern is not merely with works of art, but with political <strong>and</strong> cultural subjectivity on a<br />

broad social scale. In On the Aesthetic Education of Man (1793), Schiller provides a prescient<br />

diagnosis of the effect of a market-based society in which "material needs reign supreme <strong>and</strong><br />

bend a degraded humanity beneath their tyrannical yoke." It is a society in which "we see not<br />

merely individuals, but whole classes of men, developing but one part of their potentialities,<br />

while of the rest, as in stunted growths, only vestigial traces remain." The effect of this society is<br />

to fragment <strong>and</strong> divide human nature. Schiller advocates a therapeutic turn to the aesthetic to<br />

"restore . . . the totality of our nature."(28) Aesthetic knowledge has the redemptive capacity to<br />

imagine <strong>and</strong> figure a more holistic <strong>and</strong> humane set of social relations. The aesthetic can be<br />

taken as an implicit criticism of the existing social system, which has failed to realize the utopian<br />

potential contained in the relationship between viewer <strong>and</strong> artwork. However, in order to achieve<br />

this perspective the aesthetic must st<strong>and</strong> "outside" existing society.<br />

In his Philosophy of Right Hegel uses the concept of aesthetic distance to describe the<br />

function of the state as a "disinterested" observer, attending not to the "various parts" of society,<br />

but to the larger patterns formed by the interrelationship of these parts, <strong>and</strong> ultimately to society<br />

as it could be, rather than as it is.(29) This is the utopian moment of the aesthetic as that mode of


knowledge that can transgress existing boundaries of knowledge <strong>and</strong> transcend the here <strong>and</strong><br />

now to envision a more just <strong>and</strong> equitable society. The aesthetic grasps the complex totality of<br />

social relations <strong>and</strong> is thereby able to recognize the effect of the market in generating systematic<br />

inequalities. It combines both a unique form of knowledge <strong>and</strong> a desire for social improvement.<br />

Our perception of works of art here <strong>and</strong> now allows us to glimpse the possibility of an Ideal future<br />

in which all of our social relationships would allow for the simultaneous <strong>and</strong> non-coercive<br />

expression of the individual <strong>and</strong> the universal. The aesthetic functions as a token (to be<br />

redeemed at some unspecified future date) of a more integrated relationship between life <strong>and</strong><br />

labor, <strong>and</strong> as a symbolic embodiment of a world that could be.<br />

The aesthetic strikes a Faustian bargain, however, which allows it to think utopia but only<br />

at the cost of never being able to try to bring it about. As Schiller wrote in 1793:<br />

It is in the world of semblance alone that [the artist] possesses [a] sovereign right, in the<br />

insubstantial realm of the imagination; <strong>and</strong> he possesses it there only as long as he scrupulously<br />

refrains from predicating real existence of it in theory, <strong>and</strong> as long as he renounces all idea of<br />

imparting real existence through it in practice.(30)<br />

Even as he refuses practical engagement, however, the artist is compensated by the<br />

transcendent power of the aesthetic. The artist emerges as the ideal "disinterested" subject of<br />

modern liberalism, able to shed the cultural accouterment of a specific identity <strong>and</strong> to speak in<br />

<strong>and</strong> through a universalized aesthetic experience. In the case of Hegel's analogous political<br />

reading of the aesthetic, while the state is able to recognize the deleterious effects of the market,<br />

he refuses to grant it the authority to challenge the preeminence of the market dynamic in<br />

determining social relations. The state can observe, <strong>and</strong> even judge, civil society from the<br />

vantage point of a teleological social progress, but it is prevented from realizing this progress<br />

through any practical intervention in market forces. For Hegel, the market retains the status of an<br />

environment in which the play of forces between consumer <strong>and</strong> producer <strong>and</strong> owner <strong>and</strong> worker<br />

proceeds in a "nature-like" way <strong>and</strong> must be insulated from state interference. Thus, although<br />

Hegel was sympathetic to the plight of the poor created by the market forces at work in civil<br />

society, he was at the same time reluctant to suggest that the state should offer any large-scale<br />

program of aid to the "penurious rabble" for fear of disrupting the moral economy of capitalism in


which success or failure in the market is the sole determinant of one's well-being.(31)<br />

For Hegel, the solution to the crisis of civil society is not for the "aesthetic state" to modify<br />

the actions of the market or to challenge the centrality of property rights through any form of<br />

public regulation, but rather to exp<strong>and</strong> the boundaries of the market itself, to open up new<br />

territories or frontiers to economic exploitation. "The inner dialectic of civil society thus drives it,"<br />

as Hegel writes, "to push beyond its limits <strong>and</strong> seek markets, <strong>and</strong> so its necessary means of<br />

subsistence, in other l<strong>and</strong>s, which are either deficient in the goods it has over-produced, or else<br />

generally backward in industry." Colonization of "backward" l<strong>and</strong>s by "mature" civil society is<br />

Hegel's solution.(32) Thus, if the aesthetic state transcends civil society, the state itself is subject<br />

to a regulatory principle in the form of the market. Property, the "inner dialectic" of civil society,<br />

ultimately "transcends," <strong>and</strong> frames, the authority of the state in Hegel's political economy. It is<br />

for this reason that Hickey's indifference to the specificity of market functions in framing aesthetic<br />

experience is symptomatic. The recognition that the market makes itself felt in almost every<br />

cultural domain all too easily becomes an excuse to neglect the important differences that<br />

pertain among these sites. And the rejection of the nonprofit arts sector slides easily into an<br />

uncritical embrace of the glamorous world of galleries, dealers, collectors, <strong>and</strong> auction houses.<br />

(33)<br />

Aesthetic liberalism offers the image of a better life. But so long as the market retains its<br />

transcendent status in liberal political theory, the telos of a more just <strong>and</strong> equitable social order<br />

will remain virtual, <strong>and</strong> the experience of a universal subjectivity will remain the sole province of<br />

those who can afford it. It is this teleological dimension that links the aesthetic judgment of the<br />

bourgeois subject <strong>and</strong> the political judgment of the liberal state. They each embody Kant's<br />

"finality without end" (Zweckmassigkeit ohne Zweck) by "straining toward the end" that they are<br />

by definition prevented from reaching.(34) Thus we are left with the conclusion reached by<br />

Schiller, in his consideration of the "promise" of an aesthetic utopia on earth:<br />

In the Aesthetic State everything - even the tool which serves - is a free citizen, having equal<br />

rights with the noblest; <strong>and</strong> the mind, which would force the patient mass beneath the yoke of its<br />

purposes, must here first obtain its assent. . . But does such a State of Aesthetic Semblance<br />

really exist? And if so, where is it to be found? As a need it exists in every finely tuned soul; as a<br />

realized fact, we are likely to find it, like the pure Church <strong>and</strong> the pure Republic, only in some<br />

chosen circles, where conduct is governed, not by some soulless imitations of the manners <strong>and</strong>


morals of others, but by the aesthetic nature we have made our own.(35)<br />

One can postulate ideal forms of society endlessly, but without also engaging the difficult<br />

questions raised by how these models might be applied, they remain ineffectual abstractions. On<br />

the one h<strong>and</strong>, the aesthetic provides an autonomous refuge or sanctuary apart from<br />

instrumentality <strong>and</strong> self-interest. At the same time, the aesthetic serves as a kind of navigational<br />

marker toward the telos of a society that is united in a non-coercive common sense. But the very<br />

disengagement from the object (<strong>and</strong> by extension, from worldly concerns) that provides the<br />

disinterested outlook with a perspective from which to criticize existing social values (<strong>and</strong> from<br />

which to imagine something better) also prevents it from engaging in any concrete way with the<br />

forms of political <strong>and</strong> social power that maintain, <strong>and</strong> are maintained by, those values. The<br />

principle of an Enlightenment aesthetic is denied any means of practical or empirical application.<br />

Its effects can be produced only in the realm of ideas, <strong>and</strong> the actual transformation of society<br />

remains a teleological principle rather than a practical goal.<br />

This issue seeks to challenge the disengagement of the aesthetic from political discourse<br />

not by denying the knowledge produced by the body <strong>and</strong> the senses, but by analyzing the ways<br />

in which this knowledge both resists <strong>and</strong> collaborates with forms of social, cultural, <strong>and</strong> political<br />

power. In place of a preoccupation with beauty the following essays might be said to concern<br />

themselves with the political economy of the aesthetic. Dunn <strong>and</strong> Leeson call for a new<br />

"aesthetics of collaboration" based on "interdisciplinary approaches to change in our<br />

environment, culture, <strong>and</strong> communications." Susan Buck-Morss discusses the "anesthetizing"<br />

effect of modern culture, which works to suppress our bodily capacity for "critical cognition." She<br />

rejects the idea that sense-based experience can be partitioned from a political consciousness,<br />

arguing instead that "cultural meanings are sensed bodily as being wrong." "How else," argues<br />

Buck-Morss, "are people capable of social protest? . . . I want to say that aesthetics is the body's<br />

form of critical cognition, <strong>and</strong> that this sensory knowledge can <strong>and</strong> should be trusted politically."<br />

Greig Crysler <strong>and</strong> Abidin Kusno suggest that Hickey's "therapeutic institutions" (even those with<br />

no particular interest in "art" per se) are quite capable of deploying aesthetic techniques that<br />

engage the viewer on the level of somatic or bodily experience.(36) Thus, the Holocaust


Memorial Museum employs a veritable phantasmagoria of visual <strong>and</strong> aural techniques to solicit<br />

the viewer's identification with a series of pre-established subject positions designed to advance<br />

a liberal teleology. The image of the Jewish victim/witness proffered in the museum is the result<br />

of a process of abstraction that epitomizes the operation of Hegel's "aesthetic state." As a result<br />

of this process Judaism is made co-extensive with the emergence of the modern liberal state,<br />

while its specific "empirical" identity as a religious <strong>and</strong> cultural practice is extruded as mere<br />

"difference."<br />

Alla Efimova identifies a surprisingly strong commitment to the power of aesthetic<br />

experience in the midst of the ostensibly stolid <strong>and</strong> unimaginative art of Stalinist Russia. Rather<br />

than dry didacticism, such artists as Arkady Rylov, Alex<strong>and</strong>er Laktionov, <strong>and</strong> Konstantin Youn<br />

constantly sought to evoke what Soviet art historian A. A. Fedorov-Davydov described as a<br />

"vivid aesthetic pleasure." Efimova points to ways in which Soviet artists negotiated their<br />

commitment to an affective visuality even as they worked within the strictures of Socialist Realist<br />

doctrine. Howard Caygill draws directly from early modern aesthetic philosophy to investigate<br />

the performances <strong>and</strong> projects of the Greek-Australian artist Stelarc. Drawing on neglected<br />

sections of the Critique of Judgment, Caygill outlines a Kantian model of subjectivity <strong>and</strong> agency<br />

based on an unresolved tension between mind <strong>and</strong> body, "inside" <strong>and</strong> "outside," <strong>and</strong> art <strong>and</strong><br />

cultural transformation. Stelarc's works, according to Caygill, both challenge <strong>and</strong> extend Kant's<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the relationship between technology <strong>and</strong> the human subject through their<br />

prosthetic "reorganization of the body." In their Artists' Pages, Jill Casid <strong>and</strong> Maria DeGuzman<br />

interrogate the foundations of modern aesthetics in the faux universality of the eighteenth-century<br />

man of delicate taste. Through the staging of mock "tableaux," Casid, DeGuzman, <strong>and</strong> their<br />

collaborators seek to position "women <strong>and</strong> people of color as agents rather than as objects or<br />

icons of the primitive past, of nature, matter, or preindustrial society." Finally, Sarat Maharaj<br />

provides an outline of another set of collaborations: the Monkeydoodle project developed at<br />

Goldsmiths' College. Drawing on the influences of John Cage, Daniel Spoerri, Marcel Duchamp,<br />

<strong>and</strong> James Joyce, Maharaj's students challenge the tyranny of the analytic aesthetic through an<br />

"aconceptual" mode that blurs the boundaries between discourse <strong>and</strong> figure, <strong>and</strong> between the<br />

essay <strong>and</strong> the work of art. Taken together the following essays <strong>and</strong> projects offer a range of


meditations on the current status of the aesthetic that seek to preserve its complexity, both<br />

culturally <strong>and</strong> politically, as a practice <strong>and</strong> a discourse.<br />

NOTES<br />

1. Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. Elizabeth M. Wilkinson<br />

<strong>and</strong> L. A. Willoughby (1796; Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), 219.<br />

2. Dave Hickey, The Invisible Dragon: Four Essays on Beauty (Los Angeles: Art Issues Press,<br />

1993). See also "'B' Is for Beauty," special issue of <strong>New</strong> Art Examiner 21, no. 8 (April 1994);<br />

"The Return of Beauty," special issue of Artweek 27, no. 4 (April 1996); Richard Bolton, "Beauty<br />

Redefined: From Ideal Form to Experiential Meaning," <strong>New</strong> Art Examiner 21, no. 3 (November<br />

1993): 27-31; <strong>and</strong> Wendy Steiner, The Sc<strong>and</strong>al of Pleasure (Chicago: University of Chicago<br />

Press, 1995).<br />

3. From a draft version of Peter Dunn <strong>and</strong> Loraine Leeson's essay "The Aesthetics of<br />

Collaboration." They wrote: "it has to be acknowledged . . . that in displacing the focus to other,<br />

previously under theorized <strong>and</strong> under valued powers at work—the social, economic, ideological,<br />

<strong>and</strong> wider cultural contexts <strong>and</strong> 'readings' of the art work—many valuable new insights have<br />

been revealed. But a refusal [by postmodern critics] to engage adequately with something so<br />

central to the activity of making <strong>and</strong> viewing art—the visual power or 'beauty' of the work—left a<br />

gap that enabled the transcendentalists, institutional gate-keepers <strong>and</strong> neo-Modernists to claim<br />

this ground for their own."<br />

4. Hickey, Invisible Dragon, 13-14.<br />

5. Ibid., 29, 34. According to Hickey, Robert Mapplethorpe, Andy Warhol, <strong>and</strong> Ed Ruscha<br />

"engage individuals within <strong>and</strong> without the cultural ghetto in arguments about what is good <strong>and</strong><br />

what is beautiful. And they do so without benefit of clergy, out on the street, out on the margin"<br />

(24).<br />

6. Ibid., 30, 31.<br />

7. Hickey is associate professor of art criticism <strong>and</strong> theory at the University of Nevada at Las<br />

Vegas. He was the 1994 recipient of the Frank Jewett Mather Award, presented by the College<br />

Art Association for distinction in art criticism. He describes his views as "outrageous" in Invisible<br />

Dragon, 12.<br />

8. Ibid., 13.<br />

9. Ibid., 22.<br />

10. It would seem to be the case that Mapplethorpe's images are only confrontational or<br />

transgressive for someone with little or no awareness of gay S/M sexual practices. For other<br />

viewers they might seem simply erotic, or merely banal.<br />

11. "Gorgeous Politics, Dangerous Pleasures: Dave Hickey on Beauty's Subversive Potential,<br />

an Interview by Ann Wiens," <strong>New</strong> Art Examiner 21, no. 8 (April 1994): 15.


12. Mark Van Proyen, "A Conversation with Dave Hickey, Critic," Artweek 27, no. 4 (April 1996):<br />

14.<br />

13. As Hickey writes: ". . . the vernacular of beauty, in its democratic appeal, remains a potent<br />

instrument for change in this civilization"; Invisible Dragon, 24.<br />

14. Van Proyen, "Conversation with Dave Hickey," 14.<br />

15. Shaftesbury writes of the overwhelming "rhetorical" power of natural beauty: "I shall no<br />

longer resist the passion growing in me for things of a natural kind, where neither art nor the<br />

conceit or caprice of man has spoiled their genuine order by breaking in upon that primitive<br />

state"; Anthony Ashley Cooper, Third Earl of Shaftesbury, Characteristics of Men, Manners,<br />

Opinions, Times, etc., vol. 11, ed. John M. Robertson (1711; <strong>New</strong> York: E. P. Dutton, 1900), 125.<br />

See also Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (1790; Indianapolis:<br />

Hackett, 1987); Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty <strong>and</strong><br />

Virtue, vol. 1 of The Collected Works of Francis Hutcheson, ed. Bernhard Fabian (Hildesheim:<br />

Georg Olms Verlag, 1990); David Hume, "Of the St<strong>and</strong>ard of Taste," in Essays Moral, Political<br />

<strong>and</strong> Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1985); <strong>and</strong> Gotthold Ephraim<br />

Lessing, Laocoon: An Essay on the Limits of Painting <strong>and</strong> Poetry, trans. Edward Allen<br />

McCormick (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1984).<br />

16. See Howard Caygill, Art of Judgement (London: Basil Blackwell, 1989); David E. Wellbery,<br />

Lessing's Laocoon: Semiotics <strong>and</strong> Aesthetics in the Age of Reason (London: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1984); Luc Ferry, Homo Aestheticus: The Invention of Taste in the Democratic<br />

Age, trans. Robert De Loaiza (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993); D. N. Rodowick,<br />

"Reading the Figural," Camera Obscura 24 (1991): 11-14, <strong>and</strong> "Audiovisual Culture <strong>and</strong><br />

Interdisciplinary Knowledge," <strong>New</strong> Literary History 26 (1995): 111-21; Susan Buck-Morss,<br />

"Aesthetics <strong>and</strong> Anaesthetics: Walter Benjamin's Artwork Essay Reconsidered," October 62<br />

(Fall 1992): 3-41, <strong>and</strong> "The City as Dreamworld <strong>and</strong> Catastrophe," October 73 (Summer 1995):<br />

3-26; <strong>and</strong> Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (London: Basil Blackwell, 1990). See<br />

also J. M. Bernstein, The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from Kant to Derrida to Adorno<br />

(University Park: Penn State Press, 1992); <strong>and</strong> Dave Beech <strong>and</strong> John Roberts, "Spectres of the<br />

Aesthetic," <strong>New</strong> Left Review 218 (July/August 1996): 102-27.<br />

17. Howard Caygill, A Kant Dictionary (Oxford: Blackwell Reference, 1995), 53-56.<br />

18. In the prolegomena to his Aesthetica (1750-58), Baumgarten gives the aesthetic a<br />

multivalent definition: "The Aesthetic (understood as the theory of free ['liberal'] Art, as an aspect<br />

of epistemology, as the art of beautiful thought - or thought about the beautiful - <strong>and</strong> the art of<br />

reason analogous to thought) is the science of sense-based cognition"; Alex<strong>and</strong>er Gottlieb<br />

Baumgarten, Theoretische Asthetik: Die grundlegenden Abschnitte aus der "Aesthetica,” ed. <strong>and</strong><br />

trans. Hans Rudolf Schweizer (1780-58; Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1983), 1 (translation mine). See<br />

also Alex<strong>and</strong>er Baumgarten, Reflections on Poetry, trans. K. Aschenbrenner <strong>and</strong> W. B. Holther<br />

(1735; Berkeley: University of California Press, 1954).<br />

19. Karl Marx <strong>and</strong> Friedrich Engels, "The Communist Manifesto," in Essential Works of Marxism,<br />

ed. Arthur P. Mendel (<strong>New</strong> York: Bantam Books, 1971), 16.<br />

20. Keith Tester, Civil Society (London: Routledge, 1992), 152.<br />

21. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, 62/Ak218.


22. Ibid., 60/Ak216.<br />

23. Kant describes judgments of beauty as being "public"; ibid., 57/Ak214. David Wellbery links<br />

this "public" status to the concept of an "ideal speech situation" in the work of Jürgen Habermas<br />

<strong>and</strong> others: "The ideal of transparency, which in the Enlightenment was conceived in semantic<br />

terms, reappears in the work of Habermas <strong>and</strong> Apel as a pragmatic ideal: a communicational<br />

exchange in which subjects are transparent to themselves <strong>and</strong> others. . . . As was the case in<br />

Enlightenment theory, aesthetic representations point forward to a state of freedom in which the<br />

compulsions <strong>and</strong> opacities of speech are finally overcome"; Wellbery, Lessing's Laocoon, 242.<br />

24. Kant, Critique of Judgment, 164, 229, 228. Kant speaks of the sense of beauty as providing<br />

"a mental attunement [gunstige Gemutsstimmung] favorable to moral feeling" (165/Ak299). And<br />

he argues that someone who displays an interest in the beauty of nature must also have a<br />

"predisposition" (Anlage) to a good moral attitude (167/Ak301). Later he describes the way in<br />

which taste allows us to "make the transition" (macht gleichsam) between the realm of the<br />

senses ("sensible charm") <strong>and</strong> "habitual moral interest" "without making too violent a leap"<br />

(ohne einen zu gewaltsamen Sprung [229/Ak354]).<br />

25. Cascardi defines aesthetic liberalism in the following way: "The aesthetic moment in Kant<br />

replicates rather than resolves the tensions between the individual <strong>and</strong> the community that Kant<br />

elsewhere formulates as central to the position of the subject in the modern world. Whereas the<br />

Enlightenment reading of Kant [exemplified by Habermas] sees the third Critique as reflecting a<br />

development of the 'inner logic' of a self-contained aesthetic sphere, <strong>and</strong> tends to privilege the<br />

public discourse of taste over the experience of art itself, <strong>and</strong> whereas the Romantic response to<br />

Kant tends to see the Critique of Judgment as a reintegrative <strong>and</strong> redemptive attempt to restore<br />

unity through the formation of what Schiller called an 'aesthetic state,' to a social totality that had<br />

been shattered by the disintegrative forces of capital, I would suggest that . . . Kant leads us to<br />

conclude that the foundations of the liberal ethic reside not in the cognitive powers of mason or<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, but in the (transcendental) imagination which regrounds the liberal state as the<br />

unity of wills under the concept of an end which has subjective claim to universality"; Anthony J.<br />

Cascardi, "Aesthetic Liberalism: Kant <strong>and</strong> the Ethics of Modernity," Revue Internationale de<br />

Philosophie 45, no. 176 (1991): 12-13.<br />

26. "Gorgeous Politics, Dangerous Pleasures," 15.<br />

27. I don't consider the nonprofit sector to be necessarily "purer" than the gallery world. Rather,<br />

the conditions of the market, economic exchange, <strong>and</strong> symbolic capital simply operate there in a<br />

different way. However, this difference is of considerable importance in terms of underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

the function of artists <strong>and</strong> institutions in each site. See <strong>Grant</strong> <strong>Kester</strong>, "Rhetorical Questions: The<br />

Alternative Arts Sector <strong>and</strong> the Imaginary Public," Afterimage 20, no. 6 (January 1993): 10-16.<br />

28. Aesthetic Education of Man, 43. Schiller writes: "Everlastingly chained to a single little<br />

fragment of the Whole, man himself develops into nothing but a fragment; everlastingly in his ear<br />

the monotonous sound of the wheel that he turns, he never develops the harmony of his being,<br />

<strong>and</strong> instead of putting the stamp of humanity upon his own nature, he becomes nothing more<br />

than the imprint of his occupation of his specialized knowledge"; ibid., 35.<br />

29. Hegel's Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox (London: Oxford University Press, 1952), 189.<br />

30. Schiller, Aesthetic Education of Man, 197.


31. Hegel's Philosophy of Right, 150.<br />

32. Ibid., 151 (italics mine).<br />

33. A recent essay on the return of beauty, which actually juxtaposes quotes from Dave Hickey<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kant, includes an exchange from a 1996 lecture series at the Otis College of Art <strong>and</strong> Design<br />

at which "one audience member . . . suggest[ed] that galleries are 'the front lines, the risk-takers<br />

in search of pleasure'"; Charlene Roth, "The Light under the Bushel," Artweek 27, no. 4 (April<br />

1996): 13.<br />

34. Jacques Derrida, The Truth in Painting, trans. Geoff Bennington <strong>and</strong> Ian McLeod (Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1987), 87.<br />

35. Schiller, The Aesthetic Education of Man, 219.<br />

36. Dave Hickey, "After the Great Tsunami: On Beauty <strong>and</strong> the Therapeutic Institution," in<br />

Invisible Dragon, 53-64.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!