05.04.2013 Views

Influence of deontological versus consequentialist orientations on ...

Influence of deontological versus consequentialist orientations on ...

Influence of deontological versus consequentialist orientations on ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

European Journal <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Social Psychology<br />

Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

Published <strong>on</strong>line in Wiley InterScience<br />

(www.interscience.wiley.com) DOI: 10.1002/ejsp.493<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Influence</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> act choices<br />

and framing effects: When principles are more important than c<strong>on</strong>sequences<br />

Abstract<br />

CARMEN TANNER 1 *, DOUGLAS L. MEDIN 2<br />

AND RUMEN ILIEV 2<br />

1 Department <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Psychology, University <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Zurich, Switzerland<br />

2 Northwestern University, Evanst<strong>on</strong>, USA<br />

A l<strong>on</strong>g traditi<strong>on</strong> in decisi<strong>on</strong> making assumes that people usually take a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> perspective, which implies a focus<br />

<strong>on</strong> the outcomes <strong>on</strong>ly when making decisi<strong>on</strong>s. Such a view largely neglects the existence <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> perspective,<br />

which implies that people are sensitive to moral duties that require or prohibit certain behaviors, irrespective <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequences. Similarly, recent research has also suggested that people holding ‘‘protected values’’ (PVs) show increased<br />

attenti<strong>on</strong> to acts <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong>s and less attenti<strong>on</strong> to outcomes. The present research investigates the role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> thought and <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs <strong>on</strong> framing effects and act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> choices.<br />

In a modificati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Tversky and Kahneman’s (1981) risky choice framing paradigm, we manipulated the framing <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the<br />

outcomes (positive, negative), as well as whether the certain outcome was associated with an act or inacti<strong>on</strong>. The main<br />

results suggest that act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> tendencies are linked to <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> focus and PVs. Framing effects, <strong>on</strong> the other<br />

hand, are driven by a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> focus. Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd.<br />

The li<strong>on</strong>’s share <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> research <strong>on</strong> judgment and decisi<strong>on</strong> making has focused <strong>on</strong> secular goods such as c<strong>on</strong>sumer choices or<br />

m<strong>on</strong>etary pay<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs. There is, however, a growing body <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> evidence c<strong>on</strong>cerning the moral aspects <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> choice, particularly<br />

for the case <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs. For instance, many people think that it is morally wr<strong>on</strong>g to assign a m<strong>on</strong>etary value to human lives<br />

or to have a free market in body parts or a futures market betting <strong>on</strong> terrorist acts. Recently, terms such as protected values<br />

(PVs) (Bar<strong>on</strong> & Spranca, 1997; Ritov & Bar<strong>on</strong>, 1999), sacred values (Tetlock, Kristel, Els<strong>on</strong>, Green, & Lerner, 2000), or<br />

taboo values (Lichtenstein, Gregory & Irwin, 2007) have been developed to express the idea that some values are thought<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> as absolute and protected from trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs with other values, particularly secular values (e.g., ec<strong>on</strong>omic benefits). A<br />

pers<strong>on</strong> who engages in or c<strong>on</strong>templates making such trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs may trigger moral outrage in others and may induce both<br />

harsh reacti<strong>on</strong>s toward and intenti<strong>on</strong> to punish the violator (Tetlock et al., 2000). In additi<strong>on</strong>, people may also be highly<br />

motivated to engage in activities that protect these values from threat and violati<strong>on</strong> (Skitka, 2002).<br />

There is also general agreement that these moral values have an impact <strong>on</strong> informati<strong>on</strong> processing and have an influence<br />

<strong>on</strong> what aspects <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a decisi<strong>on</strong> people deem to be relevant (e.g., Bar<strong>on</strong> & Spranca, 1997; Ritov & Bar<strong>on</strong>, 1999). Perhaps the<br />

most striking c<strong>on</strong>trast is between <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> perspectives <strong>on</strong> decisi<strong>on</strong>s. The focal point <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

de<strong>on</strong>tology is the c<strong>on</strong>cept <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> duty; de<strong>on</strong>tology is derived from the Greek word de<strong>on</strong> (duty). Duties are morally mandated<br />

acti<strong>on</strong>s or prohibiti<strong>on</strong>s, such as the duty to keep promises or the duty not to lie (Broad, 1930). The distinctive idea <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> approaches is that the morality <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a behavior is assessed by applicati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a rule or principle that requires or<br />

prohibits certain behaviors. It is the nature <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the act per se in which moral rightness or wr<strong>on</strong>gness resides (e.g., ‘‘I did it<br />

because it was the right thing to do.’’). C<strong>on</strong>sequences per se are at best sec<strong>on</strong>dary. The most influential <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> moral<br />

theory has been that advanced by Kant (1797), who introduced the idea <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the categorical imperative.<br />

*Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence to: Carmen Tanner, Department <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Psychology, University <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Zurich, Binzmuehlestrasse 14/18, 8050 Zurich, Switzerland.<br />

E-mail: c.tanner@psychologie.uzh.ch<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd.<br />

Received 11 April 2007<br />

Accepted 13 November 2007


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tological theories <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> morality are usually c<strong>on</strong>trasted with c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (e.g., Anscombe, 1958; Birnbacher,<br />

2003; Broad, 1930). A l<strong>on</strong>g traditi<strong>on</strong> in decisi<strong>on</strong> making assumes that people’s decisi<strong>on</strong>s are aimed at maximizing some<br />

benefit functi<strong>on</strong>, without being affected by rules or factors external to outcomes. In <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> analyses, c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

about what is right or wr<strong>on</strong>g are based <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>sequences.<br />

Although there is nothing inherent in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism that precludes its applicati<strong>on</strong> to moral decisi<strong>on</strong> making,<br />

previous work suggests that sacred or PVs are <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>ten linked with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> decisi<strong>on</strong> rules (e.g., Bar<strong>on</strong> & Spranca,<br />

1997). The present work explores the cognitive c<strong>on</strong>sequences <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> for<br />

framing effects. A sec<strong>on</strong>dary goal is to explicitly examine the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between PVs and de<strong>on</strong>tology and the relati<strong>on</strong><br />

between PVs and framing effects. In the next few paragraphs, we briefly review framing effects and then turn to the<br />

relati<strong>on</strong>ship between <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>.<br />

FRAMING EFFECTS<br />

The classic example <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> framing effects involves the Asian disease problem, in which participants are told that an outbreak<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> disease threatens to kill 600 people (Tversky & Kahneman, 1981). People are asked to choose between a risky opti<strong>on</strong><br />

and a certain opti<strong>on</strong> having the same expected value. In the positive frame, the outcomes are described in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the<br />

numbers <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> lives saved and in the negative frame in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> lives lost. The comm<strong>on</strong> finding is that participants tend to<br />

choose the certain opti<strong>on</strong> when the problem is framed in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> gains, but choose the risky opti<strong>on</strong> when the problem is<br />

framed in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> losses (see Kühberger, 1998; Rothman & Salovey, 1997, for reviews).<br />

Framing effects have inspired many researchers for both theoretical and practical reas<strong>on</strong>s. A number <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> studies have<br />

revealed that framing effects are not uniformly found (e.g., Levin, Schneider, & Gaeth, 1998; Schneider, 1992) but rather<br />

are affected by factors such as topics <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> scenarios (e.g., Fagley & Miller, 1997; Schneider, 1992), size <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> social group for which<br />

a decisi<strong>on</strong> problem is described (e.g., Wang, 1996), and self-relevance <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the task (Krishnamurthy, Carter, & Blair, 2001).<br />

Given that many framing tasks involve hypothetically affecting the lives <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> others (such as life–death scenarios), it seems likely<br />

that moral questi<strong>on</strong>s about which behavior is morally or ethically right are relevant to such tasks. Despite the apparent link to<br />

morality, it is surprising that the ethical or moral side <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> decisi<strong>on</strong>s has been largely neglected in previous research <strong>on</strong> framing effects.<br />

Recently, Tanner and Medin (2004) tested the idea that PVs increase attenti<strong>on</strong> to acts <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong>s and decrease<br />

attenti<strong>on</strong> to outcomes in value-related scenarios. They ran a study that combined the gain/loss and act/omissi<strong>on</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong><br />

by modifying Tversky and Kahneman’s (1981) risky choice framing paradigm. Rather than describing <strong>on</strong>ly the outcomes<br />

in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> lives saved or lives lost, <strong>on</strong>e opti<strong>on</strong> was described as an active choice and the other as a default c<strong>on</strong>sequence.<br />

With regard to the classic Asian Disease problem, for example, participants might be told that if they adopt Plan A,<br />

200 people will be saved for sure but if they do nothing, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third chance that all 600 will be saved and a<br />

two-thirds chance that no <strong>on</strong>e will be saved. Both the framing <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcome focus (positive vs. negative outcomes) and<br />

the certainty <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcomes (risky vs. certain) associated with the opti<strong>on</strong>s were varied and counterbalanced.<br />

Tanner and Medin (2004) presented people with four envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios and asked them to make choices that<br />

were framed as gains and losses and as acti<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> default outcomes. Two results are noteworthy: first, people who<br />

indicated PVs for the envir<strong>on</strong>mental issues were more likely to prefer acts over omissi<strong>on</strong>s. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, people with PVs were<br />

insensitive to the framing <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcomes. The results suggest that for people with PVs, the act/omissi<strong>on</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> was<br />

salient. Notably, it was not relevant for PV-people whether the alternatives were associated with gains or losses, and risky<br />

or certain outcomes. This c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with previous literature (Bar<strong>on</strong> & Spranca, 1997) arguing that PVs is<br />

associated with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> rules. The present study directly examines the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between de<strong>on</strong>tology and framing effects.<br />

RELATIONSHIPS BETWEEN DEONTOLOGICAL AND CONSEQUENTIALIST ORIENTATIONS<br />

It is natural to see <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> as mutually exclusive, at least for a particular decisi<strong>on</strong><br />

maker or for a particular problem. Broadly speaking, <strong>on</strong>e might either pay attenti<strong>on</strong> to the nature <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the act (its moral<br />

correctness) or to anticipated outcomes. However, what makes an acti<strong>on</strong> right or wr<strong>on</strong>g may not be definable<br />

without c<strong>on</strong>sidering its link with c<strong>on</strong>sequences in some form or another. De<strong>on</strong>tological <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> seldom disregard<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequences entirely. For instance, if two equally moral acts have different c<strong>on</strong>sequences, even a de<strong>on</strong>tologist may take<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


outcomes into account. Similarly, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism may also include <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> comp<strong>on</strong>ents. In integrating short-term<br />

with l<strong>on</strong>g-term c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s, it may be sensible to apply general rules for acti<strong>on</strong> and to rati<strong>on</strong>alize them with<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> justificati<strong>on</strong>s (Brandt, 1992; Harsanyi, 1977). In additi<strong>on</strong>, if outcomes are equivalent, the nature <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the act<br />

may come into c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>. Our research involves choices between act and omissi<strong>on</strong>s with equal expected values which<br />

may allow for greater <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to choice. In additi<strong>on</strong>, we also examine whether <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> are really mutually exclusive.<br />

The main purpose <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the following experiment is to examine the influence <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

perspectives and PVs <strong>on</strong> act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> bias and <strong>on</strong> framing effects. Note that explanati<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> framing effects as<br />

proposed by prospect theory are predominately based <strong>on</strong> the evaluati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcomes as gains <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> losses and their<br />

riskiness or certainty. Because c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism is associated with focus <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sequences and framing causes participants<br />

to view the outcomes as gains or losses, we would expect results that are in line with prospect theory (Tversky &<br />

Kahneman, 1981); positive framing associated with risk aversi<strong>on</strong> and negative framing associated with risk seeking. With<br />

more or less strict forms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> de<strong>on</strong>tology, however, we would expect insensitivity to framing (as was found by Tanner &<br />

Medin, 2004). Finally, if <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns are combined with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns we might expect both<br />

attenti<strong>on</strong> to act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong>s and greater attenti<strong>on</strong> to outcomes, yielding framing effects.<br />

We also wished to explore the effects <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> another measure <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs. Most previous studies have used a single questi<strong>on</strong> or<br />

probe to assess a PV, a practice that may lead to low reliability. In this paper, we added a scale c<strong>on</strong>sisting <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> multiple items<br />

that were aimed at deriving a more stable measure. These items were designed to tap <strong>on</strong> important features <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> protected or<br />

sacred values, for example, trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>f resistance, unwillingness to sacrifice a value, unwillingness to compromise or to<br />

questi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e’s positi<strong>on</strong> (Tetlock et al., 2000). Based <strong>on</strong> the claim that PVs derive from <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> principles, we expect<br />

to find similar patterns with PVs to those with de<strong>on</strong>tology.<br />

To summarize, the following research tested several related questi<strong>on</strong>s: (1) what is the relati<strong>on</strong> between <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, and (2) how are these <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> related to act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> choices and framing<br />

effects? (3) How are PVs associated with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, and (4) how are PVs related to<br />

act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> choices and framing effects?<br />

EXPERIMENT<br />

In order to study the role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> perspectives and PVs, we included a set <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> multiple<br />

items to assess <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, and a set <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> items probing for PVs. We also included<br />

some items to measure general caring or pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern about the problems described in the scenario. This was d<strong>on</strong>e to<br />

verify that having PVs is not more or less the same or identical to having greater c<strong>on</strong>cern about the problem. PVs were<br />

expected to correlate <strong>on</strong>ly modestly with pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern.<br />

With regard to <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, we expected to find that these two kinds <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>ing have<br />

different effects <strong>on</strong> acti<strong>on</strong> preferences and framing effects. Specifically, we hypothesized that a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong><br />

and PVs should be associated with a bias toward acts rather than omissi<strong>on</strong>s and a tendency to be insensitive to framing<br />

effects. C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, should be associated with framing effects.<br />

Given the practical relevance <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> tendencies and framing effects, we also wished to examine such<br />

effect in samples not just comprised <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> psychology students. For this purpose, we recruited a more heterogeneous sample<br />

by undertaking the experiment <strong>on</strong> the internet.<br />

Participants and Design<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

METHOD<br />

A total <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> 248 people participated in the web experiment that was c<strong>on</strong>ducted in German. Of this sample, 65% were women<br />

and 35% were men. The resp<strong>on</strong>dents ranged in age from 15 to 70 (M ¼ 32 years). The nati<strong>on</strong>ality compositi<strong>on</strong> was 46%<br />

from Switzerland, 50% from Germany, and 4% from other countries. Most people (89%) had the equivalent <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> some<br />

college and 34% had at least the equivalent <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a bachelor’s degree.<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

We manipulated framing (positive vs. negative) and act certainty (act with certain vs. risky outcomes). De<strong>on</strong>tological<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> and PVs were assessed by separate items. The dependent variables were choices <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> acts<br />

or choices <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> risky opti<strong>on</strong>s (when we talk about framing effects).<br />

Procedure and Materials<br />

To recruit participants, a link to the web experiment was presented <strong>on</strong> the first author’s homepage and <strong>on</strong> the web<br />

experimental psychology lab <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the University <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Zurich (http://genpsylab-wexlist.unizh.ch/). People were initially<br />

informed about the purpose and procedure <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the study and then presented with scenarios and asked to make a choice. The<br />

study incorporated two envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios (drinking water c<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong>, genetically engineered crops) and a social<br />

scenario (sick elderly people) (see Appendix A). Participants were provided with two <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> those three scenarios.<br />

Each scenario c<strong>on</strong>tained a choice between an act and an omissi<strong>on</strong> (e.g., vaccinati<strong>on</strong> vs. not vaccinating children suffering<br />

from having drunk c<strong>on</strong>taminated water). In accordance with Tversky and Kahneman’s (1981) classic framing paradigm,<br />

the choice alternatives were framed either positively or negatively. In the positive frame c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, the outcomes were<br />

described in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> gains (e.g., human lives or insect species saved). In the negative frame c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, the outcomes<br />

were described in terms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> losses (e.g., lives lost, insect species harmed). Act certainty was manipulated by changing the<br />

likelihood <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcomes associated with the act. This was either certain (when the omissi<strong>on</strong> outcome was risky) or risky<br />

(when the omissi<strong>on</strong> outcome was certain), but <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> equal expected value.<br />

After making their decisi<strong>on</strong>, participants were given a set <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> probes c<strong>on</strong>sisting <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

eight items (see Appendix B for the English translati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the German verbatim). They were asked to indicate the<br />

relevance <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> various possible reas<strong>on</strong>s for their choice <strong>on</strong> a five-point scale ranging from not important at all to very<br />

important. People were later provided with two items to indicate pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the problems described in the<br />

scenarios <strong>on</strong> a five-point scale ranging from str<strong>on</strong>gly disagree to str<strong>on</strong>gly agree (‘‘This issue is pers<strong>on</strong>ally important to<br />

me.’’ ‘‘I am c<strong>on</strong>cerned about this problem.’’). After completing these tasks for a given scenario, participants were given<br />

five items designed to measure PVs and asked to indicate their extent <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> agreement <strong>on</strong> a five-point scale ranging from<br />

str<strong>on</strong>gly disagree to str<strong>on</strong>gly agree (see Appendix B for the English translati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the German verbatim; <strong>on</strong>e item with a<br />

highly skewed resp<strong>on</strong>se distributi<strong>on</strong> was eliminated; see below). This procedure was repeated for the sec<strong>on</strong>d scenario.<br />

Finally, people were asked to indicate whether they took the tasks seriously before they were debriefed. This is a<br />

comm<strong>on</strong> strategy in web studies to exclude those people from the experiment who had interests other than participating in<br />

the study (e.g., just clicked through the pages to take a look). Only people who filled out the whole questi<strong>on</strong>naire and<br />

answered this final questi<strong>on</strong> positively were included in the final dataset.<br />

Participants were randomly assigned to <strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the experimental groups corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the four possible combinati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

from two frames (positive or negative), two kinds <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> outcomes associated with an act or omissi<strong>on</strong> (certain or risky). There<br />

were three combinati<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> two scenarios, and each combinati<strong>on</strong> had two orders (e.g., scenarios A and B, or scenarios B<br />

and A). Participants were randomly assigned to <strong>on</strong>e combinati<strong>on</strong> and order. These variati<strong>on</strong>s had no effect <strong>on</strong> the results.<br />

RESULTS AND DISCUSSION<br />

First, we will describe the analyses <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the measures, that is, <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>, PV, and<br />

pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern. These analyses revealed that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> were not mutually<br />

exclusive and not negatively correlated.<br />

Analyses <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> De<strong>on</strong>tological Versus C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist Orientati<strong>on</strong> and Protected Value Measures<br />

We c<strong>on</strong>ducted a factor analysis based <strong>on</strong> the item mean scores was based <strong>on</strong> the item mean scores across scenarios, in order<br />

to avoid missing values given that participants did <strong>on</strong>ly two <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the three scenarios. After eliminating <strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the PV items<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


with a highly skewed resp<strong>on</strong>se distributi<strong>on</strong>, the <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g>, PV items, and c<strong>on</strong>cern items were entered<br />

into principal comp<strong>on</strong>ent factor analyses with promax rotati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

This analysis revealed four factors which accounted for 62% <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the variance (for item scores and factor loadings see<br />

Table 1). Overall, four items c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> mode <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>ing loaded <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e factor, four items<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>ing style loaded <strong>on</strong> the sec<strong>on</strong>d factor, four items c<strong>on</strong>sistent with PVs loaded <strong>on</strong><br />

the third factor, and two items c<strong>on</strong>sistent with pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern loaded <strong>on</strong> the fourth factor. The reliabilities <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the scales<br />

assessed by Cr<strong>on</strong>bach’s a were .81, .62, .64, and .84 for the <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g>, PV, and pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern<br />

measure, respectively.<br />

Note that if the <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> were at opposite ends <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a c<strong>on</strong>trasting dimensi<strong>on</strong>, we<br />

would have expected to observe negative correlati<strong>on</strong>s between answers to the two types <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> questi<strong>on</strong>s, a single factor<br />

soluti<strong>on</strong>, and factor loadings <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> opposite signs. Instead, the overall correlati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

answers was quite small and positive (r ¼.03, n.s.), and two factors clearly emerged.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism was also more or less orthog<strong>on</strong>al with the PV score (r ¼ .08, n.s.). De<strong>on</strong>tological orientati<strong>on</strong> and<br />

PVs represented two separate, but relatively highly correlated factors (r ¼.55, p < .001). In additi<strong>on</strong>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and PV<br />

scores are reliably but somewhat modestly correlated with pers<strong>on</strong>al importance (rs ¼ .33 and .39, respectively, ps < .001).<br />

Overall, these results c<strong>on</strong>firm that PVs are closely associated to a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>, less closely to pers<strong>on</strong>al<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cern, but relatively independent <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Analysis <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Act Choices and Framing Results<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

A multiple regressi<strong>on</strong> analysis was c<strong>on</strong>ducted that c<strong>on</strong>formed to a 2 (positive vs. negative frame) 2 (act with certain vs.<br />

risky outcomes) <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> analysis <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> variance, with the last two factors as<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tinuous variables. The c<strong>on</strong>tinuous variables were centered (Cohen, Cohen, West, & Aiken, 2003). Prior inspecti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

each scenario indicated that age and pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern were not relevant factors in any <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the scenarios, and we therefore<br />

dropped them from further c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>. Gender, however, was statistically significant, though <strong>on</strong>ly in the social<br />

scenario. 1 Gender was therefore also included in the equati<strong>on</strong> to c<strong>on</strong>trol for it.<br />

Relevant to our current c<strong>on</strong>cerns, having a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> was a significant predictor for act choices,<br />

indicating that people high in <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> were more likely than people low in <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> to<br />

prefer acts over omissi<strong>on</strong>s (b ¼ .23; p < .001). Furthermore, the significant frame act certainty interacti<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .17;<br />

p < .001) reflected the typical framing effects as dem<strong>on</strong>strated by Tversky and Kahneman (1981). These framing effects<br />

were moderated by <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>, as reflected by a (marginally) significant interacti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> frame act<br />

certainty <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .13; p ¼ .06). It indicated that people higher in <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong><br />

showed larger framing effects. More interestingly, framing effects were also qualified by a frame act<br />

certainty <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .11; p < .05) interacti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

To better understand this interacti<strong>on</strong> and the different role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> focus, it is useful to<br />

describe their effects <strong>on</strong> act choices and framing effects separately. For this purpose, we created four subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

participants corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to low and high <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> (C<strong>on</strong>sHigh, C<strong>on</strong>sLow) and low and high <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> (De<strong>on</strong>High, De<strong>on</strong>Low), based <strong>on</strong> median splits <strong>on</strong> these variables.<br />

1 Inspecti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the each scenarios revealed that the envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios revealed essentially the same pattern, while the social scenario showed a<br />

somewhat different pattern. A tendency for framing effects and act biases were found am<strong>on</strong>g the envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios, while the social scenario <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

showed act biases but no typical framing effects. Furthermore, it appeared that gender was particularly sensitive to the social issue ‘‘sick elderly,’’ which<br />

may be the reas<strong>on</strong> for the varying pattern with the social scenario. Unlike the other scenarios, gender was a relevant factor in the social scenario, with<br />

women showing a str<strong>on</strong>ger tendency than men to prefer acts. The main regressi<strong>on</strong> results with framing, act certainty, <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

orientati<strong>on</strong> and gender as predictors, and act choices as criteri<strong>on</strong> were as follows: The results across the envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios (drinking water<br />

c<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong> and genetically engineered crops) showed that people higher in <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns were more likely to prefer acts over omissi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

(b ¼ .11, p ¼ .09). The significant frame act certainty interacti<strong>on</strong> was indicative for the typical framing effects (b ¼ .24, p < .001). The significant<br />

interacti<strong>on</strong> frame act certainty <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .17, p < .05) was moderated by the interacti<strong>on</strong> frame act certainty<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .17, p < .05). Simple comparis<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>g subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> high and low <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and high<br />

and low c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism c<strong>on</strong>firmed that differences in risky choices under negative and positive frame, c<strong>on</strong>sistent with framing effects, were found<br />

am<strong>on</strong>g groups high in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (Fs > 5.19, p < .05). The social scenario (sick elderly) revealed that women and people higher in <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

c<strong>on</strong>cerns were more likely to prefer acts over omissi<strong>on</strong>s (b ¼ .12, p < .08 and b ¼ .48, p < .001, respectively). In additi<strong>on</strong>, the significant interacti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

sex act certainty (b ¼ .24, p < .01) and sex frame (b ¼ .15, p ¼ .05), reflected the fact that women were more likely to prefer acts when the opti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

represented risky acts and were framed positively. No overall framing effects were found.<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

Table 1. Item scores, factor loadings, and scale reliabilities<br />

Mean SD Factor loadings a<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tological scale .81<br />

De<strong>on</strong> 1 2.99 1.06 .83<br />

De<strong>on</strong> 2 3.26 1.18 .83<br />

De<strong>on</strong> 3 2.48 1.20 .67<br />

De<strong>on</strong> 4 2.57 1.15 .82<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist scale .62<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s 1 2.73 1.21 .45<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s 2 3.74 0.97 .76<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s 3 3.02 1.17 .67<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s 4 3.65 1.02 .77<br />

Protected value scale .64<br />

PV 1 3.34 0.99 .72<br />

PV 2 3.66 1.02 .48<br />

PV 3 2.53 1.06 .66<br />

PV 4 3.16 1.03 .70<br />

Pers<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cern .84<br />

C<strong>on</strong>cern 1 3.32 1.04 .88<br />

C<strong>on</strong>cern 2 3.31 1.11 .89<br />

Looking first at how <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> affect act choices, Table 2 reveals the important<br />

trends. As can be seen, act preferences were larger for the two high <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> groups (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>High ¼ 0.63,<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>High ¼ 0.60) than for the two low <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> groups (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>Low ¼ 0.43, C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/<br />

De<strong>on</strong>Low ¼ 0.45). These patterns suggest that act choices are likely to be a functi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> focus. The low<br />

de<strong>on</strong>tology subgroups, if anything, showed an omissi<strong>on</strong> bias.<br />

Figure 1 clarifies the four-way interacti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the regressi<strong>on</strong> analysis based <strong>on</strong> median splits <strong>on</strong> the <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> and<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> variables. The figure displays the mean proporti<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> risky choices to examine framing effects.<br />

As can be seen, larger framing effects were found am<strong>on</strong>g people high in <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns. Both groups high in<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>Low, C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>High) showed modest to large framing effects with reliable<br />

differences between risky choices under negative <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> positive frames (F (1, 61) ¼ 3.63, p ¼ .06, and F (1, 51) ¼ 19.24,<br />

p < .001, respectively). People low in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>Low, C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>High) showed no reliable<br />

difference between risky choices under negative and positive frames (Fs < 0.70, n.s.). These results provide support for the<br />

view that framing effects are a functi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> focus.<br />

Given the fact that PV scores are correlated with a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> but not a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>, combinati<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

PVs and c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism should provide very similar results to those found with the subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> low <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> high<br />

Table 2. Act preference proporti<strong>on</strong>s as a functi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> (or protected values)<br />

Overall act choices<br />

Subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong><br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>Low 0.43<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sLow/De<strong>on</strong>High 0.63<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>Low 0.45<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>High 0.60<br />

Subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>/protected values<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVLow 0.46<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVHigh 0.57<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVLow 0.40<br />

Group C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVHigh 0.64<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

Figure 1. Proporti<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> risk preferences as a functi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> frame and subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> or <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. To test this expectati<strong>on</strong>, a sec<strong>on</strong>d multiple regressi<strong>on</strong> analysis was<br />

performed in which frame, act certainty, PV, <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, their interacti<strong>on</strong>s, and gender were used to<br />

predict proporti<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> act choices.<br />

As expected, the presence <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs revealed as main predictor for act choices. People with str<strong>on</strong>g PVs showed a greater<br />

tendency to prefer acts over omissi<strong>on</strong>s (b ¼ .21; p < .001). Framing effects were c<strong>on</strong>firmed by a significant frame act<br />

certainty interacti<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .18; p < .01). These framing effects were, however, moderated by PV and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

orientati<strong>on</strong>, as reflected by a significant interacti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> frame act certainty <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .17;<br />

p < .01), and by a significant interacti<strong>on</strong> frame act certainty PV <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (b ¼ .16; p < .05).<br />

Table 2 again displays the mean proporti<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> act choices <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> subgroups based <strong>on</strong> median split <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> low <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> high PVand<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. As can be seen, the two high PV groups (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVHigh, C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVHigh) showed a<br />

str<strong>on</strong>ger tendency for act bias (mean <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> act choices were .57 and .64, respectively) than the two low PV groups (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/<br />

PVLow, C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVLow) (mean <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> act choices were .46 and .40, respectively).<br />

Figure 2 shows the trends with regard to preferences for risky choices. As can be seen, the differences between risky<br />

choices under negative and positive frames were larger for people high in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVLow,<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/PVHigh). Individual tests showed that framing effect were statistically significant for both groups (Fs > 4.4,<br />

Figure 2. Proporti<strong>on</strong>s <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> risk preferences as a functi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> frame and subgroups <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> and protected values<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

ps < .05). People low in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVLow, C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVHigh) provided no evidence <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> framing<br />

(Fs < 0.81, n.s.).<br />

In sum, the results suggest that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism are not opposites, but instead are orthog<strong>on</strong>al.<br />

Moreover, these two kinds <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>ing have different effects <strong>on</strong> acti<strong>on</strong> preferences as well as <strong>on</strong> framing effects. A<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> is associated with a bias toward acts rather than omissi<strong>on</strong>s. C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, <strong>on</strong> the other hand,<br />

was associated with framing effects. The largest framing effects were found am<strong>on</strong>g people high in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism and<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns (C<strong>on</strong>sHigh/De<strong>on</strong>High). People being more strict or ‘‘pure’’ de<strong>on</strong>tologists (i.e., low in<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, high in <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns) were insensitive to framing effects.<br />

The findings <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the present study provide further support for the idea that PVs are likely to be based <strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

reas<strong>on</strong>ing. The results were similar to those with the low <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> high <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> combinati<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sistent also with prior research by Tanner and Medin (2004), we found PV-people (C<strong>on</strong>sLow/PVHigh) who tended to<br />

prefer acti<strong>on</strong>s over omissi<strong>on</strong> and who were insensitive to framing effects. People high in PVand high in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism,<br />

however, showed large framing effects as well as a preference for acts.<br />

It should be menti<strong>on</strong>ed, however, that this pattern <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> results was not c<strong>on</strong>sistent across scenarios. Unlike the<br />

envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios, the social scenario (sick elderly people) revealed act biases but no typical framing effects.<br />

Detailed inspecti<strong>on</strong> showed that gender was a relevant factor in the social scenario, with women showing a str<strong>on</strong>ger<br />

tendency than men to prefer acts. 1 It seems that gender was particularly sensitive to the social issue, ‘‘sick elderly,’’ which<br />

may be the reas<strong>on</strong> for the varying pattern with the social scenario.<br />

GENERAL DISCUSSION<br />

The present results help clarify the role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> and PVs in both framing<br />

effect and act biases. Of theoretical interest are the findings that (1) <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinking<br />

are not directly opposed and (2) that PVs are str<strong>on</strong>gly associated with de<strong>on</strong>tology. Most importantly, however, the studies<br />

provide evidence that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> and PVs are key factors in both act bias and framing<br />

effects. The main results in this regard are as follows: (1) people high in de<strong>on</strong>tology showed a str<strong>on</strong>ger tendency to prefer<br />

acts than people low in de<strong>on</strong>tology, (2) people holding PVs revealed a str<strong>on</strong>ger preference for acti<strong>on</strong> than people without<br />

PVs, (3) people focusing <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sequences were sensitive to framing effects rather than <strong>on</strong> act-omissi<strong>on</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong>s, (4)<br />

people with str<strong>on</strong>g PVs or <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> combined with low c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism did not show framing effects.<br />

Overall, the results suggest that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> are more sensitive to distincti<strong>on</strong>s between acts and omissi<strong>on</strong>s,<br />

while a <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> appears to be more neutral between acts and omissi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tological Versus C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist Orientati<strong>on</strong>s and Relati<strong>on</strong> to Protected Values<br />

The two basic moral <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinking, are key factors in decisi<strong>on</strong><br />

making. The experiment showed that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> were very weakly correlated. This<br />

differs from traditi<strong>on</strong>al positi<strong>on</strong>s, arising primarily in moral philosophy, where de<strong>on</strong>tology and c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism are <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>ten<br />

thought to be rival theories and to be directly opposed. One reas<strong>on</strong> why they may be c<strong>on</strong>ceptualized in this way is that<br />

philosophers have invented (extreme) moral dilemmas (e.g., the trolley problem) that bring them into direct c<strong>on</strong>flict.<br />

However, it appears that people may combine or mix <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> thoughts or even integrate them.<br />

Though there are many various forms <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> moral theories which are hotly debated within moral philosophy, little<br />

empirical research has been c<strong>on</strong>ducted that assesses the factual status <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and/or <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> claims<br />

am<strong>on</strong>g people (Waterman, 1988). To our knowledge, this is the first study that provides empirical support for the view that<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g>ic positi<strong>on</strong>s are not mutually exclusive. The results str<strong>on</strong>gly suggest that in additi<strong>on</strong> to<br />

what <strong>on</strong>e might call ‘‘pure de<strong>on</strong>tologists’’ and ‘‘pure <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g>s,’’ there is also a mixed form c<strong>on</strong>sisting <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> people<br />

who reflect both <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Our results are more in line with c<strong>on</strong>temporary<br />

theories which try to expand c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>s and vice versa (e.g., Brandt, 1992; Cummiskey,<br />

1996; Harsanyi, 1977).<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


C<strong>on</strong>sistent with past literature (e.g., Bar<strong>on</strong> & Spranca, 1997), the experiment also found that PVs scores were highly<br />

correlated with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> (but fairly independent <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong>). We speculate that PVs<br />

may sometimes express both <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> reas<strong>on</strong>s. This also has implicati<strong>on</strong>s for the questi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>f reluctance. Pure (<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>) PVs are assumed to show trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>f reluctance based <strong>on</strong> rules that specify that<br />

certain acti<strong>on</strong>s should be taken or not taken, irrespective <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the outcomes. PVs that are combined with <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

orientati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, may base their resistance to making trade<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>victi<strong>on</strong> that <strong>on</strong>e should follow rules<br />

because they yield better c<strong>on</strong>sequences over the l<strong>on</strong>g-term.<br />

Preferences for Acti<strong>on</strong><br />

The results showed that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> and PVs are positively related to acti<strong>on</strong>. It is noteworthy that other<br />

research has found that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> rules and PVs are more closely related to omissi<strong>on</strong> biases (e.g., Ritov & Bar<strong>on</strong>,<br />

1999). Though it is the case that both our measures <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs and the paradigm used to assess act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> bias differ<br />

from that used by Bar<strong>on</strong> and his associates, the c<strong>on</strong>trasting results regarding the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between PV/<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

rules and act <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong> biases are not necessarily inc<strong>on</strong>sistent. De<strong>on</strong>tological rules can refer either to negative duties<br />

(e.g., do not harm, do not lie) or positive <strong>on</strong>es (e.g., take care <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> your children, bring about good) (Gert, 1973;<br />

Nunner-Winkler, 1984), with the former encouraging acts <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> omissi<strong>on</strong>s, and the latter encouraging acts <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> commissi<strong>on</strong>. It<br />

is possible that our scenarios (primarily envir<strong>on</strong>mental scenarios) were more likely to induce positive than negative<br />

obligati<strong>on</strong>s. We suspect that the pattern <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> prohibiti<strong>on</strong>s and obligati<strong>on</strong>s may vary both across situati<strong>on</strong>s and cultures, so the<br />

safest generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> is relatively more sensitive to the distincti<strong>on</strong> between acts <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

omissi<strong>on</strong>s than to the c<strong>on</strong>sequences.<br />

A c<strong>on</strong>tinuing methodological issue is the challenge <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> further improving the assessment <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PV and <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Though our items measuring <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinking seem to do a reas<strong>on</strong>able<br />

job tapping the c<strong>on</strong>structs, further research is needed to validate them. In additi<strong>on</strong>, further studies should try to manipulate<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes independently <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the judgment c<strong>on</strong>text to find str<strong>on</strong>ger support for the causal<br />

role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> these two modes. For instance, as <strong>on</strong>e reviewer <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> this article suggested, <strong>on</strong>e possibility would be to prime <strong>on</strong>e or the<br />

other orientati<strong>on</strong> and search for resp<strong>on</strong>se dissociati<strong>on</strong>s. Though the present study has provided a first promising step,<br />

further work is needed to improve the reliability and validity <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the measure <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs. We believe that our items probe<br />

aspects <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs that are close to Tetlock’s understanding <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs (sacred values): such values are neither tradeable,<br />

compromisable, nor can they even be questi<strong>on</strong>able (Tetlock et al., 2000). In this sense, our items were designed to tap<br />

various, but correlated features <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs.<br />

An additi<strong>on</strong>al avenue <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> future research c<strong>on</strong>cerns the role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> domains. Though we varied the problem descripti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

broadly in this and our previous research (e.g., Tanner & Medin, 2004), most <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> scenarios c<strong>on</strong>cerned envir<strong>on</strong>mental<br />

decisi<strong>on</strong> making. In the study presented here, the social scenario (sick elderly people) revealed gender differences that<br />

were not otherwise observed. 1 Clearly, additi<strong>on</strong>al research is needed to examine the role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> domain and associated<br />

c<strong>on</strong>textual factors.<br />

Framing Effects<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

The most striking effects are those <strong>on</strong> framing. Generally, the findings suggest that people who are more c<strong>on</strong>cerned with<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequences are the <strong>on</strong>es who are particularly susceptible to framing effects, while people who are more c<strong>on</strong>cerned with<br />

duties are more sensitive to act-omissi<strong>on</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong>s. We found insensitivity to framing effects am<strong>on</strong>g strict de<strong>on</strong>tologists<br />

(high de<strong>on</strong>tology, low c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism). Furthermore, we found str<strong>on</strong>g act preferences as well as large framing effects<br />

am<strong>on</strong>g people that combined both <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns. Given that these people showed<br />

preferences for acti<strong>on</strong> (over omissi<strong>on</strong>) and framing effects, their principle may be best described as ‘‘you have a duty to act<br />

but act in way that produces better outcomes.’’<br />

We found that PVs are linked with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns. Insensitivity to framing effects was therefore also found<br />

am<strong>on</strong>g ‘‘pure PVs’’ that focused exclusively <strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns (i.e., participants high in PVs and low in<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism). Those people who appeared to combine PVs with <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cerns also showed str<strong>on</strong>g act<br />

preferences and large framing effects.<br />

On the surface, the results c<strong>on</strong>tradict the Tanner and Medin (2004) results. They found no framing for participants high<br />

in PVs and robust framing in participants low in PVs. Both our present study populati<strong>on</strong> and our measure <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> PVs varied<br />

from those <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Tanner and Medin (2004). They did not obtain a measure <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>.<br />

Our best guess is that our sampling and selecti<strong>on</strong> yielded different mixtures <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> across the various studies. The present study would suggest that those people revealing no framing effects in<br />

Tanner and Medin (2004) were not just participants high in PVs but also low in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism. On the other hand, those<br />

participants showing robust framing effects were not just low in PVs but also high in c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism. The present study<br />

therefore appears to replicate and to extend the Tanner and Medin (2004) results by including more explicitly the<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. When participants are sorted by <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>, we c<strong>on</strong>sistently find c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism to be associated with framing effects, regardless <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> whether a<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> is or is not coupled with a <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> orientati<strong>on</strong> or PVs.<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

Previous research has largely ignored the influence <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> theories and PVs <strong>on</strong> framing<br />

effects. The current study <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fers three important findings. First, <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> and <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> modes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> thinking are<br />

not mutually exclusive. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, PVs are str<strong>on</strong>gly associated with <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> but they may be combined<br />

with <str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Third, framing effects are <strong>on</strong>ly clearly dem<strong>on</strong>strated for participants high in<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism. Together, the experiment suggests that <str<strong>on</strong>g>de<strong>on</strong>tological</str<strong>on</strong>g>/<str<strong>on</strong>g>c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>orientati<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> and PVs have<br />

pervasive effects <strong>on</strong> act bias and framing effects.<br />

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS<br />

This research was supported by the Swiss Nati<strong>on</strong>al Science Foundati<strong>on</strong> (Grant PP001-102845 and NSF Grant<br />

3000633806-SES 0527396). We wish to thank Marcel Morf for programming the internet experiment and Amanda<br />

Keller for helping in c<strong>on</strong>ducting the study. We also thank Dan Bartels for his valuable comments <strong>on</strong> a previous draft.<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy, 33, 1–19.<br />

Bar<strong>on</strong>, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected values. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Processes, 70, 1–16.<br />

Birnbacher, D. (2003). Analytische Einführung in die Ethik. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.<br />

Brandt, R. B. (1992). Morality, utilitarianism, and rights. New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Broad, C. D. (1930). Five types <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> ethical theory. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.<br />

Cohen, J., Cohen, P., West, S., & Aiken, L. (2003). Applied multiple regressi<strong>on</strong>/correlati<strong>on</strong> analysis for the behavior sciences (3rd ed.).<br />

Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.<br />

Cummiskey, D. (1996). Kantian c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Fagley, N. S., & Miller, P. M. (1997). Framing effects and arenas <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> choice: Your m<strong>on</strong>ey or your life. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and<br />

Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Making Processes, 71, 355–373.<br />

Gert, B. (1973). The moral rules. New York: Harper & Row.<br />

Harsanyi, J. (1977). Rule utilitarianism and decisi<strong>on</strong> theory. Erkenntnis, 11, 25–53.<br />

Kant, I. (1797). Die Metaphysik der Sitten in 2 Theilen. Königsberg: Nicolovius.<br />

Krishnamurthy, P., Carter, P., & Blair, E. (2001). Attribute framing and goal framing effects in health decisi<strong>on</strong>s. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior<br />

and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Processes, 85, 382–399.<br />

Kühberger, A. (1998). <str<strong>on</strong>g>Influence</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> framing <strong>on</strong> risky decisi<strong>on</strong>s: A meta-analysis. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong><br />

Processes, 75, 23–55.<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Levin, I. P., Schneider, S. L., & Gaeth, G. J. (1998). All frames are not created equal: A typology and critical analysis <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> framing effects.<br />

Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Making Processes, 76, 149–188.<br />

Lichtenstein, S., Gregory, R., & Irwin, J. (2007). What’s bad is easy: Taboo values, affect, and cogniti<strong>on</strong>. Judgment and Decisi<strong>on</strong><br />

Making, 2, 169–188.<br />

Nunner-Winkler, G. (1984). Two moralities? A critical discussi<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> an ethic <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> care and resp<strong>on</strong>sibility <str<strong>on</strong>g>versus</str<strong>on</strong>g> an ethic <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> rights and<br />

justice. In W. M. Kurtines, & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behaviour, and moral development (pp. 348–361). New York:<br />

A Wiley-Interscience Publicati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Ritov, I., & Bar<strong>on</strong>, J. (1999). Protected values and omissi<strong>on</strong> bias. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Processes, 79, 79–94.<br />

Rothman, A. J., & Salovey, P. (1997). Shaping percepti<strong>on</strong>s to motivate healthy behavior: The role <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> message framing. Psychological<br />

Bulletin, 121, 3–19.<br />

Schneider, S. L. (1992). Framing and c<strong>on</strong>flict: Aspirati<strong>on</strong> level c<strong>on</strong>tingency, the status quo, and current theories <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> risk choice. Journal <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g><br />

Experimental Psychology: Learning. Memory and Cogniti<strong>on</strong>, 18, 1040–1057.<br />

Skitka, L. J. (2002). Do the means justify the ends, or do the ends justify the means? A test <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the value protecti<strong>on</strong> model <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> justice.<br />

Pers<strong>on</strong>ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 452–461.<br />

Tanner, C., & Medin, D. L. (2004). Protected values: No omissi<strong>on</strong> bias and no framing effects. Psych<strong>on</strong>omic Bulletin and Review, 11,<br />

185–191.<br />

Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Els<strong>on</strong>, S. B., Green, M., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the unthinkable. Taboo trade-<str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g>fs,<br />

forbidden base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Journal <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Pers<strong>on</strong>ality & Social Psychology, 5, 853–870.<br />

Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> decisi<strong>on</strong>s and the psychology <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> choice. Science, 211, 453–458.<br />

Wang, X. T. (1996). Framing effects: Dynamics and task domains. Organizati<strong>on</strong>al Behavior and Human Decisi<strong>on</strong> Processes, 68,<br />

145–157.<br />

Waterman, A. S. (1988). On the uses <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> psychological theory and research in the process <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> ethical inquiry. Psychological Bulletin, 103,<br />

283–298.<br />

APPENDIX A<br />

Choice Scenarios Used in the Studies (Original Scenarios Are in German)<br />

Drinking Water C<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong><br />

De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

Imagine a refinery that processes petroleum products. An investigati<strong>on</strong> found that because <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> tank leaks, both soil and<br />

drinking water in the area <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the refinery have become c<strong>on</strong>taminated. Due to this c<strong>on</strong>taminati<strong>on</strong>, 720 children from the<br />

adjacent village may get a fatal disease. A medicine (vaccine) for this disease has been developed and tested. However, the<br />

medicine can sometimes cause side effects that can be fatal, too.<br />

Imagine that you are the head <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the local hospital. You are asked whether to prescribe the medicine or not. Please<br />

choose <strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the two opti<strong>on</strong>s. Assume that the estimates are as follows:<br />

1. Negatively framed, act with certain outcomes:<br />

(a) If the vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> 480 children will be damaged for sure.<br />

(b) If no vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the 720 children will be<br />

damaged, and a two-thirds probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will be damaged.<br />

2. Negatively framed, act with risky outcomes:<br />

(a) If the vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the 720 children will be<br />

damaged, and a two-thirds probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will be damaged.<br />

(b) If no vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> 480 children will be damaged for sure.<br />

3. Positively framed, act opti<strong>on</strong> with certain outcomes:<br />

(a) If the vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> 240 children will be saved for sure.<br />

(b) If no vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the 720 children will be saved,<br />

and a two-thirds probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will be saved.<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


Carmen Tanner et al.<br />

4. Positively framed, act opti<strong>on</strong> with risky outcomes:<br />

(a) If the vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the 720 children will be saved,<br />

and a two-thirds probability that the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will be saved.<br />

(b) If no vaccinati<strong>on</strong> is adopted, the health <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> 240 children will be saved for sure.<br />

Genetically Engineered Crops<br />

Some years ago, in the village where you live the farmers adopted eight new genetically engineered crops to save costs.<br />

Experts are c<strong>on</strong>cerned that the populati<strong>on</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> nine species <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> beneficial insects have already decreased dramatically and that<br />

these species could even become extinct. One <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the reas<strong>on</strong>s may be that the insects eat pollen from genetically modified<br />

corn. The local government is c<strong>on</strong>sidering enacting a law that would limit the use <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> genetically engineered crops from<br />

eight to two.<br />

You are a member <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the government and you have to decide whether you want to lobby for this law or not. Please<br />

choose <strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the two opti<strong>on</strong>s. Assume that the estimates are as follows:<br />

1. Negatively framed, act with certain outcomes:<br />

(a) If the law is enacted, six insect species will become extinct.<br />

(b) If the law is not enacted, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the nine insect species will become extinct, and<br />

a two-thirds probability that all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will become extinct due to other reas<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

(The other c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s were performed in analogy to the descripti<strong>on</strong> above.)<br />

Sick Elderly<br />

In the village where you live, 60 elderly (older than 70 years) have a malignant lung disease. A novel operati<strong>on</strong> can save<br />

their lives or at least improve their quality <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> life, but also leads to certain risks and very high costs—not a marginal<br />

problem, seeing that the hospital management is expected to do something against increasing health care costs. It is<br />

discussed to exclude people older than 70 years from certain costly operati<strong>on</strong>s (including the above-named lung<br />

operati<strong>on</strong>), in order to reduce costs and gain resources for other cases.<br />

The hospital has now to decide whether this 60 sick people older than 70 years will be operated or not. Either all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them<br />

will be operated or nobody, there are no other opti<strong>on</strong>s. You are the head physician and you can plead for or against it. Please<br />

choose <strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the two opti<strong>on</strong>s. Assume that the estimates are as follows:<br />

1. Negatively framed, act with certain outcomes:<br />

(a) If the operati<strong>on</strong> is implemented, 40 people will die for sure.<br />

(b) If the operati<strong>on</strong> is implemented, there is a <strong>on</strong>e-third probability that n<strong>on</strong>e <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the 60 people will die, and a two-thirds<br />

probability that all <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> them will die.<br />

(The other c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s were performed in analogy to the descripti<strong>on</strong> above.)<br />

APPENDIX B<br />

Measures <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> De<strong>on</strong>tological Versus C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist Orientati<strong>on</strong> (Original Items Are in German)<br />

I chose this opti<strong>on</strong>...<br />

...because this alternative is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with principles <strong>on</strong>e have to follow (¼ De<strong>on</strong> 1).<br />

...because I have the moral duty to behave that way (¼ De<strong>on</strong> 2).<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp


...because some behaviors are definitely right or wr<strong>on</strong>g, irrespective <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the c<strong>on</strong>sequences (¼ De<strong>on</strong> 3).<br />

...because the other alternative is morally forbidden (¼ De<strong>on</strong> 4).<br />

...because cost-benefit analyses make sense at this topic (¼ C<strong>on</strong>s 1).<br />

...because this opti<strong>on</strong> can be justified by their c<strong>on</strong>sequences (¼ C<strong>on</strong>s 2).<br />

...because the outcomes <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> the chosen opti<strong>on</strong> produce the best net value (¼ C<strong>on</strong>s 3).<br />

...because the positive outcomes outweigh the negative c<strong>on</strong>sequences (¼ C<strong>on</strong>s 4).<br />

Measures <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> Protected Values (Original Items Are in German)<br />

De<strong>on</strong>tology, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, act choices, and framing effects<br />

– I think that a compromise between both sides <str<strong>on</strong>g>of</str<strong>on</strong>g> this debate is an acceptable outcome (¼ PV 1).<br />

– This issue is about something we should not sacrifice (¼ PV 2).<br />

– I would not change my opini<strong>on</strong>, no matter what the costs (¼ PV 3).<br />

– I would have problems making any c<strong>on</strong>cessi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> this topic (¼ PV 4).<br />

Copyright # 2007 John Wiley & S<strong>on</strong>s, Ltd. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. (2007)<br />

DOI: 10.1002/ejsp

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!