07.04.2013 Views

Deleuze's Way

Deleuze's Way

Deleuze's Way

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

DELEUZE’S WAY<br />

Addressing the essential question of the relationship between ethics and aesthetics in<br />

Deleuze’s philosophy this book provides clear indications of the practical implications<br />

of Deleuze’s approach to the arts through detailed analyses of the ethical dimension<br />

of artistic activity in literature, music, and film.<br />

Bogue examines Deleuze’s “transverse way” of interrelating the ethical and the<br />

aesthetic, the transverse way being both a mode of thought and a practice of living.<br />

Among the issues examined are those of the relationship of music to literature, the<br />

political vocation of the arts, violence in popular music, the ethics and aesthetics<br />

of education, the use of music and sound in film, the role of the visual in literary<br />

invention, the function of the arts in cross cultural interactions, and the future of<br />

Deleuzian analysis as a means of forming an open, reciprocally self-constituting,<br />

transcultural global culture.<br />

Drawing on years of insight into the works of Gilles Deleuze, Ronald Bogue provides<br />

a careful and systematic study of Deleuze’s transverse way, the myriad diagonal paths<br />

connecting seemingly incommunicable domains: Deleuze’s immanent ethics as they<br />

correspond to the themes of the “minor” in literature and music; the construction of<br />

concepts through a pedagogy of images and the efficacy of fabulation; nomadology<br />

considered both as an expression of actual nomadic practices and as a comparative<br />

poetics for understanding globalization. Through this exploration of the Deleuzian<br />

method, Bogue reveals how these transversal connections constitute so many ways<br />

of thinking, of creating, and of multiplying variations that enliven and conjoin the<br />

arts and philosophy.<br />

Charles J. Stivale, Distinguished Professor of French,<br />

<strong>Way</strong>ne State University, USA


For my sister, Cynthia Bogue


Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Essays in Transverse Ethics and Aesthetics<br />

RONALD BOGUE<br />

University of Georgia, USA


© Ronald Bogue 2007<br />

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system<br />

or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording<br />

or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher.<br />

Ronald Bogue has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to<br />

be identified as the author of this work.<br />

Published by<br />

Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company<br />

Gower House Suite 420<br />

Croft Road 101 Cherry Street<br />

Aldershot Burlington, VT 05401-4405<br />

Hampshire GU11 3HR USA<br />

England<br />

Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com<br />

British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data<br />

Bogue, Ronald, 1948-<br />

Deleuze’s way : essays in transverse ethics and aesthetics<br />

1. Deleuze, Gilles 2. Deleuze, Gilles - Aesthetics<br />

3. Ethics<br />

I. Title<br />

194<br />

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data<br />

Bogue, Ronald, 1948-<br />

Deleuze’s way : essays in transverse ethics and aesthetics / Ronald Bogue.<br />

p. cm.<br />

Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.<br />

ISBN-13: 978-0-7546-6032-3 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Deleuze, Gilles, 1925-1995. 2.<br />

Ethics. 3. Aesthetics. I. Title.<br />

B2430.D454B65 2007<br />

194--dc22<br />

ISBN-13: 978-0-7546-6032-3<br />

Printed and bound in Great Britain by Antony Rowe Ltd, Chippenham, Wiltshire.<br />

2006026857


Contents<br />

Acknowledgements vii<br />

List of Abbreviations ix<br />

Introduction The Transverse <strong>Way</strong>: Du côté de chez Deleuze 1<br />

1 Immanent Ethics 7<br />

2 Minority, Territory, Music 17<br />

3 Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 35<br />

4 Search, Swim and See: Deleuze’s Apprenticeship<br />

in Signs and Pedagogy of Images 53<br />

5 Tragedy, Sight and Sound: The Birth of Godard’s<br />

Prénom Carmen from the Nietzschean Spirit of Music 69<br />

6 Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 91<br />

7 Re-Viewing Deleuze’s Sacher-Masoch 107<br />

8 Apology for Nomadology 113<br />

9 Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 123<br />

10 Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 137<br />

Bibliography 167<br />

Index 171


This page intentionally left blank


Acknowledgements<br />

I am grateful to the University of Georgia’s Willson Center for Humanities and Arts<br />

and the University of Georgia Research Foundation for their generous support of<br />

this project. For their encouragement and advice, I would like to thank Constantin V.<br />

Boundas, Ian Buchanan, Hanping Chiu, David Jones, Jean Khalfa, John K. Noyes,<br />

Michael Schwartz, Inna Semetsky, Marcel Swiboda and Jason Wirth. I am also<br />

grateful for permission to publish modified versions of essays that appeared in the<br />

following:<br />

“The Immanent Ethics of Gilles Deleuze,” in A Feast of Logos: Essays in<br />

Commemoration of the Tenth Anniversary of the Georgia Continental Philosophy<br />

Circle, eds Jason Wirth, Michael Schwartz, and David Jones (Atlanta: Georgia<br />

Philosophy Series, 2005), pp. 87–99. © Georgia Philosophy Series, reprinted with<br />

permission.<br />

“Minority, Territory, Music,” in An Introduction to the Complete Work of Gilles<br />

Deleuze, ed. Jean Khalfa (London: Continuum, 2003), pp. 114–32. © Ronald<br />

Bogue, reprinted with kind permission of the publisher.<br />

“Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom, and Black,” in Deleuze and<br />

Music, eds Ian Buchanan and Marcel Swiboda (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University<br />

Press, 2004), pp. 95–117. © Ronald Bogue, reprinted with permission of the<br />

publisher.<br />

“Search, Swim and See: Deleuze’s Apprenticeship in Signs and Pedagogy of<br />

Images,” Educational Philosophy and Theory, 36/3 (2004): 327–42. © Blackwell<br />

Publishing, reprinted with permission.<br />

“Apology for Nomadology,” Interventions, 6/2 (2004): 169–79. © Taylor and Francis<br />

, reprinted with permission.<br />

“Nomadic Flows: Globalism and the Local Absolute,” Concentric, 31/1 (2005):<br />

7–25. © Department of English, National Taiwan Normal University, reprinted<br />

with permission.<br />

“Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come,” in Deleuze and Philosophy, ed.<br />

Constantin V. Boundas (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2006). © Ronald<br />

Bogue, reprinted with permission of the publisher.


This page intentionally left blank


List of Abbreviations<br />

All translations from Deleuze, Guattari and Deleuze-Guattari are my own. For works<br />

that have appeared in English translation, citations include page numbers of the<br />

original French edition followed by the page numbers of the corresponding passages<br />

in the English translation.<br />

AO Deleuze and Guattari. L’Anti-Oedipe: Capitalisme et schizophrénie I.<br />

Paris: Minuit, 1972. Anti-Oedipus. Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and<br />

Helen R. Lane. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1977.<br />

B Deleuze. Le Bergsonisme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1966.<br />

Bergsonism. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. New York:<br />

Zone Books, 1991.<br />

CC Deleuze. Critique et clinique. Paris: Minuit, 1993. Essays Critical and<br />

Clinical. Trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Greco. Minneapolis:<br />

University of Minnesota Press, 1997.<br />

D Deleuze and Claire Parnet. Dialogues. Paris: Flammarion, 1977. Dialogues.<br />

Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. New York: Columbia<br />

University Press, 1987.<br />

DR Deleuze. Différence et répétition. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,<br />

1968. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. New York: Columbia<br />

University Press, 1994.<br />

DRF Deleuze. Deux régimes de foux: textes et entretiens 1975–1995. Ed. David<br />

Lapoujade. Paris: Minuit, 2003. Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and<br />

Interviews 1975–1995. Trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina. New<br />

York: Semiotext(e), 2006.<br />

E Deleuze. L’Épuisé (published with Samuel Beckett’s Quad). Paris: Minuit,<br />

1992. “The Exhausted,” in Essays Critical and Clinical. Trans. Daniel W.<br />

Smith and Michael A. Greco. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,<br />

1997, pp. 152–74.<br />

FB Deleuze. Francis Bacon: Logique de la sensation. Vol. 1. Paris: Editions de<br />

la différence, 1981. Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. Trans. Daniel<br />

W. Smith. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2003.


x<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

ID Deleuze. L’Île déserte et autres textes: textes et entretiens 1953–1974. Ed.<br />

David Lapoujade. Paris: Minuit, 2002. Desert Islands and Other Texts<br />

1953–1974. Trans. Michael Taormina. New York: Semiotext(e), 2004.<br />

IT Deleuze. Cinéma 2: L’image-temps. Paris, Minuit, 1985. Cinema 2: The<br />

Time-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta. Minneapolis:<br />

University of Minnesota Press, 1989.<br />

K Deleuze and Guattari. Kafka: pour une littérature mineure. Paris: Minuit,<br />

1975. Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature. Trans. Dana Polan. Minneapolis:<br />

University of Minnesota Press, 1986.<br />

LP Deleuze. Le Pli. Leibniz et la baroque. Paris: Minuit, 1988. The Fold.<br />

Leibniz and the Baroque. Trans. Tom Conley. Minneapolis: University of<br />

Minnesota Press, 1993.<br />

LS Deleuze. Logique du sens. Paris: Minuit, 1969. The Logic of Sense. Trans.<br />

Mark Lester, with Charles Stivale. Ed. Constantin V. Boundas. New York:<br />

Columbia University Press, 1990.<br />

MP Deleuze and Guattari. Mille plateaux: Capitalisme et schizophrénie, II.<br />

Paris: Minuit, 1980. A Thousand Plateaus. Trans. Brian Massumi.<br />

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.<br />

NP Deleuze. Nietzsche et la philosophie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de<br />

France, 1962. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson.<br />

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983.<br />

PP Deleuze. Pourparlers. Paris: Minuit, 1990. Negotiations. Trans. Martin<br />

Joughin. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995.<br />

PS Deleuze. Proust et les signes. 3rd edn. Paris: Presses Universitaires de<br />

France, 1976. Proust and Signs. The Complete Text. Trans. Richard Howard.<br />

London: Athlone, 2000.<br />

PT Guattari. Psychanalyse et transversalité. Paris: Maspero, 1972. Selected<br />

essays published in Molecular Revolution: Psychiatry and Politics. Trans.<br />

Rosemary Sheed. London: Penguin, 1984.<br />

PV Deleuze. Périclès et Verdi. La Philosophie de François Châtelet. Paris:<br />

Minuit, 1988.<br />

QP Deleuze and Guattari. Qu’est-ce que la philosophie?. Paris: Minuit, 1991.<br />

What Is Philosophy?. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell. New<br />

York: Columbia University Press, 1994.


List of Abbreviations xi<br />

RM Guattari. La Révolution moléculaire. Paris: Recherches, 1977. Selected<br />

essays published in Molecular Revolution: Psychiatry and Politics. Trans.<br />

Rosemary Sheed. London: Penguin, 1984.<br />

S Deleuze. Spinoza: Philosophie pratique. 2nd edn. Paris: Minuit, 1981.<br />

Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. Trans. Robert Hurley. San Francisco, CA:<br />

City Lights, 1988.<br />

SM Deleuze. Présentation de Sacher-Masoch. Paris: Minuit, 1967. Masochism:<br />

An Interpretation of Coldness and Cruelty. Trans. Jean McNeil. New York:<br />

G. Braziller, 1971.<br />

SP Deleuze and Carmelo Bene. Superpositions. Paris: Minuit, 1979. “One<br />

Less Manifesto,” trans. in The Deleuze Reader. Ed. Constantin V. Boundas.<br />

New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.


This page intentionally left blank


Introduction<br />

The Transverse <strong>Way</strong><br />

Du côté de chez Deleuze<br />

Near the end of Marcel Proust’s A la recherche du temps perdu, as the narrator<br />

reflects on time and the complex interconnections among events that surge forth in<br />

involuntary memory, he considers the figure of Mlle de Saint-Loup, and asks:<br />

Was she not – are not, indeed, the majority of human beings? – like one of those starshaped<br />

cross-roads in a forest where roads converge that have come, in the forest as in our<br />

lives, from the most diverse quarter? Numerous for me were the roads which led to Mlle<br />

de Saint-Loup and which radiated around her. Firstly the two great “ways” themselves,<br />

where on many walks I had dreamed so many dreams, both led to her: through her father<br />

Robert de Saint-Loup, the Guermantes way; through Gilberte, her mother, the Méséglise<br />

way which was also “Swann’s way.” One of them took me, by way of this girl’s mother<br />

and the Champs-Elysées, to Swann, to my evenings at Combray, to Méséglise itself; the<br />

other, by way of her father, to those afternoons at Balbec where even now I saw him again<br />

near the sun-bright sea. And then between these two high roads a network of transversals<br />

was set up. 1<br />

A network of transversals, of crisscrossing diagonal paths, interconnects the two<br />

“ways” that structure the book, the Guermantes way and the Méséglise way. Yet<br />

what is striking about these transversals is not simply that they interconnect. As<br />

Deleuze points out in his Proust and Signs, they interconnect entities that are closed<br />

in upon themselves, seemingly without communication with anything outside<br />

themselves. The Guermantes way and the Méséglise way, says the narrator, were<br />

like vases clos, chemical retorts, or sealed glass vessels. The two ways existed “far<br />

apart from one another and unaware of each other’s existence, in the sealed vessels<br />

of separate afternoons” (vol. 1, p. 147, translation modified). The same is true of<br />

every experience of involuntary memory in the Recherche. As the narrator observes<br />

when he reflects on the multiple associations tied to a given sensation<br />

… the act or gesture remains immured as within a thousand sealed vessels, each one of<br />

them filled with things of a colour, a scent, a temperature that are absolutely different one<br />

from another, vessels, moreover, which being disposed over the whole range of our years,<br />

during which we have never ceased to change if only in our dreams and our thoughts, are<br />

situated at the most various moral altitudes and give us the sensation of extraordinarily<br />

diverse atmospheres. [vol. 3, p. 903]<br />

1 Marcel Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, trans. C.K. Moncrieff and Terence<br />

Kilmartin (New York, 1982), vol. 3, pp. 1084–85.


2<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Transversals provide communication among incommunicables. The multiple sealed<br />

glass vessels of the Recherche are interconnected, says Deleuze<br />

… by transversals, which make us leap from one profile of Albertine to another, from one<br />

Albertine to another, from one world to another, from one word to another, without ever<br />

gathering the multiple within the One, without ever reassembling the multiple in a whole,<br />

but affirming the very original unity of this particular multiple, affirming without uniting<br />

all [tous] these irreducible fragments within a Whole [Tout]. [PS 153/126]<br />

The function of transversals is to assemble multiplicities, yet in such a way that the<br />

differences among entities are not effaced but intensified. As Proust’s narrator says<br />

of a railway trip, “the specific attraction of a journey lies not in our being able to<br />

alight at places on the way and to stop altogether as soon as we grow tired, but in<br />

its making the difference between departure and arrival not as imperceptible but as<br />

intense as possible.” 2 Transversals, like Proust’s railway journeys, are the passages<br />

that render maximum intensity to the differences between multiple locations.<br />

Deleuze’s way is the transverse way, the diagonal path connecting<br />

incommunicable ways, a trajectory that intensifies the distances between locations.<br />

His way is also a way of doing – a practice of making transverse connections, of<br />

assembling multiplicities that affirm their differences through their connections. In<br />

Proust, Deleuze first came upon the notion of transversality, but he met it as well,<br />

in a different guise, in the early work of his frequent collaborator, Félix Guattari. In<br />

Psychoanalysis and Transversality (1972), which assembles Guattari’s papers and<br />

interventions from the 1960s, Guattari reflects on the difficulty of bringing genuine<br />

change to the structure and operation of psychiatric institutions. He identifies two<br />

dimensions in psychiatric institutions, “a verticality that you find for example in an<br />

organizational diagram with a pyramidal structure (directors, subdirectors, etc.),”<br />

and “a horizontality like that which takes form in the hospital courtyard, in the ward<br />

for the disturbed, even more so in the wards for the senile, that is, a certain state<br />

of affairs in which things and people arrange themselves as best they can in the<br />

situation in which they find themselves” (PT 79/17). The problem, as he sees it, is to<br />

change both vertical hierarchies of authority and horizontal modes of interaction, to<br />

put into effect a “maximum communication … among different levels and above all<br />

in different directions” (PT 80/18). In a hospital, “the ‘coefficient of transversality’<br />

is [measured by] the degree of blindness of the staff,” and the modification of the<br />

institution involves an intensification of transversality such that blindness decreases<br />

and there is “a structural redefinition of the role of each individual and a reorientation<br />

of the whole group [ensemble]” (PT 80/18). Transversality is “a contrary and<br />

complementary dimension to the generative structures of pyramidal hierarchization<br />

and sterilizing modes of transmitting messages” (PT 84/22). By increasing an<br />

institution’s coefficient of transversality Guattari hopes to form a “group-subject”<br />

(as opposed to a “subjected group”), one capable of shaping itself according to its<br />

own needs and desires.<br />

Proust’s transversals and Guattari’s transversality might seem distant from one<br />

another, but both may be seen as dimensions of Deleuze’s transverse way. Proust’s<br />

2 Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, vol. 1, p. 693.


The Transverse <strong>Way</strong>: Du côté de chez Deleuze 3<br />

transversals provide connections in experience, linking sensations and memories, and<br />

thereby putting in communication incommunicable worlds and durations. They also<br />

make possible the work of art that is the Recherche, itself a structuring of transversals<br />

that emphasizes the singleness of the work as a heterogeneous multiplicity. Hence<br />

Proust’s transversals concern the domain of the aesthetic in its largest sense, that<br />

is, the realm of sense experience and the realm of art. Guattari’s transversality is<br />

primarily a social and political concept, but in Deleuze’s view, and in Guattari’s,<br />

the social and the political are inseparable from sensation and creation, whether that<br />

creation takes place in the arts, the sciences, politics, or any other sphere of human<br />

endeavor.<br />

The term “transversality” does not occupy a central place in Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s collaborative works, but it does appear in Anti-Oedipus during the<br />

authors’ exposition of the goals they foresee for “schizoanalysis.” One of these goals<br />

is the formation of a group subject, whose “libidinal investments are themselves<br />

revolutionary.” Against the stratified libidinal investments of subjected groups, it<br />

“opposes real coefficients of transversality, with neither hierarchy nor group superego”<br />

(AO 417–18/348–9). In their next book, Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari do not mention the group subject or transversality, but they do<br />

speak about the immediately social and collective nature of Kafka’s work and of his<br />

desire to form a “people to come.” This “people to come” clearly is a version of the<br />

group subject shaped by “real coefficients of transversality,” and in Kafka they argue<br />

that literature as a whole has as one of its primary aims that of inventing a people to<br />

come. Finally, in their last collaborative effort, What Is Philosophy? (1991), Deleuze<br />

and Guattari go even further and state that the arts, the sciences and philosophy,<br />

despite their fundamental differences, share the common task of creating a people to<br />

come (QP 206/218).<br />

The line of thought from “transversality” to the “people to come,” then, leads to a<br />

consideration of the social and political dimensions of the arts, and, ultimately, to the<br />

fundamental question of the relationship between the ethical, which I take in a broad<br />

sense as the domain of values and action, and the aesthetic. Proust’s transversals are<br />

constituents of experience and means of artistic construction, but they also are the<br />

tools for forming connections, and hence modes of thought that might be extended<br />

to any domain. One might say that the transverse way as mode of thought, finally,<br />

is the activity of forming transverse connections that intensify differences and bring<br />

forth new possibilities for life, in the arts, the sciences, politics, philosophy, and all<br />

other spheres of action. My effort in this volume is to explore Deleuze’s transverse<br />

way of thinking and some of the transverse pathways he traces within the aesthetic<br />

and between the aesthetic and the ethical.<br />

Although Deleuze does not develop a formal ethics as a discrete component of<br />

his philosophy, there is a sense in which the ethical permeates all his work. In the<br />

first essay of this volume, I trace the outlines of what might be deemed Deleuze’s<br />

immanent ethics, in which value emerges as a constituent of the unfolding real. From<br />

the vantage of this immanent ethics, I consider a series of subjects involving the arts<br />

and social practice. In “Minority, Territory, Music,” I examine the concept of “the<br />

minor” in literature and music, using “territory” as a means of connecting the two.<br />

Deleuze is an advocate of minor literature, whose ethical dimension lies in its effort


4<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

to invent a new collectivity, an as yet nonexistent “people to come.” I argue that for<br />

Deleuze music shares minor literature’s basic ends, and that both have as their project<br />

the deterritorialization of territories and the invention of a future collectivity that<br />

only coheres to the extent that it remains a force of deterritorialization. The ethical<br />

concern of the second essay, “Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom<br />

and Black,” is that of violence in popular culture, specifically that of violence in<br />

three forms of heavy metal music: “death metal,” “doom metal” and “black metal.”<br />

My argument here is that Deleuze’s approach to music and deterritorialization helps<br />

clarify the relationship between violent action and artistic practice, and that death,<br />

doom and black metal are not direct forms of violence, but, like all modes of artistic<br />

practice, ways of shaping materials that can be appropriated for any number of social<br />

ends.<br />

In “Search, Swim and See: Deleuze’s Apprenticeship in Signs and Pedagogy<br />

of Images,” I approach the ethics of art through a consideration of Deleuze’s<br />

scattered remarks on education. In Proust and Signs, Deleuze follows the course<br />

of the narrator’s apprenticeship in signs, which Deleuze regards as a training in<br />

the art of “thinking otherwise.” That apprenticeship, I show, resembles the process<br />

whereby one learns to swim, as Deleuze describes it in Difference and Repetition.<br />

Learning to think and to swim, I then argue, may be connected to Deleuze’s cinema<br />

theory, in which learning to think otherwise is a matter of learning to see in a new<br />

way. And it is in Godard’s “pedagogy of images,” I conclude, that Deleuze finds an<br />

especially effective method of inducing new modes of vision that function as new<br />

modes of thought. Godard’s pedagogy of images involves both sight and sound, and<br />

in “Tragedy, Sight and Sound,” I offer a Deleuzian analysis of the interrelationship<br />

of the visual and the aural in Godard’s Prénom Carmen (1983). Godard’s pedagogy<br />

of visual and sonic images, I try to show, teaches us to stop seeing and hearing the<br />

clichés that clutter the world and to see and hear the new that is already there.<br />

In his later writings, Deleuze approaches the topic of the people to come via<br />

the concept of “fabulation,” a notion he takes from Bergson’s The Two Sources of<br />

Morality and Religion, in which Bergson identifies a function of fabulation, or mythmaking,<br />

that he sees as essential to the formation of the morality and religion of<br />

traditional, closed societies. In “Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come,” I<br />

show first how Deleuze turns what is a negative function in Bergson into a positive<br />

force by redefining fabulation as an activation of the “powers of the false,” a way of<br />

falsifying orthodox truths and fashioning new truths, with the ethical aim of fostering<br />

a people to come. I then consider the curious fact that in both Bergson and Deleuze<br />

fabulation involves no genuine fabula, or story, concluding that for Bergson, music<br />

is the paradigmatic creative art, since it has no ties to the myth-making function<br />

of fabulation, whereas for Deleuze, the visual arts have a special privilege, since<br />

they render the new visible without structuring it through any pre-existing stories.<br />

In “Re-viewing Deleuze’s Sacher-Masoch,” I turn to Deleuze’s 1967 study of the<br />

novelist Sacher-Masoch and his brief reprise of that study in 1991, treating these<br />

texts as particularly striking examples of Deleuze’s preference for the visual over the<br />

narrative. I conclude that what attracts Deleuze to Sacher-Masoch, finally, is the antinarrative<br />

nature of Sacher-Masoch’s narratives, in which an aesthetic of suspended<br />

temporality, of perpetual deferral and frozen tableaus, proves to be an aesthetic of


The Transverse <strong>Way</strong>: Du côté de chez Deleuze 5<br />

the untimely event, and in this regard, an aesthetic that may be seen as an instance<br />

of Deleuzian fabulation.<br />

The last three essays of this volume focus on “nomadology,” the subject of an<br />

extended section of A Thousand Plateaus (1980). Deleuzian nomadism, one might<br />

say, is a version of the transverse way, a means of forming connections across the<br />

spheres of the arts, politics, the sciences, and culture in general. At first glance,<br />

nomadology seems to have little to do with actual nomads, but I argue in “Apology<br />

for Nomadology” that a proper understanding of the concept of the nomadic allows<br />

us to engage in meaningful analysis of actual nomadic practices in a number of<br />

cultural spheres. As an example, I consider gypsy music, first as the product of a<br />

wandering people, then as a component of popular and high art culture in East Central<br />

Europe, and finally as an element against which Bartók reacts in developing his own<br />

Hungarian version of European modernist music. In “Nomadism, Globalism, and<br />

Cultural Studies,” I propose nomadism as a means of approaching the phenomenon<br />

of globalization, the “nomadic” providing the model of an “open whole” that might<br />

lead to a “globalism” that stands in opposition to a Western-dominant process of<br />

globalization. I suggest a way in which this nomadic globalism might be related<br />

to cultural studies by offering a program for research in comparative poetics, one<br />

that would seek to formulate a transcultural poetics through a process of acentered<br />

cultural interaction. In my final essay, I review an essay by Christopher L. Miller, in<br />

which he offers an extended critique of nomadology that condemns nomadic thought<br />

and cultural analysis as arrogant and irresponsible. I argue that nomadology’s claims<br />

are not as arrogant as they might seem, and that nomadic thought does not entail an<br />

abandonment of rigor or ethical responsibility. Rather, it offers a mode of thought<br />

with genuine possibilities for innovative analysis of aesthetics and culture as a<br />

whole.<br />

The transverse way is the path in between, the diagonal across the grids of<br />

horizontal and vertical coordinates, the zigzag of a line of continuous variation. Its<br />

time is that of the entre-temps, the meantime or meanwhile, and its space is the<br />

middle, in medias res, always underway among things. The transverse way connects<br />

by affirming differences, constructing transversals that set the incommunicable in<br />

communication. Its transversals are agents of transversality, forces with the social<br />

and political function of bringing forth group subjects and inventing a people to<br />

come. The transverse way is a way of thinking, a way of making (poiesis), and a<br />

way of acting, and hence a pathway across the domains of philosophy, aesthetics and<br />

ethics. Deleuze’s transverse way is methodic and systematic, but open-ended in its<br />

method and system, only to be seized in its ongoing practice. In these essays, I have<br />

tried to examine that transverse way in some of its variations, to follow its paths and<br />

connections across the arts and into other fields. Each of the essays is intended to be<br />

comprehensible by itself, and as a result, some of Deleuze’s concepts are set forth<br />

more than once. My hope is that multiple passes at Deleuze’s often difficult ideas will<br />

prove more of a blessing than a burden to readers, both in comprehending the ideas<br />

themselves, and in observing the ways in which the ideas take on new dimensions in<br />

differing contexts. But above all, my object is to articulate some fundamental aspects<br />

of Deleuze’s art of thinking, his transverse practice of an immanent ethics of creation<br />

that opens new possibilities for life.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 1<br />

Immanent Ethics<br />

By the time of his death on November 4, 1995, Deleuze had published twenty-three<br />

books touching on subjects as varied as painting, metallurgy, mathematics, geology,<br />

anthropology and cinema. As someone who valued the discipline and history of<br />

philosophy in his own idiosyncratic way, he had commented on many key figures<br />

and prominent issues in the Western philosophical tradition. Seldom, however, did<br />

he directly address the topic of ethics, despite its centrality in what is conventionally<br />

considered to be “philosophy.” Yet there is a sense in which all of Deleuze’s work<br />

is concerned with ethics, in that ethical principles inform his basic conception of<br />

thought and what it means to think.<br />

Giorgio Agamben has suggested that we may reconstruct a genealogy of modern<br />

French philosophy along two lines of descent, a “line of transcendence” from Kant<br />

through Husserl to Levinas and Derrida, and a “line of immanence” from Spinoza<br />

through Nietzsche to Deleuze and Foucault, with Heidegger participating in both<br />

lines of descent. 1 The theme of transcendence is perhaps most strikingly evident in<br />

Levinas, whose philosophy focuses on the confrontation with the radical Other. The<br />

Other is transcendent in that it is necessarily “otherwise” than Being, and hence for<br />

Levinas ethics precedes ontology. The motif of immanence, by contrast, is constant<br />

in Deleuze – indeed, he argues in What Is Philosophy? that the entire history of<br />

philosophy may be read as an effort to establish a “plane of immanence” (QP 47/46–<br />

7). Deleuze regards Spinoza as “the prince of philosophers,” since he is perhaps<br />

the sole philosopher to make “no compromise with transcendence” (QP 49/48). For<br />

Spinoza, ethics is ontology, a point Deleuze stresses when he observes that Spinoza’s<br />

magnum opus of pure ontology is titled Ethics, and when he asserts that Spinoza’s<br />

Ethics is really an “ethology,” that is, a science of the species behavior of humans<br />

in the natural lifeworld. I believe that for Deleuze, as well as for Spinoza, ethics<br />

is ontology, and that for this reason his ethics is best conceived of as an immanent<br />

ethics. 2<br />

1 Giorgio Agamben, “Absolute Immanence,” in Potentialities: Collected Essays in<br />

Philosophy, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford, CA, 1999), p. 239.<br />

2 For an extended treatment of the theme of immanence in Deleuze’s thought, see<br />

Daniel W. Smith, “Deleuze and Derrida, Immanence and Transcendence: Two Directions in<br />

Recent French Thought,” in Paul Patton and John Protevi (eds), Between Deleuze and Derrida<br />

(London, 2003), pp. 46–66.


8<br />

Past, Present, Future<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

We may first approach the ethics of Deleuze’s thought through three themes, which<br />

may somewhat artificially be associated with stances toward the past, present and<br />

future: amor fati (the past); vice-diction (the present); and belief in this world (the<br />

future).<br />

In his early book Nietzsche and Philosophy (1962), Deleuze argues that<br />

Nietzsche’s concept of amor fati, or “love of fate,” provides an ethical principle that<br />

may replace Kant’s categorical imperative: whatever you will, also will its eternal<br />

return. What Deleuze means by this dictum is made evident in his discussion of<br />

chance and the throw of the dice. Most gamblers are bad players who want to control<br />

chance. They throw the dice and only affirm the outcome that they like. If they<br />

shoot craps, they roll again in an effort to overcome the unlucky roll and erase its<br />

consequences. Nietzsche’s good players, by contrast, roll only once, and whatever<br />

the result, they affirm that result and will its eternal return. In this way, good players<br />

avoid the ressentiment of finding the world guilty of frustrating their desires, and<br />

thereby genuinely affirm the play of the world.<br />

This Nietzschean principle of amor fati takes on a specifically Deleuzian cast<br />

in The Logic of Sense (1969) when Deleuze relates the concept to a Stoic ethics of<br />

the event. Central to Deleuze’s thought is the distinction between the virtual and the<br />

actual. The actual consists of the commonsense world of discrete forms, Newtonian<br />

space and chronological time. The virtual is a dimension of self-differentiating<br />

differences, one that is real without being actual, immanent within the actual without<br />

being reducible to it. It is a domain of individuating metamorphic processes, of a<br />

disorienting “spatializing” space, and a floating time of a simultaneous before-after.<br />

The virtual perpetually passes into the actual, that is, becomes actualized, but it is not<br />

thereby exhausted or erased, for it continues to subsist or insist within the actual. The<br />

virtual eludes our commonsense understanding, but it impinges on us in moments of<br />

vertigo when rational spatiotemporal coordinates are scrambled and a pure “event”<br />

emerges.<br />

Consider the growth of a biological organism. The single-celled ovum is<br />

traversed by multiple gradients, or zones of potential division, any one of which may<br />

be actualized through fertilization. Once cell division is initiated, an individuating<br />

process occurs whereby virtual differences become actualized in specific forms (two<br />

cells, then four, then eight), but the individuating process of becoming precedes<br />

the actually individuated forms, and that process continues throughout the life of<br />

the organism as cells are formed, nourished and replaced. The virtual is a kind of<br />

structure of self-differentiating differences that unfolds itself into the actual but<br />

remains elusively “present” within the actual, hovering over its surface, as it were.<br />

The virtual is something like the “problem” of which the actual organism is a specific<br />

solution, and at every point in the ongoing emergence of the organism the problem<br />

of that structure of self-differentiating differences persists, or insists, as a set of copresent<br />

zones of oscillating variation and potential becoming. The virtual organism<br />

is a sort of verbal infinitive, “to become dog,” “to become frog,” a differential<br />

structuring immanent within the actual dog or frog, passing into the actual in a


Immanent Ethics 9<br />

dynamic becoming at every point of the creature’s emergence, yet persisting as a<br />

problematic field of differential vectors.<br />

The world is an egg, says Deleuze (DR 323/251), and everywhere the virtual<br />

is passing into the actual while remaining immanent within it. Deleuze’s version<br />

of Nietzsche’s amor fati is an ethic of willing the virtual, of willing the virtual<br />

“event,” which is immanent within the actual and which impinges on us in moments<br />

of disequilibrium and disorientation. The quintessential event, says Deleuze, is<br />

the battle, something that hovers over the battlefield like a fog, everywhere being<br />

actualized in the bodies of the soldiers, but nowhere specifically present except as<br />

a kind of unfolding “problem” of that battle (see LS 122–3/100–101). The event of<br />

the battle is an infinitive, a “to battle,” anonymous, elusive, outside conventional<br />

time, a floating immanent aura guiding the processes of actualization but becoming<br />

manifest only as a kind of secondary emanation from the bodies that actualize it.<br />

Deleuze’s ethic is one of being worthy of that which happens, in other words, of<br />

willing the event (LS 174–9/148–53). What soldiers should affirm in the battle is not<br />

so much any specific outcome as the pure event of the battle, the virtual “to battle”<br />

that plays through any of the diverse actualizations of the battle that may take place.<br />

To be worthy of what happens is to will the virtual event immanent within one’s<br />

ongoing actualization in the world.<br />

In identifying this ethic of the event with amor fati, I am stressing its orientation<br />

toward the past. To be worthy of what happens is to will the difference, multiplicity<br />

and chance of the virtual and thereby avoid ressentiment and affirm the past events<br />

that have shaped one’s present. But one must also act in the present, and Deleuze<br />

by no means advocates a passive acceptance of everything that befalls us. One’s<br />

orientation toward the present in Deleuzian ethics we might approach through his<br />

concept of “vice-diction” (DR 245–7/189–91), as opposed to contra-diction. (In<br />

The Logic of Sense [LS 176–8/150–52], the concept goes by the name of contreeffectuation,<br />

“counter-actualization.”) Vice-diction is the process whereby one<br />

identifies and engages the virtual events immanent within one’s present world,<br />

whereby one “counter-actualizes” the virtual. Deleuze divides this process into<br />

two complementary movements, “the specification of adjunct fields” and “the<br />

condensation of singularities” (DR 245–6/190), which he likens to an Empedoclean<br />

expansion and contraction of love and hate. The specification of adjunct fields requires<br />

an outward exploration of the virtual networks of multiple connections that come<br />

together in each present moment, as well as a critique of our representations of that<br />

present moment. The virtual eludes our commonsense representations of the world,<br />

and only in moments of disequilibrium and disorientation do we sense the virtual in<br />

its passage into the actual. One task of vice-diction is to respond to this moment of<br />

disequilibrium, this unsettling “event,” first by undoing conventional representations<br />

of our situation, and second by teasing out the proliferating interconnections among<br />

self-differentiating differences that are enveloped in this particular moment of<br />

disequilibrium. Each unsettling element of a disorienting experience reveals what<br />

Deleuze calls variously a “zone of indiscernibility,” a “line of continuous variation,”<br />

or a “singularity,” a singular, remarkable difference that generates the regular forms<br />

and shapes of the commonsense world. The virtual may be conceived of as an infinite<br />

plane of singular points, each point being a zone of indiscernibility or vector of


10<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

continuous variation. The process of specifying adjunct fields consists of connecting<br />

singularities and thereby exploring the expanding surface of that infinite plane.<br />

But vice-diction involves a second moment as well: a condensation of singularities<br />

whereby one experiments on the real. We might say that vice-diction’s first moment,<br />

the specification of adjunct fields, entails an assessment of the configuration of<br />

singularities in the grand dice-throw of our present situation, and that vice-diction’s<br />

second moment, the condensation of singularities, involves a reconfiguration of<br />

singularities as we make of ourselves and our situation a second dice-throw. The<br />

object of vice-diction is not simply to comprehend the virtual differences at work<br />

in our world but also to transform them, or rather to enter into the play of virtual<br />

differences and experiment with them. Such an experimentation is a condensation<br />

of singularities in that it is an effort to engage the infinite plane of singular points<br />

and contract those points into a single event, an explosive big bang that creates new,<br />

unpredictable configurations of singularities. Vice-diction thus entails both a process<br />

of exploring and hence constructing connections among differences, and a process<br />

of undoing connections in an effort to form new ones.<br />

The concept of amor fati, then, allows us to think of the virtual in terms<br />

of an attitude toward the past, an absence of ressentiment and an affirmation of<br />

the sequence of virtual events that have come to form the actualized state of the<br />

present situation. Vice-diction frames the virtual in terms of the present moment, in<br />

which one explores the connections enveloped in the event that impinges on one’s<br />

situation and then experimentally induces metamorphic alterations of that situation.<br />

Yet implicit as well in this second moment of vice-diction is an attitude toward<br />

the future, an affirmation of the possibility of creating something new. One of the<br />

controlling themes in Deleuze’s work is that of “thinking otherwise,” of finding<br />

ways of inventing new possibilities for life, and such possibilities issue not ex nihilo<br />

but from the virtual lines of continuous variation immanent in the real. The creative<br />

side of vice-diction, the experimental activation of the disruptive potential of the<br />

virtual, implies an orientation toward the future which we may label, in Deleuze’s<br />

words, a “belief in this world.”<br />

In Cinema 2: The Time-Image (1985) Deleuze argues that the classic cinema<br />

testifies to a bond between humans and the world, whereas the modern cinema does<br />

not. “The modern fact,” Deleuze remarks, “is that we no longer believe in this world.<br />

We do not even believe in the events which happen to us, love, death, as if they only<br />

half concerned us. It is not we who make cinema; it is the world which looks to us<br />

like a bad film” (IT 223/171). The “power of modern cinema,” when it ceases to be<br />

bad cinema, is to restore “our belief in the world” (IT 223/171), not “another world”<br />

or a “transformed world,” but “this world, as it is” (IT 224/172). The world as bad<br />

film is the world of clichés, of received opinion (doxa), of that which goes without<br />

saying, of static forms and institutions, of intractable facts and inevitable results – in<br />

short, a tired world devoid of possibilities. What the great modern directors restore to<br />

us is a world within which something new can emerge, and they do so by activating<br />

virtual self-differentiating differences immanent within the real. In this activity,<br />

cinema directors do as any other artists and as do any other creators – philosophers,<br />

scientists, politicians – they experiment on the real, on the virtual’s immanent lines


Immanent Ethics 11<br />

of continuous variation. And when they do so, they affirm the creative potential<br />

immanent within the real and thereby exhibit a belief in this world.<br />

Deleuze’s immanent ethics is ultimately an ethics of the virtual, and what I have<br />

called amor fati, vice-diction and belief in this world are simply three ways of looking<br />

at the virtual. Amor fati is a backward glance that affirms the virtual within the events<br />

that have culminated in the present. Vice-diction is a topical survey of proliferating<br />

virtual connections and an activation of their potential for reconfiguration through a<br />

condensation of singularities. Belief in this world is a view through the present and<br />

toward the future, one that envisions nothing specific in that future, but that trusts in<br />

the possibilities immanent within the real to produce something genuinely new.<br />

Collectivity<br />

To this point, my focus has been on the ethics of the individual, with little direct<br />

reference to the individual’s relationship with others – a decidedly odd emphasis, one<br />

might think, given Deleuze’s enduring hostility toward the notion of the autonomous<br />

subject and any subject-grounded thought. How, then, might the social implications<br />

of an immanent ethics be considered? Three Deleuzian motifs suggest themselves:<br />

the body as domain of speeds and affects; the other as disclosure of the possible; and<br />

the invention of a people to come.<br />

Throughout his writings, Deleuze returns frequently to a remark by Spinoza that<br />

we do not yet know “what a body can and cannot do,” and hence, we do not know<br />

the extent of “the body’s capabilities.” 3 In Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (1981),<br />

Deleuze offers his most succinct explanation of the significance of this remark.<br />

Deleuze points out that Spinoza defines the body in two ways: in terms of relations<br />

of slowness and speed between an infinite number of particles; and in terms of a<br />

body’s capacities for affecting and being affected. By characterizing the body in<br />

terms of differential speeds, Spinoza emphasizes the body’s participation in a single<br />

“plane of immanence” (S 164/122), a dimension of rhythms, movements, pauses,<br />

accelerations and decelerations, in which each body’s form and function emerge as<br />

secondary products of kinetic relations among particles. By approaching the body in<br />

terms of its capacities, or powers, of affecting and being affected, Spinoza imbues<br />

the plane of immanence with a pervasive affectivity generated through interactions<br />

among multiple forces.<br />

In this analysis of bodies as affective rhythms, Deleuze finds the theoretical<br />

foundations of “what is today called ethology” (S 168/125), the study of animal<br />

behavior (a notion that in Deleuze’s usage might better be labeled “ecology”). The<br />

tick, for example, has limited capacities for affecting and being affected, its world<br />

determined solely by its receptivity to light (as it climbs a stalk or branch), to heat (as<br />

it senses an approaching mammal), to butyric acid (the substance excreted from the<br />

follicles of mammals), and to limited tactile stimuli (specifically, those provided by<br />

the hair and skin of its prey). The tick’s powers select a world, picking out a highly<br />

3 Baruch Spinoza, Complete Works, trans. Samuel Shirley, ed. Michael L. Morgan<br />

(Indianapolis, IN, 2002), p. 280.


12<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

restricted set of relational elements, excluding everything else. The tick combines<br />

with its world, taking in certain substances (light, scents, blood), emitting others<br />

(anticoagulants, bacteria), connecting with some organisms, defending itself from<br />

others, and ignoring the rest. The tick’s relations with its selected world constitute a<br />

type of musical counterpoint, its diverse powers forming a point in counterpoint to<br />

each of the elements with which it is capable of forming a connection.<br />

Humans, like ticks, select a world and form contrapuntal relations with that<br />

world’s elements. In the case of humans, however, the selected world is much wider<br />

and fuller than the tick’s, and the elements with which our powers can combine are<br />

in large measure unspecified. We do not know what a body can do, what connections<br />

the powers of the body make possible. We must therefore experiment with our<br />

bodies and seek those relations that increase our capacities. What is important to<br />

note is that the ethical imperative in bodily experimentation is not that of an increase<br />

in power over a world, but an increase in powers of affecting and being affected,<br />

a responsiveness to a selected world and an openness to interaction. As Deleuze<br />

insists in his Spinozistic reading of Nietzsche (NP 97/85), will to power manifests<br />

itself as a desire for power over others only in the reactive mentality of slaves, of<br />

those who seek to restrict others’ powers and to close themselves off from competing<br />

forces. The affirmative will to power, by contrast, seeks to extend its capacities<br />

through reciprocities of forces that combine in interconnecting affirmations of one<br />

another, and this is the will that Deleuze discerns in Spinoza’s ethology of bodies as<br />

configurations of speeds and affective intensities.<br />

Deleuze argues that Spinoza’s account of the body calls us not simply to an<br />

experimentation with the individual body in its connections with a selected world<br />

but also to the formation of more complex collective bodies, social assemblages of<br />

differential speeds and affective intensities. Rather than merely testing the relations<br />

that augment the powers of individual bodies or threaten their dissolution, we must<br />

also determine the powers that may emerge in the generation of compound bodies:<br />

It is no longer a question of utilizations or captures, but of sociabilities and communities.<br />

How do individuals enter into composition with one another in order to form a higher<br />

individual, ad infinitum? How can a being take another being into its world, but while<br />

preserving or respecting the other’s own relations and its world? … It is no longer a<br />

question of point to counterpoint, or of the selection of a world, but of a symphony of<br />

Nature, of a constitution of an increasingly wide and intense world. [S 169–70/126]<br />

The ethical question for Deleuze is not “what must we do?” but “what can we<br />

do?” What assemblages allow the formation of collective bodies that expand their<br />

capacities, that open new modes of affecting and being affected? This question<br />

is not one of imposing limits from without, but of exploring potential for growth<br />

from within. In this sense, ethics is immanent to the creation of worlds, a matter<br />

more of mutual affinities and intensities among bodies than of mutual duties and<br />

obligations.<br />

Yet is there no duty to the other in an immanent ethics? Not in the sense of<br />

a necessary restriction of one’s powers, or of the other’s, but perhaps a form of<br />

duty, a certain ethic of responsiveness or attentiveness, may be seen as consistent<br />

with Deleuze’s general ethical orientation. In Difference and Repetition (DR 333–


Immanent Ethics 13<br />

5/259–61), Deleuze remarks briefly on the Other as expression of possible worlds,<br />

taking as his example that of a terrified face which I perceive without perceiving the<br />

cause of its terror. 4 That face serves as a sign, not as signifier to signified, but as the<br />

moon’s visible surface to its dark side. The face points toward possible worlds yet<br />

unspecified, and if I am to encounter that sign, rather than simply classify it (ignore<br />

it, reject it, imitate it), I must enter with it into the composition of a world enfolded<br />

in its possibilities. To do so, I must construct a plane of immanence in which I and<br />

other are no longer fixed entities, but instead residual points of emergence within<br />

an unfolding ensemble of speeds and affects. The actualization of a specific world<br />

that arises from the unfolding of the other’s possible worlds may eventuate in a<br />

discrete self and a definite other, but the encounter itself, in which possible worlds<br />

become manifest, opens up in a dimension of apersonal affects and speeds. The<br />

encounter, if it is genuinely an encounter, is a dislocating meeting of affects – the<br />

terror of a screaming face, the startled reaction to that terror. And if it is to be a<br />

productive encounter, it will be one of mutual disturbance, in which possible worlds<br />

yet unspecified in the terror and in the shocked reaction to that terror interconnect<br />

and interact to generate an actual world. 5<br />

The duty to the other (if one must speak of duty) is to affect and be affected, to<br />

suspend, as much as one can, the categorization and comprehension of the other, and<br />

then open oneself to the undetermined, hidden possible worlds that are expressed<br />

in the affective signs of the other. The practical consequences of this openness to<br />

the other may be discerned in Deleuze’s remarks in a 1985 interview on the need<br />

for “intercessors” in various domains – in philosophy, the arts, science and politics:<br />

“Intercessors are essential. Creation is all about intercessors. Without them, there<br />

is no creative work. They can be people – for a philosopher, artists or scientists;<br />

for a scientist, philosophers or artists – but also things, even plants or animals, as<br />

in Castaneda” (PP 171/125). To intercede, for Deleuze, is not simply to advocate<br />

for the other, but also to “go between” (Latin: inter + cedere), to assist the other by<br />

intervening in the other’s world and producing creative interference (in the sense<br />

of an interference between sound or light waves). Deleuze says that “Félix Guattari<br />

and I, we are intercessors of one another” (PP 171/125), and they are so in that they<br />

do not fully understand one another. Deleuze argues that the notion that truth is<br />

created is “obvious in the sciences, for instance. Even in physics, there is no truth<br />

that does not presuppose a system of symbols, be they only coordinates. There’s no<br />

truth that doesn’t ‘falsify’ established ideas” (PP 172/126). When he and Guattari<br />

interact as mutual intercessors, each falsifies the other, “which is to say that each of<br />

us understands notions put forward by the other in his own way” (PP 172/126). The<br />

generative process of their collaboration requires an openness to the other’s different<br />

understanding of a concept, and a subsequent development of understandings through<br />

4 Deleuze and Guattari also discuss the concept of the other and the screaming face in<br />

What Is Philosophy? (QP 21–3/16–19). My own analysis of the Other combines elements<br />

found in both Difference and Repetition and What Is Philosophy?.<br />

5 I am indebted to James Williams, Gilles Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition: A<br />

Critical Introduction and Guide (Edinburgh, 2003), pp. 208–10, for pointing out the ethical<br />

implications of Deleuze’s discussion of the Other.


14<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

a mutual undoing of each other’s initial understandings. Intercession is a form of<br />

positive dissonance, made possible through an openness to interferences that disturb<br />

one’s regular harmonic vibrations. Intercessors falsify one another in various ways,<br />

via divergences in concepts (philosophy), sensations (the arts), theoretical models<br />

(the sciences), strategies (politics), via interventions across boundaries delimiting<br />

conventional fields of activity, and so on: “These powers of the false [Ces puissances<br />

du faux] to produce truth, that is what intercessors are about” (PP 172/126).<br />

Deleuze relates the process of intercession not only to individual creativity in<br />

diverse domains but also to the formation of community, to “the constitution of a<br />

people” (PP 171/125–6). Deleuze frequently cites Paul Klee’s observation that the<br />

modern artist cannot simply engage “the people” since it is precisely “the people”<br />

that is missing. Hence, Deleuze sees the need to fashion a “people to come” (QP<br />

206/218), a future, yet-to-be collectivity that has a genuine cohesiveness and<br />

functionality. As we saw earlier, Spinoza’s notion of the body as a composite of<br />

differential speeds and affects invites a conception of community as a compound<br />

body, one in which the point and counterpoint of multiple organisms produce a<br />

larger “symphony of Nature.” Such a compound body is not something stable but<br />

an essentially dynamic, metamorphic process, a mutual becoming-other of multiple<br />

bodies engaged in unpredictable unshapings and reshapings of one another. A people<br />

to come “is not exactly a people called upon to dominate the world. It is a minor<br />

people, eternally minor, taken up in a becoming-revolutionary” (CC 14/4). The object<br />

of art is to fashion a people to come, and to do so artists engage in what Deleuze calls<br />

“fabulation,” an activation of the “powers of the false” that dissolves conventional<br />

social categories and codes and invents new possibilities for life. Artists cannot<br />

fabulate alone, however. They must have intercessors who help them undo their<br />

own presuppositions, intercessors who themselves enter into fabulation with artists<br />

in the formation of a collectivity as process. Nor is the creation of a people to come<br />

the responsibility of artists alone. In What Is Philosophy?, Deleuze and Guattari<br />

distinguish philosophy from non-philosophy by emphasizing the differences among<br />

philosophy, the sciences and the arts, but they conclude that all three domains meet<br />

in the common goal of inventing a people. The three domains extract<br />

… from chaos the shadow of the “people to come,” such as that which art, but also<br />

philosophy and science, summon forth: mass-people, world-people, brain-people, chaospeople.<br />

Nonthinking thought that lodges in the three, like Klee’s nonconceptual concept<br />

or Kandinsky’s internal silence. It is here that concepts, sensations, and functions become<br />

undecidable, at the same time as philosophy, art, and science become indiscernible, as if<br />

they shared the same shadow, which extends itself across their different nature and never<br />

ceases to accompany them. [QP 206/218]<br />

Immanence<br />

Clearly, the partition of Deleuze’s immanent ethics into discrete components is<br />

artificial at best. My assignment of amor fati to the past, vice-diction to the present,<br />

and belief in this world to the future is designed only to highlight shades of emphasis<br />

in these interrelated concepts, no one of which can be understood outside a single


Immanent Ethics 15<br />

conception of time as the unfolding of the immanent event. My separation of<br />

individual from collective motifs in Deleuze’s ethical thought is likewise merely<br />

provisional, for the individual taking form in amor fati, vice-diction, and belief<br />

in this world is always merging with a multiplicity-in-formation. The body of<br />

differential speeds and affective intensities is inseparable from the world it selects,<br />

and its contrapuntal relations are always available for the constitution of compound<br />

bodies of indeterminate size. The Other is never a single other, but always the sign of<br />

many possible worlds, and, in a genuine encounter, self and other mutually dissolve<br />

in a plane of immanence from which emerges an actual world, itself a multiplicity.<br />

The invention of a people to come is the goal of philosophy, but also of thought in<br />

general, whether in the arts, sciences, politics, or any number of other domains, for<br />

the invention of a people is one with the creation of possibilities for life. To think and<br />

to act creatively is to enter into the creative unfolding of the cosmos, to participate in<br />

a metamorphic experimentation on ourselves and our world in the hopes of bringing<br />

forth something new that enhances our capacities for affecting and being affected.<br />

Deleuze’s ethics is immanent in that it is inseparable from the universe’s ongoing<br />

self-creation, from the virtual event’s perpetual actualization of possible worlds.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 2<br />

Minority, Territory, Music<br />

Deleuze and Guattari remark that in a rhizome as opposed to an arborescence,<br />

any point “can be connected to anything other, and must be” (MP 13/7). In their<br />

own rhizomatic thought, the concepts of minority and territory in general are not<br />

intimately conjoined, yet the two points can be usefully related – and indeed, as we<br />

are told, they must be. The concept of minority engages the conventional idea of a<br />

statistically small ethnic or racial group, but extends far beyond that to the broad<br />

category of what Deleuze and Guattari call the “minor,” which includes the notions<br />

of minor literature, minor culture, and the minor usage of language. 1 The concept<br />

of territory, which Deleuze and Guattari discuss in its narrow ethological sense in<br />

A Thousand Plateaus, is inseparable from the general notions of territorialization,<br />

reterritorialization and deterritorialization, which play through their thought in a<br />

wide range of contexts. The path from minority to territory runs from literature to<br />

music and suggests some of the ways Deleuze and Guattari connect the two arts.<br />

Both literature and music, we shall find, prove to be arts capable of a minor usage,<br />

whereby lines of continuous variation and a general chromaticism are engaged in a<br />

process of deterritorialization.<br />

Minority<br />

Kafka<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s first extended treatment of the topic of “the minor” can be<br />

found in their Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature (1975). Their discussion has its point<br />

of origin in a lengthy diary entry of Kafka’s, dated December 25, 1911, in which he<br />

reflects on such minor literatures as Czech literature and Jewish literature in Warsaw,<br />

noting that the absence of dominant great writers within these traditions has certain<br />

positive consequences. No single genius silences other writers, and as a result the<br />

literary community is especially lively, competitive and active. No towering figure<br />

serves as an easily emulated model, and hence the untalented are discouraged from<br />

writing, and those with talent are able to maintain their mutual independence. When<br />

such minor traditions come to construct their literary histories, no great writers<br />

arouse multiple and changing interpretations that vary with fluctuations in taste;<br />

1 We might note as well that the French word mineur(e) bears the connotation of<br />

immaturity, as in the case of an individual who has not attained his or her majority, and hence<br />

of a lack of seriousness, whereas the substantive minorité has an immediately demographic<br />

connotation.


18<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

thus, their histories offer “an unchangeable, dependable whole that is hardly affected<br />

by the taste of the day.” 2 The end result is that literature in such minor traditions<br />

takes on a much more collective function than in major traditions. The contentions of<br />

competing schools, journals, cabals and camps become the focus of national concern,<br />

the literary and the political become intertwined as literature assumes a central role<br />

in the formation of national identity, aesthetic polemics become “a matter of life<br />

and death” (Diaries 194), and literature becomes “less a concern of literary history<br />

than of the people” (Diaries 193). Thus Kafka concludes his “character sketch of the<br />

literature of small peoples” with the following outline: “1. Liveliness: a. Conflict. b.<br />

Schools. c. Magazines. 2. Less constraint: a. Absence of principles. b. Minor themes.<br />

c. Easy formation of symbols. d. Throwing off of the untalented. 3. Popularity: a.<br />

Connection with politics. b. Literary history. c. Faith in literature, can make up their<br />

own laws” (vol. 1, p. 195).<br />

Deleuze and Guattari identify three basic characteristics of minor literature: “in<br />

it language is affected with a high coefficient of deterritorialization”; “everything in<br />

[it] is political”; and “in it everything takes on a collective value” (K 29–31/16–17).<br />

The second and third characteristics clearly echo the features delineated by Kafka<br />

in his discussion of minor literature. In a major literature, the personal, familial and<br />

conjugal can remain detached from the sociopolitical sphere, which tends to function<br />

as a mere background or environment. In a minor literature, by contrast, “its cramped<br />

space forces each individual intrigue to connect immediately to politics” (K 30/17).<br />

When Kafka identifies as one of the benefits of minor literature “the dignification<br />

of the antithesis between fathers and sons and the possibility of discussing this”<br />

(vol. 1, p. 192), he is simply stressing the inextricability of the personal and the<br />

political in such traditions. In this political treatment of the familial, relations take on<br />

a collective significance and immediately extend to other spheres – the “commercial,<br />

economic, bureaucratic, juridical” (K 30/17). The “collective value” of minor<br />

literature is closely related to its immediately political nature, but what Deleuze<br />

and Guattari emphasize in this third characteristic is not simply the interpenetration<br />

of social and personal relations, but also the possibility of a collective enunciation<br />

of a group solidarity and a “revolutionary machine-to-come” (K 32/18). As Kafka<br />

points out, in minor traditions literature can bring about “the coherence of national<br />

consciousness,” which otherwise is “often unrealized in public life and always<br />

tending to disintegrate” (vol. 1, p. 191). The marginal situation of minor writers<br />

allows them “all the more the possibility to express another possible community and<br />

to forge the means for another consciousness and another sensibility” (K 32/17). And<br />

in the absence of great stylists whose individualized, personalized voices serve as<br />

models of emulation in major literatures, minor writers tend to articulate “collective<br />

assemblages of enunciation” (K 33/18) that belong to no individual subject.<br />

It might seem that Deleuze and Guattari are simply elaborating on Kafka’s<br />

empirical observations of the features of literary traditions devoid of great writers,<br />

but what they argue is that minor literature is less a matter of specific cultural<br />

communities than of a general usage of language, a minor usage that can be found<br />

2 Franz Kafka, The Diaries of Franz Kafka, ed. Max Brod, trans. Joseph Kresh (New<br />

York, 1948), vol. 1, p. 193.


Minority, Territory, Music 19<br />

in any social group and in any language. Herein lies the importance of the first<br />

characteristic of minor literature – that “in it language is affected with a high<br />

coefficient of deterritorialization” – and it is in Kafka’s minor usage of German<br />

that Deleuze and Guattari find an exemplary instance of minor literature’s<br />

deterritorialization of language. At the turn of the century, many Prague Jews felt<br />

distanced from their peasant roots and uncomfortable with the Czech language<br />

(Kafka being an exception among his contemporaries in the latter respect). Yet the<br />

German they spoke was a “paper language,” artificial and formal, as well as being the<br />

language of an oppressive minority, itself removed from its native cultural milieu.<br />

The Prague dialect, influenced by Czech, was in many regards an impoverished<br />

German, characterized by<br />

… the incorrect use of prepositions; the abuse of the pronominal; the employment of<br />

malleable verbs (such as geben, which is used for the series ‘put, sit, place, take away’<br />

and which thereby becomes intensive); the multiplication and succession of adverbs; the<br />

use of pain-filled connotations; the importance of the accent as a tension internal to the<br />

word; and the distribution of consonants and vowels as part of an internal discordance.<br />

[K 42/23] 3<br />

Prague German, then, displayed “a high coefficient of deterritorialization” in that it<br />

was at once detached from its native context and rendered artificial through its heavy<br />

bureaucratic associations, and at the same time destabilized by the way it was used –<br />

through ungrammatical constructions, words with multiple and shifting nonstandard<br />

meanings, accents and gestures that lend an elusive aura of affective intensity to the<br />

language, and so on. Prague Jews found themselves foreigners in their own tongue,<br />

and they responded in one of two ways. Some chose “to artificially enrich this German,<br />

to swell it up through all the resources of symbolism, of oneirism, of esoteric sense,<br />

of a hidden signifier” (K 34/19). Kafka, by contrast, sought to impoverish Prague<br />

German further, to destabilize it and imbue it with affective intensity through an<br />

ascetic limitation of vocabulary, an avoidance of metaphor, symbols and esoteric<br />

allusions, and a distribution of accents and rhythms that render the language both<br />

unsettlingly irregular and fastidiously obsessive. 4 Kafka’s response, in short, was to<br />

take advantage of the tendencies already present in the minor usage of German by<br />

Prague Jews, and to manipulate, develop, modify and exaggerate those tendencies in<br />

his own minor usage of the language.<br />

3 Deleuze and Guattari base their remarks on Prague German on Klaus Wagenbach’s<br />

extended discussion of the subject in Franz Kafka: Eine Biographie Seiner Jugend 1883–1912<br />

(Bern, 1958), pp. 83–95.<br />

4 Deleuze and Guattari argue that Joyce and Beckett, as Irishmen writing in English,<br />

faced a dilemma similar to that of Prague Jews at the turn of the century, and that their<br />

differing strategies for deterritorializing English resemble those adopted by Kafka and his<br />

contemporaries, Joyce artificially enriching the language, Beckett by contrast proceeding “by<br />

dryness and sobriety, a willed poverty, pushing deterritorialization to such an extreme that<br />

nothing remains but intensities” (K 19/35).


20<br />

Language<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

In the fourth section of A Thousand Plateaus, “November 20, 1923: Postulates of<br />

Linguistics,” Deleuze and Guattari outline a general theory of language that helps<br />

clarify the notion of a minor usage of language. The primary function of language,<br />

they argue, is not to communicate information but to impose power relations. To<br />

learn a language is to learn a host of categories, classifications, binary oppositions,<br />

associations, codes, concepts, logical relations and so on, whereby the world is given<br />

a certain coherence and organization. Far from being neutral, the order imposed by<br />

a language is part of a complex network of practices, institutions, goods, tools and<br />

materials imbued with relations of force. Following the line of analysis developed by<br />

speech-act theorists, Deleuze and Guattari insist that language is a mode of action, a<br />

way of doing things, and the condition of possibility of any language is the complex<br />

network of practices and material elements that shape a given world. This complex<br />

network is made up of what Deleuze and Guattari call “assemblages” (agencements),<br />

heterogeneous collections of actions and entities that somehow function together. 5<br />

These may be divided into two broad categories that function as a level of content<br />

and a level of expression, the first consisting of nondiscursive machinic assemblages<br />

of bodies, “of actions and passions, an intermingling of bodies reacting to one<br />

another,” the second of discursive collective assemblages of enunciation, “of acts<br />

and statements, of incorporeal transformations attributed to bodies” (MP 112/88).<br />

Machinic assemblages are the various patterns of practices and elements through<br />

which a world’s bodies are formed, and collective assemblages of enunciation are the<br />

patterns of actions, institutions and entities that make possible linguistic statements.<br />

Collective assemblages of enunciation induce “incorporeal transformations” of<br />

bodies in that they transform elements and configurations of the world through<br />

speech acts. 6 When the minister says, “I thee wed,” or the judge says, “I pronounce<br />

you guilty,” a transformation takes place, a body is changed from bride to wife, from<br />

defendant to felon. Although collective assemblages of enunciation and machinic<br />

assemblages are related to one another as expression to content, they are not to be<br />

understood in terms of the Saussurean categories of signifier and signified. The two<br />

5 The term agencement, translated variously as “assemblage,” “arrangement,” or<br />

“organization,” can denote both a particular arrangement of entities and the act of assembling<br />

or combining elements in a given configuration. Particularly useful are Deleuze’s remarks<br />

about language and assemblages in Dialogues: “The minimum real unit is not the word,<br />

the idea, the concept or the signifier, but the assemblage. It is always an assemblage which<br />

produces utterances. Utterances do not have as their cause a subject which would act as a<br />

subject of enunciation, any more than they are related to subjects as subjects of utterance. The<br />

utterance is the product of an assemblage – which is always collective, which brings into play<br />

within us and outside us populations, multiplicities, territories, becomings, affects, events” (D<br />

51; 65).<br />

6 The term “incorporeal transformations” Deleuze and Guattari take from the Stoic theory<br />

of incorporeals, which Deleuze discusses at several points of The Logic of Sense, especially<br />

series two, twenty and twenty-three. Deleuze’s primary sources for his understanding of the<br />

Stoics are Emile Bréhier’s La Théorie des incorporels dans l’ancien stoïcisme (Paris, 1928),<br />

and Victor Goldschmidt’s Le Système stoïcien et l’idée de temps (Paris, 1953).


Minority, Territory, Music 21<br />

types of assemblages are independent and heterogeneous: “One can never assign<br />

the form of expression the function of simply representing, describing, or averring a<br />

corresponding content … In expressing the noncorporeal attribute, and by that token<br />

attributing it to the body, one is not representing or referring but intervening in a<br />

way; it is a speech act” (MP 109–10/86).<br />

Collective assemblages of enunciation intervene in machinic assemblages, and<br />

that which puts the two forms of assemblages in relation to one another in any<br />

given instance Deleuze and Guattari call an “abstract machine,” which consists of<br />

unformed matter and nonformalized functions that are virtual without being actual,<br />

yet are immanent within the real. One means of approaching this difficult concept<br />

is by situating it within a linguistic context, and for our purposes a specific example<br />

may suffice – that of the phrase “I swear!,” a statement with varying significance in<br />

Kafka’s work. Consider first the phonemic aspect of this statement. The word “swear”<br />

may be pronounced with diverse accents and intonations, and its acoustic attributes<br />

will differ with the physiological characteristics of each speaker. Conventionally, the<br />

phoneme is thought of as a mental constant determined by its differential relations<br />

with other phonemes. Different pronunciations of the same phoneme are merely<br />

insignificant variations of a single constant; only differences that impose meaningful<br />

distinctions are pertinent, such as those that transform “swear” into “sweat” or “sway.”<br />

Deleuze and Guattari argue, however, that the constant derives from the variations,<br />

not the reverse. The multiple, heterogeneous pronunciations of the word “swear” are<br />

so many actualizations of an immanent “line of continuous variation” that passes<br />

through all potential pronunciations of the word. This line of continuous variation<br />

is a continuum of sonic possibilities that is real but not actual; it is virtual, and each<br />

pronunciation of a given phoneme may be thought of as a concrete actualization of<br />

a specific point along the continuum. This virtual line of continuous variation is a<br />

component of an abstract machine.<br />

All elements of language must likewise be regarded as determined by immanent<br />

lines of continuous variation. Thus, grammatical and syntactical rules, which are<br />

conventionally viewed as the generative causes of a well-formed statement such as<br />

“I swear!,” must instead be seen as derivative effects of grammatical/syntactical lines<br />

of continuous variation, in this instance a continuum of forms that might include “I<br />

swear,” “I do swear,” “So do I swear,” “Swear I,” “I do so swear, do I.” But most<br />

important, the semantic dimension of language must also be understood in terms<br />

of lines of continuous variation. The statement “I swear!” has a different meaning<br />

when pronounced by a son before his father (as in Kafka’s “The Judgment”), by<br />

a reluctant fiancé before a “family tribunal” (as in Kafka’s letter describing his<br />

meeting with disappointed relatives over his indefinitely postponed marriage), or<br />

by a defendant before a judge (as in The Trial). Conventionally, a single denotative<br />

core of meaning is thought to inform various utilizations of a given semantic unit, its<br />

diverse contextualizations being simply contingent variations on a basic stable sense.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari counter that each enunciation of “I swear!” is an actualization<br />

of a line of continuous variation immanent within the real, “a continuum of ‘I swear!’<br />

with the corresponding transformations” (MP 119/94). This semantic continuum is<br />

inseparable from a wide range of practices, institutions, and entities that make up<br />

the contents of the diverse, contextually embedded speech acts distributed along


22<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

that continuum. Not only is each performance of “I swear!” an actualization of<br />

phonemic, grammatical, syntactical and semantic lines of continuous variation, but<br />

it is also an action within a situation, a means of intervening in bodies and inducing<br />

incorporeal transformations in them. Each “I swear!” presupposes patterns of actions<br />

and elements that make up a collective assemblage of enunciation as well as networks<br />

of practices and entities that constitute nondiscursive machinic assemblages. And the<br />

lines of continuous variation that play through these assemblages function together<br />

as an abstract machine.<br />

One can see then that the common notions of grammatical rules, correct<br />

pronunciations, syntactical regularities, proper meanings, standard usage, and so on,<br />

are not the essential constituents of language, but the secondary effects of power.<br />

The lines of continuous variation within a given social field can be used in two basic<br />

ways. They can be constricted, regulated, organized, controlled and disciplined, or<br />

they can be set in oscillation, intensified, amplified and ramified. The inculcation of a<br />

standard, correct, proper language instills a thorough coding of the world according<br />

to a dominant order. It also entails a stabilization of inherently unstable elements and<br />

a valorization of elements in terms of a hierarchy of norms and deviations – correct<br />

vs incorrect usage; standard speech vs dialect, patois, jargon, slang; prestigious vs<br />

unprestigious discourse, and so on. A standard language does not exist by itself as a<br />

static, self-enclosed, rule-governed system; rather, it issues from multiple patterns<br />

of actions and entities organized in such a way as to restrict variation and regularize<br />

relations of force. But lines of variation may be used in other ways as well. The<br />

“impoverished” German of Prague Jews, the creoles of Caribbean islanders, the<br />

Black English of African-Americans, are diverse usages of major languages that<br />

destabilize linguistic regularities and intensify lines of continuous variation. In a<br />

similar fashion, the experimentations of writers such as Kafka, Beckett, Céline<br />

and Gherasim Luca (to name but a few of Deleuze and Guattari’s favorite authors)<br />

make “language itself stammer” by placing “all linguistic, and even nonlinguistic,<br />

elements in variation, both variables of expression and variables of content” (MP<br />

124/98). Each of these writers invents a minor usage of language, a way of being “a<br />

foreigner, but in one’s own tongue,” of being “bilingual, multilingual, but in one and<br />

the same language, without even a dialect or patois” (MP 124–5/98).<br />

Minorities<br />

We can now see what relation there is between a minor usage of language and the<br />

notion of a minority. The opposition of majority and minority is not strictly a matter<br />

of numbers but of “a constant, of expression or content, serving as a standard measure<br />

by which to evaluate it” (MP 133/105). The majority is defined by a hierarchical<br />

set of values embedded in language. One might say that the dominant standard “is<br />

the average adult-white-heterosexual-European-male-speaking a standard language<br />

(Joyce’s or Ezra Pound’s Ulysses)” (MP 133/105). The linguistic oppositions of<br />

adult/child, white/colored, heterosexual/homosexual, European/non-European,<br />

male/female encode power relations, and the dominant term of each opposition<br />

serves as a norm against which deviations are measured. Each norm is a constant,<br />

stable and unchanging, and each is reinforced by the system of linguistic constants of


Minority, Territory, Music 23<br />

a standard language, be they semantic, syntactic, grammatical, lexical, or phonemic<br />

(in that “correct speech” or “standard usage” is always value-laden). Women may<br />

outnumber men, and blacks may outnumber whites, but the majority remains male<br />

and white: “Majority assumes a state of power and domination, not the other way<br />

around. It assumes the standard measure, not the other way around” (MP 133/105).<br />

Yet curiously the majority is like Odysseus, who tells the Cyclops he is “Nobody”<br />

[Personne], whereas the minority is “everybody” [tout le monde]. The analytic<br />

standard/norm against which deviation is measured is an abstract, unchanging<br />

ideal embodied in no individual. No one measures up, everyone falls short to some<br />

extent, but most importantly, everybody changes, and change, flux, metamorphosis,<br />

becoming are the paths of creation: “That is why we must distinguish between: the<br />

majoritarian as a constant and homogeneous system; minorities as subsystems; and<br />

the minoritarian as a potential, creative and created, becoming” (MP 134/105–106).<br />

This is not to deny that numerically small minorities are frequently oppressed by<br />

majorities, or that majorities often deem themselves worthy of the norms they<br />

represent. It means, however, that the problem of minorities is not to restore a<br />

counter-identity, to return to a long-lost pure culture and tongue, but to enter into a<br />

process of becoming whereby the constants and norms of the dominant, majoritarian<br />

order are put into continuous variation. This process of becoming is a potential open<br />

to everyone, but no one automatically enters it by virtue of his or her social position.<br />

Minorities can easily inculcate their own constants and norms. As a result, they, too,<br />

must construct their own means of becoming-other, their own lines of continuous<br />

variation:<br />

All becoming is minoritarian. Women, regardless of their numbers, are a minority, definable<br />

as a state or subset; but they create only by making possible a becoming over which they<br />

do not have ownership, into which they themselves must enter; this is a becoming-woman<br />

affecting all of humankind, men and women both. The same goes for minor languages:<br />

they are not simply sublanguages, idiolects or dialects, but potential agents of the major<br />

language’s entering into a becoming-minoritarian of all of its dimensions and elements.<br />

[MP 134/106]<br />

If we return to Deleuze and Guattari’s description of minor literature in Kafka, we may<br />

now see more fully the logical relationship between its three basic characteristics,<br />

“the deterritorialization of language, the connection of the individual to a political<br />

immediacy, and the collective assemblage of enunciation” (K 33/18). Language is a<br />

mode of action informed by relations of power. The abstract machine’s virtual lines<br />

of continuous variation are actualized in collective assemblages of enunciation and<br />

nondiscursive machinic assemblages. A major usage of language fixes, regularizes<br />

and stabilizes forms and meanings, and thereby territorializes variations. It reinforces<br />

categories and distinctions that compartmentalize existence, thereby fostering an<br />

isolation of the personal and the political. It also encourages both the reinforcement of<br />

the dominant views of the majority and the illusion of the autonomy of the individual<br />

voice. By contrast, a minor usage deterritorializes language by disturbing dominant<br />

regularities and setting them in variation. In disrupting majoritarian categories, a<br />

minor usage connects the personal and the political in proliferating networks of<br />

becoming. And in activating real (albeit virtual) lines of continuous variation, a


24<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

minor usage directly engages collective assemblages of enunciation, fashioning not<br />

an individual voice but the voice of a people to come, that is, a people in the process<br />

of becoming other. It is in this sense that in minor literature “there isn’t a subject;<br />

there are only collective assemblages of enunciation, and literatures expresses these<br />

assemblages insofar as they’re not imposed from without and insofar as they exist<br />

only as diabolical powers to come or revolutionary forces to be constructed” (K<br />

33/18).<br />

Bene<br />

In his 1979 essay “One Less Manifesto,” Deleuze elaborates on the concept of minor<br />

literature, reiterating many of the points made in Kafka and A Thousand Plateaus,<br />

but also indicating ways in which the concept may be applied to the theater. The<br />

essay appears in a volume titled Superpositions, which also includes the text of the<br />

drama Richard III, or the Horrible Night of a Man of War, by the Italian playwright<br />

and filmmaker Carmelo Bene. A significant figure in the Italian theater, Bene has<br />

written and produced a number of plays based on earlier dramas, including Arden of<br />

Feversham, Othello, Macbeth and Lorenzaccio, as well as films inspired by earlier<br />

works, such as Don Giovanni, Salome and One Less Hamlet. Bene’s Richard III<br />

takes Shakespeare’s history play as its point of departure, incorporating selected<br />

characters, scenes and lines from the original, but deforming them through extended<br />

textual additions, incongruous gestures and actions, surreal sets and props, and<br />

various devices for manipulating and denaturalizing the spoken word. In Deleuze’s<br />

analysis, Bene’s Richard III, like many of his other plays and films, has a “critical<br />

function” (SP 87/204) that is both subtractive and constitutive. What Bene subtracts<br />

from Shakespeare are “the elements of power” (SP 93/206), both those represented<br />

in the drama – history, the state, royal authority – and those inherent in drama as a<br />

mode of representation – structure, standard language, lucid text, dialogue, and so<br />

on. From what remains, Bene constitutes a different set of characters – a different<br />

Richard, Lady Anne, Duchess of York, Marguerite, Elizabeth and Jane Shore<br />

(Richard III is the only male Bene retains from Shakespeare) – none of which is a<br />

coherent and consistent “subject” but instead a line of continuous variation through<br />

which the “character” and actor pass as an unfolding field of dramatic events is<br />

constructed. Bene constitutes as well as a different language, different forms of<br />

enunciation, new patterns of gesture, and new relations between speech, setting and<br />

action. In sum, from the “subtraction of the stable elements of Power,” Bene releases<br />

“a new potentiality of theater, a nonrepresentative force forever in disequilibrium”<br />

(SP 94/207).<br />

Deleuze finds in Bene’s Italian a minor usage of language, a means of making<br />

language itself stammer. Bene manages “to impose on language, as it is perfectly<br />

and soberly spoken, this line of variation that will make you a foreigner in your<br />

own language or make a foreign language your own or make your language an<br />

immanent bilingualism for your foreignness” (SP 109/213).Bene also makes use of<br />

various possibilities for metamorphosing language in oral performance, inducing<br />

a general “aphasia” through whispers, stammers, cries, groans, barely audible<br />

lines, deafeningly amplified tirades, lip-sync playback, and so on. He abandons the


Minority, Territory, Music 25<br />

conventions of properly constructed dialogue, with its rules of opening and closure,<br />

continuity and proper sequencing of exchanges. Instead:<br />

… there is no dialogue in this theater of Bene’s; for voices, simultaneous or successive,<br />

superimposed or transposed, are caught in this spatiotemporal continuity of variation. It is<br />

a kind of Sprechgesang. In song, it is a matter of maintaining the pitch, but in Sprechgesang<br />

one always varies the pitch with a dip or a rise. [SP 105/211]<br />

Bene induces as well a transmutation of speech acts through the shifting and unstable<br />

tones and attitudes with which the actors deliver their lines. Deleuze notes that Lady<br />

Anne’s statement “You disgust me!” is a different speech act when pronounced by<br />

“a woman at war, a child facing a toad, or a young girl sensing an already consenting<br />

and loving pity” (SP 104–105/211). In her extended interaction with Richard, the<br />

actress playing Lady Anne moves through all these variables at once, managing “to<br />

stand erect like a woman warrior, regress to a childlike state, and come to life again<br />

as a young girl – on a line of continuous variation, and as quickly as possible” (SP<br />

105/211). The result is a “You disgust me!” that unfixes its social coordinates and<br />

oscillates among its diverse virtual positions, entering into multiple combinations<br />

with the other oscillating speech acts of the scene.<br />

Bene’s minor use of language necessarily affects nonlinguistic aspects of his<br />

drama, among which gesture particularly interests Deleuze. One critic notes that<br />

gestures and objects in Bene’s theater often obstruct action, the actors’ bodies<br />

impinging on one another, costumes restricting their movements, objects blocking<br />

their movements. But Deleuze argues that obstruction and opposition are not central<br />

to the gestures of this theater, for these characteristics imply relations of power, and<br />

“the relations of force and opposition are part of what is shown only that it may be<br />

subtracted, cut away, neutralized” (SP 113/215). Instead, Bene treats gesture in a<br />

musical fashion, according to relations of speed and slowness that vary in irregular<br />

and unpredictable ways. Bene admires certain Italian saints, “the saints sanctified<br />

by grace: Saint Joseph of Copertino, the imbeciles, the idiot saints, Saint Francis<br />

of Assisi dancing before the Pope” (cited in SP 97–8/208), identifying “their grace<br />

with the movement of disgrace” (SP 114/215). Bene sees these saints as sanctified<br />

by that which disgraces them in the eyes of social authority, but he also regards<br />

them as imbued with a physical grace of movement determined by their departure<br />

from conventional behavior, with its regular, prescribed habits of comportment and<br />

interaction. Likewise, Richard’s constant stumbling, falling, tottering, collapse and<br />

resuscitation (noted at several points in Bene’s text) are elements of the construction<br />

of Richard’s grace through movements of disgrace, means whereby he deforms<br />

the forms of proper behavior and discovers new gestural velocities and directions.<br />

The result is that the same gesture or word is never repeated “without obtaining<br />

different characteristics of time. This is the musical formula of continuity, or of<br />

form as transformation” (SP 113/215). The abandonment of conventional gestures<br />

entails a departure from pre-established forms, but also from socially constructed<br />

roles and identities (the gestures appropriate, say, for a king, an adult, a man). In his<br />

deformation of standard gestures, Richard replaces forms with speeds and social roles<br />

with affects and intensities unassociated with any subjective identity. In this regard,


26<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

his gestures fulfill what Deleuze regards as “two essential aims of the arts,” “the<br />

subordination of form to speed, to the variation of speed, and the subordination of<br />

the subject to intensity or to affect, to the intense variation of affects” (SP 114/215).<br />

Deleuze traces an illustrative sequence of gestures in the scene of Richard’s<br />

courtship of Lady Anne. Shakespeare’s original is not parodied by Bene, “but<br />

multiplied according to the variable speeds or developments that will be combined<br />

in a single continuity of constitution (not a unity of representation)” (SP 117/216).<br />

While Richard delivers his lines of love, the actor playing the character “begins<br />

to begin to understand” (SP 31), according to Bene’s stage directions – that is, he<br />

begins to construct the gestural trajectory of a new set of movements. He takes<br />

winding sheets from the corpse of Henry VI, whose coffin is at the back of the stage,<br />

picks up various prosthetic limbs and artificial body parts stashed in cabinet drawers<br />

and strewn across the stage, and wraps them one by one to his body with the winding<br />

sheets as he speaks with Lady Anne. The prosthetic devices, signs of deformity and<br />

corporeal subtraction, gradually become part of Richard’s gestural comportment,<br />

costumes of an action that takes him beyond his historical and political role and<br />

destiny. Lady Anne reacts with disgust to Richard as the representative of state<br />

power, but as he accrues various deformities she responds with pity, sympathy, and<br />

an increasing eroticism. Gradually she helps him find prosthetics and wrap them to<br />

his body, and she herself accelerates an eccentric sequence of gestures, “continually<br />

undressing and dressing herself in a rhythm of regression-progression that responds<br />

to Richard’s subtractions-constructions” (SP 118/217). Finally, as the characters<br />

develop their separate lines of gestural variation, the two lines enter into relation<br />

with one another and form a single continuum, itself composed of indissociably<br />

related discursive and nondiscursive elements: “And each one’s vocal variations,<br />

phonemes and tonalities, form a tighter and tighter line infringing on each one’s<br />

gestures, and vice versa,” at which point there are not “two intersecting continuities<br />

but one and the same continuum in which words and gestures play the roles of<br />

variables in transformation” (SP 118/217).<br />

The theater might seem to provide exceptional instances of minor literature,<br />

in that drama necessarily involves a wide range of nonlinguistic elements that are<br />

not a part of other literary forms. But in actuality, drama simply makes evident<br />

what is implicit in all literature. In Deleuze and Guattari’s view, the discursive and<br />

the nondiscursive are inseparable (though by no means identical). Language is a<br />

mode of action informed by the interplay of machinic assemblages and collective<br />

assemblages of enunciation. Words intervene in bodies, and all the elements of<br />

language – phonemic, syntactic, semantic – derive their function from patterns<br />

of practices, institutions and material objects. Kafka’s minor usage of German<br />

intensifies the linguistic practices of Prague Jews, but in so doing it necessarily<br />

engages all the elements inherent in varying speech situations. The continuum of “I<br />

swear!” passes through words, intonations, gestures, bodies, buildings and locales,<br />

and Kafka’s minor usage of that continuum sends reverberations through all those<br />

elements. Bene’s minor theater likewise intensifies lines of variation inherent in the<br />

Italian language, and through the actors’ delivery and diverse sonic manipulations<br />

of their speech, deformations in the performance of language are induced, while<br />

the elements of gesture, costume and setting are denaturalized, transmuted and


Minority, Territory, Music 27<br />

recombined in unexpected arrangements. Yet Richard’s stammerings and groans, his<br />

constant staggering and stumbling, his prosthetic modifications of his body and his<br />

interactions with props and stage furniture, are not fully isolable from his words. A<br />

minor usage of language engages relations of action and power, which interconnect<br />

meanings, sounds, movements, bodies and decor. Bene’s minor theater dramatizes<br />

the pragmatic nature of language. In this sense it may be viewed as the theater of<br />

minor literature, a staging of the full range of elements implicit in the minor usage of<br />

language engaged in by all minor writers in all forms of literary invention.<br />

Territory<br />

The Refrain<br />

As we have seen, the concepts of minority and territory are interrelated, in that a minor<br />

usage of language effects a deterritorialization of linguistic regularities, but what<br />

this notion of “deterritorialization” has to do with concrete geographical territories<br />

remains to be determined. Throughout their collaborative works, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari make frequent use of the terms deterritorialization and reterritorialization,<br />

but it is only in section eleven of A Thousand Plateaus, “1837: Of the Refrain,”<br />

that they address the topic of territory per se, engaging the subject via an analysis<br />

of music’s relation to animal ethology. 7 Music, they assert, “is a creative, active<br />

operation that consists in deterritorializing the refrain [la ritournelle],” whereas the<br />

refrain “is essentially territorial, territorializing, or reterritorializing” (MP 369/300).<br />

Deleuze and Guattari identify three basic aspects of the refrain, which we may label a<br />

point of order; a circle of control; and a line of flight toward the outside. An instance<br />

of a point of order is that of the tune a child sings to comfort herself when she’s<br />

alone and afraid in the dark. A circle of control is evident in the perimeter of a cat’s<br />

domain marked by his spray. And a line of flight is met with in the mass movements<br />

of lemmings, birds, or lobsters. Although the point of order, circle of control and<br />

line of flight are most easily understood in terms of diverse moments and scenarios,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari insist that they are not “successive moments in an evolution,”<br />

but “three aspects of a single thing, the Refrain” (MP 383/312). Nevertheless, these<br />

three aspects of the refrain vary in their relative importance when considered in the<br />

context of different animals and their environments. The refrain in its broadest sense<br />

is a rhythmic regularity that brings order out of chaos. All animals interact with<br />

the world to fashion environments, or milieus, and each milieu is defined by the<br />

components of which it is composed; “Every milieu is vibratory, that is, a block of<br />

space-time constituted by the periodic repetition of the component” (MP 384/313).<br />

Milieus confront chaos, and rhythm “is the milieus’ answer to chaos” (MP 385/313).<br />

The amoeba’s inner metabolic rhythms, its movements in its aqueous medium, its<br />

absorptions of nutrients and reactions to external stimuli, the fluctuating waves of<br />

7 For a more extended discussion of Deleuze and Guattari’s approach to music and<br />

territoriality, see Chapters One and Three of my Deleuze on Music, Painting, and the Arts<br />

(New York, 2003).


28<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

forces and particles that impinge on its surface – all may be seen as components of<br />

an interactive system of rhythms, or regular patterns of space-time, which together<br />

constitute the refrain that characterizes a milieu. 8<br />

All animals inhabit milieus, but only some occupy territories. A territory emerges<br />

when a milieu component ceases to be merely functional and becomes expressive.<br />

The bright coloration of the male stickleback fish, for example, is not simply a<br />

mating stimulus for the female, but it serves also as a placard signaling the male’s<br />

territorial rights. The color is “both a quality and a property, quale and proprium”<br />

(MP 387/315), the qualitative expression of the territory and the signature of its<br />

possessor. What is functional in mating behavior gains autonomy, becomes detached<br />

from its milieu context. In a similar fashion, the stagemaker bird marks its territory<br />

by pulling leaves from trees and placing them in patterns on the ground. Here, leaves<br />

cease to function as parts of a tree habitat and become signs of the bird’s domain. The<br />

territory is “an act that affects milieus and rhythms, that ‘territorializes’ rhythms”<br />

(MP 386/314). Paradoxically, the territorializing act proceeds via a detachment,<br />

decoding, or “deterritorialization” of milieu components and a reinscription,<br />

recoding, or “reterritorialization” of those components as expressive qualities<br />

within a territory. Nor is the territorial act performed exclusively by the territory’s<br />

possessors. Territorialization “is an act of rhythm that has become expressive,<br />

or of milieu components that have become qualitative” (MP 388/315). Rhythm<br />

itself territorializes, which is a somewhat enigmatic way of saying that territories<br />

are emergent features of the regular patterns of complex ecological systems. The<br />

patterns are rhythms, melodies, refrains, and though produced by animals and their<br />

environments, they are relations between elements, and hence features of the system<br />

as a whole rather than any of its separate components.<br />

The “T factor, the territorializing factor,” then is found “precisely in the becomingexpressive<br />

of rhythm or melody, in other words, in the emergence of proper qualities<br />

(color, odor, sound, silhouette … )” (MP 388/316). Rhythms that are fixed and<br />

functionally coded in milieus become detached and assume new roles as expressive,<br />

proper qualities. These qualities serve as signs of the territory and its occupant’s<br />

possession of the domain, but the rhythms of a territory also tend to take on a life<br />

of their own and become more than mere signatures of ownership. Territorial motifs<br />

“form rhythmic faces or characters,” and territorial counterpoints “form melodic<br />

landscapes,” motifs and counterpoints becoming autonomous patterns that follow<br />

“an autodevelopment, in other words, a style” (MP 391–3/318–19). Further, every<br />

territory is open to an outside, and its rhythms and patterns include “lines of flight,”<br />

unstable vectors that serve both as constituents of the territory and sources of its<br />

potential dissolution. In this regard, the long-distance migrations of spiny lobsters,<br />

Alaskan salmon and Canadian geese are simply extreme instances of a general<br />

tendency of every territory to move beyond itself toward the surrounding world.<br />

8 Deleuze’s first published book, Instincts et institutions, assembles a number of brief<br />

texts on this topic, by authors as diverse as Hume, Rousseau, Kant, Darwin, Cuvier, Bergson,<br />

Malinowski, Freud, Lévi-Strauss and Eliade. Deleuze’s short introduction on the relationship<br />

between animal instincts and social institutions (ID 24–7/19–21) inaugurates a line of<br />

speculation that reappears with some frequency throughout his thought.


Minority, Territory, Music 29<br />

One can see, then, that the three aspects of the refrain correspond to three degrees<br />

of increasing deterritorialization that are met with in the generation of a territory.<br />

The refrain as point of order is a rhythmic regularity that organizes milieus in fixed<br />

patterns. Since territories encompass milieus and possess lines of flight, the refrain<br />

appears in territories in all its guises – point of order, circle of control, line of flight,<br />

“three aspects of a single thing” (MP 383/312).<br />

Music<br />

Many birds are territorial, and birdsong is often recognized as having a territorial<br />

function. Ornithologists distinguish between calls, or communicational signals of<br />

imminent danger, presence of food, proximity of mates or foes, and so on, and songs<br />

proper, which, depending on the species, may vary in length and complexity from<br />

two-to-three-second repeated motifs to extended, multisectional, improvisatory<br />

performances. In Deleuze and Guattari’s terminology, bird calls are largely milieu<br />

components, fixed to specific functions, whereas birdsongs are territorial elements,<br />

sonic components of milieus that have been unfixed and reconfigured in a more<br />

autonomous fashion. Ethologists debate whether birds are musicians, some arguing<br />

that birds sing only in response to hormonal stimuli, others insisting that birds have<br />

an aesthetic sense, take pleasure in singing for its own sake, and in a few cases,<br />

create original sonic compositions. Deleuze and Guattari concur that birds are artists,<br />

though they do not treat the issue as one of instinctual versus free activity. Art has its<br />

origin in the emergence of qualities as expressions of a territory. The stickleback’s<br />

coloration and the stagemaker’s leaves are artworks, whether produced primarily<br />

by instinct or volition. What counts are the object and its status within the act of<br />

territorialization. Birdsongs likewise are artworks, for they are deterritorialized<br />

milieu components that express a territory and a property, and in their extended<br />

and elaborate forms they become part of autonomous “rhythmic characters” and<br />

“melodic landscapes” that tend beyond the territory toward the cosmos as a whole.<br />

The bird sings its territory, or rather, the territory as relational rhythmic act sings<br />

itself through the bird, as the refrain actualizes musical points of order, circles of<br />

control and lines of flight.<br />

What relation does birdsong have to human music? Certain compositional practices<br />

of the composer Olivier Messiaen suggest an answer. 9 In a series of works from the<br />

1940s, 1950s and 1960s, Messiaen incorporates birdsongs into his music, rendering<br />

as accurately as possible through conventional musical instruments the intervals,<br />

rhythms, articulations and timbres of the melodies of various species of birds. Yet<br />

Messiaen admits that much is changed when one transfers to human instruments<br />

the microintervals and rapid tempi of birdsongs, as well as those articulations<br />

and timbres peculiar to avian physiology. 10 Once the intervals are stretched to fit<br />

9 In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari make reference to Messiaen’s music,<br />

his use of birdsong, and his concept of “rhythmic characters.” See especially MP 299–<br />

309/367–80 and 316–20/388–94. See also Deleuze, FB 48/60.<br />

10 Messiaen says of his citations of birdsongs in his music: “Personally, I’m very proud<br />

of the exactitude of my work; perhaps I’m wrong, because even people who really know the


30<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

the chromatic scale, the tempos slowed to human speeds, and the attack and tone<br />

adapted to suit orchestral instruments, the melodies are virtually unrecognizable to<br />

the most discerning of ornithologists, and once the birdsong motifs are combined<br />

in polyphonic patterns and manipulated to become parts of a compositional whole,<br />

they are even further transformed. Despite Messiaen’s efforts to imitate birdsong, his<br />

musical practice is that of a “becoming-bird,” a passage between bird and human that<br />

produces something new and unexpected, not an imitation but a deterritorialization<br />

of birdsong.<br />

Music “is a creative, active operation that consists in deterritorializing the refrain”<br />

(MP 369/300). What might seem an idiosyncratic technique in Messiaen is actually<br />

paradigmatic of all musical composition. To the extent that they create genuine<br />

music, all musicians – even birds – deterritorialize the refrain. And they are able to<br />

do so because the refrain deterritorializes itself. In its first guise as point of order,<br />

the refrain manifests itself in various milieu rhythms, which are fixed to specific<br />

functions (eating, mating, fighting, and so on). In its second guise as territorial<br />

motif, the refrain is itself a deterritorialization of milieu rhythms, and in its third<br />

aspect as line of flight, it is a deterritorialization of territorial rhythms. Even the most<br />

rudimentary of birdsongs is a deterritorialization of the milieu refrain, an unfixing and<br />

decoding of calls with particular functions, and the most complex birdsongs further<br />

deterritorialize rhythms that have been fixed and coded within territories and open<br />

them toward an outside. The compositions of Messiaen simply extend this process of<br />

deterritorialization, taking as their material the refrains of birds and submitting them<br />

to diverse operations and procedures that produce new sonic events.<br />

Yet we must not think that Deleuze and Guattari’s point is that composers simply<br />

render human analogs of the sounds of nature. The example of Messiaen’s use of<br />

birdsong is instructive, in that it suggests a direct way in which music deterritorializes<br />

the refrain, but it is potentially misleading if we do not keep in mind that the refrain<br />

is not exclusively sonic. Refrains are rhythms, relational patterns that shape milieus<br />

and territories. 11 The rhythms of mating, feeding, reproduction, nurture, play, struggle<br />

and exploration; the periodic fluctuations of weather, seasons, tides, or currents; the<br />

recurrent flows of gestures, movements, sights, sounds, smells, tastes – all combine<br />

in refrains. The task of music is less to convert natural sounds to human sounds than<br />

to render sonorous the nonsonorous forces that play through nature, and to do so by<br />

deterritorializing the rhythmic relations of the world, transforming them, and inventing<br />

new modes for their interconnection and interaction. In his monumental orchestral<br />

work From the Canyons to the Stars ... (1974), for example, Messiaen makes use of<br />

a number of birdsongs, but he also claims to render sonorous the multiple rhythms of<br />

birds might not recognize them in my music, yet I assure you that everything is real” (Olivier<br />

Messiaen, Music and Color. Conversations with Claude Samuel, trans. E. Thomas Glasow<br />

(Portland, OR, 1994), p. 94).<br />

11 Deleuze and Guattari’s discussion of territorialization as an “act of rhythm” suggests<br />

that they take “rhythm” in its broadest sense, to include both temporal and spatial patterns (as<br />

one speaks of the rhythm of the elements of a painting, sculpture or building, for example).<br />

Hence, all the relational patterns of music may be subsumed within the general category of<br />

rhythm.


Minority, Territory, Music 31<br />

the birds’ habitats throughout the course of a day, the slow rhythms of the geological<br />

formations of the Utah canyons, and the extended rhythms of the constellations. His<br />

composition engages these various refrains not by “imitating” birds, sagebrush, rocks<br />

and stars, but by extracting from milieu components their rhythmic relations and<br />

submitting these relations to processes of creative metamorphosis, first fashioning<br />

nonmimetic analogs of those relations in the form of melodic and harmonic motifs,<br />

then combining, transforming, dividing, inverting those motifs, and finally shaping<br />

them into a structurally coherent sequence of interconnected movements. Although<br />

Messiaen provides evocative titles for each of the twelve movements of this work<br />

– for example, “The Desert,” “Orioles,” “Interstellar Call,” “Zion Park and the<br />

Celestial City” – the resulting composition is less a musical evocation of a setting<br />

than a self-organized sonic response to a set of abstract relations. And though other<br />

composers may not articulate their practice in such terms, they too manipulate and<br />

transform the rhythms that surround them and pervade them whenever they create<br />

music. 12<br />

Minority and territory<br />

What, then, is the relation between minority and territory, between literature as a minor<br />

usage of language and music as the deterritorialization of the refrain? Language is a<br />

mode of action informed by relations of power. Machinic assemblages and collective<br />

assemblages of enunciation constitute patterns of practices, institutions and material<br />

objects that organize and regulate the immanent lines of continuous variation that<br />

play through the phonemic, grammatical, syntactic and semantic elements of speech<br />

and writing. The patterns of the relations of power that infuse and shape language<br />

may also be termed refrains, periodic rhythms that compose milieus and territories<br />

(as well as other forms of social-environmental organization, which we would need<br />

to detail in a thorough analysis of this problem). A minor usage of language induces<br />

a destabilization of linguistic constants, an unfixing of semiotic regularities, and in<br />

this sense it may be seen as a deterritorialization of the refrains immanent within<br />

various speech-act events. Both literature and music are experimentations on the<br />

real, means of capturing, dissolving and transmuting existing relations of force and<br />

then reshaping and reconstructing them in new configurations. Literature works<br />

with a linguistic medium, music with a sonic medium, but both engage rhythms and<br />

forces that extend through fields that include the discursive and the nondiscursive,<br />

the sonic and the nonsonic. Writers manipulate words, but words function as<br />

components of context-specific speech-acts, which are made up of multiple linguistic<br />

12 A thorough treatment of Deleuze and Guattari’s approach to music would include a<br />

review of their differentiation of Classical, Romantic and Modern compositional practices<br />

in A Thousand Plateaus (MP 337–50; 416–33). Deleuze discusses music as well in the final<br />

Chapter of The Fold (LP 164–87/121–37), concentrating primarily on music’s relation to<br />

the other arts in the Baroque, and in Périclès et Verdi. La philosophie de François Châtelet<br />

(PV). Also of interest are Deleuze’s brief articles “Making Inaudible Forces Audible” (DRF<br />

142–6.156–60) and “Occupy Time Without Counting: Boulez, Proust and Time” (DRF 272–<br />

9/292–9).


32<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

and nonlinguistic elements. A minor usage of language affects all the components<br />

of speech-acts, and in the theater one sees an explicit demonstration of literature’s<br />

implicit deterritorialization of diction, gesture, movement and setting through the<br />

manipulation of the word. Similarly, in Messiaen’s experimentations with birdsong,<br />

he necessarily engages elements beyond those of mere sound, for each birdsong<br />

is part of a complex territorial assemblage of interrelated rhythms that constitute<br />

patterns of courtship, mating, reproduction, feeding, and so on. In this sense, music’s<br />

deterritorialization of the refrain, like literature’s minor usage of language, entails an<br />

engagement of proliferating networks of relations that stretch across heterogeneous<br />

domains, the refrain incorporating sonic and nonsonic components alike, just as<br />

speech-acts involve variables of language, gesture, action, and all the nondiscursive<br />

components of the given contexts of their performance.<br />

To a certain extent, humans are territorial animals, and works of literature and<br />

music often have specifically territorial associations. Languages arise in concrete<br />

regions; tales, myths and legends are created by peoples inhabiting their native soils.<br />

The rhythmic and melodic modes of ancient Greece belong to specific locales, as<br />

do the talas (basic rhythmic units) of traditional Indian music. (Indeed, the complex<br />

relations between a geographic area and its artistic creations are such that a territory<br />

and its literature and music may be seen as mutually defining one another.) As birds<br />

sing their territory, so do humans speak or sing theirs. But the literature and music<br />

of a given territory are transfused by relations of power, and to the extent that they<br />

are territorial arts, they reinforce the domination of the majority, that is, those who<br />

represent the standard and norm against which all deviation is measured. No matter<br />

how oppressed a given group may be, a return to its native soil, to the tales and<br />

songs of the homeland, remains a return to a major culture and a major usage of<br />

language and sound. The minor is essentially homeless, nomadic, vagabond. A<br />

minor usage of language puts constants in variation, disengages them from their<br />

territorial roots, and sets them in perpetual movement. The aim of minor literature is<br />

to set all the constants of language in such continuous variation, just as it is the aim<br />

of music to deterritorialize all aspects of the refrain. In a brief remark about Viennese<br />

atonal music, Deleuze and Guattari observe that in the works of composers like<br />

Schoenberg, twelve-tone rows may deterritorialize tonality, but the other elements<br />

of music – rhythm, dynamics, attack, timbre – receive a relatively conventional<br />

treatment. What Deleuze and Guattari call for is an experimentation on all aspects<br />

of music, a “generalized chromaticism” (MP 123/97) that puts all musical constants<br />

in variation. Likewise, they support in literary creation a parallel experimentation<br />

on all aspects of language. As Deleuze remarks in “One Less Manifesto,” “a minor<br />

language contains only minimal structural constancy and homogeneity. It is not,<br />

however, a porridge, a mixture of dialects, since it finds its rules in the construction<br />

of a continuum. Indeed, the continuous variation will apply to all the sonorous and<br />

linguistic components in a sort of generalized chromaticism” (SP 100/209). Deleuze<br />

observes that Bene’s “writing and gestures are musical,” in that Bene treats all the<br />

components of drama as variations in speed and intensity. “This is the musical<br />

formula of continuity, or of form as transformation” (SP 113/215). At a certain level<br />

of abstraction, experimentations on the lines of continuous variation immanent<br />

within language and those immanent within territorial refrains may be seen as


Minority, Territory, Music 33<br />

experimentations on speeds and intensities, on relational patterns and rhythms, on<br />

oscillations, vibrations and modulations in a spatiotemporal continuum. At that level,<br />

both literature and music have a common function as minor usages of relations of<br />

power and as deterritorializations of territorial forces.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 3<br />

Violence in Three Shades of Metal<br />

Death, Doom and Black<br />

The role of violence in contemporary culture has often been raised in discussions<br />

of popular music, and this question is particularly germane to three closely related<br />

forms of heavy metal music known as death metal, doom metal and black metal. The<br />

music of all three forms is extremely loud, somber and modal, highly percussive, and<br />

often fast, with vocals generally delivered in guttural shouts, grunts, moans, screams,<br />

or whispers. The lyrics frequently offer images of mayhem, dismemberment, bodily<br />

decay and disease. And in the case of black metal, a few of its better-known artists<br />

have been convicted of arson and murder. Deleuze says little directly about popular<br />

music, and his analyses of music as an art are less copious than those of other arts,<br />

especially literature and cinema. Nonetheless, his thought, especially as developed<br />

with Guattari, provides an incisive means of articulating the issues surrounding the<br />

social dimension of music in general and those related to violence in these three<br />

forms of heavy metal music in particular.<br />

Deleuze and Music<br />

Deleuze’s most extended treatment of music is to be found in Plateaus 10 and 11<br />

of A Thousand Plateaus, where he and Guattari develop the concept of music as<br />

the “creative, active operation that consists in deterritorializing the refrain” (MP<br />

369/300). 1 Deleuze and Guattari’s fundamental goal is to situate music within the<br />

processes of the natural world and conceive of it as a specific mode of engaging<br />

patterns of action, relation and development. The refrain may be defined loosely<br />

as any rhythmic pattern that forms part of a network of relations among creatures<br />

and their environment within a milieu, territory, or social domain. Each organism<br />

traces a “developmental melody” as it grows, matures and eventually dies, and the<br />

regular rhythms of its activities function as so many motifs in counterpoint with the<br />

motifs produced by surrounding organisms and inorganic forces. Organisms possess<br />

varying degrees of autonomy in relation to their environment; milieu creatures are<br />

closely tied to their surrounding world, territorial animals less so, and certain species<br />

(such as humans) even less so again (in that humans, though showing territorial<br />

tendencies, finally are capable of inhabiting spaces in much more unfixed and shifting<br />

patterns than such territorial species as the stickleback fish or the Australian grass<br />

1 For a detailed discussion of Deleuze’s approach to music, see my Deleuze on Music,<br />

Painting, and the Arts (New York, 2003), pp. 13–76.


36<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

finch). Relative degrees of autonomy among organisms are made possible by the<br />

“deterritorialization” of refrains, by the uncoding or unfixing of rhythmic patterns<br />

within one context, and by their “reterritorialization” within another. The song of the<br />

stagemaker bird, for example, is a sonic pattern that has been “deterritorialized” from<br />

any single function – say, that of signaling danger – and has been “reterritorialized” as<br />

a multi-functional refrain integrated within diverse refrains traced in the activities of<br />

nest-building, mating, food-gathering, predator-signaling, territorial defense, and so<br />

on. The stagemaker’s song emerges within its territory as part of its lifeworld, and the<br />

bird’s overall degree of autonomy, its relative flexibility in the organization of a given<br />

block of space-time, is a function of the deterritorialization and reterritorialization of<br />

its multiple refrains.<br />

Human music is significantly less fixed in its function than is birdsong, and music’s<br />

greater degree of deterritorialization is inseparable from the human species’ general<br />

degree of flexibility in its relation to its lifeworld. Human music may be involved in<br />

any number of activities – courtship, war, ritual, worship, lament, labor, celebration,<br />

dance, intoxication, amusement – but music possesses no necessary relationship to<br />

any of these, and it tends toward an autonomy that is beyond any function other than<br />

its own process. Indeed, music’s reterritorialization of sound is largely a recoding of<br />

sound in terms of itself, that is, in terms of formal systems such as those of traditional<br />

harmony and counterpoint in Western tonal music. Yet human music is not simply<br />

a collection of deterritorialized refrains, for it is also a deterritorializing force that<br />

interacts with nonmusical rhythmic patterns and provides them with sonic analogs<br />

within musical works. For Deleuze and Guattari, all deterritorialization proceeds<br />

via a process of becoming-other, a passage between entities or categories that sets<br />

them in metamorphic disequilibrium. In Olivier Messiaen’s use of birdsong in his<br />

musical compositions, Deleuze and Guattari find an apt example of music’s function<br />

as a deterritorializing force interacting with refrains in a process of becoming-other. 2<br />

In many of his compositions, especially those of the 1950s and 1960s, Messiaen<br />

constructs motifs from various birdsongs, rendering them with what Messiaen<br />

regards as great accuracy. Yet Messiaen observes that the high pitches, rapid tempos<br />

and peculiar timbres of birdsongs require that he enlarge the intervals between<br />

tones, slow the tempos, and find substitute timbres among human instruments in<br />

order to provide musical counterparts to the original birdsongs. The result, Messiaen<br />

concedes, is a music filled with birdsongs that the most practiced of ornithologists<br />

seldom can recognize. For Deleuze and Guattari, Messiaen’s interaction with<br />

birdsong is a paradigmatic instance of the musical process of becoming-other, a<br />

becoming-bird in which something passes between the fixed coordinates of human<br />

music and birdsong to produce new sounds. Messiaen’s musical rendering of the<br />

bird’s refrain deterritorializes that refrain, extracts it from its territorial function, and<br />

then incorporates it within a musical composition that unfolds along its own lines of<br />

development. Messiaen does not imitate the birdsong but provides a sonic analog of<br />

2 Messiaen’s remarks on birdsong and their function in his music may be found in<br />

Claude Samuel, Conversations with Olivier Messiaen, trans. Felix Aprahamian (London,<br />

1976), especially pp. 62 and 75.


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 37<br />

the song, thereby giving musical embodiment to the extra-musical force of the bird’s<br />

territorial refrain.<br />

A musical becoming-other is not simply a matter of undoing fixed refrains,<br />

however, for in becoming-other one engages a dimension of reality that is qualitatively<br />

distinct from ordinary experience. Deleuze and Guattari differentiate between two<br />

domains in the real world, an actual domain of commonsense spatiotemporal entities<br />

and processes, and a virtual domain of pure becoming and self-differentiating<br />

difference. The virtual may be conceived of loosely as a field of vectors of potential<br />

development and metamorphosis, each vector a line of continuous variation along<br />

which an actual process of development and metamorphosis might unfold. The<br />

virtual is immanent within the real, and every concrete, commonsense process is an<br />

actualization of an immanent virtual line of force. As I noted in Chapter 1, the virtualactual<br />

relationship is most easily understood via the example of the genesis and<br />

growth of a biological entity. The initial single-cell ovum is crisscrossed by multiple<br />

lines of potential cleavage, only one of which is actualized upon fertilization. As the<br />

single cell divides into two cells, potential lines of further division emerge within each<br />

of the new cells, again only one of which is actualized as each new cell in turn splits<br />

in two. Rather than seeing this process of division as the mechanical implementation<br />

of a preprogrammed blueprint, Deleuze and Guattari treat it as the unfolding of an<br />

immanent vector of differentiation, whereby a virtual, self-differentiating force is<br />

continuously actualized within concrete developmental processes.<br />

“The world is an egg,” Deleuze says in Difference and Repetition (DR 323/251),<br />

in that this process of actualization of virtual lines of force is manifest throughout<br />

the real. Usually, the virtual domain of becoming and self-differentiating difference<br />

escapes us, but in moments of disequilibrium and disorientation we gain access to<br />

that realm. Then we encounter a world not of discrete objects, fixed coordinates and<br />

chronometric time, but of flows and fluxes, topological spaces and floating durations.<br />

Entities within this virtual domain may be characterized solely by “pure relations<br />

of speed and slowness between particles” and by “pure affects” (MP 270/330), or<br />

powers of affecting and being affected by other elements. The time of the virtual<br />

is not that of Chronos, or regularly measured clock time, but that of Aeon, a time<br />

like that of an infinitive, “to swim,” “to sleep,” a becoming that is unfixed and nonpulsed,<br />

unfolding in no specifiable direction and in relation to no clear coordinates.<br />

In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari designate the domain of the virtual<br />

by various names, including the body without organs, the plane of consistency, and<br />

the smooth space of the nomadic war machine. By calling it a body without organs,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari stress the affective nature of the virtual and its connection to the<br />

human body, but they caution that the body without organs is not strictly speaking an<br />

individual or human body, for the body without organs is immediately social (capital,<br />

for example, is the body without organs of the capitalist social formation) and it is<br />

always made up of flows and fluxes that include human and nonhuman elements<br />

alike. By labeling the virtual a plane of consistency, Deleuze and Guattari avoid<br />

associations with the human body entirely and highlight abstract continuities between<br />

elements, while insisting that the elements are irreducibly multiple and held together<br />

only through a loose cohesion, or glue-like consistency, emerging from relations of<br />

speed and affective intensity. And by speaking of the virtual as a smooth space (as


38<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

opposed to one that is “striated,” or graphed and gridded), which is generated by the<br />

nomadic war machine, they emphasize the fluid, ever-changing quality of the virtual,<br />

as well as its connection to forces of transformation and potential destruction.<br />

Thus, when Messiaen enters into a process of becoming-other and deterritorializes<br />

a birdsong refrain, he engages a virtual line of continuous variation that is<br />

immanent within the real, and that specific line of variation, or vector of potential<br />

development and differentiation, is interconnected with other such lines across a<br />

plane of consistency, or field of virtual vectorial forces. Messiaen’s goal (and that<br />

of all composers generally, and of modern composers especially) is to capture these<br />

virtual forces, “the forces of an immaterial, nonformal, and energetic Cosmos” (MP<br />

342–3/423), and give them sonic embodiment. He seeks to render sonorous that<br />

which is nonsonorous, to address “a problem of consistency or consolidation: How<br />

to consolidate the material, make it consistent, so that it can harness unthinkable,<br />

invisible, nonsonorous forces,” such as those of “Duration and Intensity” (MP<br />

343/423). In one sense, then, Messiaen’s compositions are directly connected<br />

to the actual material world, in that he generates thematic material through a<br />

deterritorialization of actual birdsong refrains. But in another sense, his compositions<br />

partake of a different realm – the virtual – rendering sonorous the nonsonorous<br />

forces immanent within the real. In this regard, his compositions may be seen as<br />

sonic bodies without organs, palpable planes of consistency that render perceptible<br />

what usually escapes perception – the speeds, affects and floating time of the virtual.<br />

I believe that the music of death, doom and black metal groups likewise aims at the<br />

creation of sonic bodies without organs, or palpable planes of consistency, though of<br />

a decidedly different quality than those of Messiaen.<br />

The Music of Death, Doom and Black Metal<br />

Death, doom and black metal are sub-genres of heavy metal music, a form of<br />

popular music whose origin most commentators trace to the 1969–70 release of<br />

Led Zeppelin’s Led Zeppelin II, Deep Purple’s Deep Purple in Rock, and Black<br />

Sabbath’s Paranoid. 3 Of these three, Black Sabbath’s was the album that fostered<br />

the development of death, doom and black metal. England’s Venom produced what<br />

some regard as the first death metal album, Welcome to Hell, in 1981, with other<br />

early efforts in a death vein including those of Los Angeles’ Slayer (Show No Mercy<br />

[1983], Hell Awaits [1985], and Reign in Blood [1986]), Switzerland’s Hellhammer<br />

(Apocalyptic Raids [1985]), and Florida’s Death (Scream Bloody Gore [1987],<br />

3 The best introduction to heavy metal music as a whole is Robert Walser, Running<br />

with the Devil: Power, Gender, and Madness in Heavy Metal Music (Hanover, 1993). Deena<br />

Weinstein, Heavy Metal: A Cultural Sociology (New York, 1991) also provides useful<br />

information about heavy metal culture, but her sociological analysis pays little heed to the<br />

music per se. Neither Walser nor Weinstein explicitly discusses the sub-genres of death, doom<br />

and black metal. The portraits of heavy metal listeners in Jeffrey Jensen Arnett, Metalheads:<br />

Heavy Metal Music and Adolescent Alienation (Boulder, CO, 1996) are of limited interest,<br />

especially since only one of his subjects listens to music that might be remotely classified as<br />

death, doom or black metal.


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 39<br />

Leprosy [1988]). By the early 1990s, death had become established as a prominent<br />

form of heavy metal music, leading performers during the 1990s including Morbid<br />

Angel, Deicide, Cannibal Corpse, Obituary, Monstrosity, Cryptopsy, Suffocation,<br />

Dying Fetus and Vader. At present, several hundred death bands are performing and<br />

recording worldwide.<br />

Devotees of doom metal often cite as early instances of the sub-genre mid-<br />

1980s albums by Saint Vitus and Candlemass, the title of Candlemass’ 1986 Epicus<br />

Doomicus Metallicus perhaps inspiring the sub-genre’s eventual designation. But<br />

only in the early 1990s did doom become firmly established as an important form<br />

of heavy metal music, as groups such as Paradise Lost (Lost Paradise [1990]), My<br />

Dying Bride (As the Flower Withers [1992], Turn Loose the Swans [1993]), and<br />

Anathema (Serenade [1993], Enigma [1995]) fused elements of death metal with the<br />

somber, slow-paced strains of groups such as Saint Vitus and Candlemass. Though<br />

perhaps less popular than death metal, doom continues to thrive, with at least two<br />

hundred groups active in the Americas and Europe.<br />

Black metal is often said to have arisen alongside death metal, Sweden’s Bathory<br />

showing characteristics of the sub-genre in such releases as The Return … (1985),<br />

Under the Sign of the Black Mark (1987) and Blood Fire Death (1988), but the<br />

groups most closely associated with the establishment of black metal as a distinct<br />

category, Norway’s Mayhem, Burzum, Darkthrone and Emperor, developed their<br />

music in direct response to death metal. These groups’ releases from the early 1990s<br />

inspired the formation of hundreds of black metal bands in the next decade, black<br />

metal now perhaps rivaling death in popularity among metal audiences. In addition<br />

to Darkthrone, Emperor and Mayhem, important black metal groups active in the last<br />

decade include Dark Funeral, Enslaved, Gorgoroth, Immortal, Impaled Nazarene,<br />

Marduk, Rotting Christ and Satyricon. 4<br />

4 The categories of death, doom and black are somewhat fluid, and classification of<br />

individual groups within these categories is often disputed by listeners. Nor are these the only<br />

divisions of heavy metal music that might be brought to bear on a study of the three sub-genres;<br />

thrash, grindcore, stoner rock, and speed metal, for example, are other classifications often<br />

invoked in heavy metal discussions. Assessments of the popularity of death, doom and black<br />

metal are difficult to make. The sub-genres receive virtually no television or radio airplay.<br />

CDs are produced and distributed not by major manufacturers but by a number of small labels<br />

in various countries, and in many instances by the groups themselves. Communication about<br />

the music is carried on among musicians and listeners through a few glossy publications,<br />

numerous ‘fanzines’ produced by enthusiasts of the sub-genres, several websites devoted<br />

to the music, and personal correspondence among band members and their audiences.<br />

Especially useful websites include Dark Legions Archive (www.anus.com/metal), Doommetal.com<br />

(www.doom-metal.com), American Black Metal List (www.usbmlist.cjb.net) and<br />

DarkLyrics.com (www.darklyics.com). Perhaps some rough measure of the popularity of the<br />

sub-genres may be gathered from the following data: Doom-metal.com offers detailed profiles<br />

and discographies of 291 doom metal groups, over 200 of which are currently active; the<br />

American Black Metal List includes entries for 490 black metal groups from the United States<br />

alone; and DarkLyrics archives lyrics by over 1,100 bands, at least 60 per cent of which are<br />

death, doom or black metal bands.


40<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Fundamental to death, doom and black metal, as to all heavy metal music, is<br />

the highly amplified sound of electric guitars, electric basses and drums. The basic<br />

sound is aptly named “heavy metal,” for both words convey something essential<br />

about the music. It is heavy in that it is emphatically percussive, “thick” in texture,<br />

and highly amplified in the lower registers. It is metal in that its sound is dominated<br />

by a particular gamut of high-distortion, low-frequency “grinding,” “crunching”<br />

timbres produced by amplified solid-body electric guitars. The language of timbres,<br />

of course, like the language of tastes or smells, is crude at best, but whether one can<br />

precisely name the sound or not, one can easily discriminate a basic “feel” to the<br />

sound of all death, doom and black metal. What is crucial is that the sub-genres’<br />

core sound bears little relation to any sounds produced by conventional acoustic<br />

instruments, including the guitar. It is decidedly “unnatural,” non-organic, metallic.<br />

If rock ’n’ roll generally depends for its existence on electric industrial technology,<br />

death, doom and black metal take as their fundamental sound that of the electric<br />

guitar treated as an electric industrial machine.<br />

Death, doom and black metal do not imitate the sounds of industrial machines,<br />

but they produce sonic analogs of the sounds, rhythms and patterns of the modern<br />

technological lifeworld. In this sense, death, doom and black metal may be seen as<br />

music that attempts a deterritorialization of the diverse refrains of contemporary<br />

industrial machine culture. But such an observation, besides being rather clichéd<br />

(though nonetheless true, I believe), says little about the music beyond its basic<br />

timbral qualities. If music deterritorializes non-musical refrains, it also reterritorializes<br />

sounds within conventional systems of relations: “it is through a system of melodic<br />

and harmonic coordinates by means of which music reterritorializes upon itself, qua<br />

music” (MP 372/303). Deleuze and Guattari argue that genuine creativity in music<br />

requires not simply a deterritorialization of refrains in the outside world, but also<br />

a deterritorialization of the conventions of standard musical practice, which in the<br />

case of metal music, are those of traditional seventeenth–nineteenth-century Western<br />

tonal harmony and counterpoint. Deleuze and Guattari advocate what they call a<br />

“generalized chromaticism,” a deterritorialization<br />

… affecting not only pitches but all sound components – durations, intensities, timbre,<br />

attacks … By placing all its components in continuous variation, music itself becomes<br />

a superlinear system, a rhizome instead of a tree, and enters the service of a virtual<br />

cosmic continuum of which even holes, silences, ruptures, and breaks are a part. [MP<br />

120–21/95]<br />

Yet they recognize as well that a deterritorialization of all musical components at the<br />

same time leads only to a muddled chaos of white noise: “Sometimes one overdoes it,<br />

puts too much in, works with a jumble of lines and sounds; then instead of producing<br />

a cosmic machine capable of ‘rendering sonorous,’ one lapses back to a machine of<br />

reproduction that ends up reproducing nothing but a scribble effacing all lines, a<br />

scramble effacing all sounds” (MP 424/343–4). All elements of music must be open<br />

to experimentation, but only a selected few may be worked with at a time. What is<br />

needed is “a maximum of calculated sobriety in relation to the disparate elements<br />

and the parameters,” a “sober gesture, an act of consistency, capture, or extraction


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 41<br />

that works in a material that is not meager but prodigiously simplified, creatively<br />

limited, selected” (MP 425–6/344–5). And as Deleuze and Guattari observe of<br />

literary experimentation in Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, innovation may<br />

proceed through proliferation (as in Joyce) but also through ascetic impoverishment<br />

(as in Beckett). Hence, in musical as in literary experimentation, not only does<br />

innovation require a limitation of the elements to be subjected to deterritorialization,<br />

but it also may operate through a deliberately ascetic impoverishment of elements,<br />

an intensification of musical components through their simplification.<br />

Death, doom and black metal explore a deliberately restricted range of possibilities<br />

within heavy metal music, each in its own way. Although the relationship among the<br />

three sub-genres is complex and shifting, perhaps the easiest means of characterizing<br />

them is first to delineate death metal practices and then to approach doom and black<br />

metal as responses to death. 5 One finds in death metal a concerted effort to eliminate<br />

all sweetness, tenderness and niceness from popular music – witness the repeated<br />

description of the sub-genre by its performers and listeners as “extreme” and “brutal”<br />

– and to fashion a music of frenetic speed and constant intensity. The intensity of the<br />

music is conveyed through the sheer volume of the sound, variations in volume level<br />

arising almost exclusively through brief antiphonal exchanges of solo power chords<br />

between guitarists or shifts from chord sections to monophonic sections played in<br />

unison by bass and guitars. The bass generally doubles the guitar motifs, providing<br />

a full low-frequency reinforcement of the guitars’ deep sounds, while the “bite” of<br />

the guitar attack ensures a relatively clear articulation of the rapid figures executed<br />

by the guitarists. The drums emphasize virtually every subdivision within each highspeed<br />

rhythmic motif, the highly amplified double kick-drums frequently delivering<br />

a near sub-sonic punch to each note of the prestissimo bass-guitar figures. The sound<br />

is not simply processed by the ears but also felt in the body (especially the chest), and<br />

though the ears might subordinate elements of a rhythmic motif into accented and<br />

unaccented components, the body feels each element as a distinct percussive event.<br />

The result is a music that is experienced as an unrelenting, high-speed assault of lowfrequency<br />

and mid-range pulses grouped in massive blocks or slabs of sound.<br />

Death’s harmonic palette is quite limited. Major triads are avoided, and even<br />

minor triads tend to be replaced by the open fourths and fifths of power chords.<br />

Motifs generally are based on the intervals of the blues pentatonic scale (E-G-A-<br />

B-D in the key of E), with frequent emphasis given as well to the intervals of the<br />

minor second (E-F) and augmented fourth (E-A#) characteristic of the “exotic”<br />

Phrygian and Locrian modes. There is little genuine harmonic movement in death<br />

compositions; standard blues progressions and even common metal progressions<br />

(for example, C-D-Em in E) give way to tonic-centered sections of monophony or<br />

polyphonic sections based on a single chord or on a repeated alternation of two or<br />

three open fifths that reinforce the tonic within each phrase unit. Death compositions<br />

5 I discuss death metal music at greater length in “Becoming Metal, Becoming Death<br />

…” in Deleuze’s Wake: Tributes and Tributaries (Albany, NY, 2004). Other helpful treatments<br />

of death metal music include Jack Harrell, “The Poetics of Destruction: Death Metal Rock,”<br />

Popular Music and Society, 18 (1994): 91–104, and Harris M. Berger, “Death Metal Tonality<br />

and the Act of Listening,” Popular Music, 18/2 (1999): 161–76.


42<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

are usually organized in discrete sections, each section based on a complex rhythmic<br />

motif. And if a shift in tonality occurs, it coincides with a sectional break, such that<br />

the shift provides little sense of a movement linking one tonal area to another, instead<br />

merely signaling an abrupt break between tonal blocks. The sectional organization<br />

seldom conforms to the standard verse-chorus-bridge structure of popular songs;<br />

rather, section follows section in a paratactic sequence of multiple, loosely related<br />

units, one unit simply being added on to the next. The result of these harmonic and<br />

structural practices is that in death songs a curious stasis pervades the ubiquitous<br />

high-speed motifs. Each section is like a plateau of intense constant energy, with<br />

its own mood (generally minor-modal, sometimes vaguely non-Western), full of<br />

motion but going nowhere in particular, section following section in a series of<br />

discontinuous shifts from one plateau to another, those shifts themselves possessing<br />

no identifiable developmental drive or direction.<br />

Ultimately, this interplay of speed and stasis points toward the presence of two<br />

different kinds of time in death metal, the time of Chronos and that of Aeon, as well<br />

as two different ways of understanding the concept of speed. In A Thousand Plateaus,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari cite Pierre Boulez’s distinction between pulsed and nonpulsed<br />

time in music (MP 320/262), pulsed time being the time of conventional meters and<br />

regular beats, nonpulsed time being the floating, unmarked time exhibited in certain<br />

modern compositions (Boulez’s among them) in which, for example, performers<br />

freely execute motifs within a given duration (say, fifteen seconds) at their own pace,<br />

with no pulse provided by the conductor. Deleuze and Guattari link this distinction<br />

to one drawn often by Messiaen between meter and rhythm. 6 Meter, for Messiaen,<br />

denotes a regular, measured repetition of equal pulses, whereas rhythm is a matter<br />

of incommensurable durations, irregular sequences of unequally spaced pulses. In<br />

Messiaen’s judgment, a march is the least rhythmic form of music, and it is rhythm,<br />

not meter, that he regards as the vital force of musical time. What Deleuze and<br />

Guattari call Chronos, the time of the commonsense, actual world, is a pulsed,<br />

metrical time of regular repeated intervals, whereas Aeon, the time of the virtual, is<br />

a nonpulsed rhythmic time of irregular, incommensurable intervals.<br />

It is on the basis of this distinction between pulsed, metrical Chronos and<br />

nonpulsed, rhythmic Aeon that Deleuze and Guattari make what might at first seem a<br />

paradoxical opposition of movement and speed. Speed, they argue, is not necessarily<br />

a matter of a quantitative measure of movement. Indeed, “a movement may be very<br />

fast, but that does not give it speed; a speed may be very slow, or even immobile,<br />

yet it is still speed. Movement is extensive; speed is intensive” (MP 473/381). To<br />

phrase the distinction somewhat differently, we might say that there is a quantitative<br />

speed of measurable velocities germane to the actual (an “extensive” speed, in that<br />

it belongs to the realm of Cartesian spatiotemporal extension), but that there is also<br />

a qualitative speed that defies measure and opens us to the intensive dimension of<br />

the virtual. Qualitative speed is movement out of control, and it may be encountered<br />

in extremes of mobility and immobility. Deleuze and Guattari suggest the nature<br />

of those extremes in their remarks on Kleist, who gives “time a new rhythm” in<br />

6 For more on Messiaen’s distinction between meter and rhythm, see Bogue, Deleuze<br />

on Music, Painting, and the Arts, p. 25.


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 43<br />

literature. His fiction and drama present “an endless succession of catatonic episodes<br />

or fainting spells, and flashes or rushes. Catatonia is: ‘This affect is too strong for<br />

me,’ and a flash is: ‘The power of this affect sweeps me away,’ so that the Self [Moi]<br />

is now nothing more than a character whose actions and emotions are desubjectified,<br />

perhaps even to the point of death” (MP 440/356). A rush is an acceleration that<br />

runs out of control, catatonia a vertiginous suspension of time, and the two extremes<br />

ultimately shade into one another. Just as the spokes of a wheel, moving faster and<br />

faster as the velocity of the wheel’s rotation increases, at a certain point begin to blur<br />

and form a single, still shape; so acceleration beyond commonsense perception at a<br />

certain point is transformed into a constant, vibrating hum that paradoxically seems<br />

to freeze duration while still participating in a dimension of becoming. In this sense,<br />

every intensive moment of temporal disequilibrium, even a frozen, catatonic stupor,<br />

is a moment of qualitative speed.<br />

Nearly all music involves both meter and rhythm, both pulsed and nonpulsed<br />

time; few compositions dispense entirely with evenly repeated beats and regular<br />

measures. In Deleuze and Guattari’s analysis, this is not surprising, for Chronos<br />

and Aeon, though qualitatively distinct from one another, are only experienced as<br />

tendencies within an inextricable mixture of the two. There is no experience of<br />

chronometric time that does not have at least a tincture of vertiginous becoming<br />

within it, and no experience of a floating, suspended time that does not retain at<br />

least a hint of some regular measure. What varies in music is the handling of meter<br />

and rhythm, pulsed and nonpulsed time, and the relative emphasis placed on each<br />

factor. All rock ’n’ roll has its roots in the regular meters of dance music, and death<br />

metal is no exception. The “givens” of rock ’n’ roll are the standard meters (2/4, 3/4,<br />

4/4, 6/8, 9/8, 12/8) and four-, eight-, twelve-, and sixteen-bar rhythmic groupings of<br />

Western dance forms, and death musicians accept these conventions, attempting in<br />

individual sections of their compositions to exploit a specific rhythmic motif within<br />

a standard meter, imbue it with an emphatic “heaviness,” and render it at a high rate<br />

of quantitative speed. But they also manage to create effects of qualitative speed, and<br />

through several techniques and practices.<br />

As we have already seen, one method is to avoid virtually all harmonic movement<br />

and any developmental organization of sectional units, thereby imparting to each highspeed<br />

unit a concomitant aura of atemporal stasis. A second, less common, technique<br />

is to repeat a hyper-regular figure until it becomes a hypnotic, trance-like drone (a<br />

strategy one meets in minimalists like Philip Glass, as in any number of jam bands).<br />

More important is a third technique of structuring songs in discrete rhythmic blocks<br />

that are connected by no common measure but simply placed in abrupt juxtaposition<br />

to one another. Rather than gradually accelerating or decelerating between sections,<br />

or doubling (or tripling, or halving) the pulse from one section to another, or using a<br />

common pulse to move, say, from a duple to a triple meter – all standard techniques<br />

for relating one metrical unit to another – death musicians frequently change tempo<br />

or meter from brief section to brief section (each section generally lasting between<br />

fifteen and thirty seconds) in such a way that there is no logical relation between<br />

sections, each coexisting with the others as an autonomous temporal unit. What one<br />

encounters in compositions of this sort is a series of self-contained, intensely pulsed<br />

rhythmic units punctuated by a sequence of erratic, spasmodic jolts, fits and starts. If,


44<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

in each discrete section a hyper-Chronos of quantitative speed is manifest, the time<br />

between each section is that of an Aeon of qualitative speed and incommensurable<br />

rhythm. And yet a fourth device, used sparingly but to telling effect, is to accelerate a<br />

rapid duple figure until the individually distinct rhythmic elements of the bass, guitar<br />

and drum parts merge in a nonpulsed tremolo of whirring chaos. In these moments,<br />

quantitative turns into qualitative speed, the previously pulsed units blurring in a<br />

tremolo rush that is at the same time a catatonic skid.<br />

The music of doom metal might be characterized as death metal on Quaaludes,<br />

death slowed to a funereal pace and stretched out in songs lasting sometimes as<br />

long as twenty-five or thirty minutes. The same minor-modal harmonies prevail<br />

in both, as do static chord relations within sections and loose paratactic structures<br />

linking sections to one another. The basic timbres of doom resemble those of death,<br />

and most doom metal, despite its slow pace, is insistently “heavy.” 7 But doom has<br />

a melodic component that is largely absent in death. Even monophonic motifs in<br />

death, despite their linearity, tend to function less as melodies than as percussive<br />

bass lines, whereas in doom the guitars and bass frequently articulate extended<br />

legato lines that conform to standard notions of “tunefulness.” Often the legato lines<br />

are doubled by a violin, flute or female vocalist, instruments and sounds almost<br />

never used in death. The melodies of doom, however, exploit a narrow range of<br />

expressivity, their function being primarily to establish a somber, modal exotic mood<br />

and provide continuity within sections. Doom seeks above all to create atmospheric<br />

auras, to imbue each section with its own “feel” while at the same time maintaining<br />

the heaviness of an emphatically pulsed sound. 8 Doom melodies serve to meld<br />

components within a section and give them a floating, hazy continuity, thereby<br />

creating what Deleuze and Guattari call a “haecceity,” a “thisness,” an atmosphere<br />

like a “season, a winter, a summer, an hour, a date,” with an identity that partakes of<br />

the time of Aeon, “the indefinite time of the event, the floating line that knows only<br />

speeds” (MP 318, 320/261–2). The atmospheric speed sought by doom, ultimately,<br />

7 There is some question among doom listeners as to whether some forms of socalled<br />

“atmospheric doom,” less “heavy” than the norm, even qualify as genuine doom.<br />

John Del Russi of Heirophant, when asked to define doom, comments: “I stand firmly in<br />

my resolution that doom should always maintain the earth-shattering heaviness the likes of<br />

diSEMBOWELMENT, Evoken, Thergothon etc. While there are those who strive to achieve<br />

a more ‘serene’ form of doom, attempting to express purely the sorrowful side, I find it most<br />

lacking in power in the absence of the pulverizing heaviness of the afore-mentioned pioneers<br />

of doom. … While I have no qualms with ‘calmer’ moments throughout the journey of doom,<br />

which genuinely add to the atmospheres of doom, I believe there should be a quality of<br />

‘brutality’ to its composition” .<br />

8 All music, of course, creates some sort of atmosphere, but doom (and black) metal<br />

exploit specific techniques of late-Romantic chromatic programme music and tone poems that<br />

have heavily influenced film scores and become standard elements of suspense and horror<br />

movies. The atmospheres they evoke are hence those typically associated with cinematic<br />

images of foggy landscapes, dark, mysterious spaces, graveyards, haunted houses, and so on,<br />

all conveyed musically through passages with relatively little temporal drive.


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 45<br />

is the qualitative speed of catatonia, the immobile speed of a paradoxically intense<br />

suspended animation.<br />

Black metal comes in two varieties, one fairly close to death, the other with<br />

some similarities to doom. Like doom, black metal shares the timbres, harmonies,<br />

sectional construction and overall organizational structure of death. Much of black<br />

metal, like death, is fast paced, although the range of tempos in black tends to be<br />

broader than that in death. What many black metal bands reject is death’s emphasis<br />

on virtuosity and musicianship. They strive for a messier, grungier sound, something<br />

more chaotic and raw than the precise and intricate percussive complexities of death.<br />

Such groups tend to emphasize a rhythmic figure at greater length and change tempo<br />

less frequently than do death bands, and they often replace death’s quick monophonic<br />

lines with rapid flat-pick reiterations of massive, muddy triads. One extreme of black<br />

metal, then, might be very loosely designated grunge death (Burzum and Mayhem<br />

being examples of this strain). The other extreme might be thought of as fast doom.<br />

In this form of black metal, legato melodies executed by a violin, flute or organ<br />

often lend continuity to a high-tempo section, and at times synthesizers are used to<br />

provide a vaguely choral, sustained harmonic “wash” to a section (early Emperor<br />

provides numerous examples of this latter practice). But what is common to all black<br />

metal is a concentration on mood and atmosphere. Many black metal musicians<br />

dress in black robes and wear exaggerated white-and-black “corpsepaint” on their<br />

faces, and though such practices are strictly extra-musical, they point to the basically<br />

ritual and theatrical conception of black metal music, which is meant to evoke vague<br />

auras, climates and affective settings. Like doom, black metal seeks to elicit the<br />

floating time of a catatonic Aeon, while simultaneously, like death, it pursues both<br />

quantitative speed and the qualitative speed of a hyper-accelerated rush.<br />

Voice, Words and Action<br />

In a special issue of Guitar Presents, Marc Shapiro characterizes death metal with<br />

what he calls a fairly simple equation: “It’s guitar tuned down so low that only dogs<br />

can hear it. It’s songs about the Devil, revenge from the grave, death by garden tools<br />

and other tales from the dark side delivered, for the most part, in a Linda Blair/<br />

Exorcist-like satanic growl.” 9 The satanic growl is indeed a distinctive feature of<br />

much death metal, and many doom and black vocalists adopt the same low-pitched,<br />

guttural, raspy, bark of death. Some black metal vocalists opt for incessant fullvoiced<br />

or high-pitched screams over the death growl, and doom performers often<br />

combine growls, screams and grunts with deep murmurs and slow whispers. But<br />

what is common to most death, doom and black metal is the anti-melodic, nonnatural<br />

treatment of the voice (though so-called “clean” vocals have been gradually<br />

showing up in a few groups over the last decade). If, as Deleuze and Guattari assert,<br />

“the first musical operation” is “to machine the voice” (MP 373/303), that is, to<br />

deterritorialize the voice from its ordinary, “natural” speaking function, then death,<br />

9 Marc Shapiro, “The Birth of Death: A Speed Demonology,” Guitar Presents: Speed<br />

Demons of Metal (1993), p. 8.


46<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

doom and black vocalists are fundamentally – indeed, primally – musical in their<br />

anti-lyrical non-singing, in that their growls, screams and grunts simply push music’s<br />

de-naturalization of the speaking voice to extremes (which most listeners hostile to<br />

the sub-genres would deem beyond the limits of the musical).<br />

Though death, doom and black vocalists articulate words, seldom are the words<br />

readily understandable, especially in live performance, and even in the slowest<br />

tempos of doom. The most important function of the vocals is to provide a broadly<br />

affective, percussive reinforcement of accents and phrases, to fuse vocal noises with<br />

the instrumental sounds and create semi-human, semi-machine, blocks of sound.<br />

Nonetheless, lyrics do exist (most groups provide lyrics sheets with their CDs),<br />

and they have an important musical purpose. As Shapiro suggests, death lyrics tend<br />

to focus on the dark side, the grave, corporeal decay and physical violence. These<br />

staples of horror films are common in black metal as well, with satanic themes being<br />

somewhat more prevalent in black than in death. Doom lyrics often offer sepulchral<br />

expressions of Poe-esque Liebestod (My Dying Bride’s lyrics read largely as an<br />

extended explication of the group’s name), though frequently doom bands simply<br />

voice melancholy sentiments of vague despair and hopelessness (November’s Doom<br />

is one such group). Although the lyrics of the three sub-genres often summon up<br />

dramatic tableaus, they seldom offer plots or stories, for their main purpose is to<br />

evoke emotions, moods and attitudes through highly charged images, raw, profane<br />

diction, and diverse first-person expressions of anti-social desire. In Section Four<br />

of A Thousand Plateaus, “Postulates of Linguistics,” Deleuze and Guattari argue<br />

that words do not represent things so much as they intervene in things, performing<br />

“incorporeal transformations” of bodies through speech-actions (MP 110/86).<br />

Similarly, death, doom and black lyrics intervene in the music, providing an<br />

affective specificity to what is only vaguely generated by the music. There is no<br />

inherently evil, violent, or even aggressive music (loud, yes, assertive, perhaps, but<br />

not inherently aggressive), and what the lyrics attempt is to narrow the sound’s range<br />

of affective associations, imbue the music with more precisely delineated moods<br />

grounded in concrete situations – situations, it happens, that frequently involve evil,<br />

violence and aggression.<br />

Not all songs dwell on violence and mayhem, however. Doom lyrics as a whole<br />

tend to involve violence less than do those of death and black, and even within death<br />

and black there are wide variations in the frequency and intensity of violence in the<br />

lyrics. Satanic motifs are not uncommon in death and black lyrics, but they are far<br />

from ubiquitous, and often such motifs evidence less an obsession with evil than<br />

a fascination with non-Christian, broadly pagan sensibilities, a fascination shared<br />

with bands that draw themes and imagery for their songs from Norse mythology<br />

(Emperor, among many Scandinavian groups), Babylonian mythology (Morbid<br />

Angel), or Egyptian mythology (Nile). It is clear, then, that there is no inherent<br />

relation between the music and the lyrics, that the manifest continuities in musical<br />

practices across the sub-genres do not have equally consistent continuities in the<br />

handling of lyrics. Yet when lyricists do choose to focus on violence and mayhem,<br />

one may well ask why. In such cases, if the music is not inherently violent or<br />

evil, has it been co-opted for violent or evil purposes? The difficulties of relating<br />

representations of violence (especially in film, fiction, or art) to actual violence are


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 47<br />

well-known, and they are no less problematic in the case of death, doom and black<br />

metal music. Clearly, much of the impetus behind the sub-genres’ lyrics is to shock<br />

and offend – to offend fundamentalist Christians with Satanic hymns, to offend<br />

liberals with sexist profanities, to offend just about everyone with descriptions of<br />

putrefying flesh, evisceration, blood and gore. Often, the lyrics seem to function<br />

merely as the expression of a defiant anarchistic hedonism or the cathartic release<br />

of strong emotion. Occasionally, the performers adopt a mimetic stance and argue<br />

that they are not advocating violence but simply reflecting the violence around them<br />

in their songs. And frequently one detects an ironic, and at times parodic, sense of<br />

humor in the excesses of the imagery and the exaggerated postures of the songs’<br />

personas (not unlike the humor one finds in many horror films).<br />

All of which suggests, not that art is separate from life, but that the connection<br />

between the two is complex and determinable only in specific circumstances.<br />

Representations of violence need have no relation to violent actions, but they may,<br />

though specifying causal relations must be approached with great caution and may<br />

well prove impossible. Consider the notorious case of the Norwegian black metal<br />

scene in the late 1980s and early 1990s, documented at length in Moynihan and<br />

Søderlind’s sometimes lurid Lords of Chaos: The Bloody Rise of the Satanic Metal<br />

Underground. 10 Here are the facts. On April 8, 1991, the lead singer of Mayhem,<br />

“Dead” (Per Ohlin), committed suicide with a shotgun blast to the head. Before<br />

the police arrived, “Euronymous” (Øystein Aarseth), Mayhem’s founder and lead<br />

guitarist, photographed Dead’s corpse, later bragging that he also ate pieces of<br />

Dead’s brain and gathered scraps of Dead’s skull to use as necklace decorations. In<br />

May 1992, the first of some forty-five to sixty church burnings took place, most of<br />

the subsequent incidents occurring over a three-year period, at least one-third with<br />

documented connections to the black metal scene. On August 21, 1992, “Faust”<br />

(Bård Eithun), then drummer of Emperor, murdered Magne Andreassen, a gay man<br />

who, according to Faust, approached him for sex. On August 10, 1993, “Count<br />

Grishnackh” (Varg Vikernes), guitarist of Burzum, murdered Euronymous. Later<br />

that month, Grishnackh and Faust were arrested for their respective murders. In<br />

September 1994, both were found guilty; Grishnackh was sentenced to twenty-one<br />

years in prison, Faust to a fourteen-year term. In subsequent trials, other black metal<br />

scene members were convicted of arson, including Samoth, Emperor’s lead guitarist,<br />

who received a two-year sentence.<br />

10 I am not able to address here the question of Norwegian black metal’s connection<br />

to Nazism. Since his incarceration in 1994, Varg Vikernes (Count Grishnackh) has issued<br />

statements of an increasingly racist, white-supremacist nature that have led some to associate<br />

Norwegian black metal and black metal as a whole with Nazism. In the liner notes to their<br />

1995 release, Panzerfaust, Darkthrone felt compelled to add a postscript that “Darkthrone<br />

is certainly not a Nazi-band nor a political band.” Although black metal bands with Nazi<br />

leanings do exist, they are relatively few, and many black metal fans resent the assumption<br />

among some critics that the music has an inherent tie to Nazism. For a critique of black<br />

metal as a racist form of music (an attack based largely on Vikernes’ remarks in Moynihan<br />

and Søderlind, it should be noted), see Karl Beckwith, “‘Black Metal Music is for White<br />

People’: Constructs of Colour and Identity with the Extreme Metal Scene,” M/C Journal,<br />

(2002).


48<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

What is evident from Moynihan and Søderlind’s account is that during this<br />

period in Oslo, black metal music was an important part of a genuine “scene,” a<br />

multidimensional social milieu in which musicians lived with one another, performers<br />

and fans socialized with one another at concerts and especially at Euronymous’<br />

record store, Helvet, and participants embraced modes of dress, discourse and<br />

interaction commonly associated with evil, death, the demonic and other dark<br />

forces. Euronymous was a charismatic promoter, recording and distributing CDs<br />

of various black metal bands, cleverly boosting Norwegian black metal in fanzine<br />

interviews that stressed the evil, dangerous nature of the music and of the performers<br />

(especially himself). Grishnackh, Euronymous’s junior by six years, was an equally<br />

charismatic, forceful individual, and the two of them became friends for awhile,<br />

eventually assembling around themselves a conspiratorial group of arsonists intent<br />

on demonstrating to each other how evil they could be. Grishnackh clearly resented<br />

Euronymous’s popularity and eventually came to regard Euronymous as a poseur<br />

(as well as a dishonest business associate). When Grishnackh learned that Faust<br />

had killed someone, he seemed to envy Faust’s status as a murderer, and some of<br />

Grishnackh’s associates attribute his slaying of Euronymous as much to a desire for<br />

renown among his peers as to personal and professional animosities.<br />

To deny that black metal music had any connection with the Norwegian black<br />

metal scene and its incidents of arson and murder would be foolish. But to claim<br />

that the music or the lyrics somehow caused the crimes would be equally absurd. A<br />

unique culture involving a shifting network of individuals with a host of interests,<br />

motives and desires took shape in a particular place and time, and music was an<br />

inextricable component of that culture. In Deleuze and Guattari’s ethological terms,<br />

black metal functioned as a complex of refrains in counterpoint with numerous extramusical<br />

refrains in a specific social and natural lifeworld. Just as a bird’s song may<br />

combine with postures, actions and surrounding materials (trees, twigs, worms, and<br />

so on) in patterns involved in mating, nesting, or foraging, so black metal combined<br />

with other elements to form patterns of interaction that eventually involved, among<br />

other things, arson and murder.<br />

That music can be a powerful accompaniment to violent behavior is undeniable,<br />

but the range of forms of musical expression capable of fulfilling such a role seems<br />

unlimited. (One thinks, for example, of “Helter Skelter” among the Manson family,<br />

but also of Schubert in the Nazi death camps.) Conversely, there seems to be no hard<br />

evidence that any form of music is more closely associated with violent action than<br />

any other. Black metal music was an important part of the lives of Norway’s black<br />

metal arsonists and murderers, but neither black metal as a whole, nor the related<br />

forms of death and doom metal, have been shown to have a higher incidence of<br />

suicide, assault or murder among the sub-genres’ performers or listeners than other<br />

forms of popular music. Still, one may ask, why do death, doom and black metal<br />

lyrics focus so often on gore, decay, corpses and destruction? Why this pervasive<br />

fascination with death?<br />

The answer, I believe, is that the lyrics are designed to evoke what the music<br />

seeks to create: the experience of the body without organs. In Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze<br />

and Guattari describe the body without organs as a decentered body that has ceased<br />

to function as a coherently regulated organism, one that is sensed as an ecstatic,


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 49<br />

catatonic, apersonal zero-degree of intensity that is in no way negative but has a<br />

positive existence. They argue that “the body without organs is the model of death”<br />

(AO 393/329), by which they mean that the ecstatic trance-like state of this zerodegree<br />

of intensity is the experiential analog of what is never truly experienced, at<br />

least as part of one’s ongoing being, but is sensed only as the disappearing edge of<br />

existence. Hence the human fascination with death, so widespread and multifarious in<br />

its manifestations, may be seen from this vantage as an affirmation of a fundamental<br />

dimension of experience, that of the virtual, which is encountered as a paradoxical<br />

catatonic rush or immobile whir of differential speeds and intensive affects. But<br />

Deleuze and Guattari recognize as well that there are great risks and perils in the<br />

pursuit of a body without organs, and thus in A Thousand Plateaus they speak of<br />

both a suicidal and a cancerous body without organs, each with its specific dangers.<br />

Individuals produce a body without organs by becoming-other, by deterritorializing<br />

all the ossified, sedimented strata of regular codes and structures, but if “you free<br />

[the body without organs] with too violent an action, if you blow apart the strata<br />

without taking precautions, then instead of drawing the plane [of consistency] you<br />

will be killed, plunged into a black hole, or even dragged toward catastrophe” (MP<br />

199/161). In short, the fascination with the “model of death,” the body without<br />

organs, may become a fascination with real death, a suicidal dive into an all-absorbent<br />

black hole. The cancerous body without organs, by contrast, is produced not by an<br />

incautious, precipitous deterritorialization of all coordinates, but by a fostering of<br />

partial, “totalitarian,” or “fascist” deterritorializations that are “terrifying caricatures<br />

of the plane of consistency” (MP 201/163). The virtual is immanent and everywhere<br />

manifest within the real, and hence the plane of consistency, or the body without<br />

organs, is immanent within even the most rigid and oppressive of institutions. There<br />

is thus a “BwO [body without organs] of money (inflation), but also a BwO of the<br />

State, army, factory, city, Party, etc.” (MP 201/163), and each of these bodies without<br />

organs may become an object of fascination for the individual, a kind of tumor that<br />

may proliferate and eventually take over. Deleuze and Guattari see the production of<br />

a body without organs as the only means of genuine creation, but they ask, “How can<br />

we fabricate a BwO for ourselves without its being the cancerous BwO of a fascist<br />

inside us, or the empty BwO of a drug addict, paranoiac, or hypochondriac? How<br />

can we tell the three Bodies apart?” (MP 202/163).<br />

Death, doom and black metal’s fascination with death, one might say, is a<br />

fascination with the problem of the three bodies without organs, with the liminal<br />

areas where the three shade into one another. “The BwO is desire,” say Deleuze and<br />

Guattari:<br />

Even when it falls into the void of too-sudden destratification, or into the proliferation<br />

of a cancerous stratum, it is still desire. Desire stretches that far: desiring one’s own<br />

annihilation, or desiring the power to annihilate. Money, army, police, and State desire,<br />

fascist desire, even fascism is desire. [And the problem is] to distinguish the BwO from<br />

its doubles: empty vitreous bodies, cancerous bodies, totalitarian and fascist. [MP 203–<br />

204/165]


50<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

The pursuit of an ecstatic, apersonal affective intensity can all too easily turn into a<br />

thirst for self-annihilation or a will to annihilate, and death, doom and black metal<br />

lyrics explore those moments when such desires interpenetrate.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari also say that the body without organs may function as<br />

a “war machine,” and here especially we see highlighted the dangerous relation<br />

deterritorialization may have with violence. Deleuze and Guattari posit a fundamental<br />

opposition between nomadic and sedentary modes of social life, to which correspond<br />

respectively the institutions of the war machine and the apparatus of the state.<br />

Commonly, war is taken to be a state function, but Deleuze and Guattari argue that<br />

the informing principle of war, that of a mutative, chaotic force of transformation<br />

(and this is what they mean by the term “war machine”), is antithetical to the state,<br />

and that the history of state-sponsored violence is one of an uneasy and perpetually<br />

unstable capture of this force of transformation. They note that in Indo-European<br />

mythology the warrior frequently is contrasted with such state figures as the king,<br />

lawgiver, or priest, the warrior often betraying social alliances and operating<br />

as an anarchic locus of unpredictable action. They see this mythic opposition of<br />

warrior versus king/lawgiver/priest as symptomatic of an opposition of two modes<br />

of existence, each with its own means of creating, inhabiting and propagating a<br />

specific “space,” one “smooth,” the other “striated.” Smooth space is essentially<br />

fluid, heterogeneous, without center or dimensional coordinates, whereas striated<br />

space is stable, homogeneous and crisscrossed with organizational grids. The<br />

nomads’ smooth habitat of shifting desert sands, for example, differs qualitatively<br />

from the striated fields of the sedentary state dwellers. Yet this contrast of smooth<br />

and striated spaces, though initially framed in geographic terms, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari extend in a number of ways, to include different artifacts (felt vs fabric),<br />

different kinds of time (unpulsed rhythm vs pulsed meter), different forms of thought<br />

(nomad science vs royal science, fractal geometry vs Euclidean geometry), different<br />

approaches to the arts (Egyptian, Gothic or Byzantine art vs Greco-Roman art) and<br />

so on. Ultimately, the “war machine” is simply a term for the metamorphic force of<br />

deterritorialization, and “smooth space” the name of the body without organs, or<br />

plane of consistency, created and permeated by that metamorphic force. As Deleuze<br />

explains in an interview on A Thousand Plateaus:<br />

We define the “war machine” as a linear assemblage which constructs itself on lines of<br />

flight. In this sense, the war machine does not at all have war as its object; it has as its<br />

object a very special space, smooth space, which it composes, occupies and propagates.<br />

Nomadism is precisely this combination “war machine-smooth space.” We try to show<br />

how and in what case the war machine takes war for its object (when the apparatuses of<br />

the State appropriate the war machine which does not initially belong to them). A war<br />

machine tends to be revolutionary, or artistic, much more so than military. [PP 50–51/33]<br />

The war machine does not have war as its object, yet still it is called the war machine,<br />

and though its function is primarily revolutionary or artistic, its name is inseparable<br />

from a military domain. What Deleuze and Guattari reinforce through this term is<br />

the problematic relation between deterritorializing metamorphosis and violence,<br />

which, as we have seen, they also frame in terms of the body without organs and its<br />

dangerous doubles, the suicidal and cancerous bodies without organs. The dangers


Violence in Three Shades of Metal: Death, Doom and Black 51<br />

of constructing a body without organs are dangers of violence, risks that a creative,<br />

metamorphic war machine will turn into a veritable machine of war, a negative force<br />

bent solely on destruction. It is striking how frequently images of war, especially of<br />

an apocalyptic sort, appear in the lyrics of death and black metal (and occasionally<br />

doom as well). Often the persona in death and black metal songs adopts the pose of<br />

a warrior and espouses an ethos of unrestrained destruction. The warriors imagined<br />

in these songs, however, are not representatives of an organized military regime<br />

but embodiments of an anarchic force of chaos. They inhabit a space outside the<br />

regular order of any state apparatus and serve as mythic figures of a dimension of<br />

unrestrained social upheaval. What this recurring imagery of warriors, battlefields<br />

and Armageddon suggests, finally, is that the music of death, doom and black metal<br />

is a war machine ever becoming machine of war, a machine of war perpetually<br />

turning back into a war machine, a music focused on the perilous relation between<br />

ecstatic deterritorialization and suicidal or fascistic annihilation.<br />

Music “is never tragic, music is joy,” Deleuze and Guattari claim, yet there are<br />

times when music “necessarily gives us a taste for death … Music has a thirst for<br />

destruction, every kind of destruction, extinction, breakage, dislocation. Is that not<br />

its potential ‘fascism’?” (MP 367–68/299). This thirst for destruction Deleuze and<br />

Guattari tie to music’s power as a deterritorializing force. Compared to painting,<br />

music “seems to have a much stronger deterritorializing force, at once more intense<br />

and much more collective,” which perhaps explains “the collective fascination<br />

exerted by music, and even the potentiality of the ‘fascist’ danger we mentioned<br />

a little earlier: music (drums, trumpets) draws people and armies into a race that<br />

can go all the way to the abyss” (MP 371/302). Music, one might say, is at once<br />

more abstract and more elemental than painting. As Deleuze remarks in Francis<br />

Bacon, music indeed “deeply traverses our bodies, and puts an ear in our belly, in our<br />

lungs, etc.,” but ultimately it “rids bodies of their inertia, of the materiality of their<br />

presence. It disincarnates bodies” (FB 38/47). In turn, through the manipulation<br />

of its sonic matter, it “gives the most mental [spirituelles] entities a disincarnated,<br />

dematerialized body” (FB 38/47). Music, in short, through its heightened and yet<br />

somehow dispersed, intangible sensuality, has the power of undoing the coordinates<br />

of the commonsense world and creating a sonic body of speeds and affective<br />

intensities, that sonic body traversing listeners and turning their organized, material<br />

bodies into dematerialized vectors spread out across an apersonal, trans-individual<br />

body without organs. But in music’s great power as a deterritorializing force lies its<br />

danger. Its dissolution of codes, structures and conventions can expand, accelerate<br />

and form part of an undifferentiated will to annihilation and destruction. And its<br />

abstract, dematerializing affectivity can be channeled into any number of violent,<br />

repressive and reactionary circuits of power.<br />

Like all forms of music, death, doom and black metal are modes of<br />

experimentation on the real. Their timbres, rhythms and textures are sonic analogs of<br />

the patterns and processes of contemporary electronic, industrial, machine culture.<br />

Their deterritorialization of such extra-musical refrains, however, takes place within<br />

a musical deterritorialization of popular music conventions, those conventions<br />

themselves functioning as refrains within the real. By deliberately adopting a limited<br />

musical idiom and pushing its elements to an extreme, death, doom and black metal


52<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

develop inventive deformations of standard popular music practices, concentrating<br />

especially on timbre and rhythm rather than melody and harmony. Death metal seeks<br />

a music of intensity and speed, both a quantitative speed of emphatic rapid pulses<br />

and a qualitative speed of rushes and catatonic whirs. Doom pursues a music of<br />

atmospheric auras, at once immobile and yet heavily pulsed, whereas black combines<br />

elements of death and doom to fashion raw blocks of atmospheric speed. The lyrics<br />

of death, doom and black metal intervene in the music, suggesting specific moods,<br />

emotions and attitudes as correlates of the broad and underdetermined affective<br />

dimension of the sounds. The lyrics in various ways evoke the experience of the body<br />

without organs, especially in its liminal forms in which the positive, creative body<br />

without organs merges with its violent suicidal or cancerous caricatures. The songs<br />

of death, doom and black metal are composed, performed, recorded, circulated and<br />

enjoyed within complex, multidimensional social situations, and those songs may<br />

or may not serve as refrains in counterpoint with extra-musical refrains involving<br />

violent action.<br />

The final ethical measure of any music is its ability to create new possibilities<br />

for life, and such is the measure that must be applied to an assessment of the social<br />

practices within which death, doom and black metal music and lyrics are given<br />

concrete actualization. Neither wholesale condemnation nor blanket approval of the<br />

sub-genres is called for, but instead a careful delineation of their musical, verbal and<br />

pragmatic methods and purposes, as well as an appraisal of their function within<br />

particular contexts. Deleuze and Guattari’s concepts of the refrain, deterritorialization<br />

and reterritorialization, the body without organs, speeds and intensities, haecceities,<br />

and so on, provide us with significant tools for undertaking such an analysis.


Chapter 4<br />

Search, Swim and See<br />

Deleuze’s Apprenticeship in Signs<br />

and Pedagogy of Images<br />

Deleuze was a remarkable polymath, capable of bringing penetrating insights to a<br />

wide variety of disciplines. The number of topics addressed during his career was<br />

considerable, ranging from mathematics, biology, psychology, political science and<br />

anthropology to logic, ethics, painting, literature, metallurgy and the decorative<br />

arts. One might assume that as a lifelong academic Deleuze would have turned his<br />

attention to the subject of education with some frequency, but in fact he dedicated<br />

only a small portion of his energies to this field. He did, however, devote a few<br />

passages of Difference and Repetition (1969) to the relationship between thought<br />

and learning that are especially suggestive. These passages summarize the salient<br />

points he had developed in his 1964 study Proust and Signs, in which he approached<br />

Proust’s massive A la recherche du temps perdu as an extended apprenticeship in the<br />

explication of signs. The question of teaching and its relationship to learning he left<br />

largely unexamined in these two works, but in Cinema 2: The Time-Image (1985),<br />

Deleuze spoke briefly of a “pedagogy” of images in the films of Godard, and from<br />

these remarks on Godard’s treatment of sound and sight one can discern the outlines<br />

of what might constitute a Deleuzian theory of teaching. Taken together, Deleuze’s<br />

studies of learning in Proust and teaching in Godard provide a map of directions one<br />

might pursue in developing a Deleuzian philosophy of education.<br />

Searching<br />

Proust’s Recherche, as its French title indicates, is a search for lost time, but Deleuze<br />

insists that this search is oriented toward the future rather than the past. Marcel, the<br />

hero of the Recherche, indeed explores memories of the past, but only as part of an<br />

apprenticeship that eventuates in his becoming an artist. His exploration of lost time<br />

is merely part of a search for the truth of time, which is one with the truth of signs.<br />

Signs for Deleuze are not transparent media for the communication of information.<br />

Rather, they are hieroglyphs, enigmas that point beyond themselves to something<br />

hidden. In this sense, the moon as sign is a bright surface gesturing toward its dark<br />

side. Every sign has something enfolded within it, something “other,” that must be<br />

unfolded if it is to be understood. The interpretation of signs, then, is a matter of<br />

“explicating,” or unfolding (from Latin plicare: to fold), that which is “implicated,”<br />

or enfolded.


54<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Deleuze identifies four kinds of signs in the Recherche: the worldly signs of<br />

polite society, the amorous signs of passion and jealousy, the evanescent sensual<br />

signs of involuntary memory, and the immaterial signs of art. Worldly signs are<br />

vacuous, with no genuine content, but they force Marcel to unfold their mysteries,<br />

to determine why one person is admitted to a given social circle, why another is<br />

snubbed, who belongs to which milieu, what constitutes the tone and relative prestige<br />

of a particular coterie, and so on. Amorous signs point toward the worlds hidden in<br />

the beloved, toward all those places the beloved inhabits when the lover is absent.<br />

The truth of these signs is revealed through jealousy, which compels the lover to<br />

unfold the mysteries of the worlds which are enfolded in the beloved and from which<br />

the lover is forever excluded. The sensual signs of involuntary memory are like<br />

the madeleine, whose taste suddenly fills Marcel with great joy as the unexpected<br />

presence of the Combray of his childhood comes over him. Such signs Marcel<br />

compares to tiny pieces of Japanese paper that, when placed in water, unfold and<br />

expand to reveal hidden landscapes imprinted on their surfaces. As Marcel observes<br />

of the savor of the madeleine he has just dipped in his lime tea, “in a moment all the<br />

flowers in our garden and in M. Swann’s park, and the water-lilies on the Vivonne<br />

and the good folk of the village and their little dwellings and the parish church and<br />

the whole of Combray and its surroundings, taking shape and solidity, sprang into<br />

being, towns and gardens alike, from my cup of tea.” 1 The signs of art, finally, are<br />

signs of essences, manifestations of originary worlds that unfold within the material<br />

form of a given artwork but transcend that matter and reveal the truth of the cosmos<br />

as a dynamic process of self-differentiation.<br />

Deleuze reads the Recherche as the record of an apprenticeship (apprentissage<br />

in French), or process of learning (French apprendre: to learn), and all learning, he<br />

asserts, proceeds via the interpretation of signs: “Everything that teaches us something<br />

emits signs; every act of learning is an interpretation of signs or hieroglyphs. Proust’s<br />

work is based not on the exposition of memory, but on the apprenticeship in signs”<br />

(PS 11/4). By “learning” Deleuze clearly does not mean the mere acquisition of any<br />

new skill or bit of information, but instead the accession to a new way of perceiving<br />

and understanding the world. To interpret signs is to overcome “stock notions,”<br />

“natural” or “habitual” modes of comprehending reality (PS 37/27). What often<br />

passes for learning is simply the reinforcement of commonsense notions, standard<br />

codes and orthodox beliefs. But the commonsense, conventional, orthodox world is<br />

ultimately illusory. Genuine learning, the learning through signs, takes us beyond the<br />

illusions of habit and common sense to the truths of what Proust calls “essences” and<br />

Deleuze labels “differences.”<br />

The usual assumption is that thought voluntarily seeks truth through the exercise<br />

of “good will,” but what Proust shows is that the search for truth always commences<br />

with a disruptive event that compels thought into action. Philosophy’s mistake, says<br />

Deleuze, “is to presuppose within us a benevolence of thought [une bonne volonté de<br />

penser], a natural love of truth” (PS 24/16). The ideas of the philosophical intelligence<br />

“are valid only because of their explicit, hence, conventional, signification,” and<br />

1 Marcel Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, trans. C.K. Moncrieff and Terence<br />

Kilmartin (New York, 1982), vol. 1, p. 51.


Search, Swim and See 55<br />

“explicit and conventional significations are never profound; the only profound<br />

meaning is the one that is enveloped, implicated in an external sign” (PS 24/16).<br />

Philosophy’s intellectual truths are “abstract and conventional” (PS 41/30) whereas<br />

the truths of signs are “fortuitous and inevitable” (PS 25/16). Only through a chance<br />

encounter with an unsettling sign can thought be jolted from its routine patterns,<br />

and only through such an encounter will the object of thought cease to be arbitrarily<br />

selected and attain the necessity of something that itself chooses thought, that<br />

constrains thought and sets it in motion.<br />

Common sense organizes the world according to fixed identities and stable<br />

spatial and temporal coordinates, but for Proust and Deleuze the dynamic unfolding<br />

of the world is a process that escapes common sense and defies its set categories.<br />

That process is a ceaseless becoming in which things perpetually metamorphose<br />

into something else and thereby elude identification and specification, but it is also<br />

one informed by a virtual domain of “essences” or “differences” that are, in Proust’s<br />

words, “real without being actual, ideal without being abstract.” 2 It is through signs<br />

that Marcel learns the truth of essences, and that truth is disclosed initially through<br />

revelations of the different forms of time related to each kind of sign.<br />

Worldly signs exhibit the “lost time” of frivolous activity, inevitable decline and<br />

universal alteration and annihilation. Amorous signs reveal another type of “lost<br />

time,” that of “wasted time” [le temps qu’on perd, literally, “the time one loses”]<br />

(PS 30/21), a time of deception and disappointment which can only be absorbed in<br />

retrospect, after the love relationship has come to an end. To an extent, such forms<br />

of “lost time” may be accommodated within traditional temporal schemas, but not so<br />

the time that emerges in the sensual signs of involuntary memory. The time evoked<br />

through the madeleine, the uneven paving stones of Venice, and other such sensual<br />

signs is “time regained” [le temps qu’on retrouve, literally “the time one finds again”],<br />

which in Deleuze’s reading is a version of the time of Henri Bergson’s virtual past. 3<br />

Bergson argues that a memory is not simply a faded or less complex version of an<br />

experience that once was present, but something that is qualitatively distinct from<br />

any present experience. The past is a single domain in which all past events coexist<br />

with one another. This domain is real, though it is virtual rather than actual. At each<br />

present moment, time splits in two, into a dynamic actual present thrusting toward<br />

a future, and a “memory of the present,” a virtual double of the present moment<br />

(something like a virtual mirror image of the present) that immediately forms part of<br />

the single domain of all past events. According to Bergson, when we try to remember<br />

something we leap into the virtual past as if entering a different medium. Once we<br />

find the memory we are seeking, we bring it back into the present, but usually in<br />

such a way that the memory is made to fit in with our actual, commonsense purposes<br />

and activities. As a result, the virtual character of the memory tends to escape our<br />

awareness. Only in dreams, moments of déjà-vu and other unusual experiences are<br />

we able to perceive the virtual past as it exists in itself.<br />

2 Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, vol. 3, pp. 905–906.<br />

3 For a detailed discussion of Bergson’s virtual past, see Chapter Three of Deleuze’s<br />

Bergsonism (B 45–70/51–72).


56<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Deleuze insists that Proust’s moments of involuntary memory are not mere<br />

reminiscences but experiences that disclose such a Bergsonian virtual past. In the case<br />

of the madeleine, a common quality – the taste of the madeleine – links a present and<br />

a past moment, but in such a way that an “essence of Combray” is released, a virtual<br />

Combray that has never been present, save as a virtual “memory of the present.” The<br />

great joy that fills Marcel comes from this sudden chance encounter with what Proust<br />

calls “a fragment of time in the pure state,” 4 time outside the ordinary coordinates<br />

of temporal succession. Yet Marcel’s accession to the virtual past teaches more than<br />

a simple lesson about time, Deleuze insists, for in the experience of the madeleine<br />

Marcel encounters “internalized difference, which becomes immanent” (PS 75/60).<br />

The virtual Combray is embodied in the taste of the madeleine, made internal to that<br />

taste, immanent within it, and in this sense the madeleine internalizes something<br />

different, but that virtual Combray itself is an unfolding difference, an entity whose<br />

paradoxical kind of time is merely one aspect of its being as essence.<br />

It is only in the signs of art that Marcel learns the full truth of essences and<br />

their relationship to time. The time of art is “recovered time” [le temps retrouvé,<br />

literally “time found again,” the title of the last volume of the Recherche] (PS 34/24).<br />

Recovered time is the pure form of time, an unspecified temporal medium within<br />

which various temporal experiences may be actualized. Its time is like that of the<br />

verbal infinitive – “to work,” “to sleep,” “to dream” – a floating time unmoored<br />

from any tense, person, mood, or direction, an essence of temporality that serves<br />

as a generative medium from which different specific temporal configurations may<br />

issue (“I had worked,” “she was to have slept,” “we will have been dreaming,” etc.).<br />

Such time, says Deleuze, is “complicated” (PS 58/45), a term he takes from certain<br />

Neoplatonic philosophers who speak of the cosmos as an enfolded, implicated One<br />

that unfolds, or explicates itself in the multiple, the originary state of which, before<br />

any explication, is a “complication, which envelops the many in the One and affirms<br />

the unity of the multiple” (PS 58/45). The time of art is a pure essence of time,<br />

a perpetual origin of time, as if with each work of art the world were once again<br />

coming into being for the first time.<br />

The time of art, however, is only one dimension of essences, which are enfolded<br />

virtual differences that unfold themselves in the actual world. To a certain extent<br />

Proust is Leibnizian, Deleuze claims, in that “essences are veritable monads, each<br />

defined by the viewpoint to which it expresses the world” (PS 55/41). Leibniz’s logic<br />

of “expression” is one of explication and implication, the whole expressing itself by<br />

unfolding itself in individual monads, each monad in turn expressing the whole by<br />

enfolding the whole as a specific vantage on that totality. In this sense, the world<br />

is like a city (to take a Leibnizian figure), which unfolds itself in particular places,<br />

each place enfolding the city from a given point of view. Yet in Proust there is no<br />

pre-established harmony coordinating all points of view, and hence each monad-site<br />

reveals a different city. And each such city is the expression of “difference itself, the<br />

absolute internal difference” (PS 55/42). What Deleuze means by absolute internal<br />

difference is perhaps best understood through the example of a single-cell ovum,<br />

which I presented in Chapter 1. Before fertilization, the ovum is crisscrossed by<br />

4 Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, vol. 3, p. 905.


Search, Swim and See 57<br />

multiple gradients, zones of surface tension and lines of possible division. Of these<br />

virtual lines of potential division only one becomes actualized upon fertilization.<br />

At that point, a process of differentiation begins, whereby the one cell splits into<br />

two. Rather than regarding this process of meiosis as the mechanical construction<br />

of a preformed whole, Deleuze sees it as the unfolding of an internal difference that<br />

differentiates itself in an ongoing cascade of divisions. As the one cell divides into<br />

two, a process of individuation takes place, but the individuals formed – the two<br />

cells – are the result of the process, not its cause. Individuation precedes individuals,<br />

and individuation is a process of metamorphosis and becoming, one that produces<br />

individuated entities but always continues in further metamorphic activity.<br />

“The world is an egg” (DR 279/216) in that the world is a dynamic process<br />

of metamorphosis through which virtual difference differentiates itself into actual<br />

multiple entities while itself remaining immanent within each of those entities.<br />

Everywhere difference explicates itself in multiple entities, and difference remains<br />

immanent within each entity, implicated within it. Hence, if the world is a city, it is<br />

also an egg, not a static collection of edifices but a living entity in formation. Further,<br />

it is neither a single city nor a single egg. Each locus looks out on a different city in<br />

formation, and there is no single originary ovum from which the city-organism arises.<br />

Differentiation proceeds in all directions at once, and wherever one finds oneself,<br />

there a different city is in a process of dynamic emergence. What Marcel ultimately<br />

learns through art is that the world is a city-egg in metamorphosis, each locus of which<br />

enfolds a difference that is actively unfolding itself. Common sense grasps the world<br />

in terms of stable entities and fixed relations, thereby misunderstanding difference<br />

in two ways, both as it manifests itself in the metamorphic process of becoming (the<br />

passage of the virtual into the actual) and as it exists in itself, as a virtual immanent<br />

within the actual. What art reveals is that immanent virtual domain, the domain of<br />

difference in itself, something that is “real without being actual, ideal without being<br />

abstract,” something that exists outside temporal markers, in a perpetual infinitive of<br />

multiple potential temporal unfoldings.<br />

Marcel’s apprenticeship in signs proceeds in two stages and two directions, the<br />

first stage leading him from worldly through amorous and sensual signs to the signs<br />

of art, the second following a reverse order as he learns to interpret all signs as<br />

varying manifestations of internal absolute difference. In the first stage, Marcel must<br />

overcome two illusions, those of objectivism and subjectivism. The first is the illusion<br />

that the object emitting the sign holds the secret of the sign, as if, for example, the<br />

madeleine itself somehow possessed the virtual Combray within its physical being.<br />

To make such an illusory attribution is unavoidable, for “Everything encourages us<br />

to do so: perception, passion, intelligence, even self-esteem … We think that the<br />

‘object’ itself has the secret of the signs it emits. We scrutinize the object, we return<br />

to it in order to decipher the sign” (PS 37/27). Yet once Marcel overcomes this<br />

illusion, he falls into a second, the belief that the secret of the sign is merely a matter<br />

of subjective association. The problem here is that with subjective associations,<br />

anything goes. Any object may be associated with any other object, in which case<br />

signs are merely symptoms of their interpreters. What Marcel must finally learn is<br />

that the truth of signs is neither in the objects that emit them nor in the subjects who<br />

interpret them but in the differences that are immanent in objects and subjects alike.


58<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Art leads Marcel to this truth since in each great art work a unique world is disclosed<br />

from a specific point of view, but in such a way that the artist-subject is produced<br />

by the point of view rather than himself or herself bringing the point of view into<br />

existence. Hence, if the world revealed by the great art work is a city, its revealing<br />

point of view is like a tower from which an anonymous and apersonal “one” views<br />

the dynamic unfolding of the city and the artist-subject below, and that “one” is<br />

difference itself in a process of self-differentiation.<br />

Once art has taught Marcel the truth of signs, he is able to reinterpret the signs<br />

of sensual experience, love and the world and see that all are manifestations of<br />

differences, though in varying degrees of materiality and generality. The signs of<br />

involuntary memory, such as the madeleine, are close to the signs of art, in that<br />

they unfold a world (such as the virtual Combray) and a non-chronological time<br />

(the virtual past of the madeleine being a subset of the “complicated” pure form<br />

of time of difference). Yet such signs are contingent on circumstances for their<br />

emergence, since they are thoroughly enmeshed in the matter in which they appear,<br />

unlike the signs of art, which manage to “dematerialize” the medium – the physical<br />

paint, sounds, words – in which they are embodied. The signs of love and the world<br />

are likewise contingent and embedded in intractable matter, while the worlds they<br />

disclose are even less specific than those brought forth in sensual signs. Marcel’s love<br />

of Albertine forms a series with his love of his mother, Swann’s love of Odette, and<br />

other loves, such that Marcel comes to see all these loves as the general unfolding of a<br />

“theme,” an anonymous structure of love that plays through the various heterosexual<br />

and homosexual liaisons of the Recherche. The signs of the world, finally, disclose<br />

social laws, broad regularities of thought and behavior that the sophisticates of the<br />

Recherche unconsciously reproduce as they themselves are structured and produced<br />

by these regularities.<br />

Swimming<br />

Proust’s Recherche traces the path of a very specific apprenticeship, that of a young<br />

man discovering his vocation as a writer. His training proceeds via dinners and<br />

receptions, unhappy loves, unsettling recollections, and performances of powerful<br />

works of art – hardly the standard curriculum of what is generally thought of as<br />

an education. Yet in this aesthetic apprenticeship Deleuze finds the essence of<br />

learning, which “is essentially concerned with signs” (PS 10/4). Signs are enfolded<br />

differences that impinge on thought and force thought to unfold those differences.<br />

Encounters with such signs are fortuitous yet necessary, chance moments that<br />

defy common sense and choose the interpreter rather than themselves being freely<br />

chosen as objects of interpretation. In the course of explicating signs, the interpreter<br />

necessarily passes through two illusions, that objects possess the truth of signs, and<br />

that their truth arises from subjective associations. Once beyond these illusions, the<br />

interpreter discovers the virtual domain of differences, which unfold themselves<br />

within the actual through a process of metamorphic self-differentiation, while at the<br />

same time remaining immanent within the actual.


Search, Swim and See 59<br />

In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze incorporates many of the points raised<br />

in Proust and Signs within an extended treatment of what he calls the orthodox<br />

“image of thought,” or the unstated preconceptions of thought implicit in traditional<br />

philosophy, and what might be called an “imageless,” genuine thought. As in his<br />

earlier study of Proust, Deleuze here observes that the standard assumption in<br />

philosophy is that thought voluntarily, with a free and good will, pursues truth. Good<br />

sense protects thought from nonsense and leads thought in the proper direction<br />

(sens in French having a possible meaning of “direction”), while common sense<br />

provides for a common functioning of the faculties, a sensus communis whereby the<br />

senses and mental processes are coordinated in their mutual apprehensions (as when,<br />

for example, the sight, touch, sound, memory and analysis of a given experience<br />

confirm that they are related to a single and same object of experience). Implicit<br />

in this notion of common sense is the model of thought as a form of recognition,<br />

recognition being defined through “the harmonious exercise of all the faculties upon<br />

a supposed same object” (DR 174/133). Recognition in turn grounds the notion of<br />

thought as representation, every representation presuming a unified perspective<br />

and stable objects governed by the complementary principles of “the Same and<br />

the Similar, the Analogous and the Opposed” (DR 217/167). Thought’s goal in a<br />

world of recognition and representation is to eliminate problems and find solutions,<br />

to pass from non-knowledge to knowledge. Learning in such a world is simply the<br />

passage from non-knowledge to knowledge, a process with a definite beginning and<br />

ending, in which thought, like a dutiful pupil, responds to preformulated questions<br />

and eventually arrives at pre-existing answers.<br />

What escapes orthodox thought is difference, or the genuinely “new,” which<br />

can only be engaged through an “imageless thought.” Rather than arising from a<br />

conscious exercise of good will, genuine thought must be forced into action through<br />

the disruption of ordinary habits and notions. That which is new is not orthodox<br />

but paradoxical, and hence its sense seems nonsense, not good sense. Its paradoxes<br />

include those of becoming, the virtual past, and the pure form of time, in which time’s<br />

arrow is reversed or destroyed and thought as a result proceeds not in a single, right<br />

direction but in all directions at once. Rather than reinforcing the common functioning<br />

of the senses and faculties, difference splits them apart and pushes each sense or<br />

faculty to its limits, no single and selfsame object confirming the unified operation<br />

of a sensus communis. The object of an imageless thought defies recognition, for<br />

“the new – in other words, difference – calls forth forces in thought which are not<br />

the forces of recognition, today or tomorrow, but the powers of a completely other<br />

model, from an unrecognized and unrecognizable terra incognita” (DR 177/136).<br />

Such an object is understood not through representation but through explication, for<br />

the object is a sign, an internalized difference pointing toward something other than<br />

itself. Rather than eliminating problems, the thought of difference is itself a thought<br />

of problems, and learning, rather than occupying the gap between non-knowledge<br />

and knowledge, is the process whereby thought explores the domain of problems.<br />

We have already encountered many of the characteristics of such an imageless<br />

thought in our examination of Marcel’s experience of the madeleine. Marcel<br />

is jolted from his routines by the taste of the madeleine. Its savor paradoxically<br />

enfolds a virtual Combray, whose time is an a-directional coexisting past. That


60<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

virtual Combray is something different within the madeleine, and itself a difference<br />

engaged in a process of self-unfolding. The virtual Combray differs from any seen,<br />

heard, or touched Combray, for it is a pure object of memory, one that memory<br />

alone can grasp and that divides memory from the other faculties as the object is<br />

apprehended. The madeleine defies ready recognition and representation, signifying<br />

only by pointing beyond itself to something other and without resemblance to itself.<br />

But in what regard does the madeleine disclose a domain of problems, and how is<br />

learning related to such a domain? This we can determine by looking a little further<br />

at Deleuze’s discussion of problems in Difference and Repetition.<br />

Often philosophers act as if “problems are given ready-made, and that they<br />

disappear in the responses or the solution” (DR 205/158), which perhaps accounts<br />

for dogmatic philosophy’s frequent “puerile examples taken out of context and<br />

arbitrarily erected into models” and its “infantile” proceedings in which “the master<br />

sets a problem, our task is to solve it, and the result is accredited true or false by a<br />

powerful authority” (DR 205/158). Deleuze contends, however, that problems must<br />

be both invented and discovered, and that they produce the conditions under which<br />

solutions may be judged true or false. Hence, each problem is “at once both the site<br />

of an originary truth and the genesis of a derived truth” (DR 207/159). Problems must<br />

be evaluated not according to their “resolvability,” as often happens in philosophy,<br />

but according to their importance, their ability to generate new questions and the<br />

solutions related to those questions.<br />

But problems for Deleuze are more than mere Kuhnean paradigms, for they are<br />

differential events that “do not exist only in our heads but occur here and there in<br />

the production of an actual historical world” (DR 246/190). Problems exist in a<br />

virtual domain of difference, and each problem may be characterized in terms of its<br />

“differential elements and relations along with the singular points which correspond<br />

to them” (DR 271–2/209). Deleuze draws this vocabulary of differential relations<br />

and singular points from the language of differential calculus. He notes that the basic<br />

formula for the derivative of a function, dy / dx, allows one to describe a relation<br />

between elements without determining their separate identities or specifying their<br />

values: “In relation to x, dx is completely undetermined, as dy is to y, but they are<br />

perfectly determinable in relation to one another … Each term exists absolutely only<br />

in its relation to the other” (DR 223/172). The elements of a given problem are<br />

like the x and y of the formula dy / dx, undetermined elements that become capable<br />

of determination (though still without having any specified values) through their<br />

differential relation with one another. Hence, each problem delineates “a system<br />

of ideal connections – in other words, a system of differential relations between<br />

reciprocally determined genetic elements” (DR 225/173–4). Deleuze also observes<br />

that in the geometric interpretation of the theory of differential equations one may<br />

characterize different equations in terms of their singular points, the focus of a given<br />

parabola, for example, being the singular point of the parabola generated by that<br />

equation. What is crucial for Deleuze is that one may determine the existence of such<br />

singular points and their distribution within a field of vectors without specifying<br />

their precise values or even what figures they might determine – whether a parabola,<br />

a curve, an ellipse, and so on.


Search, Swim and See 61<br />

A problem, then, is not an amorphous muddle, nor a kind of shadowy double<br />

of its eventual resolution within a specific solution, but a structured field of<br />

potential actualizations, a system of differentially related elements and their<br />

corresponding singular points. The system of reciprocally determinable relations<br />

of a given problem establishes its fundamental elements, and the singular points<br />

demarcate various zones of potential actualization. The problem is virtual – real<br />

without being actual – yet it is always engaged in a process of actualization, and it<br />

is immanent within its various actualizations. The problem of differential calculus<br />

consists of its elements (at the most rudimentary level, x and y as related through<br />

the formula for the derivative, dy / dx) and the singular points distributed within<br />

a field of vectors. The elements and singular points only have an actual existence<br />

in specific equations and solutions, which may be mapped in particular figures (a<br />

given parabola or curve, say) with precise values. But the problematic domain of<br />

differentially related elements and singular zones of potential actualization remains<br />

immanent within actual equations and solutions, each equation being a concrete<br />

manifestation of a generative zone of potential differentiation. If one considers<br />

the phonemic dimension of language, one may characterize its problem in terms<br />

of the broad field of reciprocally determinable phonemic oppositions that belong<br />

to all languages, and the particular set of pertinent differences, or singular points,<br />

that find actualization in a given language. Each enunciation of a given phoneme<br />

is a concrete and specific sonic manifestation of a zone of potential enunciations<br />

delimited by a given pertinent difference, such that variations in timbre, pitch and<br />

pronunciation of a given phoneme by different speakers “count” as enunciations of<br />

the same phoneme. One may also regard the development of a biological organism<br />

as an actualization of a problem, the reciprocally determinable elements being the<br />

differential relations common to animals in general, the singular points being zones<br />

of potential differentiation that may be actualized in the components of a dog or a<br />

cat, and that have actual embodiment in this dog or that cat. 5<br />

As should be clear from these examples, problems are not simply mental,<br />

subjective entities, at least in the common sense of those terms. They are ideal, in<br />

that they are virtual, but they are manifest in human and nonhuman, organic and<br />

even inorganic, systems alike. 6 Problems are “ideal ‘objecticities’ possessing their<br />

own sufficiency and implying acts of constitution and investment in their respective<br />

symbolic fields” (DR 206/159). Human thought obviously involves human subjects,<br />

5 In some regards, Deleuze’s concept of the problem may be related to that of “structure”<br />

in some forms of structuralism. In “How Do We Recognize Structuralism?” (ID 238–69/170–<br />

92), Deleuze characterizes structures in terms of differential relations and singular points, and<br />

he argues that the structural analyses of Lévi-Strauss, Althusser, Lacan, Foucault and others<br />

may be understood in terms of this model. One should be cautious in assimilating Deleuze to<br />

this tradition, however, for he departs from most structuralists in his emphasis on the virtual,<br />

the positive nature of difference, and the generative force of self-differentiating difference<br />

within structures.<br />

6 It should be evident that Deleuze uses the term “Idea” in an unconventional way,<br />

drawing his concept of ideas from what he identifies as Kant’s “profound theory of Ideas as<br />

problematizing and problematic” (DR 209/161). Ideas for Deleuze are in no sense transcendent,<br />

essential or eternal entities, but instead virtual problems immanent within the real.


62<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

yet, though problems do not come ready-made, and hence must be created, at the<br />

same time they are not mere fabrications of the mind, for they have a real, albeit<br />

virtual, existence as “objecticities” that manifest themselves throughout the world.<br />

Thus, when Deleuze turns to the subject of learning, he says that “Learning is the<br />

appropriate name for the subjective acts carried out when one is confronted with the<br />

objecticity of a problem (Idea), whereas knowledge designates only the generality<br />

of concepts or the calm possession of a rule enabling solutions” (DR 213–14/164).<br />

Learning and problems belong to the domain of the virtual, whereas knowledge and<br />

solutions belong to the separate domain of the actual; and learning is a matter of<br />

opening thought to the virtual domain of problems, which has its own autonomous<br />

existence, not a matter of solving specific questions and securing a permanent body<br />

of knowledge.<br />

At three different points in Difference and Repetition, Deleuze offers as an<br />

example of learning that of learning to swim. 7 In the most extended treatment of<br />

this example, Deleuze remarks first that “to learn is to enter into the universal of the<br />

relations which constitute the Idea, and into their corresponding singularities” (DR<br />

214/165). In other words, one must immerse oneself in a problem, with its system of<br />

differential relations (“the universal of the relations which constitute the Idea”) and<br />

their corresponding singular points. The sea may be considered one such problem:<br />

“The idea of the sea, for example, as Leibniz showed, is a system of liaisons or<br />

differential relations between particles, and singularities corresponding to the degrees<br />

of variation among these relations – the totality of the system being incarnated in<br />

the real movement of the waves” (DR 214/165). 8 One may say that the problem of<br />

the sea in general, its universal problem, is that of differential relations between<br />

dynamically interacting water particles, and that the problem’s singular points are<br />

the nadir and apex of diverse potential wave functions. Each concrete, physical wave<br />

is an actualization of one particular set of singular points, and the whole of the sea<br />

is an embodiment of the system of differential relations that constitute the problem<br />

of the sea. “To learn to swim,” continues Deleuze, “is to conjugate the distinctive<br />

points [points remarquables, a synonym for singular points] of our bodies with<br />

the singular points of the objective Idea in order to form a problematic field” (DR<br />

214/165). Through contact with the sea, then, the singular points which are incarnate<br />

in the swimmer’s body are conjoined with the singular points embodied in the sea,<br />

and the complex of singular points belonging to swimmer and sea together form a<br />

virtual, problematic field. The swimmer, of course, possesses an actual body, the<br />

sea has an actual material existence, and the swimmer learns to interact with actual<br />

waves. But it is this conjugation of singular points that “determines for us a threshold<br />

7 Although Deleuze nowhere says as much, it seems likely that he draws the example of<br />

swimming from Henri Bergson, who in Creative Evolution, trans. Arthur Mitchell (New York,<br />

1911), pp. 192–4, describes the effort to think something new in terms of learning to swim.<br />

8 Deleuze’s identification of the sea as a Leibnizian problem hinges on a rather<br />

unconventional reading of Leibniz’s remarks about the sound of the ocean (as, for example,<br />

in Leibniz’s Preface to New Essays on Human Understanding, trans. Peter Remnant and<br />

Jonathan Bennett (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 54–5). Deleuze develops this reading of Leibniz in<br />

Difference and Repetition (DR 275–6/213–14).


Search, Swim and See 63<br />

of consciousness at which our real acts are adjusted to our perceptions of the real<br />

relations, thereby providing a solution to the problem” (DR 214/165).<br />

Consciousness, however, does not afford us direct access to problems and their<br />

singular points. Consciousness operates via good-will, good sense and common sense,<br />

all of which distort difference and reinforce an interpretation of the world in terms<br />

of ready-made questions and pre-existing solutions. Only through an involuntary<br />

confrontation with something other does thought engage difference, and that which<br />

provokes the thought of difference is a sign (as we saw earlier in our examination<br />

of Proust). Hence, “problems and their symbolic fields stand in a relationship with<br />

signs,” for signs are those entities “which ‘cause problems’ and are developed in a<br />

symbolic field” (DR 213/164). If to learn is to conjugate singular points “in order to<br />

form a problematic field” (DR 214/165), then we may say as well that “to learn is<br />

indeed to constitute this space of an encounter with signs” (DR 35/23). In the case of<br />

swimming, the encounter with signs leads to the discovery of singular points in both<br />

the swimmer and the sea. The singular points immanent within the swimmer’s body<br />

become manifest through the body’s disorienting, subliminal micro-perceptions of<br />

an alien element. Through that body’s attempts to adjust its motions with those of<br />

the sea, thought unfolds the singular points that are enfolded in the sign-particles of<br />

the sea, and as the body and the sea together form an interactive system of motions,<br />

a problematic field emerges, one of differential relations and singular points that<br />

extend across swimmer and sea. Thus, though learning to swim entails a passage to<br />

“a threshold of consciousness at which our real acts are adjusted to our perceptions<br />

of the real relations [of the sea]” (DR 214/165), problems are:<br />

… the ultimate elements of nature [those of the sea, in the swimming example] and the<br />

subliminal objects of little perceptions [that is, micro-perceptions below the threshold of<br />

consciousness]. As a result, “learning” always takes place in and through the unconscious,<br />

thereby establishing the bond of a profound complicity between nature and mind. [DR<br />

214/165]<br />

To learn, then, is to immerse oneself within an alien element and thereby open oneself<br />

to an encounter with signs. (Think here of Marcel’s taste of the madeleine as analogous<br />

to the neophyte swimmer’s initial dive into the sea.) Signs “cause problems” through<br />

their disorienting shock, forcing thought to deal with experiences that disrupt the<br />

common, coordinated functioning of the senses and faculties (Marcel’s strange<br />

gustatory sensations resembling the swimmer’s initial unorganized tactile microperceptions).<br />

Through this encounter with signs, thought discovers a problematic<br />

field of differential relations and singular points that exists both within and without<br />

(the reminiscence field of Marcel-madeleine-virtual Combray being like the fluid<br />

sensori-motor field of swimmer-sea). Though it is within the actual that thought<br />

participates in the dynamic unfolding of the differential relations and singular points<br />

of the virtual domain of problems, that virtual domain remains apersonal and preindividual,<br />

an ideal structure of potential zones of individuation that establishes “the<br />

bond of a profound complicity between nature and mind” (DR 214/165).


64<br />

Seeing<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

In Proust and Signs, Deleuze notes that Marcel learns little from his teachers – indeed,<br />

in the encounter with the madeleine, he has no teacher other than the madeleine<br />

itself. In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze assigns the swimming teacher a rather<br />

limited role, for “the movements of the swimming instructor which we reproduce<br />

on the sand bear no relation to the movements of the wave, which we learn to deal<br />

with only by grasping the former in practice as signs” (DR 35/23). It would seem<br />

that for Deleuze the best that teachers can do is to invite their students to participate<br />

along with them in an activity rather than show them what to do or how to do it. “We<br />

learn nothing from those who say: ‘Do as I do,’” says Deleuze. “Our only teachers<br />

are those who tell us to ‘do with me,’ and are able to emit signs to be developed in<br />

heterogeneity rather than propose gestures for us to reproduce” (DR 35/23). There is<br />

finally a basic mystery to learning, in that “We never know in advance how someone<br />

will learn: by means of what loves someone becomes good at Latin, what encounters<br />

make them a philosopher, or in what dictionaries they learn to think” (DR 215/165).<br />

Still, although we cannot know in advance what paths learning will take, nor can we<br />

induce genuine learning through precept and example, there is perhaps a function<br />

for the teacher in this form of education, one that Deleuze hints at when he says<br />

that our only teachers are those who “are able to emit signs” (DR 35/23). Deleuze<br />

does not develop this insight any further in Difference and Repetition, but we might<br />

be able to discern the outlines of a pedagogy of sign emission by looking briefly at<br />

his treatment of modern film in Cinema 2: The Time-Image, and specifically at the<br />

practice of one of Deleuze’s favorite directors, Jean-Luc Godard.<br />

Deleuze divides the history of film into two basic phases, the classic cinema<br />

and modern cinema. Classic cinema is dominated by an organization of space and<br />

time according to a rational, commonsense, Newtonian/Cartesian “sensory-motor<br />

schema” (IT 40/26). Modern cinema, by contrast, is marked by the breakdown of<br />

the sensory-motor schema and the creation of images that no longer conform to a<br />

single unified spatio-temporal structure. In the classic cinema, images are linked<br />

through their ordinary, “natural” connections with one another, “according to laws<br />

of association, of continuity, resemblance, contrast or opposition” (IT 361/276),<br />

whereas in the modern cinema images are juxtaposed in such a way that the gap<br />

between images becomes primary, “the interval is set free, the interstice becomes<br />

irreducible and stands on its own” (IT 362/277). Modern directors, however, do not<br />

simply disconnect images from their orthodox, commonsense chains of association;<br />

they also re-link images, yet in such a way that a productive difference emerges<br />

between images. Godard is for Deleuze an exemplary director in this regard:<br />

For in Godard’s method, it is not a question of association. Given one image, another<br />

image has to be chosen which will induce an interstice between the two. This is not an<br />

operation of association, but of differentiation, as mathematicians say, or of disparation,<br />

as physicists say: given one potential, another one has to be chosen, not any whatever, but<br />

in such a way that a difference of potential is established between the two, which will be<br />

productive of a third or of something new. [IT 234/179–80]


Search, Swim and See 65<br />

The modern cinematic re-linking of images, then, is not arbitrary, but guided by<br />

a principle of maximum interaction, whereby the interstice between images is<br />

emphasized while at the same time the juxtaposed images are themselves altered<br />

and something new emerges in each “image-interstice-image” unit as a whole. For<br />

audiences, such differentially related “image-interstice-image” sequences pose<br />

problems, since the sequences are not readily assimilable within standard interpretive<br />

schemas. Modern cinematic images must be “read,” in the sense that they must<br />

be construed through an active interrogation of the forces connecting the images.<br />

For each sequence, the audience must ask, What specific difference motivates this<br />

connection? What new movement is created through this juxtaposition? How does<br />

this sequence interact with other sequences? How do the sequences form part of<br />

an assemblage of multiple “image-interstice-image” units that maintain a certain<br />

consistency, a specific cohesiveness of multiple parts in dynamic interaction? Such<br />

a “reading” of images is complicated by the fact that modern directors emphasize<br />

not only the gaps between images, but also the gaps of silence between sounds, the<br />

gaps separating sound effects, music and dialogue from each other, as well as the gap<br />

between the visual and audio elements of film (such that there is in modern films a<br />

constant back-and-forth of the visual and the sonic in dynamic disequilibrium rather<br />

than a mutual doubling or reinforcement of sight and sound). As a result, “a whole<br />

pedagogy is required here, because we have to read the visual image as well as hear<br />

the speech-act in a new way” (IT 322/247) and interrelate sight and sound through<br />

their differential relations with one another.<br />

Deleuze observes that over the course of his career, Godard develops “his<br />

own pedagogy, his own didacticism” (IT 323/248), one that combines a method<br />

of differentially juxtaposing images and sounds and a self-conscious reflection on<br />

that method within the film itself: “Godard’s strength is not just in using this mode<br />

of construction in all his work (constructivism) but in making it a method which<br />

cinema must ponder at the same time as it uses it” (IT 234/179). The film that “marks<br />

a first peak in this reflection” (IT 234/179) for Deleuze is Here and Elsewhere (Ici et<br />

ailleurs), a collaborative effort directed by Godard, Anne-Marie Miéville and Jean-<br />

Pierre Gorin that began in 1970 as a documentary about the Palestinian struggle and<br />

ended in 1974 as a meditation on images, sounds and what the film’s narrator calls<br />

the “uninterrupted chains of images enslaving one another,” a chain that assigns us<br />

our place “in the chain of events in which we have lost all power.”<br />

Here and Elsewhere is a film about “and,” about the links that combine images<br />

and sounds in associative chains. (The French word “chaîne,” besides denoting<br />

various kinds of physical and mental links, has associations as well with consumer<br />

and media culture – travail à la chaîne: assembly-line work; chaîne: [TV] channel.)<br />

The film moves back and forth between images of the Palestinian camps and a French<br />

family watching TV, with interspersed sections presenting a complex of sights and<br />

sounds in various formats – blank screens, screens with nothing but words (key<br />

words flashing), montages of stills (documents of the workers’ movement, photos<br />

of Nixon, Brezhnev, Hitler, Golda Meir, the Holocaust, advertisements, and so on),<br />

shots of one, four or nine television screen broadcasts, an extended shot of three<br />

slides side by side with a disembodied hand replacing one slide after another, comic<br />

didactic sequences demonstrating the nature of filmmaking, and so on. The film’s


66<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

sequences in some ways confirm well-worn chains of association, many of which<br />

are dominated by the binary oppositions recited by the narrator (victory and defeat,<br />

foreign and national, order and disorder, black and white, here and elsewhere). But<br />

the narrator’s insistent enunciation of “and,” the repeated flashing of “and” and<br />

“+” in the intertitle messages, and the several prolonged shots of two wood blocks<br />

forming the word “et” (“and”) that fill the screen, all call into question such links<br />

while raising the possibility of other connections, other uses of “and,” connections<br />

of one thing after another in an additive, non-totalizing fashion, x and p, and b,<br />

and y … . The juxtaposition of Palestinian fighters and the French family watching<br />

TV invites a propagandistic reading of this relation as one of an authentic, active<br />

and natural culture versus a media-saturated, passive, consumerist culture, just as<br />

the alternating stills of Hitler and Golda Meir suggest a facile equation of the two<br />

figures. But as the narrator states, it is “too simple and too easy to simply divide the<br />

world in two,” “too easy or too simple to say simply that the wealthy are wrong and<br />

the poor are right,” for “there are no simple images, only simple people, who will be<br />

forced to stay quiet, like an image.”<br />

Midway through the film, the narrator offers an analysis of the “enchaining” of<br />

images whereby one image displaces another in a constant flow, and consumers of<br />

the images are invited to find their place in the flow. He also remarks on sounds –<br />

how one sound dominates another, and how sounds gain power by being represented<br />

by images. The film’s critique of images, however, is not restricted to mass media<br />

images, for in the film’s final section, a female narrator subjects the directors’ own<br />

Palestinian footage to a critical interrogation. As a close-up sequence of a Palestinian<br />

woman occupies the screen, the female narrator points out that the woman is a young,<br />

beautiful actress chosen by the directors to play a pregnant woman, though she is not<br />

pregnant herself. Footage of another woman haltingly reciting lines fed to her by an<br />

off-screen prompter is accompanied by the narrator’s remarks on the woman’s initial<br />

enthusiasm at participating in the Palestinian cause and her evident boredom and<br />

unease as the recitation continues and she seemingly longs for a humbler, less elitist<br />

role in the struggle. As we watch a young girl loudly declaim a patriotic poem, the<br />

narrator comments that the girl may be innocent but her theatrical manner is not, for<br />

it echoes the poses of a revolutionary theater whose images are tired and clichéd.<br />

Besides providing a direct verbal critique of images, though, the film also offers<br />

an implicit rethinking of images through their isolation, their disconnection from<br />

conventional chains, and their reconnection in unorthodox series. The sequences of<br />

the “pregnant” actress, the stuttering reciter, and the histrionic young girl cease to<br />

function within some revolutionary saga. Isolated from narrative chains of association,<br />

the sequences function as singular points, loci of potential development that are<br />

not pre-judged and pre-viewed. The stills and documentary footage of Palestinian<br />

corpses, workers’ demonstrations and Holocaust victims interjected in unexpected<br />

patterns throughout the film finally block ready assimilation within an ideological<br />

framework, but instead force a rethinking of the meaningful differences that pertain<br />

to the violence that extends from the Russian Revolution to the present. By the close<br />

of the film, the juxtaposition of a circle of soldiers in quiet conversation and the<br />

French family watching TV has lost its clear ideological bearings. The insistent long<br />

takes of the two groups provide no new pre-digested information about the images,


Search, Swim and See 67<br />

the undercoded shots asking the audience to make its own connections between the<br />

images. The male narrator finally comments that the filmmakers were unable truly<br />

to see and hear the Palestinians when they shot their footage because they sought<br />

elsewhere the revolutionary solution to problems they could not see and hear at<br />

home. The challenge, he concludes, is “to learn to see in order to hear elsewhere. To<br />

learn to hear oneself speaking, in order to see what the others are doing. The others,<br />

the elsewhere [ailleurs] of our here [ici].”<br />

Learning to Think<br />

Learning for Deleuze is a subset of what we usually mean by learning, just as thought<br />

for him is a subset of what generally passes for thinking. What Deleuze deems<br />

genuine learning and genuine thought belong to the domain of signs, problems and<br />

the virtual, a domain that is, in Proust’s words, “real without being actual, ideal<br />

without being abstract.” To learn is to encounter signs, to undergo the disorienting<br />

jolt of something new, different, truly other, and then to explicate those signs, to<br />

unfold the differences they enfold. As one does so, one passes through objective and<br />

subjective interpretative illusions until one grasps difference itself in its immanent<br />

differentiation within the actual. Then one sees the world as an a-centered city-egg<br />

engaged in metamorphic becoming in all directions at once, but one sees as well<br />

the virtual domain of difference in itself, which is not an amorphous chaos, but an<br />

infinite collection of structured problems. Each problem consists of a general set<br />

of differentially related elements and their corresponding singular points, or zones<br />

of potential actualization. Genuine learning involves an engagement with such<br />

problems, a re-orientation of thought following its initial disorientation, such that<br />

thought may comprehend something new in its newness, as a structured field of<br />

potential metamorphic forces rather than a pre-formed body of knowledge to be<br />

mastered. One cannot teach the truly new in its newness, but one can attempt to<br />

induce an encounter with the new by emitting signs, by creating problematic objects,<br />

experiences, or concepts. Hence, the pedagogy of signs entails first a critique of<br />

codes and conventions, an undoing of orthodox connections, and then a reconnection<br />

of elements such that the gaps between them generate problems, fields of differential<br />

relations and singular points. Such teaching, however, is itself a form of learning,<br />

for it proceeds via an encounter with signs and an engagement with problems. To<br />

teach is to learn, finally, since for Deleuze genuine teaching and learning are simply<br />

names for genuine thought. The goal of teaching and learning is to think otherwise,<br />

to engage the force of that which is other, different and new. What Deleuze details in<br />

his accounts of learning and teaching is that dimension of education that inspires all<br />

true students and teachers – the dimension of discovery and creation within the everunfolding<br />

domain of the new. It is also the dimension of freedom, in which thought<br />

escapes its preconceptions and explores new possibilities for life.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 5<br />

Tragedy, Sight and Sound<br />

The Birth of Godard’s Prénom Carmen<br />

from the Nietzschean Spirit of Music<br />

In Chapter Nine of Cinema 2: The Time-Image, “The Components of the Image,”<br />

Deleuze offers a provocative account of the relationship between sonic and visual<br />

elements in silent film, classic sound film and modern film. The silent cinema is not so<br />

much silent as it is mute, says Deleuze. Certain images suggest sounds (steam coming<br />

from a whistle), other suggest speech (an actor’s moving lips). But ultimately, the<br />

visual images of silent film retain a certain naturalness through their separation from<br />

actual sound, especially from speech. Speech itself is presented through intertitles,<br />

the result being that all speech becomes indirect speech. For even when the title says<br />

“I love you!,” Deleuze argues, the audience reads it as “he says that he loves her.”<br />

With the advent of sound, the visual image loses something of its naturalness. Voices<br />

of characters, both on and off camera, affect the postures of the characters, the angles<br />

from which they are shot, the movements of the camera, the rhythms of the editing,<br />

such that the sounds of speech interact with the visual images, thereby shaping,<br />

modifying and reshaping the visual images. Verbal innuendos, lies, ironic asides,<br />

deceptive phrases, all force a suspicious reading of visual images, a questioning<br />

of appearances, and in this sense words denaturalize visual images. Speech now<br />

becomes direct, and at the same time speech itself takes on a degree of autonomy,<br />

in that a logic of pure sociability is made possible through conversation, that loose,<br />

free-form, sometimes randomly assembled discourse that tends to take on a life of<br />

its own, passing among characters as if they were simply vehicles of its production.<br />

And in the modern cinema, finally, the visual and the sonic become autonomous.<br />

Cinema, at this point, says Deleuze, is truly audio-visual. Speech in the modern<br />

cinema is neither indirect (as in silent films) nor direct (as in classic films) but free<br />

indirect. 1 What this amounts to in cinematic terms is that in the modern cinema<br />

the speech of the characters becomes denaturalized, no longer fully belonging to<br />

the characters who speak or the fictional context in which they act. Actors recite<br />

lines as if spoken by a third person. They adopt literary tones or artificial modes of<br />

enunciation. Their lines switch registers from high formality to low slang to a flat<br />

recitation of impersonal data. They mingle speech about themselves as actors or as<br />

1 Deleuze takes the term “free indirect speech” from literary criticism, in which it refers<br />

to discourse in which one cannot tell whether the words are the narrator’s or a character’s,<br />

such as in the sentences, “He felt great pain, what suffering! How could she do this? What<br />

would come next?”


70<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

real personages within their fictional exchanges. The effect of all these strategies is<br />

to create a free-floating, separate aural-verbal element that interacts with the visual<br />

images without surrendering its autonomy.<br />

It is within the context of this discussion that Deleuze speaks about the role of<br />

music in film. My concern here is to consider the practical implications of his analysis<br />

by examining from a Deleuzian perspective the use of music as a sonic element in<br />

a single film – Jean-Luc Godard’s Prénom Carmen (1983). Deleuze’s account of<br />

music’s role in the classic sound cinema hinges on an observation of Nietzsche’s from<br />

The Birth of Tragedy, in which Nietzsche appropriates Schopenhauer’s conception<br />

of music for his own theory of tragedy. It happens that Godard’s film, besides being<br />

a profound meditation on music, may also be regarded as an insightful reflection on<br />

tragedy. And that understanding of tragedy proves to be intertwined with Godard’s<br />

approach to sight and sound in cinema, and especially to his handling of music.<br />

Hence, my Deleuzian examination of music in Godard entails as well a reflection on<br />

the possibilities of a Nietzschean tragic sensibility in the modern cinema.<br />

Music, Tragedy, Images<br />

What Nietzsche means by his 1872 title “The Birth of Tragedy out of the Spirit of<br />

Music” is perhaps nowhere more clearly indicated than in sections 16 and 17 of The<br />

Birth of Tragedy. Here, Nietzsche cites at length a passage from Schopenhauer, in<br />

which music is described as the direct expression of the will (by which Schopenhauer<br />

means something like “universal force”). Music is “an expression of the world,” a<br />

“universal language,” 2 in some regards like the language of concepts, yet one that is<br />

not abstract. Music “resembles geometrical figures and numbers, which are universal<br />

forms of all possible experience … and yet are not abstract but perceptible and<br />

thoroughly determinate” (p. 101). Music expresses the “inmost soul” of phenomena,<br />

for it is “an immediate copy of the will itself, and therefore complements everything<br />

physical in the world and every phenomenon by representing what is metaphysical,<br />

the thing in itself.” For this reason, says Schopenhauer, “we might just as well call the<br />

world embodied music as embodied will” (p. 102). Melodies, like concepts, are to a<br />

certain extent abstractions of the actual, but whereas concepts are universals derived<br />

from experience, and hence abstractions that come after phenomena, melodies give<br />

us the universal before phenomena, “the inmost kernel which precedes all forms, or<br />

the heart of things” (p. 102).<br />

According to Schopenhauer, then, will is the universal, undifferentiated force<br />

that expresses itself in the embodied, individuated forms of phenomena, and music<br />

is the direct representation of that universal will. Nietzsche concludes from this that<br />

music not only expresses “the immediate language of the will” (p. 103) but also<br />

stimulates the creative faculties to fashion individuated concepts and images that<br />

embody the will. The Dionysian medium of music stimulates the Apollonian creation<br />

of individuated forms, just as the universal will generates and plays through the<br />

2 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy and The Case of Wagner, trans. Walter<br />

Kauffman (New York, 1967), p. 101.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 71<br />

individuated things of the phenomenal world. The highest Apollonian manifestation<br />

of the Dionysian will is in the tragic myth of the annihilation of the hero. Music gives<br />

birth to tragic myth, “the myth which expresses Dionysian knowledge in symbols”<br />

(p. 103). Hence, “it is only through the spirit of music that we can understand the joy<br />

involved in the annihilation of the individual. … The metaphysical joy in the tragic<br />

is a translation of the instinctive unconscious Dionysian wisdom into the language<br />

of images: the hero, the highest manifestation of the will, is negated for our pleasure,<br />

because he is only phenomenon, and because the eternal life of the will is not affected<br />

by his annihilation” (p. 104). Through tragedy, “we are forced to look into the terrors<br />

[in die Schrecken] of the individual existence – yet we are not to become rigid with<br />

fear,” since by way of the drama “we are really for a brief moment primordial being<br />

itself” (p. 104).<br />

In Cinema 2, Deleuze argues that Nietzsche’s Schopenhauerian approach<br />

to music holds the key to an understanding of music’s function in classic sound<br />

cinema. Deleuze notes that some cinema critics treat music as a component of a<br />

“sonic continuum,” made up of sounds, words and music, that is interfused with and<br />

inseparable from visual images, whereas others regard music as a kind of “‘foreign<br />

body’ in the visual image, a little like dust in the eye” (IT 311/239). Deleuze argues<br />

that both views are true, but that they are often imperfectly articulated. For Deleuze,<br />

the “moving pictures,” or “movement-images,” on the screen are merely mobile<br />

“slices” or “chunks” of a moving, open Whole of fluctuating, metamorphosing<br />

time-space. Each actual movement-image on the screen extends into an off-screen<br />

world continuous with the on-screen space (for example, the character looks offcamera<br />

to her interlocutor across the room), and that continuous off-screen world<br />

Deleuze calls a “relative out of frame.” But each on-screen movement-image also<br />

is part of the open Whole, which in the classic cinema is never directly presented,<br />

but only indirectly expressed through the images on the screen. Unlike the space of<br />

the “relative-out-of-frame,” which may be revealed in the next shot, what Deleuze<br />

calls the “absolute-out-of-frame” of the open Whole remains undisclosed on the<br />

screen in any direct fashion. Sounds, words and music may be part of the relativeout-of-frame,<br />

as when the off-camera noise of a breaking glass, the curse of an angry<br />

sailor, or the strum of a guitar, is shown in the next shot to issue from an actual<br />

glass, sailor or guitar inhabiting the same space as the preceding shot. But words<br />

may also issue from some unspecified realm outside the screen-space, as in the case<br />

of a voice-over narration, or a character’s flashback reminiscence. Likewise, music<br />

may accompany images without ever being “justified” by an off-screen source that<br />

belongs to the screen-world. In these cases, words and music are part of the absoluteout-of-frame,<br />

inhabiting the fluctuating time-space of the open Whole. Within the<br />

relative-out-of-frame space, music is part of a sonic continuum. Music may also<br />

remain within a sonic continuum in the absolute-out-of-frame space (as in a voiceover<br />

with accompanying music), yet music has the capacity as well to function as<br />

a “foreign body” within the visual image. Eisenstein argues that music and visual<br />

images should express a harmonious totality, but Eisner and others object that music<br />

often is most effective when it contrasts with the screen images, as when a soft lullaby<br />

accompanies a battle scene. Deleuze argues that the range of musical effects, from<br />

a unifying reinforcement and “echoing” of visual images to a disruptive contrast


72<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

and “irritation” of images, is made possible by music’s relation to the open Whole.<br />

In the classic cinema, music is capable of presenting a direct image of the open<br />

Whole, what Deleuze calls a direct “time-image,” which is incommensurable with<br />

the open Whole indirectly expressed by the visual images. Just as Nietzsche regards<br />

music as the immediate expression of the Dionysian will, so Deleuze treats it as the<br />

immediate expression of the open Whole. “In [Nietzschean] tragedy,” says Deleuze,<br />

“the immediate musical image is like the kernel of fire that surrounds the Apollonian<br />

visual images, and which cannot do without their unfolding parade. In the case of<br />

cinema, which is first a visual art, one may say that music adds the immediate image<br />

to the mediate images that represent the Whole indirectly” (IT 311/239). There is<br />

a relation between music and visual images, but it is not one of correspondence,<br />

for the direct expression (music) and the indirect expression (visual images) of the<br />

Whole are incommensurable.<br />

With the advent of modern cinema, however, Deleuze sees music taking on<br />

a different role. Modern directors create direct visual images of the open Whole<br />

– “time-images” – by disrupting the coordinates of commonsense time-space. Our<br />

experience is organized by a “sensory-motor schema” that allows us to function<br />

in a predictable, manageable world, yet that schema hides from us the paradoxical<br />

reality of the universe as an open time-space flux. Modern directors create images<br />

of “sheets of the past,” in which pasts coexist in a single, virtual plane; images of<br />

“peaks of the present,” in which incommensurable present moments simultaneously<br />

occur; and images of “series of time,” in which past, present and future interpenetrate<br />

in single images of becoming. They do so by disarticulating and disconnecting<br />

the continuities and regularities of the commonsense world and rearticulating and<br />

reconnecting images in non-rational assemblages, such that the gap between images,<br />

the difference between images, serves as the principle of their connection. The<br />

sequences of images in modern films force viewers to comprehend the relations<br />

produced by the non-rational juxtaposition of images. In this fashion, viewers<br />

encounter images unassimilated within conventional codes, standard narratives, or<br />

commonsense coordinates, and are thereby able to see direct images of time. As part<br />

of their effort to undo the sensory-motor schema, modern directors tend to emphasize<br />

the difference between sound and sight. They approach the sonic continuum and the<br />

visual continuum as autonomous materials, which they juxtapose in non-rational<br />

configurations within each continuum and in non-rational relations between the two<br />

continuums. Hence music in the modern cinema, though still capable of directly<br />

expressing the open Whole as it did in the classic cinema, takes on new relations<br />

to other elements of the sonic continuum as well as to the images of the visual<br />

continuum.<br />

Godard and Beethoven<br />

Jean-Luc Godard is among the modern directors Deleuze most admires, and Godard’s<br />

Prénom Carmen (1983) is perhaps Godard’s most extended meditation on music


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 73<br />

and its role in film. 3 Prénom Carmen also provides an apt occasion for a reflection<br />

on Nietzschean tragedy in modern cinema, for in many ways the film is a parodic<br />

disarticulation of the Carmen myth and the tragedy of fate. We recall, of course, that<br />

when Nietzsche renounces his early Wagnerism in The Case of Wagner (1888), it is<br />

Bizet’s Carmen he salutes as the antidote to the “damp north” and “the steam of the<br />

Wagnerian ideal.” 4 Of Bizet’s opera, Nietzsche remarks, “I know no case where the<br />

tragic joke that constitutes the essence of love is expressed so strictly, translated with<br />

equal terror into a formula, as in Don José’s last cry, which concludes the work: ‘Yes,<br />

I have killed her, / I – my adored Carmen!’” (p. 159). Godard’s film mocks the terror<br />

and tragedy of fatal love, but through its handling of images and sounds, I believe,<br />

it ultimately creates a certain terror and ecstatic joy that accord in some ways with<br />

the Nietzschean ideal of The Birth of Tragedy. And that terrifying, ecstatic joy is one<br />

with the experience of the separation and defamiliarization of sight and sound that<br />

Deleuze regards as central to the modern cinema.<br />

If, for the Nietzsche of The Birth of Tragedy, it is myth that is missing in modern<br />

art (indeed, in art from Euripides on), for Godard myth is all too present in the<br />

world around us. Early in Prénom Carmen, Godard, in the role of Carmen’s Uncle<br />

Jean, a washed-up film director, types the words “mal vu mal dit” (AS 22) on his<br />

asylum typewriter, these Beckettian phrases succinctly summing up the modern<br />

filmmaker’s problem. The world is “ill seen” and “ill said,” saturated with visual and<br />

verbal clichés, with ready-made, prepackaged images and formulas that structure<br />

and organize experience in ideological patterns. And the world is often “ill seen”<br />

because “ill said,” visual clichés arising from the narrative myths that script daily<br />

life. Godard undermines the Carmen myth of tragic love and the femme fatale<br />

through various parodic Verfremdungseffekten, including multiple visual and verbal<br />

citations, sudden shifts from high seriousness to pop informality or blunt profanity, a<br />

deliberately amateurish handling of action sequences, incongruous elements within<br />

scenes (such as the unperturbed bank customers surrounded by a raging gun battle),<br />

de-realizing references to the filmmaking process itself, and so on. Godard’s object,<br />

however, is not simply to parody myth, but also to create something new. As Godard<br />

is wont to say, he seeks not “une image juste,” but “juste une image,” an image cut<br />

off from myth and cliché, one granted a certain elemental nakedness and purity. At<br />

one point Carmen asks Joseph, “what comes before the name [le nom],” to which he<br />

responds, “Le prénom.” “No, before” she replies, “before you’re called anything”<br />

[avant qu’on vous appelle] (AS 56). Beyond the dismantling of the Carmen myth,<br />

3 A splendid shot-by-shot description of the film is available in a special 1984 issue<br />

of L’Avant scène cinema, 323/324 (1984): 19–64, and all citations, abbreviated as AS, are<br />

from this edition (translations my own). Although I speak of the film as essentially a work by<br />

Godard, it is important to note that the “scenario and adaptation” are credited to Anne-Marie<br />

Miéville, his collaborator on a number of important films. This fact, I believe, is especially<br />

important if one is to consider the implications of gender in the film, an issue that I do not<br />

address directly. See Verena Andermatt Conley, “A Fraying of Voices: Jean-Luc Godard’s<br />

Prénom Carmen,” L’esprit créateur, 30/2 (1990): 68–80, and Phil Powrie, “Godard’s Prénom<br />

Carmen (1984), Masochism, and the Male Gaze,” Forum for Modern Language Studies, 31/1<br />

(1995): 64–73, for discussion of this question.<br />

4 Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy and The Case of Wagner, p. 158.


74<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Prénom Carmen is above all an effort to extract simple, direct images from a coded<br />

network of “ill-seen” and “ill-said” visual clichés, to fashion images before names,<br />

pré-noms.<br />

Yet Prénom Carmen is also a film about sight and sound, about visual images<br />

and their relationship to what might loosely be called, after Deleuze, “sonic images,”<br />

or discrete sonic elements. One might expect Godard’s parody of Carmen to focus<br />

on Bizet’s score, but aside from two fleeting citations of the Habañera, whistled and<br />

hummed by minor characters, the opera’s music is absent from the film. Instead,<br />

Godard uses portions of Beethoven’s 9th, 10th, 14th, 15th and 16th String Quartets<br />

as the primary musical elements of his soundtrack. In a broad sense, Prénom Carmen<br />

is two films: a film of the Carmen story, and a film of a string quartet rehearsing<br />

several passages from Beethoven. The fiction that holds the two plots together is that<br />

Carmen’s lover Joseph is also the boyfriend of Claire, a member of the quartet. The<br />

film intercuts between the quartet’s rehearsals and the Carmen plot, with an early<br />

scene after a rehearsal establishing the relationship between Claire and Joseph. The<br />

two plots converge when the quartet performs in the same Intercontinental Hotel<br />

restaurant in which Carmen’s gang attempts its ill-fated kidnapping of a Polish<br />

ambassador. With only one exception, the visual images of the quartet match up with<br />

the soundtrack of the Beethoven quartets. 5 The musicians on screen, save Claire, are<br />

professional musicians (members of the Prat Quartet, as the opening credits of the<br />

film indicate) actually performing the Quartets, and the soundtrack is a live recording<br />

of their performance. (Claire’s bowing is obviously the unskilled imitations of a<br />

violinist’s actions, typical of a non-musician actor playing the role of a musician.<br />

Godard calls attention to this fact by having the first violinist chide Claire for making<br />

too many mistakes during the rehearsals.) The music, however, also accompanies the<br />

Carmen-plot images for extended stretches of the film. Clearly, Godard is playing<br />

with the notion of “sound-in” and “sound-off” camera, Beethoven now functioning<br />

as “sound-in” when the quartet is seen playing, now as “sound-off” when, for<br />

example, the music accompanies the bank heist. The ambiguity of the “sound-off”<br />

element emerges in the interplay of the images of the rehearsal and the images of the<br />

Carmen plot, the Beethoven accompaniment to the bank heist functioning both as a<br />

constituent of the “absolute-out-of-field” of a standard cinematic score and as a sonic<br />

element of the “relative-out-of-field” of the rehearsal space improbably “leaking”<br />

into the space of the bank heist.<br />

Why Beethoven?, one might ask. Pure chance, Godard suggests in one interview,<br />

since the story takes place by the sea and it was “at the seashore that I discovered, at<br />

age twenty, the quartets of Beethoven.” 6 But he also says that he sought “a fundamental<br />

5 The exception occurs midway through the film, when for eight seconds the soundtrack<br />

is dead while images of the performing quartet fill the screen. The effect is jarring, whereas at<br />

other points in the film when the visual ambient sound is missing and music accompanies the<br />

images, the effect is unremarkable because normalized within cinematic conventions. Clearly,<br />

Godard in this eight-second sequence is calling attention to the arbitrary nature of these sonic<br />

conventions in representational narrative cinema.<br />

6 Jean-Luc Godard, “Les signes du mal à vivre,” L’avant scène cinema, 323/324<br />

(1984), p. 5.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 75<br />

music, a music that had marked the history of music. A music that is both practice<br />

and theory of music. That was the case of Beethoven.” 7 In this regard, the Beethoven<br />

Quartets provide Godard with instances of “Music” writ large, paradigmatic<br />

compositions fit for an exploration of the theoretical relationship between visual<br />

images and music in general. The Quartets are also quintessential chamber-pieces,<br />

and one might argue that Prénom Carmen is itself a kind of cinematic chamber<br />

music, a work composed of a limited set of materials – created, as the film’s closing<br />

title card states, “IN MEMORIAM SMALL MOVIES” (AS 64). Yet perhaps the<br />

primary reason the Beethoven Quartets are chosen is that they are not associated<br />

with the Carmen story. And most important, they lack any relation to Bizet’s musical<br />

blending of exoticism and eroticism, instead exploiting a strictly Western art music<br />

idiom largely devoid of extra-musical associations. 8 Hence, the juxtaposition of the<br />

Beethoven Quartets and the Carmen images forces a confrontation of differences,<br />

creating unexpected resonances and frequent incongruities between sound and sight,<br />

while instigating a reflection on the relation between “pure,” self-referential, nonprogrammatic<br />

art music and the realm of the visual.<br />

Still, if there is no pre-existing relation between the Beethoven Quartets and the<br />

Carmen story, such a relation may be created after the fact, as it were, and Godard<br />

not only proceeds to fashion such a relation between sounds and images but also<br />

offers a verbal commentary on the process of that formation through the remarks<br />

of Claire and the other musicians. The quartet leader’s first comment, as the group<br />

begins its rehearsal, is “With the body” [Avec le corps] (AS 21), which suggests that<br />

the body is the medium through which image and music may be related. Shortly<br />

after the leader asks that the music be performed “avec le corps,” “Uncle Jean”<br />

Godard appears on the screen, tapping the window of his room, the metal bars of<br />

his bed, the table, the walls, the keys of his typewriter, his own chest, his head, the<br />

table again, the bars of the bed, and the mattress. With each distinctly audible tap,<br />

Godard demonstrates the corporeal dimension of sound, indicating that it is from<br />

bodies that sounds issue, and that it is with and from the body that music is produced.<br />

To underline the relation between bodies, sounds and music, Godard repeats the<br />

tapping movements near the close of the film, this time lightly striking four wine<br />

glasses with a fork in the hotel dining room. 9 The first violinist also makes musical<br />

comments that have relevance for the action unfolding in the Carmen plot. At one<br />

point, for example, he tells the other players, “It has to be more violent” (AS 26),<br />

7 Jean-Luc Godard, Jean-Luc Godard par Jean-Luc Godard, ed. Alain Bergala (Paris,<br />

1985), p. 576.<br />

8 The only exception might be the third movement of the 15th Quartet, the “Song of<br />

Thanksgiving of a Convalescence, in the Lydian Mode.” Although the movement is decidedly<br />

modal, I doubt that few listeners would describe it as exotic or non-Western. At most, listeners<br />

might possibly characterize it as monastic and typically Renaissance in its handling of<br />

harmony.<br />

9 Deleuze argues that there is a strictly visual link between the bodies of the musicians<br />

and the bodies of the Carmen plot actors. Indeed, he claims that the film repeatedly forces<br />

viewers to ask such questions as, what is the relation between the violinist’s bowing and<br />

Joseph’s embrace of Carmen?, the arch of the cellist’s fingers and the posture of the banks<br />

guard? and so on. See Deleuze, IM 253–4; 194–5.


76<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

and in the ensuing shots the bank heist escalates into a gun battle. At another, he calls<br />

for more passion, exhorting the quartet, “Push … one, two … rise … nothing more<br />

… pull … and vibrate” (that is, play with vibrato, but also literally, “vibrate”) (AS<br />

31), and in the following sequences the sensual relationship between Carmen and<br />

Joseph intensifies.<br />

But perhaps the most complex verbal links between the music and the Carmen<br />

plot issue from Beethoven’s Tagebuch of 1812–18, which Godard cites seven<br />

times in the film (see the Appendix to this Chapter). One such citation is the rather<br />

innocuous interjection of the first violinist as he stops the rehearsal, “No, no.<br />

Take the best phrase built on the harmony” (AS 29; notebook entry no. 37). Other<br />

citations, however, are more significant, and all but one are delivered by Claire (the<br />

obvious counterpart to Bizet’s Micaëla, the virginal opposite of the femme fatale<br />

Carmen). The film’s first citation from the Tagebuch occurs after the leader observes<br />

that “Claire makes too many mistakes” [Claire fait trop de fautes], to which she<br />

responds, “This I know well. I recognize it clearly. Life is not the supreme good.<br />

Among evils, the supreme evil is the mistake [la faute]” (AS 25; notebook entry no.<br />

118). Here, Godard playfully emphasizes the importance of art, as Claire indirectly<br />

suggests that artistic perfection is the supreme good, and hence superior to life. 10<br />

Yet Claire’s observation also bears on the Carmen story, for the supreme evil, as we<br />

shall see later, may be said to be “guilt,” or “culpability,” both possible translations<br />

of faute (and closer to the Tagebuch’s original Schuld). 11<br />

Claire’s next Tagebuch citation comes from an obscure 1802 “Fate tragedy” by<br />

Zacharias Werner, in which one character implores another to act and fulfill his being.<br />

Claire’s interjection, “Act instead of asking,” cleverly meshes with the rehearsal<br />

discussion of a passage from the 10th Quartet, and her continuation of the Werner<br />

citation functions neatly as a comment on the marvels of the creative imagination<br />

and its centrality in the artist’s life: “Do miracles first, if you want to unveil them,<br />

thus alone will you fulfill all your destiny” (AS 27). 12 Claire’s most extended<br />

citation reiterates the theme of destiny, in this case with a comment that enunciates<br />

the traditional theme of the Carmen myth: “Show your power, Destiny. We are not<br />

masters of ourselves. That which has been decided … let it be so” (AS 31–2). Here<br />

10 In several entries that Godard does not cite, Beethoven expresses his devotion to his<br />

art and laments the sacrifices his art demands of his personal life. “You must not be a human<br />

being, not for yourself, but only for others: for you there is no longer any happiness except<br />

within yourself, in your art” (no. 1). “Everything that is called life should be sacrificed to the<br />

sublime and be a sanctuary of art” (no. 40). “Sacrifice once and for all the trivialities of social<br />

life to your art” (no. 169).<br />

11 Actually, the lines Godard cites from Tagebuch, entry no. 118, are Beethoven’s<br />

transcription of the closing lines of Schiller’s The Bride of Messina. In the context of the play,<br />

Schuld clearly means “guilt” rather than “mistake.”<br />

12 It is worth noting that in Werner (and in the Tagebuch citation), the character is<br />

implored to fulfill his “Daseyn,” his “existence,” not his “destiny,” as the French translation<br />

has it. Claire’s reference here to “toute ta destinée” echoes her pronouncement later from<br />

entry no. 73, “Montre ta puissance, Destin,” “Zeige deine Gewalt Schicksal!” (Show your<br />

power, Fate!), a significant echo given the standard reading of the Carmen story as a tragedy<br />

of fate and destiny.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 77<br />

Godard suggests that Beethoven, at least in his Tagebuch, shares Merimée’s and<br />

Bizet’s sentiments about fate, and to the extent that the Quartets express Beethoven’s<br />

sense of the power of destiny, we have articulated in this phrase a direct connection<br />

between the film’s music and its central plot.<br />

Claire’s final two citations are pronounced in close succession as she pencils<br />

notations into her part. She first intones the Tagebuch’s cryptic fourth entry, “Verify<br />

all in the evening” (AS 32), and as she finishes the phrase a shot of the ocean shore<br />

at night comes on the screen. In the following shot, Claire is seen writing in her<br />

part, as she comments to herself, “And the clouds … the clouds, would they reveal<br />

torrents of life? [feraient-ils voir des torrents de vie, literally, ‘would they make<br />

seen torrents of life?’]” (AS 32; notebook entry no. 6). Here Godard is playfully<br />

mapping a line of association that proceeds from Beethoven’s Quartets to the film’s<br />

visual motifs. Godard inserts two shots of a cloud-filled sky in the film (shots 8 and<br />

116), in both cases in close proximity to a shot of the ocean shore. The first sky shot<br />

follows the opening shot of the sea, itself preceded by Carmen’s voiceover comment<br />

(accompanied by the sound of waves and gulls), “It’s in me, in you that it produces<br />

terrible waves [des vagues terribles]” (AS 21). A complex of verbal and visual<br />

associations, it would seem, brings together “torrents of life,” “terrible waves,”<br />

and images of the ocean and the sky, with the implication that Beethoven’s musical<br />

nighttime clouds motivate the appearance of the visual clouds. Implicit as well is<br />

that the torrents of life in Beethoven’s Quartets communicate with the terrible waves<br />

of passion that course through Carmen and Joseph – Joseph tells Claire midway<br />

through the film that “there is something taboo, a sort of force that pushes me … the<br />

tide swells [la marée monte]” (AS 53) – those waves taking on literal embodiment<br />

in the film’s twenty shots of the sea.<br />

Music and the Sonic Continuum<br />

For the most part, Godard does not directly tamper with Beethoven’s music. He<br />

does briefly allow the Beethoven score to play over Tom Waits’s ballad “Ruby’s<br />

Arms,” and at the moment that the Claire plot and the Carmen plot converge, for a<br />

few seconds two dissonant passages from the 16th Quartet are superimposed. 13 (The<br />

13 The Beethoven Quartets are the primary musical components of the film, but the<br />

importance of Waits’s ballad is not to be discounted. Clearly, the primary function of “Ruby’s<br />

Arms” is to provide a contrast to the quartets – in Deleuze’s terms, to serve as a productive<br />

difference. The Waits–Beethoven opposition is one of popular to classical music, but Waits’s<br />

ballad is hardly a prototypical piece of pop music. Waits occupies an odd niche in the popular<br />

music landscape, his work having strong ties to traditional blues as well as basic rock, while<br />

his vocal style must by any standards be deemed idiosyncratic. “Ruby’s Arms” utilizes a<br />

simple tonal harmony, somewhat more complex than the basic three-chord vocabulary of roots<br />

rock, but not especially adventurous in its harmonic idiom. Though clearly in the ballad style<br />

– slow tempo, expressive lyrics and emotional delivery – the song does not make reference to<br />

the harmonies typical of popular ballads from the 1930s and 1940s or those found in musicals.<br />

Despite its obvious differences from the Quartet scores, the ballad shares some characteristics<br />

with them. Its slow pace and straightforward progressions are compatible with the tempo


78<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

opening of the fourth movement overlaps the close of the third.) Occasionally, there<br />

are shifts in the volume levels of the recording, which also affect Beethoven’s music.<br />

Otherwise, however, the Quartets are presented as if they were being played by a<br />

conventional ensemble in rehearsal. The Quartet selections proceed in chronological<br />

order, from the 9th to the 10th Quartet, and then from the 14th through the 16th.<br />

Changes in lighting in the shots of the musicians suggest that we are viewing a series<br />

of rehearsals in which the players work their way through the corpus of the Quartets,<br />

movement by movement. The continuities in the musical passages tend to unify<br />

sections of the film, and the changes from one Quartet to another coincide with the<br />

broad structural divisions of the plot. 14<br />

and harmonies of the third movement of Beethoven’s 15th Quartet, and Waits’s use of an<br />

orchestral score links it broadly to the classical tradition. The ballad accompanies the action<br />

without interruption for 4 minutes 15 seconds. Godard denaturalizes the ballad somewhat<br />

by abruptly dropping the volume level at two points and alternating sections of relatively<br />

normal soundtrack reproduction with sections of hollow, low-bass, high-reverb reproduction,<br />

thereby calling attention to the sonic element of the film. He also superimposes a brief motif<br />

from the first movement of the 16th Quartet on the ballad. The ballad is introduced as one<br />

of the film’s most arresting and bizarre images fills the screen, that of a hand outline on a<br />

flickering blue background. The hand proves to be that of Joseph, and when the close-up of<br />

the screen (a thirty second shot) gives way to a medium shot, the blue field is shown to be a<br />

television screen. (The flickering blue screen of the television is visible in the background of<br />

the preceding hotel scenes, but the shots do not call attention to the television. I personally<br />

did not consciously note the television on a first viewing of the film, and I confess to thorough<br />

confusion when the hand/blue field image initially appeared on the screen.) Joseph is draped<br />

over the television set, his hand stroking the screen, as if he were caressing Carmen, who<br />

has left him alone in the hotel room overnight. The ballad continues to play after Carmen<br />

returns and the couple quarrel as Carmen rebuffs Joseph’s advances. The ballad is obviously<br />

associated with Joseph and expressive of his unrequited passion for Carmen, and in this regard<br />

the song has a prototypical pop-music social function. Joseph’s embrace of the television<br />

suggests that he is enamored by images and that his passion for Carmen is informed by<br />

simulacral media stereotypes. The hand-television juxtaposition might also suggest a broad<br />

association of Joseph and the domain of hand-tool “techne,” instrumental rationality and the<br />

dominance of the visible by the pragmatic. We might conclude, then, that Waits’s ballad and<br />

Beethoven’s Quartets represent a polar opposition of Joseph/popular culture/mediated images/<br />

technology and Carmen/art culture/unmediated images/nature. But such a schematization is<br />

too crude, especially in terms of its polarization of values. Godard does not mock the Waits<br />

ballad; indeed, the song seems to express genuine emotion. Conversely, though Godard treats<br />

Beethoven’s music with respect, his thoroughgoing irony makes it difficult to take anything in<br />

the film with absolute seriousness, including Beethoven.<br />

14 The sequence of quartet passages and corresponding plot elements is as follows: 9th<br />

Quartet, second movement (Andante con molto quasi Allegretto): opening rehearsal, hospital<br />

scenes with Godard and Carmen; 9th Quartet, fourth movement (Trio) coda, moving directly<br />

into the fifth movement (Allegro molto): transitional scenes, conclusion of Godard-Carmen<br />

conversation and Carmen leaving the hospital; 10th Quartet, first movement, second section<br />

(Allegro): bank heist (up to the first embrace of Carmen and Joseph); 10th Quartet, second<br />

movement (Adagio ma non troppo): Carmen and Joseph embrace on bank floor, scenes in<br />

the getaway car; 14th Quartet, fifth movement (Presto), final three notes: brief punctuation of<br />

restroom scene; 14th Quartet, sixth movement (Adagio quasi un poco andante): Carmen and


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 79<br />

But often the musical accompaniment to the Carmen story abruptly stops and<br />

then resumes without clear motivation from the plot, such discontinuities in the<br />

score calling attention to the music as an arbitrary, “foreign body” intervening in<br />

the visual image. At the same time, the frequent intermingling of the Quartets and<br />

sound effects forces recognition of music’s participation in a sonic continuum.<br />

The primary non-musical sound effects – ocean waves, traffic noises and seagull<br />

cries – are themselves treated like elements of a musical composition, the ocean<br />

and traffic sounds occasionally merging; ocean waves now surging over the music,<br />

now subsiding to form a background motif; seagull cries appearing sporadically,<br />

sometimes along with wave sounds, sometimes with traffic sounds, sometimes<br />

alone. 15 Visual images of waves and cars occasionally occupy the screen, but the<br />

sounds of ocean, traffic and gulls often are not aligned with their standard visual<br />

counterparts – indeed, in the case of the gull cries, perhaps the most intrusive of<br />

the film’s sound effects, no visual images of seagulls ever appear on screen. 16 As a<br />

result, one becomes aware of the soundtrack as an autonomous sonic milieu, whose<br />

compositional elements are ocean, traffic and gull sounds, dialogue sounds, ambient<br />

sounds of various settings, and passages from the Beethoven Quartets. 17<br />

The ocean, traffic and gull sounds serve as aural punctuation marks, discrete<br />

elements, with little relationship to the plot, that draw attention to the formal<br />

Joseph on the way to the beach apartment; 15th Quartet, third movement (Heiliger Dankgesang<br />

eines Genesenen an die Gottheit, in der lydischen Tonart/ Neue kraft fühlend): Carmen and<br />

Joseph’s romance in the beach apartment, with a reprise of the movement when the two<br />

meet again in Paris; 16th Quartet, first movement (Allegretto): brief passages during hotelroom<br />

quarrel (over Waits ballad); 16th Quartet, second movement (Vivace): Joseph pursuing<br />

Carmen, shower scene; 16th Quartet, third movement (Lento assai, cantante e tranquillo):<br />

quartet performance in hotel dining room; 16th Quartet, fourth movement (Grave ma non<br />

troppo tratto – dramatic tremolo chords): Carmen’s death; 16th Quartet, fourth movement<br />

(Grave ma non troppo tratto): Valet’s closing lines, ocean shot, final credits.<br />

15 Shortly following the last burst of seagull cries, which abruptly and improbably is<br />

heard during a scene in the gang’s Paris hotel room, Joseph transgresses the narrative frame<br />

as he comments, “There wasn’t any sea sound with it” [il y avait pas le bruit de la mer avec]<br />

(AS 60).<br />

16 In an intriguing interview, “Les Mouettes d’Austerlitz: Entretien avec François Musy,”<br />

Cahiers du cinema, 355 (January 1984): 12–17, François Musy, the sound engineer for Prénom<br />

Carmen, says that the seagull sounds were recorded two years before the film was made. He<br />

notes that seagulls cry most distinctly when they are near cliffs, and there was no provision for<br />

sea cliffs in Prénom Carmen. Fortunately, he already had a recording of gulls near sea cliffs<br />

which he used in the film. Of the film’s soundtrack in general, he remarks, “It’s a musical<br />

score in which all the sounds intervene on the same level, like instruments: the dialogue, a sea<br />

ambience, the music … The seagulls, moreover, there it’s already a composition of songs: you<br />

have some that cry louder, you have a sort of movement. The sea as well, even if it’s a little<br />

more linear. The seagulls are already more musical, closer to dialogue” (Musy 14).<br />

17 A full analysis of the sonic elements of the film would require an inventory of the<br />

ambient sounds of the various milieus, which are treated in a very self-conscious fashion.<br />

Especially noteworthy are the exaggerated clankings, thunks and echoing conversations of<br />

the asylum, as well as the traffic sounds outside the room at the Intercontinental Hotel. In both<br />

cases, ambient sounds appear, disappear, swell and subside in improbable fashion.


80<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

patterning of the sonic continuum. In a similar fashion, a discrete set of recurring<br />

images punctuates the visual continuum – images of the ocean, of the sky, of<br />

the headlight patterns of cars on a freeway, of the lighted windows of two metro<br />

trains as they cross one another over the Pont d’Austerlitz, of chandeliers in the<br />

Intercontinental Hotel. These visual punctuation marks, like their aural counterparts,<br />

have a limited relationship to the plot, and the extended duration of the shots of the<br />

waves, clouds, car headlights and metro window lights emphasizes their status as<br />

abstract geometrical forms. Such extra-narrative, geometrically patterned images,<br />

when interjected at unpredictable intervals into the stream of narrative images,<br />

emphasize the formal nature of the visual continuum as a composition of images, a<br />

composition in the process of divesting itself of conventional coding and narrative<br />

organization while becoming a patterning of images “before names.”<br />

Tragedy<br />

Through a series of allusions, Godard suggests a complex relationship between the<br />

use of images, visual and sonic, and the function of tragedy. Late in the film, Godard<br />

cites (without attribution) a line from Rilke’s first Duino Elegy: “You know, beauty<br />

is the beginning of the terror we are capable of enduring [Vous savez, la beauté, c’est<br />

le commencement de la terreur que nous sommes capables de supporter]” (AS 61). 18<br />

As he delivers this line, a close-up of Carmen’s face fills the screen. This shot is one<br />

of eighteen close-ups of Carmen that appear regularly throughout the film, some<br />

for a few seconds, others for extended periods, ranging from thirty to ninety-six<br />

seconds. (The Carmen close-ups constitute a little over eight of the film’s eighty-four<br />

minutes of running time, or about ten per cent of the film.) Several of these close-<br />

18 In her insightful essay on Prénom Carmen, “A Fraying of Voices,” Verena Conley<br />

observes that Godard’s citation of Rilke should read “La beauté n’est que le commencement<br />

de la terreur que nous sommes encore capables de supporter,” given that Rilke’s original<br />

reads: “Denn das Schöne ist nichts/ als des Schrecklichen Anfang, den wir noch gerade<br />

ertragen.” She comments that “the quotation is ‘ill said,’ since through suppression of the<br />

‘encore’ the sentence insists less on a limit, becomes more declarative, but is also stripped of<br />

its possibility of contemplative value by being introduced in a lower mimetic mode. In Rilke,<br />

it refers to the world of absolute beauty or to angels, contrasted with earthen beauty. Terror in<br />

Rilke is of a more absolute kind, that belongs to something celestial … In Godard, the same<br />

values are taken out of context and reversed. The quotation may seem funny, even pompous<br />

in the final, operatic – but also parodic – scene at the Hotel Intercontinental. The terror of<br />

beauty is attributed to the dark, hence diabolical Carmen – who, somewhat comically, is also<br />

said to have been working at a Prisunic – rather than to the angelic Claire (Myriem Roussel)<br />

who rightfully bears her name” (pp. 77–8). I concur that Godard’s citation makes Rilke’s<br />

pronouncement more absolute, but I read the reference differently. Carmen, I argue, is no<br />

longer diabolical when divested of her narrative encoding. I might add that the Carmen–Claire<br />

opposition, while clearly modeled on the Micaëla–Carmen opposition of Bizet, and hence<br />

assimilable within codes of dark/diabolical and light/angelic (reinforced by Godard by the<br />

names of the two women and the association of Carmen with a red rose and Claire with a<br />

white rose), is not reinforced particularly in the visual presentation of the two women, both of<br />

whom have fair skin and dark hair.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 81<br />

ups mark key meditative moments in the film, some of them accompanied by slow,<br />

lyrical passages from the Quartets. By following the verbal associations that are<br />

aligned with the close-ups, one can see what relation terror has to beauty, and what<br />

relation that terror might have to the terror traditionally associated with tragedy.<br />

During her initial meeting with her Uncle Jean in the asylum, Carmen is shown<br />

in close-up for thirty-seven seconds (shot 28) as Godard speaks off-camera of her<br />

mother:<br />

The shore of the sea [Le bord de la mer], with your mother [avec ta mère], like little<br />

Electra. You’re the one who doesn’t remember. I’ve always said that you had a talent for<br />

misfortune [que tu étais douée pour le malheur]. How did that end, “when there’s,” you<br />

know, “all the guilty [les coupables] in one corner, and then, and then, the innocent [les<br />

innocents] in another”? [AS 24]<br />

The reference to Electra, besides adding a second sexual and mythic dimension to the<br />

figure of Carmen, 19 proves primarily to be an allusion to Giraudoux’s Électre, a fact<br />

that becomes evident in the film’s closing shots when the final lines of Giraudoux’s<br />

play are quoted. The pun on mer and mère might invite psychoanalytic associations<br />

of the mother and primal oceanic forces (the linking of the mother and the feminine<br />

here complicated by the murderous hostility Electra exhibits toward Clytemnestra<br />

in the myth), but the pun’s main purpose is to bring together Carmen, the sea, and<br />

Uncle Jean’s reference to the apocalyptic judgment of the guilty and the innocent.<br />

Uncle Jean’s words also recall Carmen’s opening voiceover, when she speaks of<br />

“terrible waves” within (followed by a shot of the sea), and then adds, “I haven’t<br />

been to college, but I also know that the world doesn’t belong to the innocent … [le<br />

monde n’appartient pas aux innocents]” (AS 21). The world she inhabits is not the<br />

beatific realm of the Sermon on the Mount, she suggests, but as we shall see, she is<br />

not necessarily implying that the guilty, or those with a talent for “le malheur,” in the<br />

sense of “evil,” will inherit the earth.<br />

Midway through the film, Carmen recalls her Uncle Jean’s apocalyptic reference.<br />

For fifty-four seconds her face is shown in close-up (shot 119), while the Molto<br />

adagio strains of the 15th Quartet accompany her question to Joseph: “What is it<br />

called? [Comment ça s’appelle?] … There’s something about innocents there … and<br />

then the guilty, over there …” (AS 33). Later, during a forty second close-up (shot<br />

151), she asks Joseph what comes before the name, “avant qu’on vous appelle” (AS<br />

56). At this point, an association of the motifs of the prénom and the division of<br />

guilty and innocent is suggested through the verb appeler, an association whose full<br />

significance only emerges at the close of the film. There, as Carmen is dying, she<br />

asks a waiter, “What is it called [Comment ça s’appelle] when there are the innocents<br />

in one corner and the guilty ones in the other?” (AS 63). The waiter answers, “Je<br />

ne sais pas, mademoiselle” (AS 63). She then elaborates on her question, citing<br />

19 Powrie sees the Electra allusion as a means whereby Carmen is “remythified twice<br />

over” (“Godard’s Prénom Carmen,” p. 72). He gives a Lacanian reading to the sexual<br />

dimension of this allusion, reading the Giraudoux citation at the film’s close both as a<br />

distancing theatricalization of the action and a confirmation of the identity of the mother with<br />

dawn and the prelinguistic Imaginary.


82<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

portions of the penultimate lines of Giraudoux’s Électre: “But if when everyone has<br />

ruined everything, and everything is lost, but the day rises, and the air nonetheless<br />

breathes,” to which the waiter responds with Giraudoux’s final line (and the final line<br />

of Prénom Carmen), “Cela s’appelle l’aurore, Mademoiselle,” “That’s called dawn,<br />

Mademoiselle” (AS 64).<br />

Giraudoux’s play is about a judgmental Électre, an idealist who refuses to<br />

compromise. For her, the world consists of the guilty and the innocent, and she refuses<br />

to taint herself by allowing the crime of Clytemnestre and Égisthe to go unpunished,<br />

even though the circumstances of the murder are uncertain and the future of Thebes<br />

depends on Égisthe’s leadership in the impending battle with the city’s enemies. But<br />

the world is not so neatly divided into guilty and innocent, as La Femme Narsès<br />

implies in the lines Carmen partially cites: “What is it called, when the day rises,<br />

like today, and everything is ruined, everything is pillaged, and nonetheless the air<br />

breathes, and one has lost everything, the city burns, the innocents kill each other [les<br />

innocents s’entre-tuent], but the guilty are in agony [les coupables agonisent], in a<br />

corner of the day that is rising?” 20 When Le Mendiant replies, “That has a very pretty<br />

name [Cela a un très beau nom], Femme Narsès. It’s called dawn,” he suggests that<br />

“dawn” is the name of a world beyond simplistic judgments, a name for possibilities<br />

in the face of universal destruction and ruin. The innocent and guilty alike suffer in<br />

such a world, yet still the day rises, the air breathes, and something new begins.<br />

Unlike Électre, Carmen is no idealist, but she does reinforce the distinct<br />

categories of “innocent” and “guilty” in her discourse. She knows that the world<br />

does not belong to the innocent, and she is obsessed by an apocalyptic separation of<br />

sheep and goats, the innocent in one corner, the guilty in another. Hers is the milieu<br />

of crime, of course, and the cops-and-robbers drama of bank heists and kidnappings<br />

is all about verdicts of innocence and guilt. Indeed, the question of verdicts and<br />

judgments is directly raised in the film’s parodic Tribunal section, in which Joseph<br />

stands trial for his participation in the bank heist. His lawyer indicts capitalism as<br />

the true criminal, stating that his offense is not against “la société” but against “la<br />

Sociéte Générale,” large corporations and “the money of the big banks” (AS 34).<br />

The police, the prosecutor and the judge all support their actions with supposed<br />

aphorisms from Proverbs, and even Joseph counters by citing a reputed passage<br />

from Proverbs.(None of the film’s references to chapter and verse is accurate, and<br />

in fact, the aphorisms are not from Proverbs at all.) The judgments of law and the<br />

judgments of religion coincide, and the question of a Last Judgment raises the<br />

issue of justice and categorization in general. The division of the world into neat<br />

compartments brings with it an ideological classification of reality – in sum, one that<br />

masks the relationship between “la société” and “la Société Générale” and supports<br />

a simplistic differentiation of the innocent from the guilty.<br />

Carmen asks two questions: What does one call the separation of the innocent<br />

and guilty?, and What comes before the name? The two are related, but they are not<br />

the same question. When she is dying, she initially asks the Valet the first question,<br />

which he cannot answer. She then rephrases her query, and in so doing she transforms<br />

20 Jean Giraudoux, Théâtre complet, ed. Jacques Body (Paris, 1982), p. 685<br />

(translation mine).


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 83<br />

the first question into the second. When all is ruined, when categories of innocence<br />

and guilt have been abandoned, when all the judgmental categorizations of the<br />

world have been left behind, then something before categories becomes possible, an<br />

unnamed, unclassified, stark image. The Valet’s answer “cela s’appelle l’aurore” is<br />

a response to the question, “what comes before the name?” The pre-name is called<br />

“dawn,” but its name is merely a designation for the space between, the gap between<br />

night and day, the undecidable moment between dark and light. It is a name for that<br />

which cannot be named. And it is this unnamed, uncategorized world that is the<br />

source of the terrifying beauty Rilke speaks of, beauty that is “the beginning of the<br />

terror we are capable of enduring” (AS 61).<br />

It is important to note that in the film “terror” is not the same as “fear.” In her<br />

opening voiceover, Carmen says “I’m not afraid [Je n’ai pas peur], but that’s because<br />

I have never been able to, known how to, become attached [je n’ai jamais pu, su,<br />

m’attacher]” (AS 21). Throughout the script, there is a play on the words “attacher”<br />

and “détacher,” Joseph’s literal tying and untying of Carmen being related to his<br />

emotional attachment to her and her refusal to be permanently attached to anything.<br />

(A parallel play on the phrases “attirez-moi,” attract me, and “tirez-vous,” go<br />

away, reinforces this motif – see Conley, p. 70.) Carmen has no fear, for she has<br />

no attachments. Joseph, by contrast, does have fear, as Carmen insists. He claims<br />

that the reason he took so long in returning to her after his trial was shame, “j’avais<br />

honte,” “I was ashamed.” But Carmen counters, “Fear, not shame, fear [Peur, pas<br />

honte, peur].” She then asks the Valet, “Are you afraid at times? [Vous avez peur<br />

des fois, vous],” to which he replies, “Never, Mademoiselle” (AS 58). This same<br />

Valet who knows no fear is the one who answers Carmen’s question at the end of the<br />

film. He, like Carmen, it seems, forms no attachments. He can detach himself from<br />

the codes of the world and name the unnamable. He can free himself from fear and<br />

thereby open himself to the terror of beauty.<br />

The unnamable is called “aurore,” but in a sense its name is also “Carmen.” At the<br />

end of her initial voiceover, Carmen adds the phrases, “Got to hurry. Later. The one<br />

who should not be called Carmen [Celle qui ne devrait pas s’appeler Carmen]” (AS<br />

21). When “Uncle Jean” Godard enunciates Rilke’s line that “beauty is the beginning<br />

of the terror we are capable of enduring,” Carmen’s face is in close-up on the screen.<br />

She is the unattached and unattachable, that which cannot be controlled or possessed,<br />

but also that which cannot be categorized. The eighteen close-ups of Carmen spaced<br />

throughout the film are images assimilable within cinematic codes, as well as within<br />

cultural codes of feminine beauty and desirability. The slightly hazy filters and soft<br />

lighting of the close-ups echo faintly the conventions of fashion photography, but<br />

finally Godard’s aim is to detach these images from their conventional moorings,<br />

while at the same time detaching the narrative figure of Carmen from her mythical<br />

coordinates, and to make visible on the screen the pure image of her face. The pure<br />

image in its terrifying beauty “should not be called Carmen” or anything else, but if<br />

it must be given a name, a name before the name, its pre-name would be Carmen.<br />

One way of detaching an image from its codes is to strip it of its name, to divest<br />

it of its associated words, but Godard suggests as well that sounds in general impinge<br />

on images, and hence must be separated from them in order to transform them into<br />

pure images. In Carmen’s initial meeting with Uncle Jean in the asylum, he offers


84<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

to lend her his “new camera” (AS 24), which turns out to be a boom box. He holds<br />

the boom box on his shoulder as if it were a camera and plays a tape recording of<br />

“Frère Jacques” and “Au clair de la lune,” accompanied by background sounds of<br />

breaking crockery, and then sounds of an aerial bombardment. The nursery songs<br />

are performed in a primitive fashion, the melody alone pecked out spasmodically in<br />

shifting registers on an out-of-tune piano. The erratic sounds of the piano keyboard<br />

and Godard’s punching of the boom-box play and stop buttons recall Godard’s earlier<br />

strokes on the typewriter keys, which spell out “mal vu, mal dit” at the bottom of a<br />

page of garbled random letters and symbols. When Carmen asks Uncle Jean if he<br />

would like to start making films again, he replies, “Il faut fermer les yeux au lieu<br />

de les ouvrir,” “You must close the eyes rather than open them” (AS 24). As the<br />

sounds of aerial bombardment increasingly dominate the soundtrack, the boom box<br />

on Godard’s shoulder comes to resemble both a camera and a rocket launcher, and<br />

his haggard, scruffy face resembles that of a shellshock victim who has seen too<br />

much and needs to learn to close his eyes. The implication is that the camera can<br />

be a weapon, as can the tape recorder, and that the violence of visual representation<br />

is reinforced by sonic representations. The world is “mal vu, mal dit,” a page of<br />

meaningless babble, but it is also “mal entendu,” ill heard and ill understood, a tape<br />

of disintegrating nursery songs, breaking dishes and dive-bombing planes. To create<br />

“juste une image,” the image must be detached not only from visual clichés and<br />

verbal codes, but also from its sonic counterparts, and sounds themselves need to<br />

be detached from their conventional associations if they are no longer to be “mal<br />

entendus.”<br />

Music and the Spirit of Tragedy<br />

Godard does indeed separate sight and sound in Prénom Carmen, thereby creating<br />

what Deleuze would call a truly audio-visual modern film. But the status of music<br />

in the film is not simply that of a constituent of the sonic continuum. The sounds of<br />

waves, traffic and seagulls, the ambient noises of the hospital, gas station and hotel,<br />

the dialogue on-camera and off – all are treated as elements of a musical composition.<br />

But if noises and sounds attain to the level of music within a single continuum, the<br />

Beethoven Quartets are not thereby rendered mere noises within an undifferentiated<br />

sonic mix. Godard plays with the conventions of film scores, often undercutting<br />

the narrative by providing the action with incongruent accompaniment from the<br />

Quartets. The juxtaposition of the ebullient 10th Quartet’s Allegro and the bank heist,<br />

for instance, heightens the absurdity of the sequence, and the intensely dramatic<br />

cadences of the 15th Quartet’s third movement render melodramatic Carmen and<br />

Joseph’s reunion in the garage (shots 147 and 148). Yet in neither of these nor in any<br />

of the other instances of an ironic pairing of music and action is the music mocked.<br />

Rather, it is always the image that is not adequate to the music. Godard clearly has<br />

deep affection for the Beethoven Quartets, and though he interrupts the ensemble’s<br />

performance at several points, he also allows the music to continue undisturbed for<br />

extended stretches of time.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 85<br />

There are also a number of sequences in which the music and the images are<br />

not ironically juxtaposed. Throughout the film, when music accompanies shots of<br />

the ocean or close-ups of Carmen, lyrical, slow, highly emotive passages from the<br />

Quartets are used, and at no point does the music undercut the image. Particularly<br />

striking is the use of the third movement of the 15th Quartet during Carmen and<br />

Joseph’s romantic interlude at the beach apartment (shots 92–122). The beginning<br />

of the third movement coincides with the cut to shot 92, a thirty-eight second view<br />

of sea swells shot from above, the calm ebb and flow of the foam-flecked water<br />

gently washing over a small rock as the serene strains of the Molto adagio movement<br />

unfold. Passages from this movement accompany nearly half of the fourteen minutes<br />

of images set at the beach. Three-fourths of the time, the score is matched with shots<br />

of the ocean or close-ups of Carmen. Godard is certainly exploiting conventional<br />

associations of the feminine and the ocean – be it as a figure of the maternal womb<br />

or as a symbol of erotic passion – but the conjunction of Carmen’s face and the sea<br />

to the accompaniment of Beethoven is meant to undo those associations. Godard is<br />

engaged in a pedagogy of images, teaching us to see the images for themselves, and<br />

the score guides us in that lesson. Beethoven titled the opening section of the third<br />

movement “Heiliger Dankgesang eines Genesenen an die Gottheit, in der lydischen<br />

Tonart” (Sacred Song of Thanksgiving to the Godhead on a Convalescence, in the<br />

Lydian Mode), and its mood of quiet, meditative tranquility suffuses the entire<br />

beach sequence. Its modal tonality, as one commentator observes, produces “an<br />

atmosphere of mysterious and other-worldly remoteness,” an “atmosphere of<br />

Olympian contemplation” as well as an “extraordinary feeling of timelessness.” 21<br />

For the thirty-eight seconds of shot 92, we watch the wash of waves and listen to<br />

the Quartet, as if we were being instructed, “learn to see this image itself, learn<br />

to see it with the calm, serenity and harmony of the music that accompanies it.”<br />

When Carmen’s face comes on screen, the same score reinforces a similar lesson:<br />

“learn to see this face as you saw the ocean, not as a maternal or an erotic object<br />

but as a simple image.” The music does not illustrate or represent the images, but it<br />

establishes a mood and imbues the images with an affective intensity. The music’s<br />

slow tempo and the extended duration of the shots of Carmen and the ocean – shots<br />

in which visually nothing happens – together encourage contemplation. Narrative is<br />

suspended, and a timeless time allows images to emerge as forms of a visual music.<br />

To render visible the image itself requires a detachment of the image from its<br />

usual coordinates and an invention of new relationships with other images. The<br />

principle of this practice is indirectly suggested by Godard toward the close of the<br />

film, when Uncle Jean’s Nurse reads to him a phrase from Beethoven’s Tagebuch:<br />

“The perfect union of several voices entirely impedes the progress of one toward<br />

the other” (AS 62, Notebook entry no. 2). In music as in cinema, the strict unison of<br />

elements impedes the movement of elements toward one another. Only by undoing<br />

the unities and uniformities of conventional relations can new relations be forged.<br />

The separation and recombination of voices is a principle governing images, words,<br />

sounds and music in Prénom Carmen, one that makes of the film a stratigraphic<br />

layering of visual and sonic elements. Yet music still has a privileged position within<br />

21 Philip Radcliffe, Beethoven’s String Quartets (London, 1965), pp. 116–17.


86<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

these elements. What Schopenhauer finds in music is a strange sensual abstraction,<br />

a direct presentation of an affective geometry of forms immanent within things. A<br />

similar intuition informs Nietzsche’s approach to tragedy as the outgrowth of the<br />

spirit of music. And Deleuze’s sense of music in the classic cinema as the direct<br />

presentation of the open Whole likewise springs from this intuition. For Deleuze, the<br />

modern cinema gives sound a new function as the visual and the sonic are detached<br />

from one another and recombined in new relations, but it seems that music – even<br />

traditional tonal art music – already has within it a force of affective detachment and<br />

rearticulation present in the most conventional of films. Godard subverts codes and<br />

narratives, undermines visual and sonic conventions, but he accepts Beethoven and<br />

allows the Quartets to serve as the milieu within which the film takes shape. If there<br />

is a dominant spirit to Prénom Carmen, it is that of the Beethoven score.<br />

In Nietzsche’s view, tragedy makes bearable our terror at the destruction and<br />

dissolution of all material forms. In music, we are able to embrace the incessant<br />

forces of creation that give rise to forms, break them apart, and then refashion them<br />

in new configurations. Ultimately, the spirit of music for Nietzsche is the spirit of<br />

the artist-god, the “world-child Zeus” at play in his world-making, now building,<br />

now destroying, with an equally serene joy in his activity. 22 It is difficult to decide<br />

whether Godard finally subscribes to Rilke’s view that beauty is the commencement<br />

of the terror we can endure, since little in Godard is offered without ironic distance<br />

and qualification. I have argued that the revelation of the pure image brings with<br />

it the terror of disequilibrium and disorientation, but one might argue as well that<br />

Godard’s Rilkean reference is to the terroristic violence of conventional aesthetic<br />

codes. The creative spirit of the artist-god, however, seems to me to be undeniably<br />

present in Prénom Carmen. The Olympian serenity of the 15th Quartet’s Molto<br />

adagio movement suffuses the film, as does the poised playfulness that surfaces<br />

from time to time in the late Quartets. The coda of Beethoven’s last Quartet, with<br />

its pizzicato chords and light, gay tune, brings Godard’s film to its conclusion, as<br />

a final shot of the sea comes on the screen. The cheerful seriousness of the playful<br />

creator, that expansive spirit of deep feeling and distant reflection so evident in the<br />

late Quartets (as in The Tempest, I would argue), is ultimately the controlling mood<br />

of Godard’s film. Prénom Carmen is no tragedy, but if Nietzsche’s spirit of tragedy<br />

is that of the artist-creator, and if that spirit is also the spirit of music, then this film,<br />

like tragedy, is born of the spirit of music.<br />

22 I take this phrase from Nietzsche’s account of Heraclitus’s cosmos in Philosophy in<br />

the Tragic Age of the Greeks, trans. Marianne Cowan (Chicago, 1962), p. 67. In Heraclitus’s<br />

view of the universe, “only play, play as artists and children engage in it, exhibits coming-tobe<br />

and passing away, structuring and destroying, without any moral additive, in forever equal<br />

innocence. And as children and artists play, so plays the ever-living fire … Such is the game<br />

that the aeon plays with itself. Transforming itself into water and earth, it builds towers of<br />

sand like a child at the seashore, piles them up and tramples them down … The child throws<br />

its toys away from time to time – and starts again, in innocent caprice. But when it does build,<br />

it combines and joins and forms its structures regularly, conforming to inner laws” (p. 62).


Music and Modernity<br />

Deleuze says of Prénom Carmen that it<br />

Tragedy, Sight and Sound 87<br />

… uses musical movements, acts of speech, noises of doors, sounds of the sea or the<br />

metro, cries of gulls, pluckings of strings and revolver shots, slidings of bows and<br />

bursts of machine-gun fire, the “attack” of music and the “attack” in the bank, the<br />

correspondences between these elements, and above all their displacements, their cuts, in<br />

such a way as to form the power [puissance] of a single and self-same sonic continuum.<br />

[IT 305/234–5]<br />

That continuum becomes a fourth dimension of the visual image, in which the sonic<br />

elements “rival one another, cover one another, traverse each other, cut into each<br />

other,” while they simultaneously “trace a path full of obstacles in the visual space,<br />

and they do not make themselves heard without also being seen, for themselves,<br />

independently of their sources, at the same time that they make the image readable,<br />

a little like a musical score” (IT 305/235). Yet Prénom Carmen also makes use of<br />

Western tonal art music in a way that links the film to the classic cinema, its quartet<br />

score functioning as does music in Nietzsche’s conception of tragedy – as Deleuze<br />

phrases it, “like the kernel of fire that surrounds the Apollonian visual images,<br />

and which cannot do without their unfolding parade.” In Godard’s film, as in the<br />

classic cinema, “one may say that music adds the immediate image [of the Whole]<br />

to the mediate images that represent the Whole indirectly” (IT 311/239). What this<br />

suggests, finally, is that music provides common ground for the classic and modern<br />

cinema. Perhaps cinema as a whole, like tragedy, has one of its points of origin in the<br />

spirit of music – the generative ear latent in the eye.<br />

Appendix Prénom Carmen Citations from Beethoven’s Tagebuch of 1812–18<br />

Ceci, je le sens bien. Je le reconnais clairement. La vie n’est pas le bien suprême.<br />

Parmi les maux, le mal suprême c’est la faute. [spoken by Claire]<br />

#118: Dieß Eine fühl’ ich und erkenn’ es klar:<br />

Das Leben ist der Güter höchstes nicht,<br />

Der Uibel größtes aber ist die Schuld.<br />

This one thing I feel and clearly perceive:<br />

Life is not the sovereign good,<br />

But the greatest evil is guilt.<br />

[Schiller, Die Braut von Messina, closing lines]


88<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Agis au lieu de demander. [spoken by Claire]<br />

Fais d’abord des miracles, si tu veux les dévoiler, ainsi seulement tu accompliras<br />

toute ta destinée. [spoken by Claire]<br />

#60: Nicht Fragen, Thaten sollst du spenden, [;] dich selber opfern<br />

[,] ohne Ruhm und Lohn? [!] –Erst übe Wunder, willst du sie enthüllen; und [nur]<br />

so kannst du dein Daseyn nur [ganz] erfüllen.<br />

[Robert] You shall dispense not questions but deeds,<br />

Sacrifice yourself without fame and reward!<br />

If you wish to unveil miracles, first practice them;<br />

Only thus can you fulfill your existence.<br />

[excerpt from Zacharias Werner, Die Söhne des Thals, I. Theil: Die Templer auf<br />

Cypern (Berlin, 1802), Act IV, scene i.]<br />

Prendre la première phrase venue construite sur l’harmonie. [spoken by First<br />

Violinist]<br />

#37: Den ersten besten Satz in Canons erfunden auf Harmonie gebaut. [The<br />

words “in Canons” are crossed out, with dots underneath to signify “stet.”]<br />

The best opening phrases in canons are built around harmonies.<br />

Montre ta puissance, Destin. Nous ne sommes pas nos propres maîtres. Ce qui est<br />

décidé … qu’il en soit ainsi. [spoken by Claire]<br />

#73: Zeige deine Gewalt Schicksal! Wir sind nicht Herrn über uns selbst; was<br />

beschlossen ist, muß seyn, und so sey es dann [?denn]! – –<br />

Show your power, Fate! We are not masters of ourselves; what has been decided<br />

must be, and so be it!<br />

[Possibly a quotation (source unknown)]<br />

Tout vérifier le soir. [spoken by Claire]<br />

#4: alle Abends durchsehn.<br />

Look through them all in the evening.<br />

Et les nuages … les nuages feraient-ils voir des torrents de vie? [spoken by Claire]<br />

#6: Und regneten die Wolken Lebensbäche, nie wird der Weidenbaum dir<br />

Datteln tragen.


Tragedy, Sight and Sound 89<br />

And even if the clouds were to rain rivers of life<br />

Never will the willow tree bear dates.<br />

[Herder, “Verschwendete Mühe,” Zerstreute Blätter. 4th ed. (Gotha, 1792), p. 27]<br />

L’union parfaite de plusieurs voix empêche somme toute le progrès de l’une vers<br />

l’autre. [spoken by Godard’s Nurse]<br />

#2: Die genaue Zusammenhaltung mehrerer Stimmen hindert im Großen das<br />

Fortschreiten einer zur andern.<br />

The precise coinciding of several musical voices generally hinders the progression<br />

from one to the other.<br />

German citations of the Tagebuch from Maynard Solomon, “Beethoven’s Tagebuch<br />

of 1812–1818,” in Beethoven Studies 3, ed. Alan Tyson (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1982), pp. 193–293. English translations and commentary by<br />

Solomon.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 6<br />

Bergsonian Fabulation<br />

and the People to Come<br />

In a 1990 interview, Deleuze addresses the question of the relationship of politics<br />

to art via a reflection on the modern problem of the “creation of a people.” The<br />

artists Deleuze admires (he names here Mallarmé, Rimbaud, Klee, Berg, Huillet<br />

and Straub) have a deep need of a people, but the collectivity they invoke does<br />

not yet exist – the “people are missing [le peuple manque]” (PP 235/174). Artists<br />

cannot themselves create a people, and the people in their struggles cannot concern<br />

themselves directly with art, but when a people begins to take form, an interactive<br />

process emerges that connects art and the people:<br />

When a people is created [se crée: literally, “creates itself”], it does so through its own<br />

means, but in a way that rejoins something in art … or in such a way that art rejoins that<br />

which it lacks. Utopia is not a good concept: rather, there is a “fabulation” common to the<br />

people and to art. We should take up again the Bergsonian notion of fabulation and give it<br />

a political sense. [PP 235/174]<br />

Deleuze nowhere elaborates at length on the idea of fabulation, but it forms part of<br />

a rich complex of concepts central to his approach to the ethics and politics of art.<br />

It also is a rather elusive concept, which is Bergsonian only in a special sense that<br />

deserves some investigation.<br />

Closed and Open Societies<br />

On initial consideration, Bergson’s fabulation must seem antithetical to Deleuze’s,<br />

for its Bergsonian associations are basically negative, its Deleuzian largely positive.<br />

Bergson first makes use of the concept in his late The Two Sources of Morality and<br />

Religion (1932), fabulation serving a key function in what Bergson labels closed<br />

societies. 1 Ethical theory commonly assumes a continuum of values from love of<br />

family, to love of society, and eventually to a love of mankind, but Bergson argues for<br />

a qualitative difference in nature (not degree) between a love of family and society,<br />

1 The French “fabulation” is a rather uncommon word of recent provenance. Its first<br />

use documented in Robert’s Dictionnaire is from Balzac’s 1839 Curé de village, its sense<br />

being that of an “imaginary representation, fanciful [romanesque, that is, novel-like] version<br />

of a set of facts.” By 1905, psychologists had adopted the word to denote the production of<br />

imaginary or false stories, associating it with mythomania and pathological lying. Robert cites<br />

Bergson’s Two Sources as the first philosophical use of the word, its meaning being “activity<br />

of the imagination.”


92<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

manifest in closed societies, and a love of mankind, which only appears upon the<br />

envisioning of an alternative social order, that of an open society. The essence of any<br />

social organization resides in the coordinated functioning of individuals in relation<br />

to a whole, a functioning roughly analogous to that of cells within a single organism.<br />

Social organization is widespread in nature, with two evolutionary tendencies in<br />

social life represented by the extremes of hymenoptera (bees, wasps, ants) and<br />

Homo sapiens. The coordinated functioning of individuals within insect societies<br />

is regulated primarily by instinct, whereas intelligence largely guides individuals’<br />

co-functioning within human societies. Instinct and intelligence, however, are<br />

not entirely separate from one another in their social function, a certain degree of<br />

intelligence being present in insect instinct, a degree of instinct permeating human<br />

intelligence. And both instinct and intelligence serve a fundamental social purpose:<br />

“Social life is thus immanent, like a vague ideal, in instinct as well as in intelligence;<br />

this ideal finds its most complete realization in the hive or the anthill on one hand,<br />

and in human societies on the other.” 2<br />

Insect societies are relatively fixed in their structure, the configuration of relations<br />

among individuals being dictated by instinct, whereas human societies vary in their<br />

mode of organization, that variation stemming from the utilization of intelligence<br />

in the development and perpetuation of social structures. Individual insects have<br />

a minimal autonomy in relation to society, the result being that insect societies<br />

are highly stable but extremely limited in their mode of organization. Conversely,<br />

individual humans have a great deal of social autonomy, and as a result humans can<br />

use their intelligence to construct a wide range of divergent social systems. The cost<br />

of such flexibility in social organization, however, is one of instability. The autonomy<br />

of individuals in human societies, made possible by the development of intelligence,<br />

threatens to dissolve social bonds entirely. That which counters the tendency toward<br />

social dissolution in humans is what Bergson calls a “virtual instinct” (p. 998/28),<br />

a basic sense of moral obligation that individuals feel towards others. This virtual<br />

instinct dictates no specific behavior; rather, it serves as an unspecified force guiding<br />

intelligence in its social operation. Hence, the moral “ought” has its source in no<br />

rational or transcendent principle, but in the natural evolution of humans as a social<br />

species.<br />

A general sense of obligation towards others ensures social cohesion, but the<br />

extension of that sense is naturally limited, for one of the basic functions of a<br />

society is that of collective self-defense: “Who does not see that social cohesion is<br />

due, in large part, to the necessity for a society to defend itself against others, and<br />

that it is first against all other men that one loves the men with whom one lives?”<br />

(p. 1002/32–3). Although intelligence allows flexibility in the formation of social<br />

structures, it tends to fashion “closed societies,” whose essential characteristic is<br />

“to include at each moment a certain number of individuals, and to exclude others”<br />

2 Henri Bergson, Oeuvres, Edition du Centenaire, ed. André Robinet (Paris, 1959), p.<br />

997, The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, trans. R. Ashley Audra and Cloudsley Brereton<br />

(Garden City, NY, 1954), p. 27. Translations from Bergson are my own. Page references are<br />

to the French text, followed by the corresponding pages in Audra and Brereton’s English<br />

translation.


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 93<br />

(p. 1000/30). Hence, “the social instinct that we have perceived at the foundation of<br />

social obligation always aims – instinct being relatively unchangeable – at a closed<br />

society, however large it may be” (p. 1001/32). A love of all humanity, therefore,<br />

cannot develop directly out of a love of family and city (or nation), for such a<br />

universal love presumes the existence of an “open society,” one whose constitutive<br />

principle would be qualitatively different from that of closed societies.<br />

Closed societies are basically static. They are regulated by habit and custom, by<br />

those timeworn assumptions, practices and institutions that function like instincts,<br />

rendering social life automatic and somnambulistic. Language is a repository of such<br />

habits, customs, and their attendant social obligations, and religion in closed societies<br />

serves to reinforce static patterns of behavior. A central component of religion<br />

in closed societies is “fabulation” (rendered by Bergson’s English translators as<br />

“myth-making”), which Bergson characterizes as the act whereby the “fantasmatic<br />

representations” (p. 1066/108) of spirits, forces and gods are brought forth. Bergson<br />

insists that fabulation is not related to religion as cause to effect – in other words,<br />

that religion is not simply the product of humankind’s heated imagination. Rather,<br />

he sees religion as the “raison d’être of the fabulative function” (p. 1067/108–109),<br />

and both religion and fabulation as means of reinforcing social cohesion in closed<br />

societies.<br />

Fabulation is an action of the intelligence, yet its basic function is to counteract<br />

tendencies that are inherent in intelligence itself. On its own, intelligence does not<br />

necessarily conclude that the individual’s actions should support the common good;<br />

indeed, intelligence often reasons that self-interest should prevail over collective<br />

interests, and hence intelligence tends to undermine social obligations. Intelligence<br />

also establishes cause-and-effect relations, and thereby gives the individual a limited<br />

vision of the future. As a result, intelligence inevitably leads humans to foresee their<br />

own death, which has the unfortunate consequence of inducing despair. Finally,<br />

intelligence brings awareness of the limitations of human powers, for the same<br />

faculty that guides purposive rational action recognizes as well that means do not<br />

always fulfill their ends, that the hunter’s arrow, though intended to kill the deer,<br />

does not always find its mark. Religion counters intelligence’s anti-social tendency,<br />

as well as its tendency to induce despair through its recognition of the individual’s<br />

mortality and powerlessness. Fabulation is an operation of the intelligence that<br />

supports religion’s function. The role of the fabulative function, “which belongs to<br />

intelligence yet nonetheless is not pure intelligence,” is “to elaborate that religion<br />

… which we call static.” Such a religion is “a defensive reaction of nature against<br />

that which might be depressing for the individual, and dissolvent for society, in the<br />

exercise of intelligence” (p. 1150/205).<br />

Static religion instills social obligation through divinely sanctioned actions and<br />

enforced taboos. It counters the despair created through an awareness of one’s death<br />

by inducing belief in immortal spirits, and it checks the depressing recognition of<br />

one’s impotence by positing supernatural intentions in nature that individuals can<br />

attempt to utilize, placate, defer, overcome, and so on. Fabulation goes hand in<br />

hand with religion in creating the myths of forces, spirits and deities that foster<br />

social cohesion and individual contentment (the social and individual functions of<br />

religion, finally, being inseparable and mutually reinforcing, since stable societies


94<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

require stable, relatively content individuals [p. 1144/198–9]). The myths created<br />

through fabulation are products of an “intellectual instinct,” in that such myths are<br />

“representations formed naturally by intelligence, in order to protect itself, through<br />

certain beliefs, from certain dangers of knowledge” (p. 1112/162).<br />

Hallucination and Emotion<br />

At this point, we might wonder what Deleuze could find appealing in the concept of<br />

fabulation, if fabulation’s primary function is to produce closed, static societies in<br />

which habit, custom and common sense enforce somnambulistic rounds of repetitive<br />

behavior. A partial response lies in fabulation’s associations with hallucinations and<br />

vertiginous disruptions in experience. Bergson offers two intriguing anecdotes to<br />

delve into the workings of fabulation. The first concerns a woman who approached<br />

her apartment elevator with the intention of descending to the ground floor. Normally,<br />

the outer gate to the elevator shaft would not open if the car had not stopped at that<br />

floor, but the elevator was not functioning properly, and the gate was open even<br />

though the car was stationed on a flight below. As she walked toward the gate,<br />

she suddenly felt herself thrust backward; she confusedly sensed that the elevator<br />

operator had appeared before her and pushed her away. When she emerged from<br />

her startled state, she found that neither guard nor elevator car were there: “She had<br />

been about to throw herself into the void: a miraculous hallucination had saved her<br />

life” (pp. 1076–77/120). Fabulation, says Bergson, is something like the woman’s<br />

hallucination, a protective illusion that saves us from the void of social dissolution<br />

and individual despair.<br />

The second anecdote comes from William James, who tells of his experience<br />

during the San Francisco earthquake of April 1906. James reports that in the<br />

preceding December, as he left Harvard for Stanford, his friend B. had joked that<br />

he hoped James would “get a touch of earthquake” at Stanford so that he might<br />

“also become acquainted with that Californian institution” (p. 1105/154). 3 When<br />

the earthquake struck, James says, “my first consciousness was one of gleeful<br />

recognition of the nature of the movement. ‘By Jove,’ I said to myself, ‘here’s B.’s<br />

old earthquake, after all!’ And then, as it went crescendo, ‘And a jolly good one it<br />

is, too!’ I said” (p. 1105/154). Throughout the earthquake, James felt no fear, only<br />

“glee and admiration” (p. 1106/154). He experienced the earthquake as an individual<br />

entity, “B.’s old earthquake,” and as one that had come directly to him personally:<br />

“Animus and intent were never more present in any human action, nor did any<br />

human activity ever more definitely point back to a living agent as its source and<br />

origin” (p. 1106/155). Bergson argues that James’s response to the earthquake was<br />

a manifestation of the fabulative function, which, far from being present only in a<br />

“primitive mentality,” persists as a basic component of human thought. The shock<br />

of the event induces awe, elation and a spontaneous, natural attribution of intention<br />

and personhood to the earthquake. Yet, Bergson insists, this intentional entity is not<br />

3 Throughout my discussion of James’s anecdote, I cite the English translation of Two<br />

Sources, which directly quotes James’s original text.


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 95<br />

a fully formed personality; rather, “the living agent is here the earthquake itself”<br />

(p. 1107/156), this particular event, no more and no less. It is an individual event,<br />

to which have been added intention and a basic humanness that provide a bond<br />

between the event and the individual experiencing it. In James’s anecdote, we see<br />

fabulation in its barest, simplest form. Intelligence, “impelled by instinct, transforms<br />

the situation. It brings forth the image that reassures. It gives to the Event a unity<br />

and an individuality which make of the event a being that is malicious or perhaps<br />

mischievous, but a being similar to us, with something of the sociable and human<br />

about it” (p. 1109/158).<br />

Bergson observes that when fiction moves us, it is “like a nascent hallucination:<br />

it can counteract judgment and reasoning, which are the properly intellectual<br />

faculties” (p. 1067/109). A fiction, “if its image is vivid and haunting [obsédante],<br />

may precisely imitate perception, and thereby prevent or modify action” (p.<br />

1067/109). The function of fabulation is to support religion in fashioning a closed<br />

society, and thereby overcome those tendencies inherent in intelligence that dissolve<br />

social bonds. Religion’s proper sphere is action (unlike philosophy, whose primary<br />

domain is thought [p. 1148/203]), and the purpose of fabulation is to impel humans<br />

to act in accordance with religious dictates, which themselves come into existence in<br />

order to ensure socially cohesive action. Fabulation thus fulfills its ends by creating<br />

hallucinatory fictions – vivid, haunting images that imitate perception and induce<br />

action, and thereby counteract the operations of judgment and reason.<br />

Fabulation, then, emerges in the shock of an event, a vertiginous moment of<br />

disorientation in which images bypass reason and work directly on the senses to induce<br />

action. All these aspects of fabulation Deleuze takes up in his own appropriation of<br />

the concept. But in his approach to fabulation he also echoes Bergsonian motifs<br />

associated with fabulation’s opposite: creative emotion. Bergson argues that the<br />

traditional concept of imagination can be misleading, for it encourages the attribution<br />

of fabulation and genuine artistic creation to the same faculty, whereas the two stem<br />

from qualitatively different processes. To delve into the nature of true creativity,<br />

Bergson notes first that writers, for example, most often adopt ready-made concepts<br />

and words, which have been supplied by society, combine them perhaps in new<br />

configurations, but largely add nothing new to the stock of language or its expressive<br />

possibilities. Those rare writers who genuinely create, by contrast, work from a<br />

generative, unique emotion that impels the expression of the ineffable, that pushes<br />

the writer “to forge words, to create ideas,” “to do violence to words, to strain the<br />

elements of language,” and if successful, to fashion “a thought capable of taking on<br />

a new aspect for each new generation” (p. 1191/254).<br />

Emotions are involved in both ordinary composition and genuine creation, but they<br />

are of two qualitatively different types, “infra-intellectual” and “supra-intellectual.”<br />

An infra-intellectual emotion is “a consequence of an idea or a represented image” (p.<br />

1011/43); it is a conventionally coded feeling stirred by an independent intellectual<br />

representation. By contrast, a supra-intellectual emotion “is not determined by a<br />

representation which it follows and from which it is distinct”; rather, it is “pregnant<br />

with representations, no one of which is actually formed, but which it draws or might<br />

draw from its substance by an organic development” (p. 1012/43–44). In short,<br />

“alongside the emotion which is the effect of a representation and which is added to


96<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

it, there is the emotion which precedes representation, which contains it virtually and<br />

which to a certain point is its cause” (p. 1014/47). Every great artist invents a new<br />

emotion in producing an artwork, and, indeed, a new emotion is “at the origin of the<br />

great creations of art, science and civilization in general” (p. 1011/43).<br />

Each inventive, supra-intellectual emotion ultimately is a manifestation of<br />

élan vital, the force of natura naturans that creates the new. Creative emotion’s<br />

basic principles are joy, liberation and movement, and the great mystics are those<br />

who most fully engage that élan vital. Mystics, Bergson insists, are not passive<br />

and contemplative, but active proponents of a religion and a society qualitatively<br />

different from those associated with fabulation. The great mystics embrace a religion<br />

of universal love among all humanity and all creation, and that love serves as the<br />

basis of an open society that is dynamic and liberating.<br />

There are thus two sources of morality and religion, as Bergson’s title indicates,<br />

one, the “virtual instinct” associated with fabulation that leads to a morality of<br />

obligation and a closed society, the other, the creative emotion of élan vital that<br />

points toward a morality of love and an open society. The first is a means by which<br />

nature overcomes itself, in that the virtual instinct counteracts intelligence’s natural<br />

tendency to engender individual despair and social dissolution. Yet the second is also<br />

a means by which nature overcomes itself, in that creative emotion is a manifestation<br />

of nature’s own creative impulse, which breaks the hold of the virtual instinct and<br />

makes possible a new social and moral order. The fundamental principle of élan vital<br />

is creation, the dynamic inventive becoming of the new, and through mystics that<br />

principle finds expression in the vision of a creative self-formation of human society.<br />

There is no gradual transformation from a closed to an open society, for they stem<br />

from qualitatively different principles. Rather, the possibility of an open society only<br />

emerges as “a leap forward [un bond en avant]” (p. 1038/74), a break from the<br />

closed circle of what seems possible and a disconcerting jump into the apparently<br />

impossible, which, however, brings forth its own possibility in its very movement.<br />

Deleuze, like Bergson, sees artistic invention as a manifestation of a general<br />

process of cosmic creation, and he also views genuine artistic creativity as an<br />

affective activity, “desire” and “desiring production” functioning in Deleuze’s<br />

treatments of the arts as rough counterparts of Bergson’s “creative emotion.” 4<br />

Echoes of Deleuze’s notion of a minor use of language are especially evident in<br />

Bergson’s account of the writer’s effort to do violence to words and strain them in<br />

order to forge new concepts and new modes of sensibility. For Bergson, genuine<br />

creativity leads toward an open, liberating, dynamically ever-becoming society, and<br />

the future collectivity Deleuze hopes to engender might be characterized in the same<br />

terms. Yet Bergson subordinates art to religion, using artistic invention to explain<br />

the process whereby the mystic creatively envisions an open society; and he regards<br />

mystics as rare individuals who foster the formation of an open society by serving<br />

as models for emulation by others. Deleuze, by contrast, has no particular interest in<br />

religion, though he is deeply concerned with art’s social and political function; and<br />

4 The association of artistic creation and cosmic creation is especially evident in A<br />

Thousand Plateaus, Plateau 11: Of the Refrain. For a discussion of this matter, see Chapters<br />

One and Three of my Deleuze on Music, Painting, and the Arts (New York, 2003).


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 97<br />

if he is interested in the individual artist, it is primarily as a vehicle for the formation<br />

of a people – that is, an active collectivity that shapes itself and thereby fashions<br />

new modes of social existence. Bergson also separates fabulation from genuine<br />

creation, whereas Deleuze conjoins the two. When Bergson relates the anecdotes of<br />

the woman approaching the elevator shaft and of James experiencing the earthquake,<br />

his primary aim is to show that such moments of disequilibrium reveal, beneath the<br />

veneer of modern rationality, an automatic, virtually instinctual, fabulative function<br />

that is evident in the belief systems of what are often called “primitive” peoples.<br />

For Bergson, the “leap forward” of genuine creation is unrelated to the shock of the<br />

event which induces fabulation. For Deleuze, however, the leap forward is the shock<br />

of the event, and fabulation is part of the genuinely creative process that makes of<br />

the event the occasion for the invention of a people to come.<br />

The People to Come<br />

Although Deleuze mentions fabulation in his early writings on Bergson, he only<br />

makes the concept part of his own work around 1985. In his seminal 1956 article<br />

“The Concept of Difference in Bergson,” he devotes just one sentence to fabulation<br />

(ID 58/41), and in Bergsonism (1966), though he offers a lucid description of<br />

fabulation, it is only as part of a brief account of creative emotion as the means<br />

whereby intuition comes to full awareness of the workings of élan vital (B 111–<br />

19/106–13). Nonetheless, the broad concerns Deleuze later takes up in the concept<br />

of fabulation are of long standing in his thought, dating at least to the inception of<br />

his collaboration with Guattari. Two motifs from Anti-Oedipus (1972) are especially<br />

germane, both of which are initially articulated by Guattari in the 1960s. The first is<br />

the irreducibly social nature of desire, which manifests itself in the desiring subject’s<br />

hallucination of history: “beyond the Ego,” writes Guattari in 1966, “the subject finds<br />

itself exploded to the four corners of the historical universe; the delirious subject [le<br />

délirant] begins to speak foreign languages, it hallucinates history: class conflict,<br />

wars become its instruments of expression” (PT 155/27–8). The second motif is<br />

that of the group-subject, as opposed to the subjected group, a concern voiced by<br />

Guattari as early as 1962 (PT 42) and prominent throughout his activist engagement<br />

with institutional psychiatry. Unlike the subjected group, which receives its identity<br />

from outside, struggles against “any possible inscription of non-sense” (PT 53), and<br />

imposes hierarchical, fixed roles on its members, the group-subject forms itself from<br />

within, keeps itself open to other groups, and offers fluid and shifting roles for its<br />

members.<br />

In Anti-Oedipus, the desiring subject is said to pass through a series of intensive<br />

states and to identify “the names of history with those states: all the names of history<br />

are me” (AO 28/21). All investment of desire, Deleuze and Guattari insist, “is<br />

social, and in every regard concerns a social historical field” (AO 409/342). When<br />

the desiring subject “hallucinates and raves universal history, and proliferates the<br />

races” (AO 101/85), not only does desire reveal its social nature, but it also shows<br />

itself to be inseparable from the formation of a collectivity. “All delirium is racial”<br />

(AO 101/85), in that all desire concerns social groups, either the cursed races, in


98<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Rimbaud’s phrase, “inferior for all eternity” (AO 102/86), or the superior races of<br />

racist fantasy. The delirium of the cursed races is a manifestation of revolutionary,<br />

“schizo” desire, a desire to “become other” and form a new collectivity, whereas the<br />

delirium of the superior races is an expression of paranoid desire, which seeks to<br />

construct and perpetuate social structures of privilege and oppression. Revolutionary<br />

desire fosters the creation of group-subjects, whose internal relational patterns are<br />

shifting and “transverse,” “forever mortal,” “without hierarchy or group super-ego”<br />

(AO 417–18/348–9) whereas paranoid desire permeates the subjected groups of<br />

control and domination.<br />

When Deleuze and Guattari cite Nietzsche’s delirious remark in his letter to<br />

Burckhardt that “every name in history is I,” 5 or when they refer to Schreber’s mad<br />

ramblings about Germans, Aryans, Jews, Catholics, Slavs, Jesuits and Mongols<br />

(AO 106–107/89), they do so to stress both desire’s sociopolitical dimension and<br />

its irreducible non-rationality. The language of psychosis offers them a vocabulary<br />

of affective engagement with the social, yet one that affords a certain lucidity, in<br />

that it provides diagnostic tools for discerning historical and political investments of<br />

collective desire. The phantasmagoric talk of races, superior or accursed, finally is<br />

a means of discussing the primary task of schizoanalytic politics, that of forming an<br />

active, self-determining collective – in short, that of inventing a people.<br />

In Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature (1975) Deleuze and Guattari directly take<br />

up the topic of “the people” and relate it specifically to the arts. In a diary entry<br />

dated 25 December 1911, Kafka states that in the literature of a small group, such as<br />

that of the Czechs or Yiddish-speaking Jews, “literature is less a concern of literary<br />

history than of the people.” 6 Deleuze and Guattari argue that such is the case of all<br />

“minor literature,” and that one of Kafka’s chief goals as a minor writer is to foster<br />

the invention of a people. The collective consciousness of a minor people, in Kafka’s<br />

words, is “often unrealized in public life and always tending to disintegrate” (vol.<br />

1, p. 193), yet for that very reason literature has an “enunciative function” that is<br />

“collective, and even revolutionary” (K 31/17). And should the writer be “on the<br />

margins or outside of his fragile community, this situation gives him all the more<br />

opportunity to express another potential community, to forge the means for another<br />

consciousness and another sensibility” (K 31–2/17).<br />

In a minor literature, there is no speaking subject, only “collective assemblages<br />

of enunciation,” and a minor literature expresses these assemblages “as diabolic<br />

powers to come or as revolutionary forces to be constructed” (K 33/18). In the<br />

absence of a fully formed and functional community, the artist can only disclose<br />

the lines of potential collective development that are immanent within the present<br />

social field. In Kafka’s case, especially in The Trial, he presents the power relations<br />

of juridical, economic, political, religious and libidinal existence in the Austro-<br />

Hungarian empire, and then sets them in disequilibrium, warping them and mutating<br />

them in order to reveal the “diabolical powers to come” (those manifest later in<br />

5 Friedrich Nietzsche, Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche, trans. Christopher<br />

Middleton (Chicago, IL, 1969), p. 347.<br />

6 Franz Kafka, The Diaries of Franz Kafka, ed. Max Brod, trans. Joseph Kresh (New<br />

York, 1948), vol. 1, p. 193.


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 99<br />

the bureaucratic regimes of Stalinist Russia, Nazi Germany and capitalist America),<br />

while at the same time suggesting potential developmental lines for positive, fluid<br />

modes of social interaction. In Deleuze and Guattari’s analysis, Kafka, the lone<br />

artist, is not the speaking subject of The Trial, nor is the future community somehow<br />

the speaking subject; rather, “the actual [writer] and the virtual community – both<br />

of them real – are pieces of a collective assemblage” (K 150/84). The Trial is a<br />

machine, whose parts include the actual writer and the virtual community, and K in<br />

the novel is the function that brings these parts together. K is the<br />

… general functioning of a polyvocal assemblage of which the solitary individual is one<br />

part, the approaching collectivity another part, another cog – without our knowing yet<br />

what kind of assemblage it is: fascist? revolutionary? socialist? capitalist? or perhaps all at<br />

the same time, connected in the most repugnant or most diabolical fashion? [K 152/85] 7<br />

In A Thousand Plateaus (1980) Deleuze and Guattari reiterate their analysis of<br />

the problem facing the modern artist, noting that in the modern era “never has the<br />

artist had a greater need of the people, while declaring most firmly that the people<br />

is lacking – the people is what is most lacking [le peuple, c’est ce qui manque le<br />

plus]” (MP 427/346). Fabulation, however, only becomes a part of this analysis in<br />

Cinema 2: The Time-Image (1985), when Deleuze examines the “powers of the false<br />

[puissances du faux]” displayed in Pierre Perrault’s cinéma du vécu and in Jean<br />

Rouch’s cinéma vérité. Perrault and Rouch both produce what might be deemed<br />

documentary films, but they do so, not by providing an “objective” recording of<br />

an external reality, but by entering into a collaborative process of invention with<br />

their subjects. 8 In Pour la suite du monde (1963), for example, Perrault proposes<br />

that a group of Québecois islanders revive a long-abandoned communal practice of<br />

erecting a weir barrier in the St. Lawrence River to snare white dolphins, and then he<br />

films the fishermen in this enterprise. As the islanders plan and carry out their tasks,<br />

they share distant memories and ancestral lore of the hunt for the white dolphin,<br />

but they also begin to form a new community. And as they speak of the collective<br />

past, the camera captures them, in Perrault’s words, “in a state of legending,” “of<br />

legending in flagrante delicto [en flagrant délit de légender],” 9 that is, in the process<br />

of fashioning a new communal lore.<br />

This “legending” Deleuze labels “fabulation,” and he sees it as the practice of<br />

a minor people engaged in a process of self-invention. The Québécois islanders are<br />

marginalized within Anglophone Canadian society, but also within official French<br />

culture, as speakers of a non-standard dialect. Though himself Québécois, Perrault<br />

sees that he, like other well-educated Québécois, has been colonized by the images<br />

and discourse of the once-glorious French empire, for he has absorbed and been<br />

7 I discuss Deleuze and Guattari’s analysis of Kafka’s minor literature in greater detail<br />

in Chapters Three and Four of Deleuze on Literature (New York, 2003).<br />

8 For a discussion of Deleuze and Rouch’s films, see pp. 150–54 of my Deleuze on<br />

Cinema (New York, 2003).<br />

9 Pierre Perrault, “Cinéma du reel et cinema du fiction: vraie ou fausse distinction?<br />

Dialogue entre Pierre Perrault et René Allio,” in Ecritures de Pierre Perrault: Actes du<br />

colloque “gens de paroles” (Québec, 1983), p. 54.


100<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

shaped by the written forms, standard pronunciation, and orthodox values of “correct<br />

French.” As he observes:<br />

The famous Age of Enlightenment never spoke of the people of the 17th century. That<br />

century produced princely images. A princely imaginary. And a writing and a language<br />

were imposed on people who had a language and did not have writing … Each epoch<br />

produces royal images, images that normalize … My soul was conditioned by centuries<br />

of the French Academy. Through writing I became a stranger to my own surroundings.<br />

Superior. [p. 56]<br />

In Pour la suite du monde, he tries to give voice to the popular oral speech of the<br />

Québécois, and to make that speech an integral part of the project of collective selfinvention<br />

which he initiates through the film. In Deleuze’s analysis, Perrault’s effort<br />

is to counter the orthodoxies of Anglophone and high French culture whose truth<br />

“is always that of the masters or the colonizers” through “the fabulative function of<br />

the poor” (IT 196/150). In Perrault’s film, we see “the becoming of the real person<br />

as he sets himself to ‘fictioning,’ when he begins ‘legending in flagrante delicto,’<br />

and thus contributes to the invention of his people.” The real Québécois fisherman<br />

“himself becomes an other, when he sets himself to fabulating without being fictive”<br />

(IT 196/150).<br />

Fabulation challenges the received truths of the dominant social order, and in<br />

this regard it “falsifies,” but it also produces its own truths through its inventions,<br />

and in this sense it manifests the creative “power of the false.” In Perrault’s cinema,<br />

the falsifying power of fabulation is set in motion through a collaborative process<br />

involving the director and his subjects. Perrault insists that by himself he cannot<br />

escape his literate, classical French mentality. When one of his well-educated<br />

interview interlocutors suggests that in Perrault’s films “the peasant that you are<br />

[le paysan que tu es] could always speak,” Perrault counters, “No, because I have<br />

been colonized by the peasant that you are not [le paysan que vous n’êtes pas], by<br />

Le Nôtre [the seventeenth-century architect of the formal gardens of Versailles].<br />

I have learned to read by reading in the books that obeyed the geometry of Le<br />

Nôtre in order to be elected to the Academy of Richelieu” 10 (Perrault 56). He needs<br />

the Québécois islanders to serve as intercessors, for they still have contact with a<br />

living oral tradition. Yet the islanders also have need of Perrault as the initiator of<br />

a communal task that revives group memory and instigates the invention of a new<br />

collectivity: “I do not want to help give birth yet again to myths, but to allow people<br />

to give birth to themselves, to avoid myths, to escape customs, to elude Writings. I<br />

would like people to write themselves while liberating themselves from Writings”<br />

(p. 56). Perrault and the islanders are mutual intercessors, together engaged in the<br />

falsification of received truths and the “legending” of a people to come: “Thus it is<br />

that I am interceded by Alexis, and Grand-Louis and Léopold and Joachim and all of<br />

the Ile-aux-Coudres [the island community of Pour la suite du monde] and little by<br />

little by all of Québec. So that I might know what I am outside writing” (p. 56).<br />

Perrault’s relationship to his subjects might seem peculiar to his own cinematic<br />

undertakings, but Deleuze sees his films simply as particularly clear manifestations<br />

10 Ibid., p. 56.


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 101<br />

of the artist’s proper relationship to the people in all genuine creation. As in The<br />

Trial, the actual artist and the virtual community are parts of a single machine,<br />

and the work of art is the generative conjunction of those forces in their mutual<br />

intercession. Fabulation is the name for the process whereby the artwork initiates the<br />

invention of a people to come, and in the case of Perrault’s films, the lived speech of<br />

the Québécois engaged in “legending” is central to the fabulative process.<br />

Fabulation and Narration<br />

Fabulation, then, is closely associated with fiction, invention and the “power of the<br />

false.” But at a certain point, one must ask, what has fabulation to do with narration?<br />

Fabulation, after all, comes from the Latin fabula, which may be rendered as “talk,”<br />

“conversation,” or “small talk,” but also as “story,” “tale,” “myth,” or “legend.” In<br />

this regard, fabula resembles its Greek counterpart, mythos, which may be translated<br />

as “word,” “speech,” “story,” or “legend.” And the French fable, besides denoting the<br />

literary form of the fable, has as one of its older meanings that of “story,” “fiction,”<br />

“legend,” while La Fable, according to the Robert dictionary, may refer to “the set<br />

of mythological stories as a whole.” Surely, it would seem, fabulation must have<br />

something to do with the creation of fabulae, just as “legending” must bear some<br />

relation to the enunciation of legends.<br />

Curiously, Deleuze says little about narration per se in his remarks on fabulation,<br />

and in this he is a dutiful follower of Bergson. Bergson regards the mythologies of<br />

the world’s religions as products of fabulation, but he says very little about myths<br />

themselves. His accounts of the fabulative function’s basic operation focus on the<br />

invention of the personae of myths and legends – supernatural forces, local spirits,<br />

and fully-formed gods – but he virtually ignores the actions and interactions of<br />

these eternal beings once their origins have been explained, as if the stories of the<br />

gods were merely secondary and insignificant elaborations of their fundamental<br />

being. Such an emphasis seems odd, when one considers that Bergson is above all<br />

a philosopher of time, and narrative takes as its subject the irreducibly temporal<br />

dimension of experience. Bergson’s central concern, however, is not with myth itself<br />

but with religion as a force that shapes closed societies. The stories of the gods are<br />

merely complex means whereby basic social obligations may be enforced, and hence<br />

they are of little significance in themselves.<br />

Yet there also seems to be an anti-narrative bias in Bergson, one that surfaces in<br />

his occasional references to the arts. The art that Bergson appears to appreciate most is<br />

music, and though he speaks well of writers upon occasion, his highest accolades are<br />

reserved for composers. When he first introduces the notion of “supra-intellectual,”<br />

creative emotion in The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, he comments:<br />

[W]hat is more systematic, more conceptually elaborate, than a Beethoven symphony? But<br />

throughout his long labor of arrangement, rearrangement and choice of material, which<br />

he was pursuing on the intellectual plane, the composer was ascending back to a point<br />

situated outside the plane, there to seek acceptance or refusal, direction, inspiration: in this<br />

point resided an indivisible emotion that no doubt aided intelligence in unfolding itself in<br />

music, but which was itself more than music and more than intelligence. [p. 1190/252]


102<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Bergson does attribute a similar creative process to the writer, yet he seems to regard<br />

the efforts of genuinely creative writers as in some regards antithetical to their<br />

medium, for narrative has a natural affinity with fabulation and closed societies.<br />

Indeed, language itself bears such an affinity, since “the soul of society is immanent<br />

in the language it speaks” (p. 987/15), and the social obligations of closed societies,<br />

which are everywhere the first forms of human society, permeate the languages of<br />

the world.<br />

As Deleuze astutely remarks in Bergsonism:<br />

[A]rt, according to Bergson, itself has two sources. There is a fabulative art [un art<br />

fabulateur], sometimes collective, sometimes individual … And there is an emotive or<br />

creative art … Perhaps every art presents these two aspects, but in variable proportion.<br />

Bergson does not hide the fact that the fabulation aspect seems to him to be inferior in art;<br />

the novel would above all be fabulation, music, on the contrary, emotion and creation. [B<br />

117/134–5]<br />

If narrative is a temporal art, so too is music, and music has the advantage of being<br />

a directly emotive art, beyond words and all the restrictive habits, conventions,<br />

assumptions and prejudices that haunt natural languages. Perhaps, then, Bergson’s<br />

inattention to narrative simply reflects his low regard for fabulation in general and<br />

his sense of genuine art as an essentially supra-linguistic enterprise.<br />

A similar disregard for narrative can be found in Deleuze as well, despite the<br />

fact that he wrote three books on novelists. True, in Proust and Signs (1964),<br />

Deleuze does make reference to various episodes in the plot of the Recherche, but<br />

the story Deleuze unfolds in Proust is that of Marcel’s apprenticeship in signs, which<br />

eventuates in a philosophical understanding of essences that transcends the sequence<br />

of events leading to that understanding. Marcel’s final discovery of “time regained”<br />

sets him free from chronological time, which is the time of conventional narrative,<br />

and Deleuze’s interest is in the emergence of that redeemed time and the atemporal<br />

vision it afford of the world. In Présentation de Sacher-Masoch (1967), Deleuze’s<br />

extended preface to Sacher-Masoch’s Venus in Furs, Deleuze argues that Sacher-<br />

Masoch’s fantasies are essentially static and that his fiction consists of a sequence<br />

of frozen tableaus. Again, as in his analysis of Proust, Deleuze makes reference to<br />

diverse plot details in Sacher-Masoch, but he pays little attention to the narratives<br />

of the novels themselves, regarding them as mere devices for linking timeless<br />

masochistic tableaus (see Chapter 7). In Kafka, finally, he and Guattari discuss a<br />

number of Kafka’s short stories, but primarily as illustrations of concepts, such as the<br />

“schizo-incest” revealed in “The Metamorphosis,” or the “becoming-animal” evident<br />

in “Report to an Academy.” Deleuze and Guattari see Kafka’s unfinished novels as<br />

the fulfillment of his project, the novels’ supposedly defective plots actually being<br />

central aspects of their functioning as open-ended, perpetually moving machines.<br />

Perhaps most telling in this regard is Deleuze and Guattari’s argument that The Trial<br />

does not really have an ending – that the execution of K is actually a dream sequence,<br />

and that the novel has a loose, paratactic structure that allows an endless wandering<br />

from episode to episode. Once again, narrative itself seems a minor consideration.<br />

Throughout the 1980s and early 1990s, an opposition to traditional narrative<br />

recurs as an important theme in Deleuze’s work. In Francis Bacon: The Logic of


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 103<br />

Sensation (1981), Deleuze seizes on Bacon’s disdain for narrative “illustration”<br />

in painting, arguing that Bacon’s fundamental object is to free images from their<br />

conventional associations with their attendant stories and make visible “the brutality<br />

of fact” (see FB 9–10/6–7). In his two-volume study of cinema, Deleuze challenges<br />

narrative-based theories of film, giving priority instead to different conceptions of<br />

time. Film directors in his view are not master story-tellers so much as they are<br />

sculptors of time-space. Narratives are the secondary products of structures of<br />

time, the conventional narratives of classic film emerging from movement-images<br />

regulated by the sensory-motor schema, the fragmented and confusing narratives<br />

of modern film serving as indexes of non-chronological time that has been freed<br />

of the sensory-motor schema’s regulation (see especially IT 38–40/25–7). And in<br />

his 1992 study of Beckett’s television plays, “The Exhausted,” Deleuze shows how<br />

Beckett grows impatient with words and attempts to silence his characters’ voices<br />

and their interminable stories. Beckett’s effort, explains Deleuze, is to bore holes in<br />

words and extract a non-linguistic “something” beneath or between the words, and<br />

his problem “is not that words are liars; rather, they are so laden with calculations<br />

and significations, and also with intentions and personal memories, with old habits<br />

that cement them together, that scarcely has their surface been broached when it<br />

closes over again” (E 103/CC 173). Each of Beckett’s characters reveals a “possible<br />

world,” an “Other,” and “the Others – that is, the possible worlds, with their objects,<br />

with their voices that bestow on them the only reality to which they can lay claim<br />

– constitute ‘stories’” (E 67/CC 157), and it is the incessant babble of such stories<br />

that Beckett tries to bring to an end in his television plays. 11<br />

In Deleuze’s analysis, Beckett’s goal is to produce “pure images,” images stripped<br />

of all of their associations with human intentions, calculations, intentions, memories<br />

and stories, and it is the visual image finally that Deleuze himself privileges in<br />

his approach to the arts and his conceptualization of fabulation. In the late essay<br />

“Literature and Life” (in Critique et clinique, 1993), Deleuze states that literature<br />

always engages “becomings” and “powers [puissances],” metamorphic processes<br />

of becoming-other, and that such becomings and powers have nothing to do with<br />

the authors’ or the characters’ personal emotions, memories, dreams, or fantasies.<br />

Literary characters may be individuated, “but all their individual traits elevate them<br />

to a vision that carries them into an indefinite, like a becoming too powerful for<br />

them: Ahab and the vision of Moby Dick.” There is no literature without fabulation,<br />

Deleuze adds, “but, as Bergson saw, fabulation, the fabulative function, consists<br />

neither in imagining nor projecting a self [un moi]. Rather, it attains to these visions,<br />

it rises to these becomings and powers” (CC 13/3).<br />

In another late essay, devoted to T.E. Lawrence, Deleuze remarks on the reputed<br />

“mythomania” of Lawrence of Arabia in his portrayal of himself and his band of<br />

Arab guerillas, arguing that Lawrence’s effort is not to aggrandize himself and his<br />

comrades but “to project into things, into reality, into the future and even into the<br />

sky, an image of himself and of others intense enough that it lives its own life … It<br />

11 For more on Beckett’s television plays and his attitude toward language, see my<br />

Deleuze on Literature, pp. 176–86, and Deleuze’s Wake: Tributes and Tributaries (Albany,<br />

NY, 2004), pp. 127–42.


104<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

is a machine for fabricating giants, what Bergson called a fabulative function” (CC<br />

147/118). In a note to this passage, Deleuze refers the reader to Genet’s analysis in<br />

Prisoner of Love (1986) of the Palestinian fighters’ heroic postures and poses, which<br />

Genet regards as efforts to create an image of oneself that is separate from the self<br />

and that one projects into the future. Mythomania, says Genet, is merely the name<br />

for an unsuccessfully projected image, which should “live its own life” and allow<br />

the individual “to become legendary [fabuleux],” “to become an eponymous hero,<br />

projected into the world.” 12<br />

Deleuze here is clearly taking up Bergson’s association of fabulation with<br />

hallucination. Bergson, we recall, says that a fiction, “if its image is vivid and<br />

haunting [obsédante], may precisely imitate perception, and thereby prevent or<br />

modify action” (p. 1067/109). Fabulation for Bergson has the power of forcing<br />

its images on reality and countering the operations of reason and intelligence, but<br />

only in the service of a restrictive morality and a closed society. For Deleuze, the<br />

fabulative function is the function proper to art, which projects into the world images<br />

so intense that they take on a life of their own. For this reason Deleuze describes<br />

great cinema directors as “voyants,” “seers,” “clairvoyants” (DRF 200/217). For the<br />

same reason he says that one of literature’s chief ends is to push language “toward an<br />

outside or a reverse side consisting of Visions and Auditions” (CC 16/5), “Visions”<br />

and “Auditions” here denoting hallucinatory images and sounds that haunt language<br />

and manage somehow to force themselves onto the world.<br />

Fabulation, then, is a hallucinatory power that creates “visions and auditions,”<br />

“becomings,” “powers,” “giants.” If it is a myth-making power, it is one that creates<br />

a mythology not of stories but of images – images of the becoming-other of the<br />

collectivity as it fashions itself by falsifying received truths and fabricating new<br />

ones. And if there is a relationship between Deleuzian fabulation and narration, it<br />

is that of the disruption of conventional narratives and the disclosure of the time of<br />

the event.<br />

In a brief reflection on May 1968, co-written with Guattari in 1984, Deleuze<br />

observes that in every social revolution “there is always something of the event,<br />

irreducible to social determinisms, to causal series.” Historians study causal relations,<br />

“but the event is out of sync or in rupture with causalities: it is a bifurcation, a<br />

deviation in relation to laws, an unstable state that opens a new field of possibilities.”<br />

May 1968 was such an event, and most importantly, “it was a phenomenon of<br />

voyance [‘seeing,’ ‘clairvoyance’], as if a society suddenly saw what was intolerable<br />

and also saw the possibility of something else” (DRF 215–16/234). The time of the<br />

event is, in Nietzsche’s terminology, “untimely – that is to say, acting counter to<br />

our time and thereby acting on our time and, let us hope, for the benefit of a time to<br />

come.” 13 It is a time set free from the narrative causality of history and undetermined<br />

in its relation to the future.<br />

This association of seeing, the intolerable, and the disruptive event is especially<br />

evident in Deleuze’s reading of Foucault. In a 1986 interview, while reflecting on<br />

12 Jean Genet, Un captif amoureux (Paris, 1986), p. 354 (translation mine).<br />

13 Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, ed. Daniel Breazeale, trans. R.J.<br />

Hollingdale (Cambridge, 1997), p. 60.


Bergsonian Fabulation and the People to Come 105<br />

the thought of his recently deceased friend, Deleuze comments that Foucault “was<br />

an extraordinary seer/clairvoyant [voyant],” with “a power of seeing equal to his<br />

power of writing.” Deleuze explains that when one sees something “and sees it<br />

very profoundly, what one sees is intolerable.” Part of Foucault’s genius was his<br />

ability to see the intolerable, and in his works we discover “thought as vision, as the<br />

seizure of the intolerable” (DRF 256–7/274–5). In a 1988 interview, Deleuze notes<br />

further that Foucault was a writer of histories, but above all a philosopher who “used<br />

history for something else: as Nietzsche said, to act against the times, and hence<br />

on time, in favor, I hope, of a time to come” (DRF 323/346). Foucault’s attempt<br />

was to make possible something new, and to do so by separating us from the causal<br />

determinations of the past. “The new,” says Deleuze, “is the actual [l’actuel bearing<br />

both the meaning of ‘that which is real’ and ‘that which is contemporary, of the<br />

present moment’]. The actual is not what we are, but what we are becoming, what we<br />

are in the process of becoming, that is, the Other, our becoming.” In any situation, it<br />

is essential to distinguish “what we are (what we no longer are), and what we are in<br />

the process of becoming: the part of history, and the part of the actual. History is the<br />

archive, the design of that which we are and are ceasing to be, whereas the actual is<br />

the rough sketch of what we are becoming” (DRF 322–3/345).<br />

To see deeply is to see the intolerable, that is, to engage in a critique of the<br />

received truths and realities of the present. A moment of hallucinatory, clairvoyant<br />

vision is one in which the intolerable becomes suddenly visible, but one also that<br />

makes visible new possibilities unencumbered by the past. The hold of history, of the<br />

forces that have shaped our present, is broken, and the actual of what we are becoming<br />

surges forth. History, story, narrative continuity, yield to the event, a disruption<br />

in causality, a gap in the orderly and regular sequence of world occurrences. The<br />

event is like James’s earthquake, or the woman’s vertiginous moment at the brink<br />

of the elevator shaft, a breach in ordinary experience that instigates unexpected,<br />

hallucinatory images. Fabulation, we might say, is one with the event, fabulation’s<br />

visions emerging within the event, and those visions themselves constituting<br />

events. Fabulation creates visions that falsify received truths by rendering visible<br />

the intolerable, thereby critiquing the present, while those same visions loom like<br />

giant mythic figures of yet to be explored possibilities. The visions of fabulation<br />

break historical continuities and disrupt conventional narratives. They are untimely<br />

visions, becomings and powers that are dynamic but unspecified in their narrative<br />

possibilities, and hence temporal forces that may generate stories, but not themselves<br />

properly narrative elements.<br />

The Two Sources of Fabulation<br />

Bergson’s fabulation has its source in the virtual instinct that creates moral obligation<br />

and enforces the cohesion of a closed society. Intelligence naturally and inevitably<br />

tends to dissolve social bonds, as it pursues self-centered lines of reasoning, while<br />

engendering individual despair, as it deduces the facts of the individual’s mortality<br />

and limited powers. Fabulation is a function of the intelligence that counters these<br />

tendencies by creating images that imitate perception and stimulate action, those


106<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

images assuming the form of the various forces, spirits and gods that populate<br />

the mythologies and sacred writings of the world’s religions. The spontaneous<br />

fashioning of such hallucinatory images is revealed in moments of disorientation<br />

or sudden danger, such as James’s earthquake or the woman’s near-mishap with the<br />

elevator shaft. But the jolt that stimulates fabulation differs from the leap forward<br />

that accompanies genuine invention, for the fabulative function is qualitatively<br />

distinct from the creative function that inspires every advance into the new, whether<br />

that advance be in the arts, the sciences, politics, or religion. The creative emotion<br />

from which the new issues forth is a manifestation of nature’s élan vital, which is<br />

simply the name for the natural world’s dynamic, open-ended process of inventive<br />

becoming. The qualitative break evident in human creativity’s leap forward is but<br />

a specialized instance of the general cosmic discontinuity that accompanies any<br />

genuine advance into the new.<br />

Deleuze’s fabulation has its source in the event, which is both a disorienting shock<br />

and a leap toward the future. His fabulation resembles Bergson’s creative emotion<br />

in its internally generative unfolding of new possibilities, but it shares Bergsonian<br />

fabulation’s characteristics of giving rise to hallucinatory images that short-circuit<br />

the operations of common sense. Bergsonian fabulation has the political function<br />

of perpetuating a closed, static society, whereas Deleuzian fabulation promotes the<br />

invention of a people and the formation of new modes of social interaction. Deleuzian<br />

fabulation thus fulfills a function that is part of the general politics articulated in<br />

Anti-Oedipus, a politics in which the desiring subject hallucinates history, and the<br />

subject’s desiring-production in its positive function contributes to the formation<br />

of a group-subject, a self-determining, fluid and open collectivity. Fabulation is<br />

also central to the function of art outlined in Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, the<br />

artist’s desiring-production conjoining the actual artist and the virtual community<br />

in a collective assemblage of enunciation that aims at the invention of a people to<br />

come. Fabulation engages the powers of the false, falsifying received truths and<br />

fashioning new truths by “legending.” The artist and the emergent community<br />

serve as mutual intercessors, each aiding the other in a process of metamorphic<br />

departure from received categories and simultaneous approach toward only partially<br />

specified possibilities. Fabulation’s political dimension is explicit in images such as<br />

those Lawrence offers of himself and his guerilla band, but the political aspect of<br />

art is present in every projected image that takes on a life of its own. The goal of<br />

fabulation is to break the continuities of received stories and deterministic histories,<br />

and at the same time to fashion images that are free of the entangling associations of<br />

conventional narratives and open to unspecified elaboration in the construction of a<br />

new mode of collective agency.<br />

“Utopia is not a good concept” (PP 235/174), says Deleuze, for it is too fixed,<br />

too programmatic. Better is the notion of “a ‘fabulation’ common to the people and<br />

to art” (PP 235/174). It is in developing this concept that Deleuze may be said to<br />

“take up again the Bergsonian notion of fabulation and give it a political sense” (PP<br />

235/174).


Chapter 7<br />

Re-Viewing Deleuze’s Sacher-Masoch<br />

In his last book, Critique et clinique, published two years before his death in 1995,<br />

Deleuze seemed at long last to have fulfilled the promise he had made many years<br />

earlier of writing a book on literature, one that would pursue the relationship between<br />

critique in its literary sense and clinique in its medical sense. 1 His object, he had<br />

indicated, would be to examine symptomatology as the area common to the literary<br />

and medical enterprises, the writer serving as a symptomatologist of civilization, the<br />

physician as the artist-analyst disassembling syndromes (or erroneous concatenations<br />

of symptoms) and reassembling them in veridical associations. 2 By 1993, the medical<br />

component of the project seemed to have gone by the wayside, for when he initially<br />

conceived of the project in 1967, Deleuze was intensely interested in the medical<br />

areas of psychiatry and psychoanalysis, but after Anti-Oedipus in 1972, he largely<br />

abandoned those areas of investigation. Instead, he concentrated simply on the<br />

notions of the artist as healer and literature as a means of promoting life and health.<br />

It appears that Deleuze conceived of the 1993 Critique et clinique both as a<br />

formulation of his mature theory of literature and as an overview of his previous<br />

literary analyses, for in addition to the studies of Melville, Whitman, D.H. Lawrence<br />

and T.E. Lawrence, authors with whom he had not previously dealt in detail, the<br />

volume includes a brief analysis of Lewis Carroll, whom Deleuze had discussed at<br />

length in The Logic of Sense (1969), and a short essay on Leopold Sacher-Masoch,<br />

the subject of Deleuze’s 1967 book Présentation de Sacher-Masoch. Unfortunately,<br />

Deleuze was in poor health during the last decade of his life, and it appears that he<br />

did not have the physical strength to complete the design of the book as he might<br />

have intended. Several of the essays in the collection are revised versions of studies<br />

published earlier, and some of them – the essays on Kant, Spinoza, Nietzsche and<br />

Plato, for example – are literary only in a very broad sense, suggesting that the<br />

planned systematic analysis of literature had to give way to a more casually assembled<br />

collection of essays. A number of the selections are quite short – the essay on Carroll<br />

1 In a 1988 interview, when asked about his views on literature, Deleuze responded, “I<br />

have dreamed of a group of studies under the general title ‘Critique et clinique’” (PP 195/142).<br />

The idea for such a book, however, seems to date at least to 1967, when in an interview<br />

Deleuze mentions several writers in the context of critique and clinique and remarks, “What<br />

I would like to study (and that book [Présentation de Sacher-Masoch] would be only a first<br />

example) is an articulable relation between literature and clinical psychiatry” (ID 184/133).<br />

2 “Masoch is a great symptomatologist. In Proust, it is not memory he is exploring,<br />

but all sorts of signs, whose nature must be discovered according to their milieus, mode of<br />

emission, matter, regime. The Recherche is a general semiology, a symptomatology of worlds.<br />

The work of Kafka is the diagnostic of all the diabolical powers that await us. Nietzsche said<br />

it best, the artist and the philosopher are the physicians of civilization” (PP 195/142–3).


108<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

is only two pages long, the study of Sacher-Masoch, titled “Re-presentation of<br />

Sacher-Masoch,” runs about three pages – which in my view indicates not so much a<br />

sudden proclivity for aphoristic expression in Deleuze as a limited supply of physical<br />

energy that had to be carefully marshaled and selectively applied. Yet in Critique et<br />

clinique there are hints of the book Deleuze might have wanted to write, and they<br />

show up in an intriguing way in his essay on Sacher-Masoch.<br />

In the collection’s opening essay, “Literature and Life,” Deleuze formulates a<br />

conception of literature that brings together ideas that had occupied him at various<br />

points during his career. Literature is a mode of non-organic life that promotes a<br />

kind of incorporeal health, he argues, and it has four basic components: becomings,<br />

stutterings, the invention of peoples, and the creation of visions and auditions. The<br />

notion of literature as health one finds as early as Deleuze’s 1962 study of Nietzsche;<br />

the concept of stuttering in one’s own language is evident in his 1964 book on Proust;<br />

becomings and the invention of peoples are motifs associated with the concept of<br />

“minor literature,” which Deleuze and Guattari developed in Kafka (1975) and A<br />

Thousand Plateaus (1980); and the idea of visions and auditions seems to have been<br />

one of the last notions Deleuze was working on before his death.<br />

Deleuze’s “Re-presentation of Sacher-Masoch” basically provides a selective<br />

rereading of his earlier book on Sacher-Masoch in terms of the four components<br />

outlined in “Literature and Life.” After cautioning that Sacher-Masoch is not a<br />

neurotic but a symptomatologist of civilization’s ills, and noting that Sacher-<br />

Masoch’s diagnosis is focused on the concept of “waiting or suspense as plenitude”<br />

(CC 71/53–4), Deleuze comments that Sacher-Masoch’s fascination with fur and the<br />

figure of the suffering animal – horse, bull and bear, most often – is part of a general<br />

becoming-animal that permeates his work. This motif, only recognized in passing<br />

in his 1967 book, is now treated as a central feature of Sacher-Masoch’s fiction, part<br />

of a general process of becoming-other, or undoing social codes and practices, that<br />

Deleuze sees as a chief goal of literature as health. Deleuze then emphasizes the<br />

historical dimension of Sacher-Masoch’s novels and tales, especially the portrayal of<br />

the lives of minorities of the Austro-Hungarian empire – Gypsies, Jews and various<br />

Slavic groups – and what was only a virtual footnote in 1967 is now taken to be a<br />

major feature of Sacher-Masoch’s project, an effort to engage the struggles of minor<br />

peoples and thereby invent a future “people to come,” a revolutionary collectivity<br />

capable of opening up new possibilities for life. Sacher-Masoch’s style, only alluded<br />

to in a few very general remarks in 1967, is in 1993 stressed as one of the key elements<br />

of his fiction. Sacher-Masoch invents a means of stuttering in his own language,<br />

says Deleuze, a way of making German stammer and hesitate, “as if language were<br />

becoming animal” (CC 73/55). Finally, Deleuze asserts that in Sacher-Masoch’s<br />

stylistic inventions “it is language as a whole that is carried to its limit: music or<br />

silence” (CC 74/55) – a clear invocation of the notion of “auditions,” which Deleuze<br />

pairs with “visions” as the elements that constitute the limit of language. That limit,<br />

Deleuze says in the introduction to Critique et clinique, “is not outside language, it<br />

is language’s outside: the limit is made of non-linguistic visions and auditions, but<br />

which language alone makes possible” (CC 9/lv).<br />

It is curious that Deleuze alludes only to auditions in “Re-presentation of Sacher-<br />

Masoch,” given the stress Deleuze elsewhere places on visions when developing this


Re-Viewing Deleuze’s Sacher-Masoch 109<br />

obscure concept of “visions and auditions.” There is “a painting and a music proper<br />

to writing,” Deleuze comments, “as effects of colors and sonorities that rise above<br />

the words. It is across the words, between the words, that one sees and that one hears<br />

… Of each writer one must say: here’s a seer, a hearer, ‘ill seen ill said,’ a colorist, a<br />

musician” (CC 9/lv). Yet, though the writer may be both a colorist and a musician at<br />

the moment that language is pushed to its limit, in Critique et clinique when Deleuze<br />

offers specific examples of such effects in words, invariably they are visual rather<br />

than sonic, as in his brilliant essay on T.E. Lawrence (CC 144–57/115–25). In the<br />

case of Sacher-Masoch, it would have been quite simple for Deleuze to have cited<br />

instances of visions at the limit of language, for they abound in the Sacher-Masoch<br />

Deleuze presents in his 1967 book. Indeed, of all of the features of literature stressed<br />

in Critique et clinique, this alone is pervasive in Deleuze’s earlier study, albeit in a<br />

form that is not explicitly articulated as such.<br />

Deleuze’s goal in Présentation de Sacher-Masoch is to dissolve the false<br />

syndrome of sadomasochism and argue that Sade and Sacher-Masoch are each<br />

symptomatologists disclosing a separate “universe” (SM 11/13), a separate “world”<br />

or “Umwelt” (SM 37/37). Sade seeks a rational delirium of pure negation. Following<br />

Kossowski’s analysis, Deleuze distinguishes two natures in Sade: a secondary nature<br />

of destruction and creation, in which birth, metamorphosis and death are confusedly<br />

mixed together; and a primary nature of pure negation, an “original delirium, a<br />

primordial chaos made solely of furious and lacerating molecules” (SM 25/25). 3<br />

That primary nature is never given in reality; it is an Idea, delirious to be sure, but “a<br />

delirium proper to reason” (SM 25/25). Sade’s goal is to create a world of primary<br />

nature, in which a cruel order is imposed with the implacable rationality of a violent<br />

logical demonstration. The mother as procreator is associated with secondary nature,<br />

the father with primary nature – hence the central phantasy of the “father, destroyer<br />

of his own family, impelling the daughter to torture and murder the mother” (SM 52–<br />

3/52). Sacher-Masoch, by contrast, seeks an imaginary disavowal of reality. Deleuze<br />

finds two natures in Sacher-Masoch as well, but incommensurable with those in<br />

Sade. Sacher-Masoch’s secondary nature is a cruel, sensual world of perpetual war<br />

between the sexes, represented by the female figures of the ritual prostitute and the<br />

sadistic torturer. His primary nature is revealed in the figure of the oral mother, who<br />

is “cold, maternal, severe” (SML 45/45). Sacher-Masoch’s dream is of a nature free<br />

of the heat of sensuality, filled with a cool, suprasensual sentimentality and a strict,<br />

cathartic order that purifies and makes possible the miraculous parthenogenesis of a<br />

new man. If the father dominates in Sade, the mother rules in Sacher-Masoch. In the<br />

masochistic phantasy, it is the image of the father that the mother beats, humiliates<br />

and destroys when she disciplines the son, thereby enabling a reconciliation of man<br />

and woman in the triumphant moment when the son is reborn as a transformed being<br />

and united with the mother. Unlike Sadean apathy, which proceeds from a delirious<br />

rational negation, Sacher-Masoch’s coldness reflects the imagination’s disavowal of<br />

reality – a simultaneous denial and acceptance of the real, an imaginary “suspension”<br />

3 Klossowski’s primary text on Sade, and Deleuze’s source for this analysis, is Sade,<br />

mon prochain (Paris, 1947).


110<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

of the disorderly violence of secondary nature that neutralizes the real and allows the<br />

unfolding of a new, ideal world of primary nature. 4<br />

The sadist and the masochist stage and perform their own dramas, each “sufficient<br />

and complete drama, with different characters, with nothing that can make them<br />

communicate with one another, neither from the inside nor from the outside” (SM<br />

40/40). What is striking, however, is how little drama there is in these perversions,<br />

how little action in these theaters. Deleuze contrasts Sadean movement and Masochian<br />

stasis, arguing that in Sade sensuality is movement and the staging of sensuality entails<br />

“a quantitative process of accumulation and acceleration,” a “reiteration of scenes,<br />

multiplication in each scene, precipitation, overdetermination (at once, ‘I committed<br />

parricide, I committed incest, I killed, I prostituted, I sodomized’)” (SM 62/62).<br />

By contrast, in Sacher-Masoch sensuality is suspended and phantasy scenes tend to<br />

resemble frozen tableaus, paintings, groupings of statues, photographs. Yet even in<br />

Sade, the scenes of desire incorporate only a minimal development or change. They<br />

consist of simple actions – I killed, I prostituted, I sodomized – each of which might<br />

be represented in a single film clip, or even a paradigmatic photograph, the Sadean<br />

movement consisting of an insistent repetition of these micro-units of perversion.<br />

The erasure of dramatic action, or genuine development and transformation, is even<br />

more evident in Sacher-Masoch. In masochism, the real is disavowed, “suspended”<br />

in every way. Not only are individuals literally hanged, crucified, trussed and tied,<br />

but they are also subjected to a complex time of suspense and waiting, in which two<br />

temporal streams coexist, one promising an awaited pleasure, the other holding forth<br />

an expected punishment, both maintained in a perpetual state of suspension. The<br />

female objects of desire are likened to marble statues, the scenes of punishment to<br />

paintings. Everywhere there is an assimilation of the vibrant human world within the<br />

cold, still world of the plastic arts.<br />

To be sure, a certain amount of action persists in Sacher-Masoch’s world, but like<br />

that of Sade’s, it is minimal. Here is what Deleuze says would be the ideal masochistic<br />

phantasy: “a woman in shorts is on a stationary bicycle, pedaling vigorously; the<br />

subject is lying down under the bicycle, almost brushed by the vertiginous pedals,<br />

his palms pressed to her calves. All the determinations are united here, from the<br />

fetishism of the calf to the double waiting incarnated by the movement of the pedals<br />

and the immobility of the bicycle” (SM 64/63). What we have is a scene of perpetual<br />

movement, but one that goes nowhere, a staging of a situation rather than an unfolding<br />

of actions that result from decisions, consequences, counteractions, external events,<br />

and so on. Deleuze argues that the contract is central to masochism, and in this<br />

element, too, stasis is emphasized. The contract drawn up between the masochist and<br />

his dominatrix specifies a fixed relationship, a set of unchanging roles and rules for<br />

4 Jean Laplanche and Jean-Baptiste Pontalis, The Language of Psycho-Analysis, trans.<br />

Donald Nicholson-Smith (New York, 1973), define disavowal as “a mode of defence which<br />

consists in the subject’s refusing to recognize the reality of a traumatic perception – most<br />

especially the perception of the absence of the woman’s penis” (p. 118). They also note that<br />

in Freud’s study of fetishism, Freud “shows how the fetishist perpetuates an infantile attitude<br />

by holding two incompatible positions at the same time: he simultaneously disavows and<br />

acknowledges the fact of feminine castration” (p. 119).


Re-Viewing Deleuze’s Sacher-Masoch 111<br />

the execution of action-units that are to be staged repeatedly and without essential<br />

variation. Deleuze points out that Sacher-Masoch has a predilection for ritual as<br />

well as drama, and that in the staging of rites in his fiction there is a passage from<br />

the individual contractual relationship of phantasy to the collective dimension of<br />

myth. And here, too, stasis prevails. In Sacher-Masoch we find various “hunting<br />

rites, agricultural rites, rites of regeneration, of second birth” (SM 82/81), but they<br />

all tend to culminate in tableaus, as at the end of Venus in Furs, when Wanda has<br />

the narrator yoked to a cart and whipped by her black female attendants as she, in<br />

Sacher-Masoch’s words, “contemplates the scene” (cited in SM 83/82).<br />

Deleuze concludes his book on Sacher-Masoch by remarking that “masochism<br />

is a story [une histoire]” (SM 111/112), and that sadism “is itself also a story,”<br />

but “precisely, it’s an entirely different story [c’est une tout autre histoire]” (SM<br />

112/113). Yet in neither case is it much of a story. The sadist’s fundamental phantasy<br />

is that of the father forcing his daughter to murder the mother. The masochist’s is that<br />

of the mother ritually destroying the father by beating the son, with the result that<br />

the son is transformed and made a new, suprasensual man at one with the mother.<br />

In both cases, the action may be reduced to a single scene. Deleuze sees a kind<br />

of dialectic at work in Sacher-Masoch, a mythic process whereby the antithetical<br />

figures of the ritual prostitute and sadistic dominatrix are sublimated within the<br />

figure of the oral mother, yet the stress in this dialectic is not on any developmental<br />

movement from one pole to its antithesis and beyond to a synthesis, but instead on<br />

a single, momentary Aufhebung in which the oral mother transforms the son. The<br />

three female figures constitute “a symbolic order” in which the father is suppressed<br />

“for all time,” says Deleuze, and the masochist needs myth “to express this eternity<br />

of time: everything is already acted out, everything takes place between the images<br />

of the mother” (SM 56/55). The time of myth, in short, is a relatively timeless time,<br />

an already acted out event ever re-enacted anew. And ultimately, the time of myth is<br />

one with the time of phantasy, which Deleuze views as masochism’s central object.<br />

Freudian psychoanalysts define the phantasy as an “imaginary scene in which the<br />

subject is a protagonist,” 5 and Freud’s paradigmatic phantasy scene, “a child is being<br />

beaten,” is like the phantasy scenes of Sade and Sacher-Masoch, a truncated action<br />

that may be reduced to a virtually frozen tableau. Thus, when Deleuze remarks that<br />

the masochist’s mythic rite “represents the element in which reality is rendered<br />

phantasmatic” (SM 82/81), he is pointing out that Sacher-Masoch’s assimilation of<br />

personal contractual scenes of desire within collective mythic rites is a means of<br />

extending the relatively static time of phantasy from an individual or local sphere to<br />

the universal domain of the real.<br />

The logic of Deleuze’s Présentation de Sacher-Masoch is that Sacher-Masoch’s<br />

predilection for visual tableaus and suspended time derives from his particular<br />

libidinal universe and his fondness for the imaginary disavowal of phantasy. Yet the<br />

same tendency toward stasis is evident in Sade – despite Deleuze’s contention that<br />

in sadism movement is primary and rational delirium rather than phantasy produces<br />

such movement – and Sade’s stagings of desire tend to resemble visual tableaus,<br />

even though Deleuze claims that Sade is Sacher-Masoch’s antithesis in his hatred<br />

5 Laplanche and Pontalis, The Language of Psycho-Analysis, p. 314 (emphasis added).


112<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

of the plastic arts. What is evident, I believe, is that throughout his work Deleuze<br />

holds an anti-narrative conception of the arts and shows an abiding sensitivity to<br />

visual experience, and what attracts him to Sade and Sacher-Masoch in the first place<br />

is their common strategy of subverting narrative continuities through a virtually<br />

hallucinatory repetition of visual scenes, Sade’s consisting of a rapid succession<br />

of accelerating crimes, Sacher-Masoch’s of a prolonged sequence of suspended<br />

punishments. Deleuze consistently identifies conventional narratives with coercive<br />

practices and codes of power, and he sees in modernist disruptions of narrative<br />

expectations a means of inventing new possibilities for life. Thus, for Deleuze, the<br />

paradigmatic modern painter is Francis Bacon, whose obsession is to escape narrative<br />

“illustration” and render visible “the brutality of fact.” And in his books on cinema,<br />

the modern films Deleuze champions break with the “sensory-motor schema” of<br />

commonsense time and space and create direct “time-ages” that defy subsumption<br />

within the conventions of standard narratives. When, in Critique et clinique, Deleuze<br />

praises the great writers who produce “visions and auditions” at the limit of language,<br />

he does so because they make language and its concomitant codes stammer. They<br />

undo linguistic regularities and the narrative continuities imbedded within language,<br />

thereby creating hallucinatory images and sounds that seem to float above the words,<br />

like a visual and sonic aura emanating from the surface of language. In Présentation<br />

de Sacher-Masoch, Deleuze stresses the affinity between masochistic suspension and<br />

the stasis of the plastic arts, but what counts finally is less the suspension and stasis<br />

of Sacher-Masoch’s phantasies than the sensual intensity and temporal dislocation of<br />

his tableaus. The visions of Sacher-Masoch and Sade are affective emanations at the<br />

limits of language, and their purpose is not to freeze time, but to unhinge it.<br />

When Deleuze re-presents Sacher-Masoch, he emphasizes features in Sacher-<br />

Masoch he had earlier noted only in passing. Sacher-Masoch’s visions he does not<br />

mention at all. Yet perhaps those visions are in no need of being re-presented, for<br />

they are the central, if unstated, objects of Deleuze’s original analysis, and possibly<br />

important sources for the development of the concept of “visions” itself. What is<br />

needed, it may be, is not to re-present but simply to re-view Sacher-Masoch, to see<br />

what was there all along.


Chapter 8<br />

Apology for Nomadology<br />

Over the last twenty years, the notion of the “nomadic,” as developed by Deleuze<br />

and Guattari in their “Treatise on Nomadology” (Plateau 12 of A Thousand Plateaus<br />

[1980]), has been emerging as the concept of choice for theorists of various stripes,<br />

with increasing numbers of books, articles and special issues devoted to the topic. As<br />

early as 1993, Christopher Miller noted this tendency and lamented the spread of this<br />

ill-defined term, and since then, others have echoed his complaints. In his critique of<br />

nomadology, Miller faults Deleuze and Guattari for ignoring the realities of actual<br />

nomadic peoples in developing their concept, arguing that by selectively adopting<br />

elements from scattered anthropological sources they romanticize nomads and<br />

inadvertently repeat the process of colonial subjugation of the native they otherwise<br />

so clearly oppose. Miller bridles especially at the claim that Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

“nomadic thought” offers a radical alternative to conventional philosophical<br />

approaches, deeming such an assertion unwarranted, arrogant and unhelpful. Miller’s<br />

impatience with the inflated claims of some proponents of “nomadic thought” is<br />

understandable, as is his objection to Deleuze and Guattari’s apparent disregard for<br />

the complexities of nomadic populations. These concerns deserve consideration. 1<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s nomadism at first glance is what some would call a<br />

“bastard concept,” one that sits astride standard categories and confuses seemingly<br />

distinct classifications. In the broadest sense, Deleuze and Guattari apparently take<br />

the “nomadic” to be that which is unfixed, wandering, peripatetic, set adrift, and<br />

in this regard, their social model appears to be that of all individuals, groups and<br />

societies without fixed abode who are in a relatively constant state of movement.<br />

But several of the descriptive characteristics of the nomadic seem to be derived<br />

from particular cultural instances. The notion of the War Machine as a manifestation<br />

of the nomadic seems to have its origin in the Mongol hordes, whose prowess as<br />

mounted warriors culminated in the formation of the great empire of Genghis Khan<br />

in the thirteenth century. The concept of the “numbering number” (MP 484–6/389–<br />

90) also has its basis in Mongol culture, though Deleuze and Guattari note that this<br />

assignment of warriors into tens, hundreds and thousands, etc. has a biblical parallel<br />

in the Aaronic organization of troops that some researchers tie to the Hyksos nomads<br />

who may have traversed Central Asia to the Middle East in ancient times (MP 148,<br />

154/118, 122). The opposition of the nomadic War Machine and the sedentary State<br />

apparatus appears to have as its clearest exemplification the antagonism of Bedouins<br />

and city inhabitants, so dramatically demarcated by Ibn Khaldun (1332–1408) in<br />

the Muqaddimah (MP 453/366). The association of the warrior and nomadism<br />

obviously is consonant with the bellicose traditions of the Mongols and Bedouins,<br />

1 See Chapter 10 for a detailed response to Miller’s critique.


114<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

but Deleuze and Guattari also make reference to warriors and warrior groups in<br />

African and South American sedentary and hunter-gatherer societies, as well as<br />

to the fundamental opposition of warrior and king in Indo-European mythology<br />

exhaustively detailed by Georges Dumézil (MP 434–6/351–3). The notion of a<br />

“nomadic distribution” of elements, which Deleuze first treats in Difference and<br />

Repetition (1968), has as its model the sheep and goat pastoral nomads whose flocks<br />

occupy a territory to the extent of their capability (puissance), flowing over the land<br />

in a free-form, amorphous flux rather than demarcating the land according to fixed<br />

boundaries (DR 53–4/36–7). The “band,” “pack,” or “gang” organization of nomadic<br />

multiplicities, in which individuals are neither discrete units of a mass aggregate nor<br />

regular components of a stratified social structure, but instead “dividual” elements<br />

in an unstable collective distribution of varying group identity, is exemplified by the<br />

streets gangs of Bogotá in A Thousand Plateaus (MP 442/358), but other instances<br />

might include hunter-gatherer groups such as the Mbuti of Central Africa, whose<br />

“only effective political unit is the band,” according to Colin Turnbull, a unit whose<br />

composition “is fluid, to say the least, and does not follow any clear unilineal or<br />

cognatic descent system.” 2 The “smooth space” of nomadic wandering Deleuze and<br />

Guattari derive from Boulez’s contrast of striated, pulsed time and smooth, non-pulsed<br />

time, but the examples they offer are those of desert nomads, such as the Bedouins,<br />

Eskimo hunters who negotiate shifting arctic landscapes, and the “sea nomads” of<br />

Patagonia, who “do not grasp an itinerary as a whole, but in a fragmentary manner,<br />

by juxtaposing in order its various successive stages, from campsite to campsite in<br />

the course of a journey” (José Emperaire, cited in MP 474/557).<br />

In the literature on nomadism, there is considerable disagreement over the range<br />

of societies that should be designated as “nomadic,” but there is some consensus that<br />

at least three categories of mobile peoples should be recognized. The first category,<br />

to which many wish to restrict the term “nomadic,” is that of pastoral nomads, whose<br />

societies may be defined as “societies specializing in animal husbandry requiring<br />

periodic movements.” 3 Thomas Barfield usefully divides pastoral nomads into five<br />

groups, each of which inhabits a particular region and specializes in the raising of a<br />

specific animal: African pastoralists of the Sahel, such as the Masai, for whom cattle<br />

herding is the central and all-consuming cultural activity; the camel pastoralists of<br />

the Saharan and Arabian Deserts, the most notable example being the Bedouins; the<br />

sheep and goat pastoralists of the region running from the Mediterranean littoral<br />

through the Anatolian and Iranian Plateaus into mountainous Central Asia, such as<br />

the Iranian Basseri; the horse-riding nomads of the Eurasian steppe, such as the<br />

Mongols and the Kazaks; and the yak breeders of the Tibetan Plateau. The second<br />

broad category of nomads is that of hunter-gatherers, whose mode of subsistence<br />

sets them apart from both pastoralists and sedentary farmers. There are huntergatherers<br />

who have fixed abodes (just as there are sedentary pastoralists), but several<br />

social groups around the world have (or have had, in most cases) patterns of living<br />

roughly similar to those of the Mbuti of central Africa, who travel most of the year,<br />

2 Colin Turnbull, <strong>Way</strong>ward Servants. The Two Worlds of the African Pygmies (Garden<br />

City, NY, 1965), pp. 26–7.<br />

3 Thomas J. Barfield, The Nomadic Alternative (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1993), p. 4.


Apology for Nomadology 115<br />

breaking camp every month or so. Like the African Mbuti, several Amazonian tribes<br />

and Australian Aboriginal groups also are frequently classified as nomadic huntergatherers.<br />

The third basic category is that of Gypsies, itinerant basket-makers,<br />

tinkers, weavers, mimes, magicians, musicians, horse dealers, nostrum traders,<br />

carnival people, circus performers, and so on. Characterized variously as “service<br />

nomads,” “economic nomads,” “commercial nomads,” “craftsman nomads,” “nonfood<br />

producing nomads,” “floating industrial populations,” “peripatetic tribes,”<br />

“peripatetic peoples,” or plain “peripatetics,” these are spatially mobile peoples who<br />

primarily exploit resources in the social environment. 4 They occupy what Berland<br />

and Salo call a distinct peripatetic niche: “the regular demand for specialized goods<br />

and/or services that more sedentary or pastoral communities cannot, or will not<br />

support on a permanent basis.” 5 They are “interim masters of imperfect markets,” 6<br />

their habitat less geographical than structural, consisting of the gaps opened for<br />

itinerant entrepreneurs by unstable and incompletely formed markets for goods and<br />

services. Finally, outside these three broad categories there are vagabonds, traveling<br />

thieves, migrant workers, bi-coastal executives, “academic Gypsies” and other such<br />

groups occasionally classified as nomads, as well as the anomalous instance of the<br />

“sea nomads” of Patagonia, Malaysia, Indonesia and Thailand, who perhaps might<br />

be best described as nautical hunter-gatherers.<br />

From a conventional anthropological view, it would seem that Deleuze and<br />

Guattari make a number of serious category errors, ignoring important distinctions<br />

between various ambulatory populations and attributing characteristics to such<br />

populations that are far from universally valid. But Deleuze and Guattari’s object<br />

is not to systematize received anthropological taxonomies; rather, it is to articulate<br />

two tendencies – the nomadic and the sedentary – that have each a certain inner<br />

coherence and that manifest themselves in various mixed forms. Essential here is<br />

the differentiation of observations de facto (of fact) and de jure (of law or right), a<br />

distinction of long standing in Scholastic legal theory and the philosophy of natural<br />

law that Bergson revives at several points in his thought and that Deleuze returns<br />

to frequently in his work. According to natural law theorists, for example, a despot<br />

or usurper may exercise power de facto, but only a legitimate sovereign rules de<br />

jure, that is, by a right inherent in the nature of things. In his Bergsonism, Deleuze<br />

shows how Bergson modifies the de facto/de jure opposition to distinguish between<br />

empirical mixtures of elements (de facto; French, en fait) and differences in nature<br />

(de jure; French, en droit). 7 Bergson’s well-known dualisms – duration/space, quality/<br />

quantity, matter/memory, and so on – are introduced to reinstate differences in nature<br />

that are generally ignored by analysts who consider only the mixed and confused<br />

4 See Matthew T. Salo and Sheila Salo, “Rominchel Economic and Social Organization<br />

in Urban New England, 1850–1930,” Urban Anthropology, 11/3–4 (1982), p. 276.<br />

5 Joseph C. Berland and Matt T. Salo, “Peripatetic Communities: An Introduction,”<br />

Nomadic Peoples (special issue on Peripatetic Peoples), 21/22 (1986), p. 2.<br />

6 David Nemeth, “Service Nomads: Interim Masters of Imperfect Markets,” Nomadic<br />

Peoples, 21/22 (1986), p. 136.<br />

7 The translators of Deleuze’s Bergsonism render “différence en nature” as “difference<br />

in kind,” a choice that is perhaps understandable stylistically, but that tends to mask the<br />

ontological status of Bergson’s distinction as entailing a difference in nature.


116<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

forms in which such differences appear in concrete experience. “According to<br />

Bergson,” says Deleuze, “a composite [un mixte] must always be divided according<br />

to its natural articulations, that is, into elements which differ in nature … Bergson<br />

is aware that things are mixed together in reality, in fact; experience itself offers us<br />

nothing but composites” (B 11–12/22). When Bergson speaks of pure duration or<br />

pure memory, he is delineating differences in nature that are manifest only de jure,<br />

not de facto: “If the composite represents the fact, it must be divided into tendencies<br />

or into pure presences that only exist en droit” (B 13/23). Bergson demonstrates, for<br />

example, that time is typically conceived of in a spatialized form, as a succession<br />

of points on a line. As a result, the genuine nature of time as ongoing, indivisible<br />

flow, or duration (durée), is lost. Only by distinguishing a pure durée from a pure<br />

space can one grasp the true nature of time. It happens that in fact we never directly<br />

experience such a pure durée or a pure space, for our space is always a temporal<br />

space and our time always a time in space. Nonetheless, Bergson asserts, durée and<br />

space are qualitatively different from one another; they constitute a difference in<br />

nature that is real, even if we only experience that difference in a mixed form. 8<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s opposition of nomadic and sedentary is one such de<br />

jure distinction of pure differences in nature. The nomadic and sedentary are pure<br />

tendencies that are real, yet that are only experienced in various mixed states. They<br />

are qualitatively different tendencies co-present across diverse social and cultural<br />

formations. This is a fundamental aspect of the concept of “nomadism,” and one<br />

generally ignored by critics of Deleuze and Guattari (and often by those who adopt<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s terminology as well). Hence, Deleuze and Guattari would<br />

have no problem with the frequent observation that no mobile populations wander<br />

aimlessly and randomly. They would simply argue that the restricted circulation<br />

of Masai herders around a village center, the regular migratory routes of Basseri<br />

sheep herders, the improvisatory seasonal movements of Bedouin camel raisers,<br />

and the ad hoc variable circuits of South East Asian sea nomads represent so many<br />

mixtures of nomadic and sedentary tendencies, each a particular de facto composite<br />

of differences in nature.<br />

One advantage of this approach is that characteristics striking in one mobile<br />

population can be shown to be faintly present in another or perhaps manifested there<br />

in an illuminatingly modified form. Consider, for example, the opposition of nomads<br />

and the State, which plays an important role in many discussions of pastoral nomads,<br />

whose ways of life often involve complex relations of dependence, resistance and<br />

accommodation with contiguous states. Deleuze and Guattari approach the nomad/<br />

State opposition via the work of Pierre Clastres, who in Society Against the State<br />

argues that the marked differences between the cultures of the Andean high plateaus<br />

and the cultures of the Tropical Forest, so evident to early Europeans observers<br />

in South America, represent a basic opposition between State cultures and those<br />

without a State. Clastres insists that Tropical Forest cultures, unlike such Andean<br />

8 For the sake of economy and clarity in delineating the de facto/de jure distinction,<br />

I have simplified Bergson’s views on durée and its relation to space. I discuss Deleuze’s<br />

reading of Bergsonian durée at greater length in the first Chapter of Deleuze on Cinema<br />

(New York, 2003).


Apology for Nomadology 117<br />

cultures as the Incan empire, possess a political organization that is not grounded<br />

in hierarchical class distinctions. The peoples of the Tropical Forest, which include<br />

both sedentary and nomadic hunter-gatherer tribes, generally have a chief, but the<br />

chief rules by consensus rather than coercion; far from using his position to extract<br />

inordinate wealth from his followers, the chief gains prestige by giving away most<br />

of his goods. Clastres concludes that Tropical Forest chieftainships are structured<br />

to inhibit the centralization and stratification of political power. Without any direct<br />

contact with State cultures, the Tropical Forest cultures anticipate and ward off the<br />

advent of the State form; in this sense, they are societies against the State.<br />

What Deleuze and Guattari see in Clastres’s analysis of the Tropical Forest<br />

chieftainship is evidence of the existence of a non-State political structure and the<br />

immanence of two tendencies, one patent and one latent, which they identify as<br />

nomadic/anti-State and sedentary/State tendencies. This appropriation of Clastres’s<br />

distinction invites first a reconsideration of non-State Tropical Forest cultures,<br />

which include nomadic hunter-gatherer and sedentary agricultural societies alike.<br />

Clastres notes that among South American peoples, every society’s passage from<br />

a non-State to a State form of political organization has been irreversible, whereas<br />

in some instances non-State sedentarism has given way to nomadism and vice<br />

versa. 9 For Deleuze and Guattari, this would be evidence that sedentary Tropical<br />

Forest cultures possess characteristics that are more nomadic than those of Stateform<br />

sedentary cultures, and that there is a fundamental nomadic tendency across<br />

Tropical Forest cultures. Deleuze and Guattari’s appropriation of Clastres’s findings<br />

also has suggestive implications for an analysis of the political organization of<br />

pastoral nomads. Barfield, for example, concludes that pastoral nomads manifest<br />

varying degrees of stratification and centralization in social structure, ranging from<br />

acephalous segmentary lineages (the Masai) to centralized tribal states (the Mongol<br />

empires), and that centralization increases in proportion to the power and complexity<br />

of the states with which the nomadic group must interact. 10 In the light of Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s schema, this proportional correlation of centralization and proximity<br />

to states is evidence not only of a fundamental opposition between nomadism and<br />

the State form but also of a structural relationship between non-State and State<br />

forms of organization that is more than simply contingent and accidental. By this<br />

view, a nomadic population’s contact with a state, rather than directly causing<br />

State tendencies to arise, simply activates a tendency already present within the<br />

nomadic society. According to this logic as well, one would expect to find nomadic<br />

tendencies within centralized states – and indeed, Deleuze and Guattari argue that<br />

non-State and State tendencies can be discerned both within nomadic societies<br />

and within state societies. State societies, far from being the monolithic entities<br />

they purport to be, are fissured by nomadic trajectories of various sorts, including<br />

those of diverse peripatetic groups. In this analysis, the peripatetic populations that<br />

roam state societies and escape their regulation are functional components of those<br />

societies, not extrinsic exceptions to their control. What this suggests finally is that<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s apparent blunder of confusing primitive hunter-gatherers,<br />

9 See Pierre Clastres, La Société contre l’état (Paris, 1974), pp. 201–203.<br />

10 Barfield, The Nomadic Alternative, pp. 16–17.


118<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

pastoral nomads and peripatetics may be of some value. Perhaps the varying degrees<br />

of political centralization among pastoral nomads, when subsumed within a larger<br />

context that includes hunter-gatherer opposition to proto-State structures as well<br />

as the strategies of peripatetic populations such as Gypsies to resist assimilation<br />

within the states they traverse, may be shown to be but concrete responses to a single<br />

problem common to all ambulatory populations.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s analyses of pure differences in nature also make possible<br />

the isolation of inconstant experiential qualities among social groups as well as<br />

their abstraction from other seemingly heterogeneous contexts. It may well be,<br />

for instance, that no actual nomad travels, as Deleuze and Guattari seem to claim,<br />

by moving along lines without journeying from point to point, but there is an<br />

identifiable, qualitatively distinct operation of negotiating space common to Arctic<br />

hunters, Bedouin herders and Patagonian sea nomads, one that proceeds piece-bypiece,<br />

via changing, multidimensional signs, in an improvisational and experimental<br />

manner. And when one extracts general characteristics from these practices and<br />

relates them to characteristics from other practices in a broad, abstract model,<br />

such as that of Riemannian space, a potentially useful concept emerges – that of<br />

a “smooth space” of pure lines between points, directional vectors without clear<br />

dimensional determination, and distributional spaces without fixed allocation of the<br />

elements’ positions. On the basis of such an abstract configuration of systematically<br />

related qualities, one may then identify smooth spaces in a number of areas – quilt<br />

manufacture, musical compositions, naval tactics, fractals, fluid dynamics, labor<br />

practices, jewelry design, painting, and so on.<br />

The establishment of abstract, de jure oppositions, such as that of the nomadic<br />

and sedentary, is particularly advantageous in the study of aesthetic objects and<br />

social practices, since it affords a means of assessing common tendencies within<br />

various cultural spheres without reducing any of those spheres to the status of an<br />

epiphenomenal projection of another. Consider, for example, the question of Béla<br />

Bartók and Gypsy music. In his 1914 essay “Observations on Rumanian Folk<br />

Music,” Bartók remarks that “Gipsies [sic] pervert melodies, change their rhythm<br />

to ‘gipsy’ rhythm, introduce among the people melodies heard in other regions and<br />

in the country seats of the gentry – in other words, they contaminate the style of<br />

genuine folk music.” 11 Here, one finds a direct link between social movement and<br />

musical practice, with the common stigmatization of the nomadic as impure and<br />

transgressive. Gypsies literally cross borders, and in the process bring the music<br />

of separate regions in contact with one another. They also cross class boundaries,<br />

commingling peasant music and songs heard “in the country seats of the gentry.”<br />

Bartók’s sense of peasant music is that of an art intimately connected to a territory, a<br />

“product of nature,” 12 he says, and Gypsy bands pervert and contaminate that product<br />

of nature through the admixture of foreign elements.<br />

Yet Bartók also attributes the unified styles of diverse Hungarian peasant musical<br />

traditions to “the instinctive faculty of variation in a like manner of large masses<br />

11 Béla Bartók, “Observations on Rumanian Folk Music,” Essays, ed. Benjamin Suchoff<br />

(New York, 1976), p. 198.<br />

12 Bartók, Essays, p. 221.


Apology for Nomadology 119<br />

living in a spiritual kinship,” this “faculty for variation” being “nothing short of a<br />

natural force” (p. 221). Here one sees the valorization of instinct and a territorial<br />

Volkgeist, but also the recognition of a “faculty for variation,” which resonates with<br />

the notion of nomadic musical practice as the instigation of a state of what Deleuze<br />

and Guattari call “continuous variation” (MP 123/97) – and indeed, an examination<br />

of Bartók’s The Hungarian Folk Song (1924) shows that what he values in this<br />

very territorial music is an aesthetic of rich rhythmic and melodic invention that,<br />

if assimilated directly into tonal Western art music, would unsettle and disturb its<br />

regularities. Further, Bartók recognizes that “there is real gipsy music too, songs on<br />

gipsy texts, but these are known to and sung by the non-musician rural gipsies only,<br />

the regular gipsy bands never play them in public” (p. 222).<br />

The “regular gipsy bands” to which Bartók refers have an ambiguous social role,<br />

transgressive in some regards, but compromising and accommodating in others.<br />

Historically, the professional Gypsy bands served the Hungarian gentry, “who<br />

despised the peasant class and regarded it as good only for the production of labourers,<br />

indeed, for serfs for their landed properties.” 13 The Hungarian gentry embraced a pan-<br />

European aesthetic, and hence one that rejected home-grown, territorial traditions<br />

(peasant traditions being the only ones that had survived hundreds of years of Turkish<br />

occupation), but one that also maintained for the gentry associations with modern<br />

state centralization and class domination. Gypsy bands in some ways reinforced<br />

aristocratic biases through their accommodations of folk motifs to the conventions<br />

of European art music, in the process obscuring the achievements of indigenous<br />

peasant music and encouraging confusion about Hungarian sources through the<br />

introduction of Balkan and Turkish rhythms and scales into their playing – including<br />

the notorious “Gypsy interval” of the augmented second.<br />

By Bartók’s day, the Gypsy bands had taken on an even more complicated role<br />

as purveyors of an urban popular art music, which brought together a trans-regional<br />

amalgam of peasant materials and commercial, “light” classical compositions.<br />

Bartók appreciated the Gypsy bands’ resistance to what he viewed as the base,<br />

commodity music of song hits, operetta airs and jazz, but the popular art music<br />

they promulgated was itself a commodification, regularization and rigidification of<br />

already fixed and ossified material – and hence, one might argue, an anti-nomadic<br />

force that impeded continuous variation. Finally, Bartók sought through Magyar<br />

peasant music to found a truly Hungarian art music, thereby doing for his culture<br />

what Smetana had done for the Czechs and Grieg for the Norwegians, yet even in this<br />

ambiguously territorializing effort at the construction of an ethnic musical identity,<br />

Bartók introduced a decidedly nomadic element, creatively combining, altering,<br />

transmuting and deforming folk motifs in an original personal style (and hence, to a<br />

degree, in a non-collective style) that became a significant force in the development<br />

of modernist innovation and experimentation in the Western art music tradition. One<br />

might say, then, that Bartók’s introduction of faithfully preserved Magyar materials<br />

within his own art music was a form of Gypsy nomadization of the Western classical<br />

tradition.<br />

13 Ibid., p. 361.


120<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

If the nomadic and the sedentary are de jure distinctions of pure differences in<br />

nature, which manifest themselves in diverse ways in various social groups and<br />

cultural spheres, one might ask what the status of these categories may be. Are they<br />

mere mental constructions imposed on a random field of heterogeneous phenomena?<br />

Deleuze and Guattari argue that they are not. Rather, they are problems posed by<br />

the real, a given problem characterized as an abstract configuration of differences<br />

that generates multiple concrete actualizations in various spheres. Though such pure<br />

differences in nature are evident in the actual only in mixed forms, they have a<br />

real and separable existence, albeit in a virtual realm, one that is distinct from the<br />

actual yet immanent within the real. The nomadic and the sedentary are abstract<br />

problems that the real continually poses to itself in ever-changing modes, motors<br />

of actualization through which the ongoing unfolding of the world works out its<br />

experimentations and inventions. But those problems also manifest themselves in<br />

thought, and hence do have a mental counterpart. Thought, says Deleuze, is not<br />

voluntary and self-regulating, but involuntary and eccentric, the result of a violence<br />

that dislocates common sense and deregulates the senses, thereby forcing thought<br />

beyond itself to think the unthought and the previously unthinkable. Hence, though<br />

the nomadic and the sedentary have a real existence separate from a consciousness<br />

that conceives them, the categories, to the extent that they represent the products<br />

of genuine thought, are themselves generated from virtual problems that exist<br />

within the real – in this case, within the realm of thought. Yet the thought of the<br />

nomadic is itself nomadic, as is Deleuze and Guattari’s thought of pure differences in<br />

nature. If Deleuze and Guattari follow Bergson in stressing the separation of mixed<br />

elements into pure differences in nature, they do so only to instigate a metamorphic<br />

renegotiation and reconfiguration of those differences. Like Bergson, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari propose numerous binary oppositions, including that of the nomadic and<br />

the sedentary, yet their effort is not to fix categories and demarcate permanent<br />

essences, but to make something pass between the terms of a binary opposition,<br />

and thereby to foster a thought that brings into existence something new. In this<br />

regard, the categories of pure differences in nature are themselves generative forces<br />

of differentiation, which through their mutual opposition function to displace and<br />

transform one another.<br />

I have tried to suggest some of the ways in which Deleuze and Guattari’s approach<br />

to nomadism is connected to the concrete activities of actual nomadic groups, be<br />

they pastoral nomads, nomadic hunter-gatherers, or peripatetic service nomads, as<br />

well as the means whereby the concept may be extended to issues in the arts and<br />

philosophy. Since the nomadic and the sedentary always present themselves in mixed,<br />

composite forms, their delineation requires a careful discernment of fluctuating,<br />

multi-leveled tendencies that resists simplistic reduction. As I tried to demonstrate<br />

in the Bartók example, a broad contrast of nomadic Gypsy and sedentary art music<br />

is inadequate, since varying degrees of nomadism and sedentarism are evident in<br />

Magyar and Gypsy peasant music, in the music promoted by Hungarian elites, by<br />

the European popular culture industry, and by urban Gypsy bands, as well as in the<br />

ethnic-nationalist and modernist developments of the Western art music tradition.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s nomadic thought is inherently unstable, in that its use of<br />

binary oppositions is intended to be generative and mutative, but it is not therefore


Apology for Nomadology 121<br />

to be pursued in a haphazard and careless fashion. If the thought of the nomadic<br />

is to be adequate to the actual disclosure of the virtual problem of the nomadic as<br />

real difference in nature, it must engage empirical evidence and historical detail, as<br />

well as the disciplinary considerations of the various established fields of inquiry<br />

across which it moves. Only in that fashion can the concept of the nomadic foster<br />

something that is both useful and new.


This page intentionally left blank


Chapter 9<br />

Nomadism, Globalism<br />

and Cultural Studies<br />

There is no doubt that we live in an increasingly global era. The specific configuration<br />

and interconnection of elements that might eventually characterize a truly global<br />

order are by no means certain, but that some such order will eventually emerge,<br />

I believe, is inevitable. In such a context of increasing globalization, the field<br />

of cultural studies – if indeed it is a single field – faces several issues that echo<br />

concerns expressed in widespread social, economic and political debates. Is it the<br />

job of cultural studies to counter the forces of global cultural homogenization and<br />

engage in an identity politics that reinforces local specificities? Should the discipline<br />

attempt to isolate common – or even universal – concerns among cultures at the risk<br />

of promoting the asymmetrical power relations of a multinational financial-militarygovernmental<br />

technocracy? Or should cultural studies function primarily as a force<br />

of hybridization, somehow blurring local distinctions without ever allowing the<br />

emergence of a single stable global order?<br />

Over the last decade or two, the work of Deleuze and Guattari has drawn<br />

increasing attention from scholars in cultural studies and analysts interested in<br />

globalization. In cultural studies of a continental European orientation, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s influence has been marked, especially in discussions of what they call<br />

“minor literature,” and in the growing literature on globalization several of Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s concepts have made their appearance, perhaps most fully in Michael<br />

Hardt and Antonio Negri’s Empire, which may be seen as an extended development<br />

of the implications of Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus for a postmodern<br />

conception of sovereignty. Of the many concepts developed by Deleuze and Guattari,<br />

“nomadism” is one that has had an especial appeal to scholars in cultural studies and<br />

that has increasingly infiltrated discussions of globalization. In A Thousand Plateaus,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari develop a complex of terms around the notion of “nomadism,”<br />

and though the concept has been exploited frequently by others, it has not always<br />

been fully understood, nor has it often been articulated clearly and completely. I<br />

believe that the concept of “nomadism” might help us chart the course of cultural<br />

studies in a global era, but only if the concept is engaged in a detailed and thorough<br />

manner. My purpose, therefore, is to provide an extended exposition of the concept<br />

of “nomadism,” indicate its relevance for understanding the ongoing processes of<br />

globalization with which we must continue to contend, and suggest its potential role<br />

in the formation of a domain of cultural studies that promotes a positive, creative and<br />

non-totalizing “globalism.”


124<br />

Nomadic Distribution<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Deleuze and Guattari apply the concept of “nomadism” to a wide range of topics,<br />

including mathematics, physics, games, cloth manufacture, metallurgy, music and art,<br />

but the core elements of the concept derive from observations about nomadic peoples.<br />

When speaking of “nomads” and “the nomadic” in this socio-anthropological sense,<br />

Deleuze and Guattari seem to play fast and free with traditional anthropological<br />

distinctions and to make sweeping assertions about nomadic populations that ignore<br />

the complexities of actual concrete groups. Anthropologists commonly differentiate<br />

among hunter-gatherers, pastoral nomads and peripatetics, reserving the label of<br />

“nomads” for the five main groups of pastoral nomads – the African pastoralists of the<br />

Sahel, such as the Masai; the camel pastoralists of the Saharan and Arabian Deserts;<br />

the sheep and goat pastoralists of the region running from the Mediterranean littoral<br />

through the Anatolian and Iranian Plateaus into mountainous central Asia; the horseriding<br />

nomads of the Eurasian steppe; and the yak breeders of the Tibetan Plateau. 1<br />

Yet Deleuze and Guattari seem indifferent to such distinctions, citing as instances<br />

of nomadism traditional hunter-gatherer tribes of Africa and South America, various<br />

pastoral nomads, such as the Mongols and the Bedouins, the sea nomads of Patagonia,<br />

as well as peripatetics of diverse sorts – itinerant craftsmen, gypsies, street gangs,<br />

and so on. And much of what they say about nomads seems applicable to one group<br />

only, or solely to a single aspect of one group’s behavior. Some critics have seen in<br />

this treatment of nomadism signs of sloppy scholarship and a romantic idealization<br />

of mobile populations, but Deleuze and Guattari are in reality developing a concept<br />

of nomadism that deliberately cuts across traditional anthropological categories and<br />

extracts characteristics from actual social groups that are at times only intermittently<br />

and indirectly evident in those populations. Their object is to identify two broad<br />

tendencies – the nomadic and the sedentary – each of which has an inner coherence<br />

yet is manifest concretely only in various mixed forms.<br />

Crucial here is the distinction between observations de facto (of fact; French: en<br />

fait) and de jure (of law or right; French: de droit), a distinction Deleuze and Guattari<br />

take from natural law theory by way of Henri Bergson (see Chapter 8). As Deleuze<br />

and Guattari indicate at several points in A Thousand Plateaus, their opposition of the<br />

nomadic and the sedentary is a de jure distinction of pure differences in nature. The<br />

nomadic and the sedentary are qualitatively distinct and real categories, but they are<br />

experienced in fact only as tendencies within various mixed states. Hence, Deleuze<br />

and Guattari would have no difficulty explaining sedentary proclivities within<br />

nomadic populations or the patent appearance of certain nomadic characteristics<br />

solely within certain groups and not within others. In each case, a de jure difference<br />

in nature is manifest only in a de facto mixture.<br />

Although Deleuze and Guattari’s most extended treatment of nomadism is to be<br />

found in A Thousand Plateaus, as early as 1969 Deleuze engages certain elements<br />

of the topic in Difference and Repetition. There, he attempts to characterize being in<br />

terms of multiplicities that are irreducible to a dialectic of the One and the Many, and<br />

1 See Thomas J. Barfield, The Nomadic Alternative (Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1993), pp.<br />

1–19.


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 125<br />

he does so through the concept of a “nomadic distribution” of elements. In reflecting<br />

on the notion of the nomadic, Deleuze finds particularly illuminating Emmanuel<br />

Laroche’s 1949 study, History of the Root “Nem-” in Ancient Greek, an exhaustive<br />

treatment of the family of ancient Greek words that includes nemo, nemao, Nemesis,<br />

nomos, nomas and other cognates.<br />

In classical Greek of the fifth century B.C.E., nomos generally means “law” or<br />

“custom,” and Nemesis refers to “Fate.” Laroche observes that scholars traditionally<br />

attribute these meanings to an archaic sense of nomos as a partitioning and assigning<br />

of lands to various parties and of Nemesis as an allocation of separate lots, or fates,<br />

to individuals. Laroche counters that the etymological history is much more complex<br />

than this account would indicate. The key to that etymological history he finds in<br />

the eighth century B.C.E. Homeric usage of the verb nemo, which he translates as<br />

“to distribute.” The actions of “dividing into parts” and “distributing” are related<br />

in the Homeric world, as when a warrior carves a roasted lamb into parts and then<br />

distributes pieces to his comrades, but nemo refers solely to the act of distributing.<br />

The Homeric sense of nemesis is not that of fate, but that of an imputation of blame,<br />

which derives from the concept of nemesis as an improper distribution of elements.<br />

The sense of nomos as law or convention Laroche sees as a late development,<br />

with the archaic sense of nomos coming from the usages associated with pasturage<br />

and nomads. In Homer, nomos designates a place where animals graze. “Pasturage<br />

in archaic times,” notes Laroche, “is in general an unlimited space; it can be a<br />

forest, meadows beside rivers, a mountain slope.” 2 Archaic nomos in no way<br />

indicates a partitioning of land. Later, after the reforms of Solon, nomos comes to<br />

mean “assigned plot of land,” but this usage reflects an extension of city sedentary<br />

divisions to the surrounding countryside. In archaic times, by contrast, if the nomos<br />

is related to the city, it is as “an expanse of habitable land around a city before being<br />

an administrative province” (p. 117). Laroche concludes then that “nomos designates<br />

nothing other than pasturage for animals or a habitat without recognized limits for<br />

men” (p. 117). The archaic term nomas, Laroche points out, designates either a<br />

nomadic herdsman or a herd animal, a nomadic herdsman being characterized as a<br />

wandering individual with no fixed domicile, and a herd animal as a creature that<br />

moves freely and randomly across an open territory (p. 122).<br />

What Deleuze takes from Laroche’s study is the notion of nomos as a distribution<br />

of multiple elements in an open, undivided and unlimited space. In Difference<br />

and Repetition, Deleuze describes being in terms of a “nomadic distribution,” a<br />

distribution of an irreducible multiplicity that “is no longer a division of that which<br />

is distributed but rather a division among those who distribute themselves in an open<br />

space – a space that is unlimited, or at least without precise limits” (DR 54/36).<br />

In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari do not attempt a description of all<br />

being as a “nomadic distribution,” as Deleuze does in Difference and Repetition, but<br />

they do make use of the archaic Greek notion of nomos in developing the concept<br />

of “nomadism.” They cite Laroche and oppose the nomadic to the sedentary as<br />

the archaic Greek nomos of open pasturage to the partitioned territory of the city<br />

2 Emmanuel Laroche, Histoire de la racine “nem-” en Grec ancient (Paris, 1949), p.<br />

116 (translation mine).


126<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

(MP 472/557). And whenever they speak of the nomadic they conceive of it as a<br />

multiplicity distributed in an open space.<br />

One model of the nomadic, then, is that of a flock of sheep occupying an<br />

undivided landscape. The flock wanders over undulating surfaces, filling the<br />

contours of valleys, plains, hillsides, or slopes, in each case occupying space to the<br />

extent of its capabilities, its puissances, or powers. The configuration of relations<br />

among individual sheep shifts and changes, and the shape of the collective flock<br />

is in constant metamorphosis, adapting itself to the variations in the topography of<br />

the landscape. As the flock roams, it continually exceeds the limits of its external<br />

outlining edges, filling new space as it leaves previously occupied territory. The<br />

flock is a flow, a flux of multiple elements engaged in an ongoing metamorphic,<br />

dynamic process of nomadic distribution across an open and undivided space.<br />

Before proceeding to Deleuze and Guattari’s definition of nomadism, we should<br />

note two important characteristics of the multiplicities involved in a nomadic<br />

distribution of elements. First, the multiplicities are qualitative multiplicities. In<br />

Bergsonism, Deleuze credits Bergson with being the first philosopher to differentiate<br />

clearly between quantitative and qualitative multiplicities. Quantitative multiplicities<br />

are collections of elements that do not change their qualities when increased or<br />

decreased through addition, subtraction, multiplication, or division. Five bricks plus<br />

five bricks equal ten bricks, but whether a collection of five bricks or a collection of<br />

ten bricks, the multiplicity remains a collection of bricks. Qualitative multiplicities,<br />

by contrast, cannot be increased or decreased mathematically without being<br />

changed qualitatively. A room at a temperature of sixty degrees may be heated to<br />

a temperature of ninety degrees, but the multiplicity of the room at sixty degrees is<br />

qualitatively different from the room at ninety degrees. One cannot add sixty degrees<br />

to thirty degrees without creating a new qualitative multiplicity of ninety degrees,<br />

one that is incommensurable with any quantitative summation of sixty and thirty.<br />

All nomadic multiplicities are such qualitative multiplicities. In this regard, each<br />

nomadic multiplicity has an identity, but an identity that is irreducibly multiple and<br />

open to metamorphosis as its constituent elements increase or decrease. In that its<br />

identity is formed through its qualities, each multiplicity also possesses a certain<br />

affectivity.<br />

Second, nomadic multiplicities constitute what Deleuze and Guattari call<br />

“rhizomes.” In A Thousand Plateaus, they oppose rhizomes to “arborescences,” or<br />

root-tree structures. Unlike arborescences, which have a vertical, hierarchical and<br />

centralized configuration, rhizomes are horizontal, nonhierarchical formations with<br />

no center. Deleuze and Guattari liken rhizomes to crabgrass, which spreads in all<br />

directions and extends roots along every surface it occupies. There is no central root,<br />

no privileged locus of growth. Any patch of crabgrass, if uprooted and transplanted,<br />

may initiate a renewed process of growth and expansion. Not only is the rhizome<br />

nonhierarchical and acentered, but it also manifests what Deleuze and Guattari<br />

call “the principles of connection and heterogeneity: any point of a rhizome can be<br />

connected to any other point whatever, and must be” (MP 13/7). The rhizome, then,<br />

has no center, no hierarchical organization, and no stable patterns of interconnection<br />

among its elements. The rhizome, we might say, is a network much like the internet<br />

(which only came into being after Deleuze and Guattari developed the concept of the


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 127<br />

rhizome), a proliferating multiplicity of terminals and circuits, in which any terminal<br />

may be connected to any other terminal, and with such rapidity that each terminal<br />

is virtually contiguous to every other terminal, no matter how far apart the various<br />

terminals may be in terms of actual spatial distance.<br />

We may thus make the following preliminary summary of the characteristics<br />

of a nomadic multiplicity: it spreads over an unlimited and undivided space as a<br />

metamorphic flux; it constitutes a qualitative multiplicity with an identity that is<br />

irreducibly plural and affective; and it forms a rhizome, without center or hierarchy,<br />

in which each element is in virtual contiguity and connection with every other<br />

element.<br />

Nomadism, Smooth Space and the War Machine<br />

In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari define nomadism through two complex<br />

concepts: the war machine and smooth space. The relationship between nomadism,<br />

the war machine and smooth space is expressed in an especially succinct (albeit<br />

cryptic) manner in the following comment made by Deleuze in a 1980 interview on<br />

A Thousand Plateaus:<br />

We define the “war machine” as a linear assemblage which constructs itself on lines of<br />

flight. In this sense, the war machine does not at all have war as its object; it has as its<br />

object a very special space, smooth space, which it composes, occupies and propagates.<br />

Nomadism is precisely this combination “war machine-smooth space.” We try to show<br />

how and in what case the war machine takes war for its object (when the apparatuses of<br />

the State appropriate the war machine which does not initially belong to them). A war<br />

machine tends to be revolutionary, or artistic, much more so than military. [PP 50–51/33]<br />

First let us examine the notion of “smooth space.” Deleuze and Guattari oppose<br />

smooth space to striated space, identifying smooth space as “nomad space … the<br />

space in which the war machine develops,” and striated space as “sedentary space<br />

… the space instituted by the State apparatus” (MP 592/474). The opposition seems<br />

quite simple: smooth space is space undivided and unmeasured, whereas striated<br />

space is crisscrossed with grids of dividing and measuring lines. But the distinction<br />

is more complicated than it might initially appear. First, it is a de jure distinction, as<br />

Deleuze and Guattari explicitly state:<br />

[T]he two spaces only exist in fact in mixtures of one another: smooth space is ceaselessly<br />

translated, transversed into striated space; striated space is constantly reversed, turned into<br />

a smooth space … and the two can happen at the same time. Yet the de facto mixtures do<br />

not impede the de jure distinction, the abstract distinction between the two spaces. [MP<br />

593/474–5]<br />

Second, the distinction is not strictly spatial. In fact, Deleuze and Guattari take the<br />

opposition of smooth space and striated space from the composer Pierre Boulez, who<br />

uses the terms to describe different forms of time in musical compositions, smooth<br />

space characterizing the nonpulsed time of free, irregular motifs, and striated space<br />

the pulsed time of regular, metrical motifs. Thus, Deleuze and Guattari describe


128<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

literal space in terms of the smooth and the striated, but they extend the concepts<br />

as well to such figurative spaces as music, art and mathematics. Third, and most<br />

important, “smooth” and “striated” describe not simply space per se, but also ways<br />

of inhabiting and using space, and in this sense, ways of creating a smooth or a<br />

striated space.<br />

In Deleuze and Guattari’s discussion of the maritime model of smooth space,<br />

the de facto mixture of smooth and striated spaces is especially evident, as is the<br />

relationship between space and its usage. They note that though “the sea is a smooth<br />

space par excellence” (MP 598/479), the history of seafaring is one of increasing<br />

striation of that paradigmatic smooth element, various inventions allowing ever more<br />

precise measurements of positions, distances, currents and depths. Yet coexistent<br />

with these discoveries are the local practices of fishermen, transporters and travelers,<br />

which constitute “a complex and empirical nomadic navigation by way of winds,<br />

noises, colors and sounds of the sea” (MP 599/479). And though such technological<br />

innovations as sonar, radar, satellites and global positioning devices might seem<br />

to have rendered the seas an absolutely striated space, Deleuze and Guattari point<br />

out that even such a heavily gridded element can function as a smooth space. The<br />

military deployment of ships, aircraft and submarines by modern superpowers aims<br />

at the creation of a virtual force, coextensive with the oceans, that may manifest itself<br />

at any place and at any time. Such a virtual naval force, in Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

judgment, uses the striation of the seas as a means of converting the seas into a<br />

smooth surface of unlimited, acentered power, in which a submarine, a destroyer, a<br />

missile, or a squadron of aircraft may suddenly become manifest at any point of that<br />

surface. A similar military occupation extends from the sea to the air, such that “the<br />

sea, then the air and the stratosphere, become smooth spaces again, but in order to<br />

control striated space more completely, in the strangest of reversals” (MP 599/480).<br />

Smooth and striated spaces, then, are not simply givens of the natural world,<br />

but they are spaces with different modes of construction or composition. Deleuze<br />

and Guattari offer as a particularly clear example of these contrasting modes of<br />

construction the processes whereby woven fabric and felt are made. In the simplest<br />

instance, woven fabric consists of two sets of parallel threads, one horizontal, and<br />

one vertical. Each set has a prescribed function, the horizontal threads, say, serving<br />

as a fixed element, the vertical threads serving as a mobile element, passing over<br />

and under the horizontal. The fabric may be of an unlimited length, but its width<br />

must be finite (determined by the width of the loom). And the fabric has a top side<br />

and a reverse side, an outer surface and an inner surface. To weave fabric, then, is<br />

to construct a striated space, one that is crisscrossed with lines, the lines assigned<br />

prescribed functions, its production contained within set bounds, and its dimensions<br />

clearly demarcated. To create felt, by contrast, is to construct a smooth space. In felt,<br />

threads are not separated; instead, fibers are entangled by being pressed together,<br />

the microscopic variations in the fibers allowing unpredictable interconnections<br />

and adhesions. In this regard, though felt forms a smooth space, its elements are<br />

heterogeneous. Felt opposes fabric in all respects: “in principle it is infinite, open or<br />

unlimited in all directions; it has no top side, bottom side or center; it assigns no fixed<br />

or mobile functions, but rather distributes a continuous variation” (MP 594/475–6).


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 129<br />

Smooth and striated spaces also imply different modes of inhabiting space,<br />

and in this respect Deleuze and Guattari see the practices of nomadic peoples as<br />

especially illuminating. The Bedouins may follow broadly determined routes<br />

through the desert and seek out fixed landmarks, and in this sense they traverse<br />

a somewhat striated space, but the shifting sands of the landscape are in constant<br />

variation and their passage must proceed along the unpredictable sites of scattered<br />

shrubs, bushes and patches of grass that serve as pasturage for their animals. In this<br />

respect, they inhabit the desert as a smooth space. They move from oasis to oasis,<br />

but not as migrants traveling from fixed abode to fixed abode. Rather, each oasis<br />

serves as a relay in an open-ended, zigzag trajectory, a way-station in a process<br />

of continuous movement. If each oasis is seen as a point, and every path between<br />

oases as a line, one may thus say that in a smooth space points are subordinate to<br />

lines. In striated space, one moves from point to point, the line serving merely as a<br />

connection between fixed points. In smooth space, by contrast, each point is merely<br />

a pause in the ongoing movement of the line. The line in smooth space, therefore, is<br />

“a vector, a direction and not a dimension or a metric determination” (MP 597/478).<br />

The line of striated space can be measured and assigned a dimensional position,<br />

in that it always passes between fixed and clearly demarcated points. The line of<br />

smooth space, in contrast, moves through unevenly distributed points, each point<br />

functioning as an unpredictable event in the vector’s thrust. What makes possible<br />

the dimensional, metrically determined line of striated space is that “in striated<br />

space, one closes off a surface and ‘allocates’ it according to determinate intervals,<br />

following assigned breaks,” whereas the directional, vectorial line of smooth space<br />

presupposes a domain in which “one ‘distributes’ oneself over an open space,<br />

according to frequencies and along the course of one’s crossings” (MP 600/481).<br />

Thus, if we contrast smooth and striated space in terms of the three basic elements of<br />

Euclidean geometry – the one-dimensional point, the two-dimensional line and the<br />

three-dimensional volume – we may say that the smooth point is subordinate to the<br />

line, whereas the striated point dominates the line; that the smooth line is directional<br />

and vectorial, whereas the striated line is dimensional and metrical; and that the<br />

smooth volume entails a self-distribution across an open space, whereas the striated<br />

volume presumes an allocation of elements in accord with determinate intervals and<br />

assigned discontinuities.<br />

Smooth space, then, is both inhabited and created, and that which inhabits and<br />

creates such a space is the “war machine.” The concept of the “war machine” is one<br />

of the more obscure and unsettling notions of A Thousand Plateaus. Though Deleuze<br />

and Guattari talk about the war machine at length, nowhere do they provide a clear<br />

definition of the term. The name itself seems to arise from common associations of<br />

the nomadic hordes of Central Asia, such as the Golden Horde of Genghis Khan,<br />

with a pure form of terrifying violence, each horde functioning as an amorphous<br />

roaming “war machine” haphazardly encountering and destroying the sedentary<br />

settlements in its path. Deleuze and Guattari use this term in part to introduce<br />

the provocative theses that nomads invent the war machine, that the State merely<br />

appropriates and tames the war machine in the form of conventional armies, and<br />

that war in the common sense of the word is not the object of the war machine per<br />

se, but the object of the war machine as captured by the State apparatus. To grant


130<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

these arguments the detailed consideration they deserve is well beyond our scope<br />

here, but what is important to note is that the war machine is opposed to the State<br />

apparatus, and that the war machine constructs and inhabits smooth space, whereas<br />

the State apparatus constructs and inhabits striated space. Through this opposition of<br />

war machine and State apparatus, Deleuze and Guattari mean to suggest that there<br />

is a pervasive political dimension to the distinction between smooth and striated<br />

space – indeed, that every complex mixture of the smooth and the striated, whether<br />

it be social, economic, technological, scientific, mathematical, musical, literary, or<br />

philosophical, is also connected to and inseparable from the domain of the political.<br />

By identifying nomads with the war machine, Deleuze and Guattari suggest that<br />

a nomadic population may be seen as a machine, a collective entity defined by its<br />

function, which is that of creating and inhabiting a smooth space. A war machine is<br />

like a nomadic horde, a collective heterogeneous multiplicity passing through various<br />

sites, tracing vectors along which it distributes itself in open, metamorphic flows.<br />

By designating such a horde a machine, Deleuze and Guattari defamiliarize and<br />

denaturalize this anthropological example, indicating that the horde is an apersonal<br />

collective function, a force of production that does something, and that other<br />

collective entities involving both human and nonhuman components may likewise<br />

function as forces that produce smooth space. Ultimately, what Deleuze and Guattari<br />

designate by the term “war machine” is a force of transformation and metamorphosis<br />

– hence Deleuze’s remark that “A war machine tends to be revolutionary, or artistic,<br />

much more so than military” (PP 51/33). Deleuze also says that the war machine<br />

“constructs itself on lines of flight” (PP 50/33). Deleuze and Guattari frequently<br />

speak of “lines of flight,” taking the term from the French phrase for the vanishing<br />

point, or point de fuite, in a perspectival drawing (with the additional notion that a<br />

“line of flight” is a line of “leakage,” from the French usage of fuite to refer to a leak<br />

in a gas line, for example). A line of flight is a line of escape from any fixed and stable<br />

order. It is a line between things, between clearly demarcated entities and identities, a<br />

zigzag, unpredictable course that disrupts the coordinates of an organized space. The<br />

line of flight, in short, is the nomadic line of a smooth space. And what is essential<br />

is that the line of flight is a line of becoming-other, of metamorphosis and constant<br />

transformation.<br />

The war machine, says Deleuze, “composes, occupies and propagates” (PP 50/33)<br />

smooth space. As we recall, smooth space is not simply inhabited, but it is created<br />

through its usage. Hence, the “war machine,” the name by which we may refer to<br />

any nomadic multiplicity, constructs or composes the smooth space that it occupies,<br />

and as it continues to move it propagates further smooth space. The nomadic<br />

multiplicity is a wandering machine producing its own habitat and extending that<br />

habitat as it wanders. The trajectory of this wandering machine follows a line of<br />

flight, a course of constant metamorphosis, transformation and becoming-other. If<br />

we return to the model of a wandering flock of sheep, we can say that the nomadic<br />

tribe and its wandering flock together constitute a qualitative multiplicity and that<br />

the territory they inhabit is likewise a nomadic qualitative multiplicity. We must<br />

envision the nomadic tribe and flock as a dynamic, ever-changing flux, but we must<br />

also see the land they traverse as a dynamic, ever-changing flux. The nomads and<br />

their flocks constitute a rhizome of interconnected elements, and their movements


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 131<br />

in turn convert the space they inhabit into a rhizome of interconnected elements.<br />

Smooth space, finally, is less a thing than an active process. The war machine in<br />

this sense is the dynamic force immanent to the productive engendering of smooth<br />

space – or perhaps we should say, it is the force of smooth-spacing, and this ongoing,<br />

metamorphic activity of smooth-spacing is nomadism.<br />

Globalization and Globalism<br />

What has nomadism to do with globalization? In A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari frequently refer to phenomena associated with contemporary tendencies<br />

in globalization. In their discussion of the maritime model of smooth and striated<br />

space, for example, they engage the military dimension of globalization, the virtual,<br />

omni-present naval force representing the notion of a comprehensive global military<br />

order that combines the features of a smooth space of immanent, virtual force and a<br />

striated space of control and domination in the service of the states that deploy such<br />

military forces. They also relate the emergence of this military order to the formation<br />

of what Deleuze calls the “society of control” (see PP 240–47/177–82), a kind of<br />

universal social order of constant self-monitoring and self-regulation whereby<br />

individuals construct, organize, discipline and shape one another and themselves.<br />

The goal of a society of control, Deleuze and Guattari imply, is a global social order<br />

that transcends cultural divisions, one in which the very production of people – their<br />

bodies, their ways of living, their modes of subjectivity – undergoes a constant and<br />

thorough monitoring and control. Such a society of control, like the omnipresent<br />

naval force, converts the striated space of traditional social structures into a smooth<br />

space of immanent, dispersed power, but only the more effectively to control and<br />

regulate that space.<br />

But it is perhaps in their discussions of capitalism that Deleuze and Guattari most<br />

fully engage the interrelationship between nomadism and globalization. In their<br />

analysis, the basic tendency of capitalism is to undo complex social codes that limit<br />

relations of production, exchange and consumption and to convert everything into<br />

interchangeable units of capital. In traditional societies, codes determine who can<br />

produce what, which relations of exchange are permissible, which are taboo, who<br />

may consume what goods, who may not. In capitalist societies, the commodity form<br />

tends to replace all restrictive codes. Everything is converted into a quantitative unit<br />

of capital, all relations of production, exchange and consumption are commodified,<br />

and the world tends to resemble a universal machine of schizophrenic interconnecting<br />

flows that mingle commodified bits of people, places, things, processes, fantasies,<br />

ideas, and so on. Yet capitalism depends on the State apparatus for a regulation of<br />

these schizophrenic flows, and hence, though commodification tends to undo all<br />

traditional restrictive social codes, at the same time the State apparatus constantly<br />

recodes flows in newly constructed improvisatory formations. We may say, then, that<br />

capitalism is inherently globalizing in its tendency to proliferate in an unchecked<br />

decoding of flows, that in its schizophrenic interconnecting of flows it functions as a<br />

war machine in a smooth space, and that its recoding of flows via the State apparatus<br />

converts that smooth space into a striated space of control and regulation.


132<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Deleuze and Guattari note that the uneasy relationship between the State and<br />

capitalism is suggested in the emergence of “an enormous, so-called stateless,<br />

monetary mass that circulates through foreign exchanges and across borders,<br />

escaping the control of States, forming a multinational ecumenical organization,<br />

constituting a supranational de facto power, unaffected by governmental decisions”<br />

(MP 566/453). Yet they regard the existence of such a “multinational ecumenical<br />

organization” not as a phenomenon peculiar to capitalism, but as a specific<br />

manifestation of a general feature of every State apparatus. The State, they claim,<br />

does not evolve from non-State social forms. The State apparatus is ubiquitous:<br />

“there has always been a State, and quite perfect, quite well-formed” (MP 445/360).<br />

Likewise, there has always been a non-State, a social organization outside the<br />

State form. The State is the quintessential “form of interiority” (MP 446/360), a<br />

structure of enclosure, organization and regulation – in short, a structure that creates<br />

a sedentary, striated space and an appropriately structured population to inhabit it.<br />

The non-State is manifest as a “form of exteriority” (MP 446/360), a nomadic war<br />

machine that composes, occupies and propagates a smooth space. Just as the de jure<br />

sedentary striated space and nomadic smooth space only appear in de facto mixtures,<br />

so do the State apparatus and non-State forms always appear together. Further, the<br />

State apparatus is always in a relationship with the nomadic as its “outside,” and<br />

conversely non-State forms are always in a relationship with the State apparatus.<br />

Hence, Deleuze and Guattari conclude:<br />

The outside [of the State apparatus] appears simultaneously in two directions: great<br />

worldwide machines, branched out across the ecumenon at a given moment, which enjoy<br />

a large degree of autonomy in relation to States (for example, commercial organizations<br />

of the “multinational” type, or industrial complexes, or even religious formations like<br />

Christianity, Islam, certain prophetic or messianic movements, etc.); but also local<br />

mechanisms of bands, margins, minorities, which continue to affirm the rights of<br />

segmentary societies against the organs of power of the State. The modern world offers us<br />

today particularly well developed images of these two directions, one toward worldwide<br />

ecumenical machines, but also another toward a neoprimitivism, a new tribal society such<br />

as McLuhan describes it. These directions are equally present in every social field, and in<br />

all periods. [MP 445–6/360]<br />

We may say, then, that the State is always haunted by two manifestations of the “form<br />

of exteriority,” one an outside beyond its limits, an ecumenical network extending<br />

towards unlimited horizons; the other an outside within its borders, evident in all<br />

the local pockets of nomadism, underdevelopment and deviation that escape State<br />

control and riddle it with holes. What this suggests, finally, is that the “outside” of<br />

the State is not so much literally outside as that it is an essence of the outside – a pure<br />

“form of exteriority” – that is immanent within the “form of interiority” of the State.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari are often regarded as theorists who approach globalization<br />

primarily from a Marxian economic perspective. In some respects this is true, and<br />

in Hardt and Negri’s Empire one can see the extent to which Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

analysis of late capitalism may be applied to contemporary manifestations of<br />

globalization. However, Deleuze and Guattari recognize the degree to which noneconomic<br />

elements are inextricably bound with economic relations in modern


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 133<br />

societies of control (as do Hardt and Negri, we might note), and their approach to<br />

the State form and its outside suggests that they would concur that sociocultural<br />

rather than exclusively economic analyses of globalization have some validity.<br />

Roland Robertson, for example, has argued that globalization has its source in broad<br />

sociocultural changes in Europe in early modernity that go beyond mere economic<br />

developments, to which Deleuze and Guattari might simply respond that indeed,<br />

globalization in early modernity tends to proceed through means more cultural than<br />

economic, but that increasingly economic means have come to dominance in this<br />

process over the last two centuries. Some, like Mihai Spariosu, have pointed out<br />

that Robertson’s account of globalization is myopic in that it ignores instances of<br />

globalization in other parts of the world at other times, such as the development of<br />

various empires – Chinese, Assyrian, Persian, Macedonian, Roman, Incan, Mayan,<br />

and so on – that had as their object an unlimited expansion into all surrounding<br />

territories. 3 Here, too, Deleuze and Guattari would concur, for they assert that the<br />

State apparatus and its outside occur “in every social field, in all periods,” and<br />

such imperial manifestations of globalization throughout history would simply be<br />

evidence of the inherently totalizing nature of the State apparatus.<br />

Ultimately, what Deleuze and Guattari are proposing in the contrasting concepts<br />

of sedentary striated space and nomadic smooth space are two models of totality, or<br />

the Whole, both of which are manifest to varying degrees and in diverse mixtures<br />

throughout history. Striated space is an englobing, containing Whole, a totality<br />

that gains its coordinates and dimensions through its delimitation of a sphere of<br />

total control. The tendency of every striated space is to encompass a Whole that<br />

grids everything within it. Hence, Deleuze and Guattari remark, “That which<br />

is at once limited and limiting is striated space, the relative global: it is limited<br />

in its parts, which are given constant directions, which are oriented in relation to<br />

one another, divisible according to borders, and capable of interconnection” (MP<br />

474/382). Smooth space, by contrast, is an open Whole, an expanse with no limits,<br />

a ceaseless process of acentered proliferation in all directions. It is, say Deleuze and<br />

Guattari, “a local absolute, an absolute that has its manifestation in the local, and its<br />

engendering in a series of local operations with varying orientations” (MP 474/382).<br />

The open Whole appears only as an uncompleted ongoing process, and always from<br />

the vantage of the local. The open Whole is a rhizomatic multiplicity without fixed<br />

center that cannot be apprehended as an enclosed totality. One can encounter the<br />

open Whole only in the local, and at whatever local site one encounters it, that site<br />

functions as the provisional, shifting center of a proliferating process of formation<br />

of the open Whole.<br />

The sedentary and the nomadic, the striated and the smooth, then, represent two<br />

different modes of globalizing, one that is relative global, the other local absolute.<br />

Many of the critics of globalization have objected to the gross injustices and<br />

inequalities that have been fostered in much of the world through the International<br />

Monetary Fund, the World Trade Organization, Western-dominated multinational<br />

3 See Roland Robertson, Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture (London,<br />

1992), and Mihai Spariosu, Global Intelligence and Human Development. Toward an Ecology<br />

of Global Learning (Cambridge, MA, 2004).


134<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

corporations, various international financial instruments and market networks, all<br />

supported by political, technological and military means of coercion directed by the<br />

United States and its allies. They have rightly argued that “globalization” all too often<br />

amounts to the “Americanization” and “McDonaldization” of the world and that the<br />

neoliberal model of economic development is not the only course of action open<br />

to the planet’s peoples. This form of globalization, I would argue, is an especially<br />

pernicious manifestation of the relative global, of the sedentary striated space of the<br />

State apparatus. There are alternatives to such globalization, however, ones that might<br />

foster what we could call “globalism,” reserving the term “globalization” to refer<br />

to the processes of neoliberal Western economic-based expansion and domination.<br />

Globalism, in contradistinction to globalization, would entail an ongoing, open-ended<br />

process of worldwide community formation through the interactive proliferation of<br />

multiple sites of cultural invention. Such globalism, in sum, would be a manifestation<br />

of the local absolute of nomadic smooth space, and it is this globalism that should<br />

guide us in conceptualizing the field of cultural studies.<br />

Global Poetics<br />

Deleuze and Guattari are frequently associated with advocates of hybridity and border<br />

crossing in cultural studies – and with good reason, for the motif of “becomingother”<br />

is central to their thought. Yet by no means do they celebrate all processes<br />

of hybridization and blurring of identities as inherently positive. They recognize<br />

that the dissolution of social and cultural traditions may well usher in nefarious<br />

regimes of power, and they would concur with those who criticize the prophets of<br />

unrestrained hybridity for incautiously opening themselves to manipulation by the<br />

forces of globalization (in our restricted use of the term). Yet Deleuze and Guattari<br />

would have little sympathy for cultural studies that advocate an identity politics<br />

whereby local distinctions are reinforced through a return to traditional institutions<br />

and practices. What their work suggests, I believe, is that cultural studies should avoid<br />

the twin pitfalls of unqualified hybridization and reactionary identity politics and<br />

instead cultivate the local absolute as a means of engendering a genuine globalism.<br />

What does this mean in practical terms? As an instance of cultural studies,<br />

consider for a moment the analysis of traditional Navajo poetry and the position it<br />

might occupy within the domain of comparative poetics. Traditional Navajo poetry<br />

lends itself well to study from a broad cultural perspective, for in most instances it<br />

occurs only within the context of complex rituals involving a wide range of cultural<br />

practices and media. Central to Navajo culture are the rituals and ceremonies of<br />

blessing, healing, protection, exorcism, and so on, conducted by the hatáálí, the<br />

ceremonial practitioners usually referred to as “medicine men.” Among the most<br />

important of these rituals are those called Blessingway, Lifeway, Nightway,<br />

Enemyway and Monsterway, each of which consists of several days of chanting,<br />

dancing, ceremonies, prayers and ritual actions, involving various sacred objects,


Nomadism, Globalism and Cultural Studies 135<br />

sand paintings, foods, and so on. 4 The primary instances of traditional Navajo poetry<br />

are to be found in the chants and songs performed by the medicine men during these<br />

rituals.<br />

One of the major obstacles to a global comparative poetics is that the entire<br />

conceptual apparatus of literary analysis – its vocabulary, ideas, procedures, aims,<br />

objects – is specific to the Greco-Roman tradition. The notion of the literary itself,<br />

and even that of the comparative study of an art form, are foreign to many traditions<br />

of the world. Hence, a first stage in the study of traditional Navajo poetry would be to<br />

characterize it in its own terms, avoiding as much as possible the standard language<br />

and categories of literary analysis. One would recognize that the words of the chants<br />

are inseparable from the rhythms, dance movements, vocal inflections and melodic<br />

lines of their performance; that the words are efficacious and sacred, with a direct<br />

power to affect the world; that the power of the word emanates from the gods and<br />

the land; that the elements of the Navajo cosmos are thoroughly interconnected, such<br />

that the four corner-poles of the dwelling-place correspond to the four directions, to<br />

four colors, four stones, four sacred mountains, four gods, four elements, and so on;<br />

that every song participates in a vast, loosely organized body of stories stretching<br />

from creation to the present through generations of gods, humans, animals and other<br />

beings; that the words function as a medicine whereby the singer brings the recipient<br />

of the chant into a proper alignment with the forces of the universe. Within this broad<br />

cultural context, one might then explore the sense the Navajo have of the specific<br />

virtues of language – its powers, pleasures, charms, variations, rhythms, accents<br />

– and on the basis of indigenous categories construct a Navajo poetics.<br />

But this would be only a first step in the promotion of a genuine globalism.<br />

The next would be to use such a Navajo poetics as a local absolute, as a site of<br />

proliferation toward unlimited horizons. For example, one might attempt a Navajo<br />

reading of Wordsworth’s “Tintern Abbey.” Best would be if a Navajo were to conduct<br />

the reading, or if one were to collaborate with a native informant in constructing it,<br />

but let us propose the outlines of a hypothetical (and perhaps somewhat fanciful)<br />

description of the poem from the vantage of Navajo chant. We might say that<br />

Wordsworth’s medicine is slow and quiet, its power fluctuating and inconstant. His<br />

gods are nameless, but they speak together as a diffused, rolling presence. His dance<br />

is unhurried and often still, marked with periods of trance and near-paralysis. The<br />

gods dwell in the sacred landscape, but he is forced to reside in a domain abandoned<br />

by the gods. His chant is condensed and barely sung, its internal rhythms and<br />

cadences replacing the usual waves of repeating phrases, meters and movements that<br />

propel and sustain chant. He has felt the power of his medicine diminish within, but<br />

4 For transcriptions of performances of Navajo ceremonies, see James C. Faris, The<br />

Nightway: A History and a History of Documentation of a Navajo Ceremonial (Albuquerque,<br />

NM, 1990); Karl W. Luckert, Coyoteway: A Navajo Healing Ceremony (Tucson, AZ, 1979);<br />

Washington Matthews, The Mountain Chant: A Navajo Ceremony (Salt Lake City, UT, 1997);<br />

Leland Clifton Wyman, Beautyway: A Navajo Ceremonial (New York, 1957); Blessingway<br />

(Tucson, AZ, 1970); and The Mountainway of the Navajo (Tucson, AZ, 1975). On Navajo<br />

chants and religious performance, see Sam D. Gill, Native American Religious Action: A<br />

Performance Approach to Religion (Columbia, SC, 1987).


136<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

he senses that it still is efficacious and may bring healing to his sister, the recipient<br />

of his chant.<br />

An analysis such as this, however, in itself is not sufficient to decenter conventional<br />

comparative poetics, for it merely reverses the relation of dominance between the<br />

center and the margin, between Western and non-Western poetics. Hence, one would<br />

need to extend this process of analysis in multiple directions across cultures of<br />

diverse sorts. One might attempt a Navajo reading of Basho’s Narrow Road of the<br />

Interior, for example, and then a Navajo reading of traditional Tamil lyric poetry,<br />

of the Aztec Cantares Mexicanos, the lyrics of Jalaloddin Rumi, and the Shadow<br />

Songs of Léopold Sédar Senghor. The selection of objects of comparison would be<br />

determined by the fruitfulness of the encounters. The goal of each analysis would not<br />

be dominance but mutual transformation of the objects under consideration and the<br />

invention of concepts that belong wholly to no given tradition.<br />

This example may seem somewhat forced and improbable, but I hope it is<br />

sufficient to suggest how Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of nomadism might help<br />

us envision the field of cultural studies as a generative force that fosters a genuine<br />

globalism. Cultural studies in this guise, what we might call a nomadic cultural<br />

studies, would first ensure that the configuration of a given site of investigation<br />

emerges from within, through an analysis of indigenous sources and their<br />

interpretative use by local inhabitants. But then it would convert that site into a local<br />

absolute, treating that site as the provisional center of a proliferating open Whole.<br />

Yet a nomadic cultural studies would have to be multiple, with a proliferation as well<br />

of interacting provisional centers. The sites of the local absolute would need to be<br />

plural, and analysts based in various sites would have to be responsive to the diverse<br />

interpretations their own site undergoes in its encounters with analysts situated<br />

in other sites. The goal, finally, would be to allow analysts to see their respective<br />

sites both as provisional centers and as constituents of other proliferating networks<br />

provisionally centered elsewhere, and hence to promote exchanges between sites and<br />

foster efforts to conceive of an open Whole that belongs to none of the sites involved<br />

in the exchanges. In the case of a nomadic comparative poetics, the aim would be to<br />

recognize diverse local poetics, but at the same time to use them to generate a global<br />

poetics that is genuinely acentered and always in the process of formation. In the<br />

case of nomadic cultural studies as a whole, the aim would be to establish multiple<br />

sites of the local absolute, but at the same time to foster the interactive creation of an<br />

open Whole whose unfolding horizons extend beyond those of any one of the sites.


Chapter 10<br />

Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy<br />

There are two basic types of commentators on Deleuze and Guattari: those who seek<br />

to extend the experimental conceptual movement of Deleuze and Guattari’s thought,<br />

adopting the authors’ language and intensifying its tendencies; and those who try<br />

to frame Deleuze and Guattari’s thought in less esoteric terms, utilizing a more<br />

orthodox, academic terminology and testing the practical limits, implications and<br />

consequences of their thought. I am decidedly of the latter group, and for that reason<br />

I am basically sympathetic to the task Christopher L. Miller sets himself in “Beyond<br />

Identity: The Postidentitarian Predicament in Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand<br />

Plateaus” (1993; 1998), one of the most detailed critiques of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

concept of nomadology yet to appear. 1 Miller observes that “the notes to A Thousand<br />

Plateaus are the archive of nomad thought” (Miller 177), and he proposes to assess<br />

the claims of nomad thought by examining A Thousand Plateaus’s voluminous<br />

archive of references, especially the work’s anthropological citations. Again, my<br />

sympathies are with Miller. For the last twenty-five years I have been reading in the<br />

Deleuze-Guattari archive of sources, finding the footnotes in almost every instance<br />

an invaluable guide to understanding their thought. But the conclusions Miller draws<br />

from his investigation are far different from my own.<br />

Miller frames his examination of nomadology within the debates in cultural<br />

studies, gender/sexuality studies and postcolonial studies about identity, “identity<br />

politics” and “identitarian” modes of thought. He argues ultimately that nomadology<br />

is not the answer to the dilemma posed by these debates:<br />

What I think we need to help us in our predicament is a less utopian, less contradictory, less<br />

arrogant, and less messianic theorization of movement, a nomadism that acknowledges<br />

something outside itself. We need a positive cosmopolitanism that remains meticulously<br />

aware of localities and differences: a more convincing ethic of flow than the one proposed<br />

by Deleuze and Guattari. Such a cosmopolitanism of knowledge would have to face up<br />

to the consequences of the representational authority it assumes, not pretending to have<br />

no authority at all. The delusion of “nonauthority” must be abandoned. Then, perhaps,<br />

1 Miller’s essay first appeared in Diacritics, 23/3 (1993): 6–35, under the title “The<br />

Postidentitarian Predicament in the Footnotes of A Thousand Plateaus: Nomadology,<br />

Anthropology, Authority.” A slightly modified version came out in 1998 as Chapter Six<br />

of his Nationalists and Nomads: Essays on Francophone African Literature and Culture<br />

(Chicago, IL, 1998), pp. 171–209. Miller states in the Acknowledgements to Nationalists<br />

and Nomads that “I wish the present revised versions of all these essays to supersede their<br />

previous incarnations in print” (Miller xi–xii), and in keeping with his wishes, I cite the<br />

1998 version throughout. However, I will have occasion to refer to the Diacritics version<br />

from time to time.


138<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

the translation of this cosmopolitanism into knowledge would be less prone to accidents<br />

and contradictions; it would be less at odds with the basic tenets of the project as a whole.<br />

[Miller 209]<br />

Despite the softening effect of “less” and “more” in his formulation, Miller’s<br />

assessment is clear: Deleuze and Guattari are utopian, contradictory, arrogant and<br />

messianic. They are guilty of the delusion of “nonauthority” and irresponsible<br />

in the handling of the authority they do assume. They are prone to accidents and<br />

contradictions, and their work is fundamentally at odds with the basic tenets of their<br />

project as a whole. Those of us who find value in Deleuze and Guattari’s writings<br />

on nomadology, I believe, have an obligation to take seriously Miller’s findings,<br />

examine them closely, and answer some of the challenges he poses.<br />

Miller’s approach to Deleuze and Guattari is generally measured and considerate,<br />

and his rhetoric is largely restrained, although satiric formulations emerge at key<br />

points in the argument. Such benign appearances notwithstanding, the structure<br />

of Miller’s argument follows the familiar pattern of the debunkers of high theory.<br />

We start by framing the object of investigation in stark and often extreme terms,<br />

exposing the theory’s rhetorical excesses of superlatives, absolutes and claims to<br />

novelty. (To the extent that this phase involves distortion and hyperbole, we may<br />

call it the “Straw Man” phase.) We then demonstrate that its supposed innovations<br />

are not really new, and that other, more reasonable and responsible theories already<br />

occupy the field. Next, we show that the theory’s novelties are shams, and that what<br />

seems new is merely careless, self-contradictory, misinformed, poorly researched,<br />

and substandard in its scholarship. Finally, we turn the tables, showing that the<br />

revolutionary is actually a reactionary, that the radical is a closet conservative, that<br />

the rebel is a fascist, or in this case, that the postcolonial advocates of the oppressed<br />

are latent colonialists repeating the patrician European fantasies of primitivism<br />

and exoticism. The end result is that the object of investigation is shown to be<br />

unworthy of serious attention – utopian, contradictory, arrogant, messianic, careless,<br />

irresponsible, unscholarly – and hence an object that need not be read at all, let alone<br />

read with care and sympathy.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Arrogance<br />

One of Miller’s basic tactics is to substitute interpreters of Deleuze and Guattari for<br />

the authors themselves, and then to ground his critique in an analysis of the words<br />

of their surrogates. A particularly sophisticated application of this tactic is evident at<br />

the inception of his analysis. Miller’s focus is on the question of identity, and he first<br />

establishes A Thousand Plateaus as an anti-identitarian text by citing the anonymous<br />

blurb of the English-paperback translation, remarking that the book is “promoted<br />

not as a model of identity but as a way ‘to conceive of individuality free from the<br />

confines of Identity [that is, free from identitarianism (Miller’s editorial comment)],<br />

to think difference in itself, without any reference to the Same’” (Miller 137). Miller<br />

next cites the preface to A Thousand Plateaus, written by “its brilliant American<br />

translator and commentator, Brian Massumi” (Miller 173). Once Massumi is elevated<br />

through this praise to the level of Deleuze and Guattari, Miller can state that “nomad


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 139<br />

thought is presented by Deleuze, Guattari, and Massumi as a remedy, a cure for the<br />

ills attendant to capitalism, among which is identity” (Miller 173). Massumi, now a<br />

virtual co-author with Deleuze and Guattari, is then allowed to stand in for Deleuze<br />

and Guattari, and it is Massumi’s words that Miller cites in order to establish A<br />

Thousand Plateaus as an anti-identitarian text. Miller confirms this substitution by<br />

asserting that Massumi’s preface to A Thousand Plateaus “is an important statement<br />

about nomadology” (Miller 174), and that the publication of Massumi’s A User’s<br />

Guide to Capitalism and Schizophrenia in 1992 makes “Massumi an essential third<br />

collaborator for readers of English” (Miller 174).<br />

Massumi is but one of a series of surrogates for Deleuze and Guattari, others<br />

being André Pierre Colombat, Kenneth White, Eugene Holland, Paul Patton, Stephen<br />

Muecke and R. Rhadakrishnan. This substitution of interpreters for the original is<br />

a curious practice, given Miller’s condemnation of “Deleuze and Guattari and their<br />

followers” for escaping “the ethical burden of representing real, actual nomads, who<br />

might eventually have something to say in response” (Miller 178). Yet the practice<br />

might be deemed acceptable if, indeed, the interpreters faithfully represent the<br />

original. But in fact the interpreters all have their own points of view, and though<br />

their perspectives may at times be illuminating, they may also foster misleading and<br />

distorted interpretations of the original text, especially if they are read incautiously.<br />

Miller’s first job is to characterize “nomad thought.” Through a series of citations<br />

from Massumi, he establishes that nomad thought is anti-identitarian, affirmative<br />

and free from the negative. 2 Via a citation from Holland, Miller establishes that<br />

nomad thought erases “‘the last traces of humanism and even anthropocentrism’<br />

… [Holland 59]” (Miller 175). Next comes Alice Jardine, who, though opposed<br />

to Deleuze and Guattari’s enterprise, “accurately explains” (Miller 177) the nature<br />

of Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of becoming: “‘Becoming,’ for Deleuze and<br />

Guattari, means becoming caught up in a process of osmosis (not metaphor) with deanthropologized<br />

and de-identitized entities – women, infants, animals, foreigners,<br />

the insane – in order to resist the dominant mode of representation represented by<br />

any majority [52; emphasis mine (that is, Miller’s)]” (Miller 177). Paul Patton is<br />

then recruited to assure us “that nomad thought ‘lies entirely outside the domain of<br />

the reproducible, of representation [62]’” (Miller 177). And finally Miller establishes<br />

the anti-anthropological nature of nomad thought by quoting Stephen Muecke, who,<br />

says Miller, “claims that Deleuze and Guattari’s presentation of nomadology in A<br />

Thousand Plateaus ‘enables us to take on board the concept “nomad” without having<br />

recourse to anthropological definitions which would only re-integrate the concept of<br />

2 The danger of substituting spokespersons for the authors is especially evident<br />

in Miller’s cautious challenge to Deleuze and Guattari’s claim (as represented only by<br />

Massumi’s claim) that nomad thought is only apparently negative. Miller notes that “in his<br />

own book, Massumi wryly suggests that ‘molar men’ (in other words, fascists) may require<br />

Dr. Kevorkian’s treatment: ‘Their suicide may have to be assisted’ [89]” (Miller 9). Massumi’s<br />

wry suggestion may have some bearing on Deleuze and Guattari’s views, but it is formulated<br />

in terms that are considerably more extreme than one usually meets in Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

texts, and, indeed, Massumi’s humor and style generally tend to raise the confrontational<br />

dimensions of Deleuze and Guattari’s rhetoric to a new level.


140<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

the body of anti-nomadic thinking [24; emphasis mine (that is, Miller’s)]’” (Miller<br />

177–8).<br />

Thus, without quoting Deleuze and Guattari, Miller establishes that nomad thought<br />

is anti-identitarian, free of the negative, non-anthropomorphic, “nonrepresentational<br />

and nonanthropological” (Miller 178). At one point during his opening presentation,<br />

it must be admitted, Miller does cite Deleuze and Guattari themselves – specifically,<br />

their opening statement in A Thousand Plateaus that the two authors each have<br />

plural identities, and “Since each of us was several, there was already quite a crowd”<br />

(MP 9/3). And on the basis of this remark, he argues that Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

“nomadology in this case is, appropriately, free-floating, prescriptive, virtual, and<br />

nonreferential, untroubled by the genealogy of its sources and not accountable to<br />

the conditions of ‘tribe[s], nation[s] or race[s] having no permanent home,’ (the<br />

definition of ‘nomad’ in Webster’s New World Dictionary, college edition). It is an<br />

intellectual nomadism and a nomadism for intellectuals. We might call this case the<br />

‘free’ mode of nomadology … antithetical to the representational disciplines that<br />

have dealt with nomads until now, most notably anthropology” (Miller 177). 3<br />

There is some truth to Miller’s description of nomad thought, but that truth<br />

needs to be framed carefully within a complex of texts, primarily by Deleuze, that<br />

extend beyond A Thousand Plateaus. Deleuze indeed opposes a traditional ontology<br />

and epistemology anchored in the concept of identity, but he does so by examining<br />

in detail a number of traditional philosophical arguments and proposing complex<br />

responses to them. In The Logic of Sense, he considers at length the paradoxes<br />

associated with becoming and situates identity within a logic of the event and shows<br />

identity to be a secondary product of a process of differentiation. In Difference and<br />

Repetition, he elaborates on that analysis, insisting that the process of individuation<br />

precedes the actual individual and that a generative difference produces identities.<br />

In both books, he challenges anthropocentric and humanist philosophies, but not<br />

in some vague and impressionistic fashion. Rather, he argues that Kant’s supposed<br />

“Copernican revolution” in philosophy is no revolution at all if for God we<br />

merely substitute Man. Only if we abandon the authority of God, Man and World<br />

as grounding concepts can we begin to establish a genuinely non-foundational<br />

philosophy, and Deleuze’s effort in the two books is to do so by developing the<br />

notion of an immanent transcendental field of non-personal virtual forces of<br />

differentiation which unfold themselves in the actual entities of the cosmos. Deleuze<br />

offers a detailed critique of the logic of representation in Difference and Repetition,<br />

showing that the common sense of cognition requires a common functioning of the<br />

3 Miller’s argument seems to be that Deleuze and Guattari, in denying that they have<br />

any fixed, single identity, are freeing themselves from responsibility for their words and<br />

establishing themselves as the only nomads they are talking about. (“So Deleuze and Guattari<br />

are already a horde and a force of nature associated with the earth itself; we need seek no more<br />

nomads than them” [Miller 10].) I find Miller’s logic strained and his conclusions unsupported<br />

by the citation. That Deleuze and Guattari reject traditional notions of self-identity does not<br />

mean that they embrace a nonreferential, solipsistic and narcissistic practice. Miller may deem<br />

the remark on multiple identities an unconscious symptom of such narcissism, but Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s purpose clearly is not to plead exemption from all referentiality and ethical<br />

responsibility, as I hope to show.


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 141<br />

faculties (sensibility, imagination, understanding, memory, and so on), which itself<br />

presupposes a world subject to representation, whose four elements are “identity in<br />

the form of the undetermined concept, analogy in the relation between ultimately<br />

determinable concepts, opposition in the relation between determinations within the<br />

concept, resemblances in the determined object of the concept itself” (DR 44–5/29).<br />

We need not pursue the details of Deleuze’s argument here, but suffice it to say that<br />

he is not summarily dismissing the concept of representation without subjecting it to<br />

a thorough examination, nor is he simply embracing a free-floating non-referential<br />

semiosis. Rather, he is doing as many modern philosophers of various stripes have<br />

done, and that is to reject the notion of a transparent, unproblematic representation<br />

of the real through the medium of language (what Rorty calls the “mirror of nature”<br />

model) and to seek an alternative account of the relationship between words and<br />

things.<br />

There is truth as well in Massumi’s claim that nomad thought is affirmative,<br />

despite the appearance of negation in its operations, but here again, caution and<br />

precision are in order. The topic of affirmation is central to Deleuze’s reading of<br />

Nietzsche, and in Nietzsche and Philosophy Deleuze argues that the “affirmation of<br />

affirmation” in Nietzsche’s will to power is a response to the “negation of negation”<br />

central to Hegel’s philosophy. At stake are two different senses of “affirmation” and<br />

“negation.” In The Genealogy of Morals, Nietzsche reveals the two different senses<br />

of negation by contrasting the mentality of sheep and that of eagles (as figures of<br />

slaves and masters). Sheep define themselves by what they hate – the eagles that<br />

prey on them. They develop a reactive, negative sense of self, and then attempt<br />

to impose their values on the eagles, trying to make the eagles feel guilty for not<br />

being sheep. In this way, they impose purely negative, resentful values, defining<br />

good as not-eagle, and evil as not-not-eagle. The eagles, by contrast, affirm what<br />

they are, and from that affirmation they determine their differences from sheep. If<br />

they recognize the baseness of sheep, it is only as a second affirmation of what they<br />

are in contrast to what the sheep are.<br />

The two senses of affirmation derive from this differentiation of mentalities.<br />

Nietzsche argues that affirmation cannot simply be a matter of saying yes to<br />

everything, since that would entail assent to all that is generated by the resentment<br />

of the negative will to power (manifest in the sheep mentality). Genuine affirmation<br />

(as opposed to the sheep’s affirmation, which is a passive acceptance of whatever is)<br />

requires a critique of the negative mentality of resentment and a joyful destruction of<br />

reactive constructions of the negative will to power. It is in this Nietzschean sense of<br />

critique that Deleuze and Guattari see their nomad thought as essentially affirmative,<br />

and only negative in a limited sense of the word.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Superficiality<br />

What precisely Miller sees as Deleuze and Guattari’s position is not easy to determine,<br />

but he seems to believe that they practice some form of deconstruction, at least one<br />

that promotes the free play of the signifier, the subversion of commonsense categories,<br />

and the celebration of an unconstrained and unspecified politics of liberation. At


142<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

one point, Miller observes that Deleuze and Guattari’s critique of anthropology<br />

is “severely limited,” offering “nothing like the wholesale discrediting of the<br />

discipline that can be discerned, for example, in Derrida’s Grammatology” (Miller<br />

181). Presuming that Deleuze and Guattari’s aim is to engage in such wholesale<br />

discrediting, Miller suggests that they would do better to emulate Stephen Tyler<br />

in his “radical, transformed ethnography,” which, in Tyler’s words, “describes no<br />

knowledge and produces no action,” and which thus, says Miller, “could be described<br />

as ‘free’ (of representation, of correspondence with referents), postidentitarian, and<br />

therefore ostensibly compatible with nomadology” (Miller 181).<br />

Deconstruction, however, has little connection with nomad thought, as Deleuze<br />

makes explicit during his response to a question following his lecture “Nomad<br />

Thought” (his first exposition of the notion, delivered in 1973):<br />

As for the method of the deconstruction of texts, I understand very well what it is, I admire<br />

it greatly, but it has nothing to do with my method. I do not in any way see myself as a<br />

textual commentator. A text for me is only a little cog in an extratextual practice. It’s not<br />

a matter of commenting on the text through a deconstructive method, or by a method of<br />

textual practice, or by other methods; it’s a matter of seeing what function the text serves<br />

in the extratextual practice that extends the text. [ID 363/260]<br />

In A Thousand Plateaus Deleuze and Guattari approach language as a mode of<br />

action, situating linguistics within a general pragmatics. Words do not represent<br />

things, but they intervene in them, interact with them, thereby performing<br />

“incorporeal transformations” on things, categorizing them, classifying them,<br />

subjecting them to codes of power, regulation and domination. In no way is<br />

language “nonreferential,” in the sense of “divorced from the world.” It does not<br />

transparently and unproblematically “represent” things, but it certainly affects things<br />

and helps shape them. Language is but one component of interconnected patterns<br />

of action and structures of power relations, those patterns and structures having as<br />

their constituents heterogeneous elements, discursive and nondiscursive, all of them<br />

mutually shaping one another in a dynamic process of inter-formation.<br />

Nor do Deleuze and Guattari espouse an epistemology of infinite self-referential<br />

semiosis, in which all claims to truth and relevance are abandoned. Like Foucault, they<br />

are anti-foundational in their epistemology, but they recognize the practical effects<br />

of truths as power-functions. They know that truths are made, that configurations of<br />

words and things, which are informed by “regimes of signs,” make certain statements<br />

possible and exclude others (those truths being inseparable from the nondiscursive<br />

practices, institutions, physical objects, architectural constructions, geographical<br />

modifications, and so on, that are intermeshed with discursive signs). Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s nomadic methodology is what Deleuze calls a “constructivism” (PP<br />

199/146), an active effort to disrupt orthodoxies and thereby “falsify” received<br />

truths, but also to construct new, provisional truths that might open unforeseeable<br />

possibilities for life. Once again, nomad thought can be described as “nonreferential”<br />

only in a very specific and limited sense, and certainly not in the sense of “making no<br />

claims to truth” or “denying thought any efficacious relation to reality.”<br />

But most essential is the distance between deconstruction and nomad thought<br />

in the two methods’ approach to the concept of difference. Derrida develops his


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 143<br />

notion of difference from a linguistic model, whereas Deleuze and Guattari’s stems<br />

from an ontological model of Bergsonian origin. In his seminal 1956 essay “The<br />

Conception of Difference in Bergson,” Deleuze outlines a Bergsonian approach to<br />

difference that remains a formative force throughout his thought. In an essay on the<br />

philosopher Ravaisson, Bergson observes that concepts may be developed in two<br />

different ways, and to illustrate this distinction he considers two ways of thinking<br />

about the concept “color.” One is to start with red, efface its redness, then do the<br />

same to blue, to yellow, and so on, until you arrive at the abstract notion of “color,”<br />

that is, a general “colorness” that has been emptied of any specific color content.<br />

The concept is a genus in relation to several species (the individual colors), a single<br />

concept referring to several objects. The concept is generated through a process of<br />

negation (not red, not blue); there is a gap between the object and its concept, a<br />

division between thing and mind; and the relation between the object and the concept<br />

is one of subsumption. The alternative approach is to start with a rainbow continuum<br />

of colors and send them through a convergent lens that concentrates them on the<br />

same point, thereby producing a pure clear light. The concept is that pure clear light.<br />

As Deleuze explains:<br />

[T]he colors are no longer objects under a concept, but the nuances or degrees of the<br />

concept itself. Degrees of difference itself, and not differences of degree. The relation<br />

is no longer one of subsumption, but of participation … Because things have become<br />

nuances or degrees of the concept, the concept itself has become a thing. It is a universal<br />

thing, if you will, since the objects take form within it as so many degrees, but it is a<br />

concrete thing, not a genus or a generality. [ID 60/43]<br />

To speak in strictly physical terms (only a provisional step), we may say that the pure<br />

light is a generative self-differing difference, and that each color is a manifestation of<br />

a process of differentiation (here, imagine a reversal of our original model, the clear<br />

light passing through a lens to form a rainbow spectrum). The clear light is immanent<br />

within each individual color, and we may say that the spectrum of manifest colors<br />

is an unfolding of the clear light as it differentiates itself into the diverse colors. The<br />

manifest rainbow colors have an actual existence, the immanent clear light a virtual<br />

existence, and both the actual and the virtual are real. But the physical unfolding of<br />

the light is inextricable from the unfolding of the concept – the concept is a thing.<br />

Thought and its object together unfold as part of a single process of self-differing<br />

differentiation.<br />

Bergson’s basic method, Deleuze shows, is to replace false distinctions with<br />

genuine differences, which are differences of nature, that is, real differences, but<br />

which exist in their pure state as virtual entities. Time, for example, is generally<br />

misconceived, says Bergson, because it is framed in terms that confuse the temporal<br />

and the spatial, time being construed unconsciously in spatialized terms. Time,<br />

however, differs from space in nature. In the actual world, we always experience<br />

time and space in mixtures, but a pure time and a pure space exist as virtual entities.<br />

We discern those virtual entities as tendencies within the actual, and one of the<br />

primary goals of thought is to discriminate between those tendencies and extract<br />

from them the pure virtual entities that are manifested in those tendencies. Pure<br />

virtual time, what Bergson calls durée (which has as two of its dimensions memory


144<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

and élan vital), differs in nature from pure space. What complicates this example,<br />

however, is that even the distinction between pure time and pure space is provisional.<br />

Bergson argues that in a universe of incessant becoming, of ongoing and universal<br />

metamorphosis, there are no real things at all, merely fluxes and flows, perturbations,<br />

movements, vibrations. What we call “space,” even the pure space of the virtual, is<br />

simply a contraction of the vibrational Whole, and time is the infinite dilation of that<br />

Whole. In short, pure virtual space finally is merely a manifestation of durée. The<br />

two separate entities of time and space collapse into one – durée in its dilated form,<br />

durée in its contracted form. But this collapse does not lead us to a monism, for the<br />

“one,” in this case, durée, is itself a self-differing difference, and the real distinction<br />

between pure time and pure space, at which we arrived provisionally, is generated by<br />

durée as it differentiates itself. What we have, then, is a binary opposition in which<br />

one pole generates the other, but not in any temporal priority. The generative pole,<br />

durée, does not in some sense exist prior to the other pole, space. Both coexist. And<br />

the difference between durée and pure space is not some kind of illusion – it is a real<br />

difference of nature, a real manifestation of durée unfolding itself as a self-differing<br />

difference.<br />

Bergson’s analyses of differences of nature are not always as abstruse as that<br />

of the difference between time and space, nor is the final phase of the analysis, in<br />

which one pole is shown to be the differencing of the other, always present. But<br />

throughout his work, Bergson proceeds by discerning tendencies within an actual<br />

mixture, and then isolating the virtual differences of nature that manifest themselves<br />

within the actual. This Bergsonian practice may be seen clearly in Deleuze’s<br />

thought in his early study of the novelist Sacher-Masoch. There, Deleuze argues<br />

that sadomasochism is a false category, a mixture of tendencies, and that sadism and<br />

masochism represent incommensurable worlds, the one explored by Sade, the other<br />

by Sacher-Masoch, both authors being consummate symptomatologists capable of<br />

isolating the complex of elements that make up the pure virtual worlds of sadism<br />

and masochism. Something similar takes place in Anti-Oedipus as Deleuze and<br />

Guattari first challenge the orthodox distinction between psychosis and neurosis and<br />

then differentiate the pure virtual elements of schizophrenia and paranoia from one<br />

another. And in A Thousand Plateaus, this Bergsonian method is used over and over<br />

again, the distinction between the nomadic and the sedentary being one instance of<br />

such an analysis of tendencies in an actual mixture in terms of their qualitatively<br />

different, virtual sources.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Unoriginality<br />

When Miller compares Stephen Tyler’s “truly radical, transformed ethnography”<br />

to A Thousand Plateaus, he finds Deleuze and Guattari “to be quite old-fashioned”<br />

(Miller 181). In their use of the concept of “assemblages,” Miller recognizes a line<br />

of thought “more consonant with the moderate, ‘reformed’ approach to anthropology<br />

(à la James Clifford) that is now becoming commonplace than with the radically<br />

antirepresentational stance of Tyler” (Miller 186). One of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

statements, says Miller, “could have come out of Anthropology as Cultural Critique


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 145<br />

[by Marcus and Fischer] or Writing Culture [by Clifford and Marcus]” (Miller<br />

186). 4 The concept of the assemblage, Miller remarks, “is an eminently clear and<br />

reasonable one” (Miller 186), but not one that supports Deleuze and Guattari’s radical<br />

pretensions to having broken with the fundamental presuppositions of mainstream<br />

anthropology.<br />

Miller is correct that Deleuze and Guattari do not engage in the radical transformed<br />

ethnography proposed by Tyler, but they never claim to do so. He is also correct<br />

that Deleuze and Guattari’s approach to certain anthropological concerns is broadly<br />

consonant with the approach of Clifford, Marcus and Fischer, but the conceptual<br />

differences between the two are not simply a matter of rhetoric. Miller states that<br />

the moderate position of Clifford et al. is that “culture results from shared questions<br />

rather than from predetermined beliefs and exists in a state of dynamic tension with<br />

itself and its others” (Miller 186). Miller sees Deleuze and Guattari as supporting<br />

this view when they assert that a given people may exhibit “the predominance of one<br />

semiotic or another” (MP 149/119) but that “configurations change” (Miller 186). In<br />

the passage Miller cites, however, Deleuze and Guattari are saying not simply that<br />

configurations of signs change, but also that cultural practices are shaped by virtual<br />

regimes of signs that become manifest in ordinary experience only as tendencies<br />

within actual mixtures. Regimes of signs involve “assemblages,” and I would<br />

certainly agree that the latter concept is useful, but neither concept is “eminently<br />

clear and reasonable” in the sense of being straightforward and easily assimilable<br />

within standard conceptual frames.<br />

An assemblage is a heterogeneous collection of entities that somehow function<br />

together. In Deleuze’s analysis, the concept of the assemblage is similar to Foucault’s<br />

notion of the dispositif, “apparatus,” “device,” or “contrivance” (see especially<br />

Deleuze’s “Qu’est-ce qu’un dispositif?” in DRF 316–25/338–48). An assemblage<br />

in some regards is like a system in systems theory, a circuit of elements engaged in<br />

an interactive process, yet a circuit that lacks the stability, coherence and structural<br />

integrity often implied by the word “system.” In Anti-Oedipus, Deleuze and Guattari<br />

approach assemblages in terms of desiring-machines, various components cofunctioning<br />

like parts of a machine. But if an assemblage is a machine, it is a kind<br />

of Rube Goldberg machine, one made up of incongruous parts in ad hoc, shifting<br />

relations of widely varying degrees of efficiency and probability. 5 Desiring-machines,<br />

say Deleuze and Guattari, break down as they function, and their breakdown is<br />

constantly fed back into their functioning. Assemblages operate in the same fashion.<br />

Nor are assemblages exactly things. They are also processes of perpetual selfconstruction.<br />

The French agencement, translated as “assemblage,” can mean both an<br />

arrangement of things and the act of arranging those things. An agencement thus is<br />

not just an assemblage of things, but also a process of “agencing,” just as a circuit of<br />

4 It is worth noting that Anthropology as Cultural Critique and Writing Culture were<br />

both published in 1986, six years after the appearance of A Thousand Plateaus.<br />

5 In the Appendix to Anti-Oedipe included in a 1980 reprinting of the work, titled<br />

“Bilan-programme pour machines désirantes,” Deleuze and Guattari reproduce two Rube<br />

Goldberg cartoons as examples of desiring machines.


146<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

desiring-machines is a “machining” of machines, an active bringing-into-existence<br />

of its own circuitry.<br />

A regime of signs is a configuration of assemblages that guide the formation,<br />

circulation and perpetuation of signs, both linguistic and nonlinguistic. It is<br />

an agencing of heterogeneous elements, among which one may find practices,<br />

institutions, people, plants, animals, machines, artifacts, and so on, those elements<br />

functioning together to produce signs according to a “regime,” in the sense of a<br />

relatively stable pattern of power relations. Deleuze and Guattari delineate four<br />

regimes of signs, each of which is qualitatively different from the others. Each is a<br />

virtual configuration of differences which only become actualized in mixtures. Miller<br />

chides Deleuze and Guattari for what he deems the excessive claim that “there is no<br />

reason to identify a regime or a semiotic system with a people or historical moment”<br />

(MP 148/119), reading this statement as “the assertion of freedom, the denial of<br />

representation” (Miller 186), but Deleuze and Guattari are simply reiterating that<br />

a regime of signs is a virtual entity and that no actual social group manifests that<br />

virtual entity in a pure state. They are also denying that a regime of signs is to be<br />

understood exclusively as a force shaping societies. A regime of signs is at work<br />

in the anorexic’s relationship to food, in the psychoanalyst’s interaction with her<br />

patient, in Kant’s formulation of the self-legislating moral subject, as well as in<br />

Moses’ relationship with the Israelites. Hence, when Deleuze and Guattari talk about<br />

manipulating “maps” of regimes of signs (the term “map,” in its specific Deleuze-<br />

Guattari usage, denoting something like a “schematic diagram of abstract relations”),<br />

they are not trying to “take maps beyond representation and legibility, into a realm<br />

of pure complexity and incoherence” (Miller 186), but to apply the map of a regime<br />

of signs to varying situations (military, philosophical, medical, musical, and so<br />

on) of diverse dimensions (psychic, individual, familial, tribal, regional, national,<br />

planetary).<br />

Deleuze and Guattari delineate four regimes of signs in A Thousand Plateaus:<br />

the primitive, the despotic, the passional and the nomadic. Miller argues that a trite<br />

and tired evolutionary pattern is evident in this taxonomy, Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

protestations to the contrary. Specifically, Deleuze and Guattari “reproduce an<br />

extremely familiar evolutionary scheme” between the despotic and the primitive<br />

regimes, in which “the people of the first regime [the despotic] are the harried<br />

tools of capitalism; those of the second regime are primitive, ‘closer’ to nature,<br />

enjoying polyvocality and ‘relative deterritorialization’” (Miller 187). Miller treats<br />

the nomadic regime as a sort of counter-cultural fantasy that Deleuze and Guattari<br />

generate in order to envision an escape from the capitalist/despotic regime. And the<br />

fourth regime, the passional regime, “evoked in one brief sentence,” according to<br />

Miller, “is not explained” (Miller 185).<br />

Miller observes that later in the plateau on regimes of signs Deleuze and<br />

Guattari “offer the tantalizing possibility” (Miller 185) of a plane of consistency<br />

and an abstract machine. “This ‘plane,’” he comments, “sounds a lot like an ethical<br />

utopia” (Miller 185). The plane of consistency and abstract machine, in fact, are not<br />

tantalizing possibilities, but essential components of Deleuze and Guattari’s model.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari distinguish two planes: a plane of consistency and a plane<br />

of organization. The plane of consistency is the domain of the virtual, whereas the


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 147<br />

plane of organization is the domain in which the virtual becomes actualized. The<br />

virtual, when viewed in itself, is a field of self-differentiating differences, which<br />

may be understood as shifting vectors of forces, vibrating zones of variations, or<br />

oscillating lines of possible development. It is an unfixed plane of potential processes<br />

of differentiation, which is immanent in the plane of organization and in all the actual<br />

becomings of the world. The plane of consistency unfolds itself within the plane of<br />

organization, serving a kind of “pilot” role, guiding but not dictating trajectories of<br />

development and becoming.<br />

The plane of organization is the actual world of concrete, embodied things, but<br />

it is not exactly the world of commonsense entities. The virtual is “territorialized”<br />

in actual things, fixed, stabilized, coded, organized, regulated. But territorialization<br />

is never total; there is always a counter-force of deterritorialization playing through<br />

the plane of organization, undoing its codes, unsettling its regularities, inducing<br />

metamorphosis. Dominant power configurations enforce fixed structures and codes by<br />

limiting variation and stratifying relations, whereas resistance to that dominant power<br />

seeks to undo structures and codes by intensifying the immanent virtual tendencies<br />

toward variation and destratification. But even the dominant power configurations<br />

are patterned via virtual lines of variation and vectors of potential development; they<br />

simply take form in the actual through a different use of the virtual. For this reason,<br />

the plane of consistency is not utopian. It is the virtual domain which may unfold<br />

itself in a better, different world than the one we inhabit at present, but it may well<br />

unfold in a much worse world, despotic, oppressive, barbaric.<br />

The plane of consistency functions like an “abstract machine,” guiding the<br />

combinations of entities and circuits of interaction that unfold in the actual realm<br />

of the plane of organization. In the case of regimes of signs, the abstract machine<br />

puts two basic “assemblages” together, a discursive “collective assemblage of<br />

enunciation,” and a nondiscursive “machinic assemblage of bodies.” Regimes<br />

of signs are regular patterns of power relations interconnected via discursive and<br />

nondiscursive assemblages.<br />

Miller’s characterization of the passional regime as “not explained” is hard<br />

to comprehend, since Deleuze and Guattari devote several pages to this regime.<br />

In fact, one of their chief objects is to demonstrate how the virtual despotic and<br />

passional regimes interact in specific actual mixtures. Miller’s identification of the<br />

despotic regime with capitalism is unwarranted, for capitalist societies exhibit the<br />

strong influence of both the despotic and the passional regimes, as well as certain<br />

tendencies toward a nomadic dispensation of signs. 6 Deleuze and Guattari plainly<br />

indicate at several points that the despotic regime, above all, is connected with the<br />

State apparatus, and wherever there is a state, be it an empire, a kingdom, a city-<br />

6 The relationship between capitalism and the four regimes of signs is quite complex<br />

and not fully addressed as such in A Thousand Plateaus. In Anti-Oedipus, however, Deleuze<br />

and Guattari speak at length about the capitalist social machine and its circulation of signs,<br />

which they contrast with the despotic machine and its handling of signs. The difficult task<br />

facing anyone interested in the function of regimes of signs in capitalism is that of combining,<br />

integrating, and at certain points reconciling, the analyses of Anti-Oedipus and A Thousand<br />

Plateaus with one another.


148<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

state, a nation, or a dictatorship, the despotic regime is at work. This fact is crucial<br />

to understanding Deleuze and Guattari’s views on the relation between the primitive<br />

and the despotic regimes, as well as their claim that “we are not suggesting an<br />

evolutionism, we are not even doing history” (MP 149/119), a claim Miller regards<br />

as hyperbolic and hollow.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari find Pierre Clastres’s La Société contre l’état (1974)<br />

especially helpful in determining the relationship between primitive societies and the<br />

state form of governance. Clastres argues that many traditional tribal cultures exhibit<br />

mechanisms that prevent the formation of a permanent class hierarchy among its<br />

members. Leaders are chosen, but they lead only as long as others agree to follow, and<br />

as soon as the leader’s direction begins to prove unfavorable, the followers replace<br />

the leader. As a result, the leader functions more as a consensus builder who senses<br />

where the group wants to go and then leads them in that direction. The leader often has<br />

special privileges, but the leader’s position usually ends up being more burdensome<br />

than that of the followers. Customs regulating the procurement, distribution and<br />

transmission of wealth also mitigate against permanent accumulation of goods by<br />

any one individual or subgroup. Clastres concludes that many traditional societies<br />

are constructed to prevent social stratification, which he regards as fundamental<br />

to the formation of a state. The members of these anti-state societies, in Clastres’s<br />

terms, have a premonition of the imminent danger of the state form, which they<br />

attempt to ward off through their own social structures and practices. 7<br />

7 Miller criticizes Deleuze and Guattari for saying that the presignifying regime “is<br />

animated by a keen presentiment of what is to come” (MP 148/118) and is therefore, in<br />

Miller’s paraphrase, “able to combat the State (through, for example, cannibalism) without<br />

understanding it” (Miller 184). “These characteristics are tremendously loaded,” says Miller.<br />

“They can come only from a reading of texts concerned with colonized peoples in their<br />

interaction with colonial and postcolonial states: the folk of anthropology. Furthermore, these<br />

assertions reproduce one of the most questionable tactics of colonial anthropology – that<br />

of attributing to native preconscious thoughts which the Western interpreter makes explicit”<br />

(Miller 184). The language of “presentiments” and “warding off” the State (Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s verb is conjurer) comes from Clastres, a professional anthropologist who based<br />

his analyses of anti-State strategies in traditional societies on years of field work with the<br />

Guarani and Guayaki Indians of South America (see especially, Clastres 161–86). Clastres’s<br />

accounts of his field work do not at all indicate that his observations are of “colonized peoples<br />

in their interaction with colonial and postcolonial states.” Deleuze and Guattari’s remark<br />

about people in the presignifying regime not understanding the State they oppose arises in the<br />

course of their rejection of psychoanalytic terms to describe the phenomenon of presignifying<br />

State opposition: “We should avoid thinking that it is through ignorance, via repression or<br />

foreclosure of the signifier that such a semiotic functions. On the contrary, it is motivated by<br />

a heavy presentiment of that which is to come, it has no need of understanding it to combat<br />

it” (MP 148/118). Later, Deleuze and Guattari summarize Clastres’s position, saying “not<br />

only does he doubt that the State is the product of an assignable economic development, but<br />

he asks if primitives societies do not have the potential concern to ward off and prevent this<br />

monster that they supposedly do not understand” (MP 441/357). It would seem that Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s remark about the extent of native understanding of the State is simply drawn<br />

up in rebuttal to the argument that non-State societies can only oppose the State through a<br />

direct exposure to an existent State apparatus and a consciously articulated knowledge of


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 149<br />

Deleuze and Guattari regard Clastres’s work as evidence that the State does not<br />

suddenly befall innocent traditional societies from without, but that the State form<br />

is immanent as a virtual potential within those societies. They observe as well that<br />

efforts to fix a date for the origin of the State form have been inconclusive, and<br />

that “the more discoveries archaeologists make, the more empires they uncover”<br />

(MP 445/360). The State form, they conclude, has always existed throughout human<br />

history and prehistory. The State does not develop from some pre-State, but instead<br />

exists as an Urstaat. Deleuze and Guattari extend this argument from governmental<br />

forms to that of regimes of signs, asserting that the four regimes of signs have always<br />

existed. They are virtual entities capable of actualization in diverse combinations<br />

at different times. One may write a history of the appearance of those actual<br />

combinations, but the regimes themselves have no history. There is no evolutionary<br />

schema that charts the development of one regime of signs from another. Hence,<br />

when Deleuze and Guattari say “we are not suggesting an evolutionism, we are<br />

not even doing history” (MP 149/119), they are not idly supporting a vague radical<br />

nonreferentiality but stating a specific position concerning virtual regimes of signs<br />

and their relation to the actual appearance of those regimes in world history. 8<br />

The four regimes of signs have always existed (at least, as long as humans have<br />

been in existence – Deleuze and Guattari do not specifically address the question of<br />

the pre-human origins of human culture), but these regimes are not to be conceived<br />

of as absolute categories or as static structures or essences. Deleuze and Guattari<br />

identify four regimes, but “there are many regimes of signs. Our list itself is arbitrarily<br />

limited” (MP 149/119). Miller treats this assertion as a mere gesture toward radical<br />

indeterminacy, but Deleuze and Guattari’s point is that their analysis is provisional<br />

and empirical, and in fact, such hesitance is essential to their Bergsonian enterprise.<br />

They have surveyed various configurations of signs and related practices that have<br />

its functioning. Deleuze, Guattari and Clastres believe that natives have only a supposed<br />

ignorance of the State apparatus, for they recognize full well the mechanisms and forms of<br />

relation implicit in the State apparatus. Clastres did not live long enough to see A Thousand<br />

Plateaus (he died in 1977), but he did read Anti-Oedipus and responded enthusiastically to<br />

the book, especially to its analysis of non-State traditional societies. In a 1972 roundtable<br />

discussion of Anti-Oedipus, Clastres remarked: “Yes, the State exists in primitive societies,<br />

even in the most miniscule tribe of nomadic hunters. It exists, but it is ceaselessly warded off,<br />

it is ceaselessly prevented from being realized. A primitive society is a society that directs<br />

all its effort toward preventing its chief from becoming a chief (and that effort can go as<br />

far as murder). If there is history, it is the history of class struggle (in societies where there<br />

are classes, of course), so one can say that the history of societies without classes is that<br />

history of their struggle against the latent State; it is the history of their effort to code the flux<br />

of power” (ID 316–17/227). Perhaps Deleuze, Guattari and Clastres are incautious in using<br />

psychological terminology to frame their observations, but such language is understandable<br />

given the heavily psychoanalytic atmosphere of French discourse in the 1970s.<br />

8 Admittedly, Deleuze and Guattari invite confusion when they label the primitive,<br />

despotic, nomadic and passional regimes, respectively, “presignifying,” “signifying,”<br />

“countersignifying” and “postsignifying.” But they repeatedly stress that the temporal markers<br />

in these labels are merely heuristic devices to aid in the exposition of their concepts and not<br />

to be taken as supporting an evolutionary or historical approach to regimes of signs.


150<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

appeared in the actual mixtures of world history, and they have identified what<br />

they see as four tendencies, each of which points toward a “pure” regime of signs,<br />

distilled of the distracting presence of other, competing regimes. It may well be that<br />

additional regimes exist, but that Deleuze and Guattari did not recognize them in the<br />

actual mixtures they examined.<br />

It should be clear as well that regimes of signs are not mere mental constructs<br />

invented by their analysts. They have a real existence, though they are only manifest<br />

as tendencies within mixtures in the actual world. Yet they are not to be thought<br />

of as fixed structures. The virtual is a dimension of generative self-differentiating<br />

differences, and regimes of signs are configurations of such differences. They<br />

resemble structures in that they are organized, but that organization is not fully<br />

stable, and the components so organized are always guided in their becoming by the<br />

plane of consistency’s immanent vectors, lines of force, zones of variation, which<br />

are capable of multiple and divergent actualization. We can identify regimes of signs<br />

and differentiate them from one another not by elements that are totally fixed, but by<br />

the periodic oscillations of the elements, their statistical probabilities, their fields of<br />

force relations, their loosely cohesive relational patterns.<br />

Nor are regimes of signs essences, though it is easy to mistake them for such,<br />

since in attempting to characterize these elusive entities with their puzzling mode<br />

of existence, Deleuze and Guattari pile up descriptor after descriptor as if they were<br />

completing the final portrait of the nomadic regime or the despotic regime. One<br />

might say that their effort is to extract from the actual a certain kind of essence, but<br />

it is a “fuzzy” essence, neither exact nor abstract. It is, in a term they borrow from<br />

Husserl, “anexact,” something like the category of “roundness,” midway between<br />

the exact figure of a concrete circle and the abstract idea of the circle. 9 In general,<br />

we might observe, Deleuze and Guattari’s apparent tendencies toward essentialism<br />

should be seen as exercises in anexact description. When they speak of the nomad, the<br />

warrior, the migrant, the ambulant, or the itinerant, for example, they are attempting<br />

9 For Deleuze and Guattari’s appropriation of Husserl’s concept of the “anexact” (which<br />

Husserl associates with “vague essences”), see MP 454/367. Deleuze and Guattari remark<br />

here that Husserl’s vague essences “may be distinguished from sensible things, but equally<br />

from ideal, royal or imperial, essences. The science that treats these vague essences, protogeometry,<br />

is itself vague, in the sense of vagabond: it is neither inexact like sensible things,<br />

nor exact like ideal essences, but anexact and nonetheless rigorous.” Miller cites Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s statement that “anexact expressions are absolutely necessary; to designate<br />

something exactly” (MP 31/20) as a means of absolving themselves of the responsibility<br />

of accurately representing the world. He seems to regard the term “anexact” as simply a<br />

synonym for “inexact,” or “imprecise,” and in fact, in the 1993 Diacritics version of his<br />

essay, Miller quotes Deleuze and Guattari as saying that “inexact expressions are utterly<br />

unavoidable.” Although he amends his translation in the 1998 version of the essay, he does not<br />

make reference to Deleuze and Guattari’s comments on the concept of the “anexact.” Miller’s<br />

understanding of “anexact” as “imprecise” is of some consequence, since imprecision is one<br />

of the faults he finds in Deleuze and Guattari: “By virtue of being so willfully peripatetic, the<br />

authors risk superficiality and imprecision in their understanding of specific situations. This is<br />

a general problem within A Thousand Plateaus …” (Miller 190–91).


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 151<br />

to assemble the characteristics of a particular set of generative differences, not some<br />

ideal universal. 10<br />

Finally, we should observe that a regime of signs has a complex relationship to<br />

language that can easily be misconstrued. In many ways, Deleuze and Guattari’s effort<br />

to explain the concept of a regime of signs parallels Foucault’s attempt to articulate<br />

his notion of the énoncé, or “statement.” In The Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault<br />

says that a statement is something that takes place in language, but that is not quite<br />

the same thing as language. Different words may enunciate the same statement, and<br />

the same word or words may enunciate different statements. Even individual letters<br />

may function as a statement, as in the sequence AZERT, which designates a row of<br />

characters on a French typewriter and which functions as a statement in a typing<br />

manual. Statements have a certain iterability, and a certain mode of being, peculiar<br />

to themselves, immanent within language but not reducible to it.<br />

All of these characteristics may be attributed to regimes of signs. Like statements,<br />

regimes of signs are indivisible from actions. They inform the pragmatics of linguistic<br />

use, but they are not reducible to language itself, especially to “language” as construed<br />

by mainstream linguistics, which tends to view all contextual and pragmatic aspects<br />

of language use as “extra-linguistic.” This is the point of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

comment that “regimes of signs are assemblages of enunciation, which cannot be<br />

adequately accounted for by any linguistic category … Regimes of signs thus are<br />

defined by variables interior to enunciation itself, but which remain exterior to the<br />

constants of language and irreducible to linguistic categories” (MP 174–5/140). In<br />

a footnote, Miller cites this passage as evidence that Deleuze and Guattari want to<br />

escape responsibility for their own words, for<br />

… this reassertion of multiplicity and insistence on the heterogeneity of their own<br />

writing cannot prevent a reading of what does manage to assert itself within the linguistic<br />

categories that the authors use. Deleuze and Guattari want their regimes to be exempt from<br />

the rule of language, but the only way that these regimes can be created is in language.<br />

[Miller 142]<br />

Far from being an apologia for irresponsibility, however, Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

remarks are addressed to very specific issues in the conceptualization of linguistics,<br />

which they discuss in some detail in Plateau Four of A Thousand Plateaus. When<br />

10 Miller raises the issue of essentialism and Deleuze and Guattari’s characterization<br />

of cultural “types” when he criticizes Deleuze and Guattari for their use of Edmund Leach’s<br />

comparative study of sorcery in different cultures. Leach’s point is that the sorcerer’s<br />

function varies from culture to culture, whereas Deleuze and Guattari use Leach to construct<br />

an essentialized portrait of the sorcerer. Miller admits that though A Thousand Plateaus is<br />

crowded with “nearly allegorical figures, which we should not forget, have in other contexts<br />

served as the stock characters of essentialism” (Miller 190), Deleuze and Guattari can hardly<br />

be accused of essentialism. But in their utilization of Leach, “by constructing ‘the sorcerer,’<br />

Deleuze and Guattari have by far surpassed the ethnographic authority of their source” (Miller<br />

190). Deleuze and Guattari’s object in referring to Leach, however, is not to seek authority<br />

but to cite empirical instances of sorcery, which Leach has gathered and interpreted, and<br />

which Deleuze and Guattari are now interpreting according to their own very different set of<br />

theoretical assumptions.


152<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

they say that regimes of signs are “exterior to the constants of language and<br />

irreducible to linguistic categories,” they are asserting that regimes of signs cannot<br />

be assimilated within the theoretical framework of conventional linguistics, which<br />

privileges constants over variables, and which strictly isolates the linguistic from<br />

the pragmatic and the contextual. Their object is not somehow to escape the burdens<br />

of using language but to make precise the elusive nature of regimes of signs as<br />

configurations of practices immanent within, but not reducible to, language.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Imprecision<br />

One of Miller’s chief objections to Deleuze and Guattari’s work is that it is careless<br />

and given to imprecision. Miller offers as a “particularly egregious” (Miller<br />

191) instance of such imprecision Deleuze and Guattari’s reference to “African<br />

commercial circuits” and their footnote citing Godelier’s essay on the introduction<br />

of money among “the Siane of New Guinea” (MP 171/137). As Miller correctly<br />

observes, Deleuze and Guattari here commit a regrettable error in confusing the<br />

African nation of Guinea with New Guinea. For a full page, Miller expounds on the<br />

significance of this error, which he views as a symptom of a cavalier disregard of<br />

facts inherent in nomadic thought, according to whose rules, “any dualism is merely a<br />

temporary fiction, and any factual mistake should be overlooked” (Miller 191). I find<br />

no evidence, however, that Deleuze and Guattari believe that factual mistakes should<br />

be overlooked, nor have I discovered widespread evidence of imprecision in their<br />

citations or in their references to facts. In my study of the works of Deleuze, Guattari<br />

and Deleuze-Guattari, I have found glaring errors of fact, such as the confusion of<br />

Guinea and New Guinea, to be quite rare. And as I have read through the thousands<br />

of footnotes in their writings, I have been surprised at how reliable and accurate<br />

their citations are. One comes across occasional transpositions of numerals in page<br />

citations, and a few instances in which the publication information is less complete<br />

than one might like, but on the whole their references conform to the standards<br />

of traditional scholarship. Their summaries of the studies they cite, whether in the<br />

body of the text or in the footnotes, have struck me as uniformly judicious and often<br />

extremely insightful. My conclusion is that the confusion of Guinea and New Guinea<br />

is not evidence of a disregard of facts, but a sign of human frailty – unfortunate<br />

certainly, but, I would hope, forgivable.<br />

Miller implies, however, that this kind of sloppiness exists elsewhere in A<br />

Thousand Plateaus, and as an instance of “the authors’ quirky use of anthropological<br />

materials and footnotes,” he cites a passage in which Deleuze and Guattari call upon<br />

the anthropologists Robert Lowie and Claude Lévi-Strauss to testify to a contrast<br />

between Crow and Hopi ways of interpreting signs. The passage in question reads<br />

as follows:<br />

Robert Lowie tells how the Crow and the Hopi react differently when their wives cheat on<br />

them (the Crow are hunter nomads, whereas the Hopi are sedentaries tied to an imperial<br />

tradition): “A Crow Indian, whose wife has been unfaithful, slashes her face, whereas,<br />

without losing his calm, a Hopi, victim of the same misfortune, withdraws and prays that<br />

drought and famine fall upon the village.” [MP 142/113]


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 153<br />

After this citation, Miller parenthetically comments, “there is no footnote in ATP<br />

at this point to identify the text that was quoted. I have not been able to locate this<br />

quotation in any of Lowie’s writings” (Miller 188). Miller then cites the passage<br />

from A Thousand Plateaus immediately following the supposed quotation from<br />

Lowie, in which Deleuze and Guattari refer to Lévi-Strauss’s own comment on<br />

Lowie’s observation:<br />

One can see on which side is the paranoia, the despotic element or the signifying regime,<br />

“the bigotry,” as Lévi-Strauss says: “In effect, for the Hopi everything is connected: a<br />

social disturbance or a domestic incident puts in question the system of the universe,<br />

whose levels are united by multiple correspondences; a disruption on one plane is only<br />

intelligible, and morally tolerable, as a projection of other disruptions, affecting the other<br />

levels.” [MP 143/113]<br />

Miller is correct that Deleuze and Guattari do not provide a footnote immediately<br />

following their citation of Lowie, but they do supply a note after the Lévi-Strauss<br />

citation (as Miller duly observes), referring the reader to Lévi-Strauss’s Preface to the<br />

French translation of Sun Chief, a work Miller describes as “an anthropological ‘astold-to’<br />

autobiography of a Hopi Chief” (Miller 188). If one consults Lévi-Strauss’s<br />

Preface, one finds the following:<br />

To the author of these lines [that is, Lévi-Strauss], the great American ethnologist Robert<br />

H. Lowie confided, in the last years of his life, that, of the Crow and the Hopi, among<br />

whom he had lived and worked, only the first had he found congenial, but that he never<br />

managed to like the second: “Thus,” he continued, “a Crow Indian, whose wife has been<br />

unfaithful, slashes her face, whereas, without losing his calm, a Hopi, victim of the same<br />

misfortune, withdraws and prays that drought and famine fall upon the village.” In effect,<br />

for the Hopi everything is connected: a social disturbance or a domestic incident puts in<br />

question the system of the universe, whose levels are united by multiple correspondences;<br />

a disruption on one plane is only intelligible, and morally tolerable, as a projection of<br />

other disruptions, affecting the other levels. 11<br />

Perhaps Deleuze and Guattari could have come upon a slightly clearer means of<br />

indicating their sources, but their use of the passage hardly seems irresponsible and<br />

misleading, once one consults the reference they do provide. It is not surprising that<br />

Miller was “not able to locate this quotation in any of Lowie’s writings,” since it was<br />

an oral communication reported by Lévi-Strauss, but in his survey of the writings<br />

of Lowie Miller might have come upon a passage enunciating the same contrast of<br />

11 Claude Lévi-Strauss, Preface to Don C. Talayesva, Soleil Hopi: L’autobiographie d’un<br />

indien hopi, trans. Geneviève Mayou (Paris, 1959), p. vi. In Didier Eribon’s Conversations<br />

with Claude Lévi-Strauss, trans. Paul Wissing (Chicago, IL, 1991), Lévi-Strauss observes that<br />

anthropologists do not always get along well with the people they study, and that “One day<br />

every anthropologist finds himself or herself faced with this sort of situation. Robert Lowie<br />

was a great anthropologist who honored me with his friendship. His works on the Crow and<br />

the Hopi are authoritative. However, he confided to me that he got along perfectly with the<br />

first, while he could hardly stand the second” (p. 152).


154<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Crow and Hopi mentalities. In his autobiography, Robert H. Lowie, Ethnologist: A<br />

Personal Record, Lowie comments:<br />

The contrast between Pueblo and Plains Indian mentality seems to me further illustrated<br />

by the way in which violent resentment expresses itself. The Plainsman sometimes acted<br />

like a savage, as when a Blackfoot cuckold cut off the tip of an adulteress’s nose, yet<br />

the reaction, repulsive as it was (incidentally to the Crow, too) is humanly intelligible.<br />

Compare with this the reactions of a legendary Zuni who does nothing to either his wife<br />

or to her paramour, but revenges himself upon the community at large. The disgruntled<br />

village chief in a Hopi myth causes a flood or earthquake or even encourages the enemy<br />

to demolish his pueblo. 12<br />

This published passage at least shows that Deleuze and Guattari’s reputedly<br />

unattributed quotation of Lowie roughly reflects Lowie’s actual views, and that<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s phantom citation is not a pure fabrication, as one might infer<br />

from Miller’s comment.<br />

But Miller’s critique of Deleuze and Guattari’s use of Lowie and Lévi-Strauss<br />

extends beyond the fine questions of proper citational practice. As Deleuze and<br />

Guattari incorporate the words of Lowie and Lévi-Strauss into their own texts, they<br />

appropriate the authority of these experts and eventually start speaking not simply as<br />

professional anthropologists but as themselves native Americans:<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s incorporated voice, which begins as that of a reader of texts<br />

(“Robert Lowie describes how … the Crow are nomadic hunters”), and a very confident<br />

one (“It is easy to see …”), finds itself in real harmony with Lévi-Strauss’s treatment<br />

of the Hopi and winds up speaking as if they, Deleuze and Guattari themselves, were<br />

either in total control of Hopi thought or were Hopi themselves. Through the power of<br />

anthropological borrowing, the authors have achieved a mind-meld with an alien people.<br />

[Miller 189]<br />

Miller identifies Deleuze and Guattari’s use of free indirect discourse to bring about<br />

a mind-meld with the Hopi as “one of the most powerful modes of anthropological<br />

discourse” (Miller 189), and hence as evidence that Deleuze and Guattari’s claim<br />

that nomadology is “nonanthropological” (Miller 178) is false. But Miller’s analysis<br />

implies as well that Deleuze and Guattari are here repeating the colonialist/imperialist<br />

practice of dominating and speaking for the Other.<br />

Were Deleuze and Guattari writing an ethnography, perhaps they could be<br />

faulted for their incautious rhetoric, but their main purpose here is to characterize<br />

two mentalities and then extract from those mentalities the tendencies that disclose<br />

the basic features of a regime of signs. By and large, I find their presentation of the<br />

two mentalities relatively clear and not significantly different from the descriptions<br />

offered by Lowie and Lévi-Strauss. Miller’s analysis of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

rhetoric, however, is designed to show that Deleuze and Guattari are unwittingly<br />

speaking not simply as anthropologists, but as bad anthropologists. Such, I believe,<br />

is the insinuation introduced by Miller via a somewhat oblique footnote concerning<br />

12 Robert H. Lowie, Robert H. Lowie, Ethnologist: A Personal Record, (Berkeley, CA,<br />

1959), p. 75.


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 155<br />

Sun Chief, the work for which Lévi-Strauss wrote the French translation’s Preface.<br />

Miller cites the original English 1942 edition of the book, and then adds “The<br />

pseudo-autobiography, in which the anthropologist would write the life story of an<br />

informant, was a popular device. In this case, the anthropologist tells us, Don C.<br />

Talayesva of Arizona ‘definitely feels that this is his book’” (Miller 242). The past<br />

tense “was a popular device” implies that this practice is no longer acceptable, and<br />

the remark of Talayesva makes it clear that the pseudo-autobiography is essentially<br />

an exploitative genre. The footnote’s function, as I see it, is first to associate Deleuze<br />

and Guattari with a dubious source, and then to suggest that their stylistic “mindmeld<br />

with an alien people” is a repetition of Talayesva’s now-discredited practice.<br />

At this juncture, we might digress briefly to observe in this footnote the workings<br />

of what might be called the “contamination footnote” strategy. Miller’s note does<br />

not state directly that Deleuze and Guattari are imitating Talayesva’s exploitative<br />

practice, but the reader is invited to make the connection. Further, the footnote<br />

also serves to discredit Lévi-Strauss, since he was foolish enough to endorse this<br />

pseudo-autobiography by furnishing it with a preface. The contagion then extends<br />

from Lévi-Strauss to Lowie, since Lowie’s analysis is seconded by the suspect Lévi-<br />

Strauss, until all are contaminated with Talayesva’s virus.<br />

A variant of this strategy is the footnote appended to Deleuze and Guattari’s remark<br />

that they are constructing “maps of regimes of signs” which they can manipulate<br />

and reconfigure, retaining now certain coordinates or dimensions and now others,<br />

in order to describe “a social formation, a pathological delirium, a historical event,<br />

etc.” (MP 149–50/119). Miller’s note reads: “In his book How to Lie with Maps …<br />

Mark Monmonier shows how this kind of thing is often done: ‘map authors can<br />

experiment freely with features, measurements, area of coverage, and symbols and<br />

can pick the map that best presents their case or supports their unconscious bias’”<br />

(Miller 242). Deleuze and Guattari’s point is that regimes of signs may be observed<br />

in diverse situations of varying nature and scale, and that their analysis will require<br />

adjustments in the model of the regime that reflect the features that are salient in a<br />

given context but not so in others. Miller’s note, however, suggests that Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s mapping technique is fundamental to their entire enterprise, and that their<br />

manipulation of maps opens them to unconscious bias. The attack is oblique, but the<br />

contaminating implication is clear: when Monmonier “shows how this kind of thing<br />

is done,” he shows also how Deleuze and Guattari are able to lie with maps.<br />

As a final variant of the contamination strategy, consider Miller’s note concerning<br />

the African secret societies of leopard-men. Deleuze and Guattari briefly discuss<br />

the leopard-men societies and cite as their source Paul Ernest Joset’s Les Sociétés<br />

secretes des hommes-léopards en Afrique noire. After detailing Joset’s role as a<br />

colonial administrator, Miller appends the following: “The ‘leopard-man’ movement<br />

was also made known to an enormous readership through the comic-strip book Tintin<br />

au Congo, by the Belgian author Hergé. Accompanied by racist images and spoken<br />

in petit nègre, the text reports on a secret society …” (Miller 242). The note has<br />

little to do with Joset’s book, and even less with Deleuze and Guattari’s analysis,<br />

but the purpose of this tangential aside, clearly, is to contaminate Joset and Deleuze-<br />

Guattari with the taint of racism.


156<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Colonialism<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Miller’s use of the contamination strategy is not limited to footnotes but extends to<br />

significant portions of his main text as well. His treatment of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

reference to Joset and the leopard-men is a particularly striking instance of this<br />

strategy’s deployment. Joset “is a strange source for anyone writing in the late 1970s,”<br />

says Miller, since Joset’s book, “published in 1955, during the time of colonial power<br />

in Africa … is deeply involved in the exercise of that power” (Miller 194). Miller<br />

concedes that “Deleuze and Guattari cite other books and articles about Africa, of<br />

course, all of which are more respectable than Joset’s” (Miller 196). But his interest<br />

in general, as he states early in his essay, is “in a number of obscure and outdated<br />

sources that [Deleuze and Guattari] read and used,” for which reason he “will not<br />

attempt the most obvious approach to the question [of the use of anthropology in A<br />

Thousand Plateaus], a systematic reading of how Deleuze and Guattari treat their<br />

principal, canonical anthropological sources” (Miller 182). (Such an approach, he<br />

parenthetically jokes, would be “arborescent” [182].)<br />

Miller first establishes Joset’s identity as a former colonial administrator in the<br />

Belgian Congo, who led the suppression of the Kitawala movement in Kivu province<br />

in 1944. Miller then outlines Joset’s colonialist views on indigenous African culture,<br />

which show a degree of respect for native traditions, but ultimately support a<br />

transformation of native societies in accordance with Western Enlightenment norms.<br />

Miller points out that Joset’s sources for information about the leopard-men secret<br />

societies are chiefly “colonial archives, journal articles, and monographs” (Miller<br />

195), not native sources, and that Joset himself worked diligently to eradicate<br />

leopard-men societies. As for Joset’s description of the leopard-men societies itself,<br />

Miller reports that “it is full of sensational and lurid tales” (Miller 194). Joset,<br />

“like Deleuze and Guattari,” says Miller, “places great faith in his sources. By this<br />

cumulative method, Joset spreads before the reader’s eyes a cornucopia of horrors,<br />

with widows buried alive, entrails wrapped around a victim’s neck, grisly mutilations,<br />

and more; no rumor of an atrocity is too tenuous to be reported here as fact” (Miller<br />

195). Joset’s study “is not the work of a professional ethnographer, but, rather, of a<br />

professional administrator” (Miller 194), and though Miller states that “the veracity<br />

of Les Sociétés secretes” is something “which I have not attempted to determine”<br />

(Miller 195), he clearly finds it suspect. His final assessment is that “Joset’s book is<br />

a piece of anthropological kitsch” (Miller 196).<br />

Joset’s book does indeed cite several reports of murders, mutilations and other<br />

atrocities, but one looks in vain there for a lurid or sensational presentation of those<br />

reports. Joset’s effort first is to gather all available information on the leopard-men<br />

societies, and then to assess the import and viability of his sources. He does not<br />

seem especially credulous, and in fact at several points he dismisses various reports<br />

and assertions as false or distorted. (For example, he states categorically that no<br />

Europeans have been the victims of leopard-men murders, rumors to the contrary.) 13<br />

He is forthright in framing his conclusions and recommendations, but these he<br />

13 Paul-Ernest Joset, Les Sociétés secrètes des hommes-léopards en Afrique noire (Paris,<br />

1955), p. 117.


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 157<br />

presents in a section separate from his survey of the data on leopard-men societies.<br />

His final judgment is that the leopard-men murders are real phenomena and not<br />

imagined events, as many colonial administrators believe; that colonial policies are<br />

responsible for the formation of leopard-men societies, which are warped versions<br />

of indigenous institutions created in response to colonial efforts to suppress native<br />

culture; that the leopard-men societies have terrorized the native population and<br />

should be eliminated; and that African culture should be transformed through civic,<br />

secular education, free of superstition, for both sexes. 14<br />

Joset’s study may not meet the standards of contemporary ethnography, but to<br />

dismiss it as a “piece of anthropological kitsch” is excessive. Miller chides Deleuze<br />

and Guattari for using this source, and particularly for stating that it is “one of the<br />

best studies on this subject” (MP 297/539). One might ask, then, what sources<br />

they should have cited. Miller does not say. One might also ask what Deleuze<br />

and Guattari mean by “best” when they cite Joset’s as “one of the best studies.”<br />

Miller insinuates that Deleuze and Guattari have probably not consulted any other<br />

sources, though they imply as much by singling out Joset’s from other studies. To<br />

date, I have found only one other book-length study of the leopard-men societies,<br />

African Leopard Men (1954) by Birger Lindskog, a professor of sociology and<br />

specialist in African studies at Uppsala University – not a colonial administrator.<br />

Much of the information in Joset appears in Lindskog’s study. Lindskog’s survey is<br />

somewhat broader than Joset’s, but not especially so. If Joset’s work is a “cornucopia<br />

of horrors,” Lindskog’s is even more so, though in neither case is the exposition<br />

of the data lurid or sensationalistic. Both books reflect the anthropological views<br />

of their times, but neither seems grossly to misrepresent the facts of the murders<br />

associated with leopard-men societies. If one consults Jeremy Rich’s 2003 essay<br />

in the International Journal of African Historical Studies, “‘Leopard Men,’ Slaves,<br />

and Social Conflict in Libreville (Gabon), c. 1860–1879,” for example, one finds<br />

signs of different methodological assumptions, but the facts presented are consonant<br />

with those in Joset and Lindskog. The same ritual murders, involving beheadings,<br />

mutilations and organ removal, are reported by Rich, as well as the same denials<br />

by colonial officials that the murders are real; and Rich, like Jolet and Lindskog,<br />

finds strong evidence that the pressures of colonial rule led to the formation of the<br />

leopard-men societies. If, then, by “one of the best studies” Deleuze and Guattari<br />

mean one of the most comprehensive single sources of information available on the<br />

subject, it is not unreasonable or outrageous to assert that Joset’s book fulfills that<br />

description. Miller makes little of the fact that the preface to Jolet’s book was written<br />

by Marcel Griaule, one of the doyens of African anthropology in France, but perhaps<br />

Griaule recognized that the book has at least a degree of merit and is somewhat more<br />

than mere anthropological kitsch.<br />

Joset’s study is not central to Deleuze and Guattari’s enterprise. They refer to<br />

Joset only in two footnotes, and the existence of leopard-men societies itself is not<br />

crucial to their argument. Miller prefaces his discussion of Joset by observing that<br />

“Deleuze and Guattari derive their notion of becoming-animal from anthropological<br />

texts” (Miller 193), thereby implying that Joset’s text likewise has special<br />

14 See especially ibid., pp. 195–7.


158<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

significance in Deleuze and Guattari’s investigation. It is in Kafka: Toward a Minor<br />

Literature (1975) that Deleuze and Guattari first take up the topic of becominganimal,<br />

however, and “The Metamorphosis” is a much more likely source of<br />

inspiration for the concept than any anthropological text. Yet even if anthropological<br />

texts had inspired them in the development of the concept, the relationship between<br />

becoming-animal and folk beliefs in lycanthropy or other lore about human-animal<br />

metamorphosis is complex and oblique. Miller stresses that both Jolet and Deleuze-<br />

Guattari believe “this ‘becoming-animal’ is real” (Miller 196), but such an assertion<br />

only muddles distinctions Deleuze and Guattari go to great lengths to maintain.<br />

Jolet argues that the ritual murders are real, not imagined, but he does not believe<br />

that the murderers actually transform themselves into leopards, as do many of the<br />

indigenous population. Jolet has no beliefs about “becoming-animal,” since it is a<br />

concept unlike any available to him when he writes. Deleuze and Guattari claim that<br />

“becoming-animal” is real, but “becoming-animal” has little to do with dressing up<br />

like animals or imitating them. It is a process of becoming-other that allows people<br />

to undo conventional codes of the human through an interaction with animals. In the<br />

stories of shape-shifters, werewolves, leopard-men and other such human-animal<br />

transformations, which exist in all the world’s cultures, Deleuze and Guattari find<br />

evidence not of literal bodily metamorphoses of humans but of real processes of<br />

becoming-other that have been expressed through these stories. “Becoming-animal,”<br />

however, manifests itself in the actual only as a tendency, and Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

effort is to extract the virtual process from the actual and establish it as an element<br />

within a network of related concepts of virtual processes. Not surprisingly, Miller’s<br />

analysis does little to clarify Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of becoming-animal, for<br />

its main function is to link the concept to anthropological sources in general, then to<br />

Joset in particular, and thereby to establish a circuit of contamination that will infect<br />

A Thousand Plateaus as a whole. In citing the credulous, lurid and unreliable book<br />

by the racist Joset, Deleuze and Guattari have swallowed the virus of the colonial<br />

mentality and allowed it to propagate and thoroughly taint their thought.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Primitivism<br />

Yet another deployment of the contamination strategy may be found in Miller’s<br />

commentary on Pierre Hubac’s Les Nomades and its similarities to A Thousand<br />

Plateaus. Before examining the details of Miller’s commentary, however, we should<br />

pause briefly to reflect on Deleuze and Guattari’s choice of sources in general. Miller<br />

notes that “the archive of nomad thought … is overwhelmingly academic: the vast<br />

majority of sources and citations are either tracts by great thinkers, philosophers,<br />

and literary writers, on the one hand, or, on the other, scholarly studies reflecting<br />

research on specific topics” (Miller 176). Miller concedes that a few references to<br />

popular culture appear, but “for all its eclecticism, A Thousand Plateaus remains<br />

primarily a work of European ‘high’ counterculture” (Miller 176–7). Miller’s<br />

characterization of Deleuze and Guattari’s citations is basically accurate, though for<br />

reasons that may not be immediately apparent. Throughout his writings, Deleuze<br />

remains dedicated to philosophy as a practice, even if the discipline itself has often


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 159<br />

functioned as a repressive and stultifying force. He often makes clear that he is doing<br />

philosophy, by which he means that he is creating concepts. Never does he abandon<br />

rigor or seriousness in that activity, even if it does entail humor and play as well. He<br />

certainly does not champion sloppiness, vagueness, or misleading research practices.<br />

Guattari’s work shows a similar commitment to rigorous and serious thought. Both<br />

Deleuze and Guattari recognize the elitist nature of much scholarship, however, and<br />

they try to be open to influences outside the realm of academic orthodoxy. Popular<br />

culture is one possible source of inspiration for their thought, but a great deal of<br />

popular culture is generated by a mind-numbing industry of consumption, whose<br />

products are tired replicas of worn-out orthodoxies. As a result, their references to<br />

popular culture are somewhat limited. And their respect for rigorous thought and<br />

commitment to philosophy lead them to cite a number of respectable academic<br />

sources.<br />

Nevertheless, there is an important element of the nomadic archive that Miller<br />

does not mention, even though it is central to his critique of Deleuze and Guattari.<br />

If popular culture often does not supply them with adequate tools for challenging<br />

academic orthodoxy, occasionally they find such tools in idiosyncratic works<br />

– memoirs of madmen (such as Daniel Paul Schreber’s Memoirs of My Nervous<br />

Illness), marginally pornographic novels (Sacher-Masoch’s Venus in Furs), eccentric<br />

handbooks (Lipot Szondi’s Experimental Diagnostics of Drives), outmoded treatises<br />

(Geoffroy-Saint-Hilaire’s Principles of Zoological History). What they find in such<br />

sources is not ready-made components for their arguments, but hints and suggestions<br />

of possible lines of inquiry, materials with potential for development, modification<br />

or transformation. Deleuze and Guattari’s goal is to think otherwise, and sometimes<br />

a work which, as a whole, is insane, perverse, bizarre, quirky, or simply mistaken<br />

in its governing assumptions, will provide inspiration for the invention of concepts<br />

that are rigorously constructed, cogently interconnected, and viable as elements of a<br />

genuinely creative thought.<br />

One such work is Pierre Hubac’s Les Nomades (1948). Unlike Joset’s study, which<br />

is a tangential source, Hubac’s work is an important one, even though Deleuze and<br />

Guattari cite it only once, and only apropos of Hubac’s assertion of the importance of<br />

climate in nomadism. Miller introduces Hubac via the contamination gambit, saying<br />

that Les Nomades “comes from the same category of dated and dubious anthropology<br />

as Joset’s book on leopard-men” (Miller 198), but Hubac’s method differs greatly<br />

from Joset’s. It is an essayistic, lyrical meditation on nomadism, somewhat in the<br />

vein of a Nietzschean essay in universal history. Miller describes the book as “a<br />

classic example of anthropology that is more about the author’s personal vision<br />

and social ethics than about an actual society” (Miller 198–9), but classifying it as<br />

“anthropology” is strained at best. Hubac sees the opposition of the nomad and the<br />

sedentary as the universal motor of history, and his essay is an attempt to narrate the<br />

history of the world from this perspective, in a style that is deliberately emotive and<br />

evocative, supported by occasional academic references, but without great concern<br />

for the niceties of scholarly objectivity. It is precisely the kind of quirky, at times<br />

monomaniacal, sometimes brilliant, and occasionally provocative work that Deleuze<br />

and Guattari find useful in attempting to think differently.


160<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

If the line of contagion in the Joset example is from a footnote about racism in<br />

a comic book, through an ad hominem attack on Joset, to a discrediting of Joset’s<br />

research and finally to Deleuze and Guattari, in the Hubac instance the line is more<br />

direct, from Hubac’s bad anthropology to Deleuze and Guattari’s bad appropriation<br />

of it. The correspondences between Hubac and Deleuze-Guattari are actually quite<br />

fascinating, and they would be worthy of an extended examination (though at<br />

another time). There is some truth to Miller’s remark that Hubac’s “discourse is (to<br />

risk a genealogical metaphor) a cousin once removed, of an older generation, to the<br />

discourse of Deleuze and Guattari’s ‘Treatise on Nomadology’” (Miller 199). The<br />

question, of course, is how far removed this cousin is. Miller’s answer is, not much.<br />

He capably points out parallels between Hubac and Deleuze-Guattari, duly notes<br />

certain differences in their views, and suggests that what they ultimately share is a<br />

view of nomads as opponents of the state; inventors of the war machine; proponents<br />

of an ethics of flow; and inhabitants of an unlimited space. Most importantly,<br />

“underlying both texts is a fundamental, unshakable sympathy for nomadism, a<br />

desire to rehabilitate nomads, to rewrite or unwrite history” (Miller 204).<br />

All these commonalities are significant, but it is essential to recognize the<br />

incommensurable differences that underlie the conceptual frameworks of the two<br />

texts. Hubac’s history is an evolutionary account of two distinct human types, nomads<br />

and sedentaries, biologically and psychologically different from one another. Human<br />

history is an eternal conflict between the two types. Late in his essay, Hubac sums<br />

up the history he has detailed:<br />

We have seen the nomadic herdsman become warrior, then merchant, caravaneer,<br />

aristocrat, and end up emperor of the universe; we have witnessed the formation of urban<br />

and rural societies, because of the nomad, thanks to the nomad, and we can consider that<br />

this anarchist is the initial factor of every organization, of every city, of every nation, of<br />

every great human collectivity. 15<br />

Obviously, Hubac’s project is at odds with Deleuze and Guattari’s at every point.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari would reject Hubac’s biologism, his naïve evolutionism, his<br />

delineation of the nomad’s changing social roles from herdsman to emperor, his use<br />

of primarily psychological mechanisms to account for historical change, his focus<br />

on the opposition of nomads and sedentaries to the exclusion of all other categories,<br />

his genetic account of the formation of the state, his attribution of all forms of social<br />

organization to the nomad – the list could easily go on.<br />

And if we consider the most salient individual elements common to the two texts,<br />

we must again pay close attention to their conceptual differences. Hubac opposes<br />

nomads to the state, but he says little about the state per se, save that it is formed<br />

in response to nomads. Deleuze and Guattari, by contrast, expend great efforts<br />

developing a concept of the State apparatus, its relationship to cities, capitalism,<br />

number, science, subjectivity, thought, and so on. Hubac ties the invention of the war<br />

machine to a specific period in history, when Genghis Khan establishes a new, more<br />

disciplined military order, and he uses the term without offering any elaboration of<br />

its specific meaning. Deleuze and Guattari, for their part, do not associate the war<br />

15 Pierre Hubac, Les Nomades (Paris, 1948), p. 229 (translation mine).


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 161<br />

machine with a given phase in the development of nomadic existence, and they<br />

turn the descriptive phrase “war machine” into a properly philosophical concept<br />

within a network of concepts. Hubac speaks metaphorically and poetically of flows,<br />

whereas Deleuze and Guattari use the vocabulary of flows in A Thousand Plateaus<br />

after having devoted virtually the entirety of Anti-Oedipus to the exposition of a<br />

philosophy of flows and fluxes. Finally, though the “empty space” of Hubac’s nomads<br />

resembles Deleuze and Guattari’s “smooth space,” again, Hubac’s notion is vague<br />

and unspecified, whereas Deleuze and Guattari’s is defined in detail and in ways that<br />

would seem counterintuitive to the basic sense of “smooth” as opposed to “striated”<br />

(the two terms they oppose in Plateau Fourteen: The Smooth and the Striated).<br />

This last point is especially important, given Miller’s criticism of Deleuze and<br />

Guattari for indulging in “the dream of a utopia of undividedness that has so often<br />

characterized Western thought about Africa. The imagery of nomadology often<br />

describes this utopia in terms of ‘empty space,’ what Deleuze and Guattari call<br />

‘smooth space.’ The ‘making-empty’ of that space is a classic gesture of primitivism”<br />

(Miller 198). This characterization of smooth space ignores one of its fundamental<br />

qualities – it is heterogeneous, whereas striated space is homogeneous (MP 593–<br />

4/475–6).<br />

Paradoxically, striated space, through its divisions, creates an undivided,<br />

homogeneous medium, whereas smooth space, while dissolving grids and<br />

coordinates, creates a space of heterogeneous multiplicities. One might think that<br />

smooth space would be infinite and endless, as opposed to a finite and closed striated<br />

space, but such is the case only in a paradoxical sense. Striated space constitutes<br />

a “relative global” space, as opposed to the “local absolute” of smooth space. The<br />

relative global is a whole but one that always manifests its components as relative<br />

elements, whereas the local absolute is an open whole only manifest in the local. It<br />

may well be that Hubac’s “empty space” is an index of his primitivism, but Deleuze<br />

and Guattari’s “smooth space” is conceptually distinct from that notion, as well as<br />

the common notions of “empty space” associated with “the dream of a utopia of<br />

undividedness” (Miller 198).<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Pseudoradicalism<br />

In his discussion of Joset and Hubac, Miller does raise a very serious issue – that of<br />

the theme of violence in A Thousand Plateaus. Miller points out that the leopard-men<br />

of Joset’s study actually kill people. Although Deleuze and Guattari do not mention<br />

murder, “it is clear that the African practice of becoming-animal as described by<br />

Joset is intrinsically linked to murder. This is characteristic of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

happy-talk revolution: the benefits are advertised in the text, while the bodies are<br />

hidden, not even in the footnotes, but in the original source material” (Miller 195).<br />

In a similar vein, Miller remarks that Hubac<br />

… confronts the violence and death that “the” nomad war machine causes, in a way that<br />

Deleuze and Guattari fail to do. The ethics of flow described in Hubac’s book is “absorbed”<br />

into the “Treatise on Nomadology,” but in the process of digestion, the source is altered,<br />

as others were. As was the case with their use of Joset’s book, violent death has been left


162<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

out … The source material, as it enters A Thousand Plateaus, is at once evacuated of its<br />

representational force, and, in effect, sanitized for the benefits of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

“happy” nomadology. [Miller 205]<br />

What Miller suggests is that Deleuze and Guattari are engaged in a form of radical<br />

chic, in which they romanticize non-Western cultural practices, such as ritual murder<br />

or nomadic war, and recommend revolutionary action patterned on those practices,<br />

while simultaneously ignoring the violence necessarily associated with such action.<br />

In this reading, Deleuze and Guattari’s antirepresentational stance is merely a means<br />

of denying the real consequences of revolutionary struggle. Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

stance, however, is only antirepresentational in a specific, philosophical sense; they<br />

do not deny the reality of leopard-men murders, nomadic war, or the referential<br />

relevance of texts about those phenomena. Deleuze and Guattari do transform<br />

Joset and Hubac when they absorb them within their text, but they do so in order to<br />

develop a set of concepts that are grounded in presuppositions that are unlike those<br />

of their sources. They are not trying to sanitize ritual murder and nomadic war by<br />

denying referentiality, nor are they recommending that people go out and commit<br />

ritual murder and engage in nomadic war. The “happy talk” radicals Miller discerns<br />

in Deleuze and Guattari are revolutionaries who romanticize social struggle and<br />

ignore its violent consequences. They celebrate the actions of leopard-men societies<br />

and nomadic hordes while pretending that the real suffering and death inherent in<br />

those actions do not exist.<br />

In some ways this criticism resembles that leveled at Deleuze and Guattari<br />

following the publication of Anti-Oedipus. Many assumed that Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s schizoanalysis romanticized schizophrenia, and that Deleuze and Guattari<br />

were summoning everyone to “go schizo.” But they stressed in Anti-Oedipus that<br />

the “schizo” they saw as a promising possibility was not the same as the “schizo”<br />

in the psychiatric hospital. They insisted that the kind of individual they envision,<br />

and more importantly, the mode of social existence within which such an individual<br />

could arise, do not yet exist. Some critics read this position as an appropriation of the<br />

real phenomenon of schizophrenia for some theoretical revolutionary purpose, and<br />

hence as indicative of an insensitivity to the suffering of mental patients and an elitist<br />

isolation from the concrete realm of human pain. At least in Guattari’s case, however,<br />

this charge lacked force. Guattari had spent many years working with schizophrenics<br />

in psychiatric hospitals, and he was all too aware of the practical dimensions of radical<br />

action within that context. He himself was particularly critical of the romanticization<br />

of schizophrenia in some strains of the anti-psychiatry movement, especially as it<br />

was exhibited in the case of R.D. Laing’s patient Mary Barnes at Kingsley Hall<br />

(See RM 125–36/51–9). Yet he saw in schizophrenics possibilities for alternative<br />

modes of thought, and in his collaboration with Deleuze he was able to develop a<br />

conceptual framework for articulating those possibilities and integrating them with<br />

possibilities developed out of other sources.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari are not recommending that we imitate leopard-men or<br />

nomads but that we think otherwise, and that we extract from the real phenomena<br />

of leopard-men societies and nomadic hordes the processes of becoming-other<br />

that might facilitate new thought. By no means do Deleuze and Guattari ignore


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 163<br />

the real violence of ritual murders or nomadic warfare. In fact, the “Treatise on<br />

Nomadology” may finally be seen as a treatise on violence, which is the topic<br />

Deleuze and Guattari explicitly address at the end of the plateau. They are very<br />

much aware of the dangers of “becoming-other,” of the precarious nature of any<br />

dissolution of fixed social structures and the potential it holds for violent action.<br />

(This is the point they make when discussing the black hole of the suicidal body<br />

without organs and the microfascisms of the cancerous body without organs [see<br />

Chapter 3].) The nomadology plateau distinguishes the war machine from the<br />

State apparatus, and in so doing problematizes the relationship between violence<br />

and the state. The intuition Deleuze and Guattari are exploring is that the creative,<br />

metamorphic power of becoming-other is linked to violence in the war machine, and<br />

that the state appropriates the war machine for its purposes, directing its violence<br />

and controlling its metamorphic force. Deleuze and Guattari find the war machine<br />

among nomads, warriors, secret societies, and so on, and recognize its close ties to<br />

violence, but finally they ask whether it might be possible that a war machine can exist<br />

without having war as its object – in other words, whether the creative, metamorphic<br />

power of becoming-other might be divorced from violence. The question is a serious<br />

one, posed at the level of basic philosophical presuppositions. As I see it, the issue<br />

finally is whether there is a real difference between puissance and pouvoir, between<br />

good power (potency, capability, empowerment) and bad power (power over others,<br />

domination, violence), or whether the ontological model of power, forces, dynamism<br />

– in short, physics – necessarily brings with it violence and removes any viable<br />

distinction between puissance and pouvoir. It may be that Deleuze and Guattari are<br />

right and we can separate war from the war machine, pouvoir from puissance; it may<br />

be that pouvoir and puissance cannot be separated and we must live with this fact; or<br />

it may be that the entire model of physical forces is wrong, and we need to develop<br />

a different model for thinking about the cosmos. These are the questions addressed<br />

in A Thousand Plateaus, I believe, not those of a happy-talk revolution that ignores<br />

the reality of violence.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s Irrelevance<br />

At the end of his essay, Miller asks, “what should be done with nomadology then?,”<br />

and his answer is, “The most promising uses would appear to be those that would<br />

do better than Deleuze and Guattari themselves did at avoiding representation of<br />

foreign cultures: Massumi’s own book, for example” (Miller 208–209). Here Miller<br />

completes the gesture he initiated at the beginning of his discussion. Now Massumi<br />

not only speaks for Deleuze and Guattari, but replaces them. Throughout his critique<br />

Miller adopts the technique of reading Deleuze and Guattari through others, initially<br />

through the words of their interpreters, then through the words of the authors they<br />

cite. In both cases, what Deleuze and Guattari actually say begins to fade, and in<br />

its place appears the discourse of others. Through the discourse of the interpreters,<br />

a phantom deconstructive, radical-chic Deleuze-Guattari takes shape, whereas the<br />

discourse of the sources gives rise to an unwittingly racist, colonialist, primitivist,<br />

orientalist, exoticist, romantic, utopian Deleuze-Guattari monster. Miller examines


164<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s use of dubious sources, but rather than focusing on the ways<br />

the sources are transformed within a different conceptual framework, he reads<br />

Deleuze and Guattari as distorted reflections of their sources. The result is that the<br />

sources replace the text – the instance of Hubac being the full realization of this<br />

tendency, in that Hubac’s nomadology emerges as the genuine nomadology, what<br />

Deleuze and Guattari were really saying but were too dishonest to admit. (“But isn’t<br />

[Hubac], also, ultimately, more honest about the ethics of nomadology? He confronts<br />

the violence and death that ‘the’ nomad war machine causes, in a way that Deleuze<br />

and Guattari fail to do” [Miller 205].)<br />

What should be done with nomadology, then? Miller’s answer is, erase it. Dismiss<br />

Deleuze and Guattari and turn to something else. I see other alternatives, however.<br />

One might challenge Deleuze and Guattari in terms of their basic presuppositions,<br />

question their ontology, their Bergsonian methodology, their assumptions about<br />

thought, process, becoming, language, and so on, but do so by confronting their<br />

philosophy as a cohesive whole, not simply treating one concept or another without<br />

paying attention to the host of related concepts that are inextricably tied to it. One<br />

might also reverse the process of Deleuze and Guattari’s Bergsonian method.<br />

Whereas they seek to identify tendencies within the mixture of the actual and extract<br />

the pure differences in nature that inform those tendencies, one might examine the<br />

actual manifestations of those tendencies and attempt to discriminate the specific<br />

combinations of mixed elements that appear there. What aspects of the lives of an<br />

actual nomadic people conform to Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the nomadic?<br />

What aspects are sedentary, or itinerant, ambulatory, migrant? In a given speech<br />

situation, what statements bear the stamp of the despotic regime, or the primitive, the<br />

passional, or the nomadic regime? Such an empirical study of these mixtures might<br />

eventually lead one to conclude that Deleuze and Guattari are totally wrong and that<br />

these categories are not helpful, or that they are partially incorrect and that certain<br />

aspects of one concept or another should be dropped, modified, or regrouped.<br />

Miller is a sophisticated critic, with considerable skills as an interpreter, theorist<br />

and cultural commentator. His critique of Deleuze and Guattari brings to light<br />

several problems in their thought and some of the limitations of their knowledge.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari range wide in formulating their nomadology, and sometimes<br />

they traverse territory they should have mapped more thoroughly. In Anti-Oedipus<br />

and A Thousand Plateaus, they try to extend their understanding of culture beyond<br />

the Western world, but Miller is astute in pointing out that Africa is the continent<br />

whose cultures they examine in least detail. And Miller is certainly correct that<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s project suffers from a lack of African and Asian sources.<br />

He is understandably irritated by what he sees as arrogant, exaggerated claims for<br />

nomadology, and he is deeply concerned at what he deems a resurgence of reactionary<br />

attitudes and dangerous clichés in A Thousand Plateaus. Deleuze and Guattari at times<br />

do indulge in hyperbole; they enjoy making categorical, paradoxical and seemingly<br />

illogical statements that run counter to received opinions; they deliberately state their<br />

views with less caution and fewer caveats than would more academic philosophers;<br />

and their mercurial humor sometimes makes it difficult to be certain of their true<br />

intent. This style is not for everyone, but there is more here than mere posture and<br />

rhetoric, for Deleuze and Guattari, in my view, have developed concepts and modes


Nomadology’s Trial by Proxy 165<br />

of analysis that allow us to reframe basic philosophical questions in refreshing and<br />

truly innovative ways. Miller has issued a serious challenge to nomadology, and I<br />

would not have gone on at such length had this not been a serious challenge, but<br />

finally I believe that he is mistaken in his understanding of Deleuze and Guattari’s<br />

undertaking.<br />

In his Le Vocabulaire de Deleuze, François Zourabichvili argues that “we do<br />

not yet know the thought of Deleuze. Too often, hostile or adoring, we act as if his<br />

concepts were familiar, as if it were enough that the concepts simply touch us and we<br />

understand them by hints, or as if we had already made a survey of their promises.” 16<br />

The thought of Deleuze, and of Deleuze-Guattari, is difficult – stylistically so,<br />

perhaps, but above all, conceptually difficult. What, then, should be done with<br />

nomadology? If it is not simply to be ignored or plundered for spare parts, it should<br />

first be read, as much as possible, on its own terms. Once we determine, with some<br />

measure of certainty, what Deleuze and Guattari actually are saying, then we may<br />

decide what to do with them.<br />

16 François Zourabichvili, Le Vocabulaire de Deleuze (Paris, 2003), p. 3.


This page intentionally left blank


Bibliography<br />

Agamben, Giorgio. “Absolute Immanence,” in Potentialities: Collected Essays in<br />

Philosophy. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford, CA: Stanford University<br />

Press, 1999, pp. 220–39.<br />

Arnett, Jeffrey Jensen. Metalheads: Heavy Metal Music and Adolescent Alienation.<br />

Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996.<br />

Barfield, Thomas J. The Nomadic Alternative. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall,<br />

1993.<br />

Bartók, Béla. Essays. Selected and ed. Benjamin Suchoff. New York: St. Martin’s,<br />

1976.<br />

Bartók, Béla. The Hungarian Folk Song. Ed. Benjamin Suchoff, trans. M.D.<br />

Calvocoressi, with annotations by Zoltán Kodály. Albany: State University Press<br />

of New York, 1981.<br />

Beckwith, Karl. “‘Black Metal Music is for White People’: Constructs of Colour<br />

and Identity with the Extreme Metal Scene.” M/C Journal (2002) .<br />

Bene, Carmelo. Opere. Milan: Bompiani, 1995.<br />

Berger, Harris M. “Death Metal Tonality and the Act of Listening.” Popular Music,<br />

18/2 (1999): 161–76.<br />

Bergson, Henri. Creative Evolution. Trans. Arthur Mitchell. New York: Henry Holt<br />

and Company, 1911.<br />

Bergson. Henri. Oeuvres. Edition du Centenaire. Ed. André Robinet. Paris: Presses<br />

Universitaires de Paris, 1959.<br />

Bergson, Henri. The Two Sources of Morality and Religion. Trans. R. Ashley Audra<br />

and Cloudsley Brereton. Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor, 1954.<br />

Berland, Joseph C. and Matt T. Salo. “Peripatetic Communities: An Introduction.”<br />

Nomadic Peoples, (special issue on Peripatetic Peoples) 21/22 (December<br />

1986): 1–6.<br />

Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze on Cinema. New York: Routledge, 2003.<br />

Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze on Literature. New York: Routledge, 2003.<br />

Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze on Music, Painting, and the Arts. New York: Routledge,<br />

2003.<br />

Bogue, Ronald. Deleuze’s Wake: Tributes and Tributaries. Albany: State University<br />

Press of New York, 2004.<br />

Bréhier, Emile. La Théorie des incorporels dans l’ancien stoïcisme. Paris: Vrin,<br />

1928.<br />

Clastres, Pierre. La Société contre l’état: recherches d’anthropologie politique.<br />

Paris: Minuit, 1974.


168<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Clifford, James and George E. Marcus (eds). Writing Culture: The Poetics and<br />

Politics of Ethnography. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986.<br />

Conley, Verena Andermatt. “A Fraying of Voices: Jean-Luc Godard’s Prénom<br />

Carmen.” L’Esprit créateur, 30/2 (1990): 68–80.<br />

Eribon, Didier. Conversations with Claude Lévi-Strauss. Trans. Paul Wissing.<br />

Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1991.<br />

Faris, James C. The Nightway: A History and a History of Documentation of a<br />

Navajo Ceremonial. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press, 1990.<br />

Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge. Trans. A.M. Sheridan Smith.<br />

New York: Pantheon, 1972.<br />

Genet, Jean. Un captif amoureux. Paris: Gallimard, 1986.<br />

Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, Etienne. Principes de philosophie zoologique. Paris: Pichon<br />

et Didier, 1830.<br />

Gill, Sam D. Native American Religious Action: A Performance Approach to<br />

Religion. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1987.<br />

Giraudoux, Jean. Théâtre complet. Ed. Jacques Body. Paris: Gallimard, 1982.<br />

Godard, Jean-Luc. “Les signes du mal à vivre: Entretien avec Jean-Luc Godard.”<br />

L’Avant scène cinéma, 323/324 (March 1984): 4–11.<br />

Godard, Jean-Luc. Jean-Luc Godard par Jean-Luc Godard. Ed. Alain Bergala. Paris:<br />

Editions de L’Etoile/Cahiers du Cinéma, 1985.<br />

Godard, Jean-Luc, and Anne-Marie Miéville. Scenario prepared by Marc Cerisuelo.<br />

Prénom Carmen: Découpage intégral et dialogue in extenso du film. L’Avant<br />

scène cinéma, 323/324 (1984): 19–64.<br />

Godard, Jean-Luc, Anne-Marie Miéville and Jean-Pierre Gorin, directors. Ici et<br />

ailleurs. (Sonimage/IMA, France, 1974).<br />

Goldschmidt, Victor. Le Système stoïcien et l’idée de temps. Paris: Vrin, 1953.<br />

Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 2000.<br />

Harrell, Jack. “The Poetics of Destruction: Death Metal Rock,” Popular Music and<br />

Society, 18 (1994): 91–104.<br />

Hubac, Pierre. Les Nomades. Paris: La Reniassance du Livre, 1948.<br />

Joset, Paul-Ernest. Les Sociétés secrètes des hommes-léopards en Afrique noire.<br />

Paris: Payot, 1955.<br />

Kafka, Franz. The Diaries of Franz Kafka. Ed. Max Brod, tr. Joseph Kresh. New<br />

York: Schocken, 1948.<br />

Klossowski, Pierre. Sade, mon prochain. Paris: Seuil, 1947.<br />

Laplanche, Jean, and Jean-Baptiste Pontalis. The Language of Psycho-Analysis.<br />

Trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith. New York: Norton, 1973.<br />

Laroche, Emmanuel. Histoire de la racine “nem-” en Grec ancien. Paris: Klincksieck,<br />

1949.<br />

Leach, Edmund Ronald. Rethinking Anthropology. London: Athlone Press, 1961.<br />

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. New Essays on Human Understanding. Trans. Peter<br />

Remnant and Jonathan Bennett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.<br />

Lindskog, Birger. African Leopard Men. Uppsala: Studia Ethnographica<br />

Upsaliensia 7, 1954.


Bibliography 169<br />

Lowie, Robert H. Robert H. Lowie, Ethnologist: A Personal Record. Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press, 1959.<br />

Luckert, Karl W. Coyoteway: A Navajo Holyway Healing Ceremony. Tucson:<br />

University of Arizona Press, 1979.<br />

Marcus, George E. and Michael M.J. Fischer. Anthropology as Cultural Critique:<br />

An Experimental Moment in the Human Sciences. Chicago, IL: University of<br />

Chicago Press, 1986.<br />

Matthews, Washington. The Mountain Chant: A Navajo Ceremony. Salt Lake City:<br />

University of Utah Press, 1997.<br />

Messiaen, Olivier. Music and Color. Conversations with Claude Samuel. Tr. E.<br />

Thomas Glasow. Portland, OR: Amadeus Press, 1994.<br />

Miller, Christopher L. “The Postidentitarian Predicament in the Footnotes of A<br />

Thousand Plateaus: Nomadology, Anthropology, and Authority.” Diacritics, 23/3<br />

(1993): 6–35.<br />

Miller, Christopher L. Nationalists and Nomads: Essays on Francophone African<br />

Literature and Culture. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1998.<br />

Monmonier, Mark S. How to Lie with Maps. 2nd edn. Chicago, IL: University of<br />

Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

Moynihan, Michael and Didrik Søderlind. Lords of Chaos: The Bloody Rise of the<br />

Satanic Metal Underground. Venice, CA: Feral House, 1998.<br />

Musy, François. “Les Mouettes du Pont d’Austerlitz: Entretien avec François Musy.”<br />

Cahiers du cinéma, 355 (January 1984): 12–17.<br />

Nemeth, David. “Service Nomads: Interim Masters of Imperfect Markets.” Nomadic<br />

Peoples, 21/22 (December 1986): 135–51.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. Trans. Marianne<br />

Cowan. Chicago, IL: Henry Regnery, 1962.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Birth of Tragedy and The Case of Wagner. Trans. Walter<br />

Kauffman. New York: Vintage, 1967.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche. Trans. Christopher<br />

Middleton. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1969.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Untimely Meditations. Ed. Daniel Breazeale, trans. R.J.<br />

Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.<br />

Perrault, Pierre. “Cinéma du réel et cinéma de fiction: vraie ou fausse distinction?<br />

Dialogue entre Pierre Perrault et René Allio.” In Ecritures de Pierre Perrault: Actes du<br />

colloque “gens de paroles.” Québec: Cinématheque Québécoise, 1983, pp. 42–59.<br />

Powrie, Phil. “Godard’s Prénom: Carmen (1984), Masochism, and the Male Gaze.”<br />

Forum for Modern Language Studies, 31/1 (1995): 64–73.<br />

Proust, Marcel. Remembrance of Things Past. 3 vols. Trans. C.K. Moncrieff and<br />

Terence Kilmartin. New York: Vintage, 1982.<br />

Radcliffe, Philip. Beethoven’s String Quartets. London: Hutchinson University<br />

Library, 1965.<br />

Rich, Jeremy. “‘Leopard Men,’ Slaves, and Social Conflict in Libreville (Gabon),<br />

c. 1860–1879.” International Journal of African Historical Studies, 34/3 (2001):<br />

619–39.<br />

Robertson, Roland. Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture. London:<br />

Sage, 1992.


170<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Sacher-Masoch, Leopold Ritter von. Venus in Furs. Trans. Charles Raymond. New<br />

York: Privately Printed for Subscribers Only, 1928.<br />

Salo, Matthew T. and Sheila Salo. “Rominchel Economic and Social Organization<br />

in Urban New England, 1850–1930.” Urban Anthropology, 11/ 3–4 (Fall–Winter<br />

1982): 273–313.<br />

Samuel, Claude. Conversations with Olivier Messiaen. Trans. F Aprahamian.<br />

London: Steiner and Bell, 1976.<br />

Schreber, Daniel Paul. Memoirs of My Nervous Illness. Trans. and eds Ida Macalpine<br />

and Richard A. Hunter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1988.<br />

Shapiro, Marc. “The Birth of Death: A Speed Demonology.” Guitar Presents: Speed<br />

Demons of Metal, (1993): 6–9, 23, 110–12.<br />

Smith, Daniel W. “Deleuze and Derrida, Immanence and Transcendence: Two<br />

Directions in Recent French Thought.” In Between Deleuze and Derrida. Eds<br />

Paul Patton and John Protevi. London: Continuum, 2003, pp. 46–66.<br />

Solomon, Maynard. “Beethoven’s Tagebuch of 1812–1818.” In Beethoven Studies 3.<br />

Ed. Alan Tyson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982, pp.193–293.<br />

Spariosu, Mihai. Global Intelligence and Human Development. Toward an Ecology<br />

of Global Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004.<br />

Spinoza, Baruch. Complete Works. Ed. Michael L. Morgan, trans. Samuel Shirley.<br />

Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2002.<br />

Szondi, Lipot. Experimental Diagnostics of Drives. New York: Grune and Stratton,<br />

1952.<br />

Talayesva, Don C. Soleil Hopi: l’autobiographie d’un indien hopi. Trans. Geneviève<br />

Mayou. Paris: France Loisirs, 1959.<br />

Turnbull, Colin M. <strong>Way</strong>ward Servants. The Two Worlds of the African Pygmies.<br />

Garden City, NY: Natural History Press, 1965.<br />

Wagenbach, Klaus. Franz Kafka: Eine Biographie Seiner Jugend 1883–1912. Bern:<br />

Francke, 1958.<br />

Walser, Robert. Running with the Devil: Power, Gender, and Madness in Heavy<br />

Metal Music. Hanover, NH: Wesleyan University Press, 1993.<br />

Weinstein, Deena. Heavy Metal: A Cultural Sociology. New York: Lexington,<br />

1991.<br />

Williams, James. Gilles Deleuze’s Difference and Repetition: A Critical Introduction<br />

and Guide. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2003.<br />

Wyman, Leland Clifton. Beautyway: A Navaho Ceremonial. New York: Pantheon<br />

Books, 1957.<br />

Wyman, Leland Clifton. Blessingway. Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1970.<br />

Wyman, Leland Clifton. The Mountainway of the Navajo. Tucson: University of<br />

Arizona Press, 1975.<br />

Zourabichvili, François. Le Vocabulaire de Deleuze. Paris: Ellipses, 2003.


Abstract machine, 21–3, 146–7<br />

Aeon/ Chronos, 37, 42–5<br />

Agamben, Giorgio, 7<br />

Amor fati, 8–10<br />

Arnett, Jeffrey Jensen, 38<br />

Assemblages, 20, 145–6<br />

Bacon, Francis 102–3, 112<br />

Barfield, Thomas J., 114–5, 124<br />

Bartók, Béla, 118–120<br />

Beckett, Samuel, 19, 22, 41, 73, 103<br />

Beckwith, Karl, 47<br />

Becoming-animal, 158<br />

Beethoven, Ludwig von, 74–9, 84–9, 101<br />

Bene, Carmelo, 24–7, 31<br />

Berger, Harris M., 41<br />

Bergson, Henri, 28, 55–6, 62, 91–7, 101–6,<br />

115–6, 120, 124, 126, 143–4, 149,<br />

164<br />

Berland, Joseph C., 115<br />

Birdsong, 29–30, 36<br />

Bizet, Georges, 73–7, 80<br />

Black hole, 49<br />

Black metal music, 39–40, 45<br />

Body without organs, 37, 48–52, 163<br />

Boulez, Pierre, 31, 42, 114, 127<br />

Bréhier, Emile, 20<br />

Carroll, Lewis, 107<br />

Céline, Louis-Ferdinand, 22<br />

Chromaticism, generalized, 32, 40<br />

Clastres, Pierre, 116–117, 148–9<br />

Clifford, James, 144–5<br />

Collective assemblage of enunciation, 18,<br />

20–4, 26, 31, 147<br />

Conley, Verena Andermatt, 73, 80<br />

Count Grishnackh (Varg Vikernes, guitarist<br />

of Burzum), 47–8<br />

Creative emotion (in Bergson), 95–6, 102, 106<br />

Cultural studies, 123, 134–7<br />

Index<br />

De facto/ de jure, 115–6, 118, 120, 124,<br />

127–8, 132<br />

Death metal music, 38–44<br />

Derrida, Jacques, 7, 142<br />

Doom metal music, 39–40, 44–5<br />

Dumézil, Georges, 114<br />

Egg, world as, 8–9, 37–8, 56–7<br />

Fabulation, 14, 93–7, 99–106<br />

Faris, James C., 135<br />

Fischer, Michael M. J., 145<br />

Foucault, Michel, 7, 104–105, 142, 145, 151<br />

Freud, Sigmund, 110–1<br />

Genet, Jean, 104<br />

Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, Etienne, 159<br />

Gill, Sam D., 135<br />

Giraudoux, Jean, 81–2<br />

Glass, Philip, 43<br />

Globalism, 123, 134, 136<br />

Globalization, 123, 130–4<br />

Godard, Jean-Luc, 64–7, 72–87<br />

Godelier, Maurice, 152<br />

Goldberg, Rube, 145<br />

Goldschmidt, Victor, 20<br />

Griaule, Marcel, 157<br />

Guattari, Félix (as intercessor), 13, 97<br />

Gypsy music, 118–9<br />

Haecceity, 44<br />

Hardt, Michael, 123, 132 –3<br />

Harrell, Jack, 41<br />

Heidegger, Martin, 7<br />

Heraclitus, 86<br />

Hubac, Pierre, 158–62, 164<br />

Hunter-gatherers, 114–5, 124<br />

Husserl, Edmund, 7, 150<br />

Incorporeal transformation, 20, 22, 46, 142


172<br />

James, William, 94–5, 97, 105–6<br />

Joset, Paul-Ernest, 155–7, 159, 161–2<br />

Joyce, James 19, 41<br />

Kafka, Franz, 3, 17–9, 21–2, 26, 98, 102,<br />

107, 158<br />

Kandinsky, Wassily, 14<br />

Kant, Immanuel, 7–8, 28, 107, 140, 146<br />

Klee, Paul, 14, 91<br />

Kleist, Heinrich von, 42–3<br />

Klossowski, Pierre, 109<br />

Laing, R. D., 162<br />

Laplanche, Jean and Jean-Baptiste Pontalis,<br />

110–1<br />

Laroche, Emmanuel, 125<br />

Lawrence, D. H., 107<br />

Lawrence, T. E., 103–4, 106–8<br />

Leach, Edmund Ronald, 151<br />

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 56, 62<br />

Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 152–5<br />

Levinas, Emmanuel, 7<br />

Lindskog, Birger, 157<br />

Line of continuous variation, 21–2, 25, 31,<br />

37–8<br />

Lowie, Robert H. , 152–4<br />

Luca, Gherasim, 22<br />

Luckert, Karl W., 135<br />

Machinic assemblages, 20–3, 26, 31, 147<br />

Marcus, George E., 145<br />

Massumi, Brian, 138–9, 141, 163<br />

Matthews, Washington, 135<br />

Mayhem (black metal group), 47–8<br />

Melville, Herman 107<br />

Messiaen, Olivier, 29–32, 36, 38, 42<br />

Miéville, Anne-Marie, 65. 73<br />

Miller, Christopher L., 113, 137–65<br />

Minor literature, 18, 98–9, 108, 123<br />

Minority, the minor, 17–27, 31<br />

Monmonier, Mark S., 155<br />

Moynihan, Michael, and Didrik Søderlind,<br />

47–8<br />

Multiplicities, qualitative and quantitative, 126<br />

Music<br />

in cinema, 71–2<br />

and territoriality, 29–31<br />

and violence, 46–8<br />

Musy, François, 79<br />

Deleuze’s <strong>Way</strong><br />

Navajo poetry, 134–6<br />

Negri, Antonio, 123, 132–3<br />

Nemeth, David, 115<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich, 7–9, 11, 70–3, 86–7,<br />

98, 104–5, 107–8, 141, 159<br />

Nomad thought, 139–143, 152, 158<br />

Nomadic distribution, 125–6<br />

Nomadism, 50, 113–21, 123–6, 129–34,<br />

137–8, 159–61<br />

Nomadology, 113, 137–8, 160–2, 164–5<br />

People to come, 14, 97–101, 108<br />

Peripatetics, 115, 124<br />

Perrault, Pierre, 99–101<br />

Plane of consistency, 37–8, 49–50, 146–7,<br />

150<br />

Pound, Ezra, 22<br />

Powers of the false, 14, 99–101, 106<br />

Powrie, Phil, 73, 81<br />

Problems, 59–63, 66, 120<br />

Proust, Marcel 1–3, 53–60, 63, 66, 102,<br />

107–8<br />

Radcliffe, Philip, 85<br />

Refrain, 27–31, 35–6, 48, 51–2<br />

Regime of signs, 145–52, 154–5<br />

Relative global/local absolute, 133–4, 136,<br />

161<br />

Rhizome, 126–7, 130–1, 133<br />

Rhythm, 30, 42<br />

Rich, Jeremy, 157<br />

Rilke, Rainer Maria, 80, 82, 86<br />

Rimbaud, Arthur, 91, 98<br />

Robertson, Roland, 133<br />

Rouch, Jean, 99<br />

Sacher-Masoch, Leopold Ritter von, 102,<br />

107–12, 144, 159<br />

Sade, Marquis de, 109–12, 144<br />

Salo, Matthew T., 115<br />

Salo, Sheila, 115<br />

Samuel, Claude, 30, 36<br />

Schoenberg, Arnold, 32<br />

Schopenhauer, Arthur, 70–1, 86<br />

Schreber, Daniel Paul, 98, 159<br />

Shapiro, Marc, 45<br />

Signs, 53–9, 63, 66, 102, 107<br />

Smith, Daniel W., 7


Smooth space/striated space, 37–8, 50, 114,<br />

118, 127–33, 161<br />

Solomon, Maynard, 89<br />

Spariosu, Mihai, 133<br />

Speed, qualitative versus quantitative, 42–3,<br />

45, 52<br />

Spinoza, Baruch, 7, 11–2, 14, 107<br />

Swimming, 62–4<br />

Szondi, Lipot, 159<br />

Talayesva, Don C., 153, 155<br />

Territory, 27–33<br />

Transversality, 2–3, 5, 98<br />

Transversals, 1–3, 5<br />

Turnbull, Colin M., 114<br />

Tyler, Stephen 142, 144<br />

Vice-diction, 8–10<br />

Index 173<br />

Virtual and actual, 8–9, 11, 21, 37, 49,<br />

55–63, 66, 120–1, 140, 142, 146–7,<br />

158<br />

Wagenbach, Klaus, 19<br />

Waits, Tom, 77–8<br />

Walser, Robert, 38<br />

War machine, 37–8, 50–1, 113, 129–30,<br />

132, 160–1, 163<br />

Weinstein, Deena, 38<br />

Whitman, Walt, 107<br />

Williams, James, 13<br />

Wordsworth, William, 135–6<br />

Wyman, Leland Clifton, 135<br />

Zourabichvili, François, 165

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!