29.05.2013 Views

Open UKLSR Volume 1(2) - Uklsa

Open UKLSR Volume 1(2) - Uklsa

Open UKLSR Volume 1(2) - Uklsa

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

January 2013, <strong>Volume</strong> 1: Issue 2


ISSN 2050-0041 (Print)<br />

ISSN 2050-005X (Online)<br />

THE UNITED KINGDOM LAW STUDENTS’ REVIEW<br />

<strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2 – January 2013<br />

www.uklsa.co.uk/law-review.htm<br />

The <strong>UKLSR</strong> is the flagship publication of the UK Law Students’ Association. We<br />

aim to publish innovative and creative scholarship covering a wide variety of topics of<br />

interest to students and practitioners alike. The Editors wish to thank the UKLSA<br />

Executive Team as well as our university partners for their invaluable support and<br />

assistance. We would also like to acknowledge the support of the Oxford University<br />

Press in the reproduction of this Review.<br />

Please note that the views expressed in this journal are those of the authors and do not<br />

necessarily reflect those of the Editors nor of the UKLSA; we are therefore unable to<br />

accept responsibility for the consequences of any errors contained within the<br />

submissions, however every effort has been made to ensure their accuracy.<br />

© Copyright 2013 by UK Law Students’ Association. All rights reserved.


The UK Law Students’ Association<br />

Patron<br />

The Right Hon the Lord Phillips of Worth Matravers, KG PC<br />

President of the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom<br />

Honorary Board<br />

His Honour Judge Dight<br />

Professor Martin Hunter<br />

Professor David Feldman<br />

Andrew Caldecott QC<br />

Stephen Rubin QC<br />

Professor Paul Raffield<br />

Keith Simpson<br />

Tim Ludbrook<br />

Executive Committee 2012-13<br />

Thomas Innes – President<br />

Jade-Amanda Laporte – Vice-President<br />

Samantha Osborne – Secretary<br />

Nikhil Datta – Treasurer<br />

Theophilus Tawiah – Treasurer<br />

David Murray – Mooting Director<br />

Laura Allsop – Mooting Director<br />

Zeenat Islam – Pro Bono Director<br />

Janina Moutia-Bloom – Schools Director<br />

Amy Carlse – Equalities Director<br />

Helen Hayward – Marketing<br />

Alex Matheson – IT<br />

Fatos Selita – Governor<br />

Vaughan Jacob – Governor<br />

Ranamit Banerjee – Governor


The Editorial Board 2011-12<br />

Editor-in-Chief<br />

Thomas Innes, University of Reading<br />

Editors<br />

Jaclyn Paterson, University of Durham – PhD member<br />

Sarah Stirk, Exeter University – PhD member<br />

Lorraine Schwanberg, King’s College London – LLM member<br />

Awaz Raoof, LSE – LLM member<br />

Kara Cann, College of Law, Bloomsbury – BPTC member<br />

Benjamin Katz, City Law School – GE LLB member<br />

Nivedita Balaji, University of Durham – LLB member<br />

Jon Bardsley, LSE – LLB member<br />

Sophie Jones, Exeter University – LLB member<br />

Robert Mortell, University of Leicester – LLB member<br />

Submissions Manager<br />

Andrew Cebula, University of Durham


Acknowledgements<br />

The UK Law Students’ Association (UKLSA) was founded in February 2008 with the<br />

aim of bringing all UK law students together. The Association aims to provide<br />

students with a common national platform to share and develop their ideas and enrich<br />

their university experience.<br />

The Association would like to take this opportunity to thank some of those who have<br />

made this past twelve months such a success. We would like to thank our Patron and<br />

the Honorary Board for their generous support and encouragement. We would like to<br />

thank His Honour Judge Dight and Anthony Dursi (Recruitment and Outreach<br />

Manager at the Honourable Society of the Inner Temple) for making our Equalities<br />

Event a reality. We would like to thank Lord Sumption, Robert Howe QC, Andrew<br />

Caldecott QC, Tim Ludbrook and Vaughan Jacob for judging the finals of the<br />

mooting competition and Ben Wilson (Head of Communications at The Supreme<br />

Court) for his cooperation in making it a success. We would also like to thank our<br />

Governors, Fatos Selita and Vaughan Jacob, for their constant support throughout the<br />

year.<br />

The UK Law Students’ Review (<strong>UKLSR</strong>) was established with the aim of furthering<br />

the Association’s aims and it is with the greatest pleasure that I welcome the launch of<br />

UKLSA’s flagship publication. It is a student-led academic journal independent of<br />

any single law school, which aims to reflect the high standard of student-created<br />

literature through the provision of a medium to enable the incorporation of these<br />

contributions into the existing body of legal academia. The editorial board is to be<br />

congratulated for its initiative and determination in seeing it to fruition. We would<br />

like to thank the undergraduates and postgraduates students from across the UK who<br />

submitted articles for this issue of the journal – your contributions have played a key<br />

role in the qualitative development of the <strong>UKLSR</strong>.<br />

Ranamit Banerjee<br />

UK Law Students’ Association President 2011-12


CONTENTS<br />

ARTICLES<br />

In#Whose#Best#Interests?#Reconsidering#the#Judicial#Approach#Adopted#in#<br />

Relocation#Disputes.#..........................................................................................................................#1!<br />

Oliver Powell, University of Oxford<br />

#<br />

Google’s#Decision#to#Permit#Competitors#and#Rivals#to#Purchase#Keywords#of#<br />

Trademarks#Acceptable#as#Long#as#it#Does#Not#Cause#Consumer#Brand#Confusion<br />

#..................................................................................................................................................................#13!<br />

Ren-En Lim, Liverpool University<br />

#<br />

The#Human#Rights#Act#Section#2(1)#Taken#into#Account#................................................#23!<br />

Ciju Puthuppally, University of Cambridge<br />

#<br />

Violence#Against#Women#During#Armed#Conflicts#............................................................#39!<br />

Zara Qurashi, University of Nottingham<br />

#<br />

Was#The#Abolition#of#the#Doctrine#of#Doli#Incapax#Necessary?#...................................#50!<br />

Hannah Wishart, Manchester University<br />

#<br />

Battling#Bolam;'Doctors#1,#Patients#0#......................................................................................#64!<br />

Dr Kim Castle, Bangor University<br />

#<br />

CASE NOTES<br />

Al#Skeini#and#Others#v#United#Kingdom#(2011)#53#EHRR#18#........................................#89#<br />

Tom Hamilton, University of Cambridge<br />

Campbell#v#Mirror#Group#Newspapers#Ltd#[2004]#UKHL#22.#The#Relationship#<br />

Between#the#European#Convention#on#Human#Rights#and#Privacy#in#the#Common#<br />

Law#.........................................................................................................................................................#94!<br />

Emily Whittaker, Exeter University<br />

#<br />

Judgment#of#the#European#Court#of#Justice,#13#October#2011,#Pierre'Fabre'Dermo/<br />

Cosmétique'Sas,#C_439/09#Concerning#Another#Restriction#by#Object#on#Internet#<br />

Sales#Ban#...........................................................................................................................................#100!<br />

Dr. iur. Verena Klappstein, London School of Economics


IN WHOSE BEST INTERESTS? RECONSIDERING THE JUDICIAL<br />

APPROACH ADOPTED IN RELOCATION DISPUTES.<br />

Oliver Powell, University of Oxford<br />

I – Introduction<br />

The question of whether a primary carer should be permitted to relocate with the child<br />

outside the United Kingdom against the wishes of a non-resident parent is a fraught<br />

one. 1 These relocation disputes have been described as the ‘San Andreas fault of<br />

children’s law’. 2 Indeed, they raise some of the most complex questions in family law.<br />

This paper seeks to demonstrate that the approach to relocation disputes in England<br />

and Wales does not necessarily produce results that are in the child’s best interests.<br />

This proposition will be developed in three stages. Firstly, it will be evidenced that<br />

decisions from the Court of Appeal (CA) are sending messages to trial courts as to<br />

specific factors they should or should not focus on in relocation disputes. It will be<br />

argued that this approach prevents a careful evaluation of each case, and risks leading<br />

to a conclusion contrary to the child’s best interests. Secondly, an assessment of social<br />

science research from other areas of child law will be undertaken to demonstrate that<br />

what is in the child’s best interests in relocation disputes is complex: this complexity<br />

militating against the CA’s inflexible approach to relocation disputes. Finally, the<br />

approach to relocation disputes in New Zealand, Australia and Canada will be<br />

examined; this enquiry showing that, although each jurisdiction focuses on the child’s<br />

best interests as the main consideration, none approach the question like England and<br />

Wales.<br />

Given these findings the paper will conclude that the current approach to relocation<br />

disputes in England and Wales should be reconsidered, as it risks producing results<br />

that are not in the child’s best interests. In light of this, alternative approaches will be<br />

evaluated, with the Declaration developed at the Conference on International<br />

Relocation in Washington considered the best alternative.<br />

II – Current Law<br />

Applications to relocate with a child from the UK where a residence order is in force<br />

are governed by section 13(1)(b) of the Children Act 1989: the child’s welfare being<br />

the paramount consideration. 3 The now-leading case on this issue is Payne v Payne, 4<br />

involving an appeal by the father against his ex-wife’s permission to relocate with<br />

their child to New Zealand. The mother was the child’s primary carer, the father<br />

enjoying substantial contact. Dismissing the appeal, the CA considered the approach<br />

taken by UK courts to relocation applications outside the jurisdiction, with the<br />

President and Thorpe LJ giving full judgments. However, as George states, it is<br />

1 The primary carer is usually the mother, and the non-resident parent the father. For convenience this<br />

is assumed herein.<br />

2 Richard Chisholm, ‘The Paramount Consideration: Children’s Interests in Family Law’ (2002) 16<br />

AJFL 87, 107<br />

3 Children Act 1989, s 1(1)<br />

4 [2001] EWCA Civ 166 (CA)


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

Thorpe LJ’s approach that has ‘dominated the English approach’ to relocation<br />

disputes. 5<br />

Thorpe LJ explained how relocation cases have been decided consistently on two<br />

principles. Firstly, that the child’s welfare is the paramount consideration. Secondly,<br />

that refusing the primary carer’s application to relocate is likely to impact<br />

detrimentally on the welfare of the child. Therefore, relocation should be permitted<br />

unless contrary to the child’s welfare. 6 Bearing these principles in mind, Thorpe LJ<br />

laid out a ‘discipline’ for judges to apply in relocation cases to prevent ‘too<br />

perfunctory an investigation’ stemming from an assumption that ‘the mother’s<br />

proposals are necessarily compatible with the child’s welfare.’ 7<br />

III – Criticism<br />

Payne has been strongly criticized. Hayes argues that Thorpe LJ’s ‘discipline’<br />

imposes ‘a gloss on the welfare principle’ 8 causing the courts to ‘treat the impact of<br />

his ruling on the mother as the most significant consideration’. 9 Hayes stresses the<br />

need to allow judges to approach the question with an open mind considering ‘all of<br />

the factors in the welfare checklist’ to reach a conclusion in the child’s best<br />

interests. 10 Perry questions whether Payne truly puts the child’s interests as the<br />

paramount consideration. 11 Furthermore, in F v M Mostyn J states that relocation<br />

disputes, with their heavy emphasis on the emotional reaction of the primary carer,<br />

put ‘an illegitimate gloss on the purity of the paramountcy principle’. 12 Reflecting on<br />

this, we turn to consider the three apparent messages that the CA are sending to trial<br />

courts, and whether they are conducive to promoting the child’s best interests.<br />

III(a) – The mother’s wishes<br />

Given the mother-child bond of love, it seems uncontroversial to state that a mother’s<br />

wish to relocate will often correlate with the child’s best interests. However, it is<br />

submitted that the approach advocated in Payne has led the CA to focus unduly on the<br />

mother’s wish to relocate, sending messages to trial courts to do the same and<br />

blinding them to a full and proper assessment of the child’s welfare. This concern is<br />

evident in a number of cases.<br />

In Re H (A Child) Wilson LJ refused the father’s appeal, listing ten factors supporting<br />

the mother’s wish to relocate, stating that it was ‘natural’ that ‘she would wish to<br />

5 Robert George, ‘Reassessing Relocation: A Comparative Analysis of Legal Approaches to Disputes<br />

Over Family Migration After Parental Separation in England and New Zealand’ (DPhil thesis,<br />

University of Oxford 2010) 98<br />

6 Payne (n 4) [26]<br />

7 Ibid, [40]-[41]<br />

8 Mary Hayes, ‘Relocation cases: is the Court of Appeal applying the correct principles?’ [2006] CFLQ<br />

351, 359<br />

9 Ibid, 360<br />

10 Ibid, 351<br />

11 Alison Perry, ‘Case Commentary: Leave To Remove Children From The Jurisdiction’ [2001] CFLQ<br />

455<br />

12 [2010] EWHC 1346 (Fam) [8]<br />

2


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

return home’ to her native country. 13 No comparative list is developed for the father.<br />

This signals to trial courts to focus on the mother’s wishes. Equally concerning is the<br />

case of Re B (Children), Re S (Child) 14 where Thorpe LJ allowed the mother’s appeal<br />

to relocate, endorsing her statements that Australia is ‘where my future well-being<br />

will be. I feel I will be happy there’. 15 The language is centred on her well-being and<br />

wishes, not the child’s. The approval of such comments is concerning: nowhere is the<br />

wish to relocate expressed in terms of the child’s well-being. This sends powerful<br />

signals to trial courts that the mother’s wishes are of paramount concern not the<br />

child’s. Furthermore, in Re B (Children) Thorpe LJ criticized the trial judge for<br />

placing significance on a hypothetical question that the mother could not answer<br />

concerning her backup plans if the children did not settle after relocating. 16 The<br />

message sent to trial courts is clear; focus on the mother’s wishes and do not ‘stresstest’<br />

them. This is concerning given the question relates directly to the child’s welfare.<br />

The mother’s wishes may correlate with the child’s best interests, however the<br />

messages from the CA distort and narrow the enquiry by placing emphasis on<br />

acceding to them. This risks blinding trial courts to a proper enquiry of what is in the<br />

child’s best interests. Interrelated to the mother’s wish to relocate is the impact of<br />

having those wishes refused. This is a prominent factor in relocation cases that<br />

requires analysis.<br />

III(a)(1) – Impact of refusal<br />

The impact of refusing a mother’s proposal to relocate, and the consequent impact on<br />

the child’s welfare, has ‘consistently been stressed as the key factor’ by the CA in<br />

relocation disputes; 17 unsurprising given judicial utterances that this is the ‘major<br />

question’. 18 Undoubtedly, the mother’s devastation flowing from refusal may impact<br />

on the child’s well-being. However, this unwavering message from the CA has the<br />

potential to blind trial courts’ assessment of what may actually be in the child’s best<br />

interests. This concern relates particularly to the question of the mother’s ability to<br />

cope with the refusal - something the current approach of the CA arguably overlooks.<br />

In Re W (Leave to Remove), Thorpe LJ criticized all parties for not focusing on the<br />

impact of refusal on the mother. 19 However, as stated, the impact on the mother and<br />

consequent impact on the child will depend on the mother’s robustness. Crucially in<br />

Re W the trial judge, having assessed the mother in the witness box, concluded that<br />

she had ‘an exceptionally strong personality’; 20 implying she would cope with refusal<br />

and consequently the impact on the child would be less significant. Thorpe LJ’s<br />

disregard for this finding ignores the trial court’s careful assessment and encourages<br />

other trial courts to follow suit. This risks preventing a proper analysis of the degree<br />

13 [2010] EWCA Civ 915 (CA) [29]<br />

14 [2003] EWCA Civ 1149 (CA)<br />

15 Ibid, [22]<br />

16 [2004] EWCA 956 (CA) [13]<br />

17 George (n 5) 98<br />

18 Re G (Removal from Jurisdiction) [2005] EWCA Civ 170 (CA) [19]<br />

19 [2008] EWCA Civ 538 (CA) [20]<br />

20 Ibid, [19]<br />

3


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

to which the child’s welfare will actually be impacted by the mother’s reaction to<br />

refusal. Given the importance of this factor to the court’s decision, a careful<br />

assessment free from generalizations is vital in reaching a decision in the child’s best<br />

interests. Furthermore, it sends the message to trial courts that they must conclude that<br />

the mother has more than an ‘exceptionally strong personality’ otherwise their<br />

decision is likely to be appealed, potentially altering their decision making process.<br />

III(a)(2) – The non-resident parent<br />

Coupled to the messages discussed, the CA also appear to pay little attention to the<br />

father-child bond. As Wall LJ states in Re D (Children), there is a ‘perfectly<br />

respectable argument’ that Payne ‘ignores or relegates the harm done to children by a<br />

permanent breach of the relationship which children have with the left behind<br />

parent’. 21 Indeed, in Re H, having cited ten reasons to permit relocation, Wilson LJ<br />

offers one line in recognition of the excellent father-child relationship, and the ‘grave<br />

truncation’ in contact that would result from the move. 22 Context is important. One<br />

line on the father-child relationship in the context of a list of factors in favour of<br />

allowing relocation sends a clear message that although relevant, the father-child<br />

bond is less important. Furthermore, in Re B & Re S there is no reference to the<br />

father-child relationship whatsoever. 23<br />

Conversely, where the trial judge relies upon the reduction of father-child contact as a<br />

reason for refusal, the CA subject that decision to forensic analysis, unpicking the<br />

reasoning: Re S (Children). 24 This approach sends a strong message to trial courts that<br />

they must have particularly good reasons to refuse an application on this ground.<br />

The CA’s approach to the father-child bond sends messages to trial courts to give<br />

little weight to this factor. This contrasts with the weight accorded to the mother’s<br />

wishes and the impact of refusal on her. Undoubtedly, these cases may have been<br />

rightly decided, but the blanket messages that emanate from the CA risk instructing<br />

trial courts as to the approach to take in every case, distorting a careful assessment in<br />

these finely balanced, fact sensitive cases. This risks producing results contrary to the<br />

child’s best interests. Given these strong messages favouring the mother’s application<br />

to relocate, one would expect cogent evidence that relocation is generally in the<br />

child’s best interests. The picture, however, is not so clear.<br />

IV – Social Science Research<br />

The paucity of research on relocation disputes is alarming. Freeman states, ‘we don’t<br />

know’ whether relocation is in the child’s best interests. 25 Geldof disagrees, arguing<br />

that empirical evidence shows that the current ‘pro-relocation’ stance is ‘wholly<br />

destructive to a child and its family’. 26 However, Geldof’s proposition rests upon<br />

research relating to shared residence and contact where, as Herring and Taylor<br />

21 [2010] EWCA Civ 50, [33]<br />

22 Re H (n 13) [30]<br />

23 Re B, Re S (n 14)<br />

24 [2004] EWCA Civ 1724 (CA) [10-16]<br />

25 Marilyn Freeman, ‘Relocation and the Child’s Best Interests’ [2010] IFL 247, 255<br />

26 Michael Robinson, ‘Family Law: Relocation The Case for Reform’ (2011) 2<br />

4


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

highlight, there is ‘so little agreement between researchers’. 27 Nevertheless, cautious<br />

conclusions can be extracted from residence and contact research that may aid in<br />

answering whether the current approach to relocation disputes is in the child’s best<br />

interests. Research regarding the impact on the child’s welfare from a truncation of<br />

contact with the non-resident parent, and the impact on the mother of having to<br />

facilitate contact with the father after a court dispute, are both particularly relevant.<br />

IV(a) – Residence and contact research<br />

As Herring states, the dominant view in England and Wales ‘is that contact between a<br />

child and both parents is in general beneficial.’ 28 In the context of joint residence, the<br />

government have stressed that ‘children whose fathers have been actively involved in<br />

their lives experience better outcomes’. 29 Furthermore, Gilmore highlights research<br />

studies that applaud the merits of shared residence for child welfare. 30 These findings<br />

contrast with the fleeting consideration given to the father-child relationship in<br />

relocation disputes. However research from the USA appears to conclude that contact<br />

frequency is ‘not a good predictor of children’s well-being’; 31 this seemingly<br />

supporting the mother’s application to relocate. Nevertheless, Gilmore’s review of<br />

contact research indicates that ‘it is not contact per se but the nature and quality of<br />

contact that are important to children’s adjustment’ 32 and as Trinder states, ‘a certain<br />

amount of time [together] will be needed to enable a quality relationship to<br />

develop’. 33 This led to a position where fathers with high frequency contact were<br />

likely to have higher-quality relationships with their child. 34 These findings militate<br />

against the messages from the CA to ‘gloss over’ the father’s importance, as the<br />

father-child relationship may be very important to children’s welfare.<br />

This conclusion cannot be divorced from the influence that the inter-parental<br />

relationship has on contact quality. Relocation disputes often lead to parental<br />

animosity. Refusal of the mother’s application is unlikely to ease this animosity. As<br />

Gilmore states, ‘when parents are antagonistic to one another frequent visitation may<br />

do more harm than good.’ 35 These findings could prove detrimental to any benefit the<br />

child gets from maintaining contact with the father. Similar conclusions are drawn in<br />

shared residence research. 36 Indeed, Harris-Short states that the ‘tensions and<br />

complexities of a joint residence regime….may actually increase rather than decrease<br />

hostility between the parents.’ 37<br />

27 Jonathan Herring and Rachel Taylor, ‘Relocating relocation’, [2006] CFLQ 517, 521<br />

28 Jonathan Herring, Family Law, (4 th Edition, OUP 2008) 537<br />

29 Sonia Harris-Short and Joanna Miles, Family Law Text, Cases, and Materials (OUP 2007) 839<br />

30 Stephen Gilmore, ‘Contact/shared residence and child well-being: research evidence and its<br />

implications for legal decision-making’ [2006] JLPF 344, 356-357<br />

31 Ibid, 348<br />

32 Ibid, 358<br />

33 Liz Trinder, ‘Shared residence: a review of recent research evidence’ [2010] CFLQ 475, 486<br />

34 Gilmore (n 30)<br />

35 Ibid, 351<br />

36 Trinder (n 33)<br />

37 Harris-Short (n 29) 845<br />

5


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

IV(b) – Social science research conclusions<br />

Assessing the research as a whole, two cautious conclusions relevant in relocation<br />

disputes can be reached. Firstly, it is the quality of contact with the father that is<br />

important for the child’s welfare: that quality being engendered through regular<br />

contact. Against this is the potential for a hostile inter-parental relationship stemming<br />

from refusing relocation, and the effect this may have on the child’s welfare.<br />

Nevertheless, one clear conclusion is that the overall picture shows ‘a complex<br />

interaction of family dynamics’. 38 This complexity does not advocate<br />

generalizations. 39 It is submitted that the inflexible messages from the CA to trial<br />

courts fail to account for this complexity, and risk producing a judicial atmosphere<br />

supportive of generalizations in cases where acute complexities must be balanced and<br />

evaluated in order to reach a conclusion in the child’s best interests.<br />

V – Relocation in Other Jurisdictions<br />

In asking whether the approach to relocation disputes in England and Wales produces<br />

decisions in the child’s best interests, an analysis of the approach taken to relocation<br />

in other common law jurisdictions is beneficial. New Zealand, Australia and Canada<br />

put the child’s best interests at the centre of the enquiry yet, as Boshier states, ‘there<br />

are some significant differences’ between the approaches they take to answering the<br />

question compared to England and Wales. 40<br />

V(a) – New Zealand<br />

Significantly, in D v S the New Zealand Court of Appeal rejected the approach in<br />

Payne, preferring an all-factor child centred approach, 41 with no a priori assumptions<br />

regarding the impact of refusal. 42 George suggests two trends are emerging in New<br />

Zealand relocation disputes. Firstly, that the primary carer’s well-being is increasingly<br />

given little presumptive weight, and secondly that importance is given to children<br />

having relationships with both parents; 43 trends that stand in stark contrast to those<br />

developed in England and Wales.<br />

Recent New Zealand High Court decisions appear to corroborate George’s<br />

conclusions. In L v B, the court considered that relocation should be refused as<br />

insufficient consideration had been given to the need for both parents’ involvement in<br />

the child’s life and the need to preserve and strengthen family relationships. 44<br />

Similarly, in B v B the court criticized the first instance decision for not giving proper<br />

weight to the child’s interests in having a relationship with his father. 45 In LH v PH<br />

the mother’s belief that she would be devastated by a refusal to relocate was given<br />

38 Gilmore (n 30) 358<br />

39 Ibid, 358–359<br />

40 Peter Boshier, ‘Have Judges Been Missing the Point and Allowing Relocation Too Readily?’ [2010]<br />

IFL 311, 312<br />

41 [2002] NZFLR 116 (CA) [46]-[47]<br />

42 Ibid, [32]-[33]<br />

43 George (n 5) 123<br />

44 [2010] NZHC 53, [104]<br />

45 [2008] NZHC 664, [59]<br />

6


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

little consideration. 46 Irrefutably, the New Zealand approach to relocation disputes<br />

seems distinct from the approach adopted in England and Wales.<br />

V(b) – Australia<br />

The legislative framework governing relocation disputes in Australia has recently<br />

changed. Nevertheless, the child’s best interests remain paramount. Easteal and<br />

Harkins state that the ‘changes give greater emphasis to the child’s right to have a<br />

relationship with both parents’. 47 Furthermore, the new shared care provisions appear<br />

to promote a strong parent-child relationship. Overall, George states that Australia<br />

adopts an all-factor approach, with the statutory provisions militating against<br />

relocation. 48<br />

Recent decisions of the Australian Court of Appeal highlight a different approach to<br />

that adopted in England and Wales. Indeed, the lack of regard for the impact of<br />

refusal on the mother is noteworthy. As Easteal and Harkins state, references to this<br />

are made ‘indirectly and as part of a broader enquiry’: 49 scepticism of placing weight<br />

on this consideration is seen in Taylor & Barker where it was stressed that ‘expert<br />

opinion based on observation and fact rather than conjecture’ are needed to permit<br />

consideration of this factor as relevant. 50 Indeed, fewer cases are mentioning the<br />

mother’s happiness at all. 51<br />

What is considered important is the time a child spends with each parent and the role<br />

they play in the child’s life: Winter & Winter. 52 Additionally, the importance of a<br />

‘meaningful relationship’ with both parents is stressed: 53 though what constitutes a<br />

‘meaningful relationship’ has been broadly interpreted. 54 As with New Zealand, what<br />

emerges in relation to Australia’s approach to relocation disputes is quite distinct<br />

from that of England and Wales.<br />

V(c) – Canada<br />

As Chamberland indicates, the law on relocation in Canada has oscillated between<br />

various approaches, 55 with it currently being ‘extremely flexible’. 56 The leading case<br />

is Gordon v Goertz which places the best interests of the child as the ultimate<br />

question. 57 An ‘individualized assessment’ is required with no presumptive weight<br />

46 [2007] NZHC 187, [41]<br />

47 Patricia Easteal and Kate Harkins, ‘Are we there yet? An analysis of relocation judgments in light of<br />

changes to the Family Law Act’ [2008] AJFL 259, 262<br />

48 George (n 5) 20<br />

49 Easteal (n 47) 272<br />

50 [2007] FamCA 1246 [128]<br />

51 Easteal (n 47) 272<br />

52 [2008] FamCAFC 159 [81]<br />

53 McCall & Clark [2009] FamCAFC 92 [50]<br />

54 Easteal (n 47) 268<br />

55 Jacques Chamberland, ‘The Canadian Law of Parental Relocation’ [2010] IFL 17, 17<br />

56 Ibid, 23<br />

57 [1996] 2 SCR 27 [50]<br />

7


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

given to any factor: though the views of the custodial parent are given serious<br />

consideration. 58<br />

Ontario and British Columbia case law reach some interesting conclusions. In Elliot v<br />

Turcotte the court warned of permitting relocation where the father had good contact<br />

with the child. 59 Karpodinis v Kantos also stressed that maximum contact with both<br />

parents was generally in the best interests of the child. 60 Furthermore, in Falvai v<br />

Falvai, the need to maintain the father-child relationship was seen as a ‘determining<br />

factor’. 61 Little significance is placed on the impact of refusal though it has been<br />

recognized as a factor which may be relevant: Bjornson v Creighton. 62 Unlike in<br />

England and Wales, Canadian cases emphasize the disruption to the child of<br />

relocation: Young v Young. 63<br />

V(d) – Conclusions<br />

Each jurisdiction addresses the question of the child’s best interests differently in<br />

relocation disputes. Nevertheless, two themes emerge. Firstly, less weight is given to<br />

the impact of refusal on the mother in comparison to the approach in Payne. Secondly,<br />

the desire to promote a child’s relationship with both parents appears – at least in New<br />

Zealand and Australia – to be gathering momentum. These disparate approaches are<br />

perhaps due to the lack of evidence to rest principles for deciding these disputes upon.<br />

However, it is submitted that this comparative analysis adds weight to the proposition<br />

that the current approach in England and Wales is not necessarily right and risks<br />

failing to promote the child’s best interests.<br />

VI – Time for Change?<br />

In light of the analysis above, the proposition for change can be simply put. The<br />

messages sent from the CA to the trial courts instruct them to approach the relocation<br />

enquiry in a particular manner: focusing on the mother’s wishes and the impact of<br />

refusal, whilst ignoring the importance of the father. This distorts the welfare enquiry,<br />

potentially producing results contrary to the child’s best interests, as general messages<br />

as to how to approach a case are being forced upon disputes with unique facts. The<br />

complexity of the enquiry is highlighted by the social science research, which<br />

underlines the importance of a careful examination of the facts free from<br />

generalizations. Finally, the approaches in other jurisdictions value a broad ‘all-factor’<br />

enquiry, with no tendency to promote the mother’s wishes or the impact of refusal<br />

above other factors, often stressing the importance of both parents to the child’s<br />

welfare. These three elements together provide a strong argument in favour of<br />

departing from Payne. The judicial approach to relocation disputes must therefore be<br />

reconsidered.<br />

58 Ibid, [48]<br />

59 [2009] ONCA 240 [18]<br />

60 [2006] BCCA 272 [19]-[20]<br />

61 [2008] BCCA 503 [16]<br />

62 [2002] OJ No 4634 [28]<br />

63 [2003] ONCA 3320 [28]<br />

8


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

VII – Reconsidering Relocation<br />

Beneath the approach enunciated in Payne rests a laudable objective: the paramountcy<br />

of the child’s welfare. Despite its apparent focus on this virtuous goal, the welfare<br />

principle has been subject to criticism that must be borne in mind when considering<br />

alternatives. The most prominent in the context of relocation disputes is the ‘lack of<br />

transparency’ criticism. As Reece states, the welfare principle permits the untested<br />

judicial ideology to ‘exert an influence from behind the smokescreen of the<br />

paramountcy principle’. 64 In the context of relocation disputes the concern is surely<br />

that the courts are ‘easily persuaded that the child is better cared for by the mother<br />

than by the father.’ 65 Bearing this criticism in mind, alternatives can be considered.<br />

VII(a) – A rights-based approach<br />

Harris-Short states that for many the introduction of the Human Rights Act 1998<br />

‘promised long overdue changes in the judiciary’s approach to legal disputes<br />

concerning the family’. 66 Flowing from this, there are two strong arguments that can<br />

be made for a rights-based approach to relocation disputes. Firstly, the welfare<br />

principle is ‘incompatible with the demands of Article 8’ of the European Convention<br />

on Human Rights, 67 and must be reinterpreted to take account of individual’s rights. 68<br />

However, the reality is that the judiciary has not done this. 69 Harris-Short laments the<br />

fact that the domestic courts, in the private law context, have ‘generally failed to<br />

engage’ with the issue. 70<br />

Secondly, the rights-based approach appeals to reason. Herring and Taylor advance a<br />

cogent three-step rights-based approach to relocation disputes. 71 Firstly, each person’s<br />

rights should be individually weighed. Secondly, the justification for interference with<br />

the right considered, and the proportionality test applied. Thirdly, an ‘ultimate<br />

balancing exercise’ should be undertaken; the balancing exercise being workable by<br />

‘focusing on the values that underlie the right’. 72 In the context of relocation, ‘the<br />

court should consider which interference will constitute a greater blight on the vision<br />

of the good life that each had’ (or the child may have): 73 the question being ‘how far<br />

the court’s decision will interfere with that vision’. 74 This approach Herring and<br />

Taylor argue, will normally produce results similar to the current approach. However,<br />

64 Helen Reece, ‘The Paramountcy Principle. Consensus or Construct?’ in Sonia Harris-Short and<br />

Joanna Miles (eds), Family Law Text, Cases and Materials (OUP 2007) 598<br />

65 Herring (n 28) 512<br />

66 Sonia Harris-Short, ‘Family law and the Human Rights Act 1998: judicial restraint or revolution’<br />

[2005] CFLQ 329, 329<br />

67 Shazia Choudhry and Helen Fenwick, ‘Taking the rights of parents and children seriously:<br />

confronting the welfare principle under the Human Rights Act’ [2005] OJLS 453, 479<br />

68 Harris-Short (n 66) 344<br />

69 Choudhry (n 67) 480<br />

70 Harris-Short (n 66) 347<br />

71 Herring Taylor (n 27)<br />

72 Ibid, 526<br />

73 Ibid, 527<br />

74 Ibid, 527<br />

9


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

they believe it will make a difference in some cases and provide a more transparent<br />

reasoning process. 75 Conversely, Choudhry and Fenwick believe a rights-based<br />

approach will produce different results. 76<br />

This approach is persuasive. Nevertheless, the principal reason for not fully<br />

advocating a rights-based approach in this paper is that ‘the welfare principle sends an<br />

important symbolic message. It recognizes the value, the importance and the<br />

vulnerability of children’. 77 Children are vulnerable and the law should protect them.<br />

This is a moral argument upon which reasonable opinions can differ. However, ‘if the<br />

welfare principle does anything to focus the minds of the parents on the child’s<br />

welfare rather than their own rights then it has great value’. 78 Furthermore, the<br />

potential for a ‘misuse of rights’ under a rights-based approach is concerning. As<br />

Herring and Taylor state, it may lead adults to pursue their own agenda. 79 It is hard to<br />

forget the comments of the mother in Re B, Re S that Australia is ‘where my future<br />

well-being will be. I feel I will be happy there’. 80 A rights-based approach will<br />

arguably promote these selfish statements, taking the focus off the child.<br />

Notwithstanding these concerns, it is considered that greater regard must be had for<br />

the 1998 Act. Therefore, a balance between the welfare principle and a rights-based<br />

approach is required. This, it is submitted, is found in the Washington Declaration.<br />

VIII – The Washington Declaration<br />

The Conference on International Relocation in Washington developed a Declaration<br />

that has been called an ‘interesting, and potentially momentous, development’. 81 It is<br />

submitted that with two amendments, this Declaration provides the best framework<br />

for resolution of relocation disputes.<br />

VIII(a) – The Declaration explained<br />

Point three of the Declaration states that the best interests of the child should be the<br />

paramount (primary) consideration. 82 Point four provides a non-exhaustive list of<br />

thirteen factors for the judge to consider. Noteworthy is the omission of any explicit<br />

reference to the impact of refusal on the primary carer, the recognition given to the<br />

role that each parent and their families have played in the child’s life and the nature of<br />

the inter-parental relationship.<br />

VIII(b) – Discussion<br />

Four issues arise from the Declaration that require discussion. Firstly, it is apparent<br />

from Point three that the child remains the centre of the enquiry. As argued, this is<br />

considered morally correct. However, the Declaration offers a choice between<br />

75 Ibid, 527<br />

76 Choudhry (n 67) 491<br />

77 Jonathan Herring, ‘Farewell Welfare?’ [2005] JSWFL 159, 168<br />

78 Ibid, 168<br />

79 Herring (n 27) 530<br />

80 Re B, Re S (n 14)<br />

81 F v M (n 12) [10]<br />

82 Washington Declaration on International Family Relocation [2010]<br />

10


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

‘paramount’ and ‘primary’ when considering the child’s best interests. It is submitted<br />

that the child’s best interests should be the ‘primary’ consideration; thus accounting<br />

for the 1998 Act. Indeed, this is one re-interpretation of ‘paramount’ suggested as<br />

possibly compatible with the 1998 Act. 83 This alteration would permit greater<br />

recognition of the parent’s rights and interests pursuant to the demands of the rightsbased<br />

era, whilst maintaining the focus on the child.<br />

Secondly, Point three of the Declaration expressly rejects any presumption for or<br />

against relocation. Although Payne similarly rejects a presumption in favour of<br />

relocation, 84 it is hard to argue in light of the academic critique and the analysis above<br />

that the current approach to relocation is not, at the very least, tendentious: a mother’s<br />

reasonable proposals to relocate normally being granted. 85 This provision would press<br />

the judicial ‘reset button’ and help restore the need, as Hayes states, for justice to be<br />

even-handed. 86 This is coupled with express recognition in Point three that the weight<br />

to be given to any one factor will vary from case to case.<br />

Thirdly, the thirteen criteria provided to aid judges in their assessment of the case will<br />

produce a more transparent reasoning process, soothing the transparency criticism that<br />

attends the welfare principle. 87<br />

Fourthly, the impact of refusal on the mother is only implicitly recognized in factor<br />

(viii) of Point four of the Declaration. Despite concerns raised of an over-emphasis on<br />

this factor, it is nevertheless considered that the impact of refusal should have<br />

independent recognition. Throughout this paper, it has been recognized that in certain<br />

cases, this factor may be significant. However, by placing it equally among the other<br />

thirteen factors, it would sit as a consideration in the enquiry not the consideration,<br />

permitting the judge to place emphasis on it if the facts suggest it is appropriate. It is<br />

for these four reasons that the Declaration is considered the best judicial approach to<br />

“external” relocation disputes in England and Wales.<br />

IX – Conclusion<br />

Given the regularity with which the judiciary pronounce how difficult relocation<br />

disputes are, it would be easy – almost understandable - to conclude that there is no<br />

answer and that searching for a better solution is hopeless. But perseverance is<br />

necessary. This paper has sought to illustrate that the current approach to relocation<br />

disputes risks producing results that are not in the child’s best interests. This has been<br />

demonstrated through a three-stage process: these three-stages combining to produce<br />

an argument in favour of reconsidering the approach to relocation.<br />

In light of this, alternative approaches have been considered. Reconsidering the<br />

judicial approach is far from straightforward. These cases are frighteningly complex -<br />

any alternative professing a simple answer should be viewed with caution.<br />

Furthermore, the paucity of research on relocation casts doubt on any suggested<br />

alternative because we know so little about the consequences of these decisions.<br />

83 Harris-Short (n 29) 616<br />

84 Payne (n 4) [40]<br />

85 Herring (n 28) 534<br />

86 Hayes (n 8) 360<br />

87 Text to (n 64)<br />

11


Reconsidering the Judicial Approach Adopted in Relocation Disputes<br />

Nevertheless, it is believed that the approach encompassed in the Washington<br />

Declaration offers a guiding light for the resolution of these disputes: a light that<br />

focuses on the best interests of the child whilst identifying the reality of the rightsbased<br />

era. It provides the best opportunity to produce a result in the child’s best<br />

interests. Perhaps in these most tragic and complex disputes, this is all that can be<br />

hoped for.<br />

12


GOOGLE’S DECISION TO PERMIT COMPETITORS AND RIVALS TO<br />

PURCHASE KEYWORDS OF TRADEMARKS ACCEPTABLE AS LONG AS<br />

IT DOES NOT CAUSE CONSUMER BRAND CONFUSION<br />

Ren-En Lim, Liverpool University<br />

I – Introduction<br />

Google is the world’s most widely-used search engine with an audience share of over<br />

80% of global internet users. It is therefore not surprising that advertisers have<br />

recognised Google’s tremendous potential to reach out to new audiences both<br />

nationally and internationally, and Google has cleverly exploited this quality by<br />

launching its “AdWords” service. Proponents of “AdWords” laud it as a bastion for<br />

free competition and freedom of speech; Opponents (amongst them trademark<br />

owners), however, deride Google AdWords for infringing trademarks (and thereby<br />

undermining the incentive for producers to innovate), and for not recognising that the<br />

protection of a trademark’s ‘indicating origin, advertising, communication and<br />

innovation’ functions may actually be helpful in assisting producers to expand into<br />

new markets and in aiding consumers confronted with a wider range of choices. It is<br />

this inherent tension which the courts (both UK and ECJ) face when deciding cases<br />

involving AdWords. In this paper, it will be argued that the discussing statement is<br />

accurate as a likelihood of confusion is necessary before infringement actions can be<br />

brought under s.10(2) of the Trademarks Act 1994 (“TMA”). Moreover, although<br />

courts have recognised in principle that confusion is presumed under s.10(1) and that<br />

infringement of the section may occur if there is misuse of the trademark that either<br />

its indicating origin, advertising or investment functions are undermined, this is<br />

however qualified by the deliberate setting of a high evidentiary threshold for<br />

infringement of such functions to be found. With regards to s.10(3), a similar point<br />

will be made: confusion is not necessary for an action to be brought under the section,<br />

but there is also a high evidentiary threshold to be fulfilled before trademark<br />

proprietors succeed in an infringement action under it. This therefore gives rise to a<br />

plausible assertion that as long as there is no likelihood of confusion, there is little for<br />

rival advertisers who purchase keywords of their competitor’s trademark to be<br />

worried about from a legal copyright infringement perspective.<br />

I(a) – What is Google AdWords?<br />

At its simplest, Google AdWords manipulates search results to artificially prioritise<br />

an advertiser’s website over other possible results. 1 An advertiser purchases the<br />

keywords with which he wants his website and AdWords advertisements to be<br />

associated, which will link his advertisement to the purchased keywords. 2 When<br />

someone uses a Google program that runs a search, his advertisement will appear<br />

alongside other search results. The advertiser is able to decide on a maximum billing<br />

rate, which is one of two factors Google use to determine where on the search result<br />

pages the advertisement will appear. 3 The value of AdWords thus lies in the fact that<br />

1 Ashley Tan, ‘Google AdWords: Trademark Infringer or Trade Liberalizer?’ (2010) 16 Mich.<br />

Telecomm Tech L Rev, 473.<br />

2 ibid.<br />

3 The other factor being the “Quality Score” of the advertisement, a multi-criteria scoring system that<br />

attempts to objectively evaluate how relevant – or how effective – an advertisement is to the search<br />

results with which it has been associated in the past.


14<br />

The Legality of Google AdWords<br />

Google allows its keyword-linked advertisements to circumvent Google’s usual page<br />

ranking system for non-sponsored links. 4 Since the advertisements appear beside<br />

search results that have been subjected to the normal page ranking algorithms and<br />

often do not explicitly indicate that they are sponsored links, Google users may be<br />

misled to assume that the advertisements are the most relevant results. 5 The<br />

advertisement thus trades on Google’s reputation for delivering the most appropriate<br />

search results to entice users to click on them, while making a potential global<br />

advertising audience available at very low financial and technical cost. 6<br />

I(b) – Google’s policy towards the use of its AdWords service<br />

Pertaining to Google’s new trademark policy in the UK towards AdWords, third<br />

parties will be able to bid and use competitors’ marks as AdWords keywords so as to<br />

direct traffic to their own websites, providing there are no risks of confusion or unfair<br />

competition. 7 This means that Google will continue to investigate complaints about<br />

trademarks in advertising but will no longer complain about trademarks used as<br />

keywords.<br />

I(c) – The relationship between EU law and UK law<br />

Trademark law is only partially harmonised at the EU level, and the application of<br />

Union law (upon a ruling of the European Court of Justice (“ECJ”)) remains in the<br />

hands of the national courts of the EU Member States. ECJ Cases will be referred to<br />

in this paper as and when necessary as it lays down the general framework of how<br />

s.10(1), s.10(2) and s.10(3) of the TMA is to be applied by the UK Courts.<br />

II – The position under UK Law<br />

There are four ways in which a party can be found liable for trademark infringement<br />

in the UK. The first three ways are derived from s.10 of the TMA whilst the fourth is<br />

a civil action in Tort. Each will be discussed in detail and considered in relation to the<br />

potential liability of Google AdWords under them.<br />

II(a) – Section 10(2) – Likelihood of Confusion; Likelihood of Liability<br />

Section 10(2) refers explicitly to the likelihood of ‘brand consumer confusion’. The<br />

precise meaning of confusion is not in question; on the other hand, the question of<br />

how confusion is to be assessed under s.10(2) has been addressed by the courts. In the<br />

UK case of Och-Ziff 8 , the High Court noted that the principles applying to<br />

infringement under the ‘registration context’ was also applicable to that under the<br />

‘infringement context’ (of which s.10(2) deals with). 9 In so doing, the High Court<br />

4 Supra Note 1.<br />

5 ibid.<br />

6 ibid.<br />

7 Amelie Labbe-Thompson, ‘Google’s revised AdWords policy causes industrial divide’ (2010) E.C.L.<br />

&P 12(8).<br />

8 [2010] EWHC 2599.<br />

9 The only difference being that confusion under the infringement context only requires consideration<br />

of the use that has actually been made of the sign in context, while confusion under the registration<br />

context requires consideration of notional fair use of the mark applied for.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

summarised what they thought to be the ECJ’s overall approach towards confusion<br />

under s.10(2) for both word and composite marks, with reference to the cases of<br />

Portakabin v Primakabin 10 and O2 v Hutchinson 11 . As this paper is dealing with<br />

Google AdWords, only the relevant parts of the guidance dealing with word marks<br />

will be addressed.<br />

From the outset, the likelihood of confusion must be appreciated globally. There must<br />

be confusion to the average consumer of the goods or services in question, who is<br />

deemed to be reasonably well-informed, circumspect and observant, but who rarely<br />

has the chance to make direct comparisons between marks and must instead rely upon<br />

the imperfect picture of them he has kept in his mind. Moreover, it should be noted<br />

that the average consumer normally perceives a mark as a whole and does not analyse<br />

its various details. 12 Additionally, a lesser degree of similarity between the marks may<br />

be offset by a greater degree of similarity between the goods and vice versa. 13 As for<br />

highly distinctive trademarks, the courts have also recognised that there is a greater<br />

likelihood of confusion. This is, however, balanced against the recognition by the<br />

courts that mere association, in the sense that the later mark brings the earlier mark to<br />

mind, is not sufficient to constitute confusion for the purposes of s.10(2). In other<br />

words, the reputation of a trademark does not provide grounds for presuming a<br />

likelihood of confusion simply because of a likelihood of association in the strict<br />

sense. Lastly if the association between the marks causes the public to wrongly<br />

believe that the respective goods or services come from the same or economically<br />

linked undertakings, then it would lead to a finding of confusion under s.10(2).<br />

It should be noted that although the above guidance elaborates on the factors and<br />

refines and articulates the process of analysis to which those factors are subjected, the<br />

High Court in Lewis v Client Connection 14 cited with approval Jacob LJ’s earlier<br />

observation in Reed v Reed 15 to the effect that whichever approach one uses, one is<br />

essentially taking a holistic view as to whether there is significant consumer<br />

confusion. It is therefore a value judgment to be drawn from all the circumstances,<br />

and as such, further conceptual over-elaboration may tend to obscure (rather than<br />

elaborate) and is accordingly unhelpful.<br />

It should also be noted that consumer brand confusion includes that of initial interest<br />

confusion, which refers to confusion on the part of the public as to the trade origin of<br />

the goods or services in relation to which the impugned sign has been used arising<br />

from use of the sign prior to purchase of those goods or services. 16 This means that<br />

there can be a likelihood of confusion under s.10(2) at the point when a consumer<br />

10 [2011] Bus L.R. 1339.<br />

11 [2009] Bus L.R. 339.<br />

12 Such as that in Och-Ziff, where the High Court pointed out that the words ‘OCH’ and ‘Och’ were<br />

more likely than not to lead to consumer brand confusion.<br />

13 Such was the case in Och-Ziff, where the High Court rejected defendant’s counsel submission that<br />

the addition of the word ‘CAPITAL’ sufficed to avoid a likelihood of confusion. The Court explained<br />

that the word ‘CAPITAL’ is descriptive, or at least non-distinctive, for financial services and in<br />

particular investment services, for which both the plaintiffs and defendants were involved in.<br />

14 [2011] EWHC 1627.<br />

15 [2004] RPC 4.<br />

16 Supra Note 8, at [87].<br />

15


16<br />

The Legality of Google AdWords<br />

views an advertisement, whether or not the advertisement leads to a sale and whether<br />

or not the consumer remains confused at the time of any such sale. As noted by the<br />

courts, although there may be no diversion of sales where initial interest confusion<br />

arises, the proprietor may still be affected in 2 other ways, namely (a) a confusing<br />

advertisement may affect the reputation of the trademarked goods and services and<br />

(b) such confusion may erode the distinctiveness of the trademark. Thus, any use of<br />

“AdWords” which results in the above-mentioned effects will be regarded as having<br />

caused initial interest confusion.<br />

II(b) – Section 10(1) – Confusion presumed; Issue is whether specific functions of<br />

trademark are infringed<br />

Under s.10(1), it is important to note that in double identity cases falling within the<br />

section a likelihood of confusion is presumed. It is therefore immaterial whether there<br />

is a likelihood of confusion in fact, although the jurisprudence of the ECJ does require<br />

that there be an effect on at least one of three functions of the trademark (i.e.<br />

indicating origin, advertising or investment). The law regarding these three functions<br />

will be assessed as they pertain to Google AdWords in order to determine if Google<br />

AdWords infringes s.10(1).<br />

II(b)(1) – Indicating Origin Function<br />

The indicating origin function is infringed if the advertisement (1) suggests that there<br />

is an economic link between the advertiser and the proprietor of the trademark or (2)<br />

while not suggesting the existence of an economic link, is vague to such an extent on<br />

the origin of the goods or services at issue such that reasonably well-informed and<br />

reasonably observant internet users are unable to determine, or enables them only<br />

with difficulty, on the basis of the advertising link and the attached commercial<br />

message, whether the advertiser is an independent third party or whether, on the<br />

contrary, it is economically linked to the trademark proprietor. 17<br />

Pertaining to AdWords, the fact that the advertisement appears immediately after the<br />

trademark has been entered as a search term and is displayed at a point when the<br />

trademark is (in its capacity as a search term) also displayed on the screen may cause<br />

the internet user to be mistaken as to the origin of the goods or services in question.<br />

This is however counter-balanced by the fact that the assessment of this mistake is<br />

based on a reasonably well-informed internet user. 18 Thus, the fact that some internet<br />

users may have had difficulty grasping that the service provided by the third party is<br />

independent of that of the trademark proprietor is not sufficient basis for a finding that<br />

the indicating origin function has been infringed.<br />

II(b)(2) – Advertising Function<br />

As for the advertising function, the ECJ has noted both in Google France 19 and<br />

Interflora 20 that a trademark may also be used for advertising purposes designed to<br />

inform and persuade consumers. The trademark owner may thus be entitled to prevent<br />

17 See Interflora [2011] Case C-323/09, at paragraph 44.<br />

18 ibid, at [50] .<br />

19 [2011] Joined Cases C-236 to C-238/08.<br />

20 [2011] Case C-323/09.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

unauthorised use of its trademark by a third party if the third party use adversely<br />

affects the proprietor’s use of its mark as a factor in sales promotion or as an<br />

instrument of commercial strategy. Applying this to Google’s AdWords service, it is<br />

recognised that the purchase of keywords belonging to the trademark owner may have<br />

certain repercussions on the advertising use of that mark by the trademark owner and<br />

on his commercial strategy. However, the courts have drawn a distinction between<br />

‘certain repercussions’ and ‘adverse effects’, and have held that the use of a sign<br />

identical with another person’s trademark in a referencing service such as Google is<br />

not liable to have an adverse effect on the advertising function of the trademark. 21 In<br />

other words, the mere fact that the use of Google’s AdWords service (through<br />

purchasing the keywords of trademark owners) by competitors obliges the trademark<br />

owner to intensify its advertising in order to maintain or enhance its profile with<br />

consumers (for e.g., by paying a higher price per click than its competitor if it wishes<br />

to ensure that its advertisement appears before that of its competitor) is not a<br />

sufficient basis for concluding that the trademark’s advertising function has been<br />

impaired. 22<br />

From the above summary, it is clear that the ECJ is trying to balance the inherent<br />

tension between the interests of trademark owners and those in favour of free<br />

competition. As noted by the ECJ in Interflora, although the trademark is an essential<br />

element in the system of undistorted competition which European law seeks to<br />

establish, its purpose however is not to protect its proprietor against practices inherent<br />

in competition. In particular, the ECJ pointed out that in the case of the AdWords<br />

service, the advertising function was not adversely affected because the home and<br />

advertising pages of the trademark proprietor will appear in the list of the natural<br />

results, usually in the highest positions on that list. That display, which is moreover<br />

free of charge, means that the visibility to internet users of the goods or services of the<br />

proprietor of the trademark is guaranteed, irrespective of whether or not that<br />

proprietor is also successful in also securing the display, in one of the highest<br />

positions, of an advertisement under the heading ‘Sponsored Links’.<br />

Moreover, it is also perhaps evident to a certain extent that the ECJ’s decision has in<br />

effect meant that a high threshold has been set for the advertising function of a<br />

trademark to be regarded as being infringed. This has been noted by the UK Court of<br />

Appeal in L’Oreal v Bellure 23 (applying the guidance given by the ECJ), who<br />

explained at paragraph 30 that the advertising function is:<br />

“Conceptually vague and ill-defined [...] Trademark owners of famous marks will<br />

have spent a lot of money creating them and need to continue to spend to maintain<br />

them. But all advertisements for rival products will impinge on the owner’s efforts<br />

and affect the advertising function of the brand in question. [Yet] no one would say<br />

that such jostling for fame and image in the market should be stopped”. 24<br />

Seen from another light, the ECJ has expressly defined what is meant by acceptable<br />

‘certain repercussions’, but has not done so similarly for what is meant by ‘adverse<br />

effects’. In the light of such specific guidance from the ECJ, as well as the difficulties<br />

21 ibid, at [57].<br />

22 ibid.<br />

23 [2010] EWCA Civ 535.<br />

24 ibid, at [30].<br />

17


18<br />

The Legality of Google AdWords<br />

pointed out by the English courts of the difficulty in applying the ECJ test, it is<br />

submitted that it would be difficult in practice to demonstrate that the advertising<br />

function of the trademark has been infringed. This supports the assertion that from a<br />

legal perspective, competitors need only be concerned with not causing consumer<br />

brand confusion. If no such confusion results, there is very little likelihood that rival<br />

advertisers who purchase keywords of their competitor’s trademark would be held to<br />

have breached the indicating origin or advertising functions of the latter’s trademark.<br />

II(b)(3) – Investment Function<br />

Pertaining to the investment function, the ECJ has noted expressly in Interflora that a<br />

trademark may also be capable of attracting customers and retaining their loyalty<br />

based on the acquired reputation of the trademark. In such a situation, use of a<br />

trademark may be prohibited if such third-party use substantially interferes with the<br />

proprietor’s use of the trademark to acquire or preserve a reputation capable of<br />

attracting consumers and retaining their loyalty. Interestingly, however, the ECJ goes<br />

on to consider the relation between the function of indicating origin and the investing<br />

function of a trademark as follows:<br />

“However, it cannot be accepted that the proprietor of a trade mark may – in<br />

conditions of fair competition that respect the trade mark's function as an indication of<br />

origin – prevent a competitor from using a sign identical with that trade mark in<br />

relation to goods or services identical with those for which the mark is registered, if<br />

the only consequence of that use is to oblige the proprietor of that trade mark to adapt<br />

its efforts to acquire or preserve a reputation capable of attracting consumers and<br />

retaining their loyalty. Likewise, the fact that that use may prompt some consumers to<br />

switch from goods or services bearing that trade mark cannot be successfully relied on<br />

by the proprietor of the mark”. 25<br />

The above guidance seems to indicate once again a high threshold in determining<br />

whether the investment function of a trademark has been infringed. What is more<br />

interesting, however, is the ECJ’s relation to the function of indicating origin in the<br />

first sentence. This seems to be an implicit recognition by the ECJ that the way to<br />

balance the inherent tension between trademark owners and competitors is to ensure<br />

that the function of indicating origin of the trademark is not infringed. Once it is clear,<br />

however, that the function of indicating origin has not been infringed, the courts will<br />

only examine whether the other functions (i.e. advertising and investment functions)<br />

of the trademark has been infringed to the extent that it has been used for those other<br />

functions. Even so, the ECJ has set a high threshold for these other functions to be<br />

regarded as having been infringed so as to balance the interests between free<br />

competition and trademark protection. The very fact that the ECJ has provided<br />

detailed guidance to competitors as to what constitutes infringement of the other<br />

functions, but on the other hand has failed to do the same for trademark owners,<br />

supports the assertion that the ECJ is not as concerned about the infringement of the<br />

other functions of the trademark and that the practical effect of its judgments is that<br />

the use of Google AdWords is allowed as long as it does not result in consumer brand<br />

confusion. Moreover, as pointed out by the UK Court of Appeal in L’Oreal v Bellure,<br />

it is hard to imagine what is to be regarded as infringement of the investment function,<br />

25 Supra Note 20, at [64].


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

since all comparative advertising is likely to affect the value of the trademark owner’s<br />

investment, yet the ECJ has held that it is an acceptable practice.<br />

II(c) – Section 10(3) – Confusion unnecessary; Issue is whether dilution,<br />

tarnishment or unfair advantage has resulted<br />

As for s.10(3), it has been held in General Motors 26 that confusion is not required<br />

under this section. There are three possible types of damage recognised under this<br />

section, namely (i) dilution (where the trademark’s ability to identify the goods and<br />

services for which it is registered is weakened), (ii) tarnishment (i.e. the trademark’s<br />

power of attraction is reduced) and (iii) unfair advantage (defined as exploitation on<br />

the coat-tails of the mark with a reputation). Section 10(3) offers additional protection<br />

for trademarks with a reputation, since it is possible to bring an action under this head<br />

as long as a similar sign has been used, even if the advertiser is selling completely<br />

different goods.<br />

II(c)(1) – Dilution<br />

Dilution is caused when the trademark’s ability to identify the goods or services for<br />

which it is registered is weakened. This is particularly the case when the mark, which<br />

at one time aroused immediate association with the goods or services for which it is<br />

registered, is no longer capable of doing so. The ECJ in particular have held that the<br />

stronger the earlier mark’s distinctive character and reputation, the easier it will be to<br />

accept that detriment has been caused to it. However, the ECJ has also sought to<br />

balance this by requiring that such detriment to the distinctive character of the mark<br />

must be proven, which would require evidence of a change in the economic behaviour<br />

of the goods or services for which the earlier mark was registered consequent on the<br />

use of the later mark, or a serious likelihood that such a change will occur in the<br />

future. 27<br />

Such an evidentiary threshold is in fact not easy to prove, as noted in the Och-Ziff<br />

case, where the High Court was not satisfied that the plaintiffs had adduced any<br />

evidence where it would be proper to infer a change in economic behaviour on the<br />

part of consumers. Moreover, the High Court has also pointed out that the trademark<br />

must have a sufficient reputation before it can enjoy protection under s.10(3). More<br />

importantly, though, the High Court also observed that where trademarks involved a<br />

combination of words, it could very well be the case that the separate words<br />

themselves constituted an independent distinctive element (such that the reduction in<br />

distinctiveness of one of the words could not automatically lead to a presumption that<br />

either the distinctiveness of the other word, or that of the combined words, was<br />

reduced).<br />

To summarise, it is therefore clear that both the ECJ and the High Court set a<br />

relatively high evidentiary threshold for trademark owners to prove that there has<br />

been dilution of their trademarks as a result of “AdWords”.<br />

26 [1999] Case C-375/97.<br />

27 Intel Corporation Inc v CPM United Kingdom Ltd [2008] Case C-252/07, at [77].<br />

19


20<br />

The Legality of Google AdWords<br />

II(c)(2) – Tarnishment<br />

Tarnishment is caused when the goods or services for which the identical or similar<br />

sign is used by the third party may be perceived by the public in such a way that the<br />

trademark’s power of attraction is reduced. This is particularly the case when the<br />

goods or services offered by the third party possess a characteristic or a quality which<br />

is liable to have a negative impact on the image of the mark. Once again, however, it<br />

is not easy to satisfy for trademark owners to prove that their sign has been tarnished.<br />

In particular, the High Court in Och-Ziff noted that in the absence of any likelihood of<br />

confusion, it is very difficult to support the claim that the reputation of the trademark<br />

will be adversely affected. This is so even if the competitor who uses the mark is less<br />

successful than that of the trademark proprietor. In relation to Google AdWords, it is<br />

worth noting that there has thus far been no case where an action for tarnishment has<br />

succeeded in the context of Google AdWords (this can be attributed more to the fact<br />

that there has been a dearth of cases considering tarnishment in the context of Google<br />

AdWords 28 ). As such, it is only possible to speculate at this stage on the possible<br />

approach of the courts, but following Och-Ziff, it is likely that if trademark owners<br />

hope to prove tarnishment under Google AdWords, they will have to allege more than<br />

simply the contention that their competitors are less successful than them.<br />

II(c)(3) – Unfair advantage<br />

With regards to unfair advantage, it refers to an advantage obtained by the third party<br />

which, while not confusing nor otherwise damaging, is unfair as the advantage is<br />

obtained intentionally in order to benefit from the power of attraction, the reputation<br />

and the prestige of the mark and to exploit the marketing effort expended by the<br />

proprietor of the mark without making any such efforts of his own, and without<br />

compensation for any loss caused to the proprietor or for the benefit gained to the<br />

third party. In Och-Ziff, the High Court noted that two English decisions had<br />

considered the ECJ’s ruling in L’Oreal v Bellure 29 . Both decisions seemed to have<br />

slightly different views about how unfair advantage may be found, with Lloyd J in<br />

Whirlpool 30 asserting that an objective test was necessary, which involved a global<br />

assessment of factors as mentioned in Paragraphs 79 – 80 in Intel Corporation 31 . Thus,<br />

unfair advantage can only be proven by something other than intention. The Court of<br />

Appeal, in L’Oreal v Bellure (No. 2), however, seemed to contradict this view, and<br />

stated that the effect of the ECJ’s ruling was that unfair advantage may be caused by a<br />

subjective test of intention to free-ride. As long as there was an intention to free-ride,<br />

there would be unfair advantage. Interestingly, the ECJ now seems to have clarified<br />

by what is meant by unfair advantage, as it pointed out in Interflora that if a rival<br />

competitor simply purchases the keyword of the trademark proprietor so as to simply<br />

offer a genuine alternative, then there can be no unfair advantage. This statement is of<br />

course qualified by the fact that the alternative product must not be a mere imitation<br />

28 There has thus far only been the case of Interflora (as mentioned above), where the ECJ noted that<br />

the referring court (the High Court of Justice, England and Wales) did not require it to consider<br />

questions pertaining to tarnishment. Moreover, the High Court is yet to pass final judgment on the<br />

Interflora case, and it remains to be seen whether it will consider tarnishment in the context of Google<br />

AdWords then.<br />

29 [2009] Case C-487/07.<br />

30 [2010] RPC 51.<br />

31 [2008] Case C-252/07.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

of the goods of the trademark proprietor, nor can it have an adverse effect on the<br />

functions of the trademark concerned; neither can it cause dilution or tarnishment.<br />

This is especially interesting, because in practice it means that confusion is the key<br />

(and only) element that keyword purchasers/advertisers need to be worried about. As<br />

demonstrated above, there are high evidentiary thresholds set in practice for<br />

infringement of the trademark functions to be found; and where there are imitations of<br />

goods (e.g. fake goods), there is obviously, and rightly so, a likelihood of confusion.<br />

Of course, it remains to be seen how the UK Courts will apply the new guidance set<br />

out by the ECJ, but it should not be forgotten that they are bound by ECJ decisions.<br />

Google’s policy, which suggests to the effect that advertisers who make use of<br />

keyword purchasing have nothing to worry about as long as there is no likelihood of<br />

confusion, is therefore accurate as it reflects how the courts are likely to approach<br />

such cases in the future.<br />

II(d) – The Tort of Passing-Off<br />

Finally, it is necessary to consider whether keyword purchasers/advertisers may be<br />

liable under the Tort of Passing Off. The Tort of Passing Off consists of three<br />

elements, which are (1) Goodwill, (2) Misrepresentation and (3) Damage. Failure to<br />

fulfil all of the three elements will mean the collapse of any action under the Tort of<br />

Passing Off. Since the possibility of confusion is probably best represented under the<br />

misrepresentation element, it is sufficient to consider just this aspect of the tort. The<br />

High Court in Och-Ziff stated that initial interest confusion was able to give rise to a<br />

finding of misrepresentation. Thus, where the defendant successfully induces the<br />

public to do business with him by making a misrepresentation, then it ought not to<br />

matter if the falsity of the representation becomes apparent before the transaction is<br />

concluded. This is because the basis of passing off is a misrepresentation causing<br />

damage to the claimant’s goodwill, so the issue is how the consumer subjectively<br />

perceives the product. However, if there is no likelihood of confusion, it is<br />

accordingly difficult to assert misrepresentation because the average consumer will<br />

know that the product advertised is not that of the trademark proprietor’s but rather<br />

that of a competitor.<br />

To summarise, this effectively means once again that Google’s AdWords policy is<br />

perfectly acceptable, because if there is no possibility of confusion, it would be<br />

difficult to assert that passing-off has been committed.<br />

III – Conclusion<br />

In conclusion, it must be asserted that Google’s policy of permitting rivals to purchase<br />

keywords of trademarks is perfectly acceptable, as long as it does not cause consumer<br />

brand confusion. As demonstrated above, Google’s policy is supported by case law,<br />

and this may well be the practical effect of Interflora where imitations are likely to be<br />

regarded as trademark infringements, but other than that it is unclear in what practical<br />

situations trademark owners may oppose keyword advertising where the sponsored<br />

link is clear as to the origin of the goods. 32 The ECJ has imposed a high threshold on<br />

how trademark infringement can be found bar confusion, and rightly so. They<br />

recognise that trademarks can be useful in facilitating the effectiveness of the Single<br />

Market (for e.g. acting as a source identifier, which helps to facilitate trade). At the<br />

32 Neville Cordell, ‘The limits of fair competition on the Internet’ [2011] IPM (Nov) 75.<br />

21


22<br />

The Legality of Google AdWords<br />

same time, they also recognise that trademarks may also be used to consolidate the<br />

market share of existing producers, which would tend to decrease inter-State trade. A<br />

proper balance between trademark proprietors and competitors in the realm of<br />

AdWords is thus necessary. The UK, as a strong proponent of the Single Market, is<br />

likely to agree with the ECJ’s approach. This can be seen in the recent approach of the<br />

UK Courts towards ECJ guidance, where they have tended to apply the guidance<br />

without any expression of serious reservations 33 , save for Jacob LJ in L’Oreal v<br />

Bellure (No. 2) 34 . This approach is likely to be carried forward when the High Court<br />

re-considers Interflora in the near future.<br />

From the advertiser’s perspective, transparency in the advertisement is therefore very<br />

important. To minimise confusion on the part of internet users, advertisements must<br />

not conceal the source of goods, nor should it refer to the trademark. Moreover,<br />

advertises who purchase keywords also need to consider whether the trademarks have<br />

secondary meanings, such as those denoting a commercial network, and if so whether<br />

a disclaimer may be necessary. 35 If this advice is followed, it will most likely be the<br />

case that the advertisement accompanying the sponsored link will be clear as to the<br />

origin of the goods and not cause confusion. Compliant advertisers should therefore<br />

have little to fear from trademark owners.<br />

33 See for example, Och-Ziff and Lewis v Client Connection.<br />

34 This was not in relation to AdWords, bur rather to the ECJ’s view that imitations in any form are not<br />

to be tolerated even if the marketing information was explicitly clear that the imitated product was<br />

simply to offer consumers a ‘feel’ of how the real product would be.<br />

35 Rachel Fetches, ‘Keyword Advertising: a round-up of EU cases’ (2011) E.C.L. &P 13(11).


THE HUMAN RIGHTS ACT SECTION 2(1) TAKEN INTO ACCOUNT<br />

Ciju Puthuppally, University of Cambridge<br />

Abstract: On the 14 th of December 2011, Lord Irvine, the architect of the Human<br />

Rights Act 1998 (HRA), incisively criticised the courts for their handling of HRA<br />

section 2(1). According to him, the injunction on courts in s.2(1) to take the<br />

jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights into account has been<br />

transmogrified into an obligation to follow it; the courts have thus been too<br />

submissive in following Strasbourg. This criticism, however, must be questioned. In<br />

the first place, the statute and its legislative history are ambiguous. In light of this,<br />

any interpretation of s.2 should rightly defer to ulterior grounds of policy, principle<br />

and reason. Considering the UK’s international law obligations and further practical<br />

issues, the current construction of s.2 is to be defended as regards the courts’<br />

reluctance to grant lesser protection than Strasbourg. Nonetheless, Lord Irvine’s<br />

criticism should be heeded with respect to the courts’ duty under both the European<br />

Convention on Human Rights and the HRA to engage Strasbourg in dialogue, not<br />

mimicry. In particular, his criticism of the self-abnegation of British courts under the<br />

Ullah principle is to be supported. Ultimately, British judges should accept the<br />

jurisdiction they have been granted under the HRA to make a distinctive contribution<br />

to human rights law.<br />

I – Introduction<br />

British judges have borne much criticism from several quarters over their judgments<br />

on the Human Rights Act 1998 (HRA) and the European Convention on Human<br />

Rights (ECHR). On the 14 th of December 2011, for the first time publicly<br />

commenting on his intent behind HRA section 2(1), Lord Irvine decisively added his<br />

own voice to the debate. He was forcefully critical of the courts’ handling of s.2,<br />

scolding them for their submission to Strasbourg. According to him, s.2 of the HRA<br />

“means that it is our judges’ duty to decide the cases for themselves and explain<br />

clearly to the litigants, Parliament and the wider public why they are doing so. This,<br />

no more and certainly no less, is their constitutional duty.” 1 According to him, it is a<br />

duty the judges have betrayed.<br />

This is a profound and surely piercing critique from the architect of the HRA.<br />

However, the legitimacy thereof must be questioned. Firstly, the claim that the<br />

meaning of s.2 is semantically simple and plainly at odds with the courts’ approach is<br />

stretched. The statutory wording – and even the legislative history – is ambiguous. In<br />

light of this, any interpretation of s.2 should rightly defer to ulterior grounds of policy,<br />

principle and reason. These relate in particular to international obligations and<br />

practical considerations. In these terms, the courts are in large part to be defended to<br />

the extent that they have been reluctant to depart from Strasbourg authority in order to<br />

allow a prima facie violation of Convention rights. On the other hand, Lord Irvine’s<br />

criticism should be heeded as regards the role of the courts under both the ECHR and<br />

the HRA to engage Strasbourg in dialogue, not mimicry. Moreover, Lord Irvine’s<br />

voice adds further force to the view that the courts’ timidity in furthering the<br />

1 Lord Irvine of Lairg, “A British Interpretation of Convention Rights” (Bingham Centre for the Rule<br />

of Law, University College London, 14 December 2011) <br />

accessed 30 January 2012.


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

protection of human rights is undue and regrettable self-abnegation. Ultimately,<br />

British judges should accept the jurisdiction they have been given under the HRA to<br />

make a distinctive contribution to human rights law.<br />

II - Semantic Ambiguity<br />

Lord Irvine’s criticism is founded foremost on the plain meaning of the statute.<br />

Section 2(1) provides: “A court or tribunal determining a question which has arisen in<br />

connection with a Convention right must take into account any…judgment…of the<br />

European Court of Human Rights…” 2 Herein, “take into account” “can be<br />

paraphrased as ‘have regard to’, ‘consider’, ‘treat as relevant’ or ‘bear in mind’.” 3 In<br />

his opinion, however, the courts have unacceptably distorted this meaning by<br />

considering themselves “bound (or as good as bound)” 4 following Lord Slynn’s<br />

statement in the Alconbury 5 case:<br />

…Although the Human Rights Act 1998 does not provide that a national<br />

court is bound by these decisions it is obliged to take account of them so<br />

far as they are relevant. In the absence of some special circumstances it<br />

seems to me that the court should follow any clear and constant<br />

jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights. 6<br />

The requirement of exceptional circumstances to depart from the European Court of<br />

Human Rights (ECtHR) case law is, it is claimed, a fundamental misreading of the<br />

statute.<br />

‘Take account of’ is not the same as ‘follow’, ‘give effect to’ or ‘be bound<br />

by’. Parliament, if it had wished, could have used any of these<br />

formulations. 7<br />

According to Lord Irvine, this clearly denies the courts’ approach of following<br />

Strasbourg barring exceptional circumstances. It will be argued, however, that beyond<br />

the polar prohibitions of absolute ignorance and absolute submission, the statute<br />

admits of a wide range of approaches to Strasbourg jurisprudence. The courts’<br />

approach falls within that range. Even though it imposes a requirement not stated in<br />

the statute for departure from ECtHR judgments, some such addition was an<br />

inevitable result of the ambiguity of s.2. The compatibility of the courts’ approach<br />

with the statutory phrasing may finally be confirmed by reference to comparisons.<br />

Firstly, it is to be noted that a requirement that a factor be “taken into account”, though<br />

simply worded, is indubitably vague. It does not specify how the factor is to be taken<br />

into account, or to what extent. Besides the plain demand that the factor be considered,<br />

it gives no instruction as to the weight such consideration should be given.<br />

2 The Human Rights Act 1998 c.42.<br />

3 Lord Irvine (n 1) 2.<br />

4 Ibid 4.<br />

5 R (on the application of Alconbury Developments Ltd) v Secretary of State for the Environment and<br />

the Regions [2003] 2 AC 295.<br />

6 Ibid 313.<br />

7 Lord Irvine (n 1) 3.<br />

24


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

This being so, all such a requirement does – at most – is establish two prohibitions.<br />

Certainly, it bars a court from wholly ignoring the factor in question. Some<br />

consideration must be given to it in whatever way.<br />

Secondly, one might agree with the more specific statement of Lord Irvine that “take<br />

into account” in s.2 does not mean “follow”. 8 After all, as Lord Irvine mentions, an<br />

amendment to replace the ambiguity with “must follow” was rejected. 9 One might also<br />

note the judicial review principle that, given a statutory discretion, the adoption by a<br />

decision-maker of a policy without provision for exceptions constitutes unlawful<br />

fettering of such discretion. 10 So much, therefore, may properly be considered outside<br />

the specified scope of the statute.<br />

However, s.2(1) prescribes or demands nothing further, nothing more specific, than<br />

this. Surely, on a plain reading, it therefore allows for a huge range of meaning falling<br />

anywhere between these two polar extremes of absolute ignorance and absolute<br />

compulsion.<br />

The position adopted by the courts falls within this range. It does not betray the bare<br />

instruction that Strasbourg judgments are “to be taken into account”; rather, it<br />

specifies how they are to be taken into account: when Strasbourg case law is taken into<br />

account and it is “clear and constant”, this has greater weight than other factors, except<br />

that “some special circumstances” may have even greater weight. 11<br />

It is not to be said that the imprecision of that exception of “special circumstances”<br />

renders the rule tantamount to an absolute obligation. As Lord Irvine himself notes,<br />

the court in Horncastle 12 departed from Strasbourg case law, finding on that occasion<br />

that the Strasbourg court did not sufficiently appreciate or accommodate “particular<br />

aspects of our domestic process.” 13 Further, Lord Neuberger suggested in Pinnock 14<br />

that even a clear and constant line of Strasbourg jurisprudence might be departed from<br />

if it is “inconsistent with some fundamental feature of our law” 15 . This interpretation is<br />

commended by Lord Irvine as a “more nuanced” 16 approach; nonetheless, it is<br />

consistent with the general position that he criticises, for it is again merely stating an<br />

exception. One might even see such a fundamental inconsistency as a “special<br />

circumstance” of itself, and thus read it directly in line with the foundational position<br />

of Lord Slynn.<br />

Though Lord Irvine claims that this means the court is “as good as bound” 17 , this is<br />

certainly not the same as turning “must take into account” into “must follow”. The fact<br />

alone that such special circumstances arise only rarely does not mean that the<br />

8 Lord Irvine (n 1) 3.<br />

9 Lord Irvine (n 1) 3.<br />

10 R. v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p. Venables [1998] A.C. 407, 417.<br />

11 Alconbury (n 5) 313 per Lord Slynn.<br />

12 R. v Horncastle [2010] 2 A.C. 373.<br />

13 Ibid 432<br />

14 Pinnock v Manchester City Council [2010] 3 WLR 1441.<br />

15 Ibid 125.<br />

16 Lord Irvine (n 1) 5.<br />

17 Ibid 4.<br />

25


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

provision has been transformed into an obligation to follow rather than take into<br />

account. The courts have merely established an approach to the actual process of<br />

taking Strasbourg jurisprudence into account, to the assessment of the relative weight<br />

of this factor as against others.<br />

The real objection is that the courts have imposed a requirement that was not<br />

specifically directed by s.2(1) – namely that there must be some exceptional<br />

circumstance. This is true. However, this is not to be objected to on the ground that it<br />

contradicts, or exceeds the ambit of, s.2.<br />

Some assessment of the relative weight of consideration of Strasbourg case law is<br />

surely an inevitable result of the obligation to take that factor into account. Then, the<br />

question is whether the statute specified in some fashion the measure of that relative<br />

weight. On the face of it, it certainly has not; the provision does not go further than the<br />

obligation to “take into account”. It provides no terms detailing that it should be taken<br />

into account in this way and not in that. Where the provision does not answer this<br />

question that arises inexorably from the bare obligation in s.2, it seems an ineluctable<br />

conclusion that it is for the court to decide the point. As such, surely the courts are not<br />

guilty of misreading the provision in maintaining that the weight of specifically “clear<br />

and constant” Strasbourg case law is particularly great, and so requires “special<br />

circumstances” to be offset. 18 One might note that the very fact that Strasbourg<br />

authority has been singled out for obligatory consideration implies that it is indeed<br />

especially significant.<br />

Therefore, so long as following Strasbourg authority is not an absolute obligation, the<br />

courts’ approach cannot properly be said to betray the statutory wording. Finding<br />

greater merit in the existence of consistent and constant Strasbourg case law than in<br />

considerations that do not amount to special circumstances is simply the courts’<br />

process of taking Strasbourg jurisprudence into account. Consequently, the bare<br />

meaning of s.2(1) does not of itself deny the courts’ approach.<br />

Indeed one might consider for comparison approaches to such statutory wording in<br />

other scenarios. In the Oil Platforms case, 19 for example, the International Court of<br />

Justice admitted that following the general rules of treaty interpretation, 20<br />

“interpretation must take into account any relevant rules of international law<br />

applicable.” 21 This did not bar it from – nor indeed cause any conflict of mandate in –<br />

taking a similarly exceptional approach to departing from the relevant authority.<br />

Indeed it noted that “[t]he application of the relevant rules of international law relating<br />

to this question thus forms an integral [italics added] part of the task of<br />

interpretation…” 22<br />

18 Alconbury (n 5) 313.<br />

19 The Oil Platforms case (Iran v United States of America) (Merits) Reports 2003.<br />

20 Following Art.3(c) of the 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties.<br />

21 Oil Platforms (n 19) [41].<br />

22 Oil Platforms (n 19) [41].<br />

26


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Even more revealing is the approach taken to Sentencing Guidelines in the US.<br />

Delaware requires an “advisory”, or “voluntary and non-binding” 23 consideration of<br />

State Sentencing Guidelines, and yet requires that judges only depart from the<br />

standard sentence range “if they find that there are substantial and compelling reasons<br />

justifying an exceptional sentence.” 24 Indeed, compliance is at ninety per cent. 25<br />

Furthermore, “[t]he governing factor(s) leading to the exceptional sentence must be<br />

stated for the record and should be identified in the sentencing order” 26 , not unlike<br />

Lord Phillips’ requirement that the judge “giv[e] reasons for adopting this<br />

[exceptional] course.” 27 Similarly, the Minnesota Sentencing Guidelines, in its<br />

statement of purpose, claims that “[w]hile the sentencing guidelines are advisory to<br />

the sentencing judge, departures from the presumptive sentences established in the<br />

guidelines should be made only when substantial and compelling circumstances<br />

exist.” 28 The juxtaposition of the two allegedly incompatible conditions is particularly<br />

revealing. That something is non-binding and “advisory” only does not exclude the<br />

possibility that it be considered binding barring exceptional circumstances. The same<br />

must hold true of something that need only be “taken into account”.<br />

Thus Lord Irvine’s claim as regards the “plain” meaning of the provision is to be<br />

doubted. The statute is not clear, and the courts’ construction of it is compatible with<br />

the only two prohibitions that the statute does plainly establish. This is confirmed by<br />

comparison with the approach taken to departures from relevant rules in the Oil<br />

Platforms case and from “advisory” sentencing guidelines in the US. Therefore, if the<br />

courts are to be criticised, it is not over the bare meaning of the statute. The language<br />

of s.2(1), in the wide discretion that its ambiguity affords, admits of the approach that<br />

has been taken. The question then is whether the courts have or have not been properly<br />

guided by ulterior principles to adopt the best course left open to them under that<br />

discretion.<br />

III - International Obligations<br />

Lord Irvine emphasises that there is no “magic” in a clear and constant line of<br />

Strasbourg jurisprudence that renders it so compelling. This may be “no more than an<br />

extended repetition of error”. 29 However, the courts are to be defended in their<br />

commitment to such jurisprudence by consideration of the UK’s international law<br />

obligations, traditional rules of statutory construction in respect thereof, and the<br />

HRA’s legislative history.<br />

The “magic” seen by the courts in a clear and constant line of Strasbourg<br />

jurisprudence is of course implicit. A clear and constant line of Strasbourg<br />

23 Delaware Sentencing Accountability Benchbook 2010 at 18; see also Neal B. Kauder and Brian J<br />

Ostrom, State Sentencing Guidelines: Profiles and Continuum (National Center for State Courts 2006)<br />

10.<br />

24 Ibid 102.<br />

25 Kim Hunt and Michael Connelly, “Advisory Guidelines in the Post-Blakely Era” [2005] Federal<br />

Sentencing Reporter Vol. 17 No.4 at 235.<br />

26 The Delaware Benchbook (n 23) 102.<br />

27 Horncastle (n 12) at 432.<br />

28 Minnesota Sentencing Guidelines and Commentary 2011, 1.<br />

29 Lord Irvine (n 1) 5.<br />

27


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

jurisprudence effectively establishes the international law regarding Convention rights.<br />

The need to comply with international law has been what might properly be said the<br />

major ground for the courts’ deference to Strasbourg. Thus in AF v Secretary of State<br />

for the Home Department, 30 Lord Hoffmann, though disagreeing with the relevant<br />

Strasbourg decision, submitted that:<br />

As a matter of our domestic law, we could take the decision in A v United<br />

Kingdom into account but nevertheless prefer our own view. But the United<br />

Kingdom is bound by the Convention, as a matter of international law, to<br />

accept the decisions of the ECHR on its interpretation. To reject such a<br />

decision would almost certainly put this country in breach of the<br />

international obligation which it accepted when it acceded to the<br />

Convention. I can see no advantage in your Lordships doing so. 31<br />

Indeed, the UK is party to the ECHR following ratification in 1951. Under ECHR<br />

Art.46, therefore, the UK is bound to “abide by the final judgment of the Court in any<br />

case to which they are a party”. It might further be noted that the UK is also<br />

effectively bound by the ECHR under EU law, for the “Union shall respect<br />

fundamental rights, as guaranteed by the European Convention… as general principles<br />

of law” 32 . Via this route, the ECHR has force with parliamentary backing even<br />

independently of the HRA.<br />

However, Lord Irvine contends that:<br />

....excessive preoccupation with this consideration [of international<br />

obligations] has led the Courts into error. A judge’s concern for the UK’s<br />

foreign policy and its standing in international relations can never justify<br />

disregarding the clear statutory direction which s.2 of the HRA provides. 33<br />

Admittedly, Lord Irvine’s wider argument that judges should not be involved in these<br />

affairs is a powerful one. However, the argument that they have become over-involved<br />

is premised on the view that the judges have let that consideration override the<br />

obvious meaning of the statute. As has been argued, there is no such “clear statutory<br />

direction”.<br />

Given that the statute is generally ambiguous as to the extent to which it should give<br />

weight to the factor taken into account, it is far from unwarranted to rely on<br />

international obligations to guide the choice of an appropriate approach within the<br />

scope that is granted by s.2. It is hardly an “excessive preoccupation” to follow then<br />

what is by no means a novel approach to statutory interpretation. It is indeed a “wellknown<br />

rule of construction of statutes that requires statutes to be construed, if possible,<br />

consistently with the government’s treaty obligations.” 34 Under the ambiguity of s.2,<br />

this certainly is “possible”. There is surely therefore a case for presuming that<br />

Parliament did not intend to legislate contrary to its ECHR obligations.<br />

30 AF v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2010] 2 A.C. 269.<br />

31 Ibid, 357.<br />

32 Maastricht Treaty Article F(2).<br />

33 Lord Irvine (n 1) 7.<br />

34 Attorney-General v Observer Ltd [1990] 1 AC 109 at 158.<br />

28


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Was it otherwise so plain that Parliament had no such intention? Lord Irvine implies<br />

that this is evident from the legislative history of the clause. However, he himself<br />

confirmed, in the House of Lords debate that he refers to, that “[t]he United Kingdom<br />

already accepts that Strasbourg rulings bind” 35 , and that “it has been the clear desire of<br />

all the main political parties, and has had their general assent, that we comply with our<br />

convention obligations.” 36 He further stated that “human rights are valuable and they<br />

deserve protection at home—equal protection to the protection to which they are<br />

entitled at Strasbourg.” 37 Does it not appear from such statements that Parliament<br />

intended to comply with its ECHR obligations under the HRA?<br />

A potential objection raised by Lord Irvine is that it is not strictly the courts that are<br />

bound by Art.46 of the ECHR, but rather the state. The courts are obliged to decide<br />

on whether or not to follow a Strasbourg ruling independent of the UK’s treaty<br />

obligations. It is a matter for Parliament and the Foreign and Commonwealth Office<br />

to consider the potential consequences of a breach of Art.46.<br />

Yet this might just as easily be said of any treaty obligation, for it is rarely specified<br />

that the courts must give effect to them. Nevertheless, of course, that is not the<br />

position otherwise taken. So long as there is ambiguity in the wording, the<br />

presumption is not simply that Parliament intended to abide by the UK’s obligations<br />

in general, but that it did not intend to contravene them in the particular provision in<br />

question; therefore, the meaning of that provision itself is logically to be read in line<br />

with British international treaty commitments. The legislative history cited suggests<br />

that Parliament did intend to bring the UK into conformity with its treaty obligations.<br />

There is little indication that there is a peculiar exception in this case in that the UK<br />

qua the state, and not qua the courts, should be properly concerned with this<br />

obligation.<br />

At the least, then, a contrary meaning is not so plain that the courts should turn a blind<br />

eye to the UK’s treaty obligations. The ambiguity is far from settled by reference to<br />

legislative history. Nor is it to be said that the application of that rule of construction<br />

here, given that Parliament must legislate before the Government’s ratifications take<br />

effect, would be to “impute to Parliament an intention to import the Convention into<br />

domestic law by the back door” as in Brind. 38 Indeed, holding to the contrary might as<br />

well be to impute to Parliament an intention most covertly to evade treaty obligations<br />

by the backdoor. Thereto, it is to be remembered that even besides the HRA,<br />

Convention rights have been incorporated into EU law, which does have explicit<br />

statutory backing. On the whole, therefore, not only was it left perfectly open to the<br />

courts to apply the presumption that Parliament did not intend by s.2 to flout the UK’s<br />

international obligations, but this must have appeared to be Parliament’s stance with<br />

reference to Hansard.<br />

35 HL Deb 3 November 1997, vol 582, col 1228.<br />

36 HL Deb 5 February 1998, vol 585, col 755.<br />

37 Ibid vol. 585, col. 755.<br />

38 R. v Secretary of State for the Home Department Ex p. Brind [1991] 1 A.C. 696, 718.<br />

29


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

IV - Practical Considerations<br />

Further practical grounds have been raised in support of the courts’ approach. Indeed<br />

it may be regarded as appropriately guided by considerations of international influence,<br />

legal certainty and the significant delays attending appeals to the ECtHR.<br />

It is argued that refusing to abide by a Strasbourg decision requiring a minimum level<br />

of protection would set a bad example for other states party to the ECHR. 39 Lord<br />

Irvine dismisses this firstly on the ground that it is essentially a question of “foreign<br />

relations and statecraft”, and secondly on the basis that any such consideration as is<br />

warranted is duly paid by giving “considered and respectful regard” to the relevant<br />

judgment. 40 Even so, considering the numerous approaches the ambiguity of s.2(1)<br />

admits of, it does not seem inappropriate to consider the broader impact of each in<br />

practice to determine the best course. In this regard, it would be regrettable if the UK,<br />

having played a great role in the erection of the ECHR system, were to lead its decline<br />

by undermining the authority of Strasbourg.<br />

Certainly, objections of exceeding the courts’ role cannot be brought against the<br />

further argument of legal certainty. The significant judicial discretion given under the<br />

ambiguity of s.2(1) raises the well-warranted criticism of a lack of certainty in the law,<br />

as argued by Tierney. 41 If the “clear and constant”, viz. the well-established<br />

jurisprudence of Strasbourg may be dismissed without exceptional circumstances,<br />

human rights law, an area in need of special certainty, is rendered particularly<br />

unpredictable. As Masterman notes, the precedential approach sometimes taken by<br />

British courts to Strasbourg jurisprudence is one that “places legal certainty at its core<br />

and aims to deter accusations of the judge acting without reference to legal<br />

authority.” 42<br />

An additional practical concern informs Lord Slynn’s foundational position:<br />

In the absence of some special circumstances it seems to me that the court<br />

should follow any clear and constant jurisprudence of [the ECtHR]. If it<br />

does not do so there is at least a possibility that the case will go to that court<br />

which is likely in the ordinary case to follow its own constant<br />

jurisprudence. 43<br />

This is not an undue nor an insubstantial consideration. Though ideally the ECtHR<br />

should be suitably equipped, the backlog of cases with which Strasbourg has to<br />

grapple is well known. Appeals to it therefore entail significant delay, and thus it is<br />

not inappropriate to question their propriety where the relevant case-law irrevocably<br />

demonstrates the position that will be taken absenting the necessary exceptional<br />

circumstances.<br />

39 Lord Irvine (n 1) 9.<br />

40 Lord Irvine (n 1) 9.<br />

41 Tierney, “Devolution Issues and s.2(1) of the Human Rights Act 1998” [2000] EHRLR 380, 392.<br />

42 Roger Masterman, Judicial Reasoning under the UK Human Rights Act (Helen Fenwick, Gavin<br />

Phillipson and Roger Masterman ed, Cambridge University Press 2000) 60.<br />

43 Alconbury (n 5) 313.<br />

30


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Of course, one must always be wary of allowing procedural considerations to dictate<br />

the substantive law, but this consideration is also relevant to the purposive approach to<br />

statutory interpretation. Indeed, the point informed the parliamentary debate. Lord<br />

Irvine himself noted that the HRA “provides better and easier access to rights which<br />

already exist” 44 and that “human rights are valuable and they deserve protection at<br />

home—equal protection to the protection to which they are entitled at Strasbourg<br />

[italics added].” 45 Thereto, Lord Bingham, in the speech to which Lord Irvine refers,<br />

further noted that<br />

It makes no sense, and, I suggest, does not make for justice that those<br />

seeking to enforce their rights have to exhaust all their domestic remedies<br />

here before embarking on the long and costly trail to Strasbourg. 46<br />

Moreover, in his criticism itself, Lord Irvine notes “the uncertainty which is<br />

perpetuated in the interregnum.” 47 This reality should not be ignored. Albeit as a<br />

practical consideration, it lends weight to the stance that Strasbourg case law should<br />

be departed from only in exceptional circumstances, which, by that condition, truly<br />

warrant the questioning. Thus there are substantial grounds that vindicate an<br />

“exceptionalist” approach to departures from Strasbourg case law.<br />

V - Dialogue, Not Mimicry<br />

However, Lord Irvine’s criticism is at least an important caveat. Judges should not<br />

merely attempt to mimic or pre-empt Strasbourg, because they have an important role<br />

to play – within the framework both of the ECHR jurisprudence in general and the<br />

HRA. This may be seen in Strasbourg’s emphasis on margins of appreciation and<br />

subsidiarity, and in the HRA’s purpose of empowering British judges.<br />

As regards the ECHR, even though the courts are justified in considering treaty<br />

obligations, those obligations should not be overstated. A significant amount of<br />

latitude is allowed by the ECtHR. Even if other cases are regarded as establishing the<br />

opinion of the Strasbourg Court, it does not necessarily follow that the same position<br />

will be adopted with regard to the UK given the varying “margin of appreciation”<br />

granted to different countries in relation to some Articles.<br />

Moreover, Strasbourg has – as is much emphasised – a subsidiary role in the<br />

protection of human rights. In Handyside v United Kingdom, 48 the ECtHR explained:<br />

The Convention leaves to each contracting state, in the first place, the task<br />

of securing the rights and liberties it enshrines… By reason of their direct<br />

and continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries, State<br />

authorities are in principle in a better position than the international judge to<br />

give an opinion on the exact content of these requirements as well as on the<br />

‘necessity’ of a ‘restriction’ or ‘penalty’ intended to meet them. 49<br />

44 HL Deb (n 36) col 755.<br />

45 Ibid.<br />

46 HL Deb (n 35) col 1245.<br />

47 Lord Irvine (n 1) 10.<br />

48 Handyside v United Kingdom (1979-80) 1 EHRR 737.<br />

49 Ibid 748.<br />

31


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

As such, there is no indiscriminate obligation on courts to give direct effect to ECtHR<br />

decisions; rather, there is indeed discretion for the state to “implement them in<br />

accordance with the rules of its national legal system” 50 as Lord Irvine emphasises.<br />

This should be taken together with a purposive reading of the HRA s.2. Whilst it is far<br />

from clear that, in interpreting s.2, the UK’s international obligations should be<br />

neglected by the courts, the legislative history of the Bill does, as Lord Irvine states,<br />

suggest an intention to allow judges to play an assertive role. In introducing the Bill,<br />

Lord Irvine explained that it “will allow British judges for the first time to make their<br />

own distinctive contribution to the development of human rights in Europe.” 51 Lord<br />

Bingham in the Lords Debate also commented that<br />

it seems to me highly desirable that we in the United Kingdom should help<br />

to mould the law by which we are governed in this area … British judges<br />

have a significant contribution to make in the development of the law of<br />

human rights. It is a contribution which so far we have not been permitted to<br />

make. 52<br />

Given the latitude admitted by the ECtHR as noted, this intention may be seen as<br />

compatible with the presumption that Parliament did not intend to legislate contrary to<br />

the Government’s treaty obligations. A preferable reading of HRA s.2(1) can and<br />

should therefore account for both of these considerations.<br />

In light of this, it is surely inappropriate to adopt a position that merely “mimics” or<br />

“pre-empts” the judgment of Strasbourg. 53 There is a distinctive role that the British<br />

judge has to play. The “more nuanced” 54 approach of Lord Neuberger that Lord Irvine<br />

commends is instructive:<br />

This court is not bound to follow every decision of the European court.<br />

Not only would it be impractical to do so: it would sometimes be<br />

inappropriate, as it would destroy the ability of the court to engage in the<br />

constructive dialogue with the European court which is of value to the<br />

development of Convention law… Where, however, there is a clear and<br />

constant line of decisions whose effect is not inconsistent with some<br />

fundamental substantive or procedural aspect of our law, and whose<br />

reasoning does not appear to overlook or misunderstand some argument or<br />

point of principle, we consider that it would be wrong for this court not to<br />

follow that line.” 55<br />

In principle, this strikes the appropriate balance. Courts should not be<br />

constrained absolutely from improving human rights law. They are certainly<br />

entitled under s.2 of the HRA, even when read together with ECtHR<br />

jurisprudence as mentioned, to disagree with Strasbourg case law in some<br />

50 DJ Harris, M O’Boyle and C Warbrick (ed), Law of the European Convention on Human Rights<br />

(Butterworths 1995) 26.<br />

51 HL Deb (n 35) col 1227.<br />

52 HL Deb (n 35) col 1245.<br />

53 Lord Irvine (n 1) 9.<br />

54 Lord Irvine (n 1) 5.<br />

55 Pinnock v Manchester City Council [2010] 3 WLR 1441 at §48.<br />

32


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

circumstances, and this leeway should be used to “further the dialogue”. This<br />

suggestion by Lord Neuberger is by no means novel, either, but echoes Lord<br />

Steyn and Lord Hoffmann on the room for “creative dialogue” between<br />

domestic courts and Strasbourg. 56<br />

As Lord Irvine notes, however, there can be no dialogue where domestic courts<br />

are committed to mimicking Strasbourg or pre-empting their judgment. This is<br />

not “constructive”. Thus although the qualification is appropriate, British courts<br />

should not feel themselves too restricted under the “exceptional circumstance”<br />

requirement for derogation. One might rightly question therefore whether Lord<br />

Hoffmann’s submission in AF v Secretary of State for the Home Department<br />

was appropriate where he did so<br />

with very considerable regret, because I think that the decision of the<br />

ECHR was wrong and that it may well destroy the system of control<br />

orders which is a significant part of this country’s defences against<br />

terrorism. Nevertheless, I think that your Lordships have no choice but to<br />

submit. 57<br />

Without considering the merit of his regret, it must be said that the grounds for such<br />

disagreement should be considered a “special circumstance”, even if there should be<br />

no question that a subsequent rejection by Strasbourg on appeal must be taken as<br />

authoritative. In some cases, therefore, Lord Irvine’s criticism in this regard is forceful.<br />

However, this is not to be overstated. As the ECtHR emphasised in Handyside,<br />

contracting states do not have an “unlimited power of appreciation.” 58 “The Court… is<br />

empowered to give the final ruling” 59 on whether a prima facie breach is reconcilable<br />

with the ECHR. “The domestic margin of appreciation thus goes hand in hand with a<br />

European supervision.” 60<br />

Furthermore, the margin of appreciation does not and should not affect the broader<br />

thrust of fundamental principles, evident from the fact that it is not available for all<br />

Articles. A “clear and constant” line of ECtHR jurisprudence on the basic meaning of<br />

a particular principle is therefore particularly authoritative, and on such a broad aspect<br />

there is little appropriate scope for variation from country to country. Otherwise, the<br />

entire basis of the ECHR that marks it as one with a special enforcement system<br />

would be undermined. As such, Lord Neuberger’s insistence on an “exceptionalist”<br />

approach is to be supported.<br />

VI - A Distinctive Contribution<br />

Lord Irvine’s criticism is particularly forceful with regard to the courts’ failure to<br />

provide protection of human rights greater than that provided by Strasbourg case law,<br />

whether in the context of an absence of Strasbourg jurisprudence on the position, or in<br />

56 Lord Steyn, “2000-2005: Laying the Foundations of Human Rights Law in the United<br />

Kingdom”[2005] EHRLR 349, 361; R v Lyons (No.3) [2003] 1 AC 976, 997 per Lord Hoffmann;<br />

Masterman (n 37) 74.<br />

57 AF (n 30) 357.<br />

58 Handyside (n 48) 754.<br />

59 Ibid 754.<br />

60 Harris, O’Boyle and Warbrick (n 50) 13.<br />

33


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

the context of unfavourable case law. The courts’ timidity is largely based on<br />

considerations of maintaining uniformity between ECHR nations. It shall be argued,<br />

however, that such great uniformity is not sought by the ECHR in the first place, and<br />

that in any case uniformity should be sought at a higher level of protection.<br />

Firstly, a distinction is to be noted where there is no established case law. S.2(1) of the<br />

HRA only requires that the Strasbourg position be taken into account when there is in<br />

fact a relevant extant decision. It does not encourage any consideration of the fact that<br />

Strasbourg has not established a position. As such, one would think that the court<br />

should take into account the relevant factors of the case at hand as is ordinary.<br />

There is no warrant for holding, as in Ambrose v Harris 61 , that a claim cannot succeed<br />

simply on the basis that Strasbourg has not yet considered such a factual situation.<br />

Certainly this position does not fall within the ambit of s.2(1). Further, it contradicts<br />

Parliament’s intention in providing the terms, under the HRA as a whole, for the<br />

courts to make a meaningful contribution to the development of human rights law. As<br />

Lord Irvine rightly stresses, “it is this type of case – where the Strasbourg case-law<br />

does not offer any clear answer – that gives our Courts the greatest scope to enter into<br />

a productive dialogue with the ECHR, and thus shape its jurisprudence.” 62 In this<br />

sense, his criticism is perfectly appropriate. Such a position is indeed unduly “selfabnegating”<br />

and is to be lamented.<br />

The same may be said of the courts’ refusal to go beyond the protections afforded by<br />

Strasbourg. Lord Bingham’s statement in Ullah 63 represents the prevailing orthodoxy<br />

among judges on this issue:<br />

It is of course open to member states to provide for rights more generous<br />

than those guaranteed by the Convention, but such provision should not be<br />

the product of interpretation of the Convention by national courts, since<br />

the meaning of the Convention should be uniform throughout the states<br />

party to it. The duty of national courts is to keep pace with the Strasbourg<br />

jurisprudence as it evolves over time: no more, but certainly no less. 64<br />

It is surprising that this position originates from Lord Bingham, who took the different<br />

position in the Lords Debate, as noted, of recognising the contribution British judges<br />

have to make to human rights law, and regretting that until that time they had not been<br />

permitted to make it. 65<br />

Lord Irvine dismissed the argument in Ullah that judges should be concerned about<br />

Convention rights bearing the same meaning throughout the Council of Europe,<br />

pointing out that British judgments would not in any case be binding on other<br />

members or on Strasbourg. Indeed, this concern seems to be somewhat overplayed.<br />

One might add firstly that Convention rights are not in any case uniform. The margin<br />

of appreciation granted varies from country to country, in effect giving a broader<br />

meaning to terms such as “morals” and “public emergency” to some countries than to<br />

61 Ambrose v Harris [2011] 1 WLR 2435.<br />

62 Lord Irvine (n 1) 12.<br />

63 R. (on the application of Ullah) v Special Adjudicator [2004] 2 AC 323.<br />

64 Ibid 350.<br />

65 HL Deb (n 35) col 1245.<br />

34


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

others, such that the restrictions on the rights, and therefore their content, may be<br />

greater or lesser. Moreover, if one is committed to “keep[ing] pace with the<br />

Strasbourg jurisprudence” 66 , one should equally note the statement in Handyside v<br />

United Kingdom:<br />

It is not possible to find in the domestic law of the various Contracting<br />

States a uniform European conception of morals. The view taken by their<br />

respective laws of the requirements of morals varies from time to time and<br />

from place to place, especially in our era which is characterised by a rapid<br />

and far-reaching evolution of opinions on the subject. 67<br />

This has been further emphasised extra-judicially by the then-President of the ECtHR:<br />

the Court's judgments are replete with statements that customs, policies and<br />

practices vary considerably between Contracting States and that we should<br />

not attempt to impose uniformity or detailed and specific requirements on<br />

domestic authorities, which are best positioned to reach a decision as to<br />

what is required in the particular area. 68<br />

It is clear, therefore, that as a result of cultural and legal variations, there will<br />

inevitably be some variation in the substantive meaning of the Convention rights.<br />

Strasbourg has accepted this and, in the form of the margin of appreciation, it is very<br />

much part of its jurisprudence. If Lord Bingham was thus committed to the latter, he<br />

and the courts should not at once have been so concerned about national variations in<br />

the law. This is not of itself an overriding concern.<br />

Secondly, even if one desires a greater degree of uniformity, why should British courts,<br />

if they are committed to the genuine protection of human rights, refrain from<br />

attempting to achieve that uniformity on an improved position of the law? Uniformity<br />

may indeed be desirable for fundamental principles, but at what level? If British courts<br />

believe greater protection is needed for human rights in Britain than is currently<br />

provided by case law on the Convention, might it not also be necessary to protect<br />

human rights in other states? British courts should take the lead.<br />

It might be objected that this goes beyond their role and their jurisdiction. Indeed,<br />

much stress is placed on the separation of powers as a reason for not going further.<br />

Lord Hope, for example, claimed<br />

Lord Bingham's point…was that Parliament never intended to give the<br />

courts of this country the power to give a more generous scope to those<br />

rights than that which was to be found in the jurisprudence of the<br />

Strasbourg court. To do so would have the effect of changing them from<br />

Convention rights, based on the treaty obligation, into free-standing rights<br />

of the court’s own creation. 69<br />

This reasoning, however, is questionable. Parliament provided that the courts give<br />

effect to “Convention rights”. As far as regards the meaning of those rights, it provides<br />

66 Ullah (n 63) 350.<br />

67 Handyside (n 48) 753.<br />

68 Sir Nicholas Bratza, “The Relationship between the UK Courts and Strasbourg” [2011] EHRLR 505,<br />

509.<br />

69 Ambrose v Harris (n 61) 2447.<br />

35


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

only that the courts “take into account” Strasbourg authority. As has been explained,<br />

within this term there is substantial scope for discretion. Whereas one might rightly be<br />

hesitant about adopting a meaning lesser than one provided for by Strasbourg and<br />

thereby likely violating human rights, one need hardly be as diligent in providing too<br />

much protection.<br />

Moreover, it is not true that affording greater protection than Strasbourg has thus far<br />

provided would take domestic courts beyond their jurisdiction. Affording rights<br />

greater than those provided by Strasbourg case law does not transform them into<br />

freestanding rights going beyond the Convention and the UK’s treaty obligations.<br />

Strasbourg jurisprudence is more nuanced than this. Lord Hope’s position assumes<br />

that it is alone Strasbourg’s role to define the Convention rights, just as Lord Bingham<br />

claimed:<br />

The Convention is an international instrument the correct interpretation of<br />

which can be authoritatively expounded only by the Strasbourg court. 70<br />

Similarly, Buxton LJ in the Court of Appeal contended that:<br />

where an international court has the specific task of interpreting an<br />

international instrument it brings to that task a range of knowledge and<br />

principle that a national court cannot aspire to. 71<br />

Under such an interpretation, one might well claim that, Strasbourg alone being<br />

capable of defining Convention rights, it would be beyond the jurisdiction of British<br />

courts – under a maximum duty to protect “Convention rights” – to afford a definition<br />

greater than that already provided by Strasbourg.<br />

However, whilst the ECtHR should certainly have final authority on appeal, it is not<br />

specifically the case law that has absolute authority, because this may not have taken<br />

into account specific objections relating to the particular domestic, legal and cultural<br />

context in question. British society is indubitably especially liberal in its cultural<br />

traditions, and as such should rightly be beholden to a higher standard. Simply<br />

because the ECHR is a common minimum does not mean the obligations of a specific<br />

country do not go further than to maintain that minimum. As former ECtHR Judge<br />

Karel Martens has explained:<br />

[domestic courts] should go further than seeing to it that the minimum<br />

standards in the ECHR are maintained. That is because the ECHR’s<br />

injunction to further realise human rights and fundamental freedoms<br />

contained in the preamble is also addressed to domestic courts.” 72<br />

In conjunction with this, one must remember that, under Handyside, it is for domestic<br />

courts in the first place to secure the rights and freedoms the Convention enshrines. 73<br />

Where they believe they have not done so, viz. that they have not provided sufficient<br />

protection to secure the rights rather than believing that they have provided too much,<br />

70 Ullah (n 63) 350.<br />

71 R (on the application of Anderson) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2002] 2 W.L.R.<br />

1143, 1168.<br />

72 Judge Sibrand Karel Martens, “Incorporating the European convention: The Role of the Judiciary”<br />

[1998] EHRLR 5, 14.<br />

73 Handyside (n 48) 753.<br />

36


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

there must be especial grounds for going beyond case law. It is part of the Strasbourg<br />

jurisprudence that domestic courts may take the lead in interpreting and securing the<br />

relevant rights. The meaning of the Convention is not, as Lord Hope seems to suggest,<br />

fixed under treaty obligations by ECtHR case law until Strasbourg itself decides<br />

otherwise on appeal. Unlike where potentially insufficient protection is granted by<br />

domestic courts, it is difficult to imagine a domestic ruling that extends ECHR<br />

protection being rejected by Strasbourg. Rather, it is to be seen as requisite under the<br />

cultural traditions of the UK that domestic courts are better placed to understand, if<br />

not under the UK’s ECHR direction to “further realise human rights and fundamental<br />

freedoms” which is just as much addressed to the courts. 74 Therefore, where British<br />

courts perceive the need for greater protection than provided in Strasbourg case law, it<br />

is entitled to provide it within the ambit of the UK’s ECHR obligation.<br />

One might note also, with regard to Lord Bingham’s Ullah statement cited above, that<br />

Strasbourg jurisprudence does not “evolve” independently. Challenges to its position<br />

are needed to prompt development. The then-President of the Court has written that:<br />

[The Strasbourg Court] has been particularly respectful of decisions<br />

emanating from courts in the United Kingdom since the coming into effect<br />

of the Human Rights Act and this because of the very high quality of the<br />

judgments of these courts, which have greatly facilitated our task of<br />

adjudication. In many cases, the compelling reasoning and analysis of the<br />

relevant case-law by the national courts has formed the basis of the<br />

Strasbourg Court's own judgment. 75<br />

From all this it is evident that British courts are very much a part of the ECHR<br />

jurisprudence and a part of its evolution. Strasbourg recognises this, and so the British<br />

courts are entitled to do so too. Interpretation of Convention rights as greater than that<br />

provided in other cases by the ECtHR is therefore not beyond the legitimate role of<br />

British courts.<br />

Furthermore, the objection to the contrary within the Ullah principle is inconsistent. In<br />

this particular respect, the courts have restricted themselves for fear of exceeding their<br />

jurisdiction, denying themselves the ability to develop the law. Yet on the other hand,<br />

they have allowed themselves the freedom to take into account considerations beyond<br />

those applying to the protection of British law, namely that divergences of Convention<br />

rights between nations is undesirable. It is well noted that the HRA merely<br />

incorporated Convention rights into British law. 76 Where then does the court derive its<br />

authority to consider issues of ulterior scope – to let what ultimately becomes British<br />

law be decided by considerations purely of the Convention as applicable to other<br />

states? This in itself is involving the courts in issues of wider diplomacy, foreign<br />

affairs and statecraft. To deny protection felt otherwise necessary and within its<br />

jurisdiction on the basis merely of its influence beyond Britain is to accept an<br />

authority to make a wider impact, to make a “distinctive contribution to human<br />

rights” 77 .<br />

74 Judge Martens (n 72) 14.<br />

75 Bratza (n 68) 507.<br />

76 As per Lord Hoffman, In re McKerr [2004] 1 W.L.R. 807, 826.<br />

77 HL Deb (n 35) col 1227.<br />

37


The Human Rights Act Section 2(1) Taken into Account<br />

This is not to argue that that approach should not be adopted. However, one should not<br />

deny in one instance what one accepts in another. Accept it wholeheartedly. The<br />

courts have the jurisdiction to make a “distinctive contribution to human rights” – both<br />

within the framework of Strasbourg jurisprudence and within the HRA. Whilst it may<br />

not be a duty in the terms referred to by Lord Irvine, this entitlement should be used to<br />

raise human rights standards beyond that found in Strasbourg’s case law in<br />

consideration of the wider principles at stake.<br />

Indeed, if the UK is truly committed to liberty and democracy, and as such is truly<br />

committed to human rights, its judges not only have the jurisdiction to make a<br />

distinctive contribution, but they have indeed a distinctive contribution waiting to be<br />

made. It is to be remembered that it was British lawyers who played a large part in<br />

raising the standard to the level of the ECHR. It would be a shame if domestic courts<br />

now deliberately withheld from raising the standard further. This is a truly liberal and<br />

democratic country, and this should be reflected by the judiciary. So long as these<br />

remain the principles enshrined by the ECHR, it is appropriate and fitting that British<br />

courts should take the lead where they believe there is a lead to be taken. The<br />

protection of Convention rights by the judges should not be done for the sake of<br />

nominal ECHR-compliance only; it should be done for the sake of upholding the<br />

underlying principles of the ECHR.<br />

VII – Conclusion<br />

On the whole, Lord Irvine’s criticism may be challenged to the extent that it rejects the<br />

courts’ “exceptionalist” attitude to departing from Strasbourg case law. This approach<br />

falls within the range of approaches permitted by s.2(1) of the HRA, and is further<br />

supported by considerations of the UK’s obligations under international law, the need<br />

to set a positive example, legal certainty, and the significant delays attending appeals<br />

to Strasbourg. Nonetheless, Lord Irvine’s criticism is to be noted to ensure that the<br />

allowance for departures from Strasbourg case law does not become merely<br />

theoretical. Moreover, one might rightly echo his regret at the timidity of the courts<br />

under the Ullah principle. British judges, like the British drafters of the ECHR, should<br />

take the lead in raising the human rights bar.<br />

38


VIOLENCE AGAINST WOMEN DURING ARMED CONFLICTS<br />

Zara Qurashi, University of Nottingham<br />

Violence against women has been described as the ‘greatest human rights scandal of<br />

our time.’ 1 It relates to violence that is ‘directed against a woman because she is a<br />

woman’ 2 , which may result in ‘physical, sexual or psychological harm or suffering’. It<br />

includes any threats of violence, coercion or arbitrary deprivations of liberty, relating<br />

to actions that occur in both the public and private sphere. 3 Violence remains a<br />

universal issue for women and it has no social, economic or cultural boundaries. 4 It is<br />

used as a means of social control to ensure patriarchal dominance and the derogatory<br />

position of women throughout every society across the world. 5 There is still an<br />

enormous amount of work that needs to be done to ensure the greater protection of<br />

women and the eradication of violence in all its forms. It needs to be globally<br />

accepted that gender-based violence is unlawful and that it will be effectively<br />

punished.<br />

This paper shall focus on the violence that women face during armed conflicts to<br />

determine whether it is now time to break away from the focus on violence against<br />

women. This paper only examines the shortfalls in international humanitarian law in<br />

protecting women during armed conflicts and does not discuss the wider human rights<br />

implications of violence against women. The different forms of violence that females<br />

come across in warzones and in post-conflict settings will firstly be addressed to<br />

reveal the extent of women suffering. The weaknesses in international humanitarian<br />

law (IHL) in effectively protecting women will then be discussed and counterbalanced<br />

against any positive advancements that have been made in trying to combat<br />

violence against women during armed conflicts. Finally, the paper will consider<br />

gender-based violence that is suffered by men in armed conflicts, which raises the<br />

question of whether we need to stop only looking at the violence that women face by<br />

taking a simultaneous approach that looks at the violence that both genders are subject<br />

to.<br />

I – Violence against Women during Armed Conflicts<br />

The acute suffering that women face during wartime is because of their gender. Both<br />

international and internal armed conflicts increase social tolerance towards violence 6<br />

which subsequently results in females enduring abuse in the form of rape, forced<br />

1<br />

Amnesty International, ‘Stop Violence Against Women’<br />

;<br />

accessed 4 th April 2011.<br />

2 Ibid.<br />

3 Article 1 of the Declaration on the Elimination of Violence Against Women.<br />

4 UNHRC ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on ‘Violence against Women, its causes and<br />

consequences’ (6 February 2003) UN Doc E/CN/.4./2004/66.<br />

5 C. Niarchos, ‘Women, War and Rape: Challenges facing the International Tribunal for the Former<br />

Yugoslavia’ (1995)17 Human Rights Quarterly, 650.<br />

6 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on violence against women, its causes and consequences:<br />

Violence against women perpetrated and/ or condoned by the State during times of armed conflict<br />

(1997-2000)’ (23 January 2001) UN Doc E/CN.4/2001/73, 18.


Violence Against Women During Armed Conflicts<br />

prostitution, sexual mutilation, strip searches, forced nudity, forced abductions and<br />

‘marriages’ to soldiers to whom they then become a sexual slave. 7 The laws that<br />

should protect them against such atrocities are inadequate because violence against<br />

women is a well-established method of warfare that is routinely used to repress and<br />

‘break the enemy’. 8 This section aims to reveal the gravity of the dilemma facing<br />

women during armed conflicts and the discriminatory violence that they are subjected<br />

to. The different forms of violence that women have to endure in wartime will be<br />

discussed by looking at examples from both past and present conflict areas.<br />

I(a) – RAPE as a method of warfare<br />

Wartime rape has been largely accepted by historians and military leaders as an<br />

inevitable consequence of war. It is a ‘peculiar and odious’ form of violence that<br />

women have endured in all conflicts. 9 Since the twentieth century, rape has become a<br />

more self-conscious weapon of war 10 , which has ensured the continuing debasement<br />

of women. Wartime propaganda has reinforced the link between war and sexual<br />

violence by States asserting that they need to protect ‘their women’ from the enemy. 11<br />

The idea of women being ‘victims in need of protection’ exacerbates the effectiveness<br />

of rape as a tool of warfare because it suggests that raping women will be one of the<br />

worst things that the enemy could do; thus giving it more appeal.<br />

Rape of women civilians has consisted of gang rapes which take place in houses,<br />

detention centres, or in public. ‘Rape camps’ have also been a common feature in all<br />

conflicts, where detained women are raped frequently as part of a wider military<br />

strategy. 12 The Yugoslavian and Rwandan conflicts brought to the forefront of public<br />

attention how rape can be used to terrorise a local population. Gender-based violence<br />

was an essential method of assault in these conflicts and was used to impregnate the<br />

victim so that they would give birth to children of mixed ethnic descent. 13 This was an<br />

integral part of the genocide stratagem and has left long-term health concerns for<br />

victims’ reproductive organs and psychological well-being. 14<br />

Systematic rape and other sexual violence has also been a ‘hallmark’ of the nine-year<br />

conflict in Sierra Leone, where thousands of cases have been reported of<br />

individual/gang rapes, sexual assaults by inserting firewood and umbrellas etc into<br />

women’s genitilia, combined with other forms of sexual slavery and mutilation. 15<br />

7 Ibid, 14.<br />

8 C. Niarchos (n5) 689.<br />

9 Ibid 652-3.<br />

10 Ibid 662.<br />

11 Ibid 670.<br />

12 Ibid 656-7.<br />

13 Ibid 657-8.<br />

14 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on Violence against Women: Report of the mission to<br />

Rwanda on the issues of violence against women in situations of armed conflict’ (4 Feb 1998) UN Doc<br />

E/CN.4/1998/54/Add.1, 11.<br />

15 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on violence against women, its causes and consequences:<br />

Violence against women perpetrated and/ or condoned by the State during times of armed conflict<br />

(1997-2000)’ (n6) 28-29.<br />

40


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Even in smaller conflicts that do not amount to civil war, the rape of women is used<br />

as a means to insert power and dominance over a population. For example, in Haiti,<br />

where the country has been plagued with political unrest for decades, rape and other<br />

violence against women has been utilised as a form of ‘political pressure’ to ensure<br />

democratic suppression and the maintenance of a totalitarian regime in the country. 16<br />

Similarly, Human Rights Watch have recently documented that in Cote d’Ivoire, State<br />

forces have raped and killed women in far western villages where it is perceived that<br />

they may be supporters of the political opposition party. 17<br />

The rape of women during conflicts has relentless and lasting consequences affecting<br />

every aspect of a victim’s life. Women have been rejected by family members<br />

because they are seen to be ‘ruined’ and ‘dishonoured’. A sad example of this<br />

occurring is in the conflict between West Pakistan and Bangladesh, where<br />

Bangladeshi women were routinely raped by the other side and sent to military<br />

brothels. They were then unable to return to their families and husbands because they<br />

had been outcaste and degraded. 18 There are also acute concerns for the female child<br />

that is subject to sexual violence because of the greater psychological trauma that they<br />

are likely to suffer. The likelihood of contracting sexually transmitted diseases,<br />

especially for those girls that are not yet sexually mature, is also increased. Socially, it<br />

is much harder for them to reintegrate back into their families once the conflict is over.<br />

This is especially so if their ‘marriage’ to a soldier has been for a long time and that is<br />

the only life that they have come to know as reality. 19<br />

I(b)– Domestic Violence<br />

The correlation between domestic violence and violence during war is also a major<br />

concern. Evidence has shown how women are not only more vulnerable to outside<br />

violence during conflicts; they are also at higher risk from suffering at the hands of<br />

their loved ones within their own home. 20 For example, in Croatia, domestic violence<br />

against women had increased by nearly 30 per cent since the outbreak of war. 21 The<br />

situation in the Occupied Palestinian Territory also tells a similar story of gender<br />

inequality being more pronounced by the conflict situation. The increased poverty and<br />

social tensions within the region are contributing factors to the escalated domestic<br />

violence due to patriarchal rule being used as a ‘defence mechanism to keep the<br />

society intact’. 22 Refugee camps and detention facilities are another area where<br />

women are subject to violence in the post-conflict phase. For example, in Burundi,<br />

women have suffered high levels of sexual and domestic violence by other refugees<br />

16 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on violence against women, its causes and consequences:<br />

Report on the mission to Haiti’ (27 January 2000) UN Doc E/CN.4/2000/68/Add.3. 12.<br />

17<br />

Human Rights Watch, ‘Newsletter: The Week in Rights’<br />

accessed 14 April 2011.<br />

18 C. Niarchos (n5) 667.<br />

19 (n6) 16.<br />

20 Ibid, 18.<br />

21 C. Niarchos (n5) 671.<br />

22 UNHRC, ‘Report of the Special Rapporteur on violence against women, its causes and<br />

consequences: Mission to Occupied Palestinian Territory’ (2 February 2005) E/CN.4/2005/72/Add.4,<br />

14.<br />

41


Violence Against Women During Armed Conflicts<br />

and men living near to the refugee camps. 23 The fact that domestic violence escalates<br />

during armed conflicts reveals the diverse forms of violence that women suffer during<br />

wartime and how they can find no safe-haven anywhere. Effective international<br />

policies are necessary and must be implemented in order to eradicate these problems<br />

in the future.<br />

I(c) – The Post-conflict setting and the role of UN Peace-keepers<br />

There has been a shocking revelation that women must also fear violence from UN<br />

peacekeepers that are sent into a country post-conflict to try and restore the rule of<br />

law into the affected country. This is a disturbing reminder of the universal<br />

acceptance that women can be treated violently within warzones without being<br />

provided with any legal protection. Peacekeepers have been accused of engaging in<br />

sex-trafficking, soliciting prostitution, forcing children into prostitution and fathering<br />

babies which they have then left behind. 24 It was in 2004 that the media became<br />

aware of the abuses that were taking place in the UN mission to the Democratic<br />

Republic of the Congo (DRC), which then led to an official enquiry. In 2005 alone,<br />

340 cases of abuse and sexual exploitation by peacekeepers were reported. 25 The<br />

actual figures are likely to be much higher because these only represent the statistics<br />

of those willing to come forward and reveal that they were sexually abused by UN<br />

officials. Also, despite recent figures showing a decrease in sexual violence by<br />

peacekeepers, the serious risk of sexual abuse still exists. For example, in 2007, 800<br />

peacekeepers were suspended from their work in Cote d’Ivoire on allegations that<br />

they had engaged in sex with minors. 26<br />

Women in conflict zones become more vulnerable to abuse due to poverty and<br />

unemployment, which makes prostitution seem like the only way possible to earn<br />

money. However, the professional role that peacekeepers take to advance peace and<br />

protect the local population whilst working for the UN, makes it even more<br />

reprehensible that they have taken part in the sexual exploitation of women. 27 There is<br />

also the human rights concern for those abandoned babies that are provided with no<br />

money and protection from their fathers. Figures reveal that an estimated 24,500<br />

babies were fathered by peacekeepers in Cambodia alone. 28 Ndulo validly asserts that<br />

the magnitude of violence perpetuated on women during UN missions must mean that<br />

peacekeepers either believe that their actions are not wrong or that they will not be<br />

held accountable. This means that there is a need for better accountability<br />

mechanisms within the UN to address the problem of sexual violence against women<br />

and girls by peacekeepers. 29<br />

23 (n6) 22.<br />

24 M.Ndulo, ‘The United Nations Responses to the Sexual Abuse of Women and Girls during<br />

Peacekeeping missions’(2009) 27 Berkeley Journal of International Law, 129.<br />

25 Ibid 142.<br />

26 Ibid 143.<br />

27 Ibid 146.<br />

28 M.Ndulo (n24) 157.<br />

29 Ibid 144.<br />

42


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

II – IHL and its Inadequate Protections for Women<br />

IHL is the law that governs armed conflicts and is therefore the first place that we<br />

should turn to see if women are sufficiently protected against violence in international<br />

law. The specific provisions dealing with the protection of women are found in the<br />

Geneva Conventions which state that ‘women shall be especially protected against<br />

any attack on their honour, in particular against rape, enforced prostitution, or any<br />

form of indecent assault.’ 30 This demonstrates how IHL is a gender-biased law that<br />

only sees rape as a challenge to ‘honour’ rather than a violent attack on women<br />

because of their gender. 31 By linking rape to honour, it fails to recognise the brutal<br />

assault that take place on a woman’s body and psyche. It also links with society’s<br />

perceptions that women are disgraced and deserve to be outcaste once they have<br />

suffered this violence. Moreover, Article 147 of the Fourth Geneva Convention does<br />

not describe rape as a ‘grave breach’ which refutes the serious and damaging effects<br />

of rape and denies that it deserves universal jurisdiction. 32<br />

Nevertheless, some progress has been made with the 1977 Additional Protocols to the<br />

Geneva Conventions which prohibit ‘outrages upon personal dignity’. This includes<br />

rape, forced prostitution and any other degrading treatment. 33 However, the reference<br />

to ‘personal dignity’ still fails to recognise the seriousness of rape by giving it a<br />

secondary status in IHL. Another issue is that despite the improvements that have<br />

been made for women through the Protocols, their protective scope is limited because<br />

they are not widely ratified and do not amount to customary international law. 34<br />

Charlesworth and Gardam also reveal how a mighty 43 provisions of the Geneva<br />

Conventions and their protocols actually deal with women and the effects of armed<br />

conflict, yet they still remain inadequate because they only ‘deal with women in<br />

relation to others and not as individuals in their own right.’ 35 Gardam is also correct in<br />

believing that IHL looks at the protection of women from a male perspective, which<br />

therefore ensures that the laws remain inherently discriminatory and unjust. 36<br />

Women’s concerns are presented as less important compared to those of men because<br />

the language of ‘protection’ is used rather than ‘prohibition’. 37 Gardam suggests that a<br />

new protocol to protect women in times of armed conflict is necessary and is an<br />

achievable goal. 38 However, another more credible option would be to focus on<br />

reconceptualising the rules that already exist by mainstreaming gender issues within<br />

them. 39 Whatever method is used, it is clear that IHL needs to be revised so that it<br />

30 Article 27 of the Fourth Geneva Convention 1949.<br />

31 C. Niarchos (n5) 672.<br />

32 Ibid 674.<br />

33 See Article 75 and 76 Additional Protocol I 1977 and Article 4 Additional Protocol II of the Geneva<br />

Conventions.<br />

34 C. Niarchos (n5) 676.<br />

35 J. Gardam and H. Charlesworth, ‘Protection of women in armed conflict’ (2000)22 Human Rights<br />

Quarterly, 159.<br />

36 Ibid 67.<br />

37 Ibid 159.<br />

38 J. Gardam, ‘Women and the law of armed conflict: Why the silence?’ (1997) International<br />

Comparative Law Quarterly, 77.<br />

39 J. Gardam and H. Charlesworth (n35) 164.<br />

43


Violence Against Women During Armed Conflicts<br />

recognises rape as a distinct form of warfare that is used to persecute women because<br />

of their gender. 40<br />

III – International Awareness and the Progress made for Women during Armed<br />

Conflicts<br />

Despite all of the issues raised above, there has been a recent awareness made in<br />

international law to try and recognise the extent of the violence that women endure<br />

during armed conflicts. The progress that has been made will now be looked at to<br />

determine whether it is now time to focus on something other than violence against<br />

women.<br />

III(a) – International Criminal Tribunals<br />

After the grave human rights abuses that took place in the former Yugoslavia and<br />

Rwanda, a change in politics was necessary to ensure that mass rape as part of a<br />

genocide mission could never take place again. As a result, the International Criminal<br />

Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) and the International Criminal Tribunal<br />

for Rwanda (ICTR) were set up to bring accountability and future deterrence to those<br />

responsible for human rights abuses within these regions. The International Tribunals<br />

have played a crucial role in reforming international law so that it properly takes into<br />

account the violence that women face during armed conflicts. The ICTY has ‘played a<br />

critical role in setting jurisprudential benchmarks for the prosecution of wartime<br />

sexual violence’ because for the first time, crimes of sexual assault have been deemed<br />

to be grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions. They have also been given the status<br />

of crimes against humanity, war crimes and genocide. 41 These are welcomed<br />

improvements that have finally recognised sexual violence against women as a major<br />

concern within armed conflicts that is in need of greater accountability mechanisms.<br />

The ICTY decided in the cases of Tadic 42 and Blaskic 43 that rape and sexual violence<br />

can form part of a widespread and systematic campaign of terror that will amount to<br />

crimes against humanity and war crimes. The cases are significant because they<br />

accept that sexual violence in and of itself does not need to be widespread and<br />

systematic; it can be a constituent element of a widespread campaign of violence. 44<br />

This ensures that single acts of rape which are just as damaging to an individual, will<br />

not go unpunished. Furthermore, the ICTY also held that rape can amount to an act of<br />

torture 45 and that individuals may be charged with crimes of sexual violence alone,<br />

without requiring any other form of war crime to be committed. For example, in the<br />

Furundzija case 46 , a person was prosecuted for the first time, for crimes of sexual<br />

40 C. Niarchos (n5) 679.<br />

41 (n6) 9.<br />

42 Prosecutor v Dusco Tadic ICTY-94-1-T (14 th July 1997).<br />

43 Prosecutor v Tihomir Blaškić ICTY-94-1-A (2000)<br />

44 (n6) 9-10.<br />

45 Celibici Camp ICTY-96-21-T (16 th November 1998).<br />

46 Prosecutor v Furunzija (Judgement) ICTY-95-17/1- (10 th December 1998).<br />

44


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

violence alone. The Tribunal also confirmed how oral sex could be considered a form<br />

of rape as well as other ‘serious sexual assault[s] falling short of penetration’. 47<br />

The ICTR’s contribution to the sexual violence discourse has also been highly<br />

influential. In Akayesu 48 , the Court proclaimed that sexual violence can form an<br />

essential element to a genocide campaign. The ICTR applied a broad definition to<br />

what can amount to a crime of sexual violence by claiming that acts other than sexual<br />

penetration- such as forced nudity- can also fall within this notion. 49 The International<br />

Tribunals have taken a much broader understanding of what constitutes ‘rape’ than<br />

many domestic legal systems have been willing to recognise. This is a positive<br />

advancement in international law because it aims to prevent impunity for all forms of<br />

violence that may be committed against women during conflicts.<br />

Another recent achievement has been the creation of the ad hoc ‘Women’s<br />

International War Crimes Tribunal’ that was set up in the year 2000 in Japan. This<br />

Tribunal had to consider the liability of Japanese military and political officials for the<br />

State-endorsed ‘comfort system’ that was used in the 1930’s and 1940’s to rape and<br />

sexually enslave women from all across the Asia-Pacific region. The Tribunal was set<br />

up 56 years after the actual crimes had been committed, which reveals how human<br />

rights activists had worked relentlessly to ensure that crimes against women were not<br />

left forgotten and unprosecuted.<br />

The Women’s Tribunal decided that the fact that the comfort system lasted over 13<br />

years with ‘literally thousands of facilities’ across some dozen countries, adequately<br />

proved how the top authorities must have been involved in implementing the<br />

system. 50 Therefore, Japan had breached many of its treaty obligations and<br />

international laws- so the State should apologise to the rape victims and provide them<br />

with compensation. This demonstrates how outside actors can help to bring State’s to<br />

accountability for their actions, which is a remarkable step forward for women’s<br />

rights. Nevertheless, the Tokyo Tribunal’s recommendations can only ‘encourage’<br />

and ‘influence’ the State of Japan, providing no binding rules that must be followed. 51<br />

Therefore, Japan is able to ignore the findings and recommendations that have been<br />

made by the Tribunal in the same way that they have been denying their responsibility<br />

for the comfort systems for the past 56 plus years.<br />

III(b) – The ICC and UN Security Council Resolutions<br />

Another major turning point has been the UN’s recognition that violence against<br />

women during conflicts needs to end. Security Council Resolutions 1325(2000) and<br />

1820(2008) have been passed, which call on all parties to a conflict to take special<br />

measures to protect women and girls against violence. This significantly portrays how<br />

the UN regards the prevention of violence against women to be a peace and security<br />

issue 52 as well as a humanitarian concern. It also means that the need to protect<br />

47 Ibid at [186].<br />

48 ICTR- 96-4-T (2 nd October 1998).<br />

49 (n6)12-13.<br />

50 Transcript of the Oral Judgement delivered on 4 th December 2001 by the Judges of the Women’s<br />

International War Crimes Tribunal on Japan’s Military Sexual Slavery [90]-[91].<br />

51 Ibid at [70].<br />

52 M.Ndulo (n24) 133.<br />

45


Violence Against Women During Armed Conflicts<br />

women from violence has moved into ‘high politics’ which gives the issue a sense of<br />

importance and urgency that did not previously exist. 53<br />

The ICC Statute also provides another invaluable contribution to ensuring greater<br />

protection for women against violence by explicitly stating that rape and other gender<br />

violence is seriously prohibited and can constitute crimes of genocide and crimes<br />

against humanity. Article 7(1)(f) clearly claims that ‘rape, sexual slavery, enforced<br />

prostitution, forced pregnancy, enforced sterilization, or any other form of sexual<br />

violence of comparable gravity’ can constitute crimes against humanity. In addition,<br />

Article 7(1)(g) depicts how persecution of individuals because of their gender is<br />

impermissible under international law. The ICC Statute further states that judges and<br />

advisers with specific expertise on sexual and gender violence should be appointed to<br />

ensure that proper skill and attention is given to the issue of violence against women.<br />

The ICC Statute has made major progress in international law because gender-based<br />

crimes are no longer linked to a woman’s honour or dignity. 54 It also depicts how<br />

violence against women is worthy of international prohibition and prosecution.<br />

However, although the groundwork is there to suggest that we can move away from<br />

the focus on violence against women, it is submitted that the International Criminal<br />

Court does not protect women to the extent that is necessary to allow for a shift in<br />

attention. O’Connell has shown how the ICC has been unable to adequately deal with<br />

gender-based crimes due to a lack of effective investigations and substantial proof to<br />

prosecute individuals. For example, in the case of Lubunga 55 , the individual in<br />

question was not charged with any gender based crimes despite common knowledge<br />

that he had committed mass rape and violence against women in the DRC. Similarly,<br />

with the cases of Katanga and Ngudjolo 56 , the ICC was only able to charge the<br />

individuals for some of the gender based crimes that they had committed, thus<br />

amounting to partial justice for the victims concerned. 57<br />

Another disadvantage is that certain definitions within the ICC Statute are<br />

incompatible with women’s rights. Article 7(2)(f) proclaims that forced pregnancy is<br />

only prohibited when the perpetrator has an ‘intent’ to affect the ethnic composition<br />

of any population. This raises the serious concern as to why all forced pregnancies are<br />

not prohibited regardless of intent. The definition of ‘gender’ in Article 7(3) is also<br />

problematic because it relies on the biological differentiation between men and<br />

women, rather than taking a more acceptable approach that looks at the social<br />

construction of gender. 58 Furthermore, the Court only has competence to deal with<br />

those cases where States have consented in giving the ICC jurisdiction. Therefore,<br />

State impunity can flourish when States decide to not bring a case forward to the<br />

Court. Moreover, the ICC only has the capacity to deal with crimes that reach a<br />

53 R. Charli Carpenter, ‘Recognising gender-based violence against civilian men and boys in conflict<br />

situations’ (2006) 37 Security Dialogue, 85.<br />

54 S. O’Connell, ‘Gender based crimes at the International Criminal Court’ (2010) 1 Plymouth Law<br />

Review, 71.<br />

55 ICC-01/04-01/06.<br />

56 ICC-01/05-01/08.<br />

57 S. O’Connell (n54) 73-75.<br />

58 (n6) 9.<br />

46


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

sufficient gravity threshold, meaning that all instances of violence against women<br />

during armed conflicts cannot be prosecuted by the ICC. 59<br />

IV – Violence Against Men During Armed Conflicts<br />

Although the discussion has thus far been focused on the violence that women are<br />

subjected to during armed conflict, there has recently been a growing concern that the<br />

gender-based violence that men face in wartime has been left largely undocumented<br />

and ignored. Therefore, it is submitted that it is time to take a more synchronised<br />

approach that incorporates the male victim into wartime sexual-violence discourse. 60<br />

This is because it would add greater validity to the mission to end gender-based<br />

violence in totum; whether it concerns a male or female victim. As DelZotto and<br />

Jones rightfully state, the sexual violence suffered by men in wartime is no less<br />

traumatic than that which affects women 61 , which is why a gender-neutral multidimensional<br />

stance is necessary to help both men and women fight against sexual<br />

violence in the future. 62<br />

Sexual violence against men has taken place in all conflicts throughout history.<br />

Different forms of male rape occur, such as forcing victims to rape fellow victims as<br />

well as having objects inserted into their bodies. 63 Enforced sterilisation can also take<br />

place, with castration and other forms of mutilation being a common occurrence. For<br />

example, in Tadic 64 it was recalled how victims were forced to bite off other men’s<br />

testicles and were forced to perform oral sex on other victims. In addition, men have<br />

suffered from enforced nudity and enforced masturbation during conflicts. 65 The most<br />

recent example of the former occurring is in Abu Ghraib where photographic proof<br />

revealed how male detainees were forced to take off their clothes and wear women’s<br />

underwear over their heads. They were also forcibly placed into sexually derogatory<br />

positions whilst naked and were then photographed. 66 The main question is whether<br />

or not it is sufficient for these cases to come under inhuman and degrading treatment/<br />

torture, rather than under the separate category of gender-based violence? Although<br />

claiming that these actions are torture would not be wrong, it could have the effect of<br />

denying that men too, can be victims of gender-based violence.<br />

Sexual violence against men takes place for the same reasons that sexual violence<br />

against women occurs, which portrays a similarity between both forms of violence.<br />

Male sexual violence is used to disempower the victim and to rob them of their<br />

masculinity through sodomy, forced nudity and castrations. It is also used to assert<br />

power and dominance over the individual in the same way that happens with violence<br />

59 S. O’Connell (n54) 78-9.<br />

60 A. DelZotto and A. Jones, ‘Male-on-Male Sexual Violence in Wartime: Human Rights’ Last<br />

Taboo?’ accessed 4 April 2011.<br />

61 Ibid.<br />

62 S. Sivakurmaran, ‘Sexual violence against men in armed conflict’ (2007) 18 European Journal of<br />

International Law, 260.<br />

63 Ibid 263-4.<br />

64 Prosecutor v Dusko Tadic, Opinion and Judgement, IT-94-I-T.<br />

65 S. Sivakurmaran (n62)265-6.<br />

66 Ibid 256.<br />

47


Violence Against Women During Armed Conflicts<br />

against women. 67 It humiliates and stigmatises the victim and can have horrific<br />

physical and mental consequences. 68 A powerful indication of the suffering that<br />

gender-based violence can cause to men is the fact that they have been forced to rape<br />

their own daughters. They have also been made to stand and watch their female<br />

relatives being sexually abused. Little has been documented on the trauma that men<br />

must face when seeing this happen and the psychological impact that this must have. 69<br />

The improvements that have been made to recognise the violence that women face in<br />

wartimes has had a negative impact on male victims because of their complete nonrepresentation.<br />

For example, it has been claimed that no international organisation or<br />

NGO has established a research programme that focuses on male victims of sexual<br />

violence. 70 Male sufferers are less likely to admit that they have been subject to sexual<br />

violence because of the stigma and fear this can cause. There is also a lack of<br />

experienced professionals who look out for the signs of males being abused because<br />

of the greater focus on women victims. 71 This is a big problem because although we<br />

know that sexual violence against men exists in conflicts, we have no idea about the<br />

extent to which this occurs. 72 There is also a lack of sufficient humanitarian assistance<br />

available for male rape survivors, which is likely to have damaging consequences. 73<br />

Therefore, Carpenter makes the valid assertion that it is impossible to know whether<br />

women suffer more sexual violence during armed conflict than men, because no<br />

comparable data exists. 74<br />

Gender-stereotyping needs to be eradicated 75 and it has been argued that ‘the single<br />

biggest gap in programming’ needs to be closed. 76 Although a real concern exists that<br />

gender-mainstreaming could move the focus away from women and solely onto men,<br />

this could be avoided if both male and female violence is dealt with concurrently<br />

rather than as separate issues. 77 There needs to be a shift from focusing only on the<br />

violence that women face in armed conflicts because male victims are currently left<br />

voiceless, defenceless and unprotected by international law. In the same way that<br />

gender-equality cannot occur without considering the effects on both men and<br />

women; gender-based violence against women cannot be solved without also dealing<br />

with the violence that men similarly face in matching circumstances.<br />

67 Ibid 270.<br />

68 W. Russel, ‘Sexual violence against men and boys’ (2007) 27 Forced Migration Review, 22.<br />

69 R. Charli Carpenter (n53) 96.<br />

70 A. DelZotto and A. Jones (n60).<br />

71 S. Sivakurmaran (n62) 256.<br />

72 Ibid, 254.<br />

73 R. Charli Carpenter (n53) 95.<br />

74 Ibid 87-88.<br />

75 S. Sivakurmaran (n62) 275.<br />

76 R. Charli Carpenter (n53) 87.<br />

77 Ibid 99.<br />

48


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

V – Conclusion<br />

This paper has demonstrated the concerns that exist for women in conflict zones<br />

because of the mass violence that they are subjected to because of their gender.<br />

Current deficiencies in IHL and the recent improvements that have been made for<br />

women in international law have also been looked at to reveal how slow progress is<br />

taking place to allow for greater protections for women; yet many deficiencies still<br />

exist that need to be resolved. Nonetheless, a slight change of focus is necessary by<br />

looking at the gender-based violence that both men and women face in conflicts.<br />

There still remains a major gap between the laws that have been put in place and the<br />

political will of Member States to enforce these laws. Violence against women is the<br />

most effective indication of the extent to which gender inequality exists throughout<br />

every society across the world. It is a form of discriminatory force that is used to<br />

degrade women by enforcing male dominance within domestic and social settings.<br />

Despite this paper focussing on armed conflict settings, it must be remembered that<br />

women are equally vulnerable in times of peace and in times of conflict because all<br />

cultural backdrops have enabled men to exert arbitrary power over women. Only<br />

when complete gender equality exists in every society across the world, will violence<br />

against women no longer be a major global concern.<br />

49


WAS THE ABOLITION OF THE DOCTRINE OF DOLI INCAPAX<br />

NECESSARY?<br />

Hannah Wishart, Manchester University<br />

Abstract: This article considers how the 1997 New Labour election has changed what<br />

it means to hold children criminally responsible in the criminal law. In order to do so,<br />

this article will focus on examining New Labour’s decision to abolish the<br />

longstanding doctrinal defence of doli incapax via asking whether the abolition of the<br />

doctrine of doli incapax was necessary and founded upon proper grounds given the<br />

low age of criminal responsibility imposed. As a result of such an enquiry it will be<br />

revealed legal academics are still questioning the doctrine’s existence in the criminal<br />

law more than 15 years after its abolition.<br />

I – Introduction<br />

Since New Labour succeeded as the new elected Government in 1997 the Youth<br />

Justice System in England and Wales has been subjected to numerous changes. 1 One<br />

of the biggest changes to the youth justice system came in the immediate aftermath of<br />

the 1997 Government election when, the then Shadow Home Secretary, Jack Straw<br />

MP, proposed a ‘six point policy plan for juvenile crime and disorder’. 2 In his speech,<br />

Jack Straw proposed that the ‘New Labour’ Government were determined to<br />

encapsulate a future where ‘young offenders plans to promote better parenting in the<br />

family home to tackling anti-social behaviour. 3 It was the Government’s decision to<br />

endorse a ‘No More Excuses’ 4 mentality through axing the common law defence of<br />

doli incapax 5 which is the focus of this article. The reason why this decision was<br />

greeted with such widespread concern was because the Government was moving<br />

away from thinking of children as victims in need of ‘welfare’ protection within the<br />

law, for a political inspired conception of children which encompassed a promise:<br />

‘tough on crime, tough on the causes of crime’. 6 Jack Straw presented the above<br />

agenda through New Labour’s fourth policy point as follows:<br />

“At present we have medieval law-doli incapax- which assumes that<br />

youngsters 10-13 are “incapable of evil” unless the prosecution can<br />

prove the reverse. This legal presumption makes it very difficult for<br />

youth courts to convict young offenders and start the process of<br />

changing their offending behaviour.” 7<br />

When it was announced the doctrine of doli incapax would be removed from the remit<br />

of the criminal law, as mentioned, it caused much widespread concern in the legal<br />

1 The Independent Commission on Youth Crime and Antisocial Behaviour, Responding to Crime and<br />

Antisocial Behaviour, 2010, pp.11-12<br />

2 Home Office, Crime Justice and Protecting the Public, (HMSO, 1990) CM 965, at para 8.3<br />

3 Supra note. 2<br />

4 Home Office, No More Excuses, (HMSO, 1997a) p.1<br />

5 House of Commons Debates 19 th May, 1997, Column 387.<br />

6 Home Office, No More Excuses, (HMSO, 1997a) p. 1<br />

7 Supra note. 4


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

community. 8 To Keating 9 and Elliot 10 this is due to the fact that the abolition could<br />

cause severe ramifications whereby children reaching the age of 10 years of age 11<br />

would be exposed to the rigidity of the English criminal justice system with no<br />

available defence which confirms that the child’s mental and physical status (although<br />

in some cases this may not be true) would not the same as any adult offender. 12 In fact,<br />

long after Jack Straw’s 1997 statement proclaiming that New Labour were to remove<br />

the doctrine of doli incapax and the abolition itself in The Crime and Disorder Act<br />

(1998) contrary to Section 34: ‘the rebuttable presumption of criminal law that a child<br />

aged 10 or over is incapable of committing an offence is hereby abolished.’ The legal<br />

community is still referring to and commenting on the 1997 decision and therein the<br />

abolition in 1998. To many legal academics this is arguably the case because they are<br />

displeased with its removal and how the English justice system currently treats,<br />

approaches and punishes children: 15 years after the abolition of the defence of doli<br />

incapax. 13<br />

II – The Minimum Age of Criminal Responsibility<br />

The age of criminal responsibility connotes the age at which the criminal justice<br />

system can bring proceedings against an autonomous person for a criminal offence. 14<br />

When the criminal court convicts the defendant of a crime, the defendant is to be held<br />

criminally responsible and punished for breaking the criminal law. 15 In England and<br />

Wales the minimum age of criminal responsibility is 10 years of age contrary to S.16<br />

of The Children and Young Persons Act (1969). 16 Any child under 10 years of age is<br />

therefore deemed to have legal immunity from the full rigours of the criminal justice<br />

system.<br />

Legal commentators have regularly made reference in youth crime literature to the<br />

assumption that children below 10 years of age are subsequently ‘incapable of<br />

committing evil’. 17 Yet no reference has been made as to what sort of ‘evil’ acts the<br />

child was incapable of committing or how incompetent the child typically would have<br />

been below 10 years of age to make them fully immune from the criminal law.<br />

Traditionally, this line of thinking derived from the establishment of the ‘right and<br />

wrong’ responsibility tests implemented by 14 th century common law judges in order<br />

8<br />

crimes.html <br />

http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/1561917/Children-under-10-suspected-of-3000-<br />

9 Keating. H, ‘The Responsibility of Children in the Criminal Law’, 19 Child and Family Law<br />

Quarterly, 2007 at 2<br />

10 Elliott. C, ‘Criminal Responsibility and Children: A New Defence Required to Acknowledge the<br />

Absence of Capacity and Choice’, 75 Journal of Criminal Law, (2001) at 296<br />

11 The Criminal Justice Act (1963)<br />

12 Wiejers. I, Duff. R. A, Punishing Juveniles, Principle and Critique, Hart Publishing, 2002, p. 116<br />

13 The Independent Commission on Youth Crime and Antisocial Behaviour, Responding to Crime and<br />

Antisocial Behaviour, 2010, pp.11-12<br />

14 Tadros. V, Criminal Responsibility, Oxford University Press, 2005, p.21<br />

15 Supra note. 14<br />

16 Section 16 of The Children and Young Persons Act (1969)<br />

17 Arthur. R, Young Offenders and the Law, How the Law Responds to Youth Offending, Routledge,<br />

2010, p.43<br />

51


52<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

to determine the child’s competency between positive acts and crimes. 18 For<br />

Blackstone the determination of criminal responsibility rested with a test which<br />

considered whether the child defendant was able to discern between ‘good and evil’<br />

based on the strength of the child’s mental processing of judgement and the capacity<br />

of understanding the difference between the two. 19 Arguably, this does not mean that<br />

a child of 7 years as a consequence is incapable of committing a crime if the child is<br />

morally unaware of what is ‘right and wrong’ or ‘good and evil’ today, merely<br />

because legislation supports children from 10 years of age as legally blameworthy for<br />

breaking the criminal law: this can be quite the opposite. 20 From 32 out of 43 police<br />

forces around the country in 2007 revealed that almost 3,000 crimes were committed<br />

by children under 10 years of age. 21 Yet given the statutory age of criminal<br />

responsibility in England and Wales a child below 10 years of age will continue to be<br />

held unaccountable for committing crimes.<br />

Compared with the rest of Europe, England and Wales can be considered to have one<br />

of the lowest thresholds for criminal responsibility: currently 10 years of age. 22 This is<br />

indicative when in contrast other countries such as; Norway (15 years), Spain (16<br />

years) and Belgium (18 years of age). 23 Even the United Nations Committee on the<br />

Rights of the Child in 2007 expressed that a minimum age of criminal responsibility<br />

below that of 12 years of age is to be considered ‘internationally unacceptable’. 24 To<br />

the United Nations this is because children respectively under 12 years of age do not<br />

have the capacity, ability and maturity to infringe the law akin the reasonable adult<br />

offender. 25 Yet the criminal justice system in this country will punish children for<br />

crimes at the age of 10 irrespective of international recommendations and European<br />

practices. From the child’s point of view, the child will be held criminally responsible<br />

for breaking the law alike the adult offender; yet unlike the adult offender, the child<br />

may only have limited and or inaccessibility to legal right of passages in England and<br />

Wales. Legislation prohibits a child from purchasing small animals until 16 years of<br />

age, 26 buy fireworks 27 and similarly buy alcohol until 18 years of age. 28 This is<br />

perhaps why there has been much concern with regards to the decision to abolish the<br />

doctrine of doli incapax; given the fact that New Labour may have failed to take into<br />

account what it means to be entirely responsible in the law. In this case, it not only<br />

18 Crofts. T, The Criminal Responsibility of Children and Young Persons, A Comparison of English<br />

and German Law, Ashgate, 2002, p. 8-13<br />

19 Blackstone, 1769:23-4<br />

20 Fionda. J, Devils and Angels Youth Policy and Crime, Hart Publishing, 2005, p.12<br />

21<br />

crimes.html <br />

http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/uknews/1561917/Children-under-10-suspected-of-3000-<br />

22 Section 16 of The Children and Young Persons Act (1969)<br />

23 Millet. S. P, ‘The Age of Criminal Responsibility in an Era of Violence: Has Great Britain Set a New<br />

International Standard’, 28 Vanderbilt Journal of Tranational Law, (1995) at 295<br />

24 United Nations Committe on the Rights of the Child, Convention: Children’s Rights in Juvenile<br />

Justice, (2007) CRC/C/GC/10, paragraph 32.<br />

25 Ibid n. 24 para. 31.<br />

26 Contrary to The Animal Welfare Act (2007)<br />

27 The Fireworks Regulation (2004) Section. 4<br />

28 The Licensing Act (2003) Section. 145


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

means that one is to be held to a standard of criminal responsibility for not upholding<br />

the law but it also means that one has a certain level of individual autonomy to<br />

perform justified actions which are entitlements and arguably a testament to one’s age<br />

and degree of responsibility within society. Today there is a considerable age-gap<br />

and discrepancies between the degrees of responsibility a child must be expected to<br />

uphold, as opposed to what the child will receive in return for being subjected to<br />

criminal responsibility. This is clearly evident with how the rest of Europe rationalises<br />

a higher age of criminal responsibility and responds in the criminal law in contrast to<br />

England and Wales.<br />

III – The Legal Theory of Criminal Responsibility<br />

When reconciling the attachment of criminal responsibility theorist Dubber<br />

transcribes the criminal law should be concerned with answering one single question:<br />

‘who is liable for what? 29 From this style of questioning within the criminal law it is<br />

easy to contend with why Jack Straw articulated that the doctrine ought to be removed.<br />

Generally, when the criminal court convicts a defendant for an offence the defendant<br />

is held to be criminal responsible for his conduct. 30 From this it can be contended that<br />

the idea of being held to a standard of criminal responsibility is central to the criminal<br />

justice system. The reason why can to some extent be considered simple; most<br />

theorists 31 hypothesise that the criminal law’s primary concern is to prevent harm and<br />

to do so involves determining the defendant’s degree of culpability, so as to bestow a<br />

proportionate punishment for the commission of the offence. 32<br />

Some theorists further speculate that the criminal law should act retributively or<br />

employ a theory of restorative utilitarianism to prevent harm from occurring in the<br />

future. 33 A retributivist theorist, for example, would be concerned with determining<br />

the degree of the defendant’s criminal responsibility from the ethos of ‘no one can<br />

justly be punished unless he is morally responsible’. 34 In contrast, Tadros believes<br />

that it may not be morally ‘just’ to punish the young or mentally fragile agents for<br />

crimes, when it could be argued they did not possess a sound and competent mind. 35<br />

Clearly, it is plausibly within the remit of a child to make a rational choice, for<br />

example to steal money so he can buy food, or kill a man out of an emotional loss of<br />

self control as seen in DPP v Camplin. 36 Nevertheless, the question that is persistently<br />

being raised in criminal law literature is whether the law should hold either of these<br />

children (given their situations) as morally responsible agents for their lacking in<br />

moral emotions and understanding of right and wrong? For Arenella, the justification<br />

for attributing criminal responsibility falls onto the ideological notion of justice that<br />

29 Dubber. M. D, Criminal Law: Model Penal Code, New York University Press, 2000, p.5<br />

30 Alexander. L, Ferzan. K. K, & Morse. S, Crime and Culpability A Theory of Criminal Law,<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2009, p.4-5<br />

31 Duff. R. A, ‘Harms and Wrong’, Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 2001, Vol 5 at 13<br />

32 Alexander. L, Ferzan. K. K, & Morse. S, Crime and Culpability A Theory of Criminal Law,<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2009, p.4-5<br />

33 Fletcher. G, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law, OUP, 1998, p.30<br />

34 Williams. G, ‘The Criminal Responsibility of Children’, 1954, Crim LR at 494<br />

35 Tadros. V, Criminal Responsibility, OUP, 2004, p. 134<br />

36 DPP v Camplin (1978) AC 705<br />

53


54<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

the criminal law is to punish on the basis of what the offender deserves. 37<br />

Subsequently this would mean that regardless of the age of the defendant, if it is<br />

known that a defendant fulfilled the actus reus and mens reus of an offence, 38 they<br />

deserve punishment because of the harm that has been produced. 39 This is perhaps<br />

regardless of the England and Wales minimum age of criminal responsibility. 40<br />

Yet as Elliott contemplates there is a difference between accountability and<br />

responsibility for the purposes of attaching criminal liability. 41 This is due to the fact<br />

that there are specific preconditions for imposing criminal responsibility which do not<br />

solely relate to what can be proven through what the defendant performed with<br />

regards to sufficing the actus reus of the crime. 42 This can be seen from Hart’s<br />

paradigm of criminal responsibility:<br />

“Those....we punish should have had, when they acted, the normal<br />

capacities, physical and mental, for abstaining from what it forbids,<br />

and a fair opportunity to exercise these capacities.” 43<br />

When courts determine the defendant’s degree of criminal responsibility, Hart has<br />

demonstrated that two limbs are necessary; the defendant must possess the minimum<br />

levels of mental and physical capacities and have a fair opportunity to perform the<br />

defendant’s attributed capabilities. 44 Presuming, that a defendant did in fact have a<br />

‘fair opportunity’ to act in accordance with their capabilities, what is of crucial<br />

importance in determining criminality, as opposed to moral accountability for one’s<br />

actions; arguably comes from questioning and determining the characteristics of the<br />

defendant. It may be that these characteristics are obvious when one generally<br />

compares children to adults. For instance, a child of 12 years of age may be<br />

considerably smaller in height and weight in contrast to that of a 40 year old muscular<br />

6ft tall man. Neuroscience research reflects these observations because biologically a<br />

child of 10 years of age does not have the same physical composition to that of an<br />

adult. 45 An average adult’s height and weight ratios physically differ to that of a child.<br />

An adult has greater muscle mass to protect their organs from many severe injuries. 46<br />

Children on the other hand have smaller pliable skeleton systems which account for<br />

their small bones and physical appearance. 47 These physical dissimilarities<br />

37 Arenella. P, ‘Character, Choice and Moral Agency: The relevance of Character to our Moral<br />

Culpability Judgements’, Social Philosophy and Policy, Vol 7(2), 1990 at 62<br />

38 Arthur. R, Young Offenders and The Law, How the Law Responds to Youth Offending, Routledge<br />

Press, 2010, p. 43<br />

39 Dubber. M. D, Criminal Law: Model Penal Code, New York University Press, 2000, p.5<br />

40 Ibid note. 39<br />

41 Elliott. C, ‘Criminal Responsibility: A New Defence Requirement to Acknowledge the Absence of<br />

Capacity and Choice’, 75 Journal of Criminal Law, 2011 at 302.<br />

42 Ibid note. 41<br />

43 Hart. H. L. A, Punishment and Responsibility, Oxford University Press, 2008, p. 152.<br />

44 Ibid note. 43<br />

45 The Royal Society, Brian Waves: Module 4 Neuroscience and the Law, December 2011, p.14.<br />

46 http://www.ehow.com/info_8501147_characteristics-adults-vs-children.html<br />

47 Ibid note. 46


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

independent from any other information affirm that children are not on-par so-tospeak<br />

to the average adult.<br />

Notwithstanding the noticeable physiological differences, it could be correspondingly<br />

stated that children are different to adults when one examines the mental and<br />

emotional characteristics of both children and adults. The latest neuroscience research<br />

provides that up until the age of at least 20 years children undergo many comparable<br />

changes in mental, emotion and physical functioning such as: decision-making,<br />

impulsivity, memory and puberty. 48 Although it may be the case that in some court<br />

proceedings a child may exhibit the same mental and physical attributes, or as Hart<br />

refers ‘normal capacities’ to that of an adult offender. 49 Yet questioning who the<br />

defendant is can be of crucial importance, because whether the defendant is in fact a<br />

child of 11 years of age as opposed to an adult offender of 25 years of age. This could<br />

potentially effect and determine how the defendant acts, because their mental and<br />

physical attributes may significantly differ. If a child of 10 years struggles to<br />

communicate to another child in a playground how can such a child be considered to<br />

have the same normal capacities akin to the average adult for the purposes of<br />

attaching criminal responsibility and punishment? This is perhaps why there has been<br />

such widespread scrutiny and warning since the abolition as the doctrine understood<br />

and protected children who exhibited less than ‘normal’ mental, emotional and<br />

physical capacities. 50 Today, a child who exhibits less than normal adult capacities<br />

would be left without a doli incapax defence.<br />

IV – The Meaning of doli incapax<br />

The doctrine of doli incapax operated in England and Wales as a tool with two<br />

significant purposes. Firstly, it bestowed children below the minimum age of criminal<br />

responsibility with exemption from the criminal law. 51 Secondly, it provided children<br />

from the minimum age of criminal responsibly to 13 years of age with a defence<br />

which recognised the possibility that some children (emphasis placed on some, and<br />

not all children) were incapable of understanding the truancy of his or her(s) criminal<br />

actions because they did not have the prerequisite ‘normal’ 52 capacities akin to the<br />

adult offender. This was encapsulated through the use of a rebuttable presumption. 53<br />

The rebuttable presumption sanctioned the prosecution to adduce evidence to infer<br />

that the youth offender had the knowledge and an understanding of the seriousness of<br />

their actions in order to attach criminal responsibility. 54 In order to do so, Goff LJ in<br />

JM (A Minor) v Runeckles (1984) 55 illustrated in finding the child mentally and<br />

physically capable akin to the adult offender, the prosecution were prohibited from<br />

revealing evidence of the child’s actions as being naughty or mischievous. The<br />

48 The Royal Society, Brian Waves: Module 4 Neuroscience and the Law, December 2011, p.14.<br />

49 Hart. H. L. A, (2008), p. 152<br />

50 Refer to discussion on page one<br />

51 S.34 of The Crime and Disorder Act (1998)<br />

52 Hart. H. L. A, (2008), p. 152<br />

53 Goldson. B, Muncie. J, Youth Crime and Justice: Critical Issue, Sage Publications, 2006, p.12<br />

54 Pickford. J, Youth Justice: Theory and Practice, Cavendish Publishing, 2000, p. 56<br />

55 JM (A Minor) v Runeckles (1984) 79 Cr App R 255<br />

55


56<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

evidence must have gravitated towards adducing the seriousness and graveness of the<br />

child’s actions as confirmed in R v Gorrie. 56 It is worth to note that evidence of<br />

observation cannot deduce evidence of the child’s criminality: A v DPP (1992) 57<br />

bequests as much. So the courts were informed to avoid:<br />

“The trap of applying the presumption of normality.. that any child of<br />

the appellant’s age in today’s society would know perfectly well that to<br />

behave in this way was to behave in a way that was seriously<br />

wrong”. 58<br />

The presumption was on the prosecution to find if the child was fully capable and<br />

aware of the serious nature of their actions. Only then would the child take criminal<br />

responsibility for their actions barring the above procedural determinations. 59 The<br />

famous publicised case of the murder of James Bulger shows the rebuttable<br />

presumption in practice. From the psychiatric assessments of the two co-defendants,<br />

Thompson and Venables, the prosecution revealed that both children were capable of<br />

knowing right from wrong. 60 To Jack Straw ‘both children were appropriately made<br />

responsible for their actions’. 61 The two co-defendants, Thompson and Venables,<br />

were charged with murdering James Bulger. Their guilt was not merely weighted<br />

upon the presumption that they were capable of understanding the truancy of their<br />

actions. Both defendants were judged by 12 jurors who were instructed to assess their<br />

blameworthiness according to the standard of proof of ‘beyond reasonable doubt’ for<br />

the death of James Bulger. 62 From the 12 jurors’ assessment of evidence provided by<br />

the defence and prosecution, the two defendants were held criminally responsible.<br />

From this perspective it is hard to assimilate at this stage, why the government<br />

decided to abolish the doctrine of doli incapax. Historically, the doctrine had dealt<br />

with hundreds of youth cases in its time, concluding when necessary (upon the<br />

individual merits of the child) whether a child was capable of understanding the<br />

nature of his actions to be held criminally culpable. 63<br />

Thus far, it could be claimed the doctrine of doli incapax served its purpose in relation<br />

to Straw’s proposition in being able to punish young offenders for committing<br />

criminal offences. The murder convictions of Venables and Thompson was clearly<br />

indicative of the doctrine’s ability to perform in a manner which inculpates rather<br />

exculpates children for their criminal behaviour. 64 Even if it could have been<br />

established (with the use of the doctrine of doli incapax) the defendants’ did not<br />

understand their heinous actions; the doctrine of doli incapax upon this basis could<br />

56 Gorrie (1918) 83 J.P 136<br />

57 A v DPP (1992) Crim LR 34<br />

58 W (A Minor) v DPP (1996) Crim LR 320<br />

59 Ibid note. 58<br />

60 R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Venables; R v Secretary of State for the<br />

Home Department, ex parte Thompson (1997) 4 LRC 411<br />

61 Ibid note. 60<br />

62 Ibid note. 60<br />

63 See A v DPP (1992) Crim LR 34<br />

64 Supra note. 60


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

have exculpated the youths for the killing of Bulger. Although this was not the case,<br />

the doctrine plausibly served its purpose with regards to its basic core functions: to<br />

either provide a defence or inculpate on the basis of the rebuttable presumption for the<br />

co-defendants. Yet New Labour were of the opinion that it was still necessary to<br />

remove the doctrine’s defence and presumption from the remit of the criminal law<br />

because they were of the belief that it failed to make young offenders as criminally<br />

responsible for their conduct when in operation. 65<br />

V – The Emergence of ‘New Labour’<br />

‘New Labour’ in an attempt to learn from the administrational mistakes of the<br />

previous elected party conveyed a message to the public in relation to youth crime in<br />

England and Wales. 66 The message was that Labour was to take action by ‘getting a<br />

grip on youth crime’. 67 A 1997Home Office White Paper titled: ‘Tackling Youth<br />

Crime’ maintained the changes Labour wished to undertake. The paper concluded that<br />

New Labour’s agenda was to modernise the youth justice system by abolishing the<br />

doctrine of doli incapax. 68 One of the reasons why is presented in paragraph 14, the<br />

government believed at that particular time there would be practical difficulties if the<br />

rebuttable presumption existed because there would be an increase in youth offenders<br />

relying on the defence of doli incapax. 69<br />

Ironically, the rebuttable presumption undermined any ‘benevolent protection’ which<br />

was recognised by the defence of doli incapax. 70 Bandalli suggested that academic<br />

opinion was swayed toward the doctrine being misconceived, because public and<br />

media outlets connoted the child as being ‘misspent’ 71 and capable at the age of 5<br />

years of age of knowing the difference between right and wrong. 72 The representation<br />

of the ‘misspent’ child merely reflects how the new agenda was interwoven in the<br />

judicial system. As Lord Lowry in C v DPP 73 observed that when the courts lacked<br />

cogent evidence; the courts ‘often treat the rebuttal as a formality’. And in the<br />

magistrates’ courts ‘in practice, juvenile courts rarely look(ed) 74 at the doli incapax<br />

requirement’. 75 This is further evidenced by a 1992 police sample which showed 76.2<br />

percent of juvenile suspects confessed their guilt in police interviews; and at this<br />

65 Supra note. 4<br />

66 Supra note. 4<br />

67 Michael. A, Getting a Grip on Youth Crime, London Labour Party, 1993<br />

68 Home Office, Tackling Youth Crime: Reforming Youth Justice, Consultation Paper, London HMSO,<br />

1997<br />

69 Ibid n. 68<br />

70 Crofts. T, ‘Rebutting the Principle of Doli Incapax’, JCL 62(2), 1998 at 185<br />

71 Audit Commission, Misspent Youth...Young People and Crime, London, Audit Commission, 1996<br />

72 Bandalli. S, ‘Abolition of the Presumption of Doli Incapax and the Criminalisation of Children’, The<br />

Howard Journal, 37(2), 1998 at 115<br />

73 C (A Minor) v DPP (1995) 2 All ER 43, p.63D-F; Manchester 1986:8<br />

74 Word Added<br />

75 Ibid n. 68<br />

57


58<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

phase it is worth highlighting that in the criminal justice process the rebuttable<br />

presumption could only be used when in court. 76<br />

This information may have supported New Labour’s core incentives to make young<br />

offenders criminally responsible for their actions in a way which excluded the<br />

doctrine of doli incapax. Yet taking into consideration that the doctrine was only used<br />

in court, the apparent ineffectiveness of the doctrine could not have been justified<br />

simply from the number of guilty pleas given in police stations. 77 This line of<br />

reasoning was evidentially weak, even if the doctrine was applicable and used by<br />

children in the police processing stages prior to it being used in the courts as a<br />

defence. From the evidence presented above, the Government’s claim that the<br />

doctrine’s functionality was hindering criminal prosecution may not have had<br />

anything to do with fearing that the doctrine was inadequate or ineffective when it<br />

tried to inculpate with regards to the presumption. In the House of Lords decision of<br />

C (A Minor) v DPP Lord Lowry was of a similar belief when he inscribed that there<br />

were ‘popular and political overtones’ 78 which surrounded the abolition. 79 To note<br />

there was a possibility that further use of the doctrine would subject children to a<br />

future defence in criminal proceedings, if not abolished in 1998. However research<br />

has advocated that no such problem existed whereby more children would have relied<br />

on the doctrine: the presumption was rarely used. The portion of youth offenders<br />

pleading guilty in the magistrates was 81 percent and a mere 7 percent was due to a<br />

shortage of trials in 1995. 80 This in itself infers that perhaps the problems New Labour<br />

where justifying were imagined since Lord Parker CJ in B v R was still of the belief<br />

that 'the lower the child in the scale between 10 and 14, the stronger the evidence<br />

necessary to rebut the presumption'. 81<br />

VI – Was the Abolition Necessary?<br />

It would seem reasonable to assume that the decision to remove the doctrine of doli<br />

incapax from the law would have been one of conclusiveness. The doctrine of doli<br />

incapax was thought to be an irrelevant tool the criminal law no longer needed given<br />

Jack Straw’s opinion of it being a ‘medieval law... which assumed that youngsters<br />

between 10-13 were “incapable of evil”. 82 Yet for the courts to still be subjected to<br />

questioning, replying and presiding over the doctrine of doli incapax, even though<br />

S.34 clearly stated that the doctrine, including the presumption, was abolished in 1998<br />

merely reveals that the courts are still struggling to bridge the gap between imposing<br />

criminality liability and young offenders when taking into account the physiological,<br />

mental and emotional underdevelopments of children. 83<br />

76 Evans. R, ‘The Conduct of Police Interviews with Juveniles’, The Royal Commission on Criminal<br />

Justice Research, Study 8, London: HMSO<br />

77 Loc cit note 4<br />

78 C (A Minor) v DPP [1995] 2 W.L.R. 383<br />

79 Lynch. J, ‘Hello Doli, The Case for the return of the Presumption’, Archbold Review, 2010, at 4<br />

80 Home Office, Criminal Statistics For England and Wales, 1995, table 6.2<br />

81 B v R (1958) 44 Cr App R1<br />

82 Jack Straw, Labour Government Speech to Police Federation, 21/05/1997<br />

83 Supra note. 10


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

This was clearly evident in R v JTB (2009). The appellant (charged with committing<br />

several counts of sexual activities) sought advice from the House of Lords because he<br />

believed that he was unaware of the wrongness of his actions. 84 To note in 2009 it<br />

was generally explicit to the courts from Section 13 of The Sexual Offences Act<br />

(2003) that the youth (from the evidence presented) had committed the identified<br />

counts of sexual activities. Yet this criminal offence once rested upon a rebuttable<br />

presumption, akin to that of the doctrine of doli incapax. A presumption was<br />

implemented to minors under the 14 years of age in order to relieve children from<br />

criminal responsibility. Alike the doctrine of doli incapax’s abolition in 1998 this<br />

presumption was removed from the ambit of the criminal law by the way of The<br />

Sexual Offences Act (1993).<br />

If doing away with the doctrine of doli incapax was the correct and necessary decision<br />

since it was regarded as no longer needed; then, why would the appellant seek advice<br />

in relation to the doctrine when it had been clearly discontinued for 11 years? This<br />

was the problem in Crown Prosecution Service v P (2007) 85 when it was contended<br />

that P did not have a sufficient level of maturity and capacity to understand criminal<br />

proceedings or an ability to understand the serious nature of his actions. 86 . Several<br />

psychiatric reports concluded P was unfit to stand the trial process. 87 However many<br />

judges were still of the belief that the doctrine existed, Smith L.J is an example of this<br />

when he reconciled that if ‘the effect of s.34 [of the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) is<br />

to abolish the presumption that a child is doli incapax but not the defence itself.’ 88 If,<br />

as Jack Straw mentioned New Labour’s aim was to hold youth offenders criminally<br />

responsible in a way that ‘gets a grip on youth crime’; 89 presumably, parliament ought<br />

to have enshrined a clear intention to abolish the doctrine: including the defence and<br />

presumption in 1998. The then Solicitor- General gave a different opinion on the<br />

matter in the second reading of Crown v P:<br />

'The possibility is not ruled out, where there is a child who has genuine<br />

learning difficulties and who is genuinely at sea on the question of<br />

right and wrong, of seeking to run that as a special defence. All that the<br />

provision does is to remove the presumption that the child is incapable<br />

of wrong' 90<br />

Clearly, it is obvious from the Solicitor-General’s opinion in Crown v P there was<br />

(perhaps still is an) imperative to hold on to the defence of the doctrine of doli<br />

incapax, because it is possible children do not possess the minimum capacity<br />

standards to be held criminally responsible. If the government’s aspirations were to<br />

‘get a grip on crime’, as it has been frequently referenced as such in this article it<br />

seems precarious given the above judicial interpretations of S. 34 and the New<br />

Labour’s aims and objectives (to abolish the doctrine) that their true intentions were<br />

84 R v JTB (2009) UKHL 20<br />

85 Crown Prosecution Service v P (2007) EWHC 946<br />

86 Ibid note. 85<br />

87 Ibid note. 85<br />

88 (2007) 171 JP 349 at 351<br />

89 Michael. A, Getting a Grip on Youth Crime, London Labour Party, 1993<br />

90 (Hansard, HL, vol. 584, cols 595-596, 16 December 1997).<br />

59


60<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

not clearly specified in legislation. 91 Arguably, it could be retained there were clear<br />

indicators as to parliament’s underlying intentions. Crofts determined from a Home<br />

Office circular that children from the minimum age of criminal responsibility (10<br />

years) will be treated as the same as any other adult offender. 92 Yet this report could<br />

not have singlehandedly justified the intended construal and meaning of S.34. This is<br />

visibly indicative when one considers the then Solicitor-General’s reasoning of the<br />

possibility that the underlying doctrinal principle may have even evaded abolition. 93<br />

To Williams regardless of the mischief interpretation of S.34 the criminal law comes<br />

down to a simple annotation:<br />

“As a matter of policy it is highly desirable that a child who has<br />

committed what, for an adult, would be a crime, should be put to<br />

answer, even if he is afterwards acquitted on the ground that he did not<br />

know his act to be wrong”. 94<br />

The logic of Williams’ statement envisions a strong retributivist node of thinking,<br />

which it could be argued would contravene with Article 6(2) of the European<br />

Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) because ‘everyone charged with a criminal<br />

offence shall be presumed innocent until proved guilty according to law.’ 95 If the<br />

child must be ‘put to answer’ in a manner which would neglect Hart’s preconditions<br />

of criminal responsibility, there could be a motivation which initially infers guilt for<br />

the crime performed, based upon who the defendant is. This could be the case as<br />

Williams’ remarks it could be ‘just’ to articulate that the law ought to respond to<br />

attaching criminal responsibility from political policy standpoints; but would<br />

Williams strong view differ if the defendant was P?<br />

It could be maintained that for a defendant like P being ‘put to answer’ 96 may not be<br />

the correct approach. A fair trial can only appropriately function when there is a<br />

defendant who has the understanding and capacity to identify the rationale of the<br />

court trial itself and inter alia comprehend the wrongness of their actions. 97 The<br />

European Court of Human Rights similarly advocates the same rationale that a<br />

defendant should be fit to stand trial contrary to Article 6. 98 As a result in P it was the<br />

Divisional Court decided that court proceedings were premature in the light of the<br />

defendant’s lack of capacity to distinguish right from wrong. 99<br />

Therefore, can Williams’ desirable imperative to impose court proceedings upon a<br />

minor who has below the minimum mental and physical capacities as P benefit the<br />

criminal law? A weak retributivist who places consequentialist considerations at the<br />

91 Walker. N, ‘The End of an Old Song’, NLJ (1999) 149 at 64<br />

92 Crofts. T, ‘Divisional Court: Children: Doli Incapax’, JoCL (2008) 72(8)<br />

93 Supra n. 85<br />

94 Williams. G. L, ‘The Criminal Responsibility of Children’, Criminal Law Review, (1954), 493, at<br />

498<br />

95 Article 6(2) of The European Convention of Human Rights<br />

96 Telford. M, ‘Youth Justice: New Shoots on a bleak landscape - - Director of Public Prosecution v P’,<br />

CFLQ (2007) at 506<br />

97 Wortley. N, ‘No Defence of Doli Incapax: R v JTB (2009) UKHL 20’, 73 J. Crim L (2009) at 309<br />

98 SC v United Kingdom (2004) 40 EHRR 10<br />

99 R v JTB UKHL 20


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

heart of the criminal law may support Williams’ contention to make a young offender<br />

stand trial. 100 Presumably, if the young offender had the pertinent level of<br />

understanding to withstand the trail process with an ability to convey the truancy of<br />

their actions, then perhaps Williams’ proposal could be conducive. Yet unless there is<br />

an additional good benefit to make a defendant like P be ‘put to answer’, Williams<br />

may fail to receive support from a retributivist. 101 When the doctrine of doli incapax<br />

was in operation the doctrine (defence and presumption) shielded the child from the<br />

damage ensued from the criminal justice system. 102 Whether or not the presumption<br />

itself actually made or prevented convictions can only be a matter of fact, Keating<br />

claimed the presumption served as a broad shielding ensemble ‘marking the transition<br />

stage of a child’s life as special’. 103 Subsequently, once the abolition of the doctrine of<br />

doli incapax materialised the protective function ceased to exist. Today youth<br />

offenders like P and R v G (2003) 104 will be as a result subjected to the full rigours of<br />

the criminal law.<br />

The doctrinal test is unquestionably flawed, it cannot be denied that the doctrine did<br />

not go through a process of uncertainty with regards to developing a test to determine<br />

if a youth was aware of the seriousness of his/her actions, as opposed to being<br />

naughty and mischievous. 105 The doctrine (presumption) has never been consistently<br />

applied in practice as a result the doctrine was akin to inconsistent verdicts. 106 It<br />

follows then that Laws J observed in C (A Minor) that the presumption was a<br />

‘disservice to the criminal law’. 107 At the time the abolition of the doctrine of doli<br />

incapax may have been the correct decision, because it has been argued it was an<br />

outdated concept that could not reflect the improvements to formal education and the<br />

knowledge acquired through schooling. 108 It has been contended by several academics<br />

that the child today may have greater access to education consequently youths are<br />

more likely to be aware of the seriousness of their actions, but this questionably does<br />

not infer that all children can distinguish right from wrong or comprehend the<br />

seriousness of his actions. 109<br />

The doctrine represented a universal perception to which it can and has been declared<br />

some children should not be called to answer for their wrongdoing because of their<br />

diminished understanding and capacities of acting. The recent case of R v CM<br />

(2011) 110 supports that the doctrine is considered as a lost tool within the criminal<br />

justice system as a safeguard for the young offender who was likely to re-offend, who<br />

100 Crime and Culpability, (2009), p. 7<br />

101 Supra n. 94<br />

102 Keating. H, ‘Reckless Children?’, Crim L Rev (2007) at 550<br />

103 Ibid note above. 102<br />

104 R v G (2003) UKHL 50; (2004) 1 AC 1034 HL<br />

105 Supra note. 54<br />

106 C (A Minor) v DPP (1995) 1 AC 1, 33 39<br />

107 C (A Minor) v DPP (1995) 1 Cr App R 118<br />

108 Supra note. 53<br />

109 Association of Child Welfare Agencies, Newsletter 2000<br />

110 R v CM (2011) NICC8<br />

61


62<br />

The Doctrine of Doli Incapax<br />

also lacked consequential thinking, capacity and control. 111 For Duff he believed it is<br />

perfectly acceptable for society to desire that both the juvenile and adult offender<br />

should be held to answer for their criminal actions because harm has still ensued. 112<br />

Nonetheless, Duff have even questioned whether a child with diminished capacities<br />

(or lack there-of) ought to be the object of the court processes, be held liable and open<br />

to punishment as a result. 113<br />

VII – Conclusion<br />

It has been made clear that 10 years of age has emblematic significance in the<br />

criminal justice system as the starting age for criminal responsibility. This may be<br />

why it has been sympathetically pleasing to an academic to claim that the doctrine or<br />

rather the rebuttable presumption, in fact co-existed, acting as an intermediary for the<br />

low age of criminal responsibility. As Smith proclaimed the criminal law 'holds that a<br />

person is completely irresponsible on the day before his tenth birthday, and fully<br />

responsible as soon as the jelly and ice-cream have been cleared away the following<br />

day'. 114 As a result, it may well be perfectly acceptable to hold onto traditional<br />

childhood concepts of ‘innocence’ and ‘frailty’; because it ought to be thought that a<br />

safeguard should be in place to shelter the child from the criminal law. The doctrine<br />

of doli incapax operated by revealing evidence of a child’s cognitive development,<br />

thus liability if any could be affixed upon the child for the unlawful acts performed.<br />

Then again as Douglas noted, social attitudes towards children have changed since the<br />

uprising of political overtones, tension have mounted children are not considered<br />

innocent or merely naughty. 115 Social retribution and ‘using the criminal law as a<br />

weapon’ has taken focus. 116 To that end criminal responsibility now does not solely<br />

rest upon the child’s development as the doctrine of doli incapax once did: the issue is<br />

one of policy and policy considerations. 117<br />

Those in favour of the return of the doctrine of doli incapax propose that the doctrine<br />

could have been modified to manifest a positive attitude of judicial consistency and<br />

certainty. 118 Perhaps, the presumption and defence could have coexisted amicably.<br />

The White Paper ‘Tackling Crime’ proposed changes to the doctrine: the paper<br />

concluded that there were two options available. Firstly, the presumption could<br />

remain if the rebuttable onus shifted onto the defence, where the defence had to prove<br />

upon the balance of probabilities that the child did not know that his actions were<br />

seriously wrong. 119 This preference was openly favoured in JBH & JH (Minors) v<br />

O’Connell (1981) 120 and by Williams. 121 However the shift of the burden may still<br />

111 Ibid note above. 110<br />

112 Duff (2002) p. 131<br />

113 Ibid note. 112<br />

114 Smith. A.T.H, 'Doli Incapax under Threat' (1994) CLJ 426, at 427<br />

115 Douglas. G, 'The Child's Right to make Mistakes: Criminal Responsibility and the Immature Minor'<br />

in Douglas. G, and Sebba. L, Children's Rights and Traditional Values, Ashgate, (1998), p. 265<br />

116 Keating. H, (2007) at 195<br />

117 Keating. H, (2007) at 189<br />

118 Duff, (2002), p. 131<br />

119 Supra note. 57<br />

120 JBH & JH (Minors) v O’Connell (1981) Crim LR 632


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

create practical difficulties because securing a conviction may lead to the child in<br />

every case relying on the defence of doli incapax. 122 Ultimately this is why it was<br />

determined that the doctrine should respectfully be abolished.<br />

If the doctrine is not the answer, Duff has proposed that the courts should reverently<br />

have reservations not about whether the juvenile should be punished, but how the<br />

juvenile is punished. 123 A radical enquiry into this may well shed light on the need to<br />

reform and restore the juvenile’s life and educate them on right and wrong; as<br />

opposed to retributively punishing and casting the child into abyss. Inevitably this<br />

could still provide inconsistent punishments, if the courts were presiding over<br />

Venable and Thompson again, the heinousness of the crime and the retributive public<br />

outrage may well place Williams policy reasons and the spectacle of ‘putting them to<br />

answer’ 124 before the restorative reconciliation vision by Duff.<br />

In this article there has been a spirit of political substance infused right the way<br />

through which may well have provided the incentive to abolish the doctrine of doli<br />

incapax. There have been strong views in favour of the doctrines restoration and<br />

contrasting views contending that the doctrine reverently created an evading facade<br />

for not making youth offenders’ criminally responsible for their actions. Both Fionda<br />

and Keating have concurrently determined that the abolition and the youth justice<br />

system have been shaped by policy incentives. 125 Therefore the future challenge is not<br />

with debating if the youth had or did not have capacity, but how policy can be aptly<br />

shaped in the future. 126 Keating further suggested that if policy is the core incentive<br />

behind any change the question that needs to be answered is ‘why is it inappropriate<br />

to punish a youth?’ 127 This question it could be contended has aptly been applied in R<br />

v CM, notwithstanding the youth’s diminished mental capacity mentioned previously,<br />

the court still found an incentive (whether or not the conviction was politically<br />

motivated is uncertain) the youth was convicted and punished for the crimes<br />

committed. 128 This may reflect policy being shaped too strongly by retributivism,<br />

however it may be perfectly understandable to impose liability to the deserving for the<br />

harm caused regardless of the underlining stimulus. 129 On the other hand policy<br />

should also delve into the value and benefit of punishment when it concerns youth<br />

offenders. Perhaps the reason why Keating has posed the above question is because<br />

retributivism, punishment and political undertones are unavoidable. It is possible the<br />

only way forward is to accept that the future of the youth criminal justice system has<br />

no doli incapax-type defence. In the end it could be summarised that the doctrine of<br />

doli incapax, the shield and presumption, could be a lost cause.<br />

121 Williams. G, (1954) at 498<br />

122 Bandalli. S, (1998) at 115<br />

123 Weijers. I, Duff. R. A, Punishing Juveniles: Principle and Critique, Hart Publishing, 2002, p. 131<br />

124 Supra n. 30<br />

125 Keating, (2007) at 189<br />

126 Ibid note above. 125<br />

127 Ibid n. 125<br />

128 Supra n. 110<br />

129 Supra note. 30<br />

63


BATTLING BOLAM; DOCTORS 1, PATIENTS 0<br />

Dr Kim F Castle, Bangor University<br />

Florence Nightingale’s statement that ‘the very first requirement in a Hospital that it<br />

should do the sick no harm’ 1 would seem to be self-evident. Unfortunately, the fact is<br />

that for many the hospital is not a safe place; not the haven that the sick crave but a<br />

place fraught with potential dangers ranging from the careless and/or negligent<br />

activities of those who staff the ‘hallowed’ halls and also a potential cesspit alive with<br />

the modern day ‘super bugs’. Although medicine is now high powered, complex and<br />

operates in a high pressure environment, it is paramount to appreciate that health care<br />

is reliant on people more often than on machines. It is the ‘human factor’ that<br />

accounts for errors made and they must be addressed.<br />

It is clear that the number of cases finding clinical negligence has increased<br />

dramatically 2 and continues to rise at an alarming rate despite procedures<br />

implemented to ensure that safeguards with regard to clinical practice are built into<br />

the system. Improved risk management and regular audits of a clinician’s work in<br />

conjunction with the requirement of annual validation with regard to an individual’s<br />

clinical work are now mandatory but still the ‘bad apples’ are slipping through the net<br />

as it were. It would appear that the odds are stacked in a physician’s favour at least<br />

partly because the profession can employ the ‘Bolam Test’ to avoid the attachment of<br />

any blame for injuries or death that may have resulted from nonchalant clinical<br />

practice.<br />

Mr Justice McNair enunciated the locus classicus of the test with respect to clinical<br />

negligence in Bolam 3 when in directing the jury he stated that ‘…a doctor is not guilty<br />

of negligence in a medical claim if he has acted in accordance with a practice<br />

accepted as proper by a responsible body of medical men skilled in that particular<br />

art…putting it the other way round, a doctor is not negligent if he is acting in<br />

accordance with such a practice, merely because there is a body of opinion that takes<br />

a contrary view’. 4 Thus the ‘Bolam Test’ entered the annals of medico-legal law and<br />

has for over 50 years allowed medical practitioners to avoid the consequences of their<br />

actions or inactions. 5 Therein lies the rub for it is patently obvious that simply by<br />

concurring with the actions of another the legal repercussions pertaining to remiss<br />

clinical practices are avoided, perhaps wrongly so as all should be held accountable<br />

for injury done to others.<br />

1 Florence Nightingale, Notes on Hospitals (John W Parker and Sons 1859).<br />

2 Sir Liam Donaldson (Chief Medical Officer) ‘Making Amends’. A Report commissioned and<br />

published in 2003 cited an increase of 1200% in reported cases of clinical negligence over the 30 years<br />

preceding publication. This is a consultation paper setting out government proposals for reforming the<br />

approach to clinical negligence in the NHS.<br />

3 Bolam v Friern Hospital Management Committee [1957] 1 WLR 582.<br />

4 The direction given to the jury by McNair J in Bolam V Friern Hospital management Committee<br />

[1957] 2 All ER 118 at 122, [1957] 1 WLR 583 at 587.<br />

5 Kim Castle ‘Medical negligence: The Pathology of The Responsible Man’; Dissertation produced in<br />

April 2010 at The School of Law, Bangor University, North Wales.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

It could be contended that the Bolam test is no longer tenable in this modern world<br />

given that the realms of cyberspace are ever expanding such that there is now a wealth<br />

of information available to the enquiring mind with the consequence that the mystique<br />

which has characterised the medical profession is becoming more transparent. 6<br />

Consequently, ‘Joe Public’ no longer accepts that a physician’s word is gospel and<br />

irrefutable; they are fallible 7 and should be made to answer for their poor performance,<br />

particularly when the consequences can be devastating for both the afflicted and their<br />

families. All have the right to expect the best from their clinician but the problem for<br />

both parties, the aggrieved and the clinician with regard to allegations of clinical<br />

negligence, is how to prove or disprove the charge as levelled?<br />

When considering the Bolam test it must be remembered that medicine, like law, is in<br />

evolution. The two often run in tandem; developments in medicine can beget changes<br />

in the law as evidenced most dramatically by the major advances that have been made<br />

in the province of human infertility such that the Human Fertilisation and<br />

Embryology Act 8 came onto the statute books in 1990. Thus, regulating the<br />

application of new technology and guarding against unscrupulous, unethical and<br />

immoral practice.<br />

New discoveries are being made every day and, as knowledge expands into<br />

previously uncharted territory, the potential for mishaps is an ever present threat. Sir<br />

Alexander Fleming’s discovery of Penicillin in 1947 heralded a new era in the<br />

treatment of infection but few could have envisaged its import nor the potential for<br />

severe adverse reactions sometimes resulting in death. 9 It must be appreciated that<br />

there are risks associated with all forms of treatment; that which is acceptable must be<br />

balanced against that which is patently not and it is oft a question of ensuring that the<br />

former outweigh the latter. 10 Coupled with this balancing act is the competency or<br />

otherwise of the treating clinician which can quite literally mean the difference<br />

between life, death or severe iatrogenic injury. 11<br />

There is no doubt that the Bolam test is inadequate in this litigious age. It could be<br />

argued that the continued use of Bolam has resulted in a ‘time warp’ with regard to<br />

6 ibid.<br />

7 ibid.<br />

8 The Human Embryology and Fertilisation Act was first entered into the Statute books in 1990 but due<br />

to the rapid advances in medical technology amendments have had to be applied, the most recent in<br />

2008. The principal purpose of the Act is to protect the human embryo and any subsequent<br />

developments relating to an embryo such that those who would seek to exploit the vulnerable are<br />

prevented by law from doing so.<br />

9 Penicillin causes a generalised allergy in 0.7%-10% of cases and acute anaphylaxis, which is<br />

characterised by bronchospasm and sudden death in 0.004-0.015%. It is impossible to predict who will<br />

suffer an adverse reaction until the event occurs. Of course once the allergy is discovered it is<br />

incumbent upon a physician to ensure that the individual never receives the antibiotic again; to<br />

prescribe again would be both negligent and inexcusable. See Nicholas Boon, Nicki R. Colledge, Brian<br />

R. Walker (eds) (Churchill Livingstone Elsevier, 20 th ed, 2006).<br />

10 ibid, page 2.<br />

11 ibid, page 2. Iatrogenic is defined as that which is caused by the actions of physicians. In this modern<br />

age of hospital acquired infections it is of particular relevance but can apply to any procedure or<br />

therapeutic regimen.<br />

65


66<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

this area of medical law; there is in effect a glaring lacuna in the law which is worthy<br />

of both consideration and modification in the 21 st century. Challenge has been<br />

mounted by several high profile cases, the most notable of which is Bolitho 12 but there<br />

is still much that the law can do to clarify this legal minefield which has the potential<br />

to exacerbate harm sustained by all concerned and is indeed deserving of a<br />

satisfactory form of resolution. The reader must appreciate that the Bolam test has<br />

also been applied to other professions including auctioneers and the designers of<br />

double-glazed windows. 13<br />

I – The Tale of a Snail: To Whom do I Owe a Duty of Care?<br />

A gastropod with a predilection for ginger beer and a penchant for cloudy bottles<br />

slithered out of a bottle and into the annals of legal history when it sought refuge in a<br />

bottle of ginger beer. The snail contributed much to the development of the law of tort<br />

with regard to a manufacturer’s liability and the duty of care owed to any potential<br />

customer if it can be proven that there was no opportunity for tampering of the<br />

product between point of origin and use. The tale of the snail pertains to Donoghue v<br />

Stevenson 14 which concerned the appellant and a friend who purchased a bottle of<br />

ginger beer for the former. The unfortunate woman having already consumed half the<br />

drink discovered a partially decomposed snail in the remainder of the drink which<br />

slipped into her glass thereby altering the law of Tort forever. Unsurprisingly the<br />

appellant developed gastroenteritis. She successfully sued the manufacturer for<br />

negligence<br />

That infamous snail not only promoted the development of the law with regard to the<br />

rights of a consumer but also led to Lord Atkin invoking the ‘neighbour principle’<br />

when he stated that: ‘The rule that you are to love your neighbour becomes in law,<br />

you must not injure your neighbour…Who is my neighbour?...Who,…in law is my<br />

neighbour? The answer seems to be persons who are so closely and directly affected<br />

by my act that I ought reasonably have them in contemplation as being so affected<br />

that when I am directing my mind to the acts or omissions which are called into<br />

question.’ 15 That a relationship exists between healthcare staff and patient is selfevident<br />

such that the duty of care is well established but problems arise when this<br />

duty can be called into question.<br />

The relationship between the major players is paramount in this area of law. It cannot<br />

be ‘acquired’ by another. This means that a physician who prescribes medication<br />

which is then taken by another other than the individual for whom it was meant,<br />

cannot generally be held responsible should an adverse event occur to the person who<br />

consumed it. Likewise, the principle of a duty of care owed is not extended to future<br />

contacts of the single patient as was held in Goodwill v BPAS 16 . Duty of care would<br />

12 Bolitho v City and Hackney Health Authority [1997] 4 All ER 771.<br />

13 Examples of the use of Bolam include Luxmoore-May v Messenger May Baverstock [1990] 1 WLR<br />

1009, auctioneers and Adams v Rhymney Valley DC [2000] Lloyd’s Rep PN 777.<br />

14 [1932]AC 562.<br />

15 Murphy J Street on Torts (12 th Edn., Oxford University Press, New York, 2007) Page 24-25. The<br />

famous dictum as enunciated by Lord Atkin in Donoghue v Stephenson [1932] AC 562.<br />

16 [1996] 2 All ER 161. This case concerned a man, M, who underwent a vasectomy whilst still<br />

married and was subsequently informed that the operation had been successful and that contraception


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

extend to only a current partner because although the medical profession are credited<br />

with much that is laudable, they are not clairvoyant. The cases of West Bromwich<br />

Albion v El-Safty 17 and Farraj v King’s Healthcare NHS Trust 18 serve to further<br />

exemplify this point with regard to the law of tort. Lastly, the position of the doctor<br />

who encounters an accident victim must be considered; does a passing doctor owe a<br />

duty of care to the injured? The law recognises that a doctor may act in the best<br />

interests of someone who lacks the capacity to grant consent to treatment 19 but it also<br />

mandates that the doctor must not inflict harm. The latter would indeed incur a charge<br />

of clinical negligence which would be incontestable; however, the provision of<br />

necessary treatment which should have been provided has 20 21 also been<br />

acknowledged. It is of course incumbent upon a general practitioner to treat any of his<br />

patients should he encounter them injured and also upon both ambulance crews and<br />

‘Accident and Emergency’ staff to treat those seeking help. 22<br />

In the context of clinical negligence it is readily apparent that ‘closeness’ exists<br />

between a physician and his patient but when exactly does this relationship arise? At<br />

exactly what point does the transition between ‘stranger’ and ‘patient’ occur? Is it<br />

when a patient registers at a particular surgery or is it when any treatment is initiated?<br />

It is obvious that such a relationship is generated between a patient and medical<br />

institution when advice and help are sought. Recognition of the need for treatment has<br />

already been acknowledged but what if there is a failure to appreciate a said need 23 or<br />

would no longer be required. He later divorced his wife and unfortunately impregnated his new partner.<br />

The plaintiff claimed for earnings lost but the judges dismissed the case as the future sexual partners of<br />

‘M’ could never have been foreseen. It is also interesting to note that 1:2000 male sterilizations fail and<br />

recanalization of the vas deferens can occur, thereby rendering the procedure useless!<br />

17 [2006] EWCA Civ 1299. A doctor was not held liable for the negligent treatment of a footballer<br />

which resulted in financial loss for the club. The physician was not employed by the club; his duty of<br />

care was owed solely to the player.<br />

18 [2006] EWHC 1228(QB). An NHS hospital was held to owe a patient a duty of care after having<br />

commissioned some tests to be performed at a laboratory but subsequently failed to inform the patient<br />

of the results which needed to be acted upon.<br />

19 F v Berkshire HA [1989] 2 All ER 545,567 which concerned the sterilisation of a severely mentally<br />

incapacitated female patient who had started a sexual relationship with a fellow male patient. Given her<br />

mental incapacity she would not cope with any of the means of contraception available so the hospital<br />

sought sterilisation which was allowed on appeal, her mother having contested the action.<br />

20 Powell v Boldaz (1997) 39 BMLR 35. This tragic case concerned the unexpected death of a child<br />

from Addison’s disease which is difficult to diagnose. His parents attempted to claim for psychiatric<br />

injury but it was held that the duty of care was owed to the child not the parents; it did not transfer to<br />

the latter upon receipt of the news of his death.<br />

21 Longmore, Murray et al Oxford Handbook of Clinical Medicine (Oxford University Press, 5 th Edn.,<br />

China, 2001) Page 302. Primary adrenocortical insufficiency, Addison’s disease, is rare, with an<br />

incidence of about 8/1,000,000. It can have a myriad of clinical presentations such that diagnosis is<br />

often only made at autopsy. Accordingly it is a diagnosis that can very easily be overlooked even by<br />

the most experienced of medical practitioners with tragic consequences.<br />

22 Barnett v Chelsea and Kensington Hospital Management Committee [1969] 1QB 428. Three<br />

workmen fell ill after having drunk some tea and presented in the A&E department of the hospital at<br />

which they were working with acute vomiting. The casualty doctor on-call declined to see them,<br />

advising them to see the General Practitioner with whom they were registered. Sadly one died and it<br />

was subsequently discovered that the tea had been laced with arsenic.<br />

23 ibid.<br />

67


68<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

what if the need had been recognised and there was no remedy? Could the unfortunate<br />

physician who chose not to examine a patient be considered negligent in the course of<br />

his duties when there was naught that he could do to avert inevitable death? 24<br />

Does a physician owe a duty of care to the patient who chooses to ignore advice and<br />

either neglect to take medication as advised or simply refuse to do so? 25 Much has<br />

been made of autonomy in a modern world and the duty owed to a patient but surely it<br />

is incumbent upon the patient to recognise that a professional is also owed a duty<br />

which recognises the physician’s right to practise without compromise to their<br />

professional integrity? Responsibility must be assumed by both parties when a<br />

relationship is established; a contract has in effect been formulated between the<br />

parties involved.<br />

With respect to the duty of care owed by a physician or a health institution, could<br />

there ever be a public policy reason for non-prosecution? It may be that an institution<br />

is at fault rather than a particular individual, for example due to poor staffing levels or<br />

lack of suitable equipment; indeed this was recognised in A(A Child) v The Ministry<br />

of Defence 26 wherein a neonate suffered irreversible brain damage at the hands of a<br />

negligent German obstetrician during childbirth. It was held that the NHS had a duty<br />

to provide a safe and satisfactory service to a patient in the aftermath of the closure of<br />

all the British military hospitals in Germany. 27<br />

II – The Tort Trilogy and the Reasonable Man<br />

‘Duty of care’, ‘breach of that duty’ and ‘causation’ constitute the basic tenets with<br />

regard to the law of tort. All were established by reference to the ‘neighbour principle’<br />

and elaborated upon by Lord Wilberforce in Anns v Merton LBC 28 when he<br />

formulated the concept of proximity with regard to the law of tort when considering<br />

the relationship between the parties concerned; could any acts or omissions be<br />

reasonably expected to result in injury or death? Again the ‘closeness’ that exists<br />

between patient and physician must be emphasised.<br />

24 ibid. There is no cure for arsenic poisoning: once a sufficient amount of the poison has been ingested<br />

death is inevitable.<br />

25 John Griffiths and others, ‘Euthanasia and Law in Europe’ (Hart Publishing 2008) 379-380. Garnier,<br />

Conseil d’Etat, 29 July 1994, Rec p 407. Dr Garnier diagnosed breast cancer in a woman who declined<br />

both chemotherapy and radiotherapy against his advice. Instead she opted to undergo homeopathic<br />

treatment which Garnier discussed with her. Two years later she presented with advanced disease and<br />

the admitting doctor reported Garnier to the French regional disciplinary board who found that the<br />

unfortunate doctor had failed to comply with the professional standards expected of him and he was<br />

suspended from his clinical duties for the prescribing of ‘illusory treatments’, therefore depriving the<br />

patient any hope of cure.<br />

26 [2004] EWCA 641. The unfortunate infant was born to the wife of a British serviceman who was<br />

stationed in Germany at the time. The brain damage sustained at birth resulted in cerebral palsy.<br />

27 See also Bull v Devon AHA [1998] QB 730. The hospital operated on 2 sites resulting in the late<br />

arrival of the obstetric registrar which culminated in the delivery of a severely handicapped twin; his<br />

sibling was healthy. The Court of Appeal found that the hospital had failed to provide an acceptable<br />

level of care.<br />

28 [1978] AC 728. The local authority neglected to check that building work commissioned failed to<br />

comply with plans submitted with such that inadequate foundations resulted in structural problems.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

The test of the ‘reasonable man’ is that which is applied in the determination of<br />

negligence; how would the ‘reasonable man’ have acted in the same circumstances<br />

which resulted in the detrimental act/s? 29 The defendant’s actions are viewed<br />

objectively with regard to the harm that ensued but who is the ‘reasonable man’? He<br />

is the ‘man’ who would not perform a negligent act but would be guided by ‘those<br />

considerations which ordinarily regulate human affairs’. 30 Simplistic perhaps, Greer<br />

LJ 31 proffered a definition when he stated that ‘the person concerned is sometimes<br />

described as ‘the man on the street’ or…’the man on the Clapham Omnibus’, or…’the<br />

man who takes the magazines at home and in the evening pushes the lawnmower in<br />

his shirt sleeves.’ 32 It is for the judge to determine if a defendant has behaved as the<br />

‘reasonable man’. The aim of the law of tort is not only to compensate but also to<br />

deter; subsequent medical practice must be influenced by experience, adverse or<br />

otherwise. 33 Importantly, that which is considered negligent relates to available<br />

knowledge at the time of the alleged incident, the ‘retrospectoscope’ cannot be<br />

employed in the determination of negligence. 34<br />

III – Leading Cases Relating to the Common Law Approach on Medical<br />

Negligence<br />

III(a) – Bolam<br />

The case of Bolam is both interesting and horrifying. The claimant suffered from a<br />

bipolar disorder 35 which it was deemed would be greatly alleviated by electroconvulsive<br />

therapy (ECT). 36 Unfortunately the treatment is not without side-effects.<br />

29 Kim Castle ‘Medical negligence: The Pathology of The Responsible Man’; Dissertation produced in<br />

April 2010 at The school of Law, Bangor University, North Wales. Page 5.<br />

30 Chris Turner and Susan Hodge. Unlocking TORTS (Hodder Education, 2 nd Edn., Malta, 2007)<br />

31 Hall v Brooklands Auto-Racing Club [1933] 1KB 205. The case pertained to the killing of two<br />

spectators and the injuring of several others at a racetrack. The owners were accused of failing to<br />

provide adequate safety precautions but they could not have foreseen the accident.<br />

32 ibid Lord Greer at 224.<br />

33 Kim Castle ‘Medical negligence: The Pathology of The Responsible Man’; Dissertation produced in<br />

April 2010 at The school of Law, Bangor University, North Wales. Page 6.<br />

34 Clare Dyer Doctors, Patients and the Law (Blackwell Scientific publications Ltd, 1992, Bodmin)<br />

Chapter one: ‘Medical Negligence’, page 9. The classic case with regard to this area of law is that of<br />

Roe v Ministry of Health [1954]2 QB 66. An anaesthetic agent was stored in glass ampoules which in<br />

turn were immersed in disinfectant. The ampoules developed cracks so allowing the disinfectant to<br />

seep into the drug, thereby contaminating it and resulted in the permanent paralysis when administered<br />

to the plaintiff at operation. This risk was not known in 1947 when the operation was performed.<br />

Accordingly, the risk could not have been foreseen and therefore the defendant was found not guilty of<br />

negligence. Lord Denning commented further by adding that the court ‘must not look at the 1947<br />

accident with 1954 spectacles’.<br />

35 Nicholas A Boon, Nicki R Colledge, Brian R Walker Davidson’s Principles &Practice of Medicine<br />

(Churchill Livingstone Elsevier Limited, 20 th Edn., India 2006) Page 242. A ‘bipolar disorder’, also<br />

known as Manic Depression is one characterised by periods of alternate depressed and elevated moods.<br />

Unfortunately, it is a relapsing disorder and is associated with an increased lifetime risk of suicide.<br />

36 Electro-convulsive therapy is an archaic form of treatment which has aroused much controversy in<br />

the medical world. Opinion is divided as to its efficacy and the manner in which should be<br />

administered; with or without general anaesthesia, plus or minus muscle relaxants. The treatment<br />

developed in the 1930s and initially was used widely in the 1950s and 1960s but has now been mostly<br />

69


70<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

In the short term, convulsions can occur; in the long term, memory loss. Powerful,<br />

sustained convulsions can result in fractures, occurring in 1 in 10,000 treatments. The<br />

procedure is therefore not without risk. Accordingly, some clinicians, when obtaining<br />

consent from the patient, will inform them of these possibilities; however, not all are<br />

of the opinion that the patient should be informed of the potential for fracture injuries.<br />

Clinicians were also divided as to whether or not the patient should simply be<br />

restrained or muscle relaxants administered. Some felt that the latter were associated<br />

with the possibility of death and were to be avoided.<br />

Bolam was not informed of the fracture risk at consent and the only form of restraint<br />

applied during ECT was support to the lower jaw. Muscle relaxants were not<br />

administered. Unfortunately he convulsed violently resulting in bilateral upward<br />

trajectory forces applied to both femora culminating in concomitant bilateral fractures<br />

to the acetabulae with attendant severe pain. 37 Medical opinion was divided as to<br />

whether the treatment fell short of those standards that a physician owes to the patient<br />

or did it conform to ‘sound medical practice’? 38 Some would have used muscle<br />

relaxants and perhaps anaesthetic agents whereas others would have only applied<br />

restraints, and yet both methods have been considered recognised forms of adjunct<br />

treatment when administering ECT. To the lay person such differing ‘recognised’<br />

modes of treatment must make the medical profession seem even more<br />

incomprehensible than their language already does. It is a sobering thought that<br />

treatment methods with the potential for such different outcomes can be considered<br />

acceptable.<br />

III(b) – Dissecting Bolam<br />

Given the impact that this case has had on the issue of medical negligence, it is<br />

worthy of analysis. The essential question to be addressed was whether or not a health<br />

professional had breached the duty of care owed to a patient; seemingly<br />

straightforward, given the assumption that such a relationship always exists between a<br />

doctor and/or nurse and their patient. If one accepts this presumption, the next<br />

question to be answered is what series of events or acts of omission led to the mishap?<br />

The first question is easy to answer but what about the second? The premise as<br />

established in Bolam is that, as long as other ‘reasonable, respectable and responsible’<br />

medical men would have acted in such a manner that could have resulted in injury, no<br />

breach in the duty of care owed had occurred. Fundamental to the law of tort is that<br />

the breach must be proven to have caused the injury and yet this would seem at odds<br />

with the tenet established in Bolam that recognised therapies, despite being associated<br />

with acknowledged side effects, are in effect excusable if others would have done the<br />

replaced by both more modern and humane methods, particularly pharmacological and psychological;<br />

the latter are of a talkative nature! It involves the application of electrodes to the skull and passing an<br />

electric current either across the whole brain or only half of the organ. The procedure is thought to<br />

cause the release of neurotransmitters which are thought to be involved in the aetiology of depressive<br />

disorders. It is of dubious efficacy and can be associated with distressing side-effects both in the short<br />

and long term; hence its fall from grace.<br />

37 Put simply, both thigh bones broke free of his pelvis and pierced his abdomen.<br />

38 --Times Law Report, 27 November 1997. Bolitho v City and Hackney Health Authority. ‘ A court<br />

was not bound to hold that a defendant doctor escaped liability for negligent treatment or diagnosis just<br />

he led evidence from a number of medical experts who were genuinely of the opinion that his treatment<br />

or diagnosis accorded with sound medical practice.’


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

same. It is to be understood that Bolam did not address the question of causation, only<br />

that of the preferential treatment afforded to the patient.<br />

The court accepted that two conflicting opinions as to treatment regimes could still be<br />

regarded as valid if a responsible body agreed that either was acceptable, but what<br />

defines ‘the responsible body’? The medical profession who were to be judged?<br />

Importantly, it meant that the judges were not permitted to choose between competing,<br />

perhaps diametrically opposed, expert views. In effect the judges, being bound by<br />

‘medical judgements’, had their options limited from the outset. It could be argued<br />

that a decision as to whether or not a doctor was guilty of medical negligence was a<br />

fait accompli even before the case went to court; the decision in court had little to do<br />

with the law and perhaps more to do with society’s perception of those who care for<br />

its health.<br />

III(c) – Treatment options<br />

Medicine is not an exact science and there are often several treatment options<br />

available to clinicians. In Bolam there were two options, both of which had the<br />

potential for injury. The ruling in Bolam meant that even if the least popular and<br />

possibly most injurious was chosen, a medical practitioner could not be deemed<br />

negligent even if a potentially life threatening event occurred. As long as a<br />

‘competent body of medical opinion’ 39 accepts that a practice can be regarded as the<br />

norm, it will be acceptable. This is the main tenet upon which Bolam rests.<br />

It is to be appreciated that although several treatment options may be available to the<br />

clinician, it is incumbent upon him/her to choose the most appropriate and administer<br />

accordingly; to simply disagree with new advances is not sufficient reason to choose<br />

an outmoded regime. Another avenue to be explored is that often, in medicine, it is<br />

the terminally ill who are offered new and perhaps untested treatments. After all, they<br />

have nothing to lose and might be more accepting of adverse events; in effect they are<br />

‘human guinea pigs’.<br />

With regard to the incapacitated, the courts had rigidly applied Bolam, asking if the<br />

administration of a treatment came within its remit. Was it in the best interests of the<br />

patient to receive the treatment and could the treatment be carried out in the NHS? 40<br />

Criticism was levelled at the courts for their universality in the use of the test as the<br />

defining mechanism of choice in later cases establishing that Bolam should be used as<br />

a ‘filtering mechanism’ rather than the sole determinant, 41 thereby enabling the<br />

clinicians to weigh up the advantages and disadvantages of a proposed treatment; an<br />

element of rationality was introduced as opposed to a simple acceptance of one<br />

expert’s views versus another’s.<br />

Experimental therapies and the application of Bolam were considered by Dame<br />

Elizabeth Butler-Sloss in Simms v Simms, A v A (a child) 42 , concerning the tragic case<br />

of two teenagers both severely disabled and bedridden with no discernible quality of<br />

39 Chris Turner, Susan Hodge Unlocking Torts (Hodder Education, 2 nd Edn, Malta, 2007) Page 109.<br />

40 Phil Fennell ‘Medical law’ 19.15.<br />

41 ibid at 19.15.<br />

42 [2002] EWHC 2734 (Fam), [2003] 1 All ER 669.<br />

71


72<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

life due to a severe degenerative form of variant Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease (vCJD) 43 ,<br />

from which there was no hope of recovery. An experimental treatment had become<br />

available and the question was whether it was in the patients’ best interests to<br />

administer the untested treatment. It was defined as untested, because it had not been<br />

tested on humans. On laboratory animals, however, it had produced good results. It<br />

was felt in applying Bolam in a permissive manner to allow the use of an untried<br />

therapy, both the interests of society as a whole and that of the patients should be<br />

considered; the test should not be allowed to hinder medical developments. Dame<br />

Elizabeth stated: ‘...the medical evidence...consistent with the philosophy that<br />

underpinned the test, it would not in itself have been irresponsible or unethical to give<br />

the treatment to the patients...’ 44 Thus her opinion was that Bolam should not hinder<br />

medical advances but, rather, its use could promote the development of the ‘new’,<br />

particularly if society as a whole could benefit. She further elaborated on this issue<br />

with regard to vCJD in that apparent futility in treatment may in fact be beneficial to<br />

all.<br />

III(d) – The standards applicable<br />

The ruling in Bolam effectively allowed the medical profession to determine the<br />

standard of care and the conditions which decided such. The doctors were ‘policing’<br />

their own profession, akin to the police investigating complaints against serving<br />

officers before the inception of the Independent Police Complaints Commission. 45<br />

Clearly, this was unsatisfactory, yet the test was applied and endorsed by the House of<br />

Lords in Whitehouse v Jordan 46 , Sidaway v Bethlehem Royal Hospital Governors 47 ,<br />

and Maynard v West Midlands Regional Health Authority 48 , although in each case the<br />

Bolam test was applied in a different context. In Whitehouse, the House of Lords<br />

considered its application to treatment; in Sidaway to disclosure of risk and in<br />

Maynard to diagnosis. The multiplicity of application illustrates the extent to which<br />

Bolam was utilised by the courts when considering allegations of medical negligence<br />

and demonstrates the authority that was accorded to the ruling in Bolam. It was a<br />

judgement that coloured generations of cases and impeded the advancement of the<br />

law with regard to clinical negligence.<br />

43 Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease is one of a group of neuro-degenerative disorders characterised by a<br />

rapidly progressive dementia leading to death. The variant form is seen in young people and is<br />

associated with eating contaminated beef. It progresses inexorably to death at a slower rate than the<br />

classic form. There is no cure available.<br />

44 Phil Fennell ‘Medical Law’ All England Annual Review/2003/Medical Law at 19.17<br />

45 Established by the Police Reform Act which came into force in April 2004.<br />

46 [1981] 1 All ER 267. As a result of a traumatic forceps delivery, a baby sustained brain damage. The<br />

obstetrician was sued for medical negligence but he had made a clinical judgement which unfortunately<br />

was flawed, but he had not acted negligently.<br />

47 [1985] AC 871. A patient underwent spinal surgery but was not informed of the 1% risk of paralysis<br />

and permanent damage; unfortunately she sustained both. The doctors involved were found not guilty<br />

of being negligent in their duty to inform of all risks involved.<br />

48 [1985] 1 All ER 635. Two surgeons operated on a woman in order to determine a diagnosis.<br />

Unfortunately the patient sustained permanent damage to her vocal cords which resulted in speech<br />

impairment. Held that the doctors had acted in a reasonable manner.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Differences in medical opinions generally define the other problem inherent in the<br />

application of the Bolam test. A doctor’s alleged negligence is to be judged by ‘a<br />

competent body of medical opinion’ 49 but in ever-changing spheres of excellence who<br />

can be defined as an expert in any particular field? It may well be that a procedure is<br />

so new that none can be considered ‘experts in the field’. If so, who is competent to<br />

judge the doctor of dubious ability? Consider also that there may be scope for a new<br />

procedure to be performed in a variety of ways with the same objective in mind; a<br />

cholecystectomy 50 can be performed by key-hole surgery or by a classic incision. The<br />

removal of the gall bladder is the achieved aim in both, but the risks associated with<br />

each procedure differ.<br />

Factored into the equation must be the possibility that a ‘so-called expert’ in a new<br />

realm of medicine may have played a part in the development of either a new drug or<br />

procedure and may be very unwilling to concede that perhaps his research<br />

methodology is at fault. Medical researchers have also been known to falsify results 51<br />

in their pursuit of recognition in what can be a highly lucrative field of medicine;<br />

innovation and research with the possibility of entering medicine’s hall of fame.<br />

In addition, there are those in the medical profession who assume the mantle of<br />

‘expert’ despite there being no scientific evidence to back up their supposed superior<br />

knowledge. Several high profile cases recently have highlighted this problem. The<br />

Cleveland case, which occurred in the late 1980’s resulted in 121 young children<br />

being placed in care as the result of the erroneous diagnosis of sexual abuse made on<br />

the basis of very dubious physical evidence determined to be pathognomonic of such<br />

maltreatment. Two paediatricians, Drs Marietta Higgs and Geoffrey Wyatt, had<br />

determined that, when examining the children, reflex anal dilatation proved the<br />

diagnosis of abuse; in fact it is relatively common amongst unabused children as<br />

research has revealed. 52 Their controversial diagnoses resulted in the children being<br />

taken into care, contributing to the emotional trauma they had already experienced as<br />

a result of the examination and the manner in which they were treated by the doctors<br />

who in most cases failed to call the children by their first names or explain what they<br />

were doing. Perhaps most distressing is the manner in which the children were taken<br />

from their homes, sometimes in the middle of the night. 53 A total of 2007 people were<br />

affected by the scandal that dominated the news and media; the doctors continued in<br />

clinical practice and the children are still suffering the long term consequences. Many<br />

describe their treatment at the hands of the so-called medical experts as sexual abuse.<br />

49 Chris Turner, Susan Hodge. Unlocking TORTS (Hodder Education, 2 nd .Edn., Malta, 2007) Page 109.<br />

50 A cholecystectomy involves the removal of the diseased gall bladder. The classic adage is that it is a<br />

complaint common to those of the female sex who are ‘fair, fat and forty’!<br />

51 Reshma Jagsi, Nathan Sheets, Aleksandra Jankovic, Amy R. Motomura, Sudha Amarnath, and Peter<br />

A. Ubel, "Frequency, nature, effects, and correlates of conflicts of interest in published clinical cancer<br />

research" (15 June 2009) Cancer 2783.<br />

52 A Stanton, R Sutherland , ‘Prevalence of reflex anal dilatation in 200 children’ British Medical<br />

Journal vol 298 ,802, 25 March 1998. This study revealed that reflex anal dilatation is not<br />

pathognomonic of sexual abuse.<br />

53 Charles Pragnall ‘The Cleveland Child Sexual Abuse Scandal’.<br />

accessed 08 April 2010.<br />

73


74<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

And many are still suffering the long term effects of such treatment; reminiscent of<br />

Bolam? Yet neither of the doctors has ever been questioned in a criminal investigation.<br />

Considering also the case of Sally Clark 54 , another who suffered tragic consequences<br />

at the hands of the medical profession. The unfortunate woman was convicted of the<br />

murder of her two young sons on the basis of medical evidence submitted to court by<br />

self-proclaimed expert medical witnesses. Her first son died suddenly at the age of 12<br />

weeks in 1996; her second son died at the age of 8 weeks just 2 years later. ‘Sudden<br />

Infant Death Syndrome’ or, colloquially, ‘cot death’ is a well-recognised clinical<br />

entity and thankfully comparatively rare, resulting in the death of about 300 babies<br />

every year. There are several risk factors associated with the syndrome, namely<br />

prematurity, low birth weight and male sex; Harry was premature thereby qualifying<br />

for two of the risk factors.<br />

The medical profession held the view that ‘lightning could not strike twice’ in the<br />

same family and, apparently lacking sufficient evidence to ascertain the causes of<br />

death, decided that the children must have been smothered. Principally the<br />

paediatrician, Professor Meadow, was of the latter opinion; he attributed the chances<br />

of two children succumbing to cot death in the same well-to-do family as<br />

1:73,000,000. The true figure is actually around 1:200 55 but the jury was swayed by<br />

the professor’s apparent authority. It is small comfort that he was subsequently<br />

discredited as his belief in his own expertise destroyed families; units not easily<br />

‘mended’.<br />

As a result of this somewhat flawed medical evidence, Sally Clark was tried for<br />

murder, convicted and jailed. She spent 4 years behind bars before her case came<br />

before the Court of Appeal. A similar case was that of Trupti Patel 56 who was<br />

convicted of the murder of her three young children, but she too was subsequently<br />

acquitted on appeal. A lot of cases involved Professor Meadows whose firmly held<br />

beliefs caused much damage to the families involved.<br />

At appeal it transpired that the pathologist involved in the case had withheld evidence<br />

that one of the Clark boys had an infection 57 which could have contributed to his<br />

54 R v Clark [2003] EWCA.<br />

55 Tom Kelly, ‘Vital evidence not given to jury that convicted Sally Clark’ (17 May 2007) Daily Mail<br />

accessed 08 April 2010.<br />

56 Alison Holt, ‘Patel case raises questions’ 11 June 2003.<br />

accessed 17 April 2010. Trupti<br />

Patel was convicted of the murders of her three children who died at the ages of 3 months; two weeks<br />

and one day, and three weeks and one day old. The first two were classed as cot deaths but the third<br />

death aroused the suspicions of the authorities who subsequently charged Trupti with the murders of all<br />

three. It later transpired that her grandmother had lost five babies, cause unknown. With regard to these<br />

cases of multiple unexplained deaths, there may be a hitherto undiscovered genetic component linked<br />

to an immune deficiency.<br />

57 8 week old Harry was infected with Staphylococcus aureus. Although a ubiquitous organism, it can<br />

prove fatal and perhaps contributed to Harry’s death. It is of course well known to the public as<br />

MRSA; Methicillin Resistant Staphylococcus Aureus and in modern times has contributed greatly to<br />

hospital acquired infection and subsequent mortality.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

death. He had also just received the controversial combined vaccination 58 routinely<br />

given at two months of age. The pathologist was also found to have acted beyond his<br />

competence. His behaviour, coupled with that of the ‘eminent’ paediatrician, resulted<br />

in a gross miscarriage of justice. The doctors’ arrogance beggars belief and, although<br />

the paediatrician was struck off by the General Medical Council, he was reinstated as<br />

the judge felt that he had acted in ‘good faith’. This latter point illustrates the problem<br />

that the judiciary face in judging the medical profession and their expertise. This will<br />

be expanded upon later.<br />

There are inherent problems in the concept of the ‘expert witness’; not only can their<br />

expertise be questionable but time must also be factored into a situation. After the<br />

misadventure which is to be debated in court, the passage of time may well have<br />

determined the true risks associated with a new procedure; how then does ‘the expert’<br />

reconcile events of the past with new knowledge unavailable at the time an incident<br />

occurred? Lord Denning’s famous 1947/1954 spectacles; a case must be determined<br />

in line with the practice of the time and not with knowledge subsequently acquired. 59<br />

In practice, this can be difficult to do.<br />

III(e) – Consent<br />

The Bolam test has generated many questions, not least that of informed consent.<br />

How much information should be imparted to a patient and can the patient fully<br />

comprehend that information? The issue of consent is difficult given that the majority<br />

of people will only retain a fraction of information imparted to them by clinicians and<br />

it is a problematic area of law. It could also be argued that the communication of too<br />

much information, by detailing every conceivable risk will do more harm than good.<br />

If the risks are negligible, it has been argued that ‘On the one hand you alarm<br />

unnecessarily, and on the other hand, you may put him in a position where he feels<br />

that he should take the decision, albeit the doctor is obviously much better qualified to<br />

weigh up the advantages and the desirability of the proposed operation as against the<br />

risks’. 60 Ultimately, it is for the clinician to decide what is appropriate to share with<br />

the patient; it is not for medicine to further burden the ailing. Lord Diplock elaborated<br />

on this point ‘...To decide what risks the existence of which a patient should be<br />

voluntarily warned...is as much an exercise of professional skill and judgement as any<br />

other part of the doctor’s comprehensive duty of care’. 61<br />

The venturing of Bolam into the area of consent in effect dismissed ‘informed consent’<br />

from application in English law. This was much debated in Sidaway by Lord Bridge<br />

who considered the ‘different criterion as to the measure of the medical man’s duty of<br />

care to his patient when giving advice with respect to a proposed course of<br />

treatment’. 62 He also recognised that the competent adult, ‘of sound mind’, is entitled<br />

58 The combined vaccination consists of Diphtheria, Tetanus and Bordetella pertussis (whooping<br />

cough). It is the latter component that has caused much controversy and has been associated with brain<br />

damage and death. It has also been implicated in the causation of autism although the evidence to<br />

support the latter is the subject of much debate.<br />

59 Roe v Minister of Health [1954] 2 All ER 131.<br />

60 O’Malley v Board of Governors of the National Hospital for Nervous Diseases [1975] 1 BMJ 635.<br />

61 Chris Turner, Susan Hodge Unlocking Torts (Hodder Education, 2 nd Edn, Malta, 2007) Page 111.<br />

62 [1985] AC 871 at 898.<br />

75


76<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

to make a decision as to his fate, particularly when undergoing general anaesthesia;<br />

‘this entitlement is the foundation of the doctrine of informed consent’. 63 His basic<br />

premise was that although a clinician has an obligation to impart information<br />

regarding risks attributable to a procedure, it is for the clinician to temper that<br />

information in the interests of the patient. He warned against the dangers of being<br />

‘alarmist’ by stating that ‘...once the doctor has decided what treatment is, on balance<br />

of advantages and disadvantages in the patient’s best interests, he should not alarm<br />

the patient by volunteering a warning of any risk involved, however grave and<br />

substantial, unless specifically asked by the patient’. 64 He felt that it was the<br />

clinician’s duty to advise appropriately and answer those queries about specific risks<br />

when forwarded.<br />

Truly informed consent can only be given if each and every risk potentially applicable<br />

to a treatment regime is detailed. Obviously this is nearly impossible to achieve and<br />

the requirement to do so has no basis in English law. There are risks inherent in all<br />

procedures; this is accepted and all is done to minimize them.<br />

The current law pertaining to the issue of consent was established in Chatterson v<br />

Gerson; 65 consent is real if a patient is informed in broad terms of the risks involved<br />

in a procedure and has given his consent. Most clinicians will not specify every risk<br />

attributed to a therapeutic regime but will elucidate those that most commonly occur.<br />

There will always be patients who desire more information, who might even request<br />

research materials. It is to be conceded that the likelihood of some events occurring is<br />

remote, as in Bolam. 66 Consider the situation in Bolam, though; he was mentally ill<br />

and likely unable to comprehend the enormity of the procedure. Arguably, consent<br />

should have been obtained from a competent adult assuming responsibility for Bolam,<br />

as one would in the case of a child requiring treatment.<br />

Pearce v United Bristol Healthcare NHS Trust 67 elucidated the point pertaining to the<br />

informing of a patient of significant risks. In Sidaway Lord Bridge considered the<br />

question of risk and concluded that a risk of 10% could be regarded as significant.<br />

However, any risk is significant to the individual who sustains that risk and it is<br />

impossible to quantify that which is relevant to that individual.<br />

Pearce elaborated on this point as it was considered that a risk of 0.1-0.2% 68 relating<br />

to the chance of having a stillborn child when a mother is overdue is negligible, but<br />

surely not to the bereaved mother who had to deliver a dead child? The consultant in<br />

this case had withheld information when questioned by the expectant mother in<br />

63 ibid.<br />

64 ibid.<br />

65 [1981] 1 QB 432 at 443. Bristow J enunciated this principle. A patient sustained damage to her ilioinguinal<br />

nerve during herniorraphy which resulted in severe, intractable pain. Subsequently a specialist<br />

attempted to ablate the pain by instilling a nerve block which cured the pain but resulted in paraesthesia<br />

to the limb. Held that although the patient had not been informed of this potential consequence of such<br />

a procedure, the clinician was not negligent in the application of his duty.<br />

66 See earlier text, the risk of convulsions was estimated at 1:10,000.<br />

67 [1999] 48 BMLR 118.<br />

68 ibid at 125.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

deference to her emotional state. The judge applied Bolam but conceded that they<br />

were not bound to follow the test. He stipulated that the advice tendered should be<br />

rational with regard to the situation; did it address the concerns of the patient?<br />

Subsequently Sidaway was applied and the plaintiff did not succeed. So, it is<br />

incumbent upon a clinician to gauge that which his patient is capable of fully<br />

comprehending in any given clinical situation because there is no point in simply<br />

blinding someone with science.<br />

III(f) – Bolitho v City & Hackney Health Authority<br />

Bolam greatly influenced the outcome of medical negligence cases throughout the<br />

1980’s and allowed the medical profession to in effect adjudge itself. It set standards<br />

determining the care that ought to be afforded to a patient and also determined when<br />

the duty of care was breached; a wholly unsatisfactory state of affairs. Bolam also<br />

entrenched the concept of the validity of dual therapies being acceptable if endorsed<br />

by a body of ‘reasonable, respectable and responsible’ medical men, who were<br />

defined by the profession itself, quite possibly to the detriment of patient care.<br />

Bolitho v City & Hackney Health Authority 69 heralded a change in the attitude of the<br />

courts towards the continued application of the Bolam test in that they were no longer<br />

willing to base their judgements on the medical profession’s assessment of their own.<br />

It was time to allow their own opinions and judgements to hold sway in the courts,<br />

and be less reliant upon often self-professed ‘expert witnesses’. Importantly, Bolitho<br />

allowed judges to distinguish between conflicting ‘expert’ opinions and decide which<br />

made more sense, notwithstanding the clinician’s perspective.<br />

The case was tragic as it concerned the potentially avoidable death of a 2 year old boy,<br />

Patrick Bolitho. He had a history of croup 70 which is characterised by paroxysms of<br />

coughing, laryngeal stridor 71 and breathlessness which can lead to asphyxia and<br />

sudden death. Given the clinical features it is of importance to maintain the airway but<br />

intubation is associated with laryngeal spasm and may precipitate both respiratory and<br />

cardiac arrest and is therefore not without severe risk. Despite the risk attached to<br />

intubation it is accepted medical practice that maintenance of an airway at least<br />

ensures that respiratory failure does not lead to cardiac arrest.<br />

The child was admitted in January 1984 with an upper respiratory tract infection but<br />

he was not treated with any great urgency, despite his clinical history. Given that he<br />

had already suffered episodes of respiratory difficulty he should have been treated<br />

urgently. On admission two doctors were assigned to his care, Drs Horn and Rodger,<br />

although neither appears to have treated his deteriorating condition with any degree of<br />

gravity. The next day his condition markedly deteriorated. He developed severe<br />

breathing difficulties leading to respiratory arrest, cardiac failure and resultant severe<br />

brain damage from which he never recovered. One of the doctors attended the first<br />

episode of respiratory crisis but neither attended the second which ultimately led to<br />

69 [1997] All ER 771.<br />

70 Croup, acute laryngo-tracheobronchitis, is an upper respiratory tract infection, usually viral in<br />

aetiology.<br />

71 On inspiration, stridor is characterised by a high pitched breath sound. It is usually caused by<br />

laryngeal obstruction.<br />

77


78<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

the child’s demise. An experienced nurse alerted the more senior of the two doctors,<br />

Dr Horn, when the child began to deteriorate markedly but she declined to attend<br />

despite the alarming change in the child’s clinical condition of which she was<br />

informed, although in her defence she claimed that the batteries in her bleep were flat.<br />

But a doctor in a position of responsibility has a duty to ensure that at all times<br />

contact can be made by those dependent upon them.<br />

III(g) – The Bolitho judgement<br />

The main issue when the case came before the House of Lords was the question as to<br />

the alleged negligence on the part of Dr Horn who maintained that she would not have<br />

intubated even if she had attended the child during the final episode; did her care<br />

equate to that which would have been rendered by a doctor of similar skill and<br />

competency? The law of tort stipulates that those undertaking the acquisition of<br />

specialist skills are required to achieve the standard of the reasonable doctor of the<br />

same rank 72 ; had Doctor Horn in fact done so or was it yet another case of the medical<br />

profession applying their own standards?<br />

The health authority conceded that Doctor Horn had breached her duty of care;<br />

negligence was therefore established but did her failure to attend the child result in the<br />

final catastrophic event? The question as to causation had to be addressed. Would<br />

intubation have saved the child, given that the gold standard of care pertaining to the<br />

condition expressly endorses the maintenance of the airway as paramount in the<br />

avoidance of the complications experienced by Bolitho? Dr Horn’s contention was<br />

that even if she had attended the child, she would not have intubated. Eight expert<br />

witnesses could not agree as to the proper course of treatment that should have been<br />

administered. Their views very much depended on the clinical condition of the child;<br />

some evidence indicated either that the child was quite well apart from the two acute<br />

episodes whereas opposing evidence indicated a progressive decline in respiratory<br />

function leading inexorably to the final event. The indications for intubation differed<br />

according to the physical condition of the child; five would have intubated, whereas<br />

three would not have done so.<br />

Interestingly, the judge went with those who would not have intubated, thereby<br />

absolving Dr Horn, endorsing her care and finding that it did indeed measure up to<br />

those standards espoused by a doctor of similar skills and ability. One of the reasons<br />

that the judge was swayed by the arguments against intubation was the question of the<br />

discomfort that would be experienced by the child, who between episodes had<br />

appeared quite well. A counter argument, however, is that the child could have been<br />

sedated and therefore may have survived; as the old adage goes, ‘sometimes you have<br />

to be cruel to be kind’.<br />

Wilsher v Essex Area Health Authority 73 was considered and yet the doctor in this<br />

case was found to have fallen short of the standards expected of a doctor of the same<br />

level of training; a harsh judgement given the facts of the case which pertained to the<br />

72 Wilsher v Essex Area Health Authority (1986) 3 All ER 801.<br />

73 [1988] AC 1075.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

oxygen therapy administered to a premature infant, resulting in blindness. 74 The<br />

difference in judgements reached reveals an apparent dichotomy of opinion in the<br />

skills expected of junior doctors.<br />

Bolitho paved the way for development in the law related to medical negligence by no<br />

longer endorsing a medical viewpoint simply because a medical expert regarded a<br />

course of action, no matter how illogical, as an option, but still Lord Browne-<br />

Wilkinson held that ‘it will very seldom be right for a judge to reach the conclusion<br />

that views genuinely held by a competent medical expert are unreasonable. The<br />

assessment of medical risks and benefits is a matter of clinical judgement which a<br />

judge would not normally be able to make without expert evidence.’ 75 He felt that a<br />

judge’s position was to decide when a course of action could not be logically<br />

supported by the viewpoint of an expert and would, therefore, not provide a bulwark<br />

against a charge of alleged medical negligence.<br />

IV – Bolitho vs Bolam<br />

Bolam traversed the world influencing the standard of care expected of all<br />

professionals but notably that expected of doctors. Increasingly, though, its use and<br />

validity were questioned, leading to Bolitho which established that the judiciary could<br />

question the actions of clinicians that were patently illogical despite assertions by<br />

colleagues to the contrary. Bolitho did much to challenge Bolam. Importantly, it<br />

allowed the courts to challenge so-called expert witnesses and the apparent absurdity<br />

of some of the clinical decisions. For the first time the House of Lords criticised the<br />

medical profession which post-Bolam could, in some cases, seem to have got away<br />

‘with murder’. The House also rejected the notion that a doctor should escape liability<br />

for their actions simply because their colleagues would have acted in a like manner. In<br />

allowing a colleague to state that he would have acted in a similar manner given a<br />

comparable clinical scenario, a substantial benefit was awarded to those facing an<br />

allegation of clinical negligence and assured failure of the claim against them in most<br />

instances.<br />

The whole premise of Bolam depended upon the different treatment options available<br />

to clinicians and the concept that a ‘reasonable man’ would have acted in the same<br />

way, but Bolitho challenged this by allowing the court to choose between two<br />

opinions proffered. Significantly Lord Browne-Wilkinson challenged the principle<br />

enunciated in Bolam of the ‘responsible, reasonable and respectable’ medical man and<br />

stated that the use of this terminology should ‘show that the court has to be satisfied<br />

that the exponents of the body of opinion relied on can demonstrate that such opinion<br />

has a logical basis’. 76 He felt that before accepting such opinions, he must be satisfied<br />

that the clinical position was one of strength founded on good medicine. It was simply<br />

not good enough for a court to accept the views of one body of experts as opposed to<br />

74 This was an extremely harsh judgement as premature babies are prone to multiple ophthalmic<br />

problems including that of inadequate development of the eye. It is true that the administration of<br />

100% oxygen does result in retrolental fibrodysplasia which is a cause of blindness in the premature,<br />

but in this case other factors could have contributed to the child’s blindness.<br />

75 [1997] 4 All ER 771 at 780.<br />

76 [1997] 4 All ER 771 at 779.<br />

79


80<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

those of another without question; after all it is for the court to decide the standards of<br />

care expected, not the profession itself.<br />

The acceptance not to intubate in Bolitho, despite evidence to suggest that<br />

maintenance of the airway would have obviated the clinical problems resulting in the<br />

death of the child, is absurd and indeed was commented upon; ‘...the views of the<br />

defendant’s experts simply were not logical or sensible’. 77 He further commented on<br />

the fact that despite the child having experienced respiratory difficulty on two<br />

occasions prior to the terminal event, that ‘it was unreasonable and illogical not to<br />

anticipate the recurrence of a life threatening event and take the step which it was<br />

acknowledged would probably have saved Patrick from harm?’ 78<br />

This was like a breath of fresh air through legal corridors. A judge had questioned the<br />

illogicality of doctors electing not to act and accepting such inaction despite evidence<br />

that a course of treatment possessed merit. Indeed Lord Browne-Wilkinson<br />

commented in Bolitho that ‘ if, in a rare case, it can be demonstrated that the<br />

professional opinion is not capable of withstanding logical analysis, the judge is<br />

entitled to hold that the body of opinion is not reasonable or responsible’. 79<br />

That rare case to which Lord Browne-Wilkinson referred was that of Hucks v Cole, 80<br />

which predated Bolitho. A doctor withheld penicillin from a patient with sepsis; a<br />

body of expert witnesses concurred with this view but despite their evidence the Court<br />

of Appeal held the defendant was negligent. Lord Sachs said: ‘When the evidence<br />

shows that a lacuna in professional practice exists by which risks of grave danger are<br />

knowingly taken then, however small the risks, the court must anxiously examine the<br />

lacuna, particularly if the risks can be easily and inexpensively avoided...If the court<br />

finds, on an analysis...of reasons given for not taking those precautions that, in the<br />

light of current professional knowledge, there is no ...basis for the lacuna,...it is ...not<br />

reasonable that those risks should have been taken, its function is to state the fact and<br />

where necessary to state that it constitutes negligence’.<br />

Following Bolitho, judges felt able to question medical evidence in situations where<br />

they doubted its relevance. The opinions of all expert witnesses must be defensible,<br />

given honestly and sincerely held. These views must be ‘capable of withstanding<br />

logical analysis’ 81 . The Court of Appeal, for example, disallowed medical evidence in<br />

Mariott v West Midlands AHA and Others 82 . A General Practitioner (GP) failed to<br />

recognise the seriousness of a head injury incurred by a man who had fallen down the<br />

stairs rendering him unconscious. Subsequently he became increasingly lethargic,<br />

suffered headaches and lost his appetite. His GP attended him but did not think that<br />

his condition merited a referral to hospital. He lapsed into a coma and required<br />

77 [1997] All ER 771 at 778. Lord Browne-Wilkinson.<br />

78 ibid at 779.<br />

79 Bolitho v Hackney Health Authority 39 BMLR 1.<br />

80 (1968)(1993) 4 Med LR 393.<br />

81 Emily Jackson ‘Medical Law Text , Cases, and Materials’ (Oxford University Press, 2 nd ed, 2010)<br />

118.<br />

82 [1999] Lloyd’s Rep Med 23.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

surgery to remove a haematoma which left him with a permanent disability. The<br />

expert witnesses disagreed as to what course of action the GP should have adopted;<br />

one agreed with the GP’s opinion but the other disagreed and maintained that he<br />

should have been referred to hospital. In the light of developments, the evidence<br />

offered by the witness could not be logically supported. Accordingly, the General<br />

Practitioner was indeed found to be negligent in his failure to attend to the patient,<br />

even though the injury he sustained when he fell downstairs was a rare consequence<br />

of such an event. The man was ill and was denied the necessary medical treatment; a<br />

simple statement of fact.<br />

The importance of Bolitho is that a clinician’s actions were no longer considered<br />

above the law and perhaps more claimants have had cases settled in their favour, but<br />

it remains difficult to prove that a clinician did act negligently when confronted by the<br />

testimony of reasonable, responsible, respected experts, for the medical profession<br />

constitutes a powerful group of learned individuals. Notwithstanding this, it was to be<br />

expected that it would become more difficult for doctors to escape the consequences<br />

of their actions and make it harder for the profession to shield its own for none should<br />

be above the law, transgression is deserving of legal censure which should bode well<br />

for those ‘injured’ by the medical profession but is apparent that it is still very<br />

difficult to prove that a clinician’s conduct is negligent if so endorsed by another. 83<br />

The problem is that it remains very difficult for a judge to conclude that views<br />

genuinely held by a competent medical practitioner are unreasonable and therein lies<br />

the problem with regard to Wisniewski, as indeed Lord Browne-Wilkinson so<br />

commented. 84 However, in rare cases the claimant’s action has succeeded.<br />

V – Testing Bolam<br />

In the common law jurisdictions, the three basic tenets pertaining to medical<br />

negligence remain applicable: the duty of care, breach of that duty and causation. It is<br />

the last that has proven the most difficult to establish as evidenced in Bolitho amongst<br />

others. Perhaps it is also worth considering the ‘but for’ premise; a defendant can only<br />

be found negligent if the claimant would not have sustained the injury ‘but for’ the<br />

defendant’s actions or inactions. Could this have been applied in Bolitho? ‘But for’<br />

the inaction of the doctors would he have lived?<br />

Different jurisdictions have dealt with the issue of consent differently. In England,<br />

Bolam has been applied and allowed the doctrine of informed consent to be partially<br />

negated; Sidaway established quite firmly the application of Bolam to consent. Lord<br />

Templeman was firmly of the opinion that it was not in the patient’s best interests to<br />

know everything; indeed ‘a little knowledge is a dangerous thing’ but conversely it is<br />

not for the clinician to decide for the patient unless the patient cannot do so for<br />

83 See Wisniewski v Central Manchester Health Authority [1998] Lloyd’s Rep Med 223 CA. This sad<br />

case concerned a young boy who suffered from cerebral palsy as a result of having the umbilical cord<br />

knotted around his neck during a delivery which went sadly wrong. The experts could not decide on the<br />

manner in which the labour should have been managed.<br />

84 Ibid. Lord Browne-Wilkinson at p.1160A-E: ‘I emphasise that in my view it will very seldom be<br />

right for a judge to reach the conclusion that views genuinely held by a competent medical expert are<br />

unreasonable. The assessment of medical risks and benefits is a matter of clinical judgment which a<br />

judge would not normally be able to make without expert evidence’.<br />

81


82<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

himself. The courts in Singapore 85 have followed the English with regard to the<br />

application of Bolam to causation and a duty to warn patients of possible risks with<br />

several high profile cases. 86<br />

The situation is very different in the United States of America and Canada. A<br />

patient’s consent is vitiated if full information related to a procedure is not given in<br />

some American states 87 but it is difficult to understand just how such comprehensive<br />

information could be imparted. In both Canada and certain American jurisdictions,<br />

knowledge on which the patient has relied and based their decision to consent, may<br />

oust Bolam. It is therefore proposed that the test of informed consent should be an<br />

objective one based on the ruling in Canterbury v Spence 88 ; enough should be<br />

disclosed about a procedure to enable a patient to make an educated decision. 89<br />

Robinson J said that ‘respect for the patient’s right of self-determination on particular<br />

therapy demands a standard set by law for physicians rather than one which<br />

physicians may or may not impose upon themselves’. 90 The principle with regard to<br />

consent is important because it establishes the right of the competent patient not only<br />

to consent to treatment but also the right to refuse treatment.<br />

The Australian courts do not apply the Bolam test but rather consider each case on its<br />

merits; the nature of the treatment, the desire of the patient for information, the<br />

temperament and health of the patient and the general circumstances. 91 The<br />

Australians consider it the duty of the physician to warn of the ‘material risks’, i.e.<br />

those to which a reasonable person could attach significance. 92 But who<br />

defines ’material’? The Australian position is exemplified in Rogers v Whittaker. 93<br />

85 The Singapore courts consider all the elements pertinent to the application of the Bolam Test; the<br />

duty of care, breech of duty, and causation. Consider Lily Pai v Henry Yeo. The claimant became blind<br />

in one eye when the defendant was found negligent in failing to refer her to a specialist with respect to<br />

a clinical suspicion that the eye was developing serious clinical problem.<br />

86 See Denis Mathew Harte v Dr Tan Hun Hoe& Anor (Unreported) and Gunapathy Muniandy v Dr<br />

James Khoo and two others. The former case involved a patient who sustained severe bruising to both<br />

testes but his treating physician declined to examine him when requested to do so and the latter the<br />

failure of a clinician to diagnose a malignant brain tumour.<br />

87 Scholoendorf v Society of New York Hospital 211 NY 125 (1914) ‘Every human being of adult years<br />

and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his own body and surgeon who<br />

performs an operation without his his patient’s consent commits an assault for which he is liable in<br />

damages’.<br />

88 Richard Kidner Casebook on Torts (10 th edn, Oxford University Press 2008) Page 47. 464 f.2d 772.<br />

Ruling in the District of Columbia Circuit Court of Appeals.<br />

89 Ibid page 47.<br />

90 Ibid page 47. So spake Robinson J at p.748.<br />

91 K Shanmugam ‘Testing the Bolam Test: Consequences of Recent Developments’ Singapore Med J<br />

2002 Vol 43(1)accessed 22 September 2009.<br />

92 ibid.<br />

93 (1992) 175 CLR 479. This was an unfortunate case which resulted in blindness for the claimant who<br />

was not informed of the very small risk, 1:14000, which could result in the loss of sight after a surgical<br />

procedure. The claimant had been almost totally blind in her right eye following a childhood accident<br />

and the surgeon informed her that not only would surgery improve appearance it would also improve


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

The issue of consent is not a simple one and calls into question the very nature of the<br />

doctor/patient relationship. A doctor cannot be expected to educate a patient to<br />

medical degree level at consultation and it can be difficult to gauge that to which a<br />

patient will attach import. Simply applying Bolam to the question of consent may in<br />

fact be just that; too simple. Considering the judgement in Reibl v Hughes, ‘To allow<br />

expert medical evidence to determine what risks are material and ...should be<br />

disclosed and...what ...are not material is to hand over to the medical profession the<br />

entire question of the scope of the duty of disclosure...under consideration ...is the<br />

patient’s right to know what risks are involved...’ 94 Ultimately it is for the patient to<br />

make the final decision with regard to their own health.<br />

VI – Auxiliary Influences<br />

VI(a) – The Development of the Art of Medicine 95<br />

The problem with the practice of medicine is that of an ever-increasing knowledge<br />

base, with new treatments and procedures being developed and administered almost<br />

daily. Such is the way of a rapidly developing, innovative, technological world that<br />

characterises modern society. The public are well aware of significant advances in<br />

medicine, courtesy of the media and the internet and expect such to be administered<br />

accordingly, should the need arise. There are few today who do not research their<br />

complaint either prior to seeing their general medical practitioner or, more usually,<br />

before seeing the specialist to whom they have been referred. It is also to be noted,<br />

unfortunately, that although there is a wealth of good, accurate information available<br />

on the various web sites that have proliferated in recent years, there is also some<br />

misleading and inaccurate information accessible, which can make the clinician’s<br />

discussion about a treatment regime something of a trial in itself.<br />

VI(b) – The National Institute for Clinical Excellence<br />

The main aim of the National Institute for Clinical Excellence (NICE), established in<br />

1999 under s.11 of The National Health Service Act 1977 96 was to ensure and<br />

facilitate clinical excellence. It has a remit to evaluate which treatments and drugs<br />

should be available on the National Health Service (NHS) in England and Wales and<br />

has authority to rationalize the treatments available, thereby ensuring value for money.<br />

Critics argue that it is part of a health rationing exercise but it is also tasked with<br />

formulating clinical guidelines pertinent to the major issues in medicine today, one of<br />

which is clinical negligence, which is unfortunately very much on the increase within<br />

the United Kingdom and the source of both concern and controversy.<br />

sight. Unfortunately she developed sympathetic opthalmia, an inflammatory condition that can affect<br />

the healthy eye post trauma or surgery. It is rare with an occurrence of 1:14,000.<br />

94 Richard Kidner Casebook on Torts (10 th edn, Oxford University Press 2008) Page 48. 114 DLR (3d)<br />

1 at 13. The judgement of the Supreme court of Canada, given by Laskin CJC.<br />

95 Kim Castle ‘Medical negligence: The Pathology of The Responsible Man’; Dissertation produced in<br />

April 2010 at The school of Law, Bangor University, North Wales Page 7.<br />

96 This Act was subsequently modified in 1999 when a provision was made for the problem of clinical<br />

negligence.<br />

83


84<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

With regard to clinical negligence allegedly perpetuated by any member of a<br />

healthcare team but principally by the clinician, the pertinent question relates to the<br />

standard of care expected of that individual as compared to responsible medical<br />

practice. The law in England has very much depended on the expert testimony<br />

provided by other members of the profession skilled within the same discipline and<br />

guidelines have been very much side-lined, as it were. But times are changing and it is<br />

to be anticipated that the latter will play an ever increasing role in tort law relevant to<br />

medical negligence. It is hoped that they will provide the basis of the standards of<br />

care expected within the NHS, and therefore assist the courts in their task when<br />

dealing with allegations of medical negligence.<br />

VI(c) – Guidelines<br />

The formulation of clinical guidelines is a lengthy process, involving more than one<br />

clinical agency. An issue has to be identified, addressed and researched before the<br />

information collated can metamorphose into workable guidelines. Once completed<br />

and put into practice, they require both annual review and regular updates; after all,<br />

medicine is not a static science.<br />

The guidelines thus formulated are intended to provide a framework ensuring both<br />

good clinical practice and management strategy. By their very definition, that of being<br />

both research and clinically derived, it is obvious that there will inevitably be a bias<br />

towards the means of their evolution. If a research project involves only a particular<br />

part of a clinical population, as in those suffering with cancer, then the clinical<br />

guidelines will be inevitably biased in their favour. Also to be factored into the<br />

equation is that of individual susceptibility or indeed a racial one.<br />

Recent times have seen a proliferation of guidelines with varying degrees of usage,<br />

which is disappointing given that they are designed to improve working practice.<br />

Perhaps the answer to poor uptake lies in the manner of their evolution and the failure<br />

to address all pertinent issues? Perhaps those drafting the guidelines should consider<br />

their potential in the legal arena?<br />

VI(d) – Guidelines and English law<br />

As a consequence of the importance attached to the gold standard of care as specified<br />

in Bolam and later modified by Bolitho, clinical guidelines have tended to get<br />

relegated to a secondary position with the judiciary attaching more weight to the<br />

spoken word. This was evidenced by Stuart Smith LJ when he spoke about the<br />

controversial pertussis 97 vaccine which has been linked to autism, although the<br />

evidence both for and against is the subject of much controversy in the medical world.<br />

The judge preferred the spoken word as opposed to publications by learned bodies, 98<br />

which is entirely consistent with a person’s desire for their day in court to speak their<br />

piece.<br />

97 Bordetella pertussis is a bacterium which is the causative agent of whooping cough.<br />

98 Ash Samanta, Jo Samanta and Michael Gunn ‘Legal considerations of clinical guidelines: will NICE<br />

make a difference?’ J R Soc Med. 2003 March; 96(3).


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

There is evidence to suggest that there is a move towards the acceptance of guidelines<br />

as was evidenced in Bland, 99 perhaps one of the most high profile cases in recent<br />

times to invoke the use of guidelines, in this case those formulated by the Medical<br />

Ethics Committee of the British Medical Association (BMA). Lord Goff commented<br />

‘if a doctor...acts in accordance with...medical practice now being evolved by the<br />

medical ethics committee of the BMA, he will be acting with the benefit of guidance<br />

from a responsible...competent body of...professional opinion, ...required by the<br />

Bolam test’. 100<br />

In invoking Bolam he considered the duty of care owed to a patient unable to<br />

communicate with his carers who still owed him a duty to act in his best interests. He<br />

referred to cases in other jurisdictions, namely America and New Zealand, with<br />

reference to re Quinlan 101 and Superintendent of Belchertown State School v<br />

Saikewicz 102 in the former and Auckland Area Health Board v Attorney General 103 in<br />

the latter, which concerned a severe case of Guillain-Barre syndrome 104 resulting in a<br />

persistent vegetative state. 105 In all three jurisdictions, the dignity and privacy that<br />

ought to be accorded to all patients, whatever their clinical status, was emphasised<br />

and the concept of the ‘substituted judgement test’ was invoked; what would the<br />

patient have wanted if he could communicate?<br />

Despite this very public use of guidelines the future is uncertain; will they in effect<br />

‘hamstring’ the medical profession preventing innovation and compromise in the<br />

clinical setting? Would a departure from them lead to litigation even if such was done<br />

in the best interests of a patient? There is a practice in the UK of clinicians being able<br />

to prescribe ‘off licence’, i.e. disregarding the clinical indications for a drug and, as it<br />

were, go ‘off-piste’ in certain situations, having explained such to the patient and<br />

obtained written consent. Will this practice now be ‘outlawed’? Only time will tell as<br />

to how the law and guidelines will interact in the future. Perhaps this complex<br />

relationship is in an embryonic stage?<br />

VI(e) – Committees and Legislation<br />

Despite the best efforts of government to address the problem of medical negligence<br />

by the introduction of measures designed to curtail malpractice and encourage<br />

uniformity of care standards throughout the NHS, it remains a thorny problem. It has<br />

been estimated that negligence claims, which are rising annually, will cost the NHS<br />

99 [1993] 4 Medical Law Review 39.<br />

100 Ibid at 872.<br />

101 Ibid at 873. (1976) 355 A.2d 647<br />

102 Ibid at 873. 370 N.E.2d 417<br />

103 Ibid at 873. [1993] 1 N.Z.L. 235<br />

104 Guillain-Barre syndrome is an ascending polyneuritis which can result in total paralysis<br />

necessitating respiratory support. It classically is a sequel to a viral infection and can be of varying<br />

severity. Recovery is time dependent and can be total but it can also result in death.<br />

105 A persistent vegetative state is one in which an individual is totally unaware of their environment<br />

and cannot make any voluntary or purposeful movements. The important clinical feature is the<br />

complete lack of voluntary movement and they retain reflexes, but are doubly incontinent. It is usually<br />

regarded as a non-recoverable condition.<br />

85


86<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

£15.7bn a year. 106 One shudders to contemplate just how much NICE cost to set up<br />

and how much its legal wrangling in court have cost to date. It was envisaged that<br />

conformity would lead to improved standards of care and yet the NHS is still beset by<br />

problems. The Health Act 1999 s.19 led to the establishment of the Commission for<br />

Health Improvement (CHI), which has overall responsibility for the quality control<br />

within the NHS and a remit to oversee and inspect clinical governance at a local level.<br />

Clinical governance 107 was introduced to ensure consistent, high standards of care<br />

throughout the NHS and to promote continued medical education. The latter is of<br />

particular importance in the rapidly evolving world of medicine. Clinicians are<br />

expected to continue learning throughout their careers and it is incumbent upon their<br />

seniors to ensure this and audit their clinical work.<br />

Yet more legislation was enacted with the introduction of the NHS Reform and<br />

Health Care Professions Act 2002, aimed at further regulation of the medical<br />

profession to ensure quality and accountability; it also has a further remit to audit.<br />

The medical profession has attempted to curb the rising tide of clinical negligence<br />

complaints with the introduction of the licence to practise and revalidation. Both<br />

procedures are designed to ensure that a clinician is up to date with medical and<br />

therapeutic developments and fit to practise. The licence to practise was introduced in<br />

November 2009 and will require annual renewal. It is to be coupled with revalidation<br />

which is the process by which a doctor will demonstrate his capability to practise.<br />

Patients will be encouraged to provide feedback about the care they have received;<br />

but what if either should bear a grudge against a particular doctor?<br />

VII – Where to now? – Conclusion and Suggestions<br />

In spite of all the money and brain-storming that has gone into attempting to solve the<br />

problem of clinical negligence, it remains an ever-growing phenomenon. Perhaps it is<br />

time to consider the root causes instead of attempting to tackle the end result, that of<br />

the negligent doctor. It is my premise that medical education must be both improved<br />

and standardised, not only in the UK but also for those doctors who train overseas,<br />

particularly those from the third world. The issue of social engineering must also be<br />

considered in the context of medical education; we are not all equal and it is unlikely<br />

that those who do not shine at school are going to be able to cope with medicine. It is<br />

to be remembered that ‘All men are equal: but some are more so than others’. 108<br />

Not only must education be scrutinized, but attempts must be made to improve<br />

communication by ensuring an agreed level of linguistic skills. The latter must not<br />

only apply to clinicians but to all staff employed in the NHS. Recent articles in the<br />

106 M Wardrop, ‘NHS facing £15.7bn for rising number of clinical negligence claim.’ (7 February<br />

2012) The Telegraph <br />

accessed 8 February 2012. However, perhaps the<br />

rising costs are not only being fuelled by clinical practice itself but also by the growth of legal services<br />

dedicated to seeking damages.<br />

107 Nigel Starey ‘What is clinical governance?’ <strong>Volume</strong> 1, number 2. May 2001 accessed 18 April 2010.<br />

108 Alfred Walter Barrett (1869- 19??) ‘Cheerful Craft’ 1913. Most sources quote his date of death as<br />

1920, but he was tried in court in 1921, after which his whereabouts cannot be verified.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

daily press have emphasised this language problem, pointing out that although doctors<br />

entering from the EU have a requirement to pass a special English language test,<br />

ancillary workers do not. And yet the latter are just as capable of being found guilty of<br />

clinical negligence; consider the healthcare assistant who gives a meal to the ‘nil by<br />

mouth’ patient who perhaps is being prepared for theatre, or has lost the ability to<br />

swallow; either way, disaster looms.<br />

Foreign doctors from outwith the EU who seek work in the UK are required to pass a<br />

language test but, until recently, no such provision was stipulated for those entering<br />

the UK from the EU despite stipulation by the latter that they “…’shall’ 109 have<br />

knowledge of languages necessary for practising the profession in the host member<br />

state”. 110 The previous government compounded the medical manning crisis in this<br />

country with the directives it introduced with regard to the working hours of general<br />

practitioners, such that it has been necessary to ‘import’ doctors; a recipe for disaster<br />

as evidenced by the ‘German’ GP who accidentally killed a patient: the doctor’s<br />

English was so poor that, in spite of having been rejected by several locum agencies,<br />

when faced with an unfamiliar drug the doctor administered ten times the<br />

recommended dose of morphine resulting in the death of the patient. 111 It was a<br />

potentially avoidable situation. If vetting both the language and clinical skills of all<br />

those who wish to work in the NHS either on a temporary or permanent basis had<br />

been mandated at the time, and enforced, this doctor would never have been allowed<br />

to practise in this country. There must be a level playing field with regard to medical<br />

education and language skills; it should matter not where a clinician originates but his<br />

skills must be above reproach.<br />

The impact of the EU directives on working hours 112 must also be considered in the<br />

context of the potential for medical negligence. Junior doctors learn their acute<br />

medicine on the wards after qualification, not during their lectures in a sterile<br />

environment. The impact of a shorter working week can only be a negative one.<br />

Knowledge of acute medicine is assimilated when manifested at its worst in the early<br />

hours of the night. That is when the acute asthmatics go into status, the myocardial<br />

infarctions occur, the diabetics ‘go off’ and the dying die; a steep learning curve is<br />

now lost in the name of reform. Not only are junior doctors not seeing acute medicine<br />

but, because of the working hours stipulated by the EU, they are not getting to follow<br />

up the patients with consequent loss of knowledge and, with it, the potential for future<br />

clinical disaster.<br />

As to the future? There are those who envisage that the Human Rights Act 1998 has<br />

the potential to be applied in cases on medical negligence; there are others who<br />

109 --European Economic Area Doctors – Mutual Recognition and Language Testing. July 2011.<br />

accessed 5<br />

February 2012. The word ‘shall’ is emphasised in the original document. It is a legal requirement.<br />

110 ibid 1.<br />

111 James Meikle and Kate Connolly ‘German GP who accidentally killed patient was advised to go<br />

home’ (23 August 2009) The Guardian <br />

accessed 18 April 2010.<br />

112 EU Directive drives reform of junior doctor’s working hours.<br />

accessed 19 April 2010.<br />

87


88<br />

Battling Bolam<br />

consider that legislation, committees and guidelines will combat the growing problem<br />

of clinical negligence, but at the cost of stifling innovation and the promotion of<br />

defensive medicine. And as to the judiciary, perhaps it is for them to expand on<br />

Bolitho. Time to polish the gloss? 113<br />

113<br />

Nicholas Wilkes “Bolam Out?” (15 September 2003) The Lawyer<br />

accessed 19 January 2010


CASE NOTES<br />

CASE NOTE – AL SKEINI AND OTHERS V UNITED KINGDOM (2011) 53<br />

EHRR 18<br />

Tom Hamilton, University of Cambridge<br />

I - Introduction<br />

The judgment in Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom, 1 delivered jointly with Al<br />

Jedda v United Kingdom 2 by the European Court of Human Rights (“the Court”) on 7<br />

July 2011, represents the most significant Strasbourg jurisprudence on<br />

extraterritoriality to date. The approach adopted by the Court has been identified by<br />

many as a progressive step towards protecting human rights during times of armed<br />

conflict, and it is widely and rightly considered to be a substantial departure from the<br />

approach taken ten years earlier in the Bankovic case. 3 Notwithstanding some progress<br />

in defining the principles governing jurisdiction, there is a long way to go before<br />

Council of Europe states who export war will be obligated to export a full set of<br />

corresponding human rights guarantees, as demonstrated by the concurring opinion of<br />

Maltese Judge, Giovanni Bonello. Perhaps the most prescient jurisprudence to come<br />

out of the case lies in Judge Bonello’s self-confessed ‘dream’ of a functional approach<br />

to extraterritoriality.<br />

II - Previous Approaches to Extraterritorial Jurisdiction<br />

Defining the extent of jurisdiction must begin with a consideration of Article 1 of the<br />

Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (“the<br />

Convention”), which provides as follows:<br />

“The High Contracting Parties shall secure to everyone within their<br />

jurisdiction the rights and freedoms defined in Section I of [the]<br />

Convention.” 4<br />

Various interpretations of ‘within their jurisdiction’ were developed, and by the time<br />

the Court came to consider Bankovic, a number of formulations including “effective<br />

control” (Loizidou v. Turkey 5 ), “overall control” (Cyprus v. Turkey 6 ) and “personal<br />

control” (Öcalan v. Turkey 7 ) had been used to define the circumstances in which a<br />

contracting state has sufficient responsibility over an area outside of its territory such<br />

1 (2011) 53 EHRR 18.<br />

2 (2011) 53 EHRR 23.<br />

3 See, for example: Marko Milanovic, ‘Al-Skeini and Al-Jedda in Strasbourg’ E.J.I.L. 2012, 23(1),<br />

121-139, at 122, citing Bankovic and Others v Belgium and Others (2007) 44 EHRR SE5.<br />

4 Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (4 November 1950) 213<br />

UNTS 222; 312 ETS 5, entered into force 3 September 1953, Article 1 .<br />

5 (1997) 23 EHRR 513.<br />

6 (2002) 35 EHRR 30.<br />

7 (2005) 41 EHRR 45.


90<br />

Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom<br />

that extraterritorial jurisdiction applies. In Bankovic, the Court considered the<br />

complaints of civilians arising from death, injury and other losses following the<br />

bombing of Belgrade by NATO aircraft in 1999 during the war in Kosovo. The Court<br />

held that jurisdiction was essentially a territorial matter, and created a general rule<br />

that the physical territory of a contracting state would provide the boundaries of its<br />

Article 1 obligations in most circumstances. The Court recognised the existence of<br />

several exceptions developed in its case law, including military occupation and<br />

transfers of power arising from the consent, invitation or acquiescence of the<br />

government of a state. In those exceptional situations the test would be one of whether,<br />

first, the state could be considered to have effective control of an area, and second,<br />

whether the state exercised public powers that would normally be exercised by the<br />

government of the occupied state.<br />

In addition, the Court acknowledged that in order for the Convention to fulfil its<br />

purpose of ensuring human rights protections within the territories of all Council of<br />

Europe states, it was necessary for extraterritorial jurisdiction to apply throughout the<br />

espace juridique of the Convention. In other words, a contracting state would remain<br />

liable for breaches of its Convention obligations even if the breaches occurred in the<br />

territory of another contracting state. If this were not the case, the Court reasoned, a<br />

vacuum of liability would exist within the legal space of the Convention. The<br />

emphasis on the notion of espace juridique in Bankovic supported a restrictive<br />

interpretation of Article 1, limiting the commitment of contracting states to respecting,<br />

protecting and enforcing remedies for violations of human rights only within the<br />

territorial boundaries of the Council of Europe states.<br />

III – Judgment of the Court in Al Skeini<br />

The Court in Al Skeini had to consider the extent of the United Kingdom’s jurisdiction<br />

in a region of Iraq administered by the Coalition Provisional Authority from May<br />

2003 to June 2004 under the responsibility and control of the United Kingdom, whose<br />

troops were deployed in the same area. Six applicants alleged violations of their rights<br />

under the Convention arising from acts attributable to the British armed forces. In<br />

considering the general rule that jurisdiction under Article 1 was essentially territorial,<br />

the Court identified three categories of exceptions to the rule: a state agent exception;<br />

an effective control exception; and an exception based on the concept of espace<br />

juridique.<br />

The first category provides that jurisdiction may be established outside of the territory<br />

of a contracting state through the “authority and control” of a state agent. 8 Existing<br />

examples included: the authority and control held by diplomatic and consular agents;<br />

the authority and control implicit when a non-contracting state gives its consent for<br />

some or all of the public powers of its government to be exercised by a contracting<br />

state; and the authority and control arising where the use of force by an agent of a<br />

contracting state brings an individual under the control of its authorities. The second<br />

category covered situations where jurisdiction may be established as a result of<br />

military action, such that a state is in “effective control of an area” outside of its<br />

territory. 9 The definition of “effective control” appears to have been left deliberately<br />

broad by the Court, leaving scope for further refinement based on future factual<br />

8 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1) 133.<br />

9 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1) 138.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

scenarios. With regards to the third category, the Court reiterated the concept of<br />

espace juridique, relying essentially on the same grounds as Bankovic, namely that<br />

there should be no legal vacuum in the jurisdictional reach of the Convention within<br />

the territory of the Council of Europe member states. 10<br />

IV - Beyond Bankovic<br />

In Al Skeini, the Court reasserted the territorial basis of jurisdiction found in Bankovic,<br />

stating that the establishment of further exceptions would be highly dependent on the<br />

particular case. The Court stated:<br />

“In each case, the question whether exceptional circumstances exist<br />

which require and justify a finding by the Court that the state was<br />

exercising jurisdiction extraterritorially must be determined with<br />

reference to the particular facts.” 11<br />

At first blush, one might conclude that Al Skeini does not depart substantially from the<br />

basic principles in Bankovic, but it is the way in which the above three categories<br />

were applied to the facts of Al Skeini which suggests the Court had in mind an<br />

approach which extends beyond previous cases. The Court in Al Skeini arguably<br />

created a fourth category of extraterritorial jurisdiction.<br />

In its conclusions, the Court held that the United Kingdom had taken on some of the<br />

“public powers” which would normally be considered sovereign to Iraq. 12 The Court<br />

continued to reason that:<br />

“In particular, the United Kingdom assumed authority and<br />

responsibility for the maintenance of security in South East Iraq.<br />

In these exceptional circumstances, the Court considers that the United<br />

Kingdom, through its soldiers engaged in security operations in Basrah<br />

during the period in question, exercised authority and control over<br />

individuals killed in the course of such security operations, so as to<br />

establish a jurisdictional link between the deceased and the United<br />

Kingdom for the purposes of Article 1 of the Convention.” 13<br />

The passage cited above stands out because it is shows how the Court’s reasoning<br />

cannot be easily reconciled with a strict-edged approach to the three categories that<br />

were identified earlier in its judgment. Instead, the judgement suggests that the Court<br />

approached the test for jurisdiction by using a broad assessment of the overall degree<br />

to which a respondent state has adopted another state’s public powers, within which<br />

lies a consideration of the role of state agents in exercising authority over individuals<br />

and a consideration of the control of a state over the territory in question. These<br />

considerations may be better understood simply as particular aspects of the overall<br />

question of public power. In this sense a jurisdictional link between the applicants and<br />

the respondent state might be established on the basis of an overall assessment of<br />

‘public power’ attributable to the contracting state. Thus, jurisdiction might exist in<br />

situations where it is not established that the applicant was under the authority and<br />

10 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1) 141.<br />

11 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1) 132.<br />

12 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1) 149.<br />

13 ibid.<br />

91


92<br />

Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom<br />

control of the respondent state, and it is not established that the territory on which<br />

they were said to have suffered their grievance was under the authority and control of<br />

the respondent state.<br />

V - A Functional Approach to Jurisdiction<br />

This brings us to the thoughtful remarks of Judge Bonello, who has since retired from<br />

the Court. Advocating a broader approach to the extraterritorial obligations of<br />

contracting states, Judge Bonello made the point that states who have signed up to the<br />

immutable principles which underlie the fundamental functions of the Convention<br />

ought to be willing to do their utmost to work towards the supremacy of the rule of<br />

human rights law wherever they can, not just on an à la carte basis on their home turf.<br />

An alternative approach would be based on the functionality of the powers<br />

attributable to a state:<br />

“States ensure the observance of human rights in five primordial<br />

ways: firstly, by not violating (through their agents) human rights;<br />

secondly, by having in place systems which prevent breaches of human<br />

rights; thirdly, by investigating complaints of human rights abuses;<br />

fourthly, by scourging those of their agents who infringe human rights;<br />

and, finally, by compensating the victims of breaches of human rights.<br />

These constitute the basic minimum functions assumed by every state<br />

by virtue of its having contracted into the Convention.<br />

A “functional” test would see a state effectively exercising<br />

“jurisdiction” whenever it falls within its power to perform, or not to<br />

perform, any of these five functions. Very simply put, a state has<br />

jurisdiction for the purposes of Article 1 whenever the observance or<br />

the breach of any of these functions is within its authority and<br />

control.” 14<br />

The comments of Judge Bonello reward close reading, especially as he goes on to<br />

deal with a number of the potential barriers to a functional approach that were raised<br />

during the case. Against the problem of indivisibility of human rights, the Judge<br />

argues that a state need not enforce all of the rights in the Convention merely because<br />

extraterritorial jurisdiction has been established. A finding of extraterritorial<br />

jurisdiction may obligate a state to enforce certain human rights, but under a<br />

functional approach, a state would only be obligated to enforce the human rights<br />

which it is in a position to ensure. For example, although the United Kingdom as an<br />

occupying power in Iraq might not be in a position to ensure rights to education under<br />

Protocol 2 Article 1, it may very well be in a position to enforce Article 3 rights to<br />

freedom from torture.<br />

Judge Bonello admits a streak of idealism to his approach, but contends that adopting<br />

such an approach is preferable to giving in to the seductive rhetoric of “human rights<br />

imperialism.” 15 The United Kingdom government had argued earlier in the case that<br />

imposing extraterritorial jurisdiction would involve putting the United Kingdom in<br />

the position of a human rights imperialist. But as the Judge hinted, if a state is<br />

14 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1), Judgment of Judge Bonello, 10-11.<br />

15 Al Skeini and Others v United Kingdom (n 1), Judgment of Judge Bonello, 37.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

unashamed by imperialism in its military campaigns, it is unlikely to blush at<br />

accusations of adopting an imperialist approach to promoting human rights.<br />

The clarity and simplicity of a functional approach seems to cut through many of the<br />

problems that the rest of the Al Skeini judgment leaves unresolved. Although Al Skeini<br />

undoubtedly builds on Bankovic and clarifies the basic categories in which<br />

extraterritorial jurisdiction may be established, it reaffirms the position that the<br />

application of these categories is highly flexible, dependent on the particular facts of<br />

each case, and requires further interpretation before there will be true certainty in the<br />

law for victims of human rights violations perpetrated by Council of Europe states<br />

overseas.<br />

93


CASE NOTE – CAMPBELL V MIRROR GROUP NEWSPAPERS LTD [2004]<br />

UKHL 22. THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE EUROPEAN<br />

CONVENTION ON HUMAN RIGHTS AND PRIVACY IN THE COMMON<br />

LAW<br />

Emily Whittaker, Exeter University<br />

I – A Move in the Law<br />

"As a campaigner, Naomi's about as effective as a chocolate soldier.” 1 This statement<br />

by ‘The Mirror,’ can now be regarded with irony. The House of Lords’ decision in<br />

Campbell has become a landmark ruling for the recognition of privacy, arguably<br />

‘spurred’ by the integration of the Human Rights Act 1998. 2 It is considered to<br />

incorporate the invasion of privacy into the common law action of ‘breach of<br />

confidence.’<br />

Naomi Campbell brought an action on ‘breach of confidence.’ The traditional<br />

requirements for this action are outlined in Coca. 3 However, the House of Lords<br />

followed Lord Goff in Spycatcher (No2) and classified a confidential relationship as<br />

one where the ‘defendant knew or ought to know the information would be<br />

considered [by the claimant] as private.’ 4 This removed the limitation of pre-existence<br />

from the relationship, confirming a widely anticipated development 5 .<br />

The Lordships then appeared to extend the test by distinguishing between information<br />

which is ‘confidential’ and that which is ‘private’. It was this distinction which led to<br />

the phrase ‘misuse of private information.’ 6<br />

II – Misuse of Private Information: The Tests<br />

To apply what may be seen as a broadened tort one must decide what constitutes<br />

‘private information.’ Three tests arose. The first: based on the facts did the claimant<br />

have a ‘reasonable expectation of privacy?’ 7 The second: would the information be<br />

“highly offensive to a reasonable person of ordinary sensibilities”, based on the<br />

position of the claimant? 8 The third: was the information ‘obviously private?’ 9<br />

1 The Mirror, 7th Feb as cited in Campbell v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd [2004] UKHL 22 [9] (Lord<br />

Nicholls)<br />

2 Campbell v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd [2004] per Lord Nicholls<br />

3 Coca v A N Clarke [1969] F.S.R 415. [47-48]<br />

4 Attorney-General Appellants v Observer Ltd. and Others Respondents<br />

Attorney-General Original Appellant and Cross-Respondent v Times Newspapers Ltd. and Another<br />

Original Respondents and Cross-Appellants [1990] 1. A.C 109 [281] per Lord Goff of Chieveley<br />

5 Phillipson,‘Transforming Breach of Confidence? Towards a common law right of privacy under the<br />

HRA’ (2003) 66 MLR 726. As cited by Lunney.M, Oliphant.K , ’Privacy, Confidence and Human<br />

Rights;Tort Law Text and Materials’, (4th edition, 2010. New York, OUP)<br />

6 Campbell (n 2) [14] per Lord Nicholls<br />

7 ibid [11] per Lord Nicholls<br />

8 ibid per Lord Hope<br />

9 ibid


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

Does the proposal of alternate tests simply add confusion to the scope of privacy? The<br />

incorporation of a subjective element into the first two tests is welcomed. 10 The first<br />

test of ‘reasonable expectation‘ is applied by Lord Phillips in Douglas v Hello 11 and is<br />

regarded clearer and simpler than the ‘highly offensive‘ criteria. 12 It is argued by Lord<br />

Nicholls that the criteria of the second test is a more challenging bar for the claimant<br />

to prove. The concern is that, in order to evidence this, one may consider the weight<br />

of the intrusion of privacy and thus merge the question of privacy and<br />

proportionality. 13<br />

The ‘highly offensive’ test was intended by Lord Hope for application if the<br />

‘obviously private’ test did not suffice; thus when there is ‘room for doubt.’ 14<br />

Although depicted as a two part test, it could be argued that the latter is unnecessary,<br />

as ultimately the ‘highly offence’ criteria is the only hurdle the information must pass.<br />

So what is it that the ‘obviously private’ test intends to achieve? In consideration Lord<br />

Hope cites Lord Woolf; ‘the subject of a claim for privacy should not be allowed to<br />

be the subject of detailed argument.’ 15 This reasoning suggests an intention of saving<br />

time and cost. It also presents a possibility for the correction of what is perhaps a flaw<br />

in UK law; that often in order to protect privacy the claimant’s most intimate details<br />

are examined.<br />

III – Judging What is Private<br />

Is it fathomable that a claimant could circumvent private information being<br />

discussed? If so how is the information to be decided on? Baroness Hale asserts three<br />

categories as ‘obviously private’: ‘health, personal relationships and finances.’ 16<br />

However, it is not held that information which fits these classifications, no matter how<br />

marginally, shall be deemed private with no further enquiry. Consideration must be<br />

given to the individual details, for example although clearly medical information, ‘a<br />

cold or broken leg’ are not regarded as private information. 17 So, when applying the<br />

facts, how is the scope of these categories to be defined? By simply contrasting<br />

judgments considered in the later hearings of Campbell, as to whether therapy should<br />

be regarded medical treatment, one can see there is already disparity in opinion<br />

towards what falls within the categories. 18 It was, however, decided by the majority in<br />

the House of Lords that the scope of the definition of ‘medical treatment’ is now<br />

extended to included ‘therapy’.<br />

10 N.A Moreham, (2005) ‘Privacy in the common law: a doctrine and theoretical analysis’. 121 Law<br />

Quarterly Review 628.<br />

11 Douglas, Zeta-Jones and Northern &Shell plc v Hello! Ltd (No5 and 6) [2005] EWCA Civ 595 per<br />

Lord Phillips<br />

12 Campbell (n 2) [99] per Baroness Hale<br />

13 ibid.[22] per Lord Nicholls, paraphrased<br />

14 ibid [94] per Lord Hope<br />

15 A v B Plc [2003] EWCA Civ 337 [11] and [43] per Lord Woolf CJ<br />

16 Campbell (n 2) [135] per Baroness Hale<br />

17 ibid [157] per Baroness Hale<br />

18 ibid<br />

95


Campbell v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd<br />

Contrasting judicial opinions highlight that the application of the ‘obviously private’<br />

test can create uncertainty, which is undesirable in courts. Some argue against<br />

established categories, as surely what one regards to be private information is<br />

dependent on the individual. 19 Thus, the approach should not assume protected<br />

categories, but leave these areas open to a subjective view, albeit with the need of<br />

some objective restrictions. Although relative to both parties this argument is more<br />

effectively raised in order to protect free speech, as the presumption which arises<br />

based on these categories only adds to the protection of the claimant, the categories<br />

provide useful guidelines. If written in legislature they could be deemed restrictive,<br />

but the flexibility of common law can aid their evolution, even with the creation of<br />

exceptions.<br />

IV – A Shift Towards a Higher Recognition of Privacy<br />

Regardless of which test is applied there is undeniably a shift towards a higher<br />

recognition of privacy by the common law. Following Campbell, Jagger and<br />

Mckennit have received injunctions over personal relationship stories. 20 This shows<br />

that the special consideration, which Lord Woolf argued should only be afforded to<br />

marriage, is now extended to transitional relationships. 21 As the courts encompass a<br />

broader interpretation of privacy, it is now considered that in practice it is ‘very easy<br />

to get through the Article 8 doorway.’ 22 If this is true, one must consider why some<br />

‘misuse of information’ claims fail. 23<br />

This may be because ‘private information’ is also subject to the second test in<br />

Campbell: ‘Is the publication of the information proportionate when balancing Article<br />

8; the right to privacy against Article 10; freedom of expression?‘ This development<br />

of the common law can be seen as a reaction to the enactment of Human Right Act<br />

1998. Section 6(1) imposes an obligation on the UK court in its function as a ‘public<br />

body’ to act in a way which is compatible with the European Convention of Human<br />

Rights. 24<br />

At this point the law becomes relatively complex. How does one decide the weighting<br />

of each article? Lord Hoffmann states there is ‘not a presumption in favour of one or<br />

another,’ a view harmonious with Resolution 1165. 25 However the appeal in Peck v<br />

UK contradicts the stance of neutrality over each right. 26 The domestic court appears<br />

19 N.A Moreham, ‘Privacy in the common law: a doctrine and theoretical analysis’. Law Quarterly<br />

Review 2005, 628. 656<br />

20 Campbell (n 2); Ms Elizabeth Jagger v John Darling & Others [2005] EWHC 683 (Ch), Ash v<br />

Mckennit [2008] Q.B.73<br />

21 Av B (n 15)[11] and [43] per Lord Woolf CJ<br />

22 Marcus Partington of the Media Lawyers Association as cited in The Select Committee Report on<br />

press standards, privacy and libel. Published 24th Feb 2010 [26] www.publications.parliament.uk<br />

23 The claim failed in the following cases: LNS (Terry) v Persons Unknown [2010] EWHC 119 (QB),<br />

Lord Browne of Madingley v Associated Newspapers Ltd [2007] EWCA. Civ 295<br />

24 European Convention of Human Rights 1950<br />

25 Campbell (n 2) per Lord Hoffman, Resolution 1165 of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of<br />

Europe (1998)<br />

26 Peck v United Kingdom (44647/98) [2003] E.M.L.R. 15<br />

96


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

to favour freedom of expression, conversely the European Court of Human Rights<br />

applies more weighting to privacy; as evidenced by the judgments in these cases.<br />

The Human Rights Act also encompasses section12 ‘freedom of expression’, a<br />

provision which the UK parliament regarded as a ‘safeguard to the press.’ 27 The<br />

function of section12 is to acknowledge the importance of Article 10, 28 ‘where the<br />

proceedings relate to...journalistic, literary or artistic’ material. 29 This shows that it is<br />

not just the court as interpreter who recognises that a ‘freedom to publish of<br />

unjustifiable restraint [is]...the sort of society which the convention seeks to<br />

promote,’ 30 it is also the central aim of the legislature.<br />

V – The Public Interest<br />

The Human Rights Act section 12(4)(b) also gives effect to the PCC Code of Practice.<br />

Section 3; Privacy, reiterates the importance of ‘public interest’ as a defence to<br />

‘justify intrusion into one’s private life without consent.’ 31 Section 3(1)(iii) provides<br />

the justification as to why certain private details denoting Miss Campbell’s drug<br />

addiction were able to be published. Campbell had supplanted her right by lying to the<br />

public about the problem, and thus ‘The Mirror’ acted in the interest of the public to<br />

prevent them from being misled.<br />

If Miss Campbell had not misled the public, none of the story would have been<br />

deemed ‘justly’ published. This is because it does not follow that, as a ‘public figure<br />

has had a long and symbiotic relationship with the media,’ 32 publication is justified.<br />

Details of one’s life, that are not wished to be promoted, engage a residual right which<br />

the court must protect. 33 This right appears analogous to that obtained by the ordinary<br />

person. Thus, even though there may be a public interest in the life of a celebrity or<br />

sportsman, this is to be distinguished from the definition of ‘public interest’<br />

implemented by the courts. Article 10 provides publication must be ‘...necessary in a<br />

democratic society.‘ Considered crucial to democracy are matters relevant to the<br />

‘political, economic and social life of the community. 34 The order forms that of<br />

priority, with political speech notably above the rest.<br />

So, can it be implied that as the courts must apply Article 8; a right which can only be<br />

superseded on grounds of ‘genuine public interest’, that rulings post implementation<br />

of the Human Rights Act, such as Mckennit 35 and Mosley, 36 signal the end for ‘kiss<br />

27 The then Home Secretary, the RT Jack Straw MP paraphrased in (2010) The Select Committee<br />

Report on press standards, privacy and libel. Published 24th Feb [26] Available:<br />

www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm/cmcumeds.htm [16th November 2010] citing HC Deb 2 July<br />

1998, col 54.<br />

28 European Convention of Human Rights 1950, Article 10.<br />

29 Human Rights Act 1998 Section 12(4)<br />

30 Jameel v Wall Street Journal Europe SPRL (No.3) [2006] UKHL 44 [17] (Lord Bingham of<br />

Cornhill)<br />

31 Press Complaints Commission Code of Practice 1991.Avaliable: www.pcc.org.uk/cop/evolving.html<br />

[16 th November 2010]<br />

32 Campbell (n 2)[57] per Lord Hoffman<br />

33 ibid [68] per Lord Hoffman<br />

34 ibid[148] per Baroness Hale<br />

35 Niema Ash & Others v Loreena Mckennit & others [2008] Q.B.73<br />

97


Campbell v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd<br />

and tell’ stories? This is the view of a report from the ‘Reuters for the study of<br />

Journalism’ which concluded that the only chilling effect imposed on the media, as a<br />

result of the Human Rights Act, was the end of these exposés. 37 On the surface this<br />

can be regarded as a positive development, which encourages media responsibility.<br />

However could this aim become distorted in practice? Max Mosley is a figurehead of<br />

Formula One and an economic and social representative of the UK. The fact that he<br />

managed to protect his privacy, against the right to free speech, by analogy, presents<br />

the fear that other members of strategic institutions, including politicians or school<br />

teachers, may use this judgment to conceal actions that may once have led to<br />

resignation. 38 Thus blurring transparency in democracy. Recently, the Italian Prime<br />

Minister used the recourse of privacy to prevent the publication of photographs of a<br />

party, which was ‘allegedly attended by escorts.’ 39 Moreover according to staff at the<br />

newspaper ‘La Vangurdia,’ in Spain a story about a politician having an affair would<br />

not be released. 40 It is to be remembered that each member state has its own media<br />

culture, in which the question of ‘whether a journalist exceeds the latitude afforded to<br />

them’ is construed differently. 41 In the UK political speech is regarded as crucial and<br />

therefore it remains unlikely that stories which seek to protect this interest will be<br />

prevented.<br />

VI – The Whole Story<br />

In Campbell a main factor perceived to exceed the journalistic latitude was the<br />

publication of the photographs. 42 Lord Hope states ‘looking to the text only, I would<br />

have been inclined to regard the balance between these rights as about even.’ 43 The<br />

tone of the story, ‘sympathetic [or not] was neither here nor there.’ 44 This suggests<br />

that a vindictive story with no picture could, depending on the facts, be considered<br />

acceptable. So, what is it about an image which is deemed so intrusive? In Campbell<br />

the focus is not on the image itself, but the circumstances in which it was taken; on a<br />

public street, surreptitiously, without Miss Campbell’s consent. It was noted that by<br />

giving effect to decisions of the European Court of Human Rights such as Peck v UK,<br />

36 ,Mosley v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd [2008] EWHC 687<br />

37 Stephen Whittle and Glenda Cooper, Reuters for the study of Journalism,Oxford as cited by David<br />

Eady,(2010) ‘Injunctions and the protection of Privacy’, Civil Justice Quarterly vol 29, no.[internet]<br />

www.lawlib.wlu.edu. Available [12th November 2010]<br />

38 Gideon, ‘Only the public interest can justify invasion of privacy’, (2008) The Lawyer, 11 August.<br />

Available: www.thelawyer.com/only-the-public-interest-can-justify-invasions-ofprivacy/134127.article<br />

[14th November 2010]<br />

39 Prime Minister Silvio Berlusconi. As cited in (2004) Select Committee Report on press standards,<br />

privacy and libel. [internet] 24th Feb [16] www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm/cmcumeds.htm,<br />

Available [16th November 2010] cited from "Berlusconi fury over naked photos", BBC news online, 5<br />

June 2009 news.bbc.co.uk<br />

40 Select Committee Report on Press standards, privacy and libel. Published 24th Feb 2010<br />

[17]www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm/cmcumeds.htm<br />

41 Campbell (n 2) [68] per Lord Hoffman<br />

42 ibid<br />

43 ibid [121] per Lord Hope<br />

44 ibid [156] per Baroness Hale<br />

98


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

that privacy can be extended to included activities conducted in public. 45 Moreover,<br />

lack of consent is currently not enough to establish privacy in the UK. However, this<br />

could be subject to change following Von Hannover, 46 which gave Princess Caroline a<br />

right over her own image, and the domestic ruling in Murray. 47 Yet, the latter can be<br />

distinguished as applicable only to children and the former was not adopted in John v<br />

Associated Newspapers. 48<br />

VII – Conclusion<br />

The focus of Campbell seemed to be the concept of looking at everything as a whole.<br />

Although the picture or article alone were not regarded private, together they were.<br />

The right to privacy was not obtained on the basis of one specific fact, but a<br />

culmination of many. Following the Human Rights Act the common law has taken a<br />

much broader approach to privacy, with the duty to act compatibly playing a large<br />

role. Striking the balance is a more onerous task; I recommend Lord Hoffmann’s<br />

approach. He takes one fact and balances what the editor considers it adds to the story<br />

against how the claimant feels it adds to the intrusion. Despite the theory of balancing<br />

rights, there is an obvious trend towards the infringement of freedom of speech.<br />

Although John v Associated Newspapers presented resistance, 49 it is inevitable that<br />

what is actually shown is reluctance. The recent recognition in Mckennit, 50 that the<br />

principles in Von Hannover should receive a more general application highlights<br />

this. 51<br />

45 Peck (n 26)<br />

46 Von Hannover v Germany (59320/00) (2006) 43.E.H.R.R.7,<br />

47 .Murray v Express Newspapers plc and another [2008] EWCA Civ 446.<br />

48 John v Associated Newspapers Ltd. [2006] EWHC 1611 (QB)<br />

49 ibid<br />

50 Ash v Mckennit (n 35)<br />

51 Von Hannover (n 46)<br />

99


CASE NOTE – JUDGMENT OF THE EUROPEAN COURT OF JUSTICE,<br />

13 OCTOBER 2011, PIERRE FABRE DERMO-COSMÉTIQUE SAS, C-439/09<br />

CONCERNING ANOTHER RESTRICTION BY OBJECT ON INTERNET<br />

SALES BAN<br />

Dr. iur. Verena Klappstein, London School of Economics<br />

(Article 101(1) and (3) TFEU – Regulation (EC) No 2790/1999 – Articles 2 to 4 –<br />

Competition – Restrictive practice – Selective distribution network – Cosmetics and<br />

personal care products – General and absolute ban on internet sales – Ban imposed by<br />

the supplier on authorised distributors)<br />

I – Introduction<br />

The European Court of Justice (ECJ) ruled in line with recent case-law 1 on the<br />

general and absolute de facto ban of internet sales in a selective distribution network.<br />

Thereby strengthening the internet as a sales channel. Neither the protection of<br />

customers against the incorrect use of products 2 nor the manufacturer's intention to<br />

maintain its prestigious image 3 were legitimate aims to justify such a ban.<br />

Furthermore the safe harbour provided in the vertical agreements block exemption<br />

regulation (Regulation (EC) No 2790/1999, VABER 4 ) was narrowed, 5 with the<br />

application of Article 101(1) TFEU expanded. This decision of the ECJ's purports the<br />

Commission's view in its re-draft of VABER.<br />

II – The Significant Facts<br />

Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique SAS (PFDC) produces and sells cosmetics. These<br />

cosmetics are primarily sold in pharmacies, however they are not medicines. PFDC's<br />

French market share in 2007 was approximately 20% 6 . Distribution contracts for four<br />

brands of its products stipulated that sales had to be “made exclusively in a physical<br />

space, in which a qualified pharmacist must be present” 7 . With this provision PFDC<br />

excluded de facto online sales. After a general investigation of the distribution<br />

practices in the cosmetics sector, the French Competition Authority (Conseil de la<br />

concurrence) ordered PFDC “to remove from its selective distribution contracts all<br />

terms that are equivalent to a ban on internet sales [...] and to make express provision<br />

in its contracts for an option for its distributors to use that method of distribution [and]<br />

to pay a fine of EUR 17 000” 8 . PFDC appealed this order before the cour d’appel de<br />

Paris, reasoning that the decision was illegal as it denied the block exemption of<br />

VABER as well as the individual exemption of Article 101(3) TFEU. The cour<br />

d’appel de Paris asked the ECJ two questions in the preliminary process:<br />

1 ECJ 2 December 2010 (Ker-Optika bt C-108/09) Para 76.<br />

2 See below: IV(a).<br />

3 : See below: IV(a).<br />

4 Regulation (EC) No 2790/1999 of 22 December 1999, OJ L 336/21.<br />

5 See below: IV(b).<br />

6 ECJ 13 October 2011 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique SAS C-439/09 PARA 11.<br />

7 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 12.<br />

8 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 27.


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

• Firstly, whether “a general and absolute ban on selling contract goods to endusers<br />

via the internet, imposed on authorised distributors in the context of a<br />

selective distribution network, in fact constituted a “hardcore” restriction of<br />

competition by object” 9 (Article 101(1) TFEU) 10 ?<br />

• Secondly, whether this was justified either by a block exemption according to<br />

VABER 11 or by an individual exemption according to Article 101(3) TFEU 12 ?<br />

III – The Issue and the Result<br />

III(a) – The restriction of competition by object, Article 101(1) TFEU<br />

The contractual clauses used by PFDC provide a restriction by object, according to<br />

Article 101(1) TFEU. Even after individual and specific examination neither its<br />

content nor its objective nor its economic context cannot yield an objective<br />

justification.<br />

III(b) – The justification: (1) The block exemption, Regulation (EC) No 2790/1999<br />

(VABER)<br />

The block exemption provided for in Article 2 VABER with regard to Article 4(c)<br />

VABER is not applicable to a selective distribution contract with a clause prohibiting<br />

de facto internet sales.<br />

III(c) – The justification: (2) The individual exemption, Article 101(3) TFEU<br />

Though a contract with such a clause might benefit from the exception provided for in<br />

Article 101(3) TFEU the ECJ could for the lack of sufficient information not decide<br />

on this matter.<br />

IV – The Reasons<br />

IV(a) – The restriction of competition by object, Article 101(1) TFEU<br />

So do PFDC's contractual clauses provide a restriction of competition by object<br />

within the internal market? If affirmed, the French Competition Authority did not<br />

have to prove that any potential harm to competition existed. Thus the restriction of<br />

competition by object is similar to the U.S. concept called per se illegality (Section 1<br />

of the Sherman Act).<br />

To answer the first question one has to look at the precise purpose of the agreement<br />

within the economic context in which it is to be applied. 13 That involves respect to all<br />

circumstances, especially the clause's content and objectives, as well as its economic<br />

9 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 31.<br />

10 See below: IV(a).<br />

11 See below: IV(b)(1).<br />

12 See below: IV(b)(2).<br />

13 ECJ 30 June 1966 (Société Technique Minière (L.T.M.) C-56/66) ECR 1966 p. 235 (249); ECJ<br />

Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 34.<br />

101


Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique Sas, C-439/09<br />

and legal context. 14 PFDC's clause stipulates that the sales of a certain four brands of<br />

its products have to be made in an external space, where a qualified pharmacist is<br />

present, where from, it can be concluded that internet selling is de facto prohibited as<br />

it does not provide a physical external space where a pharmacist can be present. 15<br />

Thereupon, the ability of a distributor to sell PFDC's products to customers outside of<br />

his contractual area of activity is reduced, restricting competition in that very sector. 16<br />

The ECJ once again emphasised that agreements which constitute a selective<br />

distribution system necessarily affect the competition in the common market and are –<br />

as long as an objective justification is missing – restrictions by object. 17<br />

Such an objective justification might be the maintenance of a specialist trading<br />

network that is capable of providing specific services and therefore lead to a reduction<br />

of price competition, but at the same time attaining the improvement of competition<br />

to factors other than price. 18 For that, the resellers have to be chosen on the ground of<br />

objective criteria of quality, uniformly applicable to all potential resellers. Such a<br />

network has the following three requirements: firstly, it has to preserve the products’<br />

quality, secondly, it must ensure its proper use and thirdly, the criteria have to be<br />

necessary. 19 With the contractual clauses at issue PFDC laid down objective and<br />

uniformly applicable criteria to select the resellers. But the ECJ held that in a selective<br />

distribution system, the distributor could be restricted by the supplier, if – and only if<br />

– the supplier could come up with a legitimate aim that is proportionate to the given<br />

restrictions. 20 With regard to the freedoms of movement the need to provide the<br />

customer with individual advice, therewith ensuring his protection against the<br />

incorrect use of products is not sufficient if it concerns non-prescription medicines<br />

and contact lenses, thus banning internet sales. 21 As the cosmetic products are neither<br />

medicines nor similar products that provide a significant risk to the consumers, they<br />

do not need to be selectively distributed by a physically present pharmacist. The<br />

manufacturer's intention to maintain its prestigious image 22 cannot provide a<br />

sufficient and proportionate aim to justify the restriction of competition by object.<br />

To summarise, neither the protection of customers against the incorrect use of<br />

products nor the manufacturer’s intention to maintain the prestigious image of the<br />

14 ECJ 6 October 2009 (GlaxoSmithKline Services Unlimited and others Cases C-501/06 P, C-513/06<br />

P, C-515/06 P and C-519/06 P) ECR 2009 p. I-9291, para 58; Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6)<br />

para 35.<br />

15 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) paras 36 & 37.<br />

16 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 38.<br />

17 ECJ 25 October 1983 (AEG-Telefunken C-107/82) ECR 1983, p. I-3151, para 33; Pierre Fabre<br />

Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 39.<br />

18 AEG-Telefunken C-107/82 (n17); Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 40.<br />

19 ECJ 22 October 1986 (Metro SB-Großmärkte C-26/76) ECR 1977, p. I-1875, para 20; ECJ 11<br />

December 1980 (L’Oréal C-31/80) ECR 1980, p. I-3775, p. 3790 para 15 & p. 3791 para 16; Pierre<br />

Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 41.<br />

20 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 43.<br />

21 ECJ 11 December 2003 (Deutscher Apothekerverband C-322/01) ECR 2003 p. I-14887, 14996 paras<br />

106 & 107, p. 14998 para 112; ECJ 2 December 2010 (Ker-Optika bt C-108/09) para 76; Pierre Fabre<br />

Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 44.<br />

22 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) paras 45 & 46.<br />

102


UK Law Students’ Review – 2013 – <strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2<br />

products can, with regard to cosmetic products, be a legitimate aim for an objective<br />

justification, thus annulling the given restriction of competition by objective. 23<br />

IV(b) – The justification: (1) The block exemption, Regulation (EC) No 2790/1999<br />

(VABER)<br />

The ECJ then reflected on a possible justification in the case of a selective distribution<br />

contract that was rendered anti-competitive by its object.<br />

PFDC's first argument was that as the ban on internet sales was stated in a vertical<br />

agreement (Articles 2 VABER) – itself as a supplier with a market share that did not<br />

exceed 30% of the relevant market (Article 3 VABER) – then the ban was similar to a<br />

prohibition on operating out of an 'unauthorised place of establishment'. That is why<br />

PFDC should be benefiting from the block exemption according to Articles 2 and 3<br />

VABER. 24 Article 4 (c) VABER excludes the application of Article 2 VABER for<br />

vertical agreements which have as their object “the restriction of active or passive<br />

sales to end users by members of a selective distribution system operating at the retail<br />

level of trade”. The utilised contractual clauses that prohibited de facto the internet as<br />

a way of marketing have as their object the restriction of passive sales to end users<br />

who wish to buy online and in a different place from the one of the relevant member<br />

of the selective distribution system. 25 But Article 4 VABER provides in its last<br />

sentence a counter-exception for “the possibility of prohibiting a member of the<br />

system from operating out of an unauthorised place of establishment”. However,<br />

PFDC argued that the clauses used would meet this last sentence's counterexception.<br />

26 The ECJ specified that “a place of establishment” according to<br />

Article 4 (c) last sentence VABER literally concerned only outlets where direct sales<br />

take place. A broad interpretation of the block exemption Articles, to include places<br />

from which internet sales services are provided was not needed on the base of a<br />

systematic argument: the individual exception in Article 101(3) TFEU already gives a<br />

broad protection. 27 Thus, the ECJ distinguished the internet sales method from an<br />

“unauthorised place of establishment” and held the internet to be a marketing<br />

mechanism. 28 As a result, a selective distribution contract containing a clause that<br />

prohibits de facto the internet as a method of marketing the contractual products<br />

cannot be subsumed to Articles 2 & 4(c) VABER and therewith a valid justification. 29<br />

IV(b) – The justification: (2) The individual exemption, Article 101(3) TFEU<br />

As the ECJ did not deem itself to have sufficient information as to whether an<br />

individual exception according to Article 101(3) TFEU could be satisfied by the<br />

23 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 47.<br />

24 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) paras 51 & 52.<br />

25 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 54.<br />

26 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 55.<br />

27 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 56 & 57.<br />

28 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 58.<br />

29 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 59.<br />

103


Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique Sas, C-439/09<br />

clauses at issue that de facto prohibited online sales, it referred the question back to<br />

the cour d’appel de Paris. 30<br />

V – The Two Ratio Decidendi<br />

Contractual clauses that generate a general and absolute de facto ban of internet sales<br />

in a selective distribution network are a restriction of competition by object according<br />

to Article 101(1) TFEU, as long as the restriction cannot be objectively justified with<br />

attributes of the product at issue.<br />

Such a general and absolute de facto ban of internet sales in a selective distribution<br />

network cannot generally be an exemption according to Regulation<br />

(EC) No 2790/1999, VABER, though it might in exceptional circumstances be<br />

justified according to Article 101(3) TFEU.<br />

VI – The Author’s Thoughts on the Decision<br />

Internet sales in the European single market are very important, and viewed as such<br />

by the Commission and the ECJ. With regard to the Commission's supplementary<br />

guidelines on vertical restraints (2010/C 130/01, especially pp. 13 paras 52 et seqq.),<br />

of May 2010, that emphasis placed on the importance of internet sales in the<br />

European Union the ECJ judgment does not come as a surprise. Unfortunately the<br />

decision neither uses para 56 of the guidelines as a supporting argument for the<br />

interpretation of Article 4(c) VABER nor does it answer the multitudinous questions<br />

resulting from these very guidelines. But at least it confirms the Commission's view<br />

that an absolute and general ban on internet sales has more often than not to be<br />

considered to restrict, by its very object, competition as well as not being subject to a<br />

block exemption of VABER.<br />

Though manufacturers cannot prohibit their distributors the internet sale entirely,<br />

there is latitude for some restrictions. Thus under certain circumstances – for instance<br />

in contexts where the pro-competitive efficiencies resulting from such a ban outweigh<br />

the anti-competitive restriction – an individual justification according to Article<br />

101(3) TFEU might be possible. Hence a physical sales places might be a valid<br />

requirement as well as to define the minimum amount of products to be sold in that<br />

very physical place or the products presentation in the internet. While the ECJ seems<br />

to allow a loop to justify a ban of internet sales within a legal exception, there is not<br />

the tiniest hint which precise requirements fulfil such a justification, that are beyond<br />

public provisions. Furthermore, the burden of proof lies with the supplier. That is why<br />

a supplier has to analyse, with a lot of care, the situation, before he can rely on an<br />

individual exemption, even more so as the consequences can be significant.<br />

Ultimately, suppliers of luxuriousness are kept in doubt as to how to act.<br />

30 Pierre Fabre Dermo-Cosmétique (n6) para 50.<br />

104


www.oxfordtextbooks.co.uk/statutes


THE UNITED KINGDOM LAW STUDENTS’ REVIEW<br />

<strong>Volume</strong> 1, Issue 2 – January 2013<br />

www.uklsa.co.uk/law-review.htm<br />

The <strong>UKLSR</strong> is the flagship publication of the UK Law Students’ Association. We<br />

aim to publish innovative and creative scholarship covering a wide variety of topics of<br />

interest to students and practitioners alike. The Editors wish to thank the UKLSA<br />

Executive Team, the Oxford University Press and our university partners for their<br />

invaluable support and assistance.<br />

Please note that the views expressed in this journal are those of the authors and do not<br />

necessarily reflect those of the Editors nor of the UKLSA; we are therefore unable to<br />

accept responsibility for the consequences of any errors contained within the<br />

submissions, however every effort has been made to ensure their accuracy.<br />

© Copyright 2013 by UK Law Students’ Association. All rights reserved.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!