03.06.2013 Views

Slides-1 [Dynamic Semantics] - UCLA Department of Linguistics

Slides-1 [Dynamic Semantics] - UCLA Department of Linguistics

Slides-1 [Dynamic Semantics] - UCLA Department of Linguistics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Presupposition<br />

<strong>UCLA</strong>, Fall 2007<br />

Philippe Schlenker<br />

(<strong>UCLA</strong> & Institut Jean-Nicod)


Presupposition<br />

Approximation: A presupposition <strong>of</strong> S is a condition that<br />

must be met for S to be true or false.<br />

Presuppositions<br />

a. John knows that he is incompetent.<br />

π: John is incompetent.<br />

b. Does John knows that he is incompetent?<br />

π: John is incompetent<br />

c. John doesn’t know that he is incompetent.<br />

π: John is incompetent.<br />

Entailments<br />

a. John is French. => John is European.<br />

b. Is John French? ≠> John is European.<br />

c. John isn’t French. ≠> John is European.<br />

2


Why Study Presupposition ?<br />

I. Presuppositions are ubiquitous<br />

John regrets that he is incompetent.<br />

π: John is incompetent.<br />

John has stopped smoking.<br />

π: John used to smoke.<br />

It is John who left.<br />

π: Someone left.<br />

What John drank was vodka.<br />

π: John drank something.<br />

She is clever!<br />

π: The person pointed at is female.<br />

3


John too was jailed.<br />

π: Someone other than John was jailed.<br />

John was jailed again.<br />

π: John was jailed before.<br />

Only John was jailed.<br />

π: Somebody was jailed.<br />

4


Why Study Presupposition ?<br />

II. Presuppositions and <strong>Dynamic</strong> <strong>Semantics</strong><br />

Static View <strong>of</strong> Meaning<br />

Meaning = Truth Conditions<br />

<strong>Dynamic</strong> View <strong>of</strong> Meaning (after the 1980’s)<br />

Meaning = Context Change Potential<br />

= potential to change beliefs<br />

Motivations for the dynamic view<br />

a. Pronouns, e.g. Every man who has a donkey beats it.<br />

b. Presuppositions.<br />

5


Why Study Presupposition ?<br />

III. The <strong>Semantics</strong> vs. Pragmatics Divide<br />

<strong>Semantics</strong> = study <strong>of</strong> meaning as it is encoded in words<br />

John is an American student<br />

=> John is a student<br />

John is a former student<br />

≠> John is a student<br />

Pragmatics = study <strong>of</strong> the additional information that<br />

can be obtained by reasoning on the speaker’s motives<br />

Mr. Smith is unfailingly polite and always on time<br />

=> Smith is a bad student<br />

6


<strong>Semantics</strong> vs. Pragmatics<br />

7


Entailments vs. Implicatures<br />

Difference 1: Entailments follow from what is<br />

linguistically encoded. Implicatures do not.<br />

Difference 2: Entailments satisfy the following test.<br />

Implicatures generally don't.<br />

To check whether p entails q, check whether:<br />

In every conceivable situation in which it is true that p, it<br />

is true that q.<br />

Difference 3: Implicatures can be cancelled. Entailments<br />

cannot be.<br />

8


Scalar Implicatures<br />

a. Rick is a philosopher or he is a poet<br />

(B. Schwarz)<br />

b. John will leave or Mary will leave.<br />

c. Paris is pleasant or London is pleasant.<br />

9


Hypothesis 1.<br />

Disjunction is unambiguously exclusive.<br />

[[ [i or i'] ]] = true iff exactly one <strong>of</strong> [[i]], [[i']] is true<br />

Notational variant (with 1 = true, 0 = false)<br />

[[ [i or i'] ]] = 1 iff exactly one <strong>of</strong> [[i]], [[i']] is equal to 1<br />

10


1. a is predicted to be a contradiction; it should have<br />

the same status as b.<br />

a. Rick is a philosopher or he is a poet. In fact, he is both.<br />

b. #Rick is a philosopher or he is a poet but he is not both.<br />

In fact, he is both.<br />

2. Incorrect predictions<br />

a. Every Italian who is a philosopher or a poet is a<br />

socialist.<br />

b. Whenever I invite a philosopher or a poet to a party, it<br />

ends up being a success.<br />

11


Every Italian who is a philosopher or a poet is a socialist.<br />

i 1, is a philosopher but not a poet, and he is a socialist.<br />

i 2, is a poet but not a philosopher, and he is a socialist.<br />

i 3, is both a philosopher and a poet, but he is not a socialist.<br />

12


Hypothesis 2.<br />

Disjunction is ambiguous<br />

1. Cross-linguistic morphology<br />

2. The ambiguity theory predicts that a. could be<br />

understood as true in the situation we described earlier.<br />

3. Ellipsis (Fox, crediting T. Stephenson)<br />

John read Chomsky or Montague. Mary did too. In fact,<br />

she read both<br />

13


General observation about ellipsis<br />

John went to the bank. Mary did too.<br />

bank is ambiguous:<br />

bank 1 = slope near the side <strong>of</strong> a river<br />

bank 2 = financial institution<br />

Ok John went to the bank 1. Mary went to the bank 1 too.<br />

Ok John went to the bank 2. Mary went to the bank 2 too.<br />

* John went to the bank 1. Mary went to the bank 2 too.<br />

* John went to the bank 2. Mary went to the bank 1 too.<br />

Ok John went to the bank 1. Mary did go to the bank 1 too.<br />

Ok John went to the bank 2. Mary did go to the bank 2 too.<br />

* John went to the bank 1. Mary did go to the bank 2 too.<br />

* John went to the bank 2. Mary did go to the bank 1 too.<br />

14


4. Yet another problem...<br />

a. It is certain that John will read Chomsky or Montague.<br />

b. Every student read Chomsky or Montague.<br />

15


Hypothesis 3.<br />

Scalar Implicatures<br />

Hypothesis:(i) ‘or’ is inclusive disjunction. (ii) an<br />

implicature is responsible for the not and inference.<br />

S said: F or G<br />

form a scale: F and G entails F or G.<br />

If S believed that F and G, it would have been more<br />

cooperative to say: F and G<br />

Primary Implicature: NOT S believes (F and G)<br />

If John is well informed and either believes or disbelieves<br />

(F and G), we also get:<br />

Secondary Implicature: S believes NOT(F and G)<br />

16


I. Alternatives<br />

Alt(S) = {S': S' is a sentence obtained from S by replacing<br />

simultaneously any number <strong>of</strong> occurrences <strong>of</strong> or by and<br />

and any number <strong>of</strong> occurrences <strong>of</strong> and by or}.<br />

a. S 1 = Rick is a philosopher or a poet<br />

Alt(S 1) = {Rick is a philosopher or a poet, Rick is a<br />

philosopher and a poet}<br />

b. S 2 = Rick is a philosopher and a poet<br />

Alt(S 2) = Alt(S 1) = {Rick is a philosopher or a poet, Rick is<br />

a philosopher and a poet}<br />

c. S 3 = I doubt that Rick is a philosopher and a poet<br />

Alt(S 3)={I doubt that Rick is a philosopher and a poet, I<br />

doubt that Rick is a philosopher or a poet}<br />

17


Ordering<br />

II. Ordering and Cooperation<br />

Let S be a sentence and let S' be a member <strong>of</strong> Alt(S).<br />

S' is better than S if:<br />

a. S' entails S and S does not entail S'<br />

[terminology: we say that S' asymmetrically entails S]<br />

b. The speaker believes that S'<br />

Cooperation<br />

A sentence S is not uttered cooperatively if for some S' in<br />

Alt(S), S' is better than S.<br />

18


Scalar Implicatures<br />

a. Rick is a philosopher or a poet<br />

b. Alt(a)={Rick is a philosopher or a poet, Rick is a<br />

philosopher and a poet}<br />

c. __ and __ >> __ or __<br />

a. is not uttered cooperatively if the speaker believes that<br />

Rick is a philosopher and a poet.<br />

-Primary Implicature: If the speaker is cooperative, it's<br />

not the case that the speaker believes that Rick is both a<br />

philosopher and a poet.<br />

-Secondary Implicature: If the speaker has an opinion on<br />

this matter, it must be that he believes that Rick is not both<br />

a philosopher and poet.<br />

19


Scalar Implicatures<br />

a. Rick is a philosopher and a poet<br />

b. Alt(a)={Rick is a philosopher and a poet, Rick is a<br />

philosopher or a poet}<br />

c. No member <strong>of</strong> Alt(a) asymmetrically entails a, so<br />

nothing additional is inferred.<br />

20


'Scale Reversal'<br />

a. I doubt that Rick is a philosopher and a poet<br />

b. Alt(a)={I doubt that Rick is a philosopher or a poet, I<br />

doubt Rick is a philosopher and a poet}<br />

c. I doubt that __ or __ >> I doubt that __ and __<br />

a. is not uttered cooperatively if the speaker doubts that<br />

Rick is a philosopher or a poet.<br />

... hence if the speaker is cooperative, the speaker does not<br />

doubt that Rick is a philosopher or a poet (i.e. he believes<br />

that Rick is a philosopher or a poet)<br />

a philosopher and poet.<br />

21


'Scale Reversal'<br />

a. Every Italian who is a philosopher or a poet is a<br />

socialist<br />

=> no additional inference (because the version with and<br />

would be less informative)<br />

b. Every Italian who is a philosopher and a poet is a<br />

socialist.<br />

=> it’s not the case that every Italian who is a philosopher<br />

or a poet is a socialist,<br />

i.e. some Italian who is a philosopher or a poet (but not<br />

both) is not a socialist.<br />

22


'Scale Reversal'<br />

a. Whenever John is next to Mary or Ann, he behaves like<br />

an idiot<br />

=> no additional inference<br />

b. Whenever John is next to Mary and Ann, he behaves<br />

like an idiot.<br />

=> It's not the case that whenever John is next to Mary or<br />

Ann, he behaves like an idiot.<br />

23


Some, Most, Every<br />

a. Some <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever<br />

=> Not all <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever.<br />

=> A minority <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever.<br />

b. Some <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever. In fact, all <strong>of</strong> them are.<br />

a. Most <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever<br />

=> Not all <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever.<br />

b. Most <strong>of</strong> my friends are clever. In fact, all <strong>of</strong> them are.<br />

a. Whenever most <strong>of</strong> the students come to class, there is a<br />

pleasant atmosphere.<br />

b. Every student who read most <strong>of</strong> the articles on the<br />

reading list will get an A.<br />

24


<br />

Extensions<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

25


a. John read some book.<br />

Why are Scales Necessary?<br />

b. John read exactly one book.<br />

c. (b) is more informative than (a), therefore the speaker<br />

was not in a position to assert (b)<br />

d. Therefore it is likely that John didn’t read exactly one<br />

book.<br />

☞ This is the opposite <strong>of</strong> the result we want!<br />

26


Other Implicatures<br />

John is in Paris or he is in Rome<br />

=> it is not the case that:<br />

a. the speaker believes that John is in Paris.<br />

b. the speaker believes that John is not in Paris.<br />

c . the speaker believes that John is in Rome.<br />

d. the speaker believes that John is not in Rome.<br />

If John is in Paris, he is there for business.<br />

=> the speaker takes it to be possible but not certain that<br />

John is in Paris<br />

27


Experiment - Scalar Implicatures<br />

(Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland)<br />

28


[Credits: Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland]<br />

30


[Credits: Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland]<br />

31


[Credits: Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland]<br />

32


[Credits: Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland]<br />

33


[Credits: Crain & co-workers, U. Maryland]<br />

34


Children and Scalar Implicatures<br />

Children appear not to compute Scalar Implicatures in<br />

some environments where adults do.<br />

Paradox: children appear to be 'more logical' than adults!<br />

35


Scalar Implicatures Take Time<br />

Noveck and Posada 2003<br />

38


Three Properties <strong>of</strong> Scalar Implicatures<br />

Unlike entailments, they can be cancelled.<br />

They ‘disappear’ in certain environments (and ‘appear’ in<br />

others).<br />

They are acquired relatively late by children.<br />

They take time to compute.<br />

40


Presuppositions<br />

41


Presuppositions vs. Entailments<br />

Difference 1 (dubious)<br />

If an entailment <strong>of</strong> S is false, S is false, not weird.<br />

-John is French.<br />

-No. He is South African.<br />

-John knows that he is going to be fired.<br />

-No. He doesn’t know it.<br />

- No. He is going to keep his job.<br />

42


Presuppositions vs. Entailments<br />

Difference 2 (very clear)<br />

Presuppositions ‘project’ differently from entailments.<br />

a. Is John French? ≠> John is European<br />

b. John is not French. ≠> John is European<br />

c. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is French<br />

≠> Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is European<br />

≠> Some <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is European<br />

a. Does John know that he is incompetent?<br />

=> John is incompetent<br />

b. John does not know that he is incompetent<br />

=> John is incompetent<br />

c. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students knows that he is incompetent<br />

=> Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is incompetent<br />

43


Presuppositions vs. Entailments<br />

a. Does John take care <strong>of</strong> his computer?<br />

=> John has a computer<br />

b. John doesn’t take care <strong>of</strong> his computer<br />

=> John has a computer<br />

c. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students takes care <strong>of</strong> his computer<br />

=> Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students has a computer<br />

a. Did John stop smoking?<br />

=> John used to smoke.<br />

b. John didn’t stop smoking<br />

=> John used to smoke<br />

c. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students stopped smoking<br />

=> Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students used to smoke<br />

44


Presuppositions vs. Implicatures<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> presuppositions as implicatures<br />

Hypothesis: If pp’ is a clause described as having<br />

presupposition p and assertion p’:<br />

(i) pp’ has as its meaning the conjunction <strong>of</strong> p and p’<br />

(ii) but forms a scale<br />

Examples<br />

a. <br />

b. <br />

c. <br />

45


Predictions I<br />

pp’ entails p <br />

a. John knows that he is incompetent<br />

=> John is incompetent<br />

b. I’ll invite John and Mary<br />

=> I’ll invite John or Mary<br />

not pp’ implicates p <br />

because (not p) is more informative than (not pp’) !<br />

a. John doesn’t know that he is incompetent<br />

implicates: John is incompetent<br />

b. I won’t invite (both) John and Mary<br />

=> I’ll invite John or Mary<br />

46


Predictions II<br />

No student PP’ implicates Some student P<br />

because No student P<br />

is more informative than No student PP’<br />

hence the inference that not No student P<br />

i.e. Some student P<br />


Presuppositions vs. Entailments:<br />

An Experiment (French, Chemla 2007)<br />

48


Experimental Conditions<br />

Triggers<br />

• Presuppositions<br />

attitude verbs: know, be unaware<br />

change <strong>of</strong> state: start, stop<br />

definite descriptions: his computer<br />

• Implicatures: , , <br />

Environments<br />

-Inferences: universal-like and implicature-like<br />

-Operators: John ___, I doubt that John ___, More than 3<br />

<strong>of</strong> these 10 students ___ , Each <strong>of</strong> the 10 students ___,<br />

None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students ___, Exactly 3 <strong>of</strong> these 10<br />

students ____.<br />

49


Examples<br />

Less than 3 <strong>of</strong> these 10 students know that their father is<br />

about to receive a congratulation letter.<br />

=>? The father <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> these students is about to receive<br />

a congratulation letter.<br />

=>? The father <strong>of</strong> at least 3 students is about to receive a<br />

congratulation letter.<br />

None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students read the handout and did an<br />

exercise.<br />

=>? Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students did (at least) one or the other<br />

=>? At least 1 <strong>of</strong> these 10 students did (at least) one or the<br />

other<br />

50


Main Results (Chemla 2007)<br />

Presuppositions display a different a behavior from<br />

scalar implicatures under no:<br />

-Non-universal inferences for implicatures<br />

-Universal implicatures for presuppositions<br />

Not all quantifiers behave on a par:<br />

at least 3, more than 3, exactly 3 display an intermediate<br />

behavior (universal inferences half the time).<br />

Not computing a presupposition takes time.<br />

51


NO and Universal Inferences<br />

Left, from left to right<br />

1. Every student stopped<br />

smoking => every student<br />

smoked<br />

2. No student stopped<br />

smoking => at least one<br />

student smoked<br />

3. No student stopped<br />

smoking => every student<br />

smoked<br />

Right, from left to right<br />

1. Every student did A and<br />

B => every student did (at<br />

least) one<br />

2. No student student did A<br />

and B => at least one<br />

student did (at least) one<br />

3. No student did A and B<br />

=> every student did (at<br />

least) one<br />

52


NO and Universal Inferences<br />

53


Less than three and Universal Inferences<br />

54


Universal Inferences for Various Quantifiers<br />

55


Reaction Times: Universal Inferences<br />

56


Triggering Problem<br />

Questions<br />

Why do some elementary clauses have presuppositions?<br />

a. John knows that it is raining<br />

π: It is raining.<br />

b. John rightly believes that it is raining<br />

π: none, or possibly: John believes that it is raining.<br />

57


Projection Problem<br />

Questions<br />

How do the presuppositions <strong>of</strong> elementary clauses get<br />

transmitted to complex clauses ?<br />

a. If John is realistic, he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

π: John is incompetent<br />

b. If John is an idiot, he knows that he incompetent<br />

π: none, or possibly: if John is an idiot, he is incompetent<br />

58


Questions<br />

Architectural Question<br />

Where do presuppositions belong in the architecture or<br />

language?<br />

Are they a semantic or a pragmatic phenomenon?<br />

59


The Projection Problem<br />

60


Conjunction<br />

a. John knows that he is incompetent<br />

b. Is it true that John knows that he is incompetent?<br />

π: John is incompetent<br />

c. I doubt that John knows that he is incompetent<br />

π: John is incompetent<br />

d. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students knows that he is incompetent.<br />

π: Each <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is incompetent.<br />

a. John is incompetent and knows that he is.<br />

b. Is it true that John is incompetent and knows that he is?<br />

π: none<br />

c. I doubt that John is incompetent and knows that he is.<br />

π: none<br />

d. None <strong>of</strong> these 10 students is incompetent and knows it.<br />

π: none<br />

61


Conjunction<br />

a. John is depressed and his boss knows that he is<br />

incompetent<br />

b. Is it true that John is depressed and that his boss knows<br />

that he is incompetent?<br />

π: John is incompetent<br />

c. I doubt that John is depressed and that his boss knows<br />

that he is incompetent.<br />

a. John is an idiot and his boss knows that he is<br />

incompetent.<br />

b. Is it true that John is an idiot and that his boss knows that<br />

he incompetent?<br />

π: if John is an idiot, he is incompetent (?)<br />

c. I doubt that John is an idiot and that his boss knows that<br />

he is incompetent.<br />

62


Conjunction<br />

p and qq’ presupposes p ⇒ q<br />

(... to be refined)<br />

John is incompetent and he knows it / that he is<br />

π: none<br />

John is an idiot and he knows that he is incompetent<br />

π: if John is an idiot, he is incompetent<br />

John is depressed and his boss knows that he is<br />

incompetent<br />

Predicted π: If John is depressed, he is incompetent<br />

Actual π: John is incompetent<br />

Maybe because: the most plausible way to make the<br />

conditional true is to assume that its consequent is!<br />

63


Conditionals<br />

a. If John is incompetent, he knows that he is.<br />

b. Is it true that if John is incompetent, he knows that he is?<br />

c. I doubt that if John is incompetent, he knows that he is.<br />

a. If John is realistic, he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

b. Is it true that if John is realistic, he knows that he is<br />

incompetent?<br />

c. I doubt that if John is realistic, he knows that he is<br />

incompetent.<br />

a. If John is over 65, he knows he can’t apply.<br />

b. Is it true that if John is over 65, he knows he can’t apply?<br />

c. I doubt that if John is over 65, he knows he can’t apply.<br />

64


Conditionals<br />

a. If John knows that he is overqualified, he won’t apply.<br />

b. Is it true that if John knows that he is overqualified, he<br />

won’t apply?<br />

c. I doubt that if John knows that he is overqualified, he<br />

won’t apply.<br />

a. If John knows that he is overqualified, he is depressed<br />

b. Is it true that if John knows that he is overqualified, he is<br />

depressed?<br />

c. I doubt that if John knows that he is overqualified, he is<br />

depressed.<br />

a. if p, qq’ presupposes p ⇒ q<br />

b. if pp’, q presupposes p<br />

65


Disjunctions<br />

a. If John is incompetent, he knows that he is.<br />

b. Either John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

a. If John is realistic, he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

b.Either John is not realistic,or he knows he is incompetent.<br />

a. If John is over 65, he knows he can’t apply.<br />

b. Either John isn’t over 65, or he knows he can’t apply<br />

a. If John knows that he is overqualified, he won’t apply.<br />

b. Either John doesn’t know that he is over qualified, or he<br />

won’t apply.<br />

a. p or qq’ presupposes (not p) ⇒ q<br />

b. pp’ or q presupposes p<br />

66


Stalnaker’s Pragmatic Analysis<br />

67


A Pragmatic Analysis<br />

p and qq’ presupposes p ⇒ q<br />

‘... when a speaker says something <strong>of</strong> the form A and B, he<br />

may take it for granted that A (or at least that his audience<br />

recognizes that he accepts that A) after he has said it. The<br />

proposition that A will be added to the background <strong>of</strong> common<br />

assumptions before the speaker asserts that B.<br />

Now suppose that B expresses a proposition that would, for<br />

some reason, be inappropriate to assert except in a context<br />

where A, or something entailed by A, is presupposed. Even if A<br />

is not presupposed initially, one may still assert A and B<br />

since by the time one gets to saying that B, the context has<br />

shifted, and it is by then presupposed that A.’<br />

Stalnaker, ‘Pragmatic Presuppositions’, 1974<br />

68


Assumptions<br />

Assumption 1: Sentences may be true, false or #<br />

Assumption 2: A sentence S is a presupposition failure if it<br />

has the value # with respect to at least one <strong>of</strong> the states <strong>of</strong><br />

affairs compatible with what the speech act participants<br />

take for granted.<br />

Definition 1: Common Ground = what the speech act<br />

participants take for granted.<br />

Definition 2: Context Set = set <strong>of</strong> worlds compatible with<br />

what the speech act participants take for granted.<br />

Assumption 3: The Context Set is updated incrementally<br />

in discourse and in conjunctions.<br />

69


Possible Worlds<br />

A possible world w = a complete specification <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

going on. It determines for every sentence S whether<br />

[[ S ]] w = true, [[ S ]] w = false, or [[ S ]] w = #.<br />

Different clauses give rise to different functions, e.g.:<br />

The President <strong>of</strong><br />

France is Chirac<br />

w 1 → false<br />

w 2 → true<br />

w 3 → #<br />

w 4 → #<br />

...<br />

The US<br />

President is Bush<br />

w 1 → true<br />

w 2 → false<br />

w 3 → true<br />

w 4 → #<br />

...<br />

Two plus two<br />

is four<br />

w 1 → true<br />

w 2 → true<br />

w 3 → true<br />

w 4 → true<br />

70


Non-Contradiction<br />

Further Conditions<br />

A sentence S uttered in a Context Set C is deviant if S is<br />

true in no world <strong>of</strong> C.<br />

Non-Triviality<br />

A sentence S uttered in a Context Set C is deviant if S is<br />

true in every world <strong>of</strong> C.<br />

71


Stalnaker’s Analysis<br />

John knows that he is incompetent is:<br />

-true in w if John is incompetent and believes that he is<br />

-false in w if John is incompetent and doesn’t believe he is<br />

-# in w if John is not incompetent.<br />

Suppose that the speech act participants do not know<br />

whether John is or isn’t incompetent. Suppose further that<br />

the Context Set C is C = {w 1, w 2, w 3, w 4}<br />

w 1 : John is incompetent and believes that he is<br />

w 2: John is incompetent and believes he isn’t<br />

w 3: John is not incompetent but believes he is<br />

w 4: John is not incompetent and believes he isn’t<br />

72


Stalnaker’s Analysis<br />

T = John knows that he is incompetent uttered in C is a<br />

presupposition failure because this sentence is # in w 3 and<br />

w 4, which both belong to C<br />

Suppose that the speech act participants do not know<br />

whether John is or isn’t incompetent. Suppose further that<br />

the Context Set C is C = {w 1, w 2, w 3, w 4}<br />

w 1 : John is incompetent and believes that he is<br />

w 2: John is incompetent and believes he isn’t<br />

w 3: John is not incompetent but believes he is<br />

w 4: John is not incompetent and believes he isn’t<br />

73


Stalnaker’s Analysis<br />

S = John is incompetent is:<br />

-true in w if John is incompetent in w.<br />

-false in w in all other cases<br />

(i.e. the sentence does not have a presupposition)<br />

a. Acceptability<br />

Clearly, John is incompetent uttered in C is not a<br />

presupposition failure.<br />

b. Update<br />

-Initially, the Context Set was C = {w 1, w 2, w 3, w 4}<br />

-After S is uttered,<br />

the new Context Set is: C’ = {w 1, w 2}<br />

(i.e. only the worlds compatible with S are retained)<br />

74


Stalnaker’s Analysis<br />

John is incompetent. He knows it.<br />

= S. T.<br />

Step 1.<br />

-The initial Context Set is C = {w 1, w 2, w 3, w 4}<br />

-After the first sentence is uttered,<br />

the new Context Set is C’ = {w 1, w 2}<br />

Step 2.<br />

-The second sentence is evaluated with respect to C’<br />

-By construction, in each world in C’, T has a value<br />

different from #. So T is not a presupposition failure in C’.<br />

Step 3.<br />

C’ is updated to C” = {w 1} .<br />

75


Conjunction<br />

Stalnaker’s Analysis<br />

a. Treat S and T in the same way as the discourse S. T: the<br />

assertion <strong>of</strong> a conjunction is a succession <strong>of</strong> two assertions.<br />

b. Beautiful analysis <strong>of</strong> presupposition projection:<br />

every world in C that satisfies S must satisfy T.<br />

In other words: C |= S ⇒ T<br />

Limitations<br />

a. How does the analysis extend to other operators?<br />

b. How does the analysis extend to embedded<br />

conjunctions?<br />

e.g. None <strong>of</strong> my students is rich and proud <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

76


Heim’s Semantic Analysis<br />

(following in part Karttunen 1974)<br />

77


Karttunen I: The Limits <strong>of</strong> Brute Force<br />

78


Karttunen II: Admittance Conditions<br />

a. Brute Force Method<br />

define recursively the (complex!) rules by which the<br />

presuppositions <strong>of</strong> complex sentences are computed on the<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> the presuppositions <strong>of</strong> their parts.<br />

b. Admittance Conditions<br />

(i) take as primitive the notion <strong>of</strong> a context satisfying the<br />

presuppositions <strong>of</strong> an elementary clause.<br />

(ii) extend recursively the notion <strong>of</strong> satisfaction.<br />

79


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Karttunen<br />

Separate specification <strong>of</strong>:<br />

(i) admittance conditions<br />

(ii) truth-conditional (assertive) content.<br />

Gazdar’s critique (<strong>of</strong> Karttunen & Peters): this is not<br />

explanatory!<br />

Heim<br />

a. The ‘context change potential’ <strong>of</strong> an expression cannot<br />

be derived from its assertive content.<br />

b. But its assertive content cannot be derived from its<br />

context-change potential.<br />

(... once one has the right context change potential!!!)<br />

80


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Heim vs. Stalnaker<br />

a. Keep from Stalnaker’s analysis<br />

-the idea <strong>of</strong> an update<br />

-the analysis <strong>of</strong> presupposition projection in conjunctions<br />

b. Drop the pragmatic derivation <strong>of</strong> Stalnaker’s analysis.<br />

Heim vs. Karttunen<br />

-In Karttunen’s system, admittance conditions are specified<br />

separately from the assertive content <strong>of</strong> expressions.<br />

-For Heim, Context Change Potentials do double duty.<br />

The <strong>Dynamic</strong> Conception <strong>of</strong> Meaning<br />

-Old conception: meanings as truth conditions<br />

-New conception: meanings as Context Change Potentials,<br />

i.e. as functions from Context Sets to Context Sets.<br />

81


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Notation: C[F] = update <strong>of</strong> the Context Set C with F<br />

Elementary Clauses<br />

a. C[John is incompetent]<br />

= # iff C = #<br />

= {w∈C: John is incompetent in w} otherwise<br />

b. C[John knows that he is incompetent]<br />

= # iff C=# or for some w∈C, John is not incompetent in w<br />

= {w∈C: John believes he is incompetent in w}, otherwise<br />

Truth<br />

If C[S] ≠ # and w∈C, then: S is true at w iff w ∈ C[S]<br />

Conjunction<br />

C[F and G] = C[F][G]<br />

82


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Negation<br />

C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise<br />

a. not F = John doesn’t know that he is incompetent.<br />

b. C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #, iff for some w∈C, John is not<br />

incompetent in w<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise,<br />

i.e. = C - {w∈C: John believes he is incompetent in w}<br />

F<br />

83


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Negation<br />

C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise<br />

This means that<br />

not(pp’)<br />

presupposes that p<br />

a. not F = John doesn’t know that he is incompetent.<br />

b. C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #, iff for some w∈C, John is not<br />

incompetent in w<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise,<br />

i.e. = C - {w∈C: John believes he is incompetent in w}<br />

F<br />

84


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Negation<br />

C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise<br />

a. not F = John doesn’t know that he is incompetent.<br />

b. C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #, iff for some w∈C, John is not<br />

incompetent in w<br />

= C - C[F] otherwise,<br />

i.e. = C - {w∈C: John believes he is incompetent in w}<br />

F<br />

85


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Conditionals (analyzed as material implications)<br />

F<br />

C[if F, G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[F][not G] = #<br />

= C - C[F][not G], otherwise<br />

Worlds that<br />

refute<br />

if F, G<br />

G<br />

86


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Conditionals (analyzed as material implications)<br />

F<br />

C[if F, G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[F][not G] = #<br />

= C - C[F][not G], otherwise<br />

This means that if pp’, q presupposes that p,<br />

and that if p, qq’, presupposes if p, q<br />

Worlds that<br />

refute<br />

if F, G<br />

G<br />

87


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

Conditionals (analyzed as material implications)<br />

F<br />

C[if F, G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[F][not G] = #<br />

= C - C[F][not G], otherwise<br />

Worlds that<br />

refute<br />

if F, G<br />

G<br />

88


Heim’s Synthesis<br />

if F, G = If John is incompetent, he knows it<br />

C[if F, G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[F][not G] = #<br />

But C[F] ≠ # and furthermore<br />

C[F] = {w∈C: John is incompetent in w}<br />

C[F][not G] = # iff C[F][G] = #, which is not the case (by<br />

construction). Furthermore,<br />

C[F][not G] = {w∈C: John is incompetent in w}[not G]<br />

= {w∈C: John is incompetent in w}<br />

- {w∈C: John is incompetent in w and John believes he is<br />

incompetent in w}<br />

= {w∈C: John is incompetent but doesn’t believe it in w}<br />

C[if F, G] = C - {w∈C: John is incompetent but doesn’t<br />

believe it in w}<br />

89


Summary<br />

Meaning <strong>of</strong> an elementary clause = a CCP<br />

Conjunction<br />

C[F and G] = C[F][G]<br />

Negation<br />

C[not F] = # iff C[F] = #; = C - C[F] otherwise<br />

Conditionals<br />

C[if F, G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[F][not G] = #<br />

= C - C[F][not G], otherwise<br />

Disjunction<br />

C[F or G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[not F][G] = #<br />

= C[F] ∪ C[not F][G], otherwise<br />

90


Disjunctions<br />

a. If John is incompetent, he knows that he is.<br />

b. Either John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

a. If John is realistic, he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

b.Either John is not realistic,or he knows he is incompetent.<br />

a. If John is over 65, he knows he can’t apply.<br />

b. Either John isn’t over 65, or he knows he can’t apply<br />

a. If John knows that he is overqualified, he won’t apply.<br />

b. Either John doesn’t know that he is over qualified, or he<br />

won’t apply.<br />

a. p or qq’ presupposes (not p) ⇒ q<br />

b. pp’ or q presupposes p<br />

91


Heim’s Analysis<br />

Disjunction<br />

C[F or G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[not F][G] = #<br />

= C[F] ∪ C[not F][G] otherwise.<br />

F<br />

a. John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

b. C[not I or K] = # iff C[not I] = # or C[not not I][K] = #,<br />

i.e. iff C[I] = # or C[I][K] = #, which is never the case.<br />

Thus C[not I or K] = C[not I] ∪ C[I][K]<br />

G<br />

92


Heim’s Analysis<br />

Disjunction<br />

C[F or G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[not F][G] = #<br />

F<br />

= C[F] ∪ C[not F][G] otherwise.<br />

a. John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

b. C[not I or K] = # iff C[not I] = # or C[not not I][K] = #,<br />

i.e. iff C[I] = # or C[I][K] = #, which is never the case.<br />

Thus C[not I or K] = C[not I] ∪ C[I][K]<br />

G<br />

This means that<br />

pp’ or q presupposes<br />

that p,<br />

and that p or<br />

qq’presupposes<br />

if (not p), q<br />

93


Heim’s Analysis<br />

Disjunction<br />

C[F or G] = # iff C[F] = # or C[not F][G] = #<br />

= C[F] ∪ C[not F][G] otherwise.<br />

F<br />

a. John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

b. C[not I or K] = # iff C[not I] = # or C[not not I][K] = #,<br />

i.e. iff C[I] = # or C[I][K] = #, which is never the case.<br />

Thus C[not I or K] = C[not I] ∪ C[I][K]<br />

G<br />

94


Heim’s Analysis<br />

Definition <strong>of</strong> Truth<br />

If w∈C,<br />

a. F is # in w relative to C iff C[F] = #<br />

b. If ≠ #, F is true in w relative to C iff w∈C[F]<br />

John is incompetent. He knows it.<br />

= S. T.<br />

C = {w 1, w 2, w 3, w 4}<br />

C[S] = C’ = {w 1, w 2}<br />

C[S][T] = C” = {w 1} .<br />

a. Relative to w1, C, the discourse is true, since w1∈C[S][T] b. Relative to w2, C, the discourse is false , since<br />

w2∉C[S][T] 95


Heim’s Explanatory Problem<br />

Problem: is the account explanatory? (Soames 1989)<br />

C[F and G] = (C[F])[G]<br />

C[F and* G] = (C[G])[F]<br />

When F and G are not presuppositional,<br />

C[F and G]=C[F and* G]={w∈C: F is true in w and G is<br />

true in w}<br />

96


Heim’s Explanatory Problem<br />

There are many ways to define the CCP <strong>of</strong> or...<br />

F<br />

C[F or 1 G] = C[F] ∪ C[G], unless one <strong>of</strong> those is #<br />

C[F or 2 G] = C[F] ∪ C[not F][G], unless one <strong>of</strong> those is #<br />

C[F or 3 G] = C[not G][F] ∪ C[G], unless one <strong>of</strong> those is #<br />

G<br />

97


Gazdar’s Account<br />

98


Non-Contradiction<br />

Reminder 1: Non-Triviality<br />

A sentence S uttered in a Context Set C is deviant if S is<br />

true in no world <strong>of</strong> C.<br />

Non-Triviality<br />

A sentence S uttered in a Context Set C is deviant if S is<br />

true in every world <strong>of</strong> C.<br />

99


Reminder 2: Other Implicatures<br />

John is in Paris or he is in Rome<br />

=> it is not the case that:<br />

a. the speaker believes that John is in Paris.<br />

b. the speaker believes that John is not in Paris.<br />

c . the speaker believes that John is in Rome.<br />

d. the speaker believes that John is not in Rome.<br />

If John is in Paris, he is there for business.<br />

=> the speaker takes it to be possible but not certain that<br />

John is in Paris<br />

100


An Explanatory Account ?<br />

Step 1: Compute the various implicatures <strong>of</strong> a sentence<br />

Step 2: Keep only those presuppositions that are<br />

consistent with all implicatures.<br />

John is incompetent and he knows that he is.<br />

a. Implicature: If John is incompetent is uttered, it<br />

cannot be trivial that John is incompetent,<br />

i.e. C |≠ John is incompetent<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the second conjunct triggers<br />

the potential presupposition that John is incompetent.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is filtered out because it<br />

is inconsistent with the implicature.<br />

101


An Explanatory Account ?<br />

John is depressed and he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

a. Implicature: If John is depressed is uttered, it cannot<br />

be trivial that John is depressed,<br />

i.e. C |≠ John is depressed<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the second conjunct triggers<br />

the potential presupposition that John is incompetent.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is not filtered out because<br />

it is consistent with the implicature.<br />

Note: Gazdar thus predicts that the entire sentence<br />

presupposes that John is depressed. Stalnaker and Heim<br />

predict: if John is depressed, he is incompetent.<br />

Most examples go in Gazdar’s direction.<br />

102


An Explanatory Account ?<br />

If John is incompetent, he knows it.<br />

a. Implicature: The speaker cannot utter If F, G<br />

felicitously if he knows that F is true. If we represent as S<br />

the set <strong>of</strong> worlds compatible with what the speaker believes<br />

S |≠ John is incompetent<br />

from which it follows that<br />

C |≠ John is incompetent.<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the main clause triggers the<br />

potential presupposition that John is incompetent.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is filtered out because it<br />

is inconsistent with the implicature.<br />

103


Reminder: Other Implicatures<br />

John is in Paris or he is in Rome<br />

=> it is not the case that:<br />

a. the speaker believes that John is in Paris.<br />

b. the speaker believes that John is not in Paris.<br />

c . the speaker believes that John is in Rome.<br />

d. the speaker believes that John is not in Rome.<br />

If John is in Paris, he is there for business.<br />

=> the speaker takes it to be possible but not certain that<br />

John is in Paris<br />

104


An Explanatory Account ?<br />

Either John is not incompetent, or he knows that he is.<br />

a. Implicature: The speaker cannot utter F or G<br />

felicitously if he believes that F is false<br />

S |≠ John is incompetent<br />

from which it follows that<br />

C |≠ John is incompetent.<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the second clause triggers the<br />

potential presupposition that John is incompetent.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is filtered out because it<br />

is inconsistent with the implicature.<br />

Note: Gazdar thus predicts that the entire sentence<br />

presupposes that John is depressed. Stalnaker and Heim<br />

predict: if John is depressed, he is incompetent.<br />

105


An Explanatory Account ?<br />

If John is depressed, he knows that he is incompetent.<br />

a. Implicature: S |≠ John is depressed<br />

from which it follows that<br />

C |≠ John is depressed<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the main clause triggers the<br />

potential presupposition that John is incompetent.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is not filtered out because<br />

it is consistent with the implicature.<br />

Note: Gazdar thus predicts that the entire sentence<br />

presupposes that John is depressed. Stalnaker and Heim<br />

predict: if John is depressed, he is incompetent.<br />

Most examples go in Gazdar’s direction - but not all do!<br />

106


Problem for Gazdar’s Account<br />

If John is French, he must know that he can travel within<br />

the European Union without a passport.<br />

a. Gazdar’s prediction: π = John can travel within the<br />

European Union without a passport.<br />

b. Actual presupposition: probably none.<br />

a. Implicature: S |≠ John is French<br />

from which it follows that C |≠ John is French<br />

b. Potential Presupposition: the main clause triggers the<br />

potential presupposition that John can travel within the<br />

European Union without a passport.<br />

c. Filtering: The presupposition is not filtered out because<br />

it is consistent with the implicature!<br />

If John has twins, then Mary will not like his children.<br />

107


A Very Partial History<br />

1973-1974<br />

-Stalnaker’s analysis: pragmatics + local contexts.<br />

-Karttunen’s analysis: recursive admittance conditions +<br />

local contexts.<br />

1970’s<br />

-Karttunen & Peters<br />

-Gazdar’s recursive pragmatics<br />

1980’s<br />

-Heim’s theory <strong>of</strong> presupposition projection<br />

-Overgeneration problem (Soames, Rooth).<br />

1990’s<br />

van der Sandt & Geurts’s critique <strong>of</strong> Heim. DRT analysis<br />

108


Back to Heim’s Account!<br />

Accommodation<br />

109


My sister is pregnant.<br />

Global Accommodation<br />

'... it's not as easy as you might think to say something that<br />

will be unacceptable for lack <strong>of</strong> required presuppositions.<br />

Say something that requires a missing presupposition, and<br />

straightway that presupposition springs into existence,<br />

making what you said acceptable after all.' I said that<br />

presupposition evolves in a more or less rule-governed way<br />

during a conversation. Now we can formulate one<br />

important governing rule: call it the<br />

Rule <strong>of</strong> accommodation for presupposition<br />

If at time t something is said that requires presupposition P<br />

to be acceptable, and if P is not presupposed just before t,<br />

then - ceteris paribus and within certain limits -<br />

presupposition P comes into existence at t."<br />

110


Local Accommodation<br />

a. The king <strong>of</strong> France is not wise because there is no king <strong>of</strong><br />

France.<br />

b. None <strong>of</strong> my students takes good care <strong>of</strong> his car because<br />

none <strong>of</strong> my students has a car!<br />

c. John doesn't know that he is incompetent because he just<br />

isn't incompetent!<br />

a. It's not the case there is a king <strong>of</strong> France and he is wise<br />

because ...<br />

b. None <strong>of</strong> my students has a car and takes good care <strong>of</strong> it<br />

because...<br />

c. It's not the case that John is incompetent and knows it ...<br />

Question: can we do without Local Accommodation by<br />

appealing to meta-linguistic uses <strong>of</strong> various operators?<br />

111


Global vs. Local Accommodation<br />

C[not F]= # iff C[F]=#<br />

= C - C[F], otherwise.<br />

Global Accommodation:<br />

C' = {c∈C: France is a monarchy at the time and in the<br />

world <strong>of</strong> c}.<br />

We then compute C'[the king <strong>of</strong> France is not powerful].<br />

Local Accommodation: Instead <strong>of</strong> computing<br />

C - C[F] (which wouldn't even be defined, since C[F]=#),<br />

we compute:<br />

C - C'[F], where C'={c∈C: France is a monarchy at the time<br />

and in the world <strong>of</strong> c} (as in A.)<br />

112


Directions<br />

Allow for local accommodation whenever global<br />

accommodation would contradict<br />

a. the literal meaning <strong>of</strong> a sentence<br />

b. or an implicature <strong>of</strong> a sentence [or possibly: certain types<br />

<strong>of</strong> implicatures, e.g. primary implicatures]<br />

In effect, this allows us to capture the good properties <strong>of</strong><br />

Gazdar’s system within Heim’s dynamic semantics.<br />

113


Summary<br />

Presuppositions cannot be analyzed as implicatures.<br />

The dilemma <strong>of</strong> dynamic semantics<br />

a. Stalnaker’s approach is explanatory but not general<br />

Update the context set in time as you process a sentence.<br />

b. Heim’s approach is general but not explanatory<br />

The meaning <strong>of</strong> words is dynamic from the start, i.e. their<br />

lexical entries specify how they change the context set.<br />

Gazdar’s account was explanatory and general but<br />

incorrect<br />

(i) Compute the implicatures <strong>of</strong> a sentence.<br />

(ii) Project those potential presuppositions that don’t<br />

contradict the entire sentence or one <strong>of</strong> its implicatures.<br />

114


The Proviso Problem<br />

a. If the problem was easy, it is not John who solved it.<br />

b. John knows that if the problem was easy, someone<br />

solved it (Geurts 1999)<br />

Predicted presupposition <strong>of</strong> (a) and (b):<br />

If the problem was easy, someone solved it<br />

Actual presupposition <strong>of</strong> (a)<br />

Someone solved the problem<br />

Actual presupposition <strong>of</strong> (b)<br />

If the problem was easy, someone solved it<br />

115


The Proviso Problem<br />

John is an idiot and he knows that he is incompetent<br />

π: if John is an idiot, he is incompetent<br />

John is depressed and he knows that he is incompetent<br />

Predicted π: If John is depressed, he is incompetent<br />

Actual π: John is incompetent<br />

Maybe this is because the most plausible way to make<br />

the conditional true is to assume that its consequent is!<br />

... but this kind <strong>of</strong> reasoning fails to address the minimal<br />

difference between:<br />

-If the problem was easy, it is not John who solved it<br />

-John knows that if the problem was easy, someone solved<br />

it (Geurts 1999).<br />

116


The Proviso Problem<br />

Direction 1 (van der Sandt 1992, Geurts 1999)<br />

-This problem refutes the standard dynamic approaches -<br />

as well as all approaches that make similar predictions.<br />

-A different analysis must be proposed, in which<br />

presuppositions are treated in a more syntactic fashion<br />

(‘Discourse Representation Theory’)<br />

This is a major contender among current theories.<br />

Direction 2 (still promissory)<br />

With enough pragmatic reasoning, we can stick to Heim’s<br />

predictions - which in any event seem to be correct in other<br />

cases, e.g.<br />

If John is over 65, he must know that he is too old to apply<br />

117


Back to Heim’s Account!<br />

Quantification<br />

118


Replacing Worlds with Contexts<br />

Example1. An amnesiac gets lost...<br />

“An amnesiac, Rudolf Lingens, is lost in the Stanford library. He<br />

reads a number <strong>of</strong> things in the library, including a biography <strong>of</strong><br />

himself, and a detailed account <strong>of</strong> the library in which he is lost...<br />

He still won’t know who he is, and where he is, no matter how<br />

much knowledge he piles up, until that moment when he is ready to<br />

say, “This place is aisle five, floor six, <strong>of</strong> Main Library, Stanford. I<br />

am Rudolf Lingens.” [Perry 1977]<br />

“It seems that the Stanford library has plenty <strong>of</strong> books, but no<br />

helpful little maps with a dot marked “location <strong>of</strong> this map.” Book<br />

learning will help Lingens locate himself in logical space. (...) But<br />

none <strong>of</strong> this, by itself, can guarantee that he knows where in the<br />

world he is. He needs to locate himself not only in logical space but<br />

also in ordinary space”. [Lewis 1979 p. 138]<br />

119


Standford Harvard<br />

120


Standford Harvard<br />

121


Example 2. 'My pants are on fire'<br />

‘If I see, reflected in a window, the image <strong>of</strong> a man whose<br />

pants appear to be on fire, my behavior is sensitive to<br />

whether I think, ‘His pants are on fire’, or ‘My pants are on<br />

fire’, though the object <strong>of</strong> thought may be the same'<br />

(Kaplan)<br />

122


123


Referential Uncertainty<br />

Situation: Lingens, who is lost in the Stanford library, knows<br />

everything there is to know about the world.<br />

I wear a coat. My coat is black.<br />

[Lingens, a well-read amnesiac, knows everything there is to<br />

know about the world; but he does not know whether he is<br />

Alfred, who is having a conversation with Berenice, or<br />

Charles, who is having a conversation with Denise.<br />

Berenice used to smoke but Denise never did]<br />

Compare:<br />

Did you stop smoking?<br />

You are Berenice. Did you stop smoking?<br />

124


Referential Uncertainty<br />

Situation: Lingens, who is lost in the Stanford library, knows<br />

everything there is to know about the world.<br />

I wear a coat. My coat is black.<br />

[Lingens, a well-read amnesiac, knows everything there is to<br />

know about the world; but he does not know whether he is<br />

Alfred, who is pointing towards Berenice, or<br />

Charles, who is pointing towards Denise.<br />

Berenice used to smoke but Denise never did]<br />

Compare:<br />

Did she stop smoking?<br />

She is Berenice. Did she stop smoking?<br />

125


Static Account with worlds<br />

[[ it is raining ]] w = false<br />

[[ PS is in Los Angeles ]] w = true,<br />

[[ the British President is happy]] w = #<br />

Rule<br />

[[ Pro VP ]] w = true if and only if [[ Pro ]] w + w ∈ [[VP ]]<br />

where [[VP ]] + w is the set <strong>of</strong> things <strong>of</strong> which VP is true in w<br />

[[ Pro VP ]] w = false if and only if [[ Pro ]] w - w ∈ [[VP ]]<br />

where [[VP ]] - w is the set <strong>of</strong> things <strong>of</strong> which VP is false in w<br />

[[ Pro VP ]] w = # in all other cases!<br />

126


Static Account with contexts<br />

A context = <br />

<br />

[[ I smoke ]]<br />

= true if and only if PS smokes in w<br />

= false if and only PS does not smoke in w<br />

[[ She 2 smokes]]<br />

<br />

= true if and only if Mary smokes in w<br />

= false if and only Mary does not smoke in w<br />

[[ She 2 stopped smoking]]<br />

<br />

= true if and only if Mary used to smoke but doesn’t now in w<br />

= false if and only Mary used to smoke and still does in w<br />

= # if and only if Mary didn’t use to smoke.<br />

127


<strong>Dynamic</strong> Account with contexts<br />

The rules are exactly the same as before, replacing<br />

worlds with... contexts!<br />

Elementary Clauses [now C is a set <strong>of</strong> contexts]<br />

We write as c w the world <strong>of</strong> c, as c(1) the denotation <strong>of</strong> pro 1<br />

a. C[John is incompetent]<br />

= # iff C = #<br />

= {c∈C: John is incompetent in c w} otherwise<br />

b. C[John knows that he is incompetent]<br />

=# iff C = # or for some c∈C, John is not incompetent in c w<br />

= {c∈C: John believes he is incompetent in c w}, otherwise.<br />

c. C[she 2 stopped smoking]<br />

= # iff C = # or for some c∈C, c(2) didn’t smoke in c w<br />

= {c∈C: c(2) doesn’t smoke in c w}, otherwise.<br />

128


Quantification in a Static Setting<br />

[[ [no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 smokes]]<br />

≠ # iff for every d which is a student in w,<br />

[[x 1 smokes ]] ≠ #.<br />

If ≠ #,<br />

= true iff for no d which is a student in w,<br />

<br />

[[x 1 smokes]] = true.<br />

= false iff for some d which is a student in w,<br />

[[x 1 smokes]] = true.<br />

129


Quantification in a Static Setting<br />

<br />

[[[no x1: x1 student] x1 stopped smoking]]<br />

≠ # iff for every d which is a student in w,<br />

[[x 1 stopped smoking]] ≠ #.<br />

If ≠ #,<br />

= true iff for no d which is a student in w,<br />

[[x 1 stopped smoking ]] = true.<br />

= false iff for some d which is a student in w,<br />

[[x 1 stopped smoking ]] = true.<br />

130


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

Notations<br />

c[i → d] = that context which is exactly like c except that<br />

pro i denotes d<br />

C[i → d] = {c[i → d]: c∈C}<br />

C[[no x i: x i NP] x iVP] = # iff<br />

C = # or {c[i→d]: c∈C and d is an object}[x i NP] = #<br />

or {c[i→d]: c∈C and c[i→d] ∈ C[i→d][x i NP]} [x i VP] = #.<br />

If ≠ #, C[[no x i: x i NP] x i VP] = {c: c∈C and for no object<br />

d, c[i→d] ∈ C[i→d][x i NP] and c[i→d] ∈ C[i→d][x i<br />

NP][x i VP]}<br />

C[[every xi: xi NP] xiVP]: same thing as for no ..., replacing<br />

no with every.<br />

131


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 smokes<br />

Let us assume that C ≠ #. Then:<br />

C[[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 smokes] ≠ # because<br />

C = #, {c[1→d]: c∈C and d is an object}[x 1 student] ≠ #,<br />

and {c[1→d]: c∈C and c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x 1 student]} [x 1<br />

smokes] ≠ #. Furthermore,<br />

C[[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 smokes]<br />

= {c: c∈C and for no object d, c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x 1<br />

student] and c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x 1 student][x 1 smokes]}<br />

= {c: c∈C and for no object d, d is a student in c w and d<br />

smokes in c w}<br />

132


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

[no x1: x1 student] x1 smokes<br />

Let us assume that C = {c1, c2, c3, c4} and for each i, ci = , with:<br />

w1 : All students used to smoke. All students still smoke.<br />

w2: All students used to smoke. One doesn’t any more.<br />

w3: One student didn’t use to smoke. No student smokes.<br />

w4: One student didn’t use to smoke. One student smokes.<br />

C[[no x1: x1 student] x1 smokes]<br />

= {ci: i ∈ {1, 2, 3, 4} and for no object d, ∈ {: i ∈ {1, 2, 3, 4}}[x1 student] and<br />

∈ {: i ∈ {1, 2, 3,<br />

4}}[x1 student][x1 smokes]}<br />

= {ci: i ∈ {1, 2, 3, 4} and for no object d, d is a student in<br />

wi and d smokes in wi} = {c3} 133


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 stopped smoking<br />

Let us assume that C ≠ #. Then:<br />

C[[no x1: x1 student] x1stopped smoking] = #<br />

iff {c[1→d]: c∈C and d is an object}[x1 student] = #,<br />

or {c[1→d]: c∈C and c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x1 student]} [x1 stopped smoking] = #,<br />

iff {c[1→d]: c∈C and c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x1 student]} [x1 stopped smoking] = #<br />

iff for some c∈C, for some d, d is a student in cw and d<br />

didn’t use to smoke in cw. If ≠ #,<br />

= {c: c∈C and for no object d, d is a student in cw and d<br />

stopped smoking in cw} 134


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

[no x i: x i student] x i stopped smoking<br />

Let us assume that C = {c 1, c 2, c 3, c 4}<br />

(with c 1, c 2, c 3, c 4 defined as before)<br />

C[[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 stopped smoking] = # because<br />

{c[1→d]: c∈C and c[1→d] ∈ C[1→d][x 1 student]} [x 1<br />

stopped smoking]<br />

= {: i ∈ {1, 2, 3, 4} and d is a student in<br />

w i} [x 1 stopped smoking]<br />

= # because in w 3 and w 4 there are students who didn’t use<br />

to smoke.<br />

135


Quantification in a <strong>Dynamic</strong> Setting<br />

[no x i: x i student] x i stopped smoking<br />

Let us now assume that C’ = {c 1, c 2}<br />

(with c 1 and c 2 defined as before)<br />

It can be shown C’[[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 smokes] ≠ #.<br />

Furthermore, C’[[no x 1: x 1 student] x 1 stopped smoking]<br />

= {c: c∈C’ and for no object d, d is a student in c w and d<br />

stopped smoking in c w}<br />

= {c 1}<br />

136

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!