20.08.2013 Views

Dummett - Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics.pdf - Ted Sider

Dummett - Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics.pdf - Ted Sider

Dummett - Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics.pdf - Ted Sider

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

MICHAEL DUMMETT<br />

be used in mathematical pro<strong>of</strong>s. Furthermore, it might be pointed<br />

out that a formal system does not replace the intuitive pro<strong>of</strong>s as,<br />

frequently, a precise concept replaces a vague intuitive one; the<br />

formal system remains, as it were, answerable to the intuitive<br />

conception, and remains <strong>of</strong> interest only so long as it does not<br />

reveal undesirable features which the intuitive idea does not<br />

possess. An example would be Gbdel's theorem, which shows<br />

that provability in a formal system cannot do duty as a substitute<br />

for the intuitive idea <strong>of</strong> arithmetical truth.<br />

Suppose we are considering a statement <strong>of</strong> some mathematical<br />

theory. To avoid complications, assume that the theory is com-<br />

plete, that is, that it can be completely formalized, but that we<br />

are not thinking <strong>of</strong> any particular formal system. Then a Platonist<br />

will say that there exists either a pro<strong>of</strong> or a dispro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the state-<br />

ment; the fact that the statement is true, if it is true, consists<br />

in the existence <strong>of</strong> such a pro<strong>of</strong> even though we have not yet<br />

discovered it. Now if there exists a pro<strong>of</strong>, let us suppose that<br />

there is somewhere an actual document, as yet unseen by human<br />

eyes, on which is written what purports to be a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

statement. Then Wittgenstein will reply that all the same there<br />

does not yet exist a pro<strong>of</strong>, since when we discover the document<br />

it is still up to us to decide whether or not we wish to count<br />

it as a pro<strong>of</strong>. It is evident that, if this is correct, then all motive<br />

for saying with the Platonist that there either is or is not a pro<strong>of</strong>,<br />

that the statement must be either true or false, and so forth,<br />

has gone. What is not clear to me is that rejecting the Platonist's<br />

conception involves adopting this line about pro<strong>of</strong>s; it seems to<br />

me that a man might hold that, once the pro<strong>of</strong> was discovered,<br />

we had no choice but to follow it, without allowing the correctness<br />

<strong>of</strong> saying, before the pro<strong>of</strong> was discovered, that either there is a<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> or there is not. I will return to this later.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein's</strong> conception is extremely hard to swallow, even<br />

though it is not clear what one wishes to oppose to it. The pro<strong>of</strong><br />

is supposed to have the effect <strong>of</strong> persuading us, inducing us, to<br />

count such-and-such a form <strong>of</strong> words as unassailably true, or to<br />

exclude such-and-such a form <strong>of</strong> words from our language. It<br />

seems quite unclear how the pro<strong>of</strong> accomplishes this remarkable<br />

feat. Another difficulty is the scarcity <strong>of</strong> examples. We naturally<br />

332

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!