03.09.2013 Views

Must Functionalists be Aristotelians? - Robert C. Koons

Must Functionalists be Aristotelians? - Robert C. Koons

Must Functionalists be Aristotelians? - Robert C. Koons

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Must</strong> <strong>Functionalists</strong> <strong>be</strong> <strong>Aristotelians</strong>?<br />

1 Functionalism<br />

Functionalism remains the most promising strategy for 'naturalizing' the mind. It<br />

resulted from synthesizing of logical <strong>be</strong>haviorism and brain/mind identity theory.<br />

Like <strong>be</strong>haviorism, functionalism defines mental states as dispositions, intervening<br />

<strong>be</strong>tween public, measurable inputs and outputs (<strong>be</strong>haviors). Unlike classical<br />

<strong>be</strong>haviorism, which defined each mental state-­‐type directly in terms of the <strong>be</strong>havior<br />

it produces in response to each stimulus, functionalism defines mental types<br />

recursively. Each mental type is potentially both input and output for other types. A<br />

key advantage of functionalism is that, like brain/mind identity theory, it provides<br />

(on the assumption that only physical states are causally efficacious) a natural<br />

explanation of the strong supervenience of mental properties on physical ones, a<br />

critical commitment of naturalism. In fact, functionalism could taken to <strong>be</strong> either a<br />

'second-­‐order' identity theory (as in Shoemaker) or first-­‐order identity theory (as in<br />

David Lewis's version).<br />

In the early 20 th century, the motivation <strong>be</strong>hind naturalism was that of<br />

"operationalizing" psychology, eliminating the need for things like introspection,<br />

interpretation, or empathy. Such naturalism led to the demand that the fundamental<br />

vocabulary of psychology must <strong>be</strong> wholly physical (for description of inputs and<br />

outputs), plus the language of causation, dispositions, counterfactuals, or function,<br />

as well as the terms of logic and mathematics, achieving as a result a so-­‐called 'topic<br />

neutral' language.<br />

British philosopher and logician Frank Ramsey offered the logical tools needed to<br />

express mature functionalism, describing a logical process that has come to <strong>be</strong><br />

known as "Ramseyfication"or "Ramsification". We start with the true theory of<br />

psychology, one including explicitly mental terms and predicates (like 'pain' or<br />

'conscious of'). This theory is supposed to capture the one Pattern of interactions<br />

that is definitive of having a mind. We form a single, gigantic conjunction of all of the<br />

postulates of the theory and then replace each mental predicate by a second-­‐order<br />

variable of the same type (i.e., one-­‐place predicate variable for monadic predicates,<br />

two-­‐place predicate variables for binary predicates, etc.). Finally, we append a series<br />

of existential quantifiers to the <strong>be</strong>ginning of the formula, one quantifier for each<br />

variable-­‐type. The resulting "Ramsey" sentence is now in a topic-­‐neutral language,<br />

since the only predicates that remain are either part of the language of physics and<br />

mathematics, or <strong>be</strong>long to a category of causal language: either causal predicates, or<br />

operators or logical connectives of nomological necessity or subjunctive<br />

conditionality.<br />

Mental properties can now <strong>be</strong> identified either with second-­‐order physical<br />

properties (e.g., mental property n is identical to the second-­‐order property of<br />

1


having a physical property that plays the role of variable n in the actual witness to<br />

the truth of the Ramsey sentence) or with first-­‐order physical properties (e.g.,<br />

mental property n is identical, in the class of human <strong>be</strong>ings, to that physical<br />

property that in fact plays the role of variable n in the actual witness to the truth of<br />

the Ramsey sentence in the population of human <strong>be</strong>ings).<br />

Clauses of the Ramsey sentence will have a form something like one of these:<br />

(1) If the system x is in internal state Sn and in input state Im at time t, then x is at<br />

time t+1 <strong>be</strong> in internal state Sk and output state Oj. (Indicative conditional)<br />

(2) If the system x were in internal state Sn and in input state Im at time t, then x<br />

would at time t+1 <strong>be</strong> in internal state Sk and output state Oj. (Subjunctive<br />

conditional)<br />

(3) Whenever the system x is in internal state Sn, x has the disposition to enter<br />

immediately into output state Oj and internal state Sk in response to input state Im.<br />

(Dispositional state)<br />

(4) System x's <strong>be</strong>ing in internal state Sn confers upon it the power to produce output<br />

state Oj and internal state Sk immediately in response to input state Im. (Causal<br />

power)<br />

Here, x is either the whole mind or a subsystem. This could in principle <strong>be</strong> a very<br />

low level subsystem, say one that takes two truth value inputs and returns their<br />

disjunction, or a very high level one, say one that takes desires and <strong>be</strong>liefs and<br />

outputs motor activation signals.<br />

The project of Ramsifying psychology raises a num<strong>be</strong>r of questions.<br />

(a) How do we specify inputs and outputs, especially gross <strong>be</strong>havioral outputs? Can<br />

this <strong>be</strong> done without including an element of interpretation? Can it really <strong>be</strong> done<br />

entirely in the vocabulary of fundamental physics?<br />

(b) What are the 'states' – the names of which are replaced by variables when<br />

Ramsifying? States of what? Each <strong>be</strong>arer of the properties that realize the Ramsey<br />

sentence must <strong>be</strong> capable of persisting through time, since the Ramsey sentence<br />

(and the psychological theory from which it originates) makes reference to causal<br />

connections among the property-­‐<strong>be</strong>arer's internal states, and these causal<br />

connections require the passage of time. Thus, interpreting the Ramsey sentence<br />

presupposes a solution to the problem of diachronic identity for mereologically<br />

incontinent composite things – the diachronic identity of organisms, machines,<br />

organs, neurons, etc. Is diachronic persistence of the property-­‐<strong>be</strong>arer built into the<br />

functional specification? That is, are the biological and organic processes of material<br />

intake and output specified in the psychological theory? If so, this leads to biological<br />

parochialism: it entails that non-­‐organic machines and other entities cannot have<br />

2


minds. If not, can the inputs and outputs <strong>be</strong> scattered arbitrarily far apart? If so, how<br />

can we ensure that a scattered set of distinct persons and machines don't constitute<br />

a single mind? (Searle's Chinese room counter-­‐example.) Moreover, how “natural”<br />

must the states <strong>be</strong>? If we are sufficiently broad about what counts as a state, we will<br />

have the problem of too many minds. For instance, in addition to my mind, there is<br />

the danger that there will <strong>be</strong> another—“much bigger”—mind whose states are<br />

conjunctions of my neuronal states together with the spiral nature of our galaxy<br />

(which is causally irrelevant to my neuronal states and unchanging on an individual<br />

human timescale).<br />

(c) What sort of language is involved in the specification of the links <strong>be</strong>tween inputs,<br />

internal states and outputs? Does the theory make use of material or subjunctive<br />

conditionals, or does it make reference to causal powers or intrinsic dispositions?<br />

We will focus here on the third set of questions. First we will argue that the material<br />

and subjective conditional views are untenable, and then we will evaluate the<br />

dispositional and powers views. We will argue that the only plausible form of<br />

functionalism requires that the connections <strong>be</strong>tween inputs, outputs and mental<br />

states <strong>be</strong> descri<strong>be</strong>d as causal powers, in accordance with the assumptions of<br />

standard Aristotelian metaphysics (including the notions of substance, accident,<br />

essence, formal and final causes).<br />

2 Conditional functionalisms<br />

2.1 Material conditioanls<br />

Functionalisms built on indicative or subjunctive conditionals have little hope of<br />

success. The most obviously unsuccessful are material conditional accounts, simply<br />

<strong>be</strong>cause the conditional clauses will <strong>be</strong> satisfied by any system that never actually<br />

receives the inputs. The moon will count as a human-­‐level mind, just one that never<br />

actually gets to think about anything.<br />

2.2 Non-material conditionals<br />

Standard problems with conditional accounts of dispositions apply just as well to all<br />

the non-­‐material conditional forms of the accounts. We can imagine, for instance,<br />

that the individual has strapped to her a bomb that explodes if system x is in<br />

internal state Sn and receives input Im at time t, but that in fact this condition does<br />

not obtain. Then, the subjunctive conditional (2) is false, and (1) will also <strong>be</strong> false on<br />

plausible non-­‐material readings (e.g., conditional probabilities). Yet having such a<br />

bomb strapped to one, while unfortunate, does not make one not have a mind, if the<br />

bomb never goes off.<br />

3


One might try to use context-­‐sensitivity to ward off such worries, for instance by<br />

saying that in evaluating conditionals or conditional probabilities we only should<br />

consider those causal factors that are internal to the system x. But we can replace<br />

the bomb by a cancer, and the distinction <strong>be</strong>tween “internal” and “external” causal<br />

factors will <strong>be</strong>come untenable.<br />

What if the conditionals are strengthened to include the claim that the whole system<br />

survives until x+1? Here we borrow an idea from Harry Frankfurt: the introduction<br />

of a purely hypothetical neural-­‐manipulator. The manipulator wants the subject to<br />

follow a certain script. If the subject were to shown signs of <strong>be</strong>ing about to deviate<br />

from the script, then the manipulator would intervene internally, causing the<br />

subject to continue to follow the script. We are to imagine that the subject<br />

spontaneously follows the script, and as a consequence, the manipulator never<br />

intervenes.<br />

Frankfurt introduced the thought experiment to challenge the idea that freedom of<br />

the will requires alternative possibilities. We introduce it to show that the existence<br />

of mental states is independent of the truth of counterfactual conditionals linking<br />

the states to inputs, outputs and each other. It is obvious that the presence of an<br />

inactive manipulator cannot deprive the subject of his mental states. However, the<br />

manipulator's presence is sufficient to falsify all of the usual non-­‐material<br />

conditionals and conditional probabilities linking the states. It is false that if the<br />

subject were not in state Sn, then he would not immediately afterward <strong>be</strong> in state<br />

Sm, since the presence of the manipulator makes it impossible for the subject not to<br />

<strong>be</strong> in state Sm, if that is part of the script.<br />

Moreover, cognitive malfunctioning is surely possible: e.g., as a result of injury or<br />

illness. The theory to <strong>be</strong> Ramseyfied cannot plausibly incorporate the effects of<br />

every possible injury or illness, since there are no limits to the complexity of the sort<br />

of phenomenon that might constitute an injury or illness. Injury can prevent nearly<br />

all <strong>be</strong>havior – so much so, as to make the remaining <strong>be</strong>havioral dispositions so non-­‐<br />

specific as to fail to distinguish one internal state from another. Consider, for<br />

example, locked-­‐in syndrome, as depicted in the movie The Diving-Bell and the<br />

Butterfly. Therefore, the true psychological theory must contain postulates that<br />

specify the normal connections among states.<br />

But without resorting to Aristotelian teleology, our only account of normalcy will <strong>be</strong><br />

probabilistic. Thus, a system normally enters state Sm from state Sn as a result of<br />

input Im provided it is likely to do this. However, serious injury or illness can make<br />

a malfunctioning subsystem rarely or never do what it should, yet without<br />

challenging the status of the subsystem as, say, a subsystem for visual processing of<br />

shapes.<br />

Alternately, one might try to define normalcy in terms of what systems of the same<br />

type are likely to do. Thus, a system normally enters state Sm from state Sn as a<br />

result of input Im provided that most of the time systems of this type do this. A<br />

4


serious problem here is that we are giving the functional claims in order to<br />

characterize the type of system. But it is then circular in the functional claims to<br />

refer to other systems of the same type. One might try to Ramseyfy over types to<br />

solve this problem, but one will still have problems with one of a kind minds.<br />

Moreover, the probabilities of state transitions in systems of a given kind depend<br />

deeply on the environment the systems are in. A plausible account would have to<br />

say that a normal transition is one that is likely to occur in systems of the given type<br />

in a normal environment. But, again, it does not appear possible to specify a normal<br />

environment without resorting to something like teleology or proper function.<br />

3 Three rival conceptions of function, power or<br />

disposition<br />

3.1 The Aristotelian conception of powers<br />

The Aristotelian notion of power is characterized by four features:<br />

1. Powers are possessed by substances (things with a per se unity).<br />

2. Powers are intrinsic to those substances.<br />

3. Powers are defined in terms of an input/output function.<br />

4. Powers are conferred on substances by their essential or accidental natures.<br />

An Aristotelian C-­‐to-­‐E power can <strong>be</strong> defined as: under circumstances C to produce a<br />

characteristic effect E (either in oneself or in something standing in the appropriate<br />

relation R(C) to oneself).<br />

An Aristotelian power can <strong>be</strong> defeated or thwarted, and its effects can <strong>be</strong> distorted<br />

by interfering factors. There could <strong>be</strong> higher-­‐order powers, whose characteristic<br />

effect is the blocking or distorting of the exercise of lower-­‐order powers, as an<br />

antidote neutralizes the characteristic effect of a poison.<br />

Aristotelian powers are "conferred" on things by the natures of substances and<br />

accidents. This connection too is defeasible. A thing can have a nature such as to<br />

have power P and yet lack P. This too can <strong>be</strong> explained in terms of the operation of<br />

higher-­‐order powers: e.g., the power to deprive something with nature N of one of<br />

its natural powers.<br />

3.2 Rylean conception of dispositions<br />

5


Rylean dispositions correspond to the subjunctive conditional: if C were to <strong>be</strong><br />

realized, then E would result, and hence are subject to the objections to conditional<br />

views when used to formulate functionalism.<br />

3.3 Nomological-deductive model of powers<br />

A thing or system of things S has the C-­‐to-­‐E nomological-­‐deductive disposition iff<br />

there is some description D such that S has D, and there are laws of nature L such<br />

that L&C&D entails E (or, perhaps, such that the rational probability of E on L&C&D<br />

is constrained to <strong>be</strong> very high). Again, the bomb and cancer objections to<br />

conditional views rule out ND dispositions when these are used to formulate<br />

functionalism.<br />

4 An Aristotelian Functionalism?<br />

Can a plurality of substances <strong>be</strong>ar jointly something analogous to a causal power?<br />

Could they possess jointly some sort of reducible causal power? No – the only<br />

alternative to Aristotelian power is a disposition, grounded in a subjunctive<br />

conditional or in laws of nature. Powers are possessed by things by virtue (or as an<br />

aspect of) their natures, what it is to <strong>be</strong> such a thing. Mere heaps of things have no<br />

nature.<br />

An Aristotelian is a kind of ontological emergentist: the whole organism, with its<br />

associated powers, is a metaphysically fundamental entity, not merely a roundabout<br />

way of referring to its material atoms and their relations.<br />

Aristotelian powers of a substance provide an objective basis for normativity: if a<br />

substance has the Aristotelian C-­‐to-­‐E power, then it is supposed to produce effect E<br />

whenever in circumstances C (except, perhaps, when the C-­‐to-­‐E connection is<br />

overridden by one of the substance's own essential powers).<br />

Functionalism could <strong>be</strong> put in an Aristotelian mode, referring to the presence of<br />

powers to produce outputs and internal states (including other powers). The result<br />

would <strong>be</strong> a non-­‐reductive and non-­‐physicalist version of functionalism, since the<br />

form of the theory would rule out the states' realizers <strong>be</strong>ing merely physical states<br />

of constituent particles. See George Bealer, "The Self-­‐Consciousness Argument," in<br />

<strong>Koons</strong> & Bealer 2010: the Aristotelian can make use of impredicative, type-­‐free<br />

higher order theory, allowing the second-­‐order, functionally specified properties<br />

(powers) to <strong>be</strong> among the properties in the domain of the Ramsey quantifiers.<br />

5 Last-ditch defenses<br />

6


5.1 Reliance on actual causal connections?<br />

What if the functionalist reformulated the psychological theory, replacing any<br />

reference to dispositions or powers with a reference to an actual causal connection<br />

<strong>be</strong>tween tokens of the relevant types? Clauses of the resulting Ramsey sentence<br />

would look something like this:<br />

(4) There has <strong>be</strong>en at some point in the past a system x in internal state Sm and<br />

input state In such that x's <strong>be</strong>ing in states Sm and In (immediately) caused x to <strong>be</strong> in<br />

internal state Sk and output state Oj.<br />

Such a functionalism would make mental states extrinsic to their <strong>be</strong>arers. This<br />

would give rise to extreme Swampman problems. What mental state I am in -­‐-­‐ and<br />

even whether I am in any mental state at all -­‐-­‐ would depend on a large num<strong>be</strong>r of<br />

extrinsic facts about the causal history of similarly constructed systems in the<br />

remote past. My thoughts could <strong>be</strong> deprived hypothetically of some of their content,<br />

and my experience of some of its constituents, by simply deleting certain remote<br />

facts about actual causal connections among the states of entities similar to me in<br />

constitution.<br />

5.2 Merely possible causal connections?<br />

Suppose the functionalist were to replace the dispositional connections with the<br />

claim that it is metaphysically possible for items of the first kind to cause (or to <strong>be</strong><br />

part of the cause) of items of the second kind. The clauses of the Ramsey sentence<br />

would look like this:<br />

(5) It is metaphysically possible for a system x's <strong>be</strong>ing in states Sm and In to cause<br />

immediately x to <strong>be</strong> in states Sk and Oj.<br />

This requires some form of nomological or dynamic essentialism. If the causal<br />

powers are only contingently associated with a property, then every physical object<br />

would <strong>be</strong> conscious and rational, since its physical states could have the relevant<br />

causal connections. So, at the least, the functionalist must make one small step<br />

toward Aristotelianism.<br />

This account would lead to massive indeterminacy of content, thanks to the<br />

possibility of misfirings. For example, my concept of the num<strong>be</strong>r two would also <strong>be</strong><br />

a concept of the num<strong>be</strong>r three, since the first concept is capable of playing, on<br />

particular occasions, the role demanded by the second concept. To tighten this up,<br />

the account would have to introduce normativity: a state can fill a certain role if it is<br />

metaphysically possible that it does so correctly.<br />

7


Thus, any viable version of functionalism must incorporate standards of<br />

normativity.<br />

6 Accounts of normativity<br />

6.1 Aristotelian account<br />

An Aristotelian can give a straightforward account of normativity: a substance is<br />

supposed to produce E on occasions of C if and only if its nature includes the C-­‐to-­‐E<br />

power. A similar account can <strong>be</strong> given of conditional norms: a substance is supposed<br />

to produce E on occasions of C, given that it has accident A, if and only if the nature<br />

of A includes the C-­‐to-­‐E power (and this power is not neutralized or overridden by<br />

any of the substance's own natural powers).<br />

6.2 Agential intentions<br />

Normativity of a kind arises from agents' intentionally making and using things:<br />

(6) A thing is supposed to produce E on occasions C if and only if its maker or users<br />

intend it so to do.<br />

For example, hammers are supposed to drive in nails, since this is what the makers<br />

and users of hammers intend to do with them. There are two problems with<br />

incorporating this kind of normativity into our universal psychological theory of the<br />

Pattern of mind. First, it would make it a matter of metaphysical necessity that every<br />

mindful thing is an artifact, made and used by other agents. Second, it would<br />

generate an infinite regress, since the agents who are using the mindful things must<br />

themselves have minds, necessitating that they too are artifacts made and used by<br />

still earlier agents. The regress (or circularity) is vicious, since the relevant norms<br />

never acquire any content.<br />

A functionalist might instead try to make use of Wittgensteinian norms:<br />

(7) A thing x is supposed to produce E on occasions C if and only if there is a game G<br />

in which x is a participant in role R, and G includes the rule that participants playing<br />

role R produce E on occasions C.<br />

Presumably, a game's including such a rule consists in its participants' <strong>be</strong>lieving that<br />

others will satisfy the rule, and intending to satisfy it themselves, conditional on its<br />

satisfaction by others. (See David Lewis's Convention.) This again results in a vicious<br />

regress or circularity.<br />

8


Could the circularity <strong>be</strong> turned into a recursive definition of normativity? No,<br />

<strong>be</strong>cause there is no norm-­‐free base case for the specification of psychological states.<br />

6.3 Evolutionary accounts<br />

The third and final potential source of normativity is evolutionary selection. If a<br />

system x <strong>be</strong>longs to a reproductive family F, then x is supposed to produce E under<br />

circumstances C if and only if doing so is one of F's adaptations. This seems to <strong>be</strong> the<br />

most promising alternative to the Aristotelian account, since there doesn't seem to<br />

<strong>be</strong> any vicious circularity or regress.<br />

7 Objections to evolutionary accounts of normativity<br />

7.1 Backward-looking vs. forward-looking accounts<br />

Evolutionary normativity could <strong>be</strong> defined in either a backward-­‐looking or forward-­‐<br />

looking form, depending on whether an adaptation is defined in terms of a kind's<br />

actual evolutionary history or in terms of its present propensities to survive and<br />

reproduce itself.<br />

(8) Backward-­‐looking version: a C-­‐to-­‐E disposition is an adaptation of kind F if and<br />

only if:<br />

(a) F is a historical reproductive family: present mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F exist <strong>be</strong>cause they are<br />

copies of earlier mem<strong>be</strong>rs,<br />

(b) many mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F have the C-­‐to-­‐E disposition, and<br />

(c) each mem<strong>be</strong>r of F has an ancestor (or, perhaps, a large num<strong>be</strong>r of ancestors)<br />

whose successful self-­‐reproduction was caused by at least one exercise (or, perhaps,<br />

many exercises) of its C-­‐to-­‐E disposition.<br />

(9) Forward-­‐looking version: a C-­‐to-­‐E disposition is an adaptation of kind F if and<br />

only if<br />

(a) F is a potential reproductive family: many present mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F have a<br />

significant propensity to make future mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F,<br />

(b) all reproductively fit mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F have the C-­‐to-­‐E disposition, and<br />

(c) the presence of the C-­‐to-­‐E disposition in the reproductively fit mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F<br />

plays an indispensable role in the causal explanation of those mem<strong>be</strong>rs'<br />

reproductive fitness.<br />

The forward-­‐looking accounts fall down at exactly the crucial point: they require<br />

prior specification of the kind's natural or normal environment. No kind of thing is<br />

reproductively fit in all possible environments, and every kind of thing is<br />

reproductively fit in some possible environment. For example, shoes are<br />

9


eproductively fit in the context of a shoe-­‐duplicating service. In fact, every possible<br />

kind of thing is optimally adapted to some possible environment. Consequently,<br />

without a restriction to normal environments, the forward-­‐looking version would<br />

classify every possible feature as adaptive and, hence, as normative. This fact<br />

renders the forward-­‐looking account useless to the functionalist, since normative<br />

conditions are supposed to distinguish proper functioning from malfunctioning.<br />

The backward-­‐looking account sidesteps this difficulty, since it identifies the<br />

'normal' environment of a historically reproductive kind with the environmental<br />

conditions in fact encountered by ancestral mem<strong>be</strong>rs of the kind. This may lead to<br />

some over-­‐generation of normativity, since it seems plausible that living things<br />

occasionally survive very abnormal conditions by some lucky accident. The<br />

backward-­‐looking theorist must treat the features that enabled such serendipitous<br />

success as real adaptations of current mem<strong>be</strong>rs of the kind, however unlikely it is<br />

that the supposed 'adaptation' will ever <strong>be</strong> used again. However, this over-­‐<br />

generation can <strong>be</strong> mitigated by requiring a certain num<strong>be</strong>r of past repetitions of<br />

actual contributions to survival <strong>be</strong>fore a disposition counts as adaptive.<br />

7.2 Millikan's account as a paradigm of the backward-looking<br />

theory of adaptation<br />

Ruth Garrett Millikan developed such an account in considerable detail (in<br />

Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories). Here is a simplified version of<br />

her definition:<br />

(10) A thing x is supposed to produce E in circumstances C if and only x <strong>be</strong>longs to a<br />

reproductive family F, mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F do regularly produce E in circumstances C, and<br />

some past instances of successful reproduction of mem<strong>be</strong>rs of F were caused by<br />

those mem<strong>be</strong>rs' producing E in circumstances C.<br />

There is a serious problem with Millikan's account: can 'reproduction' <strong>be</strong> defined<br />

naturalistically and without reference to function or teleology? Complex organisms<br />

(especially ones that reproduce sexually) never produce exact physical duplicates of<br />

themselves. Conversely, since everything is similar to everything else in some<br />

respects, every cause could <strong>be</strong> said to <strong>be</strong> 'reproducing' itself in each of its effects.<br />

Real reproduction involves the successful copying of the essential features of a<br />

thing. For living organisms, these essential features consist almost entirely of<br />

biological functions. Hence, we cannot identify cases of biological reproduction<br />

without first <strong>be</strong>ing able to identify the biological functions of things. Yet Millikan's<br />

account requires us to put the reproductive cart <strong>be</strong>fore the functional horse.<br />

7.3 The Great Grazing Ground objection<br />

10


A Millikanian version of functionalism would have the consequence that a thing has<br />

a mind only if it <strong>be</strong>longs to a reproductive family F for which the standard Pattern of<br />

dispositions has successfully contributed to the survival of F. Thus, whether a thing<br />

has a mind depends on the evolutionary history of its kind.<br />

What does it mean for a particular disposition to 'cause' or to 'contribute' to a<br />

particular instance of F-­‐reproduction? There are two possible answers. First, we<br />

could say that the disposition contributed to the act of reproduction just in case<br />

some exercise of the disposition by the parent is in the actual causal history of the<br />

creation of the child. Second, we could instead require that the disposition <strong>be</strong> part of<br />

a contrastive explanation of the reproduction: part of a minimal explanation of why<br />

in this instance reproduction or survival occurred, as opposed to not occurring.<br />

The first answer would greatly over-­‐generate adaptations. Any feature of the parent<br />

that is both the product of some disposition of the parent and that influences in any<br />

way the process of reproduction would count as one of the kind's essential<br />

adaptations. For example, suppose that rabbits are disposed to twitch their left rear<br />

leg whenever a cosmic ray strikes the spinal cord at a single point, and suppose that<br />

this disposition was actually exercised by some rabbit in the past as it was<br />

successfully locating a bunch of carrots. Even if the twitch played no role in<br />

explaining the rabbit's survival, it would still count as adaptive, so long as it was<br />

part of the total cause of this rabbit's survival in this concrete instance.<br />

Thus, we'll need to turn to the second answer, contrastive explanations. The use of<br />

contrastive explanation fits standard biological practice, which identifies<br />

adaptations with the results of natural selection, and selection is inherently<br />

contrastive in nature.<br />

[Insert the Great Grazing Ground objection here]<br />

We can also consider a Frankfurt-­‐like variation on GGG. Suppose that there is a<br />

remote but vigilant bio-­‐manipulator who wants life on earth to follow a certain<br />

script (for obscure numerological and theological reasons). If the script is followed,<br />

the manipulator does nothing; at the first sign of incipient deviation, he annihilates<br />

the earth. In fact, the script is spontaneously and coincidentally followed by the<br />

actual course of events, so the manipulator does nothing. The manipulator's<br />

presence falsifies all the usual subjunctive conditionals, resulting in no natural<br />

selection, and, consequently, no adaptations, no evolutionary normativity, and no<br />

mental states.<br />

A second variation: in the case of deviation, the manipulator would produce a very<br />

large num<strong>be</strong>r of copies of each mem<strong>be</strong>r of a reproductive kind. In this way, each<br />

thing's functioning as it does causes a reduction in its reproductive fitness. In this<br />

scenario, every feature of living things would <strong>be</strong> maladaptive.<br />

11


7.4 Non-Humean, Realist Accounts of Causation<br />

The Millikanian might argue that the naturalized account of adaptation and<br />

normativity can <strong>be</strong> salvaged from the GGG objection by shifting from a Humean<br />

conception of contrastive causal explanation (defined in terms of subjunctive<br />

conditionals) to an anti-­‐Humean one. One way to do this would <strong>be</strong> to appeal to<br />

Aristotelian powers. A power of a biological substance is historically adaptive if<br />

there have <strong>be</strong>en cases in the history of the substance's kind in which an exercise<br />

that power, in conjunction with the exercise of other powers of that substance and<br />

of things in the substance's environment, had the substance's successful survival or<br />

reproduction as one of its effects.<br />

Is there a third way, in addition to the Humean and Aristotelian approaches? Once<br />

again, we could turn to the nomological-­‐deductive theory of dispositions. Clearly the<br />

laws in question must <strong>be</strong> defeasible or "oaken" laws, since there is no intrinsic<br />

feature of organisms that determines nomologically that that creature will succeed<br />

in surviving and reproducing itself.<br />

What sorts of properties are related by causal laws? They must <strong>be</strong> properties that<br />

occur in fundamental causal laws, or properties whose instances are linked by<br />

primitive causal ties. If we accept naturalism as the constraint on an acceptable<br />

functionalism, then it is physical properties, and more specifically, microphysical<br />

properties (fundamental properties of fundamental particles) that appear in such<br />

laws. Gross, macrophysical properties appear only in derived, non-­‐fundamental<br />

laws. However, it is impossible to derive defeasible laws about the adaptiveness of<br />

biological features without adding postulates about the normal environment of the<br />

organism in question, the issue that the functionalist was hoping to avert through an<br />

evolutionary account of normativity.<br />

12

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!