05.10.2013 Views

What is the Meaning of Shape? - Gestalt Theory

What is the Meaning of Shape? - Gestalt Theory

What is the Meaning of Shape? - Gestalt Theory

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Baingio Pinna<br />

<strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

1. On <strong>the</strong> <strong>Shape</strong><br />

The shape <strong>of</strong> an object <strong>is</strong> a primary condition fundamental for our lives. <strong>Shape</strong><br />

<strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> primary v<strong>is</strong>ual attribute among o<strong>the</strong>rs (color, shade, lighting) that elicits<br />

unambiguous identification due mainly to its constancy. Ano<strong>the</strong>r relevant<br />

perceptual property <strong>is</strong> its uniqueness. Indeed, it <strong>is</strong> unique and much more<br />

informative than any o<strong>the</strong>r object properties, i.e. color, shading (depth) and<br />

lighting (illumination).<br />

<strong>Shape</strong>s are not usually regarded as a creation <strong>of</strong> our brain but appear veridically,<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> physical world. As a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, <strong>the</strong> core meaning <strong>of</strong> shape<br />

<strong>is</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main interests and targets <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics (from topology and<br />

ma<strong>the</strong>matical analys<strong>is</strong> to trigonometry and geometry) aimed to describe and<br />

study <strong>the</strong> main properties <strong>of</strong> shapes and <strong>the</strong> relationship among <strong>the</strong>m. No o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

property has been studied from so many different perspectives and so deeply as<br />

shape (see Palmer, 1999; Pizlo, 2008). It <strong>is</strong> useful to d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>h between shape<br />

in <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical sense (i.e. as an ideal object) and shape as encoded in <strong>the</strong><br />

physical world. In <strong>the</strong> former sense, objects are ontologically neutral and not<br />

always perceptually possible and relevant.<br />

1.1. The Invention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Square<br />

Among all <strong>the</strong> known shapes, <strong>the</strong> square <strong>is</strong> a unique and special one. The<br />

emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square and its geometrical/phenomenal components (sides and<br />

angles) <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> way four segments go toge<strong>the</strong>r according to<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong> grouping and organization principles. Phenomenally, its singularity,<br />

homogeneity, regularity and symmetry are among <strong>the</strong> strongest <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> known<br />

shapes. The circle also shows unique properties, but unlike <strong>the</strong> square it <strong>is</strong><br />

present in nature (e.g. <strong>the</strong> full moon and <strong>the</strong> sun). The square <strong>is</strong> instead a human<br />

invention. It <strong>is</strong> a pure creation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human mind.<br />

The invention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> wheel (i.e. <strong>the</strong> circle) <strong>is</strong> likely one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most important<br />

inventions <strong>of</strong> all time. It was at <strong>the</strong> root <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Industrial Revolution. The oldest<br />

known wheel was attributed to <strong>the</strong> ancient Mesopotamian culture <strong>of</strong> Sumer<br />

around 3500 B.C., but it <strong>is</strong> supposed to have been invented much earlier. If<br />

<strong>the</strong> potter’s wheels were <strong>the</strong> very first wheels, <strong>the</strong> invention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square was<br />

GESTALT THEORY<br />

© 2011(ISSN 0170-057 X)<br />

Vol. 33, No.3/4, 383-422


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

likely as important as <strong>the</strong> wheel. The square <strong>is</strong>, in fact, a basic shape used to<br />

measure any kind <strong>of</strong> object, shape or space. Every shape ei<strong>the</strong>r regular or irregular<br />

<strong>is</strong> measured in squares (m2 ) or in <strong>the</strong> 3-D version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square, cubes (m3 ).<br />

The square <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> unit and, more generally, <strong>the</strong> ‘brick’ <strong>of</strong> all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r shapes. By<br />

moving around <strong>the</strong> gaze and focusing <strong>the</strong> attention on <strong>the</strong> shapes, one notices<br />

that almost everything has a square shape. Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human artifacts are made<br />

up <strong>of</strong> squares or its variations. For instance, houses are composed <strong>of</strong> windows,<br />

floors, tables, telev<strong>is</strong>ions and doors that are squares or square-like shapes.<br />

As concerns <strong>the</strong>se special phenomenal properties, we will study <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

shape starting from <strong>the</strong> square.<br />

1.2. The <strong>Shape</strong> before <strong>the</strong> “<strong>Shape</strong>”: Grouping and Figure-Ground Segregation<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong> psycholog<strong>is</strong>ts were <strong>the</strong> first to study and develop a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> shape,<br />

considered as an emergent quality. They studied <strong>the</strong> shape mostly in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

grouping and figure-ground segregation. (O<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Gestalt</strong> approaches to shape<br />

perception will be d<strong>is</strong>cussed in section 3.3.)<br />

Rubin (1915, 1921) studied <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> shape formation in terms <strong>of</strong> figureground<br />

segregation, by asking what appears as a figure and what as a background.<br />

He d<strong>is</strong>covered <strong>the</strong> following general figure-ground principles: surroundedness,<br />

size, orientation, contrast, symmetry, convexity, and parallel<strong>is</strong>m. Rubin also<br />

suggested <strong>the</strong> following main phenomenal attributes, belonging to <strong>the</strong> figure but<br />

not to <strong>the</strong> background. (i) The figure takes on <strong>the</strong> shape traced by <strong>the</strong> contour,<br />

implying that <strong>the</strong> contour belongs unilaterally to <strong>the</strong> figure (see Nakayama &<br />

Shimojo, 1990; Spillmann, 2012; Spillmann & Ehrenstein, 2004), not to <strong>the</strong><br />

background. (ii) Its color/brightness <strong>is</strong> perceived full like a surface and denser<br />

than <strong>the</strong> same physical color/brightness on <strong>the</strong> background that appear instead<br />

transparent and empty. (iii) The figure appears closer to <strong>the</strong> observer than <strong>the</strong><br />

background.<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer (1923, see also Spillmann, 2012) approached th<strong>is</strong> problem in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> grouping. The questions he answered <strong>is</strong>: how do <strong>the</strong> elements in <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual field<br />

‘go toge<strong>the</strong>r’ to form an integrated percept? How do individual elements create<br />

larger wholes? He studied some basic grouping principles useful to answer <strong>the</strong><br />

previous questions. They are: proximity, similarity, good continuation, closure,<br />

symmetry, convexity, prägnanz, past experience, common fate, and parallel<strong>is</strong>m.<br />

It <strong>is</strong> reasonable to consider that figure–ground segregation must operate before<br />

grouping (H<strong>of</strong>fman & Richards, 1984; Palmer, 1999). For example, dot<br />

elements on which grouping acts must be already segregated as a figure from<br />

<strong>the</strong> background, o<strong>the</strong>rw<strong>is</strong>e <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual system would not know which elements<br />

to group. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> same elements do not possess <strong>the</strong> figural properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> hol<strong>is</strong>tic organized and segregated figures; ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y appear as elementary<br />

384


385<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

components necessary to create boundaries. They are not surfaces, but something<br />

similar to perceptual ‘bricks’ necessary to create something more hol<strong>is</strong>tic. In spite<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> apparent differences between figure-ground segregation and grouping,<br />

what <strong>is</strong> phenomenally clear <strong>is</strong> that both dynamics are so intimately intertwined<br />

that a sharp d<strong>is</strong>tinction <strong>is</strong> likely impossible and maybe useless from a scientific<br />

point <strong>of</strong> view.<br />

Within Rubin’s and Wer<strong>the</strong>imer’s works, <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> shape formation <strong>is</strong><br />

approached in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main conditions operating in two <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> processes<br />

(grouping and figure-ground segregation) underlying but preceding <strong>the</strong> formation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape. For example, <strong>the</strong> unilateral belongingness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> boundaries can be<br />

considered as a shape <strong>is</strong>sue before <strong>the</strong> “shape” meaning. It talked about shape<br />

but it did not explain its meaning. Similarly, even if <strong>the</strong> closure principle can<br />

describe <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> a square, it cannot say anything about its properties<br />

and about <strong>the</strong> way its properties assign <strong>the</strong> special meanings we have previously<br />

described. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, it cannot explain <strong>the</strong> square variations described in <strong>the</strong><br />

next sections.<br />

Even if <strong>Gestalt</strong> grouping and figure-ground principles are part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong><br />

shape perception, <strong>the</strong>y do not face directly th<strong>is</strong> problem and, more importantly,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y do not answer basic questions like: what <strong>is</strong> shape? <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> its meaning?<br />

2. General Methods<br />

2.1. Subjects<br />

Different groups <strong>of</strong> 12 undergraduate students <strong>of</strong> architecture, design, lingu<strong>is</strong>tics<br />

participated in <strong>the</strong> experiments. Subjects had some basic knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong><br />

psychology and v<strong>is</strong>ual illusions, but <strong>the</strong>y were naive both to <strong>the</strong> stimuli and to<br />

<strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> experiments. They were male and female with normal or<br />

corrected-to-normal v<strong>is</strong>ion.<br />

2.2. Stimuli<br />

The stimuli were <strong>the</strong> figures shown in <strong>the</strong> next sections. The overall sizes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

v<strong>is</strong>ual stimuli were ~3.5 deg v<strong>is</strong>ual angle. The figures were shown on a computer<br />

screen with ambient illumination from a Osram Daylight fluorescent light (250<br />

lux, 5600° K). Stimuli were d<strong>is</strong>played on a 33 cm color CRT monitor (Sony<br />

GDM-F520 1600x1200 pixels, refresh rate 100 Hz), driven by a MacBook Pro<br />

computer with an NVIDIA GeForce 8600M GT. Viewing was binocular in <strong>the</strong><br />

frontoparallel plane at a d<strong>is</strong>tance <strong>of</strong> 50 cm from <strong>the</strong> monitor.<br />

2.3. Procedure<br />

Two methods, similar to those used by <strong>Gestalt</strong> psycholog<strong>is</strong>ts, were used.


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Phenomenological task: The task <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjects was to report spontaneously what<br />

<strong>the</strong>y perceived by providing a complete description <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main v<strong>is</strong>ual property.<br />

The descriptions were provided by at least 10 out <strong>of</strong> 12 subjects and were reported<br />

conc<strong>is</strong>ely within <strong>the</strong> main text to aid <strong>the</strong> reader in <strong>the</strong> stream <strong>of</strong> argumentations.<br />

The descriptions were judged by three graduate students <strong>of</strong> lingu<strong>is</strong>tics, naive as<br />

to <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, to get a fair representation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ones given by <strong>the</strong> observers.<br />

Subjects were allowed to make free compar<strong>is</strong>ons, confrontations, afterthoughts,<br />

to see in different ways, d<strong>is</strong>tance, etc.; to match <strong>the</strong> stimulus with every o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

one. Variations and possible compar<strong>is</strong>ons occurring during <strong>the</strong> free exploration<br />

were noted down by <strong>the</strong> experimenter. The selection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stimuli with opposite<br />

conditions and controls and <strong>the</strong> possible compar<strong>is</strong>ons among <strong>the</strong> stimuli prevent<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> generating biased experiences. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> clearly shown by <strong>the</strong><br />

differences in <strong>the</strong> results (see next sections).<br />

Scaling task: The subjects were instructed to rate (in percent) <strong>the</strong> descriptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> specific attribute obtained in <strong>the</strong> phenomenological experiments. New<br />

groups <strong>of</strong> 12 subjects were instructed to scale <strong>the</strong> relative strength or salience (in<br />

percent) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> descriptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenological task: “please rate whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

th<strong>is</strong> statement <strong>is</strong> an accurate reflection <strong>of</strong> your perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> stimulus, on a<br />

scale from 100 (perfect agreement) to 0 (complete d<strong>is</strong>agreement)”. Throughout<br />

<strong>the</strong> text we reported descriptions whose mean ratings were greater than 80. As<br />

concerns <strong>the</strong>se tasks and procedure see Pinna, (2010a, b; Pinna & Albertazzi,<br />

2011; Pinna & Sirigu, in press; Pinna & Reeves, 2009).<br />

3. Squares, Rotated Square and Diamonds<br />

3.1. Non-Square <strong>Shape</strong>s that Appear Like Squares<br />

<strong>Shape</strong> illusions are only apparently in contrast with <strong>the</strong> properties previously<br />

described: unambiguous identification, constancy, uniqueness and veridicality.<br />

These illusions are, in fact, considered to be exceptions v<strong>is</strong>ible under specific and<br />

rare conditions and, thus, ineffective for real life.<br />

The strong shape illusion, illustrated in Fig. 1a, was described like a large square<br />

with concave and convex sides. Th<strong>is</strong> description reveals a “d<strong>is</strong>tortion” that does<br />

not change <strong>the</strong> basic meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square shape. In fact, <strong>the</strong> main shape even<br />

if d<strong>is</strong>torted <strong>is</strong> still perceived like a square. Moreover, paradoxically <strong>the</strong> d<strong>is</strong>tortion<br />

reinforces and streng<strong>the</strong>ns <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square. In fact, <strong>the</strong> square <strong>is</strong><br />

amodally seen as <strong>the</strong> whole shape supporting <strong>the</strong> perceived d<strong>is</strong>tortion. Conversely,<br />

<strong>the</strong> d<strong>is</strong>tortion <strong>is</strong> what elicits <strong>the</strong> amodal wholeness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square (see Pinna,<br />

2010b). Th<strong>is</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> phenomenal dynamics also occurs when <strong>the</strong> perceived<br />

d<strong>is</strong>tortion <strong>is</strong> not illusory but “real”, as shown in Fig. 1b.<br />

386


Fig. 1 Non-square shapes that appear like squares<br />

!<br />

387<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

# $ % &<br />

)<br />

In more intense conditions in terms <strong>of</strong> d<strong>is</strong>tortion (see Figs. 1c-i), where <strong>the</strong> square<br />

and its sides or angles appear beveled, broken, crashed, gnawed, deliquescing,<br />

deformed, protruding, <strong>the</strong> main shape <strong>is</strong> again perceived as a square, while<br />

those specific descriptions reveal what happens to each square. They appear<br />

like “happenings” <strong>of</strong> a square (Pinna, 2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011). These<br />

changes and happenings can be seen as depending on or related to specific and<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

*(!+,'-,+(%,.%!/'/),0&,-(!1%2<br />

(<br />

“inv<strong>is</strong>ible” but perceptible causes affecting <strong>the</strong> shape and <strong>the</strong> material properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square. They add v<strong>is</strong>ual meanings but do not really change <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

square, which <strong>is</strong> perceived like <strong>the</strong> amodal invariant shape supporting all those<br />

happenings (see also section 5.6). From a geometrical point <strong>of</strong> view, <strong>the</strong>se are<br />

non-square shapes that appear like squares.<br />

These results suggest <strong>the</strong> following questions: Why do we perceive a square plus a<br />

happening in each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se cases, instead <strong>of</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> irregular shapes, one different<br />

from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r? <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> happening and <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r possible shape<br />

'<br />

"


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

attributes in shape formation? Which properties influence and determine <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> shape?<br />

An answer to <strong>the</strong> first question was previously reported by Pinna (2010b). In <strong>the</strong><br />

next sections, possible responses to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r questions will be proposed. We will<br />

first start by showing opposite conditions, where squares are perceived like nonsquare<br />

shapes, to understand <strong>the</strong> ways and under which conditions a square shape<br />

can be influenced and changed.<br />

3.2. Squares that Appear Like Non-Square <strong>Shape</strong>s<br />

3.2.1. Square<br />

Fig. 2a shows a square. The figure, here illustrated, appears like a “true” square,<br />

i.e. a shape that appears like a square tout court, a square without anything else.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> one-word description, “square”, does not reveal any happening or any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

relevant emerging attribute. <strong>Shape</strong> properties, like orientation, size and position,<br />

are left <strong>of</strong>f, because, under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong>y are “inv<strong>is</strong>ible” or unnoticeable<br />

like <strong>the</strong> background. These omitted properties are superfluous. The word “square”<br />

seems to contain, in fact, everything to recreate exactly <strong>the</strong> same figure and, thus,<br />

does not need any fur<strong>the</strong>r information. Th<strong>is</strong> square appears like <strong>the</strong> best example<br />

and <strong>the</strong> model <strong>of</strong> every “square”.<br />

It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile noticing that <strong>the</strong> om<strong>is</strong>sions are important information useful<br />

to understand <strong>the</strong> phenomenology <strong>of</strong> shape perception. Related to our square,<br />

we can state that <strong>the</strong> more numerous are <strong>the</strong> om<strong>is</strong>sions (inv<strong>is</strong>ible attributes), <strong>the</strong><br />

better <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> appearance as a model <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> shape, or, conversely <strong>the</strong> less <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

information described, <strong>the</strong> better <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> squareness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape. We define as<br />

“phenomenal singularity” <strong>the</strong> instance <strong>of</strong> a shape that does not need to be defined<br />

by attributes and that correspond to a one-word description. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong><br />

phenomenal singularity <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> best instance <strong>of</strong> a specific shape.<br />

By asking naive subjects “draw a square” and, afterwards, “choose <strong>the</strong> square that<br />

<strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> most ‘square’ among those illustrated” (see Figs. 2a-c), we found that most<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m (99%) represented <strong>the</strong> square exactly like <strong>the</strong> one <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2a and chose<br />

th<strong>is</strong> figure as <strong>the</strong> best example <strong>of</strong> square among <strong>the</strong> three.<br />

These results suggest <strong>the</strong> following questions: <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> relationship between<br />

<strong>the</strong> descriptive and <strong>the</strong> phenomenal notion <strong>of</strong> shape? More particularly, what <strong>is</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “square” when it denotes a singularity like <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> object perceived in Fig. 2a? By complementation, what <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

same term when it does not refer to a phenomenal singularity but emerges with<br />

v<strong>is</strong>ible attributes? <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square? <strong>What</strong> does th<strong>is</strong> shape<br />

convey, express or reveal in <strong>the</strong> way it appears?<br />

388


389<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

3.2.2. Rotated Square<br />

Fig. 2b represents an intermediate but crucial step in answering <strong>the</strong> previous<br />

questions. Th<strong>is</strong> figure <strong>is</strong> mostly described as a rotated square. Under <strong>the</strong>se<br />

conditions, subjects introduced spontaneously information about orientation,<br />

thus, creating a two-word description. The rotation becomes now v<strong>is</strong>ible, noticeable<br />

like a figure. The exact orientation <strong>is</strong>, instead, not specified spontaneously in<br />

words. Only after asking <strong>the</strong>m to describe <strong>the</strong> apparent direction and degree <strong>of</strong><br />

rotation, our subjects reported ~10° anticlockw<strong>is</strong>e.<br />

These results suggest a tw<strong>of</strong>old perception: a “true” square plus something that<br />

happens to it, namely, <strong>the</strong> rotation. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, unlike Fig. 2a <strong>the</strong> square <strong>is</strong>,<br />

now, not only a square, but also a square with a “happening” (Pinna, 2010b)<br />

defined in terms <strong>of</strong> rotation. The anti-clockw<strong>is</strong>e rotation suggests some kind <strong>of</strong><br />

minimum rotation pathway starting from <strong>the</strong> “true” square <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2a.<br />

Structurally, th<strong>is</strong> happening <strong>is</strong> similar to those described for Figs. 1c-i.<br />

Lingu<strong>is</strong>tically, <strong>the</strong> rotation <strong>is</strong> an adjective that describes <strong>the</strong> noun, which <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

square. Phenomenally, it <strong>is</strong> what happens to <strong>the</strong> shape. The primary role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

shape (square) in relation to <strong>the</strong> adjective (rotation) can be clearly perceived<br />

by comparing <strong>the</strong> two following possible descriptions: “a rotated square” and<br />

“a rotation with a square shape”. The second description appears meaningless<br />

and odd. A rotation cannot have a shape, while <strong>the</strong> shape can have a rotation.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> suggests a clear asymmetrical hierarchy between <strong>the</strong> two terms. The shape<br />

<strong>is</strong> primary, earlier in time and order than <strong>the</strong> rotation. Therefore, <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>is</strong> a<br />

noun and as such it <strong>is</strong> a word generally used to identify a class <strong>of</strong> elements. As a<br />

noun, <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>is</strong> like “a thing”, which can appear in many different ways, and<br />

<strong>the</strong> rotation <strong>is</strong> one <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> being <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape, i.e. <strong>the</strong> attribute <strong>of</strong> that<br />

specific thing.<br />

These phenomenal observations suggest <strong>the</strong> following methodological note:<br />

<strong>the</strong> asymmetrical descriptions represent a useful method <strong>of</strong> understanding <strong>the</strong><br />

primary role <strong>of</strong> one v<strong>is</strong>ual component over ano<strong>the</strong>r, e.g. <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape over <strong>the</strong><br />

rotation and, more generally, <strong>of</strong> something that becomes <strong>the</strong> primary thing over<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r perceived like its attribute. Ano<strong>the</strong>r example useful to understand <strong>the</strong><br />

effectiveness <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> method <strong>is</strong> represented by <strong>the</strong> relation between shape and<br />

color: we say “a red square” and not “a square-shaped red”. The d<strong>is</strong>tinction<br />

between things and attributes can also be demonstrated through <strong>the</strong> position<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> words one relative to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r and through <strong>the</strong> phenomenal inv<strong>is</strong>ibility,<br />

i.e. an attribute (way <strong>of</strong> being <strong>of</strong> a thing) can be inv<strong>is</strong>ible or unnoticed like a<br />

background much more than a thing.<br />

Despite th<strong>is</strong> asymmetry, rotation and square define <strong>the</strong>mselves reciprocally. The<br />

rotation <strong>is</strong> defined by <strong>the</strong> shape, i.e. <strong>the</strong> rotation can be perceived if and only<br />

if <strong>the</strong> square as a singularity <strong>is</strong> also perceived. Conversely, <strong>the</strong> rotation defines


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

<strong>the</strong> shape, i.e. without <strong>the</strong> rotation <strong>the</strong> square as a singularity could not be<br />

perceived. As soon as <strong>the</strong>y are defined, square and rotation organize <strong>the</strong>mselves<br />

asymmetrically as suggested by <strong>the</strong> two previous descriptions.<br />

! " #<br />

Fig. 2 A square (a), a rotated square (b) and a diamond (c)<br />

3.2.3. Diamond<br />

By increasing <strong>the</strong> rotation <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2b up to 45° as shown in Fig. 2c, both <strong>the</strong><br />

happening (rotation) and <strong>the</strong> square are replaced by ano<strong>the</strong>r one-word description:<br />

a diamond. Th<strong>is</strong> outcome <strong>is</strong> unexpected, if compared with <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2a.<br />

It represents a hard problem for an invariant features hypo<strong>the</strong>s<strong>is</strong>. In fact, if shapes<br />

are defined by virtue <strong>of</strong> attributes invariant over rotations, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> two shapes<br />

<strong>of</strong> Figs. 2a and 2c should be perceived as having <strong>the</strong> same shape. Therefore, <strong>the</strong><br />

square and <strong>the</strong> diamond demonstrate that different shape rotations cannot be<br />

perceived as having <strong>the</strong> same shape.<br />

Figs. 2a and 2c show <strong>the</strong> so-called Mach’s square/diamond illusion (Mach,<br />

1914/1959; Schumann, 1900), according to which <strong>the</strong> same geometrical figure <strong>is</strong><br />

perceived as a square when its sides are vertical and horizontal, but as a diamond<br />

when <strong>the</strong>y are diagonal. From a phenomenal point <strong>of</strong> view, it <strong>is</strong> more correct to<br />

state that <strong>the</strong> square <strong>is</strong> perceived when <strong>the</strong> sides are vertical and horizontal, while<br />

a diamond <strong>is</strong> seen when its angles or vertices are vertical and horizontal. Th<strong>is</strong><br />

description <strong>is</strong> more appropriate if we consider what emerges more strongly in <strong>the</strong><br />

two conditions: <strong>the</strong> sides in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square, and <strong>the</strong> angles/vertices in <strong>the</strong><br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

case $%!&'()'&%*'+*!,(,-'./')%!0*1<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> diamond. We will see in section 5 some important consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

phenomenal observations for a better understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape.<br />

One main effect related to Mach’s square/diamond illusion <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong><br />

diamond appears larger than <strong>the</strong> square. Schumann (1900) suggested that th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong><br />

related to <strong>the</strong> fact that v<strong>is</strong>ual attention <strong>is</strong> placed on <strong>the</strong> vertical-horizontal axes,<br />

which are clearly longer in <strong>the</strong> diamond condition. Th<strong>is</strong> explanation <strong>is</strong> supported<br />

by <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> a simple control experiment according to which, by focusing<br />

<strong>the</strong> attention on one side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> diamond ra<strong>the</strong>r than on one angle, during <strong>the</strong><br />

compar<strong>is</strong>on <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> size <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2a and 2c, <strong>the</strong> apparent size difference between <strong>the</strong><br />

square and <strong>the</strong> diamond <strong>is</strong> strongly reduced or even annulled.<br />

390


391<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

3.3. The Role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Frame <strong>of</strong> Reference in <strong>Shape</strong> Perception<br />

More recent and complex explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square/diamond illusion are based<br />

on object-centered reference frames. Rock (1973, 1983; see also Clément &<br />

Bukley, 2008), starting from previous <strong>Gestalt</strong> studies (Asch & Witkin, 1948a,<br />

1948b; K<strong>of</strong>fka, 1935; Metzger, 1941, 1975), suggested that <strong>the</strong> perceived<br />

shape <strong>is</strong> a description relative to a perceptual frame <strong>of</strong> reference, i.e. <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual<br />

system prefers gravitational axes over retinal or head axes. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, Rock<br />

considered Mach’s square/diamond illusion as a clear evidence that a shape<br />

<strong>is</strong> perceived in relation to an environmental frame <strong>of</strong> reference where gravity<br />

defines <strong>the</strong> reference orientation, at least in <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> intrinsic axes in <strong>the</strong><br />

object itself. If <strong>the</strong> environmental orientation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figure changes with respect<br />

to <strong>the</strong> two figures, <strong>the</strong> description <strong>of</strong> one shape does not match <strong>the</strong> description<br />

stored in memory for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r shape, <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> observer fails to perceive <strong>the</strong><br />

equivalence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two figures.<br />

The stimulus factors important in determining <strong>the</strong> intrinsic reference frame<br />

are: gravitational orientation; directional symmetry (Pinna, 2010b; Pinna &<br />

Reeves, 2009); axes <strong>of</strong> reflectional symmetry, configural orientation (Attneave,<br />

1968; Palmer, 1980) and axes <strong>of</strong> elongation (Marr & N<strong>is</strong>hihara, 1978; Palmer,<br />

1975a, 1983, 1985; Rock, 1973). These factors rule <strong>the</strong> relation between shape<br />

and orientation as it happens in o<strong>the</strong>r phenomena (e.g., <strong>the</strong> rod-and-frame and<br />

Kopfermann’s effects; Davi & Pr<strong>of</strong>itt, 1993; Kopfermann, 1930; see also Marr &<br />

N<strong>is</strong>hihara, 1978; Palmer, 1975b, 1989, 1999; Witkins & Asch, 1948).<br />

These explanations contain some serious limits especially within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenology. More particularly, <strong>the</strong>y cannot account for <strong>the</strong> reason why we<br />

perceive a square, a diamond or a rotated square without invoking names and<br />

descriptions stored in memory. More specifically, <strong>the</strong>y do not say anything about<br />

what changes phenomenally inside <strong>the</strong> shape properties when axes <strong>of</strong> reflection,<br />

gravitation and o<strong>the</strong>r factors change and about which shape properties switch<br />

when a square switches to a diamond.<br />

These limits are accompanied by <strong>the</strong> following questions: why are two names/<br />

descriptions (square and diamond) stored so differently? Are <strong>the</strong>y stored as different<br />

names because <strong>the</strong>y are perceived differently or are <strong>the</strong>y perceived differently<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y are stored in memory with different names/descriptions? These last<br />

questions are not trivial because <strong>the</strong>y are related to <strong>the</strong> important problem <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> primary role <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual perception over <strong>the</strong> higher cognitive processes (see<br />

Kanizsa, 1980, 1985, 1991). Th<strong>is</strong> implies that <strong>the</strong> difference between square and<br />

diamond can be accounted for within <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ion alone and in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

perceptual organization <strong>of</strong> shape attributes.<br />

In addition to <strong>the</strong>se <strong>is</strong>sues, <strong>the</strong> previous hypo<strong>the</strong>ses cannot explain what shapes,<br />

such as squares, diamonds or rotated squares, are, and, even more generally, <strong>the</strong>y


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

do not say anything about what a shape <strong>is</strong>. They only state that in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

square/diamond illusion some factors influence <strong>the</strong> switch from one shape to<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r. Even if <strong>the</strong>se factors are likely really effective, <strong>the</strong>y cannot explain <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> shape. As a consequence, on <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se factors what determines<br />

<strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> a square and a diamond <strong>is</strong> not accounted for.<br />

4. Doubts about <strong>the</strong> Role <strong>of</strong> Frame <strong>of</strong> Reference<br />

4.1. On <strong>the</strong> Second Order Square/Diamond Illusion<br />

The limits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se hypo<strong>the</strong>ses can be highlighted even more effectively through<br />

some new phenomenal conditions useful to understand <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape.<br />

Their rationale <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> following: if <strong>the</strong> perceived shape <strong>is</strong> a description relative<br />

to a perceptual frame <strong>of</strong> reference, <strong>the</strong>n results analogous to those achieved with<br />

<strong>the</strong> square/diamond illusion are expected to be attained through second order<br />

variations <strong>of</strong> squares and diamonds.<br />

In Fig. 3a, <strong>the</strong> square and <strong>the</strong> diamond <strong>of</strong> Figs. 2a and 2c and <strong>the</strong> rotated square<br />

<strong>of</strong> Fig. 2b are changed by making <strong>the</strong> sides concave. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions <strong>the</strong><br />

two main effects previously described, i.e. <strong>the</strong> square/diamond switch and <strong>the</strong> size<br />

difference between <strong>the</strong> horizontal and vertical conditions, are strongly reduced or<br />

even absent. They appear more easily like <strong>the</strong> same figure with different amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> rotation.<br />

392


!<br />

"<br />

#<br />

$<br />

%<br />

&<br />

'<br />

(<br />

)<br />

*<br />

Fig. 3 Second order variations <strong>of</strong> a square, a rotated square and a diamond<br />

393<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

In !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

Fig. 3b, <strong>the</strong> angles are now rounded. The two main effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square/<br />

diamond +(!,-).-,(%-/%!0)0'-1&-.(!2%3<br />

illusion are clearly absent. They are also absent in <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r conditions<br />

illustrated in Figs. 3c-g, where <strong>the</strong> changes involve <strong>the</strong> whole shapes. In Figs. 3hj,<br />

only one angle <strong>of</strong> each shape has been changed, but again <strong>the</strong> square/diamond


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

and <strong>the</strong> size difference effects are very weak or absent. These results demonstrate<br />

that under <strong>the</strong>se conditions <strong>the</strong> vertical/horizontal and gravitational ax<strong>is</strong> do not<br />

define <strong>the</strong> reference orientation and, thus, do not influence shape perception.<br />

4.2. The Square/Diamond Illusion with Polygons<br />

A second set <strong>of</strong> conditions that weaken <strong>the</strong> previous hypo<strong>the</strong>ses and, at <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time, contribute to an understanding that <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape <strong>is</strong> related to <strong>the</strong><br />

orientation <strong>of</strong> polygons. If <strong>the</strong> rotation <strong>of</strong> a square by 45 deg induces <strong>the</strong> square/<br />

diamond illusion, similar results are expected by rotating polygons.<br />

In Fig. 4, several polygons in two orientations with a different number <strong>of</strong> sides<br />

are illustrated. The polygons do not show any kind <strong>of</strong> difference in <strong>the</strong> two<br />

orientations. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>y do not have different names stored in memory<br />

and, finally, <strong>the</strong>y do not show a clear size change like <strong>the</strong> one reported in <strong>the</strong><br />

square/diamond illusion.<br />

Fig. 4 Polygons and <strong>the</strong> square/diamond illusion<br />

Why does only <strong>the</strong> square induce th<strong>is</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> illusion, while o<strong>the</strong>r polygons do<br />

not? The octagon, shown in two orientations, with <strong>the</strong> sides or with <strong>the</strong> angles<br />

394


395<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

along <strong>the</strong> vertical/horizontal ax<strong>is</strong> (see Fig. 5), <strong>is</strong> useful when answering th<strong>is</strong><br />

question. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong> two figures appear different: one flattened<br />

and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r pointed. Sides or angles emerge more strongly in one but not in <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r condition and vice versa. The vertical/horizontal alignments streng<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong><br />

salience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides and <strong>the</strong> angles. (It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile clarifying that, among <strong>the</strong><br />

previous polygons, <strong>the</strong> one geometrically and phenomenally closer to <strong>the</strong> octagon<br />

<strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> hexagon, where sides and angles are as well placed both on <strong>the</strong> vertical and<br />

on <strong>the</strong> horizontal ax<strong>is</strong>.) Although <strong>the</strong> two octagons show <strong>the</strong> difference previously<br />

described, <strong>the</strong>y do not have different names stored in memory and do not show<br />

a clear size difference like <strong>the</strong> square/diamond illusion.<br />

Fig. 5 Flattened and pointed octagons<br />

A new effect emerging in <strong>the</strong>se figures <strong>is</strong> an illusion <strong>of</strong> numerosity: <strong>the</strong> number<br />

<strong>of</strong> angles and sides <strong>is</strong> perceived higher in <strong>the</strong> octagon with <strong>the</strong> angles along <strong>the</strong><br />

vertical and horizontal axes. Th<strong>is</strong> phenomenon <strong>is</strong> likely related to <strong>the</strong> phenomenal<br />

asymmetry between <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides and <strong>the</strong> angles. Th<strong>is</strong> asymmetry<br />

will be dealt in greater depth in <strong>the</strong> next section.<br />

5. Inside <strong>the</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>: <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> a <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

5.1. <strong>What</strong> are Squares and Diamonds? Sidedness and Pointedness<br />

To understand why <strong>the</strong> second order variations illustrated in Fig. 3 are not<br />

influenced in <strong>the</strong> two main properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square/diamond effect, it <strong>is</strong><br />

necessary to go back to <strong>the</strong> properties emerging in <strong>the</strong> two octagons, which help<br />

<strong>the</strong> understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square and <strong>the</strong> diamond.<br />

In geometry, a square <strong>is</strong> defined as a regular quadrilateral, namely a shape with<br />

four equal sides and four equal angles. Sides and angles are <strong>the</strong> components <strong>of</strong> a<br />

square that emerge more easily within <strong>the</strong> gradient <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility, i.e. <strong>the</strong> gradient <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenal vividness <strong>of</strong> different v<strong>is</strong>ual attributes that do not pop out with <strong>the</strong><br />

same strength (Pinna, 2010a). If a square shape <strong>is</strong> made up <strong>of</strong> sides and angles,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it shows phenomenal properties such as “sidedness” and “pointedness” related<br />

to <strong>the</strong>se components. These two properties are only apparently equipollent. The<br />

square/diamond illusion demonstrates <strong>the</strong> vividness asymmetry between <strong>the</strong>se<br />

properties. In <strong>the</strong> square <strong>the</strong> sidedness appears stronger than <strong>the</strong> pointedness,<br />

while <strong>the</strong> diamond shows more strongly <strong>the</strong> pointedness. The perceived strength<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

<strong>of</strong> one or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r property <strong>is</strong> influenced by <strong>the</strong> vertical/horizontal and<br />

gravitational ax<strong>is</strong> that plays by accentuating <strong>the</strong> sidedness against <strong>the</strong> pointedness<br />

in <strong>the</strong> square and, vice versa, <strong>the</strong> pointedness against <strong>the</strong> sidedness in <strong>the</strong> diamond.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se properties, it appears clear why <strong>the</strong> second order variations<br />

<strong>of</strong> Fig. 3 are not involved in <strong>the</strong> square/diamond illusions. In fact, in all <strong>the</strong><br />

conditions illustrated sidedness and pointedness are not in contrast but ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

sidedness or <strong>the</strong> pointedness are attenuated or emphasized, thus weakening only<br />

one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two effects. Th<strong>is</strong> entails that one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two singularities <strong>is</strong> weakened,<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore appearing as a rotation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

The two properties can also account for <strong>the</strong> reason why we perceive a rotated<br />

square in Fig. 2b. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> due to <strong>the</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sidedness being higher than<br />

<strong>the</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pointedness.<br />

Similarly, <strong>the</strong> numerosity illusion <strong>of</strong> Fig. 5 can be considered as related to <strong>the</strong><br />

shape attribute that defines <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> elements in <strong>the</strong> octagon. We suggest<br />

that th<strong>is</strong> figure, similarly to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r polygons, <strong>is</strong> mostly defined by <strong>the</strong> sidedness<br />

and thus by <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> sides. More specifically, to answer a question like<br />

“what polygon <strong>is</strong> th<strong>is</strong>?” spontaneously we count at a glance <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> sides<br />

but not <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> vertices. The importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two properties in defining<br />

<strong>the</strong> shape appears in fact asymmetrical. Therefore, because in <strong>the</strong> pointed octagon<br />

<strong>of</strong> Fig. 5 <strong>the</strong> sidedness <strong>is</strong> weakened while <strong>the</strong> vertices are perceived with a stronger<br />

vividness, <strong>the</strong> numerosity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides <strong>is</strong> determined taking into account or starting<br />

from <strong>the</strong> angles or vertices, which induce an increasing <strong>of</strong> number <strong>of</strong> sides or a<br />

summation effect due to <strong>the</strong> numerosity fuzziness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong><br />

angles. The calculation at a glance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> number <strong>of</strong> sides can include also some<br />

vertices that pop out more strongly than <strong>the</strong> sides.<br />

These phenomenal reports suggest that, all else being equal, <strong>the</strong> perceived shape<br />

can change or switch from one shape to ano<strong>the</strong>r by accentuating <strong>the</strong> sidedness<br />

or <strong>the</strong> pointedness independently from <strong>the</strong> vertical/horizontal and gravitational<br />

axes. A demonstration <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> expectation <strong>is</strong> illustrated in Fig. 6, where, despite<br />

<strong>the</strong> configural orientation effects (i.e. <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> local spatial orientation<br />

determined by <strong>the</strong> global spatial orientational structure) studied by Attneave<br />

(1968) and Palmer (1980), rows <strong>of</strong> figures are perceived as rotated squares or as<br />

diamonds according to <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> small circle placed near <strong>the</strong> sides or<br />

near <strong>the</strong> angles <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figures (see also Pinna, 2010a, 2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi,<br />

2011). While in Figs. 6a and 6c, <strong>the</strong> geometrical diamonds are phenomenally<br />

perceived as rotated squares, in Figs. 6b and 6d, <strong>the</strong> geometrical diamonds are<br />

perceived more strongly than in <strong>the</strong> control (Fig. 6e) as diamonds.<br />

396


#<br />

2<br />

0<br />

1<br />

(<br />

Fig. 6 Rotated squares or diamonds?<br />

397<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

5.2. On <strong>the</strong> Difference between a Square and a Rotated Square<br />

It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile clarifying that a diamond and a square rotated by 45 deg as shown<br />

in Fig. 6 are different shapes, not only because <strong>the</strong>y have two different names, but,<br />

mostly, because <strong>the</strong>y show opposite phenomenal properties: pointedness in <strong>the</strong><br />

diamonds and sidedness in <strong>the</strong> rotated squares. Th<strong>is</strong> shape switch <strong>is</strong> not a minor<br />

difference but a variation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceptual meaning <strong>of</strong> shape (see Pinna, 2010b).<br />

Pointedness and sidedness are like <strong>the</strong> underlying shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape, a second<br />

level shape (meta-shape), i.e. <strong>the</strong> meanings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceived shapes, and, more<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

particularly, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> diamond and square or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two octagons illustrated in Fig.<br />

5. These phenomenal remarks are corroborated by <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> Fig. 7, where <strong>the</strong><br />

inner rectangles accentuate <strong>the</strong> sidedness or <strong>the</strong> pointedness <strong>of</strong> both <strong>the</strong> checks<br />

and <strong>the</strong> whole checkerboards, thus eliciting respectively <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> rotated<br />

squares or diamonds in <strong>the</strong> same geometrical figures. Th<strong>is</strong> result demonstrates<br />

local and global effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accentuation.<br />

Fig. 7 Rotated squares or diamonds in both <strong>the</strong> checks and <strong>the</strong> whole checkerboards<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

398


399<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

Sidedness and pointedness can also be accentuated in <strong>the</strong> two grids with <strong>the</strong><br />

same geometrical shape as shown in Fig. 8. Again, <strong>the</strong> single elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> grid<br />

(each single inner diamond shape) and <strong>the</strong> global shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> grid are perceived<br />

as rotated squares or diamonds by virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> sidedness or<br />

pointedness.<br />

Fig. 8 Rotated squares or diamonds in both <strong>the</strong> components and <strong>the</strong> whole grids<br />

These results suggest that <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> an object depends on its inner properties,<br />

on <strong>the</strong>ir accentuation due to o<strong>the</strong>r elements (d<strong>is</strong>k or empty circles) present in<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

<strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual field. Therefore, shape perception <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organization <strong>of</strong> its<br />

inner attributes, whose gradient <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility can be changed according to accents<br />

placed in a spatial position that enhances <strong>the</strong> vividness <strong>of</strong> one shape attribute<br />

against <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile showing Kopfermann’s effect demonstrating <strong>the</strong> dependence <strong>of</strong><br />

an object shape on <strong>the</strong> frame <strong>of</strong> reference (Kopfermann, 1930; see also Antonucci<br />

et al., 1995; Gibson, 1937; Wikin & Asch, 1948). The effect <strong>is</strong> shown in Fig. 9 in<br />

<strong>the</strong> four classical versions. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong> square and <strong>the</strong> diamond<br />

<strong>of</strong> Figs. 9a-b, when included within a rectangle obliquely oriented are perceived<br />

respectively as a diamond and as a rotated square (see Figs. 9c-d).<br />

Fig. 9 Kopfermann’s effect<br />

Figs. 10a and 10b demonstrate <strong>the</strong> stronger role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

sidedness or <strong>the</strong> pointedness over <strong>the</strong> larger reference frame. Due to <strong>the</strong> black<br />

dot and to <strong>the</strong> inner small rectangle, <strong>the</strong> geometrical shapes are now restored,<br />

i.e. <strong>the</strong> diamond and <strong>the</strong> rotated square perceived in Figs. 9c-d are switched into<br />

a rotated square and a diamond demonstrating <strong>the</strong> ineffectiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> larger<br />

frame <strong>of</strong> reference.<br />

!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

# 0<br />

1 2<br />

400


Fig. 10 Kopfermann’s effect annulled<br />

#<br />

0<br />

401<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

5.3. On <strong>the</strong> Accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong> Properties<br />

Sidedness and pointedness can be accentuated in many ways (see Pinna, 2010a,<br />

2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011). A powerful accentuation factor <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> reversed<br />

contrast shown in Fig. 11. Due to th<strong>is</strong> factor, <strong>the</strong> same geometrical octagons<br />

appear rotated in opposite directions, clockw<strong>is</strong>e or anticlockw<strong>is</strong>e (Figs. 11a-b).<br />

They are also perceived pointed with different strength and at different locations<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figures depending on <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> white components (Figs. 11c-d).<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

By !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

comparing Figs. 11a-b and 11c-d, <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual differences between <strong>the</strong> sidedness<br />

and <strong>the</strong> pointedness emerge very clearly. The difference in salience <strong>of</strong> sides and<br />

angles <strong>is</strong> seen very clearly also in Figs. 11e-f, where a slightly concave and convex<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides can be perceived.<br />

These differences are also accompanied by <strong>the</strong> illusion <strong>of</strong> numerosity described<br />

in section 4.2. It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile noticing that it <strong>is</strong> not <strong>the</strong> geometrical orientation<br />

which defines <strong>the</strong> numerosity, in fact it <strong>is</strong> kept constant, but <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

sidedness or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pointedness due to <strong>the</strong>ir accentuation.


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

# 1<br />

0<br />

(<br />

Fig. 11 Accentuation <strong>of</strong> sidedness and pointedness in octagons<br />

In Fig. 12, <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sidedness and pointedness through <strong>the</strong><br />

!"#$%&'(()''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

reversed !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

contrast induces diamond-shaped (Fig. 12a) or grand piano-like (Fig.<br />

12b) figures in <strong>the</strong> same geometrical objects.<br />

402<br />

2<br />

-


403<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

Fig. 12 Diamond-shaped or grand piano-like figures in <strong>the</strong> same geometrical objects<br />

#<br />

0<br />

In Fig. 13, <strong>the</strong> accentuation, due to <strong>the</strong> arrangement <strong>of</strong> black and white sides <strong>of</strong> each<br />

square, !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

produces a directional symmetry and elicits several phenomena: (i) a global<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

and local rectangle illusion, i.e. <strong>the</strong> geometrical squares, both locally (each single<br />

square) and globally (<strong>the</strong> square made up <strong>of</strong> squares), are perceived like rectangles<br />

elongated in <strong>the</strong> direction perpendicular to <strong>the</strong> black sides; (ii) <strong>the</strong> orientation <strong>of</strong><br />

each element appears polarized (upwards in Fig. 13a and downwards in Fig. 13b);<br />

(iii) <strong>the</strong> elements are grouped in columns and rows and a global waving (up &


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

down or left & right) apparent motion <strong>is</strong> clearly perceived when <strong>the</strong> gaze follows<br />

<strong>the</strong> tip <strong>of</strong> a pen moved across <strong>the</strong> patterns illustrated in Figs. 13c and 13d.<br />

These results are likely related to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> black side not only enhances<br />

<strong>the</strong> salience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sidedness, but also defines <strong>the</strong> base <strong>of</strong> each check. Th<strong>is</strong> suggests<br />

that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal accentuation <strong>of</strong> one shape property manifests vectorial<br />

properties. More particularly, <strong>the</strong> accent placed on <strong>the</strong> black side appears, under<br />

<strong>the</strong>se conditions, as <strong>the</strong> starting point <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> oriented direction. The white side<br />

<strong>of</strong> each check, opposite to <strong>the</strong> black one, <strong>is</strong> perceived as <strong>the</strong> tip <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> arrow or<br />

as <strong>the</strong> terminal point <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> oriented direction induced by <strong>the</strong> accent. Finally.<br />

<strong>the</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> vector depends on <strong>the</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accent, here kept<br />

constant. Briefly, <strong>the</strong> accents behave like Euclidean vectors considered in <strong>the</strong><br />

same acceptation used in physics.<br />

Fig. 13 The accentuation, due to black sides, produces a directional symmetry and manifests<br />

vectorial properties<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

# 0<br />

1 2<br />

404


405<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

These results demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> one shape property against<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r can induce different kinds <strong>of</strong> dimensional, direction and even motion<br />

effects, which suggest a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> shape, considered like an overall holder<br />

containing many shape attributes that compete or cooperate and whose strength<br />

can be changed or accentuated in many ways.<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r effects induced by <strong>the</strong> accentuation and by its vectorial properties are <strong>the</strong><br />

tilt and straighten up effects <strong>of</strong> Fig. 14. The dot seems to tilt fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> shape<br />

by pulling <strong>the</strong> top left-hand corner <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parallelogram in Fig. 14-left and to<br />

push <strong>the</strong> whole figure in <strong>the</strong> right-vertical direction, thus, straightening up <strong>the</strong><br />

parallelogram in Fig. 14-right.<br />

Fig. 14 Tilt and straighten up effects<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r kind <strong>of</strong> accentuation <strong>is</strong> induced by <strong>the</strong> m<strong>is</strong>sing parts or cuts <strong>of</strong> sides<br />

and angles shown in Fig. 15, thus inducing <strong>the</strong> switch from <strong>the</strong> diamond to <strong>the</strong><br />

rotated square shape both in <strong>the</strong> 2D and 3D conditions. It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile noticing<br />

that <strong>the</strong> 3D appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cube with <strong>the</strong> m<strong>is</strong>sing corner <strong>is</strong> weaker than <strong>the</strong><br />

one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cube with <strong>the</strong> cut side (see also Fig. 16). Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> likely due to <strong>the</strong><br />

directional symmetry induced by <strong>the</strong> cut, which favors <strong>the</strong> vertical organization<br />

<strong>of</strong> lines that camouflages <strong>the</strong> whole 3D perception.<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Fig . 15 Diamond and <strong>the</strong> rotated square shapes both in <strong>the</strong> 2D and 3D conditions<br />

By introducing white sides or white dots within <strong>the</strong> same shape near <strong>the</strong> corner<br />

or next to one side, <strong>the</strong> cube appearance can be ei<strong>the</strong>r weakened or optimized (cf.<br />

<strong>the</strong> control at <strong>the</strong> bottom) as shown in Fig. 16.<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

406


Fig. 16 The vertical organization weakens <strong>the</strong> 3D appearance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cubes<br />

407<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

5.4. O<strong>the</strong>r !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" <strong>Shape</strong> Properties: The Pointing<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

The shape properties are not restricted to <strong>the</strong> sidedness and pointedness. Given<br />

<strong>the</strong> vectorial attributes previously described and <strong>the</strong> relations between sides and<br />

angles and also between what appears as <strong>the</strong> base <strong>of</strong> a shape and its height, <strong>the</strong><br />

pointing <strong>is</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r significant shape property, which can be strongly influenced<br />

by <strong>the</strong> accentuation. If <strong>the</strong> pointing <strong>is</strong> a shape attribute, <strong>the</strong>n it <strong>is</strong> expected to<br />

create and define <strong>the</strong> perceived shape.<br />

In Fig. 17a, <strong>the</strong> horizontal alignment <strong>of</strong> equilateral triangles induces <strong>the</strong> pointing


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> triangles in <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir alignment. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> due to <strong>the</strong> configural<br />

orientation effect studied by Attneave (1968), Palmer (1980, 1989) and Palmer<br />

& Bucher (1981).<br />

Figs. 17b-c demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> pointing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> triangles can be deviated or<br />

redirected by <strong>the</strong> small rectangles and circles placed inside each triangle,<br />

respectively in <strong>the</strong> top left and bottom left-hand directions. These results are<br />

unexpected on <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> configural orientation effect (see also Pinna,<br />

2010a, 2010b).<br />

#<br />

2<br />

0<br />

1<br />

(<br />

Fig. 17 The pointing and <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> triangles can be influenced by <strong>the</strong> accentuation<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

408


409<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

More important than <strong>the</strong>se conditions are <strong>the</strong> following ones <strong>of</strong> Figs. 17d-e, where<br />

<strong>the</strong> pointing clearly influences <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> triangles, thus demonstrating<br />

that <strong>the</strong> pointing <strong>is</strong> a shape property. Geometrically <strong>the</strong> triangles are <strong>is</strong>osceles,<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less due to <strong>the</strong> pointing induced by <strong>the</strong> two kinds <strong>of</strong> accentuation<br />

(rectangles and circles), <strong>the</strong>y are perceived like scalene triangles. More in details,<br />

because <strong>the</strong> perceived pointing <strong>is</strong> not in <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> angle created by<br />

<strong>the</strong> two longer sides, th<strong>is</strong> induces an asymmetrical effect that propagates and<br />

determines <strong>the</strong> whole shape <strong>of</strong> each triangle making it appear as scalene.<br />

These results suggest that <strong>the</strong> pointing and all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r meta-shape attributes<br />

here studied are <strong>the</strong> main attributes responsible for <strong>the</strong> shape formation. They<br />

can explain what a shape <strong>is</strong>.<br />

Variations in <strong>the</strong> pointing <strong>of</strong> sides or vertices, due to <strong>the</strong> accentuation, clearly<br />

influence <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> figures as shown in Fig. 18. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong><br />

rows <strong>of</strong> irregular quadrilaterals are perceived as different shapes, difficult to<br />

recognize as <strong>the</strong> same figures. By determining <strong>the</strong> shape, <strong>the</strong> accent determines<br />

also <strong>the</strong> orientation <strong>of</strong> each specific shape and <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong> shape-related<br />

information about its rigidity and surface bending in <strong>the</strong> 3D space. The bending<br />

region <strong>is</strong> easily and immediately perceivable and its location changes in relation<br />

to <strong>the</strong> accent position within <strong>the</strong> figure. These results suggest <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual<br />

organization and <strong>the</strong> new conditions illustrated in <strong>the</strong> following section.


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Fig. 18 Rows <strong>of</strong> irregular quadrilaterals are perceived as different shapes<br />

5.5. The Headedness and <strong>the</strong> Organic Segmentation<br />

There <strong>is</strong> a special kind <strong>of</strong> shape formation never studied before, which subsumes<br />

a meta-shape property that we call “headedness”. Th<strong>is</strong> property <strong>is</strong> shown in <strong>the</strong><br />

irregular !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" wiggly object <strong>of</strong> Fig. 19a that assumes an organic appearance similar to<br />

an !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

amoeba or to some kind <strong>of</strong> living creature with a head and upper and lower<br />

limbs, moving in <strong>the</strong> direction defined by <strong>the</strong> shape component perceived as <strong>the</strong><br />

head <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organ<strong>is</strong>m. The object shapes up slowly and appears reversible, i.e.<br />

<strong>the</strong> same component can assume different roles (head, limb), <strong>the</strong>refore changing<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole organic segmentation and, as a consequence, <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

perceived motion, <strong>the</strong> structure, <strong>the</strong> weight and all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r static and dynamic<br />

character<strong>is</strong>tics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organ<strong>is</strong>m.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> organic segmentation can be reshaped, similarly to <strong>the</strong> ways previously<br />

410


411<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

shown in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> squares, through <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> one component<br />

against <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs in <strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong> head, thus favoring <strong>the</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

headedness shape property. Figs. 19b-e demonstrate that by changing <strong>the</strong> spatial<br />

position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> small circle <strong>the</strong> organ<strong>is</strong>m changes its shape, appearing each time<br />

as a different creature. The component defined by <strong>the</strong> circle becomes <strong>the</strong> head.<br />

As such, all <strong>the</strong> organic properties change accordingly to what <strong>is</strong> perceived as <strong>the</strong><br />

head, i.e. to <strong>the</strong> headedness property. For instance, <strong>the</strong> organ<strong>is</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> Figs. 19bc<br />

or 19d-e are perceived moving in opposite directions. The limbs appear also<br />

totally different and so on.<br />

0<br />

Fig. 19 Different organic segmentations <strong>of</strong> undulated figures<br />

!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

#<br />

2 (<br />

- +<br />

1


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Figs. 19f-c demonstrate that not all <strong>the</strong> components can assume <strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong><br />

head. The accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> bottom components cannot induce so strongly as<br />

in Figs. 19b-e <strong>the</strong> headedness property. Th<strong>is</strong> likely depends on <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

head, usually placed sideways or at <strong>the</strong> top <strong>of</strong> a living being. However, <strong>the</strong> term<br />

“usually” does not necessarily mean that <strong>the</strong> position <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> head <strong>is</strong> totally due to<br />

past experience, but that <strong>the</strong> head should be structurally located in certain spatial<br />

components and not in o<strong>the</strong>rs in order to show <strong>the</strong> strongest headedness property<br />

necessary to influence at best <strong>the</strong> entire shape.<br />

Against <strong>the</strong> headedness and organic segmentation, it can be argued that <strong>the</strong>se<br />

results are due to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> filled circle behaves or <strong>is</strong> remin<strong>is</strong>cent <strong>of</strong> an<br />

eye, thus eliciting cognitive processes that have nothing to do with <strong>the</strong> shape<br />

formation within <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual domain. The counter-arguments to th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong>sue are<br />

illustrated in <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong> Fig. 20, where <strong>the</strong> positions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> small circle<br />

and <strong>the</strong> different shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accentuation reject th<strong>is</strong> objection in favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

spontaneous organic segmentation as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> shape formation<br />

within <strong>the</strong> perceptual domain and depending on <strong>the</strong> headedness property. Figs.<br />

20f-g shows how different shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner components can create organic<br />

segmentation by putting toge<strong>the</strong>r different wiggly components that create not<br />

only a head within a body but also a face with different components (nose, mouth<br />

and so on).<br />

412


#<br />

1 2<br />

( -<br />

+<br />

413<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

Fig. 20 The positions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> small circle and <strong>the</strong> different shapes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> accentuation change <strong>the</strong><br />

headedness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> undulated figures<br />

It <strong>is</strong> !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$"<br />

worthwhile noticing that th<strong>is</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> segmentation <strong>is</strong> related to those<br />

!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/<br />

previously described, where <strong>the</strong> accentuation popped out some inner meta-shape<br />

attributes. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, like in <strong>the</strong> previous conditions, <strong>the</strong>se attributes can<br />

be spontaneously highlighted through our own gaze and <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> attention<br />

without <strong>the</strong> need <strong>of</strong> external accents. Th<strong>is</strong> free and subjective v<strong>is</strong>ual highlight can<br />

be easily demonstrated in Fig. 19a by switching spontaneously <strong>the</strong> headedness<br />

from one wiggly component to ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>refore addressing <strong>the</strong> organic<br />

segmentation in different ways.<br />

0


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

5.6. The Happening as a Fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Shape</strong> Property<br />

In <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se results, we can now go back to <strong>the</strong> conditions illustrated in<br />

Fig. 1, by reviewing <strong>the</strong> phenomenal notion <strong>of</strong> “happening”. It can, in fact, be<br />

considered as ano<strong>the</strong>r meta-shape attribute among <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Every happening<br />

<strong>is</strong> a d<strong>is</strong>continuity that accentuates one or more properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main shape.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> d<strong>is</strong>continuity gives a meaning to <strong>the</strong> shape in <strong>the</strong> same way as we have<br />

shown in <strong>the</strong> previous sections, or like, for example, in <strong>the</strong> diamond and <strong>the</strong><br />

rotated squares <strong>of</strong> Fig. 15. The m<strong>is</strong>sing portion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> side or <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> angle imparts<br />

different meanings to <strong>the</strong> shape by eliciting a diamond or a rotated square shape.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, in <strong>the</strong> same way as <strong>the</strong> happening (<strong>the</strong> geometrical d<strong>is</strong>continuity)<br />

imparts a meaning to <strong>the</strong> shape, <strong>the</strong> shape imparts a meaning to <strong>the</strong> d<strong>is</strong>continuity.<br />

For instance, <strong>the</strong> object illustrated in Fig. 1c <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a complex kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> shape formation and meaning assignment that we spontaneously define “a<br />

beveled square”. Geometrically, <strong>the</strong>re <strong>is</strong> nei<strong>the</strong>r a “square”, nor a “beveling”, or<br />

an “a” but two vertical, two horizontal and one oblique segment forming a closed<br />

figure with <strong>the</strong> oblique segment placed in <strong>the</strong> top right-hand portion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figure<br />

connecting <strong>the</strong> horizontal and vertical segments, shorter than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two. Th<strong>is</strong><br />

complex geometrical description <strong>is</strong> strongly simplified by giving a v<strong>is</strong>ual meaning<br />

to that shape, i.e. a beveled square. Differently from <strong>the</strong>se phenomenal results,<br />

good continuation, prägnanz and closure principles group <strong>the</strong> sides <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figure<br />

to form a pentagon. The d<strong>is</strong>continuous component, i.e. <strong>the</strong> oblique segment,<br />

gives a meaning to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sides, that become a square, and, at <strong>the</strong> same time,<br />

<strong>the</strong> square assigns a meaning to <strong>the</strong> d<strong>is</strong>continuity that appear like a beveling (see<br />

also Pinna, 2010a, 2010b).<br />

The notion <strong>of</strong> happening also suggests a more interesting aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> shape. <strong>Shape</strong> not only implies boundary contour formation or geometrical<br />

organization like square vs. diamond. It also contains more complex properties<br />

as suggested by Rubin introducing depth and chromatic attributes (see section<br />

1.2). Figs. 1c-i clearly demonstrate that <strong>the</strong>re are also material properties that<br />

can influence and assign different meanings to <strong>the</strong> shape. In fact, when, for<br />

example, it <strong>is</strong> broken, <strong>the</strong> material properties strongly determine its shape. If a<br />

square <strong>is</strong> made up <strong>of</strong> glass, when its shape <strong>is</strong> broken, it will be different from a<br />

square made up <strong>of</strong> pottery or fabric. The shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> break changes according<br />

to <strong>the</strong> material property. Conversely, <strong>the</strong> shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> broken square suggests its<br />

material properties. The beveled square indicates only a small number <strong>of</strong> material<br />

attributes (paper, metal, etc.) and, at <strong>the</strong> same time excludes many o<strong>the</strong>rs. They<br />

are reciprocally determined in <strong>the</strong> same way we have seen in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

diamond and <strong>the</strong> rotated square.<br />

For a more exhaustive analys<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> “happening” see Pinna (2010a,<br />

2010b) and Pinna & Albertazzi (2011).<br />

414


6. D<strong>is</strong>cussion and Conclusions<br />

415<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

In <strong>the</strong> previous sections, following <strong>the</strong> methods traced by <strong>Gestalt</strong> psycholog<strong>is</strong>ts,<br />

we studied <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape perception starting from <strong>the</strong> square/diamond<br />

illusion, which represents a problem for <strong>the</strong> invariant features hypo<strong>the</strong>s<strong>is</strong> and for<br />

any model <strong>of</strong> shape formation. Theories based on <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> frame <strong>of</strong> reference in<br />

determining shape perception were d<strong>is</strong>cussed and largely weakened or refuted in<br />

<strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> a high number <strong>of</strong> new effects, demonstrating <strong>the</strong> basic phenomenal<br />

role <strong>of</strong> inner properties in defining <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se effects, several shape properties were demonstrated. They<br />

are: (i) <strong>the</strong> sidedness and <strong>the</strong> pointedness, related to <strong>the</strong> sides and angles in <strong>the</strong><br />

case <strong>of</strong> squares, diamonds and polygons; (ii) <strong>the</strong> pointing involved mostly in<br />

<strong>the</strong> triangles; (iii) <strong>the</strong> headedness, i.e. <strong>the</strong> appearance like a head <strong>of</strong> a particular<br />

component within an irregular shape, in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a new kind <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual<br />

organization that we called “organic segmentation”; finally, (iv) <strong>the</strong> happening,<br />

i.e. <strong>the</strong> something that happens to a figure. Many o<strong>the</strong>r shape properties remain<br />

to be studied.<br />

These shape properties were demonstrated to underlie <strong>the</strong> whole notion <strong>of</strong> shape<br />

and to appear like second level shape meanings. They can be considered like<br />

transversal or elemental meta-shapes common to a large number <strong>of</strong> shapes both<br />

regular and irregular. They are like meaningful primitives, phenomenally relevant,<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong> shape perception.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> suggests that <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape can be understood on <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> a<br />

multiplicity <strong>of</strong> meta-shape attributes. Therefore, <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> shape can be<br />

phenomenally represented like a whole v<strong>is</strong>ual “thing” that contains a specific set<br />

<strong>of</strong> phenomenal primitive properties. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> shape can be considered<br />

like <strong>the</strong> holder <strong>of</strong> shape attributes. As a holder it expresses and manifests <strong>the</strong> state<br />

<strong>of</strong> organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner meta-shapes.<br />

Within <strong>the</strong> shape like a holder, <strong>the</strong> shape attributes are not placed all at <strong>the</strong><br />

same height within <strong>the</strong> gradient <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility, i.e. some emerge more strongly<br />

than o<strong>the</strong>rs depending on a number <strong>of</strong> factors that can influence <strong>the</strong>ir vividness<br />

and thus <strong>the</strong>ir v<strong>is</strong>ibility. Among <strong>the</strong>m, we studied some known factors like <strong>the</strong><br />

horizontal/vertical axes, <strong>the</strong> gravitational orientation, <strong>the</strong> configural orientation<br />

and <strong>the</strong> large reference frame. We also demonstrated <strong>the</strong>ir limits and showed <strong>the</strong><br />

reason <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir effectiveness under specific conditions. Within <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>s<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> shape like a holder, <strong>the</strong>ir effectiveness depends on <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> one<br />

specific meta-shape attribute. Therefore, in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a square, <strong>the</strong> horizontal/<br />

vertical organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sides accentuates <strong>the</strong> sidedness, while in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> diamond <strong>the</strong> pointedness <strong>is</strong> accentuated by <strong>the</strong> same factor. Th<strong>is</strong> entails that<br />

a rotated square <strong>is</strong> perceived when <strong>the</strong> sidedness <strong>is</strong> stronger than <strong>the</strong> pointedness;<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rw<strong>is</strong>e we would have perceived a rotated diamond.


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> suggests that all <strong>the</strong> shape attributes are present at <strong>the</strong> same time but some<br />

or only one emerges, due to specific factors, as <strong>the</strong> winner that imparts <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

meaning to <strong>the</strong> shape. It follows that <strong>the</strong> shape attributes can compete and<br />

cooperate and, above all, <strong>the</strong>y are all present at <strong>the</strong> same time, placed along <strong>the</strong><br />

gradient <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility and in a dynamic state <strong>of</strong> equilibrium that can be changed by<br />

accentuating <strong>the</strong> opposite or competing attribute. Several ways to accentuate <strong>the</strong><br />

shape attributes were demonstrated in most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> figures illustrated. It was also<br />

demonstrated that <strong>the</strong> accentuation operates like Euclidean vectors.<br />

The organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape attributes can create conditions <strong>of</strong> singularity<br />

where one specific attribute emerges much more than o<strong>the</strong>rs. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> case<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> square <strong>of</strong> Fig. 2a and <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> diamond <strong>of</strong> 2c. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong><br />

perceived shape manifests a unique and a special meaning similar to <strong>the</strong> one<br />

assumed by <strong>the</strong> term “Prägnanz” within <strong>the</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong> literature. Th<strong>is</strong> term was<br />

related to a special phenomenal property belonging to certain gestalts but not to<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs. Th<strong>is</strong> property makes some objects appear as unique, preferred, singular<br />

and d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>hed (Ausgezeichnet). Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> circle and <strong>the</strong> square<br />

(Metzger, 1963; 1975a; 1975b; Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, 1912a; 1912b; 1922, 1923).<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer (1923) introduced a second interesting meaning, aimed at describing<br />

not only a property but also a process: Prägnanz refers to a process bringing to a<br />

stable result and with <strong>the</strong> maximum <strong>of</strong> equilibrium. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> Prägnanz<br />

as a grouping principle (see also Metzger, 1963) directed to create <strong>the</strong> best <strong>Gestalt</strong><br />

(Tendenz zur Resultierung in guter <strong>Gestalt</strong>; gute Fortsetzung) with an inner necessity<br />

and with <strong>the</strong> minimum <strong>of</strong> requiredness (innere Notwendigkeit, Köhler, 1938). As<br />

regards <strong>the</strong> need to d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>h between <strong>the</strong> two meanings see Hüppe (1984) and<br />

Kanizsa and Luccio (1986, 1989). The third meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “Prägnanz”<br />

<strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> most controversial and states that Prägnanz refers to self-organization<br />

processes aimed at <strong>the</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> an ordered, singular (Einzigartigkeit), and<br />

d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>hed (Ausgezeichnet) outcome (Goldmeier, 1937; Köhler, 1920; Metzger,<br />

1963; 1982; Rausch, 1952, 1966; Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, 1912a, 1912b, 1922).<br />

For an interesting d<strong>is</strong>cussion on <strong>the</strong> meanings <strong>of</strong> Prägnanz see Kanizsa (1975,<br />

1991) and Kanizsa & Luccio (1986, 1989), who criticized and rejected <strong>the</strong> third<br />

meaning as part <strong>of</strong> perception and suggested d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>hing sharply <strong>the</strong> first two<br />

meanings to avoid any possible confusion. Pinna (1993, 1996, 2005) introduced<br />

a fourth meaning going beyond and solving Kanizsa and Luccio’s critiques to <strong>the</strong><br />

third meaning. It states that a tendency toward Prägnanz does not necessarily<br />

concern <strong>the</strong> modal realization <strong>of</strong> a singular perceptual result but it usually implies<br />

<strong>the</strong> amodal formation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most d<strong>is</strong>tingu<strong>is</strong>hed and singular result (amodal<br />

prägnanz).<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> idea <strong>is</strong> in agreement with <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape introduced in th<strong>is</strong> work. In<br />

fact, <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> a rotated square implies <strong>the</strong> amodal prägnanz. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> all<br />

416


417<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

<strong>the</strong> more reason for <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> happening. In fact, in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beveled<br />

square, <strong>the</strong> square appears as <strong>the</strong> amodal whole object and <strong>the</strong> beveling as <strong>the</strong><br />

modal part <strong>of</strong> it. The square <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> amodal wholeness completion <strong>of</strong><br />

something perceived as its v<strong>is</strong>ible modal portion. The square <strong>is</strong> perceived and not<br />

perceived at <strong>the</strong> same time and its amodal whole completion occurs “beyond” <strong>the</strong><br />

beveling. Th<strong>is</strong> implies that <strong>the</strong> amodal completion can be considered as a subset<br />

or as an instance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> more general problem <strong>of</strong> amodal wholeness. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> beveled square, <strong>the</strong> amodal wholeness corresponds to <strong>the</strong> amodal prägnanz.<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> suggests that every shape manifests an ideal condition where one meta-shape<br />

attribute emerges much more than o<strong>the</strong>rs. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, each shape indicates<br />

amodally its starting or converging point <strong>of</strong> singularity. Therefore, we are able to<br />

perceive how a figure can be changed or accentuated to obtain <strong>the</strong> best condition<br />

under which <strong>the</strong> shape becomes a singularity. It <strong>is</strong> worthwhile noticing that, on<br />

<strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> our results, <strong>the</strong> gradient <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shape attributes indicates<br />

that, when one attribute emerges, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs remain inv<strong>is</strong>ible or in a second plane<br />

<strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ibility.<br />

In conclusion, <strong>the</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> shape, here suggested, allows its extension to<br />

conditions never included in <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> shape so far. They are, for example,<br />

<strong>the</strong> material properties, previously considered as shape attributes (see section<br />

5.6), but also figures like those illustrated in Fig. 21, known as “Maluma-Takete”<br />

(Köhler, 1929, 1947; see also Ramachandran & Hubbard; 2001), where two<br />

opposite attributes are perceived, curviness and pointedness, and where a large<br />

set <strong>of</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r opposite properties – smoothness and sharpness, jaggedness and<br />

roundedness – are related to <strong>the</strong>se ones.<br />

Fig. 21 Maluma and Takete


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Summary<br />

The aim <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> work <strong>is</strong> to answer <strong>the</strong> following questions: what <strong>is</strong> shape? <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> its<br />

meaning? <strong>Shape</strong> perception and its meaning were studied starting from <strong>the</strong> square/<br />

diamond illusion and according to <strong>the</strong> phenomenological approach traced by gestalt<br />

psycholog<strong>is</strong>ts. The role <strong>of</strong> frame <strong>of</strong> reference in determining shape perception was<br />

d<strong>is</strong>cussed and largely weakened or refuted in <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> a high number <strong>of</strong> new effects,<br />

based on some phenomenal meta-shape properties useful and necessary to define <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> shape. The new effects studied are based on <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> following<br />

meta-shape attributes: sidedness and pointedness (in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> squares, diamonds<br />

and polygons); <strong>the</strong> pointing (in <strong>the</strong> triangles); <strong>the</strong> headedness (in irregular shapes); <strong>the</strong><br />

happening (in deformed shapes), i.e. <strong>the</strong> something that happens to a figure. Every<br />

happening <strong>is</strong> a d<strong>is</strong>continuity that accentuates one or more properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> main shape<br />

and gives a meaning to <strong>the</strong> shape.<br />

The phenomenal results demonstrated that <strong>the</strong> accentuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> meta-shape properties<br />

operates like Euclidean vectors. On <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se results we suggested that <strong>the</strong> meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> shape could be understood on <strong>the</strong> bas<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> meta-shape attributes<br />

that operate like meaningful primitives <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> complex language <strong>of</strong> shape perception.<br />

Therefore, <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> shape can be represented like a whole v<strong>is</strong>ual “thing/holder” that<br />

contains a specific organized set <strong>of</strong> phenomenal primitive properties, i.e. <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong><br />

organization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner meta-shapes.<br />

Keywords: <strong>Shape</strong> perception, <strong>Gestalt</strong> psychology, perceptual organization, v<strong>is</strong>ual<br />

meaning, v<strong>is</strong>ual illusions.<br />

Zusammenfassung<br />

Ziel der vorliegenden Arbeit <strong>is</strong>t die Beantwortung folgender Fragen: Was <strong>is</strong>t Form<br />

und was <strong>is</strong>t deren Bedeutung? Die Wahrnehmung von Form und Bedeutung wurde<br />

erstmals anhand einer Quadrat-Rauten-Täuschung (Pinna) mit Hilfe der von der<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong>psychologie entwickelten phänomenolog<strong>is</strong>chen Methode untersucht. Die<br />

Rolle des Bezugssystems für die Wahrnehmung einer Form wird d<strong>is</strong>kutiert, jedoch<br />

angesichts zahlreicher neuer Effekte größtenteils herabgestuft oder gar widerlegt. Diese<br />

neuen Effekte gehen auf einige für die Definition der Form-Bedeutung förderliche<br />

und notwendige phänomenale Meta-Form-Eigenschaften zurück. Sie beruhen auf der<br />

Akzentuierung folgender Eigenschaften: anschauliche Erstreckung von Kanten und<br />

Ecken (im Fall von Quadraten, Rauten und Polygonen); anschauliche Ausrichtung (bei<br />

Dreiecken); anschauliche Gerichte<strong>the</strong>it (bei unregelmäßigen Formen); Bezogenheit auf<br />

ein dynam<strong>is</strong>ches Ereign<strong>is</strong> (bei deformierten Formen), also auf das Etwas, das mit einer<br />

Form geschieht. Jedes Ereign<strong>is</strong> stellt eine Störung dar, die eine oder mehrere (implizite)<br />

Eigenschaften der zugrunde liegenden Form <strong>is</strong>oliert und verstärkt und dadurch der Form<br />

eine Bedeutung zuwe<strong>is</strong>t.<br />

Die Beobachtungen zeigen, dass die Meta-Form-Eigenschaften sich wie euklid<strong>is</strong>che<br />

Vektoren verhalten. Aufgrund der Ergebn<strong>is</strong>se vertreten wir die Auffassung, dass man die<br />

Bedeutung einer Form auf der Grundlage einer Vielzahl von Meta-Form-Eigenschaften<br />

verstehen kann, die sich ihrerseits wie bedeutungshaltige Primitiva der komplexen Sprache<br />

der Formwahrnehmung verhalten. Der Begriff der Form kann daher wie ein hol<strong>is</strong>t<strong>is</strong>cher<br />

“Ding-Träger” aufgefasst werden, der eine spezif<strong>is</strong>ch organ<strong>is</strong>ierte Anzahl grundlegender<br />

418


419<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

phänomenaler Eigenschaften enthält, nämlich den Zustand der Organ<strong>is</strong>ation der inneren<br />

Meta-Formen.<br />

Schlüsselwörter: Formwahrnehmung, <strong>Gestalt</strong>psychologie, Wahrnehmungsorgan<strong>is</strong>ation,<br />

v<strong>is</strong>uelle Bedeutung, Wahrnehmungstäuschung.<br />

References<br />

Antonucci, G., Fanzon, D., Spinelli, D., & Zoccolotti, P. (1995): V<strong>is</strong>ual factors affecting <strong>the</strong> rod- and-frame<br />

illusion: <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> gap size and frame components. Perception, 24, 1119-1130.<br />

Asch, S. E, & Witkin, H. A. (1948a): Studies in space orientation: I. Perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> upright with d<strong>is</strong>placed<br />

v<strong>is</strong>ual fields. Journal <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology 38, 325-337.<br />

Asch, S. E., & Witkin, H. A. (1948b): Studies in space orientation: II. Perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> upright with d<strong>is</strong>placed<br />

v<strong>is</strong>ual fields and with body tilted. Journal <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology 38, 455-477.<br />

Attneave, F. (1968). Triangles as ambiguous figures. American Journal <strong>of</strong> Psychology 81, 447-453.<br />

Clément, G., & Bukley, A. (2008): Mach’s square-or-diamond phenomenon in microgravity during parabolic<br />

flight. Neuroscience Letters 447, 179-182.<br />

Davi, M., & Pr<strong>of</strong>fit, D.R. (1993): Frames <strong>of</strong> reference and d<strong>is</strong>tinctive figural character<strong>is</strong>tics affect shape perception.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 19, 867-877.<br />

Gibson, J.J. (1937): Adaptation, after-effect and contrast in <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> tilted lines: II. Simultaneopus<br />

contrast and <strong>the</strong> areal restriction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> after-effect. Journal <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology 20, 553-569.<br />

Goldmeier, E. (1937): Über Ähnlichkeit bei gesehenen figuren. Psycholog<strong>is</strong>che Forschung 4, 146-208.<br />

H<strong>of</strong>fman, D.D., & Richards, W.A. (1984): Parts <strong>of</strong> recognition. Cognition 18, 65-96.<br />

Huppe, A., (1984): Prägnanz. Ein gestalt<strong>the</strong>oret<strong>is</strong>cher Grund-begriff. Munchen, Pr<strong>of</strong>il Verlag.<br />

Kanizsa, G. (1975): The role <strong>of</strong> regularity in perceptual organization. In Flores D’Arca<strong>is</strong>, G.B (eds.), Studies in<br />

Perception, Festschrift for Fabio Metelli, Firenze, Giunti-Martello, 48-66.<br />

Kanizsa, G. (1980): Grammatica del vedere. Bologna, Il Mulino.<br />

Kanizsa, G. (1985): Seeing and thinking. Acta Psycologica 59, 23-33.<br />

Kanizsa, G. (1991): Vedere e pensare. Bologna, Il Mulino.<br />

Kanizsa, G., & Luccio, R. (1986): Die Doppoldeutigkeiten der Prägnanz. <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> 8, 99-135.<br />

Kanizsa, G., & Luccio, R. (1989): Fenomenologia della formazione di un ordine autonomo della percezione.<br />

Riv<strong>is</strong>ta di Psicologia 3, 28-46.<br />

K<strong>of</strong>fka, K. (1935): Principles <strong>of</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong> Psychology. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, UK.<br />

Köhler, W. (1920): Die phys<strong>is</strong>chen <strong>Gestalt</strong>en in Ruhe und im stationären Zustand. Eine naturphilosoph<strong>is</strong>che<br />

Untersuchung. Vieweg, Braunschweig.<br />

Köhler, W. (1929): <strong>Gestalt</strong> Psychology. New York: Liveright.<br />

Köhler, W. (1938): The place <strong>of</strong> value in a world <strong>of</strong> facts. New York, Liveright.<br />

Köhler, W. (1947): <strong>Gestalt</strong> Psychology, 2nd Ed. New York: Liveright.<br />

Kopfermann, H. (1930): Psycholog<strong>is</strong>che Untersuchungen über die Wirkung zweidimensionaler Darstellungen<br />

körperlicher Gebilde. Psycholog<strong>is</strong>che Forschung 13, 293-364.<br />

Mach, E. (1914/1959): The Analys<strong>is</strong> <strong>of</strong> Sensation. Chicago, Open Court USA.<br />

Marr, D., & N<strong>is</strong>hihara, H. K. (1978): Representation and recognition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spatial organization<br />

<strong>of</strong> three-dimensional shapes. Proceedings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Royal Society <strong>of</strong> London 200, 269-294.<br />

Metzger, W. (1941): Psychologie: die Entwicklung ihrer Grundannhamen seit der Einführung des Experiments.<br />

Dresden, Steinkopff.<br />

Metzger, W. (1963): Psychologie. Darmstadt, Steinkopff Verlag.<br />

Metzger, W. (1975a): Gesetze des Sehens. Kramer, Frankfurt-am-Main.<br />

Metzger, W. (1975b): Die Entdeckung der Prägnanztendenz. Die Anfänge einer nicht-atom<strong>is</strong>t<strong>is</strong>chen Wahrnehmungslehre.<br />

In Flores D’Arca<strong>is</strong>, G.B (eds.), Studies in Perception, Festschrift for Fabio Metelli, Firenze,<br />

Giunti-Martello, 3-47.<br />

Metzger, W. (1982): Möglichkeiten der Verallgemeinerung des Prägnanzprinzips. <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> 4, 3-22.<br />

Nakayama, K., & Shimojo, S. (1990): Towards a neural understanding <strong>of</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual surface representation. Cold<br />

Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology LV, 911-924.<br />

Palmer, S. E. (1975a): The effects <strong>of</strong> contextual scenes on <strong>the</strong> identification <strong>of</strong> objects. Memory & Cognition<br />

3(5), 519-526.<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1975b): V<strong>is</strong>ual perception and world knowledge: Notes on a model <strong>of</strong> sensory-cognitive interaction.<br />

In D. A. Norman & D. E. Rumelhart (Eds.), Explorations in cognition, 279-307. San Franc<strong>is</strong>co: W.<br />

H. Freeman.


GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1980): <strong>What</strong> makes triangles point: Local and global effects in configurations <strong>of</strong> ambiguous triangles.<br />

Cognitive Psychology 12, 285-305.<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1983): The psychology <strong>of</strong> perceptual organization: A transformational approach. In J. Beck, B.<br />

Hope, & A. Baddeley (Eds.), Human and machine v<strong>is</strong>ion, 269-339. New York: Academic Press.<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1985): The role <strong>of</strong> symmetry in shape perception. Special Issue: Seeing and knowing. Acta Psychologica<br />

59(1), 67-90.<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1989): Reference frames in <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> shape and orientation. In B. E. Shepp & S. Ballesteros<br />

(Eds.), Object perception: Structure and process, 121-163. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Palmer, S.E. (1999): V<strong>is</strong>ion Science: photons to phenomenology, Cambridge, Massachusetts, London, England,<br />

The MIT press.<br />

Palmer, S.E., & Bucher, N.M. (1981): Textural effect in perceiving pointing <strong>of</strong> ambiguous triangle. Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance 8(5), 693-708.<br />

Pinna, B. (1993): La creatività del vedere: verso una Psicologia Integrale. Padova, Domenighini Editore.<br />

Pinna, B. (1996): La percezione delle qualità emergenti: una conferma della ”tendenza alla pregnanza”. In<br />

Boscolo P., Cr<strong>is</strong>tante F., Dell’Antonio A. e Soresi S., (eds.), Aspetti qualitativi e quantitativi nella ricerca<br />

psicologica, Padova, Il Poligrafo, 261-276.<br />

Pinna, B. (2005): Riflessioni fenomenologiche sulla percezione delle qualità emergenti: verso una riconsiderazione<br />

critica della teoria della Pregnanza. Annali della Facoltà di Lingue e Letterature Straniere dell’Università<br />

di Sassari 3, 211-256.<br />

Pinna, B. (2010a): <strong>What</strong> Comes Before Psychophysics? The Problem <strong>of</strong> ‘<strong>What</strong> We Perceive’ and <strong>the</strong> Phenomenological<br />

Exploration <strong>of</strong> New Effects. Seeing & Perceiving 23, 463-481.<br />

Pinna, B. (2010b): New <strong>Gestalt</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> perceptual organization: An extension from grouping to shape and<br />

meaning. <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> 32, 1-67.<br />

Pinna, B., & Albertazzi, L. (2011): From grouping to v<strong>is</strong>ual meanings: A new <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> perceptual organization,<br />

288-344. In L. Albertazzi, G. van Tonder, D. V<strong>is</strong>hwanath, (eds.), Information in Perception, MIT Press.<br />

Pinna, B., & Reeves, A. (2009): From Perception to art: How <strong>the</strong> brain creates meanings. Spatial V<strong>is</strong>ion 22,<br />

225-272.<br />

Pinna, B., & Sirigu, L. (in press): The Accentuation Principle <strong>of</strong> V<strong>is</strong>ual Organization and <strong>the</strong> Illusion <strong>of</strong> Musical<br />

Suspension. Seeing & Perceiving.<br />

Pizlo, Z. (2008): 3D shape: its unique place in v<strong>is</strong>ual perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Ramachandran, V.S., & Hubbard, E.M. (2001): Synaes<strong>the</strong>sia: A window into perception, thought and language.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies 8(12), 3-34.<br />

Rausch, E. (1952): Struktur und Metrik figural-opt<strong>is</strong>cher Wahrnehmung. Frankfurt, Kramer.<br />

Rausch, E. (1966): Das Eigenschaftsproblem in der <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie der Wahrnehmung. In W. Metzger, & H.<br />

Erke (hrsg.), Wahrnehmung und Bewußtsein, “Handbuch der Psychologie”, Bd 1/1, 866-951, Hogrefe,<br />

Göttingen.<br />

Rock, I. (1973): Orientation and form. New York: Academic Press.<br />

Rock, I. (1983): The logic <strong>of</strong> perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Rubin, E. (1915): Synsoplevede Figurer. Kobenhavn, Glydendalske Boghandel.<br />

Rubin, E. (1921): V<strong>is</strong>uell wahrgenommene Figuren. Kobenhavn, Gyldendalske Boghandel.<br />

Schumann, F. (1900): Beiträge zur Analyse der Gesichtswahrnehmungen. Zur Schätzung räumlicher Grössen.<br />

Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnersorgane 24, 1-33.<br />

Spillmann, L. (Eds.) (in press): Max Wer<strong>the</strong>imer: On Motion and Figure-Ground Organization. MIT Press.<br />

Spillmann, L., & Ehrenstein, W.H. (2004): <strong>Gestalt</strong> factors in <strong>the</strong> v<strong>is</strong>ual neurosciences. In L. Chalupa & J. S.<br />

Werner (eds.). The V<strong>is</strong>ual Neurosciences. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1573-1589.<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, M. (1912a): Über das Denken der Naturvölker. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 60, 321-378.<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, M. (1912b):Untersuchungen über das Sehen von Bewegung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 61, 161-<br />

265.<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, M. (1922): Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der <strong>Gestalt</strong>. I. Psycholog<strong>is</strong>che Forschung 1, 47-58.<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, M. (1923): Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der <strong>Gestalt</strong> II. Psycholog<strong>is</strong>che Forschung 4, 301-350.<br />

Witkin, H.A., & Asch, S.E. (1948): Studies in space orientation, IV. Fur<strong>the</strong>r experiments on perception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

upright with d<strong>is</strong>placed v<strong>is</strong>ual fields. Journal <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology 38, 762-782.<br />

420


421<br />

Pinna, <strong>What</strong> <strong>is</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Meaning</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Shape</strong>?<br />

Acknowledgments<br />

Supported by Finanziamento della Regione Autonoma della Sardegna, ai sensi della L.R. 7 agosto 2007, n. 7,<br />

Fondo d’Ateneo (ex 60%) and Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.<br />

Baingio Pinna, born 1962, since 2002 Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology and V<strong>is</strong>ual Perception at<br />

<strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Sassari. 2001/02 Research Fellow at <strong>the</strong> Alexander Humboldt Foundation, Freiburg,<br />

Germany. 2007 winner <strong>of</strong> a scientific productivity prize at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Sassari, 2009 winner <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

International “Wolfgang Metzger Award to eminent people in <strong>Gestalt</strong> science and research for outstanding<br />

achievements”. H<strong>is</strong> main resaerch interests concern <strong>Gestalt</strong> psychology, v<strong>is</strong>ual illusions, psychophysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> shape, motion, color and light, and v<strong>is</strong>ion science <strong>of</strong> art.<br />

Address: Facoltà di Lingue e Letterature Straniere, Dipartimento di Scienze dei Linguaggi, University <strong>of</strong><br />

Sassari, via Roma 151, I-07100 Sassari, Italy.<br />

E-Mail: baingio@un<strong>is</strong>s.it


Announcements - Ankündigungen<br />

On <strong>the</strong> occasion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 100 th anniversary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pivotal publication by<br />

Max Wer<strong>the</strong>imer on <strong>the</strong> phi-phenomenon in 1912,<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer’s symposium<br />

at <strong>the</strong> convention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Society <strong>of</strong> Psychology<br />

Bielefeld, 24 th to 27 th September 2012<br />

will take place.<br />

The symposium will be hosted by Viktor Sarr<strong>is</strong> (University <strong>of</strong> Frankfurt)<br />

and Horst Gundlach (University <strong>of</strong> Würzburg) in cooperation with <strong>the</strong> GTA<br />

– Society for <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory and its applications.<br />

The preliminary agenda contains contributions by Michael Wer<strong>the</strong>imer<br />

(University <strong>of</strong> Colorado at Boulder), Lothar Spillmann (Neurocentrum,<br />

University medical center Freiburg), Riccardo Luccio (University <strong>of</strong> Trieste),<br />

and Jürgen Kriz (University <strong>of</strong> Osnabrück).<br />

eeeee<br />

Aus Anlass des 100jährigen Jubiläums der entscheidenden Publikation<br />

von Max Wer<strong>the</strong>imer zum Phi-Phänomen im Jahre 1912 findet ein<br />

Wer<strong>the</strong>imer-Symposium<br />

auf dem Kongress der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Psychologie<br />

Bielefeld, 24. – 27. September 2012<br />

statt.<br />

Das Symposium wird in Kooperation mit der GTA - Gesellschaft für<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie und ihre Anwendungen, von Viktor Sarr<strong>is</strong> (Universität<br />

Frankfurt) und Horst Gundlach (Universität Würzburg) veranstaltet.<br />

Vorgesehen sind Beiträge von Michael Wer<strong>the</strong>imer (University <strong>of</strong> Colorado<br />

at Boulder), Lothar Spillmann (Neurocentrum, Universitätsklinikum<br />

Freiburg), Riccardo Luccio (University <strong>of</strong> Trieste) und Jürgen Kriz<br />

(Universität Osnabrück).<br />

422


GTA – Symposium<br />

Helsinki<br />

29. September 2012<br />

In <strong>the</strong> anniversary year <strong>of</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong>, <strong>the</strong> GTA – Society for <strong>Gestalt</strong><br />

<strong>Theory</strong> and its Applications – hosts a scientific symposium in Finland for<br />

<strong>the</strong> first time.<br />

Interacting with Finn<strong>is</strong>h academics, various topics focusing on <strong>Gestalt</strong><br />

<strong>Theory</strong> will be covered.<br />

Contributions on <strong>the</strong> following topics are planned: <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> -<br />

H<strong>is</strong>tory and Modern, <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> in Finland, <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> in Art and<br />

Culture, <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> in Education, <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> in Psycho<strong>the</strong>rapy,<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> and Design.<br />

eeeee<br />

Im Jubiläumsjahr der <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie veranstaltet die GTA - Gesellschaft für<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie und ihre Anwendungen, erstmals ein w<strong>is</strong>senschaftliches<br />

Symposium in Finnland.<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>oret<strong>is</strong>che Schwerpunkte aus verschiedenen Themenbereichen<br />

werden in Interaktion mit finn<strong>is</strong>chen W<strong>is</strong>senschaftlern behandelt.<br />

Geplant sind Beiträge u.a. zu folgenden Themen:<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie - Geschichte und Aktualität, <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie in Finnland,<br />

<strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie in Kunst und Kultur, <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie in Bildung und<br />

Erziehung, <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>oret<strong>is</strong>che Psycho<strong>the</strong>rapie, <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie und<br />

Design.<br />

423


The International<br />

SOCIETY FOR GESTALT THEORY AND ITS APPLICATIONS<br />

invites subm<strong>is</strong>sions for <strong>the</strong><br />

WOLFGANG METZGER AWARD 2013<br />

Th<strong>is</strong> award <strong>is</strong> named after Wolfgang Metzger, a student <strong>of</strong> Max Wer<strong>the</strong>imer and one <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> leading members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second generation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Berlin <strong>Gestalt</strong> School.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> first period <strong>of</strong> th<strong>is</strong> award it was granted by dec<strong>is</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> board <strong>of</strong> directors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

GTA to eminent people in <strong>Gestalt</strong> science and research for outstanding achievements.<br />

In 1987, <strong>the</strong> award went to Gaetano Kanizsa and Riccardo Luccio (Italy), in 1989 to<br />

Gunnar Johansson (Sweden).<br />

Since 1999 <strong>the</strong> award has been granted every second or third year by <strong>the</strong> board <strong>of</strong><br />

directors <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> GTA based on an international public award contest and a screening<br />

and review <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> submittals by an international scientific Award Committee. The first<br />

prize winners since 1999 were: Giovanni Bruno Vicario, Italy, and Yoshie Kiritani,<br />

Japan; Peter Ulric Tse, USA; Fredrik Sundqv<strong>is</strong>t, Sweden; Cees van Leeuwen, NL/Japan;<br />

Baingio Pinna, Italy.<br />

Applicants for <strong>the</strong> Metzger Award 2013 must submit a scientific paper (in Engl<strong>is</strong>h<br />

or German) inspired by <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory and that contributes to <strong>the</strong> research or <strong>the</strong><br />

application <strong>of</strong> <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory in <strong>the</strong> physical sciences, <strong>the</strong> humanities, <strong>the</strong> social sciences,<br />

<strong>the</strong> economic sciences, or any o<strong>the</strong>r field <strong>of</strong> human studies. Hence, <strong>the</strong> paper could deal<br />

with a subject from psychology, philosophy, medicine, arts, architecture, lingu<strong>is</strong>tics,<br />

musicology or o<strong>the</strong>r fields <strong>of</strong> research or application <strong>of</strong> research as long as it <strong>is</strong> inspired<br />

by a <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical approach.<br />

The first prize winner will receive € 1000, will be invited as <strong>the</strong> award speaker to <strong>the</strong> 18th<br />

international Scientific Convention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> GTA in 2013, and <strong>the</strong> paper will be publ<strong>is</strong>hed<br />

in <strong>the</strong> international multid<strong>is</strong>ciplinary journal <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> (www.gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory.net/<br />

gth/) in <strong>the</strong> submitted version or in an adapted form.<br />

Members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Award Committee for <strong>the</strong> 2013 contest are: Geert-Jan Boudewijnse<br />

(Montreal/Canada; chair), Silvia Bonacchi (Warsaw/Poland), Hellmuth Metz-Göckel<br />

(Dortmund/FRG), Baingio Pinna (Sassari/Italy), Fiorenza Toccafondi (Parma/Italy), N.N.<br />

Submittals for <strong>the</strong> Metzger Award 2013 are due by September 2012.<br />

The subm<strong>is</strong>sion must be sent as a Word or a PDF document to <strong>the</strong> Metzger Award committee<br />

at: metzger-award@gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory.net. More information about <strong>the</strong> international Society<br />

for <strong>Gestalt</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> and its Applications as well as <strong>the</strong> Wolfgang Metzger Award 2013 can<br />

be found on <strong>the</strong> website <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Society: www.gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory. net/<br />

424


Die internationale<br />

GESELLSCHAFT FÜR GESTALTTHEORIE UND IHRE ANWENDUNGEN<br />

lädt ein zu Einreichungen für den<br />

WOLFGANG-METZGER-PREIS 2013<br />

Dieser Pre<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong>t nach Wolfgang Metzger benannt, Schüler von Max Wer<strong>the</strong>imer und<br />

führendem Vertreter der zweiten Generation der Berliner Schule der <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie.<br />

In einer ersten Periode wurde der Pre<strong>is</strong> über Beschluss des Vorstandes der GTA an<br />

verdiente Persönlichkeiten für herausragende Beiträge zur Anwendung der <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie<br />

in W<strong>is</strong>senschaft und Forschung verliehen: 1987 ging der Metzger-Pre<strong>is</strong> in diesem<br />

Sinn an Gaetano Kanizsa und Riccardo Luccio (Italien), 1989 an Gunnar Johansson<br />

(Schweden).<br />

Seit 1999 wird der Pre<strong>is</strong> international öffentlich ausgeschrieben und vom GTA-Vorstand<br />

auf Grundlage der Begutachtungsergebn<strong>is</strong>se und Empfehlungen eines internationalen<br />

w<strong>is</strong>senschaftlichen Pre<strong>is</strong>-Komitees vergeben. Die ersten Pre<strong>is</strong>e gingen sei<strong>the</strong>r an<br />

Giovanni Bruno Vicario (Italien) und Yoshie Kiritani (Japan), Peter Ulric Tse (USA),<br />

Fredrik Sundqv<strong>is</strong>t (Schweden), Cees van Leeuwen (NL/Japan), Baingio Pinna (Italien).<br />

Für Bewerbungen um den Metzger-Pre<strong>is</strong> 2013 <strong>is</strong>t ein w<strong>is</strong>senschaftlicher Beitrag (in<br />

Engl<strong>is</strong>ch oder Deutsch) einzureichen, der zur Überprüfung und Weiterentwicklung<br />

der <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie in Forschung oder Anwendung in den Naturw<strong>is</strong>senschaften,<br />

den Humanw<strong>is</strong>senschaften, den Sozial- und Wirtschaftsw<strong>is</strong>senschaften oder auf<br />

einem anderen Gebiet beiträgt. Einreichungen können also be<strong>is</strong>pielswe<strong>is</strong>e aus der<br />

Psychologie, Philosophie, Medizin, Kunst, Architektur, den Sprachw<strong>is</strong>senschaften, der<br />

Musikw<strong>is</strong>senschaft oder auch aus anderen Fachgebieten kommen, solange sie sich in der<br />

Behandlung ihres Themas kompetent auf die <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie beziehen.<br />

Die Gewinnerin bzw. der Gewinner des Metzger-Pre<strong>is</strong>es 2013 erhält ein Pre<strong>is</strong>geld von<br />

€ 1000 und wird zum Pre<strong>is</strong>trägervortrag bei der 18. internationalen W<strong>is</strong>senschaftlichen<br />

Arbeitstagung der GTA im Jahr 2013 eingeladen. Die eingereichte Arbeit oder der<br />

Pre<strong>is</strong>trägervortrag wird in der internationalen multid<strong>is</strong>ziplinären Zeitschrift <strong>Gestalt</strong><br />

<strong>Theory</strong> (www.gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory.net/gth/) veröffentlicht.<br />

Mitglieder des Metzger-Pre<strong>is</strong>-Komitees 2013 sind: Geert-Jan Boudewijnse (Montreal/<br />

Kanada; Vorsitz), Silvia Bonacchi (Warschau/Polen), Hellmuth Metz-Göckel (Dortmund<br />

/D), Baingio Pinna (Sassari/Italien), Fiorenza Toccafondi (Parma/Italien), N.N.<br />

Einsendeschluss für den Metzger-Pre<strong>is</strong> 2013 <strong>is</strong>t September 2012.<br />

Einreichung als Word- oder PDF-Dokument an das Pre<strong>is</strong>-Komitee: metzger-award@<br />

gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory.net. Weitere Informationen über die GTA und den Wolfgang-Metzger-<br />

Pre<strong>is</strong>: www.gestalt<strong>the</strong>ory.net/<br />

425


<strong>Gestalt</strong>psychologie und Person<br />

Entwicklungen der <strong>Gestalt</strong>psychologie<br />

Herausgegeben von Giuseppe Galli<br />

154 Seiten, € 18,--<br />

ISBN 978 3 901811 43 2<br />

Das vorliegende Buch beschreibt die Beziehungen zw<strong>is</strong>chen <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>orie<br />

und Person und <strong>is</strong>t die Frucht der Arbeit einer Gruppe von Psychologen, die<br />

sich mit folgenden Aspekten der Person befassten: die Person und ihr Ich;<br />

die Person in Aktion; die Person in Beziehung; die Entstehung der Person;<br />

die Person in Dialog; die Person und die Zentrierung. Der hauptsächliche<br />

Zugang zur Untersuchung dieser Aspekte <strong>is</strong>t ein relationaler oder feld<strong>the</strong>oret<strong>is</strong>cher,<br />

dem zufolge die Faktoren, die das Verhalten bestimmen, nicht<br />

nur aus dem innerpersonalen System abgeleitet werden können, sondern<br />

auch von den Beziehungen zw<strong>is</strong>chen Individuum und der konkreten Situation,<br />

in das es eingebettet <strong>is</strong>t, abhängen. In der Person-Umwelt-Beziehung<br />

haben die <strong>Gestalt</strong><strong>the</strong>oretiker besonders die Ausdrucks- und Wesensqualitäten<br />

aufgewertet, die aus dem Objekt-Pol das Ego anzielen. Die Theorie<br />

des psych<strong>is</strong>chen Feldes konnte seine Fruchtbarkeit sowohl in den Untersuchungen<br />

zur Allgemeinen und Sozial-Psychologie zeigen, als auch in jenen<br />

zur Entwicklungspsychologie. In den letzten Jahrzehnten setzte sich das<br />

Feldmodell auch im psychoanalyt<strong>is</strong>chen Umfeld durch.<br />

Das Buch <strong>is</strong>t sowohl für Studierende als auch für Forschende und Therapeuten<br />

von Interesse.<br />

Fax: + 43 1 985 21 19-15 | Mail: verlag@krammerbuch.at

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!