31.12.2013 Views

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

26 The Journal of Law, Economics, 4 Organization, V12N1<br />

variable, but we assume that the parties are risk neutral, so they care only about<br />

the mean level of effort required to produce favorable information and not about<br />

variance in the level of effort. Under these assumptions, the litigants choose<br />

stopping values, {//*, T*\, which satisfy<br />

H* = argmaxf/55 1 - cH/p] such that H > 0, (3a)<br />

T* = argmax[-pS-cT/(l - p)] such that T > 0, (3b)<br />

where c is the cost of flipping and p - (a + H)/(a + b + H + T). For H > 0<br />

and T > 0, this litigation game has a unique 33 Nash equilibrium:<br />

{//*, r} = [-a + P 2 {\ - p)S/c, -b + (\- p) 2 pS/c)<br />

if H* > 0 and T* > 0.<br />

(4a)<br />

The notable thing about this equilibrium is that when both plaintiff and defendant<br />

produce strictly positive amounts of evidence, the estimator used by the<br />

jury is exact—that is,<br />

p* = H*I(H* + T*) = p. (5)<br />

Note that there is no variance to the estimator given by Equation (5). There<br />

is variance in the number of flips required to produce the estimator, but not<br />

in the estimator itself. Thus, when evidence is produced by both sides, the<br />

adversarial process and the naive jury produce a costly but accurate (unbiased<br />

and zero variance) estimate. We say it is "costly" because the litigants throw<br />

away information (unreported flips), but the reported flips are produced in<br />

exactly the "right" proportion.<br />

There are two forces at work here. First is the tendency of the party favored<br />

by the distribution to produce more favorable evidence, due to the lower costs<br />

of doing so. Second, is the tendency of the parties to "free ride" on the prior<br />

beliefs of the jury. When the jury has prior beliefs that favor one party, that<br />

party produces less evidence, which exactly counteracts the effects of the prior<br />

beliefs of the jury. This happens because jury bias lowers the marginal benefit<br />

of flipping, reducing by a the number of heads produced by the plaintiff and<br />

by b the number of tails produced by the defendant. Effectively, the jury's<br />

bias gives a "head start" to one side—it is as if they were endowed with some<br />

free evidence. And in equilibrium, when both parties choose to flip, jury bias<br />

disappears.<br />

Note that this "exactness" result depends explicitly on our characterization<br />

of the unequal costs of producing evidence as a negative binomial experiment.<br />

The litigant favored by the distribution has a lower marginal cost of evidence<br />

the distribution is "learned" as more draws are taken so that the stopping rule is similar to that used<br />

when the distribution is known in advance. For recent review of optimal stopping, see McMillan<br />

and Rothschild (1994).<br />

33. The uniqueness of the equilibrium is proved in the Appendix.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!