31.12.2013 Views

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

Naive, Biased, yet Bayesian: Can Juries Interpret Selectively ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Can</strong> <strong>Juries</strong> <strong>Interpret</strong> Setecttajry Produced Evidence? 267<br />

production, and therefore flips more in equilibrium. The equal marginal costs<br />

of flipping, as opposed to the unequal costs of evidence production, can be<br />

justified by assuming a competitive market for expert coin-flippers. An expert<br />

charging a supracompetitive rate would not attract any clients.<br />

To illustrate the equilibrium, we present a numerical example. Suppose that<br />

the true p equals |, so that the plaintiff is favored by the distribution, and the<br />

jury has a uniform prior over the unknown p, that is, [a = 1, b — 1}. Suppose<br />

further that the amount at risk is $2,000,000, and the cost of flipping is $ 100,000.<br />

In equilibrium the plaintiff reports 1.96 heads, and the defendant reports 0.48<br />

tails. On average, the plaintiff will take 2.94 flips, costing $294,000, and<br />

the defendant 1.44 flips, costing $144,000. The jury's estimate of p is exact:<br />

(1 + 1.96)/(2 + 1.96 + 0.48) = .667.<br />

When p is close to zero, or one, the marginal benefit of flipping is so small<br />

that the party favored by the distribution takes no flips. In this case, the Nash<br />

equilibrium takes the following form, depending upon who decides not to flip:<br />

{//'*, T**) = {-a-b + (l/c)(-ac(l - p)) l/2 ,0) if 7"* < 0 (4b)<br />

= {0, -a - b + (\/c)(bcpS) l/2 } if H* < O.(4c)<br />

The stronger the beliefs of the jury—that is, the larger are {a, b]—the fewer flips<br />

the respective parties take. A party produces no evidence when the bias of the<br />

jury is strong, and when p is near zero or one. In this case the marginal benefit<br />

of flipping is so small, that it is better to not flip at all. When this happens,<br />

the opposing litigant decides to flip more because the reaction functions of the<br />

litigants are upward sloping. The net effect of these changes is to bias the<br />

estimator of the jury toward the prior mean of the jury. Note that although<br />

the estimator is biased, it represents a improvement relative to the no-evidence<br />

case, because it moves the jury's estimator from the prior mean toward the<br />

true p.<br />

The Nash equilibrium is illustrated for all possible p values in three different<br />

cases for S = $2,000,000 and c = $100,000: in Figure 1, [a = 1, b = 1);<br />

Figure 2, {a = 2, b = 1}; and Figure 3, {a = 0, b = 0}. In all three figures,<br />

the true value of p is on the horizontal axis; the top graph plots the number of<br />

heads and tails reported by the litigants; and the bottom graph plots the value<br />

of the jury's estimator relative to the true value of p. In Figure 1, the jury has a<br />

uniform prior over the unknown value of p. In the top graph of Figure 1, when<br />

the value of p is near zero, only the plaintiff flips, and the jury's estimator of<br />

p is biased toward the prior mean. The jury's prior is represented by a dashed<br />

horizontal line. The bias is represented in the bottom graph as a deviation from<br />

the 45 degree line. As p increases, when the defendant begins flipping, the<br />

jury's estimator becomes exact—that is, p* — H*/(H* + T*) = p. As p<br />

approaches one, the plaintiff stops flipping, and the jury's estimator is again<br />

biased toward the prior mean.<br />

The effects of jury bias are illustrated in Figure 2, where the jury's prior

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!