11.03.2014 Views

Narrative Topic and the Contemporary Science Essay ... - JAC Online

Narrative Topic and the Contemporary Science Essay ... - JAC Online

Narrative Topic and the Contemporary Science Essay ... - JAC Online

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

118 Journal of Advanced Composition<br />

What was <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> place of <strong>the</strong> topics in <strong>the</strong>se two very different cultural<br />

conditions, Aristotle's <strong>and</strong> Eiseley's? Aristotle's common <strong>and</strong> special topics<br />

were fashioned to help <strong>the</strong> discourser construct probable arguments for<br />

general audiences. The discourser-intending to persuade ei<strong>the</strong>r a legal,<br />

political, or popular assembly of <strong>the</strong> validity of an enthymeme (not a<br />

syllogism, of course, which was reserved for <strong>the</strong> more philosophical <strong>and</strong><br />

systematic discourse of dialectic )--would move to common topics of degree,<br />

comparison, <strong>and</strong> authority or testimony to support an argument. In what was<br />

still primarily an oral culture, Aristotle needed to convince his students that<br />

oral discourse should be grounded in <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>n new common topics of<br />

abstract thought. Plato <strong>and</strong> Socrates had established <strong>the</strong> situation in which<br />

abstract reasoning-Socrates' pursuits of definitions of justice, wisdom, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ideal state, for example----could hold sway over <strong>the</strong> minds of educated<br />

citizens, even while discourse was delivered orally. Aristotle took <strong>the</strong>se<br />

abstract patterns of thought, made <strong>the</strong>m into common topics, <strong>and</strong> codified<br />

<strong>the</strong>m in a technical or h<strong>and</strong>book rhetoric. The common topics were actually<br />

located in <strong>the</strong> minds of <strong>the</strong> evolving, literate audience, <strong>and</strong> gradually replaced<br />

among <strong>the</strong> educated <strong>the</strong> formulas <strong>and</strong> mythoi of Homeric poetry.<br />

How, <strong>the</strong>n, does this interpretation of <strong>the</strong> conditions existing in Aristotle's<br />

time relate to what I have said earlier about Eiseley <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> narrative topic?<br />

I believe that science essayists such as Eiseley are moving discourse in a<br />

direction opposite to what Aristotle had accomplished in his time. No longer<br />

do educated discoursers need to be reminded of <strong>the</strong> common patterns of<br />

thinking as <strong>the</strong>y write; ra<strong>the</strong>r, in a predominantly literate culture, thinking is<br />

subconsciously controlled <strong>and</strong> organized by established topics. In fact, <strong>the</strong><br />

common topics of Aristotle are in constant friction with <strong>the</strong> more specialized<br />

topics <strong>and</strong> ways of knowing of modem disciplines. The modem identifying<br />

relationship between reader <strong>and</strong> writer is marked by acts of translation in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> special ways of knowing that characterize disciplines are transformed<br />

into <strong>the</strong> educated general reader's intuitive sense of <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

common topics. The science writer knows that <strong>the</strong> minds of readers contain<br />

<strong>the</strong> inductive <strong>and</strong> deductive paradigms of basic scientific method. But writers<br />

such as Eiseley purposely disappoint those paradigmatic expectations in<br />

readers by going to narrative <strong>and</strong> to story forms to add what he would call <strong>the</strong><br />

element of mystery to an o<strong>the</strong>rwise objective process. But <strong>the</strong>se translations<br />

of ways of knowing must be accomplished without destroying or ignoring <strong>the</strong><br />

systematic ways of knowing codified <strong>and</strong> valorized in <strong>the</strong> scientific community.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> "science essay," as Eiseley calls it, must do double-duty: it<br />

must convince readers that scientific precision <strong>and</strong> logic have been maintained<br />

in <strong>the</strong> inquiry upon which <strong>the</strong> essay is based, <strong>and</strong> it must also move <strong>the</strong><br />

reader, through its literariness, to an acceptance of <strong>the</strong> essential incomprehensibility<br />

of nature.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!