15.03.2014 Views

Statutory Interpretation - Judicial Commission of New South Wales

Statutory Interpretation - Judicial Commission of New South Wales

Statutory Interpretation - Judicial Commission of New South Wales

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Principles and pragmatism for a new age<br />

Education Monograph 4


Published in Sydney by the:<br />

<strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>Commission</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong><br />

Level 5, 301 George Street<br />

Sydney NSW 2000<br />

DX 886 Sydney<br />

GPO Box 3634<br />

Sydney NSW 2001<br />

www.judcom.nsw.gov.au<br />

National Library <strong>of</strong> Australia<br />

Cataloguing-in-publication entry<br />

<strong>Statutory</strong> interpretation : principles and pragmatism for a new age.<br />

Includes index.<br />

ISBN 9780731356195<br />

1. <strong>Judicial</strong> process — <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong>. 2. Law — <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong><br />

<strong>Wales</strong> — <strong>Interpretation</strong> and construction. 3. <strong>Judicial</strong><br />

discretion — <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong>. I. Gotsis, Tom. II. Title.<br />

(Series : Educational monograph (<strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>Commission</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong>)).<br />

347.94405<br />

© <strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>Commission</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong> 2007<br />

This publication is copyright. Other than for the purposes <strong>of</strong>, and subject to the conditions prescribed under the<br />

Copyright Act 1968 (Cth), no part <strong>of</strong> it may in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, microcopying,<br />

photocopying, recording or otherwise) be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted without prior<br />

permission. Enquiries should be addressed to the publisher.<br />

The views expressed in this monograph are the views <strong>of</strong> the individual authors and do not represent any<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial views <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Judicial</strong> <strong>Commission</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong>, nor are they necessarily shared by all members<br />

<strong>of</strong> the staff <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Commission</strong>. Whilst all reasonable care has been taken in the preparation <strong>of</strong> this publication,<br />

no liability is assumed for any errors or omissions.<br />

Editor: Tom Gotsis<br />

Graphic design and typesetting: Lorraine Beal<br />

Printed by: Emerald Press


Table <strong>of</strong> contents<br />

Foreword . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . v<br />

Editor’s Note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vii<br />

Statutes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1<br />

The Honourable WMC Gummow AC<br />

Justice <strong>of</strong> the High Court <strong>of</strong> Australia<br />

The Principles <strong>of</strong> Legality and Clear Statement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13<br />

The Honourable JJ Spigelman AC<br />

Chief Justice <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong><br />

The Intent <strong>of</strong> Legislators . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33<br />

The Honourable Justice Keith Mason AC<br />

President, <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong> Court <strong>of</strong> Appeal<br />

The High Court <strong>of</strong> Australia and Modes <strong>of</strong> Constitutional <strong>Interpretation</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45<br />

The Honourable Justice Susan Kenny<br />

Judge <strong>of</strong> the Federal Court <strong>of</strong> Australia<br />

Legislative Drafting and <strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81<br />

Ms Hilary Penfold QC<br />

First Parliamentary Counsel<br />

Commonwealth Office <strong>of</strong> Parliamentary Counsel, 1993–2004<br />

<strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong> in Canada . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Ruth Sullivan<br />

Faculty <strong>of</strong> Law, University <strong>of</strong> Ottawa<br />

Purpose and Context in <strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 127<br />

Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor RS Geddes<br />

School <strong>of</strong> Law, University <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> England<br />

Structuring Purposive <strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 159<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Philip P Frickey<br />

School <strong>of</strong> Law, University <strong>of</strong> California at Berkeley<br />

Saving the Literal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor James C Raymond<br />

Consultant in Legal Writing and Reasoning<br />

Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217<br />

Table <strong>of</strong> Statutes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 225<br />

Table <strong>of</strong> Cases . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229<br />

iii


Foreword<br />

Lawyers are traffickers in words. Words are the vehicle by which the law and legal<br />

relationships must be conveyed. Words are our basic tools <strong>of</strong> trade. Interpreting words<br />

is a large part <strong>of</strong> what we do.<br />

Lawyers, including parliamentary draftsmen, attempt to be as precise and clear as<br />

possible and to anticipate the kinds <strong>of</strong> issues that may arise in the course <strong>of</strong> application<br />

<strong>of</strong> legislation. However, clarity and precision can never be capable <strong>of</strong> complete<br />

achievement, not least because the verbal formulae devised in legislative form <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

have to be stretched to factual situations that no-one could have or did anticipate.<br />

Hence litigation about what words mean. As Lord McMillan once put it:<br />

“One <strong>of</strong> the chief functions <strong>of</strong> our courts is to act as an animated and authoritative dictionary.” 1<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the difficulties is, <strong>of</strong> course, the richness <strong>of</strong> our language which gives rise to<br />

ambiguity, indeterminacy or inexplicitness. In English, as in French, in the words <strong>of</strong><br />

Joseph Joubert:<br />

“Words are like eyeglasses, they blur everything which they do not make more clear.” 2<br />

Over the last two or three decades there appears to have been a paradigm shift in all<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> legal texts, including constitutional, statutory and contractual<br />

interpretation. The shift is from text to context. Literal interpretation — a focus on<br />

the plain or ordinary meaning <strong>of</strong> particular words — is no longer in vogue. Purposive<br />

interpretation is what we do now!<br />

Of course context was always accepted as significant. Sir Owen Dixon, who many<br />

would place at the literalist end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum <strong>of</strong> judicial approaches to interpretation,<br />

said in 1934:<br />

“The rules <strong>of</strong> interpretation require us to take expressions in their context, and to construe them<br />

with proper regard to the subject matter with which the instrument deals and the object it seeks<br />

to achieve, so as to arrive at the meaning attached to them by those who must use them.” 3<br />

Nevertheless, there does appear to have been a change in the emphasis given to context,<br />

by referring to it in the first instance and not simply after some verbal or grammatical<br />

ambiguity has been identified.<br />

Justice Learned Hand explained the approach now generally applied:<br />

“Of course it is true that the words used, even in their literal sense, are the primary, and ordinarily<br />

the most reliable, sources <strong>of</strong> interpreting the meaning <strong>of</strong> any writing: be it a statute, a contract, or<br />

1 Lord McMillan, Law and Other Things, 1937, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 163.<br />

2 J Joubert, Pensées, 1842, Section 21, Part 15.<br />

3 See R v Wilson; Ex parte Kisch (1934) 52 CLR 234 at 244.


<strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

anything else. But it is one <strong>of</strong> the surest indices <strong>of</strong> a mature and developed jurisprudence not to<br />

make a fortress out <strong>of</strong> the dictionary; but to remember that statutes always have some purpose<br />

or object to accomplish, whose sympathetic and imaginative discovery is the surest guide to their<br />

meaning.” 4<br />

However, as Felix Frankfurter once put it:<br />

“While courts are no longer confined to the language, they are still confined by it. Violence must<br />

not be done to the words chosen by the legislature.” 5<br />

The collection <strong>of</strong> essays in this monograph is a testament to the recognition by judges<br />

and legal scholars <strong>of</strong> the central significance <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation to contemporary<br />

legal practice, including litigation. There is now a widespread acceptance that statutory<br />

interpretation constitutes a distinct body <strong>of</strong> law. As I have said in the paper that is<br />

reprinted herein, many areas <strong>of</strong> law are entirely the creation <strong>of</strong> statute and no area <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law has escaped modification by statute, <strong>of</strong>ten substantial modification. It is perhaps<br />

somewhat ironic that one <strong>of</strong> the areas <strong>of</strong> the law that has been least modified by statute<br />

is the law <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation. Not least for that reason, the principles <strong>of</strong> statutory<br />

interpretation require the kind <strong>of</strong> detailed attention that appears in this monograph.<br />

The Honourable JJ Spigelman AC<br />

Chief Justice <strong>of</strong> <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong><br />

4 Cabell v Markham 148 F 2d 737 at 739 (1945).<br />

5 F Frankfurter, “Some Reflections on the Reading <strong>of</strong> Statutes” (1947) 47 Columbia Law Review 527 at 543.<br />

vi


Editor’s Note<br />

Comparing different societies, past and present, it readily becomes apparent that law is<br />

not static but adapts its form to reflect the social, economic and political characteristics<br />

<strong>of</strong> the particular society in which it operates. 1 In Australia today there are over 1000 Acts<br />

in force in <strong>New</strong> <strong>South</strong> <strong>Wales</strong> alone. 2 Our specialised, information-age society requires<br />

an A–Z set <strong>of</strong> specialised, information-age laws — and statute law is the form <strong>of</strong> law that<br />

has evolved to meet this need. 3<br />

Whether on paper or computer screen, statutes make the will <strong>of</strong> those who govern<br />

indelible. Indelible but inert, like all words, until enlivened when read. <strong>Statutory</strong><br />

interpretation — as opposed to statutory declaration, discovery or divination — is a<br />

term that explicitly alludes to the low-fidelity nature <strong>of</strong> reading and writing. 4 A reader<br />

cannot recreate a writer’s intent with the precision <strong>of</strong> copying a digital computer file; nor<br />

can a writer ensure that any particular form <strong>of</strong> words will perfectly transmit their ideas to<br />

all readers. Reading is an analogue process because words are ambiguous, irreducible<br />

to fixed units <strong>of</strong> meaning. As Justice Mason and Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Raymond explain in their<br />

respective articles, this is why dictionaries can do no more than list the various alternative<br />

meanings <strong>of</strong> a particular word and leave it up to the reader to choose which meaning<br />

is appropriate in any given context. It is the judiciary’s ongoing effort to grapple with<br />

the inherent linguistic ambiguity <strong>of</strong> statutes — a specialised exercise in hermeneutics<br />

— that gives rise to the principles and practice <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation.<br />

It follows that statutory interpretation ultimately endeavours to reduce ambiguity to<br />

background noise, so that meaning becomes discernable. Precisely how this occurs is<br />

examined by the authors <strong>of</strong> the following selected articles. Collecting and juxtaposing<br />

the different perspectives <strong>of</strong>fered by the individual authors — judicial, legislative drafter,<br />

academic, Australian, American, Canadian — adds richness to the insights <strong>of</strong>fered and<br />

provided the rationale for the form <strong>of</strong> this publication.<br />

Justice Gummow draws attention to how, despite much being said in judgments about<br />

purposive interpretation, legislative drafters cannot be released from the requirements <strong>of</strong><br />

precision <strong>of</strong> thought and expression. Purposivism cannot provide determinative answers<br />

1 P Goodrich, Reading the Law, 1986, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, Ch 1 “Ideational and Institutional Sources<br />

<strong>of</strong> Law”.<br />

2 Chief Justice Gleeson has explained that “[i]f you compare the amount <strong>of</strong> legislative output <strong>of</strong> a modern<br />

parliament with the legislative output <strong>of</strong> 100 or 50 years ago, the change is extraordinary.”: “Law is now<br />

too complex for juries to understand”, The Sydney Morning Herald, 26 March 2007.<br />

3 Chief Justice Spigelman has described our time as the “age <strong>of</strong> statutes”, where “no area <strong>of</strong> the law has<br />

escaped statutory modification”: JJ Spigelman, “The Poet’s Rich Resource: Issues in <strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong>”<br />

(2001) 21 Australian Bar Review 224 at 224. Justice Kirby has recently highlighted the importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> statute law by describing the common law as “orbiting around” statute law: MD Kirby, “Precedent Law,<br />

Practice and Trends in Australia” (2007) 28 Australian Bar Review 243 at 251. Kirby J has also recently<br />

said that “we have well and truly entered the age <strong>of</strong> statutes [but] … we still need to wean lawyers from<br />

their love affair with the common law”: “Too Rigid, No Bill <strong>of</strong> Rights: Kirby’s Constitution Verdict”, The<br />

Sydney Morning Herald, 19 March 2007.<br />

4 On the nature <strong>of</strong> language and reading, see S Pinker, The Language Instinct, 1994, Harper Collins, <strong>New</strong> York.<br />

vii


<strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

where different purposes, and perhaps cross-purposes, are apparent. His Honour then<br />

refers to a persisting attitude that statute law is less interesting and less important than<br />

“purely judge-made law”. This attitude, <strong>of</strong> English pedigree, begins in law schools, where<br />

students are plied with cases but graduate with few skills in doing what practitioners<br />

do on a daily basis — reading statutes. But the common law contained both “gross<br />

imperfection” and “grand principles”; and, in the newly federated nations <strong>of</strong> Australia<br />

and the United States, legislation enabled the gross imperfections to be eradicated and<br />

the Parliaments to adapt to ever-changing circumstances, including their citizens’ own<br />

evolving values. Justice Gummow then considers the many ways in which the presence<br />

<strong>of</strong> a written federal constitution influences the form and interpretation <strong>of</strong> statute law.<br />

Chief Justice Spigelman explains that statutory interpretation is not merely a collection<br />

<strong>of</strong> maxims, but properly forms a distinct body <strong>of</strong> law. To a substantial degree, common<br />

law protection <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights and liberties now resides within the law <strong>of</strong> statutory<br />

interpretation. His Honour, after discussing parliamentary intent, context and ambiguity,<br />

focuses on one <strong>of</strong> the most fundamental assumptions <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation — the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> legality. His Honour quotes Lord H<strong>of</strong>fman, who explained:<br />

“The principle <strong>of</strong> legality means that the Parliament must squarely confront what it is doing and<br />

accept the political costs. Fundamental rights cannot be overridden by general or ambiguous<br />

words”.<br />

Chief Justice Spigelman suggests that the test applied by a court to determine whether<br />

a particular statute has subordinated the principle <strong>of</strong> legality should be known as the<br />

clear statement principle. Nevertheless, “[t]he core difficulty remains. Clarity, like beauty,<br />

always involves questions <strong>of</strong> degree and is affected by the eye <strong>of</strong> the beholder.”<br />

His Honour then demonstrates the potential for friction between the principle <strong>of</strong> legality<br />

and the clear statement principle by examining how courts interpret statutes in cases<br />

where what is at stake is the presumption that Parliament does not intend to interfere<br />

with fundamental rights and freedoms.<br />

Justice Mason points out that the judicial experience <strong>of</strong> legislation is bound to be<br />

jaundiced — the easy issues <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation are all resolved before they<br />

proceed to court. Judges may also find legislation challenging because, apart from any<br />

real defects contained in an Act, which <strong>of</strong>ten reflect the realities <strong>of</strong> legislative drafting,<br />

legislation challenges ideas and attitudes that have taken over half a lifetime to learn.<br />

His Honour then describes the distinguishing feature <strong>of</strong> modern Australian drafting as<br />

“fussy”, as opposed to the “fuzzy” style <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> the past or the European civil<br />

system. Fussy law concentrates on detailed distinctions and specific circumstances,<br />

while fuzzy law is expressed in terms <strong>of</strong> general principles and broad legislative<br />

purposes. Judges need to be able to recognise the different styles <strong>of</strong> law and “change<br />

gear” to interpret provisions accordingly. Justice Mason then discusses developments<br />

in specific interpretive techniques, including the use <strong>of</strong> legislative context and purposive<br />

construction, before suggesting that courts can do more to develop the common law<br />

for the age <strong>of</strong> statutes.<br />

viii


Editor’s Note<br />

Justice Kenny discusses statutory interpretation in the context a singularly unique<br />

legislative creation — the Constitution <strong>of</strong> the Commonwealth <strong>of</strong> Australia. Grand<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> constitutional interpretation are eschewed in favour <strong>of</strong> interpretive practices.<br />

Her Honour outlines five interpretive modes — textual, structural, historical, doctrinal<br />

and prudential–ethical — and presents a detailed examination <strong>of</strong> how these modes<br />

determined the High Court’s reasoning in the controversial Work Choices Case.<br />

Understanding the choices each judge had when selecting a particular interpretive<br />

mode is essential to evaluating the High Court’s decision. Indeed, it is in the act <strong>of</strong><br />

choosing between competing interpretive modes that the High Court’s ongoing attempt<br />

to discharge its constitutional mandate is played out.<br />

From her vantage point as Parliamentary Counsel, Hilary Penfold QC provides an<br />

insider’s account <strong>of</strong> the processes involved in drafting legislation, including the sources<br />

<strong>of</strong> legislative change and the preparation <strong>of</strong> explanatory memoranda and second reading<br />

speeches. Ms Penfold then considers the relationship between legislative drafting<br />

and statutory interpretation. In particular, she examines whIch principles <strong>of</strong> statutory<br />

interpretation legislative drafters take seriously and which approaches to statutory<br />

interpretation are irrelevant or unhelpful to the work <strong>of</strong> the legislative drafter. She<br />

concludes by suggesting that Australian legislative drafting processes, although far from<br />

ideal, and despite the inherent ambiguity <strong>of</strong> language, produce legislation good enough<br />

for the interpretive process to start with the premise that “the words mean what they<br />

say.” At least, as she points out, there is only one text to interpret; unlike the decisions<br />

<strong>of</strong> appellate courts, where two, three or even seven independently drafted texts, taken<br />

together, form the law on a particular issue. It is an interesting counterpoint.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Geddes details how, since 1980, Parliaments have made a significant contribution<br />

to statutory interpretation and how courts have become increasingly willing to articulate<br />

the general interpretive principles on which their reasoning is based. After examining<br />

recent legislative and common law developments, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Geddes proposes that:<br />

• legislation is to be interpreted with reference to its underlying purpose and context<br />

(which includes extrinsic material);<br />

• underlying purpose and context are to be considered initially, rather than after it<br />

has been determined that ambiguity exists;<br />

• the task is informed by ss 15AA and 15AB <strong>of</strong> the Acts <strong>Interpretation</strong> Act 1901 (Cth),<br />

and equivalent State provisions, and CIC Insurance Ltd v Bankstown Football Club<br />

Ltd 5 ; and<br />

• presumptions <strong>of</strong> interpretation are to be used but are necessarily overriden by an<br />

interpretation properly informed by purpose and context.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Frickey analyses American purposivism and suggests how it might be relevant to<br />

statutory interpretation under ss 15AA and 15AB <strong>of</strong> the Acts <strong>Interpretation</strong> Act 1901 (Cth)<br />

and State equivalents. He describes the model <strong>of</strong> purposivism set out by Hart and Sacks,<br />

which is based on their assumption that all law — case law and statutes alike — involves<br />

5 (1997) 187 CLR 384 at 408.<br />

ix


<strong>Statutory</strong> <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

a purposive endeavour designed to promote social utility. He also points out that if the<br />

phrase “shall be preferred” in s 15AA is read as “shall be adopted”, then s 15AA appears<br />

to encourage purposivism above all else. However, when s 15AA is read together with<br />

s 15AB, statutory interpretation may appear to accommodate an eclectic weighing <strong>of</strong><br />

interpretive sources — text, purpose, context, canons, intent — rather than being solely<br />

grounded in purposivism. This avoids the various limitations that any interpretive theory,<br />

including purposivism, faces. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Frickey then suggests that — irrespective <strong>of</strong> the<br />

extent to which eclecticism may be accommodated — the purposivism <strong>of</strong> ss 15AA and<br />

15AB should be interpreted as a “legislative invitation to the judiciary to become more <strong>of</strong><br />

a partner in the ongoing elaboration, not just <strong>of</strong> common law, but <strong>of</strong> statutes as well”.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Sullivan provides an overview <strong>of</strong> statutory interpretation in Canada, in light<br />

<strong>of</strong> the long-standing legacy <strong>of</strong> Elmer Driedger, former Deputy Minister <strong>of</strong> Justice and<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Law. Among his many initiatives — which include numerous publications<br />

and establishing a graduate program in legislative drafting — Driedger integrated the<br />

mischief rule, literal rule and golden rule into the “modern principle”. After acknowledging<br />

some <strong>of</strong> its positive effects, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Sullivan critiques the modern principle and its<br />

application by the courts. In particular, she emphasises its own inherent ambiguity.<br />

Canadian courts have used the modern principle to justify every possible approach to<br />

interpretation and even “as a substitute for real justification”. In practice, despite the<br />

rhetoric <strong>of</strong> the modern principle, the Canadian judiciary — even its most doctrinaire<br />

members — adopt a pragmatic approach to interpretation. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Sullivan urges<br />

Australian judges to align rhetoric with reality by rejecting formulaic expressions such<br />

as Driedger’s modern principle and stating plainly the considerations that have led them<br />

to their preferred interpretation.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Raymond analyses decisions <strong>of</strong> the top-tier courts <strong>of</strong> Australia, Canada, <strong>South</strong><br />

Africa and the United States to identify and compare their respective approaches to<br />

statutory interpretation. Like Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Sullivan, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Raymond explores statutory<br />

interpretation in terms <strong>of</strong> rhetoric and reality, and emphasises pragmatism over principle.<br />

Indeed, after meticulously dissecting the diverse interpretive techniques displayed in<br />

the selected cases, he discusses the “s<strong>of</strong>t logic” <strong>of</strong> law in light <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Rhetoric<br />

and AJ Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic. He introduces the Aristotelian idea <strong>of</strong> topes<br />

— patterns <strong>of</strong> s<strong>of</strong>t logic — and suggests that, when reading law, where absolute truth<br />

is unattainable, a choice must be made as to which interpretive technique (tope) to<br />

select. And in cases where alternative interpretive modes are equally available, it is their<br />

respective consequences which distinguish between the merits <strong>of</strong> each mode. Both<br />

statutory interpretation and justice itself are relative exercises.<br />

By analysing the topic from these different perspectives, this monograph <strong>of</strong>fers a detailed<br />

exploration <strong>of</strong> how courts presently engage in statutory interpretation and encourages<br />

ongoing development <strong>of</strong> relevant principles and practice.<br />

Tom Gotsis<br />

Editor

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!