05.10.2014 Views

contraception and the natural law: a recent study - Theological Studies

contraception and the natural law: a recent study - Theological Studies

contraception and the natural law: a recent study - Theological Studies

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CONTRACEPTION AND THE NATURAL LAW:<br />

A RECENT STUDY<br />

Germain Grisez, associate professor of philosophy at Georgetown, married<br />

<strong>and</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r of four, has published an extraordinarily important philosophical<br />

<strong>study</strong> of <strong>the</strong> moral evil of <strong>contraception</strong>. 1 It is not <strong>the</strong> topics treated that<br />

would distinguish <strong>the</strong> <strong>study</strong> from o<strong>the</strong>rs on <strong>the</strong> same subject. In <strong>the</strong> Introduction,<br />

Grisez criticizes <strong>the</strong> increasingly popular attitude among Catholics<br />

that appealing to experience <strong>and</strong> neglecting ethical reasoning would justify<br />

<strong>the</strong> practice of <strong>contraception</strong> under certain circumstances. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side,<br />

he points out <strong>the</strong> inadequacy of many arguments urged against <strong>contraception</strong>,<br />

both those developed along traditional lines <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>recent</strong> "phenomenological"<br />

analyses (chap. 2). Probing more deeply, he outlines two prevalent<br />

but unsound general <strong>the</strong>ories of moral <strong>law</strong> which underlie many of <strong>the</strong><br />

arguments advanced for or against <strong>contraception</strong>. He develops a more adequate<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory of moral <strong>law</strong>, found in <strong>the</strong> later works of Thomas Aquinas<br />

(chap. 3). Applying <strong>the</strong> general principles, he shows why <strong>contraception</strong> is<br />

intrinsically <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore always immoral, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> process makes clear<br />

what is meant here by "<strong>contraception</strong>" (chap. 4). After meeting objections<br />

that concern ra<strong>the</strong>r his general <strong>the</strong>ory of morality (chap. 5), he pinpoints<br />

more concretely what constitutes <strong>contraception</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore makes an act<br />

immoral, <strong>and</strong> under what conditions <strong>the</strong>re could be, not <strong>contraception</strong>, but<br />

mere conception-preventing or conception-avoiding behavior, which might<br />

be permissible or even obligatory (chap. 6). Similarly, any contraceptive use<br />

of drugs is seen as intrinsically immoral (chap. 7), although for some conception-preventing<br />

drugs <strong>the</strong>re is a legitimate use (Appendix). From <strong>the</strong> objective<br />

conditions of morality thus far discussed, he sharply distinguishes <strong>the</strong><br />

question of subjective responsibility <strong>and</strong> morality (chap. 8). In an epilogue<br />

he prophesies a new age of Christian asceticism, when through God's grace,<br />

genuine charity, <strong>and</strong> proper training, perfect chastity will be attained <strong>and</strong><br />

easily maintained both in <strong>and</strong> out of <strong>the</strong> married state. A full-page précis of<br />

<strong>the</strong> book, prepared by <strong>the</strong> author himself, is found in <strong>the</strong> National Catholic<br />

Reporter of April 21,1965, pp. 6 <strong>and</strong> 10. However, no précis will do justice to<br />

his complex <strong>and</strong> nuanced philosophical development nor indicate <strong>the</strong><br />

breadth of his discussion of o<strong>the</strong>r writers on <strong>the</strong> subject, from Aquinas <strong>and</strong><br />

Suárez to de Lestapis, Dupré, Janssens, Van der Marck, Ford, <strong>and</strong> Kelly.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> extraordinary importance of Grisez's <strong>study</strong> does not lie in <strong>the</strong><br />

intelligent <strong>and</strong> thorough way he goes over well-trodden ground, nor in his<br />

1 Germain G. Grisez, Contraception <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Law. Milwaukee: Bruce, 1964.<br />

Pp. xüi + 245. $4.50.<br />

421


422 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES<br />

philosophical proof of his central <strong>the</strong>sis, <strong>the</strong> intrinsic immorality of <strong>contraception</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> his consequent practical conclusions. From this point of view,<br />

he will convince only <strong>the</strong> convinced. As a matter of fact, Grisez with admirable<br />

honesty admits that what he presents falls short of a rigorous philosophical<br />

demonstration. But he renders great service <strong>and</strong> raises enormous hope<br />

by advancing <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> hotly controverted question out of a tenebrous<br />

impasse into an area where <strong>the</strong>re seems finally to be possibility of light.<br />

First of all, <strong>the</strong> general thrust of <strong>the</strong> book meets a deficiency often noted<br />

in <strong>the</strong> controversy: <strong>the</strong> defending or condemning of <strong>contraception</strong> in terms<br />

of principles which are invoked as having universal validity, but whose<br />

consistent use outside <strong>the</strong> case in point seems questionable. As Grisez observes,<br />

those who are defending <strong>the</strong> practice of <strong>contraception</strong> in exceptional<br />

cases generally fail to show how <strong>the</strong> basic principles <strong>the</strong>y use apply in o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

cases, e.g., in <strong>the</strong> moral judgment on homosexuality. Must not exceptions be<br />

permitted here too? On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> principles which are derived from<br />

"conventional <strong>natural</strong>-<strong>law</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory," originating with Suárez, similarly offer<br />

difficulty when one attempts a consistent, universal application. It simply is<br />

not true, <strong>and</strong> no one holds it in practice, that to act <strong>and</strong> yet to prevent <strong>the</strong><br />

attaining of <strong>the</strong> factual <strong>natural</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> act or of <strong>the</strong> corresponding human<br />

faculty is always morally evil. "The many attempts over <strong>the</strong> years to show<br />

<strong>the</strong> intrinsic immorality of <strong>contraception</strong> using this faulty premise have<br />

exposed Catholic moral thought to endless ridicule <strong>and</strong> surely have caused<br />

harm in o<strong>the</strong>r ways" (p. 31). When <strong>the</strong> prevention described above is eo ipso<br />

morally evil—<strong>and</strong> this is <strong>the</strong> case in acts of <strong>the</strong> reproductive faculty—it is<br />

not <strong>the</strong> mere <strong>natural</strong> teleology of <strong>the</strong> act or faculty that grounds <strong>the</strong> violated<br />

moral obligation.<br />

Grisez thus marks out felicitously <strong>the</strong> crucial question: What, in general, can<br />

ground such an obligation that a given kind of external behavior will always<br />

<strong>and</strong> under all circumstances be morally evil? The main opposition to any<br />

unconditional condemnation of <strong>contraception</strong> in terms of <strong>natural</strong> <strong>law</strong> comes<br />

from those who, at least implicitly, answer this more general question negatively:<br />

<strong>natural</strong> reason can find no such obligation. Moreover, Grisez is one<br />

of <strong>the</strong> first to recognize that most of <strong>the</strong> modern attitudes whence arise <strong>the</strong><br />

negative answer, although <strong>the</strong>y differ widely among <strong>the</strong>mselves, represent<br />

a unified trend of thought. He calls <strong>the</strong> trend "situationism," for want of a<br />

better name. "Situation ethics" is but one of its modes, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> trend has<br />

completely infected <strong>the</strong> contemporary "post-Christian" intellectual atmosphere.<br />

It provides a <strong>natural</strong> temptation to Catholics dissatisfied with conventional<br />

<strong>natural</strong>-<strong>law</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. "Situationism" is perhaps a misleading tag,<br />

since <strong>the</strong> situationist, as Grisez describes him, can admit ethical principles


CONTRACEPTION AND THE NATURAL LAW 423<br />

generally applicable to external acts <strong>and</strong> condemning certain given acts as<br />

generally wrong. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> exception, which for <strong>the</strong> situationist is always<br />

possible to any general principle or prohibition, is justified because <strong>the</strong><br />

external action in a concrete situation that is unusual, though not necessarily<br />

unique, objectively calls for a principle higher than <strong>the</strong> one usually applicable.<br />

For, according to situationism, <strong>the</strong> value of anything material lies primarily<br />

in its results, i.e., <strong>the</strong> consequences its realization has for <strong>the</strong> promotion<br />

of <strong>the</strong> truly absolute values. If, <strong>the</strong>refore, a given external action (e.g.,<br />

violation of property) generally has bad effects for <strong>the</strong> absolute values, it is<br />

generally wrong. But it is always possible that in some unusual situation it<br />

will have consequences on <strong>the</strong> whole more conducive to <strong>the</strong> absolute values.<br />

In this case it will be morally right <strong>and</strong> perhaps obligatory. What characterizes<br />

situationism <strong>and</strong> opposes it sharply to Grisez's position is that all external<br />

actions (e.g., masturbation) are judged in this way.<br />

The absolute values, which must be sought unconditionally <strong>and</strong> without<br />

exceptions, are identified differently by <strong>the</strong> different ethical <strong>the</strong>ories of <strong>the</strong><br />

situationist trend, but <strong>the</strong>y are always nonmaterial, subjective, specifically<br />

personal, a certain kind of conscious experience—e.g., pleasure, au<strong>the</strong>nticity,<br />

autonomy, "charity." Procreation as such is only a bodily good <strong>and</strong><br />

hence has value for <strong>the</strong> situationist, not as an absolute ideal, but at best as<br />

<strong>the</strong> necessary condition of absolute human values (e.g., <strong>the</strong> freedom to be<br />

exercised by <strong>the</strong> new person). Procreation, consequently, can be exercised<br />

eventually to a degree sufficient from a moral point of view, when it makes<br />

possible to an extent sufficient in <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>the</strong> realization of <strong>the</strong> absolute<br />

values. When this is done, <strong>the</strong> competition of o<strong>the</strong>r material goods will neutralize<br />

<strong>the</strong> prima-facie claim of procreation to consideration. As a result,<br />

any situationist will permit <strong>contraception</strong>, at least in certain cases. "And,<br />

of course, if a situationist's key value happens to be mutual love, <strong>the</strong>n a<br />

neutralized procreative good which might interfere with sex for sentiment's<br />

sake is not worth a good second thought" (p. 59).<br />

The sounder, more adequate <strong>the</strong>ory of moral <strong>law</strong>, which Grisez prefers to<br />

situationism <strong>and</strong> conventional <strong>natural</strong>-<strong>law</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, indicates a different norm<br />

of moral "ought," namely, <strong>the</strong> principles of practical reason. Since <strong>the</strong> least<br />

condition for human action is that it have some ideal, some intelligible object<br />

towards which it can be directed, reason first <strong>and</strong> most generally prescribes<br />

that good should be pursued, i.e., every good which man can attain by using<br />

his wits <strong>and</strong> his freedom. Since, <strong>the</strong>refore, man must be open to indefinite<br />

development, to <strong>the</strong> totality of human opportunity, <strong>and</strong> since man's basic<br />

tendencies prefigure anything man can achieve, practical reason <strong>the</strong>n prescribes<br />

through specific principles each of <strong>the</strong> objects of <strong>the</strong>se <strong>natural</strong> inclina-


424 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES<br />

tions—e.g., preservation of one's own life, mating <strong>and</strong> raising children, <strong>the</strong><br />

company of o<strong>the</strong>r men, exploring <strong>and</strong> questioning. The primary practical<br />

principles turn what were experienced as mere objects of inclinations into<br />

ideals, intelligible motives, reasons for action, what ought to be.<br />

The basic principles, all affirmative, not only provide general, positive<br />

direction, but <strong>the</strong>y ground definite obligations, positive <strong>and</strong> negative. True,<br />

<strong>the</strong> basic general obligation to pursue an essential human good (e.g., procreation)<br />

does not necessarily bind an individual at a given time or even in his<br />

whole lifetime to contribute toward this particular good. But it does bind<br />

him positively in all practical reasoning to be sensitive to this good (as to all<br />

essential human goods), <strong>and</strong> this sensitivity can in certain circumstances<br />

positively oblige him to action—e.g., when a significant realization of <strong>the</strong><br />

good is in his h<strong>and</strong>s alone <strong>and</strong> he has no good reason for not contributing to<br />

it, or when he has already engaged himself to promote this good. Negatively,<br />

<strong>the</strong> love reason comm<strong>and</strong>s for each of <strong>the</strong> essential goods binds him never<br />

to act directly against <strong>the</strong> realization of any one of <strong>the</strong>m, even if it be for <strong>the</strong><br />

sake of ano<strong>the</strong>r essential <strong>and</strong> greater good. The negative obligation will consequently<br />

prohibit certain external actions as intrinsically immoral under<br />

all <strong>and</strong> any circumstances (what situationism fails to do <strong>and</strong> what conventional<br />

<strong>natural</strong>-<strong>law</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does without adequate basis).<br />

Grisez's Thomistic approach will represent to many, as to this reviewer,<br />

a welcome contribution towards <strong>the</strong> solution of <strong>the</strong> problem, but will also<br />

seem to raise questions that it does not answer. One can well accept from<br />

<strong>the</strong> start that immorality is determined <strong>and</strong> grounded only as violations of<br />

those goods which, each with a certain irreducible value, constitute <strong>the</strong> full<br />

possibilities of man's development. But how does one recognize <strong>and</strong> identify<br />

<strong>the</strong>se goods? The specific principles of reason merely define <strong>the</strong> basic possibilities<br />

man has of carrying out <strong>the</strong> firstprinciple, "Good should be pursued."<br />

Grisez is surprisingly reticent on <strong>the</strong> meaning of reason's primary practical<br />

principle. Is <strong>the</strong> predicate, "should be pursued," formally a creation of reason<br />

(e.g., in a Kantian sense) or is it merely a proportionate response to, i.e.,<br />

recognition of, values, <strong>the</strong> "shoulds" inherent in <strong>the</strong> possibilities such as<br />

those to which man's inclinations will point. Reason's most fundamental<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>, says Grisez, arises from <strong>the</strong> necessity that intelligent action have<br />

an intelligible goal. But what kind of necessity is this? And is <strong>the</strong>re any<br />

reason why <strong>the</strong>re should be intelligent action in <strong>the</strong> firstplace? Grisez's moral<br />

"ought" has <strong>the</strong> air of being ultimately hypo<strong>the</strong>tical, <strong>the</strong> psychological<br />

requirement of man's factual drive to action <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> total fulfilment of<br />

his inclinations (cf., e.g., pp. 61-62, 83). This explains excellently some of<br />

Grisez's subsequent conclusions, but would be acceptable, one fears, to few<br />

ethicians in <strong>the</strong> Christian tradition.


CONTRACEPTION AND THE NATURAL LAW 425<br />

Similarly, <strong>and</strong> more importantly for determining specific obligations, what<br />

is meant by "good," <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> fundamental principle? Grisez objects<br />

to situationism, according to which man should unconditionally pursue only<br />

<strong>the</strong> specifically, consciously personal. But he never defines or explains <strong>the</strong><br />

general, identifying characteristic of all that reason, according to his Thomistic<br />

syn<strong>the</strong>sis, prescribes to be pursued. Perhaps he means by "good" merely<br />

id quod appetitur. One would underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n why each basic, <strong>natural</strong> inclination<br />

of man has to be taken into consideration as automatically prefiguring<br />

a possible basic good of man. But although abnormal inclinations or<br />

<strong>the</strong> inclinations to want more than one's share or <strong>the</strong> instinctive appetites<br />

for sexual <strong>and</strong> sensual satisfaction may not be "basic" <strong>and</strong> "<strong>natural</strong>" (p. 77),<br />

still <strong>the</strong>ir objects seem good in <strong>the</strong> sense of id quod appetitur, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore,<br />

in virtue of reason's most fundamental principle, to be pursued for <strong>the</strong>nown<br />

sake. In o<strong>the</strong>r places (e.g., pp. 58, 71, 72, 77, 94) reason's most general<br />

principle seems to order whatever has any intrinsic value to be pursued.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>n one would expect an explanation as to what in general makes up<br />

intrinsic value. Perhaps, if Grisez had given this explanation, he would not<br />

have determined <strong>the</strong> essential, irreducible goods for man by <strong>the</strong> sole criterion<br />

of his factually basic, <strong>natural</strong> tendencies, but also by <strong>the</strong> degree of immanent<br />

value in <strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> tendency.<br />

Thus, that procreation is one of <strong>the</strong> essential human goods that must be<br />

respected Grisez proves by <strong>the</strong> facts that having children is practically a<br />

universal phenomenon <strong>and</strong> that from a biological point of view <strong>the</strong> work of<br />

reproduction is <strong>the</strong> fullest organic realization of <strong>the</strong> living substance. Such<br />

reasoning illustrates well how his specific principles correspond to "basic <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>natural</strong> tendencies," but leaves intact <strong>the</strong> mystery concerning <strong>the</strong> most<br />

general <strong>and</strong> fundamental question: what makes anything a good at all <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>refore to be pursued?<br />

However, by his own clarifying of <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>the</strong> <strong>contraception</strong> question<br />

<strong>and</strong> by his own tracing-out of <strong>the</strong> salient points of situationism, Grisez<br />

makes clear that his most decisive step lies fur<strong>the</strong>r on. He must show how <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute ideal goods a man should recognize can eventually prohibit a given<br />

external action under all circumstances. Obviously, such goods prohibit any<br />

interior act of hate or indifference in <strong>the</strong>ir regard, as well as any actions<br />

undertaken out of such motives. But how can <strong>the</strong>y prohibit objectively <strong>and</strong><br />

unqualifiedly an external action, when <strong>the</strong> total relation of any external<br />

action to an ideal good will vary with circumstances? Moreover, as he insists,<br />

it can be morally licit in certain circumstances to wish <strong>and</strong> prefer <strong>the</strong> nonrealization<br />

of <strong>the</strong> good (e.g., <strong>the</strong> cessation of <strong>the</strong> life of a friend in prolonged<br />

death agony). He may even arrange for <strong>the</strong> nonrealization by his omission<br />

or take positive action in order to allow it to take place (e.g., discontinue ex-


426 THEOLOGICAL STUDIES<br />

traordinary means by disconnecting a heart-lung machine). What is intrinsically<br />

evil is only to act in such a way as not to respect this good as irreducible<br />

ideal, i.e., to submerge or subordinate <strong>the</strong> good in <strong>the</strong> intention that<br />

<strong>the</strong> act by its very nature requires. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, that act is intrinsically<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore always immoral in which <strong>the</strong> agent necessarily, by <strong>the</strong> very<br />

nature of <strong>the</strong> act, intends as end or means <strong>the</strong> nonrealization of <strong>the</strong> good.<br />

For this reason, certain types of conception-preventing behavior are always<br />

immoral, no matter how great <strong>the</strong> good that may result from it.<br />

Grisez's conclusion would follow unquestionably from any <strong>the</strong>ory where<br />

<strong>the</strong> operative norm of obligation was <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> faculty or act, comm<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

by a divine legislator. But he rejects such <strong>the</strong>ories as inadequate.<br />

Can he, in his preferred framework of irreducible human goods, logically<br />

prohibit any given external act without qualification? Should not his sole<br />

norm, "a constant, positive love of each of <strong>the</strong> essential goods" (p. 87), a<br />

"willing that <strong>the</strong>y be" (p. 91), in its practical application look only to <strong>the</strong><br />

total results of <strong>the</strong> action, to what extent it works on <strong>the</strong> whole for or against<br />

<strong>the</strong> concrete realization of <strong>the</strong> goods? But this, Grisez recognizes, leads to<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility that any given action may, at least in exceptional circumstances,<br />

be justified. With remarkable honesty <strong>and</strong> lucidity in his effort to<br />

avoid <strong>the</strong> conclusions of situationism, he depicts his moral man as one who,<br />

in recognizing intrinsically immoral acts, is ultimately uninfluenced by <strong>the</strong><br />

results of what he does. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, apparently sensing <strong>the</strong> discrepancy<br />

between this position <strong>and</strong> his fundamental ethic of love of goods, he<br />

ascribes <strong>the</strong> ultimate irrelevance of total results to an extrinsic factor, <strong>the</strong><br />

limits of human knowledge. Since man never fully knows <strong>the</strong> consequences<br />

of his actions, he cannot act on his evaluation of <strong>the</strong> complete outcome. God,<br />

of course, does fully know, <strong>and</strong> He may well have a moral judgment on a<br />

given action quite different from that to which human ethicians must come.<br />

For <strong>the</strong>m, in <strong>the</strong>ir ignorance, <strong>the</strong> only criterion of an intrinsically immoral<br />

act is that by its very nature it shows disrespect of an ideal good, although<br />

its consequences may on <strong>the</strong> whole contribute far more to <strong>the</strong> realization of<br />

<strong>the</strong> good than against it. Thus, for Grisez, <strong>the</strong> love of a good (e.g., human<br />

life) can prohibit an action (e.g., <strong>the</strong>rapeutic abortion) even in circumstances<br />

where <strong>the</strong> action would not increase <strong>the</strong> loss of life, but might save one (pp.<br />

87, 110).<br />

The decrees of a divine legislator discerned in <strong>natural</strong> ends could well<br />

justify such a practical attitude. One could leave <strong>the</strong> responsibility for results<br />

to <strong>the</strong> legislator. But if, as Grisez <strong>and</strong> this reviewer <strong>and</strong> many Catholics today<br />

believe, <strong>the</strong> legislator has simply left man to act out of his own love for <strong>the</strong><br />

good, it is difficult to see how love can dem<strong>and</strong> anything else of an adult but


CONTRACEPTION AND THE NATURAL LAW 427<br />

responsibility for bringing <strong>the</strong> object loved to be, for <strong>the</strong> extent of concrete<br />

realization of <strong>the</strong> good—in brief, for results, estimated as best a man can.<br />

Incidentally, one might speculate that Grisez's extraordinary low opinion<br />

of man's knowledge of results may also be based on <strong>the</strong> later writings of<br />

Thomas Aquinas <strong>and</strong> not take sufficiently into account <strong>the</strong> revolution in<br />

human knowledge that began in <strong>the</strong> days of Galileo Galilei <strong>and</strong> has not yet<br />

come to a halt. Is it that ethicians such as Grisez are afraid to admit ultimate<br />

results as sole criteria of immorality because <strong>the</strong>y realize that <strong>the</strong> new<br />

sciences may invalidate current assessments of results of a particular action<br />

<strong>and</strong> give a different, if truer, picture? And <strong>the</strong>y, <strong>the</strong> ethicians, do not know<br />

what this truth might be. Perhaps it would be fairer as well as kinder to such<br />

ethicians to admit that any <strong>the</strong>ory which invokes results as sole moral criterion<br />

still must explain <strong>and</strong> not suppress a basically valid experience of all<br />

men trying to be moral, that at times one faces certain obligations <strong>and</strong> prohibitions<br />

that are independent of results in one sense, in <strong>the</strong> sense of <strong>the</strong> results<br />

of this individual act here <strong>and</strong> now assessed by this individual man.<br />

Those who, like this reviewer, see <strong>the</strong> primary value of Grisez's <strong>study</strong> as,<br />

despite itself, pointing to some ethic of <strong>the</strong> results along <strong>the</strong> lines of "situationism,"<br />

will recognize <strong>the</strong> challenge to such an ethic to integrate <strong>the</strong><br />

above experience.<br />

Fordham University JOHN G. MILHAVEN, S J.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!