23.10.2014 Views

Heidegger, Tugendhat, Davidson - University of New Mexico

Heidegger, Tugendhat, Davidson - University of New Mexico

Heidegger, Tugendhat, Davidson - University of New Mexico

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

picture still threatens to open the door to infinite regresses, and raises significant additional problems <strong>of</strong><br />

its own. First, there is the notorious problem <strong>of</strong> reference to concepts: the attempt to say anything<br />

about a concept immediately demands that it have the logical type <strong>of</strong> an object, and thus involves a<br />

crossing <strong>of</strong> levels which Frege must rule out by fiat. Second, Frege’s assumptions about the<br />

compositional structure <strong>of</strong> sentences lead him to hold that both the sense and reference <strong>of</strong> sentences<br />

must be determined by the sense and reference <strong>of</strong> their individual parts; and this leads him to the claim<br />

that predicative terms have functions or function-like objects as referents. Frege’s metaphor for such<br />

objects is that they are “unsaturated”; but as <strong>Davidson</strong> points out, it is obscure what can be meant by<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> objects that are inherently “gappy” in this sense. One can identify the “semantic value”<br />

<strong>of</strong> functional expressions with their semantic role rather than their reference, as Dummett essentially<br />

suggests; but this represents an important departure from Frege’s original picture, and makes the<br />

reference itself redundant.<br />

It is here, according to <strong>Davidson</strong>, that recursive picture improves over Frege’s. In particular, in<br />

characterizing truth-conditions <strong>of</strong> a language’s sentences as systematically dependent upon satisfaction<br />

conditions for predicates and singular terms, Tarski can account for the compositional structure<br />

underlying these conditions without invoking unsaturated entities or shadowy referents for predicates<br />

and functional expressions. More generally, the Tarskian structure avoids all <strong>of</strong> the various kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

regresses that have recurrently problematized correspondence and other theories by conceiving <strong>of</strong> truth<br />

as a unitary predicate <strong>of</strong> sentences, to be illuminated ultimately in terms <strong>of</strong> the overall truth-conditional<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> a language, rather than in terms <strong>of</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong> any particular sentence to anything else.<br />

As <strong>Davidson</strong> emphasizes, it is, here, the fact that the predicate “true,” as applied to sentences, is<br />

essentially a one-place predicate that here provides an important clue to the emptiness <strong>of</strong><br />

correspondence theories:<br />

We explain the application <strong>of</strong> a one-place predicate by reference to a relation only when there is<br />

an indefinitely large number <strong>of</strong> distinct entities to which the relation bears. There are no such<br />

entities available in the case <strong>of</strong> sentences, beliefs, judgments, or sentential utterances. It is<br />

important that truth, as applied to things in the world (utterances <strong>of</strong> sentences, inscriptions,<br />

beliefs, assertions), is a unitary property, for it is this that ties it so closely to the problem <strong>of</strong><br />

predication. A large part <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> predication is, after all, just the problem <strong>of</strong><br />

specifying what it is about predicates that explains why the sentential expressions in which they<br />

occur may be used to say something true or false. (p. 130)<br />

As <strong>Davidson</strong> here suggests, any theory <strong>of</strong> the truth <strong>of</strong> sentences that treats it as a relational property will<br />

ultimately fail to account for the kind <strong>of</strong> truth-evaluable unity that sentences exhibit. This is because<br />

any such theory will advert to a relationship between a true sentence and some entity (be it a fact, state<br />

<strong>of</strong> affairs, situation, or whatever) that makes it true; and it will then be necessary to explain the unity <strong>of</strong><br />

the sentence in terms <strong>of</strong> the unity <strong>of</strong> this entity. But this does not solve the problem <strong>of</strong> unity, but only<br />

reiterates it; and given the Slingshot argument, the only entity in terms <strong>of</strong> which it will be possible to<br />

explain the truth <strong>of</strong> any sentence will be the “maximal” entity, the True. Though this might be treated<br />

as a kind <strong>of</strong> correspondence explanation, if there is indeed at most one thing for true sentences to<br />

correspond to, “we say no more when we say ‘corresponds to the truth’ than we say by the simpler ‘is<br />

14

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!