05.11.2014 Views

Download - depictionandpainting.net

Download - depictionandpainting.net

Download - depictionandpainting.net

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2<br />

Depiction and Painting<br />

A Theory and History of Art<br />

1950 – 2000<br />

Gerry Bell<br />

© Gerry Bell 2008


3<br />

Content<br />

Part One – Theory<br />

Content 3<br />

Introduction 4<br />

Detailed Table of Contents for Part One 7-8<br />

1. The Problem with Pictures 9<br />

2. Depiction Revised 23<br />

3. Depiction Pursued: Five Issues 31<br />

4. Expression and Style 45<br />

5. Depiction and Art 55<br />

6. Art History 64<br />

7. Interpretation 72<br />

8. Realisms 79<br />

9. Painting 89<br />

10. Summary 104<br />

Part Two – History<br />

Detailed Table of Contents for Part Two 109-111<br />

11. Modernism and Abstraction 112<br />

12. Modernism 1912-1950: ‘Simultaneous and Successive Depiction’ 126<br />

13. Late Modernism 1950-1960: ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ 138<br />

14. Post-Modernism and Pop Art: Painting Printing 1960-1970 150<br />

15. Post- Modernism Continued: Painting Photography 1962-1978 164<br />

16. The End of Post-Modernism: ‘Bad’ Painting, Neo-Expressionism and New<br />

Image Painting. 176<br />

17. Abstraction in Late and Post-Modernism 189<br />

18. ‘Expanded Materials’ in Late and Post-Modernism 204<br />

19. Globalism 1985-2000 223<br />

20. Conclusion 249<br />

Bibliography 259-305


4<br />

Introduction<br />

The scope and method to this study are unusually broad. Scope extends from a<br />

review of theories of depiction, in art history, aesthetics, psychology and descriptive<br />

geometry, to related issues of style, expression, interpretation and painting, to their<br />

application in art criticism.<br />

The aim is firstly to provide an adequate theory of depiction, one that holds for the<br />

full range of examples, then to demonstrate how the theory may overcome certain<br />

stylistic problems for the study of recent art. There is a danger obviously in<br />

stretching research too thinly, in providing only a superficial account of this range<br />

and confusing some traditional boundaries. This is set against the prospect of a<br />

more effective integration, a greater understanding of depiction and a more<br />

consistent and discriminating view of recent art history.<br />

The study thus proceeds by careful and extensive reference, allows that the reader’s<br />

expertise may not extend equally to all areas visited, explains basic principles on<br />

many, perhaps obvious points. It takes time to traverse the full breadth of topic,<br />

may seem unduly pedestrian on certain points. Indeed, theoretical issues may tax the<br />

reader anxious to embark upon simply a novel art history. The study falls readily<br />

enough into two parts, theory and history, but history cannot be read with profit<br />

before theory, nor theory fully appreciated without its application to history. The<br />

theoretical issues prompt a series of bold departures, although implications for<br />

history may not always be obvious. But assuredly, all are needed to build a theory of<br />

any strength or conviction, and the problems to be addressed require just this of<br />

theory. There is no point advocating a theory of lesser scope, no point reviewing art<br />

history supported by anything less.<br />

The problems for recent art history concern firstly the concept of abstraction in<br />

depiction and its relation to competing and more concrete styles. Mistakes over the<br />

distinction between the picture plane and picture surface, about varieties of picture<br />

plane or schemes of projection and perspective and the role of painting in depiction


5<br />

are carried through to problems with stylistics. The period of Modernism inflates to<br />

unmanageable proportions and then makes problems for the extent of Post-<br />

Modernism. While the study shares an interest in these periods with a great deal of<br />

recent scholarship, it is distinctive in this concentration upon stylistics.<br />

Method of research is conspicuous where art history is more fully engaged.<br />

Research here regroups established works according to stylistic features derived<br />

from the theory of depiction. Method makes for new styles rather than the more<br />

usual elaboration on source for a given style. New styles are rarely offered as<br />

replacements for established ones, but rather as additional categories that ease and<br />

integrate the system of styles within and around the periods of Modernism and<br />

Post-Modernism.<br />

Modernism and Post-Modernism are revised in duration and constitution. However,<br />

where new sub-styles are introduced and names coined, such as ‘Overstyle’ and<br />

‘Rerealism’, they are placed in inverted commas throughout the text, acknowledging<br />

novelty. This also applies to terms introduced for special techniques or features<br />

such as ‘layout’, ‘traction’, ‘interruption’ and ‘readily-made’. Following this emphasis<br />

upon stylistics, analysis of individual works here is primarily concerned with<br />

identifying salient features and demonstrating how they work or refer, rather than<br />

interpreting the fuller ramifications of source. In cases where a substantial body of<br />

interpretation exists for a given work or artist’s style, standard publications are<br />

acknowledged in footnote, along with key agreements or disputes. Because of the<br />

amount of ground covered, descriptions are necessarily brief. Hopefully, rigour and<br />

clarity avoid any impression of flippancy.<br />

Scope and method are thus granted latitude only to address vital issues and afford<br />

necessary revision. The work of Nelson Goodman proves an underestimated<br />

resource in this. Adopting and adapting his aesthetic for this purpose makes the<br />

study a very rare foray indeed. Where the study succeeds, a good many aspects are<br />

to be credited to his work, at least by the good mannered reader. And success is to<br />

be measured in both a more adequate theory of depiction and a more complete and<br />

coherent history for recent art. This is the test the study sets itself, that sanctions<br />

departures in scope and method and that the patient reader is finally asked to apply.


6<br />

To note particulars of presentation, the study falls into twenty chapters and two<br />

parts. Chapters One to Ten are devoted to theory, Eleven to Twenty to history. A<br />

table for each part details the progression of chapters, relevant reading, artists and<br />

styles (see navigation bar). The many illustrations accompanying the text are<br />

provided by links in the PDF files or from a list on the illustrations page. This<br />

enables the illustrations to be found on-line, even as the relevant text hurries from<br />

any point on a page where an illustration might usefully be inserted. It also allows<br />

the text to use many more and often larger illustrations than might practically be<br />

inserted, many more than might be afforded in permission and copyright<br />

clearance. It is unfortunate that the illustrations cannot accompany the reader who<br />

wishes to read a printed copy, or off-line, but the reader is free to copy or print the<br />

illustrations. Hopefully this arrangement is not too inconvenient.


7<br />

Part One<br />

THEORY<br />

Chapter Title Description<br />

1<br />

Page<br />

9<br />

The Problem<br />

with Pictures<br />

Brief history of competing<br />

theories of depiction, their<br />

application in art history and<br />

aesthetics, from Gombrich to<br />

the late ni<strong>net</strong>ies.<br />

Main<br />

Reference<br />

E.H. Gombrich, Nelson<br />

Goodman, Richard<br />

Wollheim, Roland Barthes,<br />

Umberto Eco, Norman<br />

Bryson, W.J.T. Mitchell,<br />

Erwin Panofsky, Rosalind<br />

Krauss, James Elkins,<br />

Julian Bell.<br />

2<br />

Page<br />

23<br />

Depiction<br />

Revised<br />

A closer look at Nelson<br />

Goodman’s theory of<br />

reference, a revision<br />

proposed.<br />

Goodman, Gombrich,<br />

Mitchell<br />

3<br />

Page<br />

31<br />

Depiction<br />

Pursued<br />

Applies new theory to five<br />

key issues for depiction –<br />

depth, distortion, caricature,<br />

fiction and found or natural<br />

images<br />

John Willats, J. J. Gibson,<br />

Goodman, Gombrich,<br />

David Marr et al, John M.<br />

Kennedy, Wollheim,<br />

Stephanie Ross<br />

4<br />

Page<br />

45<br />

Expression<br />

and Style<br />

Reconciles the new theory of<br />

depiction with Goodman’s<br />

views of expression as<br />

metaphor, together with its<br />

relation to classification of<br />

style, or stylistics.<br />

Goodman Wollheim,<br />

Gombrich, John Constable,<br />

Monroe Beardsley, W.K.<br />

Wimsatt, Arthur Danto,<br />

5<br />

Page<br />

55<br />

Depiction and<br />

Art<br />

The problem of beauty or<br />

excellence in depiction and<br />

art. Combining the proposed<br />

theory with Goodman’s view<br />

of cognitive effectiveness.<br />

Goodman, Catherine Z.<br />

Elgin, Gombrich,<br />

Wollheim, George A.<br />

Kelly.<br />

6<br />

Page<br />

64<br />

Art History<br />

The problem in Gombrich’s<br />

historical approach to (and<br />

definition of) art, in<br />

particular concerning the<br />

twentieth century.<br />

Gombrich, Goodman, Bell,<br />

David Carrier.


8<br />

7<br />

Page<br />

72<br />

Interpretation<br />

The problem of interpretation<br />

underpinning an historical<br />

definition of art. Radical<br />

relativist approaches to<br />

interpretation (and history).<br />

An irrealist method to history<br />

outlined.<br />

Gombrich, Martin<br />

Heidegger, Jurgen<br />

Habermas, Joseph<br />

Margolis, E.D. Hirsch,<br />

Peter Caws, Claude Levi-<br />

Strauss, Jacques Derrida,<br />

Jean Baudrillard, Jean-<br />

Francois Lyotard, Michel<br />

Foucault, Hans Gadamer,<br />

James F. Harris, Harvey<br />

Siegel, Goodman<br />

8<br />

Page<br />

79<br />

Realisms<br />

A pluralistic view of stylistic<br />

realism, or realisms,<br />

demonstrated by analysis of<br />

the work of Pollock.<br />

Gombrich, Goodman,<br />

Elgin, Mitchell, Jackson<br />

Pollock, Claude Cernuschi,<br />

Irving Sandler,<br />

9<br />

Page<br />

89<br />

Painting<br />

A pluralist view of painting.<br />

The crucial difference now<br />

between the work of sole and<br />

multiple instances in<br />

depiction and art. Then looks<br />

at formalist criticism based<br />

upon theories of painting, for<br />

the formulation of<br />

Modernism, as a period style.<br />

Goodman, Wollheim,<br />

Walter Benjamin, Bell,<br />

Clement Greenberg,<br />

Immanuel Kant, Ludwig<br />

Wittgenstein, Michael<br />

Fried, Thierry de Duve,<br />

William Rubin, Frank<br />

Stella, Donald Judd.<br />

10<br />

Page<br />

104<br />

Summary<br />

The contribution made to<br />

theory here, its place within<br />

Goodman’s larger aesthetic,<br />

or irrealism.


9<br />

The Problem with Pictures<br />

The problem with pictures is in how we make sense of them, how we recognise<br />

them and the kinds of meanings found there. There are a number of conflicting<br />

explanations and disagreements are longstanding, widespread and deep-seated.<br />

Explanations quickly appeal to fundamental ideas about our understanding of the<br />

world, its organisation and customs. In particular, pictures are bound up with the<br />

concept of art, its history and criticism, and to pursue an understanding of these, we<br />

must take a position on pictures. In art history the explanation of pictures is sought<br />

in terms of their tradition and influence. Tradition is variously described in terms of<br />

a context, as the history of a culture, or in terms of a concept, as the history of<br />

depiction or pictorial properties. Neither extreme is tenable. To explain everything<br />

in terms of context, is to drain the concept of a picture of all meaning, to result in<br />

all history and no art, while to explain everything in terms of the concept of a<br />

picture, is to drain its context of meaning, and result in all art and no history. So the<br />

problem lies in deciding how much is internal to a picture, usually termed its formal<br />

or technical properties, and how much is external, the influence of time and place.<br />

In recent times discussion generally takes as its starting point the work of E. H.<br />

Gombrich. By tracing a number of influential reactions to his work, we can<br />

appreciate firstly how the problem is compounded, how disagreements over the<br />

nature of pictures add to disagreements over art and its history, and secondly how<br />

the problem persists, how even as recent efforts enlist other disciplines to explain<br />

pictures and art, these versions no longer describe the same objects of earlier study.<br />

In truth, they are no longer versions that resolve the problem with pictures, but<br />

rather new problems that urge their substitution. Gombrich’s contribution extends<br />

from the very popular introductory history, The Story of Art, to detailed studies in the<br />

psychology of visual perception and the development of pictorial style, advanced


10<br />

initially in Art and Illusion, and later in The Image And the Eye. 1 Taken together, they<br />

present a view of art as the advance of pictorial sophistication, through experiments<br />

with novel applications and techniques, towards a mode that more fully matches the<br />

experience of visual perception. This emphasis upon matching a picture to the<br />

experience of looking at an object, led many readers to assume that Gombrich took<br />

pictures to be in essence illusions; that delude the viewer in some way into believing<br />

in the presence of the object, rather than just a picture of the object. Indeed the<br />

very title of Art and Illusion hints at such a stance. It is an over-simplification to be<br />

sure, but points to a real and unwelcome consequence in appealing to principles of<br />

visual perception. It also obscures the view of art that accompanies this view of<br />

pictures.<br />

The Story of Art famously opens with the axiom ‘There really is no such thing as Art.<br />

There are only artists.’ From this, Gombrich argues that the concept or definition of<br />

art covers all objects so classified only retrospectively, that the concept properly can<br />

only be understood as an historical sequence or chain, each link continually revising<br />

the concept. It is, above all, a powerful argument for the history of art. But if art is<br />

simply the history of artists, it begs the question how the activity of artists is to be<br />

described? For Gombrich the activity is simply the advance of representation.<br />

Representation need not be narrowly understood as pictorial representation of<br />

course, but the focus of Gombrich’s history is upon the plastic arts, and gives pride<br />

of place to depiction and painting. This commitment to an advance in depiction<br />

introduces a second feature of his view of the history of art. It is the idea that<br />

developments in pictures are progressive and absolute, have a history beyond any<br />

one culture or version of art. The development of the western pictorial tradition is<br />

seen as discoveries concerning the nature of visual perception, confirmed by optics<br />

and geometry. Pictures using systems of perspective for example, are seen as<br />

coming closer to showing an object the way we ‘naturally’, or ‘really’ see it.<br />

For the moment it is enough to see how Gombrich’s view of depiction relates to his<br />

view of art history. But it is with Art and Illusion and its more substantive arguments<br />

for the development of pictures that a critical dialogue arises. Reactions to his view<br />

1<br />

Gombrich, The Story of Art, (16 th ed) Oxford/London, 1995, Gombrich, Art And Illusion,<br />

Oxford, 1960, Gombrich, The Image and the Eye, Oxford/New York, 1982.


11<br />

of pictures, did not initially pursue its relation to art, but concerned themselves<br />

rather with the explanation of pictures as illusions. Two of the most searching<br />

critiques arose in the work of the philosophers Nelson Goodman and Richard<br />

Wollheim. 2 Both rejected the behaviouristic view of perception, and the naturalism<br />

it derives from principles of optics, both rejected the idea of an illusion, fostered by<br />

marks upon a surface, as a picture. But they did so for different reasons.<br />

Wollheim pointed to the inconsistency in Gombrich’s view of perception. On the<br />

one hand Gombrich asserts that seeing is bound up with knowing, that all<br />

perception is interpretation, but on the other, that it is nevertheless possible to<br />

depict according to what we ‘really see’. 3 Yet to claim that there is some particular<br />

thing that we really see is precisely to distinguish between what is really there, and<br />

how it is interpreted. Wollheim also took issue with the view that perception<br />

operates according to a process of schema and correction. Initial schemas in<br />

perception cannot be corrected as a pictorial schema is corrected, by comparing it<br />

with an equivalent perception in real life. An initial perception can only be refuted<br />

or verified by subsequent perceptions. This crucial difference between plain<br />

perception and pictures weakens the argument for an underlying process of schema<br />

and correction. Wollheim’s objections to the idea of pictures as illusions centre on<br />

Gombrich’s discussion of the famous rabbit/duck ambiguous drawing. 4 He argued<br />

that the drawing presented two distinct interpretations, a surface and an image,<br />

which Gombrich mistakes for being mutually exclusive. For Wollheim, the<br />

interpretations are compatible yet distinct, to see the rabbit or the duck, is not to<br />

deny that they are a certain configuration of ink on paper, or a surface. The matter<br />

of an illusion arises only in the exceptional circumstances of a trompe l’oeil picture,<br />

usually a mural integrated within an architectural setting, which cannot be detected<br />

from certain angles.<br />

Goodman’s response was more sweeping, and came as part of his own theory in<br />

Languages of Art. He began by rejecting not only the idea of illusion in pictures, but<br />

2 Goodman, Languages of Art (2 nd ed) Indianapolis, 1976. The second edition is used throughout,<br />

here. Richard Wollheim, On Art and the Mind, London, 1973, pp. 261-284.<br />

3 Gombrich, 1960, p. 278.<br />

4 Ibid.4. Versions of this drawing have a long history in discussions on visual perception, both in<br />

the experiments of perceptual psychologists, such as Norma V. Scheidemann, Experiments in<br />

General Psychology, Chicago, 1939, p. 67, fig 21, and in the work of philosophers such as<br />

Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, 1953, p.194.


12<br />

of any likeness or resemblance as the means by which a picture represents an object.<br />

He advanced two powerful arguments to this end. Firstly not all resemblances are<br />

representations: two apples may resemble one another but do not therefore<br />

represent one another. Resemblance is a two-way or symmetrical relation: each<br />

apple equally resembles the other. Representation, on the other hand, is a one-way<br />

or asymmetrical relation, a picture represents an apple, but an apple does not<br />

represent a picture of one. Secondly, not all pictures are resemblances. A picture of<br />

a fictional beast such as a unicorn does not resemble anything, literally. At best it<br />

complies with preceding descriptions or pictures. Moreover, pictures resemble other<br />

pictures as much if not more than they resemble any of their objects, yet usually<br />

represent objects not other pictures. Goodman declared that pictures represent or<br />

refer, not because they resemble but because they denote, are properly a mode of<br />

notation. But while he rejected resemblance as necessary or sufficient condition for<br />

depiction he allowed that it arises between picture and object as a result of custom<br />

or familiarity. He thus allowed for realism and illusion, but insisted they are relative<br />

to notation, context and custom. While Goodman also found much to commend in<br />

the relativism of Gombrich’s account of schema and correction, he pointedly<br />

rejected the idea that the rules of perspective are faithfully derived from the laws of<br />

optics, and provided a set of damaging counter-examples, succinctly concluding:<br />

‘Briefly, the behaviour of light sanctions neither our usual nor any other way of<br />

rendering space; and perspective provides no absolute or independent standard of<br />

fidelity’. 5<br />

A measure of the impact of Goodman’s arguments is found in Gombrich’s<br />

subsequent book, The Image and the Eye. Here Gombrich abandoned arguments for<br />

perspective derived from the geometry of light, and proposed more modestly, an<br />

‘eyewitness principle’. 6 But Goodman also pointed to a more disturbing relativism<br />

in schema and correction or making and matching. Gombrich’s position was that<br />

what we match or use pictures for, depends on what we make, but the process is in<br />

the long run an accumulative one, so that by matching one thing and then another,<br />

bit by bit we make the picture perfect match, an illusion. The prospect to which<br />

Goodman pointed is that while different matches depend on different makes,<br />

5 Goodman, Languages of Art, Indianapolis, 1976, pp. 16-19.<br />

6 Gombrich, 1982, p. 281.


13<br />

different pictures of an object then have a way of turning into pictures of different<br />

objects. 7 The matches never quite add up, the makes are never just re-makes.<br />

In the essay Image and Code: Scope and Limits of Conventionalism in Pictorial Representation<br />

Gombrich sought to defend the view of naturalism in pictures and to reconcile it<br />

with the need for conventions. 8 It takes pictorial rules or conventions as versions of<br />

perception, hence versions of illusion, versions of an object. It was notable also for<br />

inclusion of a response from Goodman, who managed to seek common ground<br />

while insisting that the distinction between nature and convention was also relative.<br />

Gombrich appealed to a behaviouristic view of image recognition amongst animals<br />

and insects, and to its instinctual basis. ‘We are programmed to be more easily<br />

triggered by some configurations than by others.’ 9 The argument can establish<br />

resemblance as a necessary and ‘natural’ relation for substitution, but not<br />

representation. Birds and fish may be deceived by a representation, but it does not<br />

therefore function as a representation or reference. Distinction between<br />

resemblance, substitution and reference may be elastic, or graded, as Gombrich<br />

argued in ‘Pygmalion’s Power’ in Art and Illusion, but if the distinction between<br />

nature and convention is relative, as Goodman declared and Gombrich conceded,<br />

then reference still remains less natural, or more conventional. The lack of birds and<br />

fish enrolling in art classes might cinch this point. So there was no comfort there<br />

for Gombrich, no strict accuracy in labelling of Goodman as a conventionalist.<br />

But while the case for pictures as an illusion cannot co-opt representation to<br />

resemblance, cannot draw support from the geometry of light, nor a biological<br />

disposition to perspective, and finally cannot resist conventions, the case for<br />

pictures as denotation, also has problems. Goodman’s ideas for a depictive notation<br />

stretch the concepts of syntax and semantics into dense analogues, in order to<br />

explain why pictures can acquire resemblance, while notations such as writing<br />

cannot. In fact the combined dense analogues do little more than dissolve the<br />

concept of notation. 10 A further requirement for relative repleteness of syntax<br />

7 See treatment of invention, fiction and representation-as in Goodman, 1976, pp. 21-34<br />

8 Gombrich, 1982, pp. 279 - 297<br />

9 Ibid. pp. 285-6<br />

10 There is acknowledgement that such density is the antithesis of notation. See Goodman, 1976,<br />

p.160. Goodman divides reference into denotation and exemplification with denotation then<br />

divided into description and depiction. Descriptive notation includes writing, mathematical and


14<br />

assumes elements of one scheme of depiction may be always included within<br />

another, so that for example what is depicted in a simple line diagram, such as a<br />

floor plan, may be more fully depicted with the inclusion of tone or shading, colour<br />

and perspective. 11 But aspects of line cannot always be accommodated with aspects<br />

of tone without altering their constituent character, in fact shifting emphasis where<br />

line coincides with shade or contrasts with light, just as tone cannot be<br />

accommodated with all colours without losing key integrities of grey, and the same<br />

holds for volume, scale, projection and perspective. Thus the concept of repleteness<br />

of depictive syntax and of pictures as a mode of denotation - but without a notation<br />

- also proves something of a stumbling block.<br />

Similarly, analysis of pictures in terms borrowed from structural linguistics, or as<br />

semiotics, struggle to detect the requisite syntax. The initial studies of Roland<br />

Barthes and Umberto Eco for example, although hardly responding to Gombrich,<br />

ultimately rely upon an ‘iconic’ or resemblance relation; cannot reconcile it anymore<br />

effectively with reference nor adequately distinguish or explain ‘plastic’ qualities to<br />

depictive meaning. 12 Strictly, semiotics extends only iconographic and iconological<br />

analysis here. Following controversies between schools argue for various ranges of<br />

depiction as the proper domain of study and against the narrowness of mere<br />

linguistic transcription of depictive meaning, but do not otherwise advance the<br />

problem. 13 Later developments, grouped as post-structuralism, tend to reject a<br />

unitary code to semiotics and a fixed ideology supporting objects. Such approaches<br />

gradually disengage from the problem with pictures and its application to art<br />

history; in fact prefer to straddle disciplines, generally in the cause of social or<br />

cultural analysis. However, in the late seventies and early eighties a number of<br />

musical systems, slides toward depiction with analogue scales and dance notation for instance.<br />

Analogue density of syntax and semantics no more than collapses notation, may perhaps organise<br />

notations usefully, as in James Elkins, The Domain of Images, Ithaca/London, 1999, but can only<br />

say in ways depiction is not notation (and therefore denotation).<br />

11 The example of a floor plan is not used by Goodman, but is consistent with the argument for<br />

repleteness. See Goodman, 1976, p.230.<br />

12 See Barthes, ‘Rhétorique de l´image’, in Communications, 4, 1964, pp. 40-51, Barthes,<br />

Elements of semiology, (1967) London, 1969, and Eco, A Theory of Semiotics, (1976)<br />

Bloomington, 1980.<br />

13 For a detailed history of semiotic studies in the period see Göran Sonesson, Pictorial concepts:<br />

Inquiries into the semiotic heritage and its relevance for the analysis of the visual world. Lund,<br />

Sweden, 1989 and introductory essay, ‘Pictorial semiotics’ online at<br />

http://filserver.arthist.lu.se/kultsem/encyclo/pictorial_semiotics.html (03). Also, controversy<br />

surrounding the paraphrasing of depictive meaning, here, interestingly parallels arguments for the<br />

‘heresy of paraphrase’ in poetry. See for example, Cleanth Brooks, Modern Poetry and the<br />

Tradition, Chapel Hill, N.C. 1967.


15<br />

writers in the English-speaking world began to reflect these concerns while<br />

addressing art history more exclusively. The work of W.J.T. Mitchell, Norman<br />

Bryson and Rosalind E. Krauss, to name only three of the more prominent<br />

exponents, variously revisited the distinction between depiction and denotation. 14<br />

Mitchell’s work is the more general, surveys a history of writing about pictures as a<br />

way of noting the difference between writing and depiction, considers concepts of<br />

depiction and underlying ideologies from this. However, given the attention paid to<br />

the contributions of Goodman and Gombrich, the work is of more interest to<br />

aesthetics and art history, and given the equivocation in matters of ideology, of less<br />

interest to the roving commission of ‘critical theory’. 15 Goodman’s theory is<br />

scrutinised for historical and ideological tendencies (recklessly aligning a<br />

metaphorical iconoclasm in Goodman’s frequent reversals of orthodoxy with the<br />

literal iconoclasm of the Reformation and Puritanism) and curiously takes<br />

Goodman’s reference schemes as canonical to Modernism. 16 Gombrich’s position is<br />

taken as drawing a line between nature and convention or artifice in depiction. Yet<br />

the historical and ideological dimension to Gombrich’s position, its implicit<br />

definition of art, goes unexamined. Mitchell’s own position comes to little more<br />

than an affirmation of the value of writing about depiction, a predictable preference<br />

for writing (even in matters of pornography) and later treatments favour either the<br />

combination of text and depiction in works, as in Blake’s illuminated manuscripts or<br />

the works of Robert Morris, or no more than glosses critics such as Clement<br />

Greenberg, Michael Fried and Rosalind E. Krauss on the nature of abstraction in<br />

depiction. 17<br />

Bryson’s work also commences with a critique of Gombrich and concludes that<br />

resemblance and illusion are incompatible with the ambiguities and interpretation<br />

available to a sign or denotation. But this is assumed rather than argued. At the<br />

14<br />

Key publications for each are: W. J. T. Mitchell, Iconology: Image Text Ideology,<br />

Chicago/London, 1986, Norman Bryson, Vision and Painting: The Logic of the Gaze, New<br />

Haven/London, 1983, Rosalind E. Krauss, The Originality of the Avant-Garde and other<br />

Modernist Myths, Cambridge/Mass./London, 1986. Krauss’s influence also extends through her<br />

co-editorship of the journal October, featuring an array of prominent critics including An<strong>net</strong>te<br />

Michelson, Douglas Crimp, Yves-Alain Bois, Benjamin Buchloh and Hal Foster.<br />

15 Critical theory here used in the sense given by The Frankfurt School of Marxist analysis.<br />

16 Mitchell, 1986, p.71 footnote 27.<br />

17 Mitchell, Picture Theory, Chicago/London, 1994, 111-180, pp. 213-280.


16<br />

same time he rejects any simple structuralist analysis of iconography as too static<br />

and lacking the continual interaction with the world. The system or structure is thus<br />

understood as in a constant state of flux. Just what state of incompleteness may be<br />

taken as acceptable or useful to the dynamic sign system is unclear. 18 Rejecting a<br />

resemblance relation for depiction, Bryson persists with the application of syntax<br />

and proposes a detail of parsing and tense, in ‘deixis’ as the basis of depiction. But<br />

since the rest of syntax and semantics has proven ineffective in earlier semiotic<br />

studies, not surprisingly, this term taken in isolation hardly fares any better.<br />

‘Deixis’ is taken as the rhetoric of a narrator, of terms indicating presence of a<br />

speaker in a discourse, and so a bodily or physical aspect as well as an explicit<br />

temporal dimension. In depiction this translates as a distinction between ‘The Gaze’<br />

where deixis is absent, together with bodily and sequential reference, and ‘The<br />

Glance’, where deixis is present, through details of material indicating how long and<br />

in what way the depiction was made. The distinction thus attempts to account for<br />

the ‘plastic’ qualities that troubled early semioticians, and roughly parallels the<br />

‘indexic’ aspect to signs proposed by C. S. Peirce, but without Peirce’s overlapping<br />

and ancillary categories, relinquishes much in the way of traditional iconography and<br />

stylistics. 19 The necessary distinctions to materials and techniques are far from<br />

convincing in the array of examples provided because they assume a given identity<br />

to object depicted, and distinctions by which bodily signs are assigned materials or<br />

techniques equally beg greater scrutiny, (bodily signs surely admit subtle, minute and<br />

time-consuming gestures as well as bold, brief and grand ones, just as ‘Gazes’ grade<br />

into ‘Glances’) There is then the question of just how these distinctions are<br />

preserved any easier than preceding semiotics in the aforementioned constant flux?<br />

Finally, if most painting operates according to ‘The Gaze’ rather than ‘The Glance’<br />

as would seem to be the argument, the distinction is rendered somewhat trivial,<br />

while if ‘The Gaze’ only indicates ideological issues of sexuality and power, as<br />

Bryson seems to suggest, then depictive meaning simply collapses into ideology. But<br />

surely neither ideology nor depiction is served by such crude reduction.<br />

18 Bryson, 1983, pp. xiii-xiv.<br />

19 For Peirce on semiotics see ‘Speculative Grammar’ ‘Letters to Lady Welby’ and ‘Existential<br />

Graphs’ in C.S. Peirce, Collected Papers, Boston, 1931.


17<br />

Drastic reduction of depictive meaning to ideological ends is also a feature of the<br />

work of Krauss at this time. Famously, she argued for grids as the basis of<br />

abstraction in depiction and painting, for their rigour and constraint as the ultimate<br />

test of originality or invention, and for such originality as the basis of Modernism<br />

and a capitalist ideology. 20 The post structuralist influence here is in the rejection of<br />

pure or neutral ‘formal’ means to depiction, in their relentless assimilation by<br />

iconography, and the ultimate disclosure of a stark ideological function. The<br />

promotion of grids is also seen as fundamental to depiction in resisting commentary<br />

or language. For Krauss it represents Modernism’s ‘will to silence’ and the isolation<br />

of the visual arts in ‘a realm of exclusive visuality’. 21 This is not to say that less is<br />

written or said about abstract works, or that less abstract works encourage<br />

commentary any more, but rather how fundamental the gulf between the verbal and<br />

visual is for an understanding of depiction, and how much more obvious this<br />

becomes with abstract work and its commentary.<br />

However this sweeping thesis is unconvincing on a number of counts. There is<br />

firstly the laxity with which the term ‘grid’ is applied to various examples in order to<br />

place them at the centre of abstraction. Contrary to her claim, the ‘grid’ does not<br />

appear in Cubism for example – this is one myth Krauss actually encourages. 22 Nor<br />

is it constituted by the mere intersection of transom and mullions in the windows<br />

depicted within the examples by Friedrich and Redon, as claimed, and what<br />

metaphors they may provoke there are hardly inherited by any subsequent use of<br />

windows, glass, quadrilaterals, parallel or intersecting lines or in fact grids in<br />

depiction. Moreover, actual grids when present in paintings are neither dominant<br />

nor essential in abstraction. More importantly, abstraction does not directly inherit<br />

the content of more concrete depiction. Each formulation of the grid, or other<br />

20 Krauss, ‘The Originality of the Avant-Garde’ in The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other<br />

Modernist Myths, Cambridge/Mass./London, 1986, p.161.<br />

21 Krauss, ‘Grids’ in Ibid. p.9.<br />

22 A grid surely requires a consistency to parallel lines and intersecting angles that Cubist works<br />

simply do not possess. Lines, while mostly straight in Cubist works are neither always coextensive<br />

with the picture area, of uniform intervals, thickness or indeed parallel. They do not<br />

therefore constitute a ‘grid’ as it is commonly understood. The same holds for cited works by<br />

Malevich, Late Mondrian, Reinhardt and Albers. The grid more accurately arises in Modernism<br />

around 1918, through the influence of experimental psychology and in particular the study of<br />

colour. See for example John Gage, Colour and Culture, London/New York, 1993, p. 258.<br />

Mondrian introduces the grid in a series of works titled Composition with Grid between 1918 and<br />

1919, in a style usually described as De Stijl or Neo-Plasticism, quite distinct from Cubism,<br />

while Klee notably uses it in various works throughout the twenties and early thirties.


18<br />

arrangements of only straight lines, revises content by its formal terms. No claim<br />

for sheer or absolute originality in materials or techniques arises in abstraction for<br />

this reason; materials are no more than revised by various abstraction. Therefore<br />

Modernism places no higher premium upon originality than preceding periods, and<br />

originality in and of itself offers no distinctive character to the ideology of a period.<br />

Nevertheless this view has been influential in shaping a history of abstraction and<br />

Modernism, and is important here as an example of how the problem persists, even<br />

for an approach that hurries to ideology. It shows that the concerns of a broader<br />

social history cannot quite ignore the problem with pictures – even very abstract<br />

pictures – in advancing interpretations, without fatally compromising explanation.<br />

Iconography must recognise formal features to a picture if it is to exploit its<br />

content, and formal features depend upon a theory of depiction. There can be no<br />

‘all history and no art’ if the objective is still to address art.<br />

Mitchell, Bryson and Krauss all look to denotation to explain depiction, if not as a<br />

distantly related system then as an opposing one, feeding off or complementing<br />

depiction. Against this scrutiny of reference, the problem of depiction is also<br />

pursued in support of resemblance. The philosopher and art critic David Carrier<br />

considered at length Gombrich’s position in relation to the art history that<br />

accompanies it. Carrier surveyed a history of art history method in Artwriting and<br />

concluded that differences lay in conceptions of a picture and confusions arising<br />

from its ‘conventional’ basis. 23 He defended Gombrich’s naturalism, rejected<br />

semiotic theories, lumping together Bryson and Goodman for example, but could<br />

offer no compelling account of realism upon which to base such a defence, and<br />

curiously interpreted The Story of Art as announcing an end to depiction and art with<br />

Cubism. 24<br />

Resemblance was also at the heart of Wollheim’s Painting as an Art, which included<br />

criticisms of Gombrich and Goodman, as well as social and cultural approaches,<br />

and offered new views on pictures and art. 25 His approach emphasised a<br />

psychological context, and the importance of intention in determining depictive<br />

23 David Carrier, Artwriting, Amhurst, Mass., 1987.<br />

24 Ibid. p. 88.<br />

25 Wollheim, Painting as an Art, London/New York, 1987.


19<br />

meaning. It deftly avoided the notorious intentional fallacy by insisting upon a<br />

standard of correctness for pictorial representation, the details of which are<br />

reviewed in Chapter Four. It is enough here to indicate the emphasis upon<br />

psychology. Intention runs counter to Goodman’s theory, under which the rules of<br />

notation determine meaning, but is accommodated within Gombrich’s theory, as<br />

the means of distinguishing between skill and will, between what the maker<br />

achieved and what was attempted. 26 It might be thought that a theory grounded in<br />

illusion would have no need of such ‘conventions’, but as seen, conventions have a<br />

way of seeping into the matter.<br />

As noted, Wollheim was critical of illusion, and sought to reconcile the perception<br />

of a picture as surface and image. He referred to this as ‘two-foldness’ and argued<br />

that we see the picture as an image, on a surface. 27 But what is meant by the surface<br />

apart from the image is uncertain. If only the markings of the image comprise this<br />

surface, then we cannot see these at the same time as the image, since they are the<br />

image under one description, the markings under another. In truth Wollheim’s is a<br />

resemblance theory, adopting a psychological disposition to ‘see-in’ and find such<br />

images in a surface, as a necessary condition to depiction, and where in accordance<br />

with the intention, sufficient. It avoids the implausibility of illusion but begs the<br />

question in what way the surface is seen as resembling an object. Goodman, by<br />

contrast, consolidated his position with subsequent books, Ways of Worldmaking,<br />

stressing firstly the pluralism of his approach, and its application to stylistics, Of<br />

Mind and Other Matters refining notation and realism and Reconceptions in Philosophy and<br />

Other Arts and Sciences with Catherine Z. Elgin, expanding on multiplicity of<br />

reference and exemplification, but all three books argued against intention in<br />

determining depictive meaning. 28<br />

Two further contributions are of note, The Domain of Images by James Elkins and<br />

What Is Painting? by Julian Bell. 29 Elkins, while essentially hostile to Languages of Art,<br />

26 Gombrich, 1960, p. 56, pp. 65-67.<br />

27 Wollheim, 1987, pp. 46-47, 72-75.<br />

28 Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking, Indianapolis, 1978, Goodman, Of Mind and Other Matters,<br />

Cambridge/Mass./London, 1984 and Nelson Goodman and Catherine Z. Elgin, Reconceptions in<br />

Philosophy and Other Arts and Sciences, London, 1988. Catherine Z. Elgin, With Reference To<br />

Reference, Indianapolis, 1983, offers an extensional rather than nominalist theory of meaning.<br />

29 James Elkins, The Domain of Images, Ithaca/London, 1999, Julian Bell, What is Painting?<br />

London/New York, 1999.


20<br />

applied Goodman’s ideas of pictorial notation to examples that combine writing<br />

and decorative or abstract elements with depiction in various ways. 30 He assumed<br />

this to be a misuse of the theory, (when the theory accounts for the full spectrum of<br />

notation, of which depiction occupies one end) and assumed that even though the<br />

theory is incoherent as an account of depiction, this presented no impediment to its<br />

application to the rest of the notational spectrum. But this is rather like using a<br />

compass, knowing it cannot find true north, but expecting to navigate by the other<br />

directions. Elkins supplemented Goodman’s views with a more traditional view of<br />

pictures as resemblances - although curiously the view is drawn from Wittgenstein<br />

rather than Gombrich, and proposed a two-level model of depiction, one for<br />

resemblance to objects and relations, the other for rules of interpretation. But this<br />

no more than registers the difference between nature and artifice again.<br />

However Elkins also usefully pointed to flaws in Goodman’s argument for<br />

repleteness in the cited but unillustrated example of matching curves for a finance<br />

graph and a drawing of a wave by Hokusai. 31 Not only is it hard to find examples<br />

from these sources that suitably match curves, (although a complete match is not<br />

vital to Goodman’s point) but Goodman’s argument that all of the (hypothetical)<br />

Hokusai drawing’s properties contribute to its meaning, while only the two<br />

dimensional co-ordinates of the graph count as its meaning, rather confuses the<br />

issue. Crucially, matters of the thickness of line or texture of paper, may express, or<br />

exemplify, but do not depict the wave. The wave is not depicted as having a<br />

widening black line riding on its crest, for example. Expression and exemplification<br />

are taken as modes of reference distinct from depiction under Goodman’s theory,<br />

although all three may be present and combined under various schemes. The<br />

mistake is in confusing repleteness of reference, which combines depiction,<br />

expression and exemplification, with mere repleteness of depiction, which perhaps<br />

might amount to the conformity or acceptance of an object under a given scheme,<br />

to its realism in effect. What is otherwise notable in Elkins’ efforts is the<br />

determination to find an integration of writing with pictures and decoration, if not<br />

30 For hostility to Languages of Art see Elkins, 1999, p.66. While not a history of art, The<br />

Domain of Images does include examples of twentieth century abstraction and so is of interest<br />

here. Elkins engages more directly with 20 th century art in What Happened to Art Criticism?<br />

London & Chicago, 2003 (a prelude to a longer study, planned as Success and Failure in<br />

Twentieth Century Painting).<br />

31 Ibid. p.70.


21<br />

as notation, then in some way to say how resemblance relates to these forms of<br />

reference, to the beauty and effectiveness of decoration and design.<br />

Julian Bell’s book on the other hand came with the assistance and endorsement of<br />

Gombrich but a similar hostility to Languages of Art. 32 It ostensibly dealt with<br />

pictorial representation and Modernism, but rapidly sketched along themes of<br />

psychology, philosophy, history and economics, leaped back and forth from ancient<br />

to contemporary art, obscure to familiar works. His grave suspicions about the<br />

nature of expression have much in common with both The Story of Art and Art and<br />

Illusion. Discussion of the Gombrich - Goodman exchange commenced by<br />

considering a realist seascape by William Wylie. 33 Not only did Bell come firmly<br />

down on the side of Gombrich in finding the illusion of the sea compelling (‘we<br />

gaze at the picture and sniff the imaginary brine’) but immediately linked this to the<br />

case against iconography, (and by implication, semiotics) and an appeal once more<br />

to a native substitution or illusion as the basis of depiction. Yet the distinction<br />

between substitution and depiction goes unacknowledged, and the use of such a<br />

concept in a brief account of Goodman’s notational approach, all but renders it<br />

incoherent. What is conspicuous in the book is the slender basis provided by<br />

Gombrich’s views for an adequate account of the art of the twentieth century.<br />

Tellingly, Bell had nothing to say about the closing chapters to The Story of Art, with<br />

their extended criticism of contemporary art and society, and while Bell can at least<br />

accommodate artists such as Stella, Guston and Richter, his story echoed<br />

Gombrich’s as one of dissipation and failure.<br />

What is clear from this review of the problem with pictures is the continuing<br />

stalemate presented by the Gombrich – Goodman exchange, of resemblance versus<br />

reference. Discussion is still brought back to the claims of illusion fostered through<br />

substitution and inherited by depiction and amounting to a conventional or rule<br />

bound ‘illusion’. But is such a claim coherent, much less plausible? Against this,<br />

there are Goodman’s arguments that resemblance is symmetrical, and therefore an<br />

32 Gombrich’s endorsement appears on the front cover, Bell credits Gombrich’s assistance in the<br />

acknowledgements. Bell’s hostility toward Languages of Art registers in the description of its<br />

‘suave insensitivity’. See Bell, 1999, p. 239. His later publication Mirror of the World, London,<br />

New York 2007 looks to a more global history, significantly traces broad humanist themes rather<br />

than stylistic issues.<br />

33 Ibid. pp. 225-230.


22<br />

object ought to represent a picture as much as a picture represents an object, or that<br />

pictures resemble other pictures more than their objects, yet they refer to their<br />

objects more than other pictures. Or, that there are pictures for which there are<br />

strictly no objects for them to resemble, such as pictures of unicorns. Yet for all<br />

this, if pictures denote in order to refer, they apparently do so without a notation.<br />

The following chapter therefore returns to the issue of resemblance versus<br />

reference, to see if something has not been overlooked or unexplored. Since Bell<br />

has performed this service for Gombrich, this study does as much for Goodman.


23<br />

Depiction Revised<br />

The problem for a theory of depiction has been shown to be the reconciliation of<br />

illusion and notation. Neither is adequate, since illusion commits us to a perceptual<br />

mistake, or delusion, which does not square with the facts of everyday experience<br />

with pictures, while notation commits us to a familiar principle of reference, but<br />

cannot explain how such a notation might operate. It can explain in what ways it<br />

must differ from writing, or descriptive notation, but amounts to no more than<br />

saying it is no longer notation. On one hand the proposal is for a resemblance<br />

relation between picture and object, and on the other for a reference relation. Both<br />

agree that sooner or later they need the other, but in acquiring them they also lose<br />

some of their explanation. The illusion theory takes depiction to be tamed or<br />

conventionalised illusions, while the notation theory takes depiction to be a scheme<br />

that cultivates resemblance. But is an illusion still an illusion if it is rule bound? Is a<br />

notation still a notation if it resembles its object? Seemingly, stubbornly, the<br />

relations of resemblance and reference refuse to merge, resemblance is a<br />

symmetrical or two-way relation, reference is asymmetrical or a one-way relation.<br />

The task now is to look a little closer at Goodman’s theory of reference to see if<br />

there is a way around this. Goodman proceeds from arguments about the nature of<br />

reference, based upon denotation, but denotation is not the only mode or route of<br />

reference to his theory. He admits exemplification as the relation between a sample<br />

and referent, or the way in which it points to only some of its properties. 34 For<br />

example a swatch of cloth exemplifies colour, weave, texture and pattern of a<br />

certain type or bolt of cloth, but not its size or shape, age or smell. The swatch has<br />

these other properties, but they are not referred to, or exemplified. Equally the bolt<br />

of cloth has properties that are not possessed or sampled by the swatch, such as its<br />

34 Goodman, 1976, pp.52-57.


24<br />

place and manner of storage. Exemplification is reference to only selected<br />

properties possessed by a sample.<br />

Such reference might also be taken as a way of allowing resemblance. The sample<br />

and its referent share a symmetrical relation in selected respects, they share certain<br />

properties, and yet the sample refers to the type of cloth, while the cloth resembles<br />

in some respects, but does not refer to the sample. The fact that an exemplification<br />

refers only to some of those properties that it possesses, also suggest that it is<br />

reflexive or self-reference. One of Goodman’s objections to taking pictures as<br />

resemblances is that representation, or reference cannot be reflexive, while<br />

resemblance can – ‘An object resembles itself to the maximum degree but rarely<br />

represents itself’ – yet in the case of exemplification it evidently can represent itself<br />

in selected respects. 35 This seems much closer to the requirements for depiction and<br />

suggests that depiction might more profitably be taken as a mode of exemplification<br />

rather than denotation.<br />

The question then arises what is it that a picture exemplifies? What property does it<br />

share with its object and then sample or correctly display? 36 The property is simply<br />

two dimensions, or two-dimensionality. Two dimensions are of course contained<br />

within three dimensions in fact any number of two-dimensional planes may be<br />

constructed as slices within a three-dimensional volume. So we have a shared<br />

property between picture and object, if as yet a very general one. Does it hold for all<br />

depiction? Let us begin with the most basic pictures, for example, a single familiar<br />

object that might be produced by a pre-school, pre-historic or primitive artist,<br />

which is to say, they have basic skills in depiction, and in which is typically offered<br />

an outline or silhouette. Something like two dimensions is detected in the<br />

observation of distinct sides or single aspects of an object or in rudimentary<br />

relations between parts, in an overall profile or shape reliably identified or<br />

resembling an object. Such observations are useful because they are quick to make<br />

and easy to remember. They also make depiction easy to learn.<br />

35 Goodman, 1976, p.4.<br />

36 Although a quirk of language, makes a picture’s object, its subject, following Goodman, the<br />

term ‘object’ is maintained here for any ‘subject’ of a picture.


25<br />

A basic picture also requires the picture surface exemplify, or find the means to<br />

display its two-dimensionality. For the surface is not only a two-dimensional plane<br />

of course, even in the case of a pristine sheet of the smoothest white paper – it is<br />

still a three dimensional object, with a thickness and texture of some kind, whereas<br />

a two-dimensional plane has no thickness, no surface or texture, merely space<br />

extended along two axes. The surface can however exemplify its two-dimensional<br />

plane through the use of distinctive markings or features that not only set it apart<br />

from other kinds of surface, but then also serve to distinguish other kinds of<br />

surfaces or objects, so that properties thus distinguished then also sample materially,<br />

or much as a swatch does, and crucially, may also be taken in combination with<br />

depiction. Equally, such markings may also form distinctive patterns or designs that<br />

need not be taken as a resemblance to an object, or strictly as depiction, yet<br />

nevertheless exemplify two-dimensional elements and relations, and are also<br />

accompanied by the sampling of three-dimensionality, in the kinds of markings and<br />

material used.<br />

Line is the simplest and easiest means of translating perceived planes or shapes of<br />

objects into depiction because the two-sided nature of a line gives the inside and<br />

outside of a shape the same value – as space – in an outline of the shape. The<br />

articulation of the shape depends upon the width of the line, its extent or length,<br />

and its direction, up and down, left or right. This is two-dimensionality proper, even<br />

where the maker or user is unaware of the fact. Similarly, relations between more<br />

than one shape in a depiction share these same fundamental articulations. Once<br />

lines create shapes as outlines, we have two dimensions, and these are shared with,<br />

or truly resemble shapes detected in the sides or single aspects of an object. So we<br />

have resemblance, but do we have reference? The outline refers to an object’s<br />

shape, while an object’s shape does not refer to the outline, because the line is<br />

around the shape, rather than part of it, and is, like the exemplifying practices of a<br />

swatch, a means of displaying two dimensions upon a surface. Hence we have a<br />

one-way reference and a two-way resemblance, in certain selected respects. Line is<br />

obviously not the only means for displaying two dimensions upon a surface, but its<br />

simplicity and efficiency in these basic stages, make it the crucial example. Nor do<br />

outlines necessarily depict the shapes of an observed or three-dimensional object.<br />

Their formal or intrinsic properties as pattern or design may equally develop an


26<br />

appreciation of two-dimensional ordering; suggest fictive versions of extant objects.<br />

While such activities are commonly overlooked in an account of depiction, at the<br />

expense of pursuing parallels with writing and description, an important part of the<br />

revision of depiction lies in re-aligning pictures with patterns. 37 This aspect also<br />

becomes important in the appreciation of abstract painting. But before explaining<br />

this, we need to look briefly at why this attention to two-dimensional judgements is<br />

important.<br />

Firstly, the concept of three dimensions or depth can only be understood in<br />

contrast with two dimensions. So the reason two dimensions are so basic, is because<br />

the concept of three-dimensional space or depth is so basic. A ready objection may<br />

run that we understand three dimensions intuitively – in our ability to navigate to<br />

them, much as Gombrich urges a functional or behavioural definition for such<br />

understanding in a squirrel’s jumping abilities in ‘The Analysis Of Vision’ in Art and<br />

Illusion. 38 The difference is in definitions of understanding. The squirrel’s<br />

understanding of space and light is measured by the behaviourist as its ability to<br />

‘navigate’ them, but to perform more elaborate functions, such as remember,<br />

compare, analyse, measure, construct and communicate, requires a more elaborate<br />

view of understanding, and in this case, a more elaborate understanding of space.<br />

Discerning separate sides to an object, and the shapes associated with them, may<br />

seem an innocent task, but need hardly remain one. Such shapes not only simplify<br />

the tasks of remembering and recognising the object, by breaking it down into<br />

smaller tasks, but it also make more of the object – literally. It discerns more<br />

qualities or properties of the object and so furthers knowledge. Equally,<br />

appreciation of pattern, of measurement and proportion, axes of symmetry,<br />

37 Pattern obviously deserves a far more extensive analysis than space permits. Gombrich<br />

carefully surveyed the history and literature of pattern in the underrated, The Sense of Order,<br />

London, Phaidon, 1979. Notable preceding publications include Owen Jones, The Grammar of<br />

Ornament, London, 1856, Charles Blanc, Art in Ornament and Dress, Paris, 1886, Wilhelm<br />

Ostwald, Die Welt der Form, Entwicklung und Ordnung der gesetzlichschonen Gebilde,<br />

gezeich<strong>net</strong> und beschreiben von Wilhem Ostwald, (4 Vols) Leipzig, 1922-25. Understandably<br />

mathematicians are drawn to questions of two-dimensional geometry, such as Andreas Speiser,<br />

Theorie der Gruppen von endlicher Ordnung, Berlin, 1923, and Herman Weyl in Symmetry,<br />

Princeton, N.J. 1952. Related mathematical insights, are explored in Martin Gardner, The<br />

Ambidextrous Universe, New York, 1964, Michael Holt, Mathematics in Art, London/New York,<br />

1971, and more recently various tiling problems – complex patterns - are considered in Roger<br />

Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind, Oxford/New York, 1990, pp. 168-181 and Penrose, Shadows<br />

of the Mind, Oxford/New York, 1994, pp. 29-33.<br />

38 Gombrich, 1960, p. 276.


27<br />

variations and orientations of a motif, serve to further principles of organisation in<br />

perception and cognition. It is not so much that depiction permits opportunities<br />

unavailable to observers of an object directly, but rather that we make more<br />

opportunities, and more of the opportunities, with depiction. Contrary to<br />

Gombrich’s model of the artist matching a picture to nature, in the manner of<br />

Constable or Cezanne, the appeal more typically is to the picture more removed.<br />

We do not have or need the opportunity to look over the artist’s shoulder and<br />

compare picture with object to appreciate depiction. Rather we test the picture<br />

against our knowledge of such objects and pictures. Hence the crucial role of<br />

memory in basic depiction for the primitive, pre-historic or pre-school artist, the<br />

task is clearly not one of illusion, or even of matching a present object, but of<br />

organising and testing what is known and remembered of an object. In the simplest<br />

of examples, let us take a line drawing of a cat, (Figure A) in the manner favoured<br />

by children and created by conjoining the letters M O Q in ascending scale and<br />

descending sequence, thus:<br />

Figure A<br />

Even in such a basic depiction, we can observe a<br />

surprising number of things about this cat, such as<br />

which way does its tail point? (Left or right?) Is the<br />

cat facing us, or does it sit with its back to us? How<br />

much wider is the cat’s body than its head? Are its<br />

ear raised or lowered? Is it sitting or standing? Is it<br />

looking to the side or ahead? How tall are the ears compared with the head? In<br />

other words, any number of questions concerning measurements, placements, or<br />

plottings, across the two dimensional plane, or certain questions concerning the<br />

object’s position or attitude toward the two dimensional plane, may be answered<br />

even in a basic line drawing. Clearly this is not so much a question of realism as of<br />

resemblance struck on stark linear or two-dimensional terms. There can be no<br />

confusing of the drawing with the actual presence of a cat.<br />

Rather the drawing supplies answers to these questions on just the terms on which<br />

this resemblance is made. Indeed the power and pleasure of such basic pictures lies<br />

entirely in their appeal to memory and the understanding that guides resemblance.


28<br />

Neither the primitive, pre-historic or pre-school picture-maker concern themselves<br />

with the presence of a model for this reason; two dimensions are easier to keep in<br />

the head than the eye. A basic picture is a way of testing this memory and<br />

prompting closer understanding. The understanding is of both the depicted object<br />

and the scheme or style of depiction. The thick and wobbling line used here<br />

samples a given tool upon a surface in contrast with surrounding text and scale of<br />

font, and an uncertain level of expertise. The sample sorts the depiction against the<br />

materials used, understands materials as well as depiction.<br />

So a basic picture essentially maps or outlines a shape of an object. Indeed maps<br />

offer another good example of why two dimensions prove so useful. One is free to<br />

chart up and down, left and right, in any order, any direction or combination of<br />

directions. A map offers any number of routes, and allows one to comprehend the<br />

terrain across and between as well as along given routes. Depiction is thus bracketed<br />

with maps, diagrams, patterns and other two-dimensional schemas, because this<br />

multi-directional mapping stands in stark contrast with denotative or descriptive<br />

modes of reference. The difference arises because language and language-based<br />

references are committed to a temporal and one-directional ordering. Time may<br />

cease to be one-way in sub-atomic or macrocosmic physics, but for the sizeable<br />

stretch in between that is our main concern, it remains reliably one-way. Two<br />

dimensions of course exclude not only depth but also time, and depictions allow us<br />

to look at objects and scenes in more than one way or indeed more than one<br />

direction because of this. They may lack movement - without time - but a freeze<br />

frame, as is now so familiar, allows scrutiny of qualities unavailable in the flow of<br />

motion. A prompt objection may be that surely comic strips, film and television<br />

demonstrate that depiction and two-dimensionality need not exclude time. But the<br />

succession of images available in these examples remain fixed in a single sequence<br />

and even where they may be viewed in reverse, the sequence remains the same, we<br />

may reverse direction of a route in some circumstances, but we cannot re-route any<br />

given image in the sequence. Each image remains a given moment, and the value of<br />

the freeze frame lies precisely in what its route or motion has concealed. The point<br />

of two-dimensional perception and depiction is really to supplement a temporally<br />

ordered perception, with a spatial one, as a way to see out of time or around time,<br />

and something more of the world.


29<br />

The distinction between time and space is by no means new to discussion of<br />

depiction. It is most notably identified with Lessing’s famous essay on The Laocoon,<br />

and more recently has been the subject of an extended analysis by W. J. T.<br />

Mitchell. 39 Here the arrangement shares none of Lessing’s critical or prescriptive<br />

principles concerning art, indeed, as will become clearer in later chapters, the<br />

position is quite the opposite, recognising a complementary function to the two<br />

modes. Mitchell is largely concerned with detecting ideological tendencies beneath<br />

Lessing’s view, which need not concern us here, however it is worth noting that his<br />

attempt to demolish the time/space distinction, by claiming the difference between<br />

pictures and language as one of degree rather than kind, is one based upon a<br />

conception of pictures as a mode of denotation – after Goodman – and obviously<br />

rejected here. 40<br />

A new theory of depiction as a mode of exemplification, sampling twodimensionality<br />

has now been outlined. The theory adheres to Goodman’s<br />

framework of reference, and maintains the functions of exemplification and<br />

denotation. It accepts the syntactic and semantic analysis of notation, but finds<br />

analogue densities finally at odds with these terms, and of limited use in<br />

understanding depiction. 41 The revision is not that drastic in the larger scheme of<br />

things, as shall be shown. The new theory reconciles the requirements of a<br />

resemblance and a reference relation and avoids the commitment to an illusion in<br />

the recognition of two-dimensionality on a surface, and to a notation in its<br />

structure. An illusion may occur in as much as two-dimensions may be mistaken for<br />

three dimensions, but in general this is not the experience of looking at a picture,<br />

and part of the reason we have dwelt upon the simplest of line drawings is to<br />

emphasise this. A picture remains a reference or a representation, in as much as the<br />

39 Mitchell, ‘Space and Time: Lessing’s Laocoon and the Politics of Genre’ in Iconology, Image,<br />

Text, Ideology, Chicago/London, 1994, pp 95-115. G. E. Lessing, ‘Laocoon’ in Laocoon, Nathan<br />

the Wise, Minna von Barnelm, London/New York, 1930.<br />

40 Mitchell, 1994, p.102. In passing, Mitchell’s subsequent attempt to lump all artefacts together<br />

as ‘spatio/temporal structures’ seems less than useful, distinguishing neither between forms of<br />

art, objects or reference.<br />

41 Since depiction is so closely tied to two-dimensionality here, depiction used in discussion<br />

elsewhere, in sculpture, drama and literature for example, is consigned to loose talk. While<br />

sculpture is mainly concerned with three-dimensionality or material sampling, and so shares<br />

resemblance with depiction, in drama and literature depiction at best refers to a density or<br />

circumspection of reference, especially linked with depiction, and dealt with in Chapter Five.


30<br />

surface is altered or marked in such a way as to exemplify its two-dimensional<br />

properties, but this system is not a notation, because of its multi-directional<br />

character.<br />

But while this formulation allows for a distinction between patterns and pictures,<br />

the demarcation begs further attention. For example, simple symmetrical shapes<br />

such as a circle or a square are not generally understood as a picture of a circle or a<br />

square, but just as an instance or presentation rather than a representation. This is<br />

not to say that pictures cannot include a circle or square, or be of a circle or square<br />

in some further three-dimensional scene, or indeed use a circle or square to depict<br />

some three-dimensional object, only that a circle or square are often used for either<br />

purpose. The same outline may serve as either or both, a lesson in geometry or<br />

linear depiction. Just when a circle depicts a sphere or disc as opposed to merely<br />

instantiating a circle, is by no means clear-cut, but is largely a matter of scheme and<br />

style, even when schemes and styles allow ambiguity. But rather than pursue stylistic<br />

features directly, the next chapter tests this theory of depiction against more<br />

elaborate kinds of picture and issues raised by other theories. Implications to the<br />

reshuffle of reference within Goodman’s theory are also to be traced along this<br />

path.


31<br />

Depiction Pursued<br />

Five Issues<br />

This chapter looks at how the proposed theory of depiction handles more elaborate<br />

kinds of pictures and at the issues raised by other theories. First and foremost there<br />

is the issue of depth, and the controversy surrounding systems of projection and<br />

perspective. A second and related kind of picture is the distortion derived from an<br />

unusual lens, such as an anamorphic lens, which perhaps raises the question<br />

whether a surface’s two-dimensional markings can adequately explain our<br />

recognition of such pictures. The third issue concerns caricature, which resembles<br />

its object paradoxically, by exaggerating features and relations. A fourth and<br />

surprisingly similar issue is that of fiction, and whether a depiction of a fictional<br />

entity such as a unicorn or Homer Simpson, can truly be said to resemble their<br />

objects? (When there truly are no objects for them to resemble). Finally there are<br />

those depictions found in an idle gaze at stains on a wall or in the shapes of foliage<br />

or clouds, and whether these are truly surfaces, adequately exemplified as twodimensionality?<br />

1. Depth<br />

So far we have looked at how two dimensions can be exemplified and depict one<br />

side or aspect of an object, and build a basic picture plane. Having established this<br />

basic two-dimensionality or picture plane, further developments are essentially<br />

concerned with how to accommodate more than one side of an object upon this<br />

plane, or conversely, construct two-dimensionality at more remote and<br />

sophisticated angles to the object. The move is ultimately to accommodate depth, or<br />

three-dimensionality; to map features not only in terms of up and down, left and<br />

right but back and forward. But where two dimensions are contained in three and


32<br />

may be detected and displayed accordingly, three dimensions obviously do not ‘go<br />

into’ two. Depth must be treated differently.<br />

John Willats has demonstrated how much of this development, both in children’s<br />

pictures, and in the history of art, echoes the aims and methods of various schemes<br />

of descriptive geometry, and its elementary projections of orthogonal, oblique, and<br />

parallel oblique schemes, and various perspectives. 42 Willats rightly stresses the folly<br />

of seeing a ‘recapitulation’ or an evolutionary agenda in the comparison between<br />

children’s pictorial competence and various stages of art history, and instead points<br />

to the distinct uses for various projections and perspectives, and the shifting<br />

requirements made of pictures throughout art history.<br />

But before discussing kinds of depth, some elementary distinctions between<br />

projections and perspectives should be noted (Figure B). The basic pictures so far<br />

considered conform to<br />

orthogonal projection,<br />

and align the picture<br />

plane to one side of the<br />

depicted object. Oblique<br />

projections essentially<br />

align the edge of two<br />

sides of an object with<br />

the picture plane, using<br />

either a horizontal edge<br />

or a vertical edge. While<br />

this is clumsy as a<br />

description, it is probably<br />

more familiar in examples<br />

Figure B<br />

of photography, where a long lens is used for close-ups of distant<br />

objects, and which thereby ‘flattens’ the adjacent sides of an object<br />

against the picture plane. More adventurously, parallel oblique schemes propose a<br />

42 John Willats, Art and Representation: New Principles in the Analysis of Pictures, Princeton,<br />

N.J. 1997. Figure B is owed to this publication.


33<br />

diagonal, or oblique angle to one or more adjoining sides, as distinct from simply a<br />

diagonal shape to a side, and now serves as basically a third axis, in between the<br />

vertical and horizontal axes of the picture plane. Again, this is a view available to<br />

long lens photography and something easily found in non-pictorial or plain<br />

perception. Parallel oblique projections thus register depth at an ascending angle for<br />

objects, while vertical or horizontal planes contained, remain constant in size or<br />

length to the picture plane.<br />

Perspective supplies one or more vanishing points, according to a notional or not<br />

necessarily included, horizon. The difference between parallel oblique projections<br />

and perspectives is rather like the difference in photography between using long and<br />

wide lenses, for close and distant objects. In fact the wider the lens, the more<br />

vanishing points a scheme introduces, a very wide lens gives a ‘fisheye’ depiction,<br />

with vanishing points at every point on the perimeter of the necessarily circular<br />

picture plane. Yet we can still make sense of the picture, we can still ‘see’ in this<br />

way, even if it seems uncomfortable or unnatural. The issue of artifice and nature is<br />

returned to shortly. Here a little more of Willat’s position needs to be appreciated.<br />

While Willats is anxious to emphasise the varying uses for these schemes of depth<br />

and to some extent their co-existence, nevertheless his view of the development of<br />

pictorial depth, still places perspectives as the goal to which a picture ‘faithful’ to the<br />

principles of visual perception aspires. In this he adheres to the tradition that draws<br />

upon the work of the psychology of visual perception, particularly the work of J. J.<br />

Gibson, R. L. Gregory, Gregory’s collaborations with Gombrich, and the fieldwork<br />

of John M. Kennedy. 43 It is a view of perception that rests upon an optical stimulus,<br />

or information transmitted by the rays of light, reflected from an object to the<br />

viewer, which then allows the viewer to perceive the object. In the case of<br />

depiction, the rays of light are called upon to carry two lots of information, firstly<br />

about the picture surface, and secondly about the object depicted. Gibson<br />

characterises this information as ‘invariants’ that separate out the distance, surfaces<br />

and contours of an object, from accidental effects of time or motion, for example.<br />

Yet Gibson’s behavioural or evolutionist bias leads him to look for invariants on<br />

43 James J Gibson, The Perception Of The Visual World, Boston, 1950, R. L. Gregory, The<br />

Intelligent Eye, London, 1970, E.H Gombrich and R.L. Gregory, Illusion in Art and Nature,<br />

London, 1973, John M. Kennedy, The Psychology Of Picture Perception, San Francisco, 1974.


34<br />

only the crudest of ‘environmental’ bases, so that two-dimensionality for example,<br />

eludes him. Willats thus inherits a view of depiction as exchanging rules or<br />

conventions for depth with a more vivid experience or illusion, in keeping with a<br />

plain or natural perception.<br />

Yet as shown, we see depth in any number ways and for any number of reasons.<br />

Not only are such ways familiar to the conventions of photography as well as<br />

drawing, but to our plain or non-pictorial experience. The eye’s lens, like a camera’s<br />

lenses, is variable, and if it has an invariant it is variation. The appeal to a native<br />

perception guided only by principles of surfaces, contours, occluding lines, planes<br />

and so forth, is no more than a behaviourist’s makeover for the innocent eye, and in<br />

denial of a more than visual mind. To quote Goodman (ironically, in support of<br />

Gombrich):<br />

The eye comes always ancient to its work, obsessed by its own past, and by<br />

old and new insinuations of the ear, nose, tongue, fingers heart and brain. It<br />

functions not as an instrument self-empowered and alone, but as a dutiful<br />

member of a complex and capricious organism. Not only how but what it<br />

sees is regulated by need and prejudice. It selects, rejects, organizes,<br />

discriminates, associates, classifies, analyses, constructs. 44<br />

Goodman’s firm rejection of Gibson and Gombrich’s view of perspective and the<br />

perception of depth fuelled a long-standing controversy between theorists deriving<br />

their views from principles of optics, and those deriving their views from symbol<br />

systems such as Erwin Panofsky or Meyer Schapiro, and opposing schools of<br />

psychology such as Arnheim, and Goodman, who combines both. 45 The argument<br />

is essentially over whether perception is natural or conventional, inherent or<br />

learned. In the earlier exchange noted between Gombrich and Goodman they find<br />

common ground in the acceptance that some conventions allow for others, or that<br />

conventions are built upon conventions, and therefore some seem comparatively<br />

natural, others artificial. But Goodman then asked where do we draw the line? And<br />

is it important? 46 Pursuing the most natural is a path of infinite regress.<br />

44 Goodman, 1976, pp. 7-8.<br />

45 See for example the exchange in articles by Goodman, Gibson and Gombrich in Leonardo,<br />

1971, No 4. See also Panofsky, ‘Die Perspective als symbolische Form’ in Aufsatze, 1927, pp.<br />

99-167. Schapiro, Modern Art: 19 th and 20 th Centuries, New York, 1978, pp. 185-211, Arnheim,<br />

Art and Visual Perception Berkeley/Los Angeles, 1954.<br />

46 Gombrich, 1982, p. 284.


35<br />

Clearly Willats was unimpressed by such relativism. Yet the problem cannot be<br />

ignored, and ultimately undermines much of his findings. For example, concerning<br />

the chapter on optical denotations where he claims ‘very few artists have, in fact,<br />

attempted to replicate the appearance of the optic array directly’ - there is a<br />

disturbing lack of awareness of the sheer futility of the suggestion. 47 Not only is<br />

there no way to replicate light with paint ‘directly’, but ‘the appearance’ of the optic<br />

array surely depends upon what is being looked for, and how, in Gombrich’s terms,<br />

what can be matched depends upon what can be made. The extensive studies by<br />

Gombrich concerning just this question, and concluding with just this answer, seem<br />

to have been lost on Willats, all the more curious since Gombrich is a much cited<br />

source as well as something of a mentor. 48 Similarly, summary of Seurat’s approach<br />

to painting as ‘an artificial pictorial effect that refers to the effects of light but does<br />

not replicate them directly’ (my italics) commits him to the twin follies of a belief in<br />

pictorial effects that are not ‘artificial’, and a belief that light might somehow be<br />

substituted with paint. 49<br />

Turning to the matter of depicting several related objects and to options available to<br />

projections and perspectives, the picture plane may firstly accommodate more than<br />

one object by extending laterally or vertically. In the case of the ancient Egyptians,<br />

lateral extension also introduces a reduced directionality to the picture, and a<br />

tentative step toward writing. Two-dimensional mapping or ‘topological’ relations as<br />

Willats terms them, also result in the ‘fold-out’ picture, identified by A. L. Nicholls<br />

and J. M. Kennedy in the work of young children, and by Willats in icons of the<br />

Byzantine and Orthodox churches. 50 Here, adjacent objects in a scene may be<br />

depicted from conflicting aspects – a house seen from in front, a field seen from<br />

above, but sharing an edge as an of axis upon which one might ‘fold’ the picture to<br />

create a three dimensional model.<br />

47 Willats, 1997, p. 133.<br />

48 Ibid. p. xii. See also Gombrich, 1960, pp. 313-314, ‘For if we have learned anything in the<br />

course of these chapters it is that representation is never a replica. The forms of art, ancient and<br />

modern, are not duplications of what the artist has in mind any more than they are duplications of<br />

what he sees in the outer world’.<br />

49 Willats, 1997, p. 145.<br />

50 Nicholls and Kennedy, ‘Drawing development from similarity of features to direction’ in Child<br />

Development: 63, 1992, pp. 227-241. Willats, 1997, pp. 194-199.


36<br />

The fold-out picture may also be seen as a kind of collage or made up of a series of<br />

smaller pictures, each of a single object, and related to one other so that each shares<br />

a common axis and dimension, while their second, conflicting axis – it need not run<br />

at 90 degrees, need not be readily ‘foldable’ - constructs divergent versions of the<br />

picture plane. Depth or a third dimension here is understood in just these terms: as<br />

simply a realignment of each object/picture plane’s axes. Various kinds of multiple<br />

pictures arise, combining various projections and even perspectives, and some of<br />

these are dealt with as anomalies and some as plain ineptitude by Willats. The<br />

tradition of Persian and Indian miniatures offers many examples of depth and scale<br />

jumps that are often reminiscent of modern photo-collages, and while the use to<br />

which such a technique may be put is clear, predictably Willats concludes:<br />

Thus, although individual parts of the scene look strongly threedimensional,<br />

the eye cannot make sense of the space of the scene as a<br />

whole, and this destroys the illusion of a real three-dimensional scene and<br />

flattens the picture. 51<br />

Tactfully, one might reply that it depends on which mind the eye serves. More<br />

constructively, one might suggest that more than one look, or more than one<br />

perspective are also properties of vision, that we do not necessarily look only in one<br />

direction, or on one focal length, or from one position, in viewing a scene, let alone<br />

a picture.<br />

Beyond the foldout or multiple pictures, there is the development of more<br />

integrated approaches to depth. The picture plane, while initially aligned with a<br />

single side of an object, introduces additional and unaligned sides (or parallel<br />

oblique projections) These are the elementary projections that emphasise one<br />

corner of an object – and promptly confound Gombrich’s famous axiom for the<br />

development of perspective, namely that it ‘rests on a simple and incontrovertible<br />

fact of experience, the fact that we cannot look around a corner’. 52 Projections<br />

progress to the alignment of axis or connecting edge of two adjacent sides, leaving<br />

both or more unaligned, and hence understood as receding in depth from the<br />

aligned edge. These are the isometric, diametric and trimetric oblique projections<br />

illustrated in Figure B. In each case the picture plane is gradually separated or<br />

51 Willats, 1997, p. 228.<br />

52 Gombrich, 1960, p. 250.


37<br />

distanced from a direct alignment with the object and becomes instead a ‘slice’<br />

across a three-dimensional space or the traditionally understood ‘window’ frame<br />

before the object. In this there is general agreement with the findings of David Marr<br />

and associates, of a development from object-centred descriptions to view or scenecentred<br />

descriptions. 53<br />

The achievement of perspective, in this view, is precisely the realisation that a twodimensional<br />

plane may be constructed anywhere within a three dimensional space,<br />

and that it need not align itself wholly or solely with solid objects, but instead locate<br />

itself in relation to an horizon and one or more vanishing points. It is this flexibility,<br />

rather than its illusionary properties, that play an important role in the dominance of<br />

perspective as a pictorial tradition. Vanishing points allow depth to be understood,<br />

not in terms of any one oblique plane or angle, but as all planes or edges aligned to<br />

a vanishing point and the picture plane. It allows for a greater integration of objects,<br />

in a number of interesting ways, but the point here is simply that horizon and<br />

vanishing points provide further means of constructing three dimensions from two.<br />

2. Distortion<br />

An argument made against a two-dimensional view of the picture surface, and in<br />

favour of an optical view of perception, concerns the recognition of distorted<br />

images, such as an anamorphic image, that can only be viewed correctly when the<br />

viewer stands to the side of the picture surface rather than in front of it. Kennedy<br />

claims that such depictions support the view that it is the optical information<br />

supplied by the surface, or the light rays reflected from it, that enable the perception<br />

of a depiction, rather than the surface ‘itself’, or the surface unviewed, or perhaps<br />

the surface understood as various markings viewed only from in front of the picture<br />

surface, and presumably in a ‘light-free’ environment. 54<br />

Taking the example of a photographic plate, he argues that it is the chemical’s<br />

structure rather than the chemical’s distribution on the picture surface that directs<br />

53 Marr, ‘Representing visual information: a computational approach,’ in Computer Vision, A. R.<br />

Hanson and E. M. Riseman (eds.) New York, 1978, pp. 61-80 and Marr, Vision: A<br />

Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual<br />

Information, San Francisco, 1982.<br />

54 Kennedy, 1974, p.36.


38<br />

the light. But since the chemical’s distribution is surely part of its structure, this<br />

distinction too fails to isolate the picture surface from the light reflected from it.<br />

‘Any theory that relies on descriptions of elements and their distribution on a<br />

surface is inconvenienced by anamorphics’ he concludes, but no more<br />

inconvenienced than the viewer, of either the surface or its light isolated from each<br />

other. 55 The argument fails because it assumes the surface is to be described from<br />

only one angle - in front - while its light allows another option. But the description<br />

of the surface is the description of its reflected light. We view an anamorphic<br />

picture with light, whether we stand in front or to the side of a picture, only one<br />

view easily supplies us with a picture, but this viewing condition supplies us with the<br />

‘informative light’ only because it issues from an ‘informative’ surface, or the<br />

surface rightly taken, or so sampled.<br />

3. Caricature<br />

The issue of caricature poses problems for a theory of depiction in as much it<br />

allows deliberate exaggeration or distortion of an object for comic effect, while still<br />

preserving the object’s resemblance and identity. On the one hand we readily<br />

recognise the object, while on the other we are aware that it does not ‘really’ look<br />

this way. Apart from the surprise and humour that results, the issue draws forth<br />

several deeper questions concerning the resemblance we hold for an object, the<br />

expressive, and accidental qualities we allow it, the means by which these are<br />

brought about in depiction.<br />

Gombrich and Wollheim make important contributions to the issue and Willats has<br />

also made some interesting suggestions concerning topological functions for<br />

caricature. 56 But here attention remains on certain converging interests of<br />

Gombrich and Wollheim. 57 Gombrich’s treatment covers a broader range of<br />

caricature, dealing with both the caricature of certain persons as well as the<br />

whimsical creations of Walt Disney or James Thurber. He points firstly to the<br />

wholistic and complex nature of perceived likenesses in portraits, and faces in<br />

general, and to the difficulty of settling on a characteristic expression for an<br />

55 Kennedy, 1974, p.36.<br />

56 Willats, 1997, p. 72.<br />

57 Gombrich, 1960, pp. 279-303. Wollheim, 1987, pp. 69-70.


39<br />

individual, as well as a characteristic expression for general states of mind, such as<br />

happiness or despair (which can often look alike). For Gombrich this process<br />

amplifies his view of pictorial development, as one of schema and correction. A<br />

schema is a traditional means or format that is tested with some new aim or task,<br />

and if successful, is ‘corrected’ to include this aim, or is recognised as a new, in this<br />

case, funnier version of the tradition. With caricature the correction occurs not by<br />

trying to observe some new or different part of an object, but rather by<br />

deconstructing or toying with the means, and then testing to see if it still matches or<br />

resembles the object. For Gombrich the humorous side of this is bound up with<br />

dark psychological taboos concerning unconscious hostilities toward the object. But<br />

humour apart, this model also suggests the uneasy relation between expression and<br />

representation, between shifting properties attributed to an object, and their impact<br />

upon its identity.<br />

For the moment it is enough to indicate how this issue leads directly to that of<br />

expression. Expression is addressed in the following essay. Wollheim’s contribution<br />

finds its clearest account in Painting as an Art. 58 His view is bound up in a discussion<br />

of the kinds of things that can be painted and depicted generally. His categories for<br />

depictive content take the form of a cross-classification that runs along one axis<br />

from objects to events, and along the other from particulars to kinds. A particular<br />

object such as the portrait of Madame Moitessier by J. A. D. Ingres, is made up of<br />

kinds of particulars, so to speak, such as a portrait of a woman, a young person, a<br />

French citizen, born in the early ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century, middle class, self-assured, and<br />

so on. One constructs the individual according to which kinds one knows and sees<br />

them belonging to - except in the case of caricatures - where a person may be<br />

depicted as belonging to an impossible kind, such as an animal or, in the example<br />

used by both Wollheim and Gombrich, the French emperor Louis Phillippe turning<br />

into a pear in Les Poires by Phillipon.<br />

The idea of caricature as a misclassing has parallels with Gombrich’s model of<br />

schema and correction and the experimental or testing nature of depiction, although<br />

Wollheim does not pursue its application outside of persons, to a dog in a Thurber<br />

or Disney cartoon, for example. What is important about Wollheim’s formulation is<br />

58 Wollheim, 1987, pp. 69-71.


40<br />

its location within the categories outlined. Caricatures play with the misuse of kinds,<br />

but more earnest depiction relies upon the same ladders of kinds, rendering an<br />

object in degree of particularity. The difference between seeing a picture of a young<br />

woman and just seeing a young woman for example, is taken to lie in the greater<br />

particularity of the direct perception. 59 Yet the danger lies in offering an example<br />

purely by description, or without illustration, for the young woman hypothetically<br />

pictured, is surely located after a fashion, perhaps even to a time of day, and even<br />

when we do not learn the name and history of the young woman from the picture<br />

(a situation that may equally apply to direct perception), pictures of young women<br />

come in many kinds, from the formal portraits by Ingres, to the Madonnas of<br />

Raphael, the ballet students of Degas, the sun bathers of Renoir, and the<br />

housewives of Vermeer, for example. The particular proliferates in pictures as<br />

vigorously as in direct perception. Then again, while kinds are as common to<br />

pictures as to direct perception, yet they differ as much between direct perceptions<br />

as between pictures. So again, direct perception offers no clear model for depictive<br />

meaning. These issues are given a very different treatment by Goodman, but his<br />

discussion of caricature centres mainly on representing-as, as when a person is<br />

depicted as a pear, or vice versa, and will be considered under the following issue of<br />

fiction.<br />

However, the philosopher Stephanie Ross has provided a useful discussion of<br />

caricature, in terms strikingly consonant with Goodman’s theory. 60 She pointed<br />

firstly to the problem of establishing caricature as an exaggeration of distinctive,<br />

standard or truthful features of the object. No such features may be reliably<br />

identified. They depend upon too many conflicting interests, and kinds of pictures.<br />

Yet caricature remains a reliable category, we rarely revise what is and is not a<br />

caricature, even if acknowledging a grey area. Indeed, we can often judge a picture<br />

to be a caricature without fully identifying the object. She further argued that the<br />

practice of caricature does not require necessary and sufficient conditions, that not<br />

only can we recognise caricature on the basis of experience with pictures, take and<br />

treat them differently from other pictures, but also that our experience in these<br />

matters extends to direct perception and - crucially for Goodman’s theory - to the<br />

59 Wollheim, 1987, p. 71.<br />

60 Ross, ‘Caricature’ in The Monist, 58, 1974, pp. 284-293.


41<br />

projection of predicates. 61 Predicates and projection will also be explained under the<br />

issue of fiction. In stressing the interdependence of pictures and direct perception in<br />

complex projection, Ross effectively denies Wollheim’s distinction as well.<br />

Yet Ross’s account still leaves the problem of caricatures as pictures that are ‘less<br />

realistic and which demand we see reality (which includes people and pictures) in<br />

terms of them’. 62 In other words, there is still the paradox of the unrealistic<br />

somehow accepted as realistic. To remedy this we can firstly distinguish caricature<br />

from other less realistic pictures, for example note that caricature typically does not<br />

just build a novel perspective, such as that of a fisheye lens, nor does it achieve the<br />

complexity of a portrait by Picasso or Goya, to use Ross’s examples. So caricature is<br />

neither in the business of a comprehensive system of depth nor an especially<br />

complex version of the object. Rather, how it pictures is a matter of mere pastiche<br />

and parody, recognisable in itself, as noted. The ridicule is directed as much to the<br />

basics of drawing and portraiture as it is to its object, and because it is bound much<br />

more closely to norms of depiction it is both more superficial and amusing as well<br />

as more dependent upon a standard and familiar object. Thus we have pictures about<br />

realism, rather than realistic pictures, and objects that easily survive such minor<br />

versions. Finally, Ross rightly pointed to the parallels between metaphor and<br />

caricature. Not all caricature strictly functions as metaphor, but both ‘inhabit a<br />

continuum with literal ways of depicting reality’ and ‘are vehicles for conciseness,<br />

novelty and economy of expression’. Differences between strict depictive metaphor,<br />

or allegory, and caricature come under greater scrutiny when the study looks to the<br />

history of painting in the closing decades of the twentieth century.<br />

4. Fiction<br />

Like caricature, fiction involves the ability to deal in particulars and kinds,<br />

individuals and classes. Yet fiction asks a more pointed question of theories of<br />

depiction based upon resemblance, since there are no actual or existential objects<br />

for pictures of unicorns or Homer Simpson to resemble. Intuitively, one might<br />

suppose a resemblance to a kind of horse, with a horn on its forehead, or to a kind<br />

of middle-aged man, bald, sallow complexion, five o’clock shadow, pronounced<br />

61 Ross, 1974, pp. 284-293.<br />

62 Ibid. p. 291.


42<br />

exophthalmia, will suffice. But where reference is understood as strictly to actual<br />

individual objects, they will not. For Goodman, pictures, like names, obtain<br />

predicates, and a nominalist ontology requires fictive pictures be taken firstly to<br />

depict or denote no actual or individual object, or as null-denotation. 63 A nulldenotation<br />

is understood to reverse the direction of its reference, to point to (or<br />

place its predicate in) only a sort of picture. A unicorn-picture or a Homer Simpsonpicture,<br />

are here the preferred nomenclature, taken as a more accurate indication of<br />

reference direction, rather than implying there is an actual object, or a predicate<br />

extended beyond the fictive picture.<br />

Null denotation thus directs reference to the way we use or sort pictures, even at<br />

the expense of having a further or actual object. Expanding on sorts of pictures is<br />

not an idle exercise, as pictures of actual objects must all belong to sorts of pictures,<br />

must be an x-picture of a y-object, and sometimes a y-as-x-picture. A unicornpicture<br />

or a Homer Simpson-picture go to organising the workings of pictures in<br />

the same way as class terms sort pictures of young women as young womenpictures,<br />

not that all pictures containing young women need be classed as young<br />

women-pictures, or that young women-pictures need contain only young women.<br />

Importantly, the sorting of pictures and objects does not in Goodman’s view<br />

require prior definitions or acquaintance with rules. It proceeds by trial and error,<br />

practice and precedent, can learn sort of picture from object or vice versa, and<br />

complies with consensus. This urges the parallel with language acquisition, and the<br />

commitment to depiction taken as denotation. Yet Goodman’s view also aligns<br />

fiction with fundamental processes of classification and construal, and fiction duly<br />

emerges a more dignified and vital activity.<br />

How is this nominalist view of fiction reconciled within a view of depiction as<br />

exemplification? 64 If anything the view of depiction as exemplification makes it<br />

clearer that fictive or null depiction functions as a form of self-reference, requiring a<br />

two-way or resemblance relation. In exchanging null denotation for null depiction,<br />

the study exchanges the notion of a null yet converse denotation, for the two-way<br />

63 Goodman, 1976, pp. 21-26.<br />

64 Although Goodman explicitly denies that exemplification may be fictive (Goodman, 1984, p.<br />

60) this is taken here to apply to material exemplification, or exemplification of threedimensional<br />

properties, rather than depictive exemplification.


43<br />

reference of exemplification. The proposed theory therefore allows resemblance for<br />

fictive pictures, but only to sorts of pictures, through effective sample. Depiction<br />

may still be allied to predication. Nominalism is available even in the absence of<br />

denotation. However for ease of exposition the study remains Platonist and talk<br />

henceforth remains of properties rather than predicates.<br />

5. Found Depiction<br />

Natural objects may also exhibit depiction, such as the faces and figures found in<br />

stains on a wall, the moon, clouds or foliage. Their occurrence is generally taken as a<br />

contributing factor, to a greater or lesser extent, in the discovery or invention of<br />

depiction. Wollheim in particular places great emphasis upon them, and upon our<br />

natural ability to ‘see-in’ and find such depictions. 65 Gombrich devotes a chapter to<br />

their ability to provide suggestive ‘schemas’, which our projections can ‘correct’, and<br />

in this way serve as a source of inspiration for artists. 66 Neither view is disputed<br />

here; rather the opportunity is taken to point to something more these objects share<br />

with the perception of two dimensions.<br />

It is an obvious but overlooked quality, and it is not always associated with a<br />

surface. It may arise amongst disparate objects seen in silhouette, or in a space<br />

between the shapes of clouds. What occurs is the perception of a certain irregularity<br />

and complexity of structure that taxes expectations or familiarity with certain<br />

objects or spaces. We are caught up in unexpected detail, and look for a simpler way<br />

of organising it. We see faces and figures because we have the most elaborate and<br />

elastic constructs for these objects, and they are equally mobile or organic objects as<br />

a result. They are wilfully misapplied in such depiction, as an experiment in<br />

obtaining a simpler or more familiar configuration. They need not be illusions. That<br />

depends how wilfully they are misapplied. It is unlikely, or extremely difficult to find<br />

a depiction of a microwave or a lawnmower for example, in stains or clouds,<br />

because our perceptions of these objects lack the elasticity to accommodate enough<br />

variation, and equally difficult to find such depictions in the plain perception of<br />

complex but regular objects such as an air conditioning grill or bookshelf.<br />

65 Wollheim, 1987, pp. 48-51.<br />

66 Gombrich, 1960, pp. 154-169.


44<br />

In explaining how a surface must exemplify two dimensions in order to function as<br />

depiction, the need to ensure that the markings on the surface stand out, or alert us<br />

to their special quality as a surface, has been noted. In fact they function in much<br />

the same way as the examples drawn from nature, in foiling perception of the<br />

picture surface, as other than exemplifying two dimensions. In nature we find<br />

depictions when we cannot find enough that is predictable and simple in our<br />

perceptions, and in culture we find depictions when we learn how to reorganise<br />

surfaces, in special ways.<br />

Conclusion<br />

The proposed theory of depiction now stands consolidated by engagement with five<br />

key issues. The theory takes depth as variously constructed by schemes of<br />

projection and perspective, in projection by angle contrasted with axes of picture<br />

plane, in perspective by angles determined by nominated horizon and vanishing<br />

points. It ranges schemes according to integration of object with picture plane, to<br />

behind or beyond it. Expanding on schemes amounts to expanding on sorts of<br />

objects depicted and presents opportunities for caricature and fiction. Caricature is<br />

taken as in Gombrich and Wollheim, to be a testing of objects and pictures, and as<br />

in Ross, to be a practice that requires neither ready recognition nor resemblance for<br />

the object, nor fixed features to a scheme or style. Caricature is also interesting<br />

because it prompts the issue of expression, and with it draws depiction toward a<br />

theory of art. Similarly, fiction is taken as a further means of construction for<br />

schemes of picture and object, and available to Goodman’s nominalist ontology, by<br />

null-depiction, rather than null-denotation. The issues of distortion and found<br />

depiction here allow us to distinguish between optic conditions and favoured or<br />

available schemes for depiction, their accidental occurrence and frail conformity.<br />

Having established this broader foundation for the proposed theory, it now turns to<br />

five further issues, in expression and style (together), art and its history (together)<br />

interpretation, realism and painting.


45<br />

Expression and Style<br />

The issue of expression arose in considering caricature and the issue of style arose<br />

in Chapter Two concerning classification and practice of exemplification. This<br />

chapter traces important links between the two, looks firstly at their treatment<br />

under Goodman’s theory and shows how depiction taken as exemplification now<br />

requires some further distinction to accommodate expression, but remains<br />

consistent with Goodman’s views on reference and stylistics. The position is then<br />

contrasted with those of Gombrich and Wollheim.<br />

What is expressive and usually amusing in caricature is the latitude or variation<br />

granted the object and its sort of picture. But even caricatures vary in degree of<br />

expressiveness as well as in what is expressed, and expression is not only or even<br />

mostly by caricature. Expression in reference is commonly understood as a matter<br />

of how as opposed to what is stated. Obviously not all reference or statements are<br />

counted equally or especially expressive, rather expression registers only where<br />

means or ends offer surprising or novel variation. What is expressed in a statement<br />

sometimes amounts to the ways it departs from standard accounts, identifies a<br />

novel aspect or point of view to an issue or object. But expression more typically is<br />

a matter of how rather than what is stated, depends upon tone of voice, rhetoric<br />

and other performance in utterance, upon vocabulary and syntax in writing and<br />

especially figures of speech, sometimes upon typeface, layout and design, and in<br />

depiction upon especially materials and technique.<br />

In Languages of Art analysis of expression begins with descriptive notation or writing,<br />

and focuses upon figures of speech, their range of elements or ‘schemata’, their<br />

realm of application and importantly their occasional re-application or transfer of


46<br />

range and or realm. 67 Irony for example is understood as reversed schemata,<br />

whereby range of elements is applied to the same realm in reverse order, so that a<br />

misfortune becomes ‘a fine thing’ or a windfall ‘tough luck’. A similar revision of<br />

range might explain caricature, whereby proportion, modelling, and facial<br />

expression for example, still obtain the same realm but revise ordering of elements.<br />

But Goodman does not suggest this. Where transference is of both range and<br />

realm, figures essentially function as metaphor, but Goodman also demonstrates<br />

that the model of transfer holds for simile, euphemism, personification, synecdoche,<br />

antonomasia, litotes, hyperbole and meiosis, under and over use thereof. Expression<br />

is now seen as relative to familiarity or usage of range or realm for schemata. Talk<br />

of schemata recalls Gombrich’s schema and correction, and Goodman’s discussion<br />

of ‘ping and pong’ in synaesthetic transfers readily acknowledges the precedent. 68<br />

However, Goodman also departs from Gombrich in allowing an intimate relation<br />

between expression and exemplification in depiction.<br />

This now calls for some adjustment to the proposed theory, where depiction is<br />

already taken as a mode of exemplification. It requires a further distinction between<br />

the exemplification of two-dimensionality and three, or what shall now be termed<br />

material exemplification. In Chapter Two it was noted that in exemplifying twodimensionality<br />

a surface was distinctively reconfigured or marked so as to effectively<br />

display the sample, and that the material or three-dimensional aspects to this<br />

reconfiguration in turn may offer additional or attendant sample. Sampling becomes<br />

two-faced or double-edged in this way. It is this distinction between material<br />

exemplification and depiction that now corresponds to Goodman’s discussion of<br />

expression for exemplification and depiction. Material exemplification may offer<br />

literal or metaphorical sample to accompany depiction, which in turn may offer<br />

literal or metaphorical realms, in allegory or realism and blends. However,<br />

Goodman’s emphasis is upon transfer of material samples in expression, such as the<br />

literally grey picture that is metaphorically - expressively - bleak or lonely, (in as<br />

much as it claims a novel but effective realm).<br />

67 Goodman, 1976, pp. 68-84.<br />

68 Ibid. p.76.


47<br />

But the point is also that depiction is often accompanied by the sampling of literal<br />

material properties for themselves, not just of colour or line but also of facture or<br />

technique, size, scale or detail, expense or rarity of materials, framing and even<br />

location (for murals) amongst others, and that any or some contribute to the<br />

meaning of a picture, to how and what a picture samples. Yet to say that a picture<br />

expresses say, a roughness or whiteness, is also to suggest perhaps that it is not itself,<br />

or literally, rough or white. For this reason expression is reserved for transfers of<br />

material samples. Transfers however are not necessarily to emotional realms, to<br />

sadness or joy, say, but as often and also to synaesthetic realms indicated above, to<br />

sounds or tastes, to qualities like slipperiness or bulkiness, even for the literally<br />

small, dry and solid picture. Finally, Goodman has less to say about metaphor within<br />

depiction, of allegorical or personified pictures for example, and whether these<br />

necessarily count as expressive. Although it is clear from the conditions for effective<br />

transfer that where the realm is obvious or familiar, such as in an illustration to The<br />

Pilgrim’s Progress, or of a woman as justice or liberty, that expression and transfer<br />

are less prominent than mere statement. So expression requires prominence or<br />

exemplification of novel transfer, rather than just instantiation, and this holds for<br />

transfer in material exemplification as well, although perhaps less rigorously.<br />

Expression thus expands upon depictive meaning through metaphor and the<br />

proposed distinction here between depictive and material exemplification explains<br />

how meaning is variously combined and subtly interacts. In Chapter One criticism<br />

of Goodman’s example of a picture of a wave by Hokusai corresponding to a<br />

finance graph drew attention to the difference between literal depiction and<br />

expressive qualities attributed to the outline. The relation between them is now clear<br />

and preserves Goodman’s distinctions between meanings, for taking a stricter view<br />

of depiction.<br />

Meaning arises along roughly three routes, through structure, of literal materials,<br />

through sentiment, of metaphor or expressive transfer, and through statement, of<br />

depiction. All and only such reference is taken to constitute stylistic features for a<br />

picture, to locate it according to typical occurrence of such features for a source, as<br />

artist, time, place, school, trend, region, nation or period. Source need not be<br />

supplied by every category for a style and every category need not share a scale for


48<br />

time or place. A source may be as broad as the pre-historic period or as narrow as<br />

the artist’s blue period, as sweeping as western; or European style, through to<br />

national, regional and more local styles.<br />

Furthermore the style or combination of reference features for one source is rarely<br />

the same as those for another, so that for example, school or regional style may<br />

favour structure over statement; or the artist’s individual style favour sentiment over<br />

statement, or various weighting and combinations. Goodman’s views on style are<br />

expanded in Ways of Worldmaking, where style and stylistics are seen as an<br />

indispensable tool to understanding depiction. 69 Art history and criticism are seen as<br />

exchanging ends for means in regard to style. The historian attributes a picture to a<br />

style through document and research while the critic appraises what the picture’s<br />

inclusion means to the style, and the style to the picture, drawing on broader<br />

considerations of biography, politics, geography, economics, psychology, and other<br />

disciplines. Beyond this, interesting and unexpected features are frequently<br />

discovered through mixing styles, even jumbling pictures with other objects and<br />

reference, but this is only to contrast with established styles. Again Goodman urges<br />

that no definitive list of features need be drawn up for a style to be effective; that is<br />

something simply to be worked at and usually grasped without fully analysing its<br />

elements. As with the issue of fiction, the test is rather in our sureness and<br />

understanding of pictures, in our ability to maintain subtle distinctions between<br />

them. We profit from the challenge and find the complex and elusive style<br />

rewarding, the quick and simple mere mannerism. Appreciation of style is an<br />

integral aspect of our sensitivity and understanding of depiction and anticipates the<br />

issue of art.<br />

It is instructive at this point to compare Goodman’s views with those of Gombrich<br />

and Wollheim. Goodman pointedly contrasts his rejection of intention and<br />

synonymy for example, with Gombrich’s views while Wollheim’s later formulations<br />

are equally explicit in their rejection of Goodman. 70 Gombrich takes expression to<br />

be depictive reference to the non-visual senses, or the invisible, to ideas and<br />

69 Goodman, 1978, pp. 23-40.<br />

70 Ibid. 23. The footnote to this page identifies a Gombrich entry in International Encyclopaedia<br />

of the Social Sciences, Vol. 15, p. 353, but the account offered in Gombrich, 1960, pp. 304-329,<br />

serves as the source for discussion here. See also Wollheim, 1987, pp. 25-40.


49<br />

sentiments. It extends his position on depiction in tracing a smooth progression of<br />

‘equivalences’ or a synonymous translation between pictorial features and such nonvisible<br />

objects. But there can be no appeal to an illusion, or a natural perception<br />

with such expression. Instead Gombrich turns to elementary polarities, to Roman<br />

Jakobson’s game of ‘ping’ and ‘pong’ as well as Charles E. Osgood’s semantic<br />

experiments to propose a structure through which to establish synonymy. 71 Such<br />

schema - or schemata - allow a tradition of the plain Doric column contrasted with<br />

the ornate Corinthian column, for example, to express modesty opposed to<br />

extravagance, and later variations to build expression through related motifs, so that<br />

they may then express say, rustic purity versus worldly compromise.<br />

Hence expression in Gombrich’s theory, while similarly suggesting metaphor, is<br />

essentially concerned with allegory and versions of schema, and largely ignores<br />

material exemplification. Expression is again linked to style, in the schema<br />

preserving these traditional polarities and by synonymy of styles. Synonymy takes<br />

styles as versions of a shared object or theme, or draws a hard line between how<br />

and what, manner and matter. Synonymy allows expression to deal with metaphoric<br />

variation to such shared objects or themes, but the formulation is not so much<br />

misguided as stunted. Gombrich’s example of the individual style of John Constable<br />

is telling in this respect. Constable is seen as achieving stylistic distinction in the<br />

pastoral genre, of introducing a certain atmosphere –‘ lights, dews, breezes’ –<br />

previously unavailable, but inserted through a shrewd mixture of rebellion and<br />

compromise. 72 On the one hand it discovers a new perceptual truth, on the other it<br />

no more than refines colour schema for tradition. But the account then struggles<br />

with the success enjoyed by Constable’s sketches, and an argument is made for the<br />

superiority of the finished works, on the basis of their greater adherence to<br />

tradition. Preference for the sketches is dismissed as a superficial indulgence of ‘the<br />

beholder’s share’ or of pandering to mere suggestiveness in perception and<br />

pictures. 73 Yet Gombrich’s whole theory of depiction as illusion rests on just such<br />

suggestiveness. The real issue here is the inability to accept facture or the handling<br />

of materials as expressive features. In fact preference for the sketches rests mainly<br />

71 Osgood et al., The Measurement of Meaning, Urbana, 1957.<br />

72 Gombrich, 1960, pp. 325-326.<br />

73 Earlier, in the chapter ‘The Image in the Clouds’, Gombrich similarly parades his prejudice<br />

against the ‘manieroso’ in painting, finding such suggestiveness only for the informed – “It is<br />

always flattering to feel ‘in the know”, Gombrich, 1960, pp. 166-167.


50<br />

on the perceived expressiveness of the looser handling. Matters as general and<br />

transitory as a breezy atmosphere are not to be caught in a close attention to foliage<br />

or texture, or the careful polish of tonalities, but in a more global impression, and<br />

not just in terms of objects depicted, but also of formal properties of facture and<br />

viscosity of paint, of literal or material sampling. Breeziness in Constable’s manner<br />

of painting helps him sketch breeziness in nature.<br />

The example underlines the problem of style taken as synonymy. Gombrich is<br />

reluctant to accept the sketch because it abandons detail and finish in the interest of<br />

wholistic features, and more generally allows that the objects might have properties<br />

or appearances particular to a style. This weakens the synonymy of pictures to<br />

objects, styles to pictures, expression to styles. The same holds for the view that<br />

Constable’s landscapes restate the pastoral tradition, which in turn restates classical<br />

sentiments of modesty and rustic truth. It is to take a somewhat static view of the<br />

matter. Accepting Constable as part of the pastoral tradition means revising some of<br />

the things that style identifies, so a plea for Constable’s conformity in matters of<br />

finish rather pre-empts the issue, if accommodation is to be a two-way affair.<br />

Gombrich similarly berates Romanticism for its concentration upon novelty and<br />

invention at the expense of tradition, but his stern historian’s focus upon the<br />

constancy of tradition is just as much a mistake. 74 Tradition is traditionally open to<br />

negotiation. The fact is, manner affects matter, how a picture is made affects what a<br />

picture makes, and vice versa. Strict synonymy sells style and expression short.<br />

Expression is not simply what a metaphor transfers from the depicted object, or to<br />

where, nor the right schema for a remote realm, but also in the material sampled<br />

along with depiction, transfers to and from it.<br />

In Painting as an Art, Wollheim proposed not only a theory of pictorial meaning, but<br />

also its development within painting and its status as art. He offered a model of<br />

pictorial meaning developed through a process of ‘thematisation’. 75 This concerns<br />

the agent’s awareness of accidental, unintended, overlooked or ignored aspects<br />

within a pictorial tradition or style and of their referential possibilities. 76 The agent’s<br />

74 . Gombrich, 1960, p. 322.<br />

75 Wollheim, 1987, pp. 19-25.<br />

76 The term agent rather than artist is maintained here as in Wollheim, in deference to his<br />

distinction between artists and other makers of pictures.


51<br />

efforts to harness or incorporate them are termed the thematisation of pictorial<br />

features. This is also taken as a model for the development of individual or personal<br />

style. A personal style is taken as a necessary condition of art. Wollheim’s focus<br />

upon the individual is of a piece with his psychological approach and the role of<br />

intention in establishing pictorial meaning. It is also of a piece with idealism, as shall<br />

be demonstrated.<br />

The familiar objections to intention are met here firstly where the intention is not<br />

taken narrowly, as an explicit statement, but rather as all the thoughts, memories<br />

and feelings that occur during production of a picture, and that ‘cause’ the agent to<br />

depict in a certain way. 77 Secondly, intention is only fulfilled if the spectator is able<br />

to derive this from the experience of looking at the picture – it is not enough, in<br />

other words, to know about the intentions and just to associate them with the<br />

picture. It must be visible in the picture, in a way acceptable to the spectator. The<br />

question is, having met these requirements, are we are still talking about intention?<br />

An intention that is so attenuated as to embrace all thoughts, memories and feelings<br />

that influence or cause the agent to depict in a certain way looks uncomfortably like<br />

mere consciousness. Attempting to demarcate which mental events actually made<br />

and did not make a difference to the picture only begs the question what sort of<br />

difference counts? Different when? How? If the picture looks different as the agent<br />

anticipates dinner, has this advanced the picture? The only way to tell is from the<br />

finished picture, and all that can be told from the finished picture is all that led to its<br />

being finished. There is no separating some moments from the rest in the causal<br />

chain.<br />

Then there is the question of the fulfilment of the intentions, and whether it can,<br />

strictly speaking, still be considered an intention after fulfilment; at which time we<br />

have a deed. Wollheim refers to the fulfilled intention of the agent in a picture as<br />

the description under which the picture is so taken, much as a deed might be taken<br />

as the description under which the agent acted, or the agent’s own description of<br />

the deed. The assumption is that each deed or object may be described in a variety<br />

77 For the ‘formalist’ argument against mere intention see Monroe Beardsley and W.K Wimsatt,<br />

‘The Intentional Fallacy’, Sewanee Review, 54, 1946, pp. 3-23. See also Monroe Beardsley and<br />

Hubert M. Schueller (eds.) Aesthetic Inquiry: Essays in Art criticism and the Philosophy of Art,<br />

Belmont/California, 1967.


52<br />

of ways, and in fact must be further described in some way, to be intelligible, and<br />

that the agent has in mind just the one comprehensive description. In other words<br />

the deed or object in-itself is vague, ineffable or meaningless. Yet the deed or object<br />

under a particular description has a way of extending that description all the way to<br />

the describer, in the quest for further particularity. Ultimately matter is exchanged<br />

for mind. This is the idealist basis to Wollheim’s views, and it underwrites his<br />

commitment to psychology and personal style. Wollheim sees the fulfilled<br />

intentions being modified, and tested by the agent through playing the role of the<br />

spectator, imagining how the picture will be taken and whether the desired<br />

description of the picture can be seen. But if there are roles for what can and cannot<br />

be seen in the picture, then there are rules, and if there are rules then intention is<br />

overruled. When what the agent means only matters when they play by the rules or<br />

roles, then it is the rules we look to for meaning. Wollheim’s formulation is at best a<br />

Pyrrhic victory for intention.<br />

Wollheim’s view of expression, like his view of depiction, draws on the natural<br />

inclinations of the spectator to project onto a suitable surface. His view of<br />

expression is exclusively in terms of emotion, rejecting Gombrich’s examples of<br />

synesthesia, and Goodman’s transfers of literal properties by metaphor. 78 Indeed he<br />

considers at length an interesting objection to the view of expression as metaphor in<br />

relation to emotion. 79 It concerns the transfer of an emotion such as sadness,<br />

through metaphor, to a picture of a landscape, to take the simplest of examples.<br />

The landscape expresses sadness, or is metaphorically a sad landscape. The<br />

objection is that a landscape cannot be sad in the same way a person is sad, unless<br />

the metaphor is of the landscape as a sad person, which is then a different matter.<br />

The sadness must therefore be of an abstracted or idealized kind, in order to<br />

‘double-up’ as Wollheim terms it, for both literal and metaphorical applications.<br />

What is literally sad is a feeling, and what is metaphorically sad is a landscape, but<br />

how is a landscape to be taken as sad, unless as a person? And if both feeling and<br />

landscape are sad in the same sense, are they both then literal or metaphorical?<br />

78 Wollheim, 1987,p. 80.<br />

79 Ibid. pp. 84-85.


53<br />

In reply one might start by citing Goodman’s description of a metaphor as ‘an affair<br />

between a predicate with a past and an object that yields while protesting’. 80 A<br />

metaphor does not always apply smoothly and easily to its object. The idea is to find<br />

or make a way in which they match or make new sense. To apply sadness to a<br />

landscape is to take sadness as a place, for a person, or within a person. The<br />

disjuncture is obvious, yet intriguing. To fret about it’s disembodied or idealistic<br />

nature is to confuse its literal and metaphorical applications, or to look for one<br />

application that holds for both literal and metaphorical instances. What is shared by<br />

literal sadness and metaphorical sadness is not the ultimate in sadness, but a label<br />

and a practice, in one instance applied literally, and in the other literally misapplied.<br />

What rough and ready success this misapplication may have, no more establishes a<br />

transcendent sadness than the strict compliance of further literal applications. A<br />

metaphor makes up sadness, as much as it makes out sadness. It should also be<br />

added that much of Wollheim’s attention to this issue is directed toward defending<br />

the concept of expressive projection, by which a subject projects onto a suitable<br />

scene certain uncomfortable feelings, and in so doing is rid of them. The subject<br />

experiences the scene as sad, for example, although this does not make the subject<br />

feel sad. Just what the subject’s response is to this sudden transformation in<br />

surroundings or picture, coinciding as it does with an abrupt swing in mood, is<br />

unclear, as is the nature of the place or picture prior to projection, and indeed of the<br />

subject’s grasp of such matters.<br />

Yet expressive projection also extends to literal or material properties for a<br />

depiction in Panting as an Art, and may find bodily metaphors, as for example in the<br />

abstract paintings of de Kooning and with at least a nod to the work of Rothko. 81<br />

The theory thus offers a broader range to expression than that of Gombrich, while<br />

at the same time narrowing the realm for metaphor. Apart from this however,<br />

abstraction in Wollheim’s version is dismissed as decorative, and the literal materials<br />

of the picture are denied a stylistic function shorn of psychological metaphor. He<br />

can therefore offer neither a strictly musical metaphor to a painting by Piet<br />

Mondrian for example, as Gombrich does; nor admit to the literal or formal<br />

properties of a print by Josef Albers or Patrick Heron, as Goodman does. 82 Like<br />

80 Goodman, 1976, p. 69.<br />

81 Wollheim, 1987, pp. 348-352.<br />

82 Gombrich, 1960, pp. 311-312, Goodman, 1978, p. 33.


54<br />

Gombrich, his theory sells stylistics short, and is finally less useful in regard to<br />

twentieth century art, a shortcoming noted elsewhere. 83 His account of style and the<br />

concept of thematisation are interesting for the contrast to Gombrich’s version of<br />

making and matching, - Wollheim’s version is pointedly ahistorical and deeply selfabsorbed,<br />

a myth of ‘Ur-painting’ – while the parallels between thematisation and<br />

exemplification are equally intriguing. Thematisation might well be seen as the<br />

transfer of exemplification to a psychological realm.<br />

The comparisons show how traditional concerns with synonymy and intention<br />

variously shape expressive and other stylistic meaning, make for preference amongst<br />

structure, sentiment and statement, priority to certain works and styles. Of course<br />

other stylistic priorities may be derived from synonymy and intention and stylistic<br />

priorities are not only to be derived from synonymy and intention, so the point is<br />

firstly that stylistic resources are wider than allowed by Gombrich or Wollheim and<br />

that other formulations tend to deny some part of stylistic features. It also shows<br />

how a theory of depiction is carried over into issues of art history and criticism. In<br />

laying aside synonymy and intention, Goodman’s theory allows all three levels to<br />

style and so a broader range of meaning and more adequate stylistics, one that<br />

reflects various practices of criticism and history and offers greater integration. 84<br />

This gain however entails other commitments, although these need not be<br />

addressed immediately. Goodman offers no sustained interpretation or history of<br />

art, and it remains to be seen what difference an application of his stylistics makes,<br />

but the theory is clearly drawn to art. Indeed all three theories draw art into<br />

discussion of expression and style, as examples have indicated. Clearly pictures<br />

alone do not constitute art, and expression and style are not sufficient condition,<br />

although the sense is that they advance the cause considerably. The following<br />

chapter duly addresses the issue of depiction and art.<br />

83 Arthur Danto, ‘Art’s Infancy’ in London Review Of Books, 1993, April 22, pp. 17-18.<br />

84 Goodman acknowledges that theory no more than keeps pace with practice in this respect.<br />

Goodman, 1978, p.24.


55<br />

Depiction and Art<br />

Discussion of expression and style has shown how expression broadens meaning<br />

and contributes to categories of style. Yet not all styles are of equal value, not all<br />

pictures have as much or as interesting meaning. Some are claimed as art, most are<br />

not. What further characteristic or condition of pictures qualifies as art? The<br />

traditional answer is beauty or excellence. The picture well made, or the perfect<br />

instance of its kind, squares with our everyday usage and intuitions. But since the<br />

preceding discussion of style assures that pictures come in kinds, there are then as<br />

many versions of beauty as there are styles for depiction. So beauty does not<br />

sufficiently qualify art. The question then becomes which styles are excellent or<br />

beautiful? Less traditionally, the answer is often that the property or predicate is<br />

irreducible to a single or stable essence without compromising its application and<br />

that beauty and excellence simply are what we make of the established collection in<br />

the name of art. 85 The question, more profitably, is how is art used? Or how are<br />

further pictures and styles added to it, and others ignored?<br />

The answer here is sometimes given in terms of institutional influence, or according<br />

to the powers and politics of relevant institutions. 86 Additionally, other answers<br />

stress a vividness or impact upon underlying concerns, with visual perception for<br />

example, as in Gombrich’s theory, or the psychology of personality, as in Wollheim,<br />

85 A key strand to this argument derives from Ludwig Wittgenstein’s theory of a family or<br />

<strong>net</strong>work of resemblances determining ‘essence’ or defining a concept, rather than a single or<br />

unitary chain. See for example Morris Weitz, ‘Wittgenstein’s Aesthetics’ in Language and<br />

Aesthetics, Benjamin R. Tilghman, (ed.) Lawrence, Kansas, 1973.<br />

86 Institutional theories strictly admit all answers that allow art to be derived from its history. The<br />

answer proposed here, takes institutions as those bodies constituting an ‘Artworld’ as variously<br />

proposed by Arthur Danto. See Danto, ‘The Artworld’ in Journal of Philosophy, 61, 1964, p.<br />

580, Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace Cambridge, Mass./London, 1981, Danto,<br />

‘The Artworld Revisited: Comedies of Similarity’ in Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in<br />

Post-Historical Perspective, New York, 1992. See also George Dickie, ‘Defining Art’, in<br />

American Philosophical Quarterly, July, 1969, p. 254, Dickie, Aesthetics: an introduction,<br />

Indianapolis, 1971, Dickie, Art and the Aesthetic, Ithaca/New York, 1974.


56<br />

or with effective understanding, as in Goodman. Art is thus tethered to wider<br />

issues, shapes and is shaped by them. We look back upon and organise the past with<br />

styles to strengthen our grasp of an issue, as much as we are guided by styles, and<br />

allow them to focus current issues. To say that we merely or meekly inherit styles is<br />

as misleading as to say we reinvent them just as we please. We do both in part, and<br />

art, excellence or beauty in depiction finally lies only in the persistence of the<br />

practice, in more art. Similarly, it is pointless to look to art beyond such issues or in<br />

ideal isolation. The point is rather to show in what ways art may be contrasted with<br />

or distinguished from them. Since this study pursues Goodman’s theory, the aim is<br />

now to show how the proposed theory of depiction distinguishes a mode of<br />

understanding for art, how art maintains a dynamic or economy according to this<br />

understanding, and how, like Gombrich’s theory, it accords a distinctive role to<br />

history.<br />

To begin, it is useful to compare the function of a picture with that of a word, or<br />

between depiction and description. A picture in the proposed view exemplifies two<br />

dimensions, resembles those of objects and their spatial relations. But a picture is<br />

usually a freeze-frame, since schemes for establishing a passage of time within a<br />

single picture are rarely used. A description on the other hand derives from speech<br />

and retains a temporal dimension. Its reference to movement can even instantiate a<br />

causal direction. The apple fell to the ground, follows just such a course and cause.<br />

But this temporal structuring can also be over-selective and misleading. A picture is<br />

worth a thousand words according to some rates of exchange, simply because<br />

giving the right name to an object may in itself need a lot more explaining. For<br />

some people it is quicker to ‘draw a picture’. A picture not only helps us to see a<br />

situation more clearly, by providing more information, but may also provide<br />

unexpected or overlooked aspects as well. In fact we can sometimes see things not<br />

only more fully or clearly, but also quite differently.<br />

In the example (Figure C) the little girl may be described as pointing to a word, a<br />

sound, or a card, as being instructed or instructing. Her expression may be<br />

described as intent, or anxious or bored. She either looks away as she points, or<br />

after, or looks for direction before she points. She is an attentive six year old, the<br />

subject of an experiment in literacy, left handed, a product of the 1960s, of feminine


57<br />

Fig. C<br />

diligence, of English eccentricity, of<br />

winter gloom. All of these<br />

descriptions are supported by the<br />

depiction. What the little girl is<br />

doing is not something ineffable<br />

and beyond words, but rather is<br />

illuminated by them, even as they<br />

disagree 87 .<br />

We understand the picture as<br />

containing not only ambiguities, or<br />

differences of emphasis, but<br />

distinct and contradictory<br />

descriptions: the girl points to the<br />

word cat, or she does not point to<br />

the word cat. But if we allow a description open contradiction, we also<br />

forfeit its coherence, and its point. 88 Instead multiple descriptions or<br />

interpretations allow us to understand what the girl does in relation to the depiction.<br />

The fact that conflicting descriptions share the same picture points not so much to<br />

their inadequacy as descriptions – as not capturing the whole truth – but to a<br />

difference between pictures and words. No matter how elaborate a description<br />

becomes, how many ambiguities it can allow while still avoiding contradiction, it<br />

will still not amount to, or exhaust the meaning of the picture. Any description will<br />

simply make room for others. Quite simply a description cannot contain a<br />

depiction, nor can a depiction confine itself to a single description. This is not<br />

because the visual is non-verbal, on the contrary, as we have seen, the visual may<br />

contain any number of verbal labels, but rather because the visual belongs to a twodimensional<br />

system, with four-directional extension but literally no time, and so no<br />

one place to start or stop a description. Like the earlier example of a map permitting<br />

endless routes between any two or more points, a picture’s names and descriptions<br />

are no more than one route around the object. A depiction contains descriptions for<br />

87 Figure C is reproduced courtesy of The Hulton Getty Picture Collection Limited.<br />

88 This argument derives from Catherine Z. Elgin, ‘What Goodman Leaves Out’, Journal of<br />

Aesthetic Education, Vol 25 No 1 Spring 1991, pp. 89-96. The argument there is for multiple<br />

right interpretations against Wollheim’s proposed one right and deeply ambiguous interpretation.<br />

See Wollheim, ‘The Core of Aesthetics’ in Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol 25 No 1 Spring,<br />

1991, pp. 37-45.


58<br />

the same reason that one direction is contained in four. Whatever label a picture<br />

takes as a starting point, it can only make a map of it rather than a route.<br />

Description is necessarily selective, and to describe a depiction it must offer a<br />

sequence in place of contiguity or translate four directions into one. No matter how<br />

extensive, a route can only run in one direction at a time, and no amount of<br />

extension or detail, allow it to run in four directions at one time, or in one place.<br />

This difference between depiction and description is not so much a source of<br />

antipathy as partnership. There is no point in seeking a rigid demarcation or<br />

pursuing a purely visual realm, in the interests of art or otherwise. Rather the task of<br />

depiction involves co-operation on larger projects, to mutual advantage. The<br />

overlapping and coincidence of description, as noted, are what give a picture its<br />

richness or density of meaning. In this, the study accepts the general drift of<br />

Goodman’s notational formulations. The ease with which a depiction<br />

accommodates descriptions, also allows for the shift between literal and<br />

metaphorical, or expressive meaning. In contrast with any one description, a<br />

depiction offers a way to cluster descriptions, in a way that a simple compilation<br />

into a bigger description cannot. A depiction achieves a fuller, but less focussed<br />

meaning, more is said, but less is stressed. This allows a depiction to complement a<br />

description, by indicating surrounding and non-obvious matters and versions, and<br />

in turn allows a description to single out and give salience to a given depicted<br />

object. This is what pictures are for, and their role suggests a definition for their<br />

excellence, beauty or art.<br />

Excellence lies in the development of more and other densities of meaning. This<br />

arises through the specialisation of uses or diversification of pictures. Greater<br />

degrees of density are achieved in pictures performing more open-ended tasks. The<br />

emergence of such tasks is by and large the history of art, and such tasks are defined<br />

in terms of our understanding or cognition. Here there is also agreement with<br />

Goodman. 89 But understanding in Goodman is taken to be as much sensory and<br />

emotive as considered and conceptual. Putting things into words is not always<br />

possible or necessary, and description is not the only means of interpretation. What<br />

is discovered through art is felt as much in nerves and muscles as minds. It<br />

89 Goodman, 1976, pp. 252-265. See also Goodman, 1984, pp. 135-138.


59<br />

no<strong>net</strong>heless urges and thrives on description, and its use through comparison and<br />

experiment with meanings furthers understanding. We have seen that pictures do<br />

this in relation to words, and now it is proposed that art does this in relation to<br />

understanding. The function has so far been identified in terms of the density of<br />

meaning. More particularly, it is achieved through a kind of scouting or exploring of<br />

a domain, a reconnaissance or circumspection. 90 When this function is given<br />

sufficient latitude it permits deeper more circumspect meaning, and may well<br />

become a thing of beauty and a joy forever. It need not be exclusively a matter of<br />

realism or idealism, fact or fiction, impression or expression, the literal or<br />

metaphorical. It is a function established in relation only to understanding and<br />

achieves this end through different means. In description for example, literature<br />

pursues fictive genres and poetic language as a way to expand upon the realms of<br />

description, but may equally augment this with pictures, calligraphic or other design<br />

aspects to text, music, performance, film or video.<br />

Yet a circumspective function for depiction might seem to make classification of<br />

style difficult, if not counter-productive; to only thin the desired density by thus<br />

locating meaning more precisely. Circumspection obviously functions within<br />

constraints in this respect, while at the same time stylistic identities are notoriously<br />

labile and while style tethers meaning to a source, what is thus attributed is far less<br />

clear than to where it is attributed. Meaning remains controversial even where<br />

agreement exists about identity of source, for example to a Michelangelo or the<br />

Italian Renaissance, to a Ma<strong>net</strong> or French Impressionism. But circumspection<br />

functions not only within stylistic constraints but also phases. Even the rough and<br />

ready sortings of style at a certain point, and for some at least, are settled enough to<br />

allow greater circumspection to others. Mostly, new or recent works receive the<br />

bulk of criticism and rely upon older and traditional styles for reference, if not<br />

conformity. Such attention reflects the attraction for beauty renewed or the<br />

challenge of further circumspection. In fact criticism reinforces and to some extent<br />

settles older styles in this way, by ostensibly forging new styles. Revision of older<br />

styles also occurs however, in the recognition of a Vermeer for example in the<br />

90 The term circumspection appeals in part for the role it plays in George A. Kelly’s theory of<br />

psychology. See Kelly, The Psychology of Personal Constructs, Vol 1. New York, 1955, pp. 514-<br />

517.


60<br />

ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century, revising in a small way ideas about seventeenth century Dutch<br />

genre painting, or again, in the introduction of Mannerism, revising the transition<br />

from the Renaissance to Baroque. The point is simply that circumspection is<br />

variously maintained by a cycle of focus and dilation, by shifting attention from<br />

some styles or works to others and rebuilding them accordingly.<br />

This is really only to amplify the position taken by Goodman in certain respects.<br />

Goodman advocates cognitive efficiency as a distinctive feature of art, although<br />

supplies only a list of typical symptoms for the requisite density or complexity of<br />

denotation. 91 He also allows that works and styles enjoy a fluctuating standard of<br />

beauty or excellence, or status within art. If cognitive efficiency no longer sounds<br />

much like beauty, it is partly because Goodman applies cognition to far more than<br />

thoughts and conceptual analysis, as indicated, and partly because beauty here is not<br />

always distinct from the flavour of the month or a passing fancy. Goodman takes an<br />

expanded view of cognition, if a somewhat deflated view of beauty. This reflects his<br />

priorities. The emphasis in this aesthetic is less upon canons or rankings, than their<br />

propagation, upon the wider process, and ‘beauty’ in all its phases. Where a work<br />

offers fresh insight into the object and mode of reference used, we experience its<br />

beauty, its tempting challenge to stylistic and other constructs. The challenge allows<br />

us to sense value or potential in the whole of the work. We sense it is full of sense<br />

for us. It is a bit like falling in love. But we tend to get over it. The more we learn<br />

from or use the work, the more we take it for granted, apply it elsewhere and<br />

discover shortcomings.<br />

Goodman acknowledges just this dynamic, ‘A work may be successively offensive,<br />

fascinating, comfortable and boring. These are the vicissitudes of the vehicles and<br />

instruments of knowledge.’ 92 But the lessons learned are not entirely forgotten with<br />

newer interests; rather the interests further the lessons. There is in this respect a<br />

history or tradition to beauty and its persistence fuses the issues of canons and<br />

cognition. In this Goodman perhaps underestimates the problem, when he argues:<br />

To say that a work of art is good or even to say how good it is does not<br />

after all provide much information, does not tell us whether the work is<br />

91 Goodman, 1976, pp. 252-265. See also Goodman, 1984, pp. 135-138.<br />

92 Goodman, 1976, pp. 259.


61<br />

evocative, robust, vibrant, or exquisitely designed, still less what are its<br />

salient specific qualities of colour, shape or sound, moreover, works of art<br />

are not race-horses, and picking a winner is not the primary goal. 93<br />

Granted, picking a winner is not the end of the matter, but picking a winner is<br />

surely a step in the process. To rank a work thus is better seen as an exercise that<br />

singles out the work initially, alerts us to issues or features that now tantalise in<br />

some way. It is to respond to just the dense or circumspective nature of the work<br />

that resists other than a crude pre-emptive judgement. It is quite simply the<br />

experience of beauty at first sight. Yet to say what is good, typically involves<br />

pointing to features in which the work excels. It is to be drawn gradually into saying<br />

how it is good, to further comparisons and tests. It is perhaps to revise the<br />

judgement in disappointment. But either way, what starts out as blind ranking, ends<br />

up as a standard and style, just as what starts out as beauty ends up as a norm. In<br />

short, how good a work is, is part of what the work is, and as such ranking cannot<br />

be divorced from revelation. Yet ranking is plainly not enough, and to be fully<br />

effective as an understanding it must be transformed with time and care into a<br />

broader construction, applied to more works and styles, and assume a place in the<br />

canon.<br />

In characterising art as a mode of understanding or knowledge, Goodman also<br />

undertakes a revision of the distinction between art and science. Both in Languages of<br />

Art and Ways of Worldmaking he argues against the traditional distinctions – between<br />

feeling and fact, intuition and inference, subjectivity and objectivity, truth and<br />

beauty. None are found adequate as a demarcation, science guesses, fancies and<br />

fudges the truth, finds the best fit by adjusting facts as well as framework. Art<br />

arrives at its best fits in matters of composition and resolution through similar trial<br />

and error and both appeal to broader, global considerations of ‘rightness’. 94 The<br />

difference Goodman proposes is between domains of reference. Since<br />

circumspection is here offered as characteristic of art, some further brief<br />

characterisation for science is perhaps appropriate. The function identified here is<br />

one of narrowed focus and sharpened frameworks. Let it be called concentration. If<br />

art wanders and wonders, science seizes and settles. As with art, reference may by a<br />

93 Ibid. pp. 261-262.<br />

94 Goodman, 1976, pp. 261-262. See also Goodman, 1978, pp. 106-7, pp. 138-140.


62<br />

variety of modes. Science too has its samples, imaging, jargon and journals. The<br />

difference is the greater degree and integration of the system. Goodman identifies<br />

digital, articulate and attenuated characteristics in his analysis of denotation, and his<br />

discussion draws heavily upon notions of precision and measurement, and it is not<br />

surprising and wholly convincing that descriptive notation in these terms is strongly<br />

aligned with science. 95<br />

Defining art in contrast with science leads Goodman to briefly reflect on the<br />

historical dimension to art’s cognitive function. 96 Science is no more objective than<br />

art since controversies and arguments rage within each; the prestige of science<br />

theories is subject to fluctuations just as evaluations of art works are. Yet earlier<br />

scientific theories may be rendered obsolete by later ones, and in so far as true, are<br />

recoverable in reverse derivation. Older works of art on the other hand are not, and<br />

are threatened by indifference rather than obsolescence. They continue to function<br />

as art even if unpopular or overlooked, as such are sometimes the source of<br />

inspiration for new works or unexpected departures. The reason for this difference<br />

Goodman can find no space for, but it can be supplied partly in an appeal to the<br />

nature of circumspection and the aim of dense meaning, which permits endless<br />

interpretation, and partly in an appeal to the nature of concentration, and the<br />

function of truth within science systems. Strict derivation itself requires a rigour of<br />

system more available to scientific practice. Art has neither need nor means for it.<br />

The historical dimension introduces a further issue. On the one hand beauty is seen<br />

as transitory, the enthusiasm of the moment, subject to fashion and taste, while on<br />

the other it persists in all works, is in a sense a joy forever. The problem is not just a<br />

work’s shift in ranking, but more interestingly, that a work may shift in rank, but<br />

retain its status as a work of art. A lowered ranking cannot be an expulsion. This is<br />

more a matter of logic than legislation. A ranking is based upon a body of works, or<br />

a canon, and to reduce this body would be to alter the basis upon which the ranking<br />

is made. It would be like sawing off the branch on which one is sitting. So<br />

acceptance as a work of art or inclusion in the canon is a one-way ticket, although<br />

95<br />

Goodman, 1976, pp. 148-164. See also Catherine Z. Elgin, With Reference to Reference,<br />

Indianapolis, 1983, p 120, and Elgin, ‘Relocating Aesthetics: Goodman’s Epistemic Turn’, (pp<br />

180-181), Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 47, 1993, pp. 171-186.<br />

96 Goodman, 1978, pp. 138 – 140. See especially footnote on page 140.


63<br />

seat allocation may vary from time to time. Then again new works are recognised<br />

not only on the strength of novel rankings, but as often according to older ones,<br />

and for this reason art unlike science does not get just better and better, only bigger<br />

and bigger. Similarly, works rejected in such rankings hardly fail as pictures because<br />

of it; rather function within narrower circumspective constraints. Yet rejections may<br />

be reversed in a way acceptances cannot, as where a revision in ranking may allow a<br />

new density to a hitherto rejected work, for example in the appreciation of nonwestern<br />

works at the turn of the ni<strong>net</strong>eenth and twentieth centuries. All this is only<br />

to say that art digresses while science progresses. This difference serves to explain<br />

not only the lack of obsolescence in art, and the transient nature of its beauties, but<br />

its deep affiliation with history.<br />

So far Goodman’s theory of depiction has been traced, amended and pursued to his<br />

view of art. Art is taken as a function of cognitive effectiveness and amended here<br />

with a circumspective role in depiction. The very general terms of cognitive<br />

effectiveness also allow Goodman to consider the function apart from the standard<br />

objects and institutions of art. This is captured in his framing of the question When<br />

Is Art? 97 He resists an exclusively institutional view, and in fact proposes what he<br />

terms the implementation of this cognitive function, above and beyond institutional<br />

practices. 98 Yet as we have seen in matters of style and expression, and now<br />

concerning ranking and canons, the weight of tradition is considerable upon<br />

interpretation and understanding in depiction and art. Whether art’s density or<br />

circumspective meaning is wholly a matter of history or vice versa need detain us no<br />

further than questions of nature versus convention. The point is that this deepening<br />

reliance upon history and its institutions now raises the question of just how this is<br />

undertaken. 99 How is an historical perspective maintained, and what is entailed in a<br />

history of art? The following chapter takes up this issue looking firstly to the<br />

popular model provided by Gombrich.<br />

97 Goodman, 1978,pp. 57-70.<br />

98 Goodman, 1983, p. 145.<br />

99 The question is pursued in Stephanie Ross, ‘On Goodman’s Query’ Southern Journal of<br />

Philosophy, 19, 1981, pp. 375-87. She concludes Goodman’s theory needs an institutional basis,<br />

although does not follow this to an historical method.


64<br />

Art History<br />

As noted, Gombrich’s The Story of Art all but exchanges art for history in excluding a<br />

definition for art, only to introduce depiction and reference as the proper object of<br />

study. It is appropriate to now look a little closer at this history. Treating art simply<br />

as the history of pictures, unfortunately does not give us the whole story on art or<br />

pictures. There are too many pictures for such a history, too much history for such<br />

pictures. Nor can a history get by trading on common usage of art to refer to merely<br />

pictures and at other times as beauty or excellence, and elsewhere as beauty and<br />

excellence only in pictures. The confusion costs pictures. Fine art is a necessary<br />

distinction, or art has a capital A for this reason. However in-keeping with current<br />

practice of abbreviation, it is enough here to no more than register this deep and<br />

mischievous ambiguity.<br />

One does not abandon an essential unpredictability or loss of scope for art, in<br />

appealing to some further concept or framework for definition. In fact there is no<br />

real choice. Firstly, because history must be of something, the surprise and scope of<br />

art are meaningless if unmeasured against something. The question is only to what to<br />

appeal for a broader basis? Secondly, to assume that future works will in some way<br />

surpass whatever concept or definition one cares to propose is in truth to no longer<br />

be in the business of history or art, but prediction. Following Goodman, an appeal<br />

to art’s cognitive efficiency is advocated, and questions of how and when styles<br />

change and variously maintain this efficiency now call for a history and method. By<br />

looking more closely to Gombrich’s example a model is gauged, modifications<br />

suggested<br />

The method to The Story of Art is actually presented in more detail in Art and Illusion,<br />

where it is bound up with a set of principles for pictorial representation and visual


65<br />

perception. 100 The cornerstone to the method is the axiom that ‘making precedes<br />

matching’. This asserts that reference or symbolic relations follow from our<br />

conception of the world, that we make entities, before matching them in tasks of<br />

reference. 101 It may seem an obscure point of metaphysics, but as shall be shown, it<br />

does not remain one. Gombrich is at pains to refute notions of a platonic form or<br />

an a priori concept, guiding making, and argues instead for freely revised or elastic<br />

concepts. He offers the example of building a snowman, in which a man is seen as<br />

literally built of snow, rather than as an effigy or replica. His argument is that the<br />

man of snow is an entity first, and an effigy second. Common sense would tell us<br />

that what we have is firstly and really snow, in the form of a man, rather than firstly<br />

and really, a man, currently taking the form of snow. Or, if we drop the matter of<br />

snow and talk simply of making a human, then precedence of conception or<br />

making, before the matching of parents, looks a little silly.<br />

But since this point is crucial to Gombrich’s method, it is worth dwelling upon a<br />

little. The argument fails because it proposes a resulting concept of a man of snow,<br />

in precisely the same way as it denies a guiding concept of a man in general. The<br />

argument is not strictly coherent. If there is no guiding concept in making, nor can<br />

there be a resulting concept to be matched to anything. This is because an elastic<br />

concept can only expand or contract in relation to some definition. To propose that<br />

we need a man of snow before we can have a concept of a man (or indeed snow) is<br />

to mistake man-ness for man. Some concept of a man, or man-ness, must be taken<br />

as a guiding concept, but this concept need not, and cannot be the platonic form,<br />

but nor need it imply only and always snow. Another way of putting this would be<br />

that snow may improve or alter our concepts of a man, but snow alone does not<br />

make a man. If the notion of replication is inconvenienced by notions of an<br />

antecedent concept of a man and of snow, equally construction is inconvenienced<br />

by the subsequent ‘form’ of the concepts - of a man and of snow. This is, as<br />

Gombrich rightly states, the ‘real’ issue. 102 But Plato is not to be out-manoeuvred<br />

quite so easily. For that we must perhaps trade a dualism of real and ideal or essence<br />

and accident, for a pluralism of worlds and versions. For the moment however it<br />

100 Both in the preface and the concluding ‘Retrospect’, of Art and Illusion, Gombrich declares<br />

the essential unity of approach in the two books. See Gombrich, 1960, p. vii, pp. 330-332.<br />

101 Ibid. p. 80-98.<br />

102 Ibid. p. 85.


66<br />

will suffice to point to the symmetry of the argument, and to conclude that making<br />

does not precede matching. They are neither consecutive nor alternating, but<br />

simultaneous and relative. It is a two-way process, and they are two ways of<br />

describing the same thing. In making an individual we expand our universal, in<br />

matching a universal, we detect an individual. It makes no sense to claim it as a onesided<br />

affair, to insist on a priority, or that it can be wholly arbitrary. The process<br />

cannot be absolute either; no entity is established wholly devoid of, or in complete<br />

possession of, all of its properties, including relations. So there is always more at<br />

stake than an isolated snowman.<br />

The aim here is not simply to rehearse metaphysics however, but rather to reject<br />

the argument Gombrich offers and more especially the ends it serves. These can be<br />

summarised in three points. It is firstly an argument for the development of<br />

reference from contingencies of concept, and their elastic use and custom. But the<br />

priority given to conception is here rejected; and instead reference and conception<br />

are taken to go hand in hand. Symbols are not second in the business of making the<br />

world, but partners. There is no making without matching, nor distinction or<br />

articulation without system and symbol. Even nothing has a name, or is a name for<br />

something. Secondly it is an argument for the primacy of the individual before the<br />

group. One can have some sympathy with Gombrich’s totalitarian anxieties on this<br />

point, but they are unfounded. 103 Equally, one must deny the primacy of the group,<br />

whether material or transcendent. Both identities are elastic, relative and revisable<br />

and one cannot precede the other, or exist in isolation. In the matter of pictures and<br />

styles, no picture precedes a style or exists in isolation. The very term picture already<br />

places it as a certain type or style of artefact.<br />

Thirdly, making and matching underlie Gombrich’s distinction between schema and<br />

correction, and the belief that the artist and work can stand outside of tradition, in<br />

order to identify and correct the rules of a schema, according to the way we ‘really’<br />

see things. But the ‘correction’ a revised schema can make is equally the latitude a<br />

tradition allows. Nor does it make a difference to claim that the ‘discovery’ is<br />

accidental or unintended, or achieved through blind trial and error. If the result is<br />

taken as more realistic or illusionistic, then a scale or set of rules is implied. The<br />

103 Gombrich, 1960, pp. 16-17.


67<br />

mistake here is in assuming that even the details of a style – its schemas - present<br />

themselves for scrutiny by the ambitious artist in such a way that would allow the<br />

rules or the conventions to be grasped. For this the tradition must somehow be<br />

frozen for a moment. But there are no such intervals in history. There are no static<br />

schemas, no entire catalogue of instances for the artist to consult. Each instance<br />

revises the nature of the schema, and at any time art has many, if any, competing<br />

schemas and applications. A work’s ‘corrections’ are no more than its connections<br />

to other and older works. Hence schemas do not precede works, anymore than they<br />

proceed by correction. There is no realism for pictures outside of the tradition or<br />

the consensus to which to appeal, and there is no single and fixed form of it within<br />

the tradition, to be refined or distilled.<br />

Gombrich’s historical method in fact provides a story of realism that underlies his<br />

history of art. What is notable about the story is firstly the strength and optimism of<br />

its opening, in which the concept of art (with a capital A) is breezily tossed aside, in<br />

preference and deference to artists, and from where it can trade on art simply<br />

equating with pictures, and the gradual accumulation of realistic features through<br />

schema and correction. This is in stark contrast to the stalled and stumbling ending,<br />

with its fears for the death of art (even in 1950) its grim list of eight factors detailing<br />

where society has failed art, its scant and scattered handling of developments in the<br />

second half of the twentieth century and its general lack of appreciation or<br />

enthusiasm for the achievements there, its indifference now to the artists. It is in all<br />

respects, a sad ending. But one cannot help but reflect on the merits of the<br />

historical method, and to doubt the teller rather than the tale, when he can find no<br />

space for mention or reproduction of a Francis Bacon, a Willem de Kooning, a<br />

Mark Rothko, a Frank Stella, a Jasper Johns, a Robert Rauschenberg, a Andy<br />

Warhol, a Roy Lichtenstein, a Chuck Close, a Larry Poons, a Brice Marden, a Phillip<br />

Guston, a Sol Le Witt, a Gerhard Richter, a Anselm Kieffer, a Julian Schnabel, a<br />

Francesco Clemente, a Jonathan Lasker, a Lari Pittman, anything of the world of<br />

sculpture, of mixed and expanded media and installations, or even of Australian<br />

aboriginal painting. 104 To have lost some through the exigencies of space may be<br />

accepted as unfortunate, (although in a book running at over six hundred pages, one<br />

104 This list is based upon the 16 th edition of The Story of Art, London, 1995, but grudging<br />

acknowledgement of Rauschenburg is found in an earlier essay, see Gombrich, 1982, pp. 31-33.


68<br />

wonders how much pressure can there have been on one or two more pages?) To<br />

have lost most, may be regarded as regrettable, perhaps even rigorous, but to lose<br />

all, as Lady Bracknell might say, rather looks careless. 105 For Gombrich of course<br />

the selection is rigorous and merely excludes ‘specimens of taste and fashion’,<br />

unfortunately it also amounts to a devastating critique of his own taste. 106<br />

Yet Gombrich maintains his method is sound and it is art that has failed history.<br />

But do we have poor art, or do we have a poor art history? The whole point of The<br />

Story of Art is to allow an appreciation of art’s variety, to fail in an appreciation of<br />

the present, is to fail not just art, but also its history, forty years of it, at least. If one<br />

allows perhaps that the method succumbs in the end because there can be no shortterm<br />

history, or a history of the present, and that history requires a longer<br />

perspective, one confronts a different problem. Since Gombrich’s story proposes<br />

that art simply is its history, then if history cannot pursue art to the present it is in<br />

effect to say there is no such thing as contemporary art. If there is no contemporary<br />

art, then can it be that art and its history are at an end? Yet if its history is finally at<br />

an end, then it can at least be defined! This would be cold comfort for aspiring<br />

artists, if it were true, but the fact is art can be defined without the necessity of an<br />

end, and such a definition is precisely what is required to direct an historical enquiry<br />

in the first place.<br />

Gombrich’s story fails in the short term because he can no longer distinguish<br />

between fashions, tastes and traditions, schemers and schemas. Art becomes<br />

increasingly diverse and remote for the historian seeking the self-evident tradition<br />

and the given schema in need of correction. Yet it is not so much that they are no<br />

longer in use but rather that they never really were. Tradition on Gombrich’s terms<br />

is the product of his historical method and story, and is actually as much a<br />

historicist myth as the moods and spirits of the times he regards with some<br />

scepticism. Instead of an idealist myth of grand historical forces, we have a realist<br />

myth of minor and piecemeal insights of an absolute perception. But it too comes at<br />

a price. Firstly it is realism at the cost of art, and secondly it is realism at the cost of<br />

105 There are of course more comprehensive histories of late twentieth century art, although none<br />

so directly concerned with the basis of depiction. Rival versions are considered in the closing<br />

chapters.<br />

106 Gombrich, 1995, p. 7.


69<br />

history. It starts as realism as a goal for the correction of schemas or tradition, and<br />

then realism as the measure of expression in schemas. Gombrich allows that the<br />

process is relative, that realism cannot escape a medium and a style, but since<br />

corrections are the name of the game, sooner or later pictures will converge on<br />

realism. The terms vary with the tasks of a time and place, but successive<br />

corrections theoretically ought to accumulate into the one true realism.<br />

Every generation discovered that there were still unsuspected “pockets of<br />

resistance”; strongholds of conventions which made artists apply forms they<br />

had learned rather than paint what they really saw. 107 (My italics)<br />

The problem is not, as Gombrich concludes, that the Impressionists reached the<br />

end of the road, in their translation of supposed light values into colour, but that<br />

pictures keep ditching one schema in order to correct another. The one true realism<br />

keeps cancelling itself out. We can have volume at the cost of movement, light at<br />

the cost of depth, detail at the cost of simplicity, excitement at the cost of<br />

proportion, sentimentality at the cost of sobriety. The relativism and realism of the<br />

story are actually at odds. On the one hand Gombrich allows that there is no<br />

progress in art, since all correction is relative, but on the other, that there are<br />

genuine discoveries such as perspective or the localised colour values achieved by<br />

Constable, and that they represent a real advance for depiction. Something has to<br />

give. When art subsequently does without perspective or Constable’s localised<br />

chromatics or a good deal more, Gombrich can only conclude that it is doing<br />

without realism and that art is so much the worse for it.<br />

Less realism is taken as a measure of more expression. For Gombrich this amounts<br />

to an increasing subjectivity and the twentieth century’s retreat into introspection.<br />

But expression’s correct schema, like realism’s, proves somewhat elusive and<br />

chimerical. For Gombrich it is the quest for just this spectre that charts painting’s<br />

dissolution throughout the twentieth century. 108 But while expression abandons<br />

Expressionism, the more concrete in depiction, and even the standard materials and<br />

techniques of painting, it also adopts geometric rigour, biomorphic forms, novel<br />

and compelling facture or gesture. Reference is never quite abandoned; we never<br />

107 Gombrich, 1995, p. 561 (quoting from Gombrich, 1960, p.330).<br />

108 Much the same verdict is passed in Bell, 1999. Bell readily acknowledges the influence of<br />

Gombrich.


70<br />

quite reach nothing, anymore than realism ever quite managed to accumulate<br />

everything under its steady corrections, and for the same reason. Each ‘correction’<br />

or change supplants content, or supplies its own, and the business of reference, of<br />

resemblance – even of illusions - is actually maintained. But for Gombrich the<br />

relativism this implies threatens to unravel the whole basis of the story. The<br />

principle and the precedence of making before matching, of reality before reference,<br />

would then be hopelessly compromised. It is easier in the end to dismiss the whole<br />

period as decadent, superficial, neophyte and self-indulgent. 109<br />

The problem of course is not simply with the ending of The Story of Art, but with the<br />

story itself. To accept that the story is valid up until the twentieth century, for<br />

example, is to merely paper over the cracks. 110 The method does not hold for the<br />

twentieth century, not because the twentieth century is so utterly different, but<br />

because the principle of recognising a tradition in its constituent schemas<br />

disintegrates as it approaches the present, or once the historian is confronted with<br />

precisely the situation proposed for the artist throughout history. If the historian<br />

cannot detect it in the present, armed with a scrutiny of the past, why should one<br />

believe the artist does? Or how is it therefore adequate or acceptable to reconstruct<br />

such situations in the past? 111 The fact is the present has its artists, who are accepted<br />

and recognised, and there is no clear and cataclysmic break between the twentieth<br />

century and the preceding five thousand years or so. It is convenient to see the<br />

twentieth century as utterly different, but it is inconsistent if one is also to claim that<br />

art is an elastic concept, or only a matter of depiction and reference. The problem is<br />

really one of a diminishing hindsight.<br />

At this point one needs to consider how an historical method is to interpret the past<br />

without tripping over its own terms. The problem is how a distinction is to be<br />

109 Gombrich, 1995, pp. 612-618.<br />

110 David Carrier takes this position in his critique of art history narratives. See Carrier,<br />

Artwriting, Amherst/Penn., 1987 and Carrier, Principles Of Art History Writing, Philadelphia,<br />

1991.<br />

111 Gombrich acknowledges the dilemma, in considering the objections raised by Andre Malraux<br />

in Voices Of Silence, (see Gombrich. 1960, p.54) and proposes to overcome it through ‘historical<br />

imagination’ but does not explain how this can identify the differing mental sets, and styles for<br />

pictorial notations, except in relation to their successors, that ‘confirm or deny’ their influence.<br />

His criticism of Malraux’s reluctant historicism is pursued in a later review of Malraux’s The<br />

Metamorphosis of the Gods, reprinted in Gombrich, Reflections on the history of Art, Richard<br />

Woodfield (ed.) Berkeley/London, 1987, pp. 218-220.


71<br />

maintained between method or interpretation and history. Confusion of the two is<br />

considered the folly or fallacy of historicism, but history cannot do without<br />

interpretation, obviously. There is no way to isolate just the facts, and only those<br />

accepted as incontestable, are usually those of least interest. Method clearly makes<br />

interpretation for a history, rather than simply accompanies it. Before proceeding to<br />

an historical method consistent with Goodman’s philosophy, the following chapter<br />

considers interpretation more generally.


72<br />

Interpretation<br />

Attention to historical method encounters the problem of historicism, in separating<br />

method from matter. Historicism concerns the circular nature of an interpretation<br />

of the past in terms of the present, and the difficulty of drawing a line between the<br />

two. The tendency is to ascribe to history laws or forces that are really instruments<br />

of method rather than facts of the matter, and to unfairly extend the evidence in<br />

this way. But how or where to draw the line between facts and opinion or theory is<br />

notoriously difficult. It has lead some theorists to radically relax the distinction, to<br />

propose that historical method need do no more than expand upon current social<br />

and cultural concerns, by way of weaving a coherent story from accepted facts, and<br />

to simply repeat the exercise when it no longer satisfies. In short it is a full and<br />

frank admission of historicism, and proposes rather that everything is to be taken<br />

historically or is open to reinterpretation in light of emerging or future facts and<br />

interests. The problem now is not one of reconciling history to the present, but of<br />

simply arguing for one story over another or of accepting multiple stories.<br />

This is broadly speaking, the existential view, that gained currency in the work of<br />

Martin Heidegger and inspired the hermeneutical method of Hans-Georg Gadamer<br />

and others. 112 In hermeneutical interpretation there is no pretence that historical<br />

interpretation establishes ‘the whole and nothing but’ the truth in regard to what<br />

‘really’ happened, or what past intentions may have ‘really’ been. Truth is now taken<br />

as relative to current concerns. The hermeneuticist rather constructs a persuasive<br />

argument, or simply a good story in support of such concerns, through selection of<br />

accepted facts or texts. Citation is then paramount, argument reduced to links from<br />

one text to another. But links often struggle between extending one text and<br />

inviting another, must seesaw between method and matter. Then there is the<br />

112 Martin Heidegger, Being And Time, (1927) Oxford, 1962. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and<br />

Method, London/ New York, 1975.


73<br />

problem that the facts or texts themselves may still be disputed, that varying<br />

interpretations can share nothing, but simply amount to further texts, all trading in<br />

degrees of consensus. 113 For a theorist such as E. D. Hirsch Jnr for example,<br />

intention is an indispensable part of interpretation, but is taken as almost a platonic<br />

ideal, it guides a story, even as it recedes from it. 114<br />

In contrast with the existential immersion in history, structuralism offers a kind of<br />

isolation from it. For the structuralist, the problem is not one of drawing a line<br />

between history and the present, but between history and the field of study. Briefly,<br />

structuralism derives from Ferdinand de Saussure’s studies in linguistics, their<br />

broader application to the social sciences, generally referred to as semiotics, and less<br />

prominently, from group theory in mathematics, and its application to symbolic<br />

studies in the work of Ernst Cassirer, and to physics in the work of Sir Arthur<br />

Eddington. 115 Structuralist analysis is a closed or strict system of elements, uses<br />

functions and rules to explain the production and permutation of an object or issue.<br />

Typically structuralism emphasises synchronic relations between elements, at the<br />

expense of diachronic or historical development. The rules of the system permit<br />

certain changes and these changes simply amount to the object or topic, rather than<br />

requiring history to explain how one arrives at the set of changes or elements. The<br />

problem here is that relations are reductive and tend to subsume variations under a<br />

general rule of change. Structures tend to overwhelm their objects and history.<br />

Structuralism finds application in art history in the work of Louis Marin and Hubert<br />

Damisch for example, and Gombrich’s emphasis upon schema and correction is<br />

sometimes viewed as structuralist. 116 But structuralism is noted here mainly for its<br />

sharp contrast with existential approaches.<br />

Post-structuralist theorists reject the emphasis upon change as a given and the<br />

reductive tendency that ultimately finds all structures an echo of the structure of the<br />

113 For moderate hermeneutic approaches see Jurgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests<br />

Boston, 1971 and more recently, Joseph Margolis, Interpretation Radical but not Unruly,<br />

Berkeley/London, 1995.<br />

114 See for example, E. D. Hirsch Jnr, The Aims of Interpretation, Chicago, 1976.<br />

115 For a general survey and history of structuralism see Peter Caws, Structuralism: The Art of the<br />

Intelligible, Atlantic Highlands, N.J. 1988. Also, Goodman acknowledges the influence of<br />

Cassirer in both Ways of Worldmaking and Languages of Art.<br />

116 See for example, Mitchell, 1994, p. 342.


74<br />

mind, as Claude Levi-Strauss famously speculated (somewhat after Kant). 117 They<br />

draw upon Heidegger, and Nietzsche, and adopt a sweeping relativism of<br />

metaphysics as well as Freudian notions of the Id and Libido in constructing<br />

language and The Subject. For theorists such as Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault,<br />

Jean-Francois Lyotard, or Jean Baudrillard no one story or grand narrative will do,<br />

interpretations cannot even argue for common ground, for they pursue knowledge<br />

on different terms. 118 In other words, their relativism rules out any<br />

commensurability or points of agreement between interpretations. Understanding<br />

and knowledge are consequently taken as a matter of influence, of institutions and<br />

power in some versions. 119 For Derrida, the text or work is to be ‘deconstructed’, by<br />

playing upon the ambiguities or ‘differences’ in syntactic construction, and<br />

generating ‘slippages’. Interpretation becomes a kind of whimsical improvisation on<br />

the rules of grammar. Again the results tend to seesaw, now between poetry and<br />

academic discourse. But the radical relativism adopted in many of these theories<br />

draws grave objections concerning a lack of consistency or coherence.<br />

A claim such as Gadamer’s “all knowledge is historically conditioned” is by<br />

definition ahistorical or an open contradiction. 120 To place history outside the rest<br />

of the body of knowledge is only to beg the question how such a statement can<br />

then be claimed, or known? In the case of intention conceived ideally, the question<br />

arises where does the interpreter draw the line? In what ways is the text or style real<br />

or ideal? From where do we start to construct the notional, nominal author’s<br />

intentions? The implied duality brings in its train a distinguished body of<br />

philosophical debate. If grammatical construction is to provide a starting point, then<br />

why are not its constructions also taken to orchestrate ambiguity, or slippage as<br />

well? Poetry would seem to trade precisely in this aspect of language. Fitting<br />

deconstruction to construction in this way begins to look a little too constructive.<br />

Lyotard’s rejection of a ‘metanarrative’ tying together the world then leaves the<br />

117 Levi-Strauss, ‘Reponse a quelques questions’, Esprit, n.s. 11, 1963, pp. 596-627.<br />

118 See for example, Derrida Writing and Difference, (Paris, 1967) Chicago/London, 1978,<br />

Lyotard, The Post Modern Condition, (Paris, 1979) Minnesota, 1984, and Baudrillard, The<br />

Ecstasy of Communication, (Paris, 1984) New York, 1987.<br />

119 For a seminal post-structuralist analysis of power and knowledge see Michel Foucault, The<br />

Archaeology of Knowledge, (Paris, 1969) London, 1972. Foucault is often also taken as a<br />

structuralist, particularly in France.<br />

120 Gadamer, 1975, p. 483.


75<br />

constitution of narrative disturbing open; no narrative is then humble or small<br />

enough not to contain others. Similar objections are levelled at Goodman’s<br />

‘constructional’ philosophy, but while Goodman shares many of these convictions<br />

for relativism and pluralism, one of the reasons for adopting his aesthetic is its<br />

ability to meet such objections more successfully than has elsewhere been<br />

demonstrated.<br />

So far this aspect to Goodman’s theory has only been glimpsed in his rejection of<br />

synonymy and intention concerning stylistics. This is a suitable point at which to<br />

appreciate it more fully. Synonymy of styles amounts to versions of a shared<br />

content or object, as ways of depicting the same thing. But reconciling versions thus<br />

also reduces content – takes all differences as only a matter of style. In Goodman’s<br />

view where versions share too little or reduce content too much for ease or<br />

purpose, in finding the common denominator, we do better to treat versions not as<br />

sharing a common content or world, but as simply making different content,<br />

ultimately dealing in different worlds. Then again, when too many worlds make the<br />

going confusing, we do better to find some shared versions and simplify matters.<br />

This is Goodman’s pluralism and it is distinctive for its ‘irrealist’ attitude; that<br />

switches back and forth between versions and worlds. Before considering an<br />

historical method consistent with this view, some measure must be taken of<br />

objections to irrealism. 121<br />

The objection is mainly that two sets of rules or two levels of rule are confused or<br />

inconsistent within the theory, on one level there are rules for relativism of all<br />

terms, while on a second level there is the term of rightness as an absolute,<br />

governing relativism, and holding for all worlds. On one level the theory claims an<br />

incommensurability of worlds, while on a second, it tacitly acknowledges a<br />

commensurate world-scale in rightness, by which worlds are organised and<br />

navigated. If rightness is absolute, then the worlds made are according to one rule,<br />

and amount to one world, if rightness is taken as relative on the other hand, then<br />

there can be no rightness or rule for all worlds, nor reason to advocate them.<br />

121<br />

See for example, Harvey Siegel, Relativism Refuted: A Critique of Contemporary<br />

Epistemological Relativism, Dordecht, 1987, pp. 153-154. See also interesting commentary in<br />

James F. Harris, Against Relativity, La Salle, Illinois, 1992.


76<br />

A short defence is that the objection itself makes the mistake of demanding an<br />

absolute relativism of rightness and pluralism of worlds that makes no sense. To<br />

assume there is rightness beyond worlds is to ask for rightness of nothing. To want<br />

worlds not measured by worlds, or as worlds, is simply not to want worlds. A longer<br />

defence is that Goodman allows that varieties of rightness arise supplementing<br />

truth, in tests for truth, in categories necessary to truth but as often are indifferent<br />

to it and beyond declaration or proposition (and so truth) to fair or right sampling<br />

and depiction. 122 Controversially, Goodman claims that both truth and beauty are<br />

subordinate to rightness or are only some of the ways or parts of rightness that go<br />

to deciding what makes a world. So rightness assumes an unusual prominence in<br />

Goodman’s philosophy, certainly.<br />

The point is to appreciate that versions are right or wrong (even when not<br />

necessarily true or false, beautiful or ugly) in establishing reference to a diverse<br />

world or some world in a diverse universe. Whether one accepts diverse right<br />

versions of a single world or diverse worlds is not that important to irrealism. The<br />

one world common to all right versions reduces itself to nothing; all right worlds<br />

only make some versions of others. Goodman wittily concludes that ‘the<br />

philosopher, like the philanderer, is always finding himself stuck with none or too<br />

many’. 123 The oscillation between versions and worlds equally rejects monism and<br />

dualism. ‘The realist will resist the conclusion that there is no world; the idealist will<br />

resist the conclusion that all conflicting versions describe different worlds.’ 124<br />

Irrealist pluralism is thus effectively constrained by nihilism and requires no<br />

conflicting or double standard.<br />

To return to the issue of interpretation, it might seem the pluralist is content to<br />

accept all interpretation as simply describing different works in different worlds,<br />

that there can be no right or wrong interpretation. For the irrealist this is not the<br />

case. Interpretations share an identified work or object, are right in so far as validly<br />

derived from identification or the facts of the matter, are necessarily plural in<br />

disputing implications for a given identity. In this regard pluralism of interpretation<br />

is obviously less controversial than pluralism of worlds. It is commonplace, after all,<br />

122 Goodman, 1978, pp. 109-140.<br />

123 Ibid. p.119.<br />

124 Ibid.


77<br />

to accept that interpretations are necessarily various. Wrong interpretation may<br />

incorrectly identify a work or object, or falsely derive implications. For example<br />

Michelangelo’s David may be interpreted as a giant nudist bully, but the<br />

interpretation is wrong because scale and the biblical character of David are<br />

misidentified, and custom of undress does not follow from Old Testament Judah<br />

and Israel. 125 If right, the interpretation is not of David, if of David, the<br />

interpretation is wrong. In accepting that many interpretations may be right, the<br />

irrealist does not accept that any and every interpretation is right, or that rightness<br />

imposes no criteria for interpretation. Plural right interpretation also complements<br />

the proposed theory of art, where circumspective meaning requires just this<br />

diversity. To simply allow each interpretation a separate work, would defeat the<br />

purpose of art; reduce interpretation to identification.<br />

Yet plural right interpretation is not quite trivial either. Right interpretations trace<br />

broader implications for work or object in a variety of directions, and if implications<br />

are valid then are counted as right but do not necessarily agree with each other or<br />

add up to the one big right interpretation. Michelangelo’s David may rightly be<br />

interpreted as a) a personification of the civic spirit of Florence, b) a revival of<br />

classical heroism, c) an ideal male physique, d) a subversion of Christian piety and<br />

modesty, for example. Yet Florence is hardly personified by an ideal male physique<br />

or subversion of Christian principles; a classical hero surely deserves an ideal<br />

physique, but is uncomfortable personifying a devoutly Christian city, the ideal<br />

physique is compromised by the tasks of a teenage shepherd and the skills of a<br />

slingshot. Combined, all look variously wrong although are only one such<br />

combination in any case, while each alone seems right up to a point. Some combine<br />

certainly, might usefully simplify the clutch of interpretations, some compromise<br />

may allow others combination, then again the cost of compromise may rob<br />

interpretations of too much; mean less, if more consistently. So the irrealist, as<br />

indicated, juggles too many against too few in preserving rightness.<br />

125 Actually, the relevant Biblical text (1 Samuel 17) mentions David’s possession of a cloak and<br />

pouch at least, in which he carries five smooth stones for his slingshot, after discarding the<br />

armour and weapons offered by King Saul. The all-nude combat stance perhaps owes more to<br />

Greek traditions, taken up below, but neither source sanctions codes of undress for casual<br />

intimidation.


78<br />

Also, plural right interpretation does more than maintain a singular identification at<br />

its source. Identity is as much decided by rival interpretation as decides them. The<br />

irrealist thus uses methods to make matter, adjusts each for rightness. Beyond this,<br />

irrealism makes no conditions for any one right history. Still, the historian is<br />

perhaps confronted with a different set of priorities for ‘what really happened’<br />

where a) many versions are equally right but b) wrong versions are still to be<br />

avoided and while c) better versions are still to be had, even though d) there is no<br />

best version (or none is better than all). Not all or any right versions will do. Only<br />

the most comprehensive or efficient are preferred, yet some right implications do<br />

not easily combine with others, lessen effectiveness in so doing. The irrealist<br />

historian is torn between methods, must balance improvement of past versions<br />

against introduction of merely different versions. The irrealist historian’s method -<br />

in as much as it allows just one – trades between better and different versions.<br />

Art historical interpretation comes with more baggage. The artwork is not only<br />

identified by a source but also style. Stylistics rests upon a theory of reference and<br />

the irrealist art historian here appeals to a taxonomy of exemplification. Such<br />

structure obviously suggests structuralism in its fixed or absolute terms yet the<br />

structure here does not subsume too great a variety of features or applications<br />

under a general rule, nor eliminates diachronic differences in favour of synchronic<br />

ones. On the contrary, stylistics here has drawn further distinctions between the<br />

expressive and the stated, the literal and metaphorical, depictive and material<br />

exemplification. Breadth and nuance of meaning only gain from this stylistic<br />

structure. Diachronic or historical change is gauged by variations on these routes of<br />

reference, on what history does with them, rather than what it does to them. For, to<br />

historicize them thus would be to rob art history of any stable measure or meaning,<br />

to fall into an absolute historicism that, as indicated earlier, is not strictly coherent.<br />

An art historical method thus emerges for irrealism. Contrasts with other radical<br />

approaches to interpretation have pointed to dangers in too much relativism or the<br />

folly of absolute relativism. The study now compares an irrealist approach with that<br />

of a realist, in the following chapter looks at what story or stories of art an irrealist<br />

might tell.


79<br />

Realisms<br />

In Chapter Six The Story of Art was considered as a realist history and to have<br />

suffered in its account of later twentieth century art, largely as a consequence of its<br />

method. This now provides a convenient comparison. Earlier, the exchange<br />

between Gombrich and Goodman was noted, concerning the issue of nature versus<br />

convention in which Goodman urged further relativism to Gombrich’s views. 126 In<br />

fact Goodman’s approval of Gombrich’s work registers in a number of his<br />

books. 127 The suggestion here is really to implement the kind of relativism<br />

Goodman advocated and Gombrich tentatively supported, and from which an<br />

account of later twentieth century art in particular may benefit.<br />

The preceding chapter has shown how pluralism of interpretation is distinct from<br />

metaphysical pluralism of worlds. Similarly, realism may be limited to matters of<br />

style, taken as plural or realisms, without implying metaphysical pluralism. 128 For<br />

Goodman, stylistic realisms arise in three ways, in ease of use, through habit or<br />

preference, in novelty or revelation, and in the factual contrasted with the<br />

fictional. 129 Realism is thus relative to scheme or style of depiction, to object and<br />

system, rather than optics or illusion. Objections may run that the comfortable or<br />

preferred are not always realistic. Standard line illustrations for scientific or<br />

educational use tend to typify and simplify object, exclude the particular, incidental<br />

and so some realism. Then again, photographs used for personal identification, on<br />

files and passports for example, are almost never preferred by or comfortable for at<br />

least the bearer, and remote and strange objects such as the surface of the moon or<br />

Mars often prompt surprising scale and depth ambiguities, even in the most detailed<br />

126 Gombrich, 1982, p.284.<br />

127 Goodman 1976, Goodman, 1978, Goodman, 1984 and Goodman and Elgin, Reconceptions In<br />

Philosophy, London, 1988.<br />

128 The distinction between metaphysical and stylistic realism adopted here is made in Elgin,<br />

‘What Goodman Leaves Out’ Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 25, No 1, Spring, 1991, pp.<br />

89-95.<br />

129 Goodman, 1984, pp. 126-130.


80<br />

and ‘realistic’ of photographs. But in any case, to claim novelty as immediately or<br />

ultimately a matter of realism is also to succumb to the aesthetic of the realist.<br />

The so-called realism of a Caravaggio or a Courbet for example, was greeted as a<br />

revolt in standards of person and theme or iconography. It was not a revelation<br />

how much more realistically persons were depicted, but that such flawed or humble<br />

people were depicted in or with such controversial roles or attitudes. Such people<br />

were hardly a revelation and realism is not to be confused with mere poverty or<br />

modesty. The chiaroscuro of Caravaggio or the coarse facture of Courbet may gain<br />

in expressive range for the exercise but neither contributes to nor originates from<br />

mere realism or lowliness. Much the same holds for the reception of Impressionism,<br />

which was no more understood immediately than as only a more realistic approach<br />

to light values or Parisian pastimes, which were then hardly taken as more realistic<br />

than other kinds. Equally, the contemporaneous adoption of ‘oriental’ spatial<br />

schemes (oblique or parallel oblique projections) and striking asymmetrical framing<br />

or composition, while refreshing, hardly replaced just perspectives, or just replaced<br />

anything for very long. Even the work of Michelangelo remained deeply<br />

controversial in his day, not because of newly acquired accuracy in musculature, but<br />

because of his fixation on a supposed ideal nude at the expense of sacred themes<br />

and sentiment. Realism and revelation had very little to do with it. Then again, the<br />

striking realism of a Vermeer, in integration of tonal values for surface or texture in<br />

perspective, and something akin to a photographic depth of focus, went unnoticed<br />

in his lifetime and for some considerable time thereafter. Moreover, the proposed<br />

theory of art as dense or circumspective meaning argues against just this easy<br />

recognition or decisive revelation and is at least as much supported by history on<br />

this score as realist accounts. So novelty has no more to do with realism than<br />

idealism, as much to do with confusion and challenge as revelation.<br />

Yet Goodman is surely right that either the old or new may be accorded more<br />

realistic, the factual or fictional realistic or not and that the routes of realism are<br />

many and varied. But in as much as realism is recognised as a relation of scheme to<br />

object and system, some further explanation is perhaps owed. Derivation is<br />

suggested. In Chapter Five the difference between art and science was touched<br />

upon. Art organises works by styles and while older works cannot be conversely


81<br />

derived from later ones in the way that improvement in scientific theories<br />

accommodates – in so far as theories are true – nevertheless, some derivations for<br />

schemes or styles, objects and themes are traced, often to distinguish new ones, and<br />

amount in fact to the measures of realism. To the extent that a scheme or style<br />

contains another, may conversely derive a lesser one from its elements, a scheme is<br />

more realistic. Or, where a scheme contains others but is not contained by them, it<br />

is realistic. The commonsense appeal to realism in depiction comes to just this.<br />

A simple line illustration may be taken as less realistic than one equal in all other<br />

respects but including tonal values (that is, values of light); greater range of tonal<br />

values allows more realism, while colour in greater range improves on tone and line.<br />

In as much as object permits this expansion of scheme or scheme admits this<br />

expansion of object, the fuller colour scheme is the more realistic, allows converse<br />

derivation of tone and line; cannot be derived from them. A similar argument may<br />

be made for the converse derivation of projections from perspective, along the lines<br />

indicated in chapter three, and thus for the greater realism of perspective. Where<br />

successive schemes add to information of the same object, realism amounts to a<br />

measure of greater information or accuracy for object. Gombrich argues against<br />

truth assigned to depiction generally, only to concede that portraiture of person or<br />

place is correct (or true) where scheme correctly understood provides ‘no false<br />

information’. 130 Realism as a measure of accuracy is confidently rejected by<br />

Goodman with the example of two pictures of supposed equal information, one of<br />

reversed perspective and colour, the other normal and so more realistic by<br />

familiarity or ease of information rather than accuracy. 131 But again, the hypothetical<br />

comparison bears closer scrutiny.<br />

To introduce a scheme of colour and perspective reversal is also to stress a new<br />

alignment of the two. The reversal of one does not follow from the reversal of the<br />

other. The scheme therefore draws attention to unusual alignments of shape and<br />

distance to colour, is difficult to understand not just because of rarity of scheme,<br />

but because other information to the normal scheme is ignored or concealed in the<br />

reversal. For example treatment of surfaces, textures or contour (sharp or soft) even<br />

130 Gombrich, 1960, p. 78.<br />

131 Goodman, 1976, pp. 35-36.


82<br />

tonal contrasts for a given part or object, are confused in colour and perspective<br />

reversal and crucial symmetries and other alignments to vanishing points are<br />

replaced. 132 So an appeal to the same information between schemes does not quite<br />

hold, although information in the reversed scheme is no<strong>net</strong>heless accurate, and in as<br />

much as object is actual or factual, both schemes are realistic. In as much as aspects<br />

revealed in the reversed scheme are at the expense of more or more useful aspects<br />

in the normal scheme, the reversed scheme is less realistic. To argue that familiarity<br />

with the reversed scheme can accommodate the lost or concealed information can<br />

as easily argue that the normal scheme will no longer then offer this information<br />

(would strictly, no longer be the normal scheme) but rather, an equally confusing<br />

contrast, or for simply a reversal of information from respective schemes or of just<br />

names for schemes. Difference between schemes maintains difference in<br />

information.<br />

However the illustration also shows that accuracy of object now depends on more<br />

than one scheme, accuracy of scheme depend either on versions of object or<br />

different objects. Realism of scheme cannot thus be measured along a single<br />

derivation. Realism and derivation for scheme and object are multiple, allow<br />

conflicting schemes for the same object, (as in the normal and reversed examples)<br />

or versions of the same object for the same scheme (say, colour and perspective<br />

alignment). In so far as derivation is maintained for scheme and object, realism<br />

obtains. But as such, realism now becomes necessary yet antithetical to art; faces<br />

science and stricter uses as easily as the more circumspect and looser organisation<br />

of art. Realism, in so far as it is consistent in derivation, supplies the bottom line for<br />

art. 133 Yet information preserved or extended between schemes or styles cannot be<br />

complete anymore than synonymy may be absolute. Moreover, information derived<br />

between styles still confronts the difference between fact and fiction, sense and<br />

132 Similar if simpler reversals obtained either by mirrors or mere inversions of pictures are a<br />

common source of comparison for painters, as a way of detecting subtle imbalances or<br />

discrepancies to a painting, either in traditional genres, especially portraiture, as well as in<br />

abstract work. The abstract works of De Kooning for example were made by working the<br />

painting from all four sides and corners, usually when upright, in order to take into account just<br />

these differences to the information or composition. The familiar practice of backing away,<br />

squinting with tilted head is another way of making similar comparisons.<br />

133 Under this formulation the line between science and art obviously blurs somewhat, according<br />

to strictness and range of derivation for depiction, but does not disturb the basic distinction<br />

between digression and progression, indeed better explains the shifts in status of say, antiquated<br />

medical or engineering illustrations, where improvements to accuracy may allow new<br />

appreciation of the (now less realistic) scheme.


83<br />

nonsense and begs questions of the difference between fact and category. Pictures<br />

of unicorns and Homer Simpson or any young woman and a typical tiger may be<br />

realistic as pictures but not as information, as often are neither, or unrealistic as<br />

pictures but realistic as information. Derivation to and from fictive and class terms<br />

is thus also required of realism, and the irrealist here appeals to Goodman’s<br />

nominalism. 134<br />

Very briefly, class and fictive pictures do not depict universal and fictitious objects.<br />

As indicated in Chapter Three, they actually depict only a sort of picture, and serve<br />

to collect or sort pictures of actual objects, or individuals, so that any such<br />

collection contains a unique ordering of individuals, is an ‘individual’ collection,<br />

identified by just one and the same name. Goodman’s nominalist construction thus<br />

builds only with individuals, only to individuals. Class and fictive pictures basically<br />

point to such sortings. The difference between class and fictive pictures lies in the<br />

truth or accuracy of the sorting. The typical tiger preserves just key features to all<br />

pictures of (actual) tigers, is at least ‘nothing but the truth’ in sorting relevant<br />

schemes and object. The unicorn on the other hand is literally false as a sorting of<br />

schemes for horses and horns, although may highlight the realistic scheme in<br />

interesting ways in so doing; offer striking (and true or right) metaphor for<br />

mutation, anomaly or the unexpected. Sorts of pictures, factual and fictive, denoted<br />

by hyphenation as ‘tiger-pictures’ or ‘unicorn-pictures’ for example, thus shape the<br />

organisation of pictures, their objects and realism. Realism (and idealism) of scheme<br />

is tested or tempered by the fictive, while effective factual sorting extends actual<br />

object. Realism thus derives from both under this nominalist ontology, but again by<br />

no single or fixed route.<br />

Realism, in short, might be called a style with too many variations; conversely, a<br />

style, variation with not enough realism. How many realisms to rightly allow among<br />

styles, like how many styles to allow an art history, or indeed how much history to<br />

allow styles or realisms, depends upon a theory of depiction, given styles and how<br />

the history is focussed or framed. No history accommodates all styles; some styles<br />

exclude others. Period styles do not apply everywhere nor regional or national styles<br />

134 A full nominalist treatment for depiction, maintaining individuality to construction, is the<br />

work of another study. For details see Goodman, 1976, pp. 21-26, and Goodman, 1984, pp. 48-<br />

53.


84<br />

hold for all periods, and while personal styles are more consistent in this respect,<br />

subdivisions similarly compete for works, between an artist’s early, middle and late<br />

styles, their Paris, Munich and Rome styles, their mad, bad and sad styles, for<br />

example. Moreover, any history of a given style rarely includes its entire works, and<br />

any given work is usually grasped by a variety of styles. So history must settle for<br />

some styles, some works; trace realism between them to more or less, and to more<br />

or less realism. Choice of historical frame may be as much determined by<br />

prominence of styles or realisms, as determine them.<br />

An irrealist duly allows multiple right art histories; may either improve upon some,<br />

in right grasp of stylistics, accuracy of source, reach of styles, or diverge from them,<br />

where other works and styles are rightly included, and so amount to a different<br />

rather than better history. Either way, art history is served by a version that is right<br />

in construction, true to facts for source. This mix and match of realism and style<br />

also suggests a model for the procedure of the artist, in contrast with Gombrich’s<br />

make and match. And in just this, the difference may not seem to amount to very<br />

much: between the artist correcting a style and the artist connecting styles. One<br />

corrects realism; the other connects versions. The difference however, is more<br />

pronounced firstly in the attitude of this undertaking. For Gombrich, the activity is<br />

a fairly clear cut case of problem solving, of preferably a commission, or at least an<br />

intention, obvious and available schema, and test results gauged by potent illusion.<br />

For Goodman, grasp of style is much less clear cut; is more a matter of practice and<br />

feedback, as with the acquisition of language, the artist duly plays by feel, draws on<br />

any number of schemas or features for the right circumspection.<br />

The difference grows with the priority the problem solver must assign synonymy of<br />

object or content. Style then becomes just ways of showing the same thing. The<br />

same thing accurately added to or improved becomes the real thing and the<br />

problem solver allows perspective, tonal and colour accuracies to make more<br />

realism, to match principles of visual perception and cast rivals as mere versions, as<br />

ideal or subjective, expressive or decorative. Yet what can be made or matched is<br />

actually severely constrained by a single synonymy. Improvements in the ways of<br />

showing the same thing have a way of turning into ways of showing different


85<br />

things, or the expressive as subjective, emotive or decorative is soon overdone or<br />

wrong. The problem solver cannot then quite find the problem much less solve it.<br />

The player, by contrast, has more options. Styles need not share the same object or<br />

content, depicted objects may be native to a style, so that style then starts from<br />

mere ‘statement’. Expression is not necessarily sentiment or subjective, real or ideal,<br />

while the literal structure of a depiction, the facture, texture and material sample<br />

may be meaningful even though obviously not stating an object or expressing<br />

anything other than itself. The player is interested in a right version rather than a<br />

‘realistic’ one – in additional conditions to the realistic or idealistic, the expressive or<br />

stated, objective or subjective, and these rest with the routes of reference rather<br />

than the laws of optics. The difference is now considerable. Realism for the player is<br />

really a function of the organisation of styles within routes of reference, and is duly<br />

multiple and mobile. To re-phrase Gombrich - there really is no such thing as<br />

realism; there are only realisms.<br />

A useful contrast is suggested by Gombrich’s treatment of the work of Pollock.<br />

Pollock’s distinctive abstractions are taken as ‘the sheer handling of paint regardless<br />

of any ulterior motive or purpose’. 135 But this is decidedly at odds with the<br />

interpretation of Pollock’s work at the time and since. In the case of the example<br />

provided in the Story of Art, titled Number 31 (1950) such work is generally<br />

understood as offering both literal and metaphorical meaning, of expressing<br />

violence, freedom and improvisation, as well as being literally a uniform field,<br />

sustained on an imposing scale, rigorously achieved through the novel technique of<br />

dripping or flicking of industrial enamels. 136 As noted, Gombrich resists meaning to<br />

materials and technique as augmentation of depiction, ostensibly as a consequence<br />

of his commitment to principles of visual perception, even when here, clearly an<br />

accepted interpretation. 137 But such literal sampling also constitutes realism, and<br />

properties sampled in abstraction equally allow and rely upon derivation, upon<br />

135 Gombrich, 1995, p. 602.<br />

136 The work is lavishly reproduced in the sixteenth edition of The Story of Art, (1995) even by its<br />

own impressive standards, in a double gatefold, all the more curious for the stark interpretation<br />

that accompanies it. See Gombrich, 1995, p. 603.<br />

137 For standard interpretation of Pollock, see Claude Cernuschi, Jackson Pollock: Meaning and<br />

Significance, New York, 1992. William C. Seitz, Abstract Expressionist Painting in America<br />

Cambridge/Mass./London, 1983, Irving Sandler, Abstract Expressionism: The Triumph of<br />

American Painting, New York/London/Washington, 1970.


86<br />

precedents and versions. Whether we accept that dripping sets new standards in<br />

application of paint, or exemplifies a profound and ‘real’ quality of paint and<br />

painting, depends how it is seen contributing to matters of field composition,<br />

freedom, improvisation, scale and so forth. In other words it is a question of<br />

rightness of mix in derived realisms.<br />

Pollock’s dense, uniform compositions or ‘fields’ thus stand in comparison with<br />

those of Mirō, Masson and Tobey for example, but reject biomorphic shapes,<br />

intimacy of scale and a more unitary structure. His work equally compares with the<br />

spontaneous and gestural approaches of early Kandinsky, later Klee and<br />

contemporaries such as de Kooning, Still or Hoffman but rejects brushstroke and<br />

drawing by standard or mere easel-scale means, and more discrete composition.<br />

Further derivation arises among the characteristic large-scale work of the New York<br />

School, and Pollock’s distinctive approach of an unstretched canvas laid upon the<br />

floor, and worked from all four sides, contrasts with for example, the work at this<br />

time of Newman, Rothko or Kline. Indeed even dripping has its precedents and<br />

parallels but the point here is just that it is a mix and match of styles; that derivation<br />

is necessarily in a variety of directions and not from any single version of<br />

abstraction, or an obvious schema, and that as many are pursued as scope of study<br />

allows.<br />

It is Pollock’s work that connects these features, or in effect makes them into a<br />

single schema. Without his work or preceding it, they share no compelling link.<br />

They are not the only versions of abstraction available, nor are they necessarily the<br />

most prominent or accepted. Abstraction therefore also comes in many, if any, right<br />

versions. With Pollock’s work, meaning changes for such features by his<br />

combination or connection. The work recasts surrounding styles of abstraction,<br />

draws attention to surprising links, to realisms for materials as noted, and so places<br />

itself at the centre of this arrangement for a moment; becomes its fullest expression<br />

or the most complete of such works. Whether these derivations or influences are<br />

the only or most accurate ones for Pollock is of course, a matter of interpretation.<br />

But there is no way to admit all of Pollock’s influences; historical derivation is not<br />

absolute. To insist that influences must only be direct for example or only those


87<br />

that the artist acknowledged or demonstrably had knowledge of, is of course also to<br />

limit the influence of remaining influences, to deny that some lead to others. The<br />

‘direct’ influence rules out other than manifest replication by this route, and the<br />

whole point of influence. Then again, not all influences are as interesting or<br />

important as others. Derived features are interesting in proportion to their source,<br />

to preceding and prevailing values within a stylistic framework, but the historian<br />

cannot look for or find just any influence or derivation within a given framework.<br />

Equally, the historian cannot accept any feature as somehow derived from an<br />

accepted style or work, either. No style can be so porous as to absorb all and any<br />

features of a work, nor so potent as to project all and any features to works.<br />

Derivation must therefore balance the direct against the indirect, the meaningful, if<br />

more far-fetched, against the less meaningful, but strictly measured. Practice<br />

generally involves a two-way adjustment, some derivations reform style; others<br />

adjust work or source. To the extent that works or sources enlarge the stylistic<br />

framework while coherence is maintained, the exercise counts as successful.<br />

All the same, there is a fundamental difference between the historian committed to<br />

styles before works, and works before styles. The first allows style generous<br />

extension, embraces works and a broader source by more indirect derivation, or<br />

spirit. Interpretation is for a time or place, personality or people, culture, economy,<br />

ideology or faith for example, and sorts works ‘top down’. The second allows style<br />

much less latitude, demands more direct derivation and priority to material<br />

differences for works, interprets by intrinsic or formal means, and builds styles<br />

‘bottom up’. Of course it is rare to find an historian wholly committed to just one<br />

or the other, but plain to see how easy it is to lean one way or the other, and why<br />

Goodman’s irrealism, supported by a view of depiction as exemplification, might be<br />

bracketed with Gombrich’s schema and correction. But the irrealist here is not<br />

necessarily or only the formalist, and while the study argues for the replacement of<br />

Gombrich’s schemas with sampling, irrealism equally supports spirits to styles, for<br />

the idealist or ideologue, asks only that they identify consistent stylistic features,<br />

although perhaps would only feel right allowing enough to cancel out each others’<br />

magic. The point thus remains that one is never enough; that when or where<br />

schemas or spirits are taken depends upon the stylistic frame.


88<br />

To return to the example of Pollock, it is scarcely conceivable to offer a history of<br />

abstraction in painting without granting Pollock prominence, and what margin for<br />

interpretation this allows is all the more tantalising for this entrenchment. The more<br />

versions offered on Pollock, the more latitude they gradually win. Pollock becomes<br />

more entrenched, although his standing may yet be diminished in further versions.<br />

For example, one might then accept that Pollock must be included in some way, if<br />

not quite as big a way. But with this, Pollock then ceases to be such an enticing<br />

target. Conversely, such proliferation of versions permits other work or styles to be<br />

included. Distribution of versions thus gradually shifts the focus of art history, and<br />

distribution and focus of versions may thus enter the irrealist’s calculations of<br />

rightness here. The irrealist here acknowledges not only multiple right versions for<br />

art history, but to some extent where they are too many or too few. In this, method<br />

and story are again some distance from The Story of Art, schema and correction.<br />

A story of art nevertheless emerges, grants that some styles gain prominence, are<br />

influenced by preceding ones, variously influence others. An irrealist art history, as<br />

the name suggests, does not quite ignore realism but rather allows that this collects<br />

and connects styles, is traced in various directions and tailors numbers to the scope<br />

or frame of a history. This historical method will presently be tested against painting<br />

in the second half of the twentieth century. However painting and period present<br />

special issues and attention must next be given to painting and the materials of<br />

depiction. Just as irrealism allows realisms to styles, pluralism is also extended to<br />

materials and the practices of painting.


89<br />

Painting<br />

Discussion of depiction has encountered painting in relation to material<br />

exemplification, and it should be clear at this point that material is not limited to<br />

painting and that material sampled interacts with depiction and combines as<br />

reference. What is not yet clear is why painting should enjoy such prominence as<br />

depiction and prestige in art. Or, put another way, why depiction especially needs<br />

painting? In addressing these questions, a number of preceding issues are drawn<br />

together and lead to an extended critique of some formalist art criticism. The<br />

chapter is somewhat longer for this, but sheds light on how versions of painting<br />

influence the study of recent art history, and so ushers in the second part of the<br />

study.<br />

The proposed theory of depiction allows that two sampling schemes interact;<br />

depiction classifies its object, or alerts us to two-dimensional properties of the<br />

depicted object, the object classed in turn alerts us to other properties of the<br />

material used in depiction. One scheme deals in two-dimensionality the other in<br />

three. Where art is concerned, a premium is placed on the density or circumspection<br />

of meaning. The emphasis is upon depiction that resists ready and regular classing<br />

and pursues subtle and complex differences of scheme and object. Requirements of<br />

materials in art are thus for an optimum versatility in engaging and transforming<br />

schemes. 138 In one sense art establishes an innovative impetus, and materials must<br />

be open-ended for experiment. In another sense the requirements must ensure a<br />

stability or continuity of scheme. The objective after all, is to maintain<br />

circumspection of meaning rather than dissolve it. The requirement thus balances<br />

innovation against continuity.<br />

138 Clearly this resembles Goodman’s symptom of repleteness of depictive syntax, although here<br />

divorced from a notational framework, but affirmed as a distinctive symptom for depiction as art.<br />

For repleteness see Goodman, 1976, pp. 225-232 and Goodman, 1984, pp. 135-138.


90<br />

But versatility also arises through variety of object, through fictive and class terms.<br />

Where versions of object are no longer shared between schemes, but rather become<br />

native to them or scheme-dependent, materials are also drawn into a radical<br />

diversity. Not all schemes use the same qualities of paint in the same ways, its glazes<br />

or thinning agents, its thickening agents, viscosity and body, range of colour, drying<br />

times, permanence and finish, and related means of application, all variously allow<br />

some schemes and deny others. Not all paint or process thus find or make the same<br />

objects or for the same schemes. Pluralism is extended to materials and process in<br />

this way. Yet painting is confidently regarded as the principal material for depiction<br />

in art, is often taken as only a synonym for either or both. In what sense then does<br />

painting meet these diverse requirements yet remain one and the same practice?<br />

Painting in this respect is more usefully contrasted with printing. The distinction<br />

firstly lies between the work of sole instance and the work of multiple instances. 139<br />

The work that has only one instance obviously measures scheme or schemes against<br />

other works rather than instances, conforms or deviates in an infinite grading of<br />

ways. Such work might combine, size, location, surface and other properties that<br />

resist efficient print duplication. A print measures scheme between instances or as<br />

efficient duplication. But a painting or other work of sole instance must measure<br />

only between works, and so engages a wider, more versatile scheme. 140 Scheme is<br />

stretched by works of minimal instance to optimal diversity, stresses the subtle and<br />

vital nature of style and promotes more circumspect meaning. In this sense the<br />

work of sole instance is especially averse to realism and stricter derivation. This is<br />

not to say that painting is incapable of realism of course, or that prints are<br />

necessarily more realistic or of less value as art. Rather, it points only to the<br />

advantage of the work of sole instance in this respect, and to the acknowledged preeminence<br />

of painting over prints in art.<br />

139 This distinction is observed in part by Goodman in a more general discussion of forgery, as<br />

between the autographic, where identity is determined by history of production, and the<br />

allographic, where identity is determined by system of notation. See Goodman, 1976, pp. 113-<br />

122. But both painting and prints count as autographic on this score, and the distinction here is<br />

more narrowly between schemes for sole and multiple instances of a work.<br />

140 The painting that copies a painting clearly duplicates yet is not a print or instance of the<br />

copied painting. The painted copy remains tied to a scheme of sole instance for a work; is usually<br />

a dull, minor or irritating instance of the scheme and as such is generally disparaged. Forgeries<br />

trade on a confusion of identity. More distinct variation in ‘copying’ is a traditional source of<br />

inspiration.


91<br />

A print usually confines versatility to schemes of strict or efficient duplication,<br />

measures them both against instances of a given work and works as other instances<br />

of scheme, easing the task of each. Depictive scheme is more efficient for more<br />

instances to a given work and so scheme, allows work more widespread use and<br />

derivation. Again, this is not to say that a print of a unicorn is more realistic than a<br />

painting of one, obviously, but that depictive scheme for the print is more<br />

streamlined for dedication to duplication, delivers the same facts or fictions for<br />

every instance and grants work and scheme a stricter derivation. Interestingly, where<br />

prints are often more prized as art, is where qualities of material or process allow<br />

greater variation to a given number, impression or edition of work, as in etchings,<br />

engravings, wood or lino cuts, for example. On the other hand, advances in<br />

photography, lithography or graphics software allow duplication in new and more<br />

flexible ways but cannot equal or obviate the options available to the work of sole<br />

instance. Duplication in terms of impressive densities of tone screen or pixels still<br />

imposes a scheme for duplication, still extends instances for a work; tightens<br />

scheme and derivation.<br />

But the virtues of conformity and sheer quantity have their uses, indeed realisms.<br />

They not only ensure facts for a world, but also may sample and express their<br />

prominence in this. This is really to say only that the printed depiction often enjoys<br />

the same prestige as the printed word, but allows at least to more accurately point to<br />

the source of this authority or ‘aura’: to material exemplification. 141 Photographs in<br />

particular are taken to be more realistic or authentic as depictions for being in this<br />

way a stricter form of print, and whether the depicting surface is the glossy or<br />

textured card of a family snapshot, or the crude tone screens used for newspapers<br />

and pamphlets, such qualities often come to exemplify a conformity and integrity to<br />

given schemes that prompt faith in further and familiar objects.<br />

On the other hand photography’s profusion of applications and efficiency in<br />

duplication sometimes makes for resistance to appreciation as art. The artistic purist<br />

141 ‘Aura’ here alludes of course, to Walter Benjamin’s famous use of the term. See Benjamin,<br />

‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’ in Illuminations, Frankfurt, 1955. But<br />

the point here is that the print has an ‘aura’ of its own, rather than merely being denied that of the<br />

work of sole instance. Benjamin’s general anxiety about the status and prospects of the work of<br />

sole instance, and of art in general, rests upon a mistaken understanding of the distinction<br />

between sole and multiple instances for works, of depiction and art.


92<br />

may find it the strictest and so most unrewarding of prints. And while the<br />

photographer of even a black and white photograph is free to select a theme or<br />

object, an angle or aspect, to choose a lens length, filter supplement, field of focus,<br />

speed of film and shutter, to develop and fix the print with a variety of chemicals,<br />

crop the print to a variety of shapes, to a variety of surfaces, still, the purist may feel<br />

stymied. For even where the edition is limited to one, the scheme conforms to a<br />

print. The steps taken, options exercised remain an insidious array of conditions for<br />

duplication and scheme preservation. But in truth, such objections do not so much<br />

hold for photography, but for art more generally. The work of sole instance must<br />

also comply with some schemes, in order to experiment with others. For this reason<br />

art’s experiments fall into traditions, their objects into genres, their schemes soon<br />

rest upon standard techniques. And in this painting is reinforced in its prominence,<br />

entrenched as a preference through its history. Painting thus does not necessarily<br />

escape its schemes any more easily than photography, the difference is rather that<br />

schemes here rest upon optimal conditions for versatility and permutation, and that<br />

duplication is always secondary to this.<br />

This is not to deny exceptions or grey areas to the distinction, to radical versions of<br />

mono-print, photo-release and photo-collage for example, but only to show that it<br />

holds for an easy majority of cases and explains a number of interesting aspects to<br />

the respective practices. Nor is it to ignore that painting is hardly the sole instance<br />

of a work of sole instance. Drawings (including pencils, lead and coloured, pastels,<br />

crayons, chalks, charcoal and inks) collages, mosaics, tapestries and stained glass<br />

equally or occasionally qualify but do not enjoy the same prominence or prestige as<br />

painting. The distinction within works of sole instance firstly depends upon degree<br />

of consolidation or entrenchment, as indicated. Painting maintains a momentum or<br />

preference in versatility not simply by theme or object, but scale, mobility, speed or<br />

time, materials and cost. Less competitive versions such as mosaics, tapestries and<br />

stained glass must be content with more specialised roles. The distinction secondly<br />

may paradoxically, depend upon scheme. Scheme need not always start from<br />

materials; some features of scheme or style influence how materials are taken, rather<br />

than the converse. The distinction between painting and drawing, for example,<br />

holds for most older or traditional works, as between preliminary sketch and<br />

finished work. Period and other styles determine this application. But in some more


93<br />

recent work, where drawing is pursued exclusively, or freely combined with painting<br />

and collage, distinction between sketch and finished work clearly does not apply. Or<br />

rather, does not apply in the same way. In fact the scheme now addresses rather<br />

than is addressed by the distinction, and where effective, the relation of painting to<br />

other materials and schemes is maintained as the object of the scheme, rather than<br />

its means or materials. In such cases, drawing is effectively treated as ‘painting’.<br />

Finally, while versions of painting are tied to various schemes, not all painting<br />

amounts to such schemes, not all schemes are only for painting. What stops<br />

drawing, collage, mosaics, tapestries, stained glass and so on being taken as just<br />

versions of painting or vice versa, is also consolidation of schemes. All establish<br />

ranges or constraints of versatility. What counts as painting amongst works of sole<br />

instance, is a matter of dominance and range of schemes. They as much define<br />

painting as painting defines them. So painting has prominence and preference in art,<br />

but neither guarantees its effectiveness nor impedes the effectiveness of other<br />

materials, but rather dictates competition.<br />

Painting’s practices are necessarily partial or partisan, and painting needs conflicting<br />

versions to sustain circumspection in art. The partiality of practices finds a ready ally<br />

in criticism, particularly for contemporary work. An impartial critic is not simply a<br />

figment in the dreams of unlucky artists, but a critic hardly worthy of the name. An<br />

impartial criticism is merely to confine remarks to a consensus, or an exercise in<br />

tact. The point is rather to contest the merit of a work by appealing to extension of<br />

reference, to object or world depicted, to means and style. Sooner or later however<br />

style involves a version of history. The critic is drawn into a trade-off, between<br />

extolling the deserving and distinctive work and admitting it to an impressive yet<br />

grateful tradition. The transition is essentially from saying how a good a work is, to<br />

saying what kind of work it is, and the critic may be drawn into revising styles and<br />

history in order to effect a reconciliation or to arguing for an underlying principle to<br />

painting (although painting here might just as well be depiction or art) as the basis<br />

of such revision. The contest is thus shuffled from criticism to history. The critic<br />

tends to find the historian too long-sighted in matters of style to accurately<br />

discriminate in such cases; the historian tends to suspect the critic too short sighted<br />

to be entirely reliable.


94<br />

But the argument is really about where the conflict falls, rather than if there simply<br />

ought to be one. Controversy abounds in art history, the boundaries of Classicism<br />

and Romanticism, or Romanticism and Realism, or Realism and Impressionism<br />

continue to fuel reappraisals. Some styles it seems are rarely settled, and are only to<br />

be settled by appeals to others. Art history cannot do without criticism, and theories<br />

of painting, depiction and art find their favourites. In the second half of the<br />

twentieth century the most prominent controversy surrounds the definition and<br />

extent of Modernism as a period style, elsewhere as just a movement or trend.<br />

Often criticism and history are indistinguishable in writing on such a recent period,<br />

since the assessment of works goes hand in hand with the development of a<br />

generally accepted stylistic framework. A feature of some of the most influential<br />

criticism of the period has been its appeal to the nature of painting in revising this<br />

framework and promoting works. The arguments advanced are sometimes glossed<br />

as formalism, since they appeal to intrinsic properties of painting, and sometimes as<br />

historicism, since they appeal to a manifest progression in art history. It is<br />

instructive to look to some notable examples to see how criticism and history settle<br />

differences and urge versions of painting.<br />

Foremost amongst such formalists is Clement Greenberg, an early champion of<br />

Abstract Expressionism and an influential curator as well as critic throughout the<br />

ni<strong>net</strong>een sixties. Greenberg’s position evolved during the late thirties writing for the<br />

left wing journal Partisan Review, and drew on the work of earlier formalists such as<br />

Alfred J. Barr, Roger Fry and Clive Bell, but is distinctive for its acute focus upon<br />

depiction and painting, its attempt to reduce depiction to matters of naked material<br />

and technique and strident ranking of works, as ‘the best’ or ‘most progressive’. 142<br />

The account offered here draws largely on a later essay, Modernist Painting, which<br />

142 Two key essays are Greenberg, ‘Avant-Garde and Kitsch’ in Partisan Review, vol. vi No 5<br />

Fall 1939 pp. 34-39, reprinted in Greenberg, Art and Culture, Boston, 1961 and Greenberg,<br />

‘Towards a Newer Laocoon’ in Partisan Review, vol. vii No 4. July-August, 1940, pp. 296-310,<br />

reprinted in Greenberg, The Collected Essays and Criticism, Volume One: Perceptions and<br />

Judgements, 1939-1944, Chicago/London, 1986, pp. 23-38. Greenberg’s view of depiction is<br />

notable for the shift from Alfred Barr’s mere ‘representation’ (sharply criticised by Meyer<br />

Shapiro in ‘The Nature of Abstract Art’ in Marxist Quarterly, vol. 1 No 1 January 1937 pp. 77-<br />

98) to one of ‘illusion’ with particular emphasis upon perspective. In this respect, it precedes and<br />

is consonant with Gombrich’s Art and Illusion. Indeed, in a later publication, includes a footnote<br />

to Art and Illusion in support of arguments. See Greenberg, 1961, p. 76.


95<br />

summarises many of these concerns. 143 Greenberg’s argument is firstly for the<br />

identity of a Modernist period. He sketches a kind of intellectual crisis arising from<br />

the enlightenment, in which excessive rationality threatens the status of religion and<br />

art. The rigours of Kantian philosophy supposedly offer art the means of<br />

redemption, through a delimiting of its field of inquiry, to something like immediate<br />

experience, presentation or appearance. 144 But the essay skirts further philosophy<br />

and at best the argument is that within the period, art’s branches begin to dedicate<br />

themselves to constricting their respective fields.<br />

It quickly emerged that the unique and proper area of competence of each<br />

art coincided with all that was unique to the nature of its medium. The task<br />

of self-criticism became to eliminate from the effects of each art any and<br />

every effect that might conceivably be borrowed from or by the medium of<br />

any other art 145 .<br />

Painting therefore scrutinises its role as depiction. Realistic and illusionistic<br />

approaches are gradually rejected as ‘dissembling’ or concealing the true nature of<br />

painting (and depiction). Exactly which medium realism and illusion are to belong<br />

to remains unclear, or why these properties should then be considered alien to<br />

painting, or what is to be depicted without them, is not pursued. For Greenberg it is<br />

enough that painting from Ma<strong>net</strong> onwards rejects the vivid illusion of threedimensional<br />

space and advances on ‘the ineluctable flatness of the support that<br />

remained most fundamental to the processes by which pictorial art criticised and<br />

defined itself under Modernism’ 146 . Of course depiction is not limited to painting,<br />

even in art, so strictly speaking, mere flatness will not suffice as a unique property of<br />

painting, and any material or support is never just flat. But the history essentially<br />

143 Clement Greenberg, ‘Modernist Painting’ in Art and Literature No 4, Spring, 1965, pp. 193-<br />

201, reprinted in Modern Art and Modernism, London, Francis Frascina and Charles Harrison,<br />

(eds.), 1982, pp. 5-10 and Greenberg, The Collected Essays and Criticism, Volume Four:<br />

Modernism with a Vengeance, 1957-1969 Chicago/London, 1993, pp. 85-93. Page numbers<br />

herein refer to the reprinting in Modern Art and Modernism.<br />

144 Kant’s position is more commonly regarded as Transcendental Idealism, Formal, or Critical<br />

Idealism. In this light it is a curious regression for one of professed Marxist leanings, but explains<br />

glossing of such criticism as formalism. Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgement is notable for the<br />

priority it assigns to natural beauty, the distinction with the sublime and the function of pleasure.<br />

These matters are surprisingly given scant attention by Greenberg and the historicist impetus he<br />

assigns to self-awareness or self-criticism, suggests far more of a Hegelian orientation, a point<br />

noted in Michael Fried, Three American Painters: Ken<strong>net</strong>h Noland, Jules Olitski and Frank<br />

Stella. Cambridge, Mass. 1965, reprinted in Modern Art and Modernism, London, 1982, pp. 115-<br />

121, (see especially p.118.)<br />

145 Greenberg, 1965, pp. 5-6.<br />

146 Ibid. p. 6


96<br />

establishes a premise from which abstract painting is seen to excel in flatness, or to<br />

achieve the latest and best in flatness<br />

There are four objections to be registered. An initial objection must surely run that<br />

three-dimensional space was not eliminated quite so easily, in fact cannot be<br />

eliminated without severely limiting the notion of depiction. Ma<strong>net</strong>’s paintings for<br />

example typically contain people and objects while forgoing standard perspectives<br />

and settings, but this hardly eliminates the depiction of three-dimensions. Nor can<br />

the argument be loosened to one of Modernism’s elimination of ‘the kind of space<br />

that recognisable, three-dimensional objects can inhabit’ while retaining these same<br />

or even distantly related objects 147 . To depict a three-dimensional object quite<br />

simply is to depict a three-dimensional space, no matter which perspective or<br />

projection scheme is adopted. Arguments for a distinct realm of the pictorial, or an<br />

illusion of an otherworldly space, in so far as they are coherent, fail for the same<br />

reason 148 . That is, to imagine walking, or simply looking around such a space is to<br />

be guided by such worldly activities as walking and looking.<br />

A second objection is that if painting is glossed as the principal means of depiction<br />

in art, then depiction itself is weakly grasped. For depiction in Modernist painting is<br />

characterised by ‘flatness’, even when recognising that more accurately the concept<br />

ought to be two-dimensionality. 149 Flatness quite simply is a property of threedimensionality.<br />

Flatness characterises a certain painted surface perhaps, that of a<br />

van Eyck or an Ingres for example, with their smooth finish, but is not a property<br />

of depiction or two-dimensionality. The confusion on Greenberg’s part over twodimensionality<br />

generates further errors in the characterisation of the picture plane as<br />

merely the surface of a painting, or the area of depiction 150 . The basis for a stylistic<br />

analysis of abstraction is thus seriously skewed from the start. Beyond this lies an<br />

objection to notions of a self-contained ‘visual experience’ and the idea that ‘visual<br />

art should confine itself exclusively to what is given in visual experience’ or that<br />

Modernist painting ought to translate its objects into ‘strictly optical, two-<br />

147 Greenberg, 1965, p.8.<br />

148 Ibid.<br />

149 Ibid. pp. 6-7.<br />

150 Ibid. p.8. Greenberg repeats this error in the analysis of cubist collage in terms of maintaining<br />

a ‘picture plane’ as the supporting surface. See Greenberg, 1961, pp. 70-83. The picture plane is<br />

dealt with more accurately here in Chapter Three, concerning the issue of depth.


97<br />

dimensional terms before becoming the subject of pictorial art’ 151 . But the visual<br />

cannot be entirely isolated from other senses, anymore than the pictorial can be<br />

isolated from its material support. There is no realm of the exclusively visual, no<br />

absolute autonomy for a practice of depiction and painting. Similarly, an appeal to a<br />

Kantian disinterested mind, like that to Ruskin’s innocent eye, rests upon a vacuum.<br />

The historical perspective prompts a third objection. There is for example, the<br />

confusing claim that the neo-classicist David sought to counter the flattening effect<br />

of Rococo painting by the introduction of ‘sculptural’ values, while at the same time<br />

insisting that this arose as part of a general trend in Western painting to ‘suppress<br />

and dispel the sculptural’ 152 . David supposedly subordinated colour to tone for this<br />

reason, yet in the very next line we are told that the strength of his pictures lies in<br />

their colour! Ingres, we are told also subordinates colour to tone, or to ‘sculptural’<br />

values, and yet his pictures ‘were among the flattest, least sculptural done in the<br />

West by a sophisticated artist since the fourteenth century’ 153 . Just what ‘flattest’ can<br />

mean in this context is puzzling, for literally, flatness is a three-dimensional and<br />

hence sculptural property, while taken as a gloss for two-dimensionality, flattest can<br />

only mean that Ingres’ pictures relinquish depiction for pattern or design, notations<br />

or diagrams. Neither is a plausible much less compelling interpretation.<br />

Definition of a Modernist period is weakened not only by attenuation of the trend<br />

to as far back as the sixteenth century, but also by a vacillation within it, concerning<br />

the reductive nature of this self-critical turn and the resultant flatness or twodimensionality.<br />

This is the fourth objection. On the one hand Modernism in<br />

painting is not so very different from the preceding four hundred years, in its efforts<br />

to reject ‘sculptural’ values, and on the other, the resulting two-dimensionality<br />

cannot be absolute or ‘utter’ 154 . But if two-dimensionality is not absolute or utter,<br />

against what is a self-critical purification to be measured? Or, if painting does not<br />

pursue a purity of means, does not continue to eliminate extrinsic properties, then<br />

there is no point in appealing to its one true nature, no self-critical turn, no<br />

Modernism as a consequence. Judgements of what is best or most progressive in<br />

151 Greenberg, 1965, p .8.<br />

152 Ibid. p. 7.<br />

153 Ibid.<br />

154 Ibid. p. 8


98<br />

painting fail unless committed to the essential and absolute in painting. A true<br />

Kantian might, of course, grasp the experience offered as a ‘Form of Finality’, but<br />

Greenberg equivocates, perhaps sensing that such idealism cannot drive the history<br />

of painting very far. 155 The aim of the history is the acceptance and importance of<br />

abstraction for painting, but it is difficult to make an historical case for a version of<br />

painting when the version is unclear.<br />

Confusion over an essential flatness is only compounded by closer stylistic analysis.<br />

The treatment of Cubism crucially suffers from an approach unable to accurately<br />

relate the picture plane to object, to appreciate distinctions between perspectival<br />

and projective schemes, and that resorts to notions of illusion to explain differences<br />

in treatment of depth. 156 It leads to nonsensical claims of illusions ‘in front of the<br />

picture plane, (for a picture) or of three-dimensionality, or depth ‘minimized’,<br />

without then allowing revision of object to scheme, or that object is schemedependent<br />

or that abstraction actually entails object and so depth to scheme. 157<br />

Then there is claim for a distinction between illusion and representation, taken as<br />

depth without object or object without connotation, and following this indifference<br />

to object and vacuity to depth, the reluctant though hardly surprising conclusion<br />

that mere decoration ensues from ‘abstract literalness’. 158<br />

The lack of rigour to such analysis is hardly confined to Greenberg of course, is<br />

typical of early advocacy for abstraction. But the feeble grasp of Cubism and<br />

depiction also dilates the style, allows it to sprawl into Analytical and Synthetic<br />

phases and for Greenberg, eventually embraces all but favoured features of Abstract<br />

Expressionism, in an amorphous notion of ‘Late Cubism’. But where Cubism<br />

becomes the necessary step to abstraction, abstraction is then also haunted by<br />

decoration, the decorous or ‘tasteful’. The essay ‘American-Type Painting’ illustrates<br />

155 In Greenberg, Modernism with a Vengeance, 1957-69, Chicago/London, 1993. pp. 93-94, a<br />

lengthy footnote to the version of the essay insists that he no more than describes ‘the very best’<br />

in Modernism, does not necessarily approve of it, and that flatness and self-criticism are not<br />

sufficient condition for such excellence, indeed are no more than ‘illusions’. But if purity in selfcriticism<br />

and flatness are no more than illusions of excellence, then the explanation itself is dealt<br />

a fatal blow. It does not then explain ‘the very best’ but only offers necessary conditions, and<br />

offers no accuracy in this, but only ‘illusions’. Also, for a concise account of The Form of<br />

Finality, and Kant’s aesthetic generally, see Mary A. McCloskey, Kant’s Aesthetic, London,<br />

1987.<br />

156 Greenberg, 1961, pp. 70-83.<br />

157 Ibid. p. 75, p.77.<br />

158 Ibid. p. 80.


99<br />

this stylistic over-reach. 159 It details advances made by the Abstract Expressionists,<br />

but can only explain the striking large scale of works as an extension to flatness,<br />

relations of shape, line and colour presumably extended simply by size or<br />

number. 160 Yet such works are rarely conspicuous for simply more shapes, lines or<br />

colours, indeed, more often display to the contrary.<br />

Greenberg allowed a narrowed tonal range for works, although this is then<br />

inconsistent with the claim for flatness and greater scale. 161 The tonal range ought<br />

strictly to be widened, if greater scale is to extend flatness. He submitted extremely<br />

uniform compositions or ‘fields’ and lack of finish as other features of the style. But<br />

fields are as much native to Mirō’s Constellations of the forties, or Mondrian’s Pier and<br />

Ocean series of 1914-16, and lack of finish to Mirō’s heterogeneous materials of the<br />

thirties or to most of Picasso or Matisse. Neither is quite stylistically accurate, both<br />

are hardly more so. And where lack of finish might more usefully be related to<br />

greater scale, or fields to resulting finish, Greenberg is indifferent, instead shores up<br />

a loose analysis with the ad hoc alternative of Late Cubism, to which de Kooning or<br />

Gorky’s drawing and tonalities are attributed, as are Still’s facture or finish, as well<br />

as Gottlieb and Motherwell’s less field-like compositions.<br />

Late Cubism only conflates Synthetic Cubism with the work of Mondrian,<br />

Malevich, Mirō and Klee, is as easily lumped together as French or European tastes;<br />

is then as vague and indiscriminate as the style of abstraction under discussion and<br />

indeed as the name ‘American-Type Painting’ suggests. Abstraction suffers. The<br />

style is rightly sensed to be a sterile exercise when confined to an end in-itself.<br />

Greenberg’s apprehension registers in the essay ‘Abstract, Representational and so<br />

forth’ but can no more remedy the problem than revise flatness and depiction. 162<br />

Stylistically, the problem is abstraction is sold short by flatness. It never quite<br />

delivers the meaning advocates intuitively find in works, that rewards attention to<br />

such works. Claiming that abstraction eliminates the object, rather than properly<br />

abstracting the object, only cancels the very basis of depiction. Hence the prospect<br />

is rapidly one of a dead end, of the vacuous or merely decorative. Greenberg’s is<br />

159 Greenberg, 1961, pp.208-229.<br />

160 Ibid. p. 219.<br />

161 Ibid. p. 220.<br />

162 Ibid. pp. 133-138.


100<br />

scarcely the only, much less best account of Abstract Expressionism, but his<br />

stylistics demonstrates the problem for abstraction based upon painting as<br />

depiction. 163 An historical impetus is set in train from without, but a stylistic paucity<br />

resists from within. Negotiating this dilemma largely measures the course and<br />

influence of such criticism, and is briefly traced here not through successive and<br />

competing canons of abstract painting and their advocates, but through attempts to<br />

reconcile a version strict enough to allow progression in flatness, but relaxed<br />

enough to avoid completion.<br />

A remedy to this reductionism was proposed by Michael Fried, also an eminent<br />

critic and curator, and associate of Greenberg. Fried argued that the essence sought<br />

by the Modernist need not be:<br />

the irreducible essence of all painting, but rather that which, at the present<br />

moment in painting’s history, is capable of convincing him (the critic) that it<br />

can stand comparison with the painting of both the modernist and premodernist<br />

past whose quality seems to him beyond question 164 .<br />

Or, stated more baldly, that ‘the essence of painting is not something irreducible’ 165 .<br />

But of course essence quite simply is what is irreducible. An essence that is yet<br />

reducible is by definition not an essence. Nor does it help to appeal to an essence of<br />

some version of painting, if that version is then to be ‘compared’ with others, for<br />

this is just a long way around to claiming the same essence for all painting. 166 Fried’s<br />

163 It should also be noted that advocates of abstraction at this time are not necessarily committed<br />

to such idealism or wayward notions of the picture plane. Michel Seuphor for example, charts the<br />

course of abstraction in painting with a great deal more historical and stylistic accuracy, but<br />

offers less comprehensive appeal to a theory of painting. See for example, Seuphor, A Dictionary<br />

of Abstract Painting, (Paris, 1957) London, 1958, and Seuphor, Abstract Painting, New York,<br />

1964.<br />

164 Fried, ‘Shape as Form: Frank Stella’s New Paintings (1966)’ in New York Painting and<br />

Sculpture, 1940-1970, New York, 1969, p.422. This text is quoted in Fried’s ‘How Modernism<br />

Works: A Response to T. J. Clark’ in Pollock and After: The Critical Debate, Francis Frascina<br />

(ed.), London, 1985, pp. 65-79. For cited text see p. 69 of the reprinting.<br />

165 Fried, ‘Art and Objecthood’ in Minimal Art: A Critical Anthology, Gregory Battcock (ed.)<br />

New York, 1968, pp. 123-124. This text is also quoted in Fried, ‘How Modernism Works: A<br />

Response to T. J. Clark’ Pollock and After: The Critical Debate, Francis Frascina (ed.) London,<br />

1985, pp. 65-79.<br />

166 The view purportedly derives from Wittgenstein, presumably in relation to rules for games or<br />

for family-like trees of relations. See Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, 1953,<br />

item 67 p32 e . In which case, Fried fatally confuses membership with essence. More correctly,<br />

Wittgenstein’s view runs that while each member, like fibres constituting a thread, overlaps for<br />

some of the length of the thread, yet their overlapping or membership does not ‘run through the<br />

whole thread’ or is not reducible to an essence for the thread. Nor does the essence or identity of


101<br />

formulation points starkly to the difficulties that arise for critical assessment of<br />

works under a radically reductive view of painting. The basis of any comparison<br />

must be shared qualities, but while one might usefully compare for example a<br />

Pollock with other abstraction, on what basis might one compare a Pollock with a<br />

still life or landscape, an Ingres or Delacroix, a Vermeer or Michelangelo? Implicit<br />

in the formalist aesthetic is the insistence, as Fried indicates, on the<br />

commensurability of all painting – Modernist and pre-Modernist, (or modernist and<br />

pre-modernist) but stripped of all stylistic differences, the comparison comes to<br />

nothing, because reductionism stops at nothing.<br />

The example of another formalist critic and curator, William Rubin, in Jackson<br />

Pollock and the Modern Tradition, shows how this reductive tendency firstly strips<br />

down works of the past in order to accommodate a comparison with more recent<br />

abstraction. 167 Rubin considers the late work of Mo<strong>net</strong> as a precedent for ‘the big<br />

scintillating picture’, and Impressionism in general as a development toward an ‘allover’<br />

style, which Pollock carries forward in his famous dripped paintings. Those<br />

Impressionist paintings displaying the most all-over technique, or the evenest<br />

distribution of dabbings, are deemed ‘the most advanced’ and conversely, Pollock’s<br />

paintings are seen as inheriting something of Impressionism’s cosmopolitan<br />

attachment to the casual and accidental. 168 But this is really a sleight of hand.<br />

Pollock cannot inherit the attitude without inheriting the same all-overness,<br />

differences in the all-overness amount to differences in attitude as well.<br />

Commensurate all-overness cannot take from one, only to give to the other. Like<br />

flatness, all-overness strands itself in its own reductionism. A more extreme<br />

example arises in Frank Stella’s Working Space. 169 Stella, a prominent painter of<br />

abstractions and friend of Fried, looked for ways in which abstraction might equal<br />

the emotional impact of pre-Modernist works such as Caravaggio’s David and<br />

any single member or fibre constitute the essence of the thread. Neither essence nor reduction is<br />

sanctioned by these views.<br />

167 William Rubin ‘Jackson Pollock and the Modern Tradition’ (part I), Artforum, Feb-May 1967,<br />

pp. 14-21, (part II), Artforum, June-July, 1967, pp. 28-37.<br />

168 Ibid. pp. 29-30.<br />

169 Stella, Working Space, Cambridge, Mass. 1980. It should also be noted that while Stella,<br />

Rubin, Fried and Judd all propose versions of Modernism, they also argue for important<br />

differences in a Modernist canon from that of Greenberg. For detailed analysis of the differences<br />

between Greenberg and later canons of abstraction see Thierry de Duve, ‘The Monochrome and<br />

the Blank Canvas’ in Reconstructing Modernism: Art in New York, Paris and Montreal 1945-64,<br />

Serge Guilbaut (ed.) Cambridge, Mass./London, 1990 pp. 244-310.


102<br />

Goliath, or Titian’s The Flaying of Marsyas. But again the equation rests upon a<br />

fundamental inconsistency and misconception. What abstraction reduces in<br />

depicted objects cannot then be appealed to in the same way or for the same things.<br />

While abstraction unquestionably makes an emotional impact in many cases, it<br />

cannot expect to make the same or equal to that of more concrete depiction. It is a<br />

futile exercise and in truth need make no such impact to still be effective.<br />

Reduction and ranking are hardly to be denied of course, are necessary but not<br />

sufficient steps to effective reference. The problem lies where flatness is accepted as<br />

the absolute abstraction of depiction to painting. Then ranking with all and any<br />

depiction follows as valid. Formalist judgements thus tend to the unqualified, ‘the<br />

best’, ‘the most advanced’, ‘major’ ‘minor’ even ‘the provincial’ as opposed to the<br />

‘cosmopolitan’ or ‘sophisticated’, all insist upon a ruthless ranking on one fixed and<br />

final measure of painting. 170 But the more partisan the critic or critique, the more<br />

pronounced the limitations. Both Greenberg and Fried notoriously disparage Dada<br />

and Surrealism and work influenced by these movements as retrograde, or<br />

superficial ‘avant-gardism’ that fails to engage with what ‘really matters’ 171 . It is in<br />

effect dismissed as false or poor Modernism. Yet while no one would deny that<br />

much art at any time is mediocre, one must surely admit to a variety of styles. What<br />

separates the formalist’s ‘advanced taste’ from the avant-gardist’s ‘pseudoquestions’<br />

is less a question of excellence, than sensitivity and styles 172 . The inability of<br />

Greenberg or Fried to appreciate such work points not to its lack of merit but their<br />

flawed grasp of depiction and painting, their failure as historians.<br />

The formalist cannot remedy flaws in the advocacy of abstraction by simply ruling<br />

out alternatives. The problem is only more starkly framed. On the one hand<br />

170 The formalist obsession with ranking at the expense of stylistic distinction is pressed to the<br />

point of parody in the early critical writings of Donald Judd, where a juvenile ‘ten best’ approach<br />

to assessment is given full rein. See for example the opening paragraph and comic footnotes to<br />

Judd, ‘Bar<strong>net</strong>t Newman’ Studio International Feb 1970 pp. 67-69, also reprinted in Modern Art<br />

and Modernism: A Critical Anthology, London, 1982, pp. 129-132.<br />

171 Michael Fried ‘How Modernism Works: A Response to T. J. Clark’ in Pollock and After: The<br />

Critical Debate, Francis Frascina (editor) London, 1985, pp. 72-73. See also Greenberg, ‘Avant-<br />

Garde Attitudes: New Art in the Sixties’ in The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol 4<br />

‘Modernism with a Vengeance’1957 – 1969: Chicago/London, 1993 pp. 292-303 and Greenberg,<br />

‘Counter Avant-Garde’ in Art International, 15 May 1971, pp. 16-19.<br />

172 The terms in inverted commas here are drawn from Greenberg, ‘Avant-Garde Attitudes: New<br />

Art in the Sixties’, in The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol 4 ‘Modernism with a<br />

Vengeance’1957 – 1969, Chicago/London, 1993 pp. 292-303.


103<br />

abstraction is the most progressive or best in painting, and on the other it permits<br />

only versions, has no limits. But the formalist cannot have it both ways, if<br />

abstraction is better because it is reductive of all painting, or absolutely, then<br />

reduction permits only one right version. Or, if reduction permits many right<br />

versions, is not absolute, then it cannot be better or more progressive than variation<br />

within more concrete depiction. The argument here in fact mirrors the earlier<br />

rejection of a single realism. There it was argued that not all aspects of realism are<br />

compatible or combinable in a master version of depiction, a full and final realism,<br />

here it is argued that not all painting practices necessarily strip one another away to<br />

reveal only the absolute material, its basis as depiction.<br />

Ironically, it is the success of abstraction, the sheer variety it engenders that<br />

ultimately renders the formalist’s arguments ineffective, grants abstraction ample<br />

means to rank and style without appealing extravagantly for measure. But a stylistics<br />

based on flatness is then quickly exposed as inadequate – flatness now has too many<br />

versions for comfort, means too little in describing so many stylistic features, is in<br />

any case discredited by such narrow historicism. The dissolution inevitably calls into<br />

question Modernism. The whole reason for the period, after all, lay in the<br />

acceptance of abstraction as a progression of self-analysis. If painting has no one<br />

right version of flatness or two-dimensionality, there is no one right version of<br />

abstraction, no basis for a single progression. But then what is one to make of<br />

Modernism, indeed of depiction, painting and abstraction? Obviously a reappraisal<br />

applies to all, is due to all. Preceding chapters on depiction and related issues and<br />

initial discussion here of painting have laid the groundwork. In the second part of<br />

this study a history of painting in the second half of the twentieth century proceeds<br />

from the issues of abstraction and Modernism. But before embarking on this, a<br />

summary of the theoretical issues covered and the contribution made so far follow<br />

in the final chapter to part one.


104<br />

Summary<br />

A review of the controversy surrounding depiction was followed by a revision to<br />

the theory of reference advanced by Nelson Goodman. Steady revisions then<br />

followed for expression and style, art, its history, interpretation, realism and<br />

painting, gradually drawing theory into matters of criticism and history.<br />

Less summarily, Chapter One reviewed recent theories of depiction, their<br />

implications and applications for art. It disclosed the controversy between depiction<br />

taken as resemblance and reference. Discussion of resemblance centred on the<br />

position taken by Gombrich as an illusion or a psychological disposition, discussion<br />

of reference on the position taken by Goodman as a version of denotation. The<br />

study rejected both views. However, in Chapter Two the general framework of<br />

reference proposed by Goodman was adopted and a theory of depiction as<br />

exemplification of two-dimensionality proposed. In Chapter Three the proposed<br />

theory was shown to hold for five basic issues shared between prominent<br />

competing theories. Issues of depth or three-dimensionality, caricature, fiction,<br />

distortion and found or accidental depiction consolidated the proposed theory.<br />

Chapter Four showed how reference is organised according to styles, and again<br />

following Goodman, rejected synonymy and intention as the basis of style and<br />

expression. It showed how meaning by two-dimensionality together with literal and<br />

metaphorical sampling of materials, or more commonly, as statement, sentiment<br />

and structure, are all variously taken into an account of how a picture means or<br />

refers, and is classified according to source, to basically who, when and where.<br />

Discussion of style and expression lead to discussion of art. Chapter Five replaced<br />

Goodman’s symptoms of art, of density, repleteness and complexity, with<br />

‘circumspection’ of depiction, as multidirectional reference. It maintained<br />

Goodman’s view of beauty and excellence as cognitive effectiveness, and cognitive<br />

understood as broader than standard notions and contrasted with knowledge and


105<br />

science. Science progresses or improves, allows reverse derivation of earlier<br />

theories, in so far as correct, art does not. Art is less strict in its organisation and<br />

does not so much progress as digress. Emphasis upon its collection accordingly<br />

places greater weight upon history. In Chapter Six Gombrich’s famous history, The<br />

Story of Art was reviewed as a model of how a theory of depiction and art structure a<br />

history or tell a story. Gombrich claimed that art is simply the sum of its history, its<br />

works and artists, and that the concept of art is non-essential. Gombrich’s story is<br />

of art’s gradual convergence upon the principles of illusion, through piecemeal<br />

correction to a style’s formula or schema. The story is thus committed to realism,<br />

but struggles to make sense of art of the later twentieth century, cannot comfortably<br />

identify the schema and correction at work or illusions there. Either, the twentieth<br />

century fails in art or the theory of schema and correction fails as history. The view<br />

taken is that schema and correction confuse history with art and amount in fact to a<br />

historicist myth, for the simplicity and singularity of traditional depiction and<br />

realism.<br />

The problem of interpretation was taken up in the Chapter Seven, of distinguishing<br />

between facts and comment, matter and manner. The danger lies in confusing the<br />

two and allowing history its own laws or logic. Several notable solutions are<br />

considered, advocating radical relativism. The existential approach that originates<br />

with Heidegger, takes all method to be historical, the distinction between matter<br />

and manner then depends on the state of history. The hermeneutics of Gadamer,<br />

Habermas and others takes the past as basically a convenient fiction for the present<br />

and draws the line rather between conflicting current concerns. In contrast,<br />

structuralism insulates itself from history, advocates fixed structures and reduces<br />

changes to just these terms. Post-structural theorists (sometimes called postmodernists)<br />

readmit history or relax structures, extend the hermeneuticist’s<br />

relativism to the point where interpretation shares only language with other texts;<br />

amounts to only a variety of texts, all arguing only for attention and influence.<br />

Goodman’s irrealism shares much with this radical relativism and pluralism. But<br />

irrealism distinguishes between right and wrong versions, constrains pluralism with<br />

nihilism. Rightness rather than truth measures versions, but makes for too many or<br />

none for just one world. Interpretation is rightly multiple, but multiple right


106<br />

interpretations require a rightly identified object. The difference between an<br />

interpretation and identification lies in the plurality of one and the singularity of the<br />

other. Art historical interpretation for the irrealist here starts from a stylistics based<br />

upon a theory of depiction and balances a better version of the same history shared<br />

in rival versions, against simply a different but right version.<br />

Chapter Eight compared an irrealist approach to art history with Gombrich’s realist<br />

approach. The realist corrects a given schema and finds more realism; the irrealist<br />

connects various schemas or styles, makes another realism. But realisms here are<br />

only stylistic, the pluralism does not necessarily carry through to a metaphysical<br />

pluralism of worlds. Realisms measure derivation of scheme and information<br />

between styles. Ranges of styles and realisms depend upon scope of art history,<br />

really amount to just such history. Stylistics for the irrealist here allows realism of<br />

material, or formal or structural values for depiction, as well as realism of spirit or<br />

transcendental values for a movement or period, culture or group, but insists that<br />

both depend on rightness of scope.<br />

Chapter Nine extended irrealism to painting, recognised many practices and<br />

relativity of materials to depictive scheme and object. Yet while painting admits to<br />

various practices, collectively painting is identified by its prominence as a work of<br />

sole instance, in contrast with printing and the work of multiple instances. A work<br />

of sole instance has an important advantage in versatility where circumspection of<br />

meaning is concerned. Duplication on the other hand has an advantage where<br />

derivation and realism are concerned. Conformity of scheme for duplication<br />

reinforces rigour of shared information, often exemplifies an ‘aura’ in prints.<br />

Painting is the dominant version of a work of sole instance firstly because of<br />

feedback or momentum in schemes used and promoted. This consolidates the<br />

preference for painting. Secondly, it is dominant because conversely, painting just<br />

claims what is most versatile (or replete) in any work of sole instance. ‘Painting’ - in<br />

terms of a strict definition of materials and technique - just is what most works of<br />

sole instance do.<br />

Versions of painting provide the means to revise styles and detect new ones. The<br />

example of some prominent formalist criticism in support of abstract painting is


107<br />

considered in this light. Greenberg’s criticism proposes an expansive period of<br />

Modernism leading up to abstraction, and to some extent sustained by further<br />

abstraction, but whether this is greater abstraction, or merely versions of the same<br />

degree of abstraction remains moot. Indeed such criticism lapses with later<br />

proliferation of versions of abstraction. As a consequence, Modernism as a period is<br />

questioned. If abstraction is not absolute, offers no single course or progression for<br />

painting, how might one redefine Modernism? These are matters on which part one<br />

of the study concludes, and prepares the way for a history of painting in the second<br />

half of the twentieth century.<br />

Since Goodman’s theory has been both adopted and adapted, some measure of the<br />

contribution made here should also be taken. Goodman offers no historical method<br />

or explicit view of painting, so these additions are obvious enough, other<br />

contributions may be summarised in three points. The study has firstly proposed<br />

depiction as a mode of exemplification, accepting Goodman’s account of<br />

exemplification as reference, but now distinguishing between exemplification of<br />

two-dimensionality and three, between depiction and material sampling. In terms of<br />

the weight given to denotation in Goodman’s theory, this is a radical revision. In<br />

terms of Goodman’s views on expression and stylistics, it is comfortably<br />

accommodated. The study accepts Goodman’s three-way scheme for stylistics, as<br />

reference by statement, structure and sentiment, as well as the crucial rejection of<br />

synonymy and intention. In this the study adheres to Goodman’s broader aesthetic,<br />

or offers a version of irrealism. The phrases ‘irrealism here’ or ‘the irrealist here’ has<br />

signalled this distinction throughout.<br />

The study secondly departs from Goodman in distinguishing depiction from<br />

notation in terms of multi versus single directionality, and from this proposes a<br />

‘circumspective’ function to depiction and its refinement in art. This may seem<br />

some distance from Goodman’s symptoms of density and repleteness for syntax<br />

and semantics and of complex strings, although similarities are no<strong>net</strong>heless noted.<br />

‘Circumspection’ is comfortably accommodated under Goodman’s view of beauty<br />

or excellence as cognitive efficiency. A related adjustment inverts traditional<br />

assumptions, claiming that canons and evaluation actually precede further<br />

identification; that we say how good a work is, on the way to saying in what ways,


108<br />

and that revision of judgements is built into the process. Again, the study adheres to<br />

the broader principles of Goodman’s aesthetic, revising only matters of depiction.<br />

Whether the views advanced deserve the name of irrealism depends on how closely<br />

the theories are compared.<br />

The study thirdly augments Goodman’s terms for realism. He nominates novelty,<br />

entrenchment and factual against fictional. The study adds derivation for scheme<br />

and information. Since claims for novelty or revelation, ease or preference are<br />

shown to be insufficient and since relativism and pluralism are maintained by<br />

multiple derivations in stylistic practice, revision of realisms here no more than<br />

strengthens irrealism. The study is thus able to meet objections to Goodman’s<br />

theory considered in Chapter One while preserving crucial features of reference,<br />

stylistics, understanding, interpretation and pluralism. It demonstrates that even<br />

where emphasis on denotation is jettisoned, Goodman’s aesthetic remains not just<br />

viable but valuable, especially for reconstruction of recent art history.


109<br />

Contents for Part Two<br />

HISTORY<br />

Chapter Title Description<br />

Reference:<br />

Main Artists<br />

11<br />

Page<br />

112<br />

Modernism and<br />

Abstraction<br />

Review of the extent of<br />

Modernism, and proposed<br />

abbreviation (1912-1950).<br />

Revision of concept of<br />

abstraction in depiction.<br />

Traced from the Orphists to<br />

Art Informel and Abstract<br />

Expressionism, to threedimensional<br />

works, design and<br />

sampled materials by the<br />

middle of the century.<br />

Kupka, Delaunay,<br />

Kandinsky, Klee,<br />

Mondrian, Malevich,<br />

Masson, Pollock, Masson,<br />

Tobey, Wols, Soulages,<br />

Kline, Constructivism,<br />

The Bauhaus, collage and<br />

Duchamp.<br />

12<br />

Page<br />

126<br />

Modernism<br />

1912-1950<br />

‘Simultaneous and<br />

Successive Depiction’<br />

Revision of competing styles<br />

to abstraction. Re-defines<br />

Cubism, as pre-Modernism,<br />

rejects label of ‘Synthetic<br />

Cubism’ for ‘Overstyle’, and<br />

redefines rival trend as<br />

‘Rerealism’ (ignores<br />

Surrealism). Traces relation to<br />

abstraction, to the impasse of<br />

biomorphic abstraction, and to<br />

‘Rerealism’s dependence upon<br />

three-dimensional geometry.<br />

Picasso, Braque,<br />

Malevich, Futurism, Dada<br />

and Surrealism, Klee,<br />

Kandinsky, Miro, De<br />

Chirico, Chagall,<br />

Duchamp, Schwitters,<br />

Ernst, Dali, Magritte.<br />

13<br />

Page<br />

138<br />

Late Modernism<br />

1950-60<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’<br />

The convergence of<br />

abstraction, ‘Overstyle’ and<br />

‘Rerealism’ results in a new<br />

style -‘Reciprocal Depiction’,<br />

with versions variously<br />

stressing ‘layout’, ‘traction’<br />

and ‘interruption’.<br />

Giacometti, Dubuffet,<br />

Fautrier, CoBrA Group,<br />

Tapies, De Kooning,<br />

Bacon, Rivers,<br />

Rauschenberg, Johns,<br />

Hamilton, Blake.<br />

14<br />

Pop Art and Post-<br />

Modernism:<br />

Painting Printing<br />

1960-1970<br />

The shift in ‘Reciprocal<br />

Depiction’ to print sampling,<br />

or Pop Art. Basic graphics and<br />

text sources, link to expanded<br />

materials.<br />

Warhol, Lichtenstein,<br />

Caulfield, Adami, Kitaj,<br />

Hockney, Rosenquist,<br />

Ruscha, Art and Language<br />

Group, Kossuth.<br />

Page<br />

150


110<br />

15<br />

Page<br />

164<br />

Post-Modernism<br />

Continued:<br />

Painting Photography<br />

1962-78<br />

Painting of photography, and<br />

sampling related print<br />

processes. Photo-Realism and<br />

exhaustion of sample by late<br />

seventies.<br />

Warhol, Rauschenberg,<br />

Laing, Polke, Richter,<br />

Close, Estes, McLean,<br />

Goings, Raphael, Richter,<br />

Morley,<br />

16<br />

Page<br />

176<br />

The End of Post-<br />

Modernism:<br />

1962-1985<br />

‘Bad’ Painting, Neo-<br />

Expressionism and New Image<br />

Painting. Traced both from<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ and<br />

print sampling, firstly in<br />

Germany, then the U.S. to<br />

dissipation in mid-eighties.<br />

Polke, Penck, Immendorff,<br />

Kiefer, Clemente, Salle,<br />

Schnabel, Haring,<br />

Basquiat, Jenney, Bartlett,<br />

Lane, Green, True,<br />

Zucker, Hurson,<br />

Moscowitz, Rothenburg,<br />

17<br />

Page<br />

189<br />

Abstraction in Late<br />

and Post-Modernism<br />

Shows how the distinction<br />

between Late and Post<br />

Modernism holds for<br />

abstraction. Traces structures<br />

for colour, in scale, symmetry<br />

and basic pattern to threedimensionality,<br />

or material<br />

exemplification, finally to<br />

Pattern and Decoration,<br />

pastiche and simulation.<br />

Rothko, Newman, Still,<br />

Albers, Noland, Gene<br />

Davis, Stella, De Feo,<br />

Olitski, Poons, Marden,<br />

Mangold, Bell, Ronald<br />

Davis, McCracken, Bell,<br />

Kozloff, Kushner,<br />

Zakanitch, Mullican,<br />

Halley, Taaffe, Levine,<br />

Bidlo<br />

18<br />

Page<br />

204<br />

Expanded Materials in<br />

Late and Post-<br />

Modernism.<br />

Shows how the distinction<br />

between Late and Post<br />

Modernism holds for works of<br />

‘expanded materials’.<br />

The shift from ki<strong>net</strong>ics and<br />

performance in the fifties to<br />

Conceptual Art. Sampling of<br />

script and score, performance,<br />

place, and recording, until the<br />

mid eighties.<br />

Smith, Ken<strong>net</strong>h and Mary<br />

Martin, Tinguely,<br />

Hamilton, Fontana, Cage,<br />

Mathieu, The Gutai, Klein,<br />

Rauschenburg, Kapprow,<br />

Manzoni, Nauman, Gilbert<br />

and George, Schneeman,<br />

Christo, Bochner, Barry,<br />

Beuys, Andre, Serra,<br />

Morris, Kounellis, Fabro,<br />

Heizer, Oppenheim,<br />

Graham, Armajani,<br />

Acconci, Piper, Oiticica,<br />

Haacke, Boltanski,<br />

Kruger, Holzer


111<br />

19<br />

Page<br />

223<br />

Globalism<br />

1985 - 2000<br />

All three strands, more<br />

concrete depiction, abstraction,<br />

and works of expanded<br />

materials are now traced<br />

within an open or incomplete<br />

period up until 2000.<br />

The shift from Conceptual Art<br />

to institutional sampling in<br />

expanded materials, the shift<br />

from basic pattern to more<br />

complex versions and layout in<br />

abstraction, the shift from<br />

Neo-Expressionism and<br />

allegory to broader genres are<br />

all shown to share crucial<br />

synchrony, in Globalist<br />

strategies or projects.<br />

Koons, Steinbach, Lavier,<br />

Mucha, Cady Noland,<br />

Stockholder, Rhoades,<br />

Hirst, Orozco, Shaw, La<br />

Noue, Rae, Oehlen,<br />

Ackermann, Odita,<br />

Lasker, Aboriginal artists,<br />

Oulton, Wojnarowitz,<br />

Marshall, Occampo,<br />

Ritchie, Murakami,<br />

Pittman, Hume, Ritchie,<br />

Ruyter, Marshall, Walker,<br />

Tuymans, Doig, Neo<br />

Rauch, Scheibitz<br />

Currin, Peyton,<br />

Yuskavage, Loeb, Glenn<br />

Brown, Saville, Cecily<br />

Brown,<br />

20<br />

Page<br />

249<br />

Conclusion<br />

Reviews distinctive features,<br />

compares prominent rival<br />

versions and registers<br />

unavoidable omissions.<br />

Recent art histories by<br />

Marco Livingstone,<br />

Brandon Taylor, Edward<br />

Lucie-Smith, Daniel<br />

Wheeler, Jonathan<br />

Fineberg, Michael Archer,<br />

Hal Foster, David<br />

Hopkins, Mathew<br />

Collings, Kristine Stiles<br />

and Peter Selz, Johanna<br />

Drucker.<br />

N.B. Figure numbers given in the following text relate to illustrations provided by<br />

link to other web sites.<br />

While every effort has been made to supply details of date, medium and<br />

dimensions, to the Illustrations page, where these are unavailable the<br />

abbreviation N.D.A. appears.


112<br />

Modernism and Abstraction<br />

Discussion so far has considered Modernism as a period dedicated to the<br />

progression of abstraction in painting, but emphasis is rarely upon only formal or<br />

stylistic developments of course, usually these are taken as an index to social,<br />

political, economic and other factors. Then again, some versions recognise other<br />

styles to the period, for example Futurism, Dada and Surrealism and so place less<br />

emphasis upon abstraction, while equally looking to significant factors at their<br />

historical source. 173 But however one augments the breadth of works to the period,<br />

there remains a problem with its length and the problem starts from an<br />

understanding of abstraction. As shown in Chapter Nine, the problem is firstly a<br />

stylistic one, concerning the basis of depiction underlying an explanation of<br />

abstraction. Unable to accurately, or even coherently explain abstraction, the<br />

careless stretching of the period according to a supposed tendency to flatness then<br />

makes problems for an historical analysis. Works share too little that is distinctive,<br />

cover a period where too much is vital. To begin this revision of Modernism, the<br />

chapter first outlines why source also suffers under inadequate stylistics.<br />

173 The many advocates for Dada and Surrealism range from Andre Breton, Surrealism and<br />

Painting, (Paris, 1928) London, 1966, to Sir Herbert Read, The Philosophy of Art, London, 1964,<br />

to Dawn Ades, Dada and Surrealism, London, 1974, to Peter Bürger, Theory of The Avant-<br />

Garde, (Frankfurt, 1980) Minneapolis 1984, to Rosalind Krauss, The Optical Unconscious,<br />

Cambridge/Mass., 1993 and Hal Foster, Return of the real: the avant-garde at the end the<br />

century, Cambridge/Mass./London, 1996, to offer only a brief cross-section. The movements are<br />

variously taken in opposition or alliance with abstraction. Read, for example, urges an underlying<br />

unity with abstraction and interesting parallels with Romanticism as an extreme version of the<br />

sublime. Bürger argues for them in support of a favoured social practice – ‘the avant-garde’. In as<br />

much as he concerns himself with painting, attribution rests on a meagre stylistic basis of collage<br />

and Duchamp’s readymades. A dubious distinction is proposed for the Modernist work, as a selfcontained<br />

or autonomous object, opposed to the ‘avant-garde’ work as integrated with ‘life’.<br />

Some abstraction counts as ‘avant-garde’, such as Russian Constructivism, some counts as<br />

Modernism, such as the works of Kandinsky. Krauss and Foster argue for the importance of Dada<br />

and Surrealism as a response to intellectual trends of the time, such as psychoanalysis, (in Lacan<br />

as much as Freud), structuralism, as advanced by Levi-Strauss (in ethnographic studies and the<br />

appreciation of non-western depiction) and the criticism of Walter Benjamin, (especially on<br />

photography). However no advocate proposes the exclusion of abstraction from Modernism, or<br />

an end to Modernism with the appearance of Dada and Surrealism, and while mostly broadening<br />

the constitution of Modernism, attention to styles other than abstraction does not in itself remedy<br />

the inflated duration of Modernism at issue here.


113<br />

The length of Modernism has interestingly tended to spread backwards, as art<br />

historians throughout the twentieth century sought to integrate more recent<br />

work. 174 From Alfred J. Barr Junior’s starting point with the Post Impressionists, in<br />

his noted chart on the development of Abstract Art in 1936, the scope of<br />

Modernism has been variously redrawn to embrace Ma<strong>net</strong> and Impressionism,<br />

Realism, Romanticism, Neo-Classicism, and as shown in Greenberg’s version, even<br />

farther back. 175 Barr’s history ends in two branches of abstraction for twentieth<br />

century painting by 1935, the geometric and non-geometric, while Greenberg’s<br />

history ends in branches beyond traditional easel-scale and techniques by the<br />

ni<strong>net</strong>een fifties. 176 Modernism thus not only embraces more of the twentieth<br />

century with later versions but more of the past in order to do so. Modernism<br />

becomes a period of at least two hundred years by this, if it is also to embrace most<br />

of the twentieth century, as is generally accepted.<br />

This far exceeds the length of any period since (and possibly including) the<br />

Renaissance, and paradoxically confers a unity or stability on the period at odds<br />

with preceding history and intuitions of accelerating change. Such intuitions are<br />

captured not only in the succession of lesser movements, such as Realism,<br />

Impressionism, Post-Impressionism, Symbolism, Art Nouveau, Fauvism, Cubism<br />

and so forth but in the rapid transformation brought about by the industrial<br />

revolution, greater energy resources, new forms of transportation, greater<br />

democracy and education, the climax of colonialism, the spread of urbanisation,<br />

174 Taking the later eighteenth century as the cradle of Modernism is pervasive in recent art<br />

history. Michael Fried has pursued notions of Modernism in the eighteenth century in Fried,<br />

Absorption and Theatricality, Berkley/London, 1980. T.J. Clark maintains Modernism emerged<br />

in the mid-ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century in Clark, The Painting of Modern Life: Paris in the Art of Ma<strong>net</strong><br />

and his Followers, London/New York, 1985, and extends Modernism from 1793 to 1989 in<br />

Clark, Farewell to an Idea; episodes in a history to modernism, New Haven/ London, 1999.<br />

Other eminent authors of similar persuasion include Robert Rosenblum, Thomas Crow and<br />

Robert L. Herbert. By contrast, Richard R. Brettell, Modern Art 1851-1929 Oxford/New York,<br />

1999, argues for a shorter version, straddling the turn of the century, while including previously<br />

ignored work in eastern Europe and elsewhere.<br />

175 Alfred H. Barr Junior, Cubism and Abstract Art, New York, 1936. Barr does not strictly use<br />

the term Modernism however, and his chart tellingly ignores more concrete depiction of the<br />

period, such as the work of Ernst, Dali, Chagall, De Chirico and others. Yet in Barr, Defining<br />

Modern Art Irving Sandler and Amy Newman (eds.) New York, 1986, it is clear that Barr takes<br />

abstraction as synonymous with ‘Modern Art’ or Modernism.<br />

176 Greenberg’s ‘Modernist Painting’ offers no canon of contemporary works, however essays<br />

such as ‘The Crisis of the Easel Picture’ (1948) and ‘American-Type Painting’ (1955-58) are<br />

consistent with this position and urge such recent inclusions. See Greenberg, 1961.


114<br />

patterns of emigration and so on. Modernism conceals more than it reveals in such<br />

a sprawling version, strains the preceding structure of periods, or any single theme,<br />

such as socialism or capitalism. A remedy may seek either to start Modernism later<br />

than the eighteenth century, or to end it earlier in the twentieth century (or both). 177<br />

As shown, earlier critics and historians were often intent upon demonstrating the<br />

validity of abstraction in painting through a close integration with its precedents,<br />

and as a result are caught up in a seamless transition backwards, from one precedent<br />

to another. Hence the difficulty in finding a starting point for Modernism. But the<br />

increasing lengths taken in history only alert us to a deep uneasiness with the<br />

stylistics of abstraction, as discussed in Chapter Nine, and which ultimately the<br />

length of Modernism can neither compensate, nor disguise. Stylistically, abstraction<br />

has problems, and it makes problems for Modernism, historically.<br />

A remedy for Modernism must therefore rethink abstraction. While it is easy<br />

enough to point to where a complete or full abstraction first arises in painting, it is<br />

more difficult to say in what way it is complete or full, or to explain its basis in<br />

depiction. As shown in discussion of formalist criticism, the temptation is to<br />

exchange the picture plane (poorly grasped, in any case) with the picture surface, to<br />

assume a single, absolute picture plane for all objects depicted, all materials<br />

depicting. As also shown, this position cannot be sustained historically or<br />

stylistically. It fatally mistakes the basis of depiction and leads to a misguided<br />

intolerance. The task is therefore to say in what way full abstraction remains relative<br />

to depictive styles and to distinguish varieties of picture plane.<br />

Of course none of this determines whether Modernism should be taken as the<br />

period leading up to or away from the emergence of full abstraction - and the term<br />

might usefully be adopted for the genre - but it will suffice to simply signal this<br />

177 Bernard Smith, Modernism’s History, Sydney, 1998, introduces shorter divisions of period<br />

and puzzlingly renames Modernism ‘The Formalesque’, (although the etymology of ‘form’ is<br />

hardly less ambiguous or compromised than ‘modern’ ‘modernity’ or ‘modernism’) and actually<br />

signals an indifference to the problem of formal analysis for depiction and painting in the period.<br />

He is more concerned with introducing colonial and post-colonial contributions to accepted<br />

styles, and is content to gloss Greenberg, Fried, Krauss and others for stylistics, to inherit and<br />

compound the problems discussed in Chapter Nine. Other revisions to Modernism concerning<br />

ethnic, sexual, national and regional factors are not considered here for similar reasons. They too<br />

are concerned with tracing standard stylistics to such factors and often with thus extending<br />

Modernism through additional works, but not with the fundamental problem with depiction<br />

underlying the stylistics of abstraction. So, while the study addresses a popular topic in<br />

Modernism, concern with stylistics here presents a radical reversal of prevailing trends.


115<br />

meaning for ‘abstraction’ here. Modernism in fact might as easily be divided into<br />

low and high periods, as with the Renaissance, with the appearance of abstraction<br />

marking the turning point. The merits of such an arrangement would then depend<br />

upon relations or relevance to adjoining periods. However this falls beyond the<br />

scope of even this broad study. What is needed here is a version of Modernism with<br />

which to frame just developments in the second half of the twentieth century,<br />

indeed this duration is chosen as a measure against such period frames, and so the<br />

convenient choice is for a Modernism that starts with the appearance of (full)<br />

abstraction and to leave questions of preceding periods to another study. Clearly the<br />

emphasis for this history is firstly upon period style, even at the expense of national,<br />

regional, school and individual styles, and the following account does no more than<br />

outline Modernism.<br />

Abstraction is generally taken to emerge around 1912 with certain works by<br />

František Kupka (1871-57), Robert and Sonia Delaunay (1885–1941, 1885-1979),<br />

Stanton Macdonald-Wright (1890–1973), and Morgan Russell (1886-1953) amongst<br />

others, variously identified as Orphists and Synchronists. Less generally<br />

acknowledged is that abstraction also coincides with striking developments in more<br />

concrete depiction. It parallels the transition in the work of Pablo Picasso (1881-<br />

1973) and Georges Braque (1882-1963) from so-called Analytic Cubism to Synthetic<br />

Cubism, as well as a shift in the work of artists including Giorgio De Chirico (1888-<br />

1978), Marc Chagall (1887-1985) and Marcel Duchamp (1887-1968) toward a more<br />

complex use of perspective and its objects. These developments establish crucial<br />

relations with abstraction, channel its variety and restrict its influence, and together<br />

set the course of Modernism. However given the priority of abstraction to<br />

discussion thus far, this chapter is devoted to the revision of the concept.<br />

Competing styles are taken up in the following chapter.<br />

As noted, abstraction is usually understood as a withdrawal from depiction, a<br />

dedication to schemes of non-depictive two-dimensionality, to formal or intrinsic<br />

properties of the medium. Here it is understood to remain depiction, and to picture<br />

only a sort of picture plane. 178 Abstraction to a lesser degree is familiar to depiction<br />

178 As with other instances of self-reference so far considered, while some parts or properties are<br />

sampled, others do the sampling. No paradox arises. The shape or sides of the picture plane are<br />

sampled for only those properties engaged by the pattern or ordering of its area, and not, for


116<br />

in the sorts of objects and pictures discussed in chapter three under the issues of<br />

caricature and fiction. A picture of a young woman or a typical tiger are basically<br />

class terms or abstractions, and classing extends to fictive objects or null depiction<br />

and more elaborate arrangements of objects, to events and their necessary points of<br />

view, to their picture plane schemes, to genres and compositions. The object as a<br />

composition may then be sorted for global or general qualities, of light, motion,<br />

proportion or depth for example, so that the object then as light, motion, depth and<br />

so on, may in turn be classed as a matter of colour, line, tone, and other properties<br />

of depicting materials. In other words, the object is gradually assimilated to the<br />

picture plane and reduced to only an organisation of its sides or shape, the picture<br />

plane is as far or full as abstraction can go in depiction. Abstraction in depiction is<br />

hardly an idle exercise, of course. Establishing such patterns enables new and more<br />

complex or abstract reference, and prompts new directions in less abstract<br />

depiction, as shall be shown in the following chapter. 179<br />

But an effective ordering to this end is not easily accomplished. It must negotiate<br />

constraints from established practices, within depiction and without. In Chapter<br />

Two, non-depictive two-dimensionality was acknowledged as pattern. Symmetry,<br />

repetition, alternation, progression, dispersal and so forth may be cultivated without<br />

depiction. Similarly, basic shapes such as a square or a circle resist more concrete<br />

depiction through entrenched use in a variety of practices, in fact may be considered<br />

as two-dimensional objects. An outline of a circle is therefore not necessarily a<br />

picture of a circle. Such practices suggest a way of avoiding depictive orderings but<br />

risk also avoiding the picture plane. Patterns establish geometric relations for a<br />

theme or motif that are theoretically boundless in extension. The framing of them is<br />

example, their proportions to the width and height of the supporting wall, or their<br />

accommodation as whole numbers under a metric rather than imperial measurement. Selfreference<br />

is taken as always partial, and relative to reference scheme.<br />

179 Analysis of depiction as abstraction, or vice versa, surprisingly has received scant attention.<br />

Notable exceptions are Harold Osborne, Abstraction and Artifice in Twentieth Century Art,<br />

Oxford/New York, 1979, and Charles Harrison, ‘Abstraction’ in Primitivism, Cubism,<br />

Abstraction, Harrison, Francis Frascina, Gill Perry, (eds.) New Haven/London, 1993, pp. 184-<br />

262. Both offer rare precedents for the kind of study undertaken here. Osborne however does not<br />

proceed from a theory of depiction, and his distinction between semantic abstraction, derived<br />

from more concrete objects in depiction, and non-iconic abstraction, derived from a display of<br />

materials and techniques, while raising important questions of merit and criticism, begs closer<br />

attention to depiction (or the iconic), offers no clear history or engagement with more concrete<br />

depiction coinciding with abstraction. Harrison approaches depiction under a framework of<br />

intentional meaning, and of the concrete as mere resemblance, is more tied to a standard history<br />

of Modernism, less inclined to thoroughgoing revision.


117<br />

therefore difficult to impose as a finite extension. Thus a square of polka dots is not<br />

generally seen as a picture of a given number of dots, or as a display of square-ness<br />

but rather as just a sample of the pattern. In such cases polka dots outweigh, or outproject<br />

the square or picture plane. 180 But ‘full abstraction’ is interested in precisely<br />

the picture of the pattern, or the pattern of the picture, and in a two-dimensionality<br />

that points to the picture plane rather than through it. For this reason abstraction<br />

does not initially adopt more obvious patterns, although later with its project more<br />

secured, it accommodates more of them in certain ways.<br />

To start with however, the sampling of abstraction must carefully balance pattern<br />

against picture. Too little pattern may be too much picture or less than full<br />

abstraction. Success lies in finding how the frame may order basic elements without<br />

them amounting to an entrenched pattern, and what elements may be so ordered<br />

without falling into an obvious picture. 181 It is not of course, without its grey areas<br />

and controversies. For example the detection of a figure/ground relation is<br />

sometimes held to offer a primitive scheme for depth and hence to amount to less<br />

than ‘full abstraction’. But an appeal to precedence of figure/ground schemes must<br />

also identify the object figured and its background. There is no depth without<br />

objects, so ‘depth’ cannot argue a priori for objects. More generally, ‘full abstraction’<br />

does not rest upon the elimination of any resemblance between a two-dimensional<br />

ordering and a three-dimensional object, or of any version of depiction. Obviously<br />

that is impossible. Rather, its identity rests only with avoiding prior and prominent<br />

versions of depiction, using novel or unfamiliar versions of pattern. Works accepted<br />

as such moreover project their own resemblance and so rule out some options for<br />

less abstract depiction while attracting new versions of abstraction. No definitive list<br />

of features need be maintained, the grouping includes as opportunity allows.<br />

Thus abstraction in depiction is taken as a sampling practice relative to established<br />

or entrenched pattern. If this view initially seems to trivialise or diminish the<br />

importance of abstraction, it is an impression to be quickly dispelled. As shall now<br />

180 Projection in this sense and projectability of predicates is dealt with extensively in Goodman’s<br />

writings, in particular Goodman, 1972, 1978 and 1983.<br />

181 Thus anxiety with the decorative, noted in Greenberg, is rightly recognised as a failing of<br />

abstraction, but not as inevitable. On the contrary, the projection of abstraction steadily wins new<br />

object and meaning from the decorative, progressively converts the decorative with additional<br />

qualities of painting, or revised sampling. Threat of the decorative is not just allayed but<br />

diminished in further abstraction.


118<br />

be shown, abstraction not only maintains most of its established meaning or<br />

interpretation under this view, but also offers considerable enlargement upon it and<br />

indeed promotes a greater respect and appreciation of pattern. Furthermore, this<br />

now allows the varieties of abstraction to be traced stylistically, properly to trace the<br />

projection of abstraction, without falling into the error of assuming there is the one<br />

fixed and final picture plane or of ascribing wayward notions of ‘flatness’, a notional<br />

depth or elemental material to it.<br />

In outlining projection for abstraction, the crucial contest of styles is recognised.<br />

Importantly, works may be excluded from abstraction where stylistic affinity or<br />

projection outweighs even the seeming disintegration of object and depth. An<br />

example such as Nude Woman (1910) by Picasso (Figure 1) shows how a stylistic<br />

identity resists greater abstraction. Its use of line, tone and plane, favouring short<br />

parallels, and a distinctive facture in modulation of tone, its adherence to a warm,<br />

tertiary to grey palette, and a composition that directs detail or density to a central<br />

area against a neutral or darkened ground, all identify the work with those grouped<br />

as Analytical Cubism. Even though we may have difficulty accepting the depicted<br />

object as a nude woman, (and surely the point is that we do) we have nevertheless<br />

an object derived from a kind of disintegration of perspective, carrying in its wake a<br />

fragmentation of volume and tone. For it is notable that most examples of the style<br />

more or less maintain proportion, both anatomically, and between familiar objects,<br />

and that this governs the dispersal of parts. Here, the head, the eyes and nose<br />

remain especially proximate. The degree of disintegration while marked in this<br />

example does not therefore threaten its stylistic identity or achieve ‘full abstraction’.<br />

The Orphists and Synchronists on the other hand are conspicuous as much for the<br />

way they depart from Cubism as achieve ‘full abstraction’. While they retain a<br />

geometric basis and an emphatic facture of short parallel strokes, they introduce a<br />

distinctly spectral palette, a more strictly two-dimensional geometry, generally to<br />

resolved or integral planes, filled but not traced in outlines, and virtually excluding<br />

tonal gradation. An example such as Kupka’s Disks of Newton variously dated 1911-<br />

12 (Figure 2) offers an especially strong contrast, with its dedication to circles,<br />

segments and ellipses, pointedly avoiding the straight lines of Cubism. The spectral<br />

colour range and spare geometry suggest perhaps a hybrid of Fauvism and Cubism,


119<br />

but the combination cancels each other out here. Since Fauvism favours pure hues<br />

as values of light and Cubism favours basic geometry as values of tone and volume,<br />

when combined thus, colour strips geometry of its volume, geometry strips colour<br />

of its light. We have not spheres in light or spherical lights but simply curves and<br />

colour and since curves intersect and colours intersperse, colour comes in curves, or<br />

curves in colour. 182<br />

Yet notice that while colours here are spectral, their division offers no simple or<br />

obvious geometric relation. The title Disks of Newton reminds us perhaps that it was<br />

Isaac Newton’s formulation of a circular arrangement for the colour spectrum that<br />

first accommodated white at the centre, equidistant from all colour definitions at<br />

the circumference, and measuring chromatic intensity against a central luminosity,<br />

or brightness against lightness. 183 The circle also allows for any number of<br />

distinctions to be drawn around the circumference, to choose which hues are to be<br />

taken as primary, or at what point to draw the line at blue for example, as opposed<br />

to turquoise or purple. Kupka’s geometry does not draw its lines between colours in<br />

quite a standard or predictable way. The example offers only the pinkest of purples,<br />

yet shifts in lightness of blue, blue to black and red to yellow, but only to lightness<br />

in yellow. Equally, circles, ellipses and intersections elude stricter system. A<br />

chromatic and geometric ordering thus acquires a formidable complexity, and is<br />

often interpreted in terms of the mystical, magical or musical. Ordering is furthered<br />

in their size and position within the frame. The red circle and radial variations to the<br />

upper right, and the black, white and grey variations to the lower left direct<br />

brightness against lightness, the mauve and green bands to the upper left are echoed<br />

by the pink and green bands to the lower right, while the simplicity of the left is<br />

contrasted with the complexity of the right. 184 Furthermore the actual size of the<br />

circles, bands and ellipses determines the degree of precision and facture to the<br />

182 For standard interpretation of Orphism see Virginia Spate, Orphism: The Revolution of Nonfigurative<br />

Painting in Paris, Oxford, 1979. Further footnotes indicating established interpretation<br />

for an artist, style or work is simply prefaced by ‘On’.<br />

183 Newton’s concern was of course with the additive mixing of colour in light, rather than the<br />

subtractive mixing of colour in pigment. John Gage traces the contribution of Isaac Newton to<br />

colour theory and to Kupka’s version of a Newtonian colour chart, featuring ten hues and three<br />

levels of saturation, in Gage, Colour and Meaning, London/New York, 1999, pp. 134-153. He<br />

offers many other insights into the role of colour in abstraction, in Gage, Colour and Culture,<br />

London/New York, 1993.<br />

184 On Kupka, see Painting the Universe: František Kupka, Pioneer in Abstraction, Jaroslav<br />

Anděl and Dorothy Kosinski (eds.) Dallas/Stuttgart, 1998 and Serge Fauchereau, Kupka,<br />

Barcelona, 1989.


120<br />

filling colours. Ordering is also in the casual and provisional quality of the filling,<br />

lightness of touch, intimacy of colour to curve, all announce an attitude or spirit.<br />

Ordering then extends not only to the shape of the picture but also to its size (49.5<br />

X 65 cm, 19½ X 25¾”).<br />

As indicated, concern with two-dimensionality and pattern promptly leads to<br />

consideration of three-dimensionality, firstly to facture, or the texture created by<br />

application of paint to the supporting surface, but increasingly to more sculptural<br />

means. Alternatively, pattern may be measured against denotation, or onedirectional<br />

two-dimensionality. Then again, two-dimensional geometry need not<br />

remain basic, but offers more complex versions. This leads of course back to threedimensional<br />

geometry, or to two-dimensional schemes for depth, and firstly to<br />

works such as Contrast of Forms (1913) (Figure 3) by Ferdinand Leger (1881-1955), to<br />

patterns of cylinders, segments and cubes, and beyond that obviously to more<br />

concrete objects, which we shall leave for the moment. But more complex twodimensional<br />

geometry may simply group irregular lines and shapes for more elusive<br />

qualities. In this respect, the work of Wassily Kandinsky (1866–1944) is of interest,<br />

since he initially favours a complex repertory of lines and shapes derived from<br />

figurative or concrete objects, but progressively transformed through a<br />

redistribution of colour and tone and the adoption of an orthogonal or map-like<br />

picture plane 185 .<br />

Untitled - First abstract watercolour, (variously dated 1910-13) (Figure 4) offers a crude<br />

but instructive example. A narrow range of colour is assigned to a variety of shapes,<br />

with varying angles and curves and ranging from the more compact or lump-like, to<br />

the elongated, and to mere lines of various lengths, curve and angularity. This<br />

morphology in turn shares various relations or combinations, yet the distribution<br />

typically approaches an all-over or field structure, and serves to highlight the<br />

restricted range and distribution of colour. In this case red and blue are prominent,<br />

and form a central elliptical area, and like many of the works of this period, this<br />

185 Depiction contrasted with ‘full abstraction’ is often termed figurative or figuration and while<br />

this serves to contrast the literal two-dimensionality of ‘full abstraction’, unfortunately it also<br />

suggests a metaphoric relation for other depiction, which is misleading. Where a square depicts a<br />

cube for example, it is not figuratively or metaphorically a cube. It is literally one side of a cube.<br />

Figurative or metaphorical reference is better understood as expression. Since some such a term<br />

is nevertheless useful, the term concrete depiction is adopted, with some reservations.


121<br />

ellipse assumes a subtle diagonal axis, from lower left to upper right. As with<br />

Kupka, the basis of such colour ordering is not a simple or obvious matter and is<br />

often interpreted as a metaphor for states of mind, reflected in the manner and<br />

degree of resolution to the ordering or pattern. Yet this cumbersome morphology<br />

also confined Kandinsky to works of an elaborate, even epic conception.<br />

Significantly, he later adopted basic geometry and simpler compositions. 186<br />

Kupka also pursued complex two-dimensional geometry in works of a crystalline<br />

and botanical derivation, such as Irregular Forms – Creation (1911). Yet the degree of<br />

abstraction is less certain here, and as with the more abstract works of Georgia<br />

O’Keefe (1887-1986) such as Lake George – Abstraction (1918) works balance a use of<br />

depth against scale of object, allow colour and shape striking latitude, to render<br />

even motion or time, but also recall the increasing use of the photographic close-up<br />

and so tend to appeal to the picture over pattern. But related biomorphic forms<br />

devised by Surrealist artists such as Joan Mirō (1893-1983), Hans/Jean Arp (1886-<br />

1966) and Andre Masson (1896-1987), can sometimes pick out only a family of<br />

curves and shapes and identify the organic or living with merely a pattern. In works<br />

such as Mirō’s Painting (1933) (Figure 5) and certain of his later Constellations series<br />

(1941) a more effective version of Kandinsky’s field composition is formulated. The<br />

narrowed family of lines and shapes, the restriction to flat or single colours, hard or<br />

sharp edges and a uniformity in size enable a greater flexibility of composition, from<br />

many elements, as in the Constellations series to fewer, as in Painting (1933). 187<br />

The structure of pattern balances number of elements against variation. More<br />

elements but less variation is accommodated in a field pattern, while less elements<br />

but more variation allows for a ‘figure’ pattern, as in the works of mid-period<br />

Kandinsky and Piet Mondrian (1872-1944). Interestingly, the monochrome<br />

paintings of Kasimir Malevich (1878-1935) such as White on White (1919) (Figure 6)<br />

are figures rather than fields under this arrangement even though variation of colour<br />

all but disappears, because variation between squares becomes not simply of scale<br />

or size but also of angle to frame and of location within frame. Shape, in other<br />

186 On Kandinsky, see Rose Carol Washton Long, Kandinsky: the development of an abstract<br />

style, Oxford/New York, 1980. Hans K. Roethel and Jean K. Benjamin, Kandinsky, New York,<br />

1979, Francois Le Targat, Kandinsky, New York, 1986/7<br />

187 On Miro, see Roland Penrose, Miro, London, 1985.


122<br />

words, steers abstraction, asserts figure rather than field. The biomorphic field or<br />

figure by no means exhausts the range of lines for a pattern of a picture. Examples<br />

by Klee such as Table of Colour (in Grey Major) (1930) (Figure 7) or Green on Green<br />

(1938) (Figure 8) find a subtle range of line and shape as much by technique and<br />

materials as geometry. Here, rough hewn and casual qualities, as with the Kupka<br />

example, add to the ordering or pattern and sample a stiffness or brittleness of the<br />

material and techniques, or express a patience or tolerance in the attitude of<br />

execution. 188 In later abstraction materials and technique take on more vigorous and<br />

unusual forms, and further govern degree of field and figure in pattern.<br />

The Abstract Expressionist, Tachiste and Informel groups all arrive at pattern<br />

structures according to distinctive materials and techniques. 189 Jackson Pollock<br />

(1912-56) and Bradley Walker Tomlin (1899-1953) for example arrive at fields<br />

through contrasting techniques, while Clifford Still (1904-1980) and Mark Rothko<br />

(1903-1970) maintain figure patterns, according to distinctive viscosities and<br />

applications of paint. Equally Jean-Paul Riopelle (b.1923) and Jean Bazaine (b.1904)<br />

develop fields according to conspicuous techniques, while Wols (1913-1951) arrives<br />

at a figure structure in works such as Composition (1947) (Figure 9) where line and<br />

plane now share no simple family of lines according to drawing, but result from<br />

successive techniques of brushing, rubbing and scratching. Indeed the distinction<br />

between line, plane and colours all but dissolves here. Yet a figure emerges upon a<br />

pale ground, its parts discerned, proportions gauged. The work accordingly offers<br />

metaphors for indecision or impatience, spontaneity or improvisation, or some<br />

combination, and then again for the sobriety of red, the subtlety of brown, the<br />

relativity of line and tone. Yet beyond the variety of techniques adopted, the figures<br />

and fields developed, two-dimensionality also operates in notation, most obviously<br />

in writing, but also with music, dance, mathematics and various sciences. Such<br />

notation also holds a prospect for abstraction from pictures. Hieroglyphs and<br />

pictograms occupy a kind of middle ground, but abstraction seeks not the substance<br />

of notation or the sound of writing, but only the picture of the pattern.<br />

188 On Klee, see Marcel Fransiscono, Paul Klee – his work and thought, Chicago, 1991, and<br />

Gualtieri Di San Lazzaro, Klee, London, 1964.<br />

189<br />

On these and similar styles, see Michel Seuphor, Abstract Painting: fifty years of<br />

accomplishment from Kandinsky to Jackson Pollock, New York, 1964, Marcel Brion, L’Art<br />

abstrait, Paris, 1956, Anna Moszynska, Abstract Art, London, 1990.


123<br />

Notational abstraction occurs in a variety of Surrealist or Surrealist-inspired works.<br />

Together with the impulsive, automatic or spontaneous approaches to technique,<br />

abstract notation occurs prominently in the figure-like patterns of Jackson Pollock<br />

in works such as Male and Female (1942) as well as later more fluent and fluid fields.<br />

By contrast the intricate ‘calligraphy’ of Mark Tobey (1890-1976), offers notationlike<br />

elements in more discrete and discreet fields, in works such as Universal Field<br />

(1949). Since notation is one-directional, following sounds and sequence, notation is<br />

necessarily linear, not strictly tonal or chromatic. An abstraction of fictive notation<br />

however may toy with multi-directional fields, tonal or chromatic coding. Yet<br />

notational abstraction is not drawn only to fields. Works by Wols, Hans Hartung<br />

(1904-1989), Franz Kline (1910-1962), or Pierre Soulages (b.1919) with their<br />

predominantly black and linear elements, look not so much to a textual structure<br />

even with a textural approach, but to an alphabetical one, to figures rather than<br />

fields, and the ‘big’ variations between elements of line and shape, or notationally,<br />

between time and one-directionality. Yet the one-directional linear pattern cannot<br />

be pursued by depiction any further. It is the end of the line for one branch of<br />

abstraction. 190<br />

As noted, scrutiny of two-dimensionality also directs attention to three-dimensional<br />

qualities of a medium, firstly to texture, to novel applications and unusual materials,<br />

then to greater spatial considerations. Hence the common merging of painting with<br />

sculpture, in the painted bas-reliefs of Hans Arp (1886-1966) or Ben Nicholson<br />

(1894-1982), the wall constructions of Vladimir Tatlin (1885-1953), Lazar El<br />

Lissitzky (1890-1941), or Ivan Puni (alias Jean Pougny) (1894-1956), the mobiles of<br />

Alexander Calder (1898-1976), many of the plane-like carvings of Barbara<br />

Hepworth (1903-1975), the Perspex sheet constructions of Naum Gabo (1890-<br />

1977) and the painted constructions of August Herbin (1882-1960) or Georges<br />

Vantongerloo (1886-1965), for example. Discerning abstract two-dimensionality<br />

becomes a way of appreciating the surrounding three-dimensionality, and vice versa.<br />

Yet conventions of three-dimensionality do not deal only in picture planes and are<br />

190 However it is a branch usefully retraced by the Paris-based Letteriste group and offshoots<br />

throughout the fifties, where greater notation converges with poetry and the emphasis shifts to<br />

printing and even textiles. This tendency also emerges in the ‘layouts’ in painting and collage by<br />

the Situationist group. For a brief account of Letterisme and Situationism see Tony Godfrey,<br />

Conceptual Art, London, 1998, pp.58-61 and pp. 75-79.


124<br />

not exemplified only by the exclusion of a dimension, obviously, but by attention to<br />

the versatility of mass in materials and related presentational practices.<br />

The painted wall-construction or bas-relief offers one way of testing such practices<br />

but abstraction in sculpture also seeks distinctive qualities of a given material, firstly<br />

a ‘truth to materials’ that resists the traditional demands of depiction, then forms<br />

and arrangements held to be definitive of the material, then combined materials and<br />

construction held to be definitive to an object or function, then to an arrangement<br />

or construction held to telling to a situation or context. This broadening concern<br />

finds two distinct strategies. On the one hand Modernist sculpture is drawn to<br />

larger issues of design, to architecture, even engineering or industry. It integrates the<br />

work within a larger context and abandons the pedestal, so to speak, on which to<br />

place work. The Russian Constructivists, the Dutch de Stijl group and the German<br />

Bauhaus, amongst others, pursue this tendency. 191 On the other hand Modernist<br />

sculpture also isolates the overlooked material or construction, places it on a<br />

pedestal, so to speak, in order to appreciate otherwise ignored qualities. This<br />

tendency is pursued in Duchamp’s ready-mades, and in various collage or<br />

assemblage practices.<br />

So, one strategy integrates while the other isolates. The pedestal has either no role<br />

or a bigger role in Modernist sculpture. But the two strategies also feed off one<br />

another, some integrations make some isolations more interesting, and vice versa.<br />

The fate of Modernist sculpture does not therefore lie in just the farther reaches of<br />

civic planning or industrial design. ‘Pedestals’ find new applications and variety and<br />

in general the flow between categories makes for more rather than less categories.<br />

Similarly, abstraction in depiction and painting is strengthened rather than<br />

weakened by the pull toward sculpture. Persistent fears for the demise of depiction<br />

and painting mistake the dynamics of such developments, which conform<br />

somewhat to Newton’s third law of dynamics, whereby for every action there is an<br />

equal and opposite reaction. 192 Categories of painted sculpture, assemblage and<br />

construction, refine rather than replace sculpture and painting and help to highlight<br />

191 On Russian Constructivism, see Camilla Gray, The Russian Experiment in Art 1863-1922,<br />

London, 1962, Nicholas H. Allison (ed.) Art into Life: Russian Constructivism 1914-1932, New<br />

York, 1990. For De Stijl see Nancy Troy, The De Stijl Experiment, Cambridge, Mass. 1983. On<br />

The Bauhaus, see Bauhaus, Jeanine Fiedler and Peter Feierabend (eds.) Cologne, 2000.<br />

192 This is of course offered only as a simile, and as a ‘law’ for reference, rather than history.


125<br />

new or overlooked properties for non-sculptural painting and non-painted<br />

sculpture. This development in part measures the course of Modernism. But to<br />

understand this course more fully, the study must also look to how abstraction in<br />

painting influences and responds to developments in more concrete depiction. This<br />

is the task of the next chapter.<br />

The task here has been to explain abstraction as the sampling of two-dimensionality<br />

and the relation between depiction and pattern. It has provided an analysis of the<br />

development of abstraction along four axes, firstly between basic and complex<br />

geometry, secondly between field and figure structures, thirdly between notation<br />

and pattern and fourthly between two and three-dimensionality, or materials. These<br />

comprise the stylistic features of abstraction, and might suggest a realignment of<br />

styles with established sources in a longer study. It is enough here to distinguish<br />

these features from their standard interpretation and to show how abstraction<br />

reconceived makes for a more comprehensive and comprehensible history.


126<br />

Modernism: 1912-1950<br />

‘Simultaneous and Successive Depiction’<br />

Modernism has been taken as a period that commences with the emergence of<br />

abstraction around 1912 and abstraction has been taken as the sampling of twodimensionality<br />

for depiction rather than by depiction. Abstraction here makes<br />

patterns for pictures. But there is more to Modernism than abstraction. Competing<br />

styles of depiction start from similar concerns with novel picture planes but arrive at<br />

versions that defy abstraction and pattern. They sample conflicting objects and<br />

multiple picture planes. Can a picture have more than one object? Can a depicted<br />

object need more than one picture plane? Pictures of more than one object (as<br />

opposed to simply many unitary parts) are familiar in the form of the rabbit/duck<br />

ambiguous drawing, or in the compositions of Giuseppe Arcimboldo (c.1527-1593).<br />

Objects of more than one picture plane are less familiar, but still traditional in<br />

games with scale and perspective such as those devised by William Hogarth (1697-<br />

1764) for the etching False Perspective (1754) (Figure 10). In the first example the<br />

picture may be viewed successively but not simultaneously, offer more than one<br />

picture plane, but not at the same time, may be rabbit or duck, but not rabbit and<br />

duck. In the second, location and scale of object depend upon competing systems<br />

of perspective. The object belongs to any one system to the extent that the system<br />

is consistent throughout the picture, but since none are wholly consistent, the<br />

object properly belongs to conflicting and simultaneous picture planes.<br />

‘Simultaneous and successive depiction’ arises in roughly three styles in Modernism.<br />

Firstly it arises in an overlay and overlap of objects through multiple picture planes<br />

and is here termed ‘Overstyle’. This style commences with the experiments in<br />

collage by Picasso and Braque in 1912 and is pursued by artists such as Klee, Arp,<br />

Miro and Max Ernst (1891-1976), ultimately to a convergence with biomorphic<br />

abstraction. Secondly it leads more narrowly, to a play of styles within a single<br />

picture plane, to blends or hybrids, pastiche and parody. Here this is termed


127<br />

‘Interstyle’. This arises as a conservative and compromised tendency, but receives<br />

decisive support from Picasso in his games with neo-classicist figures and<br />

proportions, as part of his demonstrations of stylistic versatility. 193 The third style<br />

starts from works such as Passage from Virgin to Bride (1912) (Figure 11) by Marcel<br />

Duchamp, I and the Village (1911) (Figure 12) by Marc Chagall (1887-1985) and The<br />

Uncertainty of the Poet (1913) (Figure 13) by Giorgio de Chirico (1888-1978). It<br />

concerns conflicts within systems of perspective, and between objects and realism<br />

of style. This tendency culminates in the ‘dream pictures’ of Ernst, Salvador Dali<br />

(1904-1989), Yves Tanguy (1900-1955) and others, as well as the pictorial<br />

conundrums of Rene Magritte (1898-1967) and is here termed ‘Rerealism’. The term<br />

is introduced since, while much ‘Rerealism’ is the product of Surrealists, (that is,<br />

members of the Paris-based organisation of that name) not all ‘Rerealism’ is<br />

Surrealist. Duchamp, Chagall and de Chirico for example were not members.<br />

Equally, not all Surrealists painted ‘Rerealism’. Miro, Masson, Roberto Enchauren<br />

Matta (b.1911-2003) and Arshile Gorky (1904-1948) did not, for example. Nor is all<br />

‘Rerealism’ necessarily dream-like or especially oneiric – Magritte’s games with a<br />

caption in The Treachery of Images (1939) (Figure 14) or Duchamp’s Passage from Virgin<br />

to Bride (1912) for example surely engage pictorial or stylistic issues before dreams.<br />

The Surrealists, while an important source of promotion and support for<br />

‘Rerealism’ and ‘Overstyle’ are not exclusively the source of either. Finally,<br />

‘Rerealism’ captures something of the multiple or circular nature of the picture<br />

plane friction in such works. The introduction of the styles here perhaps also frees<br />

works from more rigid interpretation.<br />

‘Overstyle and ‘Rerealism’ share with abstraction the promotion of the magical,<br />

mystical and musical and extend schemes of picture plane in more radical ways. Yet<br />

the three styles compete and conflict in means. Abstraction pursues the object to a<br />

193 ‘Interstyle’ is recognised under other descriptions. For example, variants such as the Neue<br />

Sachlichkeit, Pittura Metafisica and Socialist Realism are similarly grouped in Benjamin H. D.<br />

Buchloh, ‘Figures of Authority, Ciphers of Regression’ October no 16 Spring, 1981, pp. 39-68.<br />

Although Buchloh argues not just for a conservatism to the style, but for links to dangerous<br />

political tendencies, for the style as a portent of these and for parallels with the rise of Neo-<br />

Expressionism in the late seventies and early eighties. More recently, the style is reviewed in<br />

relation to abstraction in Robert Storr, Modern art despite modernism, London/New York, 2000.<br />

Although Storr’s grouping is somewhat wider, including ‘Rerealism’ (or much of Surrealism) but<br />

excluding ‘Overstyle’ (or much of Picasso, Klee, Mirō and similar). As the title indicates, Storr<br />

juggles a more general sense of modernism, as a concern with the avant-garde or forthright<br />

progress, (and a common noun) with a tentative concession to period style, or Modernism, in<br />

delineating its conservative tendency.


128<br />

pattern of the picture plane, takes the shape or frame as outermost and its patterns<br />

as offering the requisite intangibility. ‘Overstyle’ and ‘Rerealism’ by contrast find<br />

where the centre does not hold. Conflicting picture planes may share the same<br />

object, up to a point. Conflicting objects may similarly share the same picture plane.<br />

Abstraction is not the issue unless coherence is maintained. While each starts from a<br />

distinct position, their courses soon converge, so that abstraction is outflanked by<br />

multiple picture planes and conflicting objects, but undermines objects and the<br />

concrete with new pattern. Pictures become patterns or patterns become pictures.<br />

While ‘Rerealism’ is usually to be distinguished from ‘Overstyle’ by its reliance on<br />

proportion and perspective, greater plays with and between other projections<br />

occasionally blur the difference. This chapter traces the course of ‘Overstyle’ and<br />

‘Rerealism up to the middle of the century and explains how Modernism absorbs<br />

and expands upon these competing projects.<br />

The experiments with collage by Picasso and Braque are firstly to be understood as<br />

a decisive break with Cubism. In the discussion of Analytical Cubism in the<br />

preceding chapter, the disintegration of perspective and object is shown to involve<br />

isolation of tone and volume of parts, and further to planes, lines and facture of<br />

points. Integration and a whole are a matter of density and detail. Analysing the<br />

object into parts and simple volumes also allows for diversity of projection<br />

(something inherited directly from Cezanne) and as a consequence allows<br />

orthogonal or oblique projections for parts of the picture. Yet for certain objects,<br />

volume is a slender issue. Text or notation of various kinds, wallpaper, postage<br />

stamps, playing cards, faux marbling and wood grain, are all objects that<br />

conspicuously lack volume. They are also often prints, but like patterns, they may<br />

also be considered as two-dimensional objects. To depict such objects presents the<br />

same problem as depicting a circle or square. Such objects function as both<br />

presentation and representation, (when taken as an orthogonal projection of a<br />

sphere or cube, for example). Where orthogonal projection operates in only part of<br />

a picture or object, they strengthen the contrast from part to whole. These issues<br />

arise for Picasso and Braque in the work preceding collage, and surely prompt the<br />

exchange of painted text for actual or collaged text, for the introduction of other<br />

two-dimensional objects, and for the introduction of sand and other thickening<br />

agents to paint in parts of the picture, with which to strike contrasts with ‘presented’


129<br />

three-dimensional properties of the surface and their two-dimensional integration to<br />

the whole. These features are elsewhere seen as a reflection of African practices. 194<br />

The argument here is for their inclusion as simply a more explicit demonstration of<br />

the two-dimensionality at issue.<br />

An early example such as Picasso’s Guitar, Sheet Music and Wine Glass (1912) (Figure<br />

15) combines wallpaper, wood-graining, music and newspaper texts, as well as<br />

coloured paper and a charcoal drawing of a wineglass on a separate sheet. The<br />

vertical oblique projection of the wine glass casts the ‘background’ wallpaper as a<br />

tabletop or horizontal surface, and lays guitar, newspaper and music sheet upon<br />

them. The black saucer shape that overlaps the base of the wine glass may however<br />

function as either a shadow or base of the guitar, or, in a horizontal oblique<br />

projection, as a bowl, and contain or occlude the guitar. Such construction enables<br />

Picasso and Braque to forgo integration and perspective through tone and volume<br />

for alternation or oscillation between conflicting projections. The surface is<br />

successively and contiguously read, not quite as in the rabbit/duck ambiguous<br />

drawing, since objects do not fully coincide, but rather are partial and overlapping,<br />

simultaneous and successive. Confusion in the pictures is however, regrettably<br />

reflected in much commentary. The folly often lies in assuming changes of angle<br />

between object and picture plane always accommodate the same object, or that<br />

changes of angle are all that is involved. 195<br />

Collage offers not only an intriguing supplement to painting, but also a potential<br />

substitute. It begs many more questions of depiction than Picasso or Braque care to<br />

address. For example, what happens when pictures themselves are collaged or represented?<br />

Since pictures may also be prints and belong to the category of twodimensional<br />

objects, their re-presentation ought to highlight their presentational<br />

status through contrast and integration in some greater whole and representation.<br />

194 This point is particularly argued for in Yve-Alain Bois, Painting as Model, Cambridge, Mass<br />

and London, 1993, pp. 65-97. Following Kahnweiler, he argues that the practice derives from a<br />

Grebo mask, and results in similar structures amongst Picasso and Braque’s paper sculptures. It<br />

cannot however explain the acquisition of literal text, wood graining, and of their notably twodimensional<br />

character in paintings. Conversely however, such two-dimensionality does explain<br />

the planar and linear features of the sculptures.<br />

195 On Picasso and Cubism, to offer only a few eminent examples from a broad spectrum, John<br />

Golding, Cubism: a history and analysis, 1907-1914, London, 1959, Robert Rosenblum, Cubism<br />

and Twentieth Century Art, New York/London, 1960, Yves-Alain Bois, Painting as Model,<br />

Cambridge/ Mass./London, 1993, Neil Cox, Cubism, London, 2000.


130<br />

Photographs and other forms of printed depiction however are rarely used in the<br />

collages of Picasso and Braque, but are eagerly taken up by Dada and Futurist<br />

groups, and allied groups in Russia and Germany. An example such as Malevich’s<br />

Composition with the Mona Lisa (1914) (Figure 16) uses a colour photograph or<br />

postcard of Da Vinci’s painting as a ‘real’ or presentational part to a whole picture<br />

of objects upon a blue triangular table, in a manner similar to Picasso and Braque.<br />

But since all other objects are reduced to single colours and black lines, certain of<br />

the photograph’s qualities are heightened. Its small, torn, hand-tinted (and now<br />

faded) qualities become foremost, and modify our view of this icon, as do the<br />

reproving red crosses drawn upon it. 196 This exemplification of materials coincides<br />

with abstraction’s growing attention to three-dimensionality, and may draw it back<br />

into depiction through the incorporation of such prints, or draw such depiction into<br />

abstraction through greater fragmentation, as in the works of Kurt Schwitters<br />

(1887-1948).<br />

The use of only photographic prints, or photomontage, originates as a hobby in the<br />

ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century, where parts are more smoothly integrated into a bigger picture.<br />

But where the structure of the whole is exchanged for a more abstract arrangement<br />

or theme, as in the works of Raoul Haussman (1886-1971), Hannah Hoch/Hoech<br />

(1889-1978), John Heartfield (1891-1968) and others, qualities of material as well as<br />

underlying themes of objects are highlighted. These uses of photomontage, with<br />

their conflicting objects and picture planes also reflect the influence of Chagall and<br />

de Chirico, although range of material and more satirical themes do not. The use of<br />

text on the other hand is certainly owed to Cubism, but their radically different<br />

relation to depicted objects argues against them being taken as simply another<br />

version of Cubism, as is sometimes claimed. As noted, Picasso and Braque generally<br />

resist photomontage.<br />

Yet, for that matter, it is difficult to see why the changes that collage brings to the<br />

work of Picasso and Braque are generally labelled Synthetic Cubism. The<br />

prominence of cubes, or basic volumes and their tones disappears in such work<br />

with the growing emphasis upon flat or single colours and more complex curves<br />

196 It also uncannily anticipates Duchamp’s more celebrated use of the Mona Lisa in L.H.O.O.Q.<br />

(1919).


131<br />

and textures. Nor does it make a great deal of difference to say that they are built up<br />

from, rather than broken down into basic volumes - cubes, so to speak. For surely<br />

whether an object is analysed in terms of cubes, or cubes are synthesised in terms of<br />

an object, all things being equal, must come to the same thing? In fact the difference<br />

rests not upon whether the pictures are built up from or broken down into cubes,<br />

but rather in the variety of the breaks and builds. In short, the works from Picasso<br />

and Braque’s collage period onward are neither synthetic nor Cubist. Cubism in<br />

Picasso and Braque’s work ends with the experiments in collage. ‘Overstyle’ and<br />

Modernism begin.<br />

If one compares Picasso’s Woman in an Armchair (1910) (Figure 17) with Woman in<br />

an Armchair (1913) (Figure 18) the difference is stark. It is not simply one of more<br />

but smaller breaks, contrasted with fewer but bigger breaks, but of other qualities to<br />

the breaks themselves. The breaks in the older work, with their use of straight lines<br />

to register shape, and then volume and tone, are almost Impressionist in their<br />

restrained resolution, a tonal equivalent of a late Mo<strong>net</strong>. The breaks in the later<br />

work are less concerned with any single quality of the object than with a game or<br />

scheme of greater differences between parts. In the older work we have a complete<br />

but vague person, in the later work a partial but clear person. As Gombrich noted,<br />

such games with ambiguity only work where the objects are familiar, and one might<br />

add few and simple. But Picasso excels at these games with proportions and parts,<br />

and finds the familiar through contrasting and successive novelties, as much as<br />

gauges invention according to nature.<br />

In the later example, whole/part relations still resolve from centre to frame (and<br />

later Picasso tends to sharpen this feature). Curves and texture to armchair are<br />

sometimes shared with the woman as in the ‘horizontal’ hair to the right of the<br />

inclined head, doubling as a headrest, the pink arms to the chair sharing the tucked<br />

treatment to the half-slip to the lower centre. Orientation may start from whole or<br />

parts. Surely the breasts in the centre of the picture alert us to the rib cage to the<br />

right and the raised arm and armpit above, for example. The temptation is to say<br />

that the ribs and armpit are more stylised, breasts more realistic, but this would be<br />

stretching a point, so to speak. More accurately, it is a two-way adjustment – the<br />

breasts gain resemblance given the stylistic games played by surrounding parts. But


132<br />

also breasts, like faces and hands (which the picture notably treats more radically)<br />

hold a different priority from ribs and armpits. The game is hardly just an anatomy<br />

lesson. For this reason the games with style are not arbitrary either, as is sometimes<br />

concluded. The rule is not that anything goes, but rather that what goes depends on<br />

from where and how far. Plainly, style and realism are relative to object depicted.<br />

This relativity of style to object, of parts to whole, and the game of variations on<br />

picture plane, remains the focus of Picasso and Braque’s later work.<br />

But while the game of styles is not arbitrary, it nevertheless announces a daunting<br />

variety. Picasso’s growing mastery and enthusiasm for such games quickly leads to a<br />

number of parallel styles within his work. His so-called neo-classical or conservative<br />

works such as The Painter and His Model (1914) (Figure 19) while starkly traditional in<br />

comparison with either example of Woman in an Armchair, is unmistakably a product<br />

of the twentieth century when compared with Ingres, for example. 197 More<br />

accurately, such works play with the proportions and modelling of the figure, with<br />

its canons and realism. Such games might result in Surreal or Rereal figures, if<br />

contrasted with other aspects, such as detail in figure or scale in surroundings. But<br />

no such contrasts arise here, and later, more concerted efforts in this direction are<br />

content with much less, and conflate rather than confront proportion and<br />

modelling with vigorous outline and bold brushwork. The result is a game of<br />

superficial rules or mannerisms when compared with ‘Overstyle’.<br />

‘Overstyle’ is gradually drawn to greater abstraction. The contrast of orthogonal and<br />

oblique projections with and without perspective, bring with them not just other<br />

versions of the object, but less concrete objects. The woman in an armchair<br />

becomes a creature of multiple picture planes, the reassuring subject of endless<br />

games as well as the ghostly, insubstantial vision of many styles. Artists such as Klee<br />

and Mirō take the game further in this direction. Klee’s The Tightrope Walker or The<br />

Equilibrist (1923) (Figure 20) shuffles perspectives and projections to turn the circus<br />

performer into a metaphor for the Modernist, balancing styles and picture planes.<br />

197 Comparisons with Ingres often arise in commentary on these works. The series of drawings,<br />

including portraits of Max Jacob and Ambrose Vollard from the same period, for example, where<br />

a smooth unbroken outline is maintained, and modelling and detail are centred on the face, are<br />

often taken as attributes of Ingres, although properly these are no more than academic staples,<br />

and can be traced back at least to Holbein and Botticelli, and more accurately reflect the use of<br />

tracing.


133<br />

Mirō’s Head of a pipe-smoker (1925) (Figure 21) all but indecipherable without the<br />

title, balances the simplest of profiles – through relation of eye to nose – against a<br />

line that doubles as the smoker’s smile and its black leaf-like forms at the other end,<br />

which serve as a pipe. The yellow plume of smoke echoes this profile while its<br />

flame-like tip of red is in turn echoed in the lungs of the smoker. This comic<br />

reduction now finds a creature of warring lines and colour, as transparent and<br />

transient as smoke. Such figures in both artists work are often seen as aspiring to<br />

the condition of signs, as converging upon notation. As noted, abstraction is also<br />

drawn to notation, and both artists in turn are drawn to abstraction and text on<br />

occasion, and introduce unusual techniques and materials. 198 A final step in this<br />

convergence lies in ‘Overstyle’s’ use of the ‘biomorphic’ object, the metamorphic<br />

core to this world of change. Klee’s The Twin’s Place (1929) (Figure 22) and Mirō’s<br />

Painting on Masonite (1936) (Figure 23) each picture the biomorphic blob in all its<br />

whimsical fluidity. The biomorphic object of ‘Overstyle’ and the biomorphic curve<br />

of abstraction are of course, two sides to the same coin. And it is a coin that is<br />

flipped with a certain impatience throughout the forties, by New York-based artists<br />

such as Gorky, Matta, Motherwell, de Kooning and Pollock, as well as Copenhagenbased<br />

artists such as Carl-Henning Pederson, (1913-1993) Svarvar Gudnason (1909-<br />

1988) and Asger Jorn (1914-73). 199 Before pursuing the implications of this<br />

convergence, one must first look to the other competing style to abstraction, to the<br />

‘Rerealism’ of conflicting objects.<br />

Where the play of pictures advances only in so far as the object is abstracted, the<br />

play of objects advances only in so far as style accommodates certain of their<br />

standard attributes, or attains realism. ‘Rerealism’ seldom bothers with Cubism’s<br />

studio-based tableaux, prefers more fictive, often literary themes but is distinctive<br />

for the spatial conflicts engineered between objects, and the resulting unease.<br />

Examples by Duchamp, Francis Picabia (1879-1953), Chagall and de Chirico all<br />

generate an equal confusion of scale, depth, movement and light. Duchamp does<br />

away with Cubism’s broken facture and resolves lines and planes to volumes only to<br />

198 On Mirō, see Roland Penrose, Mirō, London, 1985. On Klee, see Marcel Fransiscono, Paul<br />

Klee – his work and thought, Chicago, 1991, Gualtieri Di San Lazzaro, Klee, London, 1964.<br />

199 While these artists are more typically associated with the CoBrA publications and exhibitions<br />

of the late forties, their earlier work exhibits greater attention to biomorphic features from in their<br />

Höst exhibitions in Copenhagen from 1939. See Cobra, 40 Years After (catalogue) Chris van der<br />

Heyden (ed.) Amsterdam, 1988.


134<br />

confront a daunting spatial and tonal complexity in The Passage from Virgin to Bride<br />

(1912). We have a realistic picture of a Cubist construction, or a Cubist picture of<br />

‘only’ volumes and planes. According to the title it depicts a model or plan for<br />

sexual initiation and marriage, but comically, it can function as no more than an<br />

abstruse or failed metaphor. 200 The construction of a spatial model for an extended<br />

passage of movement is something pursued more cautiously by the Futurists. De<br />

Chirico also cultivates models and plans, but includes classical sculpture as well as<br />

less familiar constructions, and pictures within pictures to undermine the realism of<br />

objects and style, and to point to the metaphysics of depiction. 201 Yet the pictures<br />

are hardly a dry exercise in philosophy, for such confusion is as readily experienced<br />

as anxiety or disorientation. In The Uncertainty of the Poet (1913) it is felt in the<br />

conflicts of perspective, scale, depth, between torso, bananas and the strangely tilted<br />

colonnade. Nor are such experiences only the stuff of dreams, but may be just the<br />

equivalent of staring at the spelling of a word until overcome with a similar<br />

confusion. Stylistic integrity, like spelling, can sometimes be cut adrift. Chagall’s<br />

equally dislocated composition in I and the Village (1911) is keyed to red and green<br />

and inverts, displaces, compounds and superimposes objects, and is sometimes<br />

thought to structure a narrative in this way, although more accurately, incidents and<br />

folklore evoke successive and conflicting aspects of a time and place. For Chagall,<br />

this is generally provincial life in Tsarist Russia. 202<br />

As noted, conflicts between depicted objects lend themselves to photomontage, but<br />

photomontage also heightens the conflicts, not simply through different qualities of<br />

paper and printing, but through greater realism associated with their various<br />

functions (as discussed in Chapter Nine). They also prompt different objects.<br />

Among the first artists to fully exploit these possibilities is Ernst. He not only<br />

transferred the technique back into painting with a new and potent approach to<br />

fiction, in works such as The Elephant of Celebes (1921) but also applied<br />

photomontage to the theme of models and plans, in works such as Stratified rock<br />

nature’s gift composed of gneiss lava Icelandic moss 2 varieties of bladderwort 2 varieties of perineal<br />

hernia cardiac vegetation (b) the same in polished casket, a little more expensive (1920) (Figure<br />

200 On Duchamp, again from a vast array, see Dawn Ades, Neil Cox and David Hopkins, Marcel<br />

Duchamp, London, 1999, for a concise overview.<br />

201 The style of these pictures is sometimes termed Metaphysical, although metaphysics are<br />

hardly confined to this style, of course.<br />

202 On Chagall, see Jean Cassou, Chagall, London, 1965.


135<br />

24) As with the example by Duchamp, title and picture render an absurdity, but<br />

equally, offer a metaphor for scientific analysis, and model-making as an end in<br />

itself. Interestingly, such works plunder scientific and commercial sources curiously<br />

ignored by Duchamp and Picabia. Ernst’s versatility of technique and materials also<br />

carry his work into ‘Overstyle’ and abstraction. However, Magritte, Tanguy and<br />

Dali, amongst others, take up the fictive potential of ‘Comrealism’ with greater<br />

dedication.<br />

Magritte also maintains the play with models, with pictures within pictures, and the<br />

emphasis upon the role of reference or representation in the identity of objects. As<br />

with Duchamp, things are always caught standing for other things, as part of being<br />

themselves. For this reason Magritte’s work is also as much metaphysical as dreamlike<br />

or surreal. Yet Magritte also presses realism in a way that neither Duchamp nor<br />

de Chirico care for. Magritte’s objects often assume a conflicting texture or shape,<br />

and offer for example birds made of stone, or stones shaped like birds, and each<br />

may hover before their surroundings and argue identities or circumstances. The<br />

greater the realism, the more concrete the object, the greater the conflict and<br />

resulting ‘Rerealism’. In the case of Dali these conflicts of scale, texture and shape<br />

culminate in the celebrated limp wristwatches of The Persistence of Memory (1931)<br />

(Figure 25). Dali is equally noted for the use of successive picture planes, of the<br />

rabbit/duck variety - his ‘paranoiac-critical’ method. In The Metamorphosis of Narcissus<br />

(1937) (Figure 26) the repeated image of a hand holding an egg coincides on the left<br />

with the image of a crouching youth, head resting on a raised knee. But where<br />

‘Overstyle’ resists the coincidence of whole objects and picture planes in favour of<br />

partial or overlapping versions, Dali’s ‘Rerealism’ is drawn to the challenge of<br />

sustaining them. Unfortunately the pictures cannot sustain an endless kaleidoscope<br />

of objects, but typically present one or two as a set piece amid a landscape. 203 As a<br />

consequence, they seem as much hostages to ingenuity as features of the sublime or<br />

subliminal. 204<br />

203 Interestingly, it is during this period, in the late 1930s, that the prints of M.C. Escher attain<br />

their distinctive perspectival and projective structures that sustain just these kinds of<br />

multiplicities. See Escher, M.C. Escher, The Graphic Work, Cologne, 2001, p. 6.<br />

204 On Magritte and Dali see William Rubin, Dada and Surrealist Art, London, 1969, Rene<br />

Passeron, The Concise Encyclopaedia of Surrealism, London, 1984. Dawn Ades, Dada and<br />

Surrealism, London, 1974.


136<br />

Yet two-dimensionality lurks behind such ambiguous objects as much as underlying<br />

myths or primal drives. Indeed, a problem for ‘Rerealism’ lies with the consolidation<br />

of its artist’s styles and the emergence of a distinctive iconography throughout the<br />

forties. Neither Ernst’s novel techniques nor Magritte or Dali’s studied<br />

academicisms deliver a realism beyond their range of objects, nor a range of objects<br />

beyond their realism. There is no non-technique or neutral realism to which to<br />

appeal. Nor is there an object so wild, spontaneous and disturbing that it does not<br />

require a technique, or with repeated acquaintance, acquire one. In this light<br />

‘Rerealism’ begins to acquire a default formalism, may even start to look a little like<br />

a kind of ‘full abstraction’, displaying only a style of picture plane. A point<br />

supported, if one returns for a moment to the project of abstraction and its appeal<br />

to basic geometry in exemplifying the picture plane. As shown, if geometry is<br />

pursued, it encounters three-dimensional geometry, and if one were an artist<br />

committed to abstraction and wondering how three-dimensional geometry might<br />

exemplify a picture plane, one might easily exploit just such paradoxes and conflicts<br />

through perspective and proportion, just such appeals to realism.<br />

As shown, ‘Overstyle’ converges with abstraction with its biomorphic objects, and<br />

now one can see how ‘Rerealism’ is at least tentatively drawn to it. Conversely,<br />

when abstraction acquires biomorphic curves, it cannot then resist their mechanical<br />

or engineering counterparts in basic geometry. Even Mondrian’s work of the forties<br />

uses titles like Place de la Concorde (1938-43) Trafalgar Square (1939-43) and New York<br />

City 1 (1941-42) and while such titles offer at most a metaphor, abstraction<br />

nevertheless obtains such versions while creeping toward the concrete. Since all<br />

three styles emerge at the same time none can appeal to precedent of project or a<br />

greater entrenchment. Expanding pattern meets expanding picture on equal terms,<br />

and the result would seem to be a kind of stylistic stalemate.<br />

But as with the convergence of painting and sculpture considered in the previous<br />

chapter, the deadlock of styles does not quite eventuate. Firstly, many unambiguous<br />

works continue to reinforce style identity, while intermediate works never command<br />

sufficient bulk to seriously undermine the distinctions. Secondly, because<br />

intermediate works can have no more than a foot in each camp, so to speak, their<br />

impact upon the respective camps is progressively weakened, so that further


137<br />

integration becomes an exercise in diminishing returns. The stalemate thus never<br />

quite arises. Mondrian’s architectural metaphors reinforce their distance from the<br />

literal and concrete. The generic props of ‘Rerealism’ and the biomorphic objects of<br />

‘Overstyle’ cannot quite become patterns without patterns becoming pictures. Yet<br />

pressing the issue in this way has its uses, serves to direct and strengthen other lines<br />

of enquiry. For abstraction, consolidation enables the adoption of greater, more<br />

obvious pattern. For ‘Overstyle and ‘Rerealism’, further versions move beyond<br />

‘simultaneous and successive’ depiction. A crucial juncture for Modernism thus<br />

arises by the middle of the century and marks the start of a later phase. In the<br />

following chapter, Late Modernism is traced from this point along a path that<br />

departs from ‘simultaneous and successive’ depiction.


138<br />

Late Modernism 1950 – 1960<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’<br />

The study now turns to the second half of the twentieth century with a broad view<br />

of the stylistics of Modernism in place. As shown, the middle of the century<br />

represents a turning point for Modernism, where competing styles converge, then<br />

take new directions. The change earns a new but brief period. Late Modernism<br />

arises and so coincides with the lower end of the time frame for the study, but is no<br />

more significant for that. The transition is no more precise than the start of<br />

Modernism, which is to say it allows a margin of two or three years, but for<br />

convenience may be taken as starting at 1950, just as Modernism here has been<br />

rounded out to a starting point in 1912. Modernism gains a second period, as Late<br />

Modernism, and its first period consequently becomes Early Modernism. Period<br />

here also admits to a subtle shift of place. Where Early Modernism was more<br />

centred on Western Europe, Late Modernism centres more on New York and<br />

London, and marginalizes Eastern Europe, Germany and Spain. Late Modernism<br />

also involves competing styles and a version of abstraction, but ‘Overstyle’ and<br />

‘Rerealism’ undergo more radical change and attention is firstly devoted to this<br />

departure.<br />

The change in general terms is away from an affirmation of the magical, mystical<br />

and musical and toward a more brooding acceptance of their inconstancy. Work<br />

now stresses doubt, frustration, mistakes and revision. The disaffection is reflected<br />

in the distrust and dilution of preceding styles. As noted, abstraction and<br />

‘simultaneous and successive depiction’ converge in some ways. But where<br />

‘simultaneous and successive depiction’ accommodates abstraction amongst its rival<br />

picture planes or abstraction accommodates the ‘simultaneous and successive’ as a<br />

pattern of pictures, the combination cancels itself out. The result is in some respects<br />

more traditional in that objects are less abstract, the picture plane tending to the<br />

singular, but in other respects more radical in that object and picture plane variously


139<br />

exhibit a new and puzzling incompleteness, an extreme supplementation of pigment<br />

and medium and a multiplicity beyond the simultaneous or successive. In fact<br />

construction now establishes a reciprocal relation between three-dimensionality and<br />

two, the abstract and the concrete, pattern and picture. What is sampled is the<br />

mutual dependence between materials and two-dimensionality, picture plane and<br />

object. The style is here termed ‘Reciprocal Depiction’.<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ carries the rival projects of Early Modernism through to one<br />

further and final stage or style. But ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ does not just explain<br />

what becomes of the influence of Picasso, Klee and Miro on one hand, Ernst,<br />

Magritte and Dali on the other. In assimilating them it also sets in place a more<br />

complex sampling practice that rapidly suggests further projects for depiction and<br />

painting. This, as much as developments in abstraction, sets the agenda for<br />

subsequent periods to the century. However this chapter traces only the varieties of<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ for the period, while following chapters show how they<br />

arrive at a further break of period, of Post Modernism. This is, of course, only to<br />

delay considering the relation with abstraction in Late and Post-Modernism and a<br />

fuller view of the periods. But this course enables firstly a stronger grasp of<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’, of features rarely associated or properly considered in other<br />

art histories.<br />

To be clear on the terms, ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ is introduced as the name for a<br />

style of painting that arises at this time, that deals in less than full abstraction, more<br />

than traditional concrete depiction. It is not, as was the case with ‘simultaneous and<br />

successive depiction’, merely the name given to a more general category of picture,<br />

to which the historical variants of ‘Overstyle’ and ‘Rerealism’ can be assigned.<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ for just the period of Late Modernism, might aptly be called<br />

‘Ambistyle’ or more pointedly perhaps, ‘Disillusion’, if discussion of the style in<br />

subsequent periods arises. But the task is firstly to outline the main traits of<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ and to set in place sub-styles for period as need arises. Here<br />

it is enough to appreciate its pervasive presence throughout the period, its influence.<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ arises in three ways. Firstly it uses an arrangement of discrete<br />

pictures and sometimes notation within a larger map-like scheme to sample patterns


140<br />

between pictures and other elements. Or reciprocally, it samples pictures and other<br />

elements for such larger schemes or patterns. This is here termed ‘layout’, in<br />

contrast with traditional ‘composition’, understood as the organisation within a<br />

single picture. Secondly, it uses radical supplements to pigment and medium that<br />

require novel application or manipulation so that they sample qualities that resist<br />

standard depiction and objects, and reciprocally, samples depiction that nevertheless<br />

succeeds, that gains purchase or traction in such material. This is here termed<br />

‘traction’. Thirdly, it uses a fragmentation of object and picture plane that samples a<br />

kind of cross-section to the depictive process, an interrupted state in which<br />

completion or revision rest upon a range of reciprocal adjustments to material,<br />

picture plane and object. This is here termed ‘interruption’. ‘Interruption’ may<br />

include ‘layout’ or ‘traction’ while also dealing in less complete or discrete pictures,<br />

more typical materials and techniques. All or some of these ways may be used in<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’.<br />

The roots of ‘layout’ lie directly in certain works by Klee and Mirō where objects,<br />

pictures or notation alternate between literal and metaphorical relations. There are<br />

similar and stronger roots in Early Modernist photomontage, in works by<br />

Schwitters, Hoch or Ernst for example, and this practice is pursued by a wide range<br />

of artists in the fifties, from Englishmen, Eduardo Paolozzi (b.1924) and Richard<br />

Hamilton (b.1922), to New York-based Americans, Ray Johnson (b.1927) and<br />

Robert Rauschenberg (b.1925) to the West Coast-based, Bruce Connor (b.1923) for<br />

example, where fragmentation of a given photograph is less prominent than its<br />

entire inclusion within a greater whole. Roots are also found where ‘Overstyle’s<br />

orthogonal picture planes introduce biomorphic objects, their organic or cellular<br />

organisation and are augmented by pictograms and notational elements. These are<br />

prominent in the work of Gorky, de Kooning, Pollock, Motherwell and Adolph<br />

Gottlieb (1903-1974) throughout the forties. ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ arises where<br />

‘layout’ is given added emphasis, by the self-contained or framed photograph in a<br />

larger arrangement, in painting by simpler and singular picture planes and broader<br />

range of objects depicted.<br />

The paintings of the Cobra (or CoBrA) group (1949-51) frequently offer this range,<br />

favouring Klee-like masks or heads, figures, suns, buildings, boats and mythical


141<br />

beasts, but generally reducing the more elaborate games of ‘Overstyle’, settling for<br />

the isolation of object and picture in primitive orthogonal projections (where the<br />

edge of the object strictly becomes the edge of a picture plane). 205 CoBrA work<br />

becomes in this way more insistently about ‘layout’. Works thus take on the quality<br />

of a chaotic board game or chart in their placement of object or pictures. Yet these<br />

works do not simply alternate depiction with denotation, the concrete with the<br />

abstract, but are often blended, spontaneously or intuitively mapping objects and<br />

relations, even as the map is made, as in Fantasia II (1944) (Figure 27) an early work<br />

by Dane, Carl-Henning Pedersen. 206 Means shift accordingly from the smooth linear<br />

approaches of earlier work to heavier, peremptory brushstroke and muddled colour.<br />

The attraction lies in the promise of a reconciliation of depiction and denotation, a<br />

recurrent desire and source of potent metaphors. Indeed it is an attraction that<br />

persists throughout the rest of century, even as the concern with more abstract or<br />

fictive notation and esoteric symbols is replaced with more sustained picture planes,<br />

more standard text. The influence of CoBrA is widespread and felt in the work of<br />

Englishman, Alan Davie (b.1920) Frenchman, Gaston Chaissac (1910-64) German,<br />

Horst Antes (b.1936) Australian, John Olsen (b.1928) amongst many others. The<br />

attraction to notation also converges with abstraction of notation, discussed in<br />

Chapter Eleven and much CoBrA work dissipates in this convergence.<br />

‘Layout’ involving picture planes other than the orthogonal is less popular in<br />

painting at this time, although a tentative acceptance is found in the work of<br />

Rauschenberg. His use of photography in assemblages from the mid-fifties, such as<br />

Small Rebus (1956) (Figure 28) show one way in which this ‘layout’ or ‘flat-bed’<br />

composition stretches the literal and metaphoric, embraces a range of picture<br />

planes. 207 Here, a range of exertions for the person is mapped against colour,<br />

textural and linear grades, measuring performance for a multitude of factors,<br />

205 On the CoBrA or Cobra group, see Jean-Clarence Lambert, Cobra, New York, 1984. Also<br />

note useful website http://www.cobraart.dk (2003-4).<br />

206<br />

CoBrA artists such as Asger Jorn (1914-73) and Constant (a.k.a. Constant Anton<br />

Nieuwenhuys) (1920-2005) later pursue layout in the detournements of Situationism in the late<br />

ni<strong>net</strong>een fifties, literally mapping texts onto maps and other pictures.<br />

207 The term ‘flatbed’ arises in Leo Steinberg, Other Criteria, New York/ Oxford, 1972, pp. 55-<br />

92. The famous essay there of the same title, an extensive review of Modernism, concludes with<br />

a survey of Rauschenberg’s work throughout the fifties, and his various uses of the ‘flatbed’<br />

picture. The term has since become a staple in discussions of the artist’s work, although does not<br />

quite capture crucial orientations or ‘layout’ for elements within the flatbed. Steinberg also<br />

attributes the flatbed picture to a Post-Modernist period that significantly begins with the fifties.


142<br />

reciprocally mapping grades against a variety of exertions and emotions. His<br />

illustrations to Dante’s Inferno, (1959-60) such as The Thirty First Canto (Figure 29)<br />

using a form of photo-transfer, are significant not only in their forthright alignment<br />

to a classic text, but for their use of approximate sequences of images, from left to<br />

right, top to bottom, yet resisting a stricter storyboard or comic strip scheme 208 . The<br />

use of contemporary and topical photographs from the popular press reinforces the<br />

metaphorical role assigned Dante and depiction.<br />

‘Traction’ generally resists the more forthright sculptural tendencies of Modernism.<br />

The precedents for ‘traction’ lie firstly with Picasso and Braque’s Cubist works,<br />

where attention is given to the mixing of sand and other materials with paint, to<br />

highlight three-dimensional properties for parts of a picture. However ‘traction’<br />

gains greater prominence in the work of Jean Dubuffet (1901-1985) and Jean<br />

Fautrier (1898-1964) particularly in the late forties, where the medium variously<br />

incorporates plaster, glues, shellac, shoe polish and varnishes with more familiar<br />

pigments, and against which a notably basic picture plane is not so much drawn as<br />

modelled, carved or engraved. Matters of line and colour are often inseparable from<br />

accident and chemistry in these ‘high pastes’, or else so detached as to present<br />

almost a second layer. Yet it is also clear in such works that the latitude granted<br />

basic picture planes determines what it is that we appreciate about the expanded<br />

mediums, just as much as the medium underlines certain properties of the picture<br />

planes. Accordingly, both artists press objects and picture planes to greater<br />

abstraction where surface and texture suggest some potent metaphor. Fautrier’s<br />

series of Hostages (1944-5) (Figure 30) are essentially a blindfolded or hooded head<br />

in stark profile or orthogonal projection, yet all but surrender their resemblance in<br />

the interests of the striking equivocation of colour, line and texture, expressing a<br />

stifled identity. Similarly Dubuffet’s series Texturologies, from the mid to late fifties,<br />

offer literal grounds of intricate brown spatterings and complex texture, yet also<br />

208 It is notable that Rauschenberg’s approval of Botticelli’s illustrations for Dante’s Inferno<br />

rested on the view that Botticelli had “treated it like a combination road map and cartoon”,<br />

quoted in Calvin Tompkins, Off The Wall Harmondsworth/UK/New York, 1980, p. 157. For<br />

detailed commentary on Rauschenberg’s illustrations and comparison with Botticelli, see<br />

William S. Lieberman, ‘Die Illustrationen zu Dantes Inferno’ in Robert Rauschenberg: Werke<br />

1950-1980, (catalogue) Dieter Ruckhaberle (ed.) Berlin, 1980, pp. 118-255.


143<br />

depict soil microscopically, a barren landscape or even a distant galaxy,<br />

macroscopically, and express this fundamental constancy or paucity. 209<br />

It is conspicuous however that neither of these artists is drawn to the more<br />

elaborate ‘layout’ strategies considered above. For all the graffiti-like qualities of<br />

Dubuffet’s work, text or script rarely plays a part, and where it does, as in ‘Still Life<br />

with Passport (1953) (Figure 31) it remains firmly embedded in a single picture plane<br />

– an opened passport upon a table. 210 ‘Traction’ is pursued in the work of artists<br />

such as Antoni Tapies (b.1923) with stucco-like surfaces, ‘wall-fittings’ and casual<br />

notations, but also approaches greater abstraction and collage, as in the work of<br />

Alberto Burri (1915-1995) with stained and distressed burlap, and later welded steel<br />

and molten plastic assemblages 211 . ‘Traction’, like ‘layout’ resists other than an<br />

orthogonal picture plane. Rauschenberg also promotes ‘traction’, firstly through the<br />

series Black Paintings, in which a ground of crumpled and shredded newspaper is<br />

immersed in black paint, to varying degrees of transparency. The irregularity of the<br />

surface is thus asserted against its uniformity of colour, as resulting shadows and<br />

highlights vary blackness, although strictly offers no ‘Reciprocal Depiction’. But<br />

Rauschenberg, like many a Modernist, quickly grasps that such expansion need not<br />

rest with texture, the absorbency of support or transparency of pigment, and in a<br />

following series of works, titled Red Paintings, extends the painted surface to a variety<br />

of supports, including newsprint and comic strip fragments, printed fabrics, found<br />

wooden and metal panels. These works culminate in the linked screens of Minutiae<br />

(1954) (Figure 32). What is distinctive is the inclusiveness, which maintains photocollage<br />

while annexing an impressive array of materials. But ‘layout’ and ‘traction’<br />

do not always apply, or maintain ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ here. In the same year for<br />

example, he also produced works consisting entirely of a literal ground of earth<br />

sown with grass seeds, that in time and with care became ‘grass paintings’.<br />

209 On Dubuffet, see Peter Selz, The Work of Jean Dubuffet, (catalogue) New York, 1962, and<br />

Max Loreau, Dubuffet: stratégie de création, Paris, 1973. For Fautrier, see Yves Peyré, Jean<br />

Fautrier ou Les Outrages de L'Impossible, Paris, 1990.<br />

210 An interesting exception is the Messages series (1944) where casual notes for meetings or<br />

directions are jotted across newsprint, variously deleted or amended. See Yve-Alain Bois and<br />

Rosalind Krauss, Formless: a User’s Guide, New York, 1997, pp. 178-179.<br />

211 On Burri see also Currentartpics 71.


144<br />

Rauschenberg’s further contributions are taken up in Chapter Fifteen. 212 The work<br />

of his close colleague at this time, Jasper Johns (b.1930) also deals in ‘traction’ and<br />

‘layout’ but not quite ‘Reciprocal Depiction’. Johns also uses shredded newsprint,<br />

but immersed in an encaustic that similarly allows for a degree of transparency,<br />

while coating it in a thick paste. His paintings adopt a repertoire of stencilled<br />

alphabets and numbers, concentric circles, usually titled targets, and most famously,<br />

the design of the American flag, in lieu of a picture plane, such as Flag above White<br />

with Collage (1955) (Figure 33). As noted in Chapter Twelve, such objects are not<br />

strictly depicted, but rather presented. They are also, of course, the kind of ‘twodimensional<br />

objects’ that attracted Picasso and Braque and initially prompted<br />

‘Overstyle’. But here they serve quite the opposite purpose. For Picasso and Braque,<br />

any two-dimensionality may have more than one three-dimensional identity and vice<br />

versa, hence they pursue multiple and overlapping picture planes, where text and<br />

wood-grain for example, also depict or resemble other objects.<br />

For Johns however, two-dimensionality is never quite so isolated, or spoilt for<br />

choice of identity. Rather, two-dimensionality is merely readjusted with each threedimensional<br />

instance, or through attention to accompanying materials. Hence his<br />

two-dimensional objects are at once mere designs or templates, against which to<br />

display painting and three-dimensionality, yet are also gently modified by the<br />

exercise of his short and broad, patient but firm brushstrokes. The object emerges<br />

both transcendent and malleable, absorbing variations of line and colour while at<br />

the same time imposing a level of precision upon the brushwork. The exercise may<br />

seem variously meek in its conformity and narrow variation, or arrogant in its<br />

choice of such fundamental objects and idle treatment. 213<br />

The interplay between object and painting obviously functions similarly to<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’. Indeed it demonstrates the reciprocal nature of twodimensionality<br />

and three more thoroughly than any picture plane might. Yet it pays<br />

212 On Rauschenberg’s work of this period, see Andrew Forge, Rauschenberg, New York, 1969,<br />

Calvin Tompkins, Off The Wall: Robert Rauschenberg and the Art World of Our Time, New<br />

York, 1980, Mary Lynn Kotz, Rauschenburg: Art and Life, New York, 1990.<br />

213 On Johns, again only to indicate an extensive range: Jill Johnston, Jasper Johns: Privileged<br />

Information, London, New York, 1997, Michael Crichton. Jasper Johns. New York, 1994, Fred<br />

Orton, Figuring Jasper Johns. Cambridge/Mass./London, 1994. Richard Francis, Jasper Johns,<br />

New York, 1984, and Max Kozloff, Jasper Johns, New York, 1974 and finally, Currentartpics<br />

74.


145<br />

a heavy price as a sustained practice, with the restricted range of such twodimensional<br />

objects, and the template-like approach to painting. John’s subsequent<br />

work relaxes both the arrangement of the templates and the degree of conformity<br />

for painting, in works such as the series of maps of The United States such as Map<br />

(1962) (Figure 34) which also acquire a picture plane and so ‘Reciprocal Depiction’,<br />

but it is the artists that follow his example that extract more surprising and potent<br />

direction from his work. These are considered in the following chapter.<br />

Finally, ‘interruption’ arises where depiction maintains a concern with perspective<br />

and spatial conflicts between objects. It thus succeeds ‘Rerealism’ more so than<br />

‘Overstyle’. ‘Interruption’ is a demonstration of the unmaking and remaking of the<br />

picture plane and object, of a marked incompleteness. ‘Interruption’ samples the<br />

stages passed through, the trials and revisions explored, accidents exploited, in<br />

moving toward an identifiable style and a completed painting. It offers a kind of<br />

cross-section, from material to technique, technique to line, plane, object and so to<br />

more complex issues of constitution and resolution of sample. ‘Interruption’<br />

brackets the paintings of Alberto Giacometti (1901-66) from the late forties with de<br />

Kooning’s series of paintings titled Woman, beginning with Woman 1 (1950-52) the<br />

work of Francis Bacon (1909-92) from the early fifties such as Study after Velasquez’s<br />

Portrait of Pope Innocent X (1953) the work of Larry Rivers (b.1923) commencing with<br />

his version of Washington Crossing The Delaware (1953) the works of Peter Blake<br />

(b.1932) commencing with On The Balcony (1955-57) and of Richard Hamilton<br />

(b.1922) commencing with his twin series of paintings and collages, Hommage à<br />

Chrysler Corp (1957) and Hers is a Lush Situation (1957) amongst the more prominent<br />

examples of the style.<br />

The diversity of this grouping may seem surprising, since standard histories often<br />

urge national or regional interests as a priority, or favour alignments to preceding<br />

styles such as Abstract Expressionism or Surrealism. Here attention is drawn to<br />

other stylistic consistencies, while also allowing that the very resistance to<br />

completion and conformity addressed by ‘interruption’ grants a divergence, an<br />

emphasis upon the individual, the instance, even the existential. Indeed, Late<br />

Modernism in this respect is a period notable for its lack of self-proclaimed groups<br />

or organisations (CoBrA being a short-lived exception) and ‘interruption’ is


146<br />

essentially a short-tern strategy. It hovers defiantly between tradition, the<br />

conservative and current competing practices, depends upon a certain amount of<br />

Modernism even as it rejects the rest. ‘Interruption’ then can at most keep pace with<br />

rival trends, and while the study looks to the following works in chronological<br />

order, it surveys as much the shifting strategy of ‘interruption’.<br />

For Giacometti, painting is restricted to line or drawing, while depiction maintains a<br />

single perspective and much proportion. His paintings typically approach<br />

monochrome, and acquire volume and tone through a loose accumulation of line<br />

and ‘interruption’. The effect is somewhat like a Cezanne, but indifferent to colour,<br />

impatient with light and suspicious of volume. Interestingly, works also pursue a<br />

radical linearity in their emphasis upon the perpendicular, preserving bodily<br />

proportions vertically, while collapsing lateral proportions to a compelling<br />

minimum. This practice also occurs in his sculpture, and occasionally they coincide,<br />

as in Three Plaster Heads (1947) (Figure 35). 214 A different kind of one-dimensionality<br />

is approached here from that of the notational and introduces a strongly directional<br />

‘interruption’. De Kooning on the other hand looks to compound line, colour and<br />

tone through broad and clamorous brushstroke and other application, yet maintains<br />

perspective and proportion in Woman I (Figure 36) with the foreshortening in the<br />

right foot and knee, as well as modelling or shading to the midriff, chin and right<br />

side of the face. At the same time the improbable or competing proportions of the<br />

facial features, breasts and shoulders, and the unresolved extensions to the arms<br />

that arise through countless erasures and revisions, underline not so much multiple<br />

competing versions as momentary and serendipitous ones. 215 Later De Kooning<br />

retreats to greater abstraction, retaining a vigorous sense of ‘interruption’ and multivalence<br />

for formal elements of line, colour, tone, scale, etc. Again, the ease with<br />

which he shifts between the abstract and the concrete, underlines a conviction in<br />

the ‘reciprocal’.<br />

Bacon’s painting at this time also concentrates on the single figure, but<br />

‘interruption’ here occurs rather in striking relations of highlight and shadow. It is<br />

214 On Giacometti, see Yves Bonnefoy, Giacometti, New York, 1991, David Sylvester, Looking<br />

at Giacometti, London, 1994, and Peter Selz, Alberto Giacometti, New York, 1965.<br />

215 On De Kooning, see Harry F. Gaugh, De Kooning, New York, 1983, Harold Rosenberg, De<br />

Kooning, New York, 1974.


147<br />

drawn to depiction of textures, sometimes with ‘tractable’ textures, but more<br />

importantly to unusual configurations of tone for the figure, and most particularly<br />

facial expression. These are often inspired by the tonal severity in certain black and<br />

white photography and cinema. The uncertainties to resemblance here are matched<br />

with equally unusual or ambiguous surroundings and the balance is carried over into<br />

the use of heavier and broader brushstrokes and unusual wipes and smears that<br />

suggest movement, so that object and style not only share a traditional ‘shorthand’<br />

of technique, but an intervening mystery to identity of objects, spatial relations and<br />

situations. Thus, in Study After Velasquez’s Pope Innocent X (1953) (Figure 37) Bacon<br />

adopts a renowned composition only to confuse it in abrupt reworking, the upper<br />

half of the picture appears to dissolve the Pope in a mysterious pattern of vertical<br />

strokes, neither quite a transparent curtain surrounding him, nor simply behind him,<br />

while the foreground’s perfunctory purple strokes upon unprimed canvas engulf the<br />

base of the chair and surrounding railings, as possibly part drapery, part<br />

floorboards 216 .<br />

Rivers’ Washington Crossing the Delaware (Figure 38) by contrast is relatively<br />

straightforward, also adopting a familiar theme against which to display a scattered<br />

irresolution or ‘interruption’. Rivers’ ‘interruption’ does not rest with just line,<br />

brushstroke, tonality or texture however, and if anything is too all-encompassing or<br />

diffuse to successfully impose a sample of interruption; perhaps looks a little too<br />

much like an unfinished painting, rather than a painting about being unfinished.<br />

Where it is successful is in the scattering of various points of interest developed up<br />

to a stage and then petering out to primed canvas, awaiting developments<br />

elsewhere. The structure is pursued more successfully in later works such as The<br />

Studio (1956), and in other works adopts ‘layout’ and notation, and is later drawn to<br />

more forthright sculptural extension rather than ‘traction’. 217<br />

216 Another interpretation of these vertical strokes might be as reference to certain common film<br />

projector malfunctions, whereby the image fails to register in the projector gate correctly, often<br />

due to torn sprockets, resulting in a shower of vertical streaks to the projected image, usually<br />

preceding a rupture of the print, and thus expressing its own crisis for depiction. Bacon’s most<br />

celebrated cinematic reference however remains the close-up of the screaming nurse with skewed<br />

pince-nez from The Battleship Potemkin, an image that is used in a number of works from the<br />

late forties and early fifties, including some of the series of The Pope, such as Pope II (1951) and<br />

the example above. For standard interpretation of Bacon see David Sylvester, Looking Back at<br />

Francis Bacon, London, 2000, John Russell, Francis Bacon, (revised ed.) London, 1993.<br />

217 On Rivers, see Helen A. Harrison, Larry Rivers, New York, 1984, Sam Hunter, Rivers New<br />

York, 1971.


148<br />

The use of blank ground or underdeveloped areas of the painting against which<br />

disparate objects and techniques hover, is also prominent in Hamilton’s Hommage à<br />

Chrysler Corp (1957) (Figure 39). Here they function, not so much to scatter attention<br />

to interrupted developments, as to herd them into the lower left corner. The<br />

‘interruption’ cuts across contemporary car body parts, a kind of biomorphic<br />

abstraction, a collaged metallic shape and more familiar facture. 218 The car shares in<br />

a vaguely sensuous set of curves. The central headlight, cowling, bumper and grill<br />

urge a perspective while surrounding elements such as the teardrop-shaped tail light<br />

to the left argue for a more orthogonal arrangement. The upper area to the picture,<br />

with its lateral black bar and small plus sign beneath, contrasts with the curves and<br />

declare a notational design and ‘layout’. Subsequent works by Hamilton often<br />

include more of a ‘layout’ in which objects share metaphorical rather than literal<br />

spatial relations, as in the series titled $he (1958-61). 219<br />

Blake’s On the Balcony (1956-57) (Figure 40) adopts a familiar ‘Rerealist’ structure of<br />

pictures within pictures, but crucially varies style between them and reverses the<br />

expected order of realism, so that the four largest figures surrounded by their<br />

collection of pictures and mementos are rendered in a faux-naïf style, that may serve<br />

as a metaphor for the devout fan’s unformed and vulnerable personality, or the<br />

unrealness of a personality embracing quite this range of paraphernalia 220 .<br />

‘Interruption’ here is not simply a collection or collage of brand allegiances but a<br />

corresponding emptying-out or stripping down of the bigger picture in which to<br />

contain them. The hands of the girl in the red dress for example are barely indicated<br />

218 The technique here owes as much to the orthodoxy of The Slade School of Art of the day,<br />

where Hamilton was briefly a student, as to contemporary abstraction, such as the work of Sam<br />

Francis and Paul Jenkins, noted in Richard Morphet, ‘Girl and Machine’ in Richard Hamilton,<br />

(catalogue) London, 1970, p. 33.<br />

219 On Hamilton, see Morphet, Richard Hamilton (catalogue) London, 1970, Morphet, Richard<br />

Hamilton: The Longer View, (catalogue) London, 1992, and A. Seymour and D. Sylvester,<br />

Richard Hamilton, (catalogue) London, 1992.<br />

2<br />

This is not to deny that Blake’s painting also derives from Honoré Sharrer’s Workers and<br />

Pictures, (1943/4) as discussed in Robert Melville, ‘The Durable Expendables of Peter Blake’ in<br />

Peter Blake, (catalogue) Michael Compton (ed.) London, 1983, pp.36-37. But the use of pictures<br />

within pictures receives different treatment here, points more especially to certain stylistic issues<br />

absent from Sharrer. The work of de Chirico, Magritte, Dali and similar establish these, are the<br />

salient influence. Sharrer’s work however is notable for the bare, uneven quality of the borders<br />

and suggests perhaps a modest ‘interruption’. The work is reproduced in Robert Storr, Modern<br />

art despite modernism, New York, 2000. Compton’s catalogue together with Natalie Rudd, Peter<br />

Blake, London, 2003, provide standard interpretation of Blake.


149<br />

holding the long photograph of the royal family, while the other end of the<br />

photograph is merely occluded by the boy in blue jeans, whose face in turn is<br />

replaced by a copy of Life magazine. Above this, items amass as if on a green baize<br />

pin-board, as is often noted. The result is that more memorabilia is accommodated<br />

only as less of the picture is available to organise them. The collection in fact<br />

overwhelms the fans and their setting at points to become that of the painting. The<br />

picture ‘interrupts’ itself through grades of accommodation, never merely the brand<br />

on any scale or at any place, but neither always and only at home in the fans’<br />

display, or a whole picture plane. Subsequently, Blake dispenses with this intricate<br />

construction to concentrate on ‘interruption’ within the figure, remaking pin-up<br />

idols as tantalisingly half achieved and blank, as equally naïve and knowing as their<br />

fans. Such works also incorporate elaborate titles, framing and even additional<br />

figurines and occasionally autographs, stressing ‘layout’ rather than ‘interruption’.<br />

This completes the survey of features to ‘Reciprocal Depiction’. The first involves a<br />

‘layout’ stressing metaphorical relations between various depiction and notation.<br />

The second concerns ‘traction’ gained between unusual materials and basic picture<br />

planes, while the third emphasises ‘interruption’ and a mutual remaking of depiction<br />

and painting. All reject the certainties and strictures of Early Modernism; spread<br />

pictures in a pattern or pattern between pictures, reform materials only to ‘traction’<br />

for a robust picture plane or at a given ‘interruption’. Yet the disaffection of spirit<br />

and the dissolution of means are maintained only with a widening of scope for<br />

depiction and painting. Around 1961 this results in a more radical departure, called<br />

Pop Art. In the following chapter the change is traced from a reciprocal sample<br />

between depiction and painting, to one between painting and printing.


150<br />

Post-Modernism and Pop Art<br />

Painting Printing 1960-70<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ is understood as the mutual sampling of the abstract and the<br />

concrete and as a rival style to full abstraction in Late Modernism. But as<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ is pursued, the sample undergoes a crucial change. Where<br />

work adopts certain themes or objects as a measure of ‘traction’ in materials, or<br />

‘interruption’ of completeness, what is reciprocated is not so much the abstract<br />

against the concrete, but painting against printing. This change is usually identified<br />

with the movement Pop Art and is here part of a more sweeping change, to a<br />

period of Post-Modernism. In the case of key figures such as Americans Roy<br />

Lichtenstein (1923-1997) and Andy Warhol (1928-87) this change is relatively easy<br />

to trace and familiar to accounts of Pop Art. Lichtenstein initially proceeds under<br />

the influence of de Kooning and perhaps Rivers, and deals in ‘interruption’ or<br />

incompleteness, set against stock themes or objects. Yet Lichtenstein raises the<br />

stakes by combining a spontaneous and gestural approach with the comic strip<br />

characters of Mickey Mouse and Donald Duck. De Kooning had dealt with an<br />

archetypal woman; Rivers with a famous historical episode and studio tableaux,<br />

both had shown how ‘interruption’ can bring new insight to painting and a new<br />

equivocation to clichés, be at once abstract and concrete: a ‘Reciprocal Depiction’.<br />

Yet what would happen if the object were as humble or as trivial as a comic strip<br />

character? Would ‘interruption’ be mocked, or Mickey Mouse accorded new<br />

dignity?<br />

By turning to print for a more familiar theme or a bigger cliché, painting is tested<br />

somewhat differently. The gap perhaps ultimately proved too great, or technically,<br />

the exercise eluded Lichtenstein, in any case the artist soon became dissatisfied with<br />

the unlikely confrontation and out of idle curiosity decided to paint a ‘straight’


151<br />

version of a single comic strip frame. The result revealed an unsuspected expressive<br />

dimension to painting devoid of ‘interruption’, of its doubts, mistakes and<br />

confusion. Quite the opposite attitudes were now suggested. In fact, set against a<br />

comic strip character, such as Popeye (1961) (Figure 41) the ‘straight’ treatment<br />

assumes a kind of deadpan reserve, with a distinctly passive/aggressive undertone,<br />

akin to the Flaneur’s insolence, or the hipster’s cool. Nor was the comic strip frame<br />

merely transcribed in the exercise, or a completely ‘straight’ version in any case.<br />

Rather, its isolation as a single frame and dramatic enlargement magnified the<br />

comic’s narrative ‘layout’ into absurd and amusing oversimplifications. It abstracted<br />

the comic strip up to a point, highlighted ‘formal’ values, but cheapened or<br />

trivialised these into the bargain.<br />

Warhol on the other hand was initially drawn to the work of Johns, and to his use<br />

of conspicuously modified material matched to template-like objects. But Warhol<br />

chose standard line illustrations to similarly confine or channel ‘traction’ in material<br />

and technique. His insight lay in realising the picture plane need not be restricted to<br />

the orthogonal or to ‘two-dimensional objects’ in order to function as such a<br />

template. A suitably simple and familiar style of depiction would suffice. He too<br />

thus adopts comic strip characters such as Superman and Popeye, while applying<br />

not so much a distinctive paste, but a much-diluted pigment, encouraging<br />

transparency to colour and tone and frequent drips and dribbles. But he too was<br />

soon dissatisfied with the results and experimented with a ‘straight’ version,<br />

concentrating on framing of the illustration and with standard consistency of paint.<br />

In fact we can compare two versions of Storm Window (1960 Figure 42a on the left,<br />

and 1961 Figure 42b on the right) to see how a simple line illustration for a window<br />

fitting is transformed through framing and the elimination of surrounding text, and<br />

a little of how it too acquires a more unsettling attitude through the absence of<br />

‘painterly’ display.<br />

Both artists thus arrive at virtually the same style at the same time, but from slightly<br />

different directions. 221 What emerges is a version of ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ in which<br />

221 The account of Lichtenstein’s development is based on John Coplans, ‘An Interview with Roy<br />

Lichtenstein’, Artforum 2. No 4 October 1963, reprinted in Roy Lichtenstein, New York, John<br />

Coplans (ed.) 1972, pp. 51-52. The account of Warhol’s change is based on Andy Warhol and<br />

Pat Hackett, Popism: The Warhol ‘60s, New York, 1980, and essays by Kynaston McShine,


152<br />

painting now starkly defines itself in relation to depictive styles of printing. Painting<br />

cannot of course strictly sample printing as for example a collage might, but rather,<br />

where confined to only those stylistic features often and easily associated with<br />

printing, highlights crucial differences between painting and printing. Printing grants<br />

painting this new and critical role, painting’s means, such as ‘layout’, ‘traction’ and<br />

‘interruption’ now determine which properties of printing may be sampled and how.<br />

The sample reciprocally sorts styles for painting and printing. Painting does not, to<br />

be sure, immediately look to etchings or woodcuts or to the forms of printing<br />

traditionally pursued in art, quite the contrary. It looks to the commonest and<br />

cheapest forms of line and tone illustration. The objective is not so much the<br />

popular, the revered or preferred, but the pedestrian and mundane, against which to<br />

measure overlooked or unexpected properties of printing through painting and vice<br />

versa. 222<br />

So painting gains a new deadpan reserve in this sampling while the re-framing and<br />

selection of formal elements give even printing’s most prosaic illustrations a new<br />

dignity and rigour. The printing style ‘reciprocally’ points to unexpected and potent<br />

properties for painting. This arises because even if painting were to do no more<br />

than merely enlarge a print, (which it cannot do, without begging the question of its<br />

context or framing) the enlargement does not preserve all the properties of the<br />

print, such as the resolution of the inking or the texture, colour or ageing of the<br />

paper and inks, much less possible accidents such as staining, creasing and other<br />

distress to a given instance, although conceivably it might. In fact it isolates just the<br />

lines and colours, even the Benday dots (a kind of half-tone screen), in the case of<br />

Lichtenstein’s work, as a seemingly disembodied design for a given printing process.<br />

The absence of these other properties then serves to point to the supporting canvas<br />

Benjamin Buchloh and Marco Livingstone in Andy Warhol: a Retrospective, Kynaston McShine<br />

(editor) New York/Boston, 1989. For Lichtenstein see also Diane Waldeman, Roy Lichtenstein,<br />

(catalogue) New York, 1993 and Currentartpics 89. While not denying that preceding<br />

commercial designs for wrapping paper using rubber stamps, such as Bow Pattern (1959) -<br />

reproduced in Andreas Brown, Andy Warhol: his Early Works 1947-59 (catalogue) New York,<br />

1971, p.72 - already set in place many of the features of his mature work, the account here offers<br />

a rationale for his adoption of the loosely brushed approach to single motifs, and the Johns-like<br />

short hatching strokes of pencil that often demarcate edges in works of this period.<br />

222 On Pop Art, see Marco Livingstone, Pop Art: A continuing history, London, 1990, John<br />

Russell and Suzi Gablik (eds.) Pop Art Redefined, London, 1969, Sylvia Harrison, Pop Art and<br />

the origins of post-modernism, Cambridge/ New York, 2001. For broader iconological treatment,<br />

see Sidra Stich, Made In U.S.A. The Americanisation in Modern Art, the 50s and 60s,<br />

Berkeley/London, 1987.


153<br />

in a special way, emphasising its weight, scale or size of weave in relation to the<br />

immaculate lines and single colours, just as the absence of brushwork to the lines<br />

and colours also sample a certain kind of self-effacement or reticence on the part of<br />

painting, a literal flatness to its three-dimensionality or material presence, an<br />

expressive or metaphoric wryness.<br />

Such work is often still greeted with a mixture of amusement and disappointment,<br />

since painting seems at once denuded or debased in the encounter, while modest<br />

printing sources are absurdly elevated or exalted. Similarly, the work is commonly<br />

misunderstood as impersonal, mechanical; even industrial. Warhol in particular is<br />

quick to encourage this sentiment through the use of silkscreens in works such as<br />

One Dollar Bills (1962) and Green Coca-Cola Bottles (1962) that press the definition for<br />

a work of sole instance - and painting - still harder. 223 It is a smaller move to then<br />

adopt photo-silkscreens, on which he settles 224 . Yet his work remains highly<br />

distinctive or personal, with his own approach to photography and silkscreen<br />

printing technique, and no more mechanical or industrial than in the traditional<br />

supervision of studio assistants. Much the same can be said for Lichtenstein, who is<br />

largely content to adopt and give increasing prominence to Benday tone patterns.<br />

The use of photography as a further sampling of printing by painting is taken up in<br />

the following chapter.<br />

Here the study concentrates on how basic linear or graphic styles for printing<br />

provide the core of Pop Art, for it is the power and elegance of this initial print<br />

sampling by painting that effectively displaces Late Modernism. 225 Following work<br />

pursues the print sample to more diffuse sources, or more diffusely samples the<br />

223 These silk-screened enlargements of common designs also lead to sculptures, such as the<br />

collections of Brillo Boxes, Kellogg’s Cornflake packets and Mott’s Apple Juice cartons of 1964<br />

in which packaging design is printed upon smooth wooden cubes or solids. The Brillo Boxes in<br />

particular are famously held to be ‘indiscernible’ from their referent by the philosopher and art<br />

critic Arthur Danto. See Danto, ‘The Artworld’ in The Journal of Philosophy LXI 1964, pp. 571-<br />

584, (reprinted in Philosophy Looks At The Arts, Joseph Margolis (editor) Philadelphia, 1987, pp.<br />

155-167). However, the absence of folds or a double thickness to the upper edges of each box<br />

indicating a lid to the top or sides, alert the careful observer, indeed the more discerning or<br />

supermarket-savvy critic, to crucial differences either from cardboard packaging or wooden<br />

crates used in wholesale marketing. The sculptures properly echo just those concerns found in<br />

preceding and accompanying painting by Warhol, rather than ‘indiscernible’ identity.<br />

224 Regrettably the scope of this study must forego consideration of Warhol’s additional activities<br />

as graphic designer, photographer, filmmaker, journalist and publisher.<br />

225 Print sampling here and henceforth is understood only as those features of printing available<br />

to sampling in painting, rather than a stricter view of sampling.


154<br />

print source. Either way, contributes to a dissipation of the coolness of attitude, of<br />

the disturbing meagreness of source and of the subversion of traditional painterly<br />

values. Eventually such variation exhausts Pop Art. This is now traced along three<br />

paths, firstly in work that samples less obvious or potent styles for printing,<br />

secondly in work that samples ‘layouts’ less exclusively related to printing and<br />

thirdly in work that samples printing strictly in matters of text.<br />

Along the first path we first encounter work such as that of Englishman, Patrick<br />

Caulfield (b.1936). He too initially adopts the black and white of basic graphics in<br />

works such as Engagement Ring (1963) (Figure 43). While the ring itself conforms to<br />

standard illustrative style, the background grid gives it a further, less obvious or<br />

necessary setting. Caulfield quickly focuses on the use of a black outline of uniform<br />

width (initially quite thin) in perspectival picture planes and a restricted range of flat<br />

or single colours, often rich in hue. Such outlines recall a range of printing styles,<br />

from advertising and amusements to basic instructional and scientific illustration,<br />

yet the choice of objects and allocation of colour is decidedly at odds with these<br />

styles. The result is consequently a more muted uneasiness as well as cool. In an<br />

example like View of the Rooftops (1965) (Figure 44) colour relations are played off<br />

against the linear simplification and perspective of the four chimneys. The chimneys<br />

acquire a stark, somewhat comic dignity in the emphasis upon their basic volumes<br />

and configuration, while colour relations are at once reduced to an exercise in<br />

colouring-in, even as mere colouring-in assumes some of the scope and rigour of<br />

Modernism’s pure or formal colour relations. A red sky for example unavoidably<br />

offers a sunset or sunrise, even as it urges a more abstract harmony. 226<br />

Similarly, the work of Italian Valerio Adami (b.1935) and New York-based John<br />

Wesley (b.1928) falls within the projection of Pop Art through flatness or evenness<br />

of colour, strictness of outline, even though print style is again more general or<br />

weaker in sample. Adami’s work of the period such as Gil omosessuali – Privacy (1966)<br />

(Figure 45) preserves single colours and black outlines, sometimes of a modulated<br />

width, recalling brush-formed line, but here enlarged to improbable scale. The work<br />

226 On Caulfield, see Christopher Finch, Patrick Caulfield,<br />

Harmondsworth/Middlesex/Baltimore/Maryland/Ringwood/Australia, 1971, Marco Livingstone,<br />

Patrick Caulfield, (catalogue) London, 1981.


155<br />

also fragments perspective and proportion, creating a kind of graphic designer’s<br />

version of Picasso or Klee. Printing here samples and is sampled by a demure<br />

version of Overstyle. The effect is surprisingly inoffensive, given that a central te<strong>net</strong><br />

of Modernism is reduced to a slick mannerism, perhaps because the ingenuity of the<br />

drawing still gives the painting and its immaculate surface, a certain impressive<br />

presence, lost in printing. Wesley uses objects often with comic and erotic themes<br />

isolated against a single colour ground at this time. Objects are also presented as<br />

symmetrical and repeating motifs that recall textiles, wallpaper or wrapping paper,<br />

but the style of line, its thin, even, spare and somewhat clumsy articulation, and<br />

choice of object resist closer identification with a printing style, and consequently<br />

the ‘flatness’ (literal and metaphorical) sampled is less compelling. 227<br />

The comic strip, as a sequence or storyboard is also sampled as a print style in<br />

painting. Experiments in the fifties such as the collages of San Francisco-based Jess<br />

Collins (b.1923) and the drawings of Swede Oyvind Fahlström (1929-76) variously<br />

draw upon comic strips and ‘layout’, but the project of print sampling for painting<br />

redirects attention to comic strips by the mid sixties 228 . Unlike Lichtenstein or<br />

Warhol, subsequent work uses familiar characters and settings more freely, as in the<br />

work of Paris-based Haitian Hervé Télémaque (b.1937) such as Pastorale (1964) and<br />

the strident satire of San Francisco-based Peter Saul (b.1934). Saul later adopts<br />

radical contortions of the figure and thinner, multi-coloured outlines that influence<br />

the work of the Chicago-based group, The Hairy Who (1966-1969). 229 Their work<br />

also features frames in ambiguous sequence and a merging with text or calligraphy,<br />

227 On Adami, see Hubert Damisch and Henry Martin, adami, Paris, 1974. On Wesley, see<br />

Alanna Heiss, John Wesley, New York, 2000.<br />

228 Fahlström’s work is more commonly associated with the sixties, because of his presence in<br />

New York at that time, however his earlier work produced in various parts of Europe, such as the<br />

enormous Opera (1952-53) and Feast on MAD (1957-59) have more recently been<br />

acknowledged. See Raphael Rubinstein ‘Fahlström Afresh’ Art in America, July 2001, pp. 61-69<br />

and p. 113.<br />

229 On Saul, see Jonathan Fineberg, Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being, (2 nd ed.) London, pp.<br />

270-272. Also note The Hairy Who (1966-68) comprised James Falconer (b.1943), Art Green<br />

(b.1941), Gladys Nilsson (b.1940), Jim Nutt (b.1938), Suellen Rocca (b.1943) and Karl Wirsum<br />

(b.1939). On The Hairy Who, see Franz Shultze, Fantastic Images: Chicago Art since 1945,<br />

Chicago 1972, Jonathan Fineberg, Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being, (2 nd ed.) New<br />

York/London, 2000, pp. 272-276, there, also detailing less strictly print sampled work of Chicago<br />

New Imagists.


156<br />

as does the work of Frenchman Bernard Rancillac (b.1931) at this time, while<br />

similarly preserving flat colours and uniform outlines. 230<br />

The drift from standard comic strips and printing styles also projects to other sorts<br />

of ‘layout’, and brings us to the second path for Pop Art. As noted, ‘layouts’ in Late<br />

Modernism often include problematic sequence or storyboard, as in Rauschenberg’s<br />

illustrations to Dante’s Inferno, or contrasting depictive styles and materials, as in his<br />

Rebus (1956). Post-Modernist or Pop ‘layouts’ tend to narrow the range of materials<br />

and styles, so that ‘layouts’ – as the name suggests – draw more heavily upon<br />

printing styles. This path is traced in both London and New York. In London it<br />

passes through the work of Hamilton and Blake, to a group of younger artists at<br />

The Royal College of Art between 1959 and 1962. 231 Derek Boshier (b.1937),<br />

Pauline Boty (1938-66), Patrick Caulfield (b.1936), David Hockney (b.1937), Allen<br />

Jones (b.1937), R.B. Kitaj (b.1932), and Peter Phillips (b.1939) all pursue ‘layout’<br />

that variously combines depiction with text or notation. Yet such ‘layouts’ typically<br />

avoid any single or obvious print source. Hamilton’s work does not look especially<br />

like an advertisement for example, devoid as it is of brand names or a single<br />

prominent product, and even where advertising elements are detected, their use<br />

points as much to shared stylistic features with ‘Overstyle’. Similarly, Blake’s<br />

Holbein-like precision of line and characteristic modelling do not derive from pinups<br />

or amusement arcade decoration, but rather are set off in a particular way by his<br />

choice of such objects. In fact works sample printing and fairground sources by<br />

more complex means and for more complex ends. The cool attitude here ignores<br />

any one style of printing or painting, urges only degrees and provides a porous<br />

periphery to Pop Art.<br />

The works of Hockney and Kitaj from this time are key examples. Hockney’s work<br />

initially would seem to stress ‘interruption’, with its accretion of graffiti-like texts<br />

230 On Rancillac, see Serge Fauchereau, Bernard Rancillac, Paris, 1991. On Telémaque, see<br />

Marco Livingstone et al., Herve Telémaque, Des Modes Et Travaux 1959-1999, Tanlay, 1999.<br />

Also see Livingstone, Pop Art: a continuing history, London 1990, pp. 55-59, 141-146, for links<br />

with various collage in the work of Martial Raysse (b.1936), the torn posters of Mimmo Rotella<br />

(b.1918) Raymond Hains (b.1926) and Jacques de la Villegle (b.1926). But while explicitly<br />

sampling prints, often including photographs, sampling is less by painting, than by literal sample<br />

of practices of public defacement.<br />

231 The exception to this group is Patrick Caulfield, a student in the following year of the course<br />

at the R.C.A. (1960-63) yet his work at this time conforms to the features of ‘layout’ discussed<br />

here.


157<br />

over stricter background designs and casual foreground figures, in works such as<br />

The Most Beautiful Boy In The World (1961) (Figure 46a) 232 . However, the familiar<br />

theme or object that channels de Kooning’s Woman I or Rivers’ Studio here takes on<br />

a more freewheeling quality, leaving the emphasis less on ‘interruption’ than on<br />

contrasting or conflicting styles, the cool rigidity of the Alka Seltzer box against the<br />

floppiness of the valentine and phallic protuberance in the face of the vague, rather<br />

coy male below. But the contrast between parts or pictures gradually diminishes, as<br />

‘layout’ gives way to a single picture plane in Hockney’s work. Flight into Italy – Swiss<br />

Landscape (1962) (Figure 47) and The Second Marriage (1963) show how such contrasts<br />

may tentatively share a picture plane. Unlike ‘Rerealism’, the objects not only argue<br />

over location and scale, light, colour and volume, but also about line, facture and<br />

technique. The contrast is still between objects and styles, but now styles are<br />

rendered fumbling and fickle. Indeed Hockney’s idle line and cursory handling<br />

acquire an appealing insouciance. Yet it proves difficult or tiresome to maintain<br />

such contrasts, and by the end of the decade Hockney’s work all but forsakes<br />

them. 233<br />

Kitaj’s work follows a more measured trajectory and around 1963 settles on a<br />

distinctive linear assembly of persons by parts, and into larger more dispersed<br />

groupings and settings through the use of single colours for shapes that surrender<br />

perspective to basic geometry and orthogonal projections. In The Ohio Gang (1964)<br />

(Figure 48) ‘layout’ juggles degrees of pictorial continuity, so that outlines maintain a<br />

standard realism in places, such as the nude woman to the centre of the painting,<br />

while around her, line slides into more problematic depiction, as in the gesture of<br />

the woman to her right, and the blue figure to her left, and compiles a figure<br />

through a contiguity rather than a continuity of parts, in the manner of ‘Overstyle’.<br />

Print styles, along with realism play their part without acquiring particular<br />

232 Scrutiny of certain reproductions of this work reveals significant changes or stages to it, or<br />

possibly confused versions. The former would seem more likely, on the basis of the artist’s<br />

methods. The work is reproduced in Marco Livingstone, Pop Art: A Continuing History, London,<br />

2000 and in Mark Glazebrook, David Hockney: Paintings, Prints and Drawings 1960-1970,<br />

(catalogue) London, 1970 as well in David Hockney and Nikos Stangos, Pictures by David<br />

Hockney, London, 1977. The latter two reveal more and starker text in the upper left portion of<br />

the picture, a ladder linking the two small figures above the valentine to the lower left of the<br />

picture, and firmer outline to the transparent skirt worn by the figure, amongst other changes.<br />

This version, reproduced here as Figure 46b, probably represents an earlier stage, documented,<br />

but subsequently reworked prior to exhibition and sale, rather than the artist’s revision since.<br />

These curious differences are hitherto unacknowledged in publication.<br />

233 On Hockney, see Marco Livingstone, David Hockney, London, 1983.


158<br />

prominence. 234 The passivity of the central figure to her captors is paralleled by the<br />

smaller nude in a pram to the lower right, yet her vulnerability here begins to seem<br />

more like a burden to her insubstantial nurse. Here too continuity gives way to<br />

‘layout’ and metaphor, for the scale of the figures and light area to the right also<br />

depart from the four larger figures and the darkened office setting. That the work is<br />

about sex and power is obvious enough, where the power actually lies, is less<br />

certain. ‘Layout’ here does not simply marshal the figures within a familiar<br />

Modernist geometry, for the geometry is also part of the settings, so that figures and<br />

costume in effect sample the geometry and grant it a distinctly seedy décor. But like<br />

Hockney, Kitaj gradually concedes ‘layout’ to a more sustained picture plane and by<br />

the late seventies his work too lapses into more familiar depiction. 235<br />

Turning to the path in New York, Pop Art radiates to the ‘layouts’ of Jim Dine<br />

(b.1935) Tom Wesselmann (b.1931) and James Rosenquist (b.1933). Dine’s sub-<br />

Johnsian attention to ‘traction’ and three-dimensionality are farthest from print<br />

sampling, and weakest in projection. Wesselmann’s collage of photography and<br />

extended materials is in many ways closer to the spirit of British work, and also<br />

resists closer sampling of printing by painting (as pigment). Rosenquist emerged<br />

with a striking commitment to ‘layout’, in his first solo show in 1962. However, his<br />

starting point, some years earlier, was not, as one might suppose, a Magritte-like<br />

interest in unsettling juxtapositions of objects, but rather abstraction, “a cross<br />

between Mark Tobey and Bradley Walker Tomlin” and a response to the work of<br />

Johns and Rauschenberg. 236 At some point he then realised that abstraction, and the<br />

materials of painting need not start from point, line, plane, volume and so forth, but<br />

from bigger bites, so to speak, from common styles of depiction in fact, and then<br />

build a bigger and more abstract ‘layout’ through sustained contrasts. Chapter<br />

234 An interesting and generally overlooked feature of Kitaj’s work at this time is the dry-brush<br />

scrubbing or rubbing of colour as in Juan de la Cruz (1967) for example, which strikingly recalls<br />

the mottled effects of aging and wear on cheap publications, particularly the covers of<br />

paperbacks. In this respect, it converts a common if overlooked print property to a stylistic one.<br />

235<br />

On Kitaj, see John Ashbery et al., Kitaj, Paintings, Drawings and Pastels,<br />

London/Washington/Dusseldorf, 1983 and Richard Morphett (ed.) R.B. Kitaj: A Retrospective,<br />

(catalogue) London/Los Angeles/ New York, 1994 and Currentartpics 61.<br />

236 Very few of the artist’s works from this period survive. This description is quoted in Judith<br />

Goldman, Rosenquist, Denver/New York, 1985, pp. 26-27. Also in this passage, the artist<br />

describes his development thus: “Everyone was searching to get down to absolute zero, to just<br />

colour and form in their abstract pictures. So I thought I wanted to get below zero, and the only<br />

way I knew to do that was to start using imagery again”. He also attests to the influence of Johns<br />

and Rauschenberg in this.


159<br />

Twelve has shown how this strategy also becomes available to the ‘Rerealist’ such as<br />

Magritte or Dali by the middle of the century, and it is not therefore surprising that<br />

initial critical response to Rosenquist’s work often dismisses it for its derivative<br />

Surrealism 237 . But Rosenquist’s version does not focus on conflicting objects within<br />

a single picture plane so much as a smooth progression to multiple pictures, and it is<br />

in their stark assembly within a painting, in their sampling of a certain style of<br />

billboard depiction that they qualify as Pop Art and Post-Modernism.<br />

While Rosenquist’s ‘layouts’ are usually based upon a photo-collage, photographic<br />

properties are less prominent than the style of billboard illustration of the era. Then<br />

again, the general absence of brand names and accompanying copy, and the general<br />

presence of radical fragmentation make them seem less like a billboard than a<br />

collage of only certain properties of billboard illustration, or a billboard illustration<br />

of only certain properties of collage. In other words, properties of billboard and<br />

collage are mutually sampled. Yet ‘collage’ here does not assemble disparate<br />

materials, since all parts are painted, all sources are printed, but rather aggressively<br />

frames or crops pictures within and beside other pictures. Works, while often very<br />

large, rarely rise to the scale of actual billboards at this time, and as noted, mostly<br />

ignore text, to concentrate on impressive enlargement of standard scale of object, its<br />

isolation against a background of little or no distance, and emphasis upon linear and<br />

textural properties. The sample is not only a kind of close-up of billboard<br />

illustration, but reciprocally, of some of painting’s materials and technique, and early<br />

works often include additional attachments of actual objects, somewhat after the<br />

manner of Rauschenberg, to underscore the attendant three-dimensionality to such<br />

an approach.<br />

But it is the smooth, broad-brushed, de-saturated modelling, the blending of<br />

colours and tones that more effectively declare crucial properties of painting here. It<br />

is not so much a ‘flatness’ to painting, as a smoothness even blandness to technique<br />

that is highlighted, and while its sheer economy has a softening, soothing quality, its<br />

pervasiveness also alerts us to qualities omitted or hidden. As when someone<br />

continually tries to reassure us, so that our suspicions cannot help but be aroused,<br />

the smoothness of the fragments lead us to inspect the ‘layout’ for some further<br />

237 See Goldman, Rosenquist, Denver/New York, 1985, p. 13.


160<br />

insight, and occasionally these are forthcoming, as in I WILL LOVE WITH MY<br />

FORD (1962) (Figure 49) yet such works also seem somewhat obvious and<br />

disappointing. Mostly our suspicions remain unallayed as works set a blandness of<br />

depiction against an edge - literal and figurative - of ‘layout’. This spawns any<br />

number of interesting contrasts between objects and pictures or edges and frames,<br />

ranging from matters of line, colour and scale to fashion, period and prestige.<br />

Typically, there are too many or none and the blandness is reinforced by a<br />

vagueness of ‘layout’. In this way Rosenquist’s work displays an unsettling<br />

detachment or passivity, and something of the cool of a Lichtenstein or Warhol.<br />

Similarly, he resists greater variety of facture in order to make such blandness itself<br />

an expressive quality. Yet unlike the elegance of their sampling of printed depiction,<br />

Rosenquist’s sample is more complex, even messy. For the reference is not simply<br />

to billboards, nor a standard practice of collage. Rather it straddles, and not always<br />

comfortably, the stylistic boundaries between object and edge or frame of picture.<br />

While Rosenquist sustains his practice more successfully than Hockney or Kitaj, he<br />

can neither expand the stylistic parameters as impressively to those of early<br />

Hockney, nor reduce them - equally effectively - to those of early Kitaj, without<br />

compromising the desired blandness, or similarly falling back into a single picture<br />

plane.<br />

These examples show more complex ways of arranging contrasting pictures, how<br />

differing ‘layouts’ bring out different qualities for styles, and generally dissipate the<br />

issue of print sampling for painting. There are of course more straightforward<br />

‘layouts’, such as grid-like arrangements, and exponents of these also range from the<br />

Englishman JoeTilson (b.1928) and Englishwoman Pauline Boty to Americans<br />

Rosalyn Drexler (b.1926) and Allan D’Arcangelo (b.1930) but such ‘layouts’ neither<br />

sample specific printing styles in this way nor are sampled by them. Nor do these<br />

varieties exhaust the diffusion of Pop Art, but hopefully this path is now clear and<br />

attention may be turned to the sampling of printing as ‘text-only’. Painting as ‘textonly’<br />

traditionally arises as calligraphy, and is abstracted in Modernism to qualities<br />

of line, and annexed in Late Modernism to ‘layouts’. It arises in the work of Johns,<br />

where the use of alphabet stencils deal firstly in letters, and later single words, such<br />

as Tennyson (1958). But while Johns remains more interested in a template for<br />

painting and stencils for this purpose, the use of standard and familiar typefaces and


161<br />

layouts as a more elaborate kind of stencil, is pursued with impressive dedication in<br />

the work of Los Angeles-based Edward Ruscha (b.1937).<br />

Of course typefaces and layouts alone do not deliver a print sample by painting, but<br />

only of sign-writing. Yet where a distinctive typeface is coupled with a distinctive<br />

word or text, as in Ruscha’s Annie (1962) (Figure 50) the sign then refers to the title<br />

of the comic strip Little Orphan Annie, in the manner of a logo, and so to a print<br />

source. Large Trademark with Eight Spotlights (1962) adopts the perspective and setting<br />

of the Twentieth Century Fox film studios logo, and although a filmic print<br />

incorporates text within a perspectival picture plane, something Ruscha explores in<br />

a variety of works, where text seldom refers to a common print source. While<br />

choice of word or text together with typeface and layout, allows painting to point to<br />

established printing, reciprocally, such choices also allow ‘text-only’ to point to<br />

certain properties of painting, although ‘text-only’ need not be print-based to do<br />

this. Strictly speaking, this is now ‘Reciprocal Denotation’, where unusual choices of<br />

text, typeface and layout highlight paint application and support, and contrast with<br />

standard sign writing as well as printing. In works such as Chemical (1966) (Figure<br />

51) the word’s stretched spacing and exact bisection of the canvas give its shape and<br />

surface a measured precision, perhaps echoing the scientific connotation of the<br />

word, just as the shaded green background accordingly takes on a certain synthetic<br />

hue. At the same time there is some uneasiness at this ‘cool’ annexation of graphics<br />

to painting’s formal properties, much as we find with Lichtenstein and Warhol.<br />

Ruscha later expands words to phrases, even whole sentences, and also adopts<br />

silkscreens, but in contrast to Johns’ templates, they supply only backgrounds to the<br />

blanked letters, in a variety of unusual pigments, including gunpowder, Pepto-<br />

Bismol, spinach, carrot and onion stalk extracts 238 .<br />

Ruscha also pursues the sampling of printing conventions beyond painting,<br />

pigments and even ‘text-only’, to book formats, such as his Twentysix Gasoline Stations<br />

(1963) where text is replaced by a collection of photographs, while later books<br />

introduce sequences to the photographs such as Every Building on Sunset Strip (1966)<br />

and even notional events and narrative as in The Royal Road Test (1967) and Crackers<br />

1969). Here books are sampled as the collection and conformity of photography,<br />

238 See Edward Ruscha, Guacamole Airlines and Other Drawings, New York, 1980.


162<br />

with and without sequence, by the omission of text. 239 Other artists such as Los<br />

Angeles-based John Baldessari (b.1931) pursued painting as ‘text-only’ in this<br />

period, but where ‘text-only’ is extended beyond a single simple sentence, generally<br />

sampling abandons painting. Los Angeles-based Lawrence Weiner (b.1940) for<br />

example exhibited a publication or print of instructions or descriptions of a work,<br />

while New York-based Joseph Kosuth (b.1945) used enlarged and ground-reversed<br />

photocopies of dictionary definitions in works such as The First Investigation, Titled<br />

(Art as Idea as Idea)(meaning) (1967). Significantly, the work adopts a similar square<br />

composition to Ruscha’s Chemical (1966) and samples, in other words, not all and<br />

only the layout of the dictionary, but also ‘text-only’ works as photocopy and<br />

picture. The work of the British group Art and Language Press, comprising of Terry<br />

Atkinson (b.1939) Michael Baldwin (b.1945) and Mel Ramsden (b.1944) pursued<br />

‘text-only’ work in a different direction, and published a journal titled Art-Language<br />

that used self-referential texts to sample certain formats of the Art world’s more<br />

academic publications. 240<br />

‘Text-only’ works are taken up again in Chapter Eighteen. Here it is enough to see<br />

how ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ and the period of Late Modernism give way to a new<br />

emphasis upon print sampling by painting and the period of Post-Modernism. It<br />

has shown how this leads firstly to a concern with styles of depiction closely<br />

associated with printing, with common line illustrations for example, and to the<br />

style called Pop Art. Further print sampling follows on the momentum or<br />

projection of this style, to the sampling of photography most notably, as well as to<br />

‘text only’ works. But this spread at a certain point stretches the label of Pop Art,<br />

deals in less common or familiar prints, more familiar or milder qualities of painting.<br />

A principal strength to the analysis in terms of print sampling lies in the ability to<br />

explain the potency of print sampling for painting, according to the view of painting<br />

adopted earlier, as the main means for a work of sole instance, in direct contrast<br />

with printing. Print sampling also serves to integrate Pop Art with later variations or<br />

239<br />

On Ruscha, see Elbrig de Groot, (catalogue) Edward Ruscha: Paintings,<br />

Rotterdam/London/Los Angeles, 1991, Siri Engberg and Clive Phillpot, Edward Ruscha Editions<br />

1959-1999, Minneapolis, 1999 and Currentartpics 67.<br />

240 On ‘text-only’ works under other descriptions, see Joseph Kosuth, ‘Art After Philosophy’,<br />

Studio International, October 1969, p.135, Charles Harrison, Essays on Art & Language, Oxford,<br />

1991, Michael Newman and Jon Bird (eds.) Rewriting Conceptual Art (Critical Views),<br />

Oxford/New York, 1999 and Alexander Alberro and Blake Stimson, Conceptual Art: A Critical<br />

Anthology, New York/Boston, 1999.


163<br />

styles, such as ‘text only’ works and to give the period greater coherence. The<br />

following chapter traces the sampling of photography by painting to the style<br />

(strictly, sub-style) of Photo-Realism, and shows how print sampling remains crucial<br />

to the period of Post-Modernism after Pop Art.


164<br />

Post-Modernism Continued<br />

Painting Photography 1962–1978<br />

As noted, the project of print sampling by painting looks to photography quite<br />

promptly. It again seeks firstly the commonest and meanest of uses and in this is<br />

consistent with the basic line illustrations adopted by Lichtenstein and Warhol.<br />

What is sampled is the kind of photography and objects firstly associated with wide<br />

publication. The initial interest is therefore with the extended printing process for<br />

photography used in mass or popular publications, and in particular the half-tone<br />

screens used to translate a photograph to a simple inking matrix. However, even in<br />

sampling this, a variety of objects and emphases arise and as the project gains<br />

momentum, other objects and aspects to photography are sampled, steadily diluting<br />

a simple Pop Art label.<br />

The point is not so much to endorse a preferred or pure practice for Pop Art, but<br />

rather to trace a sequence – indeed history – of print sampling by painting through<br />

selected aspects of photography. This leads no<strong>net</strong>heless to a dilution of obvious and<br />

sample-able aspects to photography and roughly parallels the dilution of print<br />

illustration styles traced in the preceding chapter and to the dissipation of Pop Art<br />

as a movement. But as shall be shown, it also leads here to a dilution of painting at a<br />

more fundamental level. This chapter is therefore less concerned with a<br />

demarcation between Pop Art and the following style of Photo-realism than with<br />

the persistence of print sampling by painting and of the varieties established. To<br />

resume this history we return to the pivotal work of Warhol.<br />

In 1962 Warhol made the switch from graphic silkscreens to photo-silkscreens in<br />

his work. Shortly after, Rauschenburg made the switch from photo-collage and<br />

photo-transfers to photo-silkscreens in his work 241 . Both artists not only make the<br />

printing process a prominent part of what is nominally painting, but also adopt<br />

241 See Andy Warhol and Pat Hackett, Popism: The Warhol ’60, New York, 1980, pp. 22-23.


165<br />

distinctive ‘layouts’ in which to accommodate multiple prints, and reciprocally,<br />

sample other aspects of painting. The respective ‘layouts’ however sample different<br />

kinds of photographs for different aspects. Initially Warhol’s choice of<br />

photographs, like his choice of illustrations, tend to point to standard and familiar<br />

formats or styles, yet unlike his illustrations, the photo-silkscreens concentrate on<br />

entertainment celebrities of the time, such as Elvis Presley, Marilyn Monroe,<br />

Elizabeth Taylor and Troy Donahue. In this respect Warhol’s work deals not just in<br />

the popular but the glamorous and topical. Against this glamour he employs a<br />

systematic coarsening or degradation of the depiction, firstly through the<br />

enlargement of the published photograph, that similarly to Lichtenstein, stresses the<br />

half-tone screen, its ‘dot gain’, and compressed tonal range, secondly through the<br />

uneven inking of the silkscreen, its match to the weave of canvas, and often to the<br />

broadly allotted areas of single colour upon which the screen is placed, and thirdly<br />

through the repetition of the silkscreen print upon the canvas, so that the depiction,<br />

usually only of a head or bust, is virtually reduced to a motif in the simplest of<br />

repeating patterns – again a common print style used in textiles, wallpaper,<br />

wrapping paper and so forth. 242<br />

Yet the identity of the stars is not just preserved but strengthened by these<br />

challenges, so that their depictions emerge somewhat as icons, acquiring a kind of<br />

shorthand resemblance through fewer but starker features. The stars thus extend<br />

their resemblance through re-printing to ‘layout’ patterns and painting, while<br />

conversely, painting extends its patterns to re-printing and the depiction of stars.<br />

Whether such works are properly paintings or merely monotypes remains a moot<br />

point, but crucially, ‘layout’ determines unique placement for screens within the work<br />

or as only part of the area of the painting, and the unorthodox inking of the screen,<br />

and its erratic placement and colouring, even in repetition or grid-form, argue for<br />

the materials and technique to be now taken as a work of sole instance, and<br />

properly, painting.<br />

Warhol is not content with just the stars of the day however, and soon broadens his<br />

selection to include photographs of the Mona Lisa, the mourning Jackie Kennedy,<br />

242 Information on printing process throughout this chapter and subsequently is drawn from<br />

Helmut Kipphan (ed.) Handbook of Printed Media, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 2001.


166<br />

the thirteen most wanted men from police files, spectacular car crashes, race riots,<br />

suicides and an electric chair, amongst others. The Mona Lisa trades upon familiarity<br />

obviously, and if anything its identity as a painting points more emphatically to the<br />

coarse monochrome re-printing adopted by Warhol, and the process by which it<br />

acquires a further iconic status, even as it surrenders much detail. Other selections<br />

however pursue quite the opposite pole and trade in the disturbing and violent. Yet<br />

the striking nature of these images is preserved, even as their photographic details<br />

are lost. Morbid curiosity also earns its icons. Warhol also begins to vary ‘layout’ or<br />

pattern in four ways, firstly through more irregular placements upon the canvas, as<br />

in Mona Lisa (1963) (Figure 52) including overlapping, secondly through combining<br />

different silkscreens of the same object upon the one canvas, this can also be seen<br />

in the lower row of Mona Lisa (1963) but is more prominent in 16 Jackies (1964) and<br />

Red Race Riot (1963) thirdly through the use of the same silkscreen with different<br />

inks, as in Elvis I and II ((1964) and fourthly through a reduction in the number of<br />

silkscreens to a canvas, where the blank canvas or coloured ground now frame the<br />

silkscreen printing, and emphasise ‘layout’ in relation to the whole of the painting,<br />

as in Orange Disaster (1963) (Figure 53).<br />

In accommodating the photo-silkscreen within painting in this way Warhol<br />

obviously forfeits other means to painting and depiction, although his later work<br />

pursues some of these with limited success. There is, for example, work which<br />

introduces bold and vigorous brushwork to grounds, somewhat after the manner of<br />

de Kooning, such as the Mao series (1972) yet the gulf between painted ground and<br />

silkscreen negates any more engaging role for the gestures – unlike de Kooning. The<br />

same holds for lines introduced which trace features over the surface of the<br />

photograph but which lack the stylistic reference or resonance of say, an Adami or<br />

Caulfield and of integration of line within the photograph. Exercises with standard<br />

symbols such as Skull (1976) and Hammer and Sickle (1977) curiously lack the<br />

extended settings against which earlier work forged its icons, while attempts at<br />

abstraction such as the Oxidation series (1978) the Rorschach series (1984) and the<br />

Camouflage series (1986) all pursue familiar designs or fields, mostly in a by now


167<br />

familiar strategy, but their massive enlargements do not so much embarrass painting<br />

with mundane sources as now embarrass sources with mundane painting. 243<br />

Rauschenberg’s photo-silkscreens embrace a broader range of photographs, and<br />

more complex ‘layouts’. While his choice of photographs overlaps with Warhol’s in<br />

the use of topical figures such as President Kennedy (while Warhol adopts The First<br />

Lady) sporting events, the Statue of Liberty, and reproductions of the old masters,<br />

Rauschenberg also includes photographs of technical diagrams, ornithological<br />

charts, the NASA space programme, military craft, close-ups of mosquitoes, heavy<br />

seas, a key ring, a glass of milk and his own photographs of the New York<br />

landscape. His ‘layouts’ share with Warhol the repeated silkscreen, overlaps, changes<br />

of colour of ink to the one screen within a painting, and a rough and ready inking<br />

technique, but also introduce colour separations and close registration for certain<br />

screens, segments and objects carefully and roughly painted around and over in the<br />

same and other colours. The contrast is between properties sampled. While both<br />

exploit a coarsened version of photo-silk-screening, for Warhol the process subtly<br />

transforms familiar and compelling sources, for Rauschenberg diverse sources<br />

subtly transform the process. Warhol’s samples are icons of glamour and gloom.<br />

Rauschenberg’s samples are the grades in between, are therefore less tethered to<br />

Pop Art, while no less committed to print sampling. Here, icons blend into indexes,<br />

sources with technique 244 . This gives his work an especially elusive, discursive<br />

quality.<br />

Consider the example of Estate (1963) (Figure 54). Here ‘layout’ finds firstly an<br />

obvious metaphor in the prominent street sign with its various directions and the<br />

buildings to its right. The buildings are not literally located by the sign from the<br />

corner of Nassau and Pine of course, but extend the metaphor of ‘layout’ to<br />

location and orientation. Equally, a second, sloping version of the high-rise building<br />

in turn builds the metaphor into one of multiple orientations while the abutting<br />

silkscreen of a building site and the colour version of the interior of the Sistine<br />

243 On Warhol, see Kynaston McShine (ed.) Andy Warhol: A Retrospective, New York/ Boston,<br />

1989.<br />

244 Talk of icons and indexes drifts into Peircean terminology a little here, but is another way of<br />

saying that competing samples trade object for material, or two-dimensionality for three.<br />

Incidentally, the application of Peirce’s Semiology to photography and cinema is profitably<br />

explored in Peter Wollen, Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, London, 1972.


168<br />

Chapel beneath, serves as a projection and heritage to the orientation, to the<br />

building of buildings, in a sense. At the same time the signpost is itself realigned<br />

through the painting over of its background and base, so that directions and<br />

orientation also stop at its stop sign, and give way to a flurry of red paint that links<br />

colour and sign while contrasting with the grey geometry and detail of the buildings.<br />

A second orientation is found in the dial face superimposed upon the Sistine Chapel<br />

interior. The Sistine Chapel of course, offers an especially loaded model for<br />

painting. Yet in aligning the dial face with the vault of the ceiling and the radiating<br />

perspective lines of the walls, the dial points both to the centrality of the model and<br />

its outward projection. The bright colours and painting that bracket its top, bottom<br />

and left side, announce three ‘directions’ painting may sample the print and pursue<br />

the model, while a third version of the high-rise building to its lower left, now on its<br />

side or at ‘three o’clock’ supplies a further re-orientation. In the lower left corner an<br />

almost full colour print of the Statue of Liberty featuring a blue sky and clouds, is<br />

placed beside a red print of a NASA rocket. The statue builds on a location, then a<br />

nation and space programme. Above these, a broadly brushed, tapering column of<br />

red and yellow complements the colours below and carries their sentiment into the<br />

broad and easy brushstrokes that link them to the birds to the left, also directed<br />

skyward, and back to the stop sign, for redirection. 245<br />

‘Layout’ then orders the silkscreens according to colour, density or detail, geometry<br />

and less formal properties of the object depicted, so that some or all are present at<br />

any one placement within the ‘layout’. Again, painting and ‘layout’ meet printing and<br />

depiction, and for Rauschenberg also the scheme entails certain omissions. For<br />

while painting may trace around and blot out certain objects and sections of a print<br />

– it does not draw upon the kind of stylistic resources available to, for example a<br />

Rosenquist, a Kitaj or a Hockney. For Rauschenberg painting remains tethered to<br />

the broad and bold gestures he inherits from de Kooning and Late Modernism. By<br />

the same token, his photo-silkscreens also observe certain surprising constraints,<br />

and no use of Modernist master reproductions is made for example, or indeed of<br />

245 On Estate, see Sidra Stich, Made in U.S.A: The Americanisation in Modern Art, the 50s and<br />

60s, Berkeley/London, 1987, p. 52, Marco Livingstone, Pop Art, A Continuing History, London,<br />

1990, p. 116. For standard interpretation of similar works, see Andrew Forge, Rauschenberg,<br />

New York, 1968, pp. 92-111. For resistance to iconography in interpretation of Rauschenberg,<br />

see Branden W. Joseph, Random Order: Robert Rauschenberg and the Neo-Avant-Garde,<br />

Cambridge/ Mass./London, 2004 and Robert S. Mathison, Robert Rauschenberg: Breaking<br />

Boundaries, New Haven/ London, 2004. See also Currentartpics 73.


169<br />

Modernist photography, although later works to some extent redress this through<br />

the incorporation of his own, abstracting photography, as in Exotic Trail (1988)<br />

(Figure 55).<br />

Yet the extended printing process for photography may be sampled without<br />

silkscreens, or ‘layout’ in painting. The work of Frenchman Alain Jacquet (b. 1939)<br />

used silkscreens without ‘layout’ to sample colour separation angles in half-tone<br />

screens, yet in substituting ‘layouts’ for traditional composition as in Dejeuner sur<br />

l’herbe (1964) (Figure 56) rather weakens the potency by dividing the composition<br />

into theme and modern setting variation, and the distinction between painting and<br />

print into the bargain. The work of Englishman Gerald Laing (b. 1936) on the other<br />

hand uses ‘layouts’ without silkscreens to sample half tone dots, by ‘hand painting’<br />

works such as Deceleration No 3 (1964-9) (Figure 57) but again the sample is<br />

weakened by the restricted role assigned to the dots, with its perfunctory motor too<br />

easily preserved by the too-small dots. German, Sigmar Polke (b. 1941) pursues a<br />

more promising line in works such as Tennis-player (1964) (Figure 58) where dots are<br />

hand-painted to a scale that makes a feature of screen faults merging with the<br />

artist’s own faltering diligence. The result transforms the depiction, much like a<br />

close-up of a Warhol, but here no icon emerges, rather, as in a Rauschenberg, the<br />

tennis player becomes an index to the anonymity of the dot printing/painting<br />

degeneration. The focus of Polke’s work however soon shifts from half-tone<br />

screens and photography to include other forms of print and is pursued in Chapter<br />

Sixteen 246 .<br />

Just as ‘layouts’ and silkscreens are not necessary to sample some aspects of the half<br />

-tone process in photographic printing, the half-tone process is not necessary to<br />

sample other aspects of photography. Yet this distinction perhaps marks a<br />

convenient demarcation for Pop Art. The work of German Gerhard Richter<br />

(b.1932) is notable for his sampling of blurring in photography, in works such as<br />

Administration Building (1964) (Figure 59). At first this would seem an attribute of<br />

camera process, as loss of focus, or a slow shutter speed’s registration of movement,<br />

as if the building were glimpsed from a speeding vantage point. Yet in subsequent<br />

246 On Polke, see Martin Hentschel, et al., Sigmar Polke, The Three Lies of Painting, (catalogue),<br />

Munich, 1997 and Currentartpics 99.


170<br />

paintings the blurring becomes more ambiguous, static objects such as Kitchen Chair<br />

(1965) (Figure 60) neither register the directional sweep of movement, nor a<br />

consistent depth of field for focus. Equally publication formats such as postcards -<br />

The Sphinx at Ghiza (1964) wildlife close-ups Tiger (1965) pornography Student (1967)<br />

and the obligatory old master reproduction, The Annunciation, After Titian (1973)<br />

grant the blurring a degraded or coarsening quality of printing, a kind of summary<br />

of lowered half-tone screen rulings, without going into ‘dot gain’. Moreover the<br />

blurring can in cases be aggressively painterly, so that the dragged brushstrokes are<br />

also recorded in the blurring, as in Tiger (1965). Blurred brushing is rarely taken<br />

further, into brushy blurring so to speak, perhaps because this technique lapses into<br />

something too akin to traditional facture. Yet this is tested, against the notably<br />

photographic formats of aerial views of mountains and cities in the late sixties, such<br />

as Cityscape Madrid (1968) (Figure 61).<br />

Richter also pursues blurring to abstraction in parallel works throughout most of his<br />

career, firstly overworking colours into masses of writhing brushstrokes in works<br />

such as Triptychon (Inpainting – Grey) (Richter No 326/1-3 1972) then to their<br />

exhaustion in fields of grey, such as Grey (Richter No 361/1 1974) secondly,<br />

through seemingly soft focus close-ups of brushstrokes, as in Abstract Painting<br />

(Richter No 418 1977) to their eclipse by the massively loaded deposits and<br />

removals of paint in the eighties and ni<strong>net</strong>ies, such as Courbet (Richter No 616)<br />

(1986) (Figure 62). What starts as blurring and photography thus ends as dragging,<br />

abstraction and painting. Equally and elegantly, what is sampled throughout all of<br />

these works is not just loss of focus, movement or printing degeneration in<br />

photography, nor their combinations, but reciprocally, the way they also constitute a<br />

version of painting. Accordingly, Courbet retains vestiges of depiction in the dragging<br />

of colours into one another. While a later work such as Skull (Richter No 548/1<br />

1983) (Figure 63) resists resolution as focus, tremor or print. Yet Richter also<br />

addresses abstraction as single colours and their relations in grids or charts, and so<br />

maintains a print format, although not photography. Pointedly, no blurring or<br />

mixing occurs here, but rather the random ordering of colours is spread across<br />

saturation and luminosity to a formidable range, inevitably rendered imperceptible<br />

by complementary contrasts, and accommodated only by diminishing size of<br />

sample, as in 4096 Colours (Richter No 359 1974) (Figure 64). Abstraction is thus


171<br />

rendered relative in grids as well as in blurring or dragging. The scope and power of<br />

Richter’s approach thus does not rest with only extended printing or camera<br />

processes to photography. It largely ignores ‘layout’ for parallel series of works and<br />

encompasses geometry and grids as well as gesture, striking techniques or ‘traction’.<br />

Yet Richter’s system and samples no<strong>net</strong>heless make sacrifices. While dragging can<br />

accommodate shifts in direction, tool and colour, blurring cannot accommodate line<br />

or drawing, nor the styles and ‘layout’ available there. In this respect Richter remains<br />

a hostage to the photograph, and the single depiction models of early Warhol and<br />

Lichtenstein. 247<br />

The work of American Chuck Close (b.1940) initially samples camera process more<br />

narrowly, and concentrates on focus and depth. His paintings do not deal with great<br />

depth, but rather just the depth of facial features, generally viewed from the front,<br />

and enlarged to an overwhelming scale, often 108 X 84 ins or 274 X 213 cm, and<br />

treated with a radically narrowed depth of field for focus. Yet, as with Lichtenstein’s<br />

magnifications, certain properties are also excluded in the process, such as texture<br />

of paper, grain size of film or colour separation incident. In Mark (1978-9) (Figure<br />

65) we can see how this gives a spectacular clarity even to individual skin pores or<br />

strands of hair, and an intensified depth to the softening of focus at the shoulders<br />

and back of the head. It is this exaggeration that enables Close to exemplify depth<br />

of field 248 . The effect is unsettling but curiously unreal, and after a short time the<br />

heads come to seem more like superior waxwork dummies, because the enormous<br />

detail and precision give them an unnatural stillness 249 . Our perception of faces and<br />

portraits resists the kind of scrutiny Close engineers, to be able to focus upon a<br />

single strand of hair or skin pore, the sharpness of the pupils, and yet take in the<br />

whole of the head, gives it an utterly frozen, even dead quality. Close is able to ‘put<br />

247 On Richter, see Roald Nasgaard and Terry Neff (eds.) Gerhard Richter: Paintings, Toronto<br />

Chicago and London, 1988, Robert Storr and Gerhard Richter, Gerhard Richter: Forty Years of<br />

Painting, New York, 2002 and Currentartpics 87.<br />

248 A fact Close concedes, but not quite for the real reasons. “My paintings always transcended<br />

the photograph, even from the beginning. The paintings looked more like the people than the<br />

photographs did. I always ended up putting more into the painting. Unconsciously I was trying<br />

not to. I was trying to be very flat-footed, and effect this translation and not editorialise and not<br />

crank anything up for greater effect. But unconsciously I couldn’t help but do it.” See Chuck<br />

Close: Recent Work, (catalogue) New York, 1986, reprinted in Jochen Poetter and Helmut<br />

Friedel, Chuck Close, Ostfildern-Ruit and New York, 1994, pp 65-66.<br />

249 As is customary in discussions of photo-based painting, a disclaimer is lodged against the<br />

special limitations of reproduction for such work, since many of the crucial features are<br />

necessarily lost by the return to a photograph.


172<br />

more into them’ than the photograph, but standards of realism make this into<br />

something other than ‘life’. And this is not a shortcoming in the paintings, but<br />

rather their insight. Again, as with Lichtenstein, the divorce of the picture from<br />

matters of paper texture and printing at this level of magnification, also create a<br />

certain interest in the supporting surface and painting. Close’s airbrushed and<br />

methodical glazings deal in the thinnest of paint surfaces. The scrupulous sampling<br />

of depth of field thus reciprocally serves to demonstrate a literal flatness for<br />

painting, a fastidious rigour to depiction. Later developments however tend to<br />

retreat both from this degree of focus and flatness, with the prominence of a grid<br />

and looser interpretation of its co-ordinated tones, in works such as Francesco II<br />

(1988) (Figure 66). The grid in fact now preserves liveliness, even as focus and<br />

realism recede. The sources remain photographs, but the sample is now of printing<br />

and colour separation, albeit granted a latitude not available to Close with depth of<br />

field.<br />

However the strategy of eliminating film grain, print dots and supporting surface<br />

from massive enlargement does not render the sample only of camera process.<br />

Close’s use of depth of focus, or indeed of print process, is allied to the portrait as a<br />

single head and shoulders or bust for example, and this are also part of what is<br />

sampled. 250 Yet the sample need not always rest upon such basic or traditional<br />

formats, nor always point to a flatness in painting. It may sample styles as common<br />

and overlooked as the travel brochure illustration, for example. In On Deck (1966)<br />

by Englishman Malcolm Morley (b.1931) (Figure 67) colour saturation, wide-angle<br />

distortion, and ‘art direction’ in furniture and costumes are picked out as salient<br />

features of the polished and published photograph. While in African Lady (1971) and<br />

Lizard’s Head (1971) (Figure 68) by American Joseph Raphael (b 1933) the<br />

categories of wildlife and ethnographic photography are sampled for long lens<br />

close-ups, absence of scale or setting, hard light and ambiguous colours and<br />

textures. Morley paints with a smoothness and flatness of handling that accents the<br />

stiffness of print deprived of actual process, and gives the cruise holiday an amusing<br />

formality. Raphael favours a more broken facture and even greater enlargement,<br />

where highlights are treated in bead-like strings, akin to the ‘circles of confusion’<br />

250 On Close, see Robert Storr, Chuck Close, New York, 1998, Jochen Poetter and Helmut<br />

Friedel, Chuck Close, (catalogue) Munich/ New York, 1994 and Currentartpics 35.


173<br />

that arise beyond photographic focus. But here they blend with a version of<br />

painting as an incremental accretion, and give even science’s specimens a slight<br />

mystique. 251<br />

Other samples do not exploit enlargement to the same extent, although dealing with<br />

more elaborate objects and scenes. They also ignore obvious print process,<br />

publication categories and lens character to concentrate on more testing samples.<br />

For, the line between painting and photography is not always clear-cut, and<br />

properties sampled cannot always be easily or usefully attributed to one or the<br />

other. For example, perspective and an extended depth of field are not exclusively<br />

photographic, scrutiny of the contemporary landscape and the particulars of<br />

everyday life are not the exclusive domain of painting. A sample may be too minor<br />

or banal to be worth sampling, or too vague or elusive to be effectively sampled.<br />

Work that flirts with and often succumbs to these dangers is often described as<br />

Photo-realism. Because photography may be smoothly integrated with painting and<br />

tradition in this way, the approach attracts many proponents at this time,<br />

particularly in the United States, where they include Charles Bell (b. 1935), Robert<br />

Cottingham (b. 1935), Richard Estes (b. 1936), Audrey Flack (b. 1931) and Ralph<br />

Goings (b. 1928). Because the work can so easily fail to sample enough of<br />

photography or with enough of painting, many critics dismiss the project as flawed<br />

or futile. The paintings are either too much like photographs or not enough. And<br />

the failings are undeniable. Where painting offers no more than routine technique,<br />

and photography’s composition is too close to traditional styles of painting, what is<br />

sampled is no more than massive diligence at the service of meagre ambition.<br />

Where photography offers complex and elusive properties of object and<br />

composition, and painting technique fails to display consistency, the result is overambition<br />

married to inadequacy. Yet as slippery as the samples may be, Photorealism<br />

cannot finally be avoided. Painting must have its depiction if it is to sample<br />

more of photography, and the sample, when effective, is all the more rewarding for<br />

this acuity. 252<br />

251 On Raphael and Morley as Photo-realists, see Gregory Battcock (ed.) Super Realism: a<br />

critical anthology, New York, 1975.<br />

252 On Photo-realism, see Gregory Battcock (ed) Super Realism: a critical anthology, New York,<br />

1975, Louis K. Meisel, Photo-realism, New York, 1989 and Edward Lucie-Smith, Artoday,<br />

London, 1995, pp. 204-227.


174<br />

As shown, where sample eliminates print process, the depiction is not simply left<br />

pristine, but subtly transformed. For to ‘copy’ the depiction and ignore these factors<br />

is nevertheless to inscribe it with a new instrument, and regardless of degree of<br />

enlargement, focus and depth of field, the picture introduces the subtlest of<br />

outlines. The sample starts here for painting and stops here for photography. In<br />

Dick’s Union General (1971) (Figure 69a) by Goings we can see how this linear quality<br />

is carefully accented and creates an attendant smoothness to surfaces, an evenness<br />

to gradings. It favours the curves, modelling and detail to the pick-up for example,<br />

in a way that leaves the stains to the forecourt lacking in a further texture or<br />

resolution. It favours the linearity of signage, even to a very small scale, such as the<br />

parking sign to the rear of the pick-up, where we can still read the word ‘limit’<br />

beneath the bumper, but which leaves the adjacent shrubbery looking more cursory<br />

for it (see Figure 69b). Inspection of such detail, even in reproduction, confirms<br />

how even the faithful copy must traduce the source, when excluding film grain and<br />

print surface.<br />

Yet Going’s linearity can then subtly excel in the planes of the architecture, the crisp<br />

shadows and the complex layers of reflectance and transparency of windows, and<br />

gives truck and building, shadow and depth an additional cohesion, less prominent<br />

in a photograph. The composition does not simply balance the diagonals of the<br />

shadow to the upper left with that of the roof to the right, the blue of the truck with<br />

the blue and tan discs affixed to the side of the roof, or rhyme the period, style and<br />

social status of the building with that of the pick-up, but aligns their lines, draws<br />

them into drawing, and casts a design across depth and shadow, colour and light. It<br />

carries the signage on the pick-up’s door, with its cartoon graphic and orange<br />

border to the curves of the pick-up’s body, as one design, then to the brown frames<br />

of the building windows and roof, as one design, and then to the blue and tan disks<br />

above and the lights and wheels of the pick-up below, as one design. And that<br />

design rests on the line where photograph meets printing and printing meets<br />

painting. 253<br />

253 On Goings, see Gregory Battcock (ed.) Super Realism: a critical anthology, New York, 1975,<br />

and Linda Chase and Ralph Goings, Ralph Goings, an Interview, New York, 1988.


175<br />

Yet to carry drawing into the photograph or to carry the photograph into drawing,<br />

builds a dilemma for Photo-realism. To go further into the photograph for line and<br />

drawing is to abandon painting and sample with the photograph rather than of it. To<br />

go further from the photograph in assimilating line is to confront ‘layout’ and the<br />

kind of issues engaged by Rauschenberg or Rosenquist. Photo-realism is finally<br />

stranded betwixt and between, and stalls by the late seventies. Photography on the<br />

other hand, attains new momentum with firstly renewed interest in wide-angle deep<br />

focus depiction and something of the all-embracing composition outlined, in for<br />

example the work of Germans Bernd and Hilla Becher (b.1931 and 1934)<br />

Americans Stephan Shore (b.1947) and Robert Adams (b.1937) and others.<br />

Secondly it pursues ‘layout ‘and sequence in the work of Frenchman, Christian<br />

Boltanski (b.1944) American Duane Michaels (b.1932), Englishman and German,<br />

Gilbert and George (b.1943, b.1942) and others. Thirdly it returns to studio-based<br />

tableau, and greater graphic or printing aspects, with the work of Americans Jan<br />

Groover (b.1942), Robert Mapplethorpe (1946-89) Cindy Sherman (b.1954), and<br />

others. Fourthly it leads to photography’s own sampling of further print properties<br />

in the ‘re-photographing’ strategies of Americans Richard Prince (b.1949), Sherrie<br />

Levine (b.1947) and others. Sadly space does not allow this study to pursue<br />

photography any further, although it is touched upon again in Chapter Eighteen 254 .<br />

Finally, while the late seventies largely exhaust Photo-realism and print sampling,<br />

this does not quite exhaust Post-Modernism. Although print sampling dominates<br />

more concrete depiction up until this point and signals most clearly the abrupt<br />

departure from earlier Late Modernism, there are rival styles that gradually arise,<br />

persist and gain ascendance by this time. The following chapter traces these other<br />

strands.<br />

254 On Richard Prince, see Currentartpics 80, on Cindy Sherman see Currentartpics 12.


176<br />

The End of Post-Modernism<br />

Neo-Expressionism, ‘Bad’ Painting and New<br />

Image Painting<br />

1962–1985<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ does not lead to just print sampling in Post-Modernism. It<br />

also leads to a more radical compression of ‘layout’, ‘traction’ and ‘interruption’ and<br />

to an emphasis upon allegory that samples (reciprocally) poor or ‘bad’ depiction.<br />

This style is known as Neo-Expressionism. Initially it offers a less decisive break<br />

with ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ of Late Modernism, struggles for recognition against<br />

the pervasive cool of print sampling but gains impetus as print sampling fades and<br />

later similarly dissipates in the mid eighties as it draws Post-Modernism to a close.<br />

There is the temptation to label this phase Late Post-Modernism since it flourishes<br />

as print sampling fades, but it is rejected since both styles also share a considerable<br />

overlap in practice and chronology. This chapter concentrates upon this competing<br />

and closing style to Post-Modernism, which starts in Germany, and so also signals a<br />

shift in place for the period and contrasts it with brief parallel styles in New York,<br />

in ‘Bad’ Painting and New Image Painting.<br />

It is useful to firstly note Neo-Expressionism’s relation to print sampling and for<br />

this we return to the work of Polke. In Chapter Fifteen his sampling of<br />

photographic printing in works such as The Tennis Player (1967) (Figure 58) was<br />

noted. But Polke’s range of print samples extends beyond photography, indeed<br />

beyond painting. For he also incorporates printed fabrics, usually as a support to<br />

painting or as a substitute for canvas and the fabrics offer either fully abstract<br />

patterns such as Bohnen (1965) (Figure 70), or patterns of pictures, such as<br />

Negerplastik (1968) (Figure 71). Elsewhere in his work the print may only be a tone<br />

screen of an architect’s basic line drawing as in Haüserfront (1967) or, foregoing tone<br />

screens, adopts mere tracings such as Tibersprung (1971) and spray stencils, as in<br />

Lucky Luke (1971-5). Then again, works may combine printed fabrics and tracings,


177<br />

as in Alice in Wonderland (1970) (Figure 72) featuring its loose white lined projectortracing<br />

of Tenniel’s noted etching, while later works sample older and more familiar<br />

sources, such as the etchings of Goya and the woodcuts of Dürer, and more<br />

complex combinations, such as a tone screen of an antique etching, as in Jeux<br />

d’enfants (1985) (Figure 73) as well as including more unusual materials as pigment<br />

and support.<br />

Polke’s print samples thus arrive at a ‘layout’ of pictures as well as a diffusion of<br />

sample, through tracing and stencils to less certain derivations. Indeed it is a feature<br />

of his work that it progressively includes rather than simply exchanges these<br />

variations. Yet as the samples back away from prints, so to speak, they also back<br />

into painting and Modernism. For the more remote the print sample, the more<br />

pressing the stylistic questions for painting become. The quality of the outline to the<br />

tracing or stencil immediately present options; the width and uniformity of the line<br />

– to take only two of its most obvious properties – determining the fidelity to or<br />

simplification of the source. Source and style of line in turn suggest further<br />

categories of painting, further conditions to the picture plane. For Polke, the source<br />

in some cases dwindles to no more than the decorative cliché of a pair of heron, as<br />

in the series of Reiherbild (1969) where the treatment swells to an exuberant set of<br />

outlines and fills, as in Reiherbild IV (1969) (Figure 74). Yet such works by necessity<br />

resist projection to fuller abstraction and ‘simultaneous and successive’ depiction;<br />

instead teeter on the cusp of Modernism, in a kind of parody or Neo-<br />

Expressionism 255 . Polke’s work incorporates this feature but is rarely dominated by<br />

it (even in Reiherbild IV, printed fabric features as the support). 256 However for<br />

other artists at this time Neo-Expressionism arises for quite the opposite reason,<br />

not because they back away from print sampling in painting, but because they back<br />

away from Late Modernism.<br />

For some artists and works, metaphors prompted by ‘layout’ in ‘Reciprocal<br />

Depiction’ are fused into a single picture, and properly amount to allegory.<br />

‘Interruption’, as a cross section and incompleteness of style, is there compressed<br />

255 However works such as Polke’s Sonnenuntergang mit Reihern (1969) certainly press for a<br />

fuller abstraction, but are perhaps less successful for it.<br />

256 On Polke, see Martin Hentschel, et al., Sigmar Polke, the Three Lies of Painting, (catalogue),<br />

Munich, 1997 and Currentartpics 99.


178<br />

into a single, awkward hybrid of styles and ‘traction’ in materials deals in just these<br />

constraints. The result is not quite as drastic in revision of attitude as print<br />

sampling, but distinctive no<strong>net</strong>heless. Work now exhibits a reckless disregard for<br />

technique, a seeming indifference to style and a conspicuous preference for allegory.<br />

Allegory obtains where what is depicted serves as a metaphor for typically, more<br />

abstract objects and/or non-spatial relations. For example a river or a door may<br />

stand for Life or Death, a ladder or stairs for Experience or Knowledge, a dove for<br />

The Soul, and apt personifications for various virtues or vices. Metaphor in<br />

depiction, or allegory, is to be distinguished from metaphor in materials, or material<br />

exemplification as expression, which of course may accompany allegory. Allegory<br />

channels the depiction of the literal in certain ways and alerts us to a transfer to a<br />

remote but receptive realm. Where the metaphorical realm is familiar, greater liberty<br />

is often extended to the literal, and vice versa.<br />

What is striking in much of Neo-Expressionism is the way allegory becomes just<br />

such a way of nailing down its literal objects in the face of lax or conflicting stylistic<br />

features and of using just this untidiness as a way of highlighting or sampling<br />

allegory and enabling bolder or novel realms for transfer. Hence Neo-<br />

Expressionism is rarely simply a stylistic revival. The pictures are generally too wild<br />

or inconsistent, too poor or ‘bad’ for that. 257 The effect more often is of a riotous or<br />

punk amalgam of styles. Nor is it comfortably accommodated as a hybrid, in the<br />

manner of ‘Interstyle’ works, discussed in Chapter Twelve. The work ‘backs away’<br />

from Late Modernism, seeking ever-murkier hybrids, but can go no further than the<br />

cusp of Modernism, without embracing a greater conservatism, and so teeters there,<br />

between styles. It counts as Post-Modernism because it cuts right across Modernism<br />

in this way.<br />

What is ‘bad’ in such work is strictly speaking, its ineffectiveness as sample. The bad<br />

sample may be only the cliché, that tells us nothing new, or the muddled or<br />

confused sample that does not tell us enough. No qualities or properties are clearly<br />

257 The name ‘Bad’ Painting was first given to a slightly different trend in American painting in<br />

an exhibition at the New Museum of Art in New York in 1978. It is often bracketed with Neo-<br />

Expressionism for its contemporary, provocative spirit. See New Museum of Art (Marcia<br />

Tucker) Bad Painting (catalogue) New York, 1978.


179<br />

exemplified over others in ‘bad’ work or usefully exemplified for our categories of<br />

style. It is a badness of sample as much as a sample of badness. Yet in Neo-<br />

Expressionism some badness is all to the good. The badness of the depiction here<br />

serves as a way of pointing to an allegoric function, while picking out the necessary<br />

and nugatory literalness of objects. The impression is often of the pictures dashed<br />

off ‘any old how’ preserving only a stark metaphoric scheme. And the effect is not<br />

always comic or derisory, as one might suppose, on the contrary, it often adds<br />

poignancy. For example, in the work of A. R. Penck, alias Rolf Winkler (b.1939)<br />

one of the earliest of the Neo-Expressionists, the allegory to Systembild (1963)<br />

(Figure 75) is easily grasped: ‘the system’ of deception practised upon the little<br />

worker with his barrow. But the work is rarely taken as an amusing travesty of<br />

Socialist Realism and Modernism, a farcical marriage of say, late Paul Klee and<br />

Agitprop, but rather as a more sincere version of both, the clumsiness of the stick<br />

figures reinforcing the brutal simplification of the allegorical ‘system’. 258<br />

Penck’s work does not always rely upon such obvious allegories, but rarely strays far<br />

or long from the stick figures and silhouettes of his Modernist heritage. The work<br />

of his colleague from this time, Jörg Immendorff (b.1945) however, ventures farther<br />

a field. Like Penck, Immendorff is drawn to socialist issues, even to Socialist<br />

Realism, although his mastery or commitment remains at arm’s length. But neither<br />

does he engage more fully in the standard Expressionism of say a Ernst-Ludwig<br />

Kirchner (1880-1938) or Georg Grosz (1893-1959) much less a CoBrA artist, so<br />

that the results are left closer to the average newspaper cartoon or protest poster,<br />

for example Selbstbildnis im Atelier (Self-portrait in Studio)(1974) or Kan man damit<br />

etwas verändern? (Can one change anything with these?) (1972), that is, as a typical<br />

print ‘layout’. Yet the perfunctory means of the political cartoon receive a different<br />

scrutiny when used thus in painting. The results generally appear weak or ‘bad’,<br />

given the extended resources of painting, yet this badness can be curiously effective<br />

where some allegory is concerned. Immendorff’s work culminates in a series of<br />

elaborate allegories titled Café Deutschland, commencing in 1977 with Café Deutschland<br />

I (Figure 76). Here the lumbering composition hardly adds to the gravity of the<br />

scene. Rather, it adds to the fun and serves to ridicule. Accordingly, the metaphor<br />

258 On Penck, see Lucius Grisebach, (ed.) A R Penck, Berlin/Munich, 1988, John Yau, A R Penck,<br />

New York, 1993.


180<br />

acquires a certain half-hearted and indulgent quality. Germany, as one big crazy<br />

nightclub, appropriately struggles as an allegory. 259<br />

The work of Anselm Kiefer (b.1945) by contrast deals in more obscure literary,<br />

historical, mythical and theological metaphors. But Kiefer too relies upon a ‘bad’ or<br />

messy version of depiction, derived not directly from ‘layout’ and Late Modernism,<br />

but via the ritualistic diagrams and drawings of Joseph Beuys (1921-86). Beuys is<br />

considered more fully in Chapter Eighteen. Kiefer’s pictures typically feature an<br />

unpopulated setting, either landscape or architecture, in perspective and offering a<br />

grand recession of plane. Captions, diagrams and objects are arranged in and against<br />

this, sometimes unlikely, obscure or fictive, or else familiar to traditional allegory. In<br />

any case, metaphor is prompted by the contrast between a literal location and a<br />

‘layout’ of text upon or within it. Kiefer’s style is also distinctive for its expanded<br />

materials and techniques, for ‘traction’ for the picture plane. 260 Here the ‘bad’<br />

sample extends to material exemplification and gives expression a troubling<br />

ambiguity; the work is at once expansive and adventurous, yet sloppy and dithering,<br />

offers shambolic grandeur as well as comic pretension 261 . The materials cannot<br />

really be brought into focus as a sample because their depiction and twodimensionality<br />

are equally evasive. This expressive diffusion is matched by the<br />

radical nature of many of the allegories.<br />

Initially his works locate lofty matters literally in a loft or attic, as in Quaternity (1973)<br />

(Figure 77) where a snake and three small fires form a neat diamond upon the<br />

hatch, a mystic relation often interpreted as the confrontation of sin or evil with the<br />

holy trinity (hence the clumsy portmanteau in the title) 262 . It would be merely obtuse<br />

to allow the snake and fires are there on a more quotidian basis. But since so much<br />

of the picture is devoted to the setting, the point is also, perhaps firstly, for the<br />

259 On Immendorff, see Carl Haelein et al., Jorg Immendorff: Bilder und Zeichnungen - Paintings<br />

and Drawings, Hanover, 2000, Jörg Immendorff, Immendorff’s Handbuch der Akademie für<br />

Adler, Cologne, 1989, Thomas Krens et al. (eds.) Refigured Painting: The German Image 1960-<br />

88, (catalogue) New York/ Munich, 1988 and Currentartpics 40.<br />

260 Predictably, Kiefer’s work also includes sculpture and installations, as well as books and<br />

photographs, initially included performance.<br />

261 For contrasting views on the tone of Kiefer’s work see Peter Schjeldahl, ‘Our Kiefer’ in Art in<br />

America, March 1988 pp. 116-126, Daniel Arasse, Anselm Kiefer London/ New York, 2001 and<br />

Currentartpics 26.<br />

262 Details to this interpretation, and those of following works by Kiefer, draw on the footnotes by<br />

Jürgen Harten in Rudi Fuchs et al., Anselm Kiefer (catalogue) Düsseldorf/ Paris, 1984.


181<br />

location of these mystic issues. The relentlessly linear treatment of the room, where<br />

the ‘bad’ or clumsy wood-grain all but confuses the perspective (particularly in the<br />

foreground) and competes with the quartet, finally stresses the bare and prosaic<br />

nature of attic and picture, their sturdy if modest virtues. Giving some clean, spare<br />

little space over to fundamental issues of metaphysics or faith becomes the issue, in<br />

more ways than one. Finding space for such issues, or perhaps issues for such<br />

space, possibly indicates a national trait, surely grants space and issues a striking<br />

extension, or transfer of domain.<br />

But in later pictures no event is staged, rather captions or text are arranged or<br />

plotted throughout a setting, and re-order the space, into a kind of threedimensional<br />

model or ‘layout’, such as Varus (1976)) (Figure 78) or Deutschland’s<br />

Geisteshelden (1973) (Germany’s Spiritual Heroes) the literal spaces are now a<br />

darkened forest, and a great wooden hallway, respectively. But texts not only turn<br />

such bland locations into mythic and historic metaphors, often the metaphor is<br />

mixed, as in Nero Paints (1974) or text no more than a pat phrase, such as Märkische<br />

Heide (March Heath) (1974) (Figure 79) possibly summoning certain ni<strong>net</strong>eenth<br />

century Prussian attitudes, otherwise merely imposed upon a rugged open field. The<br />

accumulative effect is that allegory and the transferred domain all but evaporate<br />

under such diffusion. Then again some later pictures assume a greater abstraction,<br />

such as Die Meistersinger (1982) (Figure 80) where text confronts vigorous materials<br />

over little more than a diagram of lighted tapers, so that the expressive and<br />

allegorical converge, and the text, never more than an indifferent handwriting,<br />

strikes metaphors for its own idle line and ‘layout’.<br />

Yet to doggedly track the various quotations, allusions and their permutations is<br />

perhaps to risk losing sight of the underlying strategy – of the picture anchored in<br />

allegory, even to its materials, and of text drawn into depictive and material<br />

metaphors. The increasing variation and complexity to the work may also be seen as<br />

a way of drawing out just this common thread. However for other and later<br />

German Neo-Expressionists, allegory is less conspicuous if not absent – in the<br />

Berlin and Hamburg groups for example, and the style accordingly looks closer to


182<br />

an ironic revival, a pastiche or parody. 263 While Kiefer’s work concentrates on<br />

settings and texts for his allegories, the work of a group of Italian Neo-<br />

Expressionists, emerging later in the seventies focus upon the figure and gesture,<br />

often in absence of a setting. 264 This group includes Francesco Clemente (b.1952)<br />

Enzo Cucchi (b.1950) Sandro Chia (b.1946) and Mimmo Paladino (b.1948).<br />

Clemente is perhaps the most prominent. His work is notable at this time for a<br />

versatility of media rather than expansion or invention, for the clumsy or ‘bad’<br />

drawing of the person, their emphasis upon a compelling sensory engagement,<br />

particularly for the body’s orifices and their frequent self-portraiture. Metaphor here<br />

is prompted by the absence or indifference of setting, as well as the irresolute<br />

drawing and often, schematic nature of poses and related objects in works such as<br />

He teaches emotions with feelings (1980) (Figure 81).<br />

Yet what is pointed to in this way is perhaps less metaphor than metonym. For<br />

while the pictures isolate and exaggerate the bodily and sensate of experience –<br />

especially the tactile – experience is not strictly remote or removed from the body,<br />

but usually regarded as a continuum to and traditionally a duality with it. So<br />

reference, while clearly not only to the literal, is more accurately by metonymy,<br />

where part stands for whole 265 . It allows the artist to remind us of the surprising and<br />

sensual as well as alarming aspects to physical engagement with other objects (and<br />

persons) how such experiences interact with our identity and ‘self’ portrayals. It<br />

grants the bizarre unions and transformations in Clemente’s pictures such as Selfportrait<br />

with bird (1980) (Figure 82) something like the function of hyperbole,<br />

stretching the literal but maintaining metonymy. 266<br />

Concentration upon the figure rather than the setting, and the use of ‘bad’ or Neo-<br />

Expressionist depiction are pursued differently in the work of the American David<br />

263 On the varieties of German Neo-Expressionism see Wolfgang Max Faust and Gerd de Vries,<br />

Hunger Nach Bilden: deutche malerei der gegenwart, Cologne, 1982.<br />

264 In the interests of space, this account omits less influential versions arising elsewhere at this<br />

time.<br />

265 Part to whole figures of speech are usually taken as synecdoche rather than metonymy –<br />

metonymy allowing for a wider range of parts or properties of an object (including adjuncts,<br />

causes and effects) but only from part to whole, while synecdoche takes a narrower view of parts<br />

but allows for reference either way, from whole to part (as in Australia beat England by twelve<br />

runs) as well as from part to whole (as in bat dominated ball in the Fifth Test).<br />

266 On Clemente, see Lisa Dennison (organiser) Clemente (catalogue), New York, 2000 and<br />

Currentartpics 44.


183<br />

Salle (b.1952). Salle’s work at this time is drawn to ‘layout’ rather than allegory and<br />

like Polke, to a loose derivation from photographs, a weak or ‘bad’ sampling of<br />

print styles. He similarly employs additional printed fabric in works such as His<br />

Brain (1984) (Figure 83), elements of text and even occasional items of furniture, as<br />

in King Kong (1983) (Figure 84) and other areas of pattern or abstraction as in The<br />

Burning Bush (1982) (Figure 85). Salle’s figures, in contrast with Clemente’s are<br />

generally female and their poses the sexually explicit clichés of pornography.<br />

Distinctive to his work is the way ‘layout’ and ‘bad’ depiction are combined to make<br />

such work ‘about’ pornography rather than merely pornographic. Nevertheless such<br />

work stands or falls on the value given pornography. Here sexual allure at its most<br />

narrowly anatomical is sampled and sorted by overlapping and superimposed<br />

pictures and the casual exercises in line and tone that slow or halt prompt<br />

recognition. The analogy, if not the allegory, is between ‘bad’ sexuality and ‘bad’<br />

depiction. The cheap thrill of pornography is here extended to the lax tracing and<br />

modelling derived from photography, the entrenched allure and recognition of the<br />

object permitting, even encouraging a waywardness of depiction.<br />

By the same token, surrounding and contrasting pictures and objects offer less or<br />

no such easy recognition, and rather underline the limits of such depiction and<br />

allure. In as much as depiction survives in these cases, as in the houseboat in His<br />

Brain or the sketch in white of (perhaps) looting soldiers in The Burning Bush, there<br />

are grounds for allegory, but often even this much is obscured in the emphatically<br />

dilatory depiction. ‘Layout’ here not only sorts porn with ‘bad’ depiction, but with<br />

patterned fabric, as in His Brain, and the furniture and text of King Kong. Neither<br />

patterns nor furniture gain much, in the way of an erotic charge from the<br />

association. But nor are the female figures reduced to little more than decorative<br />

motifs by it. Rather porn pulls depiction one way, pattern and furniture pull it<br />

another, and the result is both comic and desolate in its severe truncation.<br />

Significantly, Salle’s later work gradually discards its Neo-Expressionist traits,<br />

acquires a smoother more consistent style as his themes and objects soften or<br />

broaden. He retains a commitment to ‘layout’, monochromes and lax print sampling<br />

that is resolutely Post-Modernist, and remains more adventurous in his selection if


184<br />

not treatment of these, than similar approaches by Robert Longo (b.1953) Troy<br />

Brauntuch (b.1954) David Wojnarowicz (1954-92) and others. 267<br />

The work of Julian Schnabel (b.1952) concentrates upon novel materials and<br />

techniques, and their resistance or ‘traction’ for depiction that ranges from allegory<br />

to ‘layouts’ and abstraction. As with Kiefer, ‘bad’ depiction is carried through to<br />

‘bad’ materials, struggles to express a coherent metaphor and results in a deeply<br />

ambiguous tone. But where Kiefer at least retains an allegorical structure for various<br />

locations or settings, Schnabel uses figures, portraits, still lives and landscapes, as<br />

well as text and other notation to variously draw the surface into twodimensionality,<br />

occasionally to allegory, even as novel materials resist ‘good’ or a<br />

recognised depictive style.<br />

Schnabel’s best-known innovation in materials consists of shattered china plates,<br />

glued to the bare or painted support and usually painted over. The fragments are<br />

generally arranged in approximate order to their wholes, stressing their derivation<br />

and disintegration. While china rarely finds a serviceable metaphor in the objects<br />

depicted or the style of depiction, they nevertheless express a fragility and<br />

destructiveness to materials, indeed a certain wanton abandon to the process of resorting.<br />

It is a process that literally labours the picture painted across or between<br />

them. Then again, the picture is adjusted to rugged surface, radical pigment or<br />

application, vast expanse, weathering or other distress, to duly draw the surface into<br />

depiction, if only ‘badly’. But while china serves to stress fragility, even<br />

extravagance, it does so clumsily. Glass or Styrofoam might equally serve, or better,<br />

some combination. For the ‘china-ness’ side to the sample remains stubbornly<br />

obvious, and confuses or weakens the sample’s ‘fragility and extravagance’. Yet such<br />

dissipation is also to the point. ‘Bad’ materials here reciprocate ‘bad’ depiction.<br />

Schnabel’s flexibility in adjusting (or misadjusting) means to ends is demonstrated in<br />

the swift progression from works such as The Patients and the Doctors (1978) (Figure<br />

86) that balance the beds of shattered china against casual outlines of blade-like<br />

shapes, to the pictogram-like ‘layout’ of Portrait of God (1981) (Figure 87) wrought in<br />

267 On Salle, see Ja<strong>net</strong> Kardon, David Salle, (catalogue) Philadelphia, 1986, Lisa Phillips, David<br />

Salle, New York, 1987, Peter Schjeldahl, Salle (an interview with David Salle), New<br />

York/Toronto, 1987 and Currentartpics 97.


185<br />

bold gesture across an imposing scale, to the dense layers of imagery in Prehistory:<br />

Glory, Honour, Privilege, Poverty (1981) (Figure 88) entangled with actual deer antlers<br />

mounted upon pony skin, to the jagged and vaguely botanical forms of A.D.<br />

(Wreath for Tennessee Williams) (1983) (Figure 89) rendered upon a massive tarpaulin<br />

with oil paint and fibreglass. Indeed this flexibility often threatens to descend into<br />

‘anything goes’; where ‘badness’ is no longer held in check and the balancing act<br />

between materials and picture (much less allegory) simply collapses. The work is not<br />

necessarily more daring for embracing this dissolution either. Actually risk<br />

disappears as options proliferate, and more accurately, the work that dilates in this<br />

way also stalls in indifference. At this time Schnabel increasingly favours found<br />

surfaces, not so much the printed fabrics of Polke or Salle, as discarded theatre<br />

backdrops, animal hides and black velvet. Accordingly, depiction often takes on a<br />

superimposed, graffiti-like quality, something also stressed by the use of spray cans<br />

in works such as Resurrection: Albert Finney meets Malcolm Lowry (1984) (Figure 90) as<br />

well as the scrawled and partly deleted inscriptions. Indeed graffiti looms as an<br />

obvious progression for such projects although rather than embrace installation or<br />

site-specific works to this end, Schnabel subsequently devotes more of his career to<br />

writing and film directing. 268<br />

The graffiti option is pursued however in the early work of the Mülheimer Freitheit<br />

group in Cologne, and by American artists such as Jean-Michel Basquiat (1960-88)<br />

Keith Haring (1958-90) and Kenny Scharf (b.1958). 269 To the extent that such work<br />

survives, it essentially betrays the spirit of graffiti, and to the extent that various<br />

styles of graffiti are sampled upon standard supports for painting, the works betray<br />

the material of graffiti. And while such work is never quite true to graffiti, nor does<br />

it remain quite true to ‘bad’ depiction or Neo-Expressionism, since its stylistic<br />

identity is streamlined or narrowed in the process, and loses some of its unruly<br />

‘badness’ in adopting the recognisable means of graffiti. Such work finally exhausts<br />

Neo-Expressionism. The expanding means of Neo-Expressionism enable greater<br />

appreciation of certain peripheral work, such as the later work of Phillip Guston<br />

268 On Schnabel, see Nicholas Serota and Joanna Skipworth (eds.) Julian Schnabel, Paintings,<br />

1976-86 (catalogue) London, 1986, Stuart Morgan, ‘Julian Schnabel interviewed by Stuart<br />

Morgan’, Artscribe, No 44, December 1983, pp. 15-21 and Currentartpics 56.<br />

269 A record of the activities of the Mülheimer Freitheit group from this time is provided in an<br />

interview with several of its members in Cordelia Oliver, ‘The Second Bombing: The Mülheimer<br />

Freitheit Group’ Artscribe, No 44, December 1983, pp. 22-26.


186<br />

(1913-80) the racial satires of Robert Colescott (b.1925) and the nudist anecdotes of<br />

Eric Fischl (b.1948), but it also consolidates ‘badness’ as a category, and with that<br />

reduces its effectiveness and interest. 270 But rather than look to these fringe<br />

benefits, or parallel developments elsewhere, the study turns to developments in<br />

New York, signalled by the exhibitions ‘Bad’ Painting and New Image Painting.<br />

Both shows appeared in 1978, and detect shifts in painting as print sampling<br />

dissipates and more painterly means are adopted for less ‘printerly’ ends – much like<br />

discussion on sampling effectiveness toward the end of Chapter Fifteen. In the<br />

earlier of the two shows, ‘Bad’ Painting, organised by Marcia Tucker at her New<br />

Museum of Art, the work of James Albertson (b.1943), Joan Brown (1938-1990),<br />

Eduardo Carrillo (1938-1998), William Copley (Cply) (1919-1996) Charles<br />

Garabedian (b.1923) Robert Chambless Hendon (N.D.A) Joseph Hilton (N.D.A.)<br />

Neil Jenney (b.1945), Judith Linhares (b.1940) P. Walter Siler (N.D.A.), Earl Staley<br />

(b.1938) Shari Urquhart (b.1941) and William Wegman (b.1943) concentrates on<br />

how comic-like graphics, occasionally traditional motifs or pattern, yield to<br />

expressive and Expressionist handling, while themes or iconography similarly reflect<br />

a more remote derivation, a mixture of irreverence and idiosyncrasy, that as<br />

discussed, is in some ways unavoidable in seeking to further the project. This is the<br />

‘Bad’ to painting, but it carries much less emphasis upon allegory and text than<br />

German variants, much less interest in strict drawing or abstraction than New<br />

Image Painting. Indeed, the division between ‘Bad’ Painting and New Image<br />

Painting, between anecdote and stylisation, to some extent splits the impact of Neo-<br />

Expressionism on American painting. But while ‘Bad’ Painting unquestionably<br />

detects a change, it lacks the focus of New Image Painting, the vigour and breadth<br />

of Neo-Expressionism.<br />

New Image Painting was the title of an exhibition at the Whitney Museum in New<br />

York in December 1978 curated by Richard Marshall. It consisted of work by<br />

Nicholas Africano (b. 1948) Jennifer Bartlett (b. 1941) Australian Denise Green<br />

(b.1946) Michael Hurson (b.1941) Neil Jenney (b.1945) Lois Lane (b.1948) Robert<br />

Moscowitz (b. 1935) Susan Rothenberg (b. 1945) David True (b.1942) and Joe<br />

270 For standard interpretation of such work see Tony Godfrey, The New Image: Painting in the<br />

1980s, New York, 1986.


187<br />

Zucker (b.1941). It highlighted a course to painting distinct from print sampling or<br />

preceding styles of concrete depiction. 271 Like Neo-Expressionism, it gains<br />

momentum as print sampling falters. Central to most of the work is the model set<br />

by the early work of Johns, with its use of a design or template-like image within a<br />

vigorously worked ground. But where Early Johns largely resists the use of familiar<br />

depiction to function thus, and where early Warhol imports standard graphics to<br />

this end, the New Imagists forge new or unfamiliar icons. Typically they build an<br />

orthogonal picture plane restricted to a spare outline and ‘fill’ of colour and facture.<br />

The model set by Johns inflects a design such as the American flag or a stencil<br />

alphabet with an intermittent or approximate compliance, through an opposing<br />

rigour of technique and novel materials. The model is not concerned with the literal<br />

and allegorical in depiction but the parameters of recognition and identity. This is<br />

the first part of the contrast with Neo-Expressionism.<br />

In New Image Painting however, the objects depicted in basic silhouettes and/or<br />

isolated within a surrounding ground never quite carry the rigour of a template or<br />

design. Instead, the images declare their drawing as invention and undermine the<br />

function of the surrounding ‘fill’ or worked grounds. The tension between the two<br />

slackens once drawing becomes an issue. Often they amount to no more than a<br />

curious contrast of techniques, a strict outline against a broadly worked ‘fill’. In the<br />

case of early Jenney and Rothenberg, facture is especially reminiscent of Johns in<br />

works such as Rothenberg’s Butterfly (1976) (Figure 91) while the more subdued<br />

techniques of Africano, Green, Lane and Moscowitz nevertheless sample facture<br />

against outline, often with a single or flat colour. Of the group, only Zucker is<br />

drawn, like Johns, to novel materials, with cotton swabs and rhomplex augmenting<br />

acrylic paint in Merlyn’s Lab (1977). 272 Only True and Zucker extend drawing beyond<br />

the isolated icon, and all but surrender to something like minor cartoon and<br />

illustration styles, while only Bartlett and Hurson are drawn to ‘layout’ and multiple<br />

pictures within it. But neither Bartlett’s grids nor Hurson’s sequences can quite<br />

ground outline and ‘fill’ more firmly either. Bartlett’s Rhapsody (1975-6) and<br />

Hurson’s Palm Springs No 2 (1971) offer deft variations but ultimately outline and<br />

271 Marshall does not quite couch his selection in these terms of course, although gropes for<br />

something along these lines. See Marshall, New Image Painting, (catalogue) New York, 1978,<br />

pp. 7-13.<br />

272 On this score Bartlett’s ceramic tiles are an alternative rather than an addition to painting.


188<br />

‘fill’ here engage only the more obvious and less interesting stylistic features for<br />

their objects.<br />

The problem is that the terms themselves – outline and ‘fill’ – are too cosy and<br />

entrenched by Johns to now offer means of testing recognition and identity more<br />

fully, or without falling into greater abstraction. 273 In this respect New Image<br />

Painting is too ‘good’, or demure. It samples too conservatively. This is the second<br />

contrast with Neo-Expressionism. Where Neo-Expressionism embraces the ‘bad’<br />

and backs away from Modernism to teeter at its cusp, renew allegory and extended<br />

reference, New Image Painting clings to the territory between Late Modernism and<br />

print sampling, only to find the crucial testing of recognition and identity now<br />

eludes mere outline and ‘fill’. On one path we test allegory and reject Modernism,<br />

on the other we preserve Modernism, but test too little and literally. Both are<br />

necessary, if troubling experiences. Both flag an end to Post-Modernism.<br />

Before embarking upon the last period to the twentieth century it is appropriate to<br />

consolidate the distinction drawn here between Late and Post Modernism. So far<br />

this break has been based solely upon developments in more concrete depiction. It<br />

now needs to be shown how the distinction holds for abstraction, what changes the<br />

proposed periods bring to abstraction. Then, given abstraction’s intimate relation to<br />

three-dimensional work and the ‘expanded materials’ indicated in Chapter Eleven, it<br />

also needs to be shown how the break holds for works beyond painting and mere<br />

sculpture and what changes occur there. The following chapter duly traces the<br />

course of abstraction across Late and Post Modernism and Chapter Eighteen does<br />

the same for works of ‘expanded materials’. Here the task has been to show how<br />

Post-Modernism contains a rival style to print sampling and how it briefly succeeds<br />

Photo-realism before concluding, along with the period, in the mid-eighties. The<br />

period is thus seen to abandon more comprehensively the te<strong>net</strong>s of Modernism<br />

(Early and Late).<br />

273 The option of pressing for greater abstraction is explored in the work of Elizabeth Murray<br />

(b.1940) a colleague of some of the New Imagists. Her work retains an outline and ‘fill’ method,<br />

where outline adopts the radical undulations of a comic strip in its depiction of inanimate objects,<br />

and dispenses with grounds for elaborate shaped canvases. The result is a little like an unwilling<br />

mix of Peter Saul and Ellsworth Kelly.


189<br />

Abstraction<br />

In Late and Post-Modernism<br />

Late Modernism has been characterised by the emergence of ‘Reciprocal Depiction’,<br />

and ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ has been characterised by mutual sampling of the<br />

abstract with the concrete. But this accommodation of the abstract can hardly do<br />

justice to the project of abstraction as a whole. In fact the compromise prompts<br />

bolder projection to pattern for abstraction. In Late Modernism bolder pattern<br />

arises in stricter symmetry and is claimed mainly where work uses issues of colour<br />

and tone for materials and techniques on a greater scale, or beyond the ‘easel scale’<br />

painting. Later, where symmetry becomes foremost, or projects to novel materials,<br />

scale, shape and colour, rather than is projected from them, Late Modernism<br />

becomes Post-Modernism. Post-Modernist abstraction pursues symmetry to more<br />

elaborate and established patterns, but where such pattern then arrives at repeating<br />

pictures or even the single motif, style and period draw to a close.<br />

This chapter can only briefly trace this arc, but hopefully with sufficient detail and<br />

persuasion to strengthen the distinctions drawn between Late and Post-Modernism.<br />

It looks firstly at how scale is used so distinctively in the fifties, particularly by the<br />

Abstract Expressionists in New York. In Modernist works such as Kupka’s Disks of<br />

Newton (1911-12) (Figure 2) and Klee’s Table of Colour (in Grey Major) (1930) (Figure<br />

7) scale and facture have been shown to be intimately linked, the small scale of the<br />

work grants the size of the brushstroke and paint viscosity an intimacy and<br />

spontaneity, and they in turn convey to colour a certain precarious character. The<br />

size of such works is thus an integral part of what is sampled. Clearly the same<br />

materials or technique function differently in larger works, often stressing quite the<br />

opposite qualities, so that a large work by Kupka such as Amorphia: Fugue in Two<br />

Colours (1912) (211 X 210 cm.) (Figure 92) with its short, chiselled brushwork and


190<br />

thick paint, give the work a strangely cautious, fussy quality, somewhat at odds with<br />

its sweeping curves and bold colour, although perhaps apt as a metaphor for the<br />

contrapuntal structure of a fugue. Similarly, large works by Sonia Delaunay, such as<br />

Electric Prisms (1914) (250 X 250cm.) or Kandinsky, such as Composition VI (1913)<br />

(195 X 300cm.) use no more than standard brushstrokes and often the short parallel<br />

strokes that derive from Cubism and Cezanne, to urge a more traditional grandeur<br />

of scale.<br />

But with the work of the Abstract Expressionists, large works exploit a new range<br />

of materials and techniques. 274 The most obvious example is Pollock’s dripping of<br />

enamels, but equally radical is the use of large sign-writing brushes by de Kooning,<br />

in works such as Woman I (1950-52) (Figure 36) that extend the range of facture -<br />

together with massive wipes, smears, scrapings, and allow the work to maintain an<br />

intimacy and spontaneity even when this is no longer an entirely comfortable<br />

experience. Scale provides de Kooning with the space to display this range of<br />

activity and its ‘interrupted’ object. This new space for techniques or techniques for<br />

space, bring other, less obvious modulations of line, tone and colour (roughly,<br />

through scumbling or mottling) that are framed in the distinctive formats adopted<br />

by Rothko, Bar<strong>net</strong>t Newman (1905-70) and Ad Reinhardt (1913-67). 275 In their<br />

works qualities of colour or tone are inseparable from issues of scale and facture.<br />

This striking integration provides a certain mystique, even sublime but also<br />

expresses some of the equivocation found in ‘Reciprocal Depiction’. One mottled<br />

colour, or toned mottle, with exquisite subtlety gauges another, combines in a<br />

further, grander harmony. Yet this sampled integration needs an equally impressive<br />

means of sampling, a striking frame or isolation to set it off and this is provided by<br />

greater, more recognisable pattern. 276<br />

1<br />

The point here is that large scale alone is not the decisive factor in this shift, as is often assumed<br />

in accounts of the style. See for example Robert Motherwell’s summary in Max Kozloff, ‘An<br />

interview with Robert Motherwell’ Artforum 4. No.1 September 1965, p. 37, “The large format at<br />

one blow, destroyed the century-long tendency of the French to domesticize modern painting, to<br />

make it intimate.” This is also quoted in Irving Sandler, Abstract Expressionism: Triumph of<br />

American Painting, London/New York/Washington, 1970, p.156 and elsewhere.<br />

275 Given the dominance of American artists in this field and period, all artists henceforth<br />

introduced in this and following essays are taken as American and New York-based, unless<br />

otherwise indicated.<br />

276 On Abstract Expressionism, see Irving Sandler, Abstract Expressionism: Triumph of American<br />

Painting, London/New York/Washington, 1970, David Anfam, Abstract Expressionism, London,<br />

1990, Michael Auping, Abstract Expressionism: The Critical Developments, Buffalo, New York,<br />

1987 and concerning its broader social history, Serge Guilbaut, How New York Stole The Idea


191<br />

In works such as Newman’s Vir Heroicus Sublimis (1950-1) (Figure 93) or Rothko’s<br />

White, Yellow Red on Yellow (1953) (Figure 94) it is notable that colour identity and<br />

attendant distinctions are wrought within conspicuous symmetry. 277 In Newman’s<br />

work this is established by parallel vertical bands, which is to say, the symmetry here<br />

runs laterally, across the middle of the picture, while in the Rothko essentially the<br />

same kind of bands typically run laterally, allowing a vertical symmetry. Reinhardt’s<br />

work usually adheres to a one or both of these. In other words, the symmetry or<br />

pattern channels colour, facture and scale distinctions along axes, laterally in most<br />

of Newman’s work, vertically in Rothko’s. 278 This is not to disregard the actual<br />

height of the Newman, or the width of the Rothko, rather to underline the fixity<br />

conferred upon them by these formats. Such works thus establish compelling new<br />

qualities for colour, tone, scale and facture by edging pictures closer to obvious<br />

pattern. 279<br />

In Late Modernism the effectiveness of greater symmetry also enables work that<br />

stretches and relaxes it. Artists such as Helen Frankenthaler (b. 1928) and Morris<br />

Louis (1912-62) deal in a similar integration of colour, facture and scale but now<br />

adopt an extremely diluted acrylic paint and novel pourings or stainings onto an<br />

unstretched bare canvas to determine the shape and other features of a colour – the<br />

colour and other features of a shape. Yet without the rigour of a sampling<br />

symmetry, usually such techniques seem no more than prompted or projected by<br />

the shape and colour properties obtained. Elsewhere works concentrate upon a<br />

Modern Art, Chicago, 1983 and Francis Frascina (ed.) Pollock and After: The critical debate,<br />

London, 1985.<br />

277 It must be acknowledged that such small reproductions of such large works, inevitably loose<br />

the distinctive modulations under consideration. This is particularly true in Newman’s case.<br />

278 The importance of symmetry to this work, while often acknowledged as often fails to<br />

accurately locate the axes. See for example discussion of symmetry in Newman’s work in Yves-<br />

Alain Bois, Painting as Model Cambridge/Mass./London, 1993 pp. 187-213, and more briefly in<br />

Jonathan Fineberg, Art Since 1940 (2 nd edition), New York/London, 2000, pp. 100-102. The<br />

complementary formats of Rothko and Newman, if not quite the symmetry, are noted in<br />

Greenberg, ‘American-Type Painting’ in Art and Culture, Boston, 1961, p.225.<br />

279 In this regard the Suprematist works of Malevich, such as Black Square (1913 or 23) and<br />

Black Cross (1923) offer interesting comparison, since they employ biaxial symmetry, upon a<br />

square canvas, but separate colour or tone from shape – so that the strict masking of the outline,<br />

while pointedly rarely quite straight or uniform, strictly avoids the involvement of colour or<br />

facture. The results are ‘a picture’ of a square or cross, approximately in shape, and in which<br />

blackness and facture are then only incidental properties. Possibly, this stresses the further<br />

intangible nature of the true or ideal square or cross. At any rate, it distinguishes such work from<br />

Late Modernism both because it resists a greater integration of colour, facture and shape and<br />

because it remains committed to traditional scale for these issues.


192<br />

single colour or tone in order to exploit facture more fully, as in Rauschenberg’s<br />

successive white and black series. In some works by Ellsworth Kelly (b. 1923) at<br />

this time, such as White Plaque: Bridge Arch and Reflection (1951-55) colour is equated<br />

with shape, not so much through facture, which here amounts to little more than a<br />

smooth coat of white paint, as with the actual shape of the support, here wood,<br />

although this feature is generally called a shaped canvas. 280 Monochrome works<br />

obviously possess symmetry, although do not necessarily display it, as is the case of<br />

the Rauschenbergs. However Kelly’s shaped paintings and collages from this time<br />

are often notably symmetrical (even while, as with this example, also offering a<br />

more concrete depiction). Yet since the pattern is stressed through the frame shape,<br />

as much as its smooth and single colour, it balances pattern and shape against<br />

picture and painting, providing a more complex formula.<br />

More obvious pattern is pursued along two paths. One abandons the elaborate<br />

systems of a Kupka or Mondrian, even the loose grids of Klee, for simpler patterns<br />

easily discernible over and above their colour content (or vice versa). The contained<br />

variations on a square by Josef Albers (1888-1976) such as Hommage to the Square:<br />

Ascending (1953) (Figure 95) and the uniform stripes of various lengths by Swiss<br />

Richard Paul Lohse (1902-88) such as Rhythmic Progression (1952-59) (Figure 96) inch<br />

forward in this direction, although still provide a sliding scale of lengths in Lohse’s<br />

example and like variation of width to height of square in Albers’ example. Yet<br />

Albers’ work also establishes a clear vertical symmetry that crucially reinforces its<br />

pattern and although neither artist’s work acquires the scale of the Abstract<br />

Expressionists, their structures anticipate the work of later artists such as Ken<strong>net</strong>h<br />

Noland (b.1924) and Gene Davis (1920-85) where greater scale is unquestionably at<br />

issue. Noland initially adopts concentric circles of varying widths rather than<br />

squares; Davis adopts stripes of uniform length as well as width.<br />

The second and lesser path at this time engages pattern less in the interests of<br />

colour, than depth. The convergence of perspective (and ‘Rerealism’) with<br />

abstraction occurs in the work of Vierra da Silva (1908-) for example Library (1949)<br />

(Figure 97-x) and Matta, for example, The Onyx of Electra (1944) and is taken further<br />

280 Monochrome abstraction continues to attract proponents following those mentioned, variously<br />

establishing equations between colour, shape and facture. Of note are the French artist, Yves<br />

Klein (1928-62) and Robert Ryman (b.1930)


193<br />

into pattern in work such as Rolleboise (1955) (Figure 97) by the Dane Richard<br />

Mortensen (1910-93) Belle Isle (1947) (Figure 98) by the Rumanian Victor Vasarely<br />

(1908-97) and also, surprisingly, in the prints of Albers, such as the Structural<br />

Constellation series produced in the early fifties (Figure 99). 281 Such work exploits the<br />

angles of perspective and projections (in Vasarely’s case, without resorting to<br />

straight lines) to generate patterns that deal in the approximate symmetry of the<br />

Vasarely as well as the more complex reversals and inversions of the Albers. This<br />

approach asserts a complexity of pattern distinct from that of Kupka or Mondrian,<br />

and in contrast to the symmetry of stripes and squares. Both paths obviously place<br />

certain constraints upon technique and colour. As works acquire an impressive<br />

scale, simple pattern offers vital latitude in technique while complex pattern would<br />

seem initially to give or gain little. Colour relations in both kinds of work, duly<br />

marshalled into Newtonian complementaries and other harmonies, are nevertheless<br />

reductive. Once isolated within the strict shapes of pattern and single luminances<br />

and intensities of a given hue, colour is not so much demonstrated within a neutral<br />

format as conforms to and demonstrates the format. 282<br />

Essentially the shift is in what is sampled in the work. Initially symmetry or pattern<br />

is at the service of colour and tonal relations with facture and scale. Yet as colour,<br />

tone, facture and scale are marshalled more strictly, pattern or geometric format<br />

becomes foremost. At a certain point colour, tone, facture and scale are now at the<br />

service of more obvious pattern, in fact reinforce the identity of pattern through<br />

their variation, and now properly sample the projection of pattern to painting. This<br />

step occurs most forcefully in the work of Frank Stella (b.1936) at the end of the<br />

fifties, and initiates a Post-Modernist period for abstraction.<br />

Stella’s key works here are the ‘Black’ or ‘Pinstripe’ series, produced between 1958<br />

and 1960, in which the picture is divided into a number of stripes of fairly even<br />

width, and which initially remain parallel to the sides of the picture, as in Tomlinson<br />

Court Park (1959) (Figure 100). A crucial determinant of width of stripe (and hence<br />

281 This untitled example is taken from Joseph Albers and Francois Bucher, Despite Straight<br />

Lines, New Haven and London, 1961, but supplies no details of size or medium.<br />

282 John Gage arrives at a similar conclusion in considering the accuracy and identity of colour<br />

sampled in such work. See Gage, Colour and Culture, London, 1993, pp. 247-268. Colour<br />

‘harmonies’ have more recently been treated in terms of ‘equiluminance’ in neurobiological<br />

studies and the result of centre/surround distribution of colour receptors in the retina. See<br />

Margaret Livingstone, Vision and Art: The Biology of Seeing, New York, 2002.


194<br />

of number and relations) is to be found in the unpainted canvas intervals between<br />

stripes (the pinstripes), where the casual brushwork avoids a sharp or hard edge and<br />

‘scrubs’ or ‘feathers’ a more approximate edge. The intervals and brushing are broad<br />

enough to ensure that they are taken as more than some minor shortcoming in<br />

execution, and also broad enough in relation to the width of the stripe to call into<br />

question the precise shape of the stripe. One does not hesitate in taking the stripes<br />

to be more or less straight, and yet the unevenness is of a nagging tolerance. 283 Like<br />

Johns’ adherence to the design of the American flag or a stencilled alphabet, the<br />

unevenness in Stella’s stripes establishes a curious degree of tolerance or<br />

compliance, not so much relative to the familiarity of the design, as with Johns, but<br />

here more to the scale of the stripes and their relation to the frame. Stella’s work<br />

no<strong>net</strong>heless may be taken as a response to Johns, and to parallel the response of<br />

Warhol, although slightly preceding it. Abstraction here is of a piece with the shift<br />

to print sampling and Post-Modernism, and shares the provocatively cool attitude.<br />

Discussion of the links between pattern and print is deferred for the moment. The<br />

immediate task is to trace which patterns are used, and in what ways they are<br />

extended or projected in painting.<br />

Where Post-Modernist abstraction initially dwells on stripes, or reasserts grids and<br />

concentrates upon interval and scale, this fundamentalist tendency is called<br />

Minimalism. It is not however drawn to stricter or more minimal ordering, to mere<br />

points at uniform intervals, to a single line or indeed a single point. However, there<br />

is one suitably singular work that illustrates just this reduction of two-dimensionality<br />

at this time. The work is The Rose (1958-64) (Figure 101) by San Francisco-based Jay<br />

DeFeo (1929-89). It also straddles the issues of monochrome and tonal constraint,<br />

materials and techniques and painting versus sculpture, and surely deserves a place<br />

in the foundation of Minimalism. 284 Almost as pointed, in more ways than one, is<br />

the later work of the Italian Argentinean Lucio Fontana (1899-1968) where line<br />

occurs as an actual incision upon a primed canvas, in works such as Spatial Concept -<br />

283 On Stella, including a puzzling denial of any relations within the stripes in works, see Michael<br />

Fried, Three American Painters, Ken<strong>net</strong>h Noland, Jules Olitski and Frank Stella,<br />

Cambridge/Mass, 1965 William Rubin, Frank Stella, New York, 1970, Robert Rosenblum,<br />

Frank Stella, London, 1971.<br />

284 On De Feo, see Jay De Feo, Jay De Feo, Selected Works: 1952-89, (catalogue) Philadelphia,<br />

1996, Donald Goddard, ‘Selected Works by Jay De Feo’, www.newyorkartworld.com (2004)


195<br />

Attese (1958). 285 But Minimalist painting generally restricts the issue of materials and<br />

technique to a certain leeway in stripe rigour. For example it finds and makes stripes<br />

in the later (Post-Modernist) works of Louis, such as Alpha Pi (1960) (Figure 102)<br />

where width, angle and symmetry of the ‘unfurled’ stripes are gained through the<br />

radical expanse of unpainted canvas in the centre of the painting. Area and sheer<br />

size determines proportion and then identity of stripe and symmetry. 286 This<br />

accommodation of novel materials and technique is sometimes referred to as the<br />

‘Process’ branch of Minimalism, whereby the physical and chemical processes of the<br />

materials are prominent in the degree of geometric rigour, or pattern attained.<br />

Process nevertheless leads to three-dimensional works, by artists such as Richard<br />

Serra (b.1939) and Eva Hesse (1936-70. Allied to Process, is ‘Systems’ Minimalism,<br />

which stresses a series of consecutive or overlaid patterns or systems, whose<br />

combination generates further and surprising pattern, such as the drawings of Sol<br />

Le Witt (b.1928) or the paintings from the late sixties of the Los Angles-based Ed<br />

Moses (b.1926). Artists such as Robert Morris (b.1931) and Barry Le Va (b.1941)<br />

apply Systems to three-dimensional work. 287<br />

Apart from Minimalism, Post-Modernist abstraction exploits the more complex<br />

geometry noted in Late Modernism. What starts as plays with conflicting<br />

projections and perspectives of colour planes, develops firstly into conflicting<br />

functions of line, in works such as Vasarely’s Markab (1956) (Figure 103) where<br />

complexity is now a matter of the density and alternation of high contrast line used<br />

to indicate volume or depth, and then to greater density in works such as Fall (1963)<br />

(Figure 104) by Englishwoman, Bridget Riley (b.1931) where complexity now<br />

generates the distinctive retinal effects of motion and depth called Op Art. 288 Such<br />

effects are not restricted to the linear, but also exploit colour equiluminance and<br />

intensity in works such as Han-San Cadence, (1963) (Figure 105) by Larry Poons<br />

(b.1937). Yet these effects, if not the exact patterns, while undeniably engaging, are<br />

285 On Fontana, see B. Ceysson et al., Lucio Fontana, (catalogue) Paris, 1987.<br />

286 On Louis, see John Elderfield, Morris Louis, (catalogue) New York, 1987, Michael Fried, Art<br />

and Objecthood: essays and reviews, Chicago, 1998.<br />

287 On Minimalism see Frances Colpitt, Minimal Art: The Critical Perspective. Seattle, 1990,<br />

David Batchelor, Minimalism Cambridge, 1997, Gregory Battcock (ed.) Minimal Art: A Critical<br />

Anthology, New York, 1968.<br />

288 More detailed analysis of these effects is found in Gombrich, The Sense of Order: a study in<br />

the psychology of decorative art London, 1979 pp. 117-148, Gregory (ed.) The Artful Eye,<br />

Oxford and New York, 1995 and Livingstone, Vision and Art: The Biology of Seeing, New York,<br />

2002. On Op Art, see Cyril Barret, An Introduction to Optical Art, London/ New York, 1971.


196<br />

hardly novel. 289 Indeed it is the recycling of patterns familiar to the psychology of<br />

visual perception that crucially allows them to be used somewhat differently in<br />

painting. The effects while still compelling, are as often surrendered to the restless<br />

or mobile viewer, indeed to the various incidental distractions of the painting’s<br />

location, so that the singularity of the ‘retinal’ pattern competes and draws attention<br />

to other qualities of the painting, to its more relaxed and various receptions, to the<br />

perceptions of the pattern that actually fall short of or avoid its optical spell (such as<br />

very close or distant inspection). In other words the patterns of Op Art now extend<br />

painting to certain particulars of the viewing situation, to matters of scale and<br />

context, and as much for a print as a painting, but for more than a pattern.<br />

Consequently, while the pattern of the Op Art painting is easily reproduced in a<br />

photograph, to reproduce it as a painting is almost impossible.<br />

In noting the varieties of pattern used in Post-Modernist abstraction we have been<br />

drawn into noting ways in which they extend and are extended by painting. This is<br />

now considered more fully by returning to Stella’s work following the Black series.<br />

Here monochrome is maintained as well as the unpainted intervals between stripes,<br />

although the unevenness is reduced to a cleaner edge and the brushstroke now<br />

highlighted by refraction from metallic particles in the industrial enamels used. The<br />

straight lines to the stripes now conform to distinctly symmetrically shaped<br />

canvases, so that stripe and interval link shape and colour in a way unavailable to<br />

Kelly, and which in turn prompt more elaborate symmetries, inversions and<br />

reversals. Works now extend in enormous T-Shapes, U-shapes Star-shapes and<br />

various zigzags. Colour variation is later introduced, together with fluorescent paints<br />

so that ordering across stripes now assumes some of the complex system noted in<br />

Kupka (Figure2) as well as the colour effects found in Op Art, and largely replaces<br />

the uneven edge as a regulator of stripe width or edge. The introduction of irregular<br />

polyhedrons and curves to the shaped canvases stretch pattern beyond just stripes,<br />

in works such as Effingham I (1967) (Figure 106) and Agbatana III (1968) (Figure<br />

107) so that pattern does not just project to canvas shape, facture and colour, but is<br />

also projected by them, and builds stripes and remaining shapes or ‘fill’ to the<br />

289 An interesting precedent occurs in The Independent Group’s display This is Tomorrow at the<br />

Whitechapel Art Gallery, London, 1956, where Hamilton, John McHale and John Voelcker’s<br />

contribution, (as Group 2) included standard perceptual test graphics printed on large wallmounted<br />

cards, supplying familiar ‘optical effects’. See Richard Morphett, Richard Hamilton,<br />

(catalogue) London, 1970, pp. 28-30, Thomas Crow, The Rise of the Sixties, London, 1996, p. 46.


197<br />

canvas into more diffuse pattern. In other works stripe and colour create<br />

intersecting and ‘interweaving’ pattern, as in Saskatoon I (1968) (Figure 108) so that<br />

pattern now acquires a basic depth, as stripes are projected by textile and basketry<br />

motifs.<br />

Stella’s work thus undergoes a steady progression. Painting as shape of canvas and<br />

industrial paints prompts more elaborate pattern. Stripes duly acquire colour ranges,<br />

curves and additional enclosed shapes or fill, and even the ‘depth’ of interweaving<br />

planes or bands. Further pattern surely urges more familiar motifs, more concrete<br />

depiction. Yet Stella resists this and instead presses painting further into bas-relief<br />

constructions and more freestanding sculpture. The result is a greater sense of<br />

relaxation and yet disappointment. This is firstly because the rigour established<br />

between pattern and painting cannot be sustained in three dimensions – three<br />

dimensions require more of a pattern than a set of curves or planes as painted<br />

surfaces. It literally requires another dimension to the governing principles of<br />

construction. 290 Secondly, it is because much in painting and sculpture at this time<br />

render Stella’s version of both decidedly pedestrian.<br />

This brings us to other ways painting is extended by pattern at this time. Stripes<br />

abandon canvas for temporary murals upon various architectural features, interior<br />

and exterior, in the work of Frenchman Daniel Buren (b.1938). Le Witt converted<br />

stripes to lines and grids, and more elaborate geometric figures, devised formulae<br />

(or perhaps scores) governing their execution as murals, sometimes without his<br />

presence. 291 Gene Davis applied his signature striped colour harmonies temporarily<br />

to roads and parking lots, such as Franklin’s Footpath (1972) a vast expanse (414’ X<br />

76’) in front of the Philadelphia Museum of Art. Artists of the Surface/Support<br />

Group in France in the late sixties, such as Claude Viallat (b.1936) favoured loose<br />

hanging rather than stretched supports and adopted various printed fabrics over<br />

which were painted striped and gridded motifs; often installed outdoors. 292<br />

290 Ironically, this is close to the criticism Stella directs at Minimalist sculpture at the time. See<br />

Rubin, Frank Stella, New York, 1970, pp. 68-70. On later Stella, see Currentartpics 47<br />

291 Interesting precedent for Le Witt’s systems arises in Francois Morellet’s ‘Op’ drawings, see<br />

for example Four Superimposed Webs (1959) in Barret, An Introduction to Optical Art, London/<br />

New York, 1971, p. 31. On LeWitt see also Currentartpics 33.<br />

292 On the Surface/ Support Group and similar, see, Philip Armstrong et al., (eds.) As Painting:<br />

Division and Displacement, Columbus/ Ohio/Cambridge/ Mass. 2001-2 and Raphael Rubenstein,<br />

‘Opening The Field’ Art in America, October 2001, pp. 57-61.


198<br />

Looking to the materials of pigment rather than of support, it has been noted how<br />

pattern is relaxed by process (and scale) in works such as Louis’ Alpha Pi (1960)<br />

(Figure 102). Similarly, in Noland’s Beginning (1958) (Figure 109) staining now<br />

reciprocates pattern with process. But where pursued, process steadily relaxes or<br />

dissolves pattern. Works such as those of Jules Olitski (b.1922) at this time initially<br />

offer simply more irregular circles and pattern through staining, but as technique<br />

expands with various pouring, spraying and spattering, in works such as Seventh<br />

Loosha (1970) (Figure 110) pattern recedes to no more than a Rothko-like framing<br />

of edge to centre. Pattern or symmetry is now radically relaxed, in a way unavailable<br />

to Rothko, even Frankenthaler or early Louis. It hovers at a compelling minimum,<br />

orders colour, tone, facture and scale accordingly. This style is called Lyrical<br />

Abstraction and also attracts the work of Poons. The pour-ability stakes are raised<br />

with the pigmented latex or polyurethane adopted by Linda Benglis (b.1941) in<br />

works such as Odalisque - hey hey Frankenthauer (1969) (Figure 111). Here, the quicksetting<br />

foam assumes a three-dimensionality that once more broaches sculpture.<br />

Later work by Olitski and Poons literally rises to the challenge. 293<br />

These examples obviously trace the extremes for the way pattern extends painting,<br />

is extended by it. On the one hand pattern stretches painting in embracing<br />

architecture and the wider environment, and on the other, painting stretches pattern<br />

in embracing further versions of pigment and support. This leaves the course of<br />

more elaborate pattern and its extension in painting. But before turning to this,<br />

mention should to be made of several moderate developments. The work of Brice<br />

Marden (b.1938) at this time broadens stripes or narrows monochromes to sets of<br />

discrete panels, such as After The Marchioness of Solana (1969) (Figure 112) where a<br />

distinctive combination of oil and wax are used in generous modulations, more<br />

tactile than Newman perhaps, but now strengthening symmetry and identifying<br />

colour by discrete panel rather than shift in technique or width of stripe. Also<br />

drawn to combined monochrome panels, Robert Mangold (b.1937) from the mid<br />

sixties onward combines them with irregular shaped canvases measured not by<br />

stripes, but typically an outline of an ellipse, also often irregular, the edge of which<br />

293 On Olitski and Poons see Fried, Art and Objecthood: essays and Reviews, Chicago, 1998.<br />

Also on Olitski see Currentartpics 52.


199<br />

meets the frame of the canvas at one or more points, offering a ‘pattern’ between<br />

outline and canvas shape. 294 The shaped canvas is pursued with tinted fibreglass and<br />

polyester resin moulds in the work of the Los Angeles-based Ronald Davis (b.1937)<br />

where shape now aligns with three-dimensional projections for irregular volumes,<br />

offering a further step toward more concrete depiction. 295 Finally, the work of<br />

similar ‘Fetish/Finish’ artists in Los Angeles, including John McCracken (b 1934)<br />

and Larry Bell (b.1939) adopts not simply industrial materials but industrial<br />

standards of finish (hence the name). In such works pattern while immaculately<br />

presented, is hardly immaculate pattern, but rather samples just such presentation.<br />

In some ways these works recall the convergence with industrial design found in<br />

certain Bauhaus works, such as Albers’ sandblasted glass designs. Equally, this<br />

attention to industrial process and standards extends concerns explored in the<br />

commission and fabrication of works for, rather than by artists, an issue taken up in<br />

Chapter Ni<strong>net</strong>een.<br />

Departing from the interweaving stripes of Stella, artists such as Sean Scully<br />

(b.1945) in the early seventies and later Los Angeles-based Don Sorenson (1949-86)<br />

and Valerie Jaudon (b.1945) developing more elaborate – even maximised - patterns<br />

of interweaving, often preserving the pale edges or intervals to the stripes, if not<br />

Stella’s more relaxed facture 296 . Although Sorenson’s later work places greater<br />

emphasis upon process, and in general the use of poured and spattered grounds<br />

confined by masking tape to stricter geometries, is commonplace throughout the<br />

decade. 297 However the paintings of Joyce Kozloff (b.1942) from around the middle<br />

of the decade, order stripes less through interweaving than the symmetries of<br />

Native American pattern, as in works such as Notions of Finish – Frieze III (1974)<br />

where stripes are in turn broken down into grids with intricate variations on colour<br />

294 On Mangold, see Richard Schiff et al, Robert Mangold, London, 2000.<br />

295 On Davis, see Charles Kessler, Ronald Davis, paintings, 1962-1976 (catalogue) San<br />

Francisco, 1976.<br />

296 On Jaudon see also Currentartpics 81.<br />

297 On Scully, although only briefly dealing with the early work cited here, see David Carrier,<br />

The Aesthete in the City: The Philosophy and Practice of American Abstract Painting in the<br />

1980s, Philadelphia, 1994, pp. 243-267. On the rather forgotten Sorenson, see Sandy Ballatore,<br />

‘Don Sorenson at Copley and Wilder’, (review) Art in America, September-October 1976, p. 115,<br />

Christopher Knight, ‘Don Sorenson – Nicholas Wilder Gallery’, (review) Artforum, December<br />

1979, p. 80. On Jaudon, see John Perreault, ‘Issues in Pattern Painting’ Artforum, November<br />

1977, pp. 32-36.


200<br />

and facture. 298 More forthright concern with traditional patterns is also<br />

accompanied by concern with their traditional mediums, with weaving, textile<br />

printing and ceramic tiling, for example. These present a formidable counter-project<br />

to painting. However, certain sampling of textiles may yet be considered as<br />

depiction and painting. For example the elaborate collages of various printed and<br />

dyed fabrics by Miriam Shapiro (b.1923) or Lucas Samaras (b.1936) such as his<br />

Reconstruction #19 (1977) (Figure 113) sample textile prints by stripes, independent<br />

of textile pattern, overlaid rather than interweaved, and closer in system and scale to<br />

a Sorenson or a Moses than a quilt or embroidery. These works function as pictures<br />

and even painting, when painting now projects such pattern and technique.<br />

Interest in more traditional pattern and mediums – particularly printed textiles - is<br />

the basis of the mainly New York-based Pattern and Decoration Movement at this<br />

time. 299 It obviously converges with other print sampling in painting, even with<br />

other textile sampling, such as that of Viallat, Polke or Rauschenberg. Yet Pattern<br />

and Decoration artists are not always and only concerned with printing and textiles,<br />

artists such as Robert Kushner (b.1949) and Robert Zakanitch (b.1935) also use<br />

quite standard painting to sample much less standard properties of pattern. For<br />

Kushner, loosely drawn - not quite Neo-Expressionist - figures, are painted over<br />

and around a ground of various printed textiles, as in Aida (1979) (Figure 114)<br />

introducing casual variations to the dancing figures as a repeating motif, as well as<br />

using printed patterns as sheer areas of colour and tone in the background.<br />

Elsewhere Kushner expands this use of printed pattern as shading to figures, much<br />

the way Lichtenstein’s Benday dots are used to indicate tone and colour. Zakanitch<br />

also paints common repeating patterns, generally floral and drawn not only from<br />

textiles, but to which vigorous brushwork introduces greater variation within the<br />

298 The use of non-western patterns at this time is also anticipated in the titles of many of Stella’s<br />

works from the late sixties, such as Agbatana III, that take their names from ancient Babylonian<br />

and Moroccan sites, alluding to exotic and ancient foundations and Islamic pattern. The tendency<br />

throughout the seventies is thus to annex peripheral or exotic pattern, as abstraction steadily<br />

advances on more familiar, current and western pattern.<br />

299 On the Pattern and Decoration Movement (or P&D) see Amy Goldin, ‘The ‘New’ Whitney<br />

Biennial: Pattern Emerging?’ in Art in America, May-June, 1975, pp. 72-73, Carrie Rickey, ‘Art<br />

of the Whole Cloth’ in Art in America, November, 1979, pp. 73-83, Jeff Perrone, ‘The<br />

Decorative Impulse’ in Artforum, November, 1979, pp. 80-81, Corinne Robins, The Pluralist<br />

Era, American Art 1968-1981, New York, 1984, pp. 131-154, Irving Sandler, Art of the<br />

Postmodern Era: From the late 1960s to the Early 1990s, New York, 1996, pp. 141-63 and<br />

Christopher Miles, ‘Tracking Patterns’ in Art in America, February, 2004, pp. 77-81.


201<br />

motif. As with Johns or Stella, the pattern is stretched by such variation, while<br />

constrained by such version of painting. 300<br />

In both cases pattern now acquires pictures, and Post-Modernist abstraction gently<br />

draws to a close. Floral patterns are not pursued to the murals of a Le Witt or the<br />

exterior installations of a Viallat, nor to the foams and pigment cocktails of a<br />

Benglis or Poons. But pattern in repeating pictures tempts the single, central motif,<br />

even as it trades in vigorous brushwork and drawing. In this respect it converges<br />

with New Image Painting, and ‘outline and fill’ designs. But where brushwork is<br />

traded for single flat colours, where drawing and object conform to the simple<br />

silhouettes of commercial and civic icons, and where support is no more than loose<br />

fabrics or sheets of paper, pattern finds one further extension for depiction and<br />

painting. The installation by Mat Mullican (b.1951) at the Mary Boone Gallery in<br />

New York (1980) accomplishes this (Figure 115). Mullican’s work soon moves away<br />

from the central and standard icon, but it is pursued in the work of Peter Halley<br />

(b.1953) such as Prison with Conduit (1981) (Figure 116) where the title points to the<br />

small square of five black vertical stripes depicting bars on a window, and perhaps a<br />

prison, while the black horizontal stripes below it form the conduit, and suggest<br />

both an electrical circuit (with another kind of cell) and a concealed access to the<br />

prison. Where Mullican counts on the loose hanging banner to draw an icon into a<br />

more decorative medium and pattern, Halley adopts the texture of a coarse paint<br />

roller to sample the strictness of the lines and stripes and the evenness of colour – a<br />

pattern of Minimalism in fact. Process and System are gently mocked in other<br />

words, more so where they allow more concrete depiction. For the prison and<br />

electrical motif, while not initially obvious, offers potent metaphor for the larger<br />

Minimalist project.<br />

Other works at this time similarly find Minimalist motifs for pictures, or vice versa.<br />

Those of Ross Bleckner (b.1940) use soft or blurred vertical stripes offset by a<br />

collage of small birds, the stripes thus rendered as a cage. Yet stripes as a cage or<br />

prison bars still allow us to recognise the Minimalist pattern, to project it to picture<br />

and object, by a delicate balance. This balance is also present in the work of Philip<br />

300 On Kushner, see Alexandra Anderson-Spivy, Robert Kushner: gardens of earthly delight,<br />

New York, 1997 and Ja<strong>net</strong> Kardon, Robert Kushner, Philadelphia, 1987.


202<br />

Taaffe (b.1955) from this time where pattern maintains a distinctive facture even as<br />

it surrenders outline to stencils and silk-screens. Patterns here neatly sample print<br />

and painting, and in examples such as South Ferry (1985-6) (Figure 117) find a<br />

mooring rope depicted in the simple diagonal motif contained within the gently<br />

asymmetrical silhouette, recalling earlier New York abstraction, such as that of<br />

Kelly, Al Held (b.1928) or Myron Stout (1908-87). The use of Bridget Riley’s<br />

patterns in some of Taaffe’s work at this time also accompanies a brief interest in<br />

how far such borrowings - as ‘appropriation’ or ‘simulation’ - may be taken before<br />

charges of plagiarism arise. The work of Sherry Levine (b.1947) and Mike Bidlo<br />

(b.1953) at this time variously duplicate particular, well-known works, usually<br />

Modernist, photography as well as painting, to plumb where the useful sample and<br />

sampling become too obscure or specialised. The project of abstraction strictly<br />

would seem to end by the mid-eighties and to underline the closure of Post-<br />

Modernism generally. 301<br />

Crucial changes in abstraction thus coincide with distinctions drawn here for the<br />

periods of Late and Post-Modernism. Late Modernist abstraction converges upon<br />

established pattern with basic symmetry and reduction of simple volumes in<br />

perspective and projection schemes to linear and tonal ambiguity. It uses pattern to<br />

sample fine distinctions between facture, scale, colour and tone and these inspire<br />

use of greater, more emphatic pattern and in turn greater latitude to facture, scale,<br />

colour and tone relations. But where pattern then becomes paramount, Post-<br />

Modernism arises and this reversal closely coincides with the arrival of Pop Art.<br />

Post-Modernist abstraction samples the projection of pattern to painting and<br />

depiction. This too inspires greater latitude to scale and materials, but when pattern<br />

is pursued to repeating pictures, to the single concrete motif, style and period are<br />

exhausted. The course of abstraction thus strengthens the claim for the periods as<br />

proposed, and grasp of stylistics. More will be made of the co-ordination in the<br />

concluding chapter. Here grasp of period is furthered by looking next to<br />

developments outside of depiction and painting. The outward projection to material<br />

sampling that arises with abstraction was noted in Chapter Eleven. In the following<br />

301 For standard interpretation of many of the artists mentioned above, at this time, see Hal<br />

Foster, ‘Signs Taken for Wonders’, in Art in America June, 1986, pp. 80-91, p.139. Also useful<br />

interviews are included in Lilly Wei, ‘Talking Abstract: Part Two’ in Art in America, December,<br />

1987, for Levine, p. 114, for Halley, pp. 120-21, p. 171, for Taaffe, p. 122, p. 171. Also on Taaffe<br />

see Currentartpics 24.


203<br />

chapter this is traced against the periods as proposed, under the description of<br />

‘expanded materials’.


204<br />

‘Expanded Materials’<br />

In Late and Post Modernism<br />

Works of ‘expanded materials’ arise where material exemplification is pursued<br />

beyond depiction and the usual categories of the plastic arts. Works firstly isolate<br />

novel properties or material, as collage, or aspects to an object, as in Duchamp’s<br />

readymades. Other works integrate painting and sculpture, architecture and applied<br />

arts or design so that they sample larger categories, such as the plastic arts or civic<br />

functions. These projects also interact with each other. Isolations then shift in<br />

materials and aspects, integrations shift in range. In Late Modernism the change is<br />

away from industrial design, of furniture, textiles, costume, tableware and so forth,<br />

toward a closer integration with the performing arts. Isolation becomes of industrial<br />

and mechanical components for motion, or ki<strong>net</strong>ics. In some cases the line between<br />

integration and isolation blurs, but by around 1960 performance is stripped to a<br />

stark minimum; motion is engineered to a standstill. Post Modernism measures a<br />

further shift in expanded materials, where integration now embraces minimal<br />

performance, literature and other recording, while isolation samples the minimal<br />

and mechanical in construction and aspects to just time or place, as a work.<br />

Even in a longer chapter, this trajectory can only be traced in summary. 302 However<br />

it will suffice where it demonstrates how these changes coincide with the distinction<br />

drawn between Late and Post Modernism, when it covers vital works of the period<br />

and shows how changes reflect and parallel those in painting. To begin, the<br />

emphasis upon motion and machinery in sculpture is traced. Motion of course, is<br />

hardly a novelty to sculpture by the middle of the century. Prominent precedents<br />

include Duchamp’s Bicycle Wheel (1913 - reconstituted 1964) the mobiles of<br />

Alexander Calder (1898-1976) from the early thirties onwards, as well as moving<br />

302 Since this chapter sketches developments beyond painting, to speed and simplify matters, no<br />

illustrations are provided.


205<br />

parts in the works of others, such as Giacometti’s Suspended Sphere (1930). However,<br />

where obvious machine parts are recombined, motion may be notable by its<br />

absence or irregularity. Or where regular, motion may result from novel or irregular<br />

use of parts. Motion and mechanics then are sampled for novel and multiple links,<br />

for just those properties obscured by earlier works. Late Modernism pursues the<br />

sample in two ways, the recycled and the geometric. The ‘junk’ sculpture of David<br />

Smith (1906-65) and Richard Stankiewicz (1922-83) for example, remake standard<br />

steel mouldings and machine parts through any number of ingenious combinations<br />

and distress. On the other hand, precision machining and pristine finishes are<br />

exploited in geometric structures in the work of the British ‘Constructionists’, such<br />

as Ken<strong>net</strong>h Martin (1905-84) and wife, Mary (1907-67). Neither tendency initially<br />

adopts motion, but the promptings of machine parts, indeed the functioning<br />

motors of ‘junk’ or the dynamics of geometry, quickly prove irresistible to some.<br />

The work of Jean Tinguely (1925-91) introduces erratic motion through remade<br />

machinery, and in later work it generates paintings onto rolls or sheets of paper or<br />

cloth, periodic horns and other sounds, foul aromas, coloured smoke, and finally<br />

self-destruction, as in Hommage to New York (1960). The progressive integration of<br />

motion, sound, smell and even two-dimensionality, and the explicit singularity of<br />

motion here mark the climax of junk sculpture. 303 The geometric tendency on the<br />

other hand finds artists such as Paris-based Venezuelan Jesus-Rafael Soto (b.1923)<br />

Israeli Yaacov Agam (b.1928) and Frenchman Francois Morellet (b.1926)<br />

introducing motion to their stricter geometric constructions, and participating<br />

(along with Tinguely) in a noted exhibition at the Galerie Denise René in Paris in<br />

1955, aptly titled Le Mouvement. While such works often acquire the complexity of<br />

Op Art, rigours of geometry and motion quickly prove a sterile partnership. Neither<br />

motion nor geometry advances very far by motor or mobile of stricter materials. A<br />

more expansive approach, sharing interest in shifting patterns of reflectance or light<br />

and new rather than recycled materials, arises with architectural displays such as<br />

those of Hamilton and the Independent Group at the institute of Contemporary<br />

303 On Tinguely, see Heide E. Violand-Hobi, Jean Tinguely: Life and Work, Munich/New York,<br />

1995, Calvin Tompkins, The Bride and the Batchelor: Five Masters of the Avant-Garde.<br />

Middlesex/UK/ Ringwood/Australia/New York, 1968.


206<br />

Art in London around the middle of the century, and the lighting fixtures of<br />

Fontana at the Milan Triennale (1951)<br />

Hamilton’s display Growth and Form (1951) dealt in micro and macroscopic scientific<br />

depiction, freely mixed in scale, origin, and technology, so that various light<br />

projections (slide, film and strobe) to various surfaces (floor, ceiling and wall, clear<br />

and occupied) interrupt and overlap and inevitably involve the shadows and motion<br />

of spectators. 304 Fontana’s work wrapped over two hundred metres of neon tubing<br />

throughout the stairwell at Milan, not only providing practical illumination but a<br />

massive and complex sculpture, even drawing, that also involved the passage of<br />

spectators and their shadows. 305 Both works draw upon the readymade, the<br />

electrical, mobile and illuminated; sample a space or place more than a sculpture and<br />

its temporary or temporal dimension. Architecture, in a sense, is permitted to spill<br />

into sculpture or painting on a short-term basis, or sculpture acquires such radical<br />

dimensions by isolating architecture, briefly. Yet such work is also constrained by<br />

occasion and novelty of technology. Where materials are without obvious or<br />

entrenched application, display dwindles to no more than gimmickry. Where<br />

occasion allows greater novelty of material, display no more than meets norms. 306<br />

The challenge in other words, quickly becomes for other places and occasions,<br />

other means or motion.<br />

Other motion may be provided by performance. Integration of performance with<br />

the plastic arts continues the Modernist project of groups such as the Bauhaus and<br />

Constructivists, but now does not rely upon greater prominence for traditional<br />

categories of set and costume design, rather looks for a more formative role, a<br />

closer integration. Performance is now expanded by more radical notions of script<br />

or score, as in the famous Theatre Piece No 1 (or The Event) (1952) by composer John<br />

304 The term display is used here to distinguish the work from exhibitions of Hamilton’s work. By<br />

later standards, the work would surely be classified as an installation. This account of Growth<br />

and Form draws from Richard Morphet, Richard Hamilton (catalogue) London, 1970, pp. 20-26.<br />

305 On Fontana, see Sarah Whitfield, Lucio Fontana, Berkeley, 1999.<br />

306 Neon lighting however is later used in smaller, less mobile works, for example in the<br />

notational sculptures of the Greek-born woman Chryssa (b.1933) from the early sixties and in<br />

later works by artists such as Robert Morris, Dan Flavin (1933-96) Keith Sonnier (b.1941) and<br />

Bruce Nauman (b.1941), but shadow and motion are largely ignored or reduced to at most,<br />

flashing. Neon lighting is also used in the late sixties by the Los Angeles- based Robert Irwin<br />

(b.1946) and James Turrell (b.1943) to create colour and spatial illusions to architectural settings,<br />

but these works too ignore or resist motion.


207<br />

Cage (1912-92) performed at the Black Mountain College in North Carolina. Or the<br />

plastic arts is now expanded by radical notions of the temporal, as in the staged or<br />

enacted paintings of Frenchman Georges Mathieu (b.1921) from the early fifties,<br />

progressively involving (standard) musical accompaniment, outdoor settings, and<br />

even television coverage. 307 Cage offers simultaneous and overlapping texts,<br />

delivered with a certain stoic restraint, together with various music, live and<br />

recorded, dance and more casual activity (including a wandering dog). 308 Mathieu<br />

matches standard music and setting, amusingly, to the production of a large-scale<br />

calligraphic abstraction, with extravagant theme and showmanship (in one<br />

performance he is costumed in a knight’s armour, for example). 309 The first shifts<br />

the emphasis from starting point in script or score to arrive at a less sequential or<br />

more spatial ‘performance’, while the second shifts emphasis from end point or<br />

product, to arrive at a more sequential or less spatial painting. However, greater<br />

integration also surrenders its origin and mooring. Work gradually strips script and<br />

performance, painting and process to a sterile end to the period in the early sixties.<br />

Cage’s influence extends firstly through collaboration with dancer and<br />

choreographer Merce Cunningham (b.1919) and Rauschenberg. Rauschenberg’s<br />

work such as Minutiae (1954) (figure 34) occasionally serves as props for a<br />

Cunningham dance but works also become more conspicuously freestanding, such<br />

as the stuffed goat in Monogram (1959) and even mobile, as in the wheels to the base<br />

307 Links between The Black Mountain College and the Bauhaus are well documented. See Paul<br />

Betts ‘Black Mountain College N.C.’ in Bauhaus, Jeannine Fiedler and Peter Feierabend (eds.)<br />

Cologne, 1999, pp. 62-65. Mathieu’s stagings derive more directly from Surrealist events and<br />

tableaux, such as those at The International Surrealist Exhibition (1938) at the Galerie de Beaux<br />

Arts in Paris. The Independent Group and Hamilton share a strong architectural and design<br />

background that also reflects the Modernist convergence. Growth and Form was opened by noted<br />

French architect Le Corbusier (1887-1965) for example, while Fontana’s interest in light and<br />

electrical activity as sculptural material is anticipated in the work of Bauhaus artist László<br />

Moholy-Nagy (1895-1946) as well as the earlier proposals by Futurist Luigi Russolo (1885-<br />

1947).<br />

308 On Cage, see Paul Griffiths, Cage, London/New York/Melbourne, 1981, Michael Nyman,<br />

Experimental Music: Cage and Beyond, London, 1974, Richard Kostela<strong>net</strong>z (ed.) John Cage: an<br />

anthology, New York, 1991.<br />

309 Mathieu’s reputation warrants defence, since it has often suffered because of his theatrical<br />

approach. The shift from ‘action’ painting to ‘acting’ painting is unfairly felt to impoverish the<br />

results. The point is surely that differences made by performance to painting are no more than<br />

latitude granted to notational means within painting. On Mathieu, see Daniel Abadie et al.,<br />

Georges Mathieu: A Retrospective Exhibition (catalogue) Paris/Milan, 2003.


208<br />

of Gift For Apollo (1959). 310 Rauschenberg also contributes a small machine that<br />

throws money to Tinguely’s Hommage to New York (1960) and retains an interest in<br />

ki<strong>net</strong>ics even as later practice relies more upon gimmicks. A later student of Cage,<br />

Allan Kaprow (b.1921) dispenses with musicians and dancers in his staged<br />

‘happenings’ in which he and a small cast perform basic tasks of painting, wrapping<br />

or unwrapping, eating or drinking, and arranging signage or text in various discrete<br />

segments often synchronised to tapes of sound effects and more familiar music. 311<br />

Like Cage, Kaprow favours simultaneous features or attractions, an uncertain<br />

interaction with the audience and a deadpan attitude. But significantly, Kaprow’s<br />

happenings at this time, together with those of Robert Whitman (b.1935) generally<br />

occur in art galleries, and the range of activity, in avoiding standard music, dance<br />

and drama, unavoidably becomes ‘about’ sculpture and painting, an extension to the<br />

plastic artist’s laconic or non-verbal interaction with materials. The happenings of<br />

Claes Oldenburg, (b.1929) Jim Dine (b.1935) and Red Grooms (b.1937) at the<br />

Judson Gallery in New York in 1959 and 1960 briefly further this tendency; but<br />

essentially signal the exhaustion of such performance.<br />

Mathieu’s influence surprisingly extends to Japan and the Gutai group in Tokyo and<br />

Osaka, who emerge in 1957 and pursue painting and sculpture as a performance to<br />

the point where they dispense with the completed or preserved work, and instead<br />

set themselves various comic interactions with materials treated purely as props,<br />

such as Challenging Mud (1955) in which Kazuo Shiraga (b.1924) crawls upon a<br />

mound of very soft mud, shaping it with his flailing legs and arms. Yet these<br />

activities do not strictly replace painting and sculpture for the group but rather serve<br />

to publicise them and the Gutai shortly return the emphasis to product over<br />

performance. The work of Frenchman Yves Klein (1928-62) similarly maintains<br />

both production and performance and wholly embraces the showmanship of<br />

Mathieu, with a distinctive costume for himself and none for his young female<br />

assistants. Klein’s performed paintings such as the Anthropometries series (1960)<br />

reduce the artist to a mobile commander while his nude assistants obediently coat<br />

themselves in his signature blue paint and imprint themselves against a canvas. The<br />

310 Interestingly, Rauschenberg’s expansion stops short of the sculpted figure or person, just as<br />

the figure and extended setting (or ‘environment’) in the work of George Segal (b.1924) or<br />

Edward Kienholz (1927-94) at this time stop short of greater mobility or duration.<br />

311 Details for this and following works draw from Adrian Henri, Environments and Happenings,<br />

London, 1974.


209<br />

artist becomes more remote, the end product stresses anatomy over standard skills.<br />

Both artist and painting isolate or sample performance as utterance and anatomy,<br />

the performer now less an artist than a mere person or persons. 312 This radical<br />

reduction signals another end to Late Modernism, another start to Post-Modernism.<br />

The Late Modernist phase of expanded materials thus stresses motion and duration,<br />

and counterpoints painting of the period in certain ways. The emphasis upon time<br />

and motion drives a new contrast between one-directional and multi-directional<br />

reference. ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ gives this directionality added weight through<br />

emphasis on ‘interruption’, and shifts between the abstract and the concrete, while<br />

abstraction of the period often stresses a two-way directionality through greater<br />

symmetry. Depiction and painting thus exploit certain properties relinquished by<br />

the work committed to motion and duration. A similar synchrony holds for Post-<br />

Modernism. Painting samples printing and pattern for sole and multiple instances,<br />

for variation and material to identity of a work. Works of expanded materials stress<br />

other grades to identity for a work. Yet because such works now tend to resist more<br />

obvious performance, motion and place and an end product of any permanence,<br />

work is often taken as ‘de-materialised’ or purely a matter of concept and so is<br />

commonly called Conceptualism or Conceptual Art. 313 This is a little misleading.<br />

More accurately, identity for a work projected beyond the plastic arts encounters<br />

other issues. Some works are identified not with number of instances, variation and<br />

material but by compliance with rules of a language, as in literature, or notation, as<br />

in the performing arts. A poem, whether handwritten, typed or published remains<br />

the same work, as long as it complies with the rules of the language of the first<br />

instance. A music score remains the same work when performed as long as the<br />

performance and instruments comply with notation and other directions of the<br />

score. Equally, the script or score constitutes a work, even when unperformed or<br />

unperformable, unpublished or unpublishable. The difference between literature<br />

312 On Klein, see Sidra Stich, Yves Klein, Stuttgart, 1994, Pierre Restany, Yves Klein, New York,<br />

1982.<br />

313 On Conceptual Art, see Tony Godfrey, Conceptual Art, London, 1998, Alexander Alberro,<br />

Blake Stimson (eds.) Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, Boston, 1999, Peter Osborne,<br />

Conceptual Art, London, 2002, Michael Newman, Jon Bird (eds.) Rewriting Conceptual Art<br />

(critical views), Oxford/New York, 1999, Lucy R. Lippard, Six Years: The Dematerialisation of<br />

the art object from 1966 to 1972, London, 1973, Gregory Battcock (ed.) Idea Art, New York,<br />

1973.


210<br />

and performances on the one hand and painting and printing on the other, also<br />

means that paintings and prints may be forged in a way that performances and<br />

copies cannot. 314 The recording of a performance by means other than script or<br />

score, by photo and electrical means, presents a similar but more recent extension<br />

of identity for a work. Recordings in this sense are rarely of a single or<br />

uninterrupted performance, but typically comply with a score or script, or where<br />

this is absent, for example in improvised or folk music or tales, with such<br />

performing and recording practices in most other respects. A copy of a recording<br />

may contravene copyright but where standards of recording are sufficiently<br />

maintained, so too is identity of performance and script or score. It is a pirate or<br />

bootleg recording, but not a forgery of the work. 315 Identity for a work outside of<br />

the plastic arts is thus a graded or attenuated affair, from only script or score, to all<br />

copies that comply with original language or notation of script or score, to all<br />

compliant performances, or those from which a single script or score may be<br />

derived, to all recordings complying with script, score, performance or recording<br />

practices, and various combinations thereof. Furthermore, translations,<br />

transcriptions, adaptations and transmissions or broadcasts, by radio, television and<br />

the Inter<strong>net</strong> disperse identity still further, although hardly arrive at anything as<br />

vacuous as a work of pure concept.<br />

Expanding the materials of painting and sculpture to include motion and<br />

performance hardly exhausts these options, of course. Rather, it invites greater and<br />

more diverse engagement with them. And works are no more conceptual or<br />

dematerialised for attending to issues of script or score and recording than to sole<br />

or multiple instances, patterns or printing. ‘Expanded materials’ here contrast with<br />

painting in offering grades or stages to the identity of a work where printing and<br />

pattern deal in other issues of instantiation. As with the treatment of Pop Art in<br />

Chapter Fourteen, the aim here is not so much to replace or discredit the label of<br />

Conceptual Art, as to show how it is integrated within a larger project and period.<br />

The term nevertheless is stripped of loose talk of pure concepts and a<br />

314 See Goodman, Languages of Art, Indianapolis 1976, pp. 112-123, pp. 194-198.<br />

315 However the artwork and packaging – that is, design and printed elements – may be a forgery,<br />

or the impersonation of an alleged performer, may constitute an equivalent of a forgery, but<br />

neither of these then directly threaten the identity of the script or score.


211<br />

‘dematerialised’ work, and clad instead in radical sampling of, not just script and<br />

score, performance and recording, but also duration and place.<br />

For the Post-Modernist work of ‘expanded materials’ may also be a sampled place<br />

for a given duration, devoid of performance or motion. Sampling larger objects or<br />

places outside of a single building, effectively involves a fixed or short-term<br />

duration, indeed sample may be as much of duration (say a famous holiday) as place.<br />

So against attenuation of identity through script, score, performance and recording,<br />

the Post-Modernist work also allows performance to be graded to duration and<br />

place, and these four options are taken to comprise ‘expanded materials’ in Post-<br />

Modernism, or Conceptual Art, re-defined. Artists committed to the project, as in<br />

preceding periods, typically combine and switch between branches. As with the<br />

introduction of full abstraction to depiction, the results need hardly remain a dry or<br />

academic exercise. Conceptual Art extends the reach and sensitivity of sampling<br />

practices and allows a new complexity to object and sample. It may result in taking<br />

some practices as objects, such as scripts or ‘text-only’ works or as documentation<br />

or recording and elsewhere in renewed appreciation of ignored or concealed aspects<br />

to established practices, such as demarcation of place and duration.<br />

The four branches are now traced separately, taking script or score, performance,<br />

place, and recording in turn. Script or score not surprisingly arises firstly with the<br />

work of writers and composers, particularly influenced by Cage. The publication<br />

Compositions (1960) by the Californian composer La Monte Young (b.1935) largely<br />

avoids Cage’s more diagrammatic or multi-directional experiments with score, to<br />

introduce elaborate direction or script, including the use of butterflies, the drawing<br />

of lines and accidental or chance options for performers and audience. The works<br />

distance performance, without quite excluding it. There are similar developments in<br />

dance notation at this time. Young’s subsequent collaboration with George<br />

Maciunas (1931-78) leads to the formation of the Fluxus group in 1963, an umbrella<br />

for similar publications and events. Another Fluxus member and student of Cage,<br />

composer George Brecht (b.1925) allows score to become simply script, and offers<br />

only the simplest directions for a performer, related only to the most general of


212<br />

situations, such as a sign indicating direction of travel, to be followed or not. 316 The<br />

work still allows performance, but on such general terms as to render it underdetermined<br />

and effectively redundant. More prominently, it equivocates between<br />

rudimentary drama, dance and even music, as well as standing alone or as other<br />

literature and even admits to a plastic dimension in the use of a direction sign, as<br />

architecture and design. 317 So it offers all arts a part, but only of a radically<br />

diminished whole. Perhaps surprisingly, such work remains more of a concern to<br />

the plastic arts than to literature or performance, but crucially this is because the<br />

plastic arts are the sampler rather than the sampled.<br />

Clearly the script in such cases, given further elaboration, draws closer to traditional<br />

literature. To avoid this unwelcome assimilation the work is constrained to a literary<br />

and literal minimalism, and at the same time looks to other means of presentation,<br />

apart from mere copy or publication. The work accordingly adopts exhibition and<br />

like more musical or dance orientated works at this time, uses presence in a gallery<br />

and so a projection to the plastic arts as a way of countering a narrower identity. Yet<br />

the script or score, treated as a ‘text-only’ work (as in Chapter Fourteen) encounters<br />

a formidable contest of emphasis in sample. 318 For print sampling in painting offers<br />

a counter project at this time to text and ‘layout’, that obscures or sacrifices just<br />

those qualities of script preserved in copy, while copy urges indifference to such<br />

matters of print and ‘layout’. Consequently such works are doubly difficult, and<br />

reward or fail where difference between text and script are not maintained. Equally,<br />

works such as those of the Art and Language Group, Kossuth and Weiner may be<br />

taken to project ‘text-only’ sampling in the other direction, beyond painting and the<br />

art gallery, to publication for example.<br />

Notable works of script and ‘text-only’ include the exhibition Working Drawings and<br />

Other Visible Things on Paper, Not Necessarily Meant To Be Viewed as Art (1966)‘curated’<br />

by Mel Bochner (b.1940) at the New York School of Visual Arts. Bochner collected<br />

316 On Fluxus, see Ken Friedman (editor) Fluxus Reader, Chichester/ UK, 1998, Thomas Kellein,<br />

Fluxus, London, 1995.<br />

317 Since Cage in an earlier work allows silence as a musical duration - and since the script does<br />

not exclude sound - incidental sound or silence may be taken as a ‘musical’ feature of such<br />

works.<br />

318 The distinction here between script and text is that text refers only to familiar print or<br />

publishing formats, while script includes these within a larger category, roughly synonymous<br />

with writing.


213<br />

and photo-copied scripts, scores, sketches, drafts, plans and sundry calculations to<br />

demonstrate a familiar grading of script or notation to depiction in loose-leaf<br />

folders placed upon plinths through the gallery. 319 Of course where copies involve<br />

more than script, they are no longer strictly instances of the script and depiction,<br />

but text, print, and records, and Bochner’s role more than mere curator. Curiously,<br />

this strategy draws little subsequent interest. Whereas script as mere gallery notice,<br />

exploited by Robert Barry (b.1936) in his noted exhibition at the Art and Project<br />

Gallery in Amsterdam in 1969, in which the work appeared upon the closed doors<br />

of the gallery, informing the public that ‘during the exhibition the gallery will be<br />

closed’ does not invite further variation, even from Barry. 320<br />

Similarly, performance is drawn to the plastic arts in the course of expanding<br />

materials, as much as the plastic arts are drawn to performance. Yet each tends to<br />

cancel the other, so that Klein’s performances reduce painting to utterance and<br />

anatomy (male and female) and performance to mere presence of a person. More<br />

forthright are the performances and products of Piero Manzoni (1933-63) that<br />

follow in 1961, where the artist’s breath is collected in balloons, his thumbprints<br />

recorded upon them or freshly boiled eggs (later distributed and eaten by the<br />

audience) or, more notoriously, his excrement collected in sealed cans (mercifully,<br />

not as a performance). And where means are relaxed as far as to allow a felt-tip pen,<br />

he signs – significantly – the bared limbs of willing members of the audience, as<br />

conspicuously temporary products. 321 Performance stripped of the artist’s skills and<br />

sampled by only scant particulars of anatomy, obviously samples only the stark or<br />

minimal person. Performance parallels the Minimalism of painting and sculpture in<br />

this respect. 322 Likewise, the course of Post-Modernist performance is one of<br />

cautious expansion of means against ends, but concludes where means revert to<br />

distinct categories of music, dance and drama, or where the increasing availability<br />

and sophistication of video offers another art.<br />

319 On Bochner, see Richard S. Field, (ed.) Mel Bochner: Thought Made Visible 1966-73<br />

(catalogue) New Haven, 1995.<br />

320 The work also recalls Duchamp’s ‘dance score’ Relache (1924), consisting of a notice of<br />

cancellation at the door of the theatre.<br />

321 On Manzoni, see Germano Celant, Piero Manzoni, Milan, 1998 and Piero Manzoni, Piero<br />

Manzoni (catalogue) Paintings, Reliefs, and Objects, London, 1974.<br />

322 On performance, see Gregory Battcock and Robert Nickas (eds.) The Art of Performance: a<br />

critical anthology, New York, 1984 and Nick Kaye, Site-specific art: performance, place and<br />

documentation, London, 2000.


214<br />

But to begin with, the minimal person is sampled by the minimal performance. The<br />

performer’s actions are not pretence or acting, but actual and tend to focus upon<br />

automatic or involuntary responses to a variously challenging situation or task.<br />

Tasks and responses range from the traumatic, as in the bloody crucifixions of<br />

Austrian Herman Nitsch (b.1938) such as First Action (1962) to the trivial, as in the<br />

simple tasks performed by Nauman such as Self Portrait as a Fountain (1966-7) where<br />

the artist squirts water from his mouth 323 . Tasks may also elicit emotional responses<br />

as well as simple motor co-ordination skills. Yet since the ‘performances’ are usually<br />

self-imposed, the emotions elicited are not quite clear-cut, the more elaborate and<br />

onerous the task performed and emotion generated - or even the more frivolous –<br />

only serves to underline the performer’s ‘real’ motives and emotions to the<br />

undertaking. Does the audience witness mere distress or masochism, deft coordination<br />

or vanity? It is this uneasy blend between what is and is not a<br />

performance, and what exactly is sampled and expressed that stimulates much Post-<br />

Modernist performance.<br />

More elaborate tasks and responses follow. The importance of props and even place<br />

involved in the task become more prominent. Even the minimal performance<br />

requires props, if anything, places greater emphasis upon them, since the<br />

performer’s use of them is often extremely intimate. Squirted water, shed clothing, a<br />

scuffed floor or wall, even the echo of a hall or gallery, all carry some of the<br />

performer’s response to tasks or situations, and are an important part of the<br />

physical and emotional expression. Yet where the performance absorbs the props in<br />

this way, the performance also loses definition to some extent. The minimal person<br />

cannot do without props, but cannot really compete with them either. Exploiting<br />

this tendency with peculiar dedication, the early performances of Joseph Beuys such<br />

as The Chief – Fluxus Chants (1963-4) literally smother the performer in props. 324 The<br />

nine-hour performance involved the performer (Beuys) wrapped inside a roll of felt<br />

upon the floor and virtually inert throughout, a dead hare protruding from either<br />

end of the roll, edges of the floor and walls sealed with fat, while he broadcast a<br />

series of low squeals or groans through a microphone to speakers in the gallery and<br />

323 On Nauman, see Currentartpics 22.<br />

324 On Beuys, see Caroline Tisdall, Joseph Beuys, London, 1979, and Germano Celant, The<br />

European Iceberg: Creativity in Germany and Italy Today, New York, 1985.


215<br />

outside, interspersed with tapes of popular music. Here the performance is literally<br />

absorbed into the surrounding material, and while muffled in one respect, is yet<br />

transmitted to the gallery and beyond. The audio transmission stands as at least a<br />

metaphor for a more thoroughgoing one. From the performer’s emotional state to<br />

the chain of surrounding materials, organic and inorganic, across various seals and<br />

insulation and back – his disturbing and inchoate cries finally make the minimal<br />

person only the most vocal of props.<br />

Yet the minimal person, as a kind of psychic conduit to surroundings, is not always<br />

so lost for words. Beuy’s later performances tend to stress the verbal, indeed<br />

become informal lectures on a range of topical issues, complete with blackboards<br />

filled with successive summary diagrams. The minimal performance as a lecture is a<br />

less certain project in other respects. Neither distinctive costume, persona nor<br />

location quite ‘out-project’ mere lecturing. In general, Post-Modernist performance<br />

gradually allows greater verbal response in a work, concedes to the scripted and<br />

scriptable. It resists additional performers, although often invites audience<br />

participation of some kind. The partnership of London-based Gilbert and George<br />

(German Gilbert Proesch b. 1943, Englishman George Passmore b. 1942) is a<br />

notable exception, ignores interaction and literally doubles their act, as in the<br />

choreographed miming in The Singing Sculpture (1969-71). In this respect they too<br />

concede to dance, makeup and costume. All of which are present in a contrasting<br />

work, Interior Scroll (1975) by Carolee Schneeman (b.1939) where the performance<br />

pointedly ranges from the intimately bodily to an amusingly dry reading. 325 Each<br />

step, of course, expands upon the minimal person and performance, while reducing<br />

the pull of the plastic arts. Post-Modernist performance gradually dissipates by the<br />

end of the ni<strong>net</strong>een seventies, not just because the plastic arts have less to offer, or<br />

fail to project any further, but because dance, music and drama now offer more.<br />

The dance of Meredith Monk (b.1943) or German Pina Bausch (b.1940), the drama<br />

of Robert Wilson (b.1941), and the music of Laurie Anderson (b.1947) for example,<br />

all draw performance into other, more promising hybrids. 326<br />

325 On Gilbert and George, see Wolf Jahn, The Art of Gilbert and George or an aesthetic of<br />

existence, London, 1989 and Currentartpics 29. For Interior Scroll, see Carolee Schneeman and<br />

Bruce McPherson (eds.) More Than Meat Joy: Complete Performance Works & Selected<br />

Writings, New York, 1979.<br />

326 These developments are usefully summarised in Marvin Carlson, Performance: a critical<br />

introduction, London/ New York, 1996, pp. 101-120.


216<br />

Indeed as dance and drama explore ‘site-specific’ performances, admit<br />

improvisation, mime, acrobatics and other skills, the cautious concessions to the<br />

minimal performance look increasingly forlorn, even inept. A common criticism in<br />

the late seventies is that it falls too often and easily into poor or ‘bad’ drama, dance<br />

or music, (and scripts equally into ‘bad’ poetry or prose, even criticism) in<br />

comparison with traditional projects. An obvious parallel arises then with<br />

developments in ‘bad’ painting at this time. Yet this holds more for script and<br />

performance than for place or recording, which equally confront competing<br />

projects. Performance of the minimal person persists in video recording, although<br />

here too increasingly elaborate production would seem to draw it into the project of<br />

film and television. But film and television is also the most recent and complex of<br />

the arts, and its own controversies effectively weaken projection to or from it. 327<br />

Unfortunately constraints of length prevent tracing this direction. The shift from<br />

minimal performance to ‘bad’ performance leads in turn to fewer but more<br />

elaborate variations in the mid eighties, but these are part of a larger periodic shift.<br />

The experiments with place likewise bring the work of ‘expanded materials’ into<br />

competition with civic custom and architecture. But resulting work is rarely seen as<br />

‘bad’ architecture or civic planning; on the contrary, over the course of Post-<br />

Modernism such works are steadily absorbed or accommodated by architecture and<br />

civic custom.<br />

It is easy enough to track the emergence of place in this sense, and to match it<br />

roughly with the start of Post- Modernism. But it is more difficult to find its course<br />

coinciding with Post-Modernism as proposed here. However, to begin with there is<br />

the greater prominence of the gallery itself as a space or place. Klein’s Le Vide<br />

(1958) strips the gallery of its fittings, repaints the walls white, Le Plein (1960) by<br />

Frenchman Arman (Armand Fernandez b.1928) completely fills the same gallery<br />

(Galerie Iris Clert in Paris) with debris and various discarded materials. Both sample<br />

a containment of architecture for a duration – or an ‘installation’ – notably without<br />

327 A key example of this division from the time is Peter Wollen ‘The Two Avant-Gardes’ in<br />

Studio International, December 1975, pp. 171-175 (reprinted in Peter Wollen, Readings and<br />

Writings London, 1982, pp. 92-104). Significantly the debate initially occurs in an art rather than<br />

film journal.


217<br />

the motion or technology of Hamilton or Fontana’s displays. Similarly, the<br />

conflation of shop and gallery in Oldenburg’s The Store (1961) give the work a<br />

specific place and time (of lease). The spread to less likely places, materials and<br />

durations extends from The Dockside Packages at Cologne (1961) by French couple,<br />

Christo (Christo Javacheff b.1935) and wife, Jeanne-Claude (b.1935) to the<br />

earthworks of Oldenburg, Michael Heizer (b.1944) and Dennis Oppenheim<br />

(b.1938) in 1967 and to larger-scale ‘Land Art’ and even ‘Sky Art’ works by the end<br />

of the decade. 328 At the same time the use of less solid or stable materials within a<br />

gallery and installation amplify duration in other ways, from the less manageable<br />

‘spill’ and ‘scatter’ works of Carl Andre (b.1935), Serra, Le Va and Morris to the<br />

noisier, smellier, even tastier installations of Beuys, Jannis Kounellis (b.1936) Lucio<br />

Fabro (b.1936) and others, featuring among carved and moulded fat, dead hares and<br />

prepared meat, live macaws and horses, pot plants and vegetables, lit candles and<br />

gas flames, playing radios, television and tapes. 329 Later installation also tends to<br />

blur the distinction with exhibition, to include stand-alone and long-term works<br />

with more temporary elements, as in the installations of Jonathan Borofsky (b.1942)<br />

or combine painting with installed materials as in the work of Judy Pfaff (b.1946) in<br />

the late seventies.<br />

But where work samples place on a longer term, as in the Land Art works of<br />

Heizer, Walter de Maria (b.1935) or Robert Smithson (1938-73) duration is not<br />

necessarily the prominent issue. Where works use industrial earthmoving equipment<br />

to create something closer to landscape gardening, works are drawn irresistibly to<br />

architecture and engineering. Short-term works persist through the seventies, such<br />

as the more restrained Land Art works of Englishmen Richard Long (b.1943) and<br />

Hamish Fulton (b.1946) the more expansive projects of Christo and Jeanne-Claude,<br />

the installations of Italian Eugenio Carmi (b.1920) of Viallat and the Surface and<br />

Support group in France, and the sledge hammer and chain-saw ‘carvings’ in<br />

derelict and condemned buildings by Gordon Matta-Clark (1945-78). But familiarity<br />

now specialises the emphasis in such works. Duration here comes to stress either<br />

328 On these American artists, see Alexander Alberro and Patricia Norvell (eds.) Recording<br />

Conceptual Art, London/Los Angeles, 2001. On Kounellis, see Gloria Moure (ed) Jannis<br />

Kounellis: works, writings 1958-2000, New York, 2000<br />

329 Something of this attention to a wider sensory sample is captured in the term Arte Povera, and<br />

often used to distinguish between European and American installations. See Germano Celant,<br />

Arte Povera, New York, 1969, Carolyn Christov-Bakargiev, (ed.) Arte Povera, London, 1999.


218<br />

increasing civic co-operation, or in the case of many British and American works, a<br />

recalcitrant isolation, in the case of Matta-Clark, often a naked demolition or<br />

vandalism.<br />

But while duration and place for Conceptual Art do not strictly last the course of<br />

Post-Modernism as proposed, two tendencies that follow from works of place do<br />

climax in the mid-eighties, and so correspond to the sought end of Post-<br />

Modernism. The first of these follows from the architectural strain to Land Art, and<br />

leads firstly to sculpture of basic buildings, such as Low Building with Dirt Roof (for<br />

Mary) (1973) by Alice Aycock (b.1946) and then to larger, more industrial<br />

structures, such as her series titled How to Catch and Manufacture Ghost Stories from the<br />

Workhouse (1979-80) with their sprawling and ki<strong>net</strong>ic elements (including<br />

performance) industrial materials and imposing scale. 330 Similar features are found<br />

in the work of Oppenheim, Dan Graham (b.1942), Vito Acconci (b.1940) Siah<br />

Armajani (b.1939) and others at this time. But the play with industrial architecture<br />

leads not only to more playground-like works but also to increasing use of<br />

commercial fabrication of components, to the artist as more of a designer or<br />

architect and to the work’s integration within broader architectural projects, such as<br />

the gardens and walkways designed by Mary Miss (b.1944) at Laumeier Park (1985)<br />

in St Louis. 331 On the one hand the pursuit of place and duration ends in the subbranches<br />

of architecture, on the other, the increasing reliance upon standard<br />

fabrication shifts the emphasis to another kind of integration. This announces an<br />

end of Post-Modernism.<br />

The second tendency follows from the increasing co-operation available for works<br />

of place. It feeds and feeds off a widespread growth in funding and administration<br />

of such events throughout the seventies, largely throughout the western world.<br />

Public art programmes, arts festivals, artists-in-residence schemes and further<br />

venues and facilities all use and shape the short-term work of place in this period.<br />

Either institutional opportunity promotes a greater boldness, even extravagance to<br />

330 On such work, see Rosalind E. Krauss, ‘Sculpture in The Expanded Field’ in The Originality<br />

of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths, Cambridge/Mass./ London, 1986, pp. 277-290<br />

331 Attention to industrial architecture is prompted possibly by the preceding engagement with<br />

large-scale earth-moving equipment in the Land Art works of Smithson or Heizer, by questions<br />

of scale and materials, similar to those found in Late Modernism, and by the growing popularity<br />

for the photographic catalogues of industrial architecture by Bernd and Hilla Becher.


219<br />

site-specific works, or places are negotiated with their constituents or community.<br />

The split is between what the work can do with a place as community, and what the<br />

community can do with a work as place. Place now becomes less a matter of remote<br />

or open spaces than of distinctive urban functions. Certain buildings for example<br />

are offered to mural projects whose themes increasingly reflect local concerns, so<br />

that physical structure, space and duration are less an issue than community<br />

projection of a collective identity. Obviously the artist interested in material issues<br />

in unlikely to be the same one to respond to community needs, but at the same time<br />

to work further with a place, is to work with its community and to exchange<br />

means. 332 Moreover, the work is increasingly a collective, and often urgently political<br />

and educational task. Groups such as Collaborative Projects (Colab) and Group<br />

Material in New York in the late seventies typify this trend. 333 Finally community<br />

concerns are also directed back to other varieties of the plastic and applied arts, and<br />

to their grouping in exhibitions and collections as Identity Art. The identity is of a<br />

community or sub-culture, variously constructed according to place, history,<br />

religion, race, economic status, ability, age or sexuality. 334 Where performance<br />

begins as the minimal person, place here ends as the social stereotype. This<br />

transition culminates in the mid eighties and marks another end to Post-Modernism.<br />

Finally, there is recording in Conceptual Art, and since we forego film and video,<br />

and audio recordings form only a small part of the style, recording of performance<br />

and place by photography, is briefly traced. As noted, recording may also influence<br />

how a performance or event is constructed. While many Conceptual Art works<br />

employ photography to document or record events, much as painting or sculpture<br />

332 The issue of how place or site is defined in relation to community remains controversial. For<br />

example the removal of Serra’s ‘site-specific’ sculpture Tilted Arc (1981) from Federal Plaza in<br />

New York City in March 1989, was contested on the grounds of spatial or architectural integrity<br />

of the work as well as contractual obligation, notably ignoring the adverse response from the<br />

surrounding buildings’ occupants, and users of the space. See Robert Storr, ‘Tilted Arc: Enemy<br />

of the People?’ in Art in America, September 1985, pp. 90-97, Harriet F. Senie, The Tilted Arc<br />

Controversy: Dangerous Precedent, Minneapolis, 2001.<br />

333 On Group Material, see Brian Wallis (ed.), Democracy: A Project by Group Material, Seattle,<br />

1990, Suzi Gablik, ‘Report from New York: The Graffiti Question’ in Art in America, October<br />

1982, p.37, and William Oleander, ‘Material World’, in Art in America, October 1989, p. 124.<br />

3 On Identity Art, see Lucy Lippard, Get The Message? A Decade Of Social Change: New York.<br />

1984, Hal Foster: ‘Artist as Ethnographer’ in Return of the real: the avant-garde at the end of the<br />

century, Cambridge/Mass./London, 1996, W.J.T. Mitchell (ed.) Art and the Public Sphere,<br />

Chicago, 1992, Robert Storr ‘Identity’ in Art 21: Art in the Twenty First Century, New York,<br />

2001.


220<br />

are regularly documented, photography is also quickly seized upon as a more<br />

formative feature to the work of performance, duration or place. It allows for<br />

example, for fictive works, such as Klein’s Leap into The Void (1960) where the artist<br />

appears to be caught mid-dive, from on high onto the bare pavement of a quiet<br />

street in Paris, and its novel presentation in a print format (in a small newspaper,<br />

‘for one day’, devoted solely to the artist’s activities). It allows for more mobile and<br />

in a sense, private performances, and for tacit ‘visual’ elements not easily devised or<br />

recorded in a script, score or plan, such as in the documented ‘actions’ of Acconci,<br />

Nauman, Oppenheim, Adrian Piper (b.1948) Ana Mendieta (1948-85) and<br />

Brazilians Helio Oiticica (1937-80) and Lygia Clark (1920-88), as well as striking<br />

points of view, such as the aerial photography used by Smithson or Oppenheim for<br />

certain Land Art works, the angles and architectural details to Matta-Clark’s<br />

demolitions and the distant views of remote Land Art works adopted by Long and<br />

Fulton.<br />

Yet photographs as records also require captions and ‘layout’ to properly point to<br />

events, and these too are distinctive in Conceptual Art. While recording here<br />

converges with other interests in script or score, ‘layout’ and print, recording is<br />

initially stressed in the prosaic nature of the photography and ‘layout’. Yet even as<br />

the recording of the work as an event or place is urged, ‘layout’ and caption build a<br />

second work, around the work. ‘Layout’ of photographs and captions is often<br />

amusingly strained in such works for sequence and salience. Captions are often terse<br />

or vague. Photographs are often uninformative or misleading. 335 The work as a<br />

record, often points to the vagaries of events and recording practices. The work<br />

here is thus one of divided identity, between record, event and even script or score,<br />

in a way striking to the plastic arts, although quite the norm in filmmaking or music<br />

recording. But the ‘real’ event does not elude such recording, anymore than such<br />

recording eludes preceding practices, in a phantom concept. Rather, event and<br />

record find and make other kinds of events and practices.<br />

335 See for example Acconci’s ‘layout’ of photographs for Security Zone (1971) where persons<br />

are largely rendered in distant silhouette hence of uncertain identity or attitude, matters<br />

supposedly sampled by the performance, and equally uncertain sequence. On Acconci, see Vito<br />

Acconci and Kate Linker, Vito Acconci, New York, 1994.


221<br />

Indeed the wider practices of photography and caption become the focus of further<br />

Conceptual works throughout the seventies, just as performance and place also<br />

change, and just as painting tires of them, as print samples. Works by Graham, Bill<br />

Beckley (b.1946) German Hans Haacke (b.1936) Englishman Victor Burgin<br />

(b.1941) French Christian Boltanski (b.1944) and others pursue standard typefaces,<br />

script or copy, photographic techniques and often found or acquired photographs,<br />

to factual and fictive objects in often strange or disturbing contexts. Practices may<br />

be pursued to publication, to their inclusion in popular magazines, or to billboards<br />

or posters. Graham’s pioneering ‘Figurative’ in Harper’s Bazaar (March 1968)<br />

supplies an enlarged supermarket receipt, disturbs the overall layout of advertising<br />

and urges a blunt financial dimension to the usual claims for personal hygiene and<br />

attraction. 336 Practice is thus tested and adjusted in a small way by fully participating<br />

in such publication, and yet unavoidably also functions as just an advertisement for<br />

the artist (his name and the title of the work are included beside the list) and the<br />

enlightened acceptance of the publication. Challenge thus extends no further than<br />

the nature of the advertisement, indeed reflects perhaps more favourably on<br />

surrounding products than the artist. 337<br />

‘Layout’ practices are also pursued to the gallery or exhibition, for captions or wallplaques,<br />

catalogue and attribution texts. The work of Haacke at this time elicits<br />

various social and economic statistics for gallery or exhibition, more controversially,<br />

offers copious provenance or history not only for works, but collections, collectors,<br />

patrons, administrators and prevailing financial arrangements. The challenge here is<br />

not simply one of propriety, but whether the practice is not out-projected by, or<br />

more efficiently pursued as journalism. 338 Other work ranges between such practices<br />

and publication. At a certain point in Conceptual Art, events and place are less<br />

important than the recording, and at a certain point recording is less important than<br />

its ‘layout’ and influence, and by the eighties the cooperation and access to such<br />

practices becomes a more prominent sample in such work than either recording or<br />

336 Later such placements target more specialised publications, notably art journals such as Art<br />

Forum, Studio International and Flash Art, in the seventies and early eighties.<br />

337 On Graham, see Alexander Alberro and Patricia Novell, (eds.) Recording Conceptual Art, Los<br />

Angeles and London, 2001 and Alexander Alberro (ed.) Two-way Mirror Power: Selected<br />

writings by Dan Graham on his art, Cambridge/Mass./ London, 1999.<br />

338<br />

On Haacke, see Brian Wallis (ed.) Hans Haacke Unfinished business, Cambridge/<br />

Mass./London, 1986, Benjamin Buchloh, ‘Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason’ in<br />

Art in America, February, 1988, pp. 96-109.


222<br />

‘layout’, for example in the publication and distribution of works by Barbara Kruger<br />

(b.1945) and Jenny Holzer (b.1950). 339<br />

Thus works of ‘expanded materials’ mostly gain in organisation under the proposed<br />

periods of Late and Post-Modernism. Importantly, they synchronise with<br />

fundamental concerns in painting, and correct and co-ordinate misleading notions<br />

of Conceptual Art. A larger, clearer picture of the periods emerges, perhaps<br />

prompts a more revealing name than Post Modernism, and so helps to frame the<br />

following chapter on the closing period to the century.<br />

339 On Kruger, see Kate Linker, Love for Sale: The words and pictures of Barbara Kruger, New<br />

York, 1990. On Holzer, see David Joselit, Jenny Holzer: (All Works and Artist's Writings)<br />

London/ New York, 1998.


223<br />

‘Globalism’<br />

1985 - 2000<br />

Post-Modernism is rarely seen as ending in the twentieth century. It is variously<br />

seen as beginning in the middle of the century, at the start of the sixties, seventies<br />

and eighties, as perhaps best started with a decade, and as the name suggests, is<br />

usually defined only by its departure from Modernism. 340 To end Post-Modernism<br />

in the mid eighties is not therefore so very different from offering yet another<br />

starting point to the period. Indeed, while this study arrives at an additional period<br />

to the century, dates nevertheless correspond to at least some versions of Post-<br />

Modernism, and to key or representative works. In which case, differences lie in<br />

label and aspects otherwise discerned, in subtlety of grasp, efficiency of links.<br />

Conceivably one might coin ‘Middle’ or ‘High Modernism’ for the fifties and<br />

maintain Late and Post-Modernism for the following periods, but the turning point<br />

in the early sixties seems greater or more decisive than merely the amplifications<br />

340 The early fifties are favoured as pivotal by Steinberg, as noted, the mid fifties by David<br />

Hopkins, After Modern Art, Oxford/New York, 2000. The sixties are preferred in Foster (ed.),<br />

The Anti-Aesthetic; essays on Post-Modern culture, New York, 1983, and Foster, Return of the<br />

real: the avant-garde at the end of the century, Cambridge/Mass./London, 1996. Brandon Taylor,<br />

Modernism, post-modernism, realism: a critical perspective for art, Winchester, 1987, finds<br />

Post-Modernism begins with Warhol in the sixties. Sylvia Harrison, Pop art and the origins of<br />

post-modernism, Cambridge/New York, 2001, agrees. The early seventies are claimed in Smith,<br />

Modernism’s History: a study in twentieth century art and ideas. Sydney, 1998, following<br />

Krauss, ‘Notes on the Index: Seventies Art in America’ in October: The First Decade,<br />

Cambridge/Mass./London, 1987. Rubin agrees in Lawrence Alloway and John Coplans, ‘Talking<br />

with William Rubin: The Museum Concept is not Infinitely Expandable’ in Artforum, October<br />

1974 p.52. So does Fineberg, Art since 1940: Strategies of Being, London/ New York, 2000.<br />

Gombrich takes his cue from architecture, accepts the mid seventies in Gombrich, The Story of<br />

Art, (16 th ed) 1995. Greenberg implicitly accepts the late seventies or early eighties in Greenberg,<br />

‘Modern and Post Modern’ Arts 54. No 5, February 1980. Robert Hughes, The Shock of the New,<br />

(2 nd ed) London, 1991, agrees. Benjamin H. D. Buchloh, ‘Figures of Authority, Ciphers of<br />

Regression’ in October No. 16, Spring, 1981, pp. 39-68, agrees. So does Robert Storr, Modern<br />

art despite modernism, London/ New York, 2000. Donald Kuspit plumps for the early eighties in<br />

Kuspit, ‘Flak from the “Radicals”: The American Case against Current German Painting’ in Jack<br />

Cowart (ed.) Expressions: New Art from Germany, St Louis/Munich 1983, pp 43-55. Peter<br />

Schjeldahl, ‘A Visit to The Salon of Autumn 1986’ Art in America, December 1986, pp. 15-21,<br />

bids for mid decade. Tomkins, Post to Neo: The Artworld of the Eighties, New<br />

York/London/Melbourne, 1988, agrees. T.J. Clark opts for October 1989 and the fall of The<br />

Berlin Wall as marking the end of Modernism in Clark, Farewell to an Idea: Episodes in the<br />

history of Modernism, New Haven/London, 1999.


224<br />

and diminutions taken here as Late Modernism. The period that follows is more<br />

accurately defined as Post-Modernism and in any case a ‘Middle Modernism’ is no<br />

more familiar to other versions of art history than a period subsequent to Post-<br />

Modernism.<br />

So the study advances a period named ‘Globalism’. The name captures something<br />

of the wider project to the period, to the greater economic and cultural integration<br />

that occurs at this time, much as Modernism (and modernism) celebrates an earlier<br />

commitment to progress in social and technological issues. It also registers a radical<br />

widening of place to the period. ‘Globalism’ can also be taken to contrast with<br />

localised or centralised issues, to indicate a more overall, holistic or ‘global’<br />

approach to certain issues that arise in Post-Modernism. Then again, like<br />

Modernism, ‘Globalism’ may stand for just those stylistic issues it makes.<br />

‘Globalism’, while apt enough, stands to be denoted by as much as to denote a<br />

period style. In any case, the period is an open one. ‘Globalism’ does not end with<br />

the century, but rather the project is maintained at least up until the year 2000.<br />

Certain developments are discerned, but do not suggest a decisive break. Because it<br />

deals with an open period, a more compact approach is adopted, although again, a<br />

somewhat longer chapter results. The style is traced by considering parallels<br />

between ‘expanded materials’, abstract and concrete depiction in painting, as in the<br />

two preceding chapters, but here compressed into one. Here also sequence is<br />

reversed, considering firstly ‘expanded materials’ then abstraction and finally more<br />

concrete depiction.<br />

‘Expanded materials’ enter a ‘Globalist’ phase when the plastic art’s projection to<br />

literature and the performing arts becomes more entrenched, and concern is<br />

deflected to supporting and adjacent institutions. The shift is basically from samples<br />

of basic events to wider institutional practices. In Chapter Eighteen this shift is<br />

traced in a number of ways, through the growing attention to local community over<br />

mere architecture or place, through Identity Art and collective works, through<br />

delegated or commissioned components to a work, and through ‘layout’ and other<br />

presentational practices used in exhibition and display. The work is increasingly<br />

about its institutional support, about its contribution to and dependence upon an<br />

aggressive infrastructure. Obviously the formidable logistics required of the works


225<br />

of Christo and Jeanne-Claude also use such support, as do the publications and<br />

billboards of Graham or Kossuth, or the television and video equipment in the<br />

work of Nam June Paik (b.1932) to offer only a few Post-Modernist examples. The<br />

difference is that the support is not made explicit or exemplified in Post-Modernist<br />

work. There, projection and sample are still to issues of duration and text. 341 The<br />

‘Globalist’ work, by contrast, can now afford to stress its institutional support, and<br />

in fact to extend it through conspicuous patronage, sponsorship, leasing, loans,<br />

commission and similar co-operation with other institutions. Work duly acquires a<br />

rather academic acceptance. Support invested and displayed urges and reassures<br />

other branches of the art world, builds a certain bullish impetus even as it traduces<br />

acceptance. This push outward, or institutional <strong>net</strong>working, becomes the project<br />

and artists committed to it again freely switch between branches. Script or score,<br />

performance, place and recording are all pursued in this way, but the study now<br />

focuses only on ‘Globalism’s’ more distinctive and discrete objects.<br />

The turning point is taken to be where work samples the products and presentation<br />

of retail display, in works such as Supremely Black (1985) (Figure 118) by Haim<br />

Steinbach (b.1944) and New Hoover Convertibles, Green, Red, Brown, New Shelton,<br />

Wet/Dry 10, Gallon Displaced, Doubledecker (1981-87) (Figure 119) by Jeff Koons<br />

(b.1955). This is because presentation here so directly engages basic exhibition<br />

practice, for gallery, museum or private collection. The work at once draws setting<br />

into presentation and selling into appreciation in a manner unnerving for both art<br />

and commerce, novel to the readymade. While visual merchandising is particularly<br />

telling to art exhibition practice, the work concerned with only several household<br />

products and common brand names is still a relatively easy or safe<br />

accommodation. 342 Where works deal in larger, more expensive items, such as a<br />

refrigerator and a safe, as in Brandt/Ficht Bauche (1984) by Frenchman Bertrand<br />

Lavier (b.1949) or in the variously stacked and juggled office furniture and fittings<br />

in the work of German Reinhard Mucha (b.1950) from this time, the effect is<br />

341 Indeed this practice must be so, for the institutional support cannot be sampled until the work<br />

has the means with which to sample it, and this arises only when the sampling of events through<br />

expanded materials becomes more routine, or when it acquires a sufficient body of preceding<br />

examples. Then, sampled may become sampler, as variations on the form or theme eventually<br />

offer new forms or themes.<br />

342 On Koons, see Klaus Kertess, ‘Bad’, Parkett, no.19, 1989, pp 30-36, Jean-Christophe<br />

Ammann, ‘Der Fall Koons’, Parkett, no.19, 1989, pp 53-56 and Currentartpics 49. On Steinbach,<br />

see Germano Celant et al., Haim Steinbach: Recent works, Bordeaux, 1988.


226<br />

somewhat the reverse. The work flaunts a range and value to material but resists<br />

naked marketing strategies for something closer to the modules of Minimalist<br />

sculpture, such as those of Donald Judd (1928-94) or Carl Andre (b.1935). Yet now<br />

standard or modular items suggest various non-obvious assemblies.<br />

Generally, where ‘Globalism’ looks to readymade objects for its materials, the<br />

tendency is to the kind of quantities, size and price that sample not just an unusual<br />

or difficult source, but one with a certain influence or prestige. Samples tend to<br />

industrial, scientific and commercial institutions, rather than say, the stable of<br />

motley horses adopted by Kounellis in Cavalli (1969) and assembly is less along<br />

sculptural models, still evident in the examples of Lavier and Mucha, than to more<br />

expansive, site specific models, or to some more cunning variation upon their<br />

standard function. Works such as the Untitled Installation (1989) in Topanga,<br />

California by Nancy Rubins (b.1952) involving a mass of used aircraft parts<br />

arranged upon a grove of trees, or the various installations by Scotsman David<br />

Mach (b.1956) using thousands of excess copies or back issues of magazines stacked<br />

in patterns and sometimes shaped into concrete depiction, from around this time,<br />

illustrate this access to an unusual industrial product, and its enterprising<br />

negotiation. 343 More complex arrangements of objects, their acquisition and<br />

sampled institutions, follow in the work of Cady Noland (b.1956) Jessica<br />

Stockholder (b.1959) and later Jason Rhoades (b.1965) amongst others. 344 Rhoades<br />

installations in particular assemble a massive array of objects and technology, such<br />

as A Few Free Years (1998) at the Kunsthalle Bremen, featuring eighteen amusement<br />

arcade machines, video monitors and players, and masses of his signature polished<br />

aluminium scaffolding. The sample now literally makes a game of its entrepreneurial<br />

ambit. These brief institutional games also revive some of the scope of Modernist<br />

343 On Rubins, see Lane Relyea, ‘Art of the Living Dead’ in Helter Skelter: L.A. Art in the 90s,<br />

(catalogue) Catherine Gudis (ed.) Los Angeles, 1992, pp. 33-43, Peter Kosenko, ‘Putting Disgust<br />

on Display: Helter Skelter: L.A. Art in the '90s at the Museum of Contemporary Art, Los<br />

Angeles’ In These Times 1-7 April 1992, pp. 20-21. On Mach, see Marco Livingstone, David<br />

Mach: towards a Landscape, (catalogue) Oxford, 1985 and Tom Bendhem, David Mach: Master<br />

Builder (catalogue) Rotterdam, 1982.<br />

344 On Stockholder, see Barry Schwabsky et al., Jessica Stockholder, London, 1995. On Noland,<br />

see Lane Relyea, ‘Holy Crusade’, Parkett, no.46 1996, pp. 72-76 and Relyea, ‘Hi-Yo Silver –<br />

Cady Noland’s America’ in Artforum, January 1993, pp. 50-54. On Rhoades, see Nancy<br />

Princenthal, ‘Jason Rhoades: Pipe Dreams’, in Art in America, January, 2001, pp. 98-100, p.141,<br />

Uta Grosenick and Burkhard Riemenschneider, Art Now, Cologne, 2002, pp. 424-27 and<br />

Currentartpics 7.


227<br />

integration of the applied arts, although now the various branches of design offer<br />

multiple but temporary integration.<br />

The bulk or wholesale readymade however is really the simplest of ‘Globalist’<br />

strategies. Work samples institutions by also participating more fully in their<br />

procedures, by looking not to the readymade product or by-product, but to the<br />

customised or commissioned version; the ‘readily-made’, and less often, to the<br />

collected or curated work, to what amounts in fact to a work of other and lesser<br />

works, where distinctions between the readymade, the ‘readily-made’ and the plain<br />

made collapse. On the one hand, the artist assumes the role of exclusively an ideas<br />

person, a designer or commissioner, on the other of simply a curator or collector.<br />

Here too, expansion encompasses other institutional roles. The ‘readily-made’ is<br />

distinct from traditional studio delegation and process in the production of a work,<br />

whereby for example, the details of casting a sculpture are rarely the exclusive<br />

province of the sculptor, or where an artist assigns preliminary or peripheral tasks to<br />

assistants in the process. The ‘readily-made’ is in many respects the reverse. The<br />

process is paramount, and the artist’s contribution almost preliminary or peripheral.<br />

The concept or idea for the work is really no more than such variations as<br />

demonstrate the efficiency of the process. ‘Readily-made’ works often have the feel<br />

of a prototype or a trial run in this respect.<br />

Koon’s stainless steel castings of readymade objects such as Rabbit (1986) (Figure<br />

120) achieve new prominence for the ‘readily-made’. 345 The work not only<br />

transforms a child’s inflatable toy into an eerie futuristic idol, a comic folly, and a<br />

massive ornament, amongst other things, but the familiar readymade source also<br />

gives the casting process itself an unusual prominence. Indeed the expense and<br />

difficulty of casting in stainless steel, a material more usually associated with<br />

industrial and trade applications, alerts us to a more general aspect to the process, to<br />

its autonomous nature, its prompt accommodation of the artist’s commission (at a<br />

price) and equally, of the artist’s accommodation of this autonomy, also at a price.<br />

Art, one might say, becomes a little more industrial for making industry a little more<br />

artistic. Both institutions are thus urged to a broader <strong>net</strong>work. The ‘readily-made’<br />

345 Also of note at this time is the work of Alan McCollum (b.1944), which features both bulk<br />

quantity and industrial casting.


228<br />

does not rest with mere casting however. Koons replaces the readymade object as a<br />

source with photographs in later works and commissions more elaborate ‘readilymades’,<br />

such as the gilded life-size portrait of pop star Michael Jackson reclining<br />

with his pet monkey in matching costumes, in Michael Jackson and Bubbles (1988)<br />

(Figure 121) a large painted porcelain work in an edition of three. Again the contrast<br />

between the material and product is prominent. While merchandising for a pop star<br />

might conceivably stretch to small and cheap figurines of some kind, a life-size and<br />

gilded porcelain product line is unlikely, to say the least. By the same token, while<br />

porcelain figures look to popular and traditional persons for their iconography, to<br />

adopt a contemporary figure from the world of pop music, or to work on this<br />

impressive scale is equally unlikely. So the work is not so much about<br />

merchandising excess or porcelain’s cautious iconography as the unlikely and<br />

hitherto unwanted area in between. In fact the work demonstrates the production<br />

process for just where the respective markets or institutions abandon it and in doing<br />

finds an outrageously up-market niche, ‘readily-made’ for art.<br />

The ‘readily-made’ is applied in the work of Charles Ray (b.1953) Englishmen<br />

Damien Hirst (b.1965) and partners Jake (b.1965) and Dinos (b.1962) Chapman, as<br />

well as Mexican, Gabriel Orozco (b. 1962) amongst others. Ray’s best-known work,<br />

Firetruck (1993) enlarged a child’s toy to full scale, while other works offer unusual<br />

variations on fibreglass mannequins, generally associated with retail, museum or<br />

educational display. Hirst’s preserved animal specimens in imposing vitrines also<br />

return to the issue of exhibition display while sampling scientific and educational<br />

practice. The Chapmans offer even more extreme variations on mannequins while<br />

Orozco’s LA.D.S. (1993) (Figure 122) customises a Citroen to a pointedly narrow<br />

purpose. 346 The ‘readily-made’ also encompasses the ki<strong>net</strong>ic and unlikely<br />

commissions in engineering. In the latter half of the ni<strong>net</strong>ies the work of Fleming<br />

Wim Delvoye (b.1965) and Roxy Paine (b.1966) for example feature machines of<br />

standard components and principles harnessed to striking ends. 347 Lastly, the<br />

346 On Hirst and The Chapmans, see Brooks Adams et al., Sensation: Young British Artists from<br />

the Saatchi Collection (catalogue) London, 1997, pp. 92-99 and pp. 68-69 respectively, Sarah<br />

Kent, Shark infested waters: the Saatchi collection of British art in the 90s, London, 1994,<br />

Currentartpics 25 and 91. On Ray, see Jefferey Deitch, Young Americans: New American Art in<br />

the Saatchi Collection, (catalogue) London, 1996.<br />

347 On Delvoye, see Wim Delvoye et al., Wim Delvoye, New York, 1998 and Dan Cameron et al,<br />

Wim Delvoye: Cloaca, new and improved, New York, 2002 and website www.cloaca.be (2003-<br />

4). On Paine see Jonathan Fineberg, Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being, New York/London,


229<br />

‘readily-made’ is not always the result of the artist commissioning industry, but can<br />

also be the result of the artist’s own product serving both art and industry. The<br />

work of film and television special effects and model makers, such as London-based<br />

Australian Ron Mueck (b.1958) and Julian La Verdiere (b.1971) apply the same<br />

skills and materials to more unlikely projects for art, although this very promiscuity<br />

also tends to weaken the sample. The work is then about too minor an industry or<br />

samples too little of it. 348<br />

Where works forgo the bulk readymade and extravagant ‘readily-made’ for a wider<br />

mix of materials, variously assembled along the lines of a film or stage set, trade<br />

stand or science exhibit, complete with laboratory tests, demonstrations or<br />

performances, they also confront a dilution of sample. Materials here comprise the<br />

artefacts of a lifestyle, stereotype, topical or historical issue, and here too must look<br />

progressively further a field in order to avoid the trivial or predictable. Works<br />

combine and conflate issues, but also are drawn to the more diffuse and peripheral,<br />

so that at some point they also begin to reflect art’s own presentation and practices.<br />

For example an installation may in fact include or comprise of a collection of ready<br />

or ‘readily-made’ paintings, as in the work of collective Group Material, Americana<br />

(1985) created for the Whitney Museum’s Biennial survey of that year, and<br />

somewhat later, the exhibition of Thrift Store Paintings (1990) by Jim Shaw<br />

(b.1952). 349 In both cases the collections deal with ‘bad’ or generally rejected works,<br />

in uneasy contrast with preceding Neo-Expressionist works, but this also allows the<br />

work to sample collecting or curatorial practice over the usual stylistic issues. The<br />

role of the artist here converges with that of the collector or curator, and while it is<br />

common enough for artists to act as collectors or curators, just as they often act as<br />

critics, it is quite another thing to take such work as works of art 350 . The work of the<br />

curator and the artist now shape toward an interesting conflict.<br />

2000, pp. 496-499, and Anne Hammond, ‘Roxy Paine at James Cohan’ (review) in Art in<br />

America, October 2001, p. 156.<br />

348 On Mueck, see Brooks Adams et al, Sensation: Young British Artists from the Saatchi<br />

Collection, (catalogue) London, 1997, pp. 126-128. On La Verdiere see Marcia E. Vetrocq,<br />

‘Julian La Verdiere’s Imperial Designs’ in Art in America, July 2001, pp. 98-103.<br />

349 See Jim Shaw, Thrift Store Paintings: paintings found in thrift stores, Hollywood/California,<br />

1990.<br />

350 The curatorial works of Kosuth from this time, such as The Play of the Unmentionable (1990)<br />

at the Brooklyn Museum in New York, are sometimes accorded this double status.


230<br />

This convergence of projects also occurs where installations increasingly deal in<br />

issues of décor and interior design, for example in the work from the ni<strong>net</strong>ies of<br />

Cuban Jorge Pardo (b.1963) Andrea Zittel (b.1965) Austrian Franz West (b.1947)<br />

German Tobias Rehberger (b.1966) and Fleming Carsten Höller (b. 1961) amongst<br />

others 351 . Such works favour the co-ordination of furniture and fittings not so much<br />

along standard stylistic lines or customary applications, as more unusual alignments<br />

of materials, colour, lighting and function, and while recalling the Modernist project<br />

to design, resist the inclusion of established works of painting or sculpture for<br />

example, at least until the end of the century. Yet attention to items of décor,<br />

nevertheless approaches collection and museum practices, and has a striking<br />

counterpart in the renewed attention to such contextual issues in art museum<br />

presentation at this time. 352<br />

Furthermore, the increasing scope for curators in this period mirrors the<br />

convergence of the work as a collection, with the work in a collection. It is<br />

significant for example that regular international surveys of contemporary art,<br />

generally on a bi-annual or tri-annual basis, not only proliferate at this time but also<br />

are initiated in regional centres, non-western and third world countries, for example<br />

in Havana, Cuba (1984) Istanbul, Turkey and Mercosur, Brazil (1987) Lyon, France<br />

(1991) Dakar, Senegal (1992) Sharjah, U.A.E. (1993) Kwangui, South Korea, and<br />

Johannesburg, South Africa (1995) Shanghai, China and Manifesta, held at shifting<br />

locations in central Europe (1996) Mexico City, and Berlin, Germany, (1998)<br />

Liverpool, U.K. (1999) and followed by Tokamachi and Echigo Tsumari, Japan,<br />

Melbourne, Australia (2000) and Yokahama, Japan, Barcelona, Spain, Tirana<br />

Albania, and Busan (renaming Pusan) South Korea (2001). The international scope<br />

of these exhibitions generally calls upon an equally international team of curators, so<br />

that the activities of the curator are globalised in a more familiar sense of the word.<br />

Yet they also provide opportunities to broaden the range of issues necessary to<br />

351 On Pardo see Currentartpics 100, on Zittel, Currentartpics 93 and on Rehberger,<br />

Currentartpics 8.<br />

352 The year 2000 for example brings a radical revision in the hanging practises of prestigious<br />

museums such as the Museum of Modern Art in New York, and the Tate’s new Museum, (Tate<br />

Modern) in London, not only asserting greater co-ordination in décor and objects, in the interest<br />

of a thematic rather than chronological ordering, but generally granting the curator a more active<br />

and ‘creative’ role. For commentary, see Charles Stuckey, ‘Modern Starts: Raising The Barr?’ in<br />

Art in America, May 2000, pp. 51-57, Eleanor Heartney, ‘Chronology Dethroned’ in Art in<br />

America, May 2001, pp. 55-63.


231<br />

works of expanded materials and to the institutional co-operation noted, and indeed<br />

particularly foster just such works. The curator in other words, continues the<br />

project of expanded materials in this way. But to appreciate this prospect more<br />

fully, the course of ‘Globalist’ painting must now also be considered.<br />

The course of abstraction in painting has been traced through projection to more<br />

obvious pattern, up to and including repeating pictures and even the single central<br />

motif or icon, while materials and techniques are pushed to three-dimensionality in<br />

experiments with the chemistry of pigments. Summarised thus, it is difficult to see<br />

where abstraction in painting might go from Post Modernism, since it would seem<br />

to have come full circle, and to confront only more concrete depiction.<br />

Understandably, some advocates of abstraction around this time pronounce the<br />

death of painting. 353 But while it unquestionably marks a turning point, in retrospect<br />

the change is not quite so drastic. Where Late Modernism toyed with more obvious<br />

pattern, and Post-Modernism wholeheartedly embraced it, ‘Globalism’ can now<br />

afford to ignore it. The emphasis shifts back to complexity and diffuseness of<br />

pattern, and pattern is less directly tied to textiles or familiar printing. Yet the move<br />

away from obvious pattern unavoidably resembles the move toward it under<br />

Modernism. ‘Globalist’ abstraction returns to or coincides with Modernism (Early<br />

and Late) to some extent and while this only confirms the gloomiest of forecasts,<br />

the reversal does not amount to a simple retreat.<br />

This is because Post-Modernist abstraction has projected to even the simplest, most<br />

traditional or familiar of patterns, so that painting now possesses patterns or<br />

pictures them with greater authority and means. To re-engage Modernist pattern or<br />

abstraction at this time is not therefore simply to re-trace the road to more concrete<br />

depiction, but rather to trace a road to more obscure pattern. Hence there is a<br />

reversal in the way depiction and painting first use pattern for abstraction and then<br />

are used by it. Those qualities to Modernist abstract that resisted easy or accepted<br />

pattern now seem too pattern-like and invite more elusive measures. The price for<br />

projection from depiction and painting to pattern is this subsequent dilation of<br />

pattern. The ‘Globalist’ project for abstraction is about this furthering of pattern. It<br />

353 See for example, Douglas Crimp, ‘The End of Painting’, October 16, 1981, pp. 69-86.<br />

Significantly, the essay is concerned mainly with abstraction.


232<br />

is not enough to simply repeat Modernist abstraction of course, or to build mere<br />

variation upon them. To sample furthering of pattern, rather than further<br />

patterning, the ‘Globalist’ work must offer more radical variation. Properties<br />

sampled must undermine or overload current or established pattern. The project<br />

may be divided into roughly two strategies, the pattern colliding with competing<br />

pattern, or the pattern collapsed under internal variation. We look first to the<br />

collision of patterns.<br />

The work of Terence La Noue (b.1941) at this time is among the most inclusive and<br />

impressive of competing pattern. La Noue’s work arises not so much from Pattern<br />

and Decoration but rather from a steady accretion upon minimalist process and<br />

system throughout the late seventies. Works maintain an unstretched and<br />

elaborately shaped canvas, discard single and central motifs for layers of gestural<br />

amendments, include smaller patterns of flat colours and strict geometry, vigorous<br />

scrapings, glazes and sundry distress. This ‘maximising’ culminates in works such as<br />

Varieties of Coral – Zen Deliverance (1984) (Figure 123). Here the work offers virtually<br />

a ‘layout’ or anthology of Modernism, in the tiny Klee-like colour grids, the column<br />

of (Miro-like?) dark lateral shapes to the left of centre with their vaguely notational<br />

alignment to the vertical stripe to the left, (and repeated on a smaller scale to the<br />

lower left) the Kandinsky-like red compound of arcs to the right, the dense, Wolslike<br />

reworking beneath, and the rugged and ravaged grounds that recall a Tapies or<br />

Fautrier. Yet for all that, the work never quite falls into mere eclecticism, rather<br />

finds tenuous but tenacious links between them in matters of line or colour, shape<br />

or scale, insidiously unravels and re-ravels. The title also points to a ‘layout’ of<br />

kinds, to the classing of nature, or problems in the nature of classing and mystical<br />

resolution. 354 La Noue’s work is notable for the breadth of pattern and patient<br />

facture, but much work at this time tends to a narrower, less effective range.<br />

Later work shifts focus, jettisons heavy and patiently worked grounds and the<br />

impression of a ravaged relic, for lighter, brighter, more brushstroke-driven pattern.<br />

Work from the late eighties and early ni<strong>net</strong>ies by Englishwoman Fiona Rae (b.1963)<br />

such as Untitled (one in brown) (1989) (Figure 124), German Albert Oehlen (b.1954)<br />

such as Untitled (1993) (Figure 125) and Lydia Dona (b.1955) all cultivate striking<br />

354 On La Noue, see Dore Ashton, Terence La Noue, New York, 1992.


233<br />

dissonance of pattern and arrive at a sprawling array, although works here tend to<br />

look to other developments, to the example of Polke and Richter in places, more<br />

than the maximising of Minimalism. Pattern here also falls into parts or lesser<br />

patterns. Rae and Oehlen for example adopt various stripes, flat colours and hard<br />

edges, against a range of facture, embracing biomorphic, more concrete and<br />

notational elements. 355 ‘Globalist’ abstraction thus arrives at certain parallels to<br />

simultaneous and successive depiction, to ‘bad’ depiction and the poor sample, but<br />

also serves as a metaphor and map for perhaps the psychology of painful and partial<br />

sortings, of conflicting cares, and personal globalising strategies. Maintaining the<br />

momentum of furthering pattern inevitably draws work back toward expanded<br />

materials. Amongst the most inclusive in this respect is the work of U.S.-based<br />

Argentinean Fabian Marcaccio (b.1963) in the later ni<strong>net</strong>ies, where work stretches<br />

from more concrete depiction to print sources and means, to novel pigmented<br />

solutions and sculptural additions including the ‘readily-made’ and to an<br />

architectural scale that converges with the concerns of a Stockholder, for<br />

example. 356<br />

Equally, the momentum drives work on to more concrete depiction, to print and<br />

‘layout’ samples, and to a direction presently to be examined more closely. Other<br />

opportunity for furthering pattern arises in works exploiting the transformation<br />

available in computer-based styles of depiction and design at this time. Computer<br />

assisted design prompts its own abstraction and coincides with print-based sampling<br />

in painting in some ways. Artists such as Germans Franz Ackermann (b.1967) in<br />

works like Untitled or Mental Map: Evasion III (1996) (Figure 126) and Frank Nitsche<br />

(b.1964) in works likes GLP-26-2001 (2001) (Figure 127) London-based Sarah<br />

Morris (b.1967) in works like Federal Reserve (Capital) (2001) (Figure 128) and Miamibased<br />

Nigerian Odile Donald Odita (b.1970) in works like Descent (2001) (Figure<br />

129), all press pattern against such new depiction at the end of the century. Pattern<br />

is projected to the graded angles of perspective (in Odita, matched to lateral,<br />

perhaps Ken<strong>net</strong>h Noland-like stripes, in Morris, to the lines and right angles of<br />

355 On Rae, see Brooks Adams et al, Sensation: Young British Artists from the Saatchi Collection,<br />

(catalogue) London, 1990, pp. 150-155 and Currentartpics 10. On Oehlen, see Uta Grosenick and<br />

Burkhard Riemenschneider, Art Now, Cologne, 2001, pp. 352-355 and Currentartpics 79.<br />

356 On Marcaccio, see Nancy Princenthal, ‘Fabian Marcaccio: Paintant’s Progress’ in Art in<br />

America, January 2002, pp. 62-65, p.119 and Gregory Volk, ‘Fabian Marcaccio at Gorney Borwn<br />

+ Lee’, (review) in Art in America, April 2000, p. 150.


234<br />

perhaps a Mondrian) to the curves of industrial design (in Nitsche) and to the<br />

recycled floral motifs and ‘layout’ (in Ackermann) exploiting the distinctive<br />

flexibilities of 3-D computer modelling. 357<br />

By contrast, the collapse of pattern deals in the softer, looser, more permeable or<br />

permissible in pattern. It is sampled for just those ambiguous features where sorting<br />

or styling stalls. This is the path less travelled, or perhaps less noticed in ‘Globalist’<br />

abstraction, but is forged with striking enterprise in the work of Jonathan Lasker<br />

(b.1948). Lasker’s work derives from Pattern and Decoration and New Image<br />

Painting, in initial silhouette-like motifs, but print patterns sampled here are in turn<br />

clearly derived from painting and biomorphic abstraction, so that sample is of a<br />

degraded or banal quality to design and affords ambiguity with painting. It is ‘bad’<br />

sampling of ‘bad’ pattern. But while this furthers Pattern and Decoration, pattern<br />

properly has been little furthered. However, around 1985 Lasker introduces a new<br />

economy of means in works such as Spring Training (1985) (Figure 130). Elements<br />

here are still notably perfunctory, a range of casually drawn circles in maroon, set<br />

against areas of coarsely hatched lines of the same colour, both distributed over a<br />

central ochre trapezium surrounded by green. But variety of line between circles and<br />

hatches is not only between smooth and idle against impasto and peremptory, but<br />

more unusually, between outline against ‘fill’.<br />

Where line can now function as outline or ‘fill’, pattern is radically furthered.<br />

Orderings within circles and hatches and across them are central to Spring Training,<br />

but greater linear integration dominates Lasker’s subsequent work. An Object of Love<br />

(1991) (Figure 131) and The Value of Pictures (1993) (Figure 132) stretch line from<br />

outline to ‘fill’, and with width of line to shape or colour, so that line and pattern<br />

collapse in myriad variation. Yet works also maintain a certain dry detachment, less<br />

a matter of the ‘bad’ or bland pattern, than of a necessary distance from standard<br />

patterning. The work has the feeling of a classroom or textbook demonstration in<br />

357 On Ackermann and Morris, see Uta Grosenick and Burkhard Riemenschneider, Art Now,<br />

Cologne, 2002, pp. 12-15, pp. 308-311, respectively and Currentartpics 2 and 28, respectively.<br />

On Nitsche, see Melissa Kuntz, ‘Frank Nitsche at Leo Koenig’ (review) in Art in America, July<br />

2002, pp. 95-96, Anna Moszynska, Eberhard Haverkost, Frank Nitsche, Thomas Scheibitz,<br />

Goldener, der Springer, Das Kalte Herz, (catalogue) London, 2000 and Currentartpics 70. On<br />

Odita, see Gregory Volk, ‘Odili Donald Odita at Florence Lynch ‘Riva’, in Art in America, May<br />

2002, pp. 147-148, Gean Moreno, ‘Odili Donald Odita, Miami Art Museum’ in Flash Art,<br />

October 2002, p. 104 and Currentartpics 14.


235<br />

this way, in the simple generic shapes and crisp composition, the even and<br />

continuous line of curves, perhaps sampling felt-tip or ballpoint pen. Work may<br />

seem flippant and ironic, bored or grim, or blithely optimistic in the way that the<br />

confident yet remote lesson can seem. Work thus achieves a furthering of pattern at<br />

the cost of nearing the instructional diagram. 358<br />

Lasker’s lessons in line are applied with equal imagination in the work of L.A-based<br />

Monique Prieto (b.1962) German Günther Förg (b.1952) and Frenchman Bernard<br />

Frize (b.1954) amongst others in the ni<strong>net</strong>ies 359 . The later work of Marden reengages<br />

line in the early eighties and increasingly attends to fields of short curves<br />

and angles, culminating in the Cold Mountain series (1988-91). But while Marden’s<br />

work clearly departs from Post-Modernism, it is less clear that it arrives at<br />

‘Globalism’. Cold Mountain 2 (1988-91) (Figure 133) reaches its field through<br />

distinctive brush weight or paint loadings that recall Modernist notational work,<br />

such as that of Tobey or Hartung, yet hardly collapses pattern by this. Where<br />

pattern is challenged is in the relative simplification of field, not quite to a figure<br />

range, but in which something of a map or ‘layout’ emerges. The title encourages<br />

this.<br />

But if Marden’s patterns seem peripheral to ‘Globalist’ abstraction in painting, taken<br />

together with certain surrounding work they assume a more assured furthering. For<br />

example, growing appreciation of contemporary Australian Aboriginal paintings at<br />

this time, such as Ceremonial Ground at Kulkuta (1981) (Figure 134) by Anatjari<br />

Tjanpitjinpa (n.d.a.) or Wakiripiri Jukurrpa (1985) (Figure 135) by Liddy Napanangka<br />

Walker, Topsy Napanangka and Judy Nampijinpa Granites (N.D.A..) with their<br />

modified ‘dreaming’ maps, urges just this. 360 Similarly, the work of Englishwoman<br />

358 On Lasker, see Hans-Michael Herzog (ed.) Jonathan Lasker: paintings 1977-97, Ostfildern-<br />

Ruit/Germany/New York, 1997, Rainer Crone and David Moos, Jonathan Lasker: Telling the<br />

Tales of Painting, Stuttgart, 1993, David Carrier, ‘Painting into Depth: Jonathan Lasker’s Recent<br />

Art’ in The Aesthete in The City; The Philosophy and Practice of American Abstract Painting in<br />

the 1980s, Philadelphia, 1994, pp. 181-189 and Currentartpics 32.<br />

359 On Frize, see also Currentartpics 62.<br />

360 This kind of contemporary Aboriginal painting is usually taken to commence in the early<br />

seventies, at the desert settlement of Papunya, see for example Wally Caruana, Aboriginal Art,<br />

London, Thames and Hudson 1993. However, its wider appreciation occurs in the eighties,<br />

particularly the later eighties, at international surveys such as the controversial Magicians Of The<br />

Earth exhibition at the Pompidou Centre in Paris in 1989, curated by Jean-Hubert Martin. It thus<br />

also represents Globalism in the more usual sense. For interesting discussion of Magicians of the<br />

Earth, see Benjamin H. D. Buchloh, ‘The Whole Earth Show, an interview with Jean-Hubert


236<br />

Therese Oulton (b. 1953) at this time, such as Deposition (1989) (Figure 136) samples<br />

an accretion of field, although by less linear means, and convincingly maps cellular,<br />

crystalline or even pattern of weaving or crochet. 361 Combined with Lasker, such<br />

work argues for Marden’s work as pattern furthered into a more abstract mapping<br />

or ‘layout’, as something like intuitive assembly from one to multi-directional<br />

reference, and a mapping of the achieved equilibrium, at ‘mountain-sized’<br />

intervals. 362 Finally, while such mapping holds for the biomorphic, it is less<br />

persuasive for stricter geometry. For example the work of Scully such as Remember<br />

(1986) (Figure 137) for all its variation of stripe by colour, length, width, direction,<br />

edge and facture, stubbornly project stripe over ‘layout’ or mapping, and so remain<br />

further pattern rather than furthered, Post-Modernist rather than ‘Globalist’. 363<br />

Since pattern is again traced to ‘layout’ for abstraction, it is a suitable point at which<br />

to consider the other side of the coin. ‘Globalism’ similarly redirects more concrete<br />

depiction. Having sampled prints and the ‘bad’ in Modernism, interest gradually<br />

shifts to styles for depiction more generally and so to their content; to how current<br />

or traditional genres are sampled or extended, not so much by sole or multiple<br />

instances, but rather rare or novel instance. Works look to a wider economy of<br />

pictorial usage, and to its subtle reshaping by painting’s participation. ‘Bad’ or Neo-<br />

Expressionist painting only adds to the impetus as growing acceptance sharpens its<br />

stylistic identity and bluntens its impact. Concrete depiction can hardly return to<br />

Modernism from here, since pattern and print sampling have now permanently<br />

altered the project for depiction and painting. Instead the task for painting becomes<br />

the sorting of pictures by bigger formal bites, so to speak. It essentially reconstructs<br />

genres. The difference now is the radically widened ambit granted genres.<br />

The merging of pattern and picture in repeating pictures and ‘layout’ is an important<br />

feature to ‘Globalist’ painting, but when advocates at this time insist that the<br />

distinction no longer holds or is unimportant, they assert at best a half truth. For<br />

Martin’, in Art in America, May 1989, pp. 150-58, 211 and 213, and Eleanor Heartney, ‘The<br />

Whole Earth Show Part II’, in Art in America, July 1989, pp. 91-96.<br />

361 On Oulton, see Sarak Kent ‘Therese Oulton’ (interview) in Flash Art, April, 1986, pp. 40-44.<br />

362 On Marden, see Klaus Kertess, Brice Marden, paintings and drawings, New York, 1992 and<br />

Currentartpics 18.<br />

363 On Scully, see David Carrier, ‘Colour in the recent Work of Sean Scully’ in The Aesthete in<br />

the City, The Philosophy and Practice of American Abstract Painting in the 1980s, Philadelphia,<br />

1994, pp. 245-253.


237<br />

they fail to explain what is now sampled in such works that allows the distinction<br />

between the abstract and the concrete to be thus downplayed or ignored. Actually<br />

pattern and picture no longer matter to painting only when their adherence to<br />

broader categories of pattern or genre becomes paramount as a sample. The sample<br />

is properly to the work of rare instance for such styles, to its conformity to and<br />

confusion of these, to its small but sure contribution to the maintenance of genre. It<br />

is as true to say that painting or printing is no longer quite the issue for depiction<br />

here. Such work is surveyed looking firstly to the convergence of pattern and<br />

‘layout’, secondly to the divergence of ‘bad’ painting and allegory to ‘Globalist’<br />

genres.<br />

Pattern and print are paired with particular piquancy in the pivotal work of Los<br />

Angles-based Lari Pittman (b.1952). Pittman mines a rich seam of ornamental<br />

motifs from décor stencilling to standard icons drawn from common graphics and<br />

signage by the mid eighties. Again such sources also reflect growing computerbased<br />

practice, and exploit deft superimposition or transparency, inversions,<br />

reversals and variation of scale for a given image. Indeed precision and complexity<br />

achieved thus can make the work seem hardly like a painting at all. Moreover, work<br />

tends to flat colours and hard edges, strengthening the sense of a print sample, as in<br />

the slightly later example, Regenerative and Needy (1991) (Figure 138). Yet rampant<br />

variation often threatens to overwhelm underlying pattern or ‘layout’. Work at this<br />

time is typically structured around a distinct if wavering asymmetry, here; the offkilter<br />

black tree trunk flanked by personified houses at its base, and inset black and<br />

white interiors across the top. Linking embellishments, such as the ‘69’- encased<br />

butterflies or flowers, and the white mice on their straight paths, further undermine<br />

and underline teetering symmetry. ‘Layout’ consequently reflects the latitude granted<br />

variation, and its uneasy accommodation. Latitude of variation is often carried<br />

through to themes of sexuality, to physical endurance or distress, and to natural<br />

transformations or cycles. Yet the sense, here and for most ‘Globalist layouts’, is<br />

often of a common and prosaic print style exploited to private or obscure ends, or<br />

the converse. Either way, painting now adds a rare instance to a general or global<br />

style, by testing variation. 364<br />

364 On Pittman, see Howard Fox, (organiser) Lari Pittman (catalogue with essays by Dave Hickey<br />

and Paul Schimmel) Los Angeles, 1996. Paul Bayley, (ed.) Lari Pittman: Paintings 1992-98<br />

(catalogue) Manchester, 1998 and Currentartpics 53.


238<br />

The use of stereotypical silhouettes, such as the mice, cat or tree in the above<br />

example, are prominent in Pittman’s work of the late eighties, and silhouettes are<br />

pursued more exclusively in the ni<strong>net</strong>ies, in the work of artists such as Englishman<br />

Gary Hume (b.1962) Lisa Ruyter (b.1968) Kara Walker (b.1969) and German<br />

Thomas Scheibitz (b.1968) 365 . Silhouettes here are less a sample of printing<br />

technique than a shorthand derivation for convenient icons. Tracing a photograph<br />

or standard picture to outline and filled by colour codes for advertising, instruction<br />

or other co-ordinating schemes, is obviously a pervasive practice. Pictures are<br />

streamlined, and such streamlining may be sampled. Where colours and silhouettes<br />

are applied in other schemes and to other objects, such easy icon-making itself is<br />

stretched, so that colours and silhouettes are re-mapped, as they re-map.<br />

Controversial issues or objects are often the occasion of similar re-mapping,<br />

although ‘layout’ and depiction are not always served in this way. The work of<br />

David Wojnarowicz (1954-92) in the mid eighties for example addresses explicit<br />

homoeroticism in works such as Water (1987) (Figure 139) and coupled with themes<br />

of pervasive spawning, imprisonment and destruction, builds a metaphor – on a<br />

‘layout’ – for implicit contagion (this at the height of the AIDS epidemic, which was<br />

to claim the artist). Yet such work may also be censured for a certain ‘literary’ or<br />

illustrational tendency, since style of depiction here never quite focuses on a<br />

distinctive wider practice, (such as silhouettes) but rather is timidly painterly or<br />

weakly print-sourced. Consequently, pictures serve the issue but are not served by it,<br />

and resulting ‘layout’ reflects this weakness. 366 Pressing social issues are more<br />

successfully aligned in later work by artists such as Chicago-based Kerry James<br />

Marshall (b.1955) in The Lost Boys (1993) (Figure 140) and L.A.-based Filipino<br />

Manuel Ocampo (b.1965) in Once Again, First in thee World (1993) (Figure 141). Here<br />

‘layout’, metaphor and allegory are less tied to printing than to the tired emblems<br />

and banners of community activism. Marshall’s work addresses the death of Afro-<br />

American youth through crime (the joyride car and pistol) and police enforcement<br />

(the blue, bullet-blossoming tree) but also makes painting a bigger window for and<br />

365 On Hume, see Currentartpics 59, on Ruyter, Currentartpics 13, on Walker, Currentartpics 64<br />

and on Scheibitz, Currentartpics 70.<br />

366 On Wojnarowicz, see Fineberg, Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being, New York/London, 2000,<br />

pp. 459-463.


239<br />

by this lamentation. 367 Likewise, Ocampo’s work deals in conspiracy and colonial<br />

oppression, but in also sampling these debased styles, complete with spurious<br />

ageing and defacement, participates in stretching and subverting a wider practice. 368<br />

‘Globalist layout’ also deals in the overlapping and stretching of comic strip and<br />

painting styles, as in the delirious ‘art-comics’ of west coast artists such as Robert<br />

Williams (b.1943) Gary Panter (b.1950) or Raymond Pettibon (b.1957) – each<br />

happily interchanging publication, exhibition or installation as means as well as<br />

extending matters of text and iconography. Throughout the ni<strong>net</strong>ies controversy<br />

tends to become more mixed or obscure as ‘layouts’ project more ambitiously. By<br />

the end of the century ‘Globalist layouts’ range from the flow charts for economic<br />

and political conspiracies by Mark Lombardi (1951-2000) to the psychedelic collages<br />

of Fred Tomaselli (b. 1956) the cartoon-inspired charts and myths for sub-ge<strong>net</strong>ic<br />

or sub-atomic events in the work of Mathew Ritchie (b.1964) the more abstract<br />

cartoon figures of Japanese Takashi Murakami (b.1962) or Inka Essenhigh (b.1969)<br />

and even to some of the caprices of L.A.-based Laura Owens (b.1970) 369 . Ritchie’s<br />

work such as Parents and Children (2000) (Figure 142) in fact converges with the<br />

concerns of a Franz Ackermann in its complex geometry and 3-D modelling, as well<br />

as in literal projection to gallery walls for temporary mural or installation works.<br />

Painting here follows not only Le Witt and score or script for painting, but<br />

integration to computer-based design and mapping practices. 370<br />

Looking away from ‘layout’, to the course of the single integral picture, the move<br />

away from ‘bad’ painting and allegory is now tracked to a more general engagement<br />

with genre. As noted, the acceptance and greater adoption of ‘bad’ painting tends to<br />

cancel its effectiveness. A remedy is not to be found in backing further away from<br />

Modernism either, or in looking to a ‘badder’ sample by including more traditional<br />

styles, although this tendency is no<strong>net</strong>heless widely pursued in the early eighties. But<br />

367 On Marshall, see Kerry James Marshall et al., Kerry James Marshall, New York, 2000, David<br />

Pagel, ‘Kerry James Marshall’ in 43 rd Biennial Exhibition of Contemporary American Painting,<br />

(catalogue) Christopher C. French (ed.) Washington D.C. 1994, pp. 68-9 and Currentartpics 95.<br />

368 On Ocampo, see Pilar Perez et al., Manuel Ocampo – Heridas de LA lengua: selected works,<br />

Santa Monica, 1997 and David Pagel, ‘Manuel Ocampo’ in 43 rd Biennial Exhibition of<br />

Contemporary American Painting, (catalogue) Christopher C. French (ed.) Washington D. C.<br />

1994, pp. 72-3.<br />

369 On Murakami see Currentartpics 49, on Essenhigh, Currentartpics 85.<br />

370 On Ritchie, see Nancy Princenthal, ‘The Laws of Pandemonium’ in Art in America, May,<br />

2001, pp. 144-149 and Currentartpics 19.


240<br />

a broader ‘badness’ by this route tends to become too diffuse or elusive and really<br />

amounts to no more than the conservativism described in Chapter Twelve as<br />

‘Interstyle’. However where work focuses on only certain features of continuity or<br />

metonymy for depiction, for example in matters of lighting or weather, elegant<br />

simplification or exaggeration of proportion, even caricature, and significantly draws<br />

upon much older styles, from Romanticism and Neo-Classicism – the result does<br />

not so much avoid conservatism and cliché as exceed them. Works are now hyperclichéd,<br />

or perhaps camp, and sample this blend of object and picture, or genre,<br />

albeit often in a crude or ‘bad’ sorting. Allegory may remain, but is no longer the<br />

focus of sampling. Sample now is of cosy or creepy little pictorial worlds of the<br />

past, and by rank cliché or associated ‘badness’.<br />

Amongst the more concerted efforts in this are the work of the ‘New Image<br />

Glasgow’ painters in Scotland, including Steven Campbell (b. 1953) Ken Currie<br />

(b.1960) Peter Howson (b.1958) and Adrian Wisniewski (b. 1958), the<br />

‘Hypermannerism’ of Italian artists such as Stefano Di Stasio (b. 1948) Ubaldo<br />

Bartolini (b.1944) and Omar Galliani (b.1954) grouped in the book of that title by<br />

Italo Tomassoni from 1986 and the German ‘Berlin-Braunschweig Group’<br />

exhibitions of this time, including Peter Chevalier (b. 1953) Stephanus Heidarker<br />

(b.1959) Herman Albert (b.1937) Andreas Weishaupt (b.1957) and Thomas<br />

Schindler (b.1959). 371 While settings range from the pastoral and idyllic (in the work<br />

of the Italians) to the urban and strife-torn (in the work of the Scots) and persons<br />

depicted range from Neo-Classical models to Romantic grotesque, and broad even<br />

comic stereotypes, works are surprisingly consistent in feel. Stressing ‘genre-ness’<br />

gives them a curious detachment, at once amusing, in treating weighty or difficult<br />

themes in a playful, simplistic manner, yet equally, excluding greater involvement<br />

and perhaps registering an alarming isolation. Indeed, a recurrent persona in such<br />

work is the dreamy, unworldly youth, personifying just this detachment.<br />

Having sampled such cliché, to further the sample or refine genre then risks diluting<br />

effectiveness and lapsing into mediocrity. Because the hyper-cliché is so precarious<br />

371 On New Image Glasgow painting, see Keith Harlty et al., The Vigorous Imagination,<br />

(catalogue) Edinburgh, 1987 and William Hardie, Scottish Painting 1837 to the Present, (2 nd ed.)<br />

London, 1990. On Hypermannerism, see Italo Tomassoni, Hypermannerism (2 nd ed.) Rome,<br />

1992. On Berlin-Braunschweig Group, see Berhard Schulz, ‘The Return of Things’ Flash Art,<br />

May-June 1986, pp. 51-53.


241<br />

to maintain in this way; and because ‘genre-ness’ prompts more versions, the style<br />

quickly stalls or stagnates. Such work is often overlooked or dismissed for this<br />

reason. The lesser stereotype or stock setting, pursued for example in the work of<br />

Scotsman Stephan Conroy (b.1964) in the late ni<strong>net</strong>een eighties and early ni<strong>net</strong>ies,<br />

offers only a diminishing return on painting’s genres. 372 By the same token, other<br />

work at this time offers striking variation on person, setting and painting, only to<br />

elude any easy genre rather than fall into too many, such as the work of Hollandbased<br />

South African Marlene Dumas (b.1953) Englishman Tony Bevan (b.1951)<br />

and L.A.-based Kim Dingle (b.1951) 373 . Such work rather constitutes too rare an<br />

instance, and so also remains at arm’s length from ‘Globalism’ and stronger<br />

projection.<br />

But where painting’s genres fail, those of printing and other depiction suggest more<br />

promising avenues. The work of Belgian Luc Tuymans (b.1958) by the late ni<strong>net</strong>een<br />

eighties proceeds not from the clichés of traditional genres but from a kind of failed<br />

or ‘bad’ photo sampling. Indeed some work can initially seem like a careless or inept<br />

imitation of Richter. But where the looser brushstrokes and drawing of a Tuymans<br />

all but lose any sample of photography (especially in comparison with Richter) other<br />

features emerge. Framing or composition, an oblique or ‘long lens’ projection of<br />

picture plane for such objects and a sharpened tonal contrast survive, but are hardly<br />

more prominent than painting qualities of cursory detail and casual colouring. Also,<br />

a return to a more modest or ‘easel’ scale – a feature of much work of rare instance<br />

in the 90s – serves to distinguish instance. Combined, such qualities in fact now<br />

treat the object with a certain indifference, even contempt, whether the breast<br />

prepared for medical inspection in der diagnostische Blick VIII – the diagnostic view<br />

(1992) (Figure 143) or the poolside greeting in Suspended (1989) (Figure 144). The<br />

object is thus revised slightly, and equally its pictures or genre enlarged by a rare but<br />

valid instance. Painting thus builds or projects to a larger genre. Tuymans’ work<br />

draws on various photographic sources, including film and television in fostering his<br />

louche detachment, even pursues them to pattern or abstraction, but is generally<br />

strongest in his treatment of everyday objects and architecture at this time. 374<br />

372 On Conroy, see Gerard Haggerty, ‘Stephen Conroy’ (review) in Art News, Oct. 1995, p.148,<br />

Natasha Edwards, ‘Stephen Conroy’ (review) in Art Forum, October 1989, pp. 190-191.<br />

373 On Dumas see also Currentartpics 45, on Bevan, Currentartpics 9.<br />

374 On Tuymans, see Ulrich Loock et al., Luc Tuymans, London, 1996 and Currentartpics 43.


242<br />

Similar approaches are later adopted in the work of Elizabeth Peyton (b.1965) and<br />

Karen Kilimnik (b.1962) where the person is more of a priority. Peyton<br />

concentrates on male teenage idols with an appropriately adolescent wavering of<br />

diligence in execution, such as Jarvis (1996) (Figure 145) while Kilimnik tends to<br />

more pre-teen idols, such as ballerinas, but with a similar attention to depiction by<br />

and for adolescent or child 375 . Work accordingly stretches the genre with rare and<br />

more knowing instances. Other approaches to the person at this time combine<br />

more diverse sources and build broader genres. The work of John Currin (b.1962)<br />

begins with simple portraits that recall a passport or formal photograph, but blurs<br />

the format, often quite literally, with simplified and painterly features, rendering<br />

person and picture curiously caricatured, as Mary O’Connel (1989) (Figure 146). Rare<br />

instance here projects the portrait at just that point where photography and painting<br />

are least certain or likely, and participates thus in building a bigger genre. Currin<br />

further dilates portrait and person by drawing upon by-gone fashion photography<br />

and other illustration as well as the gaucherie of the primitive painter, much like<br />

Shaw’s thrift store specimens, in works such as The Never-Ending Story (1993) (Figure<br />

147). Persons and portrait are now poised between the amusing and pathetic, naïve<br />

and sophisticated, clichéd and eccentric, and threaten to diffuse and defuse their<br />

acute sample. Indeed rare instance here grants painting precisely the latitude sought<br />

by but unavailable to works of the hyper-cliché, in the extravagant stereotypes now<br />

augmented by theatrical pose or gesture, dated costume, make up and hairstyle,<br />

clumsy faces and romantic setting. 376 The difference between a Conroy and a Currin<br />

lies less in appetite for parody or pastiche than in willingness to extend genre to<br />

more photographic and mundane practices and to revel in the promiscuity. The<br />

difference between a Tuymans and a Currin, on the other hand, lies less in appetite<br />

for photographic and prosaic practices than in willingness to extend them to further<br />

painting and to revel in parody and pastiche.<br />

Currin’s mixture of sources is similarly found in the work of Lisa Yuskavage<br />

(b.1962) where the child-like, or doll-like persona is wedded to the poses and props<br />

375 On Kilimnik see also Currentartpics 55.<br />

376<br />

On Currin, see Frédéric Paul and Keith Seward, John Currin: Works: 1989-1995,<br />

Limoges/France/New York, 1995, Robert Rosenblum, John Currin, New York, 2003 and<br />

Currentartpics 11.


243<br />

of pin-ups and soft porn, as in Faucet (1995) (Figure 148). Here the token role of<br />

one disarms the rigid persona of the other. 377 Similar strategies are explored in the<br />

work of New York-based Hungarian Rita Ackermann (b.1967) such as Now I’m<br />

Gonna Take A Vacation (1994) (Figure 149) Englishwoman Nicky Hoberman<br />

(b.1967) and Robin Lowe (b.1959) amongst others in the mid ni<strong>net</strong>ies. 378 The<br />

person depicted as token or doll, often coincides with depiction of the child, in<br />

comics and cartoons, advertising, instruction and entertainment, so that work<br />

applying the token person to sensitive or difficult issues, particularly of sexuality or<br />

violence, runs the double risk of confusing child with token and of trivialising rather<br />

than clarifying issues. Either fault may provoke outrage, but generally the rewards<br />

warrant the risk. The child as token person is pervasive, from counselling in matters<br />

of household hygiene and dietary adequacy, assembling and operating new<br />

equipment, and fictively conducting open hostilities against relentless rivals, forces<br />

of nature or noisy neighbours, we are generally comfortable with a cute little person<br />

of uncertain maturity, frankly improbable proportions and questionable species.<br />

Little wonder the genre prompts curiosity on other issues, comfortably extends to<br />

painting.<br />

But while this genre is widespread, genres in the ‘Globalist’ sense tend to be more<br />

scattered and fleeting. Indeed, the rare instance where effective or successful<br />

necessarily ceases to be quite so rare and so contains an in-built obsolescence. The<br />

‘return to genres’ is thus hardly a return to the stricter or more stable formulations<br />

of the eighteenth century; much less a hierarchy headed by history painting.<br />

‘Globalist’ genres are built upon wider and shifting practices and must settle for a<br />

looser more precarious existence. For example Chinese Socialist Realism provides<br />

an opportunity for works of rare instance, such as those by Wang Ziwei (b.1963) or<br />

Yu Youhan (b.1943) in the early ni<strong>net</strong>ies, as a result of political and economic<br />

developments in China leading up to this point, and such instances rapidly exhaust<br />

or transform the genre. It follows that the project of rare instance itself, given<br />

sufficient practice, must in turn bear revision. It would seem to be fated to chase<br />

the diminishing genre with the ‘rarer’ instance. Yet to detect this at the time of<br />

377 On Yuskavage, see Claudia Gould (curator) Lisa Yuskavage, Philadelphia, 2001, Carey<br />

Lovelace, ‘Lisa Yuskavage: Fleshed Out’, in Art in America, July 2001, pp. 80-85 and<br />

Currentartpics 5.<br />

378 On Ackermann, see Anna Burns, ‘Children and Sexuality in the Visual Arts’ in Contemporary<br />

Visual Arts, issue 18, 1998, pp. 38-43.


244<br />

writing presents peculiar difficulties, for the later or ‘rarer’ instance may at this point<br />

be indistinguishable from the earlier or ‘too rare’ genre. But since a ‘Globalist’ genre<br />

for the portrait has been traced with some confidence to the token person and<br />

attendant roles, parallels and extensions suggest a starting point for new genres of<br />

landscape and still life.<br />

The token setting or landscape for example arises in models or gardens, centres<br />

mainly on architectural or urban planning and finds more elaborate versions in<br />

computer practice at this time. The work of Germans Dirk Skreber (b.1961) and<br />

Eberhard Haverkost (b.1967) and Dutchwoman Carla Klein (b.1970) towards the<br />

end of the century focus on similar models for urban space and ambiguous scale<br />

with surprising painterly latitude, as in Skreber’s Untitled (beyond Taxes) (1999) (Figure<br />

150) 379 . Such models also lend themselves to more abstract treatments, and<br />

converge with the patterns of 3-D modelling discussed earlier. 380 Tangential to this<br />

architectural landscape is the work of German Neo Rauch (b. 1960) the foremost<br />

artist of The New Leipzig School whose numbers are, significantly, often graduates<br />

of Der Hochschule für Grafik und Buchkunst Leipzig and draw explicitly upon<br />

standard illustration 381 . Rauch’s work at this time, such as Kühlraum (2002) (Figure<br />

151) and Hatz (2002) (Figure 152) takes up themes of costume or uniform, of<br />

collective or corporate activities and implements but continues them to coordinated<br />

livery and décor for surrounding architecture. Work also notably deals in<br />

bizarre production or cultivation, often slipshod or awry, and a ‘layout’ of picture<br />

that extends such failings, as in Tabu (2001) (Figure 153). Yet Rauch’s work is barely<br />

a rare instance of comics or instructional illustration in this, owes perhaps as much<br />

to Kitaj or Ernst, and teeters between rarer genre and too rare instance. 382<br />

Landscape arises differently in the work of London-based Canadian Peter Doig<br />

(b.1959) from the early ni<strong>net</strong>ies. Here the genre is the family recreational snapshot,<br />

the casually framed record of ‘The Ski Resort Holiday’, ‘The Sports Stadium<br />

379 On Haverkost see also Currentartpics 30.<br />

380 On Skreber, see Uta Grosenick, Burkhard Riemenschneider, Art Now, Cologne, 2002, pp.<br />

464-67.<br />

381 On The New Leipzig School see Gregory Volk, ’Figuring the New Germany’ in Art in<br />

America, June/July 2005 and related exhibition -<br />

http://www.centralpt.com/pageview.aspx?id=16256.<br />

382 On Rauch, see Alexander Von Gravenstein et al, Neo Rauch (catalogue)<br />

Maastricht/Netherlands/Ostfildern-Ruit/Germany/New York, 2002 and Currentartpics 15.


245<br />

Forecourt’, ‘Fishing on the lake’ and similar occasions. Rare instance is derived from<br />

casual tracings of the projected photograph with surprising washes of pallid but<br />

pristine colour against qualities not unlike those of a Tuymans, in general symmetry<br />

of framing, high contrast tonality and uncertain picture plane projection (or lens<br />

length), as in Telemarker (Pas des Chevres) (1996) (Figure 154). The effect however is<br />

quite the reverse of a Tuymans, in that outline and objects take on a brittle or frail<br />

quality, the picture now literally awash with ‘sympathetic’ colour, and metaphorically<br />

with sentiment. Yet the sentiment is for picture as well as object, or for genre. 383<br />

Less concerned with landscape, but also exploiting photographic genres are works<br />

by Damien Loeb (b.1971) and Delia Brown (b.1966) in the late ni<strong>net</strong>ies. Loeb deals<br />

in photomontage of cinematic spectacle and related illustration in works such as<br />

Anything Else (1998) (Figure 155) but genre here is perhaps too obvious or narrow,<br />

or instance not rare enough for the project at this point. In contrast Brown’s<br />

watercolours deal in glamorous parties by swimming pools and in mansions; feature<br />

the costumes and etiquette of the chic or social elite, and to an extent the framing<br />

and lens values of its typical photography. The genre clearly permeates television,<br />

cinema, advertising and gossip columns, yet instance here would seem to struggle<br />

for a firmer sample, since Brown’s drawing has neither the limp tracing of a Doig,<br />

the terse reduction of a Tuymans, nor the deft pastiche of a Currin. Does projection<br />

now allow or refuse such work? Similarly, the work of Englishman Glenn Brown<br />

(b.1966) throughout the ni<strong>net</strong>ies ranges across a number of broader genres, not<br />

exclusively photographic, such as science fiction illustration (and remotely a matter<br />

of landscape, perhaps) but here means of painting remains surprisingly close or<br />

common to the genre and as a result instance would seem less rare, or genre less<br />

interesting. Elsewhere in his work, traditional painting styles and works are sampled<br />

with Richter-like soft focus or blurring, in a virtuoso demonstration of technique,<br />

blending painting and photography in a telling rare instance, albeit of obvious<br />

genre 384 . Englishman Richard Patterson (b.1963) adopts a similar strategy at this<br />

time, in ‘layouts’ for, significantly, toy soldiers and urban landscapes.<br />

383 On Doig, see Terry T. Myers et al, Peter Doig blizzard seventy- seven, (catalogue),<br />

Kiel/Nürnberg/London, 1998 and Currentartpics 51.<br />

384 On Glenn Brown see also Currentartpics 37.


246<br />

Landscape here is traced back to the person or figure and is an opportunity to<br />

consider further projection for the person or portrait. Works by Englishwomen<br />

Jenny Saville (b. 1970) and New York-based Cecily Brown (b.1969) achieve<br />

prominence at the end of the century and provide telling contrast. Saville’s work is<br />

interesting for the way the work of rare instance now projects back upon painting.<br />

Her monumental studies in nude female obesity stand in stark contrast to the token<br />

and child-like dolls that elsewhere deal in female nudity, and while they share with<br />

more conservative painting, such as that of Lucien Freud (b.1922) an interest in the<br />

extreme specimens of human anatomy, Saville’s work is distinctive for its intimate<br />

or claustrophobic framing of the figure, together with imposing scale and dogged<br />

facture. These qualities now give her painting the quality of a retreat, or denial of<br />

the more social roles of the token or doll-like nude, as well as traditional studies of<br />

character, and project a more extreme privacy, and its attendant anxiety. They<br />

sample a ‘personal space’ genre - a vacuum really – and what can be made of the<br />

naked self there is distressingly, never quite enough. In works such as the towering<br />

Hem (1999) (Figure 156) the woman virtually smothers the picture plane, is caked in<br />

paint, as if in cosmetic, while closed eyes, limp limbs, sundry scars and mutilations<br />

extort an uneasy pathos. Nude and painting in fact now embody and express the<br />

bloated self-indulgence and indolence that ensue in vicious cycle with such massive<br />

insecurity and isolation. It is the flipside to the perky waifs and pro-active roles of a<br />

Yuskavage or Ackermann, and devastates a traditional genre for painting in forging<br />

a new one. 385<br />

By contrast, Cecily Brown’s work does not quite build a new genre, nor invigorate<br />

an old one but rather finds instances of a diminished one. In works such as One<br />

Touch Of Venus (1999) (Figure 157) the abstract and the concrete once more join in<br />

vigorous and intimate contest, but here with heavy hints of torsos, heads and limbs<br />

matched against an impressive array of painting technique, recalling De Kooning,<br />

and assuming an obvious sexual metaphor. Yet maintaining this balance and<br />

avoiding the ever-present biomorphic compromise comes at a cost, of a hectic and<br />

hectoring control. Works thus tend to the fussy and technical, the cautious and thin,<br />

in comparison with the facture of a De Kooning (such as Figure 36) or a Gorky, the<br />

385 On Saville, see Brooks Adams et al, Sensation: Young British Artists from the Saatchi<br />

Collection (catalogue) London, 1994, pp. 158-163, Linda Nochlin, ‘Floating in Gender Nirvana’<br />

in Art in America, March, 2000, pp. 94-97 and Currentartpics 23.


247<br />

drawing of a Picasso (such as Figure 15) or Miro (such as Figure 18). Rare instance<br />

here, while more relaxed and gregarious than a Saville, and worked into a tizzy in<br />

ways denied a Saville, does not as yet project as far or well. 386<br />

Given the range of Pop and Photo-realist works devoted to the discrete<br />

arrangement of modest objects, still life finds surprisingly little use in the work of<br />

rare instance. Still lives occur in the work of Tuymans, where they generally sample<br />

the cinematic or photographic close-up in framing, lighting and picture plane<br />

projection and with rare contempt, as discussed. The work of London-based<br />

Canadian Lisa Milroy (b.1959) from the later eighties offers catalogues of objects in<br />

‘layout’, such as Light Bulbs (1987) (Figure 158). Painting here resists both<br />

photographic derivation and greater abstraction, while assembled objects often<br />

wittily recall Minimalist pattern and the earlier still lives of Wayne Thiebaud<br />

(b.1920). 387 The work of Will Cotton (b.1965) toward the end of the ni<strong>net</strong>ies<br />

samples a more obvious genre in panoramic studies of molten chocolate and other<br />

confectionary, such as the immense Devil’s Fudge Falls (1999) (Figure 159) recalling<br />

the emphasis on chocolate’s plastic qualities and extreme close-ups often found in<br />

advertising.<br />

This concludes the survey of the work of rare instance and the revival of genre.<br />

There now remains only to briefly consider the period as a whole. A certain mood<br />

or attitude may be discerned for example, at once lighter and more whimsical than<br />

that of Post-Modernism, as works patiently and playfully contribute to ‘Globalist’<br />

projects. Indeed by contrast, Post-Modernist work may seem heavy handed and<br />

obvious to the ‘Globalist’ sensibility, while equally the ‘Globalist’ work may seem<br />

frivolous and academic to the passionate Post-Modernist. Then again the ‘Globalist’<br />

work never quite aspires to the Modernist’s magical and musical extension, nor<br />

encounters the frustration and confusion of the Late Modernist, and while<br />

confident, and to a degree cool, like the Post-Modernist, is much less antagonistic<br />

386 On Brown, see Martin Maloney, ‘Cecily Brown’ (review) in Modern Painters, Summer 1999,<br />

p.98, Odili Donald Odita, ‘Cecily Brown, Goya, Vogue and the Politics of Abstraction’<br />

(interview) in Flash Art, November-December, 2000, pp. 70-74.<br />

387 On Milroy, see Alistair Hicks, New British Art in the Saatchi Collection, London, 1990, pp.<br />

72-79. On Cotton, see Edward Leffingwell, ‘Will Cotton at Mary Boone’, (review) in Art in<br />

America, May 2000, p.149.


248<br />

or aggressive to traditions or institutions. For the ‘Globalist’ life lies in the<br />

sensitivity to further institutions.<br />

The chapter began by considering the course of ‘expanded materials’ in the period<br />

and traced how readymade works engage wider institutional co-operation and<br />

reference; give way to the ‘readily-made’, to the sampling of institutional support of<br />

various kinds, and to the seeming convergence between the roles of artist and<br />

curator. It then considered painting for the period along three courses, abstraction,<br />

‘layout’ and more concrete depiction, and how they acquire ‘Globalist’ projects to<br />

wider pattern and genre. This now allows an appreciation of how painting and<br />

‘expanded materials’ complement each other, and constitute a larger project. The<br />

crisis anticipated in the convergence of the roles of curator and artist for identity of<br />

work and in the diminution of genre and instance in depiction importantly shares a<br />

common factor in excessive devotion. Curation and artistry here are only threatened<br />

where focus becomes exclusive. Genre and instance, installation and <strong>net</strong>work,<br />

exhaust themselves only if pursued continuously. Competition between projects<br />

thus allows curator and artist a necessary equilibrium, slows if not stalls convergence<br />

and diminution. This is not to say that ‘Globalism’ is perpetual or impervious to<br />

outside influence, but only that this balance serves to characterise ‘Globalism’ as an<br />

‘open’ style, or in lieu of saying what comes next. This concludes the history of<br />

depiction and painting between 1950 and 2000. In the final chapter a review of<br />

distinctive features and comparison with other versions complete the study. 388<br />

388 Studies in more recent trends and individual styles by the author may be found at<br />

http://currentartpics.blogspot.com .


249<br />

Conclusion<br />

The preceding history now affords review and comparison. Contribution to theory<br />

and adherence to Goodman’s irrealism have been assessed in Chapter Ten. Here its<br />

application to art history is considered. Firstly, the application proceeds against<br />

objections by Elkins and Bell that the theory is too difficult, abstruse, glib, suave or<br />

otherwise flawed. It persists against objections by Gombrich and Bell that the<br />

period represents only the failure of depiction, a disillusion for history. It perseveres<br />

against hermeneutic, deconstructionist and post-structuralist criticism that such a<br />

period defies analysis or that such analysis can still be worthwhile. The study finds<br />

to the contrary. A history of depiction and painting based upon modes of<br />

exemplification not only handles the full range of painting for the period and<br />

integrates it closely with other plastic arts, but also delivers more precise analysis of<br />

depictive features and more flexible style sources for group, place and period. The<br />

job can be done, is worth doing and is done by irrealism here.<br />

The method rests upon a theory of depiction and painting that discards absolute<br />

stylistic realism, primacy of intention, and priority of the abstract or concrete.<br />

Method begins from a more comprehensive stylistics and also allows that history<br />

has many right versions, can improve upon some; provide a novel or different<br />

version to others. It does this through matching traditional or established sources to<br />

right stylistics, new sources to traditional stylistics or simply new sources for new<br />

stylistics. Where traditional sources are secured by improved stylistics or traditional<br />

stylistics more accurately aligned with new sources, history is improved. Where new<br />

styles rival old ones or new sources replace old ones, an equally valid or right<br />

interpretation emerges and adds to rather than improves upon versions.<br />

Care taken in matters of theory now rewards history with stricter demarcation and<br />

greater breadth or diversity within periods. But method also promotes a more<br />

adventurous attitude to construction. It accepts that not all lesser styles may be


250<br />

needed or enough for a period; that others may be found or made where stylistic<br />

features for a work or source allow telling distinction, or others omitted where work<br />

or source offers less interest. Here, for example, ‘Overstyle’ ‘Rerealism’ and<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ are introduced as more accurate and useful groupings for<br />

understanding Modernism. More generally, the point is that art history need not<br />

always start from individual works or styles and ascend to larger groupings, but can<br />

equally start from period to detect lesser styles, to prompt research of individual<br />

works and styles. Art history does not ascend to a ‘meta’ level in dealing with<br />

period, is not exclusively or preferably a matter of individual works or styles (unless<br />

under a nominalist construction, of course). 389<br />

But while adventure is encouraged, constraints apply. Only if it maintains the rules<br />

of style, by accurate and consistent reference features for work and of the facts of<br />

source, only where it offers greater construction, makes more sense of surrounding<br />

periods, or thus conforms with more or longer history, only when it gives new<br />

direction to historical inquiry, or focuses attention anew, can art history be thus<br />

extended. So while irrealism here takes a more proactive stance toward style,<br />

reconstruction remains within severe limits. Whether better or different, versions<br />

follow the same rules.<br />

Revision of styles here starts with the troubled notion of abstraction. Depiction as<br />

exemplification of two-dimensionality for a three-dimensional object, firstly clarifies<br />

issues of the picture plane and distinction with pattern. Projection and influence of<br />

style explains the course of ‘a pattern of a picture plane’ (or vice versa). While<br />

abstraction here is held to be full or absolute where it asserts pattern, no one picture<br />

plane or pattern is held to dominate practice for each. On the contrary, abstraction<br />

for depiction arises just as diversity of picture planes allows ‘simultaneous and<br />

successive’ depiction new and greater play, and this synchrony is taken to signal the<br />

start of Modernism. The arrangement more accurately locates abstraction in<br />

depiction, adheres to accepted chronology and identity of works but now allows<br />

abstraction to be seen within a larger framework. The arrangement is better for<br />

389 The positivist zeal that ‘starts’ from particulars, takes the unpublished document or<br />

unrecognised work as primary, encourages the attitude that works precede styles, that the<br />

particulars of time and place come first in advancing art history. But categories or styles do not<br />

take care of themselves; much less accept any and every such detail. There are no works before<br />

or without styles, no art history without stylistics, which is as valid for period as personal style.


251<br />

explaining more works more concisely, is different rather than worse for resisting<br />

extension of source, since source rapidly splinters into factors or factions for the<br />

social, psychological, national, political, economic and so forth. To pursue source<br />

thus is the task of a different rather than better history.<br />

So Cubism and Expressionism in this view are not Modernist, nor lead to just<br />

abstraction, as is often supposed, but rather branch to opposing projects or styles,<br />

to ‘Overstyle’ and ‘Rerealism’ and their three-way competition largely measures the<br />

course of Early Modernism. ‘Overstyle’ and ‘Rerealism’ are introduced not as<br />

substitutes for Surrealism and Synthetic Cubism but because they actually pick out<br />

slightly different groups of works, stress differences in picture plane construction<br />

and crucial relations with abstraction. The change of styles also frees member works<br />

from narrower interpretation. Sampling two-dimensionality depends on a<br />

recognised three-dimensionality, and abstraction is often pursued or projected to<br />

sculpture and three-dimensional works by this, and further outward to architecture<br />

and applied design in this period. The shift from Early Modernism to Late<br />

Modernism is marked by a loss of impetus to such projection, and a convergence of<br />

competing styles of depiction around the middle of the century.<br />

Late Modernism is also a matter of competing styles. But now a compound of<br />

abstraction, ‘Overstyle’ and ‘Rerealism’ arises as ‘Reciprocal Depiction’, where the<br />

abstract counterbalances the concrete, material with picture plane and object.<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’, while a novel and perhaps clumsy term, no<strong>net</strong>heless<br />

identifies qualities to accepted works otherwise ignored or denied. For the history<br />

dedicated to the advance of abstraction, such work is no more than a compromise,<br />

a slide toward the conservative and traditional. Yet this view cannot then explain<br />

why tradition is not more fully embraced, nor Modernism more convincingly<br />

abandoned. The view remains simply insensitive to finer stylistic features and<br />

ultimately robs abstraction of valuable relations. Equally crude is the history that<br />

can only recognise such works in light of later developments, especially Pop Art,<br />

finds much of the work forerunners or pioneers, yet cannot then explain why they<br />

remain tentative, or what it is that prevents them from being more wholeheartedly<br />

Pop Art. Again the view obscures important links and finer distinction, and while it<br />

easily traces roots to Early Modernist collage for example, as often fails to note key


252<br />

differences to picture plane scheme and so ultimately robs Pop Art of valuable<br />

relations. ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ may seem to cluster a disparate group of works at<br />

first, but can point more convincingly to stylistic precedent, to related strategies of<br />

‘layout’ ‘traction’ and ‘interruption’, to a formal rigour equal to that of abstraction, a<br />

shared mood or attitude and how they variously arrive at Pop Art and Post-<br />

Modernism. It is a radical proposal, but consistent with treatment of preceding and<br />

subsequent periods.<br />

Against ‘Reciprocal Depiction’, abstraction projects more confidently to greater<br />

symmetry and scale, and distinctions here in value of scale to materials, and of<br />

location of symmetrical axes to key works particularly for New York-based<br />

abstraction, differ from standard accounts, as noted. Against painting and the plastic<br />

arts; works of ‘expanded materials’ extend to time and motion, ki<strong>net</strong>ics and<br />

performance. Competing projects again share a crucial synchrony. Depiction and<br />

pattern are mutually extended in painting, and impetus is carried through to works<br />

of ‘expanded materials’. Yet Late Modernism is a relatively brief period, lasts around<br />

ten years, and is succeeded around 1960 by Post-Modernism. Projects in Late<br />

Modernism do not so much converge or stall in transition as diverge and sprawl.<br />

‘Reciprocal Depiction’ in its Late Modernist form gives way firstly to print sampling<br />

by painting, usually called Pop Art, and here the account draws upon the theory of<br />

painting as the work of sole instance, in re-defining the style. ‘Reciprocal Depiction’<br />

less promptly contracts to a radical ‘badness’ or Neo-Expressionism, and the<br />

sampling of style against allegory.<br />

Greater pattern in abstraction at a certain point reverses its sample; is not so much<br />

by pattern of greater scale and linked materials, but by such properties, of pattern.<br />

Abstraction then enters a Post-Modernist period. Such painting becomes the<br />

striking instance or extension to even the most basic patterns and is generally called<br />

Minimalism. Sampling of motion, duration and performance in works of ‘expanded<br />

materials’ also arises, extends fine art to literature, to script or score for<br />

performance or duration and place, and to other recording practices. It is usually<br />

called Conceptual Art, but the name here is stripped of misleading notions of a<br />

work of pure concept or seeming dematerialisation. It is sensibly redressed by<br />

Goodman’s theory of sampling and a modicum of common sense. Pop Art,


253<br />

Minimalism and Conceptual Art now constitute initial competing projects for Post-<br />

Modernism. The proposed theory of depiction, of exemplification and of painting<br />

as work of sole instance thus allows vital reconstruction of styles and period. 390 If<br />

anything the name for the period is the most disappointing aspect, although at least<br />

points to a more radical juncture than that between Early and Late Modernism. The<br />

name is as often applied to a later period. But Post-Modernism here continues until<br />

the mid eighties when it is succeeded by the last period to the century, now named<br />

‘Globalism’.<br />

The name suggests not only the growing economic integration of the period, but<br />

also an emphasis upon holistic strategies, variously pursued in competing styles. The<br />

transition now offers both greater divergence for works of ‘expanded materials’, and<br />

convergence between pattern, print and depiction in painting. For works of<br />

‘expanded materials’, sampling of performance, literature and other recording, leads<br />

to greater institutional support and ultimately to sampling of institutional prestige.<br />

For abstraction and entrenched pattern, the shift leads from repeating pictures and<br />

even the single motif to ‘layouts’ of printing and more rare or diffuse pattern. Print<br />

sampling by painting on the other hand leads firstly back to ‘traction’, to minor<br />

sampling, either to Neo-Expressionism, ‘Bad’ Painting or New Image Painting. It is<br />

an end to Post-Modernism. Neo-Expressionism then leads to the clichés of Pre-<br />

Modernist traditions or genres, and to genre more widely conceived, to those<br />

depictive worlds shared by both print and painting, or globally.<br />

390 Attention to a single style such as Pop Art has for some time been content with the<br />

iconography and culture of the times rather than a more precise account of stylistic features. For<br />

example Marco Livingstone, Pop Art: A continuing history, London, 1990, p. 9, labours under<br />

the definition ‘the use of existing imagery, from mass culture already processed into two<br />

dimensions, preferably borrowed from advertising, photography, comic strips and other mass<br />

media sources’ unable to quite put his finger on print sampling, to see the forest for the trees or to<br />

acknowledge that all depiction uses ‘existing imagery’. As a consequence the book is unable to<br />

quite see either what is central and peripheral to the movement, properly its derivation or relation<br />

to Minimalism and Conceptual Art. Similarly, claims for the start of Post-Modernism with Pop<br />

Art often compound the error. For example in Brandon Taylor, Modernism, post-modernism,<br />

realism: a critical perspective for art, Winchester, 1987, p. 8, the claim is that ‘Andy Warhol<br />

became Post-Modern at the point where he stopped making images about the world and began<br />

making images about images’ Implicit in both views is the idea that there is some more direct<br />

way for depiction to be about the world than ‘existing imagery’ or that ‘existing imagery’ is not<br />

then about the world. This is really to appeal to a naive copying in depiction, thoroughly<br />

discredited since Gombrich, at least. All depiction builds on older versions – is ‘about images’ –<br />

belongs to and builds worlds – is ‘about the world’. Of course Taylor is hardly alone in this glib<br />

view of Post-Modernism, no more than falls in step with Livingstone’s Pop Art. More precisely,<br />

however, Warhol began making paintings about printing, sampled just this difference in<br />

depiction, and with it engaged those objects depicted, their world and ways of depicting, rather<br />

than merely ‘images about images’ or ‘existing imagery’.


254<br />

Interestingly, labels for competing projects in this period fail to gain wider currency.<br />

Where this period is termed Post-Modernism, the more radical print sampling of<br />

say, a Pittman or a Pettibon are often lumped in with Pop Art, or the ‘readilymades’<br />

of a Hirst or Orozco casually ceded to Conceptual Art. But there is little<br />

gained by such attenuation. Equally, claims for a Post-Modernist period at this point<br />

often amount to no more than a declaration of rampant pluralism, or paradoxically,<br />

an end to art history. 391 Obviously the two reinforce one another and discourage<br />

greater discrimination. ‘Globalism’ on the other hand acknowledges only an open<br />

period; one that does not end with the century, but is only measured against<br />

preceding periods and synchrony of projects. Admittedly, the period is at best half a<br />

description by this and theory here offers no direct support for such construction,<br />

but care taken in preceding periods and projects nevertheless carries construction<br />

further than rival versions, points to crucial integration of projects for period, to<br />

distinctions with preceding periods and works, to new distinctions within period.<br />

‘Globalism’ is not just the works labelled Post-Modernism in accounts by Michael<br />

Archer, Mathew Collings, Jonathan Fineberg, Hal Foster, David Hopkins, Edward<br />

Lucie-Smith, Brandon Taylor, or Daniel Wheeler, for example. 392 It differs in both<br />

the variety of work considered and train of development, or in both synchronic and<br />

diachronic changes. It introduces distinctions between the readymade and the<br />

‘readily-made’ for example, as well as between a Pittman and a Marshall, a Lasker<br />

and a Lombardi, a Ritchie and a Marden, a Currin and a Tuymans, a Saville and a<br />

Cecily Brown, and indeed variously between any of the above all in demonstrating<br />

the further reaches of print sampling, genre, ‘layout’ and pattern in ‘Globalism’. 393<br />

But rather than trace realisms between styles, art history here has been content to<br />

391 For strong advocacy of this termination, see Danto, The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of<br />

Art. New York/Guildford/Surrey, 1986, and Danto, Encounters And Reflections: Art In The<br />

Historical Present, Berkeley/London, 1986.<br />

392 Archer, Art since 1960, London, 1997, Collings, This is modern art, New York, 2000,<br />

Fineberg, Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being, (2 nd ed.) London /New York, 2000, Foster, Return<br />

of the real: the avant-garde at the end of the century, Cambridge, Mass, and London, 1996,<br />

Hopkins, After Modern Art: 1945-2000, Oxford/New York, 2000, Lucie Smith, Artoday, London,<br />

1995, Taylor, Modernism, post-modernism, realism: a critical perspective for art, Winchester,<br />

1987, Taylor, Avant-Garde and after: rethinking art now, New York, 1995, Wheeler, Art Since<br />

Mid Century, New York, 1991.<br />

393 Incidentally, emphasis upon a return to genre in ‘Globalism’ also suggests further research to<br />

the pre-Modernist period here, as the dismantling of genre.


255<br />

demonstrate benefits to historical derivation. At its simplest, it promotes a filing<br />

system. The history organises works and styles often ignored or dismissed along<br />

with regular favourites and so extends sensitivities, builds tolerance and curiosity.<br />

The priority has thus been with construction, with rightness of category, or fit,<br />

before realisms. This is not to say that works and styles included are exhaustive or<br />

the best, only that it provides a history that is right in several ways, better than<br />

some, different to others.<br />

Attention to such systematic rigour inevitably suggests structuralism. The typical<br />

concerns with holism, change and self-regulation to structuralist analysis are indeed<br />

shared with irrealism here. Differences lie in scope allowed historical or diachronic<br />

change as well as reference relations. Reference is not limited to exemplification;<br />

exemplification is not limited to depiction and painting. History here deals only with<br />

some of the range of reference, only for some periods, and only in some of the<br />

ways those periods follow each other. Reference is not locked into just this history.<br />

Standard objections to the rigidity or sterility of structuralism thus do not arise.<br />

Objections to a betrayal of pluralism in supporting a holism of history or reference<br />

are likewise avoided.<br />

But this is only to review the impact of theoretical resources on art history. As<br />

important as assets of clarity, scope, rigour and sensitivity, are advantages gained in<br />

looking beyond art history. Here the argument is obviously and overwhelmingly for<br />

the value of depiction and painting, for their continued vigour in reference. But the<br />

case is not just that depiction and painting remain central to fine arts, on the<br />

contrary, the case is that their contribution is only to be measured against the full<br />

spectrum of arts, that the synchrony - even symbiosis – between arts ensures that<br />

there is no one line of progress, avant-garde or prime plastic art; that multiple<br />

interactions ensure that there are many, if any. Consequently, art history must juggle<br />

too many for progress against too few for persuasion or practice. History holds no<br />

suspicious self-regulation in this regard, only gauges that of reference and concerns<br />

itself with as much as is of interest to the plastic arts at a given point.<br />

As important are links made or found between arts and periods, other practices and<br />

reference. The study points to an appreciation of surrounding practices, not only to


256<br />

curatorial practice and collection, co-operation and co-opting, but also to more and<br />

other ‘Globalisms’ of genre, pattern or publication. It points to the world beyond<br />

the works that help make it. Then again the study points to greater scope for works<br />

and study, and against, for example, prevailing practice of the massive and<br />

misguided survey of contemporary art, not so much to curb mounting curatorial<br />

power as to redirect and disperse its resources. Practices of display clearly have a<br />

part to play in art and its history, but curatorial practice serves neither by relentless<br />

conformity, frequency or expansion. More shows are only to the good so long as<br />

they are of different things in different ways. Some things and ways may even<br />

require fewer shows. But practice here cannot do justice to history or works where<br />

curatorial practice gives priority to ‘expanded materials’ for example, or assumes<br />

that hybrids succeed in competition with single arts, or that history is made only<br />

with recent works. The study in this respect urges that the task of the collector,<br />

curator or critic now lies in reconsidering how, when and where works are shown as<br />

much as what is shown, and that meaning resides as much in such practices as a<br />

narrow and neurotic historicism. In this, the argument is hardly unique perhaps, but<br />

hopefully lends new weight.<br />

An adequate review must also acknowledge certain omissions. Many of these are<br />

registered at suitable points in the study; some find no point before this. The study<br />

has conspicuously avoided social history in advancing routes of reference for<br />

example, and so avoids perhaps ‘too much history’ for its art. But circumstances<br />

and background to sources are more commonly available, so that rather than unduly<br />

extend study in this, study here readily cedes the task to rival versions, to Artoday for<br />

its many subcultures and regional differences, to After Modern Art 1945-2000 for its<br />

ideological, if uneven insights, to Art Since 1940: Strategies of Being for its detail of<br />

personality and lifestyle, to Theories and Documents of Contemporary Art for its patient<br />

catalogue of artist’s interpretations, to Return of the real for sensitivity to<br />

philosophical fashions and post-colonial interests, and Theorizing Modernism, for<br />

psychoanalytic speculations. 394 No art history can do everything, nor need try where<br />

some versions enable or assist others. A more troubling omission concerns<br />

treatment of architecture, sculpture and printing, due both to constraints of space<br />

394 Kristine Stiles and Peter Selz, (eds) Theories and Documents of Contemporary Art, a<br />

Sourcebook of Artist’s Writings, Berkley/London, 1995, Johanna Drucker, Theorizing<br />

Modernism, Visual Art and the Critical Tradition, New York, 1994.


257<br />

and concentration upon painting. 395 But here the study must be content with<br />

indicating issues of sampling and projection for three-dimensionality and other arts.<br />

Also, what initially seemed a useful contrast or counter to Gombrich’s version of<br />

Modernism, in which architecture and the applied arts influence pattern in<br />

depiction, on reflection, now perhaps overstates the reverse influence, from<br />

depiction and painting to pattern and other arts. A more accurate view allows a twoway<br />

exchange.<br />

A less troubling omission concerns the middle ground or the more conservative in<br />

painting for the period. Such work registers as ‘Interstyle’ in the account of Early<br />

Modernism here, but strictly is less distinguished or indicative of period. Works by<br />

artists such as Frenchmen Henri Matisse (1869-1954) Georges Rouault (1871-1958)<br />

and Balthus, a.k.a. Balthasar Klossowski de Rola (1908-2001) Russian Chaim<br />

Soutine (1893-1943) Italian Amedeo Modigliani (1884-1920) Germans Max<br />

Beckmann (1884-1950) and Otto Dix (1891-1969) and comparable figures in the<br />

United States and elsewhere, neither quite remain primitivist or Expressionist,<br />

accept greater abstraction or ‘simultaneous and successive’ depiction. Instead they<br />

pursue variation where it falls between projects, amount to the more traditional in<br />

Modernism, the more Modernist of tradition. In a longer study more would be<br />

made of the way such work teases tradition and period. For example, the middle<br />

ground may sometimes gauge where projects tire or tradition triumphs and in other<br />

ways may offer fresh starting points.<br />

In Late Modernism significantly, the middle ground widens. ‘Reciprocal Depiction’<br />

partially returns to single picture planes and objects against which to sample ‘layout’,<br />

‘traction’ and ‘interruption’. It relies upon tradition in this, but tradition now is not<br />

easily isolated or sampled on these terms, as noted, must contend with a middle<br />

ground and diminishing projection. In fact ‘Reciprocal Depiction’ more easily<br />

allows milder versions, or becomes an ‘Interstyle’, and uncomfortably inflates the<br />

middle ground. Works here range from the lean and linear ‘Miserablism’ of<br />

Frenchmen Bernard Buffet (1928-99) or Francois Gruber (1912-48) to the laboured<br />

plotting of Englishmen Euan Uglow (1932-2000) or Michael Andrews (1928-95) to<br />

395 The author takes up individual sculptors, photographers and Conceptual artists in the blog<br />

Currentartpics.


258<br />

the brittle bodily disproportions of Englishman Lucien Freud (b.1922) which find<br />

echoes in work by Philip Pearlstein (b.1924) and Alfred Leslie (b.1927) to the terse<br />

anecdotes and close-ups of Alex Katz (b.1927) the mythical and literary figures<br />

married to novel gesture and techniques in the work of Leon Golub (b.1922) Irving<br />

Petlin (b.1934) or Australian Sir Sidney Nolan (1917-92) as well as other, again<br />

comparable figures elsewhere. 396<br />

The impact of print sampling and end of period owe something to this diffusion.<br />

Post Modernism in turn, measures ‘Bad’ painting or Neo-Expressionism against just<br />

such compromise, settles for the cusp of Modernism as a starting point. Globalism’s<br />

revival of genre also negotiates a middle ground; must find instance not too rare<br />

and non-traditional and such practice not only revises views of earlier work such as<br />

a Katz or Buffet, but also generates its own milder instances and rarer genres. A<br />

middle ground also arises for abstraction as styles and periods allow greater<br />

differentiation and compromise, and again there are many works and artists typical<br />

of this that a longer study would comfortably accommodate. However, having<br />

indicated enough of how they fit with this history, why such omissions are made,<br />

and having reviewed distinctive features to the history, compared them with rival<br />

versions, noted further advantages and insights, a conclusion now awaits only the<br />

reader’s judgement.<br />

396 For interesting revision of such work see Storr, Modern art despite modernism, New York,<br />

2000.


259<br />

Bibliography<br />

ABADIE, Daniel, et al.<br />

Georges Mathieu: A Retrospective Exhibition (catalogue) Galleria Gruppo Credito<br />

Valtellinese and Editions Galerie Nationale du Jeu de Paume, Paris and<br />

Milan, 2003.<br />

ACCONCI, Vito and LINKER, Kate.<br />

Vito Acconci, Rizzoli, New York, 1994.<br />

ADAMS, Brooks, et al.<br />

Sensation: Young British Artist from the Saatchi Collection (catalogue) Thames and<br />

Hudson and The Royal Academy of The Arts, London, 1997.<br />

ADES, Dawn.<br />

Dada and Surrealism, Thames and Hudson, London, 1974.<br />

-----------------<br />

‘’Web of Images’ in Francis Bacon (catalogue), The Trustees of the Tate<br />

Gallery & Thames and Hudson, London, 1985.<br />

ADES, Dawn, et al.<br />

Marcel Duchamp. Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1999.<br />

ALBERRO, Alexander (ed.)<br />

Two-way Mirror Power: Selected writings by Dan Graham on his art, M.I.T. Press,<br />

Cambridge Mass. and London, 1999.<br />

ALBERRO, Alexander and STIMSON, Blake.<br />

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1999.<br />

ALLISON, Nicholas H. (ed.)<br />

Art into Life: Russian Constructivism 1914-1932, (catalogue) Rizzoli<br />

International, and Henry Art Gallery, University of Washington, Seattle,<br />

New York, 1990.<br />

ALLOWAY, Lawrence and COPLANS, John.<br />

‘Talking with William Rubin: The Museum Concept is not Infinitely<br />

Expandable’ in Artforum, October, 1974, p.52.


260<br />

AMMAN, Jean-Christophe.<br />

‘Der Fall Jeff Koons’ Parkett, No 19, 1989, pp. 53-56<br />

ANDĚL, Jaroslav and KOSINSKI Dorothy (eds.)<br />

Painting the Universe: František Kupka, Pioneer in Abstraction, Dallas Museum of<br />

Art and Verlag Gerd Hatje, Dallas and Stuttgart, 1998.<br />

ANDERSON-SPIVY, Alexandra.<br />

Robert Kushner: Gardens of Earthly Delight, Hudson Hills Press, New York,<br />

1997.<br />

ANFAM, David.<br />

Abstract Expressionism, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1990.<br />

ARASSE, Daniel.<br />

Anselm Kiefer, translated by Mary Whittall, Thames and Hudson, Harry N.<br />

Abrams Inc, London and New York, 2001.<br />

ARCHER, Michael.<br />

Art since 1960, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1997.<br />

ARMSTRONG, Philip, et al. (eds)<br />

As Painting: division and displacement, (catalogue) Wexner Center for the Arts,<br />

MIT Press, Columbus, Ohio and Cambridge, Mass., 2001-2.<br />

ARNHEIM, Rudolf.<br />

Art and Visual Perception: (2 nd ed.) University Of California Press, Berkeley<br />

and Los Angeles, 1974.<br />

-----------------------<br />

New Essays in the Psychology of Art. University of California Press, Berkeley<br />

and Los Angeles, 1986.<br />

ASHBERY, John, et al.<br />

Kitaj. Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1983.<br />

ASHTON, Dore.<br />

Terence La Noue, Hudson Hills Press, New York, 1992.<br />

AUPING, Michael.<br />

Abstract Expressionism: The Critical Developments, Albright-Knox Art Gallery,<br />

Harry N. Abrams, Buffalo and New York, 1987.<br />

BALLATORE, Sandy.<br />

‘Don Sorenson at Copley and Wilder’ (review) in Art in America, September-<br />

October 1976, p. 115.


261<br />

BANN, Stephan and ALLEN, William (eds.)<br />

Interpreting Contemporary Art. Reaktion Books, London, 1991.<br />

BARR, Alfred H.<br />

Cubism and Abstract Art, The Museum of Modern Art, New York, 1936.<br />

---------------------<br />

Defining Modern Art (edited by Irving Sandler and Amy Newman) Harry N.<br />

Abrams, New York, 1986.<br />

BARRET, Cyril.<br />

An Introduction to Optical Art, Studio Vista, E.P. Dutton, London and New<br />

York, 1971.<br />

BARTHES, Roland.<br />

‘Rhétorique de l´image’, in Communications, 4, 1964, pp. 40-51.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Elements of semiology, (Paris, 1967) translated by An<strong>net</strong>te Lavers and Colin<br />

Smith, Cape, London, 1969.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Mythologies, selected and translated by An<strong>net</strong>te Lavers, Hill and Wang, New<br />

York, 1972.<br />

BATCHELOR, David.<br />

Minimalism. Cambridge University Press and The Tate Gallery, London and<br />

Cambridge, 1997.<br />

BATTCOCK, GREGORY (ed.)<br />

The New Art, E.P. Dutton, New York, 1966.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

Minimal Art: A Critical Anthology. E.P. Dutton, New York,1968.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

Idea Art, E. P. Dutton, New York, 1973.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

Super Realism. E. P. Dutton, New York, 1975.<br />

BATTCOCK, Gregory and NICKAS, Robert (eds.)<br />

The Art of Performance: A Critical Anthology, E.P. Dutton, New York, 1984.<br />

BAUDRILLARD, Jean.<br />

The Ecstasy of Communication, (Paris, 1984) translated by Bernard and Caroline<br />

Schutze, Semiotext, New York, 1987.


262<br />

BAXANDALL, Michael.<br />

Patterns Of Intention: Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1985.<br />

BAYLEY, Paul.<br />

Lari Pittman: Paintings 1992-98, (catalogue) Cornerhouse, Manchester, 1998.<br />

BEARDSLEY, Monroe C.<br />

‘Languages of Art and Art Criticism’, Erkenntnis 12, 1978, pp. 95-118.<br />

Reprinted in The Philosophy of Nelson Goodman, Catherine Z. Elgin, ed.<br />

Volume 3, ‘Nelson Goodman’s Philosophy of Art’, Garland Publishing,<br />

New York and London, 1997, pp. 43-66.<br />

BEARDSLEY, Monroe C. and SCHUELLER, Herbert M. (eds.)<br />

Aesthetic Inquiry: Essays in Art Criticism, Dickenson Publishing Co, Belmont,<br />

California, 1967.<br />

BEARDSLEY, Monroe C. and WIMSATT W. K.<br />

‘The Intentional Fallacy’ in Sewanee Review, 54 1946, pp. 3-23.<br />

BELL, Clive.<br />

Art: Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1914.<br />

BELL, Julian.<br />

What Is Painting? Representation and Modern Art, Thames and Hudson, London<br />

and New York, 1999.<br />

__________<br />

Mirror of the World, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 2007.<br />

BENDEM, Tom.<br />

David Mach: Master Builder, (catalogue) Rotterdam, Galerie t’Venster 1982.<br />

BENJAMIN, Walter.<br />

Illuminations (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp Verlag 1955) translated by Harry Zohn,<br />

edited by Hannah Arendt, London, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Inc 1968.<br />

Key essay, ‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’ is<br />

reprinted in Modern Art and Modernism: A Critical Anthology, Frascina,<br />

Harrison and Paul (eds.) Open University and Harper & Row, London and<br />

New York, 1982.<br />

BETTS, Paul.<br />

‘Black Mountain College, N.C.’ in Bauhaus, Jeanine Fiedler and Peter<br />

Feierbend (eds.) Könemann, Cologne, 1999.<br />

BISCHOFF, Ulrich.


263<br />

Max Ernst 1891-1976: Beyond Painting, translated by Judith Harrison,<br />

Benedikt Taschen Verlag GmbH & Co, KG. Cologne, 1988.<br />

BLANC, Charles.<br />

Grammaire des arts decorative – decoration interieure de la maison, Renovard, Paris,<br />

1886.<br />

BLANK, P. et al.<br />

‘Perceiving What Paintings Express’ in Cognitive Processes In The Perception Of<br />

Art, W. R. Crozier and A. J. Chapman (eds.) Amsterdam, North Holland,<br />

1984, pp.127-143.<br />

BLECKNER, Ross.<br />

Ross Bleckner, Twin Palms Publications, Santa Fe, 1998.<br />

BLOCK, Ned (ed.)<br />

Imagery. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. 1981.<br />

BOETTGER, Suzanne.<br />

Earthworks, Art and the Landscape of the Late Sixties, University of California<br />

Press, Los Angeles, London, 2002.<br />

BOIS, Yve-Alain.<br />

Painting as Model, An OCTOBER book, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.<br />

London, 1993.<br />

---------------------<br />

Matisse and Picasso, (catalogue) Flammarion and Kimball Art Museum, Paris<br />

and Fort Worth, Texas, 2001.<br />

BOIS, Yve-Alain, et al.<br />

Piet Mondrian, (catalogue) Bullfinch Press, Boston, New York, Toronto,<br />

London, 1994.<br />

BOIS, Yve-Alain and KRAUSS, Rosalind.<br />

Formless: A User’s Guide, Zone Books, New York, 1997.<br />

BONNEFOY, Yves.<br />

Giacometti, Abbeville, New York, 1991.<br />

BOOKER, P. J.<br />

A History of Engineering Drawing, Chatto and Windus, London, 1963.<br />

BRADLEY, Fiona.<br />

Surrealism, Tate Gallery Publishing, London, 1997.<br />

BRAUER, David E. et al.


264<br />

Pop Art: U.S./U.K. Connections, 1956-1966, (catalogue) DAP, Cantz Verlag,<br />

Houston, Menil Collection, New York and Ostfildern-Ruit, Germany, 2001.<br />

BRETON, Andre.<br />

Surrealism and Painting (Le Surrealisme et la peinture, Editions Gallimard,<br />

Paris 1965) translated by Simon Watson Taylor, Icon Editions, New York,<br />

1966.<br />

BRETTELL, RICHARD R.<br />

Modern Art 1851-1929. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York,<br />

1999.<br />

BRION, Marcel.<br />

L’Art abstrait, Éditions Abin Michel, Paris, 1956.<br />

BRION, Marcel et al.<br />

Art since 1945, Thames and Hudson, London, 1958.<br />

BROOKS, Cleanth.<br />

Modern Poetry and the Tradition, University of North Carolina Press, Chapel<br />

Hill, N.C. 1967.<br />

BROWN, Andreas (ed.)<br />

Andy Warhol: His Early Works: 1947-1959 (catalogue) Gotham Book Mart<br />

and Gallery, New York, 1971.<br />

BRUGGEN, Coosje Van.<br />

Bruce Nauman, Rizzoli, New York, 1988.<br />

BRYSON, Norman.<br />

Vision and Painting: The Logic of The Gaze, Yale University Press, New Haven<br />

and London, 1983.<br />

BRYSON, Norman, HOLLY, Michael Ann. & MOXEY, Keith (eds.)<br />

Visual Theory, Blackwell, Oxford, 1991.<br />

BUCHER, Francois and ALBERS Joseph.<br />

Despite Straight Lines, Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1961.<br />

BUCHLOH, Benjamin H. D.<br />

‘Figures of Authority, Ciphers of Regression’ in October no 16 Spring 1981<br />

pp.39-68 (reprinted in Art After Modernism: Rethinking Representation, Brian<br />

Wallis (ed.) The New Museum of Contemporary Art, New York, David R.<br />

Godine Publisher Inc, Boston, 1984).<br />

------------------------------------


265<br />

‘Hans Haacke: Memory and Instrumental Reason’ in Art in America,<br />

February 1988, pp.96-109.<br />

---------------------------------------<br />

‘The Whole Earth Show’, an interview with Jean-Hubert Martin, in Art in<br />

America, May 1989, pp.150-58, p.211 and p.213.<br />

BUDD, Malcolm.<br />

‘On Looking at a Picture’ in Psychoanalysis Mind and Art (perspectives on Richard<br />

Wollheim) J. Hopkins and A. Saville (eds.) Blackwell, Oxford, 1987.<br />

--------------------<br />

Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry and Music, Allen Lane, Penguin Press, London,<br />

1995.<br />

BÜRGER, Peter.<br />

Theory of the Avant-Garde. (2 nd ed. Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt, 1980)<br />

translated by Michael Shaw, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis,<br />

1984.<br />

---------------------<br />

The Decline of Modernism, translated by Nicholas Walker, Polity Press,<br />

Cambridge, 1992.<br />

CACCIARI, Massimo and CELANT, Germano.<br />

Anselm Kiefer, (catalogue) Edizioni Charta, Milan, 1997.<br />

CAMERON, Dan et al.<br />

Wim Delvoye: Cloaca, new and improved, Rectapublishers, New York, 2002.<br />

CARLSON, Marvin.<br />

Performance: a critical introduction. Routledge, London and New York, 1996.<br />

CARRIER, David.<br />

Artwriting, University Of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, Mass., 1987.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Principles of Art History Writing. Pennsylvania State University Press,<br />

University Park, Penn., 1991.<br />

-----------------------<br />

The Aesthete in the City: The Philosophy and Practice of American Abstract Painting in<br />

the 1980s, Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, Penn., 1994.<br />

CARUANA, Wally.<br />

Aboriginal Art, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1993.


266<br />

CAWS, Mary Ann.<br />

The Eye in the Text: Essays on Perception, Mannerist to Modern. Princeton<br />

University Press, Princeton, N.J. 1981.<br />

CAWS, Peter.<br />

Structuralism: The Art of the Intelligible, Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands,<br />

N.J. 1988.<br />

CELANT, Germano (ed.)<br />

The Italian Metamorphosis, 1943-1968, Guggenheim Museum, New York,<br />

1994-95.<br />

CELANT, Germano.<br />

Arte Povera, New York, Praeger, London and Washington, 1969.<br />

---------------------------<br />

The European Iceberg, Creativity in Germany and Italy Today, Rizzoli, New York,<br />

1985.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Piero Manzoni, Charta, Milan, 1998.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Carla Accardi, Rizzoli, New York, 1999.<br />

CELANT, Germano et al.<br />

Haim Steinbach: Recent Work, capoMusée d’art contemporain, Bordeaux,<br />

1988.<br />

CELANT, Germano and OPPENHEIM, Dennis.<br />

Dennis Oppenheim, Charta, Milan, 1997.<br />

CERNUSCHI, Claude.<br />

Jackson Pollock: Meaning and Significance: Icon Editions, New York, 1992.<br />

CEYSSON, B. et al.<br />

Lucio Fontana, (catalogue) Centre Georges Pompidou, Paris, 1987.<br />

CHASE, Linda and GOINGS, Ralph.<br />

Ralph Goings: An Interview, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1988.<br />

CHRISTOV-BAKARGIEV, Carolyn, (ed.)<br />

Arte Povera, Phaidon, London and New York, 1999.<br />

CHURCH, Alonzo, and BUCHENSKI, I. M.<br />

The Problem of Universals, University of Note Dame Press, Notre Dame,<br />

Indiana, 1956.


267<br />

CLARKE, T.J.<br />

The Painting of Modern Life: Paris in the Art of Ma<strong>net</strong> and His Followers, Thames<br />

and Hudson, London, 1985.<br />

-----------------<br />

Farewell to an Idea: episodes from a history of modernism. Yale University Press,<br />

New Haven and London, 1999.<br />

COLLINGS, Mathew.<br />

This is Modern Art, Watson-Guptill publications, New York, 2000.<br />

COLPITT, Frances.<br />

Minimal Art: The Critical Perspective, University of Washington Press, Seattle,<br />

1990.<br />

------------------------(ed.)<br />

Abstract Art in the Late Twentieth Century. Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge and New York, 2002.<br />

COMPTON, Michael (organizer).<br />

Peter Blake, (catalogue) The Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1983.<br />

CONNOR, Steven.<br />

Postmodernist Culture: An introduction to Theories of the Contemporary, Blackwell,<br />

Oxford, 1989.<br />

COPLANS, John (ed.).<br />

Roy Lichtenstein, Praeger, New York, Washington, 1972.<br />

COX, Neil.<br />

Cubism, Phaidon Press, London, 2000.<br />

CRICHTON, Michael.<br />

Jasper Johns, Harry N. Abrams, Inc., in association with the Whitney Museum<br />

of American Art, New York, 1994.<br />

CRIMP, Douglas.<br />

‘The End of Painting’ October, 16, 1981 pp.69-86.<br />

----------------------<br />

On the Museum’s Ruins, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1993.<br />

CRONE, Rainer and MOOS, David.<br />

Jonathan Lasker: Telling the Tales of Painting, Edition Cantz, Stuttgart, 1993.<br />

CROW, Thomas.<br />

The Rise of the Sixties, George Weidenfeld & Nicholson, London, 1996.


268<br />

DAMISCH, Hubert,<br />

'Five Notes for a Phenomenology of the Photographic Image', in Classic<br />

Essays on Photography, ed. Alan Trachtenberg, Leete's Island Books, New<br />

Haven, 1980, pp. 287-290.<br />

DAMISCH, Hubert and MARTIN, Henry.<br />

Adami, maeght editeur, Paris, 1974.<br />

DANTO, Arthur.<br />

‘The Artworld’, Journal of Philosophy, 61, 1964, p.580.<br />

--------------------<br />

The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,<br />

Mass. and London, 1981.<br />

---------------------<br />

The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art, Columbia University Press, New<br />

York and Guildford, Surrey, 1986.<br />

---------------------<br />

Encounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present. University Of California<br />

Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London, 1986.<br />

----------------<br />

‘Description And The Phenomenology Of Perception’ in Visual Theory,<br />

Norman Bryson, Michael Ann Holly and Keith Moxey (eds.) Polity Press,<br />

Oxford, 1991, pp. 201 – 215.<br />

--------------------<br />

‘The Artworld Revisited: Comedies of Similarity’ in Beyond the Brillo Box: The<br />

Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York,<br />

1992.<br />

-------------------<br />

‘Art’s Infancy’, London Review Of Books 1993, April 22, pp. 17-18.<br />

DECRON, Benoît, STORR, Robert, TRONCHE Anne.<br />

Peter Saul, (catalogue) Musée de l'abbaye Sainte-Croix, Somogy, Paris,<br />

c.1999.<br />

DE FEO, Jay.<br />

Jay De Feo, Selected Works: 1952-89, (catalogue) The Gallery, Philadelphia,<br />

1996.<br />

De GROOT, Elbrig.


269<br />

Edward Ruscha: Paintings, (catalogue) Museum Boymans-von Beuningen,<br />

Rotterdam, London and Los Angeles, 1991.<br />

DEITCH, Jeffery.<br />

Young Americans: New American Art in the Saatchi Collection, Saatchi Gallery,<br />

London, 1996.<br />

DELVOYE Wim, et al.<br />

Wim Delvoy, D.A.P. New York, 1998.<br />

DE MICHELI, Mario.<br />

Picasso, (translated by Pearl Sanders) Sadea Editore, Florence, Thames and<br />

Hudson, London, 1967.<br />

DENNISON, Lisa (organiser)<br />

Clemente, (catalogue) Guggenheim Museum publications and Harry N.<br />

Abrams, New York, 2000.<br />

DERRIDA, Jacques.<br />

De La grammatologie (Paris 1967) trans. G. Spivak. (Of Grammatology) John<br />

Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 1976.<br />

------------------------<br />

L’écriture et la différence. (Paris 1967) translated by A. Bass, (Writing and<br />

Differences), University Of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1978.<br />

------------------------<br />

Marges de la philosophie, (Paris 1972) translated by A. Bass, (Margins of<br />

Philosophy), University Of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1982.<br />

------------------------<br />

‘The time of the thesis: punctuations’, in Philosophy in France Today, A.<br />

Montefiore (ed.) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New York,<br />

1983.<br />

------------------------<br />

The Truth In Painting, translated by Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod, The<br />

University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1987.<br />

DICKIE, George.<br />

‘Defining Art’, American Philosophical Quarterly, July, 1969, p. 254.<br />

----------------------<br />

Aesthetics: an introduction, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1971.<br />

----------------------


270<br />

Art and the Aesthetic, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y. 1974.<br />

Di SAN LAZZARO, Gualtieri.<br />

Klee. (Paris, Fernand Hazan, 1957) translated by Stuart Hood, Thames and<br />

Hudson, London, 1964.<br />

DRUCKER, Johanna.<br />

Theorizing Modernism: Visual Art and Critical Tradition, Columbia University<br />

Press, New York, Guildford Surrey, 1996.<br />

DÜCHTING, Hajo.<br />

Kandinsky, translated by Ilme Lehtpere, Bendikt Taschen Verlag GmbH,<br />

Cologne, 2000.<br />

DUVE, Thierry de.<br />

‘The Monochrome and the Blank Canvas’ in Reconstructing Modernism: Art in<br />

New York, Paris and Montreal 1945-64, Serge Guilbaut (ed.) MIT Press,<br />

Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1990 pp. 244-310.<br />

----------------------<br />

Pictorial nominalism: on Marcel Duchamp’s passage from painting to the readymade,<br />

translated by Dana Polan with the author, University of Minnesota Press,<br />

Minneapolis, 1991.<br />

----------------------<br />

Clement Greenberg between the lines, (including a previously unpublished debate<br />

with Clement Greenberg) translated by Brian Holmes, Dis vou, Paris, 1996.<br />

ECO, Umberto.<br />

A Theory of Semiotics, (Milan 1976) Indiana University Press, Bloomington,<br />

1980.<br />

EDWARDS, Natasha.<br />

‘Stephen Conroy’ (review) Art Forum, October, 1989, pp. 90-191.<br />

ELDERFIELD, John.<br />

Kurt Schwitters. Thames and Hudson, London, 1985.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Morris Louis (catalogue), Museum of Modern Art, New York, 1987.<br />

ELGIN, Catherine, Z.<br />

With Reference to Reference, Hackett, Indianapolis and Cambridge, Mass., 1983.<br />

-------------------------


271<br />

‘What Goodman Leaves Out’, Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 25, No 1,<br />

Spring, 1991, pp. 89-95.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Considered Judgement, Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J., 1996.<br />

-------------------------<br />

‘Relocating Aesthetics: Goodman’s Epistemic Turn’, Revue Internationale de<br />

Philosophie, 47, 1993, pp. 171-186. Reprinted in The Philosophy of Nelson<br />

Goodman, Elgin, ed. Volume 3, ‘Nelson Goodman’s Philosophy of Art’,<br />

Garland Publishing, New York and London, 1997, pp. 1-16, and Elgin,<br />

Between the Absolute and the Arbitrary, Cornell University Press, Ithaca and<br />

London, 1997, pp. 63-80.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Between the Absolute and the Arbitrary, Cornell University Press, Ithaca and<br />

London, 1997.<br />

------------------------ (ed.)<br />

Nelson Goodman’s Philosophy of Art, Garland Publishers, New York and<br />

London, 1997<br />

------------------------ (ed.)<br />

Nelson Goodman’s Theory of Symbols and its Applications, Garland Publishers,<br />

New York and London, 1997.<br />

------------------------ (ed.)<br />

Nominalism, Constructivism and Relativism in the Work of Nelson Goodman,<br />

Garland Publishers, New York and London, 1997.<br />

------------------------ (ed.)<br />

The Philosophy of Nelson Goodman: Selected Essays, Garland Publishers, New<br />

York and London, 1997.<br />

ELKINS, James.<br />

The Poetics of Perspective, Cornell University Press, Ithaca and London, 1994.<br />

---------------------<br />

On Pictures and The Words That Fail Them, Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge and New York, 1998.<br />

---------------------<br />

The Domain of Images, Cornell University Press, Ithaca and London, 1999.<br />

---------------------


272<br />

Why Are Pictures Puzzles? On The Modern Origins of Pictorial Complexity,<br />

Routledge, New York, 1999.<br />

----------------------<br />

What Painting Is, Routledge, New York, 1998.<br />

______________<br />

What Happened to Art Criticism? Prickly Paradigm Press, Cambridge, UK and<br />

Chicago, 2003<br />

ENGBERG, Siri and PHILLPOT, Clive.<br />

Edward Ruscha Editions 1959-1999, Walker Art Center, Minneapolis, 1999.<br />

ESCHER, M.C.<br />

Grapfiek en Tekeningen, Koninklijke Erven J.J. Tijl N.V. Zvolle, Baarne,<br />

Holland, 1959. Reprinted as M.C. Escher, The Graphic Work, translated by<br />

John E. Brigham, Taschen, Cologne, London, Madrid and New York, 2001.<br />

FAUST, Max Wolfgang, and de VRIES, Gerd.<br />

Hunger Nach Bildern: deutsche malerei der gegenwart. DuMont Buchverlag, Koln,<br />

1982.<br />

FAUCHEREAU, Serge.<br />

Kupka, Ediciones Polígrafa, S. A., Barcelona, 1989.<br />

------------------------------<br />

Bernard Rancillac, Cercle d’art, Paris, 1991.<br />

FIEDLER, Jeanine and FEIERABEND, Peter (eds.)<br />

Bauhaus, Könnemann, Cologne, 2000.<br />

FIELD, Richard S.<br />

Mel Bochner: Thought Made Visible 1966-73, (catalogue) Yale University<br />

Gallery, New Haven, 1995.<br />

FINCH, Christopher.<br />

Image as Language, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, Middlesex, Baltimore,<br />

Maryland, Ringwood, Australia, 1969.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Patrick Caulfield, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, Middlesex, Baltimore,<br />

Maryland, Ringwood, Australia, 1971.<br />

FINEBERG, Jonathan.<br />

Kandinsky in Paris (1906-1907). UMI Research Press, Ann Arbor, Michigan,<br />

1975.


273<br />

---------------------------<br />

Art since 1940: Strategies of Being. (2nd edition) Laurence King Publishing,<br />

London and New York, 2000.<br />

FORGE, Andrew.<br />

Rauschenberg. Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1969.<br />

FOSTER, Edward (organiser)<br />

Edward Ruscha, (catalogue) Minneapolis Institute of Arts, Minneapolis, 1972.<br />

FOSTER, Hal (ed.)<br />

The Anti-Aesthetic – Essays on Post Modern Culture. Washington Bay Press,<br />

Port Townsend, Washington, 1983.<br />

---------------------<br />

‘Signs Taken for Wonders’, Art in America, June 1986, pp. 80-91, p.139.<br />

---------------------<br />

Return of the Real: the Avant-garde at the End of the Century, M.I.T. Press,<br />

Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1996.<br />

---------------------<br />

Vision and Visuality, The New Press, New York, 1999.<br />

FOUCAULT, Michel.<br />

The Archaeology of Knowledge, (Paris 1969) translated by A.M. Sheridan-Smith,<br />

Tavistock, London, 1972.<br />

FOX, Howard (organiser).<br />

Lari Pittman, (catalogue with essays by Dave Hickey and Paul Schimmel) Los<br />

Angeles Country Museum of Art, Los Angeles, 1996.<br />

FRANCIS, Richard.<br />

Jasper Johns, Abbeville Press, New York, London, Paris, 1984.<br />

FRANSISCONO, Marcel.<br />

Paul Klee – his Work and Thought, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and<br />

London, 1991.<br />

FRASCINA, Francis (ed.)<br />

Pollock and After: The Cultural Debate, Harper And Row, London and New<br />

York, 1985.<br />

FRASCINA, Francis and HARRISON, Charles (eds.)<br />

Modern Art and Modernism: A Critical Anthology, Harper and Row, London and<br />

New York, 1982.


274<br />

FREDERIC, Paul and SEWARD, Keith.<br />

John Currin, (catalogue) GDS Imprimeurs, Limoges, Limousin, France, 1995.<br />

FRENCH, Christopher C. (ed.)<br />

43 rd Biennial Exhibition of Contemporary American Painting, (catalogue) Corcoran<br />

Gallery of Art, Washington, 1993.<br />

FRIED, Michael.<br />

Three American Painters: Ken<strong>net</strong>h Noland, Jules Olitski and Frank Stella, Fogg Art<br />

Museum, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass. 1965. Reprinted in Francis<br />

Frascina and Charles Harrison (editors) Modern Art and Modernism, Harper<br />

and Row, New York and London, 1982, pp. 115-121.<br />

---------------------<br />

Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and Beholder in the Age of Diderot, University<br />

of California Press, Berkeley, 1980.<br />

---------------------<br />

Art and Objecthood: essays and reviews, University of Chicago Press, Chicago,<br />

1998.<br />

FRIZOT, Michel. (ed.)<br />

A New History of Photography (Paris, 1994) translated by Susan Ben<strong>net</strong>t, Liz<br />

Clegg, John Crook, Caroline Higgit, Helen Atkins, Könemann, Cologne,<br />

1998.<br />

FUCHS, Rudi, et al.<br />

Anselm Kiefer, (catalogue) Städtische Kunsthalle Düsseldorf, Düsseldorf and<br />

Paris, 1984.<br />

GABLIK, SUZI.<br />

‘Report from New York: The Graffiti Question’, Art in America, October<br />

1982, p.37.<br />

GADAMER, Hans-Georg.<br />

Truth and Method, translated by Garrett Barden and John Cumming, Sheed &<br />

Ward, London, Seabury Press, New York, 1975.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

Philosophical Hermeneutics, translated by David Linge, University of California<br />

Press, Berkeley, 1976.<br />

GAGE, John.


275<br />

Colour and Culture: Practice and Meaning from Antiquity to Abstraction. Thames<br />

and Hudson, London and New York, 1993.<br />

------------------<br />

Colour and Meaning, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1999.<br />

GAGE, John T.<br />

In The Arresting Eye: The Rhetoric of Imagism. Louisiana State University Press,<br />

Baton Rouge, La., 1981.<br />

GALE, Mathew.<br />

Dada and Surrealism, Phaidon, London, 1997.<br />

GARDNER, Martin.<br />

The Ambidextrous Universe, Penguin Books, New York, London, Ringwood,<br />

Australia, 1964.<br />

GARVIN, Harry R. (ed.)<br />

The Arts and their Interrelation. Bucknell University Press, Lewisburg, Pa. 1979.<br />

GAUGH, Harry F.<br />

Willem de Kooning. Abbeville Press, New York, London and Paris, 1983.<br />

GELDZAHLER, Henry.<br />

New York Painting and Sculpture 1940 – 1970, E. P. Dutton, New York, 1969.<br />

GIBSON, James J.<br />

The Perception of the Visual World: Houghton-Mifflin, Boston, 1950.<br />

---------------------<br />

The Senses Considered As Perceptual Systems: Houghton-Mifflin, Boston, 1966.<br />

---------------------<br />

‘The Ecological approach To Visual Perception In Pictures’, Leonardo, 1978,<br />

11, p.231.<br />

GIDAL, Peter.<br />

Andy Warhol: Films and Paintings. Studio Vista, London and E. P. Dutton,<br />

New York, 1971.<br />

GINZBURG, Carlo.<br />

Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method, John Hopkins University Press,<br />

Baltimore and London, 1989.<br />

GLAZEBROOK, Mark (organizer)<br />

David Hockney, Lund Humpheries, London, 1970.<br />

GODDARD, Donald,


276<br />

‘Selected Works by Jay De Feo’, www.newyorkartworld.com (2004)<br />

GODFREY, Tony,<br />

The New Image: Painting in the 1980s, Abbeville, New York, London and Paris,<br />

1986.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Conceptual Art, Phaidon Press, London and New York, 1998.<br />

GOLDIN, Amy.<br />

‘The ‘New’ Whitney Biennial: Pattern Emerging?’ Art in America, May-June<br />

1975, pp. 72-73.<br />

GOLDING, John.<br />

Cubism: a history and analysis 1907-1914. (1959) Faber and Faber (3 rd ed.)<br />

London and New York, 1988.<br />

---------------------<br />

Visions of the Modern, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1994.<br />

---------------------<br />

Paths to the Absolute, Thames and Hudson, London and Princeton University<br />

Press, Princeton, N.J. 2000.<br />

GOLDMANN, Judith.<br />

James Rosenquist (catalogue) Viking/Penguin Books, The Denver Museum of<br />

Art, Denver and New York, 1985.<br />

GOMBRICH E. H.<br />

‘Andre Malraux and the Crisis of Expressionism’ Burlington Magazine<br />

(December 1954) pp. 374-378.<br />

------------------<br />

Art and Illusion: Phaidon Press, Oxford, 1960.<br />

----------------------<br />

Meditations on a Hobbyhorse: Phaidon Press, Oxford, 1963.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘On Information Available In Pictures’, Leonardo, 1971, 4, pp. 195-203.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Image and the Eye: Phaidon, Oxford and New York, 1972.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘The What And The How: Perspective, Representation and the<br />

Phenomenal World’ in Logic And Art, essays in Honour of Nelson Goodman,


277<br />

Richard S. Rudner and Israel Scheffner, (eds.) Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis,<br />

1972, pp. 129-49.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘On J. J. Gibson’s Approach to The Visual Perception of Pictures’, Leonardo,<br />

1979, 12. pp. 174-176.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘Illusion And Art’, in Illusion in Nature and Art, R. L. Gregory and E. H.<br />

Gombrich, (eds.) Scribner, New York, 1971, pp. 193-244.<br />

-------------------- -<br />

‘The Leaven of Criticism in Renaissance Art’ in The Heritage Of Apelles,<br />

Studies in the Art of the Renaissance III, Phaidon, Oxford, 1976.<br />

----------------------<br />

Means and Ends: Reflections On The History Of Fresco Painting, Thames and<br />

Hudson, London, 1976.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Sense of Order: A study in the psychology of decorative art, Phaidon (1 st ed. 1979)<br />

London and New York, 1984.<br />

----------------------<br />

Reflections on the history of Art, (Richard Woodfield, ed.) Phaidon, Oxford,<br />

1987.<br />

----------------------<br />

A Lifelong Interest: Conversations on Art and Science with Didier Eribon, Thames<br />

and Hudson, London, 1991.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Story Of Art (16 th ed.) Phaidon Press, London, 1995.<br />

GOMBRICH, E.H. and GREGORY R.L (eds.)<br />

Illusions in Nature and Art, Duckworth, London, 1973.<br />

GOODMAN, Nelson.<br />

‘On Likeness of Meaning’ Analysis, 10, 1949, pp. 1-7.<br />

--------------------------<br />

‘Some Notes on Languages of Art’, Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970) pp. 563-<br />

573.<br />

-------------------------<br />

‘Professor Gibson’s New Perspective’, Leonardo, 1971, 4, pp. 359-360.


278<br />

-------------------------<br />

Problems and Projects, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1972.<br />

--------------------------<br />

Languages of Art, (2 nd ed.) Hackett, Indianapolis, 1976.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Ways of Worldmaking, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1978.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Fact, Fiction and Forecast, (2 nd ed) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.<br />

and London, 1983.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Of Mind and Other Matters, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1984.<br />

GOODMAN, Nelson and ELGIN, Catherine Z.<br />

Reconceptions in Philosophy, Routledge, London and New York, 1988.<br />

GOULD, Claudia (curator)<br />

Lisa Yuskavage, (catalogue) Institute of Contemporary Art and University of<br />

Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, 2000.<br />

GRAVENSTEIN, Alexander et al.<br />

Neo Rauch (catalogue) Bonnefantenmuseum, Maastricht, Netherlands, Hatje<br />

Cantz, Ostfildern-Ruit, Germany, D.A.P. New York, 2002.<br />

GRAY, Camilla.<br />

The Russian Experiment in Art 1863-1922, Thames and Hudson, London,<br />

1962.<br />

GREENBERG, Clement.<br />

‘Towards a Newer Laocoon’, Partisan Review, vol. vii No 4. July-August,<br />

1940, pp. 296-310.<br />

------------------------------<br />

Art and Culture, Boston, Beacon Press, 1961.<br />

-----------------------------<br />

‘America Takes the Lead’, Art in America, 53, (August-September 1965) pp.<br />

108-9.<br />

------------------------<br />

Avant-Garde Attitudes: New Art in the Sixties, The Power Institute<br />

publications, Sydney, May 1968.


279<br />

-----------------------------<br />

‘Counter Avant-Garde’, Art International, 15 May 1971, pp. 16-19.<br />

-----------------------------<br />

The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol ‘1Perceptions and Judgments’ 1939-1944,<br />

John O’Brian (ed.) University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1986.<br />

-----------------------------<br />

The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol 2 ‘Arrogant Purpose’1945-1949: John<br />

O’Brian (ed.) University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1986.<br />

----------------------------<br />

The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol 3 ‘Affirmations and Refusals’1950 – 1956<br />

John O’Brian (ed.) University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1993.<br />

----------------------------<br />

The Collected Essays and Criticism Vol 4 ‘Modernism with a Vengeance’ 1957 –<br />

1969, John O’Brian (ed.) University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and<br />

London, 1993.<br />

----------------------------<br />

‘Modern and Post Modern’ (William Dobell Memorial Lecture, Sydney<br />

Australia, 31st October, 1979) Arts, 54, No 5, February 1980.<br />

----------------------------<br />

Homemade esthetics : observations on art and taste, Oxford University Press, New<br />

York, 1999.<br />

----------------------------<br />

Clement Greenberg, late writings, (edited by Robert C. Morgan)<br />

University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, c2003.<br />

GREGORY, R. L.<br />

The Intelligent Eye, Weidenfield and Nicholson, London, 1970.<br />

---------------------- -(ed.)<br />

The Artful Eye, Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 1995.<br />

GRIESBACH, Lucius (ed.)<br />

A.R. Penck, Nationalgalerie Berlin and Prestel Verlag, Berlin and Munich,<br />

1988.


280<br />

GRIFFITHS, Paul.<br />

Cage, The Oxford University Press, London, New York and Melbourne,<br />

1981.<br />

GROSENICK, Uta and RIEMENSCHNEIDER, Burkhard (eds.)<br />

Art Now, Taschen, Cologne, 2002.<br />

GUDIS, Catherine (ed.)<br />

Helter Skelter: L.A. Art in the 1990s. (catalogue) The Museum of<br />

Contemporary Art, Los Angeles, 1992.<br />

GUILBAUT, Serge (ed.)<br />

Reconstructing Modernism. MIT Press, Cambridge Mass. and London, 1990.<br />

-----------------------<br />

How New York Stole the Idea of Modern Art, Chicago University Press, Chicago<br />

and London, 1983.<br />

HABERMAS, Jurgen.<br />

Knowledge and Human Interests. Translated by J.J. Shapiro, Beacon Press,<br />

Boston, 1971.<br />

HAGEN, Margaret A.<br />

‘There is no development in Art’ in Visual Order: The Nature And Development<br />

Of Pictorial Representation, N. H. Freeman and M. V. Cox (eds.) Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge and New York, 1985, pp. 59-77.<br />

HAGGERTY, Gerard.<br />

‘Stephen Conroy’ (review) Art News, October 1995, p.148.<br />

HAELEIN, Carl et al.<br />

Jorg Immendorff: Bilder und Zeichnungen - Paintings and Drawings, (catalogue)<br />

Kestner Gesellschaft, Hanover, 2000.<br />

HAMMOND, Anne.<br />

‘Roxy Paine at James Cohan’ (review) Art in America, October 2001, p. 156.<br />

HARRISON, Charles.<br />

English Art and Modernism 1900-1939, Yale University Press, New Haven and<br />

London, 1981 (2 nd ed. 1994).<br />

---------------------------<br />

Conceptual Art and Painting, (further essays on art and language) M.I.T. Press,<br />

Cambridge Mass. and London, 2001.<br />

HARRISON, Charles, FRASCINA, Francis and PERRY, Gill (eds.)


281<br />

Primitivism, Cubism, Abstraction: The Early Twentieth Century. Open University<br />

Press, London, Yale University Press, New Haven and London,1993.<br />

HARRISON, Helen A.<br />

Larry Rivers, Harper Collins, New York, 1984.<br />

HARRISON, Sylvia.<br />

Pop art and the origins of post-modernism, Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge and New York, 2001.<br />

HARTLY, Keith et al.<br />

The Vigorous Imagination (catalogue) Scottish National Gallery of Modern Art,<br />

Edinburgh, 1987.<br />

HEARTNEY, Eleanor.<br />

‘The Whole Earth Show Part II’, Art in America, July 1989, pp. 91-96.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

‘Chronology Dethroned’, Art in America, May 2001, pp. 55-63.<br />

HEIDEGGER, MARTIN.<br />

Being and Time, (1927) translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson,<br />

Blackwell, Oxford, 1962.<br />

HEISS, Alanna.<br />

John Wesley, D.A.P. and P.S.1, New York, 2000.<br />

HENRI, Adrian.<br />

Environments and Happenings, Thames and Hudson, London, 1974.<br />

HENTSCHEL, Martin et al.<br />

Sigmar Polke: The Three Lies of Painting, Cantz Verlag, Munich, 1997.<br />

HEYDEN, Chris Van Der (ed.)<br />

Cobra, 40 Years After, Sdu Publishers, Amsterdam, 1988.<br />

HICKS, Alistair.<br />

New British Art in the Saatchi Collection Thames and Hudson, London and<br />

New York, 1990.<br />

HIRSCH, E.D. Jnr.,<br />

Validity in Interpretation, Yale University Press, New Haven and London,<br />

1967.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Aims of Interpretation, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1976.


282<br />

HOCKNEY, David.<br />

Pictures (selected and edited by Nikos Stangos) Thames and Hudson,<br />

London, 1976.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Secret Knowledge: Rediscovering the Lost Techniques of the Old Masters, Viking<br />

Studio, New York, 2001.<br />

HOLT, Michael.<br />

Mathematics in Art, Studio Vista, London and Van Nostrand and Reinhold,<br />

New York, 1971.<br />

HOPKINS, David.<br />

After Modern Art. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 2000.<br />

HUGHES, Robert.<br />

Nothing if not Critical, Collins and Harvill, London, 1990.<br />

-----------------------<br />

The Shock of the New (2 nd ed.) BBC Books, London, 1991.<br />

HUNTER, Sam.<br />

Rivers, Abrams/Meridian Books, New York, 1971.<br />

IMMENDORFF, Jörg.<br />

Immendorff’s Handbuch der Akademie für Adler, Walter König, Cologne, 1989.<br />

JAHN. Wolf.<br />

The Art of Gilbert and George or an aesthetic of existence, (translated by David<br />

Britt) Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1989.<br />

JAMES, William.<br />

A Pluralistic Universe, (1909) Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1977.<br />

JAY, Martin.<br />

Downcast Eyes: The Denigration Of Vision in Twentieth Century French Thought.<br />

University Of California Press, Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, 1993.<br />

JOSELIT, David.<br />

Jenny Holzer, (All Works and Artist's Writings), Phaidon, London and New<br />

York, 1998.<br />

JOSEPH, Branden W.<br />

Random Order: Robert Rauschenberg and the Neo-Avant-Garde, M.I.T. Press,<br />

Cambridge Mass. and London, 2004.


283<br />

JOHNSTON, Jill.<br />

Jasper Johns: Privileged Information, Thames and Hudson, London and New<br />

York, 1997.<br />

JONES, Owen.<br />

The Grammar of Ornament, B. Quaritch, London, 1868.<br />

JUDD, Donald.<br />

‘Bar<strong>net</strong> Newman’, Studio International, Feb. 1970, pp. 67-69, reprinted in<br />

Modern Art and Modernism: A Critical Anthology, Francis Frascina and Charles<br />

Harrison, (eds.) Open University and Harper and Row, London, 1982. pp.<br />

129-132.<br />

KARDON, Ja<strong>net</strong>.<br />

David Salle (catalogue), Institute of Contemporary Art, Philadelphia, 1986.<br />

---------------------<br />

Robert Kushner, University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, 1987.<br />

KAYE, Nick.<br />

Site specific art, performance, place and documentation, Routledge, London and New<br />

York, 2000.<br />

KELLEIN, Thomas.<br />

Fluxus, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1995.<br />

KELLY, George A.<br />

The Psychology of Personal Constructs, Vols. 1and 2. Norton, New York, 1955.<br />

KEMP, Martin.<br />

Leonardo on Painting, Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1989.<br />

-----------------<br />

The Science of Art: Optical Themes in Western Art From Brunelleschi To Seurat, Yale<br />

University Press, New Haven and London, 1992.<br />

KENNEDY, John M.<br />

The Psychology of Picture Perception. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass, 1974.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Drawing and the Blind. Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1993.<br />

KENT, Sarah,<br />

‘Interview with Therese Oulton’, Flash Art, April 1986, pp. 40-44.<br />

------------------


284<br />

Shark infested waters: the Saatchi collection of British art in the 90s, Zwemmer,<br />

London, 1994.<br />

KERTESS, Klaus.<br />

“Bad’, Parkett, No 19 1989, pp. 30-36<br />

-----------------------<br />

Brice Marden, paintings and drawings, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1992.<br />

KESSLER, Charles.<br />

Ronald Davis: Paintings, 1962-76 (catalogue), San Francisco, Oakland<br />

Museum, 1976.<br />

KIPPHAN, Helmut (ed.)<br />

Handbook of Printed Media, Springer Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg and New<br />

York, 2001.<br />

KNIGHT, Christopher.<br />

‘Don Sorenson – Nicholas Wilder Gallery’ (review) Artforum, December<br />

1979, p.80.<br />

KOSENKO, Peter.<br />

‘Putting Disgust on Display: Helter Skelter: L.A. Art in the '90s, at the<br />

Museum of Contemporary Art, Los Angeles’ in In These Times 1-7 April<br />

1992, pp. 20-21.<br />

KOSTELANETZ, Richard (ed.)<br />

John Cage: an anthology, De Capo Press, New York, 1991.<br />

KOSUTH, Joseph,<br />

‘Art after Philosophy’, Studio International, October 1969, p.135.<br />

KOTZ, Mary Lynn.<br />

Rauschenberg: Art and Life. Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1990.<br />

KOZLOFF, Max.<br />

Jasper Johns. Harry N. Abrams, Inc./Meridian Modern Artists, New York,<br />

1974.<br />

KRAUSS, Rosalind.<br />

‘Notes On The Index: Seventies Art In America’, October, Spring 1977.<br />

-----------------------<br />

‘Seeing is Believing’, Raritan 2, Fall, 1982.<br />

------------------


285<br />

The Originality of The Avant Garde and other Modernist Myths, The MIT Press,<br />

Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1986.<br />

-----------------------<br />

‘Only Project’, The New Republic, 1988, Sept. 12-19, pp. 33-38.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Optical Unconscious, M.I.T. press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1993.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Picasso Papers, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York, 1998.<br />

KRENS, Thomas, GAVIN, Michael and THOMPSON, Joseph (eds.)<br />

Refigured Painting: The German Image 1960-88, (catalogue) Solomon R.<br />

Guggenheim Museum and Prestel Verlag, New York and Munich, 1988.<br />

KROEBER Karl and WALLING William (eds.)<br />

Images of Romanticism: Verbal and Visual Affinities. Yale University Press, New<br />

Haven and London, 1978.<br />

KUDIELKA, Robert.<br />

Bridget Riley: Works 1959-78, (catalogue) British Council, London, 1978.<br />

KUNTZ, Melissa.<br />

‘Frank Nitsche at Leo Koenig’ (review) Art in America, July 2002, pp. 95-96<br />

KUSPIT, Donald.<br />

The Abstract Self-Object, Galerie nacht St Stephan, Vienna, 1988, reprinted in<br />

Abstract Art of the Late Twentieth Century, Frances Colpitt (ed.) Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge, New York and Melbourne, 2002.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘Flak from the “Radicals”: The American Case against Current German<br />

Painting’ in Expressions: New Art from Germany, (catalogue) Jack Cowan (ed.)<br />

St Louis Art Museum, St Louis, Prestel Verlag, Munich, 1983, pp. 43-55.<br />

Reprinted in Art after Modernism, Brian Wallis (ed.) The New Museum of<br />

Contemporary Art, New York and David R. Godine, Boston, 1984, pp.137-<br />

151.<br />

----------------------<br />

The Rebirth of Painting in the Late Twentieth Century. Cambridge University<br />

Press, Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, 2000.<br />

LAMBERT, Jean-Clarence.<br />

Cobra, Abbeville, New York, London, Paris, 1984.


286<br />

LANE, Michael.<br />

Structuralism: A Reader, Jonathan Cape, London, 1970.<br />

LANGER, Suzanne.<br />

Philosophy in a New Key, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1951.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Feeling and Form, Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York, 1953.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Problems of Art, Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York, 1957.<br />

LEFFINGWELL, Edward.<br />

‘Will Cotton at Mary Boone’ (review) Art in America, May 2000, p.149.<br />

LEJA, Michael.<br />

Reframing Abstract Expressionism: subjectivity and painting in the 1940s, Yale<br />

University Press, New Haven and London, 1993.<br />

LESSING, Gotthold Ephraim.<br />

Laocoön, Nathan The Wise and Minna Von Barnelm, translated by W. A. Steel,<br />

Dent and Sons Ltd, for Everyman’s Library, London and New York, 1930.<br />

LE TARGAT, Francois.<br />

Kandinsky, Rizzoli, New York, 1986-7.<br />

LEVI-STRAUSS, Claude.<br />

The View from Afar (1983) translated by Joachim Neugroschel and Phoebe<br />

Hess, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, Middlesex, Ringwood, Australia<br />

New York, 1987.<br />

--------------------------------<br />

‘Reponse a quelques questions’ Esprit, n.s. 11 Paris, 1963, pp. 596-627.<br />

LEWIS, H. P.<br />

‘Spatial representation in drawing as a correlate of development and a basis<br />

for picture preference’ Journal of Ge<strong>net</strong>ic Psychology, 102, 1963, pp. 95-107.<br />

LIGHT, P.H.<br />

‘The development of view-specific representation considered from a sociocognitive<br />

standpoint’ in Visual Order: The Nature And Development Of Pictorial<br />

Representation, N. H. Freeman and M. V. Cox (eds.) Cambridge University<br />

Press, Cambridge and New York, 1985, pp. 214-230.<br />

LINKER, Kate.


287<br />

Love for Sale: The words and pictures of Barbara Kruger, Harry N. Abrams, New<br />

York, 1990.<br />

LIPPARD, Lucy.<br />

Get The Message? A Decade Of Social Change, E. P. Dutton, New York, 1984.<br />

--------------------<br />

Distant Relations: Chicano, Irish, Mexican art and writing, Smart Art Press (DAP),<br />

New York, 1996.<br />

--------------------<br />

Lure of the Local – sense of place in a multicentred society, New Press, New York,<br />

1997.<br />

LIVINGSTONE, Marco.<br />

David Hockney, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1981.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

Patrick Caulfield, (catalogue) The Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1981.<br />

------------------------------<br />

David Mach: Towards a Landscape, (catalogue) Museum of Modern Art,<br />

Oxford, 1985.<br />

-----------------------------<br />

Pop Art: A Continuing History, (2 nd ed.) Thames and Hudson, London and<br />

New York, 2000.<br />

---------------------------- et al.<br />

Herve Telemaque, Des Modes Et Travail, 1959-1999, Centre d’art de Tonlay,<br />

Tonlay, France, 1999.<br />

LIVINGSTONE, Margaret.<br />

Vision and Art: The Biology of Seeing, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 2002.<br />

LOOCK, Ulrich, ALIAGA Juan Vicente and SPECTOR, Nancy.<br />

Luc Tuymans, Phaidon, London, 1996.<br />

LONG, Rose-Carol Washton.<br />

Kandinsky: The Development of an Abstract Style. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1980.<br />

LOREAU, Max.<br />

Dubuffet: stratégie de la création, Editions Gallimard, Paris, 1973.<br />

--------------------<br />

Dubuffet, Jardin d'émail, (catalogue) Rijksmuseum Kröller-Müller, Otterlo,<br />

Nederland, 1974.


288<br />

LOVELACE, Carey.<br />

‘Lisa Yuskavage: Fleshed Out’, Art in America, July 2001, pp. 80-85.<br />

LOWE, D.G.<br />

‘Three-dimensional object recognition from single two-dimensional images’,<br />

Artificial Intelligence, 31, 1987 pp. 355-395.<br />

LUCIE-SMITH, Edward.<br />

Artoday, Phaidon, London and New York, 1995.<br />

LYOTARD, Jean-Francois.<br />

The Postmodern Condition, translated by George Bennington and Brian<br />

Massumi, University Of Minnesota Press, Minnesota, 1984.<br />

McSHINE, Kynaston (ed.)<br />

Andy Warhol: A Retrospective, (essays by Kynaston McShine, Robert<br />

Rosenblum, Benjamin Buchloh, Marco Livingstone) Museum of Modern<br />

Art and Bullfinch Press, New York, Little Brown and Co. Boston, 1989.<br />

MALONEY, Martin.<br />

‘Cecily Brown’ (review) Modern Painters, Summer 1999, p.98.<br />

MALRAUX, Andre.<br />

Les Voix du silence (Paris 1951) translated by Stuart Gilbert, The Voices of<br />

Silence Doubleday, Garden City, New York, 1953.<br />

MANZONI, Piero.<br />

Piero Manzoni, (catalogue) The Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1974.<br />

MARGOLIS, Joseph (ed.)<br />

Philosophy Looks at The Arts, Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1987.<br />

-------------------------<br />

‘Painting as An Art’ (review) Journal Of Aesthetics and Art Criticism: 1989, 47.3.<br />

p.281.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Interpretation Radical, but Not Unruly: The New Puzzle of the Arts and History,<br />

University Of California Press, Berkeley and London, 1995.<br />

MARR, David.<br />

‘Representing visual information: a computational approach.’ in Computer<br />

Vision, A. R. Hanson and E. M. Riseman (eds.) Academic Press, New York<br />

and London, 1978, pp. 61-80.<br />

---------------


289<br />

Vision: A Computational Investigation in Human Representation and Processing of<br />

Visual Information, W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, 1982.<br />

MARSHALL, Kerry James, SULTAN, Terrie, JAFFA, Arthur.<br />

Kerry James Marshall, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 2000<br />

MARSHALL, Richard.<br />

New Image Painting, Whitney Museum Of American Art, (catalogue) New<br />

York, December 1978-January 1979.<br />

MASTERS, Christopher.<br />

Dali, Phaidon, London and New York, 1995.<br />

MATHISON, Robert S.<br />

Robert Rauschenberg: Breaking Boundaries, Yale University Press, New Haven<br />

and London, 2004.<br />

MEISEL Louis K.<br />

Photo-realism, Abradale Press, New York, 1989.<br />

MELVILLE, Robert.<br />

‘The Durable Expendables of Peter Blake’, in Motif 10 Winter 1962/3<br />

reprinted in Michael Compton (editor) Peter Blake, (catalogue) Tate Gallery<br />

Publications, London, 1983, pp. 35-39.<br />

MELVILLE, Stephan.<br />

‘Notes on the re-emergence of Allegory, the Forgetting of Modernism, the<br />

Necessity of Rhetoric and the Conditions of Publicity in Art and Criticism’<br />

in October 19 (Winter 1981) pp. 55-92.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Philosophy beside itself: on deconstruction and modernism, University of Minnesota<br />

Press, Minneapolis, 1986.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Seams: art as philosophical context, G+B Arts International, Amsterdam, 1996.<br />

MILES, Christopher.<br />

‘Tracking Patterns’, Art in America, February, 2004, pp. 77-81.<br />

MITCHELL, W. J. T. (ed.)<br />

The Language of Images. University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1980.<br />

-------------------------- --


290<br />

Art and the Public Sphere, University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1992.<br />

-----------------------------<br />

Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology, University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and<br />

London, 1986.<br />

------------------------------<br />

Picture Theory, The University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1994.<br />

MICHELSON, An<strong>net</strong>te, et al. (eds)<br />

October: The First Decade, 1976-1986. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1987.<br />

MOFFETT, Kenworth.<br />

Ken<strong>net</strong>h Noland, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1977.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Jules Olitski (catalogue) Boston Museum of Fine Arts, Boston, 1973.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Larry Poons Paintings 1971-81, (catalogue) Olympic Marketing Corporation,<br />

New York, 1984.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Morris Louis in The Museum of Fine Arts Boston, (catalogue) Boston MFA<br />

publications, Boston, 1979.<br />

MORENO, Gean.<br />

‘Odili Donald Odita, Miami Art Museum’, Flash Art, October 2002, p. 104.<br />

MORGAN, Stuart.<br />

‘Julian Schnabel interviewed by Stuart Morgan’, Artscribe, No 44, December<br />

1983, pp. 15-21.<br />

MORPHET, Richard.<br />

Richard Hamilton (catalogue Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1970.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Warhol (catalogue), Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1971.<br />

---------------------------(ed.)<br />

Richard Hamilton: The Longer View, Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1992.<br />

MOSZYNSKA, Anna.<br />

Abstract Art, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1990.<br />

----------------------------


291<br />

Eberhard Haverkost, Frank Nitsche, Thomas Scheibitz, Goldener, Der Springer, Das<br />

Kalte Herz, (catalogue) Jay Jopling, London, 2000.<br />

MOURE, Gloria (ed)<br />

Jannis Kounellis: works, writings 1958-2000, DAP, New York, 2000<br />

MYERS, Terry T. et al.<br />

Peter Doig blizzard seventy seven. (catalogue) translated by David Britt and Silke<br />

Otto-Knapp, Kerber Verlag, Kiel, and Nürnberg, Whitechapel Art Gallery,<br />

London, 1998.<br />

NASGAARD, Roald and NEFF, Terry A. (eds.)<br />

Gerhard Richter: Paintings, Toronto, Museum of Contemporary Art, Chicago,<br />

Art Gallery of Ontario and Thames and Hudson, Chicago and London,<br />

1988.<br />

NEHAMAS, Alexander.<br />

‘Painting As An Art: Persons, Artists, Spectator’s Roles’ in Psychoanalysis,<br />

Mind and Art (perspectives on Richard Wollheim) J Hopkins and A. Saville (eds.)<br />

Blackwell, Oxford, 1992.<br />

NEWMAN, Michael and BIRD, Jon (eds.)<br />

Rewriting Conceptual Art (Critical Views), Reaktion Books, Oxford and New<br />

York, 1999.<br />

NEW MUSEUM OF ART (Marcia Tucker).<br />

Bad Painting, (catalogue) New Museum of Art, New York, 1978.<br />

NICHOLLS, A. L and KENNEDY, J. M.<br />

‘Drawing development from similarity of features to direction’ Child<br />

Development: 63, 1992, pp. 227-241.<br />

NOCHLIN, Linda.<br />

‘Floating in Gender Nirvana’, Art in America, March 2000, pp. 94-97.<br />

NYMAN, Michael.<br />

Experimental Music: Cage and Beyond, Studio Vista, London, 1974.<br />

ODITA, Odili Donald.<br />

‘Cecily Brown, Goya, Vogue and the Politics of Abstraction’ (interview)<br />

Flash Art, Vol XXXIII no. 215 November-December 2000, pp. 70-74.<br />

OLEANDER, William.<br />

‘Material World’, Art in America, October 1989, p.124.


292<br />

OLIVER, Cordelia,<br />

‘The Second Bombing: The Mulheimer Freiheit Group’, Artscribe, No 44,<br />

December 1983, pp. 22-26.<br />

ORTON, Fred.<br />

Figuring Jasper Johns, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

Reaktion Books, London, 1994.<br />

OSBORNE, Harold.<br />

Abstraction and Artifice in Twentieth Century Art, Oxford University Press,<br />

Oxford and New York, 1979.<br />

OSGOOD, Charles E, SUCI, George J., TANNENBAUM Percy H.<br />

The Measurement of Meaning, University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1957.<br />

OSTWALD, Wilhelm,<br />

Die Welt der Form Entwicklung und Ordnung der gesetzlichschonen Gebilde gezeich<strong>net</strong><br />

und beschreiben, (4 vols.) Unesma, Leipzig, 1922-25.<br />

PAGEL, David.<br />

‘Kerry James Marshall’ in 43 rd Biennial Exhibition of Contemporary American<br />

Painting, (catalogue) Christopher C. Finch (ed.) The Corcoran Art Gallery,<br />

Washington D.C., 1994, pp. 68-9.<br />

---------------------<br />

‘Manuel Ocampo’ in 43 rd Biennial Exhibition of Contemporary American Painting,<br />

(catalogue) Christopher C. Finch (ed.) The Corcoran Art Gallery,<br />

Washington D.C., 1994, pp. 72-3.<br />

PANOFSKY, ERWIN.<br />

Meaning in the Visual Arts, Doubleday, New York, 1955.<br />

--------------------------<br />

Die Perspective als ‘symbolische Form’ in Aufsatze, 1927 pp. 99-167.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Three Essays on Style, Irving Lavin (ed.) M.I.T. Press. Cambridge, Mass, and<br />

London, 1997.<br />

PASSERON, Rene.<br />

The Concise Encyclopedia of Surrealism, (Editions Aimery Somogy, Paris, 1974)<br />

translated by E. M. A. Graham, Omega Books, London, 1986.<br />

PAUL, Frédéric and SEWARD, Keith.


293<br />

John Currin: Works: 1989-1995, F.R.A.C. Limousin Limoges, France, and<br />

DAP, New York, 1995.<br />

PEIRCE, C. S.<br />

The Philosophy Of Peirce, Routledge and Kegan Paul, New York, 1940.<br />

PENROSE, Roland.<br />

Miro, Thames and Hudson, London, 1970.<br />

PENROSE, Roger.<br />

The Emperor’s New Mind: concerning computers, minds and the laws of physics,<br />

Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 1989.<br />

----------------------<br />

Shadows of the Mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York, 1994.<br />

PEREZ, Pilar et al.<br />

Manuel Ocampo – heridas de LA lengua: selected works, Small Art Press, Santa<br />

Monica, 1997.<br />

PERREAULT, John.<br />

‘Issues in Pattern Painting’, Artforum, November 1977, pp. 32-36<br />

PERRONE, Jeff.<br />

‘The Decorative Impulse’, Artforum, November 1979 pp. 80-81.<br />

PEYRÉ, Yves.<br />

Jean Fautrier ou Les Outrages de L'Impossible, Éditions du Regard, Paris, 1990,<br />

PHILLIPS, Lisa.<br />

David Salle, Whitney Museum of American Art, New York, 1987.<br />

PIAGET, Jean.<br />

Le Structuralisme, (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1968,) translated by<br />

Chaninah Maschler, (Structuralism) Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1971.<br />

PIRENNE, M.<br />

Optics, Painting And Photography, Cambridge University Press, London and<br />

New York, 1970.<br />

PLANT, Margaret.<br />

Paul Klee: Figures and Faces, Thames and Hudson, London, 1978.<br />

PODRO, Michael.<br />

Depiction, Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 1998.<br />

POETTER, Jochen and FRIEDEL, Helmut.


294<br />

Chuck Close, (catalogue) Hatje Canz Verlag, Ostfildern-Ruit, Germany, and<br />

D.A.P. New York, 1994.<br />

PORZIO, Domenico and VALSECCHI, Marco (eds.)<br />

Picasso, (Rome 1973) Secker and Warburg, London, 1979.<br />

POPPER, Karl.<br />

Objective Knowledge, Oxford University Press, London, 1972.<br />

PRINCENTHAL, Nancy.<br />

‘Fabian Marcaccio: Paintant’s Progress’, Art in America, January 2002, 62-65,<br />

p. 119.<br />

-------------------------------<br />

‘The Laws of Pandemonium’, Art in America, May 2001, pp. 144-149.<br />

READ, Sir Herbert.<br />

The Philosophy of Modern Art, Faber and Faber, London, 1964.<br />

RELYEA, Lane.<br />

‘Art of the Living Dead’ in Helter Skelter: L.A. Art in the 90s, (catalogue)<br />

Catherine Gudis (ed.) Los Angeles Museum of Contemporary Art, Los<br />

Angeles, 1992, pp. 33-43.<br />

--------------------<br />

‘Hi-Yo Silver: Cady Noland’s America’, Artforum, January 1993, pp. 50-54.<br />

--------------------<br />

‘Holy Crusade’, Parkett, No 46, 1996, pp. 72-76. (Also in this issue articles<br />

on Cady Noland include, Robert Bogdan, ‘Freak Shows and Talks Shows’<br />

pp. 80-84, and Thyra Nichols Goodeve, ‘Art as Encyclopaedia, History as<br />

Vaudeville’ pp. 92-97)<br />

RESTANY, Pierre.<br />

Yves Klein, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1982.<br />

RICHARDSON, John Adkins.<br />

‘Dada, Camp and the Mode called Pop’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,<br />

24 (Summer 1966) pp. 42-47.<br />

RICHARDS, W. KOENDERINK, J. J. and HOFFMAN, D.D.<br />

‘Inferring three-dimensional shapes from two-dimensional silhouettes’,<br />

Journal of The Optical Society of America: A, 4, 1987, pp. 1168-1175.<br />

RICHTER, Gerhard et al.<br />

Richter 858, D.A.P. New York, 2002.


295<br />

RICHTER, Gerhard and BUCHLOH, Benjamin<br />

Gerhard Richter: Eight Gray (catalogue), Solomon Guggenheim Museum, New<br />

York, 2003.<br />

RICHTER, Gerhard, OBRIST, Ulrich and BRITT, David<br />

The Daily Practice of Painting: Writings 1962-1993, M.I.T. Press, New York and<br />

London, 1995.<br />

RICKEY, Carrie.<br />

‘Art of the Whole Cloth’, Art in America, November 1979, pp. 73-83.<br />

RIEMENSCHNEIDER, Burkhard, GROSENICK, Uta (eds.)<br />

Art Now, Cologne, London, New York, Taschen Icons, 2001.<br />

RIFKIN, Ned.<br />

Robert Moskowitz, Thames and Hudson and the Hirshhorn Museum, London<br />

and Washington D.C. 1989.<br />

RIGBY, Penny (organizer).<br />

Patrick Caulfield (catalogue), Hillingdon Press/Waddington Galleries,<br />

Uxbridge, 1985.<br />

ROBINS, Corinne.<br />

The Pluralist Era, American Art 1968-1981, Harper & Row, New York and<br />

London, 1984.<br />

ROETHEL, Hans K and BENJAMIN, Jean K.<br />

Kandinsky, Hudson Hills, New York, 1979.<br />

ROSENBERG, Harold.<br />

The Tradition of the New, University Of Chicago Press, Chicago and London,<br />

1959.<br />

--------------------------<br />

The Anxious Object: Art Today and Its Audience. Horizon, New York, 1964.<br />

--------------------------<br />

The De-Definition of Art: Action Art to Pop To Earthwork. Horizon, New York,<br />

1972.<br />

--------------------------<br />

De Kooning, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1974.<br />

ROSENBLUM, Robert.<br />

Cubism and Twentieth Century Art, Thames and Hudson, London, 1960.<br />

------------------------------------


296<br />

Frank Stella, Penguin Books, London, New York, 1971.<br />

------------------------------<br />

‘Pop Art and Non Pop Art’ in Art and Literature 5, Summer 1964, reprinted<br />

in Pop Art Redefined, John Russell and Suzi Gablik (eds.) Thames and<br />

Hudson, London, 1969<br />

------------------------------<br />

John Currin, Harry N. Abrams, New York 2003.<br />

ROSENTHAL, Mark<br />

Anselm Kiefer (catalogue, organised by A. James Speyer) The Art Institute of<br />

Chicago, Chicago and Philadelphia, 1987.<br />

ROSS, Stephanie.<br />

‘Caricature’, The Monist, 58 (1974) pp. 284-293.<br />

---------------------<br />

‘On Goodman’s Query’ Southern Journal of Philosophy, 19, 1981, pp. 375-387.<br />

Reprinted in The Philosophy of Nelson Goodman, Catherine Z. Elgin, ed.<br />

Volume 3, ‘Nelson Goodman’s Philosophy of Art’, Garland Publishing,<br />

New York and London, 1997, pp. 349-361.<br />

RUCKHABERLE, Dieter (editor)<br />

Rauschenberg: Werke 1950-1980 (catalogue) Staatliche Kunsthalle Berlin,<br />

Berlin, 1980.<br />

RUBIN, William S.<br />

‘Jackson Pollock and the Modern Tradition’, (part I) Artforum, Feb-May<br />

1967, pp. 14-21, (part II), June-July, 1967, pp. 28-37.<br />

---------------------<br />

Frank Stella, Museum of Modern Art, New York, 1970.<br />

RUBINSTEIN, Raphael.<br />

‘Fahlström Afresh’, Art in America, July 2001 pp. 61-9 and p.113.<br />

------------------------------<br />

‘Opening the Field’, Art in America, October 2001, pp. 57-61.<br />

RUSCHA, Edward.<br />

Twenty-six Gasoline Stations, (1 st edition 1963 400 numbered, 2 nd edition 1967,<br />

500, 3 rd edition, 1969, 3000) Los Angeles<br />

------------------------


297<br />

Every Building on the Sunset Strip, (1 st edition 1966 1000 numbered; 2 nd edition<br />

1969 500; 3 rd edition 1971, 5000) Los Angeles,<br />

----------------------------<br />

Guacamole Airlines and other drawings by Edward Ruscha, Harry N. Abrams, New<br />

York, 1980.<br />

RUSSELL, John and GABLIK, Suzi (eds.)<br />

Pop Art Redefined. Thames And Hudson, London, 1969.<br />

SANDLER, Irving.<br />

Abstract Expressionism: The Triumph Of American Painting: London, Pall Mall,<br />

Praeger, New York and Washington, 1970.<br />

----------------------<br />

Art of the Postmodern Era: From the late 1960s to the early 1990s, Harper Collins,<br />

New York and London, 1996.<br />

SAUSSURE. Ferdinand de.<br />

Cours de linguistique generale, (Payot, Paris, 1949) Charles Bally and Albert<br />

Sechehaye (eds.) in collaboration with Albert Riedlinger; translated by Wade<br />

Baskin, (Course in General Linguistics) Revised ed. Fontana, London, 1974.<br />

SCHAPIRO, Meyer.<br />

‘The Nature of Abstract Art’, Marxist Quarterly, vol. 1 No 1 January 1937 pp.<br />

77-98.<br />

------------------------<br />

Modern Art: 19 th and 20 th Centuries. George Braziller, New York, 1978.<br />

------------------------<br />

‘On some problems in the Semiotics of visual art: Field and vehicle in<br />

image-signs’ in Signs, Language and Culture, A.J. Greimas and Roman<br />

Jakobson (eds.) The Hague, 1970, pp. 487-502.<br />

------------------------<br />

Words and Pictures: On the Literal and Symbolic in the illustration of a Text. The<br />

Hague, Mouton, 1973.<br />

SCHEIDEMANN, Norma V.<br />

Experiments in General Psychology, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1939.<br />

SCHJELDAHL, Peter.<br />

‘A Visit to the Salon of Autumn 1986’, Art in America, December 1986, pp.<br />

15-21.


298<br />

---------------------------<br />

Salle (an interview with David Salle), Vintage Press through Random House,<br />

New York and Toronto, 1987.<br />

--------------------------<br />

The Hydrogen Jukebox, Berkeley, University Of California Press, Los Angeles<br />

and London, 1991.<br />

SCHNEEMAN, Carolee and McPHERSON, Bruce (eds.)<br />

More Than Meat Joy, Complete performance works and selected writings,<br />

McPherson/Documentext, New York. 1979.<br />

SCHWABSKY, Barry.<br />

The Widening Circle: Consequences of Modernism in Contemporary Art, Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge and New York, 1997.<br />

SCHWABSKY, Barry, TILLMAN, Lynne and COOKE, Lynne.<br />

Jessica Stockholder, Phaidon, London and New York, 1995.<br />

SEITZ, William.<br />

Abstract Expressionist Painting in America, National Gallery of Art, Washington<br />

and Harvard University Press, Washington and Cambridge, Mass. 1983.<br />

SELZ, Peter.<br />

The Work of Jean Dubuffet (catalogue), Museum of Modern Art, New York,<br />

1962.<br />

---------------<br />

Alberto Giacometti, (catalogue) Museum of Modern Art, New York, 1965.<br />

SENIE, Harriet F.<br />

The Tilted Arc Controversy: Dangerous Precedent, University of Minnesota,<br />

Minneapolis, 2001.<br />

SEROTA, Nicholas, and SKIPWORTH, Joanna (eds.)<br />

Julian Schnabel, Paintings 1975-86 (catalogue) Whitechapel Gallery, London,<br />

1986. Contains an essay by Thomas McEvilley, and an interview with the<br />

artist by Mathew Collings.<br />

SEUPHOR, Michel.<br />

L’Art abstrait, ses origines, ses premiers maitres, Éditions Maeght, Paris, 1949.<br />

------------------------


299<br />

A Dictionary of Abstract Painting, (Paris, La Photolith, 1957) translated by<br />

Lionel Izod, John Montague and Francis Scarfe, Metheun and Co., London,<br />

1958.<br />

----------------------<br />

Abstract Painting, translated by Haakon Chevalier, Harry N. Abrams and<br />

Dell, New York, 1964.<br />

------------------------<br />

Le Style et le cri, Éditions du Seuil, Paris, 1965.<br />

SEYMOUR, A. & SYLVESTER, D.<br />

Richard Hamilton, (catalogue) Anthony d'Offay, London, 1992.<br />

SHIFF, Richard et al.<br />

Robert Mangold. Phaidon Press, London and New York, 2000.<br />

SHULTZE, Franz,<br />

Fantastic Images: Chicago Art since 1945, Follet and Co., Chicago, 1972.<br />

SIEGEL, Harvey.<br />

Relativism Refuted: A Critique of Contemporary Epistemological Relativism, Reidel,<br />

Dordecht, 1987.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘Goodmanian Relativism’, The Monist Vol 67 No 3, July, 1984, pp. 359-375.<br />

--------------------<br />

‘Relativism, Realism and Rightness: Notes on Goodmanian Worldmaking’,<br />

Journal of Thought, vol. 19, No.4, Winter, 1984, pp. 16-35.<br />

SIMMEN, Jeannot, KOHLHOFF, Kolja.<br />

Kasimir Malevich: Life and Work, translated by Paul Aston, Könemann,<br />

Cologne, London and New York, 1999.<br />

SMITH, Bernard.<br />

Modernism’s History: a study in twentieth century art and ideas. UNSW Press,<br />

Sydney, 1998.<br />

SMITH, N. and FUCIGNA, C.<br />

‘Drawing systems in children’s pictures; contour and form’, Visual Arts<br />

Research, 14 (1) 1988, pp. 66-76.<br />

SONESSON, Göran<br />

Pictorial Concepts: Inquiries into the semiotic heritage and its relevance for the analysis of<br />

the visual world, Lund University Press, Lund, Sweden, 1989.


300<br />

--------------------------<br />

Pictorial Semiotics at www.arthist.lu.se/kultsem/encyclo/pictorial _<br />

semiotics.html (2002-3).<br />

SPATE, Virginia.<br />

Orphism: The Revolution of Non-figurative Painting in Paris, Clarendon Press,<br />

Oxford, 1979.<br />

SPEISER, Andreas.<br />

Theorie der Gruppen von endlicher Ordnung, J. Springer, Berlin, 1923.<br />

STANHOPE, Zara.<br />

Good Vibrations: The Legacy of Op Art in Australia, (catalogue) Heide Museum<br />

of Modern Art, Melbourne, 2002.<br />

STEINBERG, Leo.<br />

Other Criteria: Confrontations with Twentieth-Century Art, Oxford University<br />

Press, London, Oxford, New York, 1972.<br />

STELLA, Frank.<br />

Working Space, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London,<br />

1986.<br />

STEVENS, Timothy (organizer)<br />

Patrick Caulfield, Tate Gallery Publications, London, 1981.<br />

STICH, Sidra.<br />

Made In USA – An Americanization of Modern Art, the 50s and 60s. University<br />

Of California Press, Berkley, and London 1987.<br />

-----------------<br />

Yves Klein, Cantz Verlag, Stuttgart, 1994.<br />

STILES, Kristine and SELZ, Peter (eds.)<br />

Theories and Documents of Contemporary Art: a Sourcebook of Artist’s Writings,<br />

University of California Press, Berkley and London, 1995.<br />

STORR, Robert.<br />

‘Tilted Arc: Enemy of the People?’ Art in America, September, 1985, pp. 90-<br />

97.<br />

--------------------<br />

Philip Guston, Abbeville Press, New York, London and Paris, 1986.<br />

----------------------


301<br />

Dislocations, Museum of Modern Art and Harry N. Abrams, New York,<br />

1991.<br />

----------------------<br />

Chuck Close, Museum of Modern Art and Harry N. Abrams, New York,<br />

1998.<br />

----------------------<br />

Modern Art despite modernism, Museum of Modern Art and Harry N. Abrams,<br />

New York, 2000.<br />

STORR, Robert and RICHTER, Gerhard<br />

Gerhard Richter: Forty Years of Painting, Museum of Modern Art, New York,<br />

2002.<br />

STUCKEY, Charles.<br />

‘Modern Starts: Raising the Barr?’ Art in America, May, 2000, pp. 51-57.<br />

SYLVESTER, David.<br />

Looking at Giacometti, Chatto and Windus, London, 1994.<br />

--------------------------<br />

Rene Magritte: catalogue raisonné, (Vols. 1-4) Philip Wilson, London, 1992-7.<br />

TAYLOR, Brandon.<br />

Modernism, post-modernism, realism: a critical perspective for art, Winchester School<br />

of Art Press, Winchester UK, 1987.<br />

------------------------<br />

Avant-Garde and after: rethinking art now, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1995.<br />

TEMKIN, Ann and WALKER, Hamza (eds.)<br />

Raymond Pettibon: A Reader. Philadelphia Museum of Art and DAP,<br />

Philadelphia and New York, 1998.<br />

TILGHMAN, Benjamin R. (ed.)<br />

Language and Aesthetics, University of Kansas Press, Lawrence, Kansas 1973.<br />

TISDALL, Caroline.<br />

Joseph Beuys, Thames and Hudson, London and New York, 1979.<br />

TOMASSONI, Italo.<br />

Hypermannerism, (2 nd ed) Giancarlo Politi Editore, Rome, 1992.<br />

-------------------------<br />

Pollock (Florence, Sadea Editore 1968) translated by Caroline Beamish,<br />

Thames and Hudson, London, 1968.


302<br />

TOMKINS, Calvin.<br />

The Bride and the Batchelor: Five Masters of the Avant-Garde, Penguin Books,<br />

Middlesex, England, Ringwood, Australia, New York, 1968.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Off the Wall: Robert Rauschenberg And The Art World Of Our Time, Penguin<br />

Books, Middlesex England, Ringwood, Australia, and New York 1980.<br />

-----------------------<br />

Post – To Neo – The Art World Of the 1980s. Penguin Books, Middlesex,<br />

England, Ringwood, Australia, New York, 1988.<br />

TRULLENQUE, Alicia (co-ordinator).<br />

David Salle, (catalogue) Fundacion Caja de Pensiones, Madrid, 1988.<br />

VETROCQ, Marcia E.<br />

‘Julian La Verdiere’s Imperial Designs’, Art in America, July, 2001, pp. 98-<br />

103.<br />

VIATTE, Germain and WILSON, Sara.<br />

Aftermath France, 1945-54: New Images of Man, (catalogue) Barbican Art<br />

Gallery, London, 1982.<br />

VIOLAND-HOBI, Heide E.<br />

Jean Tinguely: Life and Work, Prestel, Munich and New York, 1995.<br />

VOLK, Gregory.<br />

‘Fabian Marcaccio at Gorney Borwn + Lee’, (review) Art in America, April,<br />

2000, p.150.<br />

-------------------<br />

‘Odili Donald Odita at Florence Lynch and Riva’ (review), Art in America,<br />

May, 2002, pp. 147-148.<br />

-------------------<br />

‘Back to the Bosphorus’, (Report from Istanbul) Art in America, March,<br />

2002, pp. 94-97.<br />

____________<br />

’Figuring the New Germany’ Art in America, June/July 2005<br />

WALDMAN, Diane.<br />

Arshile Gorky: 1904 – 1948, A Retrospective, Abrams, New York, 1981.<br />

------------------------


303<br />

Roy Lichtenstein, (catalogue) Solomon R. Guggenheim Foundation, New<br />

York, 1993.<br />

WALLIS, Brian (ed.)<br />

Art after Modernism: Rethinking Representation, The New Museum of<br />

Contemporary Art, New York, and David R. Godine Publishers, Boston,<br />

1984.<br />

------------------------------<br />

Hans Haacke, unfinished business, M.I.T. press, Cambridge Mass. and London,<br />

1986.<br />

------------------------------<br />

Democracy: A Project by Group Material, Dia Foundation, Bay Press, Seattle and<br />

New York, 1990.<br />

WARHOL Andy and HACKETT, Pat.<br />

Popism: The Warhol ‘60s, Harcourt Brace and Janovich, New York, 1980.<br />

WARTOFSKY, Max.<br />

‘Rules And Representation: The Virtues Of Constancy And Fidelity In<br />

Perspective’, Erkenntnis, 1978, pp. 12, 17-36.<br />

WEISBERGER, Edward (ed).<br />

Clemente (catalogue), Solomon R. Guggenheim Foundation, New York,<br />

1999.<br />

WEI, Lilly.<br />

‘Talking Abstract: Part Two’, Art in America, December, 1987, pp 114-122,<br />

p.171.<br />

WEITZ, Morris.<br />

Wittgenstein’s Aesthetics’ in Language and Aesthetics, Benjamin R. Tilghman,<br />

(ed.) University of Kansas Press, Lawrence, Kansas, 1973.<br />

WEYL, Hermann.<br />

Symmetry, Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J., 1952.<br />

WHEELER, Daniel.<br />

Art since Mid-Century: 1945 to the Present, Vendome Press Paris, and Prentice-<br />

Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J. and New York, 1991.<br />

WILLATS, John<br />

Art and Representation: New Principles In The Analysis Of Pictures: Princeton<br />

University Press, Princeton, N.J., 1997.


304<br />

WILSON, B. and WILSON, M.<br />

‘An iconoclastic view of the imagery sources in the drawing of young<br />

people’, Art Education: 30 (1) 1977, pp. 4-6.<br />

------------------------------------<br />

‘The case of the disappearing two eyed profile; or how little children<br />

influence the drawings of little children’, Review of Research in Visual Arts<br />

Education: 15, 1981, pp. 1-18.<br />

WILSON, Simon.<br />

Surrealist Painting, Phaidon, London, 1975.<br />

WIMSATT, William K.<br />

‘Laocoon: an oracle reconsulted’ in Hateful Contraries, University of<br />

Kentucky Press, Lexington, 1965.<br />

WITTGENSTEIN, Ludwig.<br />

Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung, in Annalen der Naturphilosophe, (1921)<br />

translated by D. F. Pears and B.F. McGuiness, (Tractatus Logico-philosophicus,)<br />

Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1961.<br />

--------------------------------<br />

Philosophical Investigations, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, Blackwell,<br />

Oxford, 1953.<br />

WÖLFFLIN, Heinrich.<br />

Principles Of Art History, translated by M. D. Hottinger, Dover Publications,<br />

New York, 1932.<br />

WOLFRAM, Eddie.<br />

History of Collage, Studio Vista, London, 1975.<br />

WOLLEN, Peter.<br />

Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, (2 nd ed.) Secker and Warburg, London, 1972.<br />

----------------------<br />

‘The Two Avant-Gardes’, Studio International, December 1975, pp. 171-175.<br />

(Reprinted in Wollen, Readings and Writings London, 1982, pp. 92-104.)<br />

--------------------<br />

Readings and Writings, Verso Editions, London, 1982.<br />

WOLLHEIM, Richard.<br />

On Art and the Mind, Allen Lane, London, 1973.<br />

---------------------------


305<br />

‘Representation: the philosophical contribution to psychology’ in The Child’s<br />

Representation of the World. G Butterworth (ed.) Plenum Press, New York,<br />

1977, pp. 173-188.<br />

---------------------------<br />

‘Are the Criteria of Identity that Hold for a Work of Art in Different Arts<br />

Aesthetically Relevant?’ in Ratio, 20, 1978, pp. 29-48.<br />

------------------------ -<br />

Art and Its Objects (2 nd ed.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge and New<br />

York, 1980.<br />

---------------------------<br />

Painting as an Art. Thames And Hudson, London and New York, 1987.<br />

---------------------------<br />

‘The Moment of Cubism Revisited’, Modern Painters, Vol. 2 Number 4.<br />

Winter, 1989-90, pp. 26-31.<br />

---------------------------<br />

‘The Core of Aesthetics’, Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 25, No. 1, Spring,<br />

1991, pp. 37-45.<br />

---------------------------<br />

The Mind and Its Depths, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass. and<br />

London, 1993.<br />

---------------------------<br />

On Formalism and its Kinds, Fundacio Antoni Tapies, Barcelona, 1995.<br />

YAU, John.<br />

A. R. Penck, Harry N. Abrams, New York, 1993.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!