16.11.2014 Views

Protecting Religious Liberty: The False Messiahs of Free Speech ...

Protecting Religious Liberty: The False Messiahs of Free Speech ...

Protecting Religious Liberty: The False Messiahs of Free Speech ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

18 JLPOL 119 Page 1<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Law & Politics<br />

Winter 2002<br />

Symposium<br />

Beyond Separatism: Church and State<br />

*119 PROTECTING RELIGIOUS LIBERTY: THE FALSE MESSIAHS OF FREE SPEECH DOCTRINE AND<br />

FORMAL NEUTRALITY<br />

Alan Brownstein [FNa1]<br />

Copyright (c) 2003 Journal <strong>of</strong> Law and Politics, Inc.; Alan Brownstein<br />

Introduction<br />

<strong>The</strong> title <strong>of</strong> this Symposium, “Beyond Separatism,” may foreshadow important changes in Religion Clause<br />

doctrine in the years ahead. However, it is always difficult to accurately forecast constitutional developments.<br />

This is particularly true if we are projecting our constitutional pre-vision beyond the doctrinal preferences <strong>of</strong> the<br />

current Court and into the more distant future.<br />

Part <strong>of</strong> the problem in predicting changes in Religion Clause doctrine should be self-evident. <strong>The</strong> constitutional<br />

case law grounded on a wall <strong>of</strong> separation between church and state has certainly had its share <strong>of</strong> problems.<br />

Some decisions seem particularly difficult to defend. <strong>The</strong> doctrinal replacement for “Separatism,”<br />

however, has not been tested, because it has not been formally established yet. If and when a new model is accepted,<br />

its utility and costs will be evaluated over time. It may be that the value <strong>of</strong> separating church and state<br />

will be better understood and appreciated after our society experiments with alternative doctrinal approaches and<br />

confronts the problems they create.<br />

As Justice Holmes once intimated, all life is an experiment. “Every year if not every day we have to wager<br />

our salvation upon some prophecy based upon imperfect knowledge.” [FN1] Constitutional law is no different.<br />

<strong>The</strong> core <strong>of</strong> our legal and political culture has been pragmatism and experimentation, not a commitment to unchangeable<br />

absolutes and fixed principles. [FN2] Nothing is, or has been, sacred in *120 constitutional law. But<br />

constitutional law is not always a one-way ratchet either. Sometimes what we learn from an experiment is that<br />

we were better <strong>of</strong>f under existing doctrine and that a change was for the worse.<br />

In this essay, I want to critically examine two developments that have become rooted in doctrine over the<br />

last ten to twenty years. One is the continuing and expanding protection <strong>of</strong> religious activities under the <strong>Free</strong><br />

<strong>Speech</strong> Clause <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment. <strong>The</strong> other is the growing acceptance <strong>of</strong> formal neutrality as a framework<br />

for protecting the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion. Both <strong>of</strong> these developments are part <strong>of</strong> the evolving replacement<br />

for Separatism. <strong>The</strong> first, the subsuming <strong>of</strong> religion under the rubric <strong>of</strong> speech, has been accepted largely<br />

uncritically. <strong>The</strong> other, manifested by the Court's holding in Employment Division v. Smith, [FN3] received<br />

overwhelming criticism at first. [FN4] Over time, however, there has been greater acceptance <strong>of</strong> this approach.<br />

Critics, while still rejecting Smith, on its face as it were, have started to make the best <strong>of</strong> it and are trying to<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 2<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

build a shield for religious practices and institutions from the bones the Court tossed to religious liberty in deciding<br />

that case. [FN5]<br />

I believe both <strong>of</strong> these developments are problematic. <strong>The</strong>y are false messiahs. Evaluating burdens on religious<br />

practices as the regulation <strong>of</strong> speech has some virtues, but the problems with this approach may outweigh<br />

its benefits. Moreover, many <strong>of</strong> the purported benefits that result from protecting religion as speech are only advantageous<br />

when they are evaluated against the anemic free exercise regime established by the Smith decision.<br />

If we compare a vigorously enforced <strong>Free</strong> *121 Exercise Clause against the religion as speech model,<br />

the perceived utility <strong>of</strong> the latter approach dissipates dramatically.<br />

As for formal neutrality, I think not only that Smith is wrong, but also that it is beyond redemption. <strong>The</strong> exceptions<br />

identified in Smith simply do not work and cannot be justified. Attempts to protect religious liberty<br />

within the confines <strong>of</strong> Smith are unlikely to be successful.<br />

I. Are <strong>Religious</strong> Activities <strong>Speech</strong> For First Amendment Purposes?<br />

Many religious activities have an expressive dimension. Proselytizing is a form <strong>of</strong> expressive advocacy implicating<br />

the core function <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause to protect persuasive speech. [FN6] Prayer is also expressive.<br />

While some prayer may be most accurately characterized as self-realizing or self-defining expression in that<br />

it does not serve any informational, persuasive, or instrumental function, [FN7] prayer is also a communicative<br />

mechanism that expresses and reinforces a shared reality and shared values among the members <strong>of</strong> a religious<br />

congregation or community. [FN8] Other forms <strong>of</strong> religious practice, such as complying with dietary rules or<br />

grooming standards, wearing required clothing or symbols, observing the Sabbath, and participating in any <strong>of</strong> a<br />

range <strong>of</strong> rituals, are conduct-intensive actions. <strong>The</strong>ir purpose may not be overtly expressive, but there is a communicative<br />

aspect to them. If nothing else, they affirm to co-religionists and outsiders the religious identity and<br />

commitment <strong>of</strong> the person engaging in the religiously-motivated activity.<br />

For constitutional purposes, there is no doubt that many <strong>of</strong> these activities can be characterized as<br />

speech. This does not mean that it is always wise or appropriate to do so. Answering that question, which is<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the purposes <strong>of</strong> this article, requires careful consideration <strong>of</strong> the consequences <strong>of</strong> such an analysis. What<br />

is clear, I think, is *122 that there is enough <strong>of</strong> an expressive component to many religious activities that conceptualizing<br />

them as speech does not require any extension or modification <strong>of</strong> the way we conventionally define<br />

speech for First Amendment purposes.<br />

But do we really have a choice here? Don't we have to conceptualize religious activities as speech and review<br />

laws restricting such activities under free speech doctrine if, in fact, there is a real speech dimension to the<br />

religious activity? I don't think constitutional law is that objective or that rigid. <strong>The</strong> demarcation lines separating<br />

constitutional frameworks are more normative than this argument suggests. Not everything that can reasonably<br />

be characterized as speech must necessarily be treated as speech for First Amendment purposes.<br />

Certainly, courts do not require that all activities involving speech must be protected as speech for constitutional<br />

purposes. <strong>Speech</strong> is an aspect <strong>of</strong> many activities. Often the regulation <strong>of</strong> these activities by the state is<br />

not subject to <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause review. Consider a straightforward example. <strong>The</strong> practice <strong>of</strong> medicine involves<br />

communication between doctor and patient and among medical personnel. Still, we do not review many<br />

laws regulating the practice <strong>of</strong> medicine as regulations <strong>of</strong> speech. This is even the case for medical regulations<br />

that are directed at medical communications, such as rules requiring informed consent before a medical proced-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 3<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ure may be performed. <strong>The</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> First Amendment review <strong>of</strong> laws regulating the practice <strong>of</strong> medicine,<br />

law, accounting, and other pr<strong>of</strong>essions involving speech isn't controversial. We decide that the subject <strong>of</strong> the<br />

regulation is more appropriately conceptualized as medicine and law rather than speech and proceed accordingly.<br />

Now assume that a law is passed regulating faith or spiritual healing, the use <strong>of</strong> prayer to cure physical illness<br />

as an alternative to modern medical practice. Are laws directed at faith healing regulations <strong>of</strong> speech or<br />

regulations <strong>of</strong> an alternative form <strong>of</strong> medicine? Spiritual healing is probably more speech intensive than much<br />

<strong>of</strong> modern medicine, but our answer will probably not depend on the extent to which speech plays a role in the<br />

activity being regulated. Thus, we might still decide that faith healing should be reviewed as a form <strong>of</strong> the practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> medicine and not as expressive activity. A variety <strong>of</strong> factors might help us to reach this conclusion, but it<br />

is unlikely that the amount <strong>of</strong> speech involved in the activity would be controlling. [FN9]<br />

*123 Finally, consider a law regulating worship services. Worship involves a great deal <strong>of</strong> speech. But prayers<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered in a church or synagogue are not all that distinguishable as speech from prayers that are <strong>of</strong>fered to<br />

heal the sick in Christian Science sanitoria. <strong>Speech</strong> is a major component <strong>of</strong> both worship and faith healing.<br />

Moreover, just as speech in the context <strong>of</strong> faith healing can be construed to be part <strong>of</strong> an alternative form <strong>of</strong><br />

medical practice, and speech can be understood to be part <strong>of</strong>, and subsumed under, the practice <strong>of</strong> law, worship<br />

can be conceptualized to be part <strong>of</strong> the practice <strong>of</strong> an equally distinct and specific mission or pursuit, the practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion. <strong>Speech</strong> used in religious practices can be considered religion, not speech, for constitutional purposes<br />

just like speech used in the practice <strong>of</strong> medicine or law can be considered medicine or law and not speech<br />

for constitutional purposes. This is not to say that religion can never be construed to be speech even if we want it<br />

to be. It is merely to recognize that religion can be legitimately understood to be either speech or religion depending<br />

on the values and constitutional vision we bring to the task <strong>of</strong> categorizing it.<br />

Why should we want to conceptualize religious activity as speech, rather than religion? One obvious answer<br />

for those <strong>of</strong> us who care about shielding religious practices from unjustified state interference is that we might<br />

extend the protection the Constitution provides to religious liberty by doing so. Maybe it is time to move out<br />

from under the free exercise umbrella that was so effectively shredded by Employment Division v. Smith and<br />

place ourselves under the sturdier canopy provided by the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. As I will explain in detail as this<br />

Article progresses, while free speech doctrine has some limited utility for the protection <strong>of</strong> religious individuals<br />

and institutions, on balance, I believe the shift from a rigorously enforced free exercise and establishment clause<br />

paradigm to a free speech model has significant problems, some <strong>of</strong> which undermine religious liberty and equality<br />

in important ways. First, however, it is necessary to explain how the interplay <strong>of</strong> free speech and Religion<br />

Clause doctrine has developed over time. <strong>The</strong>n the consequences <strong>of</strong> the current emphasis on free speech rather<br />

than on free exercise doctrine can be evaluated.<br />

*124 A. <strong>The</strong> Early History <strong>of</strong> Religion and <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Certainly, there is some historical pedigree for equating at least certain exercises <strong>of</strong> religion and<br />

speech. <strong>The</strong> overlap <strong>of</strong> the coverage <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause has been evident to<br />

courts since the 1930's, at about the time that judicial responsibility for the protection <strong>of</strong> expression first began<br />

to be taken seriously. In many <strong>of</strong> these early cases, when much <strong>of</strong> free speech doctrine was still indeterminate<br />

and just beginning to develop, religious speech was <strong>of</strong>ten the subject <strong>of</strong> regulation. Judicial decisions protected<br />

such expressive activities, but did not identify and pigeonhole the activity in question as either speech or reli-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 4<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

gion. Instead, the Court's opinions suggested that the challenged laws implicated both the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause<br />

and the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment.<br />

Cantwell v. Connecticut, [FN10] one <strong>of</strong> the earliest modern cases giving meaning both to the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause and to the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause, for example, involved a mixture <strong>of</strong> free exercise and free speech analysis.<br />

In overturning the conviction <strong>of</strong> Jehovah's Witnesses engaged in door-to-door religious solicitation, the Court<br />

explained: “[t]he fundamental law declares the interest <strong>of</strong> the United States that the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion be<br />

not prohibited and that freedom to communicate information and opinion be not abridged.” [FN11]<br />

Subsequent cases <strong>of</strong> the same period, also involving Jehovah's Witnesses, recognized the same intrinsic<br />

overlap <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause regarding the public expression <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

messages. Murdock v. Pennsylvania [FN12] involved the application <strong>of</strong> an ordinance requiring licenses for solicitors<br />

to individuals going door to door distributing religious literature. In explaining his decision that this tax<br />

violated the First Amendment, Justice Douglas described the dual nature <strong>of</strong> the activity at issue and the constitutional<br />

provisions that protected it.<br />

This form <strong>of</strong> evangelism . . . is more than preaching; it is more than the distribution <strong>of</strong> religious literature.<br />

It is a combination <strong>of</strong> both. Its purpose is as evangelical as the revival meeting. This form <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

activity occupies the same high estate under the First Amendment as do *125 worship in the<br />

churches and preaching from the pulpits. It has the same claim to protection as the more orthodox and<br />

conventional exercises <strong>of</strong> religion. It also has the same claim as the others to the guarantees <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

speech and freedom <strong>of</strong> the press. [FN13]<br />

<strong>The</strong>se early religious speech cases, <strong>of</strong> course, involved conventionally expressive activity that was virtually<br />

indistinguishable from secular speech. <strong>The</strong> Court did not intimate that other religious conduct would receive<br />

free speech protection. Indeed, at this time it was doubtful that many other religious practices would receive any<br />

serious protection under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause. <strong>Free</strong> exercise rights barely existed under the authority <strong>of</strong><br />

Reynolds v. United States, [FN14] which limited this constitutional guarantee to religious beliefs, not religious<br />

practices. [FN15] Moreover, the Court in Murdock made it clear that it was not challenging this precedent:<br />

“[W]e do not intimate or suggest . . . that any conduct can be made a religious rite and by the zeal <strong>of</strong> the practitioners<br />

swept into the First Amendment.” [FN16] Reynolds did not extend constitutional protection to the practice<br />

<strong>of</strong> polygamy, and “[o]ther claims may well arise which deserve the same fate.” [FN17]<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court did suggest in Cantwell and Murdock that religious speech, at least time-honored and traditional<br />

means <strong>of</strong> communicating religious messages, would receive free exercise protection. But there is a sense in<br />

which this conclusion constituted a kind <strong>of</strong> constitutional slight <strong>of</strong> hand. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause would protect<br />

religious speech, the Court seemed to imply, only to the extent that such speech was already protected<br />

against abridgement under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. But if that is the case, what work, if any, did the Court's repeated<br />

references to the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause perform in this analysis? <strong>The</strong> real foundation for the Court's holdings<br />

was freedom <strong>of</strong> speech. <strong>Religious</strong> liberty was *126 welcome to come along for the ride, as long as it could<br />

piggyback on the shoulders <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> speech. [FN18]<br />

Thus, these early cases provide little support for any expansive commitment to protecting religion as<br />

speech. <strong>The</strong> particular religious practices at issue were virtually indistinguishable from conventional expressive<br />

activities. More importantly, there was really no judicial recognition at the time that free exercise rights constituted<br />

a distinct constitutional interest that merited independent protection. Courts did not need to think about reconciling<br />

free exercise and free speech protection or to determine when an activity should be appropriately char-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 5<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

acterized as speech or religion, because the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause provided too little protection to warrant the effort.<br />

Constitutional law evolved substantially during the next forty years. <strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine developed into an<br />

extraordinary and increasingly complex set <strong>of</strong> rules and standards. Under current case law, characterizing an individual's<br />

activity as speech and a statute as regulating speech is no trivial constitutional matter. It invokes a<br />

massive doctrinal framework.<br />

<strong>Free</strong> exercise case law developed independently <strong>of</strong> free speech doctrine under a “separatist” regime. One<br />

simple rule allegedly controlled the review <strong>of</strong> all state-created restrictions on, interference with, and obstacles to<br />

religious practice both at individual and institutional levels. In Sherbert v. Verner [FN19] and Wisconsin v. Yoder,<br />

[FN20] the Court held that state action substantially burdening the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion must be justified<br />

under strict scrutiny. This strict scrutiny approach, obviously inadequate to the task assigned to it, was <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

honored in the breach. Some burdens on religious practice and interference with religious institutions were successfully<br />

challenged. [FN21] Many more were rejected. [FN22] Most importantly, the courts have never developed<br />

a set <strong>of</strong> sub rules and standards to deal with the complexity *127 <strong>of</strong> the problems they confronted as has<br />

been done in the free speech area. [FN23]<br />

<strong>The</strong> Establishment Clause, also committed to the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state, was interpreted to serve<br />

several functions. To a significant extent, it became the vehicle for policing government conduct to guarantee<br />

religious equality as well as religious liberty. [FN24] Here, unlike the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause, the Constitution<br />

was interpreted to impose prophylactic constraints on government. Because government regulations promoting<br />

religion and government financial support <strong>of</strong> religious institutions and practices were perceived as creating substantial<br />

risks <strong>of</strong> discrimination against disfavored faiths and interference with religious autonomy, both forms <strong>of</strong><br />

state action were prohibited. [FN25] <strong>The</strong> doctrinal tests employed to administer this framework were more complex<br />

than those adopted for free exercise cases. Generally speaking, state programs funding religious institutions<br />

or activities were reviewed under the Lemon v. Kurtzman [FN26] test, under which subsidy systems that either<br />

lacked a secular purpose, primarily advanced religion, or entangled the state with religion were struck down.<br />

[FN27] Overt favoritism toward majoritarian faiths manifested through such practices as state-mandated prayer<br />

in public schools was declared unconstitutional. [FN28]<br />

<strong>The</strong> historical and analytic foundation <strong>of</strong> Religion Clause doctrine at this time had two related themes: the<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> church and state and government neutrality toward religion. <strong>The</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> separation had roots dating<br />

back to Roger Williams. [FN29] <strong>The</strong> more contemporary historical sources cited to support its constitutional<br />

legitimacy were the writings and political actions <strong>of</strong> James Madison and Thomas Jefferson. [FN30] *128 But the<br />

core idea <strong>of</strong> separatist doctrine as it was reflected in Supreme Court cases had a pragmatic as well as a historical<br />

basis. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause and the Establishment Clause <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment were both explicitly directed<br />

at religion. But while these constitutional phrases shared some common coverage, they also seemed to be<br />

pointing in opposite directions. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause prohibited government interference with religion, and<br />

the Establishment Clause restricted government promotion <strong>of</strong> religion. <strong>The</strong> apparent divergence <strong>of</strong> these commands<br />

could be expressed and unified under a single principle, however. If government could neither interfere<br />

with nor promote religion, how could it be involved with religion at all? Thus, the Religion Clauses mandated<br />

the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state. [FN31]<br />

Whatever the merits or problems with separatist doctrine and the quest for religious neutrality may have<br />

been, during this period, the Court focused on religion as a distinct constitutional interest that invoked specific<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 6<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

constitutional concerns. <strong>The</strong> dual constitutional commands necessary to achieve the separation <strong>of</strong> church and<br />

state were distinct from the unitary mandate employed to protect other important interests, such as freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

speech and the press, because the relationship between church and state was unique. Close connections between<br />

government and other sources <strong>of</strong> private power, a partnership between government and the press, for example,<br />

might be constitutionally problematic for obvious reasons. But the pervasive role <strong>of</strong> religious belief in the lives<br />

<strong>of</strong> citizens, the communal nature <strong>of</strong> religious affiliation, and the perceived consequences <strong>of</strong> religious factionalism<br />

made the diffusion <strong>of</strong> power between secular and faith-based policies and centers <strong>of</strong> authority <strong>of</strong> paramount<br />

importance.<br />

Even the idea <strong>of</strong> neutrality reflected the special status <strong>of</strong> religion. Government neutrality toward religion<br />

could not be satisfied by ignoring the existence <strong>of</strong> religious beliefs and practices and their defining importance<br />

to individuals and communities. Neutrality under a separatist model required government to take account <strong>of</strong> religion.<br />

[FN32] *129 Neutrality implied a holistic attitude toward religion that in the aggregate treated religious<br />

and secular belief systems as equally worthy <strong>of</strong> respect, but distinguished between them in particular funding<br />

and regulatory circumstances, ostensibly favoring secular beliefs in the former context and religious beliefs in<br />

the latter.<br />

Finally, neutrality did not mean that the Constitution should be neutral between religion and other constitutionally<br />

protected interests, such as speech, and treat the former and the latter identically. <strong>The</strong> Constitution's<br />

commands regarding religion were active, separate, and discrete. [FN33] Religion was much more than speech.<br />

It was a mixture <strong>of</strong> beliefs, expression, self-defining decisions, rules <strong>of</strong> conduct, social institutions, and communities<br />

<strong>of</strong> individuals. As such, it deserved the special constitutional attention it received.<br />

B. <strong>The</strong> Inevitable Conflict Between <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and Religion Clause Doctrine<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> 1980's - Case Holdings and Unanswered Questions<br />

During the 1980's, the divergence between <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and Religion Clause case law became impossible<br />

to ignore. <strong>The</strong> overlap between the subjects <strong>of</strong> both constitutional frameworks was self-evident. Many religious<br />

activities were overtly expressive in their purpose and speech intensive in their nature. Moreover, religion was,<br />

obviously, a subject or viewpoint <strong>of</strong> expression. In many cases, the practice <strong>of</strong> religion seemed hard to differentiate<br />

from speech discussing or espousing religious beliefs. But the constitutional consequences <strong>of</strong> identifying<br />

regulated or funded activity as speech or religion were contradictory. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause required rigorous<br />

review <strong>of</strong> content or viewpoint discriminatory regulations <strong>of</strong> expression. Thus, in most situations, for speech<br />

purposes, religious and secular expression must receive identical regulatory treatment. <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause, however, provided greater protection for religious practices than *130 secular belief related activities;<br />

the Establishment Clause restricted government supported religious speech, while it permitted government expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> secular messages.<br />

Doctrinal conflict could arise in a variety <strong>of</strong> circumstances. <strong>Religious</strong> speakers might demand special free<br />

exercise protection against content-neutral laws restricting speech that secular speakers must obey. [FN34] Statutory<br />

exemptions from content-neutral regulations for religious speakers might be challenged on <strong>Speech</strong> Clause<br />

or Establishment Clause grounds and defended on free exercise grounds. [FN35] Restrictions on religious expression<br />

might be both challenged on free exercise or free speech grounds, and defended, if the speech received<br />

government support or communicated a message <strong>of</strong> government endorsement, on Establishment Clause grounds.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 7<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN36]<br />

Three cases decided in the 1980's provided initial answers to each <strong>of</strong> these three conflict scenarios. In 1981,<br />

in Heffron v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., [FN37] followers <strong>of</strong> the Krishna religion<br />

challenged a Minnesota State Fair regulation limiting the distribution or sale <strong>of</strong> expressive materials except from<br />

booths that might be reserved for that purpose. To the plaintiffs, the distribution and sale <strong>of</strong> religious materials<br />

constituted a religious ritual, the practice <strong>of</strong> Sankirtan. Yet, the Court upheld the regulation as a legitimate time,<br />

place, and manner restriction on speech under the conventional, but relatively deferential, <strong>Speech</strong> Clause standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> review applied to content-neutral laws. [FN38]<br />

Later that term, in Widmar v. Vincent, [FN39] the Court evaluated a state university regulation prohibiting<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> university buildings or grounds “for [purposes <strong>of</strong>] religious worship or religious teaching.” [FN40]<br />

Pursuant to this policy, a student group <strong>of</strong> evangelical Christians was denied access to university facilities for<br />

meetings that would include “prayer, hymns, Bible commentary, and discussion <strong>of</strong> religious views and experiences.”<br />

[FN41] <strong>The</strong> Court ruled that the university had created a *131 designated public forum when it allowed<br />

other student groups to use its buildings for expressive activities. Accordingly, the content-discriminatory exclusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the religious group was reviewed under strict scrutiny and struck down. [FN42] Eight years later, in<br />

Texas Monthly, Inc. v. Bullock, [FN43] the Court evaluated a Texas statute exempting “periodicals . . .<br />

‘published or distributed by [a religious] faith,”’ “‘consist[ing] wholly <strong>of</strong> writings promulgating the teaching <strong>of</strong><br />

[the] faith”’ and books consisting wholly <strong>of</strong> “'writings sacred to a religious faith”' [FN44] from a sales and use<br />

tax fully applicable to secular writings. This statute was struck down as a violation <strong>of</strong> the Establishment Clause.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se decisions form the foundation for today's accepted orthodoxy regarding the relationship between religion<br />

and speech. <strong>The</strong>y represent the core precedent on which recent religious speech cases rely. Yet there has<br />

been surprisingly little critical analysis <strong>of</strong> these opinions to determine if they provide an adequate doctrinal root<br />

structure for the line <strong>of</strong> authority that would ultimately develop in this area.<br />

While the specific holdings <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> these cases may be persuasively defended, the Court's discussion and<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> the relationship between speech and religion was inadequate in all three decisions. Further, the<br />

Court seemed oblivious to its prior decisions when it decided each subsequent case. No effort was made to<br />

achieve consistency or coherence. It is important to understand that when recent opinions claim to follow a developed<br />

line <strong>of</strong> authority in this area, they ground their arguments on weak, poorly thought out, and disjointed<br />

precedents.<br />

In Heffron, the first decision, the Court simply ignored two obvious questions: should plaintiffs' solicitation<br />

activities in the fairgrounds be characterized as speech rather than religious practice, and, correspondingly, why<br />

should the state's restrictions be reviewed under the relatively lenient intermediate scrutiny applied to content<br />

neutral regulations <strong>of</strong> speech rather than under the strict scrutiny review applied to substantial burdens on religious<br />

activities under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause. [FN45] <strong>The</strong> Court stated without explanation that, “[n]one *132<br />

<strong>of</strong> our cases suggest that the inclusion <strong>of</strong> peripatetic solicitation as part <strong>of</strong> a church ritual entitles church members<br />

to solicitation rights in a public forum superior to those <strong>of</strong> members <strong>of</strong> other religious groups [or their secular<br />

counterparts] that raise money but do not purport to ritualize the process.” [FN46]<br />

Justice Brennan, writing in dissent, recognized the blatant tension between the majority's analysis and the<br />

free exercise mandate “that governmental regulations which interfere with the exercise <strong>of</strong> specific religious beliefs<br />

or principles should be scrutinized with particular care.” [FN47] In an attempt to mitigate the impact <strong>of</strong><br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 8<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Heffron on generic free exercise protection, Brennan suggested that the majority opinion should be read as accepting<br />

the Court's free exercise precedents, but holding that even expressive “‘conduct protected by the <strong>Free</strong><br />

Exercise Clause,’ . . . is entitled to no greater protection than other forms <strong>of</strong> expression protected by the First<br />

Amendment that are burdened to the same extent” [FN48] by a law or regulation.<br />

While Justice Brennan recognized the problem posed in Heffron, his comments provide little assistance in<br />

resolving it. Expression is an intrinsic part <strong>of</strong> so many religious rituals and activities that an exception from free<br />

exercise protection for speech related activities could swallow much <strong>of</strong> the whole. [FN49] Without further explanation,<br />

however, all we know from Heffron is that free speech doctrine will displace the special free exercise<br />

protection religious activities receive in at least some circumstances when religious practice involves speech.<br />

However, the precise scope and parameters <strong>of</strong> this constitutional hierarchy is largely unexplained.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court's opinion in Widmar is equally perplexing. <strong>The</strong> Court holds, correctly, that providing religious<br />

students the same access to university facilities for religious activities that non-religious students receive for<br />

secular activities does not violate the Establishment Clause. *133 Thus, the university's primary justification for<br />

excluding the religious club, the need to comply with Establishment Clause requirements, was grounded on constitutional<br />

error.<br />

<strong>The</strong> more difficult question is whether the restrictions on the excluded religious group should be held to violate<br />

the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause or the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. Discriminatory restrictions on acts <strong>of</strong> worship that interfere<br />

with legitimate state interests no more than do secular activities which are freely permitted by the university<br />

seem to be completely unjustified and unconstitutional violations <strong>of</strong> free exercise rights. Yet the Court<br />

never explains why it elects to resolve this case “on the bases <strong>of</strong> speech and association rights,” while expressing<br />

no opinion as to “the extent, if any, to which free exercise interests are infringed by the challenged University<br />

regulation.” [FN50]<br />

Justice White's dissenting opinion calls the majority to task for subsuming Religion Clause concerns under<br />

the umbrella <strong>of</strong> free speech principles prohibiting content discrimination. <strong>The</strong> explicit focus <strong>of</strong> the university's<br />

regulation was a prohibition on the use <strong>of</strong> university facilities for religious worship. Plaintiffs made it clear that<br />

they believed that a public university that allowed student groups to use facilities for general meetings and activities<br />

was required by the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause to also allow those same facilities to be used for “regular church<br />

services.” [FN51] To White, prohibitions on worship were clearly the domain <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause. If the<br />

regulation <strong>of</strong> worship and church services was to be characterized as the regulation <strong>of</strong> speech, “the Religion<br />

Clauses would be emptied <strong>of</strong> any independent meaning in circumstances in which religious practices took the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> speech.” [FN52] That result would require a fundamental reconsideration <strong>of</strong> Religion Clause doctrine.<br />

Unfortunately, Justice White's Widmar critique mistakenly emphasized the Establishment Clause questions<br />

that would arise if speech intensive religious activity were to be evaluated under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause rather<br />

than the Religion Clauses. [FN53] In fact, <strong>of</strong> course, the *134 more pr<strong>of</strong>ound consequences <strong>of</strong> which Justice<br />

White wrote would be more likely to occur in free exercise cases where religious practices under Sherbert and<br />

Yoder receive greater protection than related secular activities. Here, the characterization <strong>of</strong> the activity as religion,<br />

rather than speech, and the invocation <strong>of</strong> free exercise, as opposed to free speech requirements, is crucial.<br />

Only free exercise jurisprudence justifies more protective treatment for religious activities than for secular conduct.<br />

<strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine prohibits discrimination between secular and religious subjects and viewpoints.<br />

Notwithstanding White's erroneous focus on Establishment Clause issues, the majority's response to his con-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 9<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

cerns was pitifully inadequate. Justice Powell catalogued the problems with White's approach. What principled<br />

line can be drawn between worship and conventional forms <strong>of</strong> expression such as singing, teaching and reading?<br />

How could courts administer such a dubious distinction? Wouldn't judicial inquiries inevitably require judicial<br />

entanglement in religious matters? [FN54] <strong>The</strong>se are all fair questions, but they are ultimately unresponsive<br />

to White's challenge. White did not suggest that distinguishing between religion and speech would be easy.<br />

In fact, he explicitly recognized the difficulty <strong>of</strong> such an undertaking. [FN55] What White questioned was<br />

whether such an undertaking was avoidable - particularly if the Religion Clauses were to retain independent constitutional<br />

meaning and significance. To that inquiry, Powell <strong>of</strong>fered no answer at all.<br />

*135 Justice White raised one other issue in his dissent that is relevant to the purposes <strong>of</strong> this article. White<br />

argued that the legislature should have a freer hand in formulating “policies that affect religion in divergent<br />

ways” than the Court's case law suggested. [FN56] Thus, states may accommodate religion to promote religious<br />

liberty in ways that are not required by the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause, and states may burden religion in the service <strong>of</strong><br />

Establishment Clause goals in ways that are not constitutionally mandated. Here, White argued, the university's<br />

attempt to further the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state by precluding organized religious worship in public facilities<br />

was a permissible limit on religious activities on public property, although it was not required by the First<br />

Amendment. [FN57]<br />

<strong>The</strong> majority flatly rejected this contention out <strong>of</strong> hand. <strong>The</strong> protection provided by the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause<br />

against content discrimination required the most exacting scrutiny. <strong>The</strong> state university's interest “in achieving<br />

greater separation <strong>of</strong> church and state than is already ensured under the Establishment Clause <strong>of</strong> the Federal<br />

Constitution” was not sufficiently compelling to justify its content-discriminatory regulations. [FN58]<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court's analysis in Texas Monthly, decided in 1989, may be the most bizarre <strong>of</strong> the three 1980's decisions,<br />

particularly in light <strong>of</strong> the prior two opinions. In Heffron, the Court had concluded on free speech<br />

grounds that “ritualizing” conventional expressive activities, such as the distribution <strong>of</strong> religious periodicals and<br />

the solicitation <strong>of</strong> donations, did not entitle a religious group to greater rights than those provided to secular<br />

speakers expressing secular messages. In Widmar, the Court had elected to use free speech doctrine, rather than<br />

free exercise principles, to invalidate state restrictions on the use <strong>of</strong> public buildings for worship services. Surely<br />

then, a law exempting from a generally applicable sales and use tax periodicals published or distributed by a religious<br />

faith that consisted entirely <strong>of</strong> writings promulgating the teaching <strong>of</strong> the faith should also be struck down<br />

as prohibited content discrimination under the <strong>Speech</strong> or Press Clause.<br />

<strong>The</strong> promulgation <strong>of</strong> ideas and beliefs in a book or written periodical certainly cuts close to the core <strong>of</strong> the<br />

“speech” and “press” rights the *136 First Amendment protects. [FN59] Moreover, the distribution <strong>of</strong> books or<br />

periodicals containing religious teachings, without more, seemed less clearly, or at least less intrinsically, to involve<br />

the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion than the compulsory rituals at issue in Heffron or the excluded worship services<br />

in Widmar. <strong>The</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong> religious periodicals may serve a variety <strong>of</strong> goals, including fund raising,<br />

and the decision to engage in such activities may not respond to a compulsory obligation. It is difficult to conceptualize<br />

ritual and worship as anything other than the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion.<br />

Most important, there are few clearly analogous secular counterparts to religious ritual and worship, notwithstanding<br />

the speech dimensions <strong>of</strong> both activities. <strong>The</strong> publication <strong>of</strong> ideas in books and periodicals, however, is<br />

a generic activity engaged in by secular and religious groups alike for the same essential free speech purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

persuading readers <strong>of</strong> the merits <strong>of</strong> the beliefs being communicated. Thus, exempting religious publishers and<br />

publications from tax or regulatory requirements that their secular competitors must pay or obey is a more direct<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 10<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

form <strong>of</strong> favoritism and creates a more pronounced distortion <strong>of</strong> the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas than do accommodations<br />

<strong>of</strong> ritual and worship.<br />

Yet only one justice in Texas Monthly argued that the content-discriminatory tax statute should be struck<br />

down as a violation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Speech</strong> or Press Clause. [FN60] Five justices held that the preference for religious<br />

publications violated the Establishment Clause. Three <strong>of</strong> those justices, Brennan, Marshall, and Stevens, joined a<br />

plurality opinion that mentioned the Press Clause only in passing, noting that it was unnecessary for the Court to<br />

reach that issue. [FN61] Two concurring justices, Blackmun and O'Connor, expressed concern over the difficulty<br />

in harmonizing all the overlapping constitutional provisions that might legitimately be applied to the case.<br />

[FN62] Yet for these justices, the Establishment Clause problem clearly presented the real issue. <strong>The</strong> Press<br />

Clause challenge was much easier to resolve. Thus, they surmised *137 that a broader exemption including both<br />

secular philosophical materials and religious periodicals and respecting both <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and Establishment<br />

Clause values would survive constitutional review. [FN63] Neither justice seemed concerned that such a statute<br />

would be content discriminatory on its face, nor did they explain why they thought such a law could be justified<br />

under strict scrutiny review.<br />

With the benefit <strong>of</strong> hindsight, Justice Scalia's dissent, joined by Justices Rehnquist and Kennedy, was in<br />

many ways the most difficult opinion <strong>of</strong> all to understand, not only because <strong>of</strong> past decisions, but in light <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opinions these justices would write or join in the not too distant future. To the dissenters, content discriminatory<br />

accommodations for religious expression easily trumped both Establishment Clause and <strong>Speech</strong> and Press<br />

Clause mandates. [FN64] <strong>The</strong> tension between such a position and the analysis and holding in Widmar, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, is palpable. Pursuant to this approach, the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause is a one-way ratchet when religious expression<br />

is at issue. Discrimination against religious speech is prohibited, but discrimination in favor <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

speech is permissible. <strong>The</strong> inconsistency <strong>of</strong> such a one-sided argument with the free speech goal <strong>of</strong> preventing<br />

government distortion <strong>of</strong> the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas becomes even more apparent when one considers later decisions,<br />

joined by all three Texas Monthly dissenters, that characterize religion as a viewpoint rather than a subject<br />

<strong>of</strong> expression. [FN65]<br />

<strong>The</strong> dissent's justification for such an awkward reading <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment is grounded in part on the<br />

need to leave some room for legislative discretion relating to religion between “the Scylla <strong>of</strong> what the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause demands and the Charybdis <strong>of</strong> what the Establishment Clause forbids.” [FN66] It is a fair argument<br />

if only the Religion Clauses are in play. But Justice White raised essentially the same concern in Widmar when<br />

he argued that the state should be granted some flexibility in promoting Establishment Clause values beyond<br />

what the Constitution required. <strong>The</strong> Court responded, emphatically, that legislative amplification <strong>of</strong> Establishment<br />

Clause values beyond what the Constitution required could not justify content discriminatory regulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> speech. It is difficult to understand why a *138 similar analysis does not apply to religious accommodations<br />

that are not mandated by free exercise requirements. [FN67]<br />

B. <strong>The</strong> 1990's - <strong>The</strong> Fall <strong>of</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and the Rise <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Speech</strong> Paradigm<br />

In 1990, in Employment Division v. Smith, [FN68] the Supreme Court ruled that the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion received<br />

no constitutional protection against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability. No matter how seriously such<br />

laws burdened the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion they would be upheld under rational basis review. [FN69] <strong>Religious</strong> individuals<br />

and institutions were directed to seek relief from laws that interfered with their religious practices from<br />

the political branches <strong>of</strong> government. [FN70] If sought after exemptions were denied, religious parties could<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 11<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

choose between violating the tenets <strong>of</strong> their faith or violating the law and receiving whatever sanction society<br />

imposed on such transgressions.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re were only two exceptions to this formal limit on free exercise protection. Apparently, the majority in<br />

Smith could not obtain sufficient support to overrule Sherbert and Yoder, so it crafted two artificial limits on its<br />

rule <strong>of</strong> formal neutrality. Sherbert was reinterpreted to continue to require strict scrutiny protection whenever<br />

state decisions involved “a mechanism for individualized exemptions” similar to the hardship exemptions that<br />

were granted by the state unemployment compensation commission in Sherbert. [FN71] <strong>The</strong> Court found,<br />

“where the state has in place a system <strong>of</strong> individualized exemptions, it may not refuse to extend that system to<br />

cases <strong>of</strong> ‘religious hardship’ without compelling reason.” [FN72] Yoder was now to be *139 understood as a<br />

“hybrid” rights case. When a neutral law <strong>of</strong> general applicability burdening religiously motivated conduct invokes<br />

“not the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause alone, but the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause in conjunction with other constitutional<br />

protections, such as freedom <strong>of</strong> speech and <strong>of</strong> the press . . . or the right <strong>of</strong> parents . . . to direct the education <strong>of</strong><br />

their children,” strict scrutiny would be applied to such a “hybrid situation.” [FN73]<br />

Three years after Smith, the Court modestly expanded free exercise protection in Church <strong>of</strong> Lukumi Babalu<br />

Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah. [FN74] At issue in the case were ordinances that prohibited the killing or sacrificing animals<br />

as part <strong>of</strong> any type <strong>of</strong> ritual, although they were both facially neutral and generally applicable, there was no<br />

doubt that they had been enacted for the express purpose <strong>of</strong> suppressing the Santeria faith, a minority religion in<br />

the community that slaughtered animals as part <strong>of</strong> its religious ceremonies. [FN75] Moreover, when the challenged<br />

laws were examined in the context <strong>of</strong> other regulations relating to the killing and welfare <strong>of</strong> animals, it<br />

was abundantly clear that Hialeah's ordinances constituted a “religious gerrymander” that only prohibited conduct<br />

when it was engaged in for religious purposes. [FN76] Recognizing that a law could discriminate against<br />

religion in practice as well as on its face, the Court applied strict scrutiny and struck down the <strong>of</strong>fending ordinances.<br />

Some language in Lukumi can be read liberally to provide serious protection to religious practices that are<br />

burdened by under-inclusive laws, even when the laws do not discriminate against or target religion. [FN77] On<br />

balance, however, given the clear intent <strong>of</strong> the Court not to depart from the core limits on free exercise doctrine<br />

imposed by Smith, the holding <strong>of</strong> the case seems far more limited. As Fred Gedicks has summarized the situation,<br />

after Smith and Lukumi, “a religiously neutral law does not fail the test <strong>of</strong> general applicability merely by<br />

being modestly or even substantially underinclusive; rather, the law must be so dramatically underinclusive that<br />

religious conduct is virtually the only conduct to which the law applies.” [FN78] Under-inclusive laws that predominately<br />

apply to religious practices but restrict enough secular *140 conduct to avoid condemnation for targeting<br />

or discriminating against religion will continue to be upheld under rational basis review.<br />

During the same decade, following the precedent set by Widmar, the Court aggressively utilized the <strong>Free</strong><br />

<strong>Speech</strong> Clause, rather than the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause, to protect religious activities from discrimination and exclusion.<br />

Indeed, the first case in this line <strong>of</strong> authority, Lamb's Chapel v. Center Moriches Union <strong>Free</strong> School<br />

District, [FN79] seemed to be a straight forward replay <strong>of</strong> Widmar on more appropriate facts. A school district<br />

permitted outside groups to use its facilities after hours for social, civic, recreational, and political uses, but forbade<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> school buildings for religious purposes. A local church brought suit after it was denied permission<br />

to show a film series on school property that discussed family and child rearing issues from a religious perspective.<br />

In response, the Court held that the exclusion <strong>of</strong> the religious film series violated the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Clause. [FN80] It is hard to dispute the Court's conclusion that the ban on the use <strong>of</strong> buildings for religious purposes<br />

was unconstitutional. While little in the way <strong>of</strong> explanation was <strong>of</strong>fered as to why the case should be re-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 12<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

solved on free speech rather than on free exercise grounds, it is easy to infer that the precedent <strong>of</strong> Widmar was<br />

too on point to ignore and adequately resolved the case. Moreover, here, unlike in Widmar, the religious activities<br />

in question, the showing <strong>of</strong> a film with a religious perspective, seems much more like a conventional form <strong>of</strong><br />

speech than the exercise or practice <strong>of</strong> religion.<br />

What was surprising, however, was the Court's decision to condemn the school district's regulation as<br />

“viewpoint” discrimination, rather than content discrimination. [FN81] This conclusion allowed the Court to<br />

avoid the troublesome issue <strong>of</strong> categorizing the school district's property as either a designated public forum or a<br />

non-public forum. Viewpoint-discriminatory regulations receive strict scrutiny in either forum. Content discriminatory<br />

regulations, on the other hand, receive rigorous review in a designated public forum, but they are upheld<br />

under a deferential reasonableness standard in a non-public forum.<br />

<strong>The</strong> recognized utility <strong>of</strong> a finding <strong>of</strong> viewpoint discrimination in resolving a case, however, does little to<br />

justify the substantive accuracy <strong>of</strong> the Court's conclusion. Religion, obviously, can be either a subject *141 or a<br />

viewpoint. Given the increasing difficulty <strong>of</strong> differentiating between content- (or subject matter) discriminatory<br />

laws and viewpoint-discriminatory laws, [FN82] some explanation <strong>of</strong> why religion should be construed to be a<br />

viewpoint in this case would have been more than useful.<br />

Two years later, in Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors <strong>of</strong> the University <strong>of</strong> Virginia, [FN83] the Court held<br />

that a public university's refusal to subsidize a religious periodical published by a recognized student organization<br />

with funds collected from student fees violated the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. Since the university provided subsidies<br />

to a wide variety <strong>of</strong> student groups and periodicals, the Court concluded that this denial <strong>of</strong> access (to resources<br />

as opposed to facilities) for religious activities constituted prohibited viewpoint discrimination. [FN84]<br />

Rosenberger raises several important issues that are beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this article. For present purposes,<br />

however, it is relatively easy to understand why the <strong>Speech</strong> Clause, rather than the Religion Clauses, was<br />

deemed a more appropriate vehicle for adjudicating the case. First, as was true in Lamb's Chapel, the activity in<br />

question, the publication <strong>of</strong> a periodical discussing a range <strong>of</strong> topical subjects, is a conventional form <strong>of</strong> speech<br />

and might not be easily characterized as the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion. Second, the University <strong>of</strong> Virginia denied support<br />

not only for religious activities, but also for philanthropic activities, political activities, social entertainment,<br />

and “activities that would jeopardize the University's tax-exempt status.” [FN85] While the Court did not<br />

consider this range <strong>of</strong> unfounded activities to be relevant to its determination that the refusal to fund religious<br />

activities was viewpoint discriminatory, certainly the number <strong>of</strong> excluded activities might undermine the contention<br />

that religion was in some sense targeted for unfavorable treatment. [FN86]<br />

*142 <strong>The</strong> final case, Good News Club v. Milford Central School, [FN87] is the most problematic. Here,<br />

once again, a New York school district permitted outside groups to use school facilities for social, civic, and recreational<br />

meetings, but denied similar access to a religious organization, the Good News Club. Once again, the<br />

Court held that the District's exclusionary decision constituted viewpoint discrimination and violated accepted<br />

free speech doctrine. [FN88] <strong>The</strong> difference between Good News Club and the more recent prior cases,<br />

however, was the nature <strong>of</strong> the Club's activities and the reason that it was denied access to public property. As<br />

Justice Souter persuasively demonstrates in his dissenting opinion, the Club's activities included many <strong>of</strong> the traditional<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> religious worship. Club sessions typically included organized prayer, singing religious<br />

songs, lessons from the Bible, and repeated calls for unsaved audience members to accept Christ as their Savior<br />

and to publicly acknowledge their willingness to do so. [FN89]<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 13<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

<strong>The</strong> majority never disputes the accuracy <strong>of</strong> Souter's description <strong>of</strong> Club activities. Instead, it contends that<br />

Club activities are more than “mere worship” because they are not “divorced from any teaching <strong>of</strong> moral values.”<br />

[FN90] To the majority, “the substance <strong>of</strong> the Club's activities . . . are materially indistinguishable from<br />

the activities in Lamb's Chapel and Rosenberger.” [FN91] Accordingly, the denial <strong>of</strong> access to such activities<br />

constitutes prohibited viewpoint discrimination and must be reviewed under strict scrutiny.<br />

<strong>The</strong> majority's analysis is more than problematic. Obviously, worship services in many, if not most, religions<br />

are not divorced from the teaching <strong>of</strong> moral values. That reality hardly suggests that they are not appropriately<br />

characterized as worship services. [FN92] <strong>The</strong> majority seems to *143 be saying that as long as religious<br />

services contain moral teachings, they are appropriately understood as speech expressing a viewpoint for<br />

constitutional purposes. A church service is no different than a film series discussing family values or a publication<br />

<strong>of</strong> a periodical discussing a broad range <strong>of</strong> issues from a religious perspective. Not surprisingly, Souter concludes<br />

that if the majority's position is taken seriously, “any public school opened for civic meetings must be<br />

opened for use as a church, synagogue, or mosque.” [FN93]<br />

But if church services are speech for constitutional purposes, the scope <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause is seriously<br />

diminished. <strong>The</strong> exclusion <strong>of</strong> religious services from public property targets religion directly. Even under<br />

Smith, there should be little difficulty in subjecting Milford's exclusionary policy to strict scrutiny review. Yet<br />

again, the Court chooses to subsume core religious practices under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and ignores the applicability<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Religion Clauses.<br />

Thus, when we scrutinize the case law during this decade, most <strong>of</strong> the protection provided religious activity<br />

occurred under the auspices <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause, not the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause. What accounts for this<br />

emphasis on one constitutional framework over another? Given the public evisceration <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause in Smith, one might be tempted to explain the Court's results by arguing that free speech displaced free<br />

exercise as the constitutional shield for religious activity *144 because the post-Smith <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause<br />

provided too porous a covering to be <strong>of</strong> any use. But that is clearly not the case. In Lamb's Chapel and Good<br />

News Club, the state overtly discriminated against religious expressive activities. Even after Smith, free exercise<br />

protection was arguably available in each case. [FN94]<br />

One suspects that the preference for a free speech model can be explained not so much by its suitability for<br />

resolving free exercise issues, but rather by the utility <strong>of</strong> this approach for undermining Establishment Clause<br />

constraints on state promotion and support for religion. <strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine undercuts Establishment Clause<br />

holdings in two key respects. First, speech doctrine is grounded on a non-discrimination principle that precludes,<br />

or at least requires a compelling justification for, treating one message differently from another because<br />

<strong>of</strong> its communicative impact. If religion is characterized as a viewpoint <strong>of</strong> speech, and the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause<br />

informs or controls Establishment Clause analysis, government must provide private religious institutions and<br />

groups access to the same support it provides to secular organizations. [FN95] Characterizing religion as religion<br />

and subsuming the review <strong>of</strong> its regulation under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause provides no comparable basis<br />

for avoiding Establishment Clause constraints on the state's subsidizing <strong>of</strong> religion. Indeed, if anything, the vigorous<br />

enforcement <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause as an independent basis for protecting religious practices from<br />

state interference helps to justify rigorous Establishment Clause limits on the state promotion <strong>of</strong> religion. Affirming<br />

distinct protection for religion under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause legitimates equally distinct limitations on<br />

religion under the Establishment Clause. [FN96]<br />

*145 <strong>The</strong> decision in Rosenberger to apply free speech, non-discrimination requirements to access to finan-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 14<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

cial subsidies in the same way that these requirements were traditionally applied to access to public property<br />

clearly magnified the extent to which free speech cases involving religion clashed with Establishment Clause restrictions<br />

on state aid to religious institutions. Notwithstanding explicit limits on the scope <strong>of</strong> the Court's holding<br />

in the majority opinion, [FN97] and Justice O'Connor's emphasis on the narrowness <strong>of</strong> the decision in her concurrence,<br />

[FN98] Rosenberger has been cited by Justices, commentators, and litigants for the proposition that<br />

government must (or at least is permitted to) treat religious and non-religious institutions as equally eligible for<br />

state support. [FN99]<br />

Second, free speech doctrine is conventionally understood as accepting a more limited understanding <strong>of</strong> state<br />

action than Establishment Clause cases recognize. When government opens public property for private expressive<br />

uses, it is generally recognized that the speech activities permitted in such fora are private acts entirely independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> the state for constitutional purposes. More precisely, the messages communicated are not attributed<br />

to the state, even if there is a substantial consensus <strong>of</strong> private viewpoints in an area. State action has been applied<br />

more broadly in Equal Protection and Establishment Clause cases, however. Here the state has been held<br />

responsible for private conduct on public property that communicates a message <strong>of</strong> racial disparagement or religious<br />

favoritism or endorsement. [FN100] Thus, if religious activity is characterized as speech rather than religion,<br />

there will be an increased tendency to view such activities as exclusively private in nature and beyond the<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> constitutional mandates. [FN101]<br />

*146 II. <strong>The</strong> Risks and Benefits <strong>of</strong> Conceptualizing <strong>Religious</strong> Practice as <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Persuasive criticisms may be directed at the use <strong>of</strong> free speech doctrine to undermine Establishment Clause<br />

constraints on state subsidies for religious institutions and activities. [FN102] <strong>The</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> this paper, however,<br />

is on the other side <strong>of</strong> the Religion Clause equation. What are the doctrinal consequences for free exercise purposes<br />

<strong>of</strong> an increased identification <strong>of</strong> religion with speech and the substitution <strong>of</strong> vigorously enforced free<br />

speech doctrine for an independent free exercise jurisprudence? As the proceeding analysis suggests, there are<br />

important virtues and drawbacks to such a constitutional framework that ought to be carefully evaluated before<br />

the Court proceeds any further in this direction.<br />

As noted, however, these virtues and drawbacks must be understood in relative terms. Much <strong>of</strong> the value in<br />

characterizing religion as speech is predicated on a comparison with post-Smith free exercise jurisprudence. If,<br />

as Part II <strong>of</strong> this article attempts to demonstrate, the deficiencies in Smith cannot be effectively remedied, and<br />

the decision must be overruled, a very different comparative analysis would apply. <strong>The</strong> justifications for protecting<br />

religion as speech whenever there is a sufficient speech dimension diminish substantially if the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause is vigorously enforced against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability. [FN103]<br />

*147 A. Virtues and Advantages<br />

1. Content and Viewpoint Discriminatory Regulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Speech</strong><br />

At first glance, speech cases such as Widmar, Lamb's Chapel, and Good News Club appear to <strong>of</strong>fer little<br />

solace from the draconian limits on free exercise protection imposed by Smith. <strong>The</strong>y all are predicated on discrimination<br />

against religion, and even Smith requires the rigorous review <strong>of</strong> laws singling out and disproportionately<br />

burdening religious activities. Thus, both free speech and free exercise doctrine ought to require strict<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 15<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

scrutiny review <strong>of</strong> laws that treat religious expression differently and less favorably than other subjects or viewpoints<br />

<strong>of</strong> speech. This is surely a reasonable expectation, but in at least one notorious area, that <strong>of</strong> land use regulation,<br />

it is clearly not an accurate description <strong>of</strong> current law.<br />

Land use ordinances explicitly regulating and restricting houses <strong>of</strong> worship, for example, rarely receive rigorous<br />

judicial scrutiny under free exercise review. [FN104] In part, this judicial reluctance is grounded on the<br />

courts' perception that construction <strong>of</strong> a house <strong>of</strong> worship is neither a mandatory obligation nor a central tenet <strong>of</strong><br />

the congregation's faith. [FN105] In theory, free speech doctrine provides more serious *148 protection from<br />

land use regulations to houses <strong>of</strong> worship that courts cannot easily ignore. Unlike the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion,<br />

speech is protected without regard to the speakers' motives or commitment to the message being expressed.<br />

Ideas that are discretionary expression and tangential to an individual's core beliefs are still fully protected<br />

speech.<br />

Indeed, given the close association between a house <strong>of</strong> worship and religious expression, explicit restrictions<br />

on churches, synagogues, mosques, and temples arguably constitute content-discriminatory regulations <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

expression. [FN106] A house <strong>of</strong> worship, after all, is not the site <strong>of</strong> generic expression. It is the site <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

expression in all <strong>of</strong> its diverse manifestations. Ordinances setting out distinct standards for evaluating development<br />

proposals for houses <strong>of</strong> worship or specifying the locations where houses <strong>of</strong> worship are permitted in<br />

a community classify on the basis <strong>of</strong> the content <strong>of</strong> speech. If we take the Court's analysis in Widmar and Good<br />

News Club seriously, such ordinances are viewpoint-discriminatory. Either way, they should receive strict scrutiny<br />

review.<br />

In the land use area, at least, as Robert Tuttle has demonstrated in a recent article, [FN107] courts do not employ<br />

strict scrutiny. In some cases, they simply ignore the free speech implications <strong>of</strong> the zoning <strong>of</strong> religious institutions<br />

with almost no explanation. [FN108] In others, they dispense with claims <strong>of</strong> content discrimination by<br />

employing a “secondary effects” exception to the traditional doctrine requiring rigorous review <strong>of</strong> contentdiscriminatory<br />

laws. [FN109] Under this analysis, *149 content-discriminatory regulations adopted to prevent<br />

the consequences <strong>of</strong> religious assembly in a location (such as increased traffic and congestion) rather than to restrict<br />

access to a religious message, receive the intermediate standard <strong>of</strong> review that is applied to content-neutral<br />

regulations.<br />

For the purposes <strong>of</strong> this article, however, I am more concerned about what courts should do than what they<br />

actually do. If we are going to substitute free speech for free exercise doctrine, at least we can insist that free<br />

speech principles must be enforced with all the vigor courts can muster. Judicial decisions that simply ignore<br />

the free speech implications <strong>of</strong> land use regulations are largely indefensible. <strong>The</strong> secondary effects argument<br />

has more merit, and some commentators have accepted this rationalization for applying a more lenient standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> review to the zoning <strong>of</strong> churches. [FN110] On balance, however, there are persuasive reasons for rejecting the<br />

application <strong>of</strong> this analysis to land use restrictions imposed on religious institutions.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Supreme Court, outside <strong>of</strong> the “adult speech” context, has rarely employed the secondary effects doctrine.<br />

[FN111] <strong>The</strong>re are good reasons for this reticence. <strong>The</strong> line between primary and secondary effects is too<br />

amorphous and manipulable a boundary to police the distinction between content-discriminatory and contentneutral<br />

laws. Indeed, this weakness in the doctrine is illustrated by the attempt to apply a secondary effects analysis<br />

to the zoning <strong>of</strong> houses <strong>of</strong> worship. <strong>The</strong> land use externalities associated with churches--congestion, noise,<br />

and the displacement <strong>of</strong> other valuable activities--are not attenuated consequences <strong>of</strong> speech, like the increased<br />

level <strong>of</strong> crime and prostitution associated with areas where adult businesses are located. Instead, they are ex-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 16<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

tremely common consequences <strong>of</strong> expressive activity <strong>of</strong> all kinds. If government is concerned about the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> participants engaging in expressive activity and the ensuing noise and *150 congestion, it should regulate on<br />

the basis <strong>of</strong> these neutral criteria. Alternatively, government can attempt to justify a regulation distinguishing<br />

between poetry readings and political rallies, for example, on the basis <strong>of</strong> the externalities associated with both<br />

activities, but it must do so under strict scrutiny review. Allowing the state to avoid rigorous review when it<br />

formally distinguishes between political rallies, poetry readings, religious services, union meetings, and the like<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> predictions about routine, but “secondary” consequences <strong>of</strong> expressive activity is an entirely different<br />

matter, however. Strict scrutiny <strong>of</strong> content-discriminatory regulations would be far too easily circumvented<br />

by reference to purported secondary effects if courts need only accept limited evidence <strong>of</strong> disparate externalities<br />

resulting from different subjects <strong>of</strong> expression as the basis for applying a much more lenient standard <strong>of</strong> review.<br />

[FN112]<br />

Moreover, as we have seen in several free speech decisions, religion may be characterized as a viewpoint as<br />

well as a subject <strong>of</strong> speech. No case suggests that secondary effects doctrine may be used to reduce the standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> review applied to viewpoint-discriminatory regulations. City <strong>of</strong>ficials may have every reason to believe that<br />

the headquarters <strong>of</strong> the Democrats in a particular community may produce more noise and congestion than the<br />

headquarters <strong>of</strong> the Republicans, but no one would suggest that the city may explicitly impose more rigorous restrictions<br />

on one party's headquarters than on the others and avoid strict scrutiny review under the rubric <strong>of</strong> secondary<br />

effects. If we take the Court's repeated conclusion that religion is a viewpoint <strong>of</strong> expression seriously,<br />

zoning ordinances that regulate churches should receive strict scrutiny review.<br />

2. Protection Against Neutral Laws <strong>of</strong> General Applicability<br />

Of course, free speech doctrine extends beyond discriminatory regulations and covers content-neutral regulations<br />

as well, albeit under a less demanding standard <strong>of</strong> review. [FN113] Thus, content-neutral speech regulations<br />

restricting religious activities should receive some level <strong>of</strong> review. Moreover, some free speech rules and<br />

standards apply to laws that are not directed at, or limited to, expression alone and restrict both *151 speech and<br />

unexpressive conduct. To use the vernacular <strong>of</strong> Smith, the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause sometimes applies to neutral and<br />

generally applicable laws that regulate not only speech. If religious activities are characterized as speech and<br />

protected under these approaches, the range <strong>of</strong> laws burdening religious practices and institutions receiving<br />

some form <strong>of</strong> constitutional review would extend beyond the narrow parameters set out in Smith, at least to<br />

some extent. [FN114]<br />

a. Content Neutral Laws Restricting <strong>Speech</strong><br />

While the degree <strong>of</strong> rigor applied to content-neutral speech regulations is a modest form <strong>of</strong> intermediatelevel<br />

scrutiny, there is no doubt that this standard has considerably more bite to it than the virtually total deference<br />

<strong>of</strong> rational basis review to which all free exercise claims against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability are<br />

relegated after Smith. [FN115] Early free speech cases, such as Cantwell, demonstrate the effectiveness <strong>of</strong> free<br />

speech doctrine in protecting religious expression in this regard. [FN116] Moreover, there is an important process<br />

dimension to the review <strong>of</strong> content-neutral speech regulations. <strong>The</strong> state may have considerable flexibility<br />

in deciding what standards it will employ in regulating the time, place, and manner <strong>of</strong> speech, but these standards<br />

must include clear guidelines and criteria. Under free speech principles, it is unconstitutional to vest standardless<br />

discretion in <strong>of</strong>ficials who are delegated the power to determine when, where, and how speech may occur.<br />

<strong>The</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> bias inherent in such unguided decisionmaking and the difficulty <strong>of</strong> reviewing standardless decisions<br />

after the fact mandate this result. [FN117] This procedural requirement can *152 be <strong>of</strong> considerable util-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 17<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ity for the protection <strong>of</strong> religion in a land use context. [FN118]<br />

In addition, the advantage <strong>of</strong> using free speech doctrine rather than free exercise doctrine to challenge burdensome<br />

laws extends beyond the rigor <strong>of</strong> judicial review. It also applies to the scope <strong>of</strong> the right. An intrinsic<br />

limit <strong>of</strong> free exercise doctrine has been the rigid focus <strong>of</strong> courts on whether the subject <strong>of</strong> the regulation can be<br />

correctly identified as the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion for constitutional purposes. Regulating practices that are associated<br />

with religion, locations where religious exercise will occur, and supporting activities that facilitate the exercise<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion is not characterized as burdening protected activity. [FN119]<br />

<strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine is very different. Not just speech is protected. Laws with “a close enough nexus to expression,”<br />

that are directed at “conduct commonly associated with expression,” [FN120] or “conduct that is normally<br />

engaged in for the purpose <strong>of</strong> communicating an idea” [FN121] fall within the scope <strong>of</strong> review. Clearly<br />

the location where speech occurs and the means by which speech is communicated are covered. Thus, if a law is<br />

directed at the conventional means and locations <strong>of</strong> engaging in religious expressive activities, it should be reviewed<br />

under the standard routinely applied to content neutral regulations <strong>of</strong> speech. [FN122]<br />

*153 This reasonable expectation is not always reflected by the case law, however. Once again, cases involving<br />

land use regulations demonstrate a myopic reluctance on the part <strong>of</strong> courts to recognize the free speech<br />

implications <strong>of</strong> the zoning <strong>of</strong> religious land uses. [FN123] But land use is not the only area <strong>of</strong> regulation where<br />

free speech doctrine should provide greater protection against content-neutral speech regulations than the <strong>Free</strong><br />

Exercise Clause provides. Under free speech doctrine, regulations limiting the time, place, and manner <strong>of</strong> proselytizing,<br />

worship, religious education, wearing religious symbols or insignia, displaying religious symbols or<br />

insignia on real or personal property, soliciting for donations, publishing books and magazines, radio and television<br />

broadcasts, and advertising for religious services or products should receive a more rigorous form <strong>of</strong> scrutiny<br />

than the rational basis standard required by Smith. [FN124]<br />

*154 b. <strong>Speech</strong>-Neutral Laws Restricting <strong>Speech</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> previous section focused on content-neutral regulations <strong>of</strong> speech, but many laws that burden speech do<br />

not directly regulate conventional, expressive activities alone. <strong>The</strong>y govern a range <strong>of</strong> both expressive and nonexpressive<br />

activities. Further, sometimes conduct that we would not conventionally identify as expressive is engaged<br />

in to communicate a message. Smith, <strong>of</strong> course, provides no protection to religious practice in any <strong>of</strong><br />

these contexts. Thus, to the extent that free speech doctrine applies in these circumstances, the protection it<br />

provides to religious activities that may be characterized as speech extends substantially beyond the coverage <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause after Smith.<br />

3. Applying Neutral and Generally Applicable Laws to Conventional Expressive Activity<br />

a. Facial Challenges to Laws Extending Beyond Conventional Expressive Activity<br />

Unlike current free exercise jurisprudence, free speech doctrine is not limited in its application to laws that<br />

directly and exclusively regulate speech. A general law that encompasses both expressive and non-expressive<br />

activity may in some circumstances be challenged on its face as violating the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause <strong>of</strong> the First<br />

Amendment.<br />

Consider the anti-noise ordinance at issue in Grayned v. City <strong>of</strong> Rockford, [FN125] which prohibited “the<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 18<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

making <strong>of</strong> any noise or diversion which disturbs or tends to disturb the peace or good order” on land adjacent to<br />

a school. [FN126] Obviously, this law would seem to apply to noises without regard to whether they are made<br />

for expressive purposes. Firecrackers, leaf blowers, and jackhammers may violate the ordinance to the same extent<br />

as political rallies or loudspeakers promoting the sale <strong>of</strong> commercial products. Yet, the general applicability<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law did not preclude the Court from evaluating it on free speech grounds because <strong>of</strong> its potential effect on<br />

expressive activities. <strong>The</strong> law could only be upheld as constitutional if it was narrowly tailored to further a sufficiently<br />

important state interest. [FN127]<br />

*155 Although the anti-noise ordinance was upheld in Grayned, there is no doubt that it received serious and<br />

careful review. A very different analysis would apply under post-Smith free exercise doctrine. If a loud religious<br />

practice were prohibited by a similar ordinance, the noise ordinance would be characterized as a neutral law <strong>of</strong><br />

general applicability and sustained under rational basis review. [FN128]<br />

Other cases more clearly demonstrate that overbreadth doctrine constitutes a separate, unique, and important<br />

distinction between free speech and free exercise doctrine with regard to the application <strong>of</strong> these constitutional<br />

clauses to generally applicable laws. In Coates v. Cincinnati, [FN129] for example, the Court struck down as<br />

vague and overbroad a local ordinance prohibiting “three or more persons to assemble . . . on any <strong>of</strong> the sidewalks<br />

. . . and there conduct themselves in a manner annoying to persons passing by.” [FN130] It takes little effort<br />

to imagine a range <strong>of</strong> non-expressive activities covered by the language <strong>of</strong> this ordinance that do not receive<br />

free speech protection in any manner or form. Indeed, the record before the Court did not even describe the conduct<br />

<strong>of</strong> the defendants who sought judicial review <strong>of</strong> their convictions under the ordinance. [FN131] Yet, the<br />

general applicability <strong>of</strong> the ordinance to non-expressive and unprotected activity was not enough to allow it to<br />

withstand an overbreadth challenge. Because the ordinance might be unjustifiably applied to expressive activity<br />

in a significant number <strong>of</strong> instances, the law was invalidated on its face.<br />

<strong>The</strong> juxtaposition <strong>of</strong> the overbreadth doctrine under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and the current free exercise<br />

doctrine is jarring in its dissonance. <strong>The</strong> Court made it clear in Lukumi that a law that does not discriminate<br />

against religion on its face may still receive strict scrutiny *156 review, but only if the regulation constitutes a<br />

religious gerrymander which has the effect <strong>of</strong> singling out a religious practice for unfavorable treatment. Thus,<br />

when the city ordinance prohibiting the ritual slaughter <strong>of</strong> animals in Hialeah was considered along with other<br />

laws and exemptions relating to the killing <strong>of</strong> animals, it became clear that only the killing <strong>of</strong> animals for religious<br />

reasons - indeed, only the ceremonies <strong>of</strong> a particular disfavored faith, the Santaria religion - was subject to<br />

sanction. [FN132]<br />

It is not at all evident that the Court's holding in Lukumi extends beyond this limited foundation. Thus, for<br />

example, assume that a secular fraternity in Hialeah engaged in the ritual killing <strong>of</strong> animals during its pledge<br />

week activities, and that the challenged ordinance was equally directed at, and burdensome to, that fraternity as<br />

well as Santaria religious rituals. On these facts, it is doubtful that the ordinance would violate the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise<br />

Clause under strict scrutiny review. This hypothetical law applies both to secular and religious activities<br />

and could not be characterized as discriminatory on its face or in effect.<br />

<strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine and overbreadth analysis are far more advantageous to the constitutional<br />

claimant. Confronted with a law that arguably prohibits both unprotected conduct and protected expressive<br />

activities, a plaintiff need not demonstrate discrimination against speech or expressive gerrymandering. It is<br />

enough that the law's potential applications may restrict a significant amount <strong>of</strong> protected expression for the<br />

court to conclude that it is substantially overbroad in its scope. By definition, overbroad laws are laws <strong>of</strong> gener-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 19<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

al applicability that apply to more than protected speech. Yet, far from precluding judicial review <strong>of</strong> such statutes,<br />

overbreadth doctrine exists to insure that the fact that a law is not exclusively directed at speech and may<br />

legitimately be applied to some non-expressive conduct neither immunizes it from constitutional review, nor<br />

delays challenges to its validity. <strong>The</strong> distinction between free exercise and free speech doctrine here could not<br />

be more stark. [FN133]<br />

*157 b. As Applied Challenges to Laws Extending Beyond Conventional Expressive Activity<br />

<strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause doctrine permits not only facial challenges to neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability that<br />

are not directed exclusively at expression. It also allows “as applied” challenges to broad laws that are used to<br />

penalize or prohibit protected speech. A breach <strong>of</strong> the peace statute, such as the one applied to civil rights<br />

demonstrators in Cox v. Louisiana, [FN134] is a classic example. <strong>The</strong> Louisiana statute provided that<br />

[w]hoever with intent to provoke a breach <strong>of</strong> the peace, or under circumstances such that a breach <strong>of</strong><br />

the peace may be occasioned thereby . . . crowds or congregates with others . . . in or upon a public street<br />

or public highway . . . and who fails or refuses to disperse or move on . . . shall be guilty <strong>of</strong> disturbing the<br />

peace. [FN135]<br />

Clearly, crowds engaged in non-expressive behavior fall within the parameters <strong>of</strong> this statute, and individuals<br />

may be arrested and prosecuted for failing to obey its requirements. <strong>The</strong> law is not directed solely at speech<br />

or at conduct engaged in for expressive purposes, but the expansive scope <strong>of</strong> the law does not prevent individuals<br />

engaging in protected, expressive activities from invoking the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause to challenge their conviction<br />

under this statute. In Cox, the Court held that “Louisiana may not constitutionally punish appellant under<br />

this statute for engaging in the type <strong>of</strong> conduct which this record reveals.” [FN136] While some <strong>of</strong> the speech<br />

expressed at the demonstration was inflammatory, these comments “did not deprive the demonstration <strong>of</strong> its protected<br />

character under the Constitution as free speech and assembly.” [FN137]<br />

Under existing law, a free exercise claim challenging the application <strong>of</strong> a disturbing the peace statute to religiously<br />

motivated activities would be treated far less generously. <strong>The</strong> neutral and generally applicable nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the law would preclude any invocation <strong>of</strong> free exercise rights *158 as a shield against the state's conduct. Only if<br />

the statute at issue were directed against religious disturbances <strong>of</strong> the peace would free exercise protection apply.<br />

[FN138]<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court's recent decision in Boy Scouts <strong>of</strong> America v. Dale [FN139] provides an additional example <strong>of</strong> an<br />

as-applied challenge to a law alleged to infringe on an organization's rights <strong>of</strong> expressive association. <strong>The</strong> New<br />

Jersey civil rights statute at issue provided that “[a]ll persons shall have the opportunity to obtain employment,<br />

and to obtain all the accommodations, advantages, facilities, and privileges <strong>of</strong> any place <strong>of</strong> public accommodation<br />

. . . without discrimination because <strong>of</strong> race, creed, color, national origin, ancestry, age, marital status, affectional<br />

or sexual orientation, family status or sex.” [FN140] <strong>The</strong> statute defined a “place <strong>of</strong> public accommodation”<br />

to include taverns, hotels, motels, trailer camps, manufacturers, wholesalers, stores, restaurants, bowling<br />

alleys, hospitals, and a host <strong>of</strong> other entities and facilities. Obviously, the statute was a neutral law <strong>of</strong> general<br />

applicability vis-à-vis speech and could not reasonably be construed to be targeting expression. Notwithstanding<br />

the generality <strong>of</strong> the statute, the Court confidently inquired into “whether applying New Jersey's public accommodations<br />

law in this way [forcing the Boy Scouts to accept a gay man as scoutmaster] violates the Boy Scouts'<br />

First Amendment right <strong>of</strong> expressive association.” [FN141] In concluding that this application <strong>of</strong> the state's law<br />

did violate the Scouts' freedom <strong>of</strong> expressive association, the Court never even considered whether the general-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 20<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ity <strong>of</strong> the law limited free speech review <strong>of</strong> its application. [FN142]<br />

Again, it is hard to imagine courts employing a comparable analysis if a free exercise claim were raised to<br />

protect a religious organization or institution from the reach <strong>of</strong> public accommodations statutes. Since such laws<br />

are neither aimed at religious organizations nor limited to *159 religiously motivated discrimination, the rule <strong>of</strong><br />

Smith would control to deny constitutional review. [FN143] Applying neutral and general laws in a way that interferes<br />

with religious groups and institutions has no free exercise significance today unless the administration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the law deliberately discriminates against religious organizations or religiously motivated decisions. [FN144]<br />

4. Applying Neutral and Generally Applicable Laws to Conventionally Non-Expressive Activity<br />

Certain activities, such as prayer and forms <strong>of</strong> worship, may be conventionally recognized as the practice <strong>of</strong><br />

religion in the same sense that activities such as writing and leafleting may be conventionally recognized as<br />

means <strong>of</strong> expression. Other activities, including eating (or not eating), drinking, acts <strong>of</strong> charity, child rearing,<br />

and teaching, are not intrinsically religious in nature, but they may be engaged in for religious reasons.<br />

Similarly, there are many forms <strong>of</strong> normally non-expressive conduct that may be performed for communicative<br />

purposes--to send a message. For example, a person may wear a ribbon on her clothing as a noncommunicative<br />

decoration or as a sign <strong>of</strong> solidarity or protest.<br />

It is clear after Smith that the regulation <strong>of</strong> conduct that is not conventionally recognized to be religious in<br />

nature will receive rational basis review, unless the law regulates the conduct only when it is engaged in for religious<br />

purposes. A law prohibiting wearing hats can be used to punish Jews wearing Yarmulkes, as long as persons<br />

wearing hats for secular reasons are equally subject to sanction. [FN145] It is less than clear, however, that<br />

free speech doctrine tracks this analysis. <strong>The</strong> *160 regulation <strong>of</strong> normally non-expressive conduct may receive<br />

some form <strong>of</strong> review when it is applied to conduct that is engaged in to send a message, even when the regulation<br />

is not intended to have a speech-suppressing effect.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court has set out a four-prong standard <strong>of</strong> review, the O'Brien test, to evaluate the constitutionality <strong>of</strong><br />

laws regulating conventionally non-expressive conduct, such as sleeping in a park, when that conduct is engaged<br />

in for expressive purposes. <strong>The</strong> test considers whether the challenged regulation lies within the power <strong>of</strong> government,<br />

furthers a substantial governmental interest, burdens speech no more than is necessary to further that<br />

interest, and is not related to the suppression <strong>of</strong> expression. [FN146] <strong>The</strong>re is agreement under O'Brien that regulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> symbolic or conduct-intensive expression will receive strict scrutiny when they are designed to silence<br />

a particular message. [FN147] What is uncertain is the rigor <strong>of</strong> this standard <strong>of</strong> review when it is applied<br />

to laws that lack a speech-suppressive purpose.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Supreme Court has stated on several occasions that this standard <strong>of</strong> review is essentially equivalent to<br />

the evaluation <strong>of</strong> content-neutral regulations <strong>of</strong> the time, place, and manner <strong>of</strong> speech. [FN148] Several thoughtful<br />

commentators accept the Court's assertions at face value and argue that free speech doctrine is distinguishable<br />

from free exercise doctrine in this regard. Neutral and generally applicable laws receive rational basis review<br />

under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause when they are applied to conduct that is not intrinsically religious in nature,<br />

but which may, in fact, be religiously motivated. Neutral and generally applicable laws receive a form <strong>of</strong> intermediate<br />

level scrutiny under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause when they are applied to conduct that is not intrinsically<br />

expressive in nature, but which may, in fact, be engaged in to express a message. [FN149]<br />

Other commentators, and I include myself in this group, suggest that the Court's claims about the rigor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

review provided to general regulations <strong>of</strong> conduct that incidentally burden expression are substantially in-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 21<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

flated. When the cases applying the O'Brien test are examined carefully, it is evident that the courts are employing<br />

a very *161 deferential standard <strong>of</strong> review. [FN150] From this perspective, there is little, if any, difference<br />

between free speech and free exercise doctrine in this regard, and characterizing religious activity as speech will<br />

not increase the level <strong>of</strong> constitutional protection such practices will receive.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is no need to revisit these arguments again in this article. It is sufficient to conclude that if the<br />

O'Brien test is taken seriously, free speech doctrine will be more advantageous than free exercise doctrine in<br />

challenging neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability that incidentally burden expressive religious practices. But the<br />

predicate to that conclusion remains to be established.<br />

5. Compelled Affirmation <strong>of</strong> Belief<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is historical precedent for recognizing that <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause protection against compelled affirmations<br />

<strong>of</strong> belief will be stronger and more effective than any shield the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause provides against state<br />

mandates requiring religious individuals or institutions to engage in conduct that directly or incidentally communicates<br />

a message inconsistent with their beliefs. In Minersville School District v. Gobitis, [FN151] the Court<br />

rejected a free exercise challenge by Jehovah's Witnesses to compulsory saluting <strong>of</strong> the American flag. Three<br />

years later, in West Virginia State Board <strong>of</strong> Education v. Barnette, [FN152] the Court held that school districts<br />

requiring students to salute the flag violated the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment.<br />

Since the Court's decision in Barnette, the scope <strong>of</strong> the Constitution's protection against compelled affirmations<br />

<strong>of</strong> speech has expanded dramatically. Individuals and corporations are not only protected against having to<br />

affirm or communicate the state's message, but they are also protected against being compelled to communicate<br />

any private message with which they disagree. [FN153] Nor do claimants actually have to be forced to affirm or<br />

even to say anything. It is enough that they are required to permit state or private messages to be communicated<br />

in a *162 way that associates the compulsory message with the claimant. [FN154] Similarly, compulsory exactions<br />

that are used to finance the expression <strong>of</strong> others are unconstitutional. [FN155] <strong>The</strong> message being communicated<br />

need not be political or ideological. It can be trivial or commercial in nature. All that is essential is that<br />

the compelled party disagrees with its content. [FN156]<br />

Indeed, under recent case law, it is not even necessary that the state's compulsion directly relate to expressive<br />

conduct. In Boy Scouts <strong>of</strong> America v. Dale, [FN157] the Court upheld the right <strong>of</strong> the Scouts to expel Dale,<br />

a gay Scoutmaster, in an opinion that effectively merged freedom <strong>of</strong> association and compelled affirmation <strong>of</strong><br />

belief arguments. Notwithstanding the fact that Dale had never discussed his or anyone else's homosexuality<br />

with his troop and the lack <strong>of</strong> any evidence that he intended to broach this subject with the boys in his charge,<br />

the Court found that Dale's silent presence communicated an unacceptable message. “Dale's presence in the Boy<br />

Scouts,” the majority explained, “would, at the very least, force the organization to send a message, both to the<br />

youth members and the world, that the Boy Scouts accepts homosexual conduct as a legitimate form <strong>of</strong> behavior.”<br />

[FN158]<br />

Last, but not least, the compelled affirmation <strong>of</strong> belief doctrine not only protects people from having to say<br />

things with which they disagree, but also protects them from being forced to express their own views when they<br />

would prefer to remain silent. Thus, one <strong>of</strong> the unconstitutional consequences <strong>of</strong> persons being forced to<br />

“associate” with speech they oppose is that they will feel pressured to respond to such messages. This “forced<br />

response is antithetical to the free discussion that the First Amendment seeks to foster.” [FN159]<br />

<strong>The</strong> utility <strong>of</strong> this doctrine for religious institutions may be illustrated by a recent California Court <strong>of</strong> Ap-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 22<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

peals decision, Catholic Charities <strong>of</strong> Sacramento v. Superior Court, [FN160] which is currently on appeal before<br />

the California Supreme Court. At issue is a state statute requiring *163 employers who <strong>of</strong>fer health benefits to<br />

their employees that include prescription drug benefits to also include prescription contraceptive drugs in the<br />

coverage provided. While there is a conscience clause in the statute, it is so narrow and restricted in scope that<br />

Catholic institutions, like Catholic charities, are not exempt from the statute's mandate. Since “[t]he Catholic<br />

Church explicitly teaches that artificial contraception is morally unacceptable and, if knowingly and freely engaged<br />

in, sinful,” [FN161] the burden <strong>of</strong> the law on Catholic organizations' religious commitments is obvious.<br />

Yet a direct challenge on free exercise grounds after Smith has significant difficulties. <strong>The</strong> state law (leaving<br />

aside the conscience clause for the moment) is neutral on its face and generally applicable. It applies to both religious<br />

and non-religious employers. Smith leaves little opportunity for a free exercise challenge to such a law.<br />

[FN162]<br />

A free speech challenge alleging compelled affirmation <strong>of</strong> belief may stand on stronger ground. Catholic organizations<br />

are forced to subsidize insurance coverage for practices the Church condemns as sinful. While insurance<br />

coverage is not directly communicative, it is hard to escape the associational connection between church<br />

doctrine and employment policies. If a civil rights law prohibiting discrimination “forces” the Scouts to communicate<br />

a message “accept[ing] homosexual conduct as a legitimate form <strong>of</strong> behavior” by allowing a gay man<br />

to serve as a Scoutmaster, [FN163] requiring Catholic Charities to subsidize insurance coverage for acts it condemns<br />

as sinful similarly “forces” the religious organization to communicate the message that the use <strong>of</strong> contraceptives<br />

is a legitimate method <strong>of</strong> birth control. Certainly, the law imposes considerable pressure on religious associations<br />

to respond to the insurance mandate and explain why they are subsidizing practices that are inconsistent<br />

with their faith.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reach <strong>of</strong> such a compelled affirmation <strong>of</strong> belief argument may seem unreasonably broad. It suggests<br />

that government can never impose mandates on groups that are inconsistent with the group's ideology. Yet it is<br />

difficult to deny that the Dale opinion opens the door *164 to arguments <strong>of</strong> this kind. [FN164] Moreover, when<br />

organizations exist in significant part for the purpose <strong>of</strong> communicating particular messages, such as the mission<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious organizations to convey to the community their religious beliefs by word and example, statutory<br />

mandates inconsistent with core religious beliefs seem to compel speech either by implication or in response to<br />

legal requirements.<br />

B. Drawbacks and Problems<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> Consequences <strong>of</strong> Religion as Viewpoint<br />

a. <strong>The</strong> Loss <strong>of</strong> Religion Specific Accommodations<br />

<strong>The</strong> dismantling <strong>of</strong> free exercise protection by the Smith decision shifted the responsibility for protecting religious<br />

liberty from the courts to the political branches <strong>of</strong> government. <strong>Religious</strong> individuals and institutions<br />

were forced to seek and rely on political accommodations and statutory exemptions to escape government burdens<br />

on the practice <strong>of</strong> their faiths since the constitutional courts were no longer available to provide redress.<br />

[FN165] While several acute problems result from this shift in responsibility (and I will return to these concerns<br />

later in this article), conceptualizing religion as speech, and as a viewpoint <strong>of</strong> speech at that, creates a particularly<br />

difficult issue for legislative accommodations and exemptions <strong>of</strong> religious practice.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 23<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Put simply, a great many accommodations and exemptions apply only to religious individuals and institutions.<br />

No comparable relief from regulatory burdens is provided those whose secular beliefs and belief-motivated<br />

conduct are subject to regulatory burdens or to secular organizations that are analogous, in many <strong>of</strong> their<br />

functions and purposes, to religious institutions. [FN166] If religion constitutes a viewpoint for <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Clause purposes, accommodations and exemptions for *165 religious individuals and institutions, but not their<br />

secular counterparts, should constitute viewpoint discrimination that must be justified under strict scrutiny.<br />

[FN167]<br />

If we discuss exemptions for religious speech or religiously motivated expression from a conventional content-neutral<br />

speech regulation, the viewpoint discrimination problem is obvious and exemptions are extremely<br />

difficult to uphold. Assume a law regulates the use <strong>of</strong> loud speakers, the distribution <strong>of</strong> leaflets, the size and<br />

location <strong>of</strong> signs, the scope <strong>of</strong> residential picketing or any other conventional means <strong>of</strong> expression. Is there any<br />

doubt that a statutory exception for religious speech or religiously motivated messages constitutes viewpoint discrimination<br />

or that such viewpoint discrimination cannot survive strict scrutiny? [FN168]<br />

What compelling state interest does exempting religious speech from routine time, place, and manner regulations<br />

further? <strong>The</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause after Smith does not protect religious expression from neutral and generally<br />

applicable speech regulations. Accordingly, the state cannot claim that its discrimination is justified by<br />

the need to comply with free exercise requirements. <strong>The</strong> state may argue that it is attempting to provide greater<br />

protection to religious practices and expression than the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause requires. But we have seen that<br />

the Court has explicitly rejected similar arguments when states attempt to justify discrimination against religious<br />

speech on the grounds that they are enforcing the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state beyond the *166 mandate <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Establishment Clause. [FN169] While complying with constitutional requirements could be characterized as a<br />

compelling state interest, going beyond what the Constitution requires in the service <strong>of</strong> constitutional values<br />

does not justify the abridgement <strong>of</strong> free speech rights.<br />

As courts increasingly characterize religious activities as expression for free speech purposes and insist that<br />

discrimination against such activities constitutes prohibited viewpoint discrimination, it becomes increasingly<br />

difficult, if not impossible, to avoid reaching a similar conclusion when religious activities are given favorable<br />

treatment. <strong>The</strong> Good News Club case is embarrassingly on point here. <strong>The</strong> Milford School District opened its<br />

facilities to “social, civic and recreational meetings and entertainment events, and other uses pertaining to the<br />

welfare <strong>of</strong> the community,” but refused to provide similar access to organizations intending to use school facilities<br />

for “religious worship.” [FN170] Accordingly, the Boys Scouts, Girls Scouts, and 4H Clubs were permitted<br />

access, but the Good News Club was not.<br />

To the majority, this exclusion constituted prohibited viewpoint discrimination. <strong>The</strong> fact that the Good<br />

News Club's program involved activities that could be accurately described as religious worship was entirely irrelevant<br />

to the Court's analysis. It was enough that the Club's program also involved, and could be properly<br />

characterized as, the teaching <strong>of</strong> morals and character development. Thus, if secular groups engaged in the<br />

teaching <strong>of</strong> morals and character development were permitted to use school property, religious groups seeking to<br />

use school property for worship and moral education must be permitted access as well. [FN171]<br />

If the Milford School District's policy constitutes viewpoint discrimination, clearly it is equally viewpoint<br />

discriminatory to open school facilities exclusively to religious organizations and programs, but not to the<br />

Rotary Club, Boy Scouts, and 4H clubs or other social and civic groups. More importantly, there is no reason to<br />

limit the holding <strong>of</strong> Good News Club to clubs or to school buildings. Justice Souter protested in dissent that if<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 24<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

the majority's analysis is accepted, “any public school opened for civic meetings must be opened for use as a<br />

*167 church, synagogue, or mosque.” [FN172] That seems to be the precise consequence <strong>of</strong> the majority opinion.<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> what occurs in a church or synagogue involves the teaching <strong>of</strong> morals and character development,<br />

holiday celebrations, charity work, educational programs, social gatherings, discussions <strong>of</strong> ethical issues and a<br />

host <strong>of</strong> other expressive activities that occur in secular institutions and programs. If the context and function <strong>of</strong><br />

worship does not distinguish religious organizations and programs from secular groups and activities that have<br />

no worship component for free speech purposes, discrimination in favor <strong>of</strong> civic meetings and against church,<br />

synagogue, and mosque services should indeed be held to violate the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. This means, however,<br />

that discrimination in favor <strong>of</strong> churches, synagogues, and mosques constitutes prohibited viewpoint discrimination,<br />

as well. [FN173]<br />

Further, this prohibition against viewpoint discrimination in favor <strong>of</strong> religious institutions is not limited to<br />

government property and traditional or limited public forums. <strong>The</strong> prohibition against viewpoint discrimination<br />

is a core free speech principle that extends to any regulation <strong>of</strong> expressive activity wherever it occurs.<br />

Viewpoint-discriminatory regulations <strong>of</strong> speech on private property are at least as problematic as viewpoint-discriminatory<br />

regulations limiting access to public property. [FN174] Thus, accommodations and exemptions<br />

from regulatory burdens that are available only to religious individuals and institutions raise viewpoint discrimination<br />

issues whenever the activity at issue is subsumed within the coverage <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause.<br />

A host <strong>of</strong> statutory exemptions might be constitutionally vulnerable to attack on free speech grounds under<br />

this analysis. One obvious example is the <strong>Religious</strong> Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act (RLUIPA)<br />

[FN175] enacted in 2000. RLUIPA provides important statutory *168 protection for houses <strong>of</strong> worship in the<br />

land use regulatory process by imposing a stringent burden <strong>of</strong> justification on local governments that substantially<br />

interfere with the ability <strong>of</strong> congregations to develop houses <strong>of</strong> worship in a community to otherwise use<br />

their property for religious purposes. It is an effective legislative response to serious regulatory abuses limiting<br />

opportunities for religious assembly in far too many communities. [FN176]<br />

However, the protection provided by RLUIPA is only available to religious land uses. It applies to churches,<br />

but not fraternal lodges, synagogues, but not Boy Scout cabins, mosques, but not women's centers. All <strong>of</strong> these<br />

secular facilities are used to teach morals and character development, to discuss ethical issues, and to organize<br />

and support charitable work, but they do so from a secular, rather than a religious, perspective. Why isn't<br />

RLUIPA a viewpoint-discriminatory law, which must be justified under strict scrutiny? [FN177]<br />

*169 Reasonable people may argue about whether it is a good or bad idea to insist that religious exemptions<br />

and accommodations be broadened to include secular beliefs, practices, and institutions. <strong>The</strong> argument against<br />

such an approach is basically the same whether we are talking about statutory accommodations or constitutionally-mandated<br />

exemptions (the kind we used to have before Smith was decided). Michael Paulsen states the argument<br />

against such an expansive approach succinctly when he writes that it is<br />

too generous; such a broad conception <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> ‘religion’ becomes, as a practical matter,<br />

something <strong>of</strong> a poison pill for the pro-exemptions view. It loads up the pro-exemptions reading <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Clause [or writing <strong>of</strong> statutes] with liabilities so severe and costs so great that judges [or legislatures] no<br />

longer will buy it. [FN178] Other commentators insist that only broad-based, general exemptions are appropriate.<br />

Religion should not be singled out for preferential treatment. [FN179]<br />

This article is not the place to continue, much less resolve, this debate. My point is simply that an expansive<br />

vision <strong>of</strong> religion as speech that is subsumed under and protected by the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause precludes the adop-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 25<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> many religion-only exemptions and accommodations and requires more even-handed treatment between<br />

religious and secular beliefs and viewpoints. To the extent that such a requirement is problematic for the protection<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious liberty, and I think there is a powerful argument that it is, particularly in a post-Smith world,<br />

free speech doctrine imposes serious limits on the ability <strong>of</strong> the political branches to protect religious practices<br />

and institutions from state interference.<br />

b. Subject and Viewpoint Distortions<br />

<strong>The</strong> preceding section demonstrates one <strong>of</strong> the precarious consequences <strong>of</strong> the Court's uncritical willingness<br />

to characterize religion as a viewpoint and to protect it as such under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. Legitimate legislative<br />

exemptions and accommodations that are *170 necessary to protect religious liberty become vulnerable to<br />

challenge. Characterizing religion as a viewpoint, in some circumstances, has another problematic effect,<br />

however. <strong>Religious</strong>, expressive activities are unreasonably favored when there is no persuasive justification for<br />

favoring religious speech over its secular counterpart.<br />

In one sense, the issue here is a relatively minor one, but it demonstrates the way that the Court's characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion as a viewpoint can unwittingly distort the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas. Religion is not disadvantaged<br />

under this analysis; it is actually privileged. But the way the privilege arises is difficult to accept and seems inconsistent<br />

with basic free speech values - even if it conforms to current doctrine.<br />

Assume that a school district, such as the defendant in the Good News Club case, allows various private<br />

clubs and associations to use school facilities after hours, but excludes political meetings and religious meetings.<br />

Because the school district is sufficiently selective in choosing the groups it permits to use its buildings, it<br />

does not create a designated or limited public forum but instead is held to regulate access to a nonpublic forum.<br />

[FN180] In a nonpublic forum, the doctrinal rules are relatively clear-cut. Content-discriminatory regulations<br />

will be upheld as long as they are reasonable, a relatively deferential standard <strong>of</strong> review. Viewpoint-discriminatory<br />

regulations will be reviewed under strict scrutiny. [FN181] <strong>The</strong> application <strong>of</strong> those rules is more complex<br />

than their statement, however.<br />

To begin with, how should we characterize the school district's decision to exclude political and religious<br />

meetings? One might argue in theory that the exclusion <strong>of</strong> both religious and political meetings is sufficiently<br />

general that it cannot be construed to be viewpoint-discriminatory. That argument seems foreclosed by the<br />

Court's analysis in Rosenberger, however, which held that the University's refusal to fund a religious periodical<br />

prepared by a student group constituted viewpoint discrimination, notwithstanding the University's refusal to<br />

fund a variety <strong>of</strong> other student-based expressive activities. [FN182] Accordingly, closing the school district's facilities<br />

to religious meetings should be characterized as viewpoint discrimination and reviewed under strict scrutiny.<br />

*171 But what about the ban on political meetings? It is much more difficult to classify political meetings or<br />

political expression <strong>of</strong> any kind as a viewpoint. <strong>The</strong>re is no obviously understood “political” perspective through<br />

which issues can be evaluated. Nor is it clear what the contrasting viewpoint to political expression might be.<br />

Secular beliefs may stand in opposition to religious beliefs, but there is no corresponding antithesis or perspective<br />

that competes with political speech. [FN183] Instead, political speech is a classic subject <strong>of</strong> speech, and a<br />

regulation prohibiting political expression would be characterized as content-discriminatory, not viewpointdiscriminatory.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, under the rules governing the regulation <strong>of</strong> non-public fora, the content-discriminatory<br />

exclusion <strong>of</strong> political meetings should be upheld as long as it is reasonable.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 26<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

It is not hard to imagine “reasonable” grounds for a school district deciding not to open its facilities to political<br />

meetings. It does not want students embroiled in political controversies while leaving school or becoming<br />

pawns in adult political conflicts. <strong>The</strong> district may fear that students will mistakenly believe that the district endorses<br />

the political groups using school facilities soon after classes end. <strong>The</strong> district might also worry that opening<br />

its buildings for political meetings might risk charges <strong>of</strong> favoritism, if some groups ended up with what were<br />

perceived to be better rooms or meeting times than others. <strong>The</strong> safer and more prudent course might be to have<br />

political groups conduct their business elsewhere. I do not suggest that these arguments are convincing to everyone<br />

(or to me) as a matter <strong>of</strong> policy. But that is not the applicable standard <strong>of</strong> review. <strong>The</strong> grounds suggested<br />

here need only be reasonable. In Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense and Educational Fund, [FN184] very similar<br />

arguments were accepted as a “reasonable” justification for excluding advocacy groups from participating in<br />

a federal workplace charity drive. [FN185]<br />

<strong>The</strong>se, and similar arguments, might also be cited as support for the exclusion <strong>of</strong> religious meetings.<br />

However reasonable they may be, they are not sufficient justifications to withstand strict scrutiny. <strong>The</strong><br />

Good News Club case makes that conclusion abundantly clear. [FN186] Thus, it is *172 quite possible, if not<br />

highly likely, that a court would strike down the ban on religious meetings but uphold the exclusion <strong>of</strong> political<br />

meetings.<br />

At a minimum, that is an awkward result to accept. <strong>The</strong>re may be considerable overlap between the goals <strong>of</strong><br />

political and religious meetings. A religious group may wish to discuss abortion from a religious perspective,<br />

while a political group plans to discuss abortion as a political matter. <strong>The</strong> former will be allowed to use school<br />

facilities; the latter will be denied access. It is true that religious groups supporting or opposing the right to have<br />

an abortion will have equal access to school facilities, and political groups supporting or opposing the right to<br />

have an abortion will be equally excluded. Still, this result is a difficult pill to swallow. That it comes about because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the way we interpret the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause adds little to its digestibility. Yet, results like this seem a<br />

necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the Court's willingness to see religion as a viewpoint and, thus, regulations excluding<br />

religious activities from public property as viewpoint discrimination.<br />

2. Funding Controls and Conditions<br />

In many cases, government does not directly regulate private activities in a way that burdens or infringes<br />

fundamental rights. Instead, it conditions the provision <strong>of</strong> public benefits and government largess on an individual's<br />

or an institution's willingness to forego the exercise <strong>of</strong> their rights. Sometimes, the imposition <strong>of</strong> these<br />

conditions is constitutional. In conventional, constitutional parlance, the question is whether the government is<br />

attaching unconstitutional conditions to the benefits it provides.<br />

It is fair to say that there is no underlying theory or framework that explains how courts should determine<br />

whether a condition is unconstitutional or not. Indeed, in a recent law review symposium discussing unconstitutional<br />

conditions doctrine, <strong>of</strong> the three scholars writing on the subject <strong>of</strong> a unifying theory, one characterized the<br />

task as so difficult that it was not worth undertaking, another described it as impossible, and the third, while not<br />

venturing a possible solution to the problem, argued that the attempt to develop such a theory may be worthwhile<br />

even if it can never be successfully accomplished. [FN187]<br />

*173 While there is no unifying theory <strong>of</strong> unconstitutional conditions, courts appear to recognize a difference<br />

between speech and Religion Clause doctrine regarding the identification <strong>of</strong> conditions that unconditionally<br />

limit the exercise <strong>of</strong> rights.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 27<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

In the Religion Clause case law, there is a marked tendency to seriously evaluate conditions that interfere<br />

with the exercise <strong>of</strong> religious rights. <strong>The</strong> seminal case, <strong>of</strong> course, is Sherbert. [FN188] When the South Carolina<br />

Employment Security Commission denied a Seventh Day Adventist unemployment compensation to which she<br />

would otherwise be entitled because she refused to accept employment that required her to work on her Sabbath,<br />

the Court determined that the Commission's ruling raised significant constitutional questions. <strong>The</strong> decision<br />

“forces [appellant] to choose between following the precepts <strong>of</strong> her religion and forfeiting benefits, on the one<br />

hand, and abandoning one <strong>of</strong> the precepts <strong>of</strong> her religion in order to accept work, on the other hand.” [FN189]<br />

Accordingly, the Commission's decision was reviewed under strict scrutiny and declared unconstitutional.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Religion Clause case law after Sherbert, but prior to Smith, was not always so favorable. But the Court<br />

rarely upheld conditions that interfered with religious beliefs or practices without either serious review or a determined<br />

debate among the justices. In Bob Jones University v. United States, [FN190] the Court upheld the decision<br />

<strong>of</strong> the IRS to revoke a religious university's tax exempt, section 501(c)(3), status because the institution<br />

engaged in racial discrimination. In essence, the IRS concluded that because the religious tenets <strong>of</strong> Bob Jones<br />

University required it to practice racial discrimination in its educational policies, the university's activities were<br />

so contrary to accepted public policy that it could not be construed to be charitable, an essential predicate for<br />

this tax exempt status. [FN191] Thus, a continuation <strong>of</strong> the university's tax exempt status was conditioned on its<br />

violating its religious commitment to the separation <strong>of</strong> the races.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is some language in the Court's opinion suggesting that the loss <strong>of</strong> tax-exempt status is not a condition<br />

that implicates constitutional concerns. <strong>The</strong> Court states that “[d]enial <strong>of</strong> tax benefits will inevitably have a substantial<br />

impact on the operation <strong>of</strong> private religious schools, *174 but will not prevent those schools from observing<br />

their religious tenets.” [FN192] This suggests that the loss <strong>of</strong> tax-exempt status would not directly interfere<br />

with a school's ability to obey religious obligations. <strong>The</strong> school would lose favorable tax treatment, but it<br />

would not be directly restricted by law.<br />

<strong>The</strong> core <strong>of</strong> the Court's analysis in Bob Jones University, however, recognizes that conditional tax benefits<br />

do invoke rigorous constitutional review. <strong>The</strong> IRS decision is upheld because the government's interest in<br />

“eradicating racial discrimination in education” is sufficiently compelling that it “outweighs whatever burden<br />

denial <strong>of</strong> tax benefits places on petitioners' exercise <strong>of</strong> their religious beliefs.” [FN193]<br />

In another case, Bowen v. Roy, [FN194] the justices on the Court split on the question <strong>of</strong> whether government<br />

could condition eligibility for AFDC benefits on a Native American family's willingness to identify their<br />

daughter through her social security number, a requirement that violated the family's religious beliefs. Three<br />

justices argued that the condition need not be evaluated under serious review because the conditioning <strong>of</strong> benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> this kind constituted a less intrusive burden on religious liberty than affirmative compulsions or prohibitions.<br />

Three other justices, however, insisted that Sherbert controlled the case and that strict scrutiny review<br />

must be applied. [FN195]<br />

All three <strong>of</strong> these unconstitutional condition cases were decided prior to Smith and there is no doubt that the<br />

Smith decision undermines future cases challenging neutral and generally applicable conditions that limit access<br />

to government benefits - even when compliance with the conditions would require beneficiaries to violate requirements<br />

<strong>of</strong> their faiths. However, Sherbert and later unemployment compensation cases survive Smith and<br />

remain good law. [FN196] Further, one might certainly argue that IRS determinations <strong>of</strong> what “charitable”<br />

means for 501(c)(3) purposes are sufficiently individualized decisions and would fall within this exception to<br />

Smith's general holding. Thus, a case like *175 Bob Jones University might require rigorous review today not-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 28<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

withstanding the limited scope <strong>of</strong> free exercise rights after Smith. At a minimum, some conditions can still be<br />

challenged as unconstitutional on free exercise grounds.<br />

Attempts to challenge allegedly unconstitutional conditions implicating religious beliefs and practices on<br />

free speech grounds may be less promising. <strong>The</strong> protection provided to free exercise rights in Sherbert always<br />

appeared to be more extensive and rigorous than anything courts would provide to comparable challenges on<br />

free speech grounds. Individuals might identify a broad range <strong>of</strong> expressive activities they were pursuing that<br />

interfered with their pursuits <strong>of</strong> gainful employment. Yet it is hard to believe that the Court would repudiate a<br />

commission denying unemployment benefits to individuals who turned down available work because they were<br />

writing a book or participating on a volunteer basis in a political campaign. Similarly, it is doubtful that individuals<br />

would be allowed to refuse jobs based on their secular political philosophies. A Marxist who refused to<br />

work for capitalist corporations or an environmentalist rejected work at companies that polluted the environment<br />

would almost certainly find his loss <strong>of</strong> benefits upheld. [FN197]<br />

Moreover, the controlling authority dealing with conditions that allegedly violate the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause in<br />

an institutional context could not be less protective <strong>of</strong> rights and more respectful <strong>of</strong> government power and discretion.<br />

In Rust v. Sullivan, [FN198] petitioners challenged federal regulations limiting the speech <strong>of</strong> personnel<br />

at medical clinics that received federal funds to provide family planning services. Subsidy recipients were prohibited<br />

from providing “counseling concerning the use <strong>of</strong> abortion as a method <strong>of</strong> family planning” and could<br />

not provide “referral[s] for abortion as a method <strong>of</strong> family planning.” [FN199] Also, organizations receiving<br />

government funds were prohibited “from engaging in activities that ‘encourage, promote or advocate abortion as<br />

a method <strong>of</strong> family planning.”’ [FN200] Prohibited activities included lobbying for legislation, disseminating<br />

materials, providing speakers, initiating legal action, or financially supporting *176 groups that advocate or support<br />

the availability <strong>of</strong> abortion for family planning purposes.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court upheld both regulations in sweeping terms. When government subsidizes certain speech activities,<br />

it may decline at its discretion to support other messages. Recipients <strong>of</strong> government grants must act and<br />

speak within these constraints. [FN201] Further, aside from specific exceptions, such as public forums and universities,<br />

as long as the conditions attached to government funds were directed at programs and services, such<br />

conditions would be upheld without regard to the burdens they imposed on privately funded speech and expression.<br />

A clinic receiving family planning funds must set up a separate affiliate that did not receive government<br />

support if it intended to engage in privately funded, expressive activities supporting the availability <strong>of</strong> abortion<br />

services. [FN202]<br />

If religion is characterized as speech, the effect <strong>of</strong> Rust on government funding <strong>of</strong> religious institutions engaging<br />

in expressive activities, such as religious schools, may be significant. <strong>The</strong> government may certainly claim<br />

that it is only interested in funding secular educational activities. Indeed, the Establishment Clause may prohibit<br />

it from directly funding religious worship, proselytizing, or instruction. [FN203] Under Rust, the government<br />

may disallow any project or program receiving public financial support from expressing or advocating religious<br />

messages <strong>of</strong> any kind, even with its own private resources. As was true <strong>of</strong> the family planning clinics in Rust, religious<br />

schools would have to develop separate affiliates to engage in religious programming. Since religious<br />

schools <strong>of</strong>ten try to insure that religious messages influence and pervade all <strong>of</strong> the school's educational program,<br />

not just distinct classes in religion, [FN204] these conditions would be deeply intrusive and would require a<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> the school's operations. <strong>The</strong>re is little doubt that the family planning clinics in Rust felt similarly<br />

burdened, but their constitutional protests fell on closed judicial ears. Under <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause doctrine,<br />

there seems little basis for contending that religious institutions should receive more favorable treatment.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 29<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

*177 3. <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Benign Discrimination<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the most pernicious consequences <strong>of</strong> the Smith decision is its effect on minority religions. As even<br />

Justice Scalia was forced to concede, minority faiths are likely to experience much greater difficulty in obtaining<br />

accommodations <strong>of</strong> their religious needs from the political branches <strong>of</strong> government than larger, more established<br />

religions. [FN205] Dissenting justices in Smith emphasized this concern in their criticism <strong>of</strong> the majority's position.<br />

[FN206] But the difficulty minority faiths will encounter in convincing political majorities to respect their<br />

religious practices is only part <strong>of</strong> the problem. <strong>The</strong>y will also confront serious constitutional obstacles. In particular,<br />

legislative accommodations and exemptions <strong>of</strong> religion can be challenged under the Establishment Clause<br />

on the grounds that the government's actions impermissibly promote religion or unfairly discriminate among religious<br />

faiths.<br />

One important weapon minority faiths may utilize in defending legislative exemptions and accommodations<br />

<strong>of</strong> their religion against Establishment Clause challenges is a political process analysis. True, the willingness <strong>of</strong><br />

courts to accept a political process argument is uncertain. <strong>The</strong>re are recognized problems with such an approach.<br />

But political process arguments may have some validity from the perspective <strong>of</strong> Religion Clause jurisprudence.<br />

In contrast, if religion is characterized as speech and protected under free speech doctrine, the availability<br />

<strong>of</strong> political process arguments for religious minorities seems completely foreclosed. Thus, a <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Clause approach undercuts religious exemptions and accommodations in two ways. It renders such accommodations<br />

vulnerable to challenge on viewpoint discrimination grounds, discussed previously, and it reduces the<br />

availability <strong>of</strong> political process arguments to defend accommodations against Establishment Clause attacks.<br />

<strong>The</strong> core principles underlying a political process analysis, developed in the famous Carolene Products footnote<br />

[FN207] and amplified by judges and scholars, are familiar. <strong>The</strong> courts rigorously review laws disadvantaging<br />

discrete and insular minorities because we mistrust the workings <strong>of</strong> the *178 political process when<br />

majorities burden isolated minorities. It is much harder to justify judicial intervention when majorities sacrifice<br />

their own interests and incur costs in adopting legislation that benefits smaller, less politically powerful groups.<br />

[FN208]<br />

Political process arguments are controversial, <strong>of</strong> course. In equal protection cases, the current Court has rejected<br />

this thesis in evaluating affirmative action programs that favor racial minorities. [FN209] But there is a<br />

powerful dissenting position on this issue. [FN210] Several justices, past and present, reject the majority's application<br />

<strong>of</strong> strict scrutiny to benign discrimination. <strong>The</strong>ir opinions are grounded on a tradition <strong>of</strong> vigorous criticisms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Court's developing commitment to formal equality in this area. [FN211]<br />

<strong>The</strong> relevance and persuasiveness <strong>of</strong> political process arguments in interpreting the Religion Clauses is even<br />

more complicated than equal protection doctrine. In part, this is a consequence <strong>of</strong> important differences<br />

between religion and race. Race is an artificial construct that has been used unreasonably and unfairly to treat<br />

people differently who are similarly situated. Thus, benign laws that discriminate on the basis <strong>of</strong> race are<br />

primarily justified as a response to prior mistreatment and oppression. Because that history <strong>of</strong> disadvantagement<br />

was predicated on race, it is argued, effective remedial legislation must also focus on race. [FN212] To critics <strong>of</strong><br />

such affirmative action, this race-specific cure is as problematic and dangerous as the disease. [FN213]<br />

Religions, on the other hand, are distinct from each other in terms <strong>of</strong> their beliefs and practices. Frequently,<br />

treating people <strong>of</strong> various faiths differently is not a response to past invidious discrimination. It is a recognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> current reality that members <strong>of</strong> different religions are *179 not similarly situated because <strong>of</strong> their distinct be-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 30<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

liefs and practices. [FN214] Thus, treating people differently because <strong>of</strong> their religion is necessary if people <strong>of</strong><br />

diverse faiths are to be recognized as equally worthy <strong>of</strong> respect.<br />

Moreover, the basis for an exemption, a form <strong>of</strong> benign discrimination, is grounded on what people think<br />

and do, not on physical characteristics such as race. Because <strong>of</strong> this difference, most religious exemptions do<br />

not need to refer to or name particular denominations to accomplish their benign objectives the way most affirmative<br />

action programs identify the beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> the program by their race. <strong>Religious</strong> exemptions specify religious<br />

activity or belief-based obligation as the predicate for relieving persons and institutions from regulatory<br />

burdens. Correctly or not, distinctions based on conduct have always been viewed as more legitimate than distinctions<br />

based on status (particularly status grounded on physical characteristics such as race or gender), and<br />

courts do not typically characterize belief- or activity-based distinctions as facially discriminatory, but rather as<br />

neutral laws disparately impacting different faiths. [FN215] Accordingly, the issue <strong>of</strong> benign discrimination and<br />

political process justifications for such discrimination has arisen far less <strong>of</strong>ten under the Religion Clauses than<br />

under the Equal Protection Clause.<br />

Still, the intuition that political process concerns should and do influence the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

exemptions is difficult to avoid. <strong>The</strong> Court did not explicitly discuss political process concerns in Gillette v.<br />

United States [FN216] when it upheld federal conscientious objector provisions that exempt religious groups<br />

who oppose all war, such as Quakers, from conscription, but denied an exemption to Catholics whose religious<br />

tradition distinguishes between participation in just and unjust wars. Yet surely this would have been a different<br />

and more difficult case if the conscientious objector statute had the effect <strong>of</strong> shielding all mainline Protestant<br />

groups from conscription, leaving the burden <strong>of</strong> the draft to fall entirely on Catholics, less popular Protestant denominations,<br />

and non-Christians.<br />

Certainly, some Supreme Court justices believe that political process concerns are relevant to determining<br />

the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> religious *180 exemptions and accommodations. Justice Scalia's impassioned dissent to<br />

the majority's decision in Kiryas Joel to strike down a law accommodating a small Hasidic community in New<br />

York could hardly have been more emphatic in this regard:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Founding Fathers would be astonished to find that the Establishment Clause - which they designed<br />

“to insure that no one powerful sect or combination <strong>of</strong> sects could use political or governmental<br />

power to punish dissenters” . . . has been employed to prohibit characteristically and admirably American<br />

accommodation <strong>of</strong> the religious practices . . . <strong>of</strong> a tiny minority sect. [FN217]<br />

It is equally clear that other Supreme Court justices flatly reject this proposition. In contrast to Scalia's<br />

protests, Justice Souter's majority opinion in Kiryas Joel explained that “[h]ere the benefit flows only to a single<br />

sect, but aiding this single, small religious group causes no less a constitutional problem than would follow from<br />

aiding a sect with more members or religion as a whole.” [FN218]<br />

At present, probably more justices oppose the application <strong>of</strong> a political process model to Establishment<br />

Clause challenges to accommodations and exemptions than support such an approach. [FN219] Commentary is<br />

also divided on the issue, with some scholars strongly endorsing a political process model and others sharply criticizing<br />

it. [FN220] <strong>The</strong> issue remains open. Both sides <strong>of</strong> the debate <strong>of</strong>fer significant arguments. Like the conflict<br />

over a political process framework for interpreting the Equal Protection Clause, one side may have the advantage<br />

today, but the dispute remains active and unresolved.<br />

<strong>Free</strong> speech doctrine is different. Here, unlike interpretations <strong>of</strong> the Religion Clauses and the Equal Protec-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 31<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

tion Clause, there is no *181 commitment on the Court to a political process approach. Formal neutrality or<br />

equality is the ruling philosophy. Government may not use its regulatory power to increase the ability <strong>of</strong> unpopular<br />

or minority voices to reach their audience. All points <strong>of</strong> view must be treated the same. [FN221] Even in the<br />

highly contentious area <strong>of</strong> speech during election campaigns, the Court has been adamant on this issue. In response<br />

to the claim that the government's interest “in equalizing the relative ability <strong>of</strong> individuals and groups to<br />

influence the outcome <strong>of</strong> elections” justified restrictions on expenditures relating to clearly identified candidates,<br />

the Court proclaimed that “the concept that government may restrict the speech <strong>of</strong> some elements <strong>of</strong> our society<br />

in order to enhance the relative voice <strong>of</strong> others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment.” [FN222] Benign<br />

discrimination among viewpoints <strong>of</strong> speech is unconstitutional.<br />

In light <strong>of</strong> this doctrinal distinction between the Religion Clauses and the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause, an additional<br />

disadvantage, or cost, in adopting a speech model becomes apparent. If religious activities are characterized as<br />

the practice <strong>of</strong> religion, and if laws regulating such activities are reviewed under the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and Establishment<br />

Clauses, discretionary exemptions and accommodations may be justified under a political process analysis.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is no guarantee that political process arguments will be accepted, but there is support for this approach<br />

on the Court and in commentary. <strong>The</strong>refore, the arguments cannot be dismissed out <strong>of</strong> hand. <strong>The</strong> opportunity<br />

for argument exists, and acceptance <strong>of</strong> political process justifications for exemptions and accommodations<br />

would not require dismantling the current doctrinal framework.<br />

In contrast, free speech doctrine, as it is currently interpreted, directly forecloses a political process approach.<br />

If religious activities are characterized as expression, and the review <strong>of</strong> their regulation is *182 controlled<br />

by free speech principles, then the fact that an exemption from a generally applicable law relieves a<br />

minority faith from burdens that interfere with its practices will have no bearing on the constitutional analysis.<br />

That is a real cost. At least it is a real cost for those who believe that there is an equality dimension, in the equal<br />

protection sense, underlying the Religion Clauses and that recognizing the majority and minority status <strong>of</strong> religions<br />

has an important role to play in achieving equality among the diverse faiths in our communities. Repudiating<br />

the relevance <strong>of</strong> political process concerns to the review <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions, as free speech doctrine requires,<br />

denies religious minorities a potentially valuable weapon for defending the accommodation <strong>of</strong> their beliefs<br />

and practices.<br />

C. Should Religion Be Characterized as <strong>Speech</strong>?<br />

On balance, I strongly believe that the correct answer to the question <strong>of</strong> whether religion should be characterized<br />

as speech and protected under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause is “sometimes” and “with caution.” If the question<br />

before us is simply whether religion can be understood as a subject or viewpoint <strong>of</strong> speech, or whether religion<br />

is expressive in the conventional understanding <strong>of</strong> that term, the question is a relatively simple one. Clearly,<br />

there is enough <strong>of</strong> a speech dimension to many religious activities, and religions play an important enough role<br />

in the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas, to justify a different answer than the one I propose.<br />

As I indicated in the beginning <strong>of</strong> this article, I think that the simplistic framing <strong>of</strong> this question is the wrong<br />

way to understand this issue. It employs the wrong criteria and misconstrues the nature <strong>of</strong> religion. As I have<br />

noted before, “[r]eligion is a multi-dimensional constitutional interest. In its varying aspects, it implicates personal<br />

liberty, group equality, and freedom <strong>of</strong> speech.” [FN223] Put simply, there is so much substance to religion<br />

that we can justifiably understand it to be, and to be protected as, speech, personal autonomy, a constitutionally<br />

recognized class, or some combination <strong>of</strong> the three. [FN224] Asking whether *183 speech is a sufficient<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 32<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> religion to justify treating religious activities as expression for constitutional purposes does not adequately<br />

resolve the problem <strong>of</strong> the place <strong>of</strong> religion in the constitutional scheme any more than asking whether<br />

there is a sufficient self-defining dimension to religion to justify treating it as a privacy and personal autonomy<br />

right, or asking whether religions are sufficiently like other protected classes and classifications that their regulation<br />

necessarily invokes equality principles. In one sense, an affirmative answer is appropriate to all three inquiries.<br />

How we choose to understand and protect religion is based in part on history. [FN225] More importantly,<br />

it represents a normative vision <strong>of</strong> how we intend to put these diverse constitutional pieces together to<br />

form a picture <strong>of</strong> the relationship between church and state and the protection to be provided to religious practices<br />

and institutions.<br />

I do not mean that religion should never be understood as speech for constitutional purposes. Sometimes religious<br />

activities are so similar to secular speech activities that they should be treated as expression. <strong>Religious</strong><br />

leafleting or door-to-door soliciting is speech intended to persuade the listener and should be protected as<br />

such. But we should not mistake the part for the whole. Religion is not simply an idea to be debated along with<br />

other ideologies. It is about the practice <strong>of</strong> living ethically, [FN226] one's role in a community, [FN227] and,<br />

for many, the relationship between the individual and G-d. [FN228] It is about the practice <strong>of</strong> married life, raising<br />

a child, charity, devotion to the Divine, congregational duties, and too many other activities to list. If practicing<br />

law or medicine is conduct, raising a family in a Jewish or Catholic home, operating a church or mosque,<br />

and fulfilling the obligation to *184 repair the world is conduct as well. [FN229] Much <strong>of</strong> the speech expressed<br />

in the practice <strong>of</strong> religion, including prayer, is part <strong>of</strong> an integrated whole that encompasses much more than the<br />

communication <strong>of</strong> ideas. [FN230]<br />

In the preceding analysis, I have adopted something <strong>of</strong> a pragmatic perspective. In response to what I perceive<br />

to be too much <strong>of</strong> an uncritical acceptance <strong>of</strong> a constitutional framework that equates religion and speech,<br />

I have tried to provide a fair evaluation <strong>of</strong> the benefits and disadvantages <strong>of</strong> this approach from the perspective<br />

<strong>of</strong> someone who values religious liberty. When the downside <strong>of</strong> this equation is described accurately, I think the<br />

balance is substantially one-sided. In practical terms, religion loses more than it gains when it is characterized<br />

as speech and laws relating to religion are evaluated under free speech doctrine. This is particularly the case<br />

when one recognizes that most <strong>of</strong> the virtues <strong>of</strong> treating religion as speech depend on our continuing commitment<br />

to the Smith regime <strong>of</strong> formal neutrality. In Part II <strong>of</strong> this article, I seek to explain why various efforts to<br />

mitigate the impact <strong>of</strong> Smith are ultimately unpersuasive and unsuccessful. Characterizing religion as speech<br />

can be seen in a similar light. At best, it is one more unsuccessful attempt to avoid the harsh reality <strong>of</strong> Smith.<br />

Putting pragmatic concerns aside, for the moment, there are other reasons to reject the religion-as-speech<br />

model. As an abstract proposition, it is a mistake to characterize religion as speech because doing so undermines<br />

our commitment to the idea that there is something unique and distinctive about religion in life and in<br />

constitutional law. Ultimately, I think Justice White was correct in his dissent in Widmar when he worried that<br />

equating religion with speech would empty the Religion Clauses <strong>of</strong> their content. [FN231] Even in the most<br />

*185 egregious situation, the government's destruction <strong>of</strong> a religion, one <strong>of</strong> the few burdens on religion recognized<br />

to be unconstitutional after Smith, speech doctrine could easily be employed as a substitute for free exercise<br />

protection (destroying a religion is easily characterized as suppressing an idea and silencing a voice).<br />

But destroying a religion is much more than stifling a message. It <strong>of</strong>ten involves the destruction <strong>of</strong> a community<br />

and a way <strong>of</strong> life. [FN232] <strong>Religious</strong> people <strong>of</strong> the faith under attack would not only lose the right to<br />

speak but would also lose their communal identity and the autonomy to determine how they will live.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 33<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

A similar analysis applies to less extreme and more probable regulations <strong>of</strong> religion. Regulating the size,<br />

design, and location <strong>of</strong> a house <strong>of</strong> worship, and the activities permitted to occur in it, implicates free speech concerns.<br />

But churches are much more than institutionalized speakers in the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas, and few communities<br />

regulate them because <strong>of</strong> the message they communicate. Treating religion as speech simply leaves too<br />

many other aspects <strong>of</strong> religion out <strong>of</strong> the picture on the constitutional cutting room floor. <strong>The</strong> result is a truncated<br />

version <strong>of</strong> religion and a constitutional doctrine that does not adequately serve the interests it purports to<br />

protect.<br />

Recognizing that religion is more than speech and should only be characterized as speech for constitutional<br />

purposes in limited circumstances, however, does not mean that our understanding <strong>of</strong> the Religion Clauses<br />

should ignore the implications <strong>of</strong> regulating religion for the communication <strong>of</strong> ideas. Regulating religion impacts<br />

the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas. <strong>Speech</strong> concerns should inform our interpretation <strong>of</strong> the Religion<br />

Clauses. Avoiding distortion <strong>of</strong> the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas should be one <strong>of</strong> the goals that guide the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and Establishment Clause doctrine. That objective, however, is only one <strong>of</strong> several purposes <strong>of</strong><br />

the Religion Clauses. It must be reconciled with personal autonomy and equality goals and with structural concerns.<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> belongs in the package, but only as part <strong>of</strong> a complex constitutional framework. [FN233]<br />

*186 III. <strong>The</strong> Problem with Formal Neutrality<br />

One core idea serves as the foundation for a legal regime that protects and promotes religious liberty and<br />

equality as constitutional values. <strong>The</strong>re must be a commitment to, and respect for, religious diversity in belief<br />

and practice. <strong>The</strong> essential nature <strong>of</strong> this predicate commitment should be self-evident. <strong>The</strong> range <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

beliefs throughout the United States is extraordinarily broad. <strong>The</strong> variety <strong>of</strong> rituals, forms <strong>of</strong> worship, and rules<br />

<strong>of</strong> conduct practiced by religious individuals and groups is equally substantial in scope. [FN234] A free society<br />

that aspires to protect the religious liberty <strong>of</strong> its citizens and to treat religious individuals as equal citizens has to<br />

accept this reality <strong>of</strong> difference. We are not all <strong>of</strong> one faith.<br />

Of course, differences in fact do not always require differences in treatment. Sometimes liberty and equality<br />

require that differences among religions should be ignored by the law. Law should not be used to reward or<br />

penalize people because <strong>of</strong> their religious beliefs. For aspects <strong>of</strong> life in which religious differences do not distinguish<br />

people or justify treating them differently, religion should be irrelevant. Jews, Catholics, and Moslems<br />

all are entitled to exercise the franchise, and their votes are tabulated the same way - one person, one<br />

vote. Similarly, there can be no exceptions from laws that are necessary to protect the public health and<br />

safety. Everyone caught driving through a red light gets a ticket.<br />

Often, however, liberty and equality in law require that people <strong>of</strong> one faith should be treated differently than<br />

people <strong>of</strong> another religion. <strong>Religious</strong> people who are not similarly situated in their beliefs and practices should<br />

not be treated as if they were fungible clones. In aspects <strong>of</strong> life in which religion matters for particular faith<br />

communities, government rules that ignore religious distinctions coerce *187 a false homogeneity among individuals<br />

who are different in fundamental ways. <strong>Religious</strong> liberty does not exist when the burden <strong>of</strong> a law that interferes<br />

with the practice <strong>of</strong> one's faith is ignored because the law does not interfere with the majority <strong>of</strong> people<br />

who practice a different faith. <strong>Religious</strong> equality is sacrificed when laws are tailored to accommodate the needs<br />

<strong>of</strong> majoritarian or favored religions, but not minority or disfavored faiths. [FN235]<br />

A legal regime grounded on formal neutrality is inconsistent with this core principle. I do not intend to argue<br />

this point again here. <strong>The</strong> voluminous criticism directed at the Smith decision accomplishes that task with<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 34<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

more than sufficient acumen and vigor. [FN236] My goal for the second part <strong>of</strong> this article is more modest. I<br />

want to demonstrate that there are no escape hatches from the formal neutrality prison created by Smith.<br />

Both <strong>of</strong> the exceptions to formal neutrality recognized in Smith - the hybrid rights exception and the individual<br />

exemption exception - are untenable except, perhaps, in the most narrow <strong>of</strong> circumstances. Moreover, reliance<br />

on the political branches <strong>of</strong> government to provide exemptions and accommodations is unjustified.<br />

Political accommodations and exemptions are inadequate not only because we may reasonably doubt the<br />

state's willingness to provide the necessary relief from its laws, but also because they raise almost unsolvable<br />

problems regarding the nature and scope <strong>of</strong> any constitutional standard <strong>of</strong> review to be applied to them.<br />

Thus, there is no effective way to mitigate the formal neutrality standard adopted in Smith. If formal neutrality<br />

is fundamentally inconsistent with a constitutional regime that protects religious liberty and equality, the<br />

problem can be solved only by overruling Smith.<br />

A. Hybrid Rights<br />

As noted earlier, the Smith Court's exception for hybrid rights quite obviously served a specific function. It<br />

allowed the Court to avoid overruling Yoder, [FN237] a long accepted precedent protecting free exercise rights<br />

against a neutral law <strong>of</strong> general applicability. [FN238] <strong>The</strong> solution, *188 which fooled no one, was to characterize<br />

Yoder as a hybrid rights case. Amish parents were not allowed to violate Wisconsin's compulsory education<br />

requirements solely because sending their children to public school violated their religious convictions. It<br />

was only because state law implicated two constitutional rights, the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion and the right <strong>of</strong> parents<br />

to control the upbringing <strong>of</strong> their children, that their constitutional claim was vindicated. Only when state<br />

action involved a “hybrid situation” in which the free exercise claim was connected to some other right, such as<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> speech or freedom <strong>of</strong> association, would the Court apply strict scrutiny to the challenged law.<br />

[FN239]<br />

<strong>The</strong> conventional criticism <strong>of</strong> the hybrid rights exception (in addition to its being made up out <strong>of</strong> whole<br />

cloth) is that it is intellectually incoherent. To use the crude local vernacular, it just makes no sense. Put<br />

simply, a hybrid right must mean more than the idea that a law implicates constitutional interests because almost<br />

all laws satisfy that standard. A hybrid right must also mean less than the idea that an independently viable<br />

right, other than free exercise, is being unconstitutionally infringed because, if that is the definition <strong>of</strong> hybrid<br />

rights, the law is unconstitutional whether there is a burden on the free exercise <strong>of</strong> religion or not. [FN240]<br />

Stuck between these unenviable alternatives, lower courts have not welcomed the hybrid rights exception with<br />

open arms. [FN241] Some courts have rejected the idea explicitly. [FN242] Others insist that it applies only<br />

when plaintiffs can *189 demonstrate that an independently viable constitutional claim along with free exercise<br />

can be asserted. [FN243] Still others have attempted to avoid the issue. [FN244] And some courts, obviously<br />

pressured by the conviction that the Supreme Court must have meant something intelligible when it created this<br />

exception in Smith, struggled to give meaning to hybrid rights by suggesting that they encompass a “colorable<br />

claim” based on some constitutional right linked to an independent free exercise claim. [FN245]<br />

Unfortunately, the idea <strong>of</strong> a colorable claim in this context is also unintelligible. Colorable claim language<br />

exists in a variety <strong>of</strong> legal circumstances but it is almost always in terms <strong>of</strong> a threshold, temporal contingency.<br />

Thus, courts may allow suits or discovery to go forward *190 only if a claim is colorable, or, to cite one<br />

analogy used by a Federal Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals, a colorable claim is like a claim with sufficient likelihood <strong>of</strong> success<br />

on the merits to justify the issuance <strong>of</strong> a preliminary injunction. [FN246] In all <strong>of</strong> these cases, however, the<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 35<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

colorable claim is only accepted as a basis for reaching a decision or moving forward before the claim can be<br />

fully considered on the merits. Once a claim is fully adjudicated, whether it was initially colorable or not becomes<br />

irrelevant. At that point in time, it is either a valid claim or it is not. <strong>The</strong> hybrid rights exception to Smith,<br />

however, does not represent a threshold inquiry that will be more fully evaluated at a later time. It determines<br />

the appropriate standard <strong>of</strong> review to be applied in reaching a final judgment. It is hard to understand why we<br />

should continue to characterize a claim as colorable at that point in the adjudication, rather than conclude on the<br />

merits whether it is valid (and clearly more than colorable) or invalid and no longer colorable.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is one other possible explanation for hybrid rights that may have some merit. It is grounded on the recognition<br />

that not all alleged infringements <strong>of</strong> rights are subject to the same standard <strong>of</strong> review. Thus, for example,<br />

a content-neutral speech regulation restricting residential picketing is more than a colorable claim that a<br />

law violates the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. It is a sufficient infringement <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> speech to justify applying a<br />

form <strong>of</strong> intermediate level scrutiny to the law to determine if it can be adequately justified. [FN247] Perhaps one<br />

may plausibly argue that when the ban on residential picketing is applied to religiously motivated picketing expressing<br />

a religious message, a hybrid rights situation exists, and the standard <strong>of</strong> review applied to the law<br />

should be ratcheted up to strict scrutiny.<br />

Or consider another example. In Planned Parenthood v. Casey, [FN248] the Court upheld both an informed<br />

consent requirement and a 24-hour waiting period on the grounds that neither law unduly burdened the right <strong>of</strong> a<br />

woman to choose to have an abortion. Similar statutory provisions, however, were struck down under strict scrutiny<br />

in earlier cases subsequently overruled by Casey. [FN249] Under a hybrid rights analysis, *191 if either <strong>of</strong><br />

these two regulations is applied to a woman seeking a religiously motivated abortion, arguably the law would receive<br />

strict scrutiny and would be invalidated as applied, instead <strong>of</strong> being upheld under Casey's more deferential<br />

undue burden standard.<br />

I think this understanding <strong>of</strong> hybrid rights is coherent. A hybrid rights situation involves a neutral law <strong>of</strong><br />

general applicability that substantially burdens the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion and sufficiently burdens some other constitutionally<br />

protected interest to invoke the application <strong>of</strong> the requisite standard <strong>of</strong> review, whether it is an undue<br />

burden test, some form <strong>of</strong> intermediate level scrutiny, or any other substantive standard short <strong>of</strong> strict scrutiny.<br />

If strict scrutiny were otherwise applicable because <strong>of</strong> the burden on a right, then the hybrid rights analysis<br />

would be irrelevant. <strong>The</strong> burden on free exercise would add nothing extra to the court's analysis. If no fundamental<br />

right were infringed, and the law received rational basis review, no hybrid right would be found to exist,<br />

since no right other than the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion was burdened sufficiently to warrant serious review <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state's justification for its law.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with this understanding <strong>of</strong> hybrid rights is not lack <strong>of</strong> coherence. It is that it violates basic constitutional<br />

intuitions about the nature <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights. Justice Scalia in Smith has it exactly backwards.<br />

<strong>The</strong> least appropriate circumstances for accepting free exercise exemptions are those in which some other<br />

right, in addition to freedom <strong>of</strong> religion, is being exercised by the claimant and is burdened by the challenged<br />

law. Consider the abortion example described above. *192 Under a hybrid rights approach, if regulations requiring<br />

informed consent or a 24-hour waiting period are applied to a woman seeking an abortion for secular<br />

reasons, the regulation is reviewed under the undue burden standard and is upheld. If the woman is seeking an<br />

abortion for religious reasons, this application <strong>of</strong> the law will be reviewed under strict scrutiny and invalidated.<br />

I submit that this is a very odd conclusion. It is odd because it justifies treating people differently with regard<br />

to their exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights. Hybrid rights analysis suggests that religious people should be<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 36<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

treated preferentially with regard to the exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights when their religious beliefs influence the<br />

way they exercise their rights. <strong>The</strong> protection provided free speech, the right to vote, the right to marry, maybe<br />

even protection against unreasonable searches and seizures, all may vary depending on whether or not religious<br />

conduct and institutions are being burdened. That cannot be right. <strong>The</strong>re is an equality dimension to liberty<br />

rights. Part <strong>of</strong> the core idea <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights is that all citizens have an equal right to exercise<br />

them. <strong>Religious</strong> people do not get special treatment with regard to these basic freedoms. No one does.<br />

<strong>The</strong> strongest case against the use <strong>of</strong> a hybrid rights analysis involves freedom <strong>of</strong> speech. If a content-neutral<br />

speech regulation restricts religious speech, or religiously-motivated speech, and the court applies strict scrutiny<br />

to the law under a hybrid rights analysis, then religious speech will receive more stringent protection than<br />

secular speech whenever time, place, and manner rules are at issue. Many restrictions on speech that would be<br />

upheld under the intermediate level review applied when secular speech is burdened will be invalidated under<br />

the strict scrutiny standard that hybrid rights analysis requires when religious speech is at issue. <strong>Religious</strong> leaflets,<br />

picketing, and signs may be allowed when secular leaflets, picketing, and signs are prohibited. Viewpoint<br />

discrimination in favor <strong>of</strong> religious speech would be built into the very structure <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment. This<br />

result is unacceptable. [FN250]<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with speech may be the most obvious obstacle to a hybrid-rights approach, but the difficulty<br />

with this idea goes deeper and pervades more rights than freedom <strong>of</strong> speech or the right to vote, which have obvious<br />

equality dimensions. Fundamental rights are the *193 entitlements <strong>of</strong> citizenship. <strong>The</strong>y are imbued with<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> individual dignity. Of all areas touched by law, it should be the hardest to justify different treatment<br />

here. If the idea that citizens are <strong>of</strong> equal worth does not mandate equal respect with regard to the exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

fundamental rights, what other meaning does it have in our constitutional framework?<br />

B. Individualized Exemptions<br />

Just as the exception in Smith for hybrid rights was created to avoid overruling Yoder, the exception for individualized<br />

exemptions was developed to avoid overruling the Court's other seminal free exercise precedent,<br />

Sherbert, [FN251] and subsequent unemployment compensation cases applying Sherbert's reasoning. [FN252]<br />

As the Court's revisionist history in Smith put it, these cases did not hold that neutral laws <strong>of</strong> generally applicability<br />

that substantially burden the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion must be justified under strict scrutiny. Rather, “our decisions<br />

in the unemployment cases stand for the proposition that where the State has in place a system <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

exemptions, it may not refuse to extend that system to cases <strong>of</strong> ‘religious hardship’ without compelling<br />

reason.” [FN253]<br />

Unlike the hybrid-rights exception, there is a core <strong>of</strong> coherence to this exception. First, it is clearly consistent<br />

with Smith to review the administration <strong>of</strong> a facially neutral law <strong>of</strong> general applicability under strict scrutiny<br />

if the law as enforced discriminates against religious practices. An <strong>of</strong>ficial or commission that accepts a range<br />

<strong>of</strong> requests for exemptions from the rigors <strong>of</strong> a law grounded on secular concerns, but refuses to accept any similar<br />

requests for exemption based on religious hardship, is engaged in the same kind <strong>of</strong> discrimination on a caseby-case<br />

basis that the legislature engages in, in the aggregate, when it discriminates against religious practices<br />

on the face <strong>of</strong> the law. Both kinds <strong>of</strong> decisions should be strictly scrutinized and struck down as unconstitutional.<br />

<strong>The</strong> individualized exemption exception also is arguably coherent, even when it does not involve overt discrimination<br />

against religion, if it is limited to those situations where the state provides the <strong>of</strong>ficials, charged with<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 37<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

administering and enforcing a law, with substantially *194 unguided discretion in determining how and against<br />

whom the law will be enforced. <strong>The</strong> problem here is similar to that which arises under free speech doctrine when<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials are granted unbridled discretion in licensing, or granting permits for, expressive activity. <strong>The</strong> risk <strong>of</strong> bias<br />

is sufficiently high, and the effectiveness <strong>of</strong> after-the-fact review sufficiently low except in the most egregious<br />

cases, that a prophylactic rule is necessary. Accordingly, it may make sense to inform <strong>of</strong>ficials, granted<br />

generally unfettered authority, that they will be required to justify their decisions that substantially burden the<br />

practice <strong>of</strong> religion under some level <strong>of</strong> rigorous review.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with understanding the individualized assessment exception in the limited sense <strong>of</strong> the two examples<br />

described above is obvious. It is an extremely narrow and generally unhelpful exception if these are its<br />

parameters. Few statutory frameworks will satisfy its requirements. Accordingly, some commentators have attempted<br />

to read the individualized assessment exception in Smith far more broadly. <strong>The</strong>y argue that the focus <strong>of</strong><br />

the individualized assessment exception is not so much on a state <strong>of</strong>ficial's or commission's exercise <strong>of</strong> unfettered<br />

discretion in deciding whether or not to grant exemptions, but rather on the state's under-inclusive refusal<br />

to extend the exemptions granted to secular interests to religious claims for accommodation. <strong>The</strong> genesis <strong>of</strong><br />

this contention is not always clearly identified. Sometimes it appears to be grounded directly on the individualized<br />

assessment exception in Smith. Alternatively, it is based on a definition <strong>of</strong> general applicability suggesting<br />

that under-inclusive laws fall outside the scope <strong>of</strong> those neutral and generally applicable laws to which the Smith<br />

holding applies. [FN254]<br />

*195 In either case, it is argued that any legislation which contains at least one secular exemption or a pattern<br />

<strong>of</strong> secular exemptions must also provide for religious exemptions--unless the state has a compelling interest<br />

in rejecting the religious exemption that cannot be adequately furthered in any other way. [FN255] Under the<br />

strongest version <strong>of</strong> this analysis, it does not matter that the state has also rejected numerous secular requests, so<br />

that the denial <strong>of</strong> a request for a religious exemption cannot be considered discriminatory. All statutory frameworks,<br />

which include exemptions, receive heightened review whether they are discriminatory or not. Religion is<br />

granted something like most favored nation status. If any secular interest can justify an exemption from a law,<br />

then the state must recognize that religious interests also deserve to be exempt from the law. [FN256]<br />

Eugene Volokh has raised several serious challenges to this expansive understanding <strong>of</strong> the individualized<br />

exemption exception in Smith. An extraordinary range <strong>of</strong> laws contain exemptions to their application including<br />

most civil rights laws, contract law, trespass law, copyright law, and even homicide statutes. <strong>The</strong> extraordinary<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> reading the Smith exception this way militates against such an understanding. Moreover, the mere existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> some secular exemptions does not explain why religious exemptions must also be recognized. Laws<br />

protecting private rights are complex generalizations that may cover a range <strong>of</strong> circumstances, including a significant<br />

number where countervailing interests are particularly strong, where the purpose <strong>of</strong> the law is especially<br />

weak, and where other checks or laws make the enforcement <strong>of</strong> the law less necessary. This legislative reality,<br />

standing alone, does not justify the provision <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions in every *196 case where a law contains a<br />

secular exemption. [FN257] <strong>The</strong>re is nothing about the existence <strong>of</strong> secular exemptions that demonstrates why<br />

laws containing them should be treated differently than laws that lack exemptions under the theory and reasoning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Smith decision.<br />

Richard Duncan has thoughtfully responded to Volokh's arguments in a recent article. [FN258] Citing language<br />

in the Court's Lukumi decision for support, [FN259] Duncan argues that a law substantially burdening the<br />

exercise <strong>of</strong> religion is not a law <strong>of</strong> general applicability for free exercise purposes if it is unacceptably underinclusive<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the exemptions it contains. Accordingly, such a law must receive strict scrutiny review.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 38<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Duncan explains,<br />

In order to determine if a law restricting religious exercise is underinclusive, one must ask two questions.<br />

First, what governmental purposes are being served by the restrictive law at issue? Second, does<br />

the law exempt or otherwise leave unrestricted secular conduct that endangers those governmental purposes<br />

in a similar or greater degree than the prohibited or restricted conduct <strong>of</strong> the party seeking the protection<br />

<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause? In other words, a law burdening religious conduct is underinclusive,<br />

with respect to any particular government interest, if the law fails to pursue that interest uniformly against<br />

other conduct that causes similar damage to that government interest. [FN260]<br />

Duncan cites a few recent lower court decisions to support his thesis. [FN261] Probably the most salient precedent<br />

is Fraternal Order <strong>of</strong> Police v. Newark, [FN262] a Third Circuit case. <strong>The</strong> Newark Police Department adopted<br />

a rule prohibiting police <strong>of</strong>ficers from wearing beards. But there were two exceptions. Undercover <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

and <strong>of</strong>ficers for whom daily shaving caused medical problems did not have to comply with this grooming standard.<br />

Two Muslim <strong>of</strong>ficers, whose religious beliefs *197 required them to grow beards, brought a free exercise<br />

claim against the Department when they were denied an exemption from the policy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Third Circuit ruled in favor <strong>of</strong> the religious claimants. <strong>The</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> the regulation was to achieve<br />

uniformity <strong>of</strong> appearance among police <strong>of</strong>ficers. <strong>The</strong> exemption for undercover <strong>of</strong>ficers did not make the law<br />

underinclusive because the Department has no interest in maintaining uniformity <strong>of</strong> appearance among undercover<br />

agents whose identity as police <strong>of</strong>ficers was to be kept secret. Also, such uniformity would be inconsistent<br />

with the roles they are being asked to play and would interfere with their ability to perform their duties. <strong>The</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> the medical exemption, however, undermined the general applicability <strong>of</strong> the regulation because it<br />

subordinated the Department's uniform appearance goal in circumstances where that objective clearly applied.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Department may have reasonably believed that medical concerns justified such an exemption, but<br />

once it made that value judgment, it should have extended the exemption to cover religious concerns as<br />

well. <strong>The</strong> failure to do so rendered the regulation underinclusive and subjected it to strict scrutiny review.<br />

[FN263]<br />

In addition to citing relevant authority, Duncan responds directly to Volokh's arguments. <strong>The</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individualized exemption exception will not be as broad and problematic as Volokh suggests if the most favored<br />

nation analogy for religion is accepted. First, extraordinary and inconsequential exceptions just do not<br />

count. Thus, Volokh's argument that there is an exception to state trespass laws for necessity situations, for example,<br />

is irrelevant because it is so unusual and so seldom applied. [FN264] Second, a secular exemption makes<br />

a law underinclusive only when the exemption is inconsistent with the law's purpose. Thus, an exception to a<br />

law prohibiting smoking marijuana for the medical use <strong>of</strong> marijuana does not make the law underinclusive if the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> the law is to promote the state's public health goals. Since the medical marijuana exception only allows<br />

an individual to smoke marijuana when the medical utility <strong>of</strong> the drug outweighs its harmful effects, the<br />

exception is consistent with and furthers the uniform achievement <strong>of</strong> the state's health goals. [FN265]<br />

Nor would the analysis change if the state's prohibition against smoking marijuana served multiple purposes;<br />

a public health goal and *198 the goal <strong>of</strong> avoiding harm to innocent third parties, such as injuries resulting from<br />

auto accidents that might occur if people smoked marijuana before driving. A law is generally applicable and not<br />

underinclusive for free exercise purposes “so long as the law addresses at least one legitimate governmental purpose<br />

and is not underinclusive with respect to that purpose.” [FN266] Since the medical marijuana exception is<br />

not underinclusive with regard to the state's public health goals, it does not matter that it is underinclusive with<br />

regard to other state interests furthered by the general prohibition against smoking marijuana. [FN267]<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 39<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Since Duncan's approach is far more limited than the more expansive version <strong>of</strong> this argument that requires<br />

strict scrutiny review <strong>of</strong> any law containing a secular exemption that substantially burdens the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion,<br />

it avoids some <strong>of</strong> the practical difficulties cited in Volokh's critique. Further, Duncan argues this modified<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> the Smith exception is grounded on conventional constitutional foundations.<br />

[<strong>The</strong>] underinclusion test can also be understood as harmonizing free exercise doctrine with the<br />

Court's equal protection analysis concerning legislative classifications that unequally burden fundamental<br />

rights. In Lukumi, the Court interpreted the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause as requiring the same strict scrutiny<br />

standard for underinclusive laws burdening religion that the fundamental rights/equal protection doctrine<br />

mandates for “underinclusive government action that burdens the right to procreation, the right to travel,<br />

and other fundamental constitutional rights.” [FN268]<br />

I certainly sympathize with the efforts <strong>of</strong> commentators such as Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Duncan who struggle to salvage<br />

something <strong>of</strong> free exercise value from the wreckage left by the Smith decision. As a litigator I would use these<br />

arguments. Until they are directly repudiated by the Court, they are legitimate interpretations <strong>of</strong> Smith and<br />

Lukumi, both <strong>of</strong> which *199 are far from clear as to the meaning <strong>of</strong> general applicability and the individualized<br />

exemptions exception. Still, as a long-term proposition, I think this approach to free exercise rights cannot stand.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are too many conceptual and practical problems with the analysis for it to be accepted.<br />

To begin with, at the most abstract level, there is a strange incongruity between the individualized decisionmaking<br />

exception, particularly its expansion to include laws containing categorical exemptions, and the hybridrights<br />

exception in Smith. <strong>The</strong> individualized decisionmaking, categorical exemption exception is grounded on<br />

the principle that the state should not discriminate with regard to the exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights. Thus, religious<br />

conduct should not be denied exemptions from laws when the state accommodates secular needs burdened<br />

by the same statute. But the hybrid-rights exception points in exactly the opposite direction. It requires treating<br />

religious people differently with regard to the exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights by giving them preferential treatment.<br />

It seems strange that these two exceptions in Smith should be so fundamentally inconsistent with each<br />

other.<br />

More specifically, even without this inconsistency, the very foundation for the most favored nation framework<br />

is intellectually incoherent. Under Smith, the right to engage in religious practices is subordinate to any<br />

single legitimate state interest advanced by a unitary statute. If that is so, why are religious practices not equally<br />

subordinate to two or more legitimate state interests that are reconciled in a single statute through the use <strong>of</strong> exemptions?<br />

Consider the regulations at issue in the Newark Police Department case as an example. One goal <strong>of</strong><br />

the Department is to promote the uniform appearance <strong>of</strong> its <strong>of</strong>ficers. Pursuant to that objective, standing alone<br />

and without exemptions, a regulation requiring all <strong>of</strong>ficers to be clean shaven will be upheld even when it is applied<br />

to police <strong>of</strong>ficers whose religious obligations prohibit them from shaving.<br />

Now assume that the Police Department asserts an interest in the medical health <strong>of</strong> its <strong>of</strong>ficers. Healthy <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

are more likely to be available for duty and perform at a higher level <strong>of</strong> efficiency. This interest could<br />

also justify interference with religious obligations. Thus, standing alone and without exemptions, a regulation<br />

prohibiting <strong>of</strong>ficers from engaging in cosmetic practices that resulted in adverse medical consequences would be<br />

upheld even when it was applied to <strong>of</strong>ficers whose cosmetic practices were religiously mandated. If shaving<br />

*200 resulted in adverse medical consequences for certain <strong>of</strong>ficers, the Department could prohibit them from<br />

shaving, even if the <strong>of</strong>ficers' religious obligations required them to be clean-shaven.<br />

Finally, assume the Police Department asserts it is trying to accommodate both <strong>of</strong> its goals, maintaining a<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 40<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

uniform appearance and promoting the medical health <strong>of</strong> its <strong>of</strong>ficers, by creating an exception from the requirement<br />

that <strong>of</strong>ficers must be clean-shaven for those few <strong>of</strong>ficers for whom such a requirement would be medically<br />

problematic. It is true that medical concerns outweigh religious obligations under this regulatory scheme, but<br />

they would be allowed to do so standing alone in any case. It is hard to understand why the merging <strong>of</strong> two state<br />

interests, each <strong>of</strong> which is independently sufficient to justify the burdening <strong>of</strong> religious practices, must be subordinated<br />

to religious needs and interests under strict scrutiny review.<br />

One response to this argument is that it miscasts the exception the Police Department provides to <strong>of</strong>ficers<br />

who have a medical condition that prevents them from shaving. This exception is not intended to further any departmental<br />

interests. Rather, it is for the private benefit <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>ficers themselves. <strong>The</strong> problem with this argument<br />

is that it is extremely difficult to distinguish between private and public interests in most circumstances.<br />

More <strong>of</strong>ten than not, the state can easily identify some public goal that is advanced by exempting a<br />

private interest from a regulatory burden.<br />

This brings us to the second problem with the modified most favored nation framework advanced by Duncan<br />

and others. This approach really requires double standards <strong>of</strong> review if it is to be effective. Duncan concedes<br />

that his rule requiring the rigorous review <strong>of</strong> the denial <strong>of</strong> religious exemptions will not apply when there is at<br />

least one legitimate state interest as to which the law at issue is not underinclusive. But the only way to prevent<br />

this modification from creating a doctrinal escape hatch a truck could drive through is to apply some reasonably<br />

rigorous standard <strong>of</strong> review to whatever purposes the state asserts are being furthered by the challenged<br />

law. Otherwise the state will always be able to come up with some rational purpose that is allegedly furthered<br />

by the law that is not underinclusive.<br />

Consider an example Duncan uses <strong>of</strong> a law permitting the recreational use <strong>of</strong> marijuana at rock concerts.<br />

Smoking marijuana is prohibited on all other occasions - including its use during religious ceremonies.<br />

Duncan argues that the secular exception for rock concerts makes the law underinclusive and this underinclusivity<br />

*201 requires rigorous review <strong>of</strong> the application <strong>of</strong> the law to religious ceremonies. [FN269]<br />

But does the exception for rock concerts really make the generic marijuana prohibition underinclusive? To<br />

answer that question we have to evaluate the state's asserted purpose for prohibiting marijuana use. Assume that<br />

the state claims that one <strong>of</strong> its legitimate goals in prohibiting the use <strong>of</strong> marijuana is to further the public safety<br />

goal <strong>of</strong> limiting the risk <strong>of</strong> injuries to innocent third parties who are not smoking marijuana themselves but who<br />

might be harmed, directly or indirectly, by people who do. That goal is furthered by generally prohibiting the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> marijuana. <strong>The</strong> state claims it is also furthered by an exemption for smoking marijuana during rock concerts<br />

because the state believes significant civil unrest may occur if police attempt to enforce marijuana laws at<br />

rock concerts where thousands <strong>of</strong> hyperactive teenagers are in attendance. Since the state believes civil unrest is<br />

far less likely when laws are enforced against religious practitioners, its law and exception are not underinclusive<br />

with regard to this public safety objective.<br />

I am not suggesting that this is a terribly persuasive explanation for the above law and exemption. <strong>The</strong> point<br />

is that it does not have to be very persuasive unless we are going to subject the state's asserted purpose to some<br />

serious level <strong>of</strong> review. Thus, we need to apply some rigorous standard <strong>of</strong> review to the state's asserted purposes,<br />

first. <strong>The</strong>n, if can reject enough <strong>of</strong> them so that the only ones left are underinclusive, we would apply<br />

strict scrutiny to the law. That is a double standard <strong>of</strong> review.<br />

Of course, after we reject the state's asserted purposes under our first standard <strong>of</strong> review and conclude that<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 41<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

the law is underinclusive, there may not be all that much work left for the second step <strong>of</strong> strict scrutiny review.<br />

But that conclusion simply demonstrates that the modified most favored nation framework really isn't<br />

modified at all. It requires the application <strong>of</strong> rigorous review to all laws with secular exemptions because that is<br />

the only way we can determine whether or not the law is underinclusive with regard to its stated purposes in<br />

some meaningful way. Alternatively, it would allow all laws with secular exemptions to escape heightened<br />

scrutiny because we would accept any and all conceivably rational purposes the state asserts to justify a challenged<br />

law *202 and, almost certainly, the law will not be underinclusive for at least one <strong>of</strong> those purposes.<br />

A third problem relates to the proposed limit for exemptions that are too extraordinary or inconsequential to<br />

be counted as making a law underinclusive for constitutional purposes. This is an extremely vague and indeterminate<br />

standard. Duncan suggests that the necessity privilege that may be asserted in defense <strong>of</strong> trespass actions<br />

falls into this category. [FN270] But private necessity is really nothing more than a private health and<br />

safety exception. Trespass will be permitted if it is necessary to protect the trespasser's health or safety. [FN271]<br />

It is not clear why this is any different from the medical exception to the Newark Police Department's shaving<br />

requirement. Certainly, that health exception refers to a relatively small class <strong>of</strong> individuals and circumstances<br />

as well.<br />

Finally, the most favored nation approach is not even true to the principle on which it is based. Far from<br />

preventing laws from unequally burdening the exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights, this framework virtually guarantees<br />

such results. Suppose in the Newark case, there are two separate grooming standards, one relating to shaving,<br />

the other to hair length. Muslims protest the shaving requirement. Native Americans protest the hair length<br />

requirement. [FN272] Both protests are based on religious grounds. <strong>The</strong>re is a medical exemption from the shaving<br />

requirement, but there is no exemption from the hair length requirement because there are no medical conditions<br />

that preclude cutting one's hair. Accordingly, the shaving requirement is reviewed and struck down under<br />

strict scrutiny, while the hair length requirement is upheld under rational basis review. <strong>The</strong> basis for these dramatically<br />

different constitutional evaluations and results is the fortuity that shaving occasionally causes medical<br />

problems, and haircuts do not. [FN273]<br />

*203 A similar argument could be made with regard to prohibitions on the use <strong>of</strong> wine, marijuana, and<br />

peyote. If there is a medical use for marijuana, but not one for wine or peyote, the standard <strong>of</strong> review applied to<br />

the marijuana prohibition will be much more rigorous than that applied to the wine or peyote restrictions.<br />

[FN274] Since these substances are used by different religions, some faiths will get more protection for their<br />

practices than others because <strong>of</strong> the fortuity that their sacred objects have valuable nonreligious uses which result<br />

in the granting <strong>of</strong> a secular exemption, while the sacred or ceremonial objects <strong>of</strong> other faiths have only religious<br />

utility, so that no secular exemptions are granted for their use.<br />

C. <strong>The</strong> Review <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> Exemptions<br />

<strong>The</strong> final vehicle for avoiding the rigor and injustice intrinsic to the regime <strong>of</strong> formal neutrality endorsed by<br />

Smith is political accommodation. <strong>The</strong> political branches <strong>of</strong> government, not the judiciary, can create exemptions<br />

from neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability for religious practices and institutions. Leaving aside the obvious<br />

practical question <strong>of</strong> whether the government will actually deign to adopt such exemptions, there is the more<br />

analytically complex question <strong>of</strong> how courts are to review the purpose, effect, and scope <strong>of</strong> such accommodations.<br />

In particular, how can we avoid empowering government to pick and choose among favored and disfavored<br />

faiths, exempting certain religions but not others from specific laws?<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 42<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

<strong>The</strong> case law in this area provides grossly inconsistent and ambiguous guidance on this question. In Gillette<br />

v. United States, [FN275] the Court rejected claims <strong>of</strong> religious discrimination brought by religious individuals<br />

who were conscientiously opposed to particular wars but could not fit within the selective service exemption<br />

from conscription *204 for those who objected to all wars. <strong>The</strong> Court recognized that the line drawn by the state<br />

resulted in de facto discrimination since it coincided with distinct religious traditions. Some pacifist sects objected<br />

to all wars, while other faiths distinguished between “just” and “unjust” wars. [FN276] Nonetheless, the government's<br />

conscientious objector criteria was upheld because “a claimant alleging [religious] ‘gerrymander’<br />

must be able to show the absence <strong>of</strong> a neutral, secular basis for the lines government has drawn.” [FN277] Here,<br />

secular grounds for limiting the scope <strong>of</strong> the exemption to those who objected to all wars existed, including the<br />

difficulty <strong>of</strong> fairly implementing and policing a system that permitted exemptions based on objections to particular<br />

wars.<br />

<strong>The</strong> difficulty with this analysis is the ostensibly low standard <strong>of</strong> review it applies to religious exemptions<br />

that result in de facto discrimination among sects. <strong>The</strong> requirement that claimants must show the absence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

neutral, secular basis for the lines the government has drawn seems uncomfortably close to the conventional understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> rational basis review, which places the burden on claimants “to negative every conceivable basis<br />

which might support” a challenged law. [FN278] If the burden <strong>of</strong> justification on the government is this low and<br />

the showing required <strong>of</strong> claimants is so difficult to achieve, government has virtually total discretion to pick and<br />

choose among the faiths it will exempt from general regulations.<br />

Other cases suggest that underinclusive exemptions among religious faiths may receive more careful review,<br />

but <strong>of</strong>ten either the nature <strong>of</strong> that review or the conditions that invoke it are unclear. In Estate <strong>of</strong> Thornton v.<br />

Caldor, [FN279] the Court struck down a Connecticut law requiring employers to recognize the right <strong>of</strong> any employee<br />

not to work on a day he designated as his Sabbath. <strong>The</strong> law in Caldor is not technically an exemption<br />

since it protects religious individuals against private interference with their faith rather than relieving them <strong>of</strong><br />

government imposed burdens. Still, the reason the law was found to violate the Establishment Clause would<br />

seem applicable to narrow religious exemptions as well. As Justice O'Connor explained in her concurring opinion,<br />

the problem with this statute was that it “singles out Sabbath *205 observers for special and, as the Court<br />

concludes, absolute protection without according similar accommodation to ethical and religious beliefs and<br />

practices <strong>of</strong> other private employees.” [FN280]<br />

It remains unclear, however, why this discrimination should be viewed as qualitatively different from the<br />

discrimination upheld in Gillette. Not all faiths observe a Sabbath, but not all faiths object to all wars. In both<br />

cases, benefits are predictably provided to certain religious groups and not to others. Further, while the ability<br />

to choose one's day <strong>of</strong>f is certainly a valuable right that many employees, religious or not, would desire and<br />

prize, it is hardly clear that it is <strong>of</strong> greater utility and desirability than the right not to be drafted. Certainly,<br />

those who cannot take advantage <strong>of</strong> the exemption from conscription may incur far greater personal loss and injury<br />

than employees denied the opportunity to have weekend days <strong>of</strong>f from work.<br />

Perhaps the most emphatic case challenging the legislature's discretion to pick and choose the religious<br />

groups it will include within a regulatory exemption is Larson v. Valente, [FN281] a case that is <strong>of</strong>ten cited for<br />

its ringing declaration that “the clearest command <strong>of</strong> the Establishment Clause is that one religious denomination<br />

cannot be <strong>of</strong>ficially preferred over another.” [FN282] Larson obviously is an exemption case. It reviews a<br />

Minnesota law that exempts religious organizations from certain registration requirements imposed on groups<br />

engaged in charitable solicitations, but only if the religious entity received at least half <strong>of</strong> its contributions from<br />

members or affiliated organizations. Further, the law is struck down on the grounds that it “grants denomination-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 43<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

al preferences” to certain faiths but not to others. [FN283] What is missing is any intelligible explanation <strong>of</strong> why<br />

the discrimination in this case violates the Constitution, but the discrimination evaluated in other cases like Gillette<br />

does not.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court concedes that a facially neutral law is not unconstitutional simply because the secular criteria it<br />

employs disparately impact some religions more than others. Yet, the Court insists that the Minnesota registration<br />

exemption is not such a law because it “makes explicit and deliberate distinctions between different religious<br />

organizations.” [FN284] In *206 the very next sentence, however, the Court suggests that the registration<br />

law “effectively” [FN285] distinguishes between well established churches that can rely on member contributions<br />

for support and new churches that either need public support or seek such support as a matter <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

policy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court never explains how a law that “effectively” distinguishes between faiths is different from a law<br />

that disparately impacts different faiths. Nor does the Court effectively respond to Justice White's characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> its contention, that the law discriminates on its face, as patently wrong. In White's words,<br />

<strong>The</strong> rule itself . . . names no churches or denominations that are entitled to or denied the exemption.<br />

It neither qualifies nor disqualifies a church based on the kind or variety <strong>of</strong> its religious belief.<br />

Some religions will qualify and some will not, but this depends on the source <strong>of</strong> their contributions,<br />

not on their brand <strong>of</strong> religion. [FN286]<br />

<strong>The</strong> Court's attempt to distinguish Gillette is also unpersuasive. <strong>The</strong> majority explains that the distinction<br />

drawn by the conscientious objector laws between objections to all wars and those only to unjust wars “does not<br />

discriminate on the basis <strong>of</strong> religious affiliation.” [FN287] That is true if it refers to the fact that no religious denomination<br />

is singled out by name in the federal exemption. But that is also true for the Minnesota exemption.<br />

<strong>The</strong> conscientious objector exemption's coverage does correlate with and distinguish between faiths in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

their religious tenets. Why is the Minnesota law that distinguishes between faiths that are doctrinally committed<br />

to seeking public support and those that are not any different?<br />

<strong>The</strong> majority also suggests that the Minnesota law is problematic because it “focuses precisely and solely<br />

upon religious organizations.” [FN288] That is also true, but it is not clear why it is relevant, much less controlling.<br />

Is the distinction between individuals and organizations paramount? If that is the determining factor,<br />

does that mean a law distinguishing between pacifist religious organizations that objected to *207 all wars and<br />

religious organizations that only condemned unjust wars would be reviewed under strict scrutiny following Larson<br />

rather than the much less demanding scrutiny provided in Gillette? Or is the fact that the exemption in the<br />

Minnesota law is reserved exclusively for religious organizations the critical variable? It is true that after Welch<br />

and Seeger, [FN289] conscientious objector exemptions extend beyond religious beliefs and are available to secular<br />

pacifists as well. As I will suggest shortly, there is a doctrinal foundation for this kind <strong>of</strong> argument, but<br />

nothing in Larson supports it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> final explanation for the Court's decision in Larson is grounded on the legislative history underlying the<br />

Act. <strong>The</strong> law was apparently tailored to avoid its application to the Roman Catholic Church. Further, the statements<br />

<strong>of</strong> several legislators suggested a deliberate intent to target the Unification Church and treat it differently<br />

from other religious groups. [FN290] Leaving aside the conventional concerns that are typically raised against<br />

relying on direct pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> invidious intent to determine the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> laws, [FN291] there is the added<br />

question <strong>of</strong> what constitutes an invidious motive in this circumstance. Is the intent to relieve a particular religious<br />

group <strong>of</strong> a regulatory burden also problematic? What if the scope <strong>of</strong> the exemption is tailored using neut-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 44<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ral language to exclude particular religions from its protection because the practices <strong>of</strong> those faiths directly implicate<br />

the problem the state is attempting to resolve? Larson provides no answers to the numerous questions it<br />

raises.<br />

<strong>The</strong> most recent and contentious Supreme Court decision striking down a religious accommodation is Board<br />

<strong>of</strong> Education <strong>of</strong> Kiryas Joel Village School District v. Grumet. [FN292] Here, the Court struck down New York<br />

legislation which constituted as a separate school district the village <strong>of</strong> Kiryas Joel, a community populated by<br />

Satmar Hasidim, members <strong>of</strong> a small, very traditional, Jewish sect, whose beliefs conflict with many <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mores <strong>of</strong> contemporary American culture. <strong>The</strong> goal <strong>of</strong> this unusual legislative decision was to enable Satmar<br />

children with special educational needs to receive remedial services to which they were entitled under federal<br />

law without having to attend school outside <strong>of</strong> their home community. While New York's action is similar to the<br />

law *208 struck down in Thornton v. Caldor, in that it does not technically relieve religious individuals or institutions<br />

from a regulatory burden, the Court's grounds for rejecting this accommodation seem directly applicable<br />

to legislative exemptions, as well. New York's creation <strong>of</strong> a separate school district for this Hasidic community<br />

violated the Establishment Clause because it “single[d] out a particular religious sect for special treatment.”<br />

[FN293]<br />

Justice O'Connor's explanation for the Court's decision is probably the clearest statement <strong>of</strong> the issue, although<br />

it is expressed in a concurring opinion:<br />

On its face, this statute benefits one group--the residents <strong>of</strong> Kiryas Joel. Because this benefit was<br />

given to this group based on its religion, it seems proper to treat it as a legislatively drawn religious classification.<br />

I realize that this is a close question, because the Satmars may be the only group who currently<br />

need this particular accommodation. <strong>The</strong> legislature may well be acting without any favoritism, so that if<br />

another group came to ask for a similar district, the group might get it on the same terms as the Satmars.<br />

But the nature <strong>of</strong> the legislative process makes it impossible to be sure <strong>of</strong> this. A legislature, unlike<br />

the judiciary or many administrative decisionmakers, has no obligation to respond to any group's requests.<br />

A group petitioning for a law may never get a definite response, or may get a “no” based not on<br />

the merits but on the press <strong>of</strong> other business or the lack <strong>of</strong> an influential sponsor. Such a legislative refusal<br />

to act would not normally be reviewable by a court. Under these circumstances, it seems dangerous to<br />

validate what appears to me a clear religious preference. [FN294]<br />

Once again, it is hard to know the parameters <strong>of</strong> the rule or standard suggested by this analysis. <strong>The</strong> Satmar<br />

Hasidim are the only beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> the legislature's decision in this case. But this is hardly uncommon when<br />

legislatures create religious exemptions from *209 regulatory statutes. Often a particular faith or groups <strong>of</strong> faiths<br />

is burdened by the law, citizens <strong>of</strong> that faith are the political force the legislature responds to when it creates an<br />

exemption, and even a neutrally drawn exemption will primarily benefit a limited class <strong>of</strong> religions or sometimes<br />

only one. Sometimes other faiths will seek similar exemptions at a later time. If those exemptions are rejected,<br />

should the legislature's refusal to extend the exemption receive strict scrutiny? [FN295] Alternatively, are<br />

exemptions that fail to include all religious faiths potentially burdened by a law always and immediately subject<br />

to rigorous review? If not, how are these situations different from the accommodation struck down in Kiryas<br />

Joel?<br />

Not surprisingly, lower court judges and decisions are in complete disarray when issues relating to the scope<br />

and nature <strong>of</strong> exemptions and accommodations arise. In Grumet v. Pataki, [FN296] by a 4- 3 vote over a strong<br />

dissent, the New York Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals rejected the State's third attempt to allow Kiryas Joel to create its own<br />

school district, despite a concerted effort by the legislature to craft a more neutral and general framework for ac-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 45<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

commodation. <strong>The</strong> Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals ruled that the framework for creating new school districts was still too narrow<br />

in scope and unconstitutionally favored a particular faith. Conversely, in Stark v. Independent School District,<br />

[FN297] by a 2-1 vote over a strong dissent, the Eighth Circuit upheld a School District's arrangement with<br />

a small, religious group, the Brethren. <strong>The</strong> arrangement enabled religious parents to send their children to a public<br />

school containing one multi-age classroom (opened in a building owned by the religious group) that conformed,<br />

where practical, to the group's religious tenets opposing the use <strong>of</strong> educational technology such as computers.<br />

This unique arrangement with a particular religious faith was not found to constitute an unconstitutional<br />

preference. In Children's Healthcare is a Legal Duty, *210 Inc. v. Min De Parle, [FN298] a different divided<br />

Eighth Circuit panel, over a strong dissent, upheld provisions in the federal Medicare and Medicaid Acts that<br />

provided non-medical benefits to patients treated in “religious nonmedical health care facilities” against an Establishment<br />

Clause challenge. Claimants argued unsuccessfully that, notwithstanding the neutral language in the<br />

statute, the intent and effect <strong>of</strong> the legislation was to provide support almost exclusively to Christian Scientist<br />

sanitoria. Citing Gillette, the court held that the fact that the provisions predictably and almost exclusively benefited<br />

the facilities <strong>of</strong> a single faith did not render them unconstitutional as long as the criteria employed by the<br />

statute “reflect [ed] valid secular justifications.” [FN299]<br />

While many <strong>of</strong> these decisions involve divided courts, consensus among the members <strong>of</strong> a reviewing court<br />

does not necessarily suggest that the resolution <strong>of</strong> the issue is persuasive. In Catholic Charities, [FN300] a case<br />

now before the California Supreme Court, a unanimous Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals had little difficulty upholding one <strong>of</strong><br />

the most narrow and arguably irrational religious exemptions ever enacted. <strong>The</strong> state legislature enacted a law<br />

requiring employers that provided their employees health insurance coverage with prescription drug benefits to<br />

include prescription contraceptives in the insurance plan. Not surprisingly, Catholic organizations protested that<br />

this mandate violated Catholic religious tenets and asked for a religious exemption from the law's requirements.<br />

In response, the legislature adopted a conscience clause that applied only to religious employers satisfying the<br />

following criteria: (A) <strong>The</strong> inculcation <strong>of</strong> religious values is the purpose <strong>of</strong> the entity; (B) <strong>The</strong> entity primarily<br />

employs persons who share the religious tenets <strong>of</strong> the entity; (C) <strong>The</strong> entity serves primarily persons who share<br />

the religious tenets <strong>of</strong> the entity; (D) <strong>The</strong> entity is a nonpr<strong>of</strong>it organization pursuant to Section 6033(a)(2)(A)(i)<br />

or (iii) <strong>of</strong> the Internal Revenue Code. [FN301]<br />

On its face and in context, this conscience clause makes no sense. Since Catholic charitable organizations<br />

do not proselytize and do not discriminate on the basis <strong>of</strong> religion in hiring or in the provision <strong>of</strong> *211 services,<br />

the terms <strong>of</strong> the exemption do not apply to the very religious group that requested it. Nor is it easy to understand<br />

why religious organizations that neither discriminate nor proselytize should be exposed to regulatory burdens<br />

that other religious organizations that do discriminate and proselytize need not obey. [FN302] <strong>Religious</strong> discrimination<br />

and proselytizing <strong>of</strong> clients may be permitted in the name <strong>of</strong> religious liberty, but surely discrimination<br />

and proselytizing are not preferred approaches for providing charity. Finally, the scope <strong>of</strong> the conscience clause<br />

is so narrow that a missionary organization that hires only adherents <strong>of</strong> the faith it espouses and has as its<br />

primary purpose the proselytizing <strong>of</strong> non-believers would not be exempt under the clause, because the entity<br />

would not primarily serve persons who share its religious tenets.<br />

Yet, the Court <strong>of</strong> Appeals had no difficulty in upholding the conscience clause against constitutional challenge.<br />

Even if the narrowly drawn conscience clause had the disparate impact <strong>of</strong> excluding Catholic organizations,<br />

the court explained, the clause was constitutional if it was neutral and generally applicable and reflected<br />

rational secular purposes. [FN303] But the court's justification for its conclusions about neutrality and secular<br />

purposes were extraordinarily conclusory and inadequate. <strong>The</strong> alleged secular purpose <strong>of</strong> the statute and its exemption<br />

was to prevent discrimination against women in employer health insurance plans and to avoid discrim-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 46<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ination among religions. [FN304] But neither <strong>of</strong> these purposes explains why religious employers who proselytize<br />

and discriminate should be treated differently from those who do not. <strong>The</strong> court also suggests that the activities<br />

not covered by the exemption are really secular pursuits. [FN305] But discrimination in hiring and services<br />

and proselytizing are not the hallmarks <strong>of</strong> all religions. <strong>The</strong>se conditions certainly do not represent any rational<br />

demarcation between the religious and the secular, much less a *212 coherent basis for determining whether the<br />

religious integrity <strong>of</strong> institutions warrants protection.<br />

<strong>The</strong> only possibly plausible justification for the narrowness <strong>of</strong> the conscience clause the court suggested is<br />

that by limiting the scope <strong>of</strong> the exemption to employers that discriminate in hiring, the state reduced the likelihood<br />

that employees who disagree with the religious beliefs <strong>of</strong> their employer will lose the benefit <strong>of</strong> the law.<br />

[FN306] But even if this contention justified one <strong>of</strong> the factors required by the conscience clause, it does nothing<br />

to explain or defend the remaining criteria.<br />

<strong>The</strong> difficulty courts experience with this issue may reflect intrinsic problems with legislative exemptions<br />

under the Smith regime. Put simply, courts are placed in an untenable position. Smith eliminates free exercise<br />

protection against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability, but demands strict scrutiny for laws that are neither neutral<br />

nor general. But religious exemptions by definition are neither neutral nor general. <strong>The</strong> exemptions facially<br />

apply only to religious organizations, individuals, and practices. <strong>The</strong>y are directed at religion alone.<br />

Further, to the extent that an exemption applies only to certain beliefs or practices, it is difficult to characterize<br />

it as general in any meaningful sense. An exemption predicated on religious opposition to all wars is not any<br />

more general than an exemption predicated on religious opposition to eating pork. If that is a general exemption,<br />

the term has no meaning in this context.<br />

Certainly, in the Catholic Charities case, it is absurd to describe a law that classifies on the basis <strong>of</strong> a religious<br />

organization's commitment to proselytizing or its willingness to work with non-believers as neutral or general.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se are essentially religious convictions. [FN307] Grounding law on such criteria is inherently discriminatory.<br />

As a matter <strong>of</strong> constitutional policy, it is simply unacceptable to give government the unfettered discretion to<br />

pick and choose which faiths it will relieve from regulatory burdens inconsistent with their religious obligations<br />

and which faiths it will insist must be subject to such mandates. <strong>The</strong> inequality and unfairness <strong>of</strong> such an approach<br />

is obvious. Unpopular faiths can be singled out for burdens by exempting *213 more politically powerful<br />

religions from legal mandates. Yet it is equally implausible to insist that all religious exemptions must be<br />

strictly scrutinized. By their nature, these exemptions will correlate with certain religious tenets more than with<br />

others and, correspondingly, will benefit some faiths more than others. <strong>The</strong> legislature's focus is almost certainly<br />

going to be on particular faiths that bring the conflict between a general law and a particular religion's beliefs<br />

and practices to its attention. [FN308] Requiring uniformity, consistency, and equal treatment for all religious<br />

exemptions may well impose a burden on such provisions that can seldom be satisfied. Certainly, at some point,<br />

legislatures confronted with increasingly onerous litigation, challenging their attempts to exempt religious practices<br />

and institutions from regulatory burdens, will conclude that discretion is the better part <strong>of</strong> valor and increasingly<br />

resist granting any exemptions in the first place. [FN309]<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>Free</strong> speech principles should be utilized as a substitute for <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and Establishment Clause doctrine<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 47<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

only in narrow and limited circumstances. Smith repudiendus est. [FN310]<br />

[FNa1]. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Law, University <strong>of</strong> California, Davis. B.A. 1969, Antioch College: J.D. 1977, Harvard University.<br />

<strong>The</strong> author wishes to thank Vikram Amar and Mary Lederman for reading drafts <strong>of</strong> this article and<br />

providing helpful criticism. I also wish to acknowledge the considerable help I received from my research assistants,<br />

Shawn Jensvold and Melanie Shender.<br />

[FN1]. Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN2]. As Jack Rakove has wisely noted in comparing Madison's and Jefferson's attitudes toward constitutional<br />

interpretation and change,<br />

In the end, it was Jefferson who better grasped the habits <strong>of</strong> democracy, Madison who better understood<br />

its perils. But perhaps Jefferson also saw more clearly than his friend what the experience <strong>of</strong> founding a republic<br />

finally meant, even to the conservative framers themselves. Having learned so much from the experience <strong>of</strong><br />

a mere decade <strong>of</strong> self-government, and having celebrated their own ability to act from “reflection and choice,”<br />

would they not find the idea that later generations could not improve upon their discoveries incredible? How<br />

could those who wrote the Constitution possibly understand its meaning better than those who had the experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> observing and participating in its operation?<br />

Jack N. Rakove, Original Meanings: Politics and Ideas in the making <strong>of</strong> the Constitution 367 (1996).<br />

[FN3]. 494 U.S. 872 (1990).<br />

[FN4]. See Frederick Mark Gedicks, <strong>The</strong> Normalized <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause: Three Abnormalities, 75 Ind. L.J.<br />

77, 80 n.9 (2000) (listing articles critical <strong>of</strong> Smith) [hereinafter Gedicks, Normalized].<br />

[FN5]. See, e.g., Richard F. Duncan, <strong>Free</strong> Exercise is Dead, Long Live <strong>Free</strong> Exercise: Smith, Lukumi and the<br />

General Applicability Requirement, 3 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 850 (2001); Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4; Robert<br />

W. Tuttle, How Firm a Foundation? <strong>Protecting</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> Land Uses After Boerne, 68 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 861<br />

(2000).<br />

[FN6]. See David A. Strauss, Persuasion, Autonomy, and <strong>Free</strong>dom <strong>of</strong> Expression, 91 Colum. L. Rev. 334 (1991)<br />

.<br />

[FN7]. See, e.g., Reuven Hammer, Entering Jewish Prayer: A Guide to Personal Devotion and the Worship Service<br />

3-4 (1994) (explaining that sometimes prayer “is an end in itself [reflecting peoples' desire] to feel close to<br />

God ... to express their feelings, their fears, their hopes ... [and] to celebrate their joys in a way that will deepen<br />

their intensity”).<br />

[FN8]. See, e.g., Hammer, supra note 7, at 15-16 (noting the importance <strong>of</strong> communal prayer in Judaism because<br />

it is “a way <strong>of</strong> strengthening the ties <strong>of</strong> the individual with the Jewish community” and because “sanctifying<br />

God's name is a public act” which requires the presence <strong>of</strong> a minimum number <strong>of</strong> people in attendance).<br />

[FN9]. See, e.g., National Association for the Advancement <strong>of</strong> Psychoanalysis v. California Board <strong>of</strong> Psychology,<br />

228 F. 3d 1043, 1054 (9 th Cir. 2000) (that psychoanalysts employ speech to treat their clients does not entitle<br />

them, or their pr<strong>of</strong>ession, to special First Amendment protection).<br />

[FN10]. 310 U.S. 296 (1940).<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 48<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN11]. Id. at 307.<br />

[FN12]. 319 U.S. 105 (1943).<br />

[FN13]. Id. at 108-09. See also Follett v. Town <strong>of</strong> McCormick, 321 U.S. 573 (1944) (protecting the right <strong>of</strong> Jehovah's<br />

Witnesses engaged in religious soliciting to be free from the burdens <strong>of</strong> a licensing tax on free exercise<br />

and free speech grounds).<br />

[FN14]. 98 U.S. 145 (1878).<br />

[FN15]. Id. at 166.<br />

[FN16]. Murdock, 319 U.S. at 109.<br />

[FN17]. Id. at 110.<br />

[FN18]. Justice Scalia would later cite these cases as support for the idea that the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause only<br />

provided protection against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability in hybrid rights situations where more than one<br />

right was burdened by the state's action. See infra notes 235-45 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN19]. 374 U.S. 398 (1963).<br />

[FN20]. 406 U.S. 205 (1972).<br />

[FN21]. See e.g., Hobbie v. Unemployment Appeals Comm'n <strong>of</strong> Fla., 480 U.S. 136 (1987); Thomas v. Review<br />

Bd. <strong>of</strong> the Indiana Employment Sec. Div., 450 U.S. 707 (1981).<br />

[FN22]. See, e.g., Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Ass'n, 485 U.S. 439 (1988); Goldman v. Weinberger,<br />

475 U.S. 503 (1986); United States v. Lee, 455 U.S. 252 (1982).<br />

[FN23]. See Board <strong>of</strong> Educ. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 718 (1994) (O'Connor, J., concurring in part and concurring<br />

in the judgment).<br />

[FN24]. Alan E. Brownstein, Harmonizing the Heavenly and Earthly Spheres: <strong>The</strong> Fragmentation and Synthesis<br />

<strong>of</strong> Religion, Equality, and <strong>Speech</strong> in the Constitution, 51 Ohio St. L.J. 89 (1990) [hereinafter Brownstein, Harmonizing].<br />

[FN25]. Id. at 131.<br />

[FN26]. 403 U.S. 602 (1971).<br />

[FN27]. Id. at 612-13.<br />

[FN28]. Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421 (1962).<br />

[FN29]. See generally Mark DeWolfe Howe, <strong>The</strong> Garden and <strong>The</strong> Wilderness: Religion and Government in<br />

American Constitutional History (1965).<br />

[FN30]. See School Dist. <strong>of</strong> Abington Township v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 235 (1963) (Brennan, J., dissenting);<br />

Everson v. Board <strong>of</strong> Educ., 330 U.S. 1, 32-44 (1947) (Rutledge, J., dissenting); see also Leonard W. Levy,<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 49<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

<strong>The</strong> Establishment Clause: Religion and the First Amendment (2nd ed. 1994); Thomas J. Curry, <strong>The</strong> First<br />

<strong>Free</strong>doms: Church and State in America to the Passage <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment (1986).<br />

[FN31]. Similarly, if government could not advance or inhibit religion, there was a sense in which the Constitution<br />

required a state posture <strong>of</strong> neutrality on matters <strong>of</strong> faith. Although neither phrase is mentioned in the text <strong>of</strong><br />

the Constitution, the ideas <strong>of</strong> the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state and <strong>of</strong> government neutrality toward religion became<br />

enshrined as conceptual shorthand for describing the unique purposes and goals <strong>of</strong> the Religion Clauses.<br />

[FN32]. Certainly, government neutrality toward religion did not suggest constitutional neutrality toward religion.<br />

<strong>The</strong> emphasis on neutrality did not suggest that the Constitution should turn a blind eye toward religion-<br />

-taking no sides while government and the majority interfered with or promoted religion for better or worse as a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> political discretion. See, e.g., Martha Minow, <strong>The</strong> Constitution and the Subgroup Question, 71 Ind.<br />

L.J. 1, 8 (1995) (“<strong>The</strong> state must not be neutral, in the sense <strong>of</strong> doing nothing to accommodate those with religious<br />

beliefs, where the state's own starting point excludes or burdens them. Otherwise, anyone with religious<br />

beliefs simply must dispense with them in order to operate in the secular, public sphere.”). Nor did neutrality<br />

suggest that religious beliefs, practices, and institutions must be treated no differently than their secular counterparts.<br />

<strong>The</strong> case law made it clear that the Religion Clauses required the distinctive protection <strong>of</strong> religion from<br />

government and distinctive restrictions on the promotion <strong>of</strong> religion by government. See Sherbert, 374 U.S. at<br />

409; Engel, 370 U.S. at 433.<br />

[FN33]. See Michael W. McConnell, <strong>The</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Singling Out Religion, 50 DePaul L. Rev. 1 (2000).<br />

[FN34]. See Alan E. Brownstein, State RFRA Statutes and <strong>Free</strong>dom <strong>of</strong> <strong>Speech</strong>, 32 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 605<br />

(1999) [hereinafter Brownstein, State RFRA Statutes].<br />

[FN35]. See id.<br />

[FN36]. See, e.g., Cole v. Oroville Union High Sch. Dist., 228 F.3d 1092 (9th Cir. 2000).<br />

[FN37]. 452 U.S. 640 (1981).<br />

[FN38]. Id. at 654-55.<br />

[FN39]. 454 U.S. 263 (1981).<br />

[FN40]. Id. at 265 n.3.<br />

[FN41]. Id. at 265 n.2.<br />

[FN42]. Id. at 277.<br />

[FN43]. 489 U.S. 1 (1989).<br />

[FN44]. Id. at 40-41 (White, J., concurring).<br />

[FN45]. See Brownstein, State RFRA Statutes, supra note 34, at 616 n.21 (noting that Court does not explain<br />

ISKCON's mysterious abandonment <strong>of</strong> its free exercise argument which was successful before the Minnesota<br />

Supreme Court).<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 50<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN46]. Heffron, 452 U.S. at 652.<br />

[FN47]. Id. at 660 n.3 (Brennan, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN48]. Id. (Brennan, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN49]. See Thomas C. Berg, <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> in the Workplace: Harassment or Protected <strong>Speech</strong>?, 22 Harv.<br />

J.L. & Pub. Pol'y 959, 981 n.73 (1999).<br />

<strong>The</strong> Heffron holding might be limited in a variety <strong>of</strong> ways. It could apply only to regulations restricting<br />

expressive activities in traditional or limited public fora. It might apply only to religious rituals involving<br />

the core free speech function <strong>of</strong> persuasive expression directed at changing the beliefs or behavior <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

Finally, it might suggest that modest restrictions on the location where ritualized speech may be expressed<br />

do not constitute a substantial burden on the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion. But the Court does not even attempt to confine<br />

the scope <strong>of</strong> its analysis.<br />

[FN50]. Widmar, 454 U.S. at 273 n.13.<br />

[FN51]. Id. at 286 n.4 (White, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN52]. Id. at 284 (White, J., dissenting). See also Robert M. O'Neil, <strong>Religious</strong> Expression: <strong>Speech</strong> or Worship-<br />

-Or Both?, 54 Mo. L. Rev. 501, 504-05 (1989) (criticizing “the majority's casual, barely explicit assimilation <strong>of</strong><br />

religious expression (including worship) to other forms <strong>of</strong> speech” and for its “failure to recognize that religious<br />

expression may be pr<strong>of</strong>oundly different-- that it is not simply speech <strong>of</strong> which the subject happens to be religion”).<br />

[FN53]. Widmar, 454 U.S. at 282 (White, J., dissenting) (contending that recent Establishment Clause decisions<br />

prohibiting prayer in the public schools and the posting <strong>of</strong> the Ten Commandments in classrooms required government<br />

to make the kind <strong>of</strong> content-based decisions the Court was condemning here).<br />

While Establishment Clause cases do prohibit government support <strong>of</strong> religious activities involving religious<br />

speech, there is no need to distinguish between government support <strong>of</strong> expressive and non-expressive religious<br />

activities. Government may unconstitutionally favor or promote religion in a variety <strong>of</strong> ways, both expressive<br />

and non-expressive. <strong>The</strong> Establishment Clause may be violated both by what the government says and<br />

by what it does. <strong>The</strong> key issue is the extent <strong>of</strong> government involvement in the advancement <strong>of</strong> religion. If there<br />

is no such involvement, there is no constitutional violation. If there is sufficient involvement, the Establishment<br />

Clause is violated whether state promotion <strong>of</strong> religion is explicitly expressive or not. Thus, while it is correct<br />

for <strong>Speech</strong> Clause purposes that the government is not prohibited from making content or viewpoint discriminatory<br />

choices with regard to its own speech, it is prohibited for Establishment Clause purposes from “speaking” in<br />

ways that establish religion. Recognizing that religious expressive activities can be characterized as speech does<br />

not seriously undercut Establishment Clause case law, because it is so clear that speech can establish religion.<br />

But see O'Neil, supra note 52, at 504-05 (arguing that religious expression can be seen as both free exercise <strong>of</strong><br />

religion and free speech raising constitutional law dilemmas).<br />

[FN54]. Widmar, 454 U.S. at 270 n.6.<br />

[FN55]. Id. at 285 (White, J., dissenting) (“Although I agree that the line may be difficult to draw in many cases,<br />

surely the majority cannot seriously suggest that no line may ever be drawn.”).<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 51<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN56]. Id. at 282 (White, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN57]. Id. at 289 (White, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN58]. Id. at 276.<br />

[FN59]. Indeed, in Widmar, the Court rejected Justice White's argument that the Religion Clause rather than the<br />

<strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause should govern that case because <strong>of</strong> the difficulty in distinguishing expressive activities such<br />

as the teaching and reading <strong>of</strong> biblical principles, which were rightly regarded as conventional forms <strong>of</strong> speech<br />

for <strong>Speech</strong> Clause purposes, from the activities that traditionally occurred in a worship service. Widmar, 454<br />

U.S. at 270 n.6.<br />

[FN60]. Justice White has this distinction. Texas Monthly, 489 U.S. at 25-26 (White, J., concurring in the judgment).<br />

[FN61]. Id. at 17 n.7.<br />

[FN62]. Id. at 27 (Blackmun, J., concurring in the judgment).<br />

[FN63]. Id. at 27-28 (Blackmun, J., concurring in the judgment).<br />

[FN64]. Id. at 33, 44 (Scalia, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN65]. See infra notes 81-91 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN66]. Texas Monthly, 498 U.S. at 42 (Scalia, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN67]. <strong>The</strong> dissent's alternative justification for upholding the statute is that an exemption from a neutral sales<br />

and use tax for religious publications comes very close to being constitutionally mandated, if, in fact, it is not<br />

actually required by the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause. An exemption that is all but constitutionally mandated must, at a<br />

minimum, be constitutionally permissible, Scalia argues. Id. (Scalia, J., dissenting). <strong>The</strong> very next year,<br />

however, Scalia would write the Court's opinion in Smith, eliminating free exercise protection for any and all religious<br />

activities against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability, and Rehnquist and Kennedy (along with Justices<br />

White and Stevens) would join his majority opinion. 494 U.S. 872 (1990). In a constitutional world in which<br />

free exercise exemptions from neutral laws simply do not exist, <strong>of</strong> course, there are no close questions and almost<br />

mandated accommodations <strong>of</strong> religion protecting religious activities from a generally applicable sales and<br />

use tax. Thus, the very next year after his dissent in Texas Monthly, Scalia wrote an opinion which destroyed the<br />

doctrinal foundation on which his argument was based. Id.<br />

[FN68]. 494 U.S. 872 (1990).<br />

[FN69]. Id. at 882.<br />

[FN70]. Id. at 890.<br />

[FN71]. Id. at 884.<br />

[FN72]. Id.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 52<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN73]. Id. at 881.<br />

[FN74]. 508 U.S. 520 (1993).<br />

[FN75]. Id. at 534.<br />

[FN76]. Id. at 535.<br />

[FN77]. See Duncan, supra note 5, at 863-67.<br />

[FN78]. Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 114.<br />

[FN79]. 508 U.S. 384 (1993).<br />

[FN80]. Id. at 394.<br />

[FN81]. Id. (“<strong>The</strong> principle that has emerged from our cases ‘is that the First Amendment forbids the government<br />

to regulate speech in ways that favor some viewpoints or ideas at the expense <strong>of</strong> others.’ ... That principle<br />

applies in the circumstances <strong>of</strong> this case ....”).<br />

[FN82]. See, e.g., DeBoer v. Village <strong>of</strong> Oak Park, 267 F.3d 558, 571 (7th Cir. 2001) (suggesting that a policy<br />

denying access to any group planning to use a public facility to “promote or espouse [its] philosophy, ideas or<br />

beliefs” was viewpoint-discriminatory because it had “the effect <strong>of</strong> disfavoring all individual viewpoints”); see<br />

Alan E. Brownstein, Alternative Maps for Navigating the First Amendment Maze, 16 Const. Comment. 101, 105<br />

(1999) [hereinafter Brownstein, Alternative Maps].<br />

[FN83]. 515 U.S. 819 (1995).<br />

[FN84]. Id. at 843.<br />

[FN85]. Id. at 825.<br />

[FN86]. To its credit, the Court did try to explain why the University's regulation should be characterized as<br />

viewpoint-discriminatory rather than content-discriminatory. Id. at 830. Perhaps the most persuasive demonstration<br />

<strong>of</strong> support for the Court's conclusion rests on a simple experiment. Assume that the University refused to<br />

fund “secular activities,” including periodicals written from a secular perspective, but did fund religious activities.<br />

My intuition, at least, is that such a distinction would be viewpoint-discriminatory. If it is, reversing the<br />

standard must also be viewpoint-discriminatory.<br />

[FN87]. 533 U.S. 98 (2001).<br />

[FN88]. Id. at 120.<br />

[FN89]. Id. at 137-38 (Souter, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN90]. Id. at 112 n.4.<br />

[FN91]. Id.<br />

[FN92]. Id. at 138-39 (Souter, J., dissenting). <strong>The</strong> problem here is very different from the one the Seventh Cir-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 53<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

cuit confronted in DeBoer v. Village <strong>of</strong> Oak Park, 267 F.3d 558 (7th Cir. 2001). <strong>The</strong>re, the court struck down as<br />

viewpoint-discriminatory the Village's decision to deny access to a group hosting a National Day <strong>of</strong> Prayer service<br />

for community, state, and national leaders from a public facility open for civic programs relating to government.<br />

In reaching this conclusion, however, the court recognized that groups seeking to use the facility for regular<br />

religious services could be denied access because those religious activities bore “no relationship to a specific<br />

civic purpose” involving the government. Id. at 570 n.11. No similar distinction is available to limit the scope <strong>of</strong><br />

the Good News Club holding. Morality and character development are sufficiently broad categories that they<br />

will include virtually all civic groups and religious services. If religious organizations engaging in worship services<br />

cannot be distinguished from secular civic groups and their activities because both sets <strong>of</strong> activities involve<br />

the promotion <strong>of</strong> morality in some sense <strong>of</strong> the term, there is no constitutional basis for treating church<br />

services more or less favorably than a broad range <strong>of</strong> secular pursuits with some connection to this common denominator.<br />

[FN93]. Good News Club, 533 U.S. at 139. Justice Souter does not believe that the majority's holding actually<br />

extends this far. Thus, he argues that “if the majority's statement ignores reality [by ignoring the true nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the activities <strong>of</strong> the Good News Club], as it surely does, then today's holding must be understood only in equally<br />

generic terms.” Id. Thus, the Court's decision may not require treating discrimination for or against regular<br />

church services (or a house <strong>of</strong> worship) as viewpoint discrimination. For the purposes <strong>of</strong> this article, the issue is<br />

not whether the holding <strong>of</strong> the Good News Club requires this conclusion or not. It is whether future cases following<br />

this line <strong>of</strong> authority will reach this result. Clearly, the Court can still shift direction and, following<br />

Souter's advice, read Good News Club more narrowly than the language <strong>of</strong> the majority opinion suggests.<br />

It is also important to recognize that one may be critical <strong>of</strong> the Court's reliance on the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Clause in Good News Club without sharing all <strong>of</strong> Justice Souter's concerns. Souter clearly believes allowing<br />

churches and synagogues to hold regular services in public buildings open to other private uses is a serious problem.<br />

Id. I see little danger in small congregations, not yet capable <strong>of</strong> acquiring land and constructing a house <strong>of</strong><br />

worship in a community, using open and unused government facilities on a temporary basis for religious services.<br />

In my judgment, the difficulty with the Court's decision in Good News Club is its analysis, not its result.<br />

[FN94]. <strong>The</strong> only case that would raise an issue in this regard is Rosenberger, since the University restricted the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> student fees in a variety <strong>of</strong> circumstances, not simply for religious purposes. Just as the Court concluded<br />

that the University's policies involved multiple discrimination for free speech purposes, a comparable argument<br />

might apply for free exercise purposes. Whether such a free exercise argument survives Smith is unclear.<br />

[FN95]. See Alan E. Brownstein, Constitutional Questions About Charitable Choice, in Welfare Reform and<br />

Faith-Based Organizations 219, 247-48 (Derek H. Davis & Barry Hankins eds., 1999) [hereinafter Brownstein,<br />

Constitutional Questions]; Alan E. Brownstein, Interpreting the Religion Clauses in Terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong>, Equality,<br />

and <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Values - A Critical Analysis <strong>of</strong> ‘Neutrality <strong>The</strong>ory” and Charitable Choice, 13 Notre Dame J.L.<br />

Ethics & Pub. Pol'y 243, 270 (1999) [hereinafter Brownstein, Religion Clauses]; Alan E. Brownstein, On School<br />

Vouchers and the Establishment Clause: Evaluating School Voucher Programs Through a <strong>Liberty</strong>, Equality, and<br />

<strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Matrix, 31 Conn. L. Rev. 871, 928 (1999) [hereinafter Brownstein, School Vouchers].<br />

[FN96]. See Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 279; Brownstein, School Vouchers, supra note 95,<br />

at 899-900.<br />

[FN97]. Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 841; see also Brownstein, Constitutional Questions, supra note 95, at 230.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 54<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN98]. Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 849 (O'Connor, J., concurring).<br />

[FN99]. See, e.g., Mitchell v. Helms, 530 U.S. 793, 806 (2000); Petitioner's Brief at 35, Mitchell v. Helms, 530<br />

U.S. 793, No. 98-1648 (2000), at http://www.appellate.net/briefs/mitchell.pdf; Brownstein, Religion Clauses,<br />

supra note 95, at 270; Eugene Volokh, Equal Treatment is Not Establishment, 13 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub.<br />

Pol'y 341, 365-66 (1999); Carl H. Esbeck, A Constitutional Case for Governmental Cooperation With Faith-<br />

Based Social Service Providers, 46 Emory L.J. 1, 7 (1997).<br />

[FN100]. Alan E. Brownstein, Prayer and <strong>Religious</strong> Expression at High School Graduations: Constitutional<br />

Etiquette in a Pluralistic Society, 5 NEXUS 61, 73-75 (2000) [hereinafter Brownstein, Prayer and <strong>Religious</strong> Expression].<br />

[FN101]. Justice O'Connor's concurring opinion in Capital Square Review & Advisory Board v. Pinette, 515<br />

U.S. 753 (1995), demonstrates this distinction concisely. O'Connor maintains that the Establishment Clause is<br />

violated when private religious speech so dominates a public forum that it creates the perception <strong>of</strong> an endorsement<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion, even when the criteria the state employs in determining access to its property are facially neutral.<br />

Id. at 777 (O'Connor, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment). No one argues, however, that<br />

the state is responsible for the domination <strong>of</strong> a public forum by private speakers committed to one side or the<br />

other <strong>of</strong> any conventional public policy debate or that such a result violates the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause prohibition<br />

against viewpoint discrimination. <strong>The</strong> broader reach <strong>of</strong> state action in Establishment Clause cases is the only<br />

persuasive justification for these different results.<br />

[FN102]. See Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 276-78; Brownstein, School Vouchers, supra note<br />

95, at 928-29.<br />

[FN103]. A full discussion <strong>of</strong> how the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause should be interpreted if Smith is overruled is beyond<br />

the scope <strong>of</strong> this article. Certainly, the pre-Smith regime, which applied strict scrutiny only periodically, deserves<br />

substantial criticism. <strong>The</strong> Court's frequent explanations as to why rigorous review was inappropriate were<br />

rarely persuasive and the cases, taken in the aggregate, did not establish coherent doctrinal standards that could<br />

be justified and consistently applied in future discussions.<br />

To cure these problems, a post-Smith free exercise jurisprudence would have to recognize that Religion<br />

Clause doctrine cannot be reduced to a few simple formulas or standards <strong>of</strong> review. Complex constitutional interests<br />

require nuanced and multi-faceted doctrinal frameworks that can protect them while providing adequate<br />

respect for the community's needs and interests. <strong>The</strong> Supreme Court has never taken the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause<br />

seriously enough even to attempt to develop such a framework for decision-making. Establishment Clause cases<br />

have utilized a multi-factor analysis, but they have ineffectively connected the factors the Court takes into consideration<br />

with the constitutional values that are relevant to such an inquiry. See Alan Brownstein, <strong>The</strong> Souter<br />

Dissent: Correct but Inadequate, in Church-State Relations in Crisis: Debating Neutrality 151-72 (Stephen V.<br />

Monsma ed., 2002).<br />

[FN104]. See Tuttle, supra note 5, at 871-80 (describing the difficulty religious institutions encounter in pursuing<br />

free exercise claims in the land use context, even in state courts that have historically been more receptive to<br />

such claims); Von G. Keetch & Matthew K. Richards, <strong>The</strong> Need for Legislation to Enshrine <strong>Free</strong> Exercise in the<br />

Land Use Context, 32 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 725 (1999); Douglas Laycock, State RFRAs and Land Use Regulation,<br />

32 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 755, 763-769 (1999).<br />

[FN105]. See, e.g., Tuttle, supra note 5, at 871-875; Laycock, supra note 104, at 765 n.35. <strong>The</strong>se arguments are<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 55<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

<strong>of</strong> dubious merit. To the extent that the ordinance at issue lists permissible and impermissible locations for<br />

houses <strong>of</strong> worship on its face, one may argue that the issue <strong>of</strong> religious obligation and centrality <strong>of</strong> belief ought<br />

to be irrelevant. Discrimination against a religious activity should raise free exercise concerns without regard to<br />

the substantiality <strong>of</strong> the burden, the obligatory or supernumerary nature <strong>of</strong> the practice, or the centrality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

tenet. Surely even a minimal land use fee imposed solely on houses <strong>of</strong> worship raises free exercise issues. See<br />

Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 988 (1992) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (suggesting that a one cent tax on<br />

the sale <strong>of</strong> religious books alone would be unconstitutional). But many courts hold that land use regulations facially<br />

discriminating against houses <strong>of</strong> worship do not merit rigorous review. See, e.g., Civil Liberties for Urban<br />

Believers v. City <strong>of</strong> Chicago, No. 94-CV6151, 2001 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 17213 (N.D. Ill. Oct. 17, 2001); Korean<br />

Buddhist Dae Won Sa Temple <strong>of</strong> Haw. v. Sullivan, 953 P.2d 1315 (Haw. 1998); Int'l Church <strong>of</strong> the Foursquare<br />

Gospel v. City <strong>of</strong> Chicago Heights, 955 F. Supp. 878, 881 (N.D. Ill. 1996); Messiah Baptist Church v. County <strong>of</strong><br />

Jefferson, 859 F.2d 820 (10th Cir. 1988).<br />

<strong>The</strong> recent enactment <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Religious</strong> Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act in 2000 demonstrates<br />

Congress' perception that courts were not effectively enforcing free exercise rights in the land use context. See<br />

Roman P. Storzer & Anthony R. Picarrello, Jr., <strong>The</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act <strong>of</strong><br />

2000: A Constitutional Response to Unconstitutional Zoning Practices, 9 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 929, 940-41<br />

(2001); Tuttle, supra note 5, at 863-65.<br />

[FN106]. See Tuttle, supra note 5, at 894 (suggesting that zoning ordinances that exclude religious uses while allowing<br />

similar secular uses appear to be facially content-based).<br />

[FN107]. Tuttle, supra note 5.<br />

[FN108]. See, e.g., Messiah Baptist Church, 859 F.2d 820; Lakewood, Ohio Congregation <strong>of</strong> Jehovah's Witnesses,<br />

Inc. v. City <strong>of</strong> Lakewood, 699 F.2d 303 (6th Cir. 1983).<br />

[FN109]. See, e.g., Cornerstone Bible Church v. City <strong>of</strong> Hastings, 948 F.2d 464, 468 (8th Cir. 1991). <strong>The</strong> secondary<br />

effects doctrine was initially utilized by the Court in City <strong>of</strong> Renton v. Playtime <strong>The</strong>aters, 475 U.S. 41<br />

(1986), to uphold a dispersal zoning ordinance regulating the location <strong>of</strong> adult theaters in a community. It<br />

provides that a content-discriminatory regulation predicated on indirect “secondary” effects <strong>of</strong> speech, such as<br />

the increases in urban blight, prostitution, drug use, and crime that accompany the congregation <strong>of</strong> adult businesses<br />

in an area, may be evaluated under the more lenient standard <strong>of</strong> review applied to content-neutral speech<br />

regulations, rather than strict scrutiny review. Thus, although a dispersal zoning ordinance on its face classifies<br />

theaters based on the content <strong>of</strong> the movies they show, it is reviewed as a time, place, and manner regulation because<br />

the state's discrimination is directed not at the message communicated by the movies or its direct influence<br />

on an audience, but rather, at the attenuated consequences <strong>of</strong> the theater's operations. Id. at 46. See Alan E.<br />

Brownstein, Illicit Legislative Motive in the Municipal Land Use Regulation Process, 57 U. Cin. L. Rev. 1,<br />

91-92 (1988) [hereinafter Brownstein, Legislative Motive].<br />

[FN110]. See Tuttle, supra note 5, at 894-96.<br />

[FN111]. Brownstein, Alternative Maps, supra note 82, at 108-09 n.26.<br />

[FN112]. Brownstein, Legislative Motive, supra note 109, at 94.<br />

[FN113]. Courts apply a multi-factor balancing test to review content-neutral regulations <strong>of</strong> speech. <strong>The</strong> importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the state interest, the tailoring <strong>of</strong> the regulation, and the availability <strong>of</strong> alternative avenues <strong>of</strong> communic-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 56<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

ation are all evaluated under this standard <strong>of</strong> review. See City <strong>of</strong> Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U.S. 43, 53 (1994).<br />

[FN114]. <strong>The</strong> ensuing discussion <strong>of</strong> the protection provided speech against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability<br />

demonstrates the blatant inaccuracy and obvious error <strong>of</strong> Justice Scalia's contention in Smith that it would be<br />

“anomalous” to protect the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion against such laws, since other rights are not protected in similar<br />

circumstances. Smith, 494 U.S. at 886 (characterizing free exercise rights against neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability<br />

as “a constitutional anomaly”); see also Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 82-84 (demonstrating that<br />

the Court's free exercise jurisprudence is itself deviant in its failure to require any significant review <strong>of</strong> neutral<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability that substantially burden religious practices); Alan E. Brownstein, Constitutional<br />

Wish Granting and the Property Rights Genie, 13 Const. Comment. 7, 14-26 (1996).<br />

[FN115]. See Brownstein, Alternative Maps, supra note 82, at 115 n.45 (demonstrating the seriousness with<br />

which lower courts review content-neutral laws).<br />

[FN116]. See supra notes 10-18 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN117]. See City <strong>of</strong> Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publishing Co., 486 U.S. 750, 758-59 (1988).<br />

[FN118]. See Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 85-96; Tuttle, supra note 5, at 892-913. Tuttle's article focuses<br />

on land use regulations. Gedicks considers the protection <strong>of</strong> religious activity under a free speech rubric<br />

from a broader perspective. <strong>The</strong>re is one other critical distinction between the approaches endorsed by these two<br />

authors. Tuttle justifies the standard <strong>of</strong> review he endorses because religious activities and institutions involve<br />

speech. Gedicks argues that religious practices should receive the same protection as speech whether the religious<br />

practices have a speech dimension or not. As Gedicks puts it, in his view “religious exercise should not be<br />

protected as speech, but rather like speech.” Frederick Mark Gedicks, Toward a Defensible <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Doctrine,<br />

68 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 925, 930 (2000) [hereinafter Gedicks, Defensible <strong>Free</strong> Exercise].<br />

[FN119]. See, e.g., Tuttle, supra note 5, at 871-74 (describing cases in which courts found that zoning ordinances<br />

did not burden religious beliefs).<br />

[FN120]. See Plain Dealer, 486 U.S. at 759.<br />

[FN121]. See Barnes v. Glen <strong>The</strong>atre, Inc., 501 U.S. 560, 578 n.4 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring).<br />

[FN122]. See Messiah Baptist Church, 859 F.2d at 829 (McKay, J., dissenting) (arguing that “[t]he outright prohibition<br />

or the discretionary power (unaccompanied by adequate standards) to deny parade or protest permits on<br />

public property surely is not more odious to the first amendment [sic] than the outright prohibition or legally discretionary<br />

power to deny the right to use buildings for worship, religious communication, and religious assembly<br />

on one's own property”); Gedicks, Defensible <strong>Free</strong> Exercise, supra note 118, at 936 (noting that many<br />

land use regulations restricting religious exercise are directly analogous to time, place, and manner regulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> speech in that they “directly control where, when, and under what circumstances religious activity may take<br />

place, in the same way that parade permits, sound ordinances, and other such restrictions directly regulate<br />

where, when, and under what circumstances otherwise protected expression may occur”).<br />

[FN123]. It is hard to imagine a more conventionally accepted place and means for conducting religious assemblies<br />

than a house <strong>of</strong> worship. Even if the zoning <strong>of</strong> houses <strong>of</strong> worship does not constitute content or viewpoint<br />

discrimination, at a minimum it should receive intermediate-level scrutiny. Churches are among the primary<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 57<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

places where religious expression occurs, and limits on the size, structural features, and accessory uses <strong>of</strong> a<br />

house <strong>of</strong> worship influence the manner <strong>of</strong> the expressive activities that may occur there. Thus, the zoning <strong>of</strong><br />

churches should be reviewed as a regulation <strong>of</strong> the place and manner <strong>of</strong> religious assembly. Applying the secondary<br />

effects doctrine to land use regulations governing religious institutions yields a roughly similar standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> review. Moreover, the procedural requirements applied to the permitting or licensing <strong>of</strong> speech should apply<br />

here as well. Administrative discretion to determine the content <strong>of</strong> conditional use permits granted to houses <strong>of</strong><br />

worship should be constitutionally cabined by acceptable guidelines, just as systems for granting permits for<br />

other expressive activities must include clear and reviewable criteria. See Tuttle, supra note 5, at 903-13.<br />

Unfortunately, courts do not always comply with these standards or apply this form <strong>of</strong> review.<br />

<strong>Religious</strong> land uses <strong>of</strong>ten receive less protection than the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause would seem to require. Id.<br />

at 894-903. Perhaps this occurs because courts conceptualize religion as something that is distinct from speech<br />

for constitutional purposes. See, e.g., Civil Liberties for Urban Believers, 2001 U.S. Dist. LEXIS at *36-37<br />

(contending that “the operation <strong>of</strong> a house <strong>of</strong> worship does not equate with ‘religious speech,’ any more than the<br />

operation <strong>of</strong> a shoe store equates with commercial speech”). Presumably, a continued emphasis on the protection<br />

<strong>of</strong> religion as speech, and not as the exercise <strong>of</strong> religion, would eventually change that perception.<br />

[FN124]. See Brownstein, Alternative Maps, supra note 82, at 110 n.30 (discussing lower courts' striking down<br />

content neutral speech regulations in a wide variety <strong>of</strong> circumstances). Indeed, in cases involving religious<br />

speech that include both free speech and free exercise claims, there is a striking difference between the length<br />

and rigor <strong>of</strong> the courts' analysis under the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause and the typically truncated and dismissive evaluation<br />

<strong>of</strong> plaintiffs' free exercise claims. See, e.g., Daniels v. City <strong>of</strong> Arlington, 246 F.3d 500 (5th Cir. 2001)<br />

(applying more substantial free speech review to police department ban on uniformed <strong>of</strong>ficers' wearing any pin<br />

or badge on their uniform, including a cross); Watchtower Bible & Tract Soc'y <strong>of</strong> N.Y., Inc. v. Village <strong>of</strong> Stratton,<br />

240 F.3d 553 (6th Cir. 2001), cert. granted, 122 S. Ct. 392 (2001) (providing much more extensive free<br />

speech review <strong>of</strong> content-neutral regulation restricting door to door soliciting and canvassing); Quental v. Connecticut<br />

Comm'n on the Deaf & Hearing Impaired, 122 F. Supp. 2d 133 (D. Conn. 2001) (reviewing disciplinary<br />

action taken against public employees engaged in religious proselytizing to clients far more rigorously under<br />

free speech standard).<br />

[FN125]. 408 U.S. 104 (1972).<br />

[FN126]. Id. at 108.<br />

[FN127]. Thus, the Court explained,<br />

[w]e recognize that the ordinance prohibits some picketing that is neither violent nor physically obstructive.<br />

Noisy demonstrations that disrupt or are incompatible with normal school activities are obviously<br />

within the ordinance's reach. Such expressive conduct may be constitutionally protected at other places or other<br />

times, ... but next to a school, while classes are in session, it may be prohibited.<br />

Id. at 120.<br />

[FN128]. <strong>The</strong> Court claimed to be responding to an overbreadth challenge in Grayned. Its analysis, however,<br />

was virtually indistinguishable from the conventional review <strong>of</strong> content-neutral speech regulations.<br />

[FN129]. 402 U.S. 611 (1971).<br />

[FN130]. Id. at 611.<br />

[FN131]. Id. at 612.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 58<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN132]. Lukumi, 508 U.S. at 535.<br />

[FN133]. Some overbroad laws may be challenged on free exercise grounds on the theory that they involve individualized<br />

assessments, an exception to the Smith holding. See infra notes 249-51 and accompanying text.<br />

While concerns about the exercise <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficial discretion represent part <strong>of</strong> the underlying foundation <strong>of</strong> overbreadth<br />

doctrine, not all laws that might be struck down as overbroad necessarily involve unrestricted discretion.<br />

Moreover, the extent to which the individualized assessments language in Smith applies to <strong>of</strong>ficial discretion in<br />

interpreting laws as opposed to <strong>of</strong>ficial authority to grant exemptions to laws is unclear. Finally, free speech<br />

doctrine allows individuals to assert vicarious standing in challenging overbroad laws. <strong>The</strong> exception in Smith<br />

does not provide a comparable extension <strong>of</strong> prudential standing rules.<br />

[FN134]. 379 U.S. 536 (1965).<br />

[FN135]. Id. at 544.<br />

[FN136]. Id. at 545.<br />

[FN137]. Id. at 546.<br />

[FN138]. Again, there may be some circumstances in which the individual assessment exception to Smith might<br />

permit a free exercise challenge to the application <strong>of</strong> such open-ended laws. See supra note 133.<br />

[FN139]. 530 U.S. 640 (2000).<br />

[FN140]. Id. at 661-62.<br />

[FN141]. Id. at 644.<br />

[FN142]. <strong>The</strong> Court did criticize the expansive interpretation <strong>of</strong> the statute given to it by the state courts, which<br />

increased the potentiality <strong>of</strong> conflict between the law and the associational rights <strong>of</strong> a private organization. Id. at<br />

657. But that gratuitous comment does nothing to detract from the law's general focus on non-expressive activities<br />

and groups. See also Donaldson v. Farrakhan, 762 N.E.2d 835, 841 (Mass. 2002) (holding that forcing a<br />

mosque and its leaders to admit women would “impermissibly burden” their “freedom <strong>of</strong> association under the<br />

First Amendment”).<br />

[FN143]. See, e.g., Salvation Army v. Dep't <strong>of</strong> Cmty. Affairs, 919 F.2d 183, 200 (3rd Cir. 1990) (providing<br />

stronger protection to religious organization under freedom <strong>of</strong> association than free exercise doctrine against<br />

neutral laws <strong>of</strong> general applicability because “[u]nlike the derivative right <strong>of</strong> religious association, the right to<br />

associate for free speech purposes does not require that the challenged state action be directly addressed to the<br />

constitutionally protected activity”).<br />

[FN144]. <strong>The</strong> selection <strong>of</strong> clergy is an isolated exception to the general rule. Under this “ministerial exception,”<br />

courts recognize that both the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause and the Establishment Clause protect religious institutions<br />

from state interference with the employment relationship between religious organizations and clergy. See, e.g.,<br />

Gellington v. Christian Methodist Episcopal Church, Inc. 203 F.3d 1299 (11th Cir. 2000); EEOC. v. Catholic<br />

Univ. <strong>of</strong> Am., 83 F.3d 455 (D.C. Cir. 1996). <strong>The</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> this exception is limited, however. It does not extend<br />

to employment relationships with lay employees, for example, EEOC v. Fremont Christian Sch., 781 F.2d 1362,<br />

1369-70 (9th Cir. 1986), or to disputes that do not implicate core Religion Clause concerns, Bollard v. California<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 59<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Province <strong>of</strong> Soc'y <strong>of</strong> Jesus, 196 F.3d 940, 946-50 (9th Cir. 1999).<br />

[FN145]. See, e.g., Goldman v. Weinberger, 475 U.S. 503 (1986).<br />

[FN146]. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 377 (1968).<br />

[FN147]. United States v. Eichman, 496 U.S. 310 (1990).<br />

[FN148]. See, e.g., Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781 (1989); Clark v. Cmty. for Creative Non-<br />

Violence, 468 U.S. 288 (1984).<br />

[FN149]. See Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 90-94; Tuttle, supra note 5, at 896-97.<br />

[FN150]. See, e.g., Littlefield v. Forney Indep. Sch. Dist., 268 F.3d 275, 286-87 (5th Cir. 2001) (upholding<br />

school uniform policy under cursory and conclusory review); see Brownstein, Alternative Maps, supra note 82,<br />

at 108-12; Ira C. Lupu, <strong>The</strong> Failure <strong>of</strong> RFRA, 20 U. Ark. Little Rock L.J. 575, 592-93 (1998); Eugene Volokh,<br />

A Common-Law Model for <strong>Religious</strong> Exemptions, 46 UCLA L. Rev. 1465, 1512 n.148 (1999) [hereinafter<br />

Volokh, A Common-Law Model].<br />

[FN151]. 310 U.S. 586 (1940), overruled by West Virginia State Bd. <strong>of</strong> Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943).<br />

[FN152]. 319 U.S. 624 (1943).<br />

[FN153]. See Pacific Gas & Electric Co. v. Pub. Util. Comm'n, 475 U.S. 1 (1986).<br />

[FN154]. Id. at 18.<br />

[FN155]. Abood v. Detroit Bd. <strong>of</strong> Educ., 431 U.S. 209 (1977).<br />

[FN156]. United States v. United Foods, Inc., 533 U.S. 405, 410 (2001).<br />

[FN157]. 530 U.S. 640 (2000).<br />

[FN158]. Id at 653. Justice Stevens in dissent forcefully challenged this conclusion, noting that while<br />

“participating in the Scouts could itself conceivably send a message on some level, it is not the kind <strong>of</strong> act that<br />

we have recognized as speech.” Id. at 695 (Stevens, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN159]. Pacific Gas, 475 U.S. at 16.<br />

[FN160]. 109 Cal. Rptr. 2d 176 (Cal. Ct. App. 2001), review granted, 31 P.3d 1271 (Cal. 2001).<br />

[FN161]. Petitioner's Brief on the Merits at 3, Catholic Charities <strong>of</strong> Sacramento, Inc. v. Superior Court, 109 Cal.<br />

Rptr. 2d 176 (Cal. 2001) (No. S-099822), at http://www.sweeny-grant.com/briefs/opening.pdf.<br />

[FN162]. Catholic Charities, 109 Cal. Rptr. 2d at 185-86 (rejecting <strong>Free</strong> Exercise claim on grounds that challenged<br />

law is neutral and generally applicable and does not target religion).<br />

[FN163]. Boy Scouts <strong>of</strong> America, 530 U.S. at 653.<br />

[FN164]. Andrew Koppelman persuasively describes the expansive understanding <strong>of</strong> compelled affirmation <strong>of</strong><br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 60<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

belief doctrine that seems to underlie the Court's decision in Dale. He also subjects that analysis to withering criticism.<br />

Andrew Koppelman, Signs <strong>of</strong> the Times: Dale v. Boy Scouts <strong>of</strong> America and the Changing Meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

Nondiscrimination, 23 Cardozo L. Rev. 1819 (2002). He also acknowledges that far less protection would be<br />

provided to religious organizations under post-Smith free exercise doctrine. Id. at 1833 (explaining that under<br />

the majority opinion in Dale “[p]rejudice is thereby given a legal privilege that is denied to religious scruples”).<br />

[FN165]. See Smith, 494 U.S. at 889.<br />

[FN166]. See Lisa Schwartz Bressman, Accomodation and Equal <strong>Liberty</strong>, 42 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1007 (2001)<br />

(discussing numerous religion exemptions that might justifiably be extended to secular practice and institutions).<br />

[FN167]. See, e.g., Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 268-78; Bressman, supra note 166, 1020<br />

(suggesting that many religious exemptions are unconstitutional under the equal treatment principle enforced under<br />

free speech doctrine). <strong>The</strong>re is substantial agreement that religious exemptions cannot be provided to conventional<br />

speech regulations without violating the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause. See, e.g., Berg, supra note 49, at 980-81;<br />

William P. Marshall, <strong>The</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Free</strong>dom Restoration Act: Establishment, Equal Protection, and <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong><br />

Concerns, 56 Mont. L. Rev. 227, 244-47 (1995); McConnell, supra note 33, at 40. Disagreement arises,<br />

however, as to the range <strong>of</strong> laws under which religious exemptions are invalid because <strong>of</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause constraints.<br />

Some commentators warn, as Berg does, see supra note 49, at 981 n.73, that this principle must be<br />

strictly limited to avoid undermining the possibility <strong>of</strong> religious accommodations. Others wonder, as Volokh<br />

does, Eugene Volokh, Intermediate Questions <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> Exemptions--A Research Agenda with Test Suites,<br />

21 Cardozo L. Rev. 595, 614-16 (1999) [hereinafter Volokh, Intermediate Questions], whether any limit on this<br />

principle is possible, or argue that free speech constraints limit most exemptions except for those noncommunicative<br />

practices “at the periphery <strong>of</strong> religious exercise.” William P. Marshall, In Defense <strong>of</strong> Smith and<br />

<strong>Free</strong> Exercise Revisionism, 58 U. Chi. L. Rev. 308, 312-13 (1991).<br />

<strong>The</strong> thesis <strong>of</strong> this article is that the conflict between free speech doctrine and religious exemptions and<br />

accommodations can and should be resolved, but the Court's recent religion as speech cases make it increasingly<br />

more difficult to do so.<br />

[FN168]. Brownstein, State RFRA Statutes, supra note 34.<br />

[FN169]. See discussion <strong>of</strong> Widmar, 454 U.S. 263, supra notes 50-59 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN170]. Good News Club, 533 U.S. at 102-03 (citation omitted).<br />

[FN171]. See supra notes 87-93 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN172]. Good News Club, 533 U.S. at 139 (Souter, J., dissenting); see supra notes 87-93 and accompanying<br />

text.<br />

[FN173]. See Berg, supra note 49, at 981 n.73 (acknowledging that the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause principle <strong>of</strong><br />

“content-neutrality, if pushed too far, would create a ‘negative hybrid’ in which expressive elements <strong>of</strong> religious<br />

conduct barred the application <strong>of</strong> increased protection for such conduct”).<br />

[FN174]. R.A.V. v. St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377 (1992) (holding that viewpoint discrimination is even forbidden when<br />

regulating unprotected speech).<br />

[FN175]. 42 U.S.C.A. § 2000cc (West Supp. 2001). Another obvious example <strong>of</strong> a potentially viewpoint-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 61<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

discriminatory law favoring religion is the so-called Leonard Law, Cal. Educ. Code § 94367 (West Supp. 1996).<br />

This law attempts by statute to provide students at private colleges the same protection for their expressive<br />

activities from administrators that students at public universities receive under the First Amendment. Significantly,<br />

however, the law “does not apply to any private post-secondary educational institution that is controlled<br />

by a religious organization, to the extent that the application <strong>of</strong> this [law] would not be consistent with the religious<br />

tenets <strong>of</strong> the organization.” Id. at § 94367 (c). <strong>The</strong> Leonard Law was used to strike down Stanford University's<br />

hate speech code. Corry v. Stanford, No. 740309 (Cal. Super. Ct. Santa Clara County Feb. 27, 1995)<br />

(unreported decision), available at http://lawschool.stanford.edu/library/special/corrym.shtml). It would not be<br />

applied to protect students from a similar code adopted by Pepperdine University. <strong>The</strong> exemption for religious<br />

schools seems inherently viewpoint-discriminatory.<br />

[FN176]. Storzer, supra note 105. I do not mean to suggest that the Court's holding in Good News Club requires<br />

the conclusion that RLUIPA is unconstitutional. <strong>The</strong>re is a sufficient disconnect between the majority's analysis<br />

and the nature <strong>of</strong> the Good News Club's activities to create real uncertainty as to the scope <strong>of</strong> the case's holding.<br />

See supra note 93. <strong>The</strong> important question is whether the Court will continue in the direction it is moving, making<br />

decisions that would place RLUIPA in constitutional jeopardy, or whether it will begin to limit the subsuming<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious practice and institutions under free speech doctrine<br />

[FN177]. See, e.g., Volokh, supra note 167, at 614 (noting that “[r]equests for exemptions <strong>of</strong> religious meetings<br />

from zoning requirements are generally aimed at facilitating religious speech - prayer, sermons, and the like”<br />

and questioning whether it is constitutional under free speech doctrine to exempt such religious expressive activities<br />

from zoning laws).<br />

In 1999, a year before RLUIPA was enacted, various religious and civil liberties groups in California<br />

attempted to convince the state legislature to adopt a state law providing something like the protection afforded<br />

to religious land uses by RLUIPA. I testified before the Senate Judiciary Committee in support <strong>of</strong> that<br />

law. <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Free</strong>dom Protection Act: Hearing on S.B. No. 38 Before the Senate Judiciary Committee, 1999<br />

Leg. (Cal. 1999) (testimony <strong>of</strong> Alan E. Brownstein, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Law, U.C. Davis). During the hearing, State<br />

Senator John Burton asked me whether a Catholic Church and a Masonic Temple that both wanted to locate in a<br />

similar area in a town would receive different treatment under the law and how I could justify providing more<br />

favorable regulatory treatment to the religious institution. My answer, I'm sure, explained that religion was special.<br />

<strong>The</strong> understanding at the time was that the Religion Clauses <strong>of</strong> the First Amendment exist because religion<br />

is understood to require distinct constitutional protection and regulatory treatment. It is unclear how one would<br />

answer that question today or in the future if it is conceded that regulations disadvantaging religious institutions<br />

are viewpoint-discriminatory violations <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Clause.<br />

[FN178]. Michael Stokes Paulsen, God is Great, Garvey is Good: Making Sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Free</strong>dom, 72 Notre<br />

Dame L. Rev. 1597, 1603 (1997).<br />

[FN179]. Douglas Laycock, <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong> as <strong>Liberty</strong>, 7 J. Contemp. Legal Issues 313 (1996).<br />

[FN180]. Arkanas Educ. Television Comm'n v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666, 679-80 (1998).<br />

[FN181]. Id. at 677-78.<br />

[FN182]. Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 843-46.<br />

[FN183]. But see Air Line Pilots Ass'n, Int'l v. Dep't <strong>of</strong> Aviation, 45 F.3d 1144 (7th Cir. 1995) (suggesting that<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 62<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

limits on political speech may be justified by the intrusive and disruptive nature <strong>of</strong> the speech).<br />

[FN184]. 473 U.S. 788 (1985).<br />

[FN185]. Id. at 797.<br />

[FN186]. Good News Club, 533 U.S. at 118-19.<br />

[FN187]. See Frederick Schauer, Too Hard: Unconstitutional Conditions and the Chimera <strong>of</strong> Constitutional Consistency,<br />

72 Den. U. L. Rev. 989 (1995); Larry Alexander, Impossible, 72 Den. U. L. Rev. 1007 (1995); Roberto<br />

L. Corrada, Justifying a Search for a Unifying <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Unconstitutional Conditions, 72 Den. U. L. Rev. 1011,<br />

1013 (1995).<br />

[FN188]. 374 U.S. 398 (1963).<br />

[FN189]. Id. at 404.<br />

[FN190]. 461 U.S. 574 (1983).<br />

[FN191]. Id. at 598-99.<br />

[FN192]. Id. at 603-04.<br />

[FN193]. Id. at 604.<br />

[FN194]. 476 U.S. 693 (1986).<br />

[FN195]. Julie A. Nice, Making Conditions Constitutional by Attaching <strong>The</strong>m to Welfare: <strong>The</strong> Dangers <strong>of</strong> Selective<br />

Contextual Ignorance <strong>of</strong> the Unconstitutional Conditions Doctrine, 72 Den. U. L. Rev. 971, 977-80<br />

(1995).<br />

[FN196]. See infra notes 253-53 and accompanying text (describing individualized exemptions exception in<br />

Smith).<br />

[FN197]. Brownstein, Harmonizing, supra note 24, at 132<br />

[FN198]. 500 U.S. 173 (1991).<br />

[FN199]. Id. at 179.<br />

[FN200]. Id. at 180 (citation omitted).<br />

[FN201]. Id. at 198.<br />

[FN202]. Id. at 197-99.<br />

[FN203]. Mitchell, 530 U.S. at 840-41 (O'Connor, J., concurring).<br />

[FN204]. Id. at 885-87 (Souter, J., dissenting).<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 63<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN205]. Smith, 494 U.S. at 890 (explaining that “[i]t may fairly be said that leaving accommodation to the<br />

political process will place at a relative disadvantage those religious practices that are not widely engaged in<br />

....”).<br />

[FN206]. Justice Blackmun, for example, challenged the majority's conclusion that “the repression <strong>of</strong> minority<br />

religions is an ‘unavoidable consequence <strong>of</strong> democratic government.”’ Id. at 909 (Blackmun, J., dissenting)<br />

(citation omitted).<br />

[FN207]. United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 153 n.4 (1938).<br />

[FN208]. See generally John Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust (1990).<br />

[FN209]. Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200 (1995); City <strong>of</strong> Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488<br />

U.S. 469 (1989).<br />

[FN210]. Adarand Constructors, 515 U.S. at 242 (Stevens, J., dissenting); Id. at 264 (Souter, J., dissenting); Id.<br />

at 271 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting); J. A. Croson Co., 488 U.S. at 528 (Marshall, J., dissenting); Id. at 528<br />

(Blackmun, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN211]. See Regents <strong>of</strong> Univ. <strong>of</strong> California v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 324-79 (1978) (Brennan, J., concurring in<br />

the judgment in part and dissenting in part); Id. at 387-402 (Marshall, J., concurring in the judgment in part and<br />

dissenting in part); Id. at 402-21 (Blackmun, J., concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part).<br />

[FN212]. J. A. Croson Co., 488 U.S. at 536-37 (Blackmun, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN213]. Adarand Constructors, 515 U.S. at 241 (Thomas, J., concurring).<br />

[FN214]. Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 250-51; Brownstein, School Vouchers, supra note 93,<br />

at 893-94.<br />

[FN215]. See, e.g., Gillette v. United States, 401 U.S. 437 (1971); Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U.S. 599 (1961);<br />

McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. 420 (1961).<br />

[FN216]. 401 U.S. 437 (1971).<br />

[FN217]. Board <strong>of</strong> Educ. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 732 (1994) (Scalia, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN218]. Id. at 705.<br />

[FN219]. See Ira C. Lupu, Uncovering the Village <strong>of</strong> Kiryas Joel, 96 Colum. L. Rev. 104, 113-14 (1996).<br />

[FN220]. Compare Brownstein, Harmonizing, supra note 24, at 142-45, Abner S. Greene, Kiryas Joel and Two<br />

Mistakes About Equality, 96 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 63-82 (1996), Mark C. Rahdert, A Jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> Hope:<br />

Justice Blackmun and the <strong>Free</strong>dom <strong>of</strong> Religion, 22 Hamline L. Rev. 1, 97-98 (1998), David E. Steinberg, <strong>Religious</strong><br />

Exemptions as Affirmative Action, 40 Emory L.J. 77 (1991), and Tseming Yang, Race, Religion, and Cultural<br />

Identity: Reconciling the Jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> Race and Religion, 73 Ind. L.J. 119, 180-84 (1997), with<br />

Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 99-105, and Lupu, supra note 219, at 113-120.<br />

[FN221]. Brownstein, Alternative Maps, supra note 82, at 111-12; Alan E. Brownstein, Rules <strong>of</strong> Engagement for<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 64<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

Cultural Wars: Regulating Conduct, Unprotected <strong>Speech</strong>, and Protected Expression in Anti-Abortion Protests,<br />

29 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 553, 621 (1996) [hereinafter Brownstein, Rules <strong>of</strong> Engagement]; Cass R. Sunstein,<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> in the Welfare State: <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> Now, 59 U. Chi. L. Rev. 255, 299-301 (1992) (advocating extra assistance<br />

for minority viewpoints, while noting that current free speech doctrine does not permit such assistance);<br />

Michael Rosenfeld, Metro Broadcasting, Inc. v. FCC: Affirmative Action at the Crossroads <strong>of</strong> Constitutional<br />

<strong>Liberty</strong> and Equality, 38 UCLA L. Rev. 583, 627 (1991) (suggesting giving minority viewpoints priority to increase<br />

viewpoint diversity); Owen M. Fiss, <strong>Free</strong> <strong>Speech</strong> and Social Structure, 71 Iowa L. Rev. 1405, 1415-16<br />

(1986) (acknowledging that free speech doctrine does not permit elevation <strong>of</strong> one viewpoint over another, but<br />

advocating for such government action).<br />

[FN222]. Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 48-49 (1976).<br />

[FN223]. Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 256.<br />

[FN224]. In Brownstein, School Vouchers, supra note 95, at 886-87, I explain that,<br />

[r]eligion for constitutional purposes involves personal and institutional liberty and autonomy (in my<br />

view the right <strong>of</strong> the individual and congregations, rather than the state, to make self-defining decisions). It involves<br />

equality among groups; a form <strong>of</strong> equality that is analogous to, but in some ways distinct from, the equality<br />

mandated by the Equal Protection Clause that protects certain classes against discrimination. It also involves<br />

speech and belief. Government should avoid distorting the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas through state action that empowers<br />

or silences religious expression.<br />

[FN225]. I agree with Michael McConnell that “it is virtually impossible to understand our tradition <strong>of</strong> the separation<br />

<strong>of</strong> church and state without recognizing that religion raises political and constitutional issues not raised<br />

by other institutions or ideologies.” McConnell, supra note 33, at 3. Indeed, I think religion is even more distinctive<br />

and deserving <strong>of</strong> being singled out than he does, certainly for Establishment Clause purposes, and, correspondingly,<br />

I am more committed to the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state.<br />

[FN226]. See, e.g., Rabbi Joseph Telushkin, Jewish Wisdom: Ethical, Spiritual, and Historical Lessons from the<br />

Great Works and Thinkers 3, 6 (1994) (explaining that “ethics is at Judaism's core . ... ethical behavior constitutes<br />

Judaism's essence”).<br />

[FN227]. See, e.g., Frederick Mark Gedicks, Toward a Constitutional Jurisprudence <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong> Group Rights,<br />

1989 Wis. L. Rev. 99 (1989).<br />

[FN228]. McConnell, supra note 33, at 28-31.<br />

[FN229]. See, e.g., Telushkin, supra note 226, at 4 (noting that “Judaism imposes upon the Jewish people the<br />

obligation to help bring about tikkun olam, the repair (or perfection) <strong>of</strong> the world”).<br />

[FN230]. For example, as Reuven Hammer explains, Jewish prayer<br />

is an integral part <strong>of</strong> the complete religious life <strong>of</strong> a Jew--an essential part, but nevertheless only a<br />

part. It cannot be isolated from the rest except artificially, for it interweaves with everything else to create the<br />

harmonious whole that is Judaism. <strong>The</strong> other major components <strong>of</strong> a full Jewish life are study, ritual practice,<br />

and moral living. Although prayer is our way <strong>of</strong> communicating with God, we must remember that it is not the<br />

only way. All <strong>of</strong> these paths lead to God, and all <strong>of</strong> them are interconnected.<br />

Hammer, supra note 7, at 3.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 65<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN231]. See infra notes 252-56 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN232]. See Yoder, 406 U.S. at 216.<br />

[FN233]. See, e.g., Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 268-78 (explaining that vigorous enforcement<br />

<strong>of</strong> both <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and Establishment Clause principles create <strong>of</strong>fsetting impacts on the communication<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious messages and may minimize the distortion <strong>of</strong> the marketplace <strong>of</strong> ideas); Brownstein, School Vouchers,<br />

supra note 95, at 927-29 (describing how weakening <strong>of</strong> Establishment Clause constraints on public funding<br />

<strong>of</strong> religious schools through voucher programs may result in the privileging <strong>of</strong> certain religious messages over<br />

others).<br />

[FN234]. See, e.g., James W. Fraser, Between Church and State: Religion & Public Education in Multicultural<br />

America 4 (1999) (noting that “[a]t the dawn <strong>of</strong> the new millenium the peoples <strong>of</strong> the United States are more<br />

secular, especially in their public culture, more religious, in many different private forms, and more diverse than<br />

ever before in the nation's history”); Nancy L. Rosenblum, Pluralism, Integralism, and Political <strong>The</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> <strong>Religious</strong><br />

Accommodation, Introduction to Obligations <strong>of</strong> Citizenship and Demands <strong>of</strong> Faith: <strong>Religious</strong> Accommodation<br />

in Pluralist Democracies 11-12 (Nancy L. Rosenblum ed., 2000) (explaining that “[I]n the United<br />

States,...the proliferation <strong>of</strong> faiths-- through schism, invention <strong>of</strong> new religions...and importation <strong>of</strong> nonwestern<br />

religions--is ceaseless. Today there are literally hundreds <strong>of</strong> religious sects”).<br />

[FN235]. Brownstein, Religion Clauses, supra note 95, at 281.<br />

[FN236]. See Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4.<br />

[FN237]. 406 U.S. 205 (1972).<br />

[FN238]. See Douglas Laycock, <strong>Free</strong> Exercise and the <strong>Religious</strong> <strong>Free</strong>dom Restoration Act, 62 Fordham L. Rev.<br />

883, 902 (1994).<br />

[FN239]. Smith, 494 U.S. at 881; Yoder, 406 U.S. at 233-34.<br />

[FN240]. Justice Souter's withering criticism <strong>of</strong> the idea in his dissent in Lukumi, 508 U.S. 520 (1993), states<br />

the problem succinctly:<br />

[i]f a hybrid claim is simply one in which another constitutional right is implicated, then the hybrid exception<br />

would probably be so vast as to swallow the Smith rule .... But if a hybrid claim is one in which a litigant<br />

would actually obtain an exemption from a formally neutral, generally applicable law under another constitutional<br />

provision, then there would have been no reason for the Court in what Smith calls the hybrid cases to have<br />

mentioned the <strong>Free</strong> Exercise Clause at all.<br />

Id. at 567 (Souter, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN241]. As at least one circuit judge has noted, “[n]o court would eagerly enter the jurisprudential thicket surrounding<br />

the intersection <strong>of</strong> First Amendment free exercise concerns [predicated on the hybrid rights exception<br />

to Smith] and civil rights created by fair housing laws” because “Smith itself is fraught with complexity both in<br />

doctrine and in practice.” Thomas v. Anchorage Equal Rights Comm'n, 220 F.3d 1134, 1147 (9th Cir. 2000) (en<br />

banc) (O'Scannlain, J., concurring).<br />

[FN242]. See, e.g., Knight v. Conn. Dep't <strong>of</strong> Pub. Health, 275 F.3d 156, 167 (2d Cir. 2001) (dismissing hybrid<br />

rights language in Smith as dicta in concluding that “[t]he allegation that a state action that regulates public con-<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 66<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

duct infringes more than one <strong>of</strong> a public employee's constitutional rights does not warrant more heightened scrutiny<br />

than each claim would warrant when viewed separately”); Kissinger v. Bd. <strong>of</strong> Trustees <strong>of</strong> Ohio State Univ.,<br />

5 F.3d 177, 180 (6th Cir. 1993) (refusing to apply heightened scrutiny to a hybrid rights situation); Salvation<br />

Army, 919 F.2d at 199-200 (holding that hybrid rights <strong>of</strong> free exercise and freedom <strong>of</strong> association do not<br />

provide additional protection against neutral law <strong>of</strong> general applicability than freedom <strong>of</strong> association right receives<br />

standing alone).<br />

[FN243]. See, e.g., Brown v. Hot, Sexy & Safer Productions, 68 F.3d 525, 539 (1st Cir. 1995) (dismissing hybrid<br />

rights claim because plaintiffs did not state a viable privacy or substantive due process claim); EEOC v.<br />

Catholic Univ. <strong>of</strong> Am., 83 F.3d 455, 467 (D.C. Cir. 1996) (finding that violation <strong>of</strong> Establishment Clause in conjunction<br />

with burden on free exercise rights constitutes hybrid rights situation).<br />

[FN244]. See, e.g., Thomas, 165 F.3d 362, reh'g granted, 220 F.3d 1134 (9th Cir. 2000) (en banc) (vacating decision<br />

finding violation <strong>of</strong> hybrid rights on ripeness grounds), cert. denied, 531 U.S. 1143 (2001).<br />

[FN245]. See, e.g., Swanson v. Guthrie Indep. Sch. Dist. Number I-L, 135 F.3d 694, 699-700 (10th Cir. 1998). It<br />

is not clear what courts mean when they refer to a “colorable” claim, however. In Swanson, for example, the<br />

court determined that the plaintiffs' right to direct the education <strong>of</strong> their children had not been infringed by the<br />

school district's decision allowing only full-time students to attend classes. <strong>The</strong>n, after concluding that<br />

“[p]laintiffs have shown no colorable claim <strong>of</strong> infringement on the constitutional right to direct a child's education,”<br />

the court explained, “[w]hatever the Smith hybrid-rights theory may ultimately mean, we believe that it at<br />

least requires a colorable showing <strong>of</strong> infringement <strong>of</strong> recognized and specific constitutional rights, rather than<br />

the mere invocation <strong>of</strong> a general right such as the right to control the education <strong>of</strong> one's child.” Id. at 700. Nothing<br />

in the court's analysis clarifies how one distinguishes a “colorable” showing <strong>of</strong> infringement <strong>of</strong> a specific<br />

right from one that is not “colorable.”<br />

Judge O'Scannlain's opinion in Thomas, 165 F.3d at 704-07, provides the most extensive discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> a “colorable” claim in the case law. Ultimately, however, he concludes that to be colorable “a<br />

hybrid-rights plaintiff must show a ‘fair probability'--a ‘likelihood'--<strong>of</strong> success on the merits <strong>of</strong> his companion<br />

claim.’' Id. at 706. O'Scannlain insists, however, that this does not mean that the companion claim has to be independently<br />

viable. Id. at 704. Unless he is suggesting that the court should never rule on the validity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

companion claim, it is hard to understand how these two conclusions can be reconciled. At some point, presumably,<br />

the court will evaluate the merits <strong>of</strong> the companion claim. If it is ultimately determined to be invalid, there<br />

is no longer any likelihood that it will succeed on the merits and the claim is no longer colorable for hybrid<br />

rights purposes.<br />

[FN246]. Thomas, 165 F.3d at 705-06.<br />

[FN247]. Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 481 (1988).<br />

[FN248]. 505 U.S. 833 (1992).<br />

[FN249]. See City <strong>of</strong> Ohio v. Akron Ctr. for Reprod. Health, Inc., 462 U.S. 416, 426 (1983) (holding unconstitutional<br />

an informed consent requirement); Thornburgh v. American Coll. <strong>of</strong> Obstetricians & Gynecologists, 476<br />

U.S. 747, 759-64 (1986) (invalidating informed consent under strict scrutiny). But see Casey, 505 U.S. at 870<br />

(upholding informed consent and 24-hour waiting period and thus overruling those parts <strong>of</strong> Akron and Thornburgh<br />

invalidating such statutes).<br />

Even Justice Scalia, the author <strong>of</strong> Smith, who cited laws burdening free exercise and free speech rights<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 67<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

as an example <strong>of</strong> a hybrid rights situation in that opinion, apparently no longer believes that hybrid free exercise/<br />

free speech cases should receive heightened review. In Watchtower Bible and Tract Soc'y <strong>of</strong> New York v. Village<br />

<strong>of</strong> Stratton, 536 U.S. 150 (2002), the Court struck down a village licensing ordinance that required individuals<br />

engaged in door to door canvassing to first register with and obtain a permit from municipal authorities.<br />

Plaintiffs in the case were Jehovah's Witnesses who challenged the law on both free exercise and free speech<br />

grounds. Justice Scalia concurred in the Court's judgment, but he made it explicitly clear that he believed the religious<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> plaintiffs' expressive activities were irrelevant to the Court's analysis and decision. Justice<br />

Scalia wrote, “If a licensing requirement is otherwise lawful, it is in my view not invalidated by the fact that<br />

some people will choose, for religious reasons, to forego speech rather than observe it. That would convert an<br />

invalid free-exercise claim, see Employment Div., Dept. <strong>of</strong> Human Resources <strong>of</strong> Ore. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872<br />

(1990), into a valid free-speech claim - and a more destructive one at that. Whereas the free exercise claim, if<br />

acknowledged, would merely exempt the Jehovah's Witnesses from the licencing requirement, the free-speech<br />

claim exempts everybody, thanks to the Jehovah's Witnesses.” Id. at 223.<br />

[FN250]. See generally Brownstein, State RFRA Statutes, supra note 34; see also discussion <strong>of</strong> Widmar, supra<br />

notes 50-59 and accompanying text.<br />

[FN251]. 374 U.S. 398 (1963).<br />

[FN252]. See, e.g., supra note 22.<br />

[FN253]. Smith, 494 U.S. at 884 (citing Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693, 708 (1986)).<br />

[FN254]. Cases and commentary supporting this position do not effectively explain whether they are interpreting<br />

the scope <strong>of</strong> the individualized assessment exception to the Smith holding or, instead, are interpreting the<br />

holding itself by defining what are generally applicable laws. Berg, for example, cites the individualized exception<br />

language in Smith to support his position. Thomas C. Berg, Slouching Toward Secularism: A Comment on<br />

Kiryas Joel School District v. Grumet, 44 Emory L.J. 433, 467 n.155 (1995). While Gedicks appears to recognize<br />

that granting <strong>of</strong>ficials unfettered discretion when the exercise <strong>of</strong> fundamental rights may be at issue raises<br />

constitutional questions standing alone, Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 115 n.170, he argues that this concern<br />

is derivative <strong>of</strong> a more basic principle condemning any underinclusive decisions that suggest unprotected<br />

secular interests are more highly valued than constitutionally protected religious interests. From this perspective,<br />

categorical exemptions that render a law underinclusive are at least as problematic as individualized exemptions.<br />

Id. at 118 n.180. Duncan agrees that the state's granting <strong>of</strong> exemptions to some secular claimants while rejecting<br />

comparable religious accommodations, whether individualized or categorical, raises constitutional questions that<br />

require strict review, but he construes the rule to be “a subset <strong>of</strong> the general applicability requirement” set out in<br />

Smith. Duncan, supra note 5, at 861.<br />

<strong>The</strong> case law is similarly indeterminate. In Fraternal Order <strong>of</strong> Police v. Newark, 170 F.3d 359, 365-66<br />

(3d Cir. 1999), for example, the court extends the principle expressed in Smith requiring heightened review in a<br />

system involving individualized exemptions to cover laws containing categorical exemptions. But it does not focus<br />

on the issue <strong>of</strong> general applicability. Instead, it suggests that the decision to deny a religious exemption from<br />

a regulation while recognizing at least one secular exemption “is sufficiently suggestive <strong>of</strong> discriminatory intent<br />

so as to trigger heightened scrutiny.” Id. at 365. In Rader v. Johnson, 924 F. Supp. 1540, 1551-52 (D. Neb.<br />

1996), on the other hand, the court expresses some doubt as to whether a free standing exception to Smith for individualized<br />

exemptions even exists. It applies heightened review to a governmental process involving individualized<br />

decisionmaking on the grounds that individualized exemptions are “one <strong>of</strong> several factors” to consider in<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 68<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

determining whether a law is generally applicable or not. Id. at 1552 n.24.<br />

[FN255]. See, e.g., Berg, Slouching, supra note 254, at 467; Douglas Laycock, <strong>The</strong> Remnants <strong>of</strong> <strong>Free</strong> Exercise,<br />

1990 Sup. Ct. Rev. 1, 48-51.<br />

[FN256]. See Berg, Slouching, supra note 254, at 467.<br />

[FN257]. See Volokh, Intermediate Questions, supra note 166, at 630-34; Volokh, A Common-Law Model,<br />

supra note 149, at 1539-42.<br />

[FN258]. Duncan, supra note 5.<br />

[FN259]. Id. at 863-67.<br />

[FN260]. Id. at 868.<br />

[FN261]. See, e.g., id. at 869-72 (discussing Rader v. Johnson, 924 F. Supp. 1540 (D. Neb. 1996)).<br />

[FN262]. 170 F.3d 359 (3d Cir. 1999), cert. denied, 528 U.S. 817 (1999).<br />

[FN263]. Id. at 365-66.<br />

[FN264]. Duncan, supra note 5, at 876-77.<br />

[FN265]. Id. at 877-79.<br />

[FN266]. Id. at 878.<br />

[FN267]. Id.<br />

[FN268]. Id. at 882 (citing Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 104-21). As Duncan recognizes, Gedicks does<br />

not believe this conclusion is established by Lukumi. Gedicks, Normalized, supra note 4, at 113-14. Gedicks argues<br />

that the Court should move in this direction.<br />

[FN269]. Duncan, supra note 5, at 878-79.<br />

[FN270]. Id. at 876.<br />

[FN271]. Restatement (Second) <strong>of</strong> Torts § 197 (1965).<br />

[FN272]. See Diaz v. Collins, 114 F.3d 69, 72 n.18 (5th Cir. 1997) (describing the religious significance <strong>of</strong> long<br />

hair in many Native American religions).<br />

[FN273]. One response to this argument is that the most favored nation analysis is not limited to particular laws.<br />

It applies with equal force to any state interest or purpose without regard to the number <strong>of</strong> specific regulations<br />

the state employs to advance that interest. Thus, if the state's goal is to promote the uniform appearance <strong>of</strong> police<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficers, that objective may be furthered by a range <strong>of</strong> regulations requiring daily shaving, haircuts, freshly<br />

laundered uniforms, regularly shined shoes, and prohibiting the wearing <strong>of</strong> buttons, or unauthorized headgear,<br />

etc. A secular exemption from any one <strong>of</strong> these regulations would require the state to grant religious exemptions<br />

to any or all laws serving a common purpose--unless the denial <strong>of</strong> the exemption could be justified under strict<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 69<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

scrutiny review. This rejoinder avoids some <strong>of</strong> the inequality inherent in a law-specific, most favored nation approach,<br />

but it does so at the cost <strong>of</strong> dramatically increasing the scope <strong>of</strong> the rule. As the number <strong>of</strong> laws to which<br />

the most favored nation approach applies increases, it becomes harder to explain why we should continue to uphold<br />

an ever-narrowing understanding <strong>of</strong> Smith rather than overrule the decision in its entirety.<br />

[FN274]. I realize that Duncan suggests that an exemption for medical marijuana does not render a law prohibiting<br />

the general use <strong>of</strong> marijuana underinclusive because the exception serves the same public health goal as the<br />

general regulation. Duncan, supra note 5, at 878. For the purposes <strong>of</strong> my hypothetical, let us assume that laws<br />

prohibiting the use <strong>of</strong> marijuana, wine, and peyote do not serve public health goals, but rather are grounded on<br />

other costs resulting from the abuse <strong>of</strong> such substances.<br />

[FN275]. 401 U.S. 437 (1971).<br />

[FN276]. Id. at 452.<br />

[FN277]. Id.<br />

[FN278]. FCC v. Beach Communications, Inc., 508 U.S. 307, 315 (1993) (quoting Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore<br />

Auto Parts Co., 410 U.S. 356, 364 (1973)).<br />

[FN279]. 472 U.S. 703 (1985).<br />

[FN280]. Id. at 711 (O'Connor, J., concurring).<br />

[FN281]. 456 U.S. 228 (1982).<br />

[FN282]. Id. at 244.<br />

[FN283]. Id. at 246.<br />

[FN284]. Id. at 247 n.23.<br />

[FN285]. Id.<br />

[FN286]. Id. at 261 (White, J., dissenting).<br />

[FN287]. Gillette, 401 U.S. at 450.<br />

[FN288]. Larson, 456 U.S. at 247 n.23.<br />

[FN289]. Welsh v. United States, 398 U.S. 333 (1970); United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1965).<br />

[FN290]. Larson, 456 U.S. at 254-55.<br />

[FN291]. See, e.g., Brownstein, Legislative Motive, supra note 109, at 44-52.<br />

[FN292]. 512 U.S. 687 (1994).<br />

[FN293]. Id. at 706.<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 70<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

[FN294]. Id. at 716-17 (O'Connor, J., concurring).<br />

[FN295]. Several lower courts, for example, have wrestled with the constitutionality <strong>of</strong> the federal government's<br />

decision to grant an exemption to Native American religions for the use <strong>of</strong> peyote while denying similar accommodations<br />

to religions that use marijuana in their ceremonies. Although the courts accepted the general principle<br />

that government could not discriminate among faiths, they upheld the refusal to provide exemptions for the religious<br />

use <strong>of</strong> marijuana on the grounds that it was not analogous to peyote, with regard to the government's reasons<br />

for restricting its use and because <strong>of</strong> the special relationship between the federal government and Native<br />

American tribes. See, e.g., Olsen v. Drug Enforcement Admin., 878 F.2d 1458 (D.C. Cir. 1989); McBride v.<br />

Shawnee County, 71 F. Supp. 2d 1098 (D. Kan. 1999).<br />

[FN296]. 93 N.Y.2d 677 (N.Y. 1999).<br />

[FN297]. 123 F.3d 1068 (8th Cir. 1997).<br />

[FN298]. 212 F.3d 1084 (8th Cir. 2000).<br />

[FN299]. Id. at 1091. See also Kong v. Min De Parle, No. C 00-4285 CRB, 2001 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 18772 at *13<br />

(N.D. Cal. Nov. 13, 2001) (noting that “[w]hile it is true that no facilities aside from Christian Science sanatoria<br />

presently qualify [for the challenged benefit], this fact alone does not make [the medicare provision] impermissibly<br />

discriminatory”).<br />

[FN300]. 109 Cal. Rptr. 2d 176 (Cal. Ct. App. 2001), reh'g granted, 31 P.3d 1271 (2001).<br />

[FN301]. Id. at 184.<br />

[FN302]. <strong>The</strong> issue here is distinguishable from the question <strong>of</strong> whether or not an organization is properly characterized<br />

as religious to determine its entitlement to an exception. Certainly, the very idea <strong>of</strong> a religious exemption<br />

presupposes some inquiry as to whether or not an institutional claimant is in fact religious in nature.<br />

But the legislative exemption at issue in Catholic Charities is a conscience clause, not an identity<br />

clause. It is questionable whether the California legislature's criteria would even be appropriate for the purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> distinguishing between religious and secular entities. <strong>The</strong> criteria are entirely irrational when the purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

the exemption is to protect rights <strong>of</strong> conscience.<br />

[FN303]. Id. at 201.<br />

[FN304]. Id. at 192.<br />

[FN305]. Id. at 190.<br />

[FN306]. Id. at 189.<br />

[FN307]. See Corporation <strong>of</strong> the Presiding Bishop <strong>of</strong> the Church <strong>of</strong> Jesus Christ <strong>of</strong> Latter-Day Saints v. Amos,<br />

483 U.S. 327 (1987) (upholding an exemption from Title VII permitting religious organizations to discriminate<br />

in hiring on the basis <strong>of</strong> religion because decisions about whom to hire and whether job functions involve religious<br />

obligations are so likely to reflect religious concerns).<br />

[FN308]. See, e.g., Kong, 2001 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 18772 (recognizing that Congress was responding to the needs<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.


18 JLPOL 119 Page 71<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

<strong>of</strong> Christian Scientists when it enacted religious accommodation in the Medicare statute).<br />

[FN309]. See, e.g. Teresa Stanton Collett, Heads, Secularists Win; Tails, Believers Lose--Returning Only <strong>Free</strong><br />

Exercise to the Political Process, 20 U. Ark. Little Rock L.J. 689, 714 (1998) (arguing that continued ambiguity<br />

concerning Establishment Clause constraints on religious exemptions “invariably will bias government <strong>of</strong>ficials<br />

toward no accommodation”).<br />

[FN310]. Smith must be overruled. See Adrian Goldsworthy, <strong>The</strong> Punic Wars 333 (2000) (quoting Marcus Porcius<br />

Cato, “Delenda Est Cathargo,” “Carthage must be destroyed”). “Smith improdandus est” or “Smith rejectiendus<br />

est” probably conveys the same idea. This language is anachronistic and out <strong>of</strong> context, according to<br />

Latin experts, but it provides an aesthetic parallel to Cato's Carthage quote. A more authentic expression that a<br />

medieval clerk might use to convey the idea is “Smith irretetur et pro nollo habeatu,” but it lacks the symmetry<br />

<strong>of</strong> the shorter statements.<br />

18 J.L. & Pol. 119<br />

END OF DOCUMENT<br />

© 2012 Thomson Reuters. No Claim to Orig. US Gov. Works.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!