16.11.2014 Views

Foundational Issues in Presupposition - New York University

Foundational Issues in Presupposition - New York University

Foundational Issues in Presupposition - New York University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Let’s beg<strong>in</strong> by look<strong>in</strong>g at some of the standard examples of the phenomenon we are <strong>in</strong>terested<br />

<strong>in</strong>. There is a long list of such examples: what follows is merely an illustrative sample. For a more<br />

complete list, see Lev<strong>in</strong>son (1983, ch.4).<br />

(8) Referential expressions/def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions<br />

The K<strong>in</strong>g of France has/hasn’t talked to Jane.<br />

Presuppose: There is a K<strong>in</strong>g of France, Jane exists.<br />

(9) Factives<br />

Jane regrets / does not regret that she <strong>in</strong>sulted the Provost.<br />

Presuppose: Jane <strong>in</strong>sulted the Provost.<br />

(10) Cleft sentences<br />

It was/wasn’t Jane who laughed.<br />

Presuppose: Someone laughed.<br />

(11) too<br />

Jane laughed / didn’t laugh too. [emphasis on Jane]<br />

Presuppose: Someone other than Jane laughed.<br />

(12) Implicative verbs<br />

Jane forgot / didn’t forget to lock the door.<br />

Presuppose: Jane <strong>in</strong>tended to lock the door.<br />

As this list shows, presuppositions are sometimes associated with a particular word or construction;<br />

<strong>in</strong> other cases, whole classes of items – such as factives, or def<strong>in</strong>ite descriptions – are associated<br />

with a particular type of presupposition. The nature of this “association” between lexical items and<br />

presuppositions is a matter of debate; we return to this issue below.<br />

In addition to survival under entailment-cancell<strong>in</strong>g operators, illustrated above, presuppositional<br />

implications are generally noted to have a cluster of further properties. The classical claim about<br />

presuppositions concerns truth value judgments: If a person believes any presupposition of an<br />

assertion to be false, she will consider it to be truth valueless; or at any rate, will consider that the<br />

issue of truth or falsity of the assertion “does not arise” (see Strawson 1956). However, truth value<br />

judgments are not robust, and have lost currency <strong>in</strong> the current literature as a way of identify<strong>in</strong>g<br />

presuppositions. (For discussion of this topic, see von F<strong>in</strong>tel 2004.)<br />

One characteristic of presuppositions is that the speaker of a presuppos<strong>in</strong>g utterance seems to<br />

“take the presupposition for granted.” A good deal of the theoriz<strong>in</strong>g about presupposition amounts<br />

to spell<strong>in</strong>g out just what that means; as a start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t, we might say that to produce an utterance<br />

with presupposition p is to <strong>in</strong>dicate that p is noncontroversial for you and your <strong>in</strong>terlocutors. Indeed,<br />

the standard l<strong>in</strong>e on presupposition is that utterance of a presuppos<strong>in</strong>g sentence is conversationally<br />

appropriate only if its presuppositions <strong>in</strong>deed are noncontroversial for you and your <strong>in</strong>terlocutors.<br />

On the other hand, it has been well documented that a speaker can use presuppositions to give<br />

new <strong>in</strong>formation to an addressee. The follow<strong>in</strong>g, for example, is a very natural case:<br />

(13) Ann: The new guy is very attractive.<br />

Bob: I’m sure his wife th<strong>in</strong>ks so too.<br />

-2-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!