20.12.2014 Views

Edinburgh Working Papers in Sociology Nick Prior (2000) ENLIGHTENMENT

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

School of Social and Political Studies<br />

<strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> <strong>Work<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>Papers</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Sociology</strong><br />

<strong>Work<strong>in</strong>g</strong> Paper No. 19<br />

<strong>Nick</strong> <strong>Prior</strong> (<strong>2000</strong>)<br />

THE ART OF CRITICISM:<br />

THE CRITIC AS ARBITER OF TASTE IN<br />

THE SCOTTISH <strong>ENLIGHTENMENT</strong><br />

http://www.sociology.ed.ac.uk/research/docs.html<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

ISBN: 1-900522-90-X


ABSTRACT<br />

This paper attempts to explore the relationship between art, criticism and civil<br />

society <strong>in</strong> Scotland <strong>in</strong> the late eighteenth century. It seeks to exam<strong>in</strong>e to what extent<br />

the emergence of aesthetic criticism served to establish taste cultures that marked the<br />

onset of cultural dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> the modern cultural field. Hume’s essay, “On the<br />

Standard of Taste” is highlighted, <strong>in</strong> particular, as key<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the emerg<strong>in</strong>g status of<br />

the critic as arbiter of taste <strong>in</strong> Scotland. The oscillation between the subjective and<br />

objective <strong>in</strong> standards of taste struck at the heart of the aesthetic problematic.<br />

Hume’s solution, which rested on the jo<strong>in</strong>t verdict of critics, was a projection of the<br />

social position of <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>’s literati <strong>in</strong> the late eighteenth century and of the<br />

grow<strong>in</strong>g complexity of the artistic field.<br />

<strong>Nick</strong> <strong>Prior</strong> is lecturer <strong>in</strong> <strong>Sociology</strong> at the University of <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>. He is the author of<br />

recent work on art museums, urban history and the cultural sociology of Pierre<br />

Bourdieu.<br />

1


THE ART OF CRITICISM: THE CRITIC AS<br />

ARBITER OF TASTE IN THE SCOTTISH<br />

<strong>ENLIGHTENMENT</strong><br />

<strong>Nick</strong> <strong>Prior</strong><br />

The Connoisseurs, David Allan, 1770s<br />

The basic configuration of ideas, discourses and <strong>in</strong>stitutions that supported modern<br />

artistic production was first assembled <strong>in</strong> the eighteenth century (Hauser, 1962;<br />

Mattick, 1993; Burg<strong>in</strong>, 1986; Crow, 1985). Throughout Europe, cultural fields<br />

emerged as relatively autonomous spheres of social practice through which art was<br />

marked off as a specialised sphere with its own <strong>in</strong>ternal laws and forms (Bourdieu,<br />

1993). The critic was a key figure <strong>in</strong> this process because his output was part of the<br />

discursive formulation of the modern matrix of art and its reception (Eagleton, 1990;<br />

Kivy, 1994). This paper attempts to explore the relationship between art, criticism<br />

and civil society <strong>in</strong> Scotland <strong>in</strong> the late eighteenth century. It seeks to exam<strong>in</strong>e to<br />

what extent the emergence of aesthetic criticism served to establish taste cultures that<br />

marked the onset of cultural dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> the modern cultural field.<br />

2


Raymond Williams notes <strong>in</strong> his Keywords that criticism developed from the<br />

seventeenth and eighteenth centuries as an orientation <strong>in</strong> literature towards taste,<br />

cultivation and discrim<strong>in</strong>ation that depended upon “judgement as the predom<strong>in</strong>ant<br />

and even natural response”. The role of the critic was bound up with the articulation<br />

of standards of taste, backed up by “the social confidence of a class and later a<br />

profession” (Williams, 1976: 75). As the body of ideas treat<strong>in</strong>g of “taste”, “beauty”<br />

and “art”, aesthetics became part of the movement away from antiquated relations of<br />

patronage and po<strong>in</strong>ted towards the construction of a modern object - the work of art.<br />

It helped to express the very ideology of art as a dist<strong>in</strong>ct entity to be apprehended <strong>in</strong><br />

and for itself, to be addressed as a specialised regime of value and practice (Eagleton,<br />

1990)<br />

This presupposed a new k<strong>in</strong>d of human subject whose orientation to the<br />

world - dis<strong>in</strong>terested, sensitive and delicate - would do most to discrim<strong>in</strong>ate between<br />

the “tasteful” and “vulgar” with<strong>in</strong> the universe of cultural objects. Aesthetics would<br />

beg<strong>in</strong>, therefore, to ask questions not merely of the rules of beauty <strong>in</strong> the construction<br />

of art works but of aesthetic experience from the position of the viewer, the person<br />

experienc<strong>in</strong>g beauty, the critic. The concept of taste was crucial to this endeavour<br />

because it signified the existence of an “<strong>in</strong>ner sense” that <strong>in</strong> its pure form, and<br />

possessed by the right type of critic, could recognise the transcendental value of<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> objects.<br />

The very existence of critics and a body of aesthetic thought, then, was an<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex of develop<strong>in</strong>g art worlds and <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> the appearance of “treatises”,<br />

“enquiries” and “essays” on relevant artistic subjects gives us the impression that this<br />

was a cultural field undergo<strong>in</strong>g significant growth (<strong>Prior</strong>, 1998; Macmillan, 1986).<br />

Indeed the convergence between the output of some of <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>’s writers and those<br />

on the cont<strong>in</strong>ent seems to express a k<strong>in</strong>d of “catch<strong>in</strong>g up” of <strong>in</strong>tellectual output <strong>in</strong><br />

Scotland’s capital. But who writes and why? As we might expect the key writers <strong>in</strong><br />

aesthetics were also those of the Scottish Enlightenment <strong>in</strong> general. 1 The eighteenth<br />

1 By the “Scottish Enlightenment” I take to mean the <strong>in</strong>tellectual outpour<strong>in</strong>g of modern ideas,<br />

practices and values based on modern “rational” precepts that swept away many of the older traditions<br />

of a feudal, religious and rural universe <strong>in</strong> lowland Scotland. The late eighteenth century <strong>in</strong> particular<br />

(considered as “the age of reason”, “the age of improvement”, or “the golden age”) was a period of<br />

<strong>in</strong>tense development founded on a bedrock of ideas regard<strong>in</strong>g improvement, education, understand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and toleration that spread beyond Scotland and England <strong>in</strong>to the very heart of European modernity<br />

(Rendall, 1978; Chitnis, 1976; Daiches, 1986; McElroy,1969; Phillipson, 1973a, 1973b; Lenman,<br />

3


century conta<strong>in</strong>ed the likes of Henry Kames, Francis Hutcheson, David Hume and<br />

Thomas Reid all writ<strong>in</strong>g substantial pieces on questions of taste, beauty and<br />

perception.<br />

Francis Hutcheson’s Inquiry <strong>in</strong>to the Orig<strong>in</strong>al of our Ideas of Beauty and<br />

Virtue, and Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, both of<br />

the 1720s, were probably the first tracts <strong>in</strong> Scotland to deal with aspects of taste and<br />

the idea of an “<strong>in</strong>ner sense”. His <strong>in</strong>fluence on aesthetics and moral philosophy as a<br />

whole <strong>in</strong> Scotland was considerable (Purviance, 1991; Kivy, 1976; Downie, 1994;<br />

Wilk<strong>in</strong>son, 1992; Daiches, 1986; Rendall, 1978). The Glasgow-based Hutcheson<br />

posited, as Shaftesbury had done, a relationship between a “natural” sense of moral<br />

good and the pleasures of the contemplation of poetry, pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, architecture or<br />

knowledge. Such a sense, he argued, was dist<strong>in</strong>ct from the enjoyment ga<strong>in</strong>ed from<br />

the immediacy of the “external senses”, such as those associated with the palate, as it<br />

was <strong>in</strong> the Kantian antipathy towards primal, bodily pleasures. The power to perceive<br />

ideas and works of beauty, which Hutcheson called “f<strong>in</strong>e genius or taste”<br />

(Hutcheson, IOB: 11) implied a displacement of the more “objective” criteria<br />

stipulated <strong>in</strong> the composed sets of directions for the standard rules of beauty and of<br />

mere rationality. “Internal sense”, <strong>in</strong>stead, was a maxim for taste or aesthetic<br />

appreciation which lived <strong>in</strong> the potentially subjective realm of feel<strong>in</strong>gs and<br />

perception.<br />

Hutcheson wrote of beauty as “the idea raised <strong>in</strong> us” (Hutcheson, IOB: 10)<br />

and <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so stressed the faculties of perceptual appreciation that the “<strong>in</strong>ternal<br />

sense” was able to capture. 2 This, of course, created new problems of consistency <strong>in</strong><br />

the construction of a system of universal standards that Enlightenment th<strong>in</strong>kers all<br />

over Europe still desired: the endur<strong>in</strong>g notion that the classics appealed to all<br />

historical periods, for <strong>in</strong>stance. How, then, could the emphasis on the mechanics of<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual perception be squared with the idea of a “correct” or “universal” taste that<br />

transcended subjectivity? This was the question that reached to the heart of the<br />

aesthetic problematic as it unfolded <strong>in</strong> the eighteenth century: Scotland was no<br />

exception.<br />

1981; Dev<strong>in</strong>e, 1990; Smout, 1969).<br />

2 Or as Hutcheson himself puts it: “All beauty is relative to the sense of some m<strong>in</strong>d perceiv<strong>in</strong>g it”<br />

(Hutcheson, IOB: 23).<br />

4


Thomas Reid, the “common-sense” philosopher, professional cleric and critic<br />

of Hume’s scepticism, was another Glasgow-based philosopher who dwelt on<br />

aesthetic matters. Reid was appo<strong>in</strong>ted to the Chair of Moral Philosophy at Glasgow<br />

University <strong>in</strong> 1764 and wrote Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (1785),<br />

Essays on the Active Powers of Man (1788), Inquiry <strong>in</strong>to the Human M<strong>in</strong>d (1764)<br />

and Lectures on F<strong>in</strong>e Arts (1774). All of these posed questions on perception and<br />

beauty <strong>in</strong> a manner rem<strong>in</strong>iscent of Hutcheson. While never abandon<strong>in</strong>g the thesis<br />

that beauty resides <strong>in</strong> the objective matter of certa<strong>in</strong> objects, Reid traced the<br />

production of an aesthetic response <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d of the perceiver.<br />

Beauty appeared as objective <strong>in</strong> Reid’s analyses to the extent that it expressed<br />

some mental excellence, some “orig<strong>in</strong>al pr<strong>in</strong>ciple” of human nature. Objects are<br />

beautiful, <strong>in</strong> other words, when they come to express certa<strong>in</strong> perfections of the m<strong>in</strong>d<br />

(Nauckhoff, 1994). So, a pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is beautiful, for Reid, when it represents “the<br />

passions and dispositions of men <strong>in</strong> the attitudes and countenances” (Reid, LFA, 50).<br />

Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gs which depict a relaxed and languid repose derive their beauty from<br />

signification of natural signs of ease which themselves express a k<strong>in</strong>d of passion of<br />

human sentiment. “We do not” writes Nauckhoff, summaris<strong>in</strong>g Reid, “attribute<br />

beauty to the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g on the basis of how it makes us feel; neither do we look beh<strong>in</strong>d<br />

it to the artist’s frame of m<strong>in</strong>d. Rather, it is the passion itself, which we attend to: we<br />

apprehend ease itself, through its natural signs. Beauty, then, resides ‘<strong>in</strong>’ the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> the sense that the pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g represents signs which <strong>in</strong> turn express perfections of the<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d” (Nauckhoff, 1994: 187). Aesthetic pleasure was not, here, a matter of<br />

corporeal sense as <strong>in</strong> the literal mean<strong>in</strong>g of “taste” but resided, for Reid, <strong>in</strong> a last<strong>in</strong>g<br />

disposition or quality of perception that <strong>in</strong>dicated an “<strong>in</strong>ternal sense”. Indeed, it was<br />

this formulation that <strong>in</strong>formed the portraitist, Henry Raeburn’s pa<strong>in</strong>terly excursions<br />

<strong>in</strong>to the role of perception and his rejection of the abstract and ideal.<br />

The very presence of th<strong>in</strong>kers such as Reid, who wrote and published on<br />

questions which had a bear<strong>in</strong>g on artistic practice, could not fail to energise the local<br />

artistic field as a whole. <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> was beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to witness an explosion <strong>in</strong><br />

criticism the likes of which it had never seen. Figures like Lord Kames, James<br />

Beattie, Alexander Gerard, Allan Ramsay, Hugh Blair and Archibald Alison, the<br />

latter a friend of Henry Raeburn, wrote various amounts on aspects of taste, mostly<br />

5


<strong>in</strong> relation to moral philosophy. This all helped to def<strong>in</strong>e the space of the critic <strong>in</strong><br />

relation both to the modern public and the universe of propriety by the second half of<br />

the eighteenth century. By rais<strong>in</strong>g modern questions on the status of the artistic<br />

object, on the issue of the particularity of taste, and on the role of the observer, the<br />

critic moved <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>to the seat of judgement.<br />

Hence, the “public” dimension to writ<strong>in</strong>g had taken on an air of “socialized<br />

dependence” as writers sought public legitimation for their efforts <strong>in</strong> civil society<br />

(Berry, 1997). Hume, for <strong>in</strong>stance, regularly gauged the success of his books <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> and mulled over the public’s reaction to his Treatise on Human Nature.<br />

Greater responsiveness to the world of op<strong>in</strong>ion connected with the display of taste<br />

that was important to this class of critics: the desire to express discrim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong><br />

literature as well as manners, furniture as well as poetry, art as well as food. The<br />

public world of debate and reception which took off by the mid-eighteenth century<br />

delivered to aesthetic criticism a role that began to meld it to the cultural field as a<br />

whole. While <strong>in</strong> no way did criticism <strong>in</strong> eighteenth-century <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> exhibit the<br />

normative power of its modern n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-century counterpart, critics did at least<br />

beg<strong>in</strong> to contribute to the symbolic value of certa<strong>in</strong> cultural forms and products,<br />

consecrat<strong>in</strong>g works which fitted with the ideals of a classical education <strong>in</strong> particular.<br />

Moreover, critics began to occupy a space with<strong>in</strong> the field that was structurally and<br />

functionally homologous with the audience for which they wrote.<br />

Lord Kames, for <strong>in</strong>stance, a central figure <strong>in</strong> the agricultural modernisation of<br />

Scotland, turned his critical acumen to aspects of classical literature and aesthetics,<br />

and <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so pitted the <strong>in</strong>sights of the critic aga<strong>in</strong>st the vulgar, ignorant and<br />

“deformed”. 3 Elements of Criticism was published <strong>in</strong> 1762, to Voltaire’s rather<br />

critical reception, and placed Kames with<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tellectual field of the European<br />

literati. His theoretical <strong>in</strong>terventions <strong>in</strong>to aesthetics and literary criticism, however,<br />

also marked the impulse to ref<strong>in</strong>ement, polished manners and cultural civility that, <strong>in</strong><br />

his own view, was beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to strengthen <strong>in</strong> Scotland:<br />

It is an admirable sign of the progress of the human spirit that we should have com<strong>in</strong>g from Scotland<br />

3 Kames was born <strong>in</strong> 1696 <strong>in</strong>to a wealthy Berwickshire landown<strong>in</strong>g family. He became Lord of<br />

Justiciary <strong>in</strong> 1763, and ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed close companionship with David Hume. His contributions to legal<br />

theory, to the various clubs and societies <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> and to “national improvement” <strong>in</strong> general, has<br />

been noted by Lehmann, among others (Lehmann, 1971).<br />

6


today rules of taste <strong>in</strong> all the arts, from the epic poem to garden<strong>in</strong>g. L’esprit huma<strong>in</strong> is extend<strong>in</strong>g itself<br />

every day, and we need not despair of very soon receiv<strong>in</strong>g treatises on poetics and rhetoric from the<br />

Orkney Islands (quoted <strong>in</strong> Lehmann, 1971: 44-5).<br />

The role of the “rational science of criticism”, here, was itself to cultivate “to a high<br />

degree of ref<strong>in</strong>ement...the heart no less than the understand<strong>in</strong>g” (ibid.: 222-23). And,<br />

for Kames, the basis to all aspects of taste was a naturally derived human capacity<br />

which could be studied empirically and through the faculties of reason. Hence, the<br />

uncerta<strong>in</strong>ties that various other writers encountered <strong>in</strong> the establishment of taste was<br />

by-passed <strong>in</strong> Kames’ view to the extent that a valid and universally acknowledged<br />

standard of taste with <strong>in</strong>dependent ontological status was posited. In literature this<br />

was expressed <strong>in</strong> the valorisation of the classics: Cicero, Virgil and Homer, as well<br />

as Shakespeare, Addison and Macpherson’s Ossian.<br />

Kames concentrated on rhetoric and literature more than on pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g or music<br />

and over half of Elements of Criticism comprised a psychological analysis of various<br />

human sentiments and passions embodied <strong>in</strong> the classical tenets of literature. 4 The<br />

confidence with which the potential variations of taste and quality are reduced to a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle standard of taste is testament to the belief <strong>in</strong> the “natural” superiority of<br />

Kames’ aristocratic ties (as compared to the less certa<strong>in</strong> position of some of the more<br />

“bourgeois” critics, for <strong>in</strong>stance). If great literature was transcendental, if it passed<br />

the test of time, it was only critics possessed of the knowledge, leisure time and taste<br />

that were able reveal this transcendence. Kames was unequivocal <strong>in</strong> this. Only those<br />

with ref<strong>in</strong>ed sensibilities and a classical education would fit the bill. We should not,<br />

he exclaimed, refer to everyone’s op<strong>in</strong>ion equally. The “greater part of mank<strong>in</strong>d”,<br />

those who rely for their livelihoods on “bodily labour” should be excluded because<br />

they lack any k<strong>in</strong>d of taste so far as “f<strong>in</strong>e arts is concerned” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Berry, 1997:<br />

178).<br />

Like elsewhere, therefore, the critic as arbiter of taste <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> worked<br />

with the logic of dist<strong>in</strong>ction and distanciation that began to take shape <strong>in</strong> the realm of<br />

civil society. The critic established standards of taste that marked the ability of this<br />

class to “play the game” of criticism and aesthetic appreciation (Bourdieu, 1993).<br />

4 The book was received well <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> and was lauded for its “very extensive erudition, the many<br />

nice and accurate criticisms <strong>in</strong>terspersed throughout, [show<strong>in</strong>g] with what close attention and ref<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

taste he has perused the most admirable authors, both ancient and modern” (Scottish Literary Review,<br />

quoted <strong>in</strong> Lehmann, 1971: 228).<br />

7


Taste <strong>in</strong> the arts allowed the aristocracy and literati to mark their membership of this<br />

“polished” or “civilized” urban public. On the one hand, “high culture”, <strong>in</strong> its nascent<br />

form, was identified with (and appropriated by) the block of cultural and <strong>in</strong>tellectual<br />

leaders that emerged <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> from the middle to late eighteenth century<br />

(Phillipson, 1973; 1975). On the other hand, part of the def<strong>in</strong>ition of a ref<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

culture, and of civil society as a whole, was the construction of its opposite - the<br />

vulgar, deformed, bodily and ignorant. It was <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>’s enlightenment precepts,<br />

for <strong>in</strong>stance, that underp<strong>in</strong>ned the gradual <strong>in</strong>stitutionalisation of the mad, the sad and<br />

the bad <strong>in</strong> purpose-built spaces such as asylums, prisons, cl<strong>in</strong>ics and asylums<br />

(Markus, 1993). A codification of the lower “other” was similarly reiterated <strong>in</strong> the<br />

emerg<strong>in</strong>g spaces of the public sphere. The very def<strong>in</strong>ition of “civil society” written<br />

for the <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>-based Encyclopedia Britannica of 1771 is sufficient to make the<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t:<br />

The welfare, nay, the nature of civil society, requires that there should be a subord<strong>in</strong>ation of orders or<br />

diversity of ranks and conditions <strong>in</strong> it; - that certa<strong>in</strong> men, or orders of men, be appo<strong>in</strong>ted to<br />

super<strong>in</strong>tend and manage such affairs as concerns the public and happ<strong>in</strong>ess...The superiority of the<br />

higher orders, or the authority with which the state has <strong>in</strong>vested them, entitle them, especially if they<br />

employ their authority well, to the obedience and submission of the lower, and to a proportionate<br />

honour and respect from all. The subord<strong>in</strong>ation of the lower ranks claims protection, defence, and<br />

security from the higher...Public spirit, heroic zeal, love of liberty, and the other political duties, do,<br />

above all others, recommend those who practise them to the admiration and homage of mank<strong>in</strong>d;<br />

because, as they are the offspr<strong>in</strong>g of the noblest m<strong>in</strong>ds, so they are the parents of the greatest bless<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

to society (1771, vol. iii. 295, my emphasis).<br />

All of which br<strong>in</strong>gs us to why Hume’s problematic <strong>in</strong> the essay “On the Standard of<br />

Taste” is such a powerful expression of the project of the literati to atta<strong>in</strong> social and<br />

cultural leadership <strong>in</strong> the second half of the eighteenth century. While it may be<br />

<strong>in</strong>appropriate to disengage Hume from the British context as a whole (his<br />

philosophical conversations with Shaftesbury, Addison and Locke are of course<br />

formative) it should be recognised that Hume’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs had an effect on the local<br />

field <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>. His writ<strong>in</strong>gs were published <strong>in</strong> the capital and his presence <strong>in</strong> the<br />

city was a constant stimulus to other writers and practitioners - Allan Ramsay fitt<strong>in</strong>g<br />

both categories here. Further, his connections with cont<strong>in</strong>ental thought when<br />

transposed to <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>’s civic landscape can not have failed to ignite the sparks of<br />

ideational complexity that aesthetics were beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to show <strong>in</strong> the capital. So while<br />

Kant writes of Hume’s <strong>in</strong>fluence as follows: “it was David Hume’s remark<br />

8


that...<strong>in</strong>terrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave a completely different direction to<br />

my enquiries <strong>in</strong> the field of speculative philosophy” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Wilk<strong>in</strong>son, 1992:<br />

236), the effect of these same writ<strong>in</strong>gs on the more local environment should not go<br />

unnoticed.<br />

Criticism was a subject identified <strong>in</strong> Hume’s preface to the Treatise on<br />

Human Nature that the “science of man” would raise to the heights of excellence.<br />

Like many other established writers of the Enlightenment, Hume was concerned to<br />

reveal certa<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of criticism and their relationship to standards of taste.<br />

Hume’s social circle <strong>in</strong>cluded many of the Scottish writers mentioned above whose<br />

civic impulse to socialise, discuss and improve always reta<strong>in</strong>ed the idea of a natural<br />

public of common professionals, men of letters and taste. To this extent, a<br />

community of cultural association promoted the idea of the critic as a natural leader<br />

<strong>in</strong> matters of taste, but a critic who was representative of a consensus view. 5<br />

In Hume’s aesthetics, the will-to-consensus was a deeply rooted desire to<br />

establish a constituency of spokesmen who would represent the dis<strong>in</strong>terested ideal of<br />

taste. Just as art struggled to be set apart from skill or abundance and took on the<br />

qualities of a sensibility <strong>in</strong> Scotland, so virtue l<strong>in</strong>ked <strong>in</strong> with a taste for the beautiful,<br />

civil and ref<strong>in</strong>ed: that which marked the character of the gentleman and philosopher.<br />

Questions of taste, beauty and aesthetics are posed <strong>in</strong> many of Hume’s<br />

writ<strong>in</strong>gs of the 1740s and 50s. The publication of Essays, Moral and Political <strong>in</strong><br />

1741, with new essays added throughout this decade, displayed a heavily aesthetic<br />

agenda with<strong>in</strong> the context of moral philosophy. By 1758 the study had been renamed<br />

Essays, Moral, Political and Literary and <strong>in</strong>cluded Hume’s key account “Of<br />

the Standard of Taste”. This essay added to the comments already made <strong>in</strong> essays<br />

such as: “Of the Delicacy of Taste and Passion”, “Of the Rise and Progress of the<br />

Arts and Sciences”, and “Of Ref<strong>in</strong>ement <strong>in</strong> the Arts”. “Arts” <strong>in</strong> this context still bore<br />

the relatively undifferentiated status of human skill and the humanities, but there are<br />

enough comments <strong>in</strong> these essays allud<strong>in</strong>g to a develop<strong>in</strong>g sphere of “high culture”<br />

5 The importance of such an agreement can also be seen <strong>in</strong> the thought of Enlightenment figures such<br />

as Hutcheson, whose community of common sentiment was dependent on the <strong>in</strong>tersubjectively shared<br />

judgements of its members (Purviance, 1991), as well as <strong>in</strong> Kant himself <strong>in</strong> the form of the sensus<br />

communis. The role of the “impartial spectator”, similarly, for Adam Smith was “to prevent those<br />

contradictions and arrive at a more stable judgment of th<strong>in</strong>gs, we fix on some steady and general po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

of view, and always <strong>in</strong> our thoughts, place ourselves <strong>in</strong> them, whatever may be our general situation”<br />

(quoted <strong>in</strong> Becker, 1994: 56).<br />

9


to warrant critical attention. This is particularly apparent <strong>in</strong> Hume’s comments on<br />

taste (<strong>in</strong> the later essays, for <strong>in</strong>stance) where the “polite” and “f<strong>in</strong>er” arts, are placed<br />

alongside ideas of “genius”, and a “true standard of taste”. 6<br />

Despite the age-old recognition that artistic judgments varied - de gustibus<br />

non disputandum est - this maxim was vitiated <strong>in</strong> the movement towards a “natural”<br />

standard of taste, a rule by which the various sentiments of “men” may be<br />

harmonised. Put another way, the potential subjectivity that was raised <strong>in</strong> the<br />

acceptance of a perceptual dimension to the reception of beauty was immediately put<br />

down <strong>in</strong> favour of “real matters of fact” that signified an endur<strong>in</strong>g standard. For<br />

Hume, underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g critical acumen were certa<strong>in</strong> possessions, of which he mentions<br />

five: “strong sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by<br />

comparison and cleared of all prejudice” (Hume, EMP: 241). When <strong>in</strong>dividuals who<br />

have these characteristics agree upon aesthetic judgements, that agreement “is the<br />

standard of taste and beauty”. Tautologically posed, good art was what critics agreed<br />

upon and a critic with taste was one who def<strong>in</strong>ed good art. To achieve the required<br />

sentiment towards works of art, Hume, like those before him, <strong>in</strong>voked the “<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

sense” (“strong sense” as it is termed <strong>in</strong> Hume’s five dispositions) possessed by<br />

some men with “delicacy of taste” to appreciate the subtleties of beauty and the<br />

deformities of lesser works:<br />

There is a delicacy of taste observable <strong>in</strong> some men, which very much resembles this delicacy of<br />

passion, and produces the same sensibility to beauty and deformity of every k<strong>in</strong>d, as that does to<br />

prosperity and adversity, obligations and <strong>in</strong>juries. When you present a poem or a picture to a man<br />

possessed of this talent, the delicacy of his feel<strong>in</strong>g makes him be sensibly touched with every part of<br />

it; nor are the masterly strokes perceived with more exquisite relish and satisfaction, than the<br />

negligences or absurdities with disgust and uneas<strong>in</strong>ess (Hume, EMP: 4).<br />

Hume’s aim, <strong>in</strong> a nutshell, was to f<strong>in</strong>d a logical l<strong>in</strong>k between the existence of a<br />

“correct taste” which underwrote the timeless appeal of the classics, with this theory<br />

of an “<strong>in</strong>ner sense”. For the latter theory did not sit well with static “rules of art”,<br />

with the idea of a “durable admiration, which attends those works, that have survived<br />

all the caprices of mode and fashion, all the mistakes of ignorance and envy” (Hume,<br />

EMP: 233). The dilemma seemed to be compounded by the apparent lack of<br />

6 Hume does write about “pictures” but not <strong>in</strong> much detail; his examples tend to be drawn from poetry<br />

and literature.<br />

10


agreement amongst Hume’s fellow critics as to what qualities aesthetic objects must<br />

have to make them tasteful. For Addison it was the sublime, novelty and beauty; for<br />

Shaftesbury it was harmony and proportion; for Hutcheson it was “uniformity amidst<br />

variety”; and for Kames it was objective classical beauty. Hume tried to reconcile<br />

and unite these potential differences by putt<strong>in</strong>g his trust <strong>in</strong> a constant feature of<br />

human nature, cast <strong>in</strong> terms of the “<strong>in</strong>ner sense”, but which on occasions was subject<br />

to <strong>in</strong>terference from other factors and which rema<strong>in</strong> ill-def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the essay. 7 In the<br />

last analysis, however, it was still the ideal community of critics who reta<strong>in</strong>ed the<br />

power to judge, because, <strong>in</strong> Hume’s view, a true judge can never be wrong. 8 The<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>t verdict of such critics, arrived at through acts of reason and discussion so<br />

carefully represented <strong>in</strong> Allan’s picture The Connoisseurs, determ<strong>in</strong>ed the “true<br />

standard of taste and beauty” (Hume, EMP: 241). Indeed by the end of the essay<br />

Hume was much more confident <strong>in</strong> this assertion, as he was <strong>in</strong> the existence of<br />

“correct” and “<strong>in</strong>correct” tastes:<br />

Though men of delicate taste be rare, they are easily to be dist<strong>in</strong>guished <strong>in</strong> society, by the soundness<br />

of their understand<strong>in</strong>g and the superiority of their faculties above the rest of mank<strong>in</strong>d...The general<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of taste are uniform <strong>in</strong> human nature: Where men vary <strong>in</strong> their judgments, some defect or<br />

perversion <strong>in</strong> the faculties may commonly be remarked; proceed<strong>in</strong>g either from prejudice, from want<br />

of practice, or want of delicacy; and there is just reason for approv<strong>in</strong>g one taste, and condemn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

another (Hume, EMP: 243).<br />

Now, many commentators have mused on the oscillation <strong>in</strong> Hume’s “Of the Standard<br />

of Taste” between the “objectivity thesis” (that there are def<strong>in</strong>ite rules and standards<br />

of artistic taste à la classicism) and the “subjectivity thesis” (that beauty must also<br />

reside <strong>in</strong> what the perceiver br<strong>in</strong>gs to the encounter with art – what Hume calls<br />

“understand<strong>in</strong>g”) (Sh<strong>in</strong>er, 1996; Perricone, 1995; Noel, 1994; Gracyk, 1994; Shelley,<br />

1994). What these accounts fail to mention, however, are the social and ideological,<br />

rather than philosophical, exigencies, which made it a priority for Hume to reta<strong>in</strong><br />

both the objective and subjective <strong>in</strong> relation to questions of judgement. Clearly, if<br />

7 Wilk<strong>in</strong>son, for <strong>in</strong>stance, manages to summarise Hume’s position as follows: “S<strong>in</strong>ce there is an<br />

<strong>in</strong>variant structure of <strong>in</strong>ner sense, the only way to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stances of divergent aesthetic judgment is<br />

to suppose that the operations of the <strong>in</strong>ner sense have been disrupted by other factors. (If on a given<br />

occasion you judge Virgil to be dull, the fault is <strong>in</strong> you, not Virgil)” (Wilk<strong>in</strong>son, 1992: 237). Still,<br />

Wilk<strong>in</strong>son is as vague as Hume as to what these disruptions might be.<br />

8 To this extent Hume’s “double standard of taste” - that of the rules of art and that of the jo<strong>in</strong>t verdict<br />

of critics - cannot conflict given the true judge’s perfection. Or as Shelley puts it: “correctly<br />

formulated rules of art turn out simply to be the rules accord<strong>in</strong>g to which the critical faculty of a true<br />

judge operates” (Shelley, 1994, 441).<br />

11


one belongs to a newly emerg<strong>in</strong>g cultural and <strong>in</strong>tellectual elite whose dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

rests on a propensity <strong>in</strong> matters of civility and high culture, then one would need to<br />

reta<strong>in</strong> a role <strong>in</strong> civil society for such a community. But what role is there <strong>in</strong> matters<br />

of taste if either a) the rules of art and beauty yield so easily to mere reason; that<br />

aesthetics was no different to any other scientific undertak<strong>in</strong>g, or b) questions of<br />

judgement were relative and phenomenological; that aesthetics was a matter of<br />

“anyth<strong>in</strong>g goes”? Hume plumps for a middle ground between these two positions,<br />

often draw<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> aspects of both, precisely because the critics he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d would<br />

be perceptive and “delicate <strong>in</strong> taste” and yet would also discover or gravitate to a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> regularity <strong>in</strong> matters of beauty, the laws of which exist outside of him. Hume,<br />

<strong>in</strong> other words, projects his own social position <strong>in</strong>to the solution to the problem of<br />

aesthetics by affirm<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> the last analysis, the natural foundational uniformity of his<br />

class.<br />

Introduc<strong>in</strong>g the question of the sociological with<strong>in</strong> the aesthetic this way<br />

reveals the project of all the critics mentioned to have a socio-genesis and function<br />

with<strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>choate bourgeois public sphere. The will-to-consensus, to judgement, to<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction and to distanciation arose both from the literati’s position with<strong>in</strong> the field,<br />

and, homologously, from their own social backgrounds. The ideal connoisseur <strong>in</strong><br />

each case was someone with education, leisure and wealth; <strong>in</strong> short, a member of the<br />

aristocratic and professional classes. 9 Like Kant, Hume stressed the critical<br />

prerequisite of “dis<strong>in</strong>terestedness”: he essentialised the ideal of a “m<strong>in</strong>d free from all<br />

prejudice”, which contemplated noth<strong>in</strong>g but the work of art itself - “the very object<br />

which is submitted to his exam<strong>in</strong>ation” (Hume, EMP: 239). Clearly, this faculty was<br />

a product of the educated habitus (Bourdieu, 1977), of the socio-economically<br />

privileged, whose distance from labour and whose level of exposure to the requisite<br />

cultural works predisposed them to speak of certa<strong>in</strong> standards, taste preferences and<br />

orientations towards the pure object.<br />

While the likes of Hutcheson, Reid, Kames and Hume appeared to<br />

9 Indeed that Hume privileges the professional middle class is apparent <strong>in</strong> his essay “Of the Middle<br />

Station of Life”. This social position is conducive to virtue, ambition and happ<strong>in</strong>ess, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

Hume, foster<strong>in</strong>g advancements <strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g and the arts. In this it is dist<strong>in</strong>guished both from the<br />

miseries of the low, who are “too much occupy’d <strong>in</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g for the Necessities of Life, to hearken<br />

to the calm Voice of Reason” (Hume, EMP: 546), and from the excesses of the “great” - “There are<br />

more natural Parts, and a stronger Genius requisite to make a good Lawyer or Physician, than to make<br />

a great Monarch”, (Hume, EMP: 548).<br />

12


acknowledge the role of society and culture <strong>in</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g the proper exercise of taste<br />

- one half of the Enlightenment project of education, democratisation and<br />

improvement - they simultaneously disavowed this role by constantly referr<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

“universal and natural standards”, to “general pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of taste...uniform <strong>in</strong> human<br />

nature” (Hume, EMP: 249) and to a commonality of human cognition, free from all<br />

social difference and <strong>in</strong>fluence. Hume writes <strong>in</strong> “Delicacy of Taste”, for <strong>in</strong>stance:<br />

“we are pretty much masters what books we shall read, what diversions we shall<br />

partake of, and what company we shall keep” (Hume, EMP: 5). If taste is <strong>in</strong> some<br />

sense socio-historically detached, then civil society’s prevalent aesthetic judgements<br />

atta<strong>in</strong> the status of natural or ontological givens rather than provisional and<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>gent products of history. In order to by-pass the problem of aesthetics all that<br />

Hume needed, as Shusterman notes, was an “<strong>in</strong>tersubjectively shared” objective<br />

standard: “His deep purpose, a purpose he himself did not fully fathom, was social<br />

stability under the aegis of the <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly ascendant bourgeoisie and its liberal<br />

ideology” (Shusterman, 1993: 102).<br />

Like other critics of the eighteenth century, Hume’s community of taste was<br />

one separate from the feudal order of absolutism, of the judgements of s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

tyrannical leaders; but also one <strong>in</strong> contradist<strong>in</strong>ction to the vulgar pleasures of lower<br />

constituencies. In Hume this took the form of a rejection of “prejudice”, “<strong>in</strong>terest”,<br />

“labour” and “barbarism”; <strong>in</strong> Kames it was the “exclusion of classes so many and<br />

numerous [which] reduces with<strong>in</strong> a narrow compass those who are qualified to be<br />

judges <strong>in</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>e arts” (quoted <strong>in</strong> Shusterman, 1993: 107). In Smith’s Theory of<br />

Moral Sentiments (1759), on the other hand, the advancement of a consensual mode<br />

of perception and solidarity among members of the new elite turned on the idea that<br />

the useful, mechanical, bodily and detailed should be excluded from the aesthetic<br />

process. What def<strong>in</strong>ed the “impartial spectator” here was the suppression of the<br />

“other”- bodily appetites, for <strong>in</strong>stance - which were considered antithetical to proper<br />

citizenship and judgement. Indeed, the exclusion of women from this public universe<br />

of taste, criticism and citizenship may well have been bound up with the denial of the<br />

particular (Bohls, 1993). 10<br />

10 Bohls l<strong>in</strong>ks the set of ideas <strong>in</strong>form<strong>in</strong>g the civic humanist ideal (the male citizen who abstractly<br />

contemplates the aesthetic object à la Reynolds) with a corollary movement to suppress sense<br />

gratification, private <strong>in</strong>terest and the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. The ideational connections made between women and<br />

13


So while taste is considered to be pure when devoid of “fever”, “disease” or<br />

other aberrational <strong>in</strong>terferences, giv<strong>in</strong>g it a natural quality, it is clear that the “true<br />

judge” is not some primal savage or <strong>in</strong>nocent but a highly educated and tra<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

(male) <strong>in</strong>dividual with an abundance of cultural capital. “For what is the requisite<br />

practice, comparison, and good sense of Hume’s critic”, asks Shusterman, “except<br />

for the achievement and exercise of dispositions (socially acquired and ref<strong>in</strong>ed) to<br />

react to the right objects <strong>in</strong> the culturally right way or to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> ways that society<br />

regards as reasonable?” (Shusterman, 1993: 105). And although the de-particularized<br />

framework of art and contemplation did not catch on <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> as much as it did<br />

<strong>in</strong> London due to the lack of a central Royal academy like Reynolds’, and of the<br />

greater aristocracy to support such a view, elements of such a powerful ideology did<br />

leak <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>in</strong>stitutions and discourses of enlightened <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> - <strong>in</strong> landscape<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as well as criticism, for <strong>in</strong>stance (<strong>Prior</strong>, 1998).<br />

To conclude, then. What criticism did <strong>in</strong> the capital was take up a space<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the public sphere: it articulated a new system of aesthetics and supported the<br />

erasure of an older, patronal system. The critic helped to provide the ideational<br />

catalyst for a more modern system of f<strong>in</strong>e art <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>, by consecrat<strong>in</strong>g the idea<br />

of art as an object <strong>in</strong> itself. Hume, Kames, Hutcheson and Reid all, therefore, played<br />

their part <strong>in</strong> stimulat<strong>in</strong>g the theory and practice of art. For the first time <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>,<br />

treatises and essays constituted a new object <strong>in</strong> discourse - the monadic art object,<br />

relatively autonomous from previous rules of beauty and religious directives.<br />

Criticism also expressed the priorities of an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly confident middle class,<br />

backed by an aristocracy, whose aim it was to dist<strong>in</strong>guish itself as a block of natural<br />

leaders, from above and below. If Enlightenment and civil society meant open<strong>in</strong>g up,<br />

it also meant clos<strong>in</strong>g down; its dynamic was both democratic and elitist; its public<br />

was modern but exclusive; its priorities were not merely to educate and ref<strong>in</strong>e but to<br />

distanciate and dist<strong>in</strong>guish. This brought it <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>e with cultural trends elsewhere <strong>in</strong><br />

Europe, mark<strong>in</strong>g a break with previous discourses of judgement and contribut<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

the rise of bourgeois aesthetics <strong>in</strong> mid eighteenth-century Europe as a whole.<br />

bodily or material nature is particularly apt here. As she writes: “The dis<strong>in</strong>terested aesthetic attitude,<br />

the de-particularized artwork or picturesque view, and the impartial spectator all work to universalise<br />

modes of perception made possible only by material privilege - to assume or render them generally<br />

shared. Fem<strong>in</strong>ist criticism repeatedly rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that such moves exclude not only women but any<br />

group at a distance from the privileged center of such perception” (Bohls, 1993: 43).<br />

14


The question rema<strong>in</strong>s, of course, to what extent thought outweighed, or<br />

became a substitute for action <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>. Writ<strong>in</strong>g about art and aesthetics is<br />

different to actually practic<strong>in</strong>g art and it is clear that the volume and reputation of<br />

Scotland’s pa<strong>in</strong>ters came nowhere near that of critics. Apart from Raeburn and<br />

Ramsay, Scotland’s “golden age” did not produce equivalents to Hume, Ferguson,<br />

Smith, Black, Hutton and Cullen. Perhaps writ<strong>in</strong>g and the <strong>in</strong>tellectual sphere did not<br />

suffer as much as the visual arts from years of accumulated poverty, cultural<br />

uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty and political <strong>in</strong>stability. It is true that Scotland’s visual output was<br />

subject to detrimental forces that appeared not to impact so heavily on other forms -<br />

architecture is another example.<br />

In defence of pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, however, <strong>in</strong> addition to the tangible contacts between<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> theorists and pa<strong>in</strong>ters (Hume and Ramsay, Reid and Raeburn), the fact is<br />

writers, <strong>in</strong>tellectuals and pa<strong>in</strong>ters were discursively connected <strong>in</strong> that they shared the<br />

emerg<strong>in</strong>g space of civil society and the public sphere. Advances <strong>in</strong> one region of this<br />

space always rubbed off on other regions, particularly <strong>in</strong> a relatively small urban unit<br />

like <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>. Ultimately, all members of civil society and the public sphere were<br />

responsible for a certa<strong>in</strong> complexification and differentiation with<strong>in</strong> the cultural field<br />

as a whole. Merely by talk<strong>in</strong>g of “art” <strong>in</strong> the spaces of literature, the coffee houses<br />

and taverns was enough to direct attention to the status of an object that had<br />

previously been taken for granted.<br />

The differentiated art object did not spr<strong>in</strong>g fully-formed from the pens of<br />

critics, but developed slowly <strong>in</strong> an accumulated process of attention and practice.<br />

That <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> did not possess public art galleries or major spaces for exhibition at<br />

the end of the eighteenth century can be attributed to the forces that for centuries<br />

kept the field <strong>in</strong> check - poverty, <strong>in</strong>stability and the lack of centralised forms of<br />

patronage. In Bourdieu’s terms (1993), furthermore, the dynamic struggle between a<br />

modern and an ancient faction with<strong>in</strong> the rul<strong>in</strong>g class (between the extremes of a<br />

professional middle class striv<strong>in</strong>g for autonomy and a nobility/aristocracy positioned<br />

at the pole of heteronomy/commerce) was nascent, not yet deliver<strong>in</strong>g the vital<br />

impetus towards progression that Romanticism was later to br<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>Prior</strong>, 1995). The<br />

literati, <strong>in</strong> this sense, were still part of the dom<strong>in</strong>ant (rather than dom<strong>in</strong>ated) faction<br />

of the dom<strong>in</strong>ant class.<br />

15


In the shift away from the guilds, the rise of the market and collections, the<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g popularity of landscape pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g and portraiture, as well as the<br />

development of aesthetics, however, the vital organs of a modern art body were<br />

assembl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>. The agency of such a transition <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>, united for<br />

the moment, was that block of literati and aristocracy that desired to render itself<br />

visually present to itself and others <strong>in</strong> acts of dist<strong>in</strong>ction - not grand or heroic, but<br />

civic and tasteful. In this, Scotland’s idiosyncratic position <strong>in</strong> Europe was its already<br />

de-centralised cultural system and fertile civil society. At once, this made for an<br />

ambiguous cultural field: lack<strong>in</strong>g the official forms of power and patronage to take<br />

issue with, and yet enjoy<strong>in</strong>g an advanced <strong>in</strong>stitutional and discursive cultural system.<br />

Into the heart of the f<strong>in</strong>e arts was such a double-edged process etched; <strong>in</strong>to the very<br />

pictures were the nuances of socio-cultural change coded; and <strong>in</strong>to the morphology<br />

of the city were such ambiguities and double-codes made spatially visible.<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY<br />

Becker, M. (1994) The Emergence of Civil Society <strong>in</strong> the Eighteenth Century,<br />

Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.<br />

Berry, C. J. (1997) Social Theory of the Scottish Enlightenment, <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>:<br />

<strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> University Press.<br />

Bohls, E. (1993) “Dis<strong>in</strong>terestedness and Denial of the Particular: Locke, Adam<br />

Smith, and the Subject of Aesthetics”. In Mattick, Jr, P. (ed), 16-51.<br />

Bourdieu, P. (1977) Outl<strong>in</strong>e of a Theory of Practice, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Bourdieu, P. (1993) The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature,<br />

Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Burg<strong>in</strong>, Victor (1986) The End of Art Theory, London: Macmillan.<br />

Chitnis, A. (1976) The Scottish Enlightenment: A Social History, London: Croom<br />

Helm.<br />

Crow, Thomas E (1985) Pa<strong>in</strong>ters and Public life <strong>in</strong> Eighteenth Century Paris, New<br />

Haven: Yale University Press.<br />

Daiches, David, et al (Eds.) (1986) The Scottish Enlightenment 1730-1790: A Hotbed<br />

of Genius, <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>: Saltire Society.<br />

Dev<strong>in</strong>e, T. M. (ed) (1990) Conflict and Stability <strong>in</strong> Scottish Society, <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>: John<br />

Donald.<br />

Downie, R. S. (1994) Introduction to Francis Hutcheson: Philosophical Writ<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

Orion: London.<br />

Eagleton, Terry (1990) The Ideology of the Aesthetic, Basil Blackwell: Oxford.<br />

Gracyk, T. (1994) “Reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Hume’s Standard of Taste”, The Journal of Aesthetics<br />

and Art Criticism, 52, 2, Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 169-182.<br />

16


Hauser, Arnold (1962) The Social History of Art, vol. III: Rococo, Classicism,<br />

Romanticism, London: Routledge.<br />

Hume, David (1779) Essays: Moral, Political and Literary (EMP), edited by Miller,<br />

E., Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1987.<br />

Hutcheson, Francis, Inquiry Concern<strong>in</strong>g Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design, <strong>in</strong><br />

Inquiry <strong>in</strong>to the Orig<strong>in</strong>al of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (IOB), ed. Peter<br />

Kivy, The Hague: Mart<strong>in</strong>us Nijhoff, 1973.<br />

Kivy, Peter (1976) The Seventh Sense: A Study of Francis Hutcheson’s Aesthetics<br />

and its Influence <strong>in</strong> Eighteenth-Century Brita<strong>in</strong>, New York: Burt Frankl<strong>in</strong><br />

and Co.<br />

Kivy, Peter (1994) “From Literature as Imag<strong>in</strong>ation to Literature as Memory: A<br />

Historical Sketch”, <strong>in</strong> Institutions of Art: Reconsiderations of George<br />

Dickie’s Philosophy, Robert J. Yanal (ed), Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State<br />

University Press, 1994.<br />

Lehmann, W. (1971) Henry Home, Lord Home and the Scottish Enlightenment, The<br />

Hague: Mart<strong>in</strong>us Nijhoff.<br />

Lenman, B. (1981) Integration, Enlightenment and Industrialisation: Scotland 1745-<br />

1832, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Nauckoff, J. C. (1994) “Objectivity and Expression <strong>in</strong> Thomas Reid’s Aesthetics”,<br />

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 52, 2, Spr<strong>in</strong>g, 183-191.<br />

McElroy, D. (1969) Scotland’s Age of Improvement, Pullman: Wash<strong>in</strong>gton State<br />

University Press.<br />

MacMillan, D. (1986) Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Scotland: The Golden Age, Oxford: Phaidon.<br />

Markus, T. (1993) Build<strong>in</strong>gs and Power: Freedom and Control <strong>in</strong> the Orig<strong>in</strong> of<br />

Modern Build<strong>in</strong>g Types, London: Routledge.<br />

Mattick, Paul (ed) (1993) Eighteenth Century Aesthetics and the Reconstruction of<br />

Art, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Noel, J. (1994) “Space, Time and the Sublime <strong>in</strong> Hume’s Treatise”, British Journal<br />

of Aesthetics, vol. 34, no. 3, July, 218-225.<br />

Perricone, C. (1995) “The Body and Hume’s Standard of Taste”, The Journal of<br />

Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 53, 4, Fall, 371-378.<br />

Phillipson, Nicholas (1973) "Towards a Def<strong>in</strong>ition of the Scottish Enlightenment", <strong>in</strong><br />

Fritz, P. and Williams, D. (eds.), City and Society <strong>in</strong> the Eighteenth Century,<br />

<strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>: John Donald, 1973.<br />

Phillipson, Nicholas (1975) "Culture and Society <strong>in</strong> the Eighteenth Century<br />

Prov<strong>in</strong>ce: The Case of <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong> and the Scottish Enlightenment", <strong>in</strong> Stone,<br />

L. (ed), The University <strong>in</strong> Society, Vol. II, London: Oxford University Press,<br />

1975.<br />

<strong>Prior</strong>, <strong>Nick</strong> (1995) "<strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>, Romanticism and The National Gallery of Scotland",<br />

Urban History, vol. 22, pt 2, August.<br />

<strong>Prior</strong>, <strong>Nick</strong> (1998) Taste, Nations and Strangers: A Socio-Cultural History of<br />

National Art Galleries, with particular reference to Scotland, unpublished<br />

PhD thesis, University of <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>.<br />

Purviance, Susan (1991) “Intersubjectivity and Sociable Relations <strong>in</strong> the Philosophy<br />

of Francis Hutcheson”, <strong>in</strong> Sociability and Society <strong>in</strong> Eighteenth-Century<br />

Scotland, John Dwyer and Richard B. Sher (eds.), <strong>Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh</strong>: Mercat Press,<br />

1991.<br />

Reid, Thomas, Lectures on the F<strong>in</strong>e Arts (LFA), <strong>in</strong> Thomas Reid’s Lectures on the<br />

17


F<strong>in</strong>e Arts, edited by Peter Kivy, The Hague: Mart<strong>in</strong>us Nijhoff, 1973.<br />

Rendall, Jane (1978) The Orig<strong>in</strong>s of the Scottish Enlightenment 1707-1776, London:<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Shelley, J. (1994) “Hume’s Double Standard of Taste”, The Journal of Aesthetics<br />

and Art Criticism, 52, 4, Fall, 437-445.<br />

Sh<strong>in</strong>er, R. A. (1996) “Hume and the Casual Theory of Taste”, The Journal of<br />

Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54, 3, Summer, 238-249.<br />

Shusterman, R. (1993) “Of the Scandal of Taste: Social Privilege as Nature <strong>in</strong> the<br />

Aesthetic Theories of Hume and Kant”, <strong>in</strong> Mattick, Jr. P. (ed), Eighteenth<br />

Century Aesthetics and the Reconstruction of Art, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1993.<br />

Smout, T. C. (1969) A History of the Scottish People 1560-1830, London: Coll<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Wilk<strong>in</strong>son, M. (1992) “Hume’s Of the Standard of Taste”, <strong>in</strong> Bartholomew, M., Hall,<br />

D. and Lent<strong>in</strong>, A. (eds.), The Enlightenment, Milton Keynes: Open University<br />

Press.<br />

Williams, R. (1976) Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society, London:<br />

Croom Helm.<br />

18

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!