27.01.2015 Views

Two Accounts of Aristotle's Logic - Nicolas Fillion

Two Accounts of Aristotle's Logic - Nicolas Fillion

Two Accounts of Aristotle's Logic - Nicolas Fillion

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the University <strong>of</strong> Western Ontario<br />

<strong>Nicolas</strong> <strong>Fillion</strong><br />

250 387 509<br />

<strong>Two</strong> <strong>Accounts</strong> <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s <strong>Logic</strong><br />

A Comparison <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s and Corcoran-Smiley’s Reconstructions<br />

Seminar on Aristotelian <strong>Logic</strong><br />

Ph.D. in Philosophy<br />

April 16, 2007<br />

Faculty <strong>of</strong> Arts<br />

the University <strong>of</strong> Western Ontario


CONTENTS 2<br />

Contents<br />

1 Introductory Remarks 4<br />

2 Critical Presentation <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s View 6<br />

2.1 The Nature <strong>of</strong> Syllogism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7<br />

2.2 Perfect Syllogisms, Reduction and Rejection Pro<strong>of</strong>s . . . . . . . . 12<br />

2.3 <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Proposition as Preceding the <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Terms . . . . . . . 21<br />

2.4 ̷Lukasiewicz’s Symbolic System for Aristotle’s <strong>Logic</strong> . . . . . . . 23<br />

2.5 Summary <strong>of</strong> the Discussion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25<br />

3 Presentation <strong>of</strong> the Corcoran-Smiley View 26<br />

3.1 Explanation <strong>of</strong> the Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27<br />

3.2 Formal Natural Deduction System . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29<br />

3.3 Objections to the View <strong>of</strong> Syllogistic as a Natural Deduction System 31<br />

4 Conclusion: <strong>Two</strong> Traditions in <strong>Logic</strong> 32


CONTENTS 3<br />

Abstract<br />

It is widely accepted, and quite rightly, that Frege’s publication <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Begriffsschrift in 1879 begat the most prolific era <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

However, related to this is the highly dubious view, that “mathematical<br />

logic differs from the traditional formal logic so markedly in method, and<br />

so far surpasses it in power and subtlety, as to be generally and not unjustifiably<br />

regarded as a new science.” (Quine, 1965) The obvious ideological<br />

correlate <strong>of</strong> this claim is, that traditional formal logic no longer retains<br />

any theoretical interest, except maybe for archaic philosophers. The effect<br />

<strong>of</strong> this view is that contemporary logicians have looked upon Aristotle’s<br />

logic with jaundiced eyes, identifying as many mistakes as possible and<br />

exclusively emphasizing discontinuities.<br />

In this paper, I will argue that this view is wrong ins<strong>of</strong>ar as Aristotle’s<br />

logic can be reformulated in a way that satisfies the standards <strong>of</strong> modern<br />

mathematical logic without compromising its underlying philosophy. The<br />

argument will consist <strong>of</strong> a compact presentation and a critical examination<br />

<strong>of</strong> the two most famous attempts to produce such a model, namely<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’ reconstruction <strong>of</strong> syllogistic as an extension <strong>of</strong> propositional<br />

calculus (1957) and Corcoran-Smiley’s natural deduction system (1973-4).<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’s central interpretive claims are (1) that syllogistic is not a<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> logically valid arguments but a system <strong>of</strong> tautologies and (2)<br />

that it is not a self-sufficient system <strong>of</strong> logic, since it depends on propositional<br />

logic for its correctness. This view will be shown to be inadequate,<br />

since it fails to do justice to Aristotle’s methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>. Therefore, despite<br />

its authoritative position in the literature, ̷Lukasiewicz’s view does<br />

not render its lettres de noblesse to traditional logic.<br />

Corcoran and Smiley have developed a much more promising alternative.<br />

Their two central theses are opposed to those <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz: (1)<br />

Aristotelian syllogistic is a theory <strong>of</strong> logically valid arguments and (2) it<br />

is a self-sufficient theory <strong>of</strong> logic that presupposes no other system. It will<br />

be shown that by giving an account <strong>of</strong> syllogistic as a system <strong>of</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> inference,<br />

it is possible to make sense <strong>of</strong> most <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s claims regarding<br />

the constitutive elements <strong>of</strong> logic and his methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> (conversion,<br />

ecthesis, per impossibile). As a reconstruction <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s syllogistic<br />

according to our current standards, this model shows that Aristotelian<br />

logic still has a theoretical interest, and still is an active field <strong>of</strong> research.


1 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS 4<br />

1 Introductory Remarks<br />

A very important event for the historical development <strong>of</strong> logic took place in<br />

1879, when Frege published the Begriffsschrift. Many subsequent logicians had<br />

been for ever praising for this seminal work. This very typical attitude is, e.g.,<br />

adopted by Quine (1951, p. 1):<br />

[. . . ] mathematical logic differs from the traditional formal logic so<br />

markedly in method, and so far surpasses it in power and subtlety,<br />

as to be generally and not unjustifiably regarded as a new science.<br />

Such claims may be very useful as a piece <strong>of</strong> propaganda for one’s own philosophical<br />

agenda (in this case, promoting logical atomism over and above what<br />

reason tolerates), but it seems to us to be entirely wrong. Firstly, it is factually<br />

wrong to state that the methods developed by Frege are constitutive <strong>of</strong><br />

contemporary logic. There is a trend working in the footsteps <strong>of</strong> Frege, but<br />

it is by no means the dominant trend. 1 Secondly, this attitude is misleading<br />

because the alleged discontinuity is clearly an overstatement. There are important<br />

differences between traditional formal logic and contemporary formal logic;<br />

there is no debating that point. The point <strong>of</strong> a Quine-like claim, however, is<br />

to suggest that since a radical break happened in 1879, the previous works are<br />

theoretically worthless. The consequence <strong>of</strong> this attitude regarding Aristotle’s<br />

logic have been inauspicuous:<br />

Modern writers tended to look upon Aristotle’s logic with jaundiced<br />

eyes, finding fault wherever possible and emphasising differences between<br />

what they took to be Aristotle’s logic and what they took to<br />

be modern logic. (Corcoran & Scanlan, 1982, p. 76)<br />

In this paper, my primary motivation is to give grounds for attenuating this<br />

unfortunate prejudice. In order to do so, I will examine some contemporary<br />

contributions to the Aristotelian scholarship on categorical logic. More precisely,<br />

I will present and critically assess two models <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian logic built with<br />

the tools <strong>of</strong> contemporary mathematical logic. The notion <strong>of</strong> model relevant<br />

here is not the so-called “model-theoretic” notion <strong>of</strong> model. Rather, following<br />

Corcoran (1974b, 124-5), the notion <strong>of</strong> ‘model’ that I will use “is the ordinary<br />

one used in discussion, e.g., wooden models <strong>of</strong> airplanes, plastic model <strong>of</strong> boats,<br />

etc. Here the adjective ‘mathematical’ indicates the kind <strong>of</strong> material employed<br />

in the model.” The claim will thus not be that this or this model is actually<br />

Aristotelian logic. Rather, I will try to identify which model best succeeds in<br />

reproducing most logically relevant features <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s sayings and practices.<br />

I have two main motivations for undertaking this study. The first reason,<br />

a “theoretical” one, is that I agree with Frege (1895, p. 33) that “where a line<br />

1 See, e.g., Hintikka (1988), or our own study <strong>of</strong> this question in <strong>Fillion</strong> (2006).


1 INTRODUCTORY REMARKS 5<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought can be perfectly expressed in symbols, it will appear briefer and<br />

more perspicuous in this form than in words.” The second reason, a “pragmatic<br />

one”, is that – as Aristotle used to say – we must begin with what is familiar<br />

to us. Since most philosophy students are nowadays taught logic by means <strong>of</strong><br />

symbolic logic textbooks, it seems reasonable to use the medium to approach<br />

Aristotelian logic. I am confident that such an exercise may pave the way for a<br />

better understanding <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s logic. Also, and this has not to be neglected,<br />

this kind <strong>of</strong> study <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian logic by means <strong>of</strong> contemporary logic may well<br />

shed some light on contemporary logic itself!<br />

Various approaches have been explored in view <strong>of</strong> modelizing categorical<br />

syllogistic. Novak (1980) recorded and compared four attempts, each using<br />

different mathematical tools: (1) first-order predicate calculus, (2) extensions <strong>of</strong><br />

propositional calculus, (3) theory <strong>of</strong> classes and (4) Leśniewski’s ontology. The<br />

most famous use <strong>of</strong> (2) is ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the syllogistic as an<br />

axiomatized extension <strong>of</strong> propositional calculus. It should also be noticed that<br />

(5) natural deduction system and (6) diagrammatic logic (see Raymond, 2006)<br />

have been used.<br />

The first to become autoritative is ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction:<br />

In some ways this approach has come to be considered standard,<br />

probably (and justly) due to the wealth <strong>of</strong> detailed and critical observations<br />

contained in ̷Lukasiewicz’ work which makes numerous<br />

references to the texts <strong>of</strong> Aristotle himself. (Novak, 1980, p. 233)<br />

Later, in the seventies, the alternative view (5) have been developed and is now<br />

considered the standard view. My attention in this paper will be devoted to<br />

these two models. Here is an overview <strong>of</strong> the “battlefield” that we will examine:<br />

• ̷Lukasiewicz. This view has initially been presented in ̷Lukasiewicz (1929,<br />

chap. V), and more thoroughly in ̷Lukasiewicz (1957). Some <strong>of</strong> the most<br />

famous works along this line are those <strong>of</strong> Bocheński (1948, 1961, 1963)<br />

and Patzig (1968).<br />

• Corcoran-Smiley. This view has been developed independently and presented<br />

simultaneously in Corcoran (1972, 1974a,b) and Smiley (1973).<br />

Along this line, we also find Lear (1980), Corcoran & Scanlan (1982) and<br />

Corcoran (1994).<br />

The ̷Lukasiewiczian view takes Aristotle’s logic to be an axiomatized system presupposing<br />

the propositional calculus, whereas the Corcoran-Smiley view takes<br />

Aristotle’s logic to be an axiomless logic, i.e. a natural deduction system. 2 For<br />

each view, I will examine if they succeed in giving a logically correct account <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle. As criteria <strong>of</strong> adequacy, I will assume (1) that the model recovering<br />

2 We also note en passant the existence <strong>of</strong> intermediary approaches, such as Thom (1979).


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 6<br />

the largest part <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s explicit doctrine will be preferred and (2) that the<br />

model recovering Aristotle’s results via methods essentially similar to Aristotle’s<br />

will be preferred. 3<br />

These evaluation criteria may give rise to this concern, that “the perhaps<br />

rather obvious and irritating criticism must be made, that it exaggerates the<br />

extent to which Aristotle himself was, consistently and self-consciously, on the<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the angels.” (Austin, 1952, p. 395-6) To my defense, I will simply say<br />

that the principle <strong>of</strong> charity must be applied here, since my goal is to show<br />

that there is a reliable reconstruction <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s logic such that the alleged<br />

gap between traditional logic and contemporary logic is largely filled. As Smith<br />

(1989, p. vii) observed, “Aristotle is a major part <strong>of</strong> our philosophical ancestry,<br />

and we come to understand ourselves better by studying our ideal origins.”<br />

2 Critical Presentation <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s View<br />

̷Lukasiewicz (1957) made an extremely influential reconstruction <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian<br />

logic along the lines <strong>of</strong> modern mathematical logic. This work is the result <strong>of</strong> at<br />

least forty years <strong>of</strong> work. It probably contributed more than any other publication<br />

on the subject to what could be called the “received view” on Aristotle’s<br />

logic among mathematical logicians. Such comments are typical:<br />

[̷Lukasiewicz] performed his role [as an analyst and interpreter <strong>of</strong><br />

Organon and Metaphysics] in a creative manner by clarifying the author’s<br />

ideas while preserving his meaning unchanged. (Kotarbiński,<br />

1958, p. 58)<br />

He was lately considered – which seems right – the highest authority<br />

on Aristotle’s logic [. . . ]. (Kotarbiński, 1958, p. 59)<br />

A reviewer <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s book even proclaimed that:<br />

In any case, the reviewer firmly believes that this interpretation and<br />

exposition <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian syllogistic is definitive, as far as the simple<br />

categorical syllogism is concerned. (Boehner, 1952, p. 210)<br />

However, it also received it just part <strong>of</strong> criticisms. Since my objective is mainly<br />

to show why it is not an adequate reconstruction, I will focus <strong>of</strong> the latter.<br />

3 An impediment to the achievement <strong>of</strong> these goals is my ignorance <strong>of</strong> ancient Greek. It<br />

seems to me that Barnes’ translation is tainted by ̷Lukasiewicz’s view, while Smith’s seems to<br />

be tainted by the Corcoran-Smiley view (see Gasser, 1991, for a critical review <strong>of</strong> the translation).<br />

To overcome this difficulty, I have used and compared the translations <strong>of</strong> Jenkinson,<br />

Smith, Barnes and Tricot for difficult passages. It greatly helped me while I was trying to<br />

make sense in an unbiased way <strong>of</strong> “the intention <strong>of</strong> the text”. I have also received precious<br />

help from Gilles Plante and François Chassé (both specialists <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian philosophy), for<br />

which a am very thankful.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 7<br />

Each part <strong>of</strong> this section will on the one hand present ̷Lukasiewicz’s view on<br />

a central aspect <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s categorical syllogistic. On the other hand, critical<br />

remarks will be made via a comparison with the relevant excerpts from Aristotle’s<br />

text and, when appropriate, via presentation <strong>of</strong> some secondary litetarure.<br />

As we will see, what represents a real challenge in such a modelizing enterprise is<br />

to give a correct account <strong>of</strong> the methods <strong>of</strong> deduction. I will therefore organize<br />

the content <strong>of</strong> this section in order to be able to capture this aspect as efficiently<br />

as possible. For this reason, I will set aside what concerns the importance <strong>of</strong><br />

the number <strong>of</strong> figures, what concerns the definition <strong>of</strong> minor, major and middle<br />

terms, the order <strong>of</strong> the premises, the number <strong>of</strong> premises, the generalization <strong>of</strong><br />

decision problem, etc.<br />

2.1 The Nature <strong>of</strong> Syllogism<br />

The following syllogism is <strong>of</strong>ten given as an example <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian syllogism:<br />

All men are mortal,<br />

Socrates is a man,<br />

therefore, Socrates is mortal.<br />

(“False Form”)<br />

̷Lukasiewicz (1957, p. 1) considers that it is a False Form <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian syllogism,<br />

and he gives two main reasons to support the claim:<br />

1. It introduces singular terms or premises in the syllogistic (e.g. “Socrates”<br />

or “Socrates is a man”), whereas Aristotle does not;<br />

2. It is an inference from two premisses accepted as true to the conclusion,<br />

which does not correspond to Aristotle’s sayings. 4<br />

The central interpretive thesis characterizing ̷Lukasiewicz’s view is the following:<br />

Syllogisms are implication with the conjunction <strong>of</strong> premises as antecedent<br />

and a conclusion. 5<br />

He also notices two minor differences between Aristotle’s syllogisms and the<br />

False Form. Firstly, Aristotle always put the predicate first. Thus, instead <strong>of</strong><br />

having a sentence <strong>of</strong> the form “All A is B”, we must have “B is predicated <strong>of</strong><br />

all A”. 6 Moreover, an exact translation <strong>of</strong> the conclusion would also include a<br />

mark <strong>of</strong> necessity, i.e. “A must be predicated <strong>of</strong> all B”:<br />

4 Formulated with the currently used symbolism (e.g. Kleene, 1967), the reason advanced<br />

here is that it takes the syllogism to be <strong>of</strong> the form A, B ⊢ C instead <strong>of</strong> the correct ((A∧B) →<br />

C).<br />

5 “All Aristotelian syllogisms are implications <strong>of</strong> the type ‘If α and β, then γ’, where α and<br />

β are the two premisses and γ is the conclusion. The conjunction <strong>of</strong> the premisses ‘α and β’<br />

is the antecedent, the conclusion γ is the consequent. [. . . ] The implication is also regarded<br />

as true for all values <strong>of</strong> the variables A, B, and C.” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 20)<br />

6 This form is supposed to be as odd in Greek as in English. “Thus, ‘A belongs to all B’<br />

becomes ‘All B is A’. In the former, ‘all’ is part <strong>of</strong> an expressed relation between the subject<br />

and the predicate. In the latter, ‘all’ qualifies the subject.” (Raymond, 2006, pp. 3-4)


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 8<br />

This word ‘must’ (ἀνάγκη) is the sign <strong>of</strong> the so-called ‘syllogistic<br />

necessity’. It is used by Aristotle in almost all implications which<br />

contain variables and represent logical laws, i.e. laws <strong>of</strong> conversion<br />

or syllogisms. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 10)<br />

̷Lukasiewicz gives as an example the passage where Aristotle lays down the laws 7<br />

<strong>of</strong> conversion:<br />

[. . . ] if A belongs to some <strong>of</strong> the Bs, then necessarily B belongs<br />

to some <strong>of</strong> the As. (For if it belongs to none, then neither will A<br />

belong to any <strong>of</strong> the Bs.) But if A does not belong to some B, it is<br />

not necessary for B also not to belong to some A. (Pr. An., A.2,<br />

25a20-24)<br />

We notice, however, that it is somewhat exaggerated to say that Aristotle uses<br />

it in almost all conversion laws and syllogisms. For example, Aristotle does not<br />

use this word “necessary” when he introduces the conversion <strong>of</strong> A-premises and<br />

E-premises some five lines before the excerpt referred to by ̷Lukasiewicz (Pr.<br />

An., A.2,25a14-19). It is used when describing Barbara (and the two invalid<br />

first-figure moods with premises AE and EE), but not Celarent (Pr. An.,<br />

A.4, 25b38-40 & 26a1-2). Aristotle likely means it, but ̷Lukasiewicz’s appeal to<br />

textual support is, in this case, at best “borderline”.<br />

From this alleged systematical use <strong>of</strong> necessitation, ̷Lukasiewicz understands<br />

that Aristotle uses the sign <strong>of</strong> necessity in the consequent <strong>of</strong> a true implication<br />

to emphasize that the implication is true <strong>of</strong> all variables occurring in the<br />

implication (whether a law <strong>of</strong> conversion or a syllogism). In contemporary<br />

terms, we would uses quantifiers instead <strong>of</strong> the sign <strong>of</strong> necessity: we would write<br />

“∀a, b(Iab → Iba)” for conversion laws and “∀a, b, c[(Abc ∧ Aab) → Aac]” for<br />

syllogistic laws. 8<br />

Taking the two major and the two minor differences between the False Form<br />

and Aristotle’s form into account, we obtain the following, which is “the true<br />

form <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian syllogism” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 3):<br />

If A is predicated <strong>of</strong> all B<br />

and B is predicated <strong>of</strong> all C<br />

(True form)<br />

then (it follows <strong>of</strong> necessity that) A is predicated <strong>of</strong> all C.<br />

7 Whether these are laws or rules will be subject to discussion later. For now, we just adopt<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’ terminology.<br />

8 This must be taken with caution. In the classical presentations <strong>of</strong> propositional logic,<br />

necessity is assimilated to generality (in a truth-functional way); however, there is nothing<br />

that indicates that Aristotle did so: “Rather, Aristotle is working the presemantic idea <strong>of</strong><br />

interpretation by replacement: a statement-form is seen to have various instances. One obtains<br />

an interpretation <strong>of</strong> a syllogistic formula by substituting specific terms, <strong>of</strong> the appropriate<br />

logical category, for the schematic letters.” (Lear p. 8) The reduction ̷Lukasiewicz makes<br />

treats necessity as a truth-functional rather than a modal notion. To say the least, it may be<br />

doubted that it is appropriate.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 9<br />

Material Implication. As we have seen, the strong claim constituting ̷Lukasiewicz’s<br />

view is that Aristotle’s theory <strong>of</strong> syllogism is a system <strong>of</strong> true propositions.<br />

Following Leśniewski, he calls all true propositions (whether axioms or<br />

theorems) “theses”. There are four basic constants or operators (represented<br />

by A, E, I, and O), each characterizing a type <strong>of</strong> proposition <strong>of</strong> this system <strong>of</strong><br />

truths. Each <strong>of</strong> these operator takes two arguments. The arguments <strong>of</strong> these<br />

operators are universal terms. The following may thus be taken as a short technical<br />

description <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s syllogistic: “The logic <strong>of</strong> Aristotle is a theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relations A, E, I, and O in the field <strong>of</strong> universal terms.” (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 14) Universal terms correspond to the grammatical category <strong>of</strong> common<br />

nouns. Aristotle’s logic contain two kinds <strong>of</strong> implication. The conversion laws<br />

contain two propositions (A, E, I, O) that are connected by a material conditional.<br />

Syllogisms contain three propositions (A, E, I, O), one <strong>of</strong> them being the<br />

consequent <strong>of</strong> a material implication and two being put in conjunction to form<br />

the antecedent <strong>of</strong> the implication.<br />

<strong>Two</strong> kinds <strong>of</strong> argument are proposed to support this claim. The first argument<br />

is the textual support:<br />

It must be said emphatically that no syllogism is formulated by<br />

Aristotle as an inference with the word ‘therefore’ (ἄρα), as is done<br />

in traditional logic. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 21)<br />

He claims that the transition from the implicational form to the inferential one<br />

has only taken place with Alexander. For this reason, he makes the distinction<br />

between the Aristotelian and the Traditional syllogism. The differentiation he<br />

makes follows the distinction between proposition and rule <strong>of</strong> inference. Syllogisms<br />

as implications are propositions, and as propositions must be either true<br />

or false. The traditional syllogism (False Form) is not a proposition, but a set <strong>of</strong><br />

propositions forming not a single proposition but an inference. Since inferences<br />

are not propositions, they are neither true nor false. Rather, they are said to be<br />

valid or not. More precisely, the traditional syllogism is said to be an inference<br />

when it is stated in concrete terms. When it is stated with variables, it is a rule<br />

<strong>of</strong> inference. As rules <strong>of</strong> inference, they mean that for A, B, and C such that<br />

the premises ‘A belongs to all B’ and ‘B belongs to all C’ are true, therefore<br />

the conclusion ‘A belongs to all C’ must also be accepted as true. Whether<br />

syllogisms should be taken as implication or as inference connects to the use <strong>of</strong><br />

concrete terms as follows:<br />

But if the syllogism is formulated in the [traditional form] with the<br />

variables S, M, P , this cannot mean that one considers the premises<br />

with the variables to be true: no one will say that the expression<br />

“All M is P ” is true. That expression is neither true nor false<br />

before definite terms are substituted for the variables M and P . If<br />

we want to impart sense to [the traditional form], formulated with<br />

variables, we must treat it as a scheme <strong>of</strong> inference which expresses


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 10<br />

the following rule: whoever accepts sentences <strong>of</strong> the type “All M is<br />

P ” and “All S is M”, he is also entitled to accept a sentence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

type “All S is P ”. In this rule we refer not to the acceptance <strong>of</strong><br />

the sentence “All M is P ”, but to the acceptance <strong>of</strong> a sentence <strong>of</strong><br />

the type <strong>of</strong> “All M is P ”. And by sentences <strong>of</strong> the types <strong>of</strong> “All M<br />

is P ” we understand those sentences which are obtained from the<br />

expression “All M is P ” by the substitution for the variables <strong>of</strong> some<br />

definite terms.” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1963, p. 11)<br />

That Aristotle held the view vindicated by ̷Lukasiewicz is supported by the fact,<br />

at least ̷Lukasiewicz takes it to be a fact, that concrete terms are not part <strong>of</strong> logic<br />

(see next subsection), and by his alleged systematical use <strong>of</strong> “if–then” versus<br />

“therefore”. Regarding this second argument, two rather strong criticisms must<br />

be made. The first concerns ̷Lukasiewicz’s exaggeration <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s strict<br />

adherence to “if–then” which, as Austin noticed, can hardly pass:<br />

[Aristotle] does sometimes formulate syllogisms with the fatal ἄρα<br />

[. . . ]. And what <strong>of</strong> the formulation (e.g. in Post. An. i,13 ) which<br />

has a conclusion beginning with ὥστε Moreover, ̷Lukasiewicz himself<br />

shows that Aristotle’s pro<strong>of</strong>s by reductio ad impossibile (pp. 54<br />

ff.) involve treating the syllogism as an inference. (Austin, 1952,<br />

p. 397)<br />

The second strong criticism that has to be addressed concerns the seemingly<br />

inconsistency <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s historical claims. In the Elements, he affirms the<br />

following:<br />

[Frege] was the first, as it seems, to notice the difference between<br />

the premises on which a reasoning is based, and the rules <strong>of</strong> inference,<br />

that is the rules which determine how we are to proceed in<br />

order to prove a given thesis on the strength <strong>of</strong> certain premises.<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1963, p. 5)<br />

In Aristotle’s Syllogistic, he however seems to suggest that this distinction had<br />

first been done by the Stoics, some fifty years after Aristotle (1957, p. 48). The<br />

tricky question is thus: if Frege or the Stoics have first made the distinction<br />

between implication and inference after Aristotle’s writing <strong>of</strong> the Organon, is<br />

it really reasonable to suppose that Aristotle strictly applied it, with the right<br />

terminology and all that follows Clearly, ̷Lukasiewicz’s suggestion is misleading.<br />

Elimination <strong>of</strong> Concrete Terms. As we have seen, one <strong>of</strong> the two major<br />

reasons given by ̷Lukasiewicz for rejecting the False Form is that it contains<br />

concrete terms whereas Aristotle does not use them.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 11<br />

In Aristotle’s systematic exposition <strong>of</strong> his syllogistic no examples are<br />

given <strong>of</strong> syllogisms with concrete terms. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 7)<br />

̷Lukasiewicz understands by this that concrete terms are not part <strong>of</strong> logic. 9<br />

Rather, he says that Aristotle used variables to express all valid syllogisms in<br />

their generality. On the other hand, Aristotle does exemplify invalid combinations<br />

<strong>of</strong> premises by concrete terms. This, however, was by no mean necessary<br />

and Aristotle could have simply proceeded by identifying variables. But<br />

it “seems that the straight way in this problem, i.e. the way by identifying<br />

variables, was not seen by Aristotle.” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 9)<br />

The argument that supports this claim – i.e. that concrete terms are no part<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic – is based on the following excerpt:<br />

Now, <strong>of</strong> all the things that are, some are such as to be predicated<br />

<strong>of</strong> nothing else truly universally (for example, Kleon and Kallias<br />

and what is individual and perceptible) but to have other things<br />

predicated <strong>of</strong> them (for each <strong>of</strong> these is both a man and an animal);<br />

some are themselves predicated <strong>of</strong> others but do not have<br />

other things predicated previously <strong>of</strong> them; and some are both predicated<br />

<strong>of</strong> others and have others predicated <strong>of</strong> them (for example,<br />

man is predicated <strong>of</strong> Kallias and animal <strong>of</strong> man).<br />

[. . . Some other things may not] be predicated (except as a matter <strong>of</strong><br />

opinion), but they are predicated <strong>of</strong> others. Neither can individuals<br />

be predicated <strong>of</strong> other things, but instead other things are predicated<br />

<strong>of</strong> them. But is is clear that for those in between, predication is<br />

possible in both ways (for they can be said <strong>of</strong> other things, and<br />

other things can also be said <strong>of</strong> them). And arguments and inquiries<br />

are almost always chiefly concerned with these things.” [Pr. An.,<br />

A.1, 27, 43a25-43]<br />

The laws <strong>of</strong> conversion require that a term may act as a subject and as a<br />

predicate. This is the real reason, for ̷Lukasiewicz, that explains why Aristotle<br />

is occupied solely with those terms that can be predicated and can predicate:<br />

It is essential for the Aristotelian syllogistic that the same term may<br />

be used as a subject and as a predicate without any restriction.<br />

[. . . ] Syllogistic as conceived by Aristotle requires terms to be homogeneous<br />

with respect to their possible positions as subjects and<br />

predicates. This seems to be the true reason why singular terms<br />

were omitted by Aristotle. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 7)<br />

9 (Bocheński, 1948, p. 17) formulates it in a very transparent way: “[. . . ] our syllogistic<br />

proposition is evidently a frame. But as full propositions never occur in formal logic (except<br />

with bound variables), there is no fear <strong>of</strong> confusion.”


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 12<br />

But he does not think that Aristotle was right in doing that. He claims that the<br />

last sentence <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s excerpt – that we chiefly deal with terms that predicate<br />

both ways – is just false: “It is plain that individual terms are as important<br />

as universal, not only in everyday life but also in scientific reasearches. This<br />

is the greatest defect <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian logic, that singular terms and propositions<br />

have no place in it.”<br />

There are some criticisms that should be addressed here:<br />

Doubtless ̷Lukasiewicz is right in saying that syllogistic “requires<br />

terms to be homogeneous with respect to their possible positions<br />

as subjects and predicates” (p. 7), if that means (as it is better<br />

put on p. 130) that syllogistic has no application to terms which<br />

are not such. Yet it is scarcely the case that Aristotle omitted, or<br />

actually ‘eliminated’, singular terms from his system so explicitly<br />

as ̷Lukasiewicz suggests. [. . . ] Aristotle is said to be “inexact” in<br />

this chapter [. . . where he talks about Callias]. While this may be<br />

perfectly correct, the argument cannot really begin until the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s terms, and other passages bearing on the subject, have<br />

been discussed, and until the meaning <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s terms also<br />

has been explained. If Aristotle is inexact here, it is an inexactitude<br />

in which he persevered. (Austin, 1952, p. 396)<br />

From what we have already seen, there seems to exist some ground for doubting<br />

that ̷Lukasiewicz’s interpretation in entirely correct. Let us continue our<br />

analysis.<br />

2.2 Perfect Syllogisms, Reduction and Rejection Pro<strong>of</strong>s<br />

Perfect and Imperfect Syllogisms Prior Analytics is about demonstration<br />

(or pro<strong>of</strong>), and demonstration is a kind <strong>of</strong> deduction 10<br />

Deduction [syllogism] should be discussed before demonstration because<br />

deduction is more universal: a demonstration is a kind <strong>of</strong> deduction<br />

[syllogism], but not every deduction [syllogism] is a demonstration.<br />

(Pr. An., A.4, 25b28-31)<br />

Aristotle distinguishes two kinds <strong>of</strong> syllogisms:<br />

I call a deduction [syllogism] complete if it stands in need <strong>of</strong> nothing<br />

else besides the things taken in order for the necessity to be evident;<br />

10 A strange fact, considering that the very first line <strong>of</strong> Prior Analyticslays down what is<br />

the object <strong>of</strong> logic, is ̷Lukasiewicz’s claim that Aristotle did not answered to that question:<br />

“What is therefore, according to Aristotle, the object <strong>of</strong> logic, and why is his logic called<br />

formal The answer to this question is not given by Aristotle himself but by his followers, the<br />

Peripatetics.” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 13)


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 13<br />

I call it incomplete if it still needs either one or several additional<br />

things which are necessary because <strong>of</strong> the terms assumed, but yet<br />

were not taken by means <strong>of</strong> premises. (Pr. An., A.1, 24b22-26)<br />

By this distinction, it seems that Aristotle’s strategy consists in isolating a<br />

handful <strong>of</strong> obviously valid inferences, and to justify the remaining ones by a sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> demonstration. In others words, it would be possible to make do without<br />

them and still move from the premises to the conclusion (Lear, 1980, p. 6).<br />

However, this explication does not satisfy ̷Lukasiewicz and he thinks that a<br />

“translation into logical terminology” is needed (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 43). As<br />

we have seen, he takes syllogism to be true material implications. On this basis,<br />

the distinction between perfect and imperfect syllogisms reduces to being or not<br />

being an axiom:<br />

What Aristotle says means, therefore, that in a perfect syllogism<br />

the connexion between the antecedent and the consequent is evident<br />

<strong>of</strong> itself without an additional proposition. Perfect syllogisms<br />

are self-evident statements which do not possess and do not need<br />

a demonstration; they are indemonstrable, ἀναπόδεικτοι. Indemonstrable<br />

true statements <strong>of</strong> a deductive system are now called axioms.<br />

The perfect syllogisms, therefore, are the axioms <strong>of</strong> the syllogistic.<br />

On the other hand, the imperfect syllogisms are not self-evident;<br />

they must be proved by means <strong>of</strong> one or more propositions which<br />

result from the premisses, but are different from them. (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 43)<br />

Clearly, under ̷Lukasiewicz’s account, a syllogism is not (correctly) described<br />

as valid or as cogent, but only as true or as logically true or tautological. A<br />

syllogism has nothing to do with proving theorems, but is itself a proposition<br />

to be proved. From this point <strong>of</strong> view, imperfect syllogisms are not axioms and<br />

need to be proved, i.e. established as theorems. To do that, Aristotle uses a few<br />

methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>, namely pro<strong>of</strong>s by conversion, pro<strong>of</strong>s by ecthesis and pro<strong>of</strong>s by<br />

reductio ad impossibile. As we will see, ̷Lukasiewicz thinks that these pro<strong>of</strong>s are<br />

deficient, and rather propose to replace them by the laws <strong>of</strong> a more primitive<br />

logical theory (namely propositional logic). He thinks that such an alteration is<br />

necessary, because the pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> imperfect syllogisms is a crucial component <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotelian logic:<br />

[Aristotle] does not speak <strong>of</strong> ‘axioms’ or ‘basic truths’ but <strong>of</strong> ‘perfect<br />

syllogisms’, and does not ‘demonstrate’ or ‘prove’ the imperfect<br />

syllogisms but ‘reduces’ them (ἀνάγει or ἀναλύει) to the perfect.<br />

[. . . The Aristotelian theory <strong>of</strong> syllogism] is an axiomatized deductive<br />

system, and the reduction <strong>of</strong> the other syllogistic moods to those <strong>of</strong><br />

the first figure, i.e. their pro<strong>of</strong>s as theorems by means <strong>of</strong> the axioms,<br />

is an indispensable part <strong>of</strong> the system. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 44)


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 14<br />

Thus, as we see, ̷Lukasiewicz admittedly says that he made some alterations.<br />

What he does not say, however, is to which extent these alien notions affect the<br />

very nature <strong>of</strong> the system.<br />

These alterations are source <strong>of</strong> embarassement for ̷Lukasiewicz’s view, especially<br />

with respect to Aristotle’s actual methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s: “the price <strong>of</strong> accepting<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’s account <strong>of</strong> syllogisms is [. . . ] wholesale rejection <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> their reduction.” (Smiley, 1973, p. 138) But it is also embarrassing<br />

with respect to another fundamental aspect:<br />

[. . . ] one cannot make sense <strong>of</strong> the claim that a pro<strong>of</strong> [demonstration]<br />

is a type <strong>of</strong> syllogism (25b28ff) if one treats a syllogism as a<br />

conditional. A pro<strong>of</strong> is an argument, with a definite structure, from<br />

several sentences functioning as premises to a conclusion. It is not<br />

a single sentence. (Lear, 1980, p. 9)<br />

Taking syllogisms as conditional propositions, ̷Lukasiewicz is forced to conclude<br />

that Aristotle was mistaken, i.e. that Aristotle’s statement that demonstration<br />

is a type <strong>of</strong> syllogism, is false. Under ̷Lukasiewicz’s reading, Aristotle would<br />

be making the absurd claim that every pro<strong>of</strong> is a proposition, and that some<br />

propositions are pro<strong>of</strong>s. The point is that a pro<strong>of</strong>, e.g. the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the incommensurability<br />

<strong>of</strong> the diagonal, is not a single proposition. The only way to get<br />

out <strong>of</strong> this situation is to claim that Aristotle was confused, and to “translate<br />

into logical terminology”.<br />

[. . . ] While ̷Lukasiewicz writes as if Aristotle were concerned with<br />

nothing more than ‘the right answers’, it has long been clear [. . . ]<br />

that in Prior Analytics Aristotle is most concerned with the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> how conclusions are derived from premises. An obvious example<br />

<strong>of</strong> this interest is Aristotle’s lengthy discussion <strong>of</strong> the difference between<br />

direct and indirect deductions, i.e. sullogismoi. (Gasser, 1991,<br />

p. 238)<br />

This inability to handle correctly this very basic feature may suggest that<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’s claim that Aristotelian syllogisms are material implication is erroneous.<br />

In what follows, we will examine his account and critique <strong>of</strong> the methods<br />

<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s.<br />

Pro<strong>of</strong>s by Conversion Those pro<strong>of</strong>s are what is <strong>of</strong>ten called “direct pro<strong>of</strong>s”<br />

in the secondary literature. These are plausibly the most easy to account for.<br />

However, ̷Lukasiewicz judges that it is important to make some “enhancements”<br />

to the actual procedure used, because “Aristotle performs the pro<strong>of</strong> intuitively”<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 53). He claims that Aristotle is right when he says that<br />

only two syllogisms <strong>of</strong> the first figure are needed to build up the whole theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> syllogisms. He also claims the following strange thing:


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 15<br />

He forgets, however, that the laws <strong>of</strong> conversion, which he uses to reduce<br />

the imperfect moods to the perfect ones, also belong to his theory<br />

and cannot be proved by means <strong>of</strong> the syllogisms. (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 45)<br />

To say that Aristotle forgot that conversion rules are part <strong>of</strong> his theory is somewhat<br />

awkward, since he uses them explicitly. What is ̷Lukasiewicz’s point,<br />

then<br />

Aristotle’s system <strong>of</strong> logic includes three laws (or rules) <strong>of</strong> conversion: the<br />

conversion <strong>of</strong> the E-premise, <strong>of</strong> the A-premise, and <strong>of</strong> the I-premise. Aristotle<br />

proves the conversion <strong>of</strong> the E-premise by what he calls ecthesis (Pr. An., A.2,<br />

25a14-26). But, as we shall see, ̷Lukasiewicz takes it to be “a logical process<br />

lying outside the limits <strong>of</strong> the syllogistic” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 45). For him,<br />

as it cannot be proved otherwise, it must be stated as a new axiom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

system. Likewise, he claims that the conversion <strong>of</strong> the A-premise is proved by<br />

a thesis belonging to the square <strong>of</strong> opposition <strong>of</strong> which there is no mention in<br />

the Prior Analytics. For this reason, we must accept as fourth axiom either<br />

this law <strong>of</strong> conversion or the thesis <strong>of</strong> the square <strong>of</strong> opposition, from which this<br />

law follows. 11 ̷Lukasiewicz does not think he makes important modifications<br />

here, but rather that he is “analysing Aristotle’s intuitions” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 51). The result is as follows:<br />

It follows from this analysis that if we add to the perfect syllogisms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the first figure and to the laws <strong>of</strong> conversion three laws <strong>of</strong> the logic<br />

<strong>of</strong> propositions, viz. the law <strong>of</strong> the hypothetical syllogism and two<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> the factor, we get strictly formalized pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> all imperfect<br />

syllogisms except Baroco and Bocardo. These two moods require<br />

other theses <strong>of</strong> the propositional logic. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 54)<br />

There is again some doubts concerning the truthfulness <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction.<br />

Did he only make explicit what was already there, or did he make<br />

important modifications Let us continue our examination before concluding.<br />

Pro<strong>of</strong>s by Reductio ad impossibile The moods Baroco and Bocardo cannot<br />

be reduced to the first figure by conversion (under ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction,<br />

it includes the propositional add-ons). This is why “Aristotle tries to<br />

prove these two moods by a reductio ad impossibile, ἀπαγωγὴ εἰς τὸ ἀδύνατον.”<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 54) Aristotle’s pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the mood Baroco goes as follow:<br />

Next, if M belongs to every N but does not belong to some X, it is<br />

necessary for N not to belong to some X. (For if it belongs to every<br />

11 He affirms that the law <strong>of</strong> conversion <strong>of</strong> the I-premise can be proved without a new axiom.<br />

However, under his account, it is so because he adds laws <strong>of</strong> identity that Aristotle nowhere<br />

explicited.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 16<br />

X and M is also predicated <strong>of</strong> every N, then it is necessary for M to<br />

belong to every X: but it was assumed not to belong to some.) And<br />

if M belongs to every N but not to every X, then there will be a<br />

deduction that N does not belong to every X. (The demonstration<br />

is the same.) (Pr. An., 1.5, 27a36-b3)<br />

This is a very concise pro<strong>of</strong> that is traditionally explained along those lines: (1)<br />

it is admitted that the premises ‘M belongs to every N’ and ‘M does not belong<br />

to some X’ are true, and (2) we conclude from this that the conclusion ‘N does<br />

not belong to some X’. For if it were false, its contradictory, ‘N belongs to all<br />

X’, would be true. This proposition is the starting point <strong>of</strong> the reduction. As<br />

it is admitted that the premise ‘M belongs to every N’ is true, we get from this<br />

premise and the proposition ‘N belongs to every X’ the conclusion ‘M belongs<br />

to all X’ by the mood Barbara. But this conclusion is false, for it is admitted<br />

that its contradictory ‘M does not belong to some X’ is true. Therefore, the<br />

starting point <strong>of</strong> our reduction, ‘N belongs to every X’, which leads to a false<br />

conclusion, must be false, and its contradictory, ‘N does not belong to some X’,<br />

must be true. Aristotle himself explains this method <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> in this way:<br />

A demonstration [leading] into an impossibility differs from a probative<br />

demonstration in that it puts as a premise what it wants<br />

to reject by leading away into an agreed falsehood, while a probative<br />

demonstration begins from agreed positions. More precisely,<br />

both demonstration take two agreed premises, but one takes the<br />

premises which the deduction is from, while the other takes one <strong>of</strong><br />

these premises and, as the other premise, the contradictory <strong>of</strong> the<br />

conclusion. (Pr. An., B.14, 62b29-34)<br />

For ̷Lukasiewicz, such an explication is anathema, for it relies on the conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> syllogisms as (rules <strong>of</strong>) inference. This is why this “argument is only apparently<br />

convincing; in fact, it does not prove the above syllogism” (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 54). Not, at least, if syllogisms are taken to be material implications.<br />

As such, a syllogism is an implication which is true for all values <strong>of</strong> the variables<br />

M, N, and X, and not only for those values that verify the premises. This is<br />

why ̷Lukasiewicz claims that the “pro<strong>of</strong> given by Aristotle is neither sufficient<br />

nor a pro<strong>of</strong> by reductio ad impossibile” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 55). The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

a syllogistic mood qua implication by reductio ad impossibile can not suppose<br />

the negation <strong>of</strong> the conclusion only:<br />

The indirect pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the mood Baroco should start from the negation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this mood, and not from the negation <strong>of</strong> its conclusion, and<br />

this negation should lead to an unconditionally false statement, and<br />

not to a proposition that is admitted to be false under certain conditions.<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 56)


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 17<br />

̷Lukasiewicz proposes an alternative to these “insufficient” pro<strong>of</strong>s by using the<br />

following propositional law: ((p∧q) → r) → ((p∧¬r)¬q). It is obvious that provided<br />

such an axiom, ̷Lukasiewicz’s suggestion works in a straightforward way.<br />

However, as ̷Lukasiewicz willingly confess, it “can easily be seen that this genuine<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the mood Baroco by reductio ad impossibile is quite different from<br />

that given by Aristotle” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 56). 12 This is however supposed<br />

to be an advantage <strong>of</strong> his presentation over Aristotle’s, for the insufficiency <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle’s approach is merely a sign <strong>of</strong> his being short-sighted:<br />

In the systematic exposition <strong>of</strong> the syllogistic these valid pro<strong>of</strong>s are<br />

replaced by insufficient demonstrations per impossibile. The reason<br />

is, I suppose, that Aristotle does not recognize arguments ἐξ<br />

ὑποθέσεως as instruments <strong>of</strong> genuine pro<strong>of</strong>. All demonstration is<br />

for him pro<strong>of</strong> by categorical syllogisms; he is anxious to show that<br />

the pro<strong>of</strong> per impossibile is a genuine pro<strong>of</strong> in so far as it contains<br />

at least a part that is a categorical syllogism. [. . . ] All this is, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, not true; Aristotle does not understand the nature <strong>of</strong> hypothetical<br />

arguments. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> Baroco and Bocardo by the law <strong>of</strong><br />

transposition is not reached by an admission or some other hypothesis,<br />

but performed by an evident logical law; besides, it is certainly<br />

a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> one categorical syllogism on the ground <strong>of</strong> another, but<br />

it is not performed by a categorical syllogism. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

pp. 57-8) 13<br />

This, <strong>of</strong> course, is only the case if ̷Lukasiewicz’s interpretive thesis that syllogisms<br />

are material implications holds. By now, it should be clear that there are<br />

serious doubts that it is the case. Another aspect <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s saying about<br />

pro<strong>of</strong>s by reductio ad impossibile that can not be accounted for by ̷Lukasiewicz<br />

is Aristotle’s claims that any conclusion that can be derived by per impossibile<br />

can be proved by a direct syllogism from the same premises. As noticed by<br />

Lear (1980, p. 9), this “distinction therefore requires that one attributes to the<br />

syllogism an argumentative structure which a conditional lacks.” The relevant<br />

excerpt is the following:<br />

Deductions [syllogisms] which lead into an impossibility are also in<br />

the same condition as probative ones: for they too come about by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> what each term follows or is followed by, and there is<br />

the same inquiry in both cases. For whatever is proved probatively<br />

can also be deduced through an impossibility by means <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

terms, and whatever is proved through an impossibility can also be<br />

deduced probatively [. . . ]. (Pr. An., A.29, 45a22-28)<br />

12 Among other things, it admits the possibility <strong>of</strong> syllogism ridiculosi (see Thom, 1979,<br />

p. 757).<br />

13 This has supposedly been corrected by the Stoics, who used the aforementioned propositional<br />

law: “This is one <strong>of</strong> the neatest argument we owe to the Stoics. We see that competent<br />

logicians reasoned 2,000 years ago in the same way as we are doing today.” (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 59) It seems to suggest that Aristotle is not competent!


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 18<br />

The point is that arguing validly requires more than making valid inferences.<br />

It also requires that the inferences done be known to be valid. By showing the<br />

equivalence <strong>of</strong> those methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>, Aristotle addresses the latter requirement:<br />

“[. . . ] the problem <strong>of</strong> one’s knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> a per impossibile<br />

syllogism is reduced to that <strong>of</strong> our knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> a direct inference.”<br />

(Lear, 1980, p. 53) Thus, it is guaranteed that the only difference between<br />

per impossibile and direct syllogisms, within the confines <strong>of</strong> syllogistic, is one <strong>of</strong><br />

argumentative structure. It is impossible to account for this part <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

theory if syllogisms are material implications.<br />

Pro<strong>of</strong>s by Ecthesis Apart from the pro<strong>of</strong>s by conversion and the pro<strong>of</strong>s<br />

per impossibile, there is still a third kind <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> used by Aristotle, namely<br />

the pro<strong>of</strong>s by exposition or ἔκθεσις. According to ̷Lukasiewicz, there are three<br />

passages where Aristotle uses that kind <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> in Prior Analytics 14 : (1) pro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the conversion <strong>of</strong> the E-premise, (2) the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the mood Darapti and (3)<br />

the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the mood Bocardo. The word ‘ecthesis’, however, appears only in<br />

(2). ̷Lukasiewicz thinks that this logical process lies outside the limits <strong>of</strong> the<br />

syllogistic, and that new axioms are needed in their place (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 45) Let us examine the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> conversion:<br />

First, let premise AB be universally privative. Now, if A belongs to<br />

none <strong>of</strong> the Bs, then neither will B belong to any <strong>of</strong> the As. For if it<br />

does not belong to some (for instance to C), it will not be true that<br />

A belong to none <strong>of</strong> the Bs, since C is one <strong>of</strong> the Bs. (Pr. An., A.2,<br />

25a14-17)<br />

The pro<strong>of</strong> by exposition requires the introduction <strong>of</strong> a new term, called the<br />

‘exposed term’; here it is C. In his commentary, Alexander says that C is a<br />

singular term given by perception. For ̷Lukasiewicz, this would not do since “a<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> by perception is not a logical pro<strong>of</strong>” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 60). On the<br />

other hand, if C is a universal term, then the pro<strong>of</strong> would require existential<br />

quantifiers (since it produces an instantiation). For this, however, an extension<br />

<strong>of</strong> syllogistic to quantification theory would be needed.<br />

This was perhaps the reason why he dropped this kind <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong><br />

in his final chapter (7) <strong>of</strong> Book I <strong>of</strong> the Prior Analytics, where he<br />

sums up his systematic investigation <strong>of</strong> syllogistic. Nobody after him<br />

understood these pro<strong>of</strong>s. It was reserved for modern formal logic to<br />

explain them by the idea <strong>of</strong> the existential quantifier. (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 67)<br />

This issue will be discussed in more details in the next subsection about rejection.<br />

14 See (Raymond, 2006, p. 33ff) and Smith (1982) for a detailed discussion.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 19<br />

Rejection In Prior Analytics, Aristotle does not only give pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> correct<br />

syllogisms, but also shows that the others must be rejected. ̷Lukasiewicz claims<br />

that Aristotle uses two different methods <strong>of</strong> rejection. The first method is the<br />

most common. Consider the following syllogistic form: If A belongs to all B and<br />

B belongs to no C, then A does not belong to some C. To show that this form<br />

is not correct, we must show that there exists values <strong>of</strong> the variables A, B and<br />

C such that the premises are verified but the conclusion is not. Obviously, the<br />

“easiest way <strong>of</strong> showing this is to find concrete terms verifying the premisses<br />

[. . . ] but not the conclusion” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 69). Let us examine an<br />

instance <strong>of</strong> this way <strong>of</strong> proceeding:<br />

For it is possible for the first extreme to belong to all as well as to<br />

none <strong>of</strong> the last. Consequently, neither a particular nor a universal<br />

conclusion becomes necessary; and, since nothing is necessary because<br />

<strong>of</strong> these, there will not be a deduction [syllogism]. Terms for<br />

belonging to every are animal, man, horse; for belonging to none,<br />

animal, man, stone. (Pr. An., A.4, 26a5-10)<br />

Here, Aristotle rejects a form by means <strong>of</strong> the concrete terms ‘man’, ‘animal’,<br />

‘horse’, and ‘stone’. This procedure necessitates the use <strong>of</strong> concrete terms, and<br />

̷Lukasiewicz criticizes this method <strong>of</strong> rejection as follows:<br />

This procedure is correct, but it introduces into logic terms and<br />

propositions not germane to it. ‘Man’ and ‘animal’ are not logical<br />

terms, and the proposition ‘All men are animals’ is not a logical<br />

thesis. <strong>Logic</strong> cannot depend on concrete terms and statements. If<br />

we want to avoid this difficulty, we must reject some forms axiomatically.<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 72)<br />

According to ̷Lukasiewicz, the second method that Aristotle used is much more<br />

“logical” in nature. 15 In examining second-figure forms, Aristotle rejects a form<br />

by reducing it to another form already known to be false (Pr. An., A.5, 27b9-<br />

23).<br />

Aristotle, however, does not finish his pro<strong>of</strong> [by finding concrete<br />

terms], because he sees another possibility: if the form with universal<br />

negative premisses: (6) If M belongs to no N and M belongs to no<br />

X, then N does not belong to some X, is rejected, (5) [If M belongs<br />

to no N and M does not belong to some X, then N does not belong<br />

to some X,] must be rejected too. For if (5) stands, (6), having<br />

a stronger premiss than (5), must also stand. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 71)<br />

15 Whether it has a real importance in Aristotle’s theory is not that clear, because there is<br />

no primitive rejection law stated. Raymond (2006, p. 209) even considers that it is not part<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s methodology for rejecting forms: “In fact, Aristotle never relies upon a rule to<br />

establish invalidity. Nor does he limit the semantics to a certain class <strong>of</strong> assertions.”


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 20<br />

The rejection strategy in such a case is to show that the falsity <strong>of</strong> a form follows<br />

<strong>of</strong> necessity from the falsity <strong>of</strong> another form. Thus, on the basis <strong>of</strong> some<br />

axiomatically rejected forms, it is possible to prove the rejection <strong>of</strong> other forms.<br />

̷Lukasiewicz sees this procedure as literally mirroring Aristotle’s method for perfecting<br />

syllogisms. Since he takes syllogisms to be material implications, and<br />

that it is crucial to his conception that the perfection <strong>of</strong> syllogisms is the pro<strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> a theorem from axioms, this second method <strong>of</strong> rejection is supposed to be an<br />

operation opposed to Frege’s assertion (see ̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 71ff). Since<br />

the concrete terms necessary for the first kind <strong>of</strong> rejection are not part <strong>of</strong> logic,<br />

this second method based on axiomatic rejection should be considered as the<br />

true Aristotelian method for the rejection <strong>of</strong> false forms.<br />

Many commentators rightly noticed that it is patently unfaithful to Aristotle’s<br />

sayings 16 :<br />

There seems to be some special pleading here. The sense in which<br />

Aristotle “uses rejection” is far-fetched: he is shown to have used<br />

once, not very self-consciously, the modus tollens, but not to have<br />

alluded even once to axioms <strong>of</strong> rejection, the more crucial matter.<br />

(Austin, 1952, p. 401)<br />

Before closing this subsection, a few more words on the use <strong>of</strong> concrete terms<br />

for rejection are in order. A pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> rejection aims to show that nothing follows<br />

<strong>of</strong> necessity from a set <strong>of</strong> premises:<br />

Since a syllogistic consequence follows <strong>of</strong> necessity from the premisses,<br />

to establish sterility one must prove a certain possibility.<br />

That is, one must show that it is possible for the premisses <strong>of</strong> the<br />

form in question to be true without any syllogistic conclusion, linking<br />

the major and minor terms in the prescribed order, being true.<br />

(Lear, 1980, p. 54)<br />

The easiest way to show that is to show instances where it does not work, such<br />

as Aristotle’s terms ‘animal’, ‘man’, and ‘stone’. But these terms are supposedly<br />

not germane to logic, and that made ̷Lukasiewicz say that producing an instance<br />

is not a proper logical pro<strong>of</strong>. Geach (1972) agreed with ̷Lukasiewicz on that<br />

point, with the reserve that it is logically correct if it is based on the exposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> a logical object. 17 He therefore proposes to use Caroll’s diagrams to make<br />

these pro<strong>of</strong>s in an appropriate logical way (Geach, 1972, p. 299ff). Likewise,<br />

Copi (1961, p. 166ff) proposed to use Venn diagrams. These two tools consist<br />

in appealing to our spatial intuition, i.e. to some kind <strong>of</strong> graphs, to expose<br />

the validity or invalidity <strong>of</strong> a syllogistic form. Their objection to Aristotle’s<br />

examples is therefore not about the procedure <strong>of</strong> exposition per se, but rather<br />

16 See also Corcoran (1974b, 1994).<br />

17 What is a logical object is unclear, and there are serious doubts that it may be characterized<br />

in logical terms (<strong>Fillion</strong>, 2006, chap. 5).


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 21<br />

to the kind <strong>of</strong> object or term that Aristotle used as counterexamples. They<br />

think that if the objects or terms exposed are not logical in nature, the pro<strong>of</strong><br />

would be contingent on the constitution <strong>of</strong> the world. Aristotle took as example<br />

swans, supposing that all swans are white; however, we now know that there are<br />

black swans. Diagrams thus seem more appropriate (whether Carroll’s, Venn’s<br />

or Euler’s). But is it really the case<br />

If we draw an Euler diagram on a sheet <strong>of</strong> paper, it is convincing<br />

because we assume that the surface on which it is drawn has the<br />

same topology as a Euclidean plane. (Lear, 1980, p. 62)<br />

Now, in the same way that we have discovered black swans, we have discovered<br />

non-Euclidean topological structures. Actually, Euler diagrams fail to exhibit<br />

validity and invalidity <strong>of</strong> our canonically accepted inference if they are represented<br />

on a torus (which is a perfectly logically acceptable topological structure).<br />

In response, it may be suggested that they can only be taken as heuristic devices.<br />

But in this case, we are brought back, with Aristotle, to the use <strong>of</strong> actual<br />

counterexamples that have nothing <strong>of</strong> the logical objects that Geach was after.<br />

Therefore, both ̷Lukasiewicz’s and Geach’s suggestions have no significant<br />

advantage over Aristotle’s in explaining the ‘why’ <strong>of</strong> the rejection.<br />

2.3 <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Proposition as Preceding the <strong>Logic</strong> <strong>of</strong> Terms<br />

We have seen many important differences between what Aristotle actually does,<br />

and what ̷Lukasiewicz says that Aristotle does. ̷Lukasiewicz takes these differences<br />

to be mere corrections <strong>of</strong> a technical nature, not making any deep<br />

alteration to Aristotle’s system. In other words, he thinks he just “filled the<br />

gaps”. These gaps are all related to the fundamental flaw <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s logic:<br />

he did not understand that some problems can not be expressed by the four<br />

syllogistic premises. Most importantly, Aristotle did not understand that the<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> syllogisms he himself created was an instance against the doctrine that<br />

all problems may be resolved by syllogisms. Here is the main grief:<br />

The syllogistic moods, being implications, are propositions <strong>of</strong> another<br />

kind than the syllogistic premisses, but nevertheless they are<br />

true propositions, and if any <strong>of</strong> them is not self-evident and indemonstrable<br />

it requires a pro<strong>of</strong> to establish its truth. The pro<strong>of</strong>, however,<br />

cannot be done by means <strong>of</strong> a categorical syllogism, because an implication<br />

does not have either a subject or a predicate, and it would<br />

be useless to look for a middle term between non-existent extremes.<br />

(̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 44)<br />

Aristotle cultivated many ambiguities on that very point, so that “no one can<br />

fully understand Aristotle’s pro<strong>of</strong>s who does not know that there exists besides<br />

the Aristotelian system another system <strong>of</strong> logic more fundamental than


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 22<br />

the theory <strong>of</strong> syllogism” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 47). Concerning those pro<strong>of</strong>s,<br />

̷Lukasiewicz emphasized (1) that Aristotle’s pro<strong>of</strong>s by conversion are insufficient<br />

and need to be completed, (2) that pro<strong>of</strong>s by reductio ad impossibile and by ecthesis<br />

must replaced by axiomatic acceptation or rejection <strong>of</strong> some propositions<br />

and (3) that laws <strong>of</strong> conversions must be accepted axiomatically. Basically, he<br />

has “shown” that all methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s can only be understood if we replace<br />

them by a formalistic deduction in propositional logic. This is why, according<br />

to ̷Lukasiewicz, it is only possible to understand Aristotle’s pro<strong>of</strong>s if it is<br />

understood that they necessitate propositional calculus.<br />

Propositional logic was completely ignored by Aristotle. ̷Lukasiewicz affirms<br />

that the first system <strong>of</strong> propositional logic was invented about half a century<br />

after Aristotle, by the Stoics. However, the understanding <strong>of</strong> the more fundamental<br />

character <strong>of</strong> this logical system has only been acquired in the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

nineteenth century, as a consequence <strong>of</strong> the 1879 event, due to the great German<br />

logician Gottlob Frege. This theory has been later brought to perfection by the<br />

authors <strong>of</strong> Principia Mathematica, Whitehead and Russell, who developed it so<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>oundly that they made it the core <strong>of</strong> all mathematics. 18 To observe the<br />

difference between propositional logic and syllogistic, it is sufficient to compare<br />

Aab and p → q:<br />

They differ in their constants, which I call functors: in the first formula<br />

the functor reads ‘all–is’, in the second ‘if–then’. Both are<br />

functors <strong>of</strong> two arguments which are here identical. But the main<br />

difference lies in the arguments. In both formulae the arguments are<br />

variables, but <strong>of</strong> a different kind: the values which may be substituted<br />

for the variable A are terms [. . . ]. The value <strong>of</strong> the variable p<br />

are not terms but propositions [. . . ]. This difference between termvariables<br />

and proposition-variables is the primary difference between<br />

the two formulae and consequently between the two systems <strong>of</strong> logic,<br />

and, as propositions and terms belong to different semantical categories,<br />

the difference is a fundamental one. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 47-8)<br />

For ̷Lukasiewicz, in contrast with the syllogistic, which is a set <strong>of</strong> true material<br />

implications, propositional logic is a system <strong>of</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> inference, and that makes<br />

it the primitive logic underlying all logical reasoning.<br />

[. . . ] Aristotle’s logic is not a primitive logical theory, and for its<br />

foundation requires a certain earlier theory that investigates sentences<br />

in general, without engaging in the study <strong>of</strong> the details <strong>of</strong><br />

their structure. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1963, p. 106)<br />

That it is the case, however, depends on his being justified in making the propositional<br />

additions to Aristotle’s doctrine. We must first notice that ̷Lukasiewicz<br />

18 See ̷Lukasiewicz (1957, p. 48) for the literal text <strong>of</strong> the propaganda.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 23<br />

avowedly says that it finds no direct support in Prior Analytics:<br />

It seems that Aristotle did not suspect the existence <strong>of</strong> another system<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic besides his theory <strong>of</strong> the syllogism. Yet he uses intuitively<br />

the laws <strong>of</strong> propositional logic in his pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> imperfect<br />

syllogisms, and even sets forth explicitly three statements belonging<br />

to this logic in Book II <strong>of</strong> the Prior Analytics. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 49)<br />

The question naturally arises how exactly this system corresponds with the<br />

syllogistic as developed by Aristotle. We will report our final verdict to the<br />

section 2.5, and will first present the formalistic reconstruction.<br />

2.4 ̷Lukasiewicz’s Symbolic System for Aristotle’s <strong>Logic</strong><br />

What <strong>of</strong>ten causes difficulty for contemporary logicians who want to understand<br />

Aristotelian logic is that it is a formal logic without being a formalistic logic.<br />

The goal <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz was to provided a formalistic system for Aristotelian<br />

logic. In a compact formulation, the system is the following:<br />

Formal Axiomatized Theory for ̷Lukasiewicz’ Syllogistic (LS):<br />

1. The alphabet <strong>of</strong> LS contains:<br />

(a) propositional connectives ‘¬, ⇒, ∧’;<br />

(b) propositional variables ‘p, q, r, s, . . .’;<br />

(c) term variables ‘a, b, c, d, . . .’;<br />

(d) syllogistic operators ‘A, I’.<br />

2. The atomic formulas <strong>of</strong> LS are the following:<br />

(a) for any a, b that are term variables, Aab and Iab are atomic formulas;<br />

(b) nothing else is an atomic formula.<br />

3. The well-formed formulas <strong>of</strong> LS are the following:<br />

(a) all atomic propositions are wffs;<br />

(b) all propositional variables are wffs;<br />

(c) for any p, q that are propositional variables, ¬p, p ⇒ q are wffs;<br />

(d) nothing else is a wff.<br />

4. The axioms <strong>of</strong> LS are:<br />

(a) Aaa (Identity Law)<br />

(b) Iaa (Identity Law)


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 24<br />

(c) (Abc ∧ Aab) ⇒ Aac (Barbara)<br />

(d) (Abc ∧ Iba) ⇒ Iac (Datisi)<br />

(e) p ⇒ (q ⇒ p) (Law <strong>of</strong> Simplification)<br />

(f) (p ⇒ q) ⇒ ((q ⇒ r) ⇒ (p ⇒)) (Law <strong>of</strong> Hypothetical Syllogism)<br />

(g) (p ⇒ (q ⇒ r)) ⇒ (q ⇒ (p ⇒ r)) (Law <strong>of</strong> Commutation)<br />

(h) p ⇒ (¬p ⇒ q) (Law <strong>of</strong> Duns Scotus)<br />

(i) (¬p ⇒ p) ⇒ p (Law <strong>of</strong> Clavius)<br />

(j) (p ⇒ q) ⇒ (¬q ⇒ ¬p) (Law <strong>of</strong> Transposition)<br />

(k) ((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ (p ⇒ (q ⇒ r)) (Law <strong>of</strong> Exportation)<br />

(l) p ⇒ (((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ (q ⇒ r))<br />

(m) (s ⇒ p) ⇒ (((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ ((s ∧ q) ⇒ r))<br />

(n) ((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ ((s ⇒ q) ⇒ ((p ∧ s) ⇒ r))<br />

(o) (r ⇒ s) ⇒ (((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ ((q ∧ p) ⇒ s))<br />

(p) ((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ ((p ∧ ¬r) ⇒ ¬q)<br />

(q) ((p ∧ q) ⇒ r) ⇒ ((¬r ∧ q) ⇒ ¬p)<br />

(r) ((p ∧ ¬q) ⇒ ¬r) ⇒ ((p ∧ r) ⇒ q)<br />

5. The following propositions are axiomatically rejected:<br />

(a) (Acb ∧ Aab) ⇒ Iac<br />

(b) (Ecb ∧ Eab) ⇒ Iac<br />

6. The rules <strong>of</strong> inference <strong>of</strong> LS are:<br />

(a) (Substitution) If p is an asserted expression <strong>of</strong> LS, then any expression<br />

produced from p by a valid substitution is also an asserted<br />

expression. The only valid substitution is to put for term variables<br />

a, b, c other term-variables, e.g. b for a.<br />

(b) (Detachment) If p ⇒ q and p are asserted expressions <strong>of</strong> LS, then q<br />

is an asserted expression.<br />

(c) (Rejection by detachment) If the implication p ⇒ q is asserted, but<br />

the consequent q is rejected, then the antecedent p must be rejected<br />

too.<br />

(d) (Rejection by substitution) If q is a substitution <strong>of</strong> p, and q is rejected,<br />

then p must be rejected too.<br />

The semantics <strong>of</strong> the system is more or less clear, so we will not present it here.


2 CRITICAL PRESENTATION OF ̷LUKASIEWICZ’S VIEW 25<br />

2.5 Summary <strong>of</strong> the Discussion<br />

̷Lukasiewicz (1957, p. 130) reconstructed Aristotle’s syllogistic in a mathematical<br />

framework and, doing so, he has “tried to set forth this system free from foreign<br />

elements.” He does not think that he made serious alterations to the system,<br />

but rather that he just used formal pro<strong>of</strong>s where Aristotle used propositional<br />

logic intuitively.<br />

In our critical presentation, however, we have seen that “the price <strong>of</strong> accepting<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’s account <strong>of</strong> syllogisms is [. . . ] wholesale rejection <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> their reduction” (Smiley, 1973, p. 138). More precisely, we have<br />

seen that ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction fails (1) to make sense <strong>of</strong> the distinction<br />

between perfect and imperfect syllogisms, (2) to make sense <strong>of</strong> the claim that<br />

some demonstrations are syllogisms (but not all syllogisms are demonstrations),<br />

(3) to make sense <strong>of</strong> direct pro<strong>of</strong>s (by conversion), (4) to make sense <strong>of</strong> reductio<br />

ad impossibile, (5) to make sense <strong>of</strong> ecthesis and (6) to make sense <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

method for the rejection <strong>of</strong> invalid syllogisms. These elements – should I<br />

emphasize it – are fundamental parts or Aristotle’s categorical logic.<br />

The question now arises how exact a correspondence this system has with<br />

Aristotle’s theory <strong>of</strong> categorical syllogisms. Among the arguments provided by<br />

̷Lukasiewicz to justify his point <strong>of</strong> view, we find textual and theoretical reasons.<br />

We have seen that ̷Lukasiewicz’s appeals to textual support are to a large<br />

extent shakier than he claimed. The theoretical arguments also lead to complications.<br />

Notwithstanding the unfortunate consequence that Aristotle’s methods<br />

<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> are all erroneous, there is also embarrassing discrepancies regarding the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> logic. The chief concern is related to the recourse to propositional<br />

logic. There doubtlessly are many important differences between Aristotelian<br />

and propositional logic; it is also doubtless that they diverge regarding what<br />

pertains to logic. This point has a special importance here, since ̷Lukasiewicz’s<br />

refers to “what pertains to logic” to justify that Aristotle could not have used<br />

concrete terms except in a heuristic way. This claim is central for ̷Lukasiewicz’s<br />

analysis since it decides that syllogisms are axioms, and not inferences or rules<br />

<strong>of</strong> inference. As we have seen, ̷Lukasiewicz takes syllogisms to be true (truthfunctionally<br />

true, or tautological) implications. However, to my knowledge,<br />

there is not a single passage in the Prior Analytics where Aristotle discussed or<br />

even mentioned tautological propositions, as being the subject matter <strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

Is it an unimportant detail, or is it due to the more likely fact that for Aristotle,<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> logic was not just to catalogue tautologies 19 If the latter is the case,<br />

it would explain why Aristotle did not use ̷Lukasiewicz’s laws <strong>of</strong> identity and<br />

why he did not use axiomatic rejection. It would also explain Aristotle’s methods<br />

<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>, all <strong>of</strong> which make no sense if we take syllogisms to be axioms, but<br />

make perfect sense if we take them to be rules <strong>of</strong> inference (see next section).<br />

19 For Corcoran (1972, p. 696), this is not a coincidence: “The fact that each sentence<br />

contains two distinct nonlogical constants reflects a systematic avoidance by Aristotle <strong>of</strong> “sentences”<br />

such as Axx or Sxx.”


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 26<br />

The influence <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction was and still is great. Firstly,<br />

it had the fortunate consequence that mathematical logicians were to have a<br />

familiar medium through which Aristotelian logic could be learned. The unfortunate<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the story, however, is that his critique <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s methods<br />

<strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s contributed more than anything to reinforced the idea that the “real<br />

thing” is propositional logic, and that Aristotelian logic presents no more theoretical<br />

interest.<br />

The last question that arises here is the following: Despite the discrepancies<br />

<strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction, should we accept it as the best we can do in<br />

reconstructing Aristotle’s logic by means <strong>of</strong> mathematical models If it were<br />

the case, then ̷Lukasiewicz would be, in a sense, justified. If, however, there<br />

is a more faithful and rigorous reconstruction, then we would have no reason<br />

whatsoever not to reject ̷Lukasiewicz’s reconstruction – however influential it<br />

may be. In the next section, we will present such a reconstruction.<br />

3 Presentation <strong>of</strong> the Corcoran-Smiley View<br />

As we have seen, ̷Lukasiewicz rejected the traditional account <strong>of</strong> syllogisms as<br />

inference and contended that the “true” form <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian syllogisms is that<br />

<strong>of</strong> a material implication. However, if Aristotle’s methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s are to make<br />

any sense, it seems necessary to treat syllogisms as being “essentially something<br />

with a deductive structure as well as premisses and conclusions” (Smiley, 1973,<br />

p. 136), i.e. an inference.<br />

Why is it that the ̷Lukasiewiczian view treated syllogisms as if they were<br />

material implications To answer that is to emphasize a difference <strong>of</strong> perspective<br />

regarding what is the nature <strong>of</strong> logic. ̷Lukasiewicz took logic to be what has<br />

been developed in the previous decades by Frege and Russell. 20 According to<br />

them, the central concept <strong>of</strong> logic is the monadic property “logical truth” rather<br />

than the traditional dyadic relation “logical consequence”. This is what explains<br />

̷Lukasiewicz’s desire to reformulate the syllogistic not as a system <strong>of</strong> deductions<br />

<strong>of</strong> consequences from arbitrary (and therefore sometimes false) premises, but<br />

rather a system <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> logical truths (tautologies) based on logical axioms<br />

and rules (Corcoran & Scanlan, 1982, p. 78). This difference is crucial, since it<br />

determines what is the philosophical role <strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

The influence <strong>of</strong> the Frege-Russell view <strong>of</strong> logic started to decline in the<br />

1930s. <strong>Two</strong> important technical developments in logic did accelerate this change<br />

<strong>of</strong> attitude: (1) Tarki’s rigorization <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> logical consequence and<br />

(2) the construction <strong>of</strong> rigorous systems <strong>of</strong> natural deduction by Gentzen and<br />

Jaśkowski (Pelletier, 1999). The Corcoran-Smiley view can be seen as a byproduct<br />

<strong>of</strong> these developments. Taking benefit <strong>of</strong> this more traditional but<br />

mathematically rigorous approach, they found themselves in a position to argue,<br />

20 We may add Wittgenstein, Quine, and the Polish school in general.


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 27<br />

as opposed to ̷Lukasiewicz, that Aristotelian logic is logically sound in every<br />

detail:<br />

[. . . ] Aristotle’s Prior Analytics contained a logical theory involving<br />

a well-developed logical system (in the modern sense) which is<br />

at once self-contained (not presupposing a prior underlying logic)<br />

and comparable with standard systems <strong>of</strong> propositional logic in simplicity,<br />

precision, correctness, and comprehensiveness. (Corcoran &<br />

Scanlan, 1982, p. 76)<br />

In this section, we will examine their approach.<br />

3.1 Explanation <strong>of</strong> the Approach<br />

The approach adopted by the proponents <strong>of</strong> the Corcoran-Smiley view is (to my<br />

knowledge) best explained in Corcoran & Scanlan (1982). In this subsection, I<br />

will summarize their methodological discussion.<br />

In their framework, the object <strong>of</strong> logic in general – and a fortiori <strong>of</strong> the<br />

syllogistic – is the study <strong>of</strong> valid arguments. It is thus completely natural for<br />

them to see Prior Analytics as being a treatise about deductive reasoning and,<br />

more generally, about the methods <strong>of</strong> determining the validity and invalidity <strong>of</strong><br />

premise-conclusion arguments. An argument has two parts: (1) a set <strong>of</strong> propositions,<br />

called the premises and (2) a single proposition, called the conclusion.<br />

An argument is valid if and only if the conclusion is a logical consequence <strong>of</strong><br />

the premises. The argument is otherwise said to be invalid. Any argument is in<br />

itself either valid or invalid, and this without regard to whether anyone knows<br />

which one is the case. The epistemological function <strong>of</strong> logic is thus to develop<br />

methods providing thinking humans with the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> arguments.<br />

For some very simple arguments, mostly having one or two premises,<br />

the knowledge <strong>of</strong> their validity is obvious, in the sense that each <strong>of</strong> them can be<br />

seen to be valid without considering any other arguments already known to be<br />

valid. Of course, most arguments are not obviously valid, and this is why we<br />

need logic as a discipline. A central topic studied in logic is how we can validly<br />

chain together obviously valid arguments to gain knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong><br />

more complex arguments.<br />

The basic procedure is very neatly described as follow:<br />

The procedure for establishing validity contains a familiar “Kernel+<br />

P rocess” structure. There is a Kernel <strong>of</strong> valid arguments whose validity<br />

is seen ab initio and there is a Process which produces knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> validity from knowledge <strong>of</strong> validity. (Corcoran & Scanlan,<br />

1982, p. 79)<br />

Aristotle, and logicians in general, focus on two epistemic processes:


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 28<br />

1. the process <strong>of</strong> establishing knowledge that a conclusion follows necessarily<br />

from a set <strong>of</strong> premises;<br />

2. the process <strong>of</strong> establishing knowledge that a conclusion does not follow<br />

necessarily from a set <strong>of</strong> premises.<br />

Basically, an argument is known to be invalid when the premises are known to<br />

be true, and the conclusion is known to be false. Such a basic case is called a<br />

counter-example. This method applies trivially to simple cases, but it applies<br />

only to a very limited class <strong>of</strong> arguments. More generally, we obtain knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> the invalidity <strong>of</strong> arguments through a process involving arguments already<br />

known to be invalid. For this reason, it may be said that the procedure <strong>of</strong><br />

establishing invalidity also contains a “Kernel + P rocess” structure: “There<br />

is a Kernel <strong>of</strong> invalid arguments whose invalidity is established ab initio and<br />

there is a Process which produces knowledge <strong>of</strong> invalidity from knowledge <strong>of</strong><br />

invalidity” (Corcoran & Scanlan, 1982, p. 79).<br />

On this basis, we characterize what is a deduction (syllogism) and a pro<strong>of</strong>.<br />

A deduction is the process <strong>of</strong> correctly (validly) inferring a conclusion from<br />

premises, and this process provides us with knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> an<br />

argument. In other words, it is by means <strong>of</strong> a deduction that one comes to see<br />

(for oneself) or to show (to another) that the argument is valid. 21 A deduction<br />

is a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> its conclusion if the premises <strong>of</strong> the deduction are known to be<br />

true. In this framework, we naturally have the result, with Aristotle, that every<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> is a deduction but not every deduction is a pro<strong>of</strong>.<br />

Under this conception <strong>of</strong> logic, deduction in general (and syllogisms in particular)<br />

have an argumentative structure. This view allows to efficiently make<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s distinction between perfect and imperfect syllogisms. Perfect<br />

syllogisms are those arguments whose validity is seen ab initio. Imperfect<br />

syllogisms are those in need <strong>of</strong> a deduction to be known as valid. In other words,<br />

imperfect syllogisms are “perfected” by chaining together (simple) perfect deductions<br />

(syllogisms and/or conversions). For this reason, Corcoran & Scanlan<br />

(1982, p. 80) claim that “Aristotle’s process <strong>of</strong> perfecting imperfect syllogisms<br />

is identified with our process <strong>of</strong> deducing.” Likewise, this conception allows to<br />

easily account for Aristotle’s distinction between direct and indirect deductions.<br />

This distinction “is entirely a matter <strong>of</strong> how their conclusions are derived” (Smiley,<br />

1973, p. 136). When Aristotle says that every argument that can be proved<br />

indirectly can also be proved directly, and vice-versa, he just means that we<br />

can gain knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> an argument by two different (types <strong>of</strong>)<br />

deductions.<br />

Now that we are acquainted with the general character <strong>of</strong> their approach,<br />

21 It is important to distinguish argument and deduction: “A deduction is <strong>of</strong>ten also called<br />

an argument but there should be no confusion because the deduction includes a chain <strong>of</strong><br />

reasoning over and above the premises and the conclusion and it is by means <strong>of</strong> a deduction<br />

that ones comes to see that the (included) argument is valid.” (Corcoran & Scanlan, 1982,<br />

p. 79)


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 29<br />

let us see their technical reconstruction <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s syllogistic as a natural<br />

deduction system.<br />

3.2 Formal Natural Deduction System<br />

Deductive system for Corcoran-Smiley’s Syllogistic (CS) 22 :<br />

1. The alphabet for CS contains:<br />

(a) A set V <strong>of</strong> term constants ‘a, b, c, d, . . .’;<br />

(b) syllogistic operators ‘A, E, I, O’.<br />

2. The well-formed formulas L for CS are the following:<br />

(a) for any two distinct term constants a and b, Aab, Eab, Iab and Oab<br />

are wffs (or sentences);<br />

(b) nothing else is a wff.<br />

3. The rules <strong>of</strong> inference for CS. For any x, y, z ∈ V ,<br />

C1 Exy ⊢ Eyx (conversion)<br />

C2 Axy ⊢ Iyx (conversion)<br />

C3 Ixy ⊢ Iyx (conversion)<br />

PS1 Azy, Axz ⊢ Axy (Barbara)<br />

PS2 Ezy, Axz ⊢ Exy (Celarent)<br />

PS3 Azy, Ixz ⊢ Ixy (Darii)<br />

PS4 Ezy, Ixz ⊢ Oxy (Ferio)<br />

CTR If P, C(d) ⊢ e and P, C(d) ⊢ C(e), then P ⊢ d (Reductio) 23<br />

Definition 1 (Argument) An argument is an ordered pair (P, d) where P is<br />

a set <strong>of</strong> sentences (called the premises) and d is a single sentence (called the<br />

conclusion).<br />

Definition 2 (Direct Deduction) A direct deduction in CS <strong>of</strong> d from P is<br />

defined to be a finite list <strong>of</strong> sentences ending with d, beginning with all or some<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sentences in P and such that each subsequent line (after those in P ) is<br />

either<br />

• a repetition <strong>of</strong> a previous line;<br />

• a CS-conversion <strong>of</strong> a previous line;<br />

22 See (Corcoran, 1972) and (Smiley, 1973).<br />

23 Axy and Exy are defined to be contradictories <strong>of</strong> Oxy and Ixy respectively (and vice<br />

versa) and C(d) indicates the contradictory <strong>of</strong> d.


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 30<br />

• a CS-inference from two previous lines.<br />

Definition 3 (Indirect Deduction) An indirect deduction in CS <strong>of</strong> d from<br />

P is defined to be a finite list <strong>of</strong> sentences ending in a pair <strong>of</strong> contradictories [e<br />

and C(e)], beginning with a list <strong>of</strong> all or some <strong>of</strong> the sentences in P followed by<br />

the contradictory <strong>of</strong> d, and such that each subsequent additional line (after the<br />

contradictory <strong>of</strong> d) is either<br />

• a repetition <strong>of</strong> a previous line;<br />

• a CS-conversion <strong>of</strong> a previous line;<br />

• a CS-inference from two previous lines.<br />

As usual in natural deduction systems, we also define a system <strong>of</strong> annotation<br />

for deductions:<br />

+ Axy := assume Axy as a premise<br />

Axy := we want to show why Axy follows (we interject the conclusion Axy as<br />

Axy after the premisses to indicate the goal)<br />

h Axy := suppose Axy for the purpose <strong>of</strong> reasoning (for indirect deductions)<br />

a Axy := we have already accepted Axy<br />

c Axy := by conversion Axy is entered<br />

s Axy := by syllogistic inference Axy is entered<br />

Ba Axy := at the last line <strong>of</strong> an indirect deduction ‘B’ is prefixed to its other<br />

annotation so that ‘Ba Axy’ is read ‘but we have already accepted Axy’<br />

To illustrate how the system works, consider the annotation <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

deduction <strong>of</strong> the mood Cesare (Pr. An., A.5, 27a5-8):<br />

Let M be predicated <strong>of</strong> no N [+ Enm] and <strong>of</strong> all X [+ Axm] [omitted:<br />

Exn]. Then since the negative premise converts, N belong<br />

to no M [c Emn]. But it was supposed that M belongs to all X<br />

[Ba Axm]. Therefore, N will belong to no X [s Exn].<br />

In the classical representation by means <strong>of</strong> a Fitch Diagram 24 , we obtain:<br />

1 Nnm Premise<br />

2 Axm Premise<br />

Deduction <strong>of</strong> Cesare<br />

3 Nmn Conversion, 1<br />

4 Axm Reiteration, 2<br />

7 Nxn Celarent, 3–4<br />

24 Neither Corcoran nor Smiley use Fitch diagrams, but it seems to me to be an improvement,<br />

from a didactic point <strong>of</strong> view, on their presentation.


3 PRESENTATION OF THE CORCORAN-SMILEY VIEW 31<br />

Here is an illustration <strong>of</strong> an indirect deduction, namely Aristotle’s deduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mood Baroco (Pr. An., A.6, 28b8-12):<br />

For if R belongs to all S [+ Asr], but P does not belong to some S<br />

[+ Osp], it is necessary that P does not belong to some R [ Orp].<br />

For if P belongs to all R [h Arp], and R belongs to all S [Ba Asr],<br />

the P will belong to all S [s Asp]. But we assumed that is did not<br />

[Ba Osp].<br />

The same example represented in a Fitch Diagram:<br />

1 Asr Premise<br />

2 Osp Premise<br />

3 Arp Hypothesis<br />

Deduction <strong>of</strong> Baroco<br />

4 Asr Reiteration, 1<br />

5 Asp Barbara, 3, 4<br />

6 Osp Reiteration, 2<br />

7 Orp Reductio, 3–6<br />

3.3 Objections to the View <strong>of</strong> Syllogistic as a Natural Deduction<br />

System<br />

Without having to compare ̷Lukasiewicz’s view to Corcoran-Smiley’s point by<br />

point, it appears clear that the latter provides a much better reconstruction<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s categorical logic. The fact that they succeed to explain and justify<br />

Aristotle’s methods <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> is entirely sufficient to make us prefer their<br />

approach. It is more sensitive than ̷Lukasiewicz’s approach both from the historical<br />

and from the theoretical point <strong>of</strong> view.<br />

However, despite the merits <strong>of</strong> this reconstruction, there is always place for<br />

some improvement. Raymond (2006) formulated some criticisms <strong>of</strong> this reconstruction.<br />

The idea underlying all <strong>of</strong> them is that their notation for premiseconclusion<br />

arguments – the ordered pair (P, d) – is not explicitly found in Aristotle’s<br />

writings. Whether it is important or not is not entirely clear. However,<br />

he contends that the choice <strong>of</strong> a notation has a strong influence on our understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the basic intuition <strong>of</strong> a system and, for this reason, should not be<br />

neglected:<br />

Of the three components to an underlying logic – notation, system <strong>of</strong><br />

deduction and a system <strong>of</strong> semantics – notation is the one component<br />

that is presupposed by the other two: a system <strong>of</strong> deduction and a


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 32<br />

system <strong>of</strong> semantics both presuppose and exploit the features <strong>of</strong> a<br />

system <strong>of</strong> syntax. (Raymond, 2006, pp. 12-3)<br />

He considers that many hermeneutic problems remain unexplained due to the<br />

inadequacy <strong>of</strong> their linear system <strong>of</strong> notation for premise-conclusion arguments.<br />

Here are nine <strong>of</strong> those problems (Raymond, 2006, p. 114):<br />

1. why, in a treatment that appears to be systematic and complete, is the<br />

fourth figure missing<br />

2. what makes the first figure obvious, when compared to the second and the<br />

third<br />

3. what explains the changing account <strong>of</strong> the major, minor and middle terms<br />

in a syllogism<br />

4. how can Aristotle say that probative pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> imperfect syllogisms produce<br />

the first figure<br />

5. how can Aristotle say that indirect pro<strong>of</strong>s (per impossibile) come about<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> the first figure<br />

6. how to account in a satisfying way for Aristotle’s claim that what is ‘no<br />

syllogism’ can become ‘a syllogism’ by conversion<br />

7. what is to be done with the incompatibility <strong>of</strong> the linear view (where<br />

there is one and only one conclusion) with Aristotle’s claim about the<br />

relationship between the number <strong>of</strong> terms and the number <strong>of</strong> conclusions<br />

in a syllogism<br />

8. why is it said that every syllogism is through three terms<br />

9. why is it that Aristotle’s immediate successor, Theophrastus, added a<br />

indirect first figure but no fourth figure<br />

To answer these questions, Raymond develops an alternative notation making<br />

use <strong>of</strong> diagrams similar to the commutative diagrams used in category theory<br />

(see Goldblatt, 1979). However, I will not examine it here. Instead, I will end<br />

this paper by a discussion <strong>of</strong> the underlying stakes <strong>of</strong> the discussion I have<br />

presented.<br />

4 Conclusion: <strong>Two</strong> Traditions in <strong>Logic</strong><br />

Understanding Aristotle’s theory <strong>of</strong> syllogism is in itself important. However,<br />

in the context <strong>of</strong> our discussion, it is especially important, for it illustrates<br />

fundamental issues about what the nature <strong>of</strong> logic is (or ought to be). An interesting<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the comparison between ̷Lukasiewicz’s and Corcoran-Smiley’s


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 33<br />

reconstructions is to clarify a plurivocity in the discourse <strong>of</strong> contemporary logicians,<br />

concerning what they take logic to be. It has long been noticed that<br />

there are two qualitatively distinct traditions in contemporary logic. In his famous<br />

paper, van Heijenoort (1967) calls them “logic as calculus” and “logic as<br />

language”. Shapiro (2005) calls the former “the algebraic perspective”, while<br />

Hintikka (1997) calls the latter “logic as universal medium”. Peckhaus (2004)<br />

calls them, respectively, “logic as lingua characterica” and “logic as calculus<br />

rationcinator”, after Leibniz famous distinction. However, I think Corcoran<br />

(1994) makes the most precise characterization <strong>of</strong> the two traditions, by calling<br />

them, respectively, “formal ontology” and “formal epistemology”. If both<br />

groups <strong>of</strong> logicians call themselves “formal logicians”, it should be emphasized<br />

that it is for very different reasons. The formal ontologists justify their use <strong>of</strong><br />

the adjective ‘formal’ by the contention that the propositions they deal with are<br />

expressed “exclusively in general logical terms, without the use <strong>of</strong> names denoting<br />

particular objects, particular properties, etc.” (Corcoran, 1994, p. 19) This<br />

point appears to be ̷Lukasiewicz’s real motivation for the claim that concrete<br />

terms do not pertain to logic. On the other hand, the formal epistemologists<br />

justify their use <strong>of</strong> the adjective ‘formal’ by the contention that they deal not<br />

with the content <strong>of</strong> the scientific discourse, but with its form.<br />

Not surprisingly, ̷Lukasiewicz (1957, pp. 4-5) himself distinguishes two trends<br />

in mathematical logic. The first, he calls “the algebraic approach”, and it<br />

includes logicians such as Boole, de Morgan, Peirce, Schröder, Venn, Hilbert,<br />

etc. The second, which he calls “ontology” (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957, p. 15), has<br />

been founded by Frege in 1879, and it has been further developed by Russell<br />

& Whitehead, Lesniewski, the Polish School in general, etc. The question that<br />

seems to animate the debate between the proponents <strong>of</strong> the ̷Lukasiewiczian view<br />

and the Corcoran-Smiley view concerns where Aristotle stands. If ̷Lukasiewicz<br />

is right to claim that Aristotle’s logic is a formal ontology, then we can take<br />

Aristotle to be presenting a system <strong>of</strong> propositions organized deductively. On<br />

the other hand, if Corcoran and Smiley are right, then we can take Aristotle to<br />

be presenting a system <strong>of</strong> deductions, organized epistemically.<br />

Let us examine more closely the two alternatives. ̷Lukasiewicz clearly takes<br />

Aristotle to be doing formal ontology:<br />

In the light <strong>of</strong> investigations by mathematical logic, Aristotle’s syllogistic<br />

is a small fragment <strong>of</strong> a more general theory founded by<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essor S. Leśniewski and called by him ontology. (̷Lukasiewicz,<br />

1957, p. 15)<br />

From this point <strong>of</strong> view, Aristotle (and logicians in general) aims not to understand<br />

the processes <strong>of</strong> determining the validity <strong>of</strong> premise-conclusion arguments,<br />

but he aims to establish as true or as false, as the case may be, <strong>of</strong> certain universally<br />

quantified material implications. This is why it is not an option for the<br />

proponents <strong>of</strong> ̷Lukasiewicz’s view to take syllogisms as inferences. <strong>Logic</strong> does<br />

not examine the logical soundness <strong>of</strong> arguments; it investigates “certain general


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 34<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> ‘reality’, <strong>of</strong> ‘being as such’, in itself and without regard to how (or<br />

even whether) it may be known by thinking agents” (Corcoran, 1994, p. 17).<br />

The best excerpt we can find to illustrate this view is probably one <strong>of</strong> Russell<br />

himself:<br />

[. . . ] logic is concerned with the real world just as zoology, though<br />

with its more abstract and general features. (Russell, 1919, p. 169)<br />

The emphasis is put on (structural) ontology, i.e. on the most general characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> reality itself, and not on the epistemic methods for obtaining<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> the validity or invalidity <strong>of</strong> arguments. Of course, the proponents<br />

<strong>of</strong> this conception need to refer to an epistemic dimension in a way or another.<br />

The point is only that this dimension is not what logic is about. <strong>Logic</strong> is about<br />

deducing the truth <strong>of</strong> propositions that can be expressed using only generic<br />

terms (individual, property, relation, etc.) and other logical expressions. Those<br />

expressions include only variables and non-logical constants (i.e. symbols for<br />

logical operators). In this framework, this generality <strong>of</strong> expression is the only<br />

difference between formal logic and science (since science have to use concrete<br />

terms).<br />

The ontological view <strong>of</strong> logic does not emphasize the epistemic role <strong>of</strong> logic<br />

in any way. The motivation for this attitude goes back to Frege (1994), more<br />

precisely his celebrated charge <strong>of</strong> psychologism against Husserl. This is a fact<br />

that the proponents <strong>of</strong> the view <strong>of</strong> logic as formal ontology generally think<br />

that the study <strong>of</strong> reasoning is not a part <strong>of</strong> logic, but a part <strong>of</strong> psychology.<br />

̷Lukasiewicz, too, agrees on that point:<br />

It is not true, however, that logic is the science <strong>of</strong> the laws <strong>of</strong> thought.<br />

[. . . ] <strong>Logic</strong> has no more to do with thinking than mathematics has.<br />

[. . . ] But the laws <strong>of</strong> logic do not concern your thoughts in a greater<br />

degree than do those <strong>of</strong> mathematics. What is called ‘psychologism’<br />

in logic is a mark <strong>of</strong> the decay <strong>of</strong> logic in modern philosophy. For<br />

this decay Aristotle is by no means responsible. (̷Lukasiewicz, 1957,<br />

p. 12-3)<br />

For ̷Lukasiewicz, it was absolutely essential to defend Aristotle against the possible<br />

charge <strong>of</strong> psychologism that could have resulted from treating his logic as<br />

formal epistemology. From this standpoint, the only kind <strong>of</strong> epistemology that<br />

is acceptable, as Popper (1972) later said, is an “epistemology without knowing<br />

subject”. 25 ̷Lukasiewicz saw Aristotle as making an application <strong>of</strong> the informal<br />

axiomatic method to logic (i.e. formal ontology). This is why he did not notice,<br />

or did not want to notice, that Aristotle was more plausibly describing methods<br />

for the study <strong>of</strong> deductive reasoning.<br />

<strong>Logic</strong> as formal epistemology adopts a radically opposed standpoint. Aristotle’s<br />

syllogistic – and logic in general – is concerned with a methodological episte-<br />

25 See Tournier (1987) for a discussion <strong>of</strong> what is at stake – namely the third world.


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 35<br />

mological problem, namely that <strong>of</strong> developing methods for obtaining knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> the logical validity <strong>of</strong> arguments. Typically, we gain this knowledge by making<br />

a deduction following logically valid rules <strong>of</strong> inference. This is precisely why<br />

natural deduction systems are superior to axiomatic systems to treat this epistemological<br />

problem. However, one may argue, is it not the case that logical<br />

validity is defined in terms <strong>of</strong> truth-conditions In other words, is it not the<br />

case that those inferences that are logically acceptable are the truth-preserving<br />

ones If it were the case, the distinction between formal ontology and formal<br />

epistemology would be, at best, artificial. This widely spread opinion is not<br />

exact 26 , for what really matters is the consequence-conservative property. An<br />

example <strong>of</strong> inference that is truth-preserving but not consequence-conservative<br />

is mathematical induction. As a rule <strong>of</strong> inference, it is logically erroneous, since<br />

there is more information in the conclusion than in the premises. However, as a<br />

constitutive law for the “mathematical realm”, it is totally acceptable. When we<br />

think <strong>of</strong> logical consequence merely in truth-functional terms, the importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the epistemological part may seem to vanish.<br />

For the proponents <strong>of</strong> the Corcoran-Smiley view, Aristotle was concerned<br />

with how human beings deduce a conclusion from premises that logically imply<br />

it. In other words, Aristotle was concerned with the methodology <strong>of</strong> deduction<br />

and invalidation. This aspect <strong>of</strong> his philosophy naturally took place as a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> his general epistemology. For Aristotle, science is axiomatic. Traditionally,<br />

in an axiom system, we prove theorems from axioms that are known to be true<br />

<strong>of</strong> their objects. However, doing that, we make use <strong>of</strong> an underlying logic, i.e.<br />

a system <strong>of</strong> rules <strong>of</strong> deduction that justifies the passage from a proposition to<br />

another. This underlying logic is not itself a part <strong>of</strong> any axiom system, but is<br />

rather presupposed by the axiomatic method itself. From this point <strong>of</strong> view,<br />

logic governs the passage from proposition to proposition and has no ontological<br />

import whatsoever. Such a theory naturally took place in Aristotle’s Organon in<br />

the Prior Analytics, the preamble to his examination <strong>of</strong> the axiomatic science in<br />

the Posterior Analytics. Thus, under the Corcoran-Smiley view, Aristotle is not<br />

making use <strong>of</strong> an informal axiomatic method that would need to be “translated<br />

in logical terminology” (as ̷Lukasiewicz said), for the simple reason that he<br />

did not employ the axiomatic method for his theory <strong>of</strong> syllogisms. Rather, his<br />

syllogistic is meta-axiomatical or metascientific – metascience being a discourse<br />

taking science for object, i.e. what we nowadays call epistemology.<br />

The contemporary discipline bearing the name logic is a far cry from what<br />

it was for Aristotle. <strong>Logic</strong> today includes things going from critical thinking<br />

26 “To say that deduction is truth-preserving is an understatement at best; it is usually an<br />

insensitive and misleading half-truth; and it <strong>of</strong>ten betrays ignorance <strong>of</strong> logical insights already<br />

achieved by Aristotle. [. . . ] Deduction is not merely truth-preserving, it is informationconservative,<br />

i.e. consequence-conservative in the sense that every consequence <strong>of</strong> a proposition<br />

deduced from a given set <strong>of</strong> propositions is already a consequence <strong>of</strong> the given set; there is<br />

no information in the deduced proposition not already in the set <strong>of</strong> propositions from which it<br />

was deduced. Not every truth-preserving transformation is consequence-conservative, but, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, every consequence-conservative transformation is truth-preserving.” (Corcoran, 1994,<br />

p. 15)


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 36<br />

to axiomatic set theory. The canonical view is that we have various first-order<br />

axiomatized systems <strong>of</strong> logic whose metalogic is presented in set-theoretical<br />

terms. This metalogic, which is nothing but a more or less informal version <strong>of</strong><br />

axiomatic set theory, is itself justified by its metatheory. Most <strong>of</strong> the time, this<br />

metametatheory is presented in a non-axiomatized way, most <strong>of</strong> all consisting<br />

in appeals to the meaning <strong>of</strong> the basic logic terms (‘and’, ‘or’, ‘belongs to’,<br />

‘necessarily’, etc.) We can separate all these parts <strong>of</strong> the discipline logic in two<br />

categories: (1) axiomatized formal theories and (2) underlying logic (that makes<br />

the axiomatic exercise possible). If we take for account this stratification <strong>of</strong> logic,<br />

absent in Aristotle’s time, we would say, with Lear (1980, p. 13), that “Aristotle<br />

shares with contemporary logicians a primary interest in metalogic.” Banks<br />

(1948) even proposes strong arguments to sustain that Aristotle’s conception <strong>of</strong><br />

logic is nothing but our current conception <strong>of</strong> metalogic.<br />

If we grant that logic, in its most genuine philosophical sense, is an underlying<br />

logic, the debate between ̷Lukasiewicz and Corcoran-Smiley would have the<br />

following crucial historical stake:<br />

[. . . ] if the ̷Lukasiewicz view is correct, then Aristotle cannot be regarded<br />

as the founder <strong>of</strong> the science <strong>of</strong> logic. Indeed Aristotle would<br />

merit the title no more than Euclid, Peano, or Zermelo, regarded as<br />

founders, respectively, <strong>of</strong> axiomatic geometry, axiomatic arithmetic<br />

and axiomatic set theory. Each <strong>of</strong> these three man set down axiomatizations<br />

<strong>of</strong> bodies <strong>of</strong> information without explicitly developing<br />

the underlying logic [in Church (p. 317) sense].” (Corcoran, 1974a,<br />

p. 280)<br />

If logic is actually the underlying part <strong>of</strong> axiomatic sciences, then it is a formal<br />

epistemology. The direct consequence is that ̷Lukasiewicz is wrong, all the way<br />

down. Also, it would show that the proponents <strong>of</strong> formal ontology are wrong in<br />

saying that axiomatized propositional logic is the ultimately primitive system<br />

<strong>of</strong> logic.<br />

After this discussion, it seems to be objectively clear that the Corcoran-<br />

Smiley reconstruction works much better than ̷Lukasiewicz’s. Being myself more<br />

inclined to adopt the view <strong>of</strong> logic as formal epistemology, it is a satisfying fact<br />

to have a pillar <strong>of</strong> philosophy such as Aristotle on my side. This may certainly<br />

suggest that this view is philosophically more sound. However, even if it is<br />

accepted that Aristotle stands better on the side <strong>of</strong> formal epistemologists, he<br />

may well have been wrong on this point. Deciding which one <strong>of</strong> these conception<br />

is preferable is extremely difficult, as it is always the case when a comparison<br />

between different research programmes is required. However, considering the<br />

long-standing presence <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s philosophy <strong>of</strong> logic, versus the relatively<br />

very short-standing presence <strong>of</strong> the Fregean philosophy <strong>of</strong> logic, we are confident<br />

that adopting the view <strong>of</strong> logic as formal epistemology is better grounded.


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 37<br />

References<br />

Austin, J.L. (1952). Critical Notice on Aristotle’s Syllogistic, from the Standpoint<br />

<strong>of</strong> Modern Formal <strong>Logic</strong>, by J. ̷Lukasiewicz. Mind, 61(243): 395–404.<br />

Banks, P. (1948). On the Philosophical Interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>: An Aristotelian<br />

Dialogue. In: Menne (1962), pp. 1–14. D. Reidel Publishing Company.<br />

Bocheński, I.M. (1948). On the Categorical Syllogism. In: Menne (1962), pp.<br />

15–39. D. Reidel Publishing Company.<br />

——— (1961). A History <strong>of</strong> Formal <strong>Logic</strong>. Notre Dame: University <strong>of</strong> Notre<br />

Dame Press. Tr. I. Thomas.<br />

——— (1963). Ancient Formal <strong>Logic</strong>. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing<br />

Company.<br />

Boehner, P. (1952). Review <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint <strong>of</strong><br />

Modern Formal <strong>Logic</strong>, by Jan ̷Lukasiewicz. The Journal <strong>of</strong> Symbolic <strong>Logic</strong>,<br />

17(3): 209–10.<br />

Copi, I.M. (1961). Introduction to <strong>Logic</strong>. New York: The MacMillan Company.<br />

Corcoran, J. (1972). Completeness <strong>of</strong> an Ancient <strong>Logic</strong>. The Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

Symbolic <strong>Logic</strong>, 37(4): 696–702.<br />

——— (1974a). Aristotelian Syllogisms: Valid Arguments or True Universalized<br />

Conditionals Mind, 83(330): 278–81.<br />

——— (1974b). Aristotle’s Natural Deduction System. In: J. Corcoran,<br />

(Ed.) Ancient <strong>Logic</strong> and Its Modern Interpretations, pp. 85–131. Dordrecht-<br />

Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.<br />

——— (1994). The Founding <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>: Modern Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Aristotle’s<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>. Ancient Philosophy, 14: 9–24.<br />

Corcoran, J. et al. (1982). The Contemporary Relevance <strong>of</strong> Ancient <strong>Logic</strong>al<br />

Theory. The Philosophical Quaterly, 32(126): 76–86.<br />

<strong>Fillion</strong>, N. (2006). The Frege-Hilbert Controversy on the Foundations <strong>of</strong> Geometry.<br />

Master’s thesis, Université Laval, Quebec City.<br />

Frege, G. (1895). Letter from Frege to Hilbert dated 1 October 1895. In:<br />

Frege (1980), pp. 32–4. The University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.<br />

——— (1980). Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. Chicago: The<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press. 214 p.<br />

——— (1994). Review <strong>of</strong> E.G. Husserl, Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Arithmetic I. In:<br />

B. McGuinness, (Ed.) Gottlob Frege: Collected Papers on Mathematics,<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>, and Philosophy. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 38<br />

Gasser, J. (1991). Aristotle’s <strong>Logic</strong> for the Modern Reader. History and<br />

Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>, 12: 235–40.<br />

Geach, P.T. (1972). <strong>Logic</strong> Matters. Los Angeles: University <strong>of</strong> California<br />

Press.<br />

Goldblatt, R. (1979). Topoi. The Categorial Analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>. New York:<br />

North-Holland Publishing Company. 486 p.<br />

van Heijenoort, J. (1967). <strong>Logic</strong> as Calculus and <strong>Logic</strong> as Language. Synthese,<br />

17: 324–30.<br />

Hintikka, J. (1988). On the Development <strong>of</strong> the Model-Theoretic Viewpoint<br />

in <strong>Logic</strong>al Theory. Synthese, 77: 1–36.<br />

——— (1997). Hilbert Vindicated Synthese, 110: 15–36.<br />

Kleene, S.C. (1967). Mathematical <strong>Logic</strong>. New York: John Wiley & Sons Inc.<br />

Kotarbiński, T. (1958). Jan ̷Lukasiewicz’s Works on the History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>.<br />

Studia <strong>Logic</strong>a, VIII: 57–62.<br />

Lear, J. (1980). Aristotle and <strong>Logic</strong>al Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 123 pp.<br />

̷Lukasiewicz, J. (1929). Elementy Logiki Matematycznej. Warsaw: PWN –<br />

Polish Scientific Publishers, 1st edn.<br />

——— (1957). Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint <strong>of</strong> Modern Formal<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2nd edn.<br />

——— (1963). Elements <strong>of</strong> Mathematical <strong>Logic</strong>. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1st<br />

edn. 1st Polish edition in 1929.<br />

Menne, A., (Ed.) (1962). <strong>Logic</strong>o-Philocophical Studies. Dordrecht-Holland: D.<br />

Reidel Publishing Company, 136 pp.<br />

Novak, J.A. (1980). Some Recent Work on the Assertoric Syllogistic. Notre<br />

Dame Journal <strong>of</strong> Formal <strong>Logic</strong>, XXI(2): 229–42.<br />

Patzig, G. (1968). Aristotle’s Theory <strong>of</strong> the Syllogism: A <strong>Logic</strong>o-Philological<br />

study <strong>of</strong> book A <strong>of</strong> the Prior Analytics. Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel Publishing<br />

Company.<br />

Peckhaus, V. (2004). Calculus Ratiocinator vs. Characteristica Universalis<br />

The <strong>Two</strong> Traditions in <strong>Logic</strong>, Revisited. History and Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>,<br />

25(1): 3–14.<br />

Pelletier, F.J. (1999). A Brief History <strong>of</strong> Natural Deduction. History and<br />

Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Logic</strong>, 20: 1–31.


4 CONCLUSION: TWO TRADITIONS IN LOGIC 39<br />

Popper, K.R. (1972). The Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach.<br />

Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Quine, W.V.O. (1951). Mathematical <strong>Logic</strong>. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard<br />

University Press, Revised edn. 346 p.<br />

Raymond, D. (2006). Qua. Ph.D. thesis, The University <strong>of</strong> Western Ontario,<br />

London.<br />

Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. New York:<br />

Dover Publications. 1991. 208 p.<br />

Shapiro, S. (2005). Categories, Structures, and the Frege-Hilbert Controversy:<br />

the Status <strong>of</strong> Meta-Mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 13(1): 61–77.<br />

Smiley, T.J. (1973). What is a Syllogism Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophical <strong>Logic</strong>, 2:<br />

136–54.<br />

Smith, R. (1982). What is aristotelian ecthesis<br />

<strong>Logic</strong>, 3: 113–27.<br />

History and Philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

Smith, R., (Ed.) (1989). Prior Analytics. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing<br />

Company.<br />

Thom, P. (1979). Aristotle’s Syllogistic. Notre Dame Journal <strong>of</strong> Formal <strong>Logic</strong>,<br />

XX(4): 751–9.<br />

Tournier, F. (1987). Les Enjeux du Troisième Monde. Les Cahiers<br />

d’épistémologie, UQAM, no 8702, Montréal.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!