09.03.2015 Views

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Beyond Bioethics:<br />

A Proposal for Modernizing<br />

the Regulation of Human Biotechnologies<br />

Francis Fukuyama & Franco Furger<br />

Paul H. Nitze School Advanced International Studies<br />

Washington, DC


Executive Summary<br />

1 Overview<br />

This report presents a proposal for a new approach to regulating reproductive medicine and<br />

biomedical research in the United States. It is the product of more than three years of research,<br />

and of a study group convened in Washington, D.C., dedicated to this subject. The members of<br />

the study group, numbering 42 people, were chosen to be representative of the different<br />

stakeholders in reproductive medicine and biomedical research, including the American Society<br />

for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM), the Federation of American Societies for Experimental<br />

Biology (FASEB), the American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS), the<br />

Council of Scientific Society Presidents (CSSP), the President’s Council on Bioethics, the<br />

Biotechnology Industry Organization (BIO), the National Osteoporosis Foundation (NOF), and<br />

the Food and Drug Administration (FDA). While they have intensively discussed various issues<br />

raised in this report, these organizations have not been asked to endorse this report or its final<br />

conclusions, which the report’s primary authors take full responsibility for.<br />

It is our belief that the existing system for regulating reproductive medicine and biomedical<br />

research in the United States, while unrivaled in many respects by that of any other country,<br />

contains certain gaps or omissions that will render it increasingly inadequate to meet the<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enges posed by new biotechnologies and medical procedures in the coming years. Other<br />

developed countries have put new regulatory institutions in place already, or are in the process of<br />

doing so in anticipation of new developments, and the United States must follow suit.<br />

In putting forth the proposals laid out in this report, we fully understand the downsides of<br />

regulation. If you regulate something, you get less of it, and many people fear that excessive<br />

regulation of biomedicine will stifle innovation and progress in many areas critical to human<br />

health and well-being. While this fear is often well-founded, we believe that properly designed<br />

regulation can have the exact opposite effect: It can promote research and scientific advances by<br />

establishing a clear framework under which innovation can take place, a framework that<br />

reassures the broader society that the research is being conducted safely and ethic<strong>all</strong>y.<br />

1.1 Domain of Inquiry<br />

In this report, we intend to focus on technologies and medical practices related to human<br />

reproduction and on research activities focused on reproductive tissues. Our reasons for choosing<br />

these areas are that they encompass most of those technologies, existing, over the horizon, and<br />

possible in the more distant future, that bioethicists have pointed to as raising significant moral<br />

and ethical issues. Within this domain lie – among other things – human cloning, prenatal<br />

genetic diagnosis, genetic testing, germ-line modifications, embryonic stem cell research, the<br />

creation of human-animal chimeras and hybrids, and novel forms of reproduction (such as the<br />

creation of embryos from the genetic material from one, three, four, or more parents). It includes<br />

medical and clinical practices involving both old and new assisted reproductive technologies<br />

1


(ARTs) as well as laboratory research involving embryos, both as an object to be manipulated<br />

and as a source of biological tissues like stem cells, and other reproductive tissues.<br />

It should be noted at the outset that to say that these technologies are related to human<br />

reproduction does not necessarily mean that they are intended to produce children. This is<br />

particularly true of embryonic stem cell research, whose end is, of course, the development of<br />

treatments for diseases affecting already-living human beings. Nonetheless, the fact that such<br />

stem cells are derived from embryos and may in the future be capable of producing embryos<br />

means that it is impossible to regulate the broader field of human reproduction without regulating<br />

them. Indeed, the manipulation of stem cells may become the primary technological gateway<br />

through which many of the other reproductive technologies noted above become possible.<br />

To say that these practices should be regulated is not to say that they should be banned or<br />

unduly restricted. As we explain in greater detail below, it is our view that stem cell research<br />

would greatly benefit from being placed within a regulatory framework. But precisely because<br />

embryonic stem cell research today requires the use of embryos and may at some point in the<br />

future lead to the creation of embryos, it is not possible to separate this kind of work from<br />

research and medical practices that aim directly at creating children.<br />

1.2 Embryo Politics<br />

It is safe to say that in the United States, <strong>all</strong> legislation in the general area of reproductive<br />

medicine and biomedical research is made vastly more complicated by the underlying societal<br />

controversy over the moral status of the embryo. Other developed countries that have passed<br />

legislation in this area have reached consensus either to permit (as in the case of Britain) or to<br />

prohibit (as in the cases of Germany and Canada) certain forms of embryo research. In the<br />

United States, there are passionate proponents of both the pro-life and pro-choice positions.<br />

We do not begin from a pro-life position. We believe that human embryos have an<br />

intermediate moral status. They are, on the one hand, not the moral equivalents of newborns;<br />

destruction of an embryo, for us, is not tantamount to murder. On the other hand, we do not<br />

believe that embryos are just clumps of cells like any other tissue specimen; because they are<br />

potential human life, they deserve some degree of respect. We believe that a regulatory system<br />

that keeps track of such embryos, permitting them to be used for select scientific purposes but<br />

prohibiting their casual creation or destruction, is an appropriate way of recognizing this<br />

intermediate status. Our ethical concerns in this area relate not to embryo destruction per se as<br />

much as to other technological possibilities that are either emerging now or will appear in the<br />

coming years.<br />

We raise this issue not to persuade others of our case, but rather to point out that there are<br />

several deeply held alternative views on this issue, over which it is not likely that there will be<br />

consensus any time in the near future. These large moral questions cannot possibly be delegated<br />

to a regulatory agency. They must rather be adjudicated at higher levels of the political system,<br />

in Congress and the state legislatures or, less optim<strong>all</strong>y, through the court system (as has actu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

happened in the case of the legalization of abortion). Indeed, if any kind of regulatory system<br />

2


involving human embryos is to succeed, it is critical to fence off the realm of delegated authority<br />

from the issues of abortion and embryos’ moral status.<br />

We believe that embryonic stem cell research should proceed with federal funding, and that<br />

a new regulatory system will actu<strong>all</strong>y promote that end. We note that Britain, with its Human<br />

Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), has one of the world’s strictest regulatory<br />

environments in this area, and yet is a leader in stem cell research.<br />

1.3 Regulation: General Considerations<br />

Most Americans rightly regard regulation as a necessary evil; with the rapid growth of the<br />

state sector in developed countries in the twentieth century, it became clear by the 1970s to many<br />

people that many parts of the American economy were over-regulated. Much of the thrust of<br />

policy in the United States since then has been to cut back on regulation in areas ranging from<br />

airlines to trucking to electricity to telecommunications. In some cases, like telecom<br />

deregulation, this has led to great success; in others, less so. The dangers of over-regulation<br />

remain, however, and the burden of proof ought to lie with anyone who argues that new<br />

regulatory bodies are necessary.<br />

A useful prudential rule in public administration is not to multiply regulatory agencies<br />

unnecessarily when the new functions required can be performed just as easily by existing ones.<br />

On the other hand, certain historical precedents suggest that it is at times wiser to create a new<br />

institution to deal with a new problem. Take the case of transportation, for example. The former<br />

Interstate Commerce Commission (ICC) was created in 1887 to regulate the new railroad<br />

industry. At the beginning of the twentieth century, the rise of interstate trucking posed the<br />

question of who should regulate this new industry. The Hepburn Act of 1906 gave regulatory<br />

authority to the ICC on the grounds that trucking and railroads were similar, both being means of<br />

moving goods across state borders. Most experts in administrative law believe now, in retrospect,<br />

that this was a mistake: The economics of the rail and trucking industries were very different, the<br />

interest groups involved differed substanti<strong>all</strong>y, and the technical expertise require to regulate rail<br />

service did not spill over into trucks.<br />

When commercial aviation emerged in the 1920s, regulation of this sector could have been<br />

given to the ICC on the grounds that airplanes are simply another means of interstate commerce.<br />

Instead, the Air Commerce Act of 1926 created a new independent Aeronautics Branch within<br />

the Commerce Department to promote and ensure the safety of civil aviation. With the advent of<br />

commercial jet aircraft after World War II, this branch eventu<strong>all</strong>y evolved into two independent<br />

agencies – the Federal Aviation Administration and the Civil Aeronautics Board. It is doubtful<br />

that anyone today regrets this choice to create new agencies to regulate aviation rather than<br />

building on the authority of the ICC.<br />

The question to consider here, then, is not the broad one of whether or not to regulate<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research, as a positive choice was made in this area long<br />

ago. The question, rather, is whether we are currently at a juncture somewhat like the mid-1920s,<br />

when civil aviation first emerged as a new but highly promising industry. Do we regard the<br />

3


issues raised by new biotechnologies as cases of problems with which we are already familiar, or<br />

are they sufficiently different in kind as to merit new regulatory powers? Surely, no one in a<br />

liberal society wants to multiply regulatory agencies unnecessarily or add more layers of<br />

bureaucracy. On the other hand, it is sometimes more efficient to begin afresh rather than trying<br />

to change bureaucratic cultures to handle problems they were never designed to handle.<br />

2 Sources of Concern<br />

2.1 General Ethical Principles<br />

We believe that human reproduction is a particularly important and mor<strong>all</strong>y meaningful part<br />

of human life, and that society has an inherent interest in protecting the human values associated<br />

with it. We will begin by laying out a general set of ethical principles that we believe should<br />

guide regulation in the domain we have defined above – namely, medical practices related to<br />

human reproduction and research activities involving reproductive tissues. We believe that these<br />

general principles are ones that the American public will broadly support, and we have<br />

considerable polling data to back this up. The following is a set of principles that we believe any<br />

regulatory system touching on this domain should promote.<br />

The well-being and health of children. Since reproduction aims at the creation of children,<br />

their welfare ought to be placed first and foremost as an objective of regulation. We believe that<br />

this means, in the first instance, better and more systematic monitoring of health outcomes.<br />

Compared to other developed countries, public oversight of assisted reproductive technologies in<br />

the United States is limited, and funds to carry out studies have thus far also been very limited.<br />

It may seem obvious that the well-being and health of children ought to have priority over<br />

the interests of other stakeholders in reproductive medicine, including parents, doctors, clinics,<br />

and biomedical researchers. Many discussions of new reproductive technologies, however, often<br />

put the wishes and desires of potential parents foremost. Clearly, parents who want children also<br />

want the best for their children, and so the law gener<strong>all</strong>y <strong>all</strong>ows them generous discretion in<br />

following their own instincts, under the assumption that this will also lead to good outcomes for<br />

their children. But it is not always necessarily the case that what parents want will correspond to<br />

the best interest of their children.<br />

We interpret “well-being and health” broadly to mean not just physical health, but<br />

psychological and social well-being as well. We believe that this means that every child has the<br />

right to be genetic<strong>all</strong>y related to a mother and a father, even though they may be brought up in a<br />

variety of households in which the genetic mother and father may be absent. We believe that this<br />

right overrides the interest of parents in creating biological offspring through novel medical<br />

techniques like cloning or the harvesting of fetal eggs (see the following section on prohibited<br />

activities).<br />

4


Equal access to ARTs on the part of infertile couples. At this point, more than one<br />

million children have been born worldwide through ARTs. The benefits of these technologies to<br />

infertile parents have been enormous, and equal access to them ought to be a priority. In the<br />

United States, however, treatment for infertility is often not regarded as an insurable medical<br />

condition, but rather as a health option. Insurance coverage varies by state, and many Americans<br />

do not have access to ARTs because of their cost. Expanding the availability of safe ARTs and<br />

equalizing their costs ought to be a policy priority.<br />

The well-being and health of women. ARTs frequently involve special risks to women,<br />

particularly due to the need to take fertility drugs that stimulate ovulation. Most ARTs involve<br />

invasive medical procedures; new techniques that may become available in the future could lead<br />

to pregnancy complications that do not exist now. We place the priority of women’s well-being<br />

and health somewhat lower than that of children and of infertile couples, only because the<br />

women who take these risks gener<strong>all</strong>y do so voluntarily and in full knowledge of possible<br />

adverse consequences.<br />

Informed consent. It is important to recognize that a great deal of what happens in ART<br />

clinics constitutes a form of experimental medicine. It is very important, therefore, that parents<br />

be fully informed ahead of time as to existing risks, and in cases where procedures are genuinely<br />

novel, that they be informed of this as well. This, in turn, generates requirements for better data<br />

collection on actual risks.<br />

Limits to commercialization. While the practice of medicine using assisted reproductive<br />

technologies constitutes a business for the doctors and clinics participating in it, we believe that<br />

there should be limits to the commercialization of many aspects of reproduction. This involves<br />

limits on production and sale of eggs and sperm, and particularly on the production and sale of<br />

embryos.<br />

Therapeutic over enhancement uses of ARTs. We believe that the priority in biomedical<br />

research and clinical practice ought to be given to therapeutic ends – that is, healing the sick and<br />

relieving the pain and suffering of those suffering from pathological conditions.<br />

These general principles, then, need to be translated into specific rules that would be used to<br />

guide regulators. The rules are divided into two categories: (1) activities that we believe ought to<br />

be banned outright, and (2) activities that should be permitted, but regulated.<br />

2.2 Targets of Prohibition<br />

On the list of banned activities are:<br />

Reproductive cloning. All versions of the cloning legislation that have been introduced in<br />

Congress since 2001 have included bans on reproductive cloning. Human reproductive cloning is<br />

not today something that can be done safely, and for that reason alone should be banned on the<br />

basis of the principle of prioritizing the health and well-being of children.<br />

Creation of chimeras and hybrids. We believe that the creation of human-animal chimeric<br />

and hybrid embryos for the purposes of reproduction should be banned. Other situations in which<br />

5


human and animals cells, tissues, and organs are mixed for purposes of biomedical research are<br />

less problematic and should not be subject to significant restrictions. Animal-derived organs are<br />

now routinely implanted in humans, and animal-derived genes may be available in the future for<br />

treating human diseases; <strong>all</strong> of these are by and large legitimate activities. There may be complex<br />

cases where the degree of human and animal mixing may become ethic<strong>all</strong>y problematic; we<br />

believe that determining this boundary is something that can be left to the regulatory authority, at<br />

least initi<strong>all</strong>y.<br />

Germ-line modification. Germ-line modification of human beings, of the sort that is now<br />

done routinely with plants and animals, cannot now be done safely, and should therefore be<br />

banned. It necessarily involves a kind of experimentation on human beings who will clearly not<br />

be able to give their informed consent, and therefore violates the first and fourth ethical<br />

principles laid out above.<br />

New reproductive possibilities that alter the genetic relationship of parents and<br />

children. There are a number of technologies emerging that will make possible the creation of<br />

children who are not the offspring of one man and one woman, as every human child has been up<br />

to now in the history of our species. We believe that the first ethical principle enunciated, placing<br />

priority on the well-being of children, gives <strong>all</strong> children a right to be born out of the union of a<br />

man and a woman, and that technologies that alter this fundamental relationship ought to be<br />

banned.<br />

Patenting of human embryos. We believe that property rights in a human embryo should<br />

be banned. Property rights are usu<strong>all</strong>y granted to stimulate research and innovation; there will be<br />

plenty of other incentives to conduct necessary embryo research in the absence of ownership<br />

rights in specific embryos.<br />

2.3 Targets of Regulation<br />

Other activities we believe are ethic<strong>all</strong>y legitimate, but ought to be carried out under<br />

carefully controlled circumstances, include:<br />

Research cloning. We believe that research cloning should be permitted but tightly<br />

regulated. We see why many people who are not troubled by the use of excess embryos in stem<br />

cell research may yet oppose the deliberate creation of cloned embryos for research purposes.<br />

We believe, however, that whatever extra instrumentalization this act may imply does not<br />

outweigh the gains potenti<strong>all</strong>y to be derived from this kind of research. It is, however,<br />

particularly important for the regulatory authority to monitor and control this kind of research<br />

very carefully – not just because of what we c<strong>all</strong> the intermediate moral status of embryos, but<br />

also because it is the only way to enforce a ban on reproductive cloning.<br />

Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis. Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) is a service<br />

performed by many fertility clinics. We believe it is an important way for couples with heritable<br />

genetic disorders to ensure that those conditions are not passed down to their children. On the<br />

other hand, PGD involves certain kinds of risks and creates incentives (for example, for the<br />

production of large numbers of eggs and embryos) that could pose serious health problems for<br />

6


the women involved. Using PGD for non-therapeutic purposes raises a host of ethical issues, and<br />

should be strongly discouraged by the regulatory system.<br />

Biomedical research involving early-stage embryos or blastocysts. We believe that<br />

medical research on embryos or blastocysts is important and legitimate, but that it ought to be<br />

done under carefully controlled circumstances, given the intermediate moral status of embryos.<br />

This means that the regulatory authority ought to monitor and control the creation and transfer of<br />

<strong>all</strong> embryos used for these purposes, much as the British HFEA does currently. This kind of<br />

regulatory capacity will also be necessary in order to enforce any reproductive cloning ban.<br />

Commercialization of elements of human reproduction. We believe that the buying and<br />

selling of human embryos should be strictly regulated, again, given their intermediate moral<br />

status. We believe that embryos can be used for research purposes and that a limited market<br />

should be <strong>all</strong>owed to develop to facilitate their transfer (for example, excess embryos from ART<br />

clinics), but that <strong>all</strong> such transfers should be carefully tracked by the regulatory authority.<br />

3 The Current Legislative and Regulatory Framework<br />

3.1 Federal Regulators<br />

Human biomedicine is and has for a long time been one of the most heavily regulated areas<br />

of endeavor in the United States. The FDA’s “gold standard” of costly, double-blind clinical<br />

trials for pharmaceuticals is unmatched anywhere the world. On the other hand, the FDA<br />

regulates only drugs, medical devices, and biological products (or “biologics”), and can regulate<br />

them only on the basis of safety and efficacy. It does not directly regulate the practice of<br />

medicine, which means that the large area of medicine involving assisted reproductive<br />

technologies receives virtu<strong>all</strong>y no direct federal government oversight. While the FDA strictly<br />

enforces testing procedures for new drugs, it does not control their off-label uses, meaning that<br />

doctors are free to innovate and in effect experiment on their patients in such cases.<br />

The other big regulatory institution in the United States is the National Institutes of Health<br />

(NIH), which through its control over federal funding exerts enormous control over the nature,<br />

scope, and direction of scientific research in biomedicine. It is the NIH that now oversees bodies<br />

like the Recombinant DNA Advisory Committee (RAC), and requires institutional review boards<br />

(IRBs) to monitor research involving human subjects. The NIH is not limited to considerations<br />

of safety and efficacy like the FDA; it can and has introduced moral and ethical concerns into its<br />

decision-making. President Bush’s August 2001 decision limiting feder<strong>all</strong>y funded stem cell<br />

research to existing stem cell lines reflected his concerns over protecting embryos, and was<br />

implemented by the NIH. Here, the limits of regulatory authority are different than in the case of<br />

the FDA. The NIH can influence science only through its control of funding; it cannot prohibit<br />

privately funded research, and it has no say over what happens in the private biotech industry.<br />

In addition to the statutes governing the FDA and the NIH, there are other federal statutes<br />

relevant to assisted reproduction, including the Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments<br />

7


(CLIA) of 1988 and, more importantly, the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act<br />

(FCSRCA) of 1992. CLIA was designed to ensure that clinical laboratories meet a range of<br />

quality and safety standards, but it does not provide regulatory guidance for ethic<strong>all</strong>y problematic<br />

reproductive choices. FCSRCA did establish a model program for the certification of embryo<br />

labs that could play a central role in facilitating monitoring practices of reproductive medicine<br />

and compliance assurance. This program, however, has not been implemented by any state, and<br />

would in any event lack credible sanctions.<br />

Publicly funded research on human subjects (by the NIH or any other federal agency) is<br />

governed in large measure by institutional review boards, as required by what is known as the<br />

“Common Rule.” Privately funded research involving human subjects also is subject to IRB<br />

review, but in these cases, IRB review rules and procedures drafted by the FDA apply.<br />

Neither the Common Rule nor the FDA’s own set of regulations governing IRBs and<br />

privately funded research on human subjects establish clear jurisdiction and authority over<br />

potenti<strong>all</strong>y controversial research involving reproductive technologies. IRBs are designed to<br />

protect human research subjects, and not to make judgments about the ethical appropriateness of<br />

the research protocols.<br />

There are, of course, any number of other agencies that have regulatory authority over<br />

various aspects of human biomedicine, including the U.S. Patent Office and the Drug<br />

Enforcement Agency. This agencies’ main mission, however, is not to regulate reproductive<br />

medicine or biomedical research; their impact is not insignificant, but is indirect.<br />

3.2 Direct Legislative Intervention<br />

Since 2001, Congress has attempted more than 40 times to pass legislation related to cloning<br />

and stem cell research. None of these initiatives has become law. These legislative proposals f<strong>all</strong><br />

essenti<strong>all</strong>y in two distinct categories – prohibitions of any kind of cloning research, and bills that<br />

explicitly ban, and often criminalize, cloning for reproductive purposes, but legalize cloning for<br />

research purposes.<br />

An example of the latter is Senate Bill 303, referred to the Senate Judiciary Committee in<br />

2003, where it has languished ever since. This bill establishes a legal framework for conducting<br />

research cloning, requiring that nuclear transplantation research be scrutinized by an institutional<br />

review board, and that informed consent must be obtained from the human subjects involved in<br />

the research. As indicated above, the ability of IRBs to make complex ethical determinations is<br />

very limited, and thus the oversight provided by this framework is inadequate. The British<br />

HFEA, which seeks to facilitate stem cell and embryo research, subjects researchers to much<br />

stricter scrutiny than is laid out in Senate Bill 303.<br />

3.3 Regulation by States<br />

States, and not the federal government, are the primary regulators of the practice of<br />

medicine. The rules they establish in this area may or may not be specific to assisted<br />

reproduction. State regulation includes the licensure of physicians, facility licensure, hospital<br />

8


credentialing, requirements for DEA registration on the part of doctors and hospitals,<br />

enforcement of informed consent rules, establishment of requirements for malpractice insurance<br />

coverage, and other requirements. In theory, states could use these powers to revoke the licenses<br />

of physicians that practice unsafe procedures like reproductive cloning, though it is not clear how<br />

well any state agencies are set up to make rules in this area and to enforce them.<br />

Several states have enacted legislation in the area of reproductive medicine, but state-level<br />

legislations are gener<strong>all</strong>y limited to very specific aspects of reproductive medicine. Recent state<br />

laws either attempt to ban any kind of cloning or limit the ban to reproductive human cloning.<br />

Among the states that have banned both reproductive and research cloning are Arkansas, Iowa,<br />

North Dakota, South Dakota, and Michigan. New Jersey and California, both home to large<br />

biotech sectors, have passed legislation banning reproductive cloning but legalizing research<br />

cloning. In our view, these state measures have failed to provide sufficient regulatory oversight.<br />

California is notable insofar as it drafted model legislation in 2003 to provide for state regulatory<br />

oversight of embryo research, legislation that was then superseded by Proposition 71. The latter,<br />

which passed in November of 2004, removed most prior institutional safeguards, and is in our<br />

view tot<strong>all</strong>y inadequate as a regulatory model.<br />

3.4 Self-Regulation<br />

Both foes and advocates of regulation often see industry self-regulation as quite distinct<br />

from government oversight, but in fact the line between the two is often blurred. The government<br />

often relies on private sector groups to achieve public goals (for example, the Underwriters<br />

Laboratories’ role in consumer safety), or else backs up private enforcement through an implicit<br />

threat of formal sanctions (for example, the Securities and Exchange Commission).<br />

Over the last 25 years, the American Society for Reproductive Medicine has developed most<br />

of the currently existing medical and ethical guidelines in the area of reproductive medicine. The<br />

Society for Assisted Reproductive Technologies (SART), which comprises most of the nation’s<br />

ART programs, has a well-established though narrow history of self-regulation that gathers data<br />

about ART success rates.<br />

In our view, these programs rarely meet the standards of legal precision expected by legal<br />

scholars and policy-makers. Often, they come dangerously close to being simple exhortatory.<br />

Nevertheless, this admittedly incomplete system of private governance provides an important<br />

basis for increment<strong>all</strong>y and selectively strengthening the oversight of the ART industry.<br />

4 Recent Regulatory Initiatives in Other Countries<br />

4.1 The British HFEA<br />

The British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) was established in 1990<br />

on the basis of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, which in turn sprang out of the<br />

earlier Warnock Commission. The act established the HFEA as a new regulatory body to oversee<br />

9


the activities of both private and public clinics and laboratories dealing with ARTs, providing a<br />

licensing scheme for treatment services, the storage of gametes and embryos, and embryo<br />

research. The HFEA monitors and tracks <strong>all</strong> embryos in the United Kingdom. Violation of the<br />

act is considered a criminal offense under British law. The HFEA’s statute creates a governance<br />

mechanism consisting of a 17-member board, appointed for three-year terms that are renewable<br />

once. The board must consist of both men and women, and the number of “lay” members must<br />

exceed the number of those connected with the clinical or scientific research communities.<br />

Positions on the board are advertised, and the selection is made by officials in the UK Health<br />

Ministry. The HFEA is ultimately accountable to Parliament through the minister of health.<br />

Both stem cell research and research cloning are legal in the United Kingdom. While some<br />

decisions by the HFEA have been criticized for being excessively restrictive of the reproductive<br />

rights of potential parents, the organization has by and large facilitated Britain’s emergence as a<br />

leader in reproductive medicine and stem cell research.<br />

4.2 The Assisted Human Reproduction Agency of Canada<br />

The Assisted Human Reproduction Act (AHRA) of 2004 established the Assisted Human<br />

Reproduction Agency of Canada (AHRAC), which as of early 2006 is still in the process of<br />

implementation. This agency was created after a decade-long process of public consultation in<br />

Canada, and it reflects consensus views of Canadian society. The AHRA established a set of<br />

guiding principles from which is derived a list of proscribed and regulated activities. It bans both<br />

reproductive and research cloning; it permits stem cell research, but only that involving excess<br />

embryos. Treatment, storage, and research on human embryos are regulated through licensing.<br />

Both public and private research are covered by the AHRA, which also regulates the sale of<br />

gametes, embryos, and surrogacy.<br />

The AHRAC is an administrative agency modeled on the British HFEA. It is different,<br />

though, in what it regulates, as in Canada, neither research cloning nor stem cell research not<br />

derived from excess embryos is legal. This underlines the fact that similar regulatory powers and<br />

institutional designs can serve societies that make different decisions on the question of the<br />

moral status of the embryo.<br />

4.3 Other Legislative Initiatives<br />

In addition to Britain and Canada, many other countries have enacted legislation to deal with<br />

new reproductive technologies in recent years. Often, the scope of these legislative initiatives is<br />

quite broad. In our report, we have identified 10 issues that these legislations tend to address.<br />

They are embryo research broadly defined, reproductive cloning, research cloning, stem cell<br />

research, pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, chimera and hybrid creation, germ-line genetic<br />

engineering, reproductive services, and the trade and sale of gametes. The table below<br />

summarizes the situation for a subset of these issues, namely reproductive cloning, research<br />

cloning, and PGD. The first column indicates whether a country, as part of its recent legislative<br />

efforts, has established a new regulatory entity.<br />

10


New Regulatory Reproductive Cloning Research Cloning PGD<br />

Authority<br />

Canada Yes Prohibited Prohibited Legislated<br />

Australia Yes Prohibited Three-year moratorium Prohibited<br />

Germany No Prohibited Prohibited Prohibited<br />

UK Yes Prohibited Regulated Legislated/regulated<br />

France Yes Prohibited Prohibited Legislated/regulated<br />

Italy No Prohibited Prohibited Prohibited<br />

Spain No Prohibited Prohibited Legislated/regulated<br />

Sweden No Prohibited Legal Legislated<br />

Japan No Prohibited Legal No action<br />

China No Prohibited Legal Legislated<br />

Singapore No Prohibited Legal No action<br />

South Korea No Prohibited Legal Legislated/regulated<br />

US No Prohibited (de facto) No action No action<br />

Limited space prevents us from including the entire table here, but the essential point is clear<br />

enough: With regard to most of the 10 issues identified above, the United States is an outlier. See<br />

Appendix G for additional information.<br />

5 Pros and Cons of Alternative Approaches<br />

5.1 Maintaining the Status Quo<br />

Pros. Maintaining the status quo, in the eyes of the proponents of this strategy, has one<br />

distinct benefit: It doesn’t cost anything, either to the taxpayer or in terms of opportunity costs. It<br />

is not so much a strategy as the expression of the belief that no government action is needed at<br />

this time. Should the need for governmental intervention arise, it may be possible to simply use<br />

existing statutory and regulatory tools. The FDA de facto prohibition of reproductive cloning is a<br />

case in point. In 2001, the FDA restricted reproductive cloning by requiring that anyone seeking<br />

to provide cloning services receive IRB approval and submit an investigational new drug (IND)<br />

application, conditions that no practitioner of reproductive medicine is likely to fulfill. Until this<br />

administrative decision is successfully ch<strong>all</strong>enged in court, reproductive cloning in the United<br />

States is effectively banned.<br />

Cons. The failure to anticipate the need for new regulatory powers invites societal<br />

overreaction when the inevitable scandal, abuse, or disaster happens. Agricultural biotechnology<br />

provides a vivid example. During the early 1990s, the agricultural biotech firm Monsanto, which<br />

had initi<strong>all</strong>y favored certain forms of regulation like the labeling of genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified foods,<br />

changed policy and argued before the Bush administration that no new regulations were needed.<br />

After the company began marketing its Bt corn and roundup-ready soybeans in Europe, the BSE<br />

scandal broke in the United Kingdom, convincing many European consumers that food safety<br />

regulators were not doing their job. Much of the opposition to genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified foods in<br />

Europe was irrational, but some was based on a view that consumers had a right to decide for<br />

11


themselves whether or not to eat foods that had been genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified. By not supporting<br />

relatively modest forms of regulation like labeling, U.S. biotech firms like Monsanto found<br />

themselves shut out of European markets as the EU imposed its own extremely strict safety rules<br />

on genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified products.<br />

The argument that existing statutory powers can be used to deal with new technologies is<br />

very limited. While it is true that the existing FDA regulatory authority has been interpreted as<br />

giving the agency power to regulate reproductive cloning, the legal grounds for this decision are<br />

weak. Human embryos do indeed consist of “cellular products,” but it is doubtful that the courts<br />

would consider them just another biological material. And there are clear limits to what the FDA<br />

could do. The FDA’s enabling statutes establish that the agency is to regulate on the basis of<br />

safety and efficacy only, and that it does not have authority over the practice of medicine. Apart<br />

from the legal question of whether the statute can be stretched to in effect sneak in new powers,<br />

there is also a legitimate question of whether the FDA has the right kind of bureaucratic culture<br />

and expertise to exercise this kind of authority. Specialists in public administration point out that<br />

agencies are often built around a traditional goal, and that when they are given new goals, they<br />

often have a hard time adapting.<br />

5.2 Increment<strong>all</strong>y Expanding Statutory and Regulatory Authority<br />

Pros. A regulatory strategy designed to increment<strong>all</strong>y and selectively expand existing<br />

statutory and regulatory authority has several distinct benefits. From a pragmatic standpoint, it<br />

may be considerably easier to accomplish most if not <strong>all</strong> of the intended policy goals. Sm<strong>all</strong>,<br />

incremental changes may attract broader political support. Congressional representatives may<br />

conclude that the benefits of implementing this strategy compare favorably to the costs. It may<br />

also be easier to generate sufficient support among stakeholders who are likely to bear some of<br />

the costs associated with new regulations. In addition, selective interventions, by their nature, are<br />

likely to produce fewer unintended consequences. For example, one could envisage modifying<br />

the regulations that govern IRBs so as to make IRBs a more credible institution of ethical<br />

scrutiny. One could also envisage making implementation of the FCSRCA model program<br />

mandatory, and bolstering its implementation by including credible sanctions.<br />

Cons. Nothing speaks against selectively expanding statutory and regulatory powers, per se.<br />

It could make eminent sense, for example, to update the regulations governing IRB review or to<br />

strengthen the FCSRCA. At the same time, minimalist interventions alone are very unlikely to<br />

provide an adequate response to the ch<strong>all</strong>enges raised by new reproductive treatments and<br />

medical research. Nor it is necessarily true that it would be easier to have Congress pass them. It<br />

is quite possible that proposals for the incremental expansion of statutory and regulatory<br />

authority would be ignored by the Congress until an egregious case of abuse receives extensive<br />

media coverage.<br />

12


5.3 Direct Legislative Intervention<br />

Pros. Congress can obviously speak the most authoritatively on important moral questions,<br />

and we assume that large ethical issues will have to be decided in this fashion. Proposed<br />

legislation in the area – like Senate Bill 303, which would ban reproductive cloning but permit<br />

research cloning – has some provisions for regulatory oversight, as do similar bills proposed or<br />

adopted at the state level.<br />

Cons. Typic<strong>all</strong>y, legislative interventions are narrowly focused on a single, idiosyncratic<br />

problem; the intervention may be effective, but its cost rarely justifies its benefits. Legislation,<br />

by its nature, tends to be rigid and difficult to amend. In addition, Congress does not have either<br />

the administrative resources or the technical expertise to debate and discuss the large number of<br />

issues that will emerge as new technologies are developed. For example, specific legislation like<br />

Senate Bill 303 that was introduced into the Senate to permit research cloning does not contain<br />

adequate provisions for regulatory oversight of embryo research, relying as it does on IRB<br />

review alone. Nor does it require that the production and use of embryos be tracked.<br />

5.4 Self-Regulation<br />

Pros. The practice of reproductive medicine already has an elaborate system of selfregulation<br />

in place. Some measure of self-regulation is indeed a necessary requirement for any<br />

effective regulatory system. Designing a credible and effective rule often requires information<br />

and expertise available only to the regulated community. Perhaps surprisingly, self-regulation<br />

can have a significant impact on the practice of reproductive medicine and on medical research,<br />

even in the absence of formal mechanisms of monitoring and enforcement. In some cases,<br />

informal mechanisms of sanction can be quite effective. The case of the Recombinant DNA<br />

Advisory Commission is a case in point.<br />

Cons. Trade associations and professional societies are almost always likely to favor selfregulation<br />

over more formal regulatory approaches; how effective this is depends on the nature<br />

of the sector and the incentives facing the actors in it. Prior to the collapse of Enron, the<br />

American accounting industry believed that its system of self-regulation was adequate to counter<br />

possible abuses; the fact that it was not led directly to passage of the Sarbanes-Oxley bill, which<br />

created a host of new formal accounting rules.<br />

The record of self-regulation in reproductive medicine raises questions as to whether the<br />

procedures currently in place will be sufficient to guard against potential future abuses. There is<br />

considerable evidence that trade associations, absent powerful selective incentives, are reluctant<br />

to take measures that could be interpreted by their members as policing activities. And the RAC<br />

remains an effective tool of self-regulation only as long as the risk of a major public health<br />

disaster is perceived by the scientific community as a real possibility.<br />

13


5.5 Creating a New Regulatory Institution<br />

Pros. There are important reasons why ARTs should be singled out as an area deserving<br />

special legislative scrutiny. Assisted reproduction is not just another branch of medicine<br />

dedicated to restoring a patient’s health; it makes children. The ART field is structured to meet<br />

the needs and desires of potential parents; it is less well-organized to protect the long-term<br />

interests of the children it produces. It is also the area in which new technological possibilities<br />

for reproduction will be developed. Over<strong>all</strong>, a new regulatory system would more effectively<br />

protect the safety and well-being of children. It would also forcefully protect new areas of<br />

promising but controversial medical research. Last but not least, it would endow the United<br />

States with an infrastructure of government geared toward addressing genuine public questions<br />

in a public way, rather than de facto delegating these societal choices to business and scientific<br />

interests.<br />

Cons. Most arguments against a new regulatory system in the area of human reproduction<br />

stem from considerations germane to government regulation, per se. If the government regulates<br />

an activity, there is less of it, and there is a prima facie reason to support the most rapid possible<br />

advance of scientific research into human biomedicine. Regulation always produces<br />

unanticipated consequences as private agents seek to avoid them; one consequence here could be<br />

the moving abroad of both researchers and biotech companies seeking a more favorable<br />

regulatory climate. The United States is the world leader in biomedical research, and would be<br />

hobbling its own competitive advantages by over-regulating itself, not to mention denying<br />

patients the advantages of the latest technologies.<br />

A new regulatory system is costly. These costs include not just the direct cost to researchers<br />

and businesses of complying with new regulations, and the costs to the U.S. government of<br />

running regulatory agencies, but also the opportunity costs of the new research, services, and<br />

products that do not come into being as a result of regulation. That is, a new regulatory<br />

institution risks slowing down the pace of technological advancement and innovation, imposes<br />

opportunity costs, and risks unintended consequences. In addition, new federal regulatory powers<br />

over ARTs will set a precedent for the federal regulation of the practice of medicine.<br />

6 A New Regulatory Institution<br />

6.1 General Design Considerations<br />

In this report, we are proposing that the United States consider creating an entirely new<br />

regulatory institution to deal with human reproduction. We believe that rather than trying to<br />

reinterpret or augment the statutory powers of current regulators like the FDA or the NIH, or<br />

passing new targeted legislation, it is much better to start afresh with a federal agency designed<br />

de novo to deal with the problems and ch<strong>all</strong>enges that will be posed by new reproductive<br />

technologies. To pick up an analogy used earlier, rather than trying to add airlines to the ICC’s<br />

14


egulatory portfolio of railroads and trucks, we want to create the equivalent of a new Federal<br />

Aviation Administration.<br />

We begin with several general institutional design considerations. Highest among our<br />

priorities is the need to design a regulatory institution that cannot be manipulated by any political<br />

constituency. Much of the discomfort among scientists with federal legislation originates with<br />

the fear that the scientific enterprise will f<strong>all</strong> victim to ideological manipulations. On the other<br />

end, opponents of unencumbered scientific and medical research believe that science and<br />

medicine are on their way to becoming “rogue” societal institutions accountable only to<br />

themselves. A credible regulatory institution effectively must dispel these widespread<br />

perceptions; it cannot be perceived as pandering to powerful interest groups. It must operate in<br />

an independent manner.<br />

Ensuring independence in this context is similar but not identical to preventing regulatory<br />

capture. All good regulatory institutions, if they are to do their jobs, must avoid being “captured”<br />

by the sector or interests they are meant to regulate. On the other hand, the regulators need to<br />

work closely with those they regulate, because the agency will be dependent on the latter for<br />

information, implementation, and other matters. Just as institutions should avoid capture, they<br />

should also avoid f<strong>all</strong>ing into a highly adversarial relationship with those they regulate.<br />

The second, seemingly contradictory design consideration pertains to accountability. A<br />

“rogue” regulatory agency that operates in an arbitrary and capricious way is bound to quickly<br />

loose its credibility and to invite intervention by the Congress and the president, not to mention<br />

judicial review. In certain circumstances, technical decisions provide an effective check against<br />

unaccountable behavior. Agencies such as the Federal Aviation Administration (responsible for<br />

aviation safety) and the Nuclear Regulatory Commission (responsible for the safety of nuclear<br />

power plants) are certainly no example of “bureaucratic drift,” even though they do enjoy a<br />

measure of formal independence. The situation in the case of reproductive medicine and<br />

biomedical research bears only limited similarity to these cases. Ensuring the health and safety of<br />

future generations would require our agency to make choices largely based on scientific and<br />

medical evidence. In other cases, however, the agency would have to resolve difficult ethical<br />

dilemmas for which no independent or scientific guidance is likely to exist. Under these<br />

circumstances, independence may be perceived as “bureaucratic drift.”<br />

A third, related design consideration is avoiding political gridlock. The practice of medicine<br />

involving assisted reproduction as well as the scientific research community doing work in the<br />

area of reproductive medicine, stem cells, and developmental biology would strongly prefer to<br />

work without regulatory constraints, and indeed with substantial government funding for<br />

research in this area. There are, on the other hand, pro-life groups that strongly oppose any<br />

research that involves the destruction of embryos, including stem cell research and research<br />

cloning. Both groups are just politic<strong>all</strong>y strong enough to block the other from achieving its<br />

agenda.<br />

Our report shows that these polarized interest groups actu<strong>all</strong>y do not represent the views of<br />

the general American public, which in many ways is more flexible and centrist on issues<br />

15


egarding reproductive biomedicine than the current debate would suggest. Looking over 120<br />

survey questions asked from 1993 to 2004, three consistent tendencies emerge. First, large<br />

majorities of Americans oppose reproductive cloning outright. Second, there is considerable<br />

ambivalence about research cloning: It is opposed by a two-to-one margin if the question is<br />

posed in a “neutral” fashion; opposition rises to 80 percent if the question mentions only embryo<br />

destruction, and f<strong>all</strong>s to approximately 50 percent if only the benefits of cloning are mentioned.<br />

Third, there is fairly strong support for embryonic stem cell research; a recent Harris poll, for<br />

example, shows 72 percent of respondents favoring human embryonic stem cell research if<br />

excess embryos are used, compared to only 13 percent opposed. The public, in other words,<br />

favors policies that lie somewhere between the libertarian scientific community and the<br />

restrictive pro-life community, and would be favorable to proceeding, as we suggest, with<br />

embryo research that was closely regulated.<br />

The governance structure for this new agency would be built on three levels. Congress<br />

would delegate regulatory authority to a newly established administrative agency, just as is done<br />

currently in the British, Canadian and Australian cases. The agency could be either an<br />

independent or an executive agency. Our report explores design options for both. The main<br />

benefit of establishing an independent agency lies obviously in its independence from the White<br />

House. An executive agency may not enjoy the same independence from the office of the<br />

president, but would have other benefits, chief among them being efficiency in decision-making.<br />

In either case, a regulatory agency should be sufficiently insulated from undue political<br />

influences and regarded by <strong>all</strong> affected parties as a credible and trustworthy regulatory<br />

institution.<br />

The second level of this new regulatory structure is a permanent advisory board. The<br />

advisory board would have two main goals: to carefully explore <strong>all</strong> relevant ethical<br />

considerations pertaining to complex ethical dilemmas, and to provide medical and scientific<br />

advice to the regulatory institution. The board would operate in accordance with rules established<br />

in the enabling legislation designed to protect the appointment process against political<br />

manipulations. In particular, the statute would ensure that the board is broadly representative of<br />

the three main constituencies in this field – reproductive medicine, biomedical research, and the<br />

public at large. The statute also would establish the relative weight of each constituency on this<br />

board.<br />

The third level encompasses a variety of novel mechanisms of public consultation in<br />

combination with a more structured rule-making process. Broad public consultation should<br />

protect the agency not only against undue political influence, but also against agency drift. It is,<br />

in other words, a quintessential accountability mechanism. These institutions of public<br />

consultation would have to meet several requirements: Participants need to be well-informed<br />

about the scientific and medical aspects of the controversy, the consultation process must be<br />

deliberative, and the participating sample should be representative of the public at large. Clearly,<br />

not <strong>all</strong> of these requirements can be met equ<strong>all</strong>y well and at the same time. We do, however,<br />

16


elieve that it is possible to design institutions of public consultation that are far superior to both<br />

current administrative practices and recent proposals designed to democratize science policy.<br />

6.2 The Independent Commission<br />

We believe the organizational format in the best position to meet a Congressional mandate is<br />

an independent commission. The newly established regulatory agency often will be c<strong>all</strong>ed upon<br />

to adjudicate among competing ethical claims in the light of fairly generic statutory provisions.<br />

Resolving these controversies is not too dissimilar from issuing a judicial opinion. To be<br />

regarded as authoritative by <strong>all</strong> affected constituencies, these decisions must be based on a<br />

careful examination of <strong>all</strong> ethical aspects. The “finding of fact” would benefit from a deliberative<br />

approach to resolving ethical dilemmas. Deliberation also would contribute to produce consensus<br />

policies rather than simply majority positions. On the other end, decision-making would be<br />

relatively slow. In this case, however, a slow pace of decision-making must be regarded as a<br />

benefit rather than as a drawback. In areas as controversial as reproductive medicine and<br />

biomedical research, producing policies widely regarded as legitimate by <strong>all</strong> affected parties is<br />

more important than efficient decision-making. An independent commission is well-positioned<br />

to meet these requirements.<br />

When it comes to the creation of an independent commission, many precedents exist,<br />

beginning with the Interstate Commerce Commission in 1887. Appointment rules are specified<br />

by statute to produce some combination of political balance, expertise, and independence. The<br />

commissioners are appointed by the president for a fixed term and have to be approved by the<br />

Senate; they do not serve “at the pleasure” of the president, and can be removed only “for<br />

cause.” Furthermore, commissioners on the new agency would serve for fixed terms. The terms<br />

of office could be set so as not to coincide with the presidential term. Appointments could be<br />

limited to one term only, and neither political party should hold a clear majority on the<br />

commission. These are uncontroversial rules that have often been adopted throughout the history<br />

of the administrative state.<br />

6.3 The Permanent Advisory Board<br />

Regulatory interventions in reproductive decisions and scientific research are so sensitive<br />

and controversial as to warrant consulting <strong>all</strong> parties that are directly and negatively affected by<br />

these interventions. In addition, the commission would not embody the broad range of ethical,<br />

medical, and scientific expertise necessary to craft authoritative policies. A suitably designed<br />

permanent advisory board would fill this gap. The board should include specific positions for<br />

representatives of the ART sector, patients groups, the scientific community, and the biotech<br />

industry.<br />

The permanent advisory body is not too dissimilar from a board of directors. To prevent this<br />

board from being dominated by the regulated interests, appointing independent board members<br />

might be a wise approach. Over the last 15 years, the private sector has recognized that there is<br />

considerable wisdom in appointing independent board members. These individuals are selected<br />

17


to represent constituencies that are crucial to the financial well-being and the public image of the<br />

firm. In our report, we follow the spirit of this approach by recommending that the enabling<br />

statute explicitly require appointing a number of independent board members equal to or greater<br />

than the total number of board members representing specific constituencies.<br />

The criteria for selecting and appointing independent board members, also included in the<br />

enabling legislation, must ensure that the selected individuals are regarded by <strong>all</strong> constituencies<br />

as genuinely independent. Thus, viable candidates for the position of independent board member<br />

should not have strong ties to the ART and biotech industries or to the scientific community.<br />

They should not have close relatives with medical conditions that could be cured by promoting<br />

certain types of research, nor should they have financial interests in companies that may be<br />

affected by the commission’s policies. They should also bring with them the analytical skills and<br />

life experience required to navigate complex questions at the intersection of ethics, science, and<br />

medicine in a charged political environment. Importantly, they should not be advocates<br />

representing scientific, trade, professional, or religious groups.<br />

Unlike the independent commission, the advisory board would make recommendations by<br />

majority vote, and would include minority positions in its recommendations as deemed<br />

appropriate. The advisory board task is not to develop consensual recommendations that would,<br />

by their nature, restrict the range of ethical considerations, but rather to provide the<br />

commissioner with a broad ethical and scientific analysis of the issue under consideration. The<br />

board would also serve as an institutionalized link between the commission and the regulated<br />

communities. In this role, it would also make negotiations between regulators and those<br />

regulated more transparent, and reduce the room for regulatory capture.<br />

6.4 Traditional Mechanisms of Public Consultation<br />

One of the most often recurring and most important themes in public administration is<br />

agency accountability. It is fair to say that no consensus exists among commentators on the<br />

proper balance between agency discretion and agency accountability, or on the appropriate<br />

mechanisms to ensure accountability. Our report suggests that this debate has placed too much<br />

attention on traditional mechanisms of accountability, such as Congressional oversight, executive<br />

scrutiny, notice-and-comment, and judicial review, and has ignored some relatively<br />

straightforward alternatives.<br />

It has long been a common legislative and administrative practice to ensure some measure of<br />

accountability by requiring public participation in the regulatory process. Tradition<strong>all</strong>y, this has<br />

often meant that agencies have resorted to public hearings, and in some cases to notice-andcomment<br />

(mandated by the Administrative Procedure Act) as their main vehicle to engage the<br />

general public.<br />

Both approaches are ill-suited to engage a broader audience. By the time a proposed new<br />

rule is published in the Federal Register, it has already been extensively vetted by the agency in<br />

consultation with leading interest groups. Comments usu<strong>all</strong>y produce only marginal changes, and<br />

the process is used by the agency to build its record in the case of judicial review, and not as a<br />

18


tool of public participation. Public hearings, for their part, are used most effectively by wellorganized<br />

interest groups to express their views on controversial agency decisions. As a result,<br />

they tend to reflect only the views of established interest groups, and thus tend to distort the<br />

process of public consultation rather than broaden it. Agencies, for their part, can use public<br />

hearings in strategic ways so as to minimize interference with their decision-making processes.<br />

In sum, public hearings are ineffective at best and have a distorting impact at worst on the<br />

administrative decision-making process.<br />

The c<strong>all</strong> for the democratization of decision-making in the area of science and technology<br />

policy has produced a few institutional innovations, such as citizens’ juries, citizens’ advisory<br />

panels, and consensus conferences. The Environmental Protection Agency and the Department<br />

of Energy, in particular, have frequently relied on citizens’ panels to implement highly<br />

controversial policies at the local level. In this role, these approaches gener<strong>all</strong>y have been<br />

beneficial. Their role in decision-making at the federal level is much more problematic, however,<br />

mainly because the relationship between citizens and regulators has never been specified, and<br />

because it is often unclear to what extent the views expressed by these sm<strong>all</strong> groups of citizens<br />

may be regarded in any way as indicative of broader public sentiments. Against this background,<br />

it is not immediately clear why a regulatory agency should take the recommendations adopted by<br />

such a sm<strong>all</strong> group seriously. In sum, neither traditional tools of public consultation nor more<br />

recent approaches for engaging the public provide sufficient safeguards against arbitrary and<br />

capricious agency behavior.<br />

6.5 New Approaches to Public Consultation<br />

We believe that formal rule-making authority should lie with the agency, but that the latter<br />

should be required to gauge public opinion through certain structured mechanisms for public<br />

consultation. As mentioned earlier, one of the main goals of this process is to reach out to the<br />

public beyond established interest groups; the credibility of the process should rest on two main<br />

elements: The consulted sample should be representative of the general public, and the<br />

participating individuals should be reasonably well-informed about underlying scientific facts. In<br />

addition, the consultation process should be deliberative – that is, it should seek to mold<br />

preferences through debate and discussion rather than simply to record preferences. More<br />

specific<strong>all</strong>y, deliberation, if properly designed, may help expand the “argument pool,” may<br />

facilitate finding common ground on controversial issues, and may gener<strong>all</strong>y push participants<br />

toward more nuanced positions. We suggest that the new agency make use of either one of the<br />

following mechanisms for public participation.<br />

6.5.1 Deliberative Panels<br />

Our first proposal expands and refines the concepts of consensus conferences and citizens’<br />

panels. As pointed out earlier, the modest size of the panels means that recommendations<br />

developed at consensus conferences are not representative and lack legitimacy. A simple and<br />

straightforward way to increase the legitimacy of these panels is to assemble several of them.<br />

19


“Deliberative panels,” the term we use in our report to identify this approach, could be organized<br />

around the country, both in urban and rural areas. Each panel would consist of up to a dozen<br />

participants; this size ensures that deliberation remains feasible, yet makes assembling the panels<br />

a manageable task. Recruitment would reflect key socio-demographic variables such as sex, age,<br />

and education. Locations would be selected to account for important cultural and regional<br />

differences. At each location, deliberative panels should be conducted more than once and with<br />

different participants.<br />

This approach has existed in the form of town h<strong>all</strong> meetings, which are familiar means of<br />

engaging the public on matters of national importance. In the present case, however, we envision<br />

the agency conducting more than half a dozen deliberative panels, while reducing dramatic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

the number of participants. Clearly, the more deliberative panels the agency convenes, the more<br />

representative the results. Just how many panels can and should be convened is not as important<br />

as the observation that the upper bound is likely to be much higher than one might anticipate.<br />

The decentralized nature of this process and the need to query scientific experts representing<br />

various positions (biotech industry specialists, academic scientists, regulatory scientists, and so<br />

on) c<strong>all</strong> for making extensive use of new information technologies in the form of a centralized<br />

information and consultation clearinghouse. An Internet-based clearinghouse could greatly<br />

facilitate learning and information exchange among <strong>all</strong> lay panelists. In addition to providing<br />

basic scientific information, the clearinghouse would serve as a central repository for any<br />

question submitted by panelists to experts and for the answers provided by these experts. The<br />

clearinghouse would also serve as a repository for the conclusions reached by each deliberative<br />

panel.<br />

At the present time, there are only few examples of Web-based resources designed as both<br />

informational and deliberative resources. Our own Human Biotechnology Governance Forum<br />

was intended to serve exactly these two goals, but constraints on our resources have prevented us<br />

from fully implementing it. 1 The Center for Genetics and Society Web site is probably the single<br />

best source of information available in this area, but it does not include an interactive<br />

component. 2 The Geneforum, a non-profit initiative launched in Oregon in 1998, pursues similar<br />

goals, but it is still under development. 3 None of these Web resources fully implements the<br />

concept of information clearinghouse as envisioned here, but taken together, they suggest that<br />

implementation is within reaching distance. They also demonstrate that implementing our<br />

approach is both a financi<strong>all</strong>y and organization<strong>all</strong>y feasible proposition that an average federal<br />

agency could easily accomplish.<br />

Consultative panels are clearly superior to both traditional surveys and one-shot, sm<strong>all</strong>group<br />

consultations such as consensus conferences and citizens’ panels, and should be preferable<br />

and far more credible than traditional methods of public consultation such as hearings and<br />

1<br />

2<br />

3<br />

See http://www.biotechgov.org.<br />

See http://genetics-and-society.org/.<br />

See http://www.geneforum.org/.<br />

20


notice-and-comment. As such, it would be difficult for well-established interest groups and for<br />

elected representatives to dismiss the recommendations emerging from deliberative panels as<br />

unreliable or not representative.<br />

6.5.2 Consultative College<br />

The second option we examine in our report is what we c<strong>all</strong> the consultative college. The<br />

consultative college is reminiscent of but not identical to James Fishkin’s deliberative polling. A<br />

consultative college consists of a randomly selected, representative sample of the general<br />

population. Key to this institution of public consultation is the Internet. The members of the<br />

consultative college are not required to physic<strong>all</strong>y meet in one location for a limited period of<br />

time. Instead, the consultative process takes place over an extended period of time. For example,<br />

college members could meet online on a regular basis, say once or twice a week, for two months.<br />

To facilitate the discussion, participants would be assigned to sm<strong>all</strong>er groups of approximately a<br />

dozen individuals. This is the approach that the Genetics and Public Policy Center took in the<br />

summer of 2004 to study public attitudes toward new reproductive technologies.<br />

The consultative process follows a familiar plot: College members would first familiarize<br />

themselves with the scientific underpinnings of the issues at stake. This could be accomplished<br />

in the same way as discussed for deliberative panels. Participants will be given an opportunity to<br />

engage a panel of experts. Questions (and answers) posed by one group would be made available<br />

online to <strong>all</strong> members of the consultative college. The convening agency would then put several<br />

questions to the online groups, including questions designed to elicit ethical reasons for and<br />

against a new medical or reproductive procedure, and questions aimed at evaluating policy<br />

options. In the final step, the agency would summarize and evaluate the range of expressed<br />

concerns and attitudes toward various policy options.<br />

Polling organizations for years have assembled permanent or semi-permanent representative<br />

panels. These panels are being polled on a regular basis on any number of current topics, mainly<br />

by telephone. In recent years, organizations such as Knowledge Networks have begun using the<br />

Internet to enable online discussions among the panel members. And, as mentioned above, over<br />

the summer of 2004, the Genetics and Public Policy Center conducted an Internet-based<br />

deliberative poll similar to what we are proposing here. The logistics of online deliberation are<br />

not trivial, nor are its costs. At the same time, the Genetics and Public Policy Center’s experience<br />

with online deliberation clearly demonstrates that it is both possible and perfectly sensible to<br />

envision mechanisms of public consultation above and beyond either traditional surveys or focus<br />

groups.<br />

Compared to other forms of public consultation, the consultative college has several<br />

benefits. It is more cost-effective, although perhaps not as much so as one might think. The entry<br />

barriers for average citizens are lower, since joining a consultative college does not encroach on<br />

the participants’ daily routines. In addition, online discussion may have desirable attributes not<br />

shared by traditional, face-to-face communication. For example, in an anonymous setting, the<br />

21


participants may be able to engage each other in a way much less encumbered by individual<br />

status and prestige.<br />

Having emphasized the benefits of the consultative college, we should point out some<br />

difficulties. The quality of online deliberation may not be comparable to traditional, face-to-face<br />

deliberation. This may indeed be the price for ensuring representativeness. Just how much the<br />

quality of the dialogue would suffer from a shift to online deliberation is an important and stillopen<br />

question. Heavy reliance on information technologies could prove a barrier for some,<br />

especi<strong>all</strong>y among the poor and the uneducated. Access to information technologies is less and<br />

less of a problem, however, as most public libraries, even in remote locations, provide free<br />

access to the Internet. A more important hurdle is literacy. Being required to read and write<br />

messages may constitute a serious problem for people with little education. Conceivably, the<br />

convening agency could recruit volunteers willing to help these individuals overcome what may<br />

be a significant barrier. There may well be other ways to address these concerns. We recognize<br />

that convening a consultative college may raise a host of issues and concerns that we haven’t<br />

discussed or addressed. Our aim here is not to develop a full-blown proposal for reforming<br />

modern institutions of representative democracy. Rather, we want to make a sufficiently specific<br />

case for experimenting with new forms of public consultation. We hope our readers will find our<br />

discussion compelling enough to explore our proposals in more depth and offer suggestions as to<br />

how to develop them more fully.<br />

6.5.3 Semi-Traditional Survey Techniques<br />

Expanding the number of deliberative panels is a straightforward way to ensure<br />

representativeness. Similarly, assembling a large consultative college would <strong>all</strong> but ensure that<br />

the recommendations emerging from the consultation process would be quite reliable.<br />

Realistic<strong>all</strong>y, it may not always or even often be possible to fully implement this vision.<br />

Depending on the availability of time and resources, an agency may have to limit itself to<br />

assembling a sample that is not large enough to be considered representative of the whole U.S.<br />

population. To address this limitation, one could consider exploring the panoply of instruments<br />

nowadays available to survey researchers. Resorting to survey techniques would <strong>all</strong>ow<br />

administrators and politicians systematic<strong>all</strong>y to assess the relative importance of ethical<br />

arguments in the general population. The agency responsible for the consultative process could<br />

compile a list of the highest-ranking ethical arguments in favor of and the against a controversial<br />

ART procedure or research field. It would then use this information to conduct a representative<br />

survey of the general population. The agency should control for several key variables, including<br />

a priori views and levels of expertise. Participants in this case would simply be asked to weigh<br />

on a scale the extent of their agreement or disagreement with the ethical arguments uncovered by<br />

the deliberative panels. A similar approach could be used to evaluate alternative policy options.<br />

While purists may find this suggestion distasteful, we believe that in combination with novel<br />

institutions of public consultation, survey techniques would provide regulators and<br />

22


Congressional representatives with a picture of public attitudes unmatched by current<br />

approaches.<br />

6.6 <strong>Final</strong> Remarks<br />

Some commentators might criticize the institutions of public consultation proposed in this<br />

report as not being “open and transparent.” We freely acknowledge that public consultation as<br />

envisaged here, perhaps paradoxic<strong>all</strong>y, would not appear to be as open or transparent as<br />

traditional mechanisms like public hearings. The legitimacy and credibility of the outcomes<br />

produced by our institutions of public consultation depend cruci<strong>all</strong>y on the convening agency<br />

maintaining tight control over the process itself. “Opening” the consultation process to anyone<br />

and everyone would obviously undermine any claim to representativeness and make the<br />

deliberative stage unmanageable, not to mention expose the entire consultative process to blatant<br />

manipulations by organized interests. The proper place for the general public and interest groups<br />

to provide their feedback is the notice-and-comment phase afforded to <strong>all</strong> citizens by the<br />

Administrative Procedure Act. To facilitate public feedback, the agency would be required not<br />

only to publish the proposed rule in the Federal Register, but also to take steps to make the<br />

consultation process and <strong>all</strong> related materials broadly available.<br />

7 Constitutional Constraints<br />

Deciding whether restrictions on the use of new reproductive technologies may be<br />

unconstitutional is a question fraught with difficulties. For starters, the label “new reproductive<br />

technologies” includes several and very diverse technologies that would have to be examined<br />

individu<strong>all</strong>y. The particular use of a given reproductive technology and the circumstances of its<br />

use do of course matter a great deal. Yet the Supreme Court, as a matter of general practice,<br />

renders its opinions on narrow grounds, and is very reluctant to generalize its rulings above and<br />

beyond the case under consideration. In addition, there are only a few judicial precedents<br />

relevant to this field of medicine, and there certainly are no well-established societal traditions<br />

that the Court could invoke absent relevant case law.<br />

There is considerable agreement among legal commentators that the Constitution does not<br />

explicitly recognize a fundamental reproductive right, i.e., a positive right to reproduce. The<br />

same commentators also agree that the Supreme Court is likely to recognize this right under<br />

limited circumstances. A variety of precedents related to establishing a right to privacy and to<br />

family, intimate relationships, and reproduction support the view that the Court would probably<br />

recognize this right, at least in those cases that involve intimate relationships and traditional<br />

forms of procreation.<br />

Whether the Court would be inclined to expand a fundamental but limited right to<br />

procreation to protect the use of any and every new reproductive technology designed not just to<br />

facilitate procreation but also to exercise an increasingly tight control over it is doubtful. The<br />

Court, more often than not, has ruled on negative reproductive rights, and has never defined the<br />

23


outer limits of the right to privacy. The Court could invoke unenumerated rights, but it would<br />

also have to show that these rights are consistent with enumerated rights. We believe that<br />

technologies of reproductive control are not simply a natural extension of more traditional forms<br />

of assisted reproduction, but that they represent a radical departure from well-established assisted<br />

reproductive technologies. The Court should not grant them fundamental status before society<br />

and Congress have had an opportunity to properly debate their pros and cons.<br />

8 International Considerations<br />

There has been a great deal of legislative experimentation at the domestic level in many<br />

OECD countries. The scope of adopted legislative and regulatory measures varies significantly<br />

from country to country, and seems to reflect both cultural sensitivities and political realities.<br />

Our report has scrutinized numerous legislative approaches ranging from Europe to Asia,<br />

Australia, and Canada. The only consistent finding emerging from this review is that apart from<br />

a ban on reproductive cloning, there is very little agreement across nations on the nature and<br />

scope of legislative and regulatory interventions. Certainly, there is no agreement on whether to<br />

ban or regulate research cloning. Other less visible but just as controversial issues, such as the<br />

use of PGD for non-therapeutic uses, research on human embryos broadly defined, and the<br />

production of hybrids and chimeras, often do attract the attention of domestic legislators, but no<br />

coherent pattern has yet to emerge from this flurry of domestic legislative activities. They are<br />

documented in some detail in our report.<br />

The divergence of national priorities and the widely different scope of these approaches<br />

suggest that it is far too early to envisage crafting broad international treaties. The repeated and<br />

failed attempts by the United States and Costa Rica to ban both reproductive and research<br />

cloning at the international level clearly illustrate this fact. Against this background, it would<br />

also be unwise to c<strong>all</strong> for the criminalization of any or <strong>all</strong> of these technologies, as some<br />

commentators have suggested. Resorting to the International Court of Justice to render verdicts<br />

on matters that have just barely begun to be debated at domestic levels strikes us as ill-advised.<br />

For the time being, the least damaging course of action seems indeed to be simply <strong>all</strong>owing<br />

nations to develop their legislative responses, and addressing international disputes in this area<br />

on a case-by-case basis.<br />

24


Acknowledgements<br />

Although this is the work of two individuals, its contents reflect the contributions of many<br />

people. We would like first to thank <strong>all</strong> members of our study group. Their interest in this topic<br />

and their probing comments have greatly improved the quality of this report. A special thank<br />

goes to Leon Kass. His work as Chairman of the President’s Council on Bioethics and his<br />

participation in our study group have been a precious source of inspiration. We owe special<br />

gratitude to Rebecca Dresser, Gail Javitt, O. Carter Snead, Mary Ann Glendon, Steven Goldberg,<br />

Erika Lietzan, Lorie Knowles and Steven Croley for their help in matters concerning the<br />

administrative law and constitutional aspects of our projects. A special thank goes to Michele<br />

Garfinkel, Dan Sarewitz and Richard Hayes for their encouragement and detailed feedback on<br />

various parts of our report. Kathy Hudson and Joan Scott have been an invaluable source of<br />

information on reprogenetics and participatory methods. We would also like to thank Sean<br />

Tipton for his helping us better understand the reproductive sector and Marty Apple for his<br />

critical comments. Jennifer J. Kurinczuk has been very patient in guiding us through the maze of<br />

epidemiological studies on the safety of reproductive procedures. We also owe a debt of<br />

gratitude to Jon Tucker, Christopher T. Hill, and Roberto Mazzoleni, with whom over the years<br />

we had numerous and invaluable conversations. We would like to thank Cynthia Paddock<br />

Doroghazi, Robin Washington, and our research assistants Wayne Mei and Antje Uhlig for their<br />

assistance in helping to produce the current report.<br />

We are very grateful to the Smith Richardson Foundation, the Lynde and Harry Bradley<br />

Foundation, and the Richard Lounsbery Foundation for their generous support of this project.<br />

25


About the Authors<br />

Francis Fukuyama is Bernard L. Schwartz Professor of International Political Economy at<br />

the Paul H. Nitze School of Advanced International Studies in Washington, DC. He is the author<br />

of, among other books, The End of History and the Last Man, and Our Posthuman Future. He<br />

was a member of the President's Council on Bioethics from 2001-2005.<br />

Franco Furger is currently an independent consultant based in Lucerne, Switzerland. Until<br />

2005 he was head of the Science and Society research group at the Institute of Communication<br />

and Culture of the University of Lucerne, Switzerland. Before joining Lucerne University he was<br />

Research Professor at the School of Advanced International Studies (SAIS) in Washington DC.<br />

Prior to joining SAIS he was Research Associate Professor at the Institute of Public Policy,<br />

George Mason University. He was also Senior Fellow at the Institute of Social Research in<br />

Frankfurt am Main. Dr. Furger holds a B.A. in Electrical Engineering from the Swiss Federal<br />

Institute of Technology and a Ph.D. in Environmental Sciences from the same institution. His<br />

research interests include environmental and science policy and economic sociology. He has<br />

published numerous papers and two books.<br />

27


Table of Contents<br />

EXECUTIVE SUMMARY....................................................................................................................................... 1<br />

1 OVERVIEW ........................................................................................................................................................ 1<br />

1.1 Domain of Inquiry ................................................................................................................................... 1<br />

1.2 Embryo Politics ....................................................................................................................................... 2<br />

1.3 Regulation: General Considerations ..................................................................................................... 3<br />

2 SOURCES OF CONCERN..................................................................................................................................... 4<br />

2.1 General Ethical Principles ..................................................................................................................... 4<br />

2.2 Targets of Prohibition ............................................................................................................................. 5<br />

2.3 Targets of Regulation .............................................................................................................................. 6<br />

3 THE CURRENT LEGISLATIVE AND REGULATORY FRAMEWORK..................................................................... 7<br />

3.1 Federal Regulators.................................................................................................................................. 7<br />

3.2 Direct Legislative Intervention ............................................................................................................... 8<br />

3.3 Regulation by States ................................................................................................................................ 8<br />

3.4 Self-Regulation ........................................................................................................................................ 9<br />

4 RECENT REGULATORY INITIATIVES IN OTHER COUNTRIES ........................................................................... 9<br />

4.1 The British HFEA .................................................................................................................................... 9<br />

4.2 The Assisted Human Reproduction Agency of Canada....................................................................... 10<br />

4.3 Other Legislative Initiatives.................................................................................................................. 10<br />

5 PROS AND CONS OF ALTERNATIVE APPROACHES......................................................................................... 11<br />

5.1 Maintaining the Status Quo .................................................................................................................. 11<br />

5.2 Increment<strong>all</strong>y Expanding Statutory and Regulatory Authority .......................................................... 12<br />

5.3 Direct Legislative Intervention ............................................................................................................. 13<br />

5.4 Self-Regulation ...................................................................................................................................... 13<br />

5.5 Creating a New Regulatory Institution ................................................................................................ 14<br />

6 A NEW REGULATORY INSTITUTION .............................................................................................................. 14<br />

6.1 General Design Considerations ........................................................................................................... 14<br />

6.2 The Independent Commission............................................................................................................... 17<br />

6.3 The Permanent Advisory Board ........................................................................................................... 17<br />

6.4 Traditional Mechanisms of Public Consultation................................................................................. 18<br />

6.5 New Approaches to Public Consultation ............................................................................................. 19<br />

6.6 <strong>Final</strong> Remarks........................................................................................................................................ 23<br />

7 CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRAINTS................................................................................................................... 23<br />

8 INTERNATIONAL CONSIDERATIONS............................................................................................................... 24<br />

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ................................................................................................................................... 25<br />

ABOUT THE AUTHORS ...................................................................................................................................... 27<br />

1 INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................................................................. 37<br />

29


1.1 THE CHALLENGE OF NEW BIOTECHNOLOGIES ............................................................................................ 37<br />

1.2 TO REGULATE OR NOT TO REGULATE ......................................................................................................... 38<br />

1.3 THE DOMAIN OF INQUIRY OF THIS REPORT ................................................................................................. 40<br />

1.4 SCIENCE, POLITICS, AND DEMOCRACY: SOME GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS ............................................ 41<br />

1.5 ABORTION POLITICS AND THE MORAL STATUS OF THE EMBRYO .............................................................. 44<br />

1.6 BIBLIOGRAPHY.............................................................................................................................................. 47<br />

2 HUMAN GROWTH HORMONES FOR CHILDREN OF IDIOPATHIC SHORT STATURE:<br />

MEDICAL TREATMENT OR ENHANCING THERAPY?..................................................................... 49<br />

2.1 INTRODUCTION.............................................................................................................................................. 49<br />

2.2 IS THERE A NEED FOR LEGAL GUIDANCE?.................................................................................................. 51<br />

2.3 DISCUSSION................................................................................................................................................... 54<br />

2.4 BROADENING THE ETHICAL DEBATE........................................................................................................... 57<br />

2.5 BIBLIOGRAPHY.............................................................................................................................................. 61<br />

3 ETHICAL PRINCIPLES ................................................................................................................................. 63<br />

3.1 GENERAL ETHICAL PRINCIPLES GUIDING THE REGULATION OF TECHNOLOGIES AND MEDICAL<br />

PRACTICES RELATED TO HUMAN REPRODUCTION...................................................................................... 63<br />

3.2 TRANSLATING PRINCIPLES INTO RULES ...................................................................................................... 67<br />

3.3 ACTIVITIES TO BE PROHIBITED .................................................................................................................... 67<br />

3.4 ACTIVITIES TO BE REGULATED.................................................................................................................... 69<br />

3.5 NEXT STEPS................................................................................................................................................... 70<br />

3.6 BIBLIOGRAPHY.............................................................................................................................................. 73<br />

4 NEW FRONTIERS OF REPRODUCTIVE SCIENCE AND MEDICINE ............................................. 75<br />

4.1 AREAS OF INQUIRY ....................................................................................................................................... 75<br />

4.2 STANDARD REPRODUCTIVE TECHNIQUES ................................................................................................... 77<br />

4.3 INNOVATIVE REPRODUCTIVE TREATMENTS................................................................................................ 80<br />

4.3.1 Tinkering with Biological Parenthood.............................................................................................. 81<br />

4.3.2 Oocyte Cryopreservation (Freezing of Human Eggs) ..................................................................... 83<br />

4.3.3 Co-Culture .......................................................................................................................................... 85<br />

4.3.4 Other Experiments.............................................................................................................................. 86<br />

4.4 REPRODUCTIVE CUSTOMIZATION TECHNOLOGIES...................................................................................... 88<br />

4.4.1 Technologies of Sex-Selection: MicroSort........................................................................................ 90<br />

4.4.2 Pre-Implantation Genetic Diagnosis for Therapeutic Uses ............................................................ 93<br />

4.5 BIOMEDICAL RESEARCH INVOLVING REPRODUCTIVE TISSUES.................................................................. 95<br />

4.5.1 Cloning Technologies......................................................................................................................... 97<br />

4.5.2 Making Sperm...................................................................................................................................100<br />

4.5.3 Making Eggs .....................................................................................................................................103<br />

4.5.4 Remaking the Machinery of Gestation............................................................................................104<br />

4.5.5 Hybrids and Chimeras .....................................................................................................................105<br />

30


4.6 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................109<br />

5 THE CURRENT LEGAL AND REGULATORY FRAMEWORK........................................................117<br />

5.1 FEDERAL LEGISLATION ..............................................................................................................................117<br />

5.1.1 The Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992...................................................117<br />

5.1.2 Public Health Service Act ................................................................................................................120<br />

5.1.3 The Clinical and Laboratory Amendments of 1988 .......................................................................122<br />

5.1.4 Institutional Review Boards and Human Subject Protection ........................................................123<br />

5.1.5 Federal Funding of Embryo Research............................................................................................126<br />

5.1.6 The National Organ Transplantation Act.......................................................................................126<br />

5.1.7 Regulation by Tort............................................................................................................................127<br />

5.1.8 Regulation by the Market.................................................................................................................127<br />

5.2 RECENT LEGISLATIVE INITIATIVES............................................................................................................128<br />

5.2.1 Congressional Initiatives .................................................................................................................128<br />

5.2.2 Senate Bill 303..................................................................................................................................129<br />

5.2.3 Legislative Initiatives at the State Level .........................................................................................131<br />

5.3 SELF-REGULATORY INITIATIVES................................................................................................................133<br />

5.3.1 Introduction ......................................................................................................................................133<br />

5.3.2 Self-Regulation in the ART Industry................................................................................................135<br />

5.3.3 Self-Regulation of Medical Research..............................................................................................141<br />

5.4 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................145<br />

6 INTERNATIONAL LEGISLATIVE AND REGULATORY APPROACHES ....................................149<br />

6.1 ITALY – FROM THE “WILD WEST” TO “POLITBURO”? ..............................................................................150<br />

6.2 AUSTRALIA – REGULATED SELF-REGULATION.........................................................................................153<br />

6.2.1 Regulatory Precedents .....................................................................................................................153<br />

6.2.2 The Prohibition of Human Cloning Act of 2002 ............................................................................154<br />

6.2.3 The Research Involving Human Embryos Act of 2002 ..................................................................156<br />

6.3 CANADA: GROPING TOWARD A NEW REGULATORY STRUCTURE............................................................160<br />

6.3.1 The Assisted Human Reproduction Act of 2004 .............................................................................160<br />

6.4 THE HUMAN FERTILISATION AND EMBRYOLOGY ACT – BLUEPRINT FOR ACTION OR A CASE OF BRITISH<br />

PECULIARITY?.............................................................................................................................................168<br />

6.4.1 Introduction ......................................................................................................................................168<br />

6.4.2 The HFE Act .....................................................................................................................................170<br />

6.4.3 The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority ....................................................................171<br />

6.4.4 Licensing ...........................................................................................................................................174<br />

6.4.5 The Code of Practice........................................................................................................................177<br />

6.5 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS...................................................................................................................178<br />

6.6 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................181<br />

7 CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRAINTS? .....................................................................................................183<br />

31


7.1 TRADITIONAL REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES VERSUS TECHNOLOGIES OF REPRODUCTIVE CONTROL183<br />

7.2 QUESTIONS OF CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION .................................................................................186<br />

7.2.1 Selecting a Level of Generality........................................................................................................186<br />

7.2.2 From Levels of Generality to Principled Interpretation................................................................190<br />

7.2.3 An Idiosyncratic Approach to Constitutional Interpretation.........................................................190<br />

7.2.4 Robertson’s Concept of “Presumptive Procreative Liberty”........................................................192<br />

7.3 A DIFFERENT PERSPECTIVE .......................................................................................................................194<br />

7.4 PROCREATIVE DRIVE OR FAMILIAL DESIRES?...........................................................................................199<br />

7.5 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................205<br />

8 PUBLIC SENTIMENTS TOWARD NEW REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES AND<br />

BIOMEDICAL RESEARCH.........................................................................................................................207<br />

8.1 INTRODUCTION............................................................................................................................................207<br />

8.2 GENERAL ATTITUDES TOWARD SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY..................................................................208<br />

8.3 REPRODUCTIVE CLONING...........................................................................................................................209<br />

8.4 RESEARCH CLONING...................................................................................................................................212<br />

8.5 STEM CELL RESEARCH ...............................................................................................................................214<br />

8.6 GENETIC ENGINEERING ..............................................................................................................................218<br />

8.7 AWARENESS AND FAMILIARITY .................................................................................................................219<br />

8.8 THE CULTURE WARS: A MYTH? ...............................................................................................................222<br />

8.9 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................227<br />

9 POSSIBLE SOCIETAL RESPONSES ........................................................................................................229<br />

9.1 MAINTAINING THE STATUS QUO................................................................................................................229<br />

9.2 TARGETED LEGISLATIVE INTERVENTION ..................................................................................................234<br />

9.3 SELF-REGULATION .....................................................................................................................................236<br />

9.4 REGULATORY RESPONSES..........................................................................................................................238<br />

9.5 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................243<br />

10 CORRECTING POLITICAL AND REGULATORY DISTORTIONS ................................................245<br />

10.1 REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES: A CASE OF POLITICAL FAILURE............................................................245<br />

10.2 A PROBLEMATIC START: THE PROFESSIONALIZATION OF ETHICAL DILEMMAS.....................................251<br />

10.3 ELEMENTS OF A SOLUTION: NOTICE-AND-COMMENT ..............................................................................253<br />

10.4 WHY CONSULT WITH THE PUBLIC?............................................................................................................256<br />

10.5 WHO SHOULD BE CONSULTED?.................................................................................................................259<br />

10.6 SCIENTIFIC LITERACY AND PUBLIC PARTICIPATION .................................................................................262<br />

10.7 KEY FEATURES OF INSTITUTIONS OF PUBLIC CONSULTATION .................................................................264<br />

10.7.1 Deliberation: Vehicle of Consensus or Catalyst of Conflict? .....................................................264<br />

10.7.2 Other Features................................................................................................................................268<br />

10.8 INSTITUTIONAL OPTIONS............................................................................................................................270<br />

10.8.1 Public Hearings..............................................................................................................................271<br />

32


10.8.2 Consensus Conferences .................................................................................................................272<br />

10.9 PUBLIC PARTICIPATION AT THE FEDERAL LEVEL .....................................................................................277<br />

10.9.1 The National Environmental Policy Act of 1969..........................................................................278<br />

10.9.2 The Comprehensive Environmental Response, Compensation, and Liability Act of 1980........281<br />

10.10 BIBLIOGRAPHY ..........................................................................................................................................287<br />

11 INDEPENDENT AGENCIES .......................................................................................................................293<br />

11.1 WHY AN INDEPENDENT AGENCY? .............................................................................................................293<br />

11.2 DESIGN CONSIDERATIONS..........................................................................................................................300<br />

11.2.1 The Advisory Board........................................................................................................................305<br />

11.2.2 The Advisory Board as a Board of Directors?.............................................................................308<br />

11.2.3 Appointment Rules..........................................................................................................................309<br />

11.3 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................313<br />

12 DESIGNING MECHANISMS OF PUBLIC CONSULTATION ............................................................315<br />

12.1 DELIBERATIVE PANELS ..............................................................................................................................316<br />

12.1.1 Questions of Implementation .........................................................................................................317<br />

12.1.2 Considerations of Feasibility.........................................................................................................318<br />

12.2 CONSULTATIVE COLLEGE...........................................................................................................................319<br />

12.3 PUBLIC CONSULTATION AND RULE-MAKING............................................................................................324<br />

12.4 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................327<br />

13 IMPLEMENTATION ISSUES .....................................................................................................................329<br />

13.1 MONITORING AND INFORMATION GATHERING .........................................................................................329<br />

13.1.1 Embryos ..........................................................................................................................................331<br />

13.1.2 Oocytes............................................................................................................................................332<br />

13.1.3 Sperm...............................................................................................................................................333<br />

13.2 STANDARD REPRODUCTIVE PROCEDURES.................................................................................................334<br />

13.3 INNOVATIVE REPRODUCTIVE TREATMENTS..............................................................................................335<br />

13.4 TECHNOLOGIES OF REPRODUCTIVE CUSTOMIZATION...............................................................................342<br />

13.5 BIOMEDICAL RESEARCH.............................................................................................................................342<br />

13.6 DESIGNING A SYSTEM OF COMPLIANCE ASSURANCE ...............................................................................345<br />

13.7 OPERATING COSTS......................................................................................................................................348<br />

13.8 BIBLIOGRAPHY............................................................................................................................................353<br />

APPENDIX A – STUDY GROUP MEMBERS ................................................................................................357<br />

APPENDIX B – THE SYNTHETIC HUMAN GROWTH HORMONE (HGH)........................................361<br />

MEDICAL INDICATIONS .......................................................................................................................................361<br />

SAFETY AND EFFICACY .......................................................................................................................................362<br />

SOCIAL-PSYCHOLOGICAL PATHOLOGIES ...........................................................................................................363<br />

T<strong>all</strong>ness – a Requisite for Success?..............................................................................................................364<br />

33


Shortness as a Psychological and Social Impairment?...............................................................................365<br />

PATTERNS OF USE ...............................................................................................................................................367<br />

THE MARKET FOR HUMAN GROWTH HORMONE ...............................................................................................368<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY ....................................................................................................................................................371<br />

APPENDIX C – IVF HEALTH AND SAFETY RISKS: SOME ILLUSTRATIONS................................373<br />

MAJOR BIRTH DEFECTS ......................................................................................................................................373<br />

LOW BIRTH WEIGHT ...........................................................................................................................................374<br />

NEUROLOGICAL DISORDERS ...............................................................................................................................375<br />

ECTOPIC PREGNANCIES.......................................................................................................................................375<br />

CRANIOSYNOSTOSIS ............................................................................................................................................376<br />

BECKWITH-WIEDEMANN SYNDROME ................................................................................................................377<br />

ANGELMAN SYNDROME......................................................................................................................................378<br />

THE CLOACAL-BLADDER EXSTROPHY-EPISPADIAS COMPLEX.........................................................................378<br />

BIBLIOGRAPHY ....................................................................................................................................................381<br />

APPENDIX D – CONGRESSIONAL LEGISLATIVE ACTIVITIES 2001-2004......................................383<br />

APPENDIX E – COMMITTEE OPINIONS.....................................................................................................389<br />

GUIDELINES .........................................................................................................................................................389<br />

TECHNICAL BULLETINS.......................................................................................................................................390<br />

EDUCATIONAL BULLETINS..................................................................................................................................391<br />

GUIDELINES AND MINIMUM STANDARDS ..........................................................................................................392<br />

JOINT REPORTS....................................................................................................................................................392<br />

APPENDIX F – ASRM ETHICS COMMITTEE REPORTS AND STATEMENTS ................................393<br />

APPENDIX G – STATE-LEVEL LEGISLATIVE INITIATIVES ..............................................................395<br />

ENACTED LEGISLATION ......................................................................................................................................395<br />

Reproductive cloning.....................................................................................................................................395<br />

Research (Therapeutic) Cloning...................................................................................................................395<br />

Stem Cell Research (explicitly).....................................................................................................................395<br />

Embryonic Research (in general).................................................................................................................396<br />

PENDING LEGISLATION .......................................................................................................................................397<br />

LEGISLATION THAT HAS DIED OR WAS WITHDRAWN.......................................................................................398<br />

APPENDIX H – LEGISLATIVE INITIATIVES AT THE INTERNATIONAL LEVEL ........................401<br />

STATUTES ............................................................................................................................................................401<br />

KEY PROVISIONS .................................................................................................................................................403<br />

APPENDIX I – SELECT SUPREME COURT CASES..................................................................................407<br />

MEYER V. NEBRASKA (1923) .............................................................................................................................407<br />

PIERCE V. SOCIETY OF SISTERS (1925) ..............................................................................................................407<br />

34


SKINNER V. OKLAHOMA (1942) .........................................................................................................................407<br />

GRISWOLD V. CONNECTICUT (1965) ..................................................................................................................408<br />

EISENSTADT V. BAIRD (1972).............................................................................................................................409<br />

STANLEY V. ILLINOIS (1972) ..............................................................................................................................410<br />

ROE V. WADE (1973) ..........................................................................................................................................410<br />

CLEVELAND BOARD OF EDUCATION V. LAFLEUR (1974).................................................................................411<br />

CAREY V. POPULATION SERVICES INTERNATIONAL (1977)..............................................................................412<br />

APPENDIX J – ATTITUDES TOWARD SCIENCE AND MEDICAL RESEARCH ..............................413<br />

APPENDIX K – REPRODUCTIVE CLONING..............................................................................................419<br />

APPENDIX L – RESEARCH CLONING.........................................................................................................431<br />

APPENDIX M – STEM CELL RESEARCH....................................................................................................439<br />

APPENDIX N – GENETIC ENGINEERING ..................................................................................................451<br />

APPENDIX O – AWARENESS AND KNOWLEDGEABILITY .................................................................457<br />

APPENDIX P – ATTITUDES TOWARD STEM CELL RESEARCH BY INDIVIDUALS OF<br />

RELIGIOUS AND OTHER ORIENTATIONS .........................................................................................463<br />

APPENDIX Q – ACRONYMS ............................................................................................................................469<br />

ORGANIZATIONS..................................................................................................................................................469<br />

LEGISLATION .......................................................................................................................................................470<br />

TERMS..................................................................................................................................................................471<br />

35


1 Introduction<br />

This report presents a proposal for a new approach to regulating human biomedicine in the<br />

United States. It is the product of more than three years of research, and of a study group<br />

convened in Washington, D.C., dedicated to this subject. The members of the study group (listed<br />

in Appendix A) were chosen to be representative of the different stakeholders in human<br />

biomedicine; while they have intensively discussed various issues raised in this report, they have<br />

not been asked to endorse the report or its final conclusions. Those remain the responsibility of<br />

the report’s primary authors.<br />

It is our belief that the existing system for regulating human biomedicine in the United<br />

States, while unrivaled in many respects by that of any other country, contains certain gaps or<br />

omissions that will render it increasingly inadequate to meet the ch<strong>all</strong>enges posed by new<br />

biotechnologies and medical procedures in the coming years. Other developed countries have put<br />

new regulatory institutions in place already or are in the process of doing so in anticipation of<br />

new developments, and the United States needs to follow suit.<br />

In putting forth this proposal, the authors of this report fully understand the downsides of<br />

regulation. If you regulate something, you get less of it, and many people fear that excessive<br />

regulation of biomedicine will stifle innovation and progress in many areas critical to human<br />

health and well-being.<br />

While this fear is often well-founded, we believe that properly designed regulation can have<br />

the exact opposite effect: It can promote research and scientific advance by establishing a clear<br />

framework under which innovation can take place, a framework that reassures the broader<br />

society that the research is being conducted safely and ethic<strong>all</strong>y. Clinical trials for new drugs are<br />

facilitated, for example, by having clear rules established for human subject research by the<br />

National Institutes of Health (NIH) and the Food and Drug Administration (FDA). As we will<br />

demonstrate below, the benefits of a properly designed regulatory environment would be felt in<br />

one particular area of acute concern – embryonic stem cell research.<br />

1.1 The Ch<strong>all</strong>enge of New Biotechnologies<br />

It has been clear for more than a generation that advances in biomedical technology pose<br />

ethical ch<strong>all</strong>enges deeper and more abiding than those raised in other areas of scientific research.<br />

Biotechnology from the start spawned a whole new field of bioethics; information technology,<br />

by contrast, has not led universities to train professionals in “information ethics.” Recombinant<br />

DNA (or rDNA), cloning, psychotropic drugs, and behavioral genetics have generated moral and<br />

political controversies due to the ways that they could potenti<strong>all</strong>y affect human well-being, both<br />

for good and ill.<br />

37


When societal concerns about biotechnology first appeared in the 1970s, the scientific<br />

research community and the biomedical industry reacted responsibly, putting in place new<br />

institutions to reassure the public that biotechnological advance was not coming at the expense of<br />

human safety or dignity. The scientific community, for example, organized the Recombinant<br />

DNA Advisory Committee (RAC) under NIH auspices to vet new research projects in this area<br />

and guard against the emergence of “superbugs.” There was also a major push to fund advisory<br />

committees on bioethics at major research and medical institutions, and a whole series of<br />

governmental boards, commissions, and councils were established to provide ethical guidance to<br />

the U.S. government. The Human Genome Project has regularly devoted 3 percent of its research<br />

budget to studying the ethical, legal, and social implications of genetic research.<br />

The various communities involved in human biomedical research in the United States have<br />

thus developed a model of self-policing in which bioethics plays a role, but only in an advisory<br />

capacity. This model has by and large worked over the past generation. However, as John Evans<br />

has pointed out, 4 this model was also put in place deliberately as a means of fending off more<br />

overt regulation. All of the different bioethics advisory boards around the country have<br />

effectively served as a cover for the scientific community, <strong>all</strong>owing it to argue that it was paying<br />

attention to ethical issues while not giving those bodies any real authority to limit or sanction<br />

research. The professional bioethics community, moreover, has tended to adopt a rather “thin”<br />

view of ethical concerns centered on principles like autonomy, fairness, beneficence, and justice,<br />

as opposed to the “thicker” moral views held by many Americans.<br />

Bioethical discussion and debate remains critical; there are many ethical concerns that do<br />

not have black-and-white answers and cannot be addressed through laws or regulation. But it is<br />

our view that the time has come to move beyond bioethics and to begin considering a different<br />

kind of regulatory system for human biomedicine that goes beyond current considerations of<br />

safety and efficacy and takes ethical and normative concerns into account. How to<br />

institutionalize a system that is representative of the interests of the different stakeholders and of<br />

the general public, one capable of fostering rational deliberation and likely to promote necessary<br />

and beneficial research and innovation, is the subject of this report.<br />

1.2 To Regulate or Not to Regulate<br />

Having just argued that the scientific community has held off overt regulation of many<br />

forms of research and of biotechnology, it may seem contradictory to assert in the same breath<br />

that human biomedicine is and has for a long time been one of the most heavily regulated areas<br />

of endeavor in the United States. But both statements are true: The regulatory scene is a<br />

contradictory patchwork of both under- and over-regulation. The FDA’s “gold standard” of<br />

costly double-blind clinical trials for pharmaceuticals is unmatched in any other country in the<br />

world. On the other hand, the FDA regulates only drugs and medical products, and can regulate<br />

4<br />

John H. Evans, Playing God? Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public Bioethical Debate<br />

(Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2002).<br />

38


them only on the basis of safety and efficacy. It does not regulate the practice of medicine, which<br />

means that the large area of medicine involving assisted reproductive technologies (ARTs)<br />

receives virtu<strong>all</strong>y no government oversight. In Europe, things are typic<strong>all</strong>y rather different:<br />

Drugs are given less careful scrutiny, while ARTs are closely monitored by governments. While<br />

the FDA strictly enforces testing rules for new drugs, it does not control their off-label uses,<br />

meaning that doctors are free to innovate, and in effect experiment on their patients in such<br />

cases.<br />

The other major regulatory institution in the United States is the National Institutes of<br />

Health, which through its control over federal funding exerts enormous influence over the nature,<br />

scope, and direction of scientific research in biomedicine. 5 It is the NIH that now oversees bodies<br />

like the RAC, and establishes requirements for institutional review boards (IRBs) to monitor<br />

research involving human subjects. The NIH is not limited to considerations of safety and<br />

efficacy like the FDA; it can and has introduced moral and ethical concerns into its decisionmaking.<br />

President George W. Bush’s August 2001 decision limiting feder<strong>all</strong>y funded stem cell<br />

research to existing stem cell lines reflected his concerns over protecting embryos, and was<br />

implemented by the NIH. Here, the limits of regulatory authority are different than in the FDA’s<br />

case. The NIH can influence science only through its control of funding; it cannot prohibit<br />

privately funded research and has no say over what happens in the private biotech industry.<br />

No one designed this over<strong>all</strong> regulatory system. It was put together piecemeal in response to<br />

scandals like those over sulfanilamide elixir and thalidomide, or those in response to the<br />

Tuskegee or Willowbrook abuses. The fact that the United States regulates some things very<br />

strictly and other things not at <strong>all</strong> is largely a path-dependent and contingent product of its<br />

history. The question that confronts us is whether this system is adequate to meet the ch<strong>all</strong>enges<br />

of twenty-first century biomedicine.<br />

What some of those ch<strong>all</strong>enges are and why the present system may not be adequate to cope<br />

with them is the subject of the growth hormone case study given in chapter 2. In light of these<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enges, we face a problem of institutional design: Do we stick with the existing regulatory<br />

framework, or do we seek to introduce new regulatory powers or different kinds of institutions?<br />

Most Americans rightly regard regulation as a necessary evil; with the growth of state<br />

sectors in the twentieth century, it became clear to many people by the 1970s that many sectors<br />

of the American economy were over-regulated. Much of the thrust of policy in the United States<br />

since then has been to cut back on regulation in areas ranging from airlines to trucking to<br />

electricity to telecommunications. In some cases, this has been met with great success; in others,<br />

less so. The dangers of over-regulation remain, however, and the burden of proof should lie with<br />

anyone who argues that new regulatory bodies are necessary. A useful prudential rule in public<br />

administration is not to multiply regulatory agencies unnecessarily when the new functions<br />

required can be performed just as easily by existing bodies.<br />

5<br />

There are, of course, any number of other agencies that have regulatory authority over various aspects of human<br />

biomedicine, including the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), the U.S. Patent Office, the Drug<br />

Enforcement Agency, and state licensing boards.<br />

39


On the other hand, certain historical precedents suggest that it is at times wiser to create a<br />

new institution to deal with a new problem. Take the case of transportation, for example. The<br />

Interstate Commerce Commission (ICC) was created in 1887 to regulate the new railroad<br />

industry. 6<br />

The Interstate Commerce Act that established it was a milestone in American<br />

administrative law, extending for the first time the writ of the federal government into areas that<br />

had previously been reserved for states.<br />

At the beginning of the twentieth century, the rise of interstate trucking posed the question<br />

of who should regulate this new industry. The Hepburn Act of 1906 gave regulatory authority to<br />

the ICC on the grounds that trucking and railroads were similar, both being means of moving<br />

goods across state borders. Most experts in administrative law believe now, in retrospect, that<br />

this was a mistake: The economics of the rail and trucking industries were very different, the<br />

interest groups involved differed substanti<strong>all</strong>y, and the technical expertise require to regulate rail<br />

service did not spill over into trucking.<br />

When commercial aviation emerged in the 1920s, the ICC could have been charged with<br />

regulating this sector on the grounds that airplanes are simply another means of interstate<br />

commerce. Instead, the Air Commerce Act of 1926 created a new, independent Aeronautics<br />

Branch within the Commerce Department to promote and ensure the safety of civil aviation.<br />

With the advent of commercial jet aircraft after World War II, this branch eventu<strong>all</strong>y evolved<br />

into two independent agencies – the Federal Aviation Administration and the Civil Aeronautics<br />

Board. It is doubtful that anyone today regrets this choice to create new agencies to regulate<br />

aviation rather than building on the authority of the ICC.<br />

The question to consider here, then, is not the broad one of whether or not to regulate human<br />

biomedicine and biotechnology, as a positive choice was made in that area long ago. The<br />

question, rather, is whether we are currently at a juncture similar to the mid-1920s, when civil<br />

aviation first emerged as a new and highly promising industry. Do we regard the issues raised by<br />

new biotechnologies as problems we are already familiar with, or are they sufficiently different<br />

as to merit new regulatory powers? Surely, no one in a liberal society wants to multiply<br />

regulatory agencies or add more layers of bureaucracy unnecessarily. On the other hand, it is<br />

sometimes more efficient to begin afresh rather than trying to change bureaucratic cultures to<br />

handle problems they were never designed to handle. The idea that a democracy may want to<br />

create a new statutory authority to deal with new technologies cannot be tot<strong>all</strong>y outlandish, as a<br />

number of other developed countries have decided to do precisely that.<br />

1.3 The Domain of Inquiry of this <strong>Report</strong><br />

Human biomedicine is a huge field, and it is necessary at the outset to define the realm of<br />

technologies and practices that we believe need to be regulated. There are many existing and<br />

potential targets of regulation, including drugs and medical devices, various types of scientific<br />

6<br />

The ICC was disbanded in 1995 and its powers were given to the National Surface Transportation Board.<br />

40


esearch, and clinical and medical practices. Many critics of the FDA have argued that the<br />

agency over-regulates many drugs, preventing patients from having timely access to important<br />

pharmaceuticals. This could well be true; a complete overhaul of the American regulatory system<br />

may require deregulation of some areas as well as new regulation of others at the same time.<br />

In this report, we intend to focus more narrowly – on the one end on technologies and<br />

medical practices related to human reproduction, and on the other on biomedical research<br />

involving embryos and other reproductive tissues. Our reason for choosing these areas is that<br />

they encompass most of those technologies – existing, on the horizon, and possible in the more<br />

distant future – that bioethicists have pointed to as raising significant moral and ethical issues.<br />

Within this domain lie not only traditional ARTs, the most important of which remains in vitro<br />

fertilization (IVF), but also novel forms of reproduction (the creation of embryos from genetic<br />

material from one, three, four, or more parents, for example) and new reproductive services like<br />

pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and sex-selection technologies and, possibly, germline<br />

genetic modifications (see chapter 3). This domain also includes laboratory research<br />

involving embryos. Embryonic stem cell research is a well-known example; less familiar but just<br />

as relevant is the creation of human-animal chimeras and hybrids.<br />

It should be emphasized at the outset that to say that these technologies are related to human<br />

reproduction does not necessarily mean that they are intended to produce children. This is<br />

particularly true of embryonic stem cell research, whose end is of course the development of<br />

treatments for diseases affecting already-living human beings. Nonetheless, the fact that such<br />

stem cells are derived from embryos and may in the future be capable of producing embryos<br />

means that it is impossible to regulate the broader field of human reproduction without regulating<br />

them. Indeed, the manipulation of stem cells may become one of the means through which other<br />

reproductive technologies become possible.<br />

To say that these practices should be regulated is not to say that they should be banned or<br />

unduly restricted. As we explain at greater length below, it is our view that stem cell research<br />

would benefit greatly from being placed within a regulatory framework. But precisely because<br />

embryonic stem cell research today requires the use of embryos and may at some point in the<br />

future lead to the creation of embryos, it is not possible to separate this kind of work from<br />

research and medical practices that aim directly at the creation of children.<br />

In defining the domain of inquiry in this fashion, we are excluding a great many other issues<br />

that may deserve greater or lesser degrees of regulation. Psychopharmacology is an area of<br />

pharmaceutical development that is exploding, one that is regulated already and may deserve a<br />

fresh look in light of new drugs coming on the market in the near future. These are issues,<br />

however, that lie beyond the scope of the current report.<br />

1.4 Science, Politics, and Democracy: Some General Considerations<br />

Many people, including some members of our own study group, are strongly opposed to any<br />

regulation of scientific research, and believe that science is a self-contained, self-justifying<br />

41


enterprise that should be shielded from politics. To many people, the idea of Congress<br />

intervening in this area evokes images of Galileo being prosecuted by the medieval Catholic<br />

Church. As Congressman Ted Strickland of Ohio said during the House debate on cloning<br />

legislation in 2001, “We should not <strong>all</strong>ow theology, philosophy, or politics to interfere with the<br />

decision we make on this issue.” It is therefore worth stepping back and raising the more general<br />

question of who, legitimately, gets to make rules in this area.<br />

This issue was settled in principle long ago: All scientific research is ultimately subject to<br />

rules set not by scientists, but by the broader political community. In a liberal democracy, that<br />

community consists of the sovereign people speaking through their elected representatives – that<br />

is, Congress (and, in the case of presidential systems like that of the United States, the president).<br />

Indeed, in a democracy, the people are sovereign not only over science, but over every other<br />

field of activity. 7<br />

The reasons for this are straightforward. Scientists qua scientists have no special authority to<br />

make ethical or political judgments about the ends of their scientific research. Data is data: Even<br />

if obtained by deliberately infecting experimental subjects with deadly disease agents in doubleblind<br />

clinical trials, as was done by Nazi scientists, the results are still scientific<strong>all</strong>y meaningful.<br />

The fact that we do not <strong>all</strong>ow this kind of research to be carried out in the United States reflects<br />

an ethical judgment that it is wrong, based in part on the crimes of the Nazis. Virtu<strong>all</strong>y <strong>all</strong><br />

American scientists strongly support existing rules protecting human subjects of research. They<br />

do so, however, not in their capacity as scientists, but as citizens, moral agents, religious<br />

believers, or simply as human beings. It is precisely “theology, philosophy, and politics” that<br />

provides guidance on this kind of issue.<br />

While it is clear in principle that Congress and the president ultimately have legitimate<br />

authority to set rules and boundaries for science and scientists, in practice science operates in a<br />

much more autonomous fashion. There is a general political consensus that science and scientific<br />

progress are good things that should be encouraged, and also a recognition on the part of elected<br />

officials that they do not have the knowledge to intervene in most scientific issues. This has led<br />

to a certain degree of self-restraint on the part of political authorities when it comes to scientific<br />

rule-making, and a willingness to delegate considerable rule-making power to the epistemic<br />

communities directly involved in scientific research and technology research and development.<br />

Congressman Strickland’s comments about theology, philosophy, and politics interfering in<br />

science reflect a default condition in which scientists regulate themselves, subject to broad<br />

political guidelines set by Congress. While most Americans would accept the right of politicians<br />

to regulate science, most also hope – rightly – that this does not happen too often.<br />

7<br />

Strictly speaking, in a liberal democracy like the United States, popular sovereignty is limited by a pre-existing<br />

set of individual rights, which in the American case are said to come from nature rather than the people’s will.<br />

Practic<strong>all</strong>y speaking, the definition of what constitutes these “natural” rights is a matter of popular choice (i.e.,<br />

through ratification of the Bill of Rights and its subsequent interpretation through the courts), but one based on<br />

supermajorities rather than simple majorities.<br />

42


Congress’ powers over scientific research and technology research and development come<br />

in many different forms. In some cases, the government has statutory powers to set rules, like the<br />

FDA’s power to regulate drugs and medical devices. In other cases, political influence is<br />

exercised through funding decisions made by agencies like the NIH or the National Institute of<br />

Mental Health (NIMH). The fact that the United States chooses to wage a “war on cancer” rather<br />

than sponsor research on tropical diseases like malaria reflects political judgments about U.S.<br />

national priorities. Activities like embryonic stem cell research that are not banned but also not<br />

feder<strong>all</strong>y funded reflect either political compromises or complex judgments as to their moral<br />

acceptability. In light of these decisions, no one should pretend that the types and levels of<br />

research carried out in the United States do not embed a host of normative judgments made by<br />

the broader political community.<br />

The issue we seek to address in this report is the proper modality of political intervention. In<br />

doing so, we hope to avoid several pitf<strong>all</strong>s. The first is routine intervention by Congress to ban or<br />

limit certain practices, technologies, or medical procedures. In 2001, legislation was introduced<br />

into Congress to ban, in one version, reproductive cloning, and in another, both reproductive and<br />

research cloning. While the latter bill passed the House of Representatives, neither made it<br />

through the Senate due to a failure to agree on the legitimacy of research cloning. While one of<br />

the present authors is on record in support of the broad cloning ban, neither of us believes that<br />

this bill represents a good general model for future Congressional intervention in biomedicine.<br />

While human cloning constitutes an important symbolic threshold meriting Congressional<br />

action, 8 many future innovations emerging over the coming decades will not. We do not believe<br />

that Congress has the time, energy, or expertise necessary to pass specific new laws in response<br />

to the many future innovations that will emerge.<br />

On the other hand, we also do not believe that the current model under which authority is<br />

de-facto delegated to the epistemic communities and their stakeholders is adequate to meet future<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enges. The regulatory authority of the FDA and NIH is not only limited by statute in the<br />

ways described above; it is administered almost exclusively by the epistemic communities<br />

involved, with little opportunity for participation by other societal actors with an interest in<br />

biomedicine. (Institutional review boards, with their statutory requirement that they include<br />

members drawn from outside the scientific community, are the one exception). On the adequacy<br />

of this arrangement, see chapter 5 below.) In designing new regulatory institutions, the issue then<br />

is not only whether they should be given statutory authority to go beyond safety and efficacy as<br />

criteria for regulatory decisions, but also whether those making the decisions on an agency level<br />

should include people from outside the scientific research communities and the biotech and<br />

reproductive industries.<br />

We do not by any means mean to suggest that existing epistemic communities should be<br />

deprived of their traditional self-regulatory powers. Rather, the question is whether participants<br />

8<br />

The recent report of the President’s Council on Bioethics Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of<br />

New Biotechnologies outlines a possible legislative agenda that would in effect ban reproductive cloning as well<br />

as a number of other procedures, like the production of human-animal hybrids.<br />

43


in the standard-setting process can be broadened to include other stakeholders more<br />

representative of the broader society. There are a number of reasons for wanting to do this. While<br />

the scientific community, ART professionals and the biotech and pharmaceutical industries are<br />

the primary sources of knowledge about human reproductive medicine and biomedical research,<br />

they are also self-interested actors whose goals and ethical orientations do not necessarily<br />

coincide with those of the larger society. And even though scientists gener<strong>all</strong>y aspire to the<br />

disinterested search for truth as an ideal, many also have financial relationships with biotech or<br />

pharmaceutical companies that affect their personal incentives. These communities will continue<br />

to play an important role in this field, if for no other reason than their possession of critical<br />

scientific and medical information. The purpose of broadening participation in the resolution of<br />

contemporary moral and ethical dilemmas is not to dilute this expertise, but to make the<br />

regulatory body more representative of the society around it.<br />

The final pitf<strong>all</strong> to avoid is the under- or over-delegation of authority to a new regulatory<br />

authority. Regulatory agencies exist in the first place because Congress lacks the time or<br />

knowledge to make the myriad complex decisions required by the statutes it enacts. Legislators<br />

do not want to have to decide how many parts per million constitutes a dangerous level of<br />

contamination for a particular chemical, or whether the results of a clinical trial are statistic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

significant. On the other hand, there are certain issues that are much too large and controversial<br />

to be delegated to a regulatory agency, and that ultimately must be debated and decided by the<br />

broader political community. The key issue for the design of a new regulatory authority,<br />

therefore, is what authority Congress should delegate and what issues it has responsibility for<br />

deciding directly. Nowhere is this more true than in the area of stem cell and cloning research.<br />

1.5 Abortion Politics and the Moral Status of the Embryo<br />

It is safe to say that in the United States, <strong>all</strong> legislation in the general area of reproductive<br />

medicine and embryo research is made vastly more complicated by the underlying societal<br />

controversy over the moral status of the embryo. Other developed countries that have passed<br />

legislation in this area have reached consensus either to permit (as in the case of Britain) or to<br />

prohibit (as in the cases of Germany and Canada) certain forms of cloning research. In the<br />

United States, there are passionate proponents of both the pro-life and pro-choice positions. One<br />

reason that cloning legislation has remained st<strong>all</strong>ed in the Senate since 2001 is that neither side<br />

can muster more than about 40 votes for its preferred version of a cloning ban.<br />

For what it is worth, we do not begin from a pro-life position. We believe that human<br />

embryos have an intermediate moral status. 9 They are, on the one hand, not the moral equivalents<br />

9<br />

Some people have argued that human moral status is an “on” or “off” condition, and that the concept of an<br />

intermediate moral status is incoherent. There are, however, other entities that have such intermediate status.<br />

Dead human bodies are one example: We permit them to be used instrument<strong>all</strong>y for research and training<br />

purposes, on the one hand, but we do not <strong>all</strong>ow them to be used for less dignified ends, or to be disposed of<br />

casu<strong>all</strong>y.<br />

44


of newborns; destruction of an embryo for us is not tantamount to murder. On the other hand, we<br />

do not believe that embryos are just clumps of cells like any other tissue specimen; because they<br />

are potential human lives, they deserve some degree of respect. We believe that a regulatory<br />

system that keeps track of such embryos, permitting their use for select scientific purposes of<br />

scientific research but prohibiting their casual creation or destruction, is an appropriate way of<br />

recognizing this intermediate status. Our ethical concerns in this area relate not to embryo<br />

destruction per se as much as to other technological possibilities that are either emerging now or<br />

will appear in the coming years (see chapter 4 below).<br />

We raise this issue not to persuade others of our case, but rather to point out that there are<br />

several deeply held alternative views on this issue, among which there is unlikely to be<br />

consensus any time in the near future. This kind of large moral question cannot possibly be<br />

delegated to a regulatory agency. They must rather be adjudicated at higher levels of the political<br />

system, in Congress and the state legislatures or, less optim<strong>all</strong>y, through the court system (as has<br />

happened in the case of the legalization of abortion). Indeed, if any kind of regulatory system<br />

involving human embryos is to succeed, it is critical to fence off the realm of delegated authority<br />

from the issues of abortion and the moral status of embryos.<br />

It is important to understand that a system to monitor and regulate biomedical research,<br />

artificial reproductive technologies, and related areas does not necessarily presuppose a<br />

particular position on the moral status of embryos. That is, such a system can be used to monitor<br />

and enforce a ban on research cloning, stem cell research, and the like, or it can be used to<br />

promote some or <strong>all</strong> of these activities. 10 The Germans and Canadians have constructed systems<br />

to do the former, while the British have constructed a system to do the latter. The institutional<br />

design of the regulatory system is in some sense independent of one’s stand on the underlying<br />

moral question.<br />

If we are to proceed with the construction of a new regulatory system, then, the political<br />

system has to make a decision on the underlying legitimacy of embryo research and the broad<br />

realms of what will be permitted and restricted in this area. These are not regulatory issues but<br />

political ones. Only when the society has made a decision on the prior question will it be possible<br />

to proceed to construct an institution capable of enforcing the agreed-upon rules.<br />

As noted at the outset, we believe that embryonic stem cell research should proceed with<br />

federal funding, and that a new regulatory system will actu<strong>all</strong>y promote that end. To those<br />

opposed to any form of embryo research, we would point out that achieving their goals would<br />

require a similar type of regulatory system. The current system, in which feder<strong>all</strong>y funded<br />

research is restricted but private research is virtu<strong>all</strong>y unregulated, serves the interests of neither<br />

camp.<br />

If at a future point the American political system decides to drop existing limits on federal<br />

funding of stem cell research, a solid regulatory system will become <strong>all</strong> the more necessary.<br />

10<br />

Indeed, a regulatory system with good enforcement powers is particularly essential if the government seeks to<br />

permit some activities and restrict others.<br />

45


Many people (ourselves included) are not concerned with the destruction of embryos per se, but<br />

rather with potential slippery-slope consequences of using embryos in this fashion (for example,<br />

setting a precedent for the harvesting of tissues and organs from cloned fetuses). Such concerns<br />

could be largely put to rest if embryonic stem cell research were conducted under a<br />

comprehensive regulatory framework that among other things kept track of cloned embryos to<br />

prevent them from being implanted or grown into fetuses. The minority position taken by<br />

supporters of stem cell research on the President’s Council on Bioethics argued in favor of<br />

precisely such a regulatory environment. 11 While most stem cell research proponents make at<br />

least a nod to the need for a regulatory framework for embryo research, relatively few have<br />

thought seriously about the institutional design that would make this possible. It is noteworthy<br />

that Britain, with its Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), has one of the<br />

world’s strictest regulatory environments in this area, and yet is a leader in stem cell research.<br />

We do not have any illusions that the American political system will produce a clear<br />

consensus one way or another on the issue of the legitimacy of embryo research, and we<br />

therefore anticipate that the kinds of regulatory changes we propose in this report will face an<br />

uphill struggle to be enacted. As in the case of other regulatory initiatives, it may take a major<br />

scandal or controversy on the order of Thalidomide or the Enron collapse to persuade the<br />

American people and Congress to act. We do believe, however, that we need to initiate a debate<br />

over the adequacy of the current regulatory system, and to begin a broad discussion of the types<br />

of institutions that will be sufficient to carry us into the twenty-first century.<br />

11<br />

See President's Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New Biotechnologies<br />

(Washington, D.C.: 2004).<br />

46


1.6 Bibliography<br />

Evans, John H. Playing God? Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public<br />

Bioethical Debate. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2002.<br />

President's Council on Bioethics. Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New<br />

Biotechnologies. Washington, D.C., 2004.<br />

47


2 Human Growth Hormones for Children of Idiopathic Short Stature:<br />

Medical Treatment or Enhancing Therapy?<br />

2.1 Introduction<br />

Before turning our attention to new bioethical dilemmas, let us examine in some detail the<br />

recent decision by the FDA to approve the use of human growth hormone (hGH) for the<br />

treatment of children of idiopathic short stature (ISS). The case of the hGH is representative of<br />

the many ch<strong>all</strong>enges regulators are likely to face in the not-too-distant future. Like many<br />

reproductive treatments, synthetic hGH origin<strong>all</strong>y was developed to treat a narrowly defined<br />

medical condition, chronic growth hormone deficiency in children. As for many other drugs, the<br />

use of hGH has expanded over time to include indications initi<strong>all</strong>y not envisaged by the company<br />

that developed it.<br />

In this chapter, we examine the role the FDA played in sanctioning the shift from purely<br />

therapeutic uses to what many have described as the cosmetic use of hGH. “Cosmetic use” is the<br />

term the FDA uses to identify treatments or drugs that are not designed to cure a medical<br />

condition, or that are intended to treat a condition that affects only the physical appearance of an<br />

individual. In the following discussion, we prefer to use the term “enhancing.” “Cosmetic” and<br />

“enhancing” are not always or necessarily synonymous terms. In the present case, however,<br />

“enhancing treatment” better captures the nature of the underlying ethical dilemma. The FDA<br />

decision to approve what may be described as an enhancing treatment then provides considerable<br />

insight into how existing regulatory agencies are likely to resolve controversies surrounding the<br />

use of medical technologies that are neither clearly therapeutic nor uniquely enhancing.<br />

Until the mid-1980s, children with severe growth hormone deficiency could only be treated<br />

with growth hormone obtained from cadavers. The amount of hGH so obtained was minuscule<br />

compared to the number of children in need of treatment; the cure was extremely expensive and<br />

not entirely safe, and some children treated with natural hGH contracted Creutzfeldt-Jakob<br />

Disease. 1<br />

Recombinant DNA technology changed <strong>all</strong> this, making it possible for biotech<br />

companies to produce a once-scarce biological resource in large quantities of very high and<br />

consistent quality. Human growth hormone was one of the very first drugs to be produced<br />

through recombinant DNA technology, the use of which use was approved by the FDA in 1985<br />

for the treatment of severe growth deficiency.<br />

In subsequent years, the availability of synthetic hGH quickly increased, though the<br />

treatment has remained very expensive. Since its introduction in 1985, human growth hormone<br />

has been prescribed for a variety of approved and unapproved indications, including inadequate<br />

1<br />

American Academy of Pediatrics and Committee on Drugs and Committee on Bioethics, "Considerations<br />

Related to the Use of Recombinant Human Growth Hormone in Children," Pediatrics 99, no. 1 (1997).<br />

49


endogenous growth hormone secretion, chronic renal insufficiency, and Turner Syndrome,<br />

among others. 2 With the f<strong>all</strong> 2003 approval of the use of synthetic hGH for the treatment of<br />

idiopathic short stature, the FDA sanctioned a medical treatment that is neither obviously<br />

therapeutic nor clearly enhancing.<br />

Its obscure name notwithstanding, this condition can easily be explained: ISS children are<br />

considerably below the mean stature for their sex and age group, yet their short stature cannot be<br />

attributed to any physiological deficiency; their growth hormone levels are well within the norm,<br />

and their parents’ stature is not gener<strong>all</strong>y below average. By <strong>all</strong> accounts, these are short but<br />

otherwise healthy, normal children. In this and similar cases, the medical profession simply<br />

assumes that the phenomenon under consideration is a condition whose origins are unknown;<br />

hence the term “idiopathic.”<br />

It should be pointed out that the FDA decision certainly cannot be described as an egregious<br />

case of regulatory failure. The FDA did not endorse the prescription of hGHs for every case of<br />

idiopathic shortness. The FDA approved this treatment only for extremely short children – that<br />

is, for children two standard deviations below the mean for sex and age group. In addition, the<br />

regulators were well aware of some of the broader societal implications of their decision. If this<br />

was indeed a case of a regulatory agency sanctioning an enhancing therapy, it was neither a<br />

spectacular nor an obviously outrageous decision. Paradoxic<strong>all</strong>y, it is precisely the ordinary<br />

nature of the hGH case that makes it relevant to our discussion. Enhancing medical treatments,<br />

as a rule, are unlikely to achieve dramatic improvements. Their effectiveness is often modest or<br />

even controversial. In addition, they may raise considerable safety concerns. In sum, enhancing<br />

treatments are likely to deliver only incremental benefits – benefits that regulators may not<br />

consider important enough to warrant limiting their accessibility on the basis of considerations<br />

other than safety and efficacy.<br />

In each of these cases, patient groups and pharmaceutical and biotechnology companies,<br />

with the more-or-less active support of the medical profession, are likely to portray a so-c<strong>all</strong>ed<br />

cosmetic treatment as an instance of the therapeutic use of a medical technology. Opponents, for<br />

their part, will undermine the enhancing aspects of the treatment in question, or even dispute that<br />

the proposed treatment constitutes a medical therapy. This is precisely why the case of the hGH<br />

is so insightful: It is a very realistic test of the ability of existing regulatory agencies to recognize<br />

the ambivalent nature of new, so-c<strong>all</strong>ed medical treatments, and to address the ethical dilemmas<br />

raised by medical treatments and technologies that are neither purely therapeutic not entirely<br />

enhancing.<br />

2<br />

These are <strong>all</strong> approved indications. For a more detailed discussion of the approval history of hGH indications,<br />

see Minnesota Department of Health Health Technology Advisory Committee, The Use of Growth Hormone for<br />

Children with Idiopathic Short Stature (Minnesota Department of Health, 2000 [cited April 24, 2006]); available<br />

from http://www.health.state.mn.us/htac/hgh.htm.<br />

50


2.2 Is There a Need for Legal Guidance?<br />

The FDA approved the cosmetic use of synthetic hGH based on a favorable<br />

recommendation by the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee, one of its<br />

many scientific advisory boards. The committee made the recommendation at its June 10, 2003,<br />

meeting, the transcripts of which shed considerable light on the committee’s rationale for<br />

approving the drug’s cosmetic use. The transcripts also provide a detailed insight into the<br />

workings of scientific advisory boards more gener<strong>all</strong>y.<br />

At issue at this committee meeting was the application by Eli Lilly and Company to approve<br />

Humatrope, a popular hGH, for the treatment of ISS children. The Eli Lilly application was<br />

certainly not the first of its kind. The FDA often has been c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to approve cosmetic<br />

treatments. Therapies to treat baldness, to eliminate wrinkles, to reduce weight, and to treat many<br />

other conditions can <strong>all</strong> be described as cosmetic treatments, or as treatments that can be<br />

prescribed for other-than-therapeutic indications. In <strong>all</strong> these cases, the FDA position has been<br />

quite clear: The agency, in evaluating applications, focuses exclusively on its twin statutory<br />

mandates of safety and efficacy – whether the drug (or medical device or biologic) in question<br />

was designed for therapeutic or cosmetic uses or both. It tends to exclude other considerations,<br />

such as whether a specific drug use may or may not be appropriate, acceptable, or desirable.<br />

In the case of hGH, the FDA had no intention to take a different stance. From its point of<br />

view, the question of whether treating ISS children with hGH constitutes a cosmetic use was not<br />

part of the committee charges. At the same time, the FDA was well aware that the committee<br />

might have been tempted to deviate from the prescribed course. As noted by David Orloff,<br />

director of the Division of Metabolic and Endocrine Drug Products at the Center for Drug<br />

Evaluation and Research (CDER):<br />

[…] I just want to raise one other issue that has not actu<strong>all</strong>y been raised here explicitly, but may be<br />

in the back of some people’s minds, and in the minds of those perhaps listening from the audience.<br />

And that is, to some extent, it’s kind of the flip side of the clinical significance question that’s<br />

been asked and will be asked again, and that is whether the use of growth hormone in non-growth<br />

hormone deficient short stature represents “cosmetic” use of growth hormone, and […] might be<br />

construed somehow as setting a broad precedent for cosmetic use of drugs.<br />

The first point I’d like to say is that any decision that’s made with regard to growth hormone in<br />

this instance will be based upon a judgment of a favorable balance of risk versus benefit for the<br />

proposed indication, and that would not, in our minds, be setting a broad policy with regard,<br />

gener<strong>all</strong>y, to the use of drugs for cosmetic purposes.<br />

I’d also propose that it is not the purpose of this meeting to debate the merits of approvals of other<br />

drugs for what some – usu<strong>all</strong>y those unaffected by the target condition – might construe as<br />

cosmetic purposes. And I think it’s safe to say that we should concede that once demonstrated to<br />

be safe and effective, the choice of whether to attempt therapy for, for example, baldness, or mild<br />

acne, or even overweight is up to doctors, patients, and their families, as they weigh the potential<br />

benefits of the therapy against the potential risks.<br />

And, I guess I said it before, but I’ll just point it out one more time: that we don’t see a regulatory<br />

stance favoring approval for the use of growth hormone putting this division or the agency on a<br />

51


slippery slope toward blanket uses of – cosmetic uses of – growth hormone, as well as for other<br />

drugs. 3<br />

As this quote demonstrates, the FDA tried very hard to avoid getting involved in what it<br />

probably regarded as a sterile controversy over its role in sanctioning the cosmetic use of hGH.<br />

In this, it largely succeeded. The Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee,<br />

despite some hesitations, ultimately focused its attention on safety, efficacy, and what medical<br />

practitioners label “clinical significance.” This is an interesting concept that refines and expands<br />

the meaning of effectiveness. A drug or a medical treatment may be effective, in the sense that it<br />

may produce the intended medical outcomes, yet it may not be “clinic<strong>all</strong>y significant” in the<br />

sense that it may be unable to cure the core concerns associated with a condition. In the present<br />

case, addressing clinical significance meant that the committee was c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to determine (1)<br />

whether idiopathic shortness should be considered a condition, (2) in what sense this medical<br />

condition affects the health and well-being of ISS children, and (3) whether the treatment in<br />

question not only raises the final height of affected children but also contributes significantly to<br />

mitigating the associated psychological impairment and provides other benefits beyond merely<br />

height.<br />

In their presentation to the committee, Eli Lilly and its advisers identified several possible<br />

benefits of treating short children with Humatrope, ranging from reaching the minimal height<br />

required by some jobs to being able to buy normal clothes and being able to sit at least 10 inches<br />

away from a steering wheel, as air bag safety regulations require. A senior Eli Lilly adviser<br />

offered considerable evidence about the negative psychological impact of short stature. His<br />

presentation was complemented by the testimony of short children describing in considerable<br />

detail patterns of bullying and teasing by their peers.<br />

Despite Eli Lilly’s considerable efforts to demonstrate not only efficacy but also clinical<br />

significance, a large fraction of the committee members was not convinced. Of nine<br />

commissioners, five expressed serious doubts about the benefits of hGH treatment, three were<br />

unconcerned, and one was agnostic. It is worth quoting some of the dissenting voices at some<br />

length:<br />

[…] Just to summarize what was just said, I think that we’ve been shown that treatment with<br />

growth hormone can improve height, but that the effect is, I think, fairly sm<strong>all</strong>; on the average,<br />

about one-and-a-half inches; and that there’s been no demonstration of the impact of this on<br />

quality of life. 4<br />

I think the testimony we’ve heard, and probably from everybody’s own experience, we know the<br />

enormous hurt and pain of the stigma of extreme shortness. And I think the kind of changes we’ve<br />

seen here don’t address that. So I’m leaning on the side of thinking that we’ve heard that,<br />

clinic<strong>all</strong>y, this much change in height is not enough. 5<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

Food and Drug Administration Center for Drug Evaluation and Research, "Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs<br />

Advisory Committee Meeting," ed. Food and Drug Administration Department of Health and Human Services<br />

(October 7, 2003), p.248-49.<br />

Commissioner Grady, Ibid., p.257 emphasis added.<br />

Commissioner Worcester, Ibid., p.267 emphasis added.<br />

52


[…] I re<strong>all</strong>y think there should be additional data on some type of benefit besides simply the<br />

height. Now, I agree that if the height was dramatic – six inches – you probably wouldn’t have to<br />

show anything else. But because the height benefit is much sm<strong>all</strong>er than that, I am concerned that<br />

here is a very expensive treatment, in which the benefits are not clearly shown. 6<br />

Not every committee member subscribed to these views. The committee chair remarked:<br />

[…] In regards to the clinical importance, I think this is the crux of the problem that many of us<br />

are having with this. Dr. Grady nicely brought out that there’s no re<strong>all</strong>y good evidence that oneand-a-half<br />

inches or so is going to improve quality of life. I’m also concerned about the resource<br />

<strong>all</strong>ocation issues, about who’s going to pay for this, and the potential worsening of the drag on<br />

health care dollars over time. Nevertheless, I don’t think that’s re<strong>all</strong>y the charge of the committee.<br />

The charge of the committee is re<strong>all</strong>y to determine whether this is safe and efficacious, and<br />

clinic<strong>all</strong>y important. 7<br />

The committee chair went on to explain that in his view, clinical relevance is re<strong>all</strong>y a<br />

question that must be decided by parents and children in cooperation with their doctors. In other<br />

words, clinical relevance, in his view, is re<strong>all</strong>y a matter of informed consent. His take on this<br />

matter was predicated on the assumption that hGH treatment was indeed effective. This<br />

assumption was by no means shared by <strong>all</strong> committee members.<br />

Several committee members noted that from a statistical standpoint, the treatment seemed<br />

moderately effective (with, on average, a gain in final height of one to one-and-a-half inches),<br />

but questioned whether such a modest gain would actu<strong>all</strong>y have any significant positive impact<br />

on the life and well-being of the children. This question was raised several times, but no<br />

convincing answer was provided. In addition, it was noted that, based on the data presented by<br />

Eli Lilly, individual participants in the clinical trials had responded very differently to the<br />

treatment, with some participants not responding at <strong>all</strong> and others responding very well. In other<br />

words, the treatment did not seem to have a sufficiently predictable impact on the final height of<br />

the participating children. The only critic invited to give a presentation at the meeting, an<br />

internation<strong>all</strong>y renowned endocrinologist, pointed out that in the study presented by Eli Lilly, the<br />

final height reached by children in the control group (that is, in the group that had received a<br />

placebo) and the final height reached by the children who had received the treatment were in fact<br />

quite similar. (This problem is not confined to this particular type of hGH; other hGHs suffer<br />

from the same limitation.) 8<br />

In sum, the committee members seemed to disagree not only on what might constitute<br />

efficacy in a narrow technical sense (Is a one-and-a-half inch gain in final height sufficient to<br />

demonstrate efficacy?), but also on what the benefits of the treatment might be. These<br />

reservations notwithstanding, the committee recommended by an eight-to-two vote and with<br />

minimal qualifications that the FDA approve Humatrope for the treatment of ISS children as<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

Commissioner Schade, Ibid., p.263 emphasis added.<br />

Commissioner Brunstein, Ibid., p.258.<br />

Harvey J. Guyda, "Four Decades of Growth Hormone Therapy for Short Children: What Have We Achieved?,"<br />

The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 84, no. 12 (1999).<br />

53


proposed by Eli Lilly – a rather surprising outcome given the discomfort demonstrated by many<br />

committee members, and one that warrants closer scrutiny.<br />

2.3 Discussion<br />

To what extent can the FDA’s Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee be<br />

regarded as a viable model for untangling future ethical dilemmas? In its present form, this<br />

committee is clearly in no position to tackle broader ethical dilemmas, as illustrated by the<br />

distinction between therapeutic and enhancing uses of hGHs. The FDA is characterized by an<br />

organizational culture centered mostly on safety and efficacy. Tackling broader ethical dilemmas<br />

would be not only on dubious statutory ground and outside of FDA’s core competencies; it<br />

would also not be part of the committee’s charge as established in its charter. 9 Thus, it would be<br />

unfair to criticize existing regulatory structures for failing to address ethical questions that they<br />

were not intended to answer in this first place. The committee recommendation and the FDA<br />

decision to approve the cosmetic use of hGH must be evaluated on their own terms.<br />

At first, it is tempting to conclude that the FDA’s decision was sound. The FDA has made<br />

the hGH treatment available to very short children – children at least 2.25 standard deviations<br />

below the average height for their sex and age. Eli Lilly estimates that in the United States there<br />

are approximately 400,000 of such children. The agency came to its conclusion after what<br />

appears to be a thorough examination of the safety, efficacy, and clinical significance of the<br />

proposed treatment. It also emphasized that its decision was not to be interpreted as a general<br />

expression of support for cosmetic treatments. In this sense, the FDA decision-making process<br />

does not seem to raise any major concerns.<br />

A closer examination of the transcripts suggests a different conclusion. Concerns about<br />

clinical significance notwithstanding, the committee members failed to adequately examine<br />

perhaps the most important aspect of clinical significance – the empirical evidence concerning<br />

the negative impact of short stature on the well-being of ISS children (and short children in<br />

general). Remember that the rationale behind Eli Lilly’s application was based precisely on the<br />

assumption that short stature has an empiric<strong>all</strong>y demonstrable and systematic negative impact on<br />

children. As mentioned earlier, one of Eli Lilly’s consultants spent considerable time making this<br />

case, and the committee members seemed gener<strong>all</strong>y to accept the presentation’s main conclusion.<br />

In the eyes of most committee members, and indeed most people confronted with this issue,<br />

preventing suffering and long-term psychological harm to short children would be a very strong<br />

rationale for supporting the proposed treatment. But the evidence presented by Eli Lilly was<br />

vigorously disputed by an internation<strong>all</strong>y renowned endocrinologist invited to the meeting by the<br />

9<br />

The committee charter establishes that it is the committee’s responsibility to “[…] review and evaluate data<br />

concerning the safety and effectiveness of marketed and investigational human drug products for use in the<br />

treatment of endocrine and metabolic disorders, and make appropriate recommendations to the Commissioner of<br />

Food and Drugs.” The complete Charter text is available at<br />

http://www.fda.gov/cder/audiences/acspage/Endocrinologiccharter1.htm.<br />

54


FDA. The expert in question pointed to numerous recent studies showing that short stature in<br />

children may be a source of distress but has minimal or no lasting negative effect on their wellbeing.<br />

Yet the subsequent discussion as documented in the transcripts suggests that the expert’s<br />

opinion did not affect the commissioners’ thinking in the least. Nor did any commissioner<br />

actu<strong>all</strong>y ch<strong>all</strong>enge Eli Lilly’s core assumption that shortness causes significant psychological<br />

harm.<br />

Our own review of the literature also casts considerable doubt on the view that shortness<br />

causes lasting psychological harm. 10 As with many scientific and medical controversies, the<br />

conclusion that short stature does not cause psychological harm is hardly unassailable. However,<br />

it is difficult to ignore two simple facts. First, studies showing psychological harm are gener<strong>all</strong>y<br />

very old. More recent empirical data and more sophisticated research designs do not support the<br />

early conclusions. Second, the majority of the studies reviewed do not show harm. Against this<br />

background, the committee’s failure to explore more thoroughly the <strong>all</strong>eged negative<br />

psychological impact of short statute on children deserves further scrutiny.<br />

There are two main reasons for this myopic behavior. Both of them suggest important<br />

lessons. For one thing, numerous psychological studies have demonstrated that for a dissenting<br />

view to be heard, it must have roughly equal weight as other views. In the case of the committee<br />

meeting on Humatrope, this requirement clearly was not met. As the frustrated dissenter<br />

observed, he was the only critical voice amidst an army of industry representatives, their<br />

advisers, and supporting families. Under these circumstances, a dissenting voice will simply be<br />

ignored, while the dominant view will be reinforced. This phenomenon is known as group<br />

polarization, and it is well documented. 11<br />

Committee composition is the second factor affecting the likelihood that dissenting views<br />

will be heard. The Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee consists of ten<br />

members and an executive secretary. Of the ten committee members at the time of the debate on<br />

Humatrope, eight represented one branch of endocrinology or another. All of them were<br />

university professors, and some of them department chairs. One was a biostatistician, one an<br />

epidemiologist, and one – the “consumer representative” (a term meant to identify with a broader<br />

lay audience) – was a specialist in women’s health. Certainly this was a very distinguished and<br />

knowledgeable panel, but their respective medical backgrounds hardly prepared them to question<br />

psychological or sociological stereotypes. The presence of a single consumer representative on<br />

the committee – the only dissenting voice – had no discernible impact on the committee at large,<br />

as predicted by the literature on committee behavior. This is an excellent example of group<br />

polarization: The homogeneous nature of the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory<br />

10<br />

11<br />

See Appendix B for details.<br />

See chapter 10.7.1 for an in-depth discussion.<br />

55


Committee tended, predictably, to reinforce widely held beliefs and marginalize dissenting<br />

views. 12<br />

Group polarization is a common phenomenon in sm<strong>all</strong> deliberative bodies, and it is probably<br />

responsible for many ill-informed administrative decisions. Its pernicious influence is not limited<br />

to sm<strong>all</strong> groups, however, as we show throughout this report. Legislators, trade and professional<br />

groups, and scientific societies, among others, are not immune to this phenomenon. Fortunately,<br />

it appears that in many cases it is relatively easy to reverse group polarization. To this end, sm<strong>all</strong><br />

group decision-making bodies must be chartered so as to ensure that <strong>all</strong> relevant views are<br />

represented in roughly equal proportions – a straightforward but often neglected consideration.<br />

The preceding discussion suggests that the current system of scientific advisories, as<br />

exemplified by the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee, is unable to cope<br />

with broader ethical dilemmas (a task it was never intended to perform.) It also shows serious<br />

limitations in discharging its public mandate. Advocates of the status quo may point out that to<br />

ensure balance, the federal government only needs to make sure that the provisions of the<br />

Federal Advisory Committee Act of 1972 (FACA) are properly implemented. FACA governs the<br />

establishment and operation of <strong>all</strong> federal advisory committees, including FDA scientific<br />

advisory committees. 13 FACA is an example of a good governance law; it was passed mainly to<br />

mitigate the excessive influence of organized interest groups. Among other things, FACA<br />

requires the convening agency to appoint members to an advisory committee so as to ensure that<br />

the committee be “balanced” – in other words, that a broad range of views is represented on the<br />

committee. 14<br />

Can the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee be considered balanced?<br />

The committee charter c<strong>all</strong>s for appointing members with proven expertise in endocrinology,<br />

epidemiology, or statistics, and for including a consumer advocate with recognized technical<br />

expertise. Given the committee’s charge, this composition seems indeed quite reasonable. Nor is<br />

there any prima facie reason to assume that this committee violates any key FACA provisions.<br />

On the other hand, it is difficult to believe that a committee balanced in any strong sense of the<br />

term is prone to group polarization. On closer examination, the committee charter and FACA<br />

provisions for balanced composition may turn out to be in conflict, but the courts have gener<strong>all</strong>y<br />

refrained from providing specific guidance on how to ensure balance. 15<br />

As a result,<br />

administrative agencies tradition<strong>all</strong>y have had considerable latitude in the interpretation of this<br />

provision, latitude that administrations of both parties have routinely exploited for their own<br />

narrow political goals.<br />

12<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

Ironic<strong>all</strong>y, and perhaps surprisingly, deliberation among committee members in this case did not produce<br />

depolarization, but rather the opposite.<br />

See http://www.fda.gov/cder/audiences/acspage/Endocrinologiccharter1.htm.<br />

See Public Law 92-463, Sec. 5(b)(2).<br />

Steven P. Croley and William F. Funk, "The Federal Advisory Committee Act and Good Governance," Yale<br />

Journal on Regulation 14 (1997).<br />

56


2.4 Broadening the Ethical Debate<br />

As it stands, the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee could be<br />

described as a decision-making body that is likely to routinely recast ethical dilemmas in narrow<br />

medical terms. It is also likely to reduce eminently public choices to private decisions. The heavy<br />

reliance on science advisory boards, the skewed composition of these boards, the limited pool of<br />

ethical arguments presented to these panels, and their inadequate statutory authority <strong>all</strong><br />

contribute to this outcome.<br />

Some commentators may argue that that the Public Health Service Act and the Food, Drug,<br />

and Cosmetics Act afford the FDA much more regulatory discretion than suggested by current<br />

FDA regulatory practices. In particular, under some legal theories, the FDA would be able to<br />

include considerations other than safety and efficacy in its approval process. We are in no<br />

position to evaluate the merits of this claim, but even if it could be demonstrated that the FDA<br />

would have to statutory authority to inject ethical considerations into its decision-making<br />

process, the agency is very unlikely to do so. The FDA does not consider regulatory demands<br />

other than those pertaining to safety and efficacy as part if its core mission. In the agency’s view,<br />

these demands represent a regulatory distraction, a mis<strong>all</strong>ocation of scarce administrative<br />

resources that drag the agency into legal battles with uncertain outcomes. Importantly, the<br />

agency’s organizational culture and its professional expertise, both of which have developed<br />

around safety and efficacy, make the FDA ill-suited to address broad ethical dilemmas.<br />

But what are the ethical dilemmas neglected by the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Advisory<br />

Committee? In the remainder of this chapter, we touch upon some of the arguments that in our<br />

view have not received sufficient attention. Some have argued that severe hGH deficiency is a<br />

physiological impairment that deserves close medical attention, whereas idiopathic short stature<br />

is not at <strong>all</strong> a medical condition. 16 Children can be unhappy about many things; they may not like<br />

their noses, for example, but should we be in the business of prescribing nose jobs? In this view,<br />

children suffering from severe hGH deficiency and ISS children do not re<strong>all</strong>y represent<br />

commensurable cases. By prescribing hGH treatment for idiopathic shortness, are we not simply<br />

indulging profoundly human but nevertheless unjustifiable parental desires? Should health<br />

insurance plans (that is to say, the public) be required to cover the costs of hGH treatment for an<br />

adolescent who is desperate to follow in his father’s footsteps and embrace a basketb<strong>all</strong> career?<br />

At the other extreme, if there is no solid evidence of ubiquitous and systematic harm to short<br />

children, why should the state encourage the mis<strong>all</strong>ocation of scarce financial resources?<br />

These arguments have been made often and do not require further discussion. By contrast,<br />

one question that should have received considerable attention but has barely been acknowledged<br />

is what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed the medicalization of societal problems. Dr. Nancy Worcester, the<br />

consumer representative on the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Advisory Committee, was the<br />

only commissioner who touched upon this concern, although only margin<strong>all</strong>y so. Not<br />

16<br />

Peter H. Schwartz, "Genetic Breakthroughs and the Limits of Medicine: Short Stature, Growth Hormone, and the<br />

Idea of Dysfunction," St. Thomas Law Review 13 (2001).<br />

57


coincident<strong>all</strong>y, she was also one of only two commissioners who voted against the Eli Lilly<br />

application. 17 In our view, this concern lies at the heart of many contemporary controversies over<br />

new reproductive technologies and biomedical research, and it is worth exploring in some depth.<br />

In its most general form, the argument goes like this: New scientific and medical<br />

developments have a differential impact on society. Some technologies tend to reinforce preexisting,<br />

widespread beliefs and cultural orientations; they resonate with the public and as a<br />

result they are quickly embraced. Others may actu<strong>all</strong>y be incompatible with widely shared<br />

cultural values. This means that the latter may be at a disadvantage compared to other<br />

technologies more in tune with domestic traditions, values, and orientations. New technologies,<br />

in other words, do not f<strong>all</strong> on a cultur<strong>all</strong>y neutral ground; powerful, pre-existing habits of the<br />

heart and mind tend to nurture some and reject others. 18<br />

Applied to the case of human growth hormone, this argument suggests that the tendency to<br />

describe idiopathic shortness as a condition deserving medical attention is informed in large<br />

measure by at least three deeply entrenched American values: (10 the unshakable belief in the<br />

power of technology to solve even the most intractable problems, including political and social<br />

ones; (2) a strong sense of individual responsibility and self-reliance; and (3) a deep-seated<br />

distrust of government. 19 The obsession with restoring physical height through medication rather<br />

than by focusing on the political means to fight intolerance for physical differences is but one<br />

example of a pervasive tendency in the contemporary United States to redefine social problems<br />

as technological ch<strong>all</strong>enges, and to rely on private initiative rather than on political action. It is<br />

not too difficult, then, to predict the impact that hGH availability would have on parents with ISS<br />

children; it would reinforce a view of short stature as a medical condition rather than as a<br />

manifestation (albeit a mild one) of intolerance, to be cured by medical means rather than<br />

addressed by PTAs, school districts, and local governments.<br />

The use of synthetic hGH to treat shortness is only the latest example of the medicalization<br />

of societal problems. Supposedly miraculous cures peddled as means to solve social and political<br />

problems have a long history. In the 1930s, for example, an entrepreneur made a fortune for<br />

himself by selling an ointment to African-Americans that promised – correctly as it turned out, at<br />

least for a limited period of time – to “whiten” their skin. 20 One could easily imagine a cosmetic<br />

product that, unlike its predecessor, has a permanent whitening effect; should this treatment<br />

receive FDA blessing only because it is both safe and effective? Wouldn’t many of us, and not<br />

only African-Americans, reject the notion that racial discrimination should be fought by<br />

medication rather than by political means?<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

20<br />

Center for Drug Evaluation and Research, "Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee Meeting,"<br />

p.322.<br />

Langdon Winner, "Technology Today: Utopia or Dystopia?," Social Research 64, no. 3 (1997).<br />

Seymour Martin Lipset, American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword (New York: W.W. Norton &<br />

Company, 1996).<br />

Carl Elliott, Better Than Well: American Medicine Meets the American Dream (New York: W.W. Norton &<br />

Company, 2003), p.191-93.<br />

58


Whether the broad availability of synthetic hGH will erode our tolerance for physical<br />

differences and perhaps, over time, also undermine now widely shared notions of tolerance<br />

remains to be seen, but this would certainly be a price too high to pay. The incessant drive<br />

toward physical perfection, as illustrated by the staggering sums of money spent every year on<br />

cosmetics and plastic surgery, is a reminder that in contemporary America, certain forms of<br />

intolerance have already achieved the status of national obsession. The popularity of antidepressants,<br />

on the other end, seems to suggest not merely that many Americans are unable to<br />

cope with the difficulties of modern life, but that the pressure to live up to certain supposedly<br />

widespread notions of success and “the good life” has become consuming. 21<br />

The case of the synthetic hGH strongly suggests that existing regulatory institutions are<br />

simply inadequate to address the ch<strong>all</strong>enges raised by new reproductive treatments and<br />

biomedical research. In Homer’s Odyssey, Achilles resisted the suave but deadly chants of the<br />

Sirens by ordering his crew to bind him to the mast of his boat. Like modern argonauts, we may<br />

soon be exposed to the chants of medical and scientific Sirens we may be too weak to resist.<br />

Achilles’ response to the Sirens’ threatening chants is an acknowledgment both of human frailty<br />

and ingenuity. Modern societies have developed elaborate ways to resist temptation. Mindful of<br />

our weakness, we often delegate to regulatory agencies the task of protecting us against our selfdestructive<br />

inclinations. 22 New reproductive treatments and medical technologies are only the<br />

latest illustration of a technological and scientific development that perhaps we are too weak to<br />

control. It is certainly not too late to take measures that will protect us against ourselves, but to<br />

do so, contemporary debates about new reproductive and medical technologies must be moved<br />

decidedly into the public realm. This report is a contribution to this debate.<br />

21<br />

22<br />

Peter D. Kramer, Listening to Prozac: The Landmark Book About Antidepressants and the Remaking of the Self<br />

(New York: Penguin Books, 1997).<br />

Modern commentators speak of second-order preferences, i.e., preferences about preferences. For example, a<br />

drinking habit may be described as a first-order preference, and regulations against drinking as an example of a<br />

second-order preference. For a discussion, see Cass Sunstein and Edna Ullmann-Margalit, "Second-Order<br />

Decisions," Ethics 110 (1999).<br />

59


2.5 Bibliography<br />

American Academy of Pediatrics, and Committee on Drugs and Committee on Bioethics.<br />

"Considerations Related to the Use of Recombinant Human Growth Hormone in<br />

Children." Pediatrics 99, no. 1 (1997): 122-29.<br />

Center for Drug Evaluation and Research, Food and Drug Administration. "Endocrinologic and<br />

Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee Meeting." edited by Food and Drug<br />

Administration Department of Health and Human Services, October 7, 2003.<br />

Croley, Steven P., and William F. Funk. "The Federal Advisory Committee Act and Good<br />

Governance." Yale Journal on Regulation 14 (1997): 451-539.<br />

Elliott, Carl. Better Than Well: American Medicine Meets the American Dream. New York:<br />

W.W. Norton & Company, 2003.<br />

Guyda, Harvey J. "Four Decades of Growth Hormone Therapy for Short Children: What Have<br />

We Achieved?" The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 84, no. 12 (1999):<br />

4307-16.<br />

Health Technology Advisory Committee, Minnesota Department of Health. The Use of Growth<br />

Hormone for Children with Idiopathic Short Stature Minnesota Department of Health,<br />

2000 [cited April 24, 2006]. Available from http://www.health.state.mn.us/htac/hgh.htm.<br />

Kramer, Peter D. Listening to Prozac: The Landmark Book About Antidepressants and the<br />

Remaking of the Self. New York: Penguin Books, 1997.<br />

Lipset, Seymour Martin. American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword. New York: W.W.<br />

Norton & Company, 1996.<br />

Schwartz, Peter H. "Genetic Breakthroughs and the Limits of Medicine: Short Stature, Growth<br />

Hormone, and the Idea of Dysfunction." St. Thomas Law Review 13 (2001): 965-78.<br />

Sunstein, Cass, and Edna Ullmann-Margalit. "Second-Order Decisions." Ethics 110 (1999): 5-<br />

31.<br />

Winner, Langdon. "Technology Today: Utopia or Dystopia?" Social Research 64, no. 3 (1997):<br />

989-1017.<br />

61


3 Ethical Principles<br />

No proposal for regulation can begin without a discussion of the larger ends that regulation<br />

is intended to serve. A great deal of regulation in the United States has come about as a result of<br />

specific harms or incidents, like the sulfanilamide elixir scandal that led to passage of the Food,<br />

Drug, and Cosmetics Act, or more recently the Enron and WorldCom accounting scandals that<br />

paved the way for passage of the Sarbanes-Oxley reforms. Our proposal to regulate human<br />

biomedicine is different: It is being driven not in response to pressing current problems, but<br />

rather in anticipation of possible future problems that fast-moving technologies might introduce.<br />

We will begin by laying out a general set of ethical principles that we believe should guide<br />

regulation in the domain we have defined in the first chapter – namely, technologies and medical<br />

practices related to human reproduction and to biomedical research involving the use and/or<br />

destruction of human embryos. We believe that these general principles are ones that the<br />

American public will broadly support, and we have considerable polling data to back this up (see<br />

chapter 8). These principles are similar in many instances to those laid out in the 2004 report by<br />

the President’s Council on Bioethics, “Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New<br />

Biotechnologies.” The following section will list the principles, and elucidate some of their more<br />

concrete implications.<br />

3.1 General Ethical Principles Guiding the Regulation of Technologies and Medical<br />

Practices Related to Human Reproduction<br />

We believe that human reproduction is a particularly important part of human life, and that<br />

society has an inherent interest in protecting the human values associated with it. The following<br />

is a set of ethical standards that we believe any regulatory system touching on this domain should<br />

promote. These guiding principles touch mainly on the means and the ends of assisted<br />

reproduction, and only secondarily on issues of access. Access is partly examined in chapter 7, in<br />

which we discuss possible constitutional constraints on the regulation of ARTs, but is otherwise<br />

not a subject of this discussion. The ethical principles that we endorse are as follows:<br />

• The well-being and health of children should be protected.<br />

• Biomedical procedures on human embryos must respect their intermediate moral<br />

status.<br />

• Access to ARTs on the part of infertile couples should be promoted.<br />

• The well-being and health of women should be protected.<br />

• Free and informed consent must be required on the part of those making use of<br />

ARTs.<br />

63


• Limits on the commercialization of eggs, sperm, and embryos should be imposed.<br />

• Therapeutic uses should be favored over enhancement uses of biomedicine.<br />

Let us discuss each of these principles in turn.<br />

The well-being and health of children. Since reproduction inherently aims to create<br />

children, the welfare of children ought to be placed first and foremost as an objective of<br />

regulation. We believe that this means, in the first instance, better and more systematic<br />

monitoring of health outcomes, including long-term longitudinal surveys, of IVF children.<br />

Compared to other developed countries, public oversight of ARTs in the United States is limited,<br />

and funds to carry out studies have thus far been limited.<br />

It may seem obvious that the well-being and health of children ought to have priority over<br />

the interests of other stakeholders in reproductive medicine, including parents, doctors, clinics,<br />

and biomedical researchers. Many discussions of new reproductive technologies, however, often<br />

put the wishes and desires of potential parents foremost. Clearly, parents who want children also<br />

want the best for their children, and so the law gener<strong>all</strong>y <strong>all</strong>ows them generous discretion in<br />

following their own instincts, under the assumption that this will also lead to good outcomes for<br />

their children. But it is not always necessarily the case that what parents want will correspond to<br />

the best interest of their children. This is most obviously true in the case of mothers who drink<br />

alcohol or take drugs while pregnant. There is also the case of a deaf lesbian couple that wanted<br />

to intention<strong>all</strong>y disable the hearing of their child so that the child would be part of their deaf<br />

“culture.” 1<br />

We interpret “well-being and health” broadly to mean not just physical health, but<br />

psychological and social well-being as well. This means, among other things, that every child<br />

has the right to be biologic<strong>all</strong>y related to a mother and a father, even though they may be brought<br />

up in a variety of households in which the biological mother and father may be absent. We<br />

believe that this right overrides the interests of parents in creating biological offspring through<br />

novel medical techniques, like cloning or the harvesting of fetal eggs (see the following section<br />

on prohibited activities).<br />

The intermediate moral status of human embryos. We do not believe that an embryo is<br />

the moral equivalent of a human being. The potential for an embryo to eventu<strong>all</strong>y develop into a<br />

child, per se, does not establish equality. Just like an acorn and an oak tree are not identical<br />

objects, so there are ethic<strong>all</strong>y meaningful differences between an embryo and a fully developed<br />

human being. At the other end, we don’t share the view, common among scientists, that a human<br />

embryo is simply a tiny clump of cells that can be manipulated at will. Embryos occupy an<br />

ethic<strong>all</strong>y gray zone – they are due some respect, but not the same respect due to human beings.<br />

Equal access to ARTs on the part of infertile couples. At this point, approximately two<br />

million children have been born worldwide through IVF. The benefits of this technology to<br />

1<br />

M. Spriggs, "Lesbian Couple Create a Child Who Is Deaf Like Them," Journal of Medical Ethics 28 (2002).<br />

64


infertile parents have been enormous, and equal access to it ought to be a priority. In the United<br />

States, however, treatment for infertility is often not regarded as an insurable medical condition,<br />

but rather as a health option. Insurance coverage varies by state, and for many Americans, IVF is<br />

cost-prohibitive. Expanding the availability of safe ARTs should be a policy priority. 2<br />

An<br />

unproblematic focus of this policy should be infertile heterosexual couples, whether married or<br />

not. An important and largely unresolved question is whether the benefits of this policy should<br />

be extended to singles, minors, homosexual couples, and women who would like to procreate<br />

using the gametes of their recently deceased husbands. As mentioned earlier in this report, we<br />

focus mainly on the ends and the technological means, and only margin<strong>all</strong>y on questions of<br />

access.<br />

The well-being and health of women. ARTs frequently involve special risks to women,<br />

particularly due to the need to take fertility drugs that stimulate ovulation. Most ARTs involve<br />

invasive medical procedures; new techniques that may become available in the future could lead<br />

to pregnancy complications that do not exist now. We place the priority of women’s well-being<br />

and health somewhat lower than that of children and of infertile couples, only because the<br />

women who take these risks gener<strong>all</strong>y do so voluntarily and in full knowledge of possible<br />

adverse consequences.<br />

Free and informed consent. It is important to recognize that a great deal of what happens<br />

in IVF clinics constitutes a form of experimental medicine, as techniques like intracytoplasmic<br />

sperm injection (ICSI) and pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) move from the laboratory<br />

directly to clinical practice. Many techniques have never been tested in animal models, and while<br />

there have not to date been any major problems experienced with new technologies leading to,<br />

for example, major birth defects, this remains a constant possibility. It is very important,<br />

therefore, that parents be fully informed ahead of time as to existing risks, and in cases where<br />

procedures are genuinely novel, that they be informed of this as well. This makes doubly<br />

important the collection of comprehensive and comparable data on the long-term health<br />

consequences of different ARTs and procedures to ensure that doctors and clinics have the<br />

proper incentives to inform their patients fully and adequately of whatever risks are known to<br />

exist.<br />

Limits to commercialization. While the practice of medicine using artificial reproductive<br />

technologies constitutes a business for the doctors and clinics participating in it, we believe that<br />

there should be limits to the commercialization of many aspects of reproduction. This involves<br />

limits on production and sale of eggs and sperm, and particularly on the production and sale of<br />

embryos. In particular, we believe that the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office should not issue<br />

patents on embryos or fetuses at any stage of development.<br />

Therapeutic over enhancement uses of biomedicine. We believe that the priority in<br />

biomedical research and clinical practice ought to be given to therapeutic ends – i.e., to healing<br />

2<br />

For an in-depth discussion of the economics of the ART market, see Debora L. Spar, The Baby Business: How<br />

Money, Science, and Politics Drive the Commerce of Conception (Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press,<br />

2006).<br />

65


the sick and relieving the pain and suffering of those afflicted with pathological conditions. One<br />

of the large issues opened up by many new biotechnologies is the possibility that the very same<br />

techniques used for therapeutic purposes could also be used to enhance the qualities of children<br />

who suffer from no abnormal or pathological conditions. There is very little disagreement over<br />

the therapeutic uses of medicine, but there is a great deal of societal unease over so-c<strong>all</strong>ed<br />

“enhancement” uses of biomedicine, for example, the use of growth hormone to make a child of<br />

average height t<strong>all</strong>er than the mean.<br />

We do not believe that this unease should translate mechanic<strong>all</strong>y into blanket prohibitions or<br />

red lines. Many people have argued (1s) that there is no clear distinction between therapeutic and<br />

enhancement uses of biomedicine; 3 (2) that in any case we permit many procedures like breast<br />

implants or cosmetic surgery that constitute enhancement; and (3) that enhancement technologies<br />

will be positively desirable as a means of overcoming limited existing human capacities.<br />

We believe that these are serious arguments deserving full discussion – fuller, indeed, than<br />

we can provide here. 4<br />

While the borderline between therapeutic and enhancement uses of<br />

biomedical technologies is often unclear, the distinction remains a valid and important one.<br />

Using PGD or gene therapy to prevent a genetic disorder like Huntington’s or Tay-Sachs is<br />

clearly quite different from using these techniques to produce children with different hair color<br />

or height. The United States already sets regulatory boundaries between the therapeutic and<br />

enhancement uses of various psychotropic drugs like selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors<br />

(SSRIs) and Ritalin to treat depression and attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD),<br />

where the borderline between pathology and normality can be extremely ambiguous.<br />

The use of biomedicine for enhancement purposes raises at least three complex social and ethical<br />

issues. The first concerns equality and equal access. While therapeutic uses of medicine pull<br />

people up to the mean, enhancement uses will potenti<strong>all</strong>y increase natural inequalities in ways<br />

that are likely to add to existing social inequalities. Second, many potential targets of<br />

enhancement confer only relative gains, which may be advantageous for the individuals seeking<br />

them, but not for society as a whole. An existing example is the widespread use of sex selection<br />

techniques in some parts of Asia, which has produced large-scale imbalances between boys and<br />

girls. While parents may think that having a son confers social advantages, most societies<br />

encounter an array of problems when sex ratios f<strong>all</strong> out of balance. <strong>Final</strong>ly, enhancement raises<br />

ethic<strong>all</strong>y troubling arguments over the nature of human goods. Potential targets of enhancement,<br />

like skin color or proclivities towards homosexuality, are not gener<strong>all</strong>y accepted as bad things to<br />

be overcome. Enhancement may also produce unintended consequences, particularly if they lead<br />

3<br />

4<br />

There are many other examples of cases where the distinction between therapy and enhancement is blurred. Is<br />

offering heart-bypass surgery or chemotherapy to an 85-year-old patient suffering from heart disease or cancer<br />

truly therapeutic, or does it amount in effect to an unnatural form of life-extension, and thus enhancement? Many<br />

drugs like Ritalin can be taken for either therapeutic or enhancement purposes; the diagnostic criteria for<br />

conditions like ADHD that distinguish one use from the other are flexible, and to some extent subjective.<br />

For an excellent discussion of the many dimensions of enhancement, see the President’s Council on Bioethics,<br />

Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness (Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office,<br />

2003).<br />

66


to population-level changes in human characteristics (as is already the case with sex selection in<br />

Asia).<br />

It is a well-established utilitarian principle that greater risks are permissible when treating a<br />

clearly pathological condition than in cases of elective treatment. Certainly, in terms of resource<br />

<strong>all</strong>ocation, there is no question that therapy ought to have much higher priority than<br />

enhancement. Yet while it is neither possible nor desirable for society to ban enhancement<br />

outright, it is perfectly legitimate for the government to raise higher regulatory hurdles and steer<br />

resources away from practices aimed at enhancement rather than therapy.<br />

3.2 Translating Principles into Rules<br />

These general principles, then, need to be translated into specific rules that would be used to<br />

guide regulators. These rules would be divided into two categories: (1) activities that we believe<br />

ought to be banned outright, and (2) activities that should be permitted but regulated. Neither list<br />

is meant to be definitive; they reflect our interpretation of how the principles outlined above<br />

should be interpreted in light of technological possibilities that either exist now or can be<br />

anticipated based on current trends. Some of our choices – for example, whether research<br />

cloning ought to be banned or regulated – will be extremely controversial. It should be noted,<br />

however, that the same regulatory institution can preside over different sets of rules. For<br />

example, the new Assisted Human Reproduction Agency of Canada bans research cloning, while<br />

the British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority permits it. In most other respects,<br />

these agencies look very similar. (Indeed, the Canadian agency was modeled after the HFEA.)<br />

3.3 Activities to Be Prohibited<br />

We believe that there are several activities made possible by biotechnology that ought to be<br />

prohibited outright, with prohibitions enforced through criminal sanctions. The role of a<br />

regulatory body would be twofold – to enforce the prohibitions, with some scope for interpreting<br />

their meaning, and to promulgate regulations in accordance with the ethical guidelines<br />

established by Congress. We believe that prohibited activities should include the following:<br />

• Reproductive cloning<br />

• Human-animal chimera and hybrid creation<br />

• Germ-line genetic modifications<br />

• New reproductive possibilities that alter the biological relationship of parents and<br />

children<br />

• Commercialization of certain aspects of human reproduction<br />

Reproductive cloning. As indicated in chapter 8.3, a large majority of Americans do not<br />

favor reproductive cloning; <strong>all</strong> versions of the cloning legislation that have been introduced in<br />

Congress since 2001 have included bans on reproductive cloning. The reasons that Americans<br />

67


give for opposing this practice vary; some cite safety reasons while others believe that the<br />

possibility is inherently wrong or distasteful. As the National Bioethics Advisory Committee and<br />

the President’s Council on Bioethics have both stated in their reports on cloning, human<br />

reproductive cloning is not today something that can be done safely, and for that reason alone<br />

should be banned on the basis of the principle that gives priority to the health and well-being of<br />

children.<br />

Creation of chimeras and hybrids. Following the recommendations of the President’s<br />

Council on Bioethics, we believe that the creation of human-animal hybrid embryos – the<br />

fertilization of a human egg with animal sperm or the use of human sperm to fertilize an animal<br />

egg – should be banned. Other situations in which human and animals cells, tissues, and organs<br />

simply are mixed are less problematic and should not be subject to an outright ban. These<br />

include the many forms of chimerism that are currently used in biomedical research, such as the<br />

implanting of human stem cells in animal tissues. Animal-derived organs are now routinely<br />

implanted in humans, and in the future, animal-derived genes may be available for treating<br />

human diseases; in our view, <strong>all</strong> of these are by and large legitimate activities. There may be<br />

complex cases where the degree of mixing of human and animal may become ethic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

problematic; we believe that determining this boundary is something that can be left to the<br />

regulatory authority, at least initi<strong>all</strong>y.<br />

Germ-line genetic modifications. Germ-line modifications of human beings, of the sort<br />

that is now done routinely with plants and animals, cannot now be done safely and should<br />

therefore be banned. Germ-line modifications would necessarily involve a kind of<br />

experimentation on human beings who clearly will not be able to give their informed consent,<br />

and therefore it violates the first and fourth ethical principles laid out above.<br />

There is considerable debate over how far in the future human germ-line engineering lies.<br />

While many until recently have derided this possibility as a fantasy, it appears that stem cell<br />

research may provide a fast and safe route to germ-line genetic modifications. 5 If and when<br />

human germ-line genetic modifications become possible and predictably safe, it may be<br />

necessary to re-open the question of whether the technique should be banned or merely<br />

regulated. Some people believe that the technique itself poses ethical problems, because it<br />

involves changes not just to the genotype of the child in question, but to <strong>all</strong> of that child’s<br />

subsequent descendants. If a safe and effective means of correcting heritable genetic disorders<br />

through germ-line modification becomes available, conceivably germ-line genetic modifications<br />

could be moved from the prohibited to the regulated category. The undeniable benefits of this<br />

move notwithstanding we believe human germ-line genetic modifications should remained<br />

banned. In our view the risk that this technology would be abused far outweigh its medical<br />

benefits.<br />

5<br />

Susannah Baruch et al., "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues and Options for Policymakers,"<br />

(Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center, 2005).<br />

68


New reproductive possibilities that alter the biological relationship of parents and<br />

children. There are a number of technologies emerging that will make possible the creation of<br />

children who are not the offspring of one man and one woman, as every human child has been up<br />

to now in the history of our species. Laboratory research has suggested possibilities such as<br />

reproductive cloning; the creation of artificial oocytes from stem cells (which will, in theory,<br />

<strong>all</strong>ow males to produce eggs and females sperm); embryo fusing (which could lead to children<br />

with more than two biological parents); or the harvesting of fetal eggs (which would lead to an<br />

offspring whose mother had never been born). We believe that the first ethical principle<br />

enunciated above, placing priority on the well-being of children, gives <strong>all</strong> children a right to be<br />

born out of the union of a man and a woman, and that technologies that alter this fundamental<br />

relationship should be banned.<br />

Patenting of human embryos. We believe that property rights to human embryos should be<br />

banned. Property rights are usu<strong>all</strong>y granted to stimulate research and innovation; there will be<br />

plenty of other incentives to perform necessary embryo research in the absence of ownership<br />

rights in specific embryos.<br />

3.4 Activities to Be Regulated<br />

There are other activities that we believe are ethic<strong>all</strong>y legitimate but ought to be carried out<br />

under carefully controlled circumstances. These include: 6<br />

• Research cloning<br />

• Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

• Biomedical research involving early-stage embryos or blastocysts<br />

• Commercialization of elements of human reproduction<br />

Research cloning. We believe that research cloning should be permitted, but that it should<br />

be tightly regulated. We see why many people who are not troubled by the use of excess<br />

embryos in stem cell research may yet oppose the deliberate creation of cloned embryos for<br />

research purposes. We believe, however, that whatever extra instrumentalization this act may<br />

imply does not outweigh the gains potenti<strong>all</strong>y to be derived from this kind of research. It is,<br />

however, particularly important for the regulatory authority to monitor and control this kind of<br />

research very carefully – not just because of what we c<strong>all</strong> the intermediate moral status of<br />

embryos, but also because it is the only way to enforce a ban on reproductive cloning. That is, if<br />

a large industry dedicated to producing cloned embryos ever comes into being, it will be much<br />

more difficult to take one of those embryos and implant it into a woman’s uterus for the purpose<br />

of creating a child if the regulatory authority registers and tracks every such embryo.<br />

6<br />

Note that this list is not meant to be exhaustive. In chapter 4 we discuss many more instances of ethic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

problematic medical and scientific developments that may need to be regulated.<br />

69


We recognize that for some people, the fact that we have put research cloning in the<br />

“regulated” and not the “prohibited” category will simply cause them to stop reading further,<br />

because they feel that our project is simply endorsing the deliberate creation and destruction of<br />

nascent life. We would point out, however, that if we were to move this activity from the<br />

regulated to the prohibited category, we would in effect be transforming the British system into<br />

the Canadian one – a system that in virtu<strong>all</strong>y <strong>all</strong> other respects would look identical. Thus, if a<br />

societal consensus develops that believes research cloning to be clearly wrong, one would still<br />

want to create the kind of institution we are laying out here.<br />

Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis. PGD is a service performed by many fertility clinics.<br />

We believe that it is an important way for couples with heritable genetic disorders to ensure that<br />

those conditions are not passed down to their children. On the other hand, PGD involves certain<br />

kinds of risks and creates incentives (for example, for the production of large numbers of eggs<br />

and embryos) that could pose serious health problems for the women involved. Using PGD for<br />

non-therapeutic purposes raises a host of ethical issues, and should be strongly discouraged by<br />

the regulatory system.<br />

Biomedical research involving early-stage embryos or blastocysts. We believe that<br />

biomedical research on embryos or blastocysts is important and legitimate, but that it ought to be<br />

done under carefully controlled circumstances, given the intermediate moral status of embryos.<br />

This means that the regulatory authority should monitor and control the creation and transfer of<br />

<strong>all</strong> embryos used for these purposes, much as the British HFEA does currently. This kind of<br />

regulatory capacity will also be necessary in order to enforce any reproductive cloning ban.<br />

Commercialization of elements of human reproduction. We believe that the buying and<br />

selling of human embryos should be strictly regulated, again in keeping with their intermediate<br />

moral status. We believe that embryos can be used for research purposes, and that a limited<br />

market should be <strong>all</strong>owed to develop to facilitate their transfer (for example, excess embryos<br />

from IVF clinics), but that <strong>all</strong> such transfers should be carefully tracked by the regulatory<br />

authority. We also believe that the donation of embryos, eggs, and sperm for reproductive<br />

purposes should be regulated, and that the free and unrestricted trade of human gametes,<br />

including sperm, should be prohibited.<br />

3.5 Next Steps<br />

While some readers may disagree with us on our suggestions to prohibit or regulate a given<br />

medical procedure or a certain type of research, few would reject the twin notions that<br />

distinguishing between ethic<strong>all</strong>y acceptable and unacceptable practices of biomedicine should be<br />

done by legislative means, and that these distinctions should be informed by a set a coherent<br />

ethical principles. In this sense, which medical procedures or research protocols should be<br />

banned and which ones should be regulated is less important than establishing the principle that a<br />

new regulatory infrastructure backed by a statutory framework is needed and that this new<br />

statutory framework should be informed by a set of broadly acceptable ethical principles.<br />

70


Accordingly, our proposal for a new regulatory entity is largely immune with regard to changes<br />

in the medical procedures or research protocols to be banned or regulated. Ours, in other words is<br />

an argument for selectively strengthening the administrative state and not merely an examination<br />

of arguments for or against the medical procedure or the scientific experiment of the day, an<br />

argument that is laid out in the remainder of this report.<br />

71


3.6 Bibliography<br />

Baruch, Susannah, Audrey Huang, Daryl Pritchard, Andrea Kalfoglou, Gail Javitt, Rick<br />

Borchelt, Joan Scott, and Kathy Hudson. "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues<br />

and Options for Policymakers." Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center,<br />

2005.<br />

President’s Council on Bioethics. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness<br />

Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 2003.<br />

Spar, Debora L. The Baby Business: How Money, Science, and Politics Drive the Commerce of<br />

Conception. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 2006.<br />

Spriggs, M. "Lesbian Couple Create a Child Who Is Deaf Like Them." Journal of Medical<br />

Ethics 28 (2002): 283.<br />

73


4 New Frontiers of Reproductive Science and Medicine<br />

4.1 Areas of Inquiry<br />

In chapter 3, we introduced several ethical principles germane to any discussion of<br />

reproductive technologies and biomedical research. We have also provided a few illustrations of<br />

how these principles may inform political choices. In this chapter, we turn our attention to<br />

several recent developments in reproductive medicine and biomedical research and discuss some<br />

of the ethical concerns they may raise. We do so by characterizing each of these developments as<br />

an instance of a broader class of cases – in other words, by adopting a taxonomy of reproductive<br />

treatments and biomedical research. This approach represents a significant departure from the<br />

practice, common among policy-makers and legal scholars, to focus narrowly on just one or<br />

perhaps two specific applications of a medical or scientific development.<br />

There are obvious reasons for taking a broader approach to discussing controversial ethical<br />

dilemmas. When the Congress decided that aviation needed a separate administrative entity<br />

responsible for ensuring its safety, it did not charged the newly established FAA with regulating<br />

only the types of aircrafts existing at the time. The FAA was responsible for aviation safety in<br />

general, i.e., for the safety of <strong>all</strong> existing and future aircraft models. Similarly, the FDA is<br />

charged with ensuring the safety and efficacy of most current and future drugs, biologics, and<br />

medical devices, not just of those in existence at the time its enabling legislation was passed.<br />

Translated to our context, this means, for example, that we consider intracytoplasmic sperm<br />

injection (ICSI) an instance of a standard reproductive technique, while pre-implantation genetic<br />

diagnosis (PGD) is better described as a technology of reproductive customization. The former<br />

type of reproductive treatment raises mainly health and safety concerns. The latter is<br />

controversial for reasons other than just health and safety.<br />

Standard reproductive techniques and technologies of reproductive customizations are two<br />

of four distinct policy domains to be discussed in this chapter. The other two are innovative<br />

reproductive treatments and biomedical research involving human reproductive tissues. Taken<br />

together, these four policy domains define the scope of possible legislative and regulatory<br />

interventions to be discussed in this report. As for any other typology, there may be instances of<br />

reproductive treatments or biomedical research that cannot unambiguously be assigned to a<br />

specific category. Some would probably consider ICSI an instance of an innovative rather than a<br />

standard reproductive technique. Other examples could be found. These difficulties are intrinsic<br />

to any classificatory scheme, and must be dealt with on a case-by-case basis. It is also worth<br />

mentioning that ours is certainly not the only possible categorization. Other equ<strong>all</strong>y useful<br />

75


taxonomies are likely to exist. For example, in “Reproduction and Responsibility,” the<br />

President’s Council on Bioethics adopts a similar but by no means identical taxonomy. 1<br />

The commercialization of reproductive treatments would require a separate discussion. By<br />

this term, we mean both the commercial trade of human reproductive tissues and the various<br />

contractual arrangements made possible by the market for reproductive tissues. Many<br />

reproductive treatments, standard or otherwise, raise distinctive ethical and legal questions if the<br />

gametes involved stem from one or more third parties. Also to be included in this category is<br />

surrogacy, or the delegation of a pregnancy to a surrogate mother. While these questions are by<br />

no means trivial or negligible, in this report we will not discuss them in detail. The<br />

transformation of human procreation from an intimate act to a set of contractual obligations is a<br />

tendency that certainly does not leave us indifferent. At the same time, this trend is not new, and<br />

does not raise fundamental new ethical dilemmas. For this reason, in this report we focus mainly<br />

on new technological possibilities in the narrow sense of this term.<br />

Our classificatory scheme is designed to emphasize what we believe are distinctive<br />

attributes of various reproductive technologies and lines of biomedical research. By classifying a<br />

new reproductive technique as an instance of a familiar type of reproductive treatment, policymakers<br />

would have at their disposal several tried and tested ethical arguments. Reliance on<br />

ethical precedents would of course greatly simplify the task of identifying the most appropriate<br />

regulatory response. This is an important benefit, considering the often puzzling nature of new<br />

bioethical dilemmas. A quasi-judicial approach to the resolution of controversial ethical<br />

questions would also minimize the opportunities for interest groups to influence or distort the<br />

regulatory process. In the process, it would make judicial review a less attractive option. <strong>Final</strong>ly,<br />

a classificatory scheme would discipline regulators by encouraging the adoption of consistent<br />

policies, thus reducing the scope for arbitrary and capricious agency behavior. In sum, a<br />

taxonomy of reproductive treatments and biomedical research would increase both the<br />

consistency and fairness of the rule-making process. 2<br />

1<br />

2<br />

There are considerable similarities here between resolving classificatory ambiguity and the task faced by<br />

common law judges (and the Supreme Court, for that matter) in determining exactly which precedents are<br />

relevant to judicial case. We will return to this question in chapter 7.<br />

Ethicists may find the approach proposed here reminiscent of casuistry. Cf. Carson Strong, Ethics in<br />

Reproductive and Perinatal Medicine: A New Framework (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997).<br />

Social scientists could point out that classificatory schemes have been at the center of heated debates in the<br />

sociology of science for many years. See Barry Barnes, "On the Conventional Character of Knowledge and<br />

Cognition," in Science Observed. Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, ed. Karin Knorr-Cetina and<br />

Michael Mulkay (London: Sage Publications, 1983); Barry Barnes, David Bloor, and John Henry, Scientific<br />

Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1996); David Bloor,<br />

Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions (London: Routledge, 1997); Harry M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication<br />

and Induction in Scientific Practice (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992); Harry M. Collins and<br />

Trevor Pinch, The Golem. What Everyone Should Know About Science (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1993); Mary Douglas, Risk and Blame: Essays in Cultural Theory (London: Routledge, 1992).<br />

76


4.2 Standard Reproductive Techniques<br />

Standard reproductive treatments are the first type of reproductive treatment to be discussed<br />

in this chapter. These are treatments that have been in use for many years, are quite familiar to<br />

ART practitioners, and are part of the curriculum of any medical school. In addition, there is<br />

widespread agreement among ART practitioners on how to perform these procedures, at least<br />

with regard to their main steps. Standard reproductive procedures include IVF, gamete<br />

intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer (GIFT), zygote intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer (ZIFT), intrauterine insemination<br />

with washed sperm (IUI), and intravaginal culture (fertilization of oocytes in an air-free plastic<br />

capsule placed into the maternal vagina). 3 In this category, we also include well-established<br />

procedures such as embryo and sperm cryopreservation and micromanipulations such as ICSI.<br />

Strictly speaking, these are not reproductive treatments; they may be regarded as preliminary or<br />

ancillary procedures performed prior to an actual reproductive treatment. ICSI, for example, is<br />

not a reproductive procedure; it is often used to overcome male infertility, and may be performed<br />

as part of an IVF cycle.<br />

The constitutive attribute of standard reproductive procedures is their largely<br />

uncontroversial nature. The ethical concerns raised by these procedures are limited mostly to the<br />

health and safety risks for the mother and the child. 4 The child’s well-being and the health and<br />

safety of the woman undergoing ART treatments are two of the guiding ethical principles<br />

identified in chapter 3. It is not our intention to examine in great detail possible health and safety<br />

risks associated with standard reproductive techniques, but a few observations are in order.<br />

Thirty years after the first “test-tube” baby was born, it remains very difficult to reliably<br />

quantify the health and safety risks associated with ART procedures. In the United States, a<br />

robust system of health and safety monitoring for ART children does not exist. Implementation<br />

costs, lack of government funding, excessive professional fragmentation in the medical<br />

profession, and logistical difficulties <strong>all</strong> have contributed to exacerbating this problem. ART<br />

practitioners, for example, follow a pregnancy only for the first three months – they do not<br />

examine the newborn baby, nor do they conduct follow-up examinations. 5<br />

In addition, a<br />

meaningful comparison of children born through ART and natur<strong>all</strong>y conceived children requires<br />

a matched parental control group. In practice, this requirement can rarely be met, as couples<br />

seeking ART services by definition are not representative of the general population. This means<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "Survey of Assisted Reproductive Technology: Embryo Laboratory<br />

Procedures and Practices. Appendix G: Survey Summary Responses," (Atlanta, GA: 1999).<br />

Mostly, but not exclusively. Case in point is the wish of an Australian woman to become pregnant with the<br />

sperm of her deceased husband, a wish the Australian Supreme Court in 2005 granted her after an eight-year<br />

legal battle. Similar cases have been reported in the United States and Britain.<br />

Laura A. Schieve et al., "Assessment of Outcomes for Assisted Reproductive Technology: Overview of Issues<br />

and the U.S. Experience in Establishing a Surveillance System," in Current Practices and Controversies in<br />

Assisted Reproduction. <strong>Report</strong> of a Meeting On "Medical Ethical and Social Aspects of Assisted Reproduction" ,<br />

September 17-21 2001, ed. Effy Vayena, Patrick Rowe, and David P. Griffin (Geneva, Switzerland: World<br />

Health Organization, 2002), p.364-65.<br />

77


that an investigator may not be able to ascertain with a high degree of confidence whether an<br />

observed higher incidence of certain conditions among ART children is attributable to the ART<br />

treatment itself, or whether the cause lies with the parents.<br />

Partly motivated by the recommendations contained in “Reproduction and Responsibility,”<br />

and partly triggered by studies reporting a significantly higher percentage of birth defects in<br />

children born through IVF and ICSI, 6 the American Society for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM)<br />

announced in 2003 that it was convening a panel of experts to thoroughly review the available<br />

empirical evidence on the health and safety risks of ART treatments. The panel presented the<br />

study’s main findings at the 2004 Annual Meeting of the American Society of Human Genetics<br />

(ASHG). It identified more than 2,400 studies pertaining to the health and safety of ARTs,<br />

selected 169 studies for further scrutiny, and ignored more than 2,000 studies that did not meet<br />

the panel’s criteria for inclusion in the study. 7 Based on this evidence, the panel concluded that<br />

there is no reason for concern, with a notable exception – they found “suggestive but not<br />

conclusive evidence” that ART children may suffer from a higher incidence of two rare<br />

disorders, Angelman and Beckwith-Wiedemann syndromes.<br />

In theory at least, this review should have provided definitive answers to the question of<br />

whether ART treatments expose ART children to elevated health and safety risks. Unfortunately,<br />

definitive answers are not forthcoming. Although the study’s main conclusions have been<br />

reported widely by the news media, as of this writing the report has not been made available to<br />

the public, and it has not been published in a peer-reviewed journal. In addition, the experts<br />

selected by the Genetics and Public Policy Institute to conduct the study represent the ART<br />

industry itself; thus, the study in essence amounts to a self-evaluation. While this is not<br />

necessarily a reason to dismiss the report’s findings, the self-evaluatory nature of this report does<br />

cast some doubts on its credibility. In fairness, evaluative efforts often face a trade-off between<br />

recruiting the best experts in a given field of inquiry and ensuring independence and credibility.<br />

At the same time, the public release of this report certainly would have increased the credibility<br />

of the panel’s findings.<br />

As our report is focused on new reproductive technologies rather than on standard<br />

reproductive treatments, we won’t delve into health and safety issues in great detail.<br />

Conversations with reproductive endocrinologists have shown that the profession gener<strong>all</strong>y is<br />

dismissive of any concerns about the health and safety of assisted reproductive technologies.<br />

These same conversations also show that practitioners seem to be unaware of studies showing a<br />

statistical relationship between ART treatments and increased health risks. For this reason, we<br />

felt it important to include in this report several illustrations of elevated health and safety risks<br />

associated with ART treatments, which are included in Appendix C. (Appendix C focuses<br />

exclusively on IVF, which remains by far the most common standard ART treatment in the<br />

6<br />

7<br />

Michèle Hansen et al., "The Risk of Major Birth Defects after Intracytoplasmic Sperm Injection and in Vitro<br />

Fertilization," New England Journal of Medicine 346, no. 10 (2002).<br />

Tracy Hampton, "Panel Reviews Health Effects Data for Assisted Reproductive Technologies," Journal of the<br />

American Medical Association 292, no. 24 (2004).<br />

78


United States. According to a 2002 CDC survey of ART success rates, IVF accounts for more<br />

than 90 percent of <strong>all</strong> performed cycles involving fresh non-donor eggs.) 8<br />

IVF safety has received considerable attention in the clinical literature, though mostly<br />

abroad. Among the risks associated with IVF mentioned in the literature are birth defects, low<br />

birth weight, neurological disorders, ectopic pregnancies, craniosynostosis, Beckwith-<br />

Wiedemann syndrome, Angelman syndrome, and the cloacal-bladder exstrophy-epispadias<br />

complex. Some of these risks are minute, while others are quite large. In most cases, however, it<br />

should be remembered that these risks reflect statistical associations and not causal relationships.<br />

Before turning our attention to innovative reproductive treatments, a few words about what<br />

has become known as collaborative reproduction are in order. 9 Collaborative reproduction ranges<br />

from fairly prosaic procedures, such as sperm donation, to medical interventions, such as oocyte<br />

and embryo donation. In the United States, sperm donation is a well-established practice,<br />

facilitated by numerous sperm banks. (Interestingly, no one seems to know just how many, even<br />

though the FDA now requires sperm banks to be registered.) 10 From a public health perspective,<br />

this practice is by no means unproblematic. In the late 1990s, the need to prevent the spread of<br />

infectious diseases prompted the FDA to regulate the trade of human tissues, including sperm,<br />

oocyte, and embryo donation. 11<br />

Sperm donation does raise some important ethical questions that go beyond considerations<br />

of safety and efficacy. There remains considerable skepticism about the wisdom of tolerating a<br />

free market for sperm. Much more controversial and problematic from an ethical standpoint are<br />

oocyte and embryo donation. Collaborative reproduction involving oocytes is far less common<br />

than anonymous sperm donation, partly because retrieving oocytes is a costly and painful<br />

medical procedure, but also because oocytes are far more difficult to preserve, though as we<br />

show below, cryopreservation technologies are making progress. The use of third-party embryos<br />

remains very uncommon, in large measure because a full-fledged market for embryos seems to<br />

many to be a very problematic proposition. Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, only approximately two percent<br />

of cryopreserved embryos have been put up for adoption – less than number of embryos donated<br />

for research. 12<br />

In some extreme cases, four individuals may be involved in the reproductive process: the<br />

prospective legal parents and the oocyte and the sperm donor. A surrogate mother may also<br />

8<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

12<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National<br />

Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," (Atlanta, GA: National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and<br />

Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health, 2004).<br />

Helen M. Alvare, "The Case for Regulating Collaborative Reproduction: A Children's Rights Perspective,"<br />

Harvard Journal on Legislation 40 (2003); Kenneth Baum, "Golden Eggs: Towards the Rational Regulation of<br />

Oocyte Donation," Brigham Young University Law Review (2001).<br />

Note that “donation” in this context should not be interpreted liter<strong>all</strong>y. Sperm donation in the United States is a<br />

lucrative business and an industry, complete with its own trade association.<br />

The FDA has promulgated three main new rules: the “establishment registration and listing” rule, the “donor<br />

eligibility” rule, and the “good tissue practice” rule. See chapter 5.1.2 for details.<br />

William Saletan, Leave No Embryo Behind (June 3, 2005 [cited March 14, 2006]).<br />

79


ecome part of this complex transaction, raising the total number of individuals involved to five.<br />

These contractual arrangements raise numerous legal questions, for which few if any leg<strong>all</strong>y<br />

binding answers have been provided. For example, how should the rights and obligations of<br />

prospective parents vis-à-vis a surrogate mother be defined? Should the anonymity of the sperm<br />

and oocyte donors enjoy unqualified protection? What rules, if any, should apply to embryo<br />

adoption? As this brief discussion demonstrates, collaborative reproduction may raise a host of<br />

difficult ethical questions. These are not new questions for the most part, and they are issues that<br />

have been debated frequently by bioethicists and legal scholars, though as is often the case, there<br />

has been very little consensus. In this report, we discuss these questions only tangenti<strong>all</strong>y, mainly<br />

in the chapter 7.<br />

4.3 Innovative Reproductive Treatments<br />

The term “innovative reproductive treatment” identifies any procedure performed by a<br />

reproductive endocrinologist designed to induce a pregnancy. While the aim of standard and<br />

innovative reproductive treatments remains the same – namely, achieving a pregnancy –<br />

innovative reproductive treatments differ significantly from the standard reproductive procedures<br />

discussed in the preceding section: The nature and the magnitude of the health and safety risks<br />

involved differ significantly. When performing an innovative reproductive treatment, an ART<br />

practitioner is very unlikely to know the precise nature of the risks to the mother and the baby.<br />

To the extent that the nature of the risks involved is familiar, very little is known about statistical<br />

probabilities. This is in marked contrast to standard reproductive procedures, where the nature of<br />

the risks involved is usu<strong>all</strong>y well-known and the magnitude of the risks is also familiar, though<br />

not always with a high degree of accuracy. This situation reflects a simple fact: While standard<br />

reproductive procedures have been the subject of numerous epidemiological studies, innovative<br />

reproductive treatments, by their nature, are performed largely without the benefit of clinical<br />

information.<br />

The innovative reproductive treatments discussed below raise more than just health and<br />

safety concerns. These concerns range from the <strong>all</strong>egation that ART practitioners, for <strong>all</strong> intents<br />

and purposes, are experimenting on human subjects, unconstrained by the usual regulatory<br />

checks, to the view that children should not have more than two genetic parents, or that children<br />

should not be created from unborn mothers. Whatever the nature of the specific ethical concern<br />

raised in each case, innovative reproductive treatments can easily be distinguished from standard<br />

reproductive procedures precisely because they are very likely to raise significant ethical<br />

concerns.<br />

Unlike standard reproductive procedures, innovative reproductive treatments tend to be<br />

poorly documented and often are not familiar to ART practitioners. This is not entirely<br />

surprising, as these treatments gener<strong>all</strong>y are attempted only when the usual standard techniques<br />

have been tried and have failed. The controversial nature of innovative reproductive treatments<br />

may also induce some ART practitioners to avoid publicity. When information about a novel<br />

80


treatment surfaces, it is usu<strong>all</strong>y an indication that the treatment has been performed with some<br />

success, as has been the case for ooplasm transfer. 13<br />

The cases discussed below were gleaned from the news media or obtained from targeted<br />

bibliographic searches. Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, despite our best efforts, we have not been able to<br />

obtain first-hand information about these treatments from industry representatives. The following<br />

discussion is intended to provide a sense of what constitutes an innovative reproductive<br />

procedure, and what ethical concerns these procedures might raise. How policy-makers should<br />

respond to these ch<strong>all</strong>enges is the topic of chapter 11.<br />

4.3.1 Tinkering with Biological Parenthood<br />

Over the last few years, several reproductive technologies have been developed to address<br />

specific forms of infertility or to prevent passing on genetic diseases. These novel treatments<br />

have two attributes in common: The children so conceived have three genetic parents, and the<br />

treatments produce inheritable genetic modifications, though they are not instances of human<br />

genetic engineering in the narrow sense of this term. 14<br />

These treatments include ooplasm<br />

transfer, a technique developed in the early 1990s, and various forms of reproduction by nuclear<br />

transfer. (The term “reproduction by nuclear transfer” is ours. Surprisingly, these techniques<br />

have not been associated with a specific medical term – another indication perhaps of their<br />

experimental nature.)<br />

Reproductive specialists developed ooplasm transfer in an effort to remedy a form of<br />

infertility attributable to shortcomings in the cytoplasm of the egg. In this procedure, the egg is<br />

fertilized as in any other IVF cycle, but before it is transferred back to the uterus, its cytoplasm is<br />

replaced with the cytoplasm of a younger, healthy egg. According to news stories, the technique<br />

has been quite successful. 15 Worldwide, at least 30 women have become pregnant through<br />

ooplasm transfer. However, in July of 2001, the FDA effectively banned this procedure by<br />

declaring ooplasm transfer as a “clinical investigation.” Conducting a clinical investigation<br />

requires the submission of an investigational new drug (IND) application, a requirement that has<br />

since discouraged ART practitioners from performing this experimental medical procedure. 16<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

16<br />

Jason A. Barritt et al., "Mitochondria in Human Offspring Derived from Ooplasmic Transplantation," Human<br />

Reproduction 16, no. 3 (2001).<br />

Erik Parens and Eric Juengst, "Inadvertently Crossing the Germ Line," Science 292, no. 5516 (2001).<br />

Leila Abboud, "FDA Seeks Rigorous Review of New Fertility Treatment," W<strong>all</strong> Street Journal, October 7, 2002;<br />

Gina Kolata, "Babies Born in Experiment Have Genes from Three People," New York Times, May 5, 2001;<br />

Helen Pearson, Egg Injection Boosts Fertility – New Mitochondria May Pep up Ageing Eggs, without Creating<br />

'Three-Parent' Babies (news@nature.com, October 20, 2004 [cited April 26, 2006]); available from<br />

http://www.nature.com/news/2004/041018/full/041018-10.html; Treatment for Infertile Women Yields Babies<br />

with Three Sets of Genes (Kaiser Family Foundation, May 7, 2001 [cited August 2, 2005]); available from<br />

http://report.kff.org/archive/repro/2001/5/kr010507.11.htm.<br />

See the letter to sponsors and researchers, available at http://www.fda.gov/cber/ltr/cytotrans070601.htm. How<br />

the FDA managed to prohibit ooplasm transfer provides an illustration of the limits imposed by the current<br />

statutory framework on this agency. The FDA does not have jurisdiction over surgical and medical procedures,<br />

and it is therefore not entirely clear whether its authority extends to the field of reproductive medicine in general,<br />

81


These concerns are not unfounded, as two embryos created by this technique but later aborted<br />

had Turner Syndrome. 17<br />

The same FDA requirements apply to a form of nuclear transfer developed at a New York<br />

City hospital in the early 1990s. In this case, cytoplasm is not merely replaced. Researchers<br />

fertilize not one but two eggs, one from the prospective mother, and one from an anonymous<br />

donor. The nucleus from the donated egg is then removed and replaced with the nucleus from the<br />

prospective mother’s egg. In an effort to circumvent FDA regulations, a leading U.S. scientist in<br />

2001 decided to outsource the procedure to colleagues in China. The Chinese researchers<br />

transferred two embryos. The procedure was successful, but the fetuses died at weeks 24 and 29,<br />

respectively, due to complications apparently unrelated to the technique used in the experiment. 18<br />

Had a child been born with this technique, he or she would have had genetic material not from<br />

two, but from three individuals – his or her genetic parents as well from the egg donor. This is so<br />

because the cytoplasm of the donor egg (or any other cell) contains mitochondrial DNA. 19<br />

Slightly different concerns are raised by a very similar procedure recently proposed by<br />

British scientists. 20 In this case, only one embryo is created, from the gametes of the two<br />

prospective parents. To avoid health risks associated with the egg’s mitochondria, the nucleus is<br />

removed and inserted in a healthy egg from an anonymous donor. Unlike the preceding<br />

procedure, this technique is meant to benefit both the parents and the child, who otherwise might<br />

have been born with degenerative genetic diseases. 21 These children would also carry genetic<br />

material from three persons.<br />

All of these procedures raise ethical concerns above and beyond health and safety<br />

considerations. A reproductive procedure that creates babies carrying DNA from three<br />

individuals – and therefore with three genetic parents – is problematic enough to preclude its<br />

wide adoption based exclusively on effectiveness. Scientists have pointed out that the amount of<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

20<br />

21<br />

and to ooplasm transfer in particular. Be that as it may, until ART professionals successfully ch<strong>all</strong>enge the FDA<br />

in court, for <strong>all</strong> intents and purposes, ooplasm transfer cannot be performed in the United States.<br />

Ooplasm Transfer as Method to Treat Female Infertility (FDA’s Biological Response Modifiers Advisory<br />

Committee Meeting, May 9, 2002 [cited August 2, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.fda.gov/OHRMS/DOCKETS/ac/02/briefing/3855B1_01.pdf<br />

Shaoni Bhattacharya and Sylvia Pagàn Westphal, Controversial Three-Parent Pregnancy Revealed (New<br />

Scientist, October 14, 2003 [cited August 2, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.newscientist.com/article.ns?id=dn4266 ; David Derbyshire, Foetuses Had Three Genetic Parents<br />

(Telegraph Group, October 13, 2003 [cited August 2, 2005]); Denise Grady, "Where Anti-Clone Collides with<br />

Pro-Baby," International Herald Tribune, October 15, 2003; Steve Kirschner, "The Ooplasm Transfer Debate,"<br />

Genomics and Proteomics, November 1, 2002; Rick Weiss, "U.S.-Banned Fertility Method Tried in China:<br />

Woman Became Pregnant through Egg Transfer Technique but Lost All Three Fetuses," Washington Post,<br />

October 14, 2003.<br />

Mitochondria can be described as a cell’s energy source.<br />

James Randerson, Scientists Seek to Create 'Three-Parent' Babies (New Scientist, October 19, 2004, 2004 [cited<br />

August 2, 2005]); available from http://www.newscientist.com/article.ns?id=dn6547; Ian Sample, "Can a Baby<br />

Have Two Mothers?," The Guardian, October 21, 2004.<br />

For an extensive discussion of ooplasm transfer for therapeutic uses, see John A. Robertson, "Oocyte Cytoplasm<br />

Transfer and the Ethics of Germ-Line Intervention," Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 26 (1998).<br />

82


inherited foreign DNA is minuscule, and it is therefore a gross exaggeration to claim that a child<br />

has three genetic parents. In our view, the fact that these children receive only approximately 35<br />

genes from a third party is largely irrelevant. What is disturbing is that these reproductive<br />

treatments undermine a fundamental biological principle – namely that every human being has a<br />

biological mother and father. At stake in this case is not only the health of these children, but<br />

also their well-being and the impact that having three genetic parents may have on their<br />

psychological development and on the development of their identities.<br />

Whether the implications of departing from this principle are serious enough to justify a ban<br />

remains to be seen. What is clear is that this question should not be settled by ART practitioners<br />

and patients, nor should it be decided simply in instrumental terms or portrayed as a purely<br />

private choice removed from public scrutiny. 22 Its resolution entails making a choice among<br />

competing goods, a choice that should be made at the legislative or more likely at the regulatory<br />

level, and not delegated to a profession and its clients. The fact that the U.S. scientist who<br />

developed one of these techniques decided to circumvent FDA regulations by conducting the<br />

experiment in China only underscores the need for a broader involvement of governmental<br />

authorities.<br />

4.3.2 Oocyte Cryopreservation (Freezing of Human Eggs)<br />

For a variety of reasons, including the large size of eggs, freezing human oocytes is<br />

considerably more difficult than cryopreserving sperm or embryos. According to ART<br />

practitioners, only approximately 100 women to date have become pregnant using a thawed egg.<br />

The procedure is univers<strong>all</strong>y considered experimental. Its success rate compared to standard<br />

reproductive techniques is low, approximately 15 percent, though researchers are hard at work to<br />

improve it. 23 The main rationale for developing this technology is therapeutic: Freezing eggs<br />

could help certain patients, especi<strong>all</strong>y young women, preserve their fertility despite devastating<br />

conditions or treatments with damaging side effects such as radiation therapy. 24<br />

Because of the experimental nature of oocyte cryopreservation, the procedure’s health and<br />

safety risks to women and their offspring are largely unknown. What makes oocyte<br />

22<br />

23<br />

24<br />

This approach usu<strong>all</strong>y translates into an excessive preoccupation for informed consent, to the detriment of any<br />

other considerations. See for example Andrea Bonnicksen, "Innovative ARTs and Informed Consent,"<br />

(Gaithersburg, MD: FDA’s Biological Response Modifiers Advisory Committee Meeting, 2002).<br />

Sarah Boseley, "Frozen Egg Baby Hailed as Fertility Milestone," The Guardian, October 11, 2002; First Frozen<br />

Egg Babies to Be Born in May (Xinhuanet (Xinhua News Agency), March 30, 2004 [cited August 2, 2005]);<br />

available from http://news.xinhuanet.com/english/2004-03/30/content_1391270.htm; Christina Ianzito, "Putting<br />

Your Eggs in a Different Basket," The Washington Post, September 21, 2004; Jeremy Laurance, "Italian Births<br />

Raise Hopes for Egg-Freezing Treatment," The Independent, September 15, 2004; Linda Marsa, "Frozen Eggs<br />

Yield Promising Results," Los Angeles Times, September 20, 2004; Helen Pearson, "Infertility Specialists<br />

Counsel Caution over Frozen Eggs – Reproduction Techniques Not Ready for Prime Time," Nature 431, no.<br />

7011 (2004); Shari Roan, "Fertility in Reserve," Los Angeles Times, February 2, 2003; S<strong>all</strong>y Wadyka, "For<br />

Women Worried About Fertility, Egg Bank Is a New Option," New York Times, September 21, 2004.<br />

On the state of this technology, see Brandon Bankowski et al., "The Social Implications of Embryo<br />

Cryopreservation," Fertility and Sterility 84, no. 4 (2005), p.829-30.<br />

83


cryopreservation a good example of an innovative reproductive procedure, however, is its<br />

unclear but potenti<strong>all</strong>y far-reaching societal impact. Oocyte cryopreservation is beginning to<br />

transform itself from a purely therapeutic procedure to an elective one. ART practitioners, while<br />

cautioning that this technology is still very much under development, are already considering the<br />

possibility that egg freezing could also be an attractive solution for professional women trying to<br />

reconcile career goals and the desire for a family. Not surprisingly, some entrepreneurs have<br />

already caught on and started offering egg cryopreservation as a commercial service. 25<br />

It is easy to anticipate at least a few of the consequences that the broad availability of this<br />

reproductive option might have on society. 26 Over time, egg cryopreservation may lead to a<br />

reduction in the number of frozen embryos. While many would welcome this development, its<br />

impact may not be unambiguously positive. For example, the availability of cryopreserved<br />

embryos for research is likely to diminish. The exact number of cryopreserved embryos currently<br />

donated for research is unknown, but it is likely very few. Further reducing this limited pool of<br />

available embryos might undermine the delicate political compromise negotiated in many<br />

industrialized countries on stem cell research, and may also induce scientists to advocate a much<br />

more liberal (and much more controversial) policy for deriving new stem cell lines.<br />

Egg cryopreservation would also stimulate the emergence of a whole new and very lucrative<br />

industry devoted to the retrieval, storage, and sale of human oocytes. This is certainly not a<br />

development that many would welcome. The free trade of oocytes could expose women –<br />

especi<strong>all</strong>y young, poor, or uneducated women – to significant risks. But perhaps the most<br />

troubling and the least discussed consequence of making oocyte cryopreservation widely<br />

available is precisely what is currently being touted as one of its main benefits – the woman’s<br />

ability to choose the precise time of procreation. 27 What to well-educated and ambitious women<br />

understandably appears to be a very attractive option could have several less desirable<br />

consequences. For example, the average parental age would likely increase, perhaps dramatic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

so. Whether having older parents would be detrimental to a child’s development is unclear, and<br />

we are not suggesting that is necessarily so, but it is certainly a question worth pondering.<br />

Delayed reproduction may also turn into less reproduction or no reproduction at <strong>all</strong>. A<br />

successful professional career may dissuade many women from considering motherhood at a<br />

later age. Some may argue that if this development makes it easier for women to pursue a<br />

professional career, it should be a reason for celebration, not a possible cause for concern. Others<br />

may disagree. Also worth pondering is whether oocyte cryopreservation might further weaken<br />

25<br />

26<br />

27<br />

For example, on its Web site, the Fertility Institutes in California aggressively promotes their “frozen donor egg<br />

bank.” See http://www.fertility-docs.com/egg_freezing_right.phtml.<br />

For a fuller discussion, see Baum, "Golden Eggs: Towards the Rational Regulation of Oocyte Donation";<br />

Margaret Jane Radin, "Market-Inalienability," Harvard Law Review 100 (1987).<br />

Not everyone agrees. See John A. Robertson, "Technology and Motherhood: Legal and Ethical Issues in Human<br />

Egg Donation," Case Western Reserve Law Review 39 (1989).<br />

84


the institution of the family, as increased individual autonomy may make it more difficult for<br />

prospective parents to reach a consensus on when to have a baby. 28<br />

That egg cryopreservation is rapidly becoming a matter of public concern is demonstrated<br />

by the interest that the American Society for Reproductive Medicine has taken in this issue. In a<br />

recently published report titled “Ovarian Tissue and Oocyte Cryopreservation,” the ASRM<br />

discusses whether egg freezing should serve exclusively therapeutic purposes, or whether it<br />

should also be recommended as a means to defer procreation. The report concludes that oocyte<br />

cryopreservation should be offered exclusively for therapeutic reasons, 29 based exclusively on<br />

health and safety considerations. The ASRM does not explore the potential broader societal<br />

implications of widespread adoption of this technology – in our view, one more reason to<br />

broaden the debate on new reproductive technologies.<br />

4.3.3 Co-Culture<br />

The FDA considers co-culture an instance of xenotransplantation. 30 In co-culture, human<br />

embryos come into contact with animal cells outside the human body. In FDA terminology, the<br />

recipient of an embryo cultivated on non-human tissues is therefore the recipient of a<br />

xenotransplantation “product.” As a laboratory technique, co-culture is not new. According to<br />

news reports, fertility clinics started offering co-culture to select patients as early as 1989. The<br />

technique is actu<strong>all</strong>y older than that. It was developed in the 1960s and tested on mice and rats,<br />

but never on humans before it was offered as a reproductive service.<br />

Co-culture meets <strong>all</strong> the requirements of an innovative reproductive procedure. It only came<br />

to regulators’ attention in 2002, although it has been around for much longer. 31<br />

It is not<br />

commonly used and it is certainly not considered a standard reproductive procedure by the CDC<br />

or by ART professionals. To our knowledge, the long-term health and safety impact of this<br />

technology on children has never been studied. Clearly, co-culture is likely to meet with<br />

considerable resistance both on safety and ethical grounds.<br />

28<br />

29<br />

30<br />

31<br />

Some may argue that this argument is discriminatory, as men, for <strong>all</strong> intents and purposes, already have the<br />

ability to delay reproductive choices. However, this argument is not entirely convincing, as men’s ability to<br />

procreate well into old age is not the result of any medical progress.<br />

Practice Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine, "Ovarian Tissue and Oocyte<br />

Cryopreservation," Fertility and Sterility 82, no. 4 (2004).<br />

See http://www.fda.gov/cber/infosheets/humembclin.htm.<br />

Medical researchers have been experimenting with co-culture as a means to improve ART success rates for quite<br />

some time, but it appears that they have done so mostly on animal models. See H.L Feng et al., "Fertilization and<br />

Early Embryology: Effect of Different Co-Culture Systems in Early Human Embryo Development," Human<br />

Reproduction 11 (1996); F.S. Nietro et al., "The Effects of Cocolture with Autologous Cryopreserved<br />

Endometrial Cells on Human in Vitro Fertilization and Early Embryo Morphology: A Randomized Study,"<br />

Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 13 (1996); J. Thibodeaux and R. Godke, "In Vitro Enhancement<br />

of Early Stage Embryos with Coculture," Archives of Pathology and Laboratory Medicine 116 (1992); K.E.<br />

Wiemer et al., "Embryonic Morphology and Rate of Implantation of Human Embryos Following Coculture on<br />

Bovine Oviductal Epethelial Cells," Human Reproduction 8 (1993).<br />

85


A 2003 news story published in Popular Science magazine describes in some detail the<br />

motivation for performing this procedure, and the procedure itself. 32 The technique is used to<br />

cure particularly difficult cases of infertility. In this case, the wife’s reproductive organs were<br />

severely dysfunctional, and her immune system had rejected her husband’s sperm. In addition,<br />

the husband’s sperm count was very low and of poor quality. After traditional reproductive<br />

treatments failed to result in pregnancy, the couple was persuaded to try co-culture. The<br />

woman’s eggs were retrieved, fertilized in vitro, and grown for several days on tissue obtained<br />

from a cow uterus. The embryos were then transferred back into the woman’s uterus. The<br />

technique was quite successful. The couple now has three children, <strong>all</strong> of them conceived<br />

through co-culture.<br />

The story provides an excellent illustration of both parental desperation and of the risky<br />

choices parents and their doctors are willing to make. According to the news story the couple is<br />

not apologetic for trying a largely untested technique. Asked whether he was concerned about<br />

possible long-term effects on his children the father replied:<br />

Is there a possibility of long-term effects? Yeah, there is. And that worries us. But even if we’d<br />

found the kids would be at higher risk, we would have still done it <strong>all</strong>. 33<br />

As this quote illustrates, there seems to be some justification to the view that parents do not<br />

necessarily or always have the best interest of their offspring at heart. More gener<strong>all</strong>y, our<br />

discussion of co-culture suggests that innovative reproductive treatments should not be<br />

performed on a routine basis until safety and ethical concerns have not properly been addressed.<br />

To this end, it is necessary to broaden the debate about the future of reproductive technologies<br />

beyond the narrow circle of ART practitioners and patient groups.<br />

4.3.4 Other Experiments<br />

That some reproductive endocrinologists and scientists are willing to push the ethical<br />

envelope is illustrated by the following two instances of (failed) innovative reproductive<br />

treatments. In the first case, a group of Israeli scientists demonstrated that oocytes retrieved from<br />

aborted fetuses can be fertilized and may be viable. In the second case, a U.S. researcher created<br />

a chimeric human embryo by adding cells from a male embryo to a female human embryo.<br />

Oocytes grown from aborted fetuses – to our knowledge – have not actu<strong>all</strong>y been used in a<br />

clinical setting. Had the fertilized eggs in the aforementioned case been transferred to a woman’s<br />

uterus, a child might have been conceived by an unborn mother – a very problematic proposition<br />

at best, and an utterly unacceptable procedure at worst. As for other innovative treatments, there<br />

is a perfectly plausible, if purely instrumental, reason for developing this procedure. The Israeli<br />

scientists argued that aborted fetuses are a precious source of human tissue, and that retrieving<br />

oocytes from these fetuses would circumvent many of the ethical problems norm<strong>all</strong>y associated<br />

with the retrieval of human oocytes from adult females. That this argument is incomplete goes<br />

32<br />

33<br />

Rebecca Skloot, "S<strong>all</strong>y Has 2 Mommies and 1 Daddy," Popular Science, March 1, 2003.<br />

Ibid.<br />

86


almost without saying. Children born through this procedure could suffer severe psychological<br />

harm, as a crucial aspect of their personal identity – a biological mother – would be missing.<br />

Interestingly, the scientists in question were not prepared to re-examine the rationale for<br />

conducting this line of research despite the outcry that the experiment generated among their<br />

peers. 34 They simply acknowledged the strong negative reactions their experiment produced,<br />

noting that “probably, in some places, it will be ethic<strong>all</strong>y acceptable.” 35<br />

Another case of an innovative reproductive treatment that met with considerable resistance<br />

from the ART community was the announcement by a U.S. researcher that he had added cells<br />

from a male embryo to a female embryo, thus creating a chimeric human embryo. 36 The creation<br />

of chimeras is nothing new in biology, but this appeared to be the first documented case of a<br />

researcher actu<strong>all</strong>y creating and growing, albeit for only a few days, a human chimera.<br />

The justification offered by the researcher for creating the chimeric human embryo was<br />

rather nebulous. The experiment was designed to test an innovative therapy to cure severe<br />

combined immunodeficiency (SCID), also known as “bubble boy disease.” By adding healthy<br />

embryo cells to a diseased embryo, the resulting baby is likely to acquire healthy cells that might<br />

be able to fight the disease. This, at least, was the hope expressed by the researcher in this case.<br />

The scientist decided to add male embryo cells to a female embryo because male embryo cells<br />

are easier to track. The researcher was hoping that the male embryo cells would distribute<br />

homogeneously over the female embryos, which apparently they did. In this narrow, sense the<br />

experiment was successful.<br />

The sharply negative reaction the announcement of this experiment produced is both a<br />

testimony to a shared sense of professional responsibility among the members of the ART<br />

community and a demonstration of the limits of professional self-regulation. Many of the<br />

researcher’s colleagues questioned the scientific rationale for conducting this experiment. They<br />

also emphasized the damage that the announcement of this experiment might cause to the<br />

reputation of the entire ART industry.<br />

Some may interpret these statements as an illustration of reputational incentives at work. 37<br />

In a narrow sense, this is true, but it would be misleading to draw broad lessons from this<br />

34<br />

35<br />

36<br />

37<br />

Shaoni Bhattacharya, Aborted Fetuses Could Become 'Unborn Mothers' (New Scientist, July 1, 2003 [cited<br />

August 2, 2005]); available from http://www.newscientist.com/news/news.jsp?id=ns99993889; Ian Sample,<br />

"Prospect of Babies from Unborn Mothers," The Guardian, July 1, 2003; Jeevan Vasagar, "Use of Foetal Eggs<br />

Grotesque, Say Campaigners," The Guardian, July 2, 2003.<br />

Bhattacharya, Aborted Fetuses Could Become 'Unborn Mothers' ([cited).<br />

Shaoni Bhattacharya, 'She-Male' Embryos Created in Lab (New Scientist, July 3, 2003 [cited April 26, 2006]);<br />

available from http://www.newscientist.com/news/news.jsp?id=ns99993905; Steve Connor, "Scientists Outraged<br />

over Fusion of Male and Female Embryos Condemn Attempt to Combine Male and Female Cells," The<br />

Independent, July 3, 2003; Emma Ross, "European Group Denounces Chimera Embryo," Associated Press, July<br />

2, 2003; Ian Sample, "Scientists Hit out at Creator of 'She-Males'," The Guardian, July 3, 2003.<br />

See, for example, David Charny, "Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships," Harvard Law Review 104<br />

(1990); Ronald J. Mann, "Verification Institutions in Financial Transactons," Georgetown Law Journal 87<br />

(1999); Eric A. Posner, "The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal Sanctions on<br />

Collective Action," University of Chicago Law Review 63 (1996).<br />

87


episode. Reputational incentives are an effective sanctioning mechanism only when highly<br />

visible controversies erupt. As mentioned earlier, innovative reproductive treatments gener<strong>all</strong>y<br />

are conducted discreetly; the news media, regulators, and the public learn about these<br />

experiments only sporadic<strong>all</strong>y, and sometimes not at <strong>all</strong>. In this sense, the role of reputational<br />

incentives as an effective sanctioning mechanism must be regarded as quite limited.<br />

4.4 Reproductive Customization Technologies<br />

While the reproductive technologies discussed so far were initi<strong>all</strong>y developed exclusively<br />

for therapeutic reasons, in this section we turn to ART treatments that are not designed to treat a<br />

physiological condition, though they do have some specific medical applications. The primary<br />

use of these reproductive technologies is simply the accommodation of parental wishes of one<br />

kind or another. In this sense, these are reproductive customization technologies rather than<br />

reproductive treatments, in the narrow sense of this term. They are intended to provide<br />

prospective parents with the means to exercise control over the reproductive process rather than<br />

simply to help them conceive.<br />

With this type of technology, we enter into one of the most controversial areas of<br />

reproductive medicine. Unlike innovative reproductive treatments – where the technical means<br />

may be controversial but the goal served (procreation) remains the same – in the present case we<br />

are dealing with technologies that are beginning to redefine the very meaning and nature of<br />

procreation. They do so not in a dramatic or spectacular way, to be sure. Some uses of these<br />

technologies, considered in isolation, could even be described as prosaic. From a pragmatic<br />

perspective, it is difficult to quarrel with a mother who, after having three boys, wishes to have a<br />

girl. But, as is so often the case in the field of artificial reproduction, things are not quite so<br />

simple. Many people feel uncomfortable with suggestions that conception could be customized,<br />

though they may not be able to articulate the precise reasons for their discomfort. Others, fearing<br />

the degradation of human reproduction to a commercial transaction, will find any technology of<br />

customization altogether unacceptable. Still others take the opposite stance, advocating freedom<br />

of choice in matters considered purely private. 38<br />

An obvious example of the non-therapeutic use of a reproductive technology is elective sex<br />

selection. Currently, two options exist to choose the sex of a child – pre-implantation genetic<br />

diagnosis and MicroSort ® . While MicroSort is still being tested, PGD is already available.<br />

Reliable data is hard to come by, but according to industry insiders, PGD is rapidly gaining<br />

popularity as a sex-selection technology. Another example of a reproductive technology’s nontherapeutic<br />

use is genetic engineering, i.e., germ-line genetic modification. Human genetic<br />

engineering, just a few years ago derided by many scientists as en entirely speculative and utterly<br />

irrelevant scenario, is becoming a reality much more rapidly than was initi<strong>all</strong>y anticipated, as a<br />

38<br />

In this regard, some of the ethical principles introduced in chapter 3 – such as privileging therapeutic over<br />

enhancing uses of reproductive technologies and protecting the health and well-being of children, but also<br />

promoting access to reproductive technologies – may be able to structure these controversies.<br />

88


ecent review of the scientific literature conducted by the Johns Hopkins University Genetics and<br />

Public Policy Center indicates. 39<br />

The notion of reproductive customization raises the question of whether it is actu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

possible to accurately distinguish between therapeutic and enhancing uses of reproductive<br />

technologies. Professional bioethicists have often criticized this distinction has being<br />

conceptu<strong>all</strong>y weak and incapable of resolving most ethical dilemmas. Technic<strong>all</strong>y, these<br />

criticisms may be correct, but it would be utterly misleading to conclude that ambiguous<br />

conceptual categories should play no role in public debates and in policy-making. Were <strong>all</strong><br />

categorical ambiguities to be banned from public discourse, it would no longer be possible to<br />

pass laws or craft policies. As the human growth hormone case discussed in chapter 2 has shown,<br />

even two seemingly straightforward categories like safety and efficacy are not free of<br />

ambiguities. This has not prevented the FDA from routinely using safety and efficacy as its main<br />

guiding principles in rule-making.<br />

Against this background, whether a general audience finds the distinction between<br />

therapeutic and enhancing applications of reproductive technologies useful is a question of some<br />

import. Two surveys, one conducted in the United States and the other in Germany, shed some<br />

light on this issue. The Genetics and Public Policy Center has conducted extensive research on<br />

public attitudes toward new reproductive and genetic technologies in the United States. In 2002,<br />

it surveyed the awareness of 1,211 Americans ages 18 and older about genetic technology. Of<br />

particular interest to our discussion is the following question:<br />

Would you approve or disapprove if parents were<br />

offered a way to use pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

to:<br />

(a) make sure their baby does NOT have a serious<br />

genetic disease?<br />

(b) make sure their baby would be a good match to<br />

donate his or her blood or tissue to a brother or sister<br />

who is sick and in need of a transplant?<br />

(c) make sure their baby does NOT have a tendency to<br />

develop a disease like cancer when he or she is an<br />

adult?<br />

Approve Disapprove Don’t Know Refused to<br />

Answer<br />

74 22 4 *<br />

69 25 5 1<br />

60 33 6 *<br />

(d) choose the sex of their child? 28 68 4 *<br />

39<br />

Germ-line genetic modification is possible in laboratory animals, and some techniques could be adapted for use<br />

in humans, although none have been tried. Scientists are able to replace a faulty gene with a “normal” copy in<br />

mouse embryonic stem cells, and then introduce those stem cells into an early mouse embryo, where they can<br />

give rise to genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified sperm or eggs. The next generation of mice that results from the modified<br />

sperm or eggs contains the “normal” copy of the gene. It is now possible to replace a gene in human embryonic<br />

stem cells, overcoming a huge obstacle to human germ-line genetic modification. In addition, scientists have<br />

been able to derive genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified sperm directly from mouse stem cells. Together, these developments<br />

suggest that human germ-line genetic modification may not be as far off as we thought even five years ago. Cf.<br />

Baruch et al., "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues and Options for Policymakers," p.5.<br />

89


Would you approve or disapprove if parents were<br />

offered a way to use pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

to:<br />

(e) make sure their baby has desirable characteristics,<br />

such as high intelligence and strength?<br />

Approve Disapprove Don’t Know Refused to<br />

Answer<br />

22 72 5 *<br />

Table 1: Attitudes toward various uses of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis. 40<br />

As this table demonstrates, U.S. respondents seem to make a clear distinction between<br />

therapeutic uses of PGD (questions a, b, and c) and reproductive customization (questions d and<br />

e). A two-thirds to three-quarter majority supports therapeutic uses, while a very similar<br />

proportion rejects customization. Similar results emerged from a survey recently conducted in<br />

Germany. The detailed results have not yet been published, but a summary is available. 41<br />

Researchers interviewed 416 former East Germans and 1,694 former West Germans ages 18 to<br />

50 in late 2003. Of <strong>all</strong> respondents, 76 percent favored legalizing therapeutic uses of PGD, such<br />

as screening for genetic diseases, a procedure that is banned in Germany. Only 20 percent of<br />

respondents favored maintaining a strict ban on any use of PGD. It is noteworthy that the<br />

proportion of respondents supporting legalizing therapeutic uses of PGD is very similar to the<br />

proportion of U.S. respondents who favor the use of PGD for the same therapeutic purposes. In<br />

sum, its conceptual ambiguities notwithstanding, the distinction between therapeutic and<br />

enhancing uses of PGD (and of genetic engineering more broadly) provides a useful framework<br />

for structuring public debates on the acceptable uses of this technology.<br />

In the next two sections, we discuss some of the ethical concerns that technologies of<br />

customization could raise. The technologies in question are MicroSort, a technique specific<strong>all</strong>y<br />

designed to select the sex of a child, and pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for non-therapeutic<br />

reasons.<br />

4.4.1 Technologies of Sex-Selection: MicroSort<br />

MicroSort is a technology designed to select the sex of embryos. Male and female embryos<br />

come in slightly different sizes, a difference that MicroSort depends on to separate them.<br />

According to the technology’s developer, the Genetics & IVF Institute located in Fairfax,<br />

Virginia, MicroSort has a success rate of 91 percent for female and 76 percent for male<br />

embryos. 42 The Genetics & IVF Institute is currently in the process of conducting an FDAapproved<br />

clinical trial. When the FDA will approve MicroSort is unclear.<br />

40<br />

41<br />

42<br />

Genetics and Public Policy Center, "Public Awareness and Attitudes About Genetic Technology," (Washington,<br />

D.C.: Johns Hopkins University, 2002), p.7.<br />

Ada Borkenhagen et al., "Was Denken Die Deutsche Bevölkerung Und Kinderwunschpaare Über Die PID? Eine<br />

Vergleichende Studie," (Fertility Center Berlin, DRK-Clinics Westend, Leipzig University, Department of<br />

Medical Psychology and Medical Sociology, 2004).<br />

See http://www.microsort.com/. See also Joseph G. Schenker, "Gender Selection: Cultural and Religious<br />

Perspectives," Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002), p.403.<br />

90


Aware of the controversial nature of this technology, the institute currently offers its<br />

services only for the purpose of “family balance.” This term identifies families that, after having<br />

several children of one sex, desire to have a baby of the opposite sex. According to the institute,<br />

the demand for sex-selection services is very strong and is by no means limited to families<br />

seeking “balance.” This suggests that the market for this technology is much larger than the<br />

demand for family balance indicates, though it is unclear just how large this market might be. It<br />

is certainly large enough to make investors in the Genetics & IVF Institute very rich. For this<br />

reason, it is very unlikely that the institute will continue offering its services exclusively for the<br />

purpose of family balance once it receives FDA approval for this sex-selection technology. The<br />

FDA, for its part, has no authority to limit the use of MicroSort if it has deemed the technology<br />

both safe and effective.<br />

Should anyone be concerned about the widespread use of sex-selection technologies such as<br />

MicroSort? Providing a definitive answer to this question is surprisingly difficult. Some<br />

commentators have pointed out that in countries where sex-selection technologies (of any kind)<br />

have been available for some time, male and female birth ratios have experienced dramatic<br />

distortions. In Korea, Taiwan, China, and India, for example, patriarchal values and perverse<br />

economic incentives have produced strong familial preferences for boys; female infanticide has<br />

often been the result. In more recent times, the increasing availability of medical technologies<br />

such as ultrasound imaging and amniocentesis has produced an astounding number of selective<br />

abortions, shifting birth ratios from a normal 102-103 boys to 100 girls to 120 boys for 100 girls<br />

and higher. The consequences are predictable – pervasive scarcity of females and an associated<br />

increase in social unrest and crime attributable to a growing population of young, unattached<br />

males. 43<br />

One may argue that Western industrialized countries are very unlikely to face this problem.<br />

The empirical evidence in this regard is mixed. A handful of European surveys have consistently<br />

shown that the sex of the first-born child is largely a matter of indifference. In Germany, only 14<br />

percent of respondents have a clear preference for a boy, 10 percent for a girl, and 76 percent of<br />

respondents claims to be indifferent. 44 Similar results were obtained in the United Kingdom,<br />

where 12 percent of respondents would prefer a boy as their first-born child, and 19 percent a<br />

girl, the rest being indifferent. 45 On the other end, a survey of 17 European countries found a<br />

43<br />

44<br />

45<br />

M. Ansari-Lari and M. Saadat, "Changing Sex Ratios in Iran 1976-2000," Journal of Epidemiology and<br />

Community Health 56 (2002); Cecilia L. W. Chan et al., "Gender Selection in China: Its Meanings and<br />

Implications," Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002); Elizabeth Hervey Stephen,<br />

"Demographic Implications of Reproductive Technologies," Population Research and Policy Review 19, no. 4<br />

(2000).<br />

E. Dahl et al., "Preconception Sex Selection for Non-Medical Reasons: A Representative Survey from<br />

Germany," Human Reproduction 18, no. 10 (2003).<br />

H. Statham et al., "Choice of Baby's Sex," Lancet 341, no. 8844 (1993).<br />

91


strong preference for a mixed family, 46 suggesting that there may indeed be a significant demand<br />

for sex-selection services, at least for the purpose of “family balancing.”<br />

Policy preferences seem consistent with general attitudes. A recently released consultative<br />

report on sex selection prepared by the British HFEA shows that 82 percent disagreed with the<br />

statement “The use of sperm sorting should be permitted in sex selection for non-medical<br />

reasons.” 47<br />

Even sex selection for the purpose of “family balancing” did not gather much<br />

sympathy – 82 percent again rejected this option. 48 Similar results were obtained by a much more<br />

rigorous survey conducted in Germany, 49 where 92 percent of respondents were not interested in<br />

using sperm-sorting technology to select the sex of a child. Postulating that the sex-selection<br />

process could be carried out in a much more straightforward way did not change this pattern. 50<br />

The data for the United States is somewhat more ambiguous. A study conducted in the early<br />

1990s, along with a 2002 survey, suggests that the preference for a male first child in the United<br />

States is much higher than in Europe, ranging between 58 percent for men and 40 percent for<br />

women. 51 The 2002 study puts the proportion of respondents that would be willing to use sexselection<br />

technologies, if available, at 21 percent. Of this 21 percent, men would overwhelmingly<br />

prefer a boy (75 percent), whereas women had only a slight preference for boys (56 percent).<br />

These results were obtained from a non-random sample of undergraduate students, and should<br />

not be taken at face value. A much more rigorous and recent study produced somewhat different<br />

results. 52 A representative sample of 1,197 individuals ages 18 to 45 was asked five questions<br />

designed to elicit possible preference for a sex and interest in using a sex-selection technology.<br />

As with prior studies, participants in this survey expressed a fairly strong preference for a male<br />

first born (39 percent), 19 percent would prefer a girl and 42 percent were indifferent. The actual<br />

interest in using sex-selection technologies, however, is modest. Only 8 percent of respondents,<br />

given its estimated cost, would consider using a sex-selection technology. This figure increases<br />

to 18 percent if the sex of a child could be chosen simply by medication, whereas 59 percent<br />

were still uninterested. A somewhat similar pattern emerges from a large, comparative survey of<br />

practitioners and the general population on the acceptability of potenti<strong>all</strong>y controversial<br />

46<br />

47<br />

48<br />

49<br />

50<br />

51<br />

52<br />

Karsten Hank and Hans-Peter Kohler, "Gender Preferences for Children in Europe: Empirical Results from 17<br />

FFS Countries," Demographic Research 2, no. 1 (2000).<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), "HFEA Annual <strong>Report</strong> 2003/04," (London: 2004),<br />

p.24.<br />

Ibid.<br />

Dahl et al., "Preconception Sex Selection for Non-Medical Reasons: A Representative Survey from Germany."<br />

“Suppose there was a medication enabling parents to choose the sex of their children. Couples simply had to<br />

ingest a blue pill to ensure the birth of a boy, or a pink pill to ensure the birth of a girl. Would you take<br />

advantage of such medication?”Ibid., p.2232.<br />

Roberta Steinbacher and Faith Gilroy, "Sex Selection Technology: A Prediction of Its Use and Effect," Journal<br />

of Psychology 124, no. 3 (1990); Doreen Swetkis, Faith Gilroy, and Roberta Steinbacher, "Firstborn Preference<br />

and Attitudes toward Using Sex Selection Technology," The Journal of Genetic Psychology 163, no. 2 (2002).<br />

Edgar Dahl et al., "Preconception Sex Selection Demand and Preferences in the United States," Fertility and<br />

Sterility 85, no. 2 (2006).<br />

92


diagnostic technologies. This study found that there is strong opposition to elective sex selection<br />

in <strong>all</strong> countries, but less so in the United States. 53<br />

What should we make of this data? There is no strong empirical evidence to suggest that at<br />

the present time, the broad availability of sex-selection technologies such as MicroSort would<br />

induce prospective parents to systematic<strong>all</strong>y choose one sex over the other. At the same time,<br />

this finding does not render superfluous a broad public debate about the use and abuse of sexselection<br />

technologies. Some commentators, though not necessarily worried about skewed sex<br />

ratios, are concerned about the impact that the broad availability of this technology might have<br />

on our very understanding of procreation, reducing it to an act of design – an expression of<br />

parental whims. Still others fear that sex selection may fuel sexual discrimination. 54 These are <strong>all</strong><br />

legitimate concerns that should be examined in some detail before moving forward with this<br />

technology on a grand scale.<br />

4.4.2 Pre-Implantation Genetic Diagnosis for Therapeutic Uses<br />

To date, pre-implantation genetic diagnosis is the one reproductive procedure that comes<br />

closest to the ideal of a technology of reproductive customization. First tested in 1989, PGD<br />

consists essenti<strong>all</strong>y of removing one cell from a blastocyst at the eight-cell stage. The cell so<br />

removed <strong>all</strong>ows the ART practitioner to conduct a variety of genetic tests. Embryos can be<br />

screened for genetic diseases, for the predisposition to a genetic disease, and for sex-linked<br />

diseases. They can also be selected for specific physiological attributes such as blood type. In<br />

principle at least, PGD could also be used to screen embryos for any physiological attribute or<br />

higher trait, provided science could identify the genetic foundations of these attributes. 55 Even<br />

under the best of circumstances, however, PGD is a very cumbersome technology of<br />

customization, and a passive one: It only <strong>all</strong>ows the screening of existing embryos, but not the<br />

creation of embryos with specific physiological attributes. In this sense, PGD is a far cry from<br />

true genetic engineering.<br />

Much has been said and written about PGD, and we will not rehash that discussion here<br />

other than to note that the ethical import of genetic screening is not determined simply by its<br />

limited ability to serve as a tool of procreative customization. The practice of genetic screening is<br />

53<br />

54<br />

55<br />

Dorothy C. Wertz et al., "Has Patient Autonomy Gone Too Far? Geneticists' Views in 36 Nations," The<br />

American Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 4 (2002).<br />

Lisa Belkin, "Getting the Girl," New York Times Magazine, July 25, 1999; Ethics Committee of the American<br />

Society for Reproductive Medicine, "Preconception Gender Selection for Nonmedical Reasons," Fertility and<br />

Sterility 75 (2001); Charles Hanson, Lars Hamberger, and Per Olof Janson, "Is Any Form of Gender Selection<br />

Ethical?," Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002); John A. Robertson, "Preconception<br />

Gender Selection," American Journal of Bioethics 1, no. 1 (2001); E. Scott Sills and Gianpiero D. Palermo,<br />

"Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Elective Sex Selection, the IVF Market Economy, and the Child –<br />

Another Long Day's Journey into Night?," Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002).<br />

For an overview, seeGenetics and Public Policy Center, "Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis. A Discussion of<br />

Ch<strong>all</strong>enges, Concerns, and Preliminary Policy Options Related to Genetic Testing of Human Embryos,"<br />

(Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center, 2003).<br />

93


controversial not because it provides an effective means to customize conception (which<br />

currently it does not), but rather for its potential ability to undermine widely shared cultural<br />

conceptions of equality and tolerance, those intangible values so often taken for granted but<br />

indispensable to any functioning democracy. 56<br />

A second instance of customized conception is the use of PGD for tissue matching.<br />

Typic<strong>all</strong>y, this procedure is attempted when parents with a child affected by an incurable disease<br />

are unable to find a compatible tissue donor. In these cases, ART specialists may resort to PGD<br />

to screen for specific physiological attributes. For example, doctors may try to strengthen the<br />

failing immune system of a child affected by Diamond Blackfan Anemia (DBA), a painful and<br />

incurable disease, by extracting stem cells from the umbilical cord of a baby selected to be a<br />

tissue match.<br />

What should we make of this practice? Are we facing a deplorable application of PGD, or<br />

are we simply using PGD for therapeutic purposes? Is the well-being of the children created<br />

solely to benefit an older sibling imperiled, or can we assume that they will be welcomed into the<br />

family? Do these manipulative medical procedures prepare us to more readily accept future<br />

reproductive techniques expressly designed to customize conception rather than to treat a<br />

medical condition? Medical professionals offer the following rationale for performing this<br />

procedure: Tissue matching is a straightforward case of a therapeutic use of PGD. A young child<br />

would die if the procedure were not performed. In addition, the older sibling is not saved at the<br />

expense of the younger one. The life of the younger child is not traded against the life of his or<br />

her afflicted older sibling. Furthermore, what reasons could possibly justify losing a child if he or<br />

she could indeed be saved?<br />

Pro-life groups offer a very different assessment. They point to the instrumental nature of<br />

this procedure, i.e., a child being conceived exclusively to benefit an older sibling. They also are<br />

disturbed by the need to create (and discard) numerous embryos before a suitable one is found.<br />

Advocates for the disabled, for their part, have vehemently criticized genetic screening and tissue<br />

matching, arguing that it amounts to a eugenic program against the disabled. According to these<br />

groups, PGD likely will foster a culture of perfection incompatible with liberal values of mutual<br />

tolerance and respect. The news media, for its part, has fueled these controversies by<br />

characterizing tissue matching as the creation of “designer babies.” 57 The term is obviously<br />

meant to provoke, but it is not entirely without justification.<br />

It is useful to examine how the British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority has<br />

addressed this dilemma. The British Parliament established the HFEA in 1990 when it passed the<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act. Among other things, the Parliament delegated to the<br />

HFEA responsibility for addressing the ethical controversies generated by new developments in<br />

56<br />

57<br />

Francis Fukuyama, Our Post-Human Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution (New York: Farrar,<br />

Straus and Giroux, 2002).<br />

Shaoni Bhattacharya, Banned 'Designer Baby' Is Born in UK (New Scientist, June 19, 2003 [cited April 26,<br />

2006]); available from http://www.newscientist.com/news/print.jsp?id=ns99993854; Colin Blackstock,<br />

"Matched and Hatched, Britain's First 'Designer Baby' Born to Save Brother," The Guardian, June 19, 2003.<br />

94


eproductive medicine (See chapter 6.4 for a more detailed discussion of the act and the agency).<br />

Whether the use of PGD for tissue matching should be <strong>all</strong>owed, and if so under what<br />

circumstances, is exactly the kind of controversy the HFEA was designed to settle.<br />

Until recently, it was HFEA policy to authorize PGD only when the procedure would also<br />

benefit the future baby, for example, by preventing the birth of a child with an inheritable<br />

disease. Thus, the HFEA favored a view of PGD that emphasized therapeutic applications, but<br />

only in a very narrow sense. Not every therapeutic use of PGD is designed to benefit the childto-be,<br />

and under HFEA policy, certain applications were prohibited. For instance, Diamond<br />

Blackfan Anemia is not an inheritable condition, so performing PGD to produce a tissue match<br />

for a child affected by DBA would benefit the older sibling but not the future baby. Consistent<br />

with its policy, the HFEA turned down demands to authorize the use of PGD to save children<br />

affected by DBA. 58<br />

By contrast, the HFEA approved performing PGD to cure cases of<br />

Thalassemia. Unlike DBA, Thalassemia is an inheritable disease. In this case, PGD benefits the<br />

child-to-be as well as the older child.<br />

Not surprisingly, parents whose PGD applications were turned down ch<strong>all</strong>enged the HFEA<br />

policy in court. In July of 2004, following a string of judicial decisions, the HFEA changed its<br />

policy regarding tissue matching to <strong>all</strong>ow this procedure to be performed even when no<br />

inheritable disease is involved. 59<br />

One may or may not agree with HFEA policies, but there is one important benefit from<br />

resolving this and similar controversies through the regulatory and judicial system rather than<br />

through private choices. One provision of the British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act<br />

of 1990 requires the HFEA to explicitly include in its consideration the well-being of children.<br />

While the parents of children affected by Diamond Blackfan Anemia understandably disagreed<br />

sharply with the earlier HFEA policy on PGD, the policy was clearly informed by the HFEA<br />

obligation to balance parental interests and the well-being of future children. As we have shown<br />

in this chapter, private choices tend to privilege parental interest, to the detriment of ART<br />

children. In this sense, a regulatory approach to deciding what at first may appear as purely<br />

private choices is preferable to delegating these choices to parents and the medical profession.<br />

4.5 Biomedical Research Involving Reproductive Tissues<br />

The fourth and last policy area to be examined in this chapter is research involving<br />

reproductive tissues. By reproductive tissues we mean oocytes, sperm, and embryos, either<br />

human or animal. The lines of research discussed in this section can be grouped into two distinct<br />

categories. On the one end, we find research aimed at exploring issues pertaining specific<strong>all</strong>y to<br />

human reproduction and infertility. This kind of research may loosely be referred to as ART<br />

58<br />

According to news reports, parents whose applications were turned down by the HFEA were able to get the<br />

treatment in the United States.<br />

59<br />

"High Court Ban on 'Designer Babies' Overturned," The Guardian, April 8, 2003; 'Saviour Sibling' Perfect<br />

Genetic Match for Brother (BioNews, 320, August 8, 2005 [cited April 26, 2006]).<br />

95


esearch. On the other end are situated research protocols that involve the use and manipulation<br />

of human reproductive tissues but focus on medical research more broadly. Stem cell research<br />

provides an illustration; it depends on the availability of human embryos but is largely unrelated<br />

to questions pertaining to the study of infertility, though advances may come about as an<br />

unanticipated benefit.<br />

This ambiguity cannot easily be eliminated. Both areas of research touch upon the beginning<br />

of human life, and both types of research make use of human reproductive tissues. In addition,<br />

there is a considerable amount of organizational and institutional overlapping; many scientists<br />

involved in one kind of research are also involved in the other. Both kinds of research often are<br />

conducted at the same research organization. And, as we show below, experimentation in these<br />

two areas of research raise significant ethical concerns. For <strong>all</strong> these reasons, we decided not to<br />

distinguish explicitly between medical research involving the use of reproductive tissues and<br />

ART research proper.<br />

Research protocols in this area raise a fairly unique set of ethical questions. By its nature,<br />

research on reproductive tissues is very unlikely to have an immediate impact on children and/or<br />

their parents. It is also not very likely to affect the practice of medicine, at least in the short term,<br />

nor does it undermine important societal values. In this sense, the immediate, short-term risks<br />

associated with these research activities are relatively modest. The destruction of human<br />

embryos for research purposes of course remains a very contentious and problematic proposition.<br />

It is certainly an important (if not the most important) ethical concern raised by biomedical<br />

research involving reproductive tissues. On the other hand, excessive attention to research<br />

involving human embryos tends to ignore other important research developments. These research<br />

protocols are problematic not because of immediate ethical concerns, but for difficult ethical<br />

dilemmas they are likely to produce in the not-too-distant future.<br />

Before discussing actual cases of problematic scientific protocols, we need to respond to an<br />

important criticism. Science advocates insist that regulatory interventions should be explored<br />

only in the presence of immediate and clear harm. In this view, harmful effects that have yet to<br />

manifest themselves do not justify government interventions. 60 The concept of the slippery slope,<br />

a metaphorical term used to identify a technological trajectory associated with undesirable<br />

societal consequences, has been described by these critics simply as a rhetorical device invoked<br />

by technology skeptics unable to muster specific reasons for opposing a scientific or<br />

technological development.<br />

We submit that this argument is itself the manifestation of an unreconstructed faith in<br />

another kind of slope – the virtuous slope. If we apply the critics’ reasoning to a potenti<strong>all</strong>y<br />

beneficial line of research, we may say that as long as the research has not produced any useful<br />

results, there is simply no reason to assume that these results will materialize. Therefore, there is<br />

no prima facie reason to shield research activities from governmental interventions. Rejecting<br />

60<br />

John A. Robertson, "Two Models of Human Cloning," Hofstra Law Review 27 (1999); Eugene Volokh, "The<br />

Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope," Harvard Law Review 116 (2003).<br />

96


this argument implies that there is a causal connection between today’s research protocols and<br />

tomorrow’s cures, i.e., a virtuous slope that connects the current research to future beneficial<br />

outcomes, or at least a very strong presumption that today’s research will produce tomorrow’s<br />

cures. But if a virtuous slope exists, why should we assume that a slippery one does not?<br />

Technological optimism denies the relevance of the slippery slope – the view that a technology<br />

could move in a detrimental direction in a fairly predictable way – but does so by assuming that<br />

science and technology indeed move in a predictably beneficial fashion, developing along a<br />

virtuous slope. To put it in cruder terms, it is simply incoherent to argue that science and<br />

technology are riding a virtuous trajectory and therefore should be protected from governmental<br />

intervention, but to deny that science and technology could actu<strong>all</strong>y find themselves on a<br />

trajectory to societal harm. Why should harm presumptively be proved if benefits cannot<br />

presumptively be demonstrated?<br />

We are not suggesting that the slippery slope concept necessarily implies early and<br />

aggressive regulatory interventions. What it does suggest is that scientific research should be<br />

monitored much more systematic<strong>all</strong>y. We shouldn’t regulate research lightly, but we don’t want<br />

to be surprised by problematic and perhaps irreversible scientific developments. A system of<br />

monitoring serves not only as an early warning system – it may also help identify unanticipated<br />

interactions among seemingly independent lines of research. Considered in isolation, many of the<br />

experiments discussed in this section may not raise significant concerns. Their significance<br />

changes dramatic<strong>all</strong>y if examined in the context of other scientific experiments. 61<br />

A few<br />

experiments on mice demonstrating that it is possible to derive sperm cell precursors from stem<br />

cells may not mean much. If we learn that it is also possible to derive oocytes from stem cells,<br />

and that it has been demonstrated that sperm cells can be genetic<strong>all</strong>y manipulated, the original<br />

research results begin to appear in an entirely new light.<br />

Much of the information used in the remainder of this section was gleaned from science<br />

magazines and news reports and through extensive online research. Efforts to obtain first-hand<br />

information about these experiments have produced very modest results – another indication,<br />

perhaps, of the need to more closely monitor research involving reproductive tissues.<br />

4.5.1 Cloning Technologies<br />

Cloning (or somatic cell nuclear transfer, as some leading scientists would like the rest of<br />

the world to c<strong>all</strong> this process) 62 provides a good illustration of a procedure that is of considerable<br />

import both to assisted reproduction and to medical research: Whether one contemplates<br />

reproductive or research cloning, the actual process is identical. In essence, it consists of<br />

removing the genetic material (the nucleus) from a donated oocyte and replacing it with the<br />

61<br />

62<br />

Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, unanticipated interactions among the components of a technical system are one key attribute<br />

of technological complexity. Cf. Charles Perrow, Normal Accidents: Living with High Risk Technologies (New<br />

York: Basic Books, 1984). See also Nathan Rosenberg, "Why Technology Forecasts Often Fail," The Futurist<br />

July 1 (1995).<br />

Bert Vogelstein, Bruce Alberts, and Kenneth Shine, "Please Don't C<strong>all</strong> It Cloning," Science 295 (2002).<br />

97


nucleus of a somatic cell, such as a skin cell. To trigger the process of cell division, the<br />

“unfertilized embryo” is exposed to a short burst of electricity. 63 If successful, somatic cell<br />

nuclear transfer produces an individual that is an almost perfect genetic replica of the somatic<br />

cell donor – almost perfect because the clone will share with the egg donor the genetic material<br />

contained in her mitochondria, genes that are obviously not present in the somatic cell of the<br />

individual that has been cloned.<br />

Reproductive and research cloning raise distinct ethical questions. Reproductive cloning in<br />

particular has received considerable attention. 64 Many arguments have been put forward both in<br />

favor of and against what some have described as a reproductive procedure, and what others<br />

have more accurately but unsuccessfully characterized as human replication. 65 These questions<br />

have been extensively debated, and we see no reason to contribute to that debate here, other than<br />

to point out that it is very unlikely that the general public will ever consider this procedure an<br />

acceptable procreative option, even if it can be performed safely. 66<br />

With regard to research cloning, the situation is more interesting. In the last few years, the<br />

rationale offered by scientists for conducting somatic cell nuclear transfer in humans has<br />

changed significantly. Initi<strong>all</strong>y, the scientific community described this procedure as an<br />

indispensable prerequisite for creating organs compatible the recipient’s immune system. But<br />

critics have pointed out that scientists are many years away from being able to precisely control<br />

the development of stem cells, a situation that apparently has been the source of considerable<br />

frustration among developmental biologists.<br />

Public skepticism has induced the scientific community to adopt a different rationale for<br />

research cloning – that it is an important technique that would <strong>all</strong>ow scientists to develop a much<br />

better understanding of the development of genetic diseases that cannot otherwise be studied. An<br />

example is Parkinson’s disease, a degenerative condition of the brain that obviously cannot be<br />

studied in adult subjects. The emphasis thus has shifted from applied to fundamental medical<br />

research.<br />

Other scientists are not ready to abandon the initial vision of growing replacement organs<br />

just yet. It has been shown that if human embryonic germ cells are derived from five-, six-,<br />

seven-, and 11-week-old primordial germ cells (i.e., germ cells of a fetus several weeks old),<br />

they can be injected or grafted onto a diseased organ, where they continue their development. 67<br />

Other experiments have demonstrated that cloning makes it possible to produce specialized<br />

63<br />

64<br />

65<br />

66<br />

67<br />

Strictly speaking, the term “unfertilized embryo” is meaningless. Unfortunately, a proper technical term for this<br />

biological construction does not exist.<br />

See, for example, Glenn McGee, ed., The Human Cloning Debate (Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Hills Books, 2002);<br />

President’s Council on Bioethics, "Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry," (Washington,<br />

D.C.: 2002).<br />

George J. Annas, "Human Cloning: A Choice or an Echo?," Dayton Law Review 23 (1998).<br />

In this regard, see also the survey data in chapter 8.<br />

Michael J. Shamblott et al., "Human Embryonic Germ Cell Derivates Express a Broad Range of<br />

Development<strong>all</strong>y Distinct Markers and Proliferate Extensively in Vitro," Proceedings of the National Academy<br />

of Sciences 98, no. 1 (2001).<br />

98


cellular tissue compatible with the somatic cell donor. For these techniques to work effectively,<br />

however, it is necessary to grow a cloned embryo well beyond the customary 10 to 14 days. In<br />

addition, these embryos, for now at least, must be grown in vivo (in other words, in a mother’s<br />

uterus) and subsequently aborted; embryos grown in vitro, for reasons not entirely understood,<br />

have not shown the same effectiveness. 68<br />

These experiments have been conducted on animal models. Exactly how long cloned<br />

human embryos would have to be grown in vivo is not clear. What is clear is that the derivation<br />

of suitable cellular tissue would require aborting a developing human embryo at a fairly<br />

advanced stage, or perhaps even a fetus, to “culture” an embryo well beyond the customary 10 to<br />

14 days. What is interesting about this case is that no one re<strong>all</strong>y can say with a high degree of<br />

confidence that these experiments have not already been replicated in humans. Also telling is the<br />

fact that while public debates about new biomedical research in the last several years have<br />

focused almost exclusively on stem cells derived from early-stage embryos, several research<br />

groups were already experimenting with stem cells derived from animal embryos several weeks<br />

or even a few months old. 69<br />

What should we make of these developments? As a perceptive reporter has noted, these<br />

experiments may ch<strong>all</strong>enge the notion that stem cell lines should only be derived from 10- to 14–<br />

day-old embryos. Why stop at 14 days? What are the specific reasons for this constraint? It<br />

appears that the justification for the 14-day rule is pretty thin – thin enough, in any case, to<br />

convince many that it may be worthwhile exploring the possibility of extending the cutoff date<br />

for experimenting on human embryos to three weeks or a month. We are certainly not advocating<br />

this measure. What this story suggests is that the concept of a slippery slope is not simply a<br />

rhetorical device invoked by opponents to stymie scientific and medical progress. It is a concern<br />

expressed even by leading scientists, as the following statement made at a 2003 meeting of the<br />

President’s Council on Bioethics implicitly illustrates:<br />

[…] I am concerned, I mean, as a biologist I'm concerned. I'm concerned about a number of issues.<br />

It makes it sound as if most of the time that scientists aren't concerned, that we're just going along<br />

in a fashion that, you know, science for science sake.<br />

And I only have to remind you over the last few months to see the use of human embryonic stem<br />

cells in mouse chimeras, the use of chimeric human embryos that has been done, that you say<br />

there's no reason that these things should have been done. I mean, there's no scientific basis for<br />

this.<br />

68<br />

69<br />

Benjamin Dekel et al., "Human and Porcine Early Kidney Precursors as a New Source for Transplantation,"<br />

Nature Medicine 9, no. 1 (2003); Robert Lanza et al., "Regeneration of the Infarcted Heart with Stem Cells<br />

Derived by Nuclear Transplantation," Circulation Research 94 (2004); Robert P. Lanza et al., "Generation of<br />

Histocompatible Tissues Using Nuclear Transplantation," Nature Biotechnology 20 (2002); Robert Lanza et al.,<br />

"Long-Term Bocine Hematopoietic Engraftment with Clone-Derived Stem Cells," Cloning and Stem Cells 7, no.<br />

2 (2005).<br />

A fuller account of this story can be found in William Saletan, The Organ Factory (Slate, July 25, 2005 [cited<br />

September 27, 2005]); available from http://slate.msn.com/id/2123269/entry/2123270/.<br />

99


And we have to have some degree – and I'm not going to c<strong>all</strong> it regulation, I don't like that term,<br />

obviously, but there has to be some consensus as to what should be permitted and shouldn't be<br />

permitted in almost a global way. 70<br />

As for other lines of medical research discussed in this chapter, there is no reason to<br />

entertain immediate radical regulatory interventions. The sense of unease that these experiments<br />

are likely to trigger in many readers is, however, a clear indication that potenti<strong>all</strong>y controversial<br />

medical research can only move forward if adequate legal safeguards are put in place and if<br />

Congress takes the necessary steps to ensure compliance. That we learned about these<br />

experiments serendipitously only underscores just how precarious our ability to identify and<br />

monitor momentous scientific developments is. There is a subtle but important difference<br />

between trust and blind trust. A much more systematic approach to monitoring scientific<br />

activities would go a long way toward restoring public confidence in the scientific enterprise.<br />

4.5.2 Making Sperm<br />

Over the last few years, science magazines and scientific journals have reported on several<br />

important experiments pertaining to the creation of human sperm. Like other research protocols<br />

discussed in this section, none of these experiments, taken in isolation, is of immediate relevance<br />

to clinicians, and they do not, therefore, raise immediate ethical concerns. All of them, however,<br />

are suggestive of momentous future clinical applications.<br />

The first two experiments involved growing sperm in mice. Already, in 2002, a research<br />

group had succeeded in grafting testicular tissue from goats and pigs under the skin of mice. 71<br />

The experiment showed that the immature testicular tissue does indeed develop into normal<br />

sperm. In the f<strong>all</strong> of 2004, researchers at Yale University conducted a similar experiment, this<br />

time using human testicular tissue. They were able to growth testicular tissue taken from adult<br />

humans with immature testes under the skin of mice. The tissue was still viable after 19 weeks,<br />

when it was retrieved for analysis. 72 According to the researchers, these experiments eventu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

should <strong>all</strong>ow development of a technique that could restore fertility in children undergoing<br />

chemotherapy. More gener<strong>all</strong>y, this line of research should lead to more effective cures for male<br />

infertility.<br />

Should anyone be concerned about this line of research? From a narrow, utilitarian point of<br />

view, these experiments, per se, do not seem to raise any serious ethical concerns. After <strong>all</strong>, their<br />

declared goal is purely therapeutic, and it would be difficult to argue that anyone would be<br />

harmed by the clinical applications of these techniques. At the same time, the claim that these<br />

experiments have no broader significance presumes that the technology in question will be used<br />

70<br />

71<br />

72<br />

John P. Gearhart, Rudolf Jaenisch, and David Prentice, Stem Cell Research: Recent Scientific and Clinical<br />

Developments (Session 3, President's Council on Bioethics Meeting, July 24-25, 2003 [cited September 16,<br />

2005]); available from http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/july03/session3.html.<br />

James Meek, "Mice May Provide Human Sperm Bank," The Guardian, August 15, 2002.<br />

James Randerson, "Human Testicular Tissue Grown in Mice," New Scientist, October 19, 2004.<br />

100


exclusively for the purpose it was developed for, an assumption obviously not supported by the<br />

history of science and medicine.<br />

A far more consequential research protocol involving the production of sperm was reported<br />

from Japan in 2003. 73 In this experiment, the Japanese researchers cultivated embryonic stem<br />

cells in a culture known to stimulate the growth of sperm. They then took these cells and<br />

implanted them in mice testes, where apparently they fully developed into sperm. The<br />

researchers retrieved the sperm and fertilized mice eggs, which began to divide.<br />

According to the Japanese researcher, the study should improve our understanding of<br />

embryonic development. The scientists were not secretive about what this generic statement may<br />

mean. Their goal, according to one news story, was to enhance our ability to engineer sperm –<br />

i.e., to produce artificial sperm based on specific genetic criteria. This could become possible<br />

because, as the researchers pointed out, scientists already know how to insert genes into stem<br />

cells.<br />

Engineering sperm? Perhaps the Japanese scientist was simply naïve; or perhaps he<br />

sincerely believed that engineering sperm is a research proposition as legitimate and<br />

unproblematic as any other. Whatever the case may be, the view that human sperm could in the<br />

not-too-distant future be genetic<strong>all</strong>y engineered to meet specific parental desires is qualitatively<br />

different from the kind of rationales offered by scientists involved in potenti<strong>all</strong>y controversial<br />

medical research. Whether there may be reasons good enough to justify engineering sperm<br />

remains to be seen, but this question certainly cannot be decided by the scientific community<br />

alone. 74<br />

A more advanced version of the Japanese experiment was conducted by Harvard University<br />

scientists in 2003. 75 In this case, the scientists were able to grow sperm cell precursors entirely in<br />

a lab dish; implantation in testes was not necessary. They then injected these sperm-like cells<br />

into a mouse egg cell. In some cases, the fertilized egg developed into an early-stage embryo, or<br />

blastocyst. The scientists then tried to impregnate a mouse, without success. The Harvard group<br />

is now replicating these results in human embryonic stem cells. The researchers were careful to<br />

emphasize the scientific nature of their experiment and explicitly downplayed the possibility of<br />

developing cures for male infertility. In essence, this method for producing sperm cell precursors<br />

<strong>all</strong>ows scientists to study imprinting, the process that regulates which genes are turned on or off<br />

during embryo development, depending on whether they are inherited from the mother or the<br />

73<br />

74<br />

75<br />

Stem Cells Stimulated to Be Sperm (Associated Press, September 15, 2003 [cited August 2, 2005]); available<br />

from http://www.wired.com/news/medtech/0,1286,60454,00.html; Rick Weiss, "Sperm Made from Stem Cells:<br />

Development in Mice Raises Issues for Human Reproduction," Washington Post, September 16, 2003.<br />

That this research was conducted at a privately funded university only underscores the need for public oversight.<br />

Josh Chamot and Leslie Fink, Researchers Engineer Mouse Embryonic Stem Cells to Form Sperm Cell<br />

Precursors (National Science Foundation, Office of Legislative and Public Affairs, December 10, 2003 [cited<br />

August 3, 2005]); available from http://www.nsf.gov/od/lpa/news/03/pr03142.htm; Sylvia Pagàn Westphal,<br />

"Stem Cells Can Become 'Normal Sperm'," New Scientist, May 7, 2003; Gretchen Vogel, "Embryonic Stem<br />

Cells: Scientists Make Sperm in a Dish," Science 302, no. 5652 (2003).<br />

101


father. The experiment could also lead to a better understanding of cancer development, and of<br />

the causes of birth defects and of male infertility.<br />

Another suggestive experiment was conducted in 2004 by a group of U.S. and Japanese<br />

scientists. The researchers managed to insert foreign DNA into the spermatogonia (or immature<br />

sperm cells) of zebra fish and to growth them to maturity. This was the first time that researchers<br />

had succeeded in culturing entirely in vitro spermatogonia of a species other than mice. The<br />

zebra fish is a popular animal model in developmental biology because it shares many of the<br />

same genes with humans, and because its embryos are transparent. 76 The researchers used the<br />

cultivated sperm to fertilize zebra fish eggs. Of 1,100 eggs exposed to the genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified<br />

sperm, 104 were fertilized and 89 grew into zebra fish. Of these, five carried the foreign gene.<br />

One possible clinical application of this research is gene therapy. If perfected in humans,<br />

this technique would enable scientists to genetic<strong>all</strong>y modify sperm, either by adding a specific<br />

gene or by removing a defective gene, so as to prevent passing on a genetic disease. Clinical<br />

applications, however, are many years away. A much more likely application of this technique is<br />

the efficient creation of transgenic animals. Current techniques to engineer transgenic animals<br />

are not very effective. Many animals so created display “mosaicism,” i.e., only a fairly sm<strong>all</strong><br />

fraction of the animal’s cells carries the foreign gene.<br />

The experiments described in this section raise several important ethical questions. Is<br />

research on human sperm simply another form of medical research, or is it necessary to<br />

scrutinize this line of research more carefully? Should bright lines be drawn only when this<br />

research comes to fruition? Should these research efforts succeed in producing viable human<br />

sperm from embryonic stem cells, what kind of constraints, if any, should society impose on the<br />

production of sperm from embryonic stem cells? For example, should it be permissible for ART<br />

practitioners to create embryos using sperm derived from stem cells? In other words, should it be<br />

possible for children to be born from unborn parents? We think not. The fact that many children<br />

have been born from anonymous sperm donors does not provide a rationale for creating children<br />

without biological parents or with ambiguous biological roots. Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, in recent<br />

times, the news media has reported on the concerted (and increasingly successful) efforts by<br />

teenagers born through anonymous sperm donations to track down their biological parents –<br />

another indication of the powerful role and the importance of biological origins on one’s sense of<br />

identity. 77 On the other end, would it be acceptable to offer young boys affected by leukemia a<br />

chance protect their reproductive chances? Certainly. A regulatory agency is in an excellent<br />

position to proscribe the former procedure and regulate the latter.<br />

76<br />

77<br />

Philip Cohen, "Test-Tube Sperm Get New Genes," New Scientist, January 26, 2004; Human GM Sperm Will Be<br />

Possible One Day, Researchers Indicate (Medical News Today, January 28, 2004 [cited August 3, 2005]); Tim<br />

Radford, "Scientists Modify Sperm to Add New Fish to the Gene Pool," The Guardian, January 27, 2004; Geoff<br />

Spencer, Transgenic Animals Produced Using Cultured Sperm: Study Opens New Possibilities for Biological<br />

Research, Gene Therapy (NIH News, National Institutes of Health, January 26, 2004 [cited August 3, 2005]);<br />

available from http://www.nih.gov/news/pr/jan2004/nhgri-26.htm.<br />

Amy Harmon, "Hello, I'm Your Sister. Our Father Is Donor 150," The New York Times, November 20, 2005;<br />

Rob Stein, "Found on the Web, with DNA: A Boy's Father," The Washington Post, November 13, 2005.<br />

102


4.5.3 Making Eggs<br />

After twenty years of research on mouse embryonic stem cells (ESCs), scientists have been<br />

able to coax these cells into just about any kind of cell. Since a group of researchers at the<br />

University of Pennsylvania announced in 2003 that they had succeeded in transforming mouse<br />

ESCs into eggs, it has now been demonstrated that mouse ESCs can indeed be converted into<br />

any kind of mouse cell – i.e., that they are totipotent. 78 Coaxing mouse stem cells into becoming<br />

oocytes did not require a sophisticated cocktail of growth factors, a fact prompting optimism in<br />

the scientific community about replicating these results in higher mammals, primates, and<br />

humans. The eggs were produced through a process similar to ovulation. The oocytes underwent<br />

meiosis, the process by which eggs and sperm give up half of their genetic material, and<br />

produced embryo-like structures through a process known as “parthenogenesis.” Interestingly,<br />

eggs were produced by both female and male ESCs.<br />

What is the scientific rationale for this experiment? According to the University of<br />

Pennsylvania scientists, the experiment could defuse many concerns surrounding research<br />

cloning. Somatic cell nuclear transfer is notoriously very inefficient and requires a large number<br />

of oocytes to succeed. Retrieving human oocytes in large numbers is an ethic<strong>all</strong>y questionable<br />

undertaking at best and an unacceptable proposition at worst. The researchers hope that<br />

dramatic<strong>all</strong>y increasing the availability of oocytes will change the terms of the debate about<br />

research cloning: If embryos could entirely be produced in vitro, many opponents of research<br />

cloning might find this line of research far less objectionable. A large supply of artificial eggs<br />

would also prevent a market for natural oocytes from emerging; the scientists also indicated that<br />

their research could advance our understanding of infertility and of menopause.<br />

The rationale offered by these scientists for attempting to produce artificial oocytes is<br />

laudable and hopefully not entirely unrealistic. But as pointed out earlier, important scientific<br />

experiments often have applications not anticipated by the researchers. In the present case, it is<br />

not too difficult to identify some of these unanticipated consequences. As noted above, scientists<br />

have made eggs not only from female, but also from male embryonic stem cells. Conceivably,<br />

then, a gay couple may be able to produce their own genetic<strong>all</strong>y related children through IVF and<br />

surrogacy. In this scenario, one man would contribute the sperm and the other the eggs. While<br />

some in the gay community may salute this development as an important step toward equal<br />

access to parenthood, others may point to possible deleterious consequences for the well-being<br />

and the personal identity of children. In <strong>all</strong>owing men to become mothers, this procedure would<br />

also undermine the principle that each child should have a genetic father and mother.<br />

78<br />

Claire Ainsworth, "Artificial Human Eggs Created," New Scientist, July 2, 2001; Rachel Nowak, "Mice Born<br />

from Rat-Matured Eggs," New Scientist, September 28, 2002; Sylvia Pagàn Westphal, "Embryonic Stem Cells<br />

Turned into Eggs," New Scientist, May 1, 2003; Azim Surani, "Stem Cells: How to Make Eggs and Sperm,"<br />

Nature 427 (2004); Nicholas Wade, "Pennsylvania Researchers Turn Stem Cells to Egg Cells," New York Times,<br />

May 2, 2003; Rick Weiss, "In Laboratory, Ordinary Stem Cells Are Turned into Eggs," Washington Post, May 2,<br />

2002.<br />

103


The availability of oocytes in large numbers would also make it much more attractive for<br />

prospective parents seeking an egg donor to consider genetic<strong>all</strong>y engineered eggs. As noted<br />

elsewhere, scientists have already developed the ability to insert and remove specific genes in<br />

embryonic stem cells. Genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified stem cells could be used as means to produce eggs<br />

with specific genetic traits, in the process making genetic modifications inheritable. A more<br />

realistic consequence of this line of research is the postponement of motherhood. Being able to<br />

replenish their own supply of eggs through somatic cell nuclear transfer could become a<br />

proposition too attractive for many women to resist. 79<br />

4.5.4 Remaking the Machinery of Gestation<br />

“Ectogenesis” is the technical term used to identify the gestation of a baby outside a<br />

woman’s womb. Two recent experiments suggest that this possibility may not be as hypothetical<br />

as it seems. In one experiment, a group of scientists at Cornell University Medical College in<br />

New York took human uterine tissue samples and grew them on a model uterus. To the<br />

scientists’ amazement, embryos implanted in this tissue survived and developed for six days<br />

before the experiment was terminated. 80 Japanese scientists, for their part managed, to gestate<br />

goats in a fully artificial womb for three weeks. 81 Whether these experiments are consequential<br />

in any way is not entirely clear. Some have argued that it is impossible, for a variety of<br />

physiological reasons, to actu<strong>all</strong>y design a fully functional human ectogenetic chamber. 82<br />

Detailed information about scientific and medical progress in this area is sparse, and clinical<br />

applications appear to be years away. If the debate about genetic engineering is any indication<br />

however, progress in this area may occur much faster than anticipated. A brief discussion of<br />

possible societal consequences is therefore appropriate.<br />

79<br />

80<br />

81<br />

82<br />

Incident<strong>all</strong>y, there is some evidence that the natural supply of eggs, contrary to common opinion, may not be<br />

limited after <strong>all</strong>. In mid-2004, it was widely reported by the news media that ovaries – at least in mice – are<br />

capable of producing fresh eggs throughout their adult life Helen R. Pilcher, Could We Defeat the Menopause?<br />

Mouse Ovaries Offer up Secret of New Egg Cells (News@nature.com, July 1, 2004 [cited April 26, 2006]);<br />

available from http://www.nature.com/nsu/040628/040628-18.html. Whether this result can be reproduced in<br />

humans is unclear, but the researchers who conducted the experiment pointed out that female flies, fish, birds,<br />

and now mice <strong>all</strong> do make new eggs throughout life, and that there is no reason to assume that this would be<br />

different in humans<br />

It is unclear whether the scientist in question, Dr. Hung-Ching Liu, has published the results of this experiment.<br />

An account of the Japanese experiments can be found in N. Unno et al., "Development of an Artificial Placenta:<br />

Survival of Isolated Goat Fetuses for Three Weeks with Umbilical Arteriovenous Extracorporeal Membrane<br />

Oxygenation," Fetal Diagnosis & Therapy 5 (1990). and Ronald Bailey, Babies in a Bottle: Artificial Wombs<br />

and the Beginning of Human Life (Reason, August 20, 2003 [cited April 26, 2006]); available from<br />

http://reason.com/rb/rb082003.shtml; Y. Kubawara et al., "Long-Term Extrauterine Incubation of Isolated Goat<br />

Fetuses," Artificial Organs 13 (1989); Robin McKie, "Men Redundant? Now We Don't Need Women Either,"<br />

The Guardian, February 10, 2002; Jeremy Rifkin, "The End of Pregnancy," The Guardian, January 17, 2002;<br />

Sacha Zimmerman, "Fetal Position: The Real Threat to Roe V. Wade," The New Republic, August 13, 2003.<br />

See Bailey, Babies in a Bottle: Artificial Wombs and the Beginning of Human Life ([cited).. Curiously, this<br />

author’s skepticism is in stark contrast to his otherwise enthusiastic support for many other controversial medical<br />

and technological developments.<br />

104


As for many other medical technologies, experiments involving ectogenetic chambers have<br />

been conducted with a narrow therapeutic goal in mind. In this case, scientists had hoped to save<br />

the lives of extremely premature babies and to help women with uterine malformations to<br />

become pregnant. The possible applications of an ectogenetic chamber do not stop here,<br />

however. Once this technology has been fully developed, some perfectly healthy women may<br />

find it attractive to avoid the hassles and the pains, not to mention the forced temporary<br />

retirement, associated with pregnancy by “outsourcing” it to a machine. Women may not be the<br />

only ones to find this option attractive. The availability of ectogenetic chambers may induce<br />

business firms to adopt policies that strongly encourage their female employees to accept<br />

artificial pregnancies. Health insurance companies may find an artificial pregnancy more costeffective<br />

and less risky than a natural one. An entirely artificial gestation could also have a<br />

dramatic impact on the abortion debate. A key argument of the pro-choice camp – that the state<br />

cannot impose on women the physical and emotional burdens associated with an unwanted<br />

pregnancy – would suddenly be removed from the equation. 83<br />

Also of considerable import are possible risks to the health and well-being of the babies.<br />

These risks are <strong>all</strong> but unknown, but they may well be significant. For example, we know that<br />

fetuses respond to the mother’s heartbeat and to her emotions. Can we re<strong>all</strong>y dispense with these<br />

subtle but perhaps critical interactions? One may also wonder whether an artificial pregnancy<br />

would weaken the bond between mother and child. How can we be so sure that we will be able to<br />

redesign in just a few years what took nature millions of years to create and perfect? Even if we<br />

could accomplish this feat, should this practice be indulged or even encouraged for the sake of<br />

avoiding stretch marks, weight gain, and over<strong>all</strong> inconvenience? Is economic efficiency reason<br />

enough for tolerating this practice? Is this technology re<strong>all</strong>y liberating, as some feminists no<br />

doubt will claim? Or should it rather be viewed as a particularly perverse attempt by a maledominated<br />

society to marginalize women?<br />

It is neither our intention nor our desire to provide definitive answers to these questions.<br />

More important to the present discussion is the observation that the broad availability of<br />

ectogenetic chambers is likely to spark a variety of applications, ranging from the purely<br />

therapeutic to the dubious and the downright unacceptable. And as for other scientific and<br />

medical developments discussed in this report, only a regulatory agency would have both the<br />

expertise and the legitimacy to distinguish between acceptable and unacceptable uses of this<br />

technology.<br />

4.5.5 Hybrids and Chimeras<br />

Their vaguely menacing names notwithstanding, we are <strong>all</strong> familiar with hybrids and<br />

chimeras. A hybrid is simply the result of the fertilization of one species’ egg with another<br />

species’ sperm. Mules, the offspring of a female horse and a male donkey, are a classic example.<br />

In Greek mythology, a chimera is a monstrous animal with the head of a lion, the body of a goat,<br />

83<br />

Zimmerman, "Fetal Position: The Real Threat to Roe V. Wade."<br />

105


and the tail of serpent. In biology, chimeric animals consist of cells from at least two genetic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

distinct progenitors, either two different animals or a human and an animal. They can be created<br />

in a variety of ways – for example, by inserting cells from one species into the embryo or the<br />

fetus of another. Stem cells have also been used for this purpose. Chimeras can be conceived<br />

natur<strong>all</strong>y, such as when twin embryos fuse (a rare but not unknown phenomenon).<br />

If there ever was a truly horrifying scenario to the average person, it is the possibility that<br />

scientists one day could create entities that are neither clearly human nor animal. The term<br />

“humanzee” evokes precisely this kind of imagery. The “humanzee” is a creature that is half<br />

human and half chimpanzee. Why anyone would want to create a humanzee is of course a very<br />

important question that has not received convincing answers. Some have suggested that<br />

humanzees could perform degrading and dangerous tasks; others, that they could be designed to<br />

serve as soldiers. A more realistic proposition is the possibility that chimeric individuals could be<br />

created for superior athletic performance. Whatever the rationale for creating a human-animal<br />

chimera, should a suitable technology become available, it is not at <strong>all</strong> implausible that some<br />

individuals may want to use it, despite the unanimous opposition of the scientific community and<br />

the ART industry. This situation is reminiscent of reproductive cloning, and raises similar ethical<br />

concerns.<br />

It is relatively easy to justify banning the creation of anything resembling a humanzee or a<br />

super-athlete. The ethical arguments in this case are not too dissimilar from those offered to ban<br />

reproductive cloning. Respect for individual autonomy prevents us from establishing in advance<br />

the ultimate purpose of any human life, including human chimeric life. Creation of such a hybrid<br />

furthermore raises nightmarish questions of moral status, such as what kinds of political rights<br />

such a creature would have. On the other end, there may well be lines of research involving<br />

chimeras and/or hybrids that could be justified, both from a scientific and an ethical standpoint.<br />

To our knowledge, there have been only two published experiments involving the creation<br />

of human-animal hybrids, both conducted in 2003. In one of these experiments, a Chinese<br />

scientist removed the nuclei from rabbit eggs and replaced them with human nuclei obtained<br />

from the skin of two five-year-old boys, two men, and a 60-year old woman. 84 The experiment is<br />

noteworthy not only because human-animal embryos were created for the first time, but also<br />

because it was the first documented case of somatic cell nuclear transfer in humans. It was, in<br />

other words, a cloning experiment. As disturbing as this experiment may appear, it was<br />

conducted for a straightforward reason. The Chinese scientist was hoping to develop a technique<br />

for producing what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed ethical embryos – embryos that could be produced in large<br />

numbers and used as a source of human stem cells without stirring public controversies.<br />

Predictably, the experiment did trigger a controversy, but not because of the procedure involved.<br />

84<br />

"China's Human-Cloning Policy Fudges Law on Cross-Species Fusions," Nature 427 (2004); Carina Dennis,<br />

"Chinese Fusion Method Promises Fresh Route to Human Stem Cells," Nature 424 (2003); Antonio Regalado,<br />

"Chinese Scientists <strong>Report</strong> Advance in Stem-Cell Work," W<strong>all</strong> Street Journal, August 13, 2003; Rick Weiss,<br />

"Cloning Yields Human-Rabbit Hybrid Embryo," Washington Post, August 14, 2003; Richard Y<strong>all</strong>op,<br />

"Professor Backs Use of Hybrid Embryos," The Australian, October 28, 2004.<br />

106


Several scientists expressed serious doubts about the claim that the cells derived from these<br />

embryos were indeed embryonic stem cells, because the Chinese researcher failed to demonstrate<br />

that the resulting cells were indeed able to self-replicate indefinitely.<br />

One possible way to interpret this line of research is to compare it to xenotransplantation.<br />

The transplantation of animal organs into the human body is now common practice in the United<br />

States and abroad. Numerous tissue banks exist, and the FDA has thoroughly regulated this field<br />

of medicine. Perhaps this experiment could be described as an instance of xenotransplantation; as<br />

controversial as transplantation of animal organs into the human body once was, it now has<br />

become an accepted medical practice.<br />

In a similar direction points a line of research involving the creation of chimeric sheep. 85 In<br />

these experiments, a group of scientists at the University of Nevada in Reno injected human<br />

embryonic stem cells into the fetuses of sheep. What is distinctive about these experiments is that<br />

the proportion of human cells in some organs (including the skin, the liver, the heart, and the<br />

pancreas) is unusu<strong>all</strong>y large – between 7 and 15 percent. The researchers hope eventu<strong>all</strong>y to be<br />

able to grow animals whose organs will not be rejected by humans. Clinical applications remain<br />

a distant goal, however.<br />

An important open question is whether the injected human stem cells might end up in the<br />

brains of these animals in significant numbers. At this time, scientists are simply unable to<br />

provide definitive answers, though they do not exclude this possibility. Nor is it clear that an<br />

animal with a significant proportion of human brain cells would have any human cognitive<br />

capacities. That scientists at this time are unable to provide even the beginning of an answer to<br />

this question is certainly a good reason to carefully monitor these experiments. Precisely this<br />

question was raised at a conference organized in October of 2004 by the National Academy of<br />

Sciences in Washington, D.C. 86 The question was prompted by research being conducted at<br />

Stanford University involving the injection of diseased human embryonic stem cells into animal<br />

models. 87 To this end, scientists have created mice with a substantial proportion of humanderived<br />

brain cells. This raises, of course, the possibility that mice could acquire human-like<br />

cognitive capabilities, a possibility that some scientists participating in the conference seemed to<br />

take seriously. Also problematic to participating scientists was prospect that male and female<br />

chimeric mice could mate. Other scientists expressed doubts about the wisdom of creating<br />

chimeric mice to study disease development. 88<br />

The discussion among participating scientists showed that researchers are not of one opinion<br />

about the wisdom of quickly moving forward in this area. Some have argued, quite reasonably in<br />

85<br />

86<br />

87<br />

88<br />

Sylvia Pagàn Westphal, "'Humanised' Organs Can Be Grown in Animals," New Scientist, December 17, 2003.<br />

Erika Check, "Biologists Seek Consensus on Guidelines for Stem-Cell Research," Nature 431 (2004).<br />

For a moderately technical overview, see the presentation by Professor Irving Weissman prepared for the<br />

Conference on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, organized by the National Academies and<br />

held in Washington, D.C., on October 12-13, 2004 (available at<br />

http://dels.nas.edu/bls/stemcells/powerpoints.html).<br />

Nicholas Wade, "Is the World Ready for a Man-Mouse?," International Herald Tribune, November 28, 2002.<br />

107


our view, that the scientific community, as part of its self-regulatory efforts, should first try to<br />

determine which experiments involving chimeric animals should be considered unproblematic,<br />

which ones are questionable, and which ones should be avoided entirely before moving forward.<br />

That this suggestion was ignored is more evidence that a regulatory intervention in this area may<br />

indeed be necessary.<br />

108


4.6 Bibliography<br />

Abboud, Leila. "FDA Seeks Rigorous Review of New Fertility Treatment." W<strong>all</strong> Street Journal,<br />

October 7, 2002.<br />

Ainsworth, Claire. "Artificial Human Eggs Created." New Scientist, July 2, 2001.<br />

Alvare, Helen M. "The Case for Regulating Collaborative Reproduction: A Children's Rights<br />

Perspective." Harvard Journal on Legislation 40 (2003): 1-63.<br />

Annas, George J. "Human Cloning: A Choice or an Echo?" Dayton Law Review 23 (1998): 247-<br />

75.<br />

Ansari-Lari, M., and M. Saadat. "Changing Sex Ratios in Iran 1976-2000." Journal of<br />

Epidemiology and Community Health 56 (2002): 622-23.<br />

Bailey, Ronald. Babies in a Bottle: Artificial Wombs and the Beginning of Human Life Reason,<br />

August 20, 2003 [cited April 26, 2006]. Available from<br />

http://reason.com/rb/rb082003.shtml.<br />

Bankowski, Brandon, Anne D. Lyerly, Ruth Faden, and Edward W<strong>all</strong>ach. "The Social<br />

Implications of Embryo Cryopreservation." Fertility and Sterility 84, no. 4 (2005): 823-<br />

32.<br />

Barnes, Barry. "On the Conventional Character of Knowledge and Cognition." In Science<br />

Observed. Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, edited by Karin Knorr-Cetina and<br />

Michael Mulkay, 19-51. London: Sage Publications, 1983.<br />

Barnes, Barry, David Bloor, and John Henry. Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis.<br />

Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

Barritt, Jason A., Carol A. Brenner, Henry E. Malter, and Jacques Cohen. "Mitochondria in<br />

Human Offspring Derived from Ooplasmic Transplantation." Human Reproduction 16,<br />

no. 3 (2001): 513-16.<br />

Baruch, Susannah, Audrey Huang, Daryl Pritchard, Andrea Kalfoglou, Gail Javitt, Rick<br />

Borchelt, Joan Scott, and Kathy Hudson. "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues<br />

and Options for Policymakers." Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center,<br />

2005.<br />

Baum, Kenneth. "Golden Eggs: Towards the Rational Regulation of Oocyte Donation." Brigham<br />

Young University Law Review (2001): 107-66.<br />

Belkin, Lisa. "Getting the Girl." New York Times Magazine, July 25, 1999, 26-55.<br />

Bhattacharya, Shaoni. Aborted Fetuses Could Become 'Unborn Mothers' New Scientist, July 1,<br />

2003 [cited August 2, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.newscientist.com/news/news.jsp?id=ns99993889<br />

———. Banned 'Designer Baby' Is Born in UK New Scientist, June 19, 2003 [cited April 26,<br />

2006]. Available from http://www.newscientist.com/news/print.jsp?id=ns99993854.<br />

———. 'She-Male' Embryos Created in Lab New Scientist, July 3, 2003 [cited April 26, 2006].<br />

Available from http://www.newscientist.com/news/news.jsp?id=ns99993905<br />

Bhattacharya, Shaoni, and Sylvia Pagàn Westphal. Controversial Three-Parent Pregnancy<br />

Revealed New Scientist, October 14, 2003 [cited August 2, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.newscientist.com/article.ns?id=dn4266<br />

Blackstock, Colin. "Matched and Hatched, Britain's First 'Designer Baby' Born to Save Brother."<br />

The Guardian, June 19, 2003.<br />

Bloor, David. Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. London: Routledge, 1997.<br />

109


Bonnicksen, Andrea. "Innovative ARTs and Informed Consent." Gaithersburg, MD: FDA’s<br />

Biological Response Modifiers Advisory Committee Meeting, 2002.<br />

Borkenhagen, Ada, Yve Stoebel-Richter, Carolyn Fink, E. Braehler, and H. Kentenich. "Was<br />

Denken Die Deutsche Bevölkerung Und Kinderwunschpaare Über Die PID? Eine<br />

Vergleichende Studie." Fertility Center Berlin, DRK-Clinics Westend, Leipzig<br />

University, Department of Medical Psychology and Medical Sociology, 2004.<br />

Boseley, Sarah. "Frozen Egg Baby Hailed as Fertility Milestone." The Guardian, October 11,<br />

2002.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success<br />

Rates: National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for<br />

Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health,<br />

2004.<br />

———. "Survey of Assisted Reproductive Technology: Embryo Laboratory Procedures and<br />

Practices. Appendix G: Survey Summary Responses." Atlanta, GA, 1999.<br />

Chamot, Josh, and Leslie Fink. Researchers Engineer Mouse Embryonic Stem Cells to Form<br />

Sperm Cell Precursors National Science Foundation, Office of Legislative and Public<br />

Affairs, December 10, 2003 [cited August 3, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.nsf.gov/od/lpa/news/03/pr03142.htm.<br />

Chan, Cecilia L. W., Paul S. F. Yip, Ernest H. Y. Ng, P. C. Ho, Celia H. Y. Chan, and Jade S. K.<br />

Au. "Gender Selection in China: Its Meanings and Implications." Journal of Assisted<br />

Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002): 426-30.<br />

Charny, David. "Nonlegal Sanctions in Commercial Relationships." Harvard Law Review 104<br />

(1990): 375-467.<br />

Check, Erika. "Biologists Seek Consensus on Guidelines for Stem-Cell Research." Nature 431<br />

(2004): 885.<br />

"China's Human-Cloning Policy Fudges Law on Cross-Species Fusions." Nature 427 (2004):<br />

278-79.<br />

Cohen, Philip. "Test-Tube Sperm Get New Genes." New Scientist, January 26, 2004.<br />

Collins, Harry M. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Chicago,<br />

IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992.<br />

Collins, Harry M., and Trevor Pinch. The Golem. What Everyone Should Know About Science.<br />

Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993.<br />

Connor, Steve. "Scientists Outraged over Fusion of Male and Female Embryos Condemn<br />

Attempt to Combine Male and Female Cells." The Independent, July 3, 2003.<br />

Dahl, E., M. Beutel, B Brosig, and K.-D. Hinsch. "Preconception Sex Selection for Non-Medical<br />

Reasons: A Representative Survey from Germany." Human Reproduction 18, no. 10<br />

(2003): 2231-34.<br />

Dahl, Edgar, Ruchi S. Gupta, Manfred Beutel, Yve Stoebel-Richter, Hans-Rudolf Tinneberg, and<br />

Tarun Jain. "Preconception Sex Selection Demand and Preferences in the United States."<br />

Fertility and Sterility 85, no. 2 (2006): 468-73.<br />

Dekel, Benjamin, Tatyana Burakova, Fabian D. Arditt, Shlomit Reich-Zeliger, Oren Milstein,<br />

Sarit Aviel-Ronen, Gideon Rechavi, Nir Friedman, Naftali Kaminski, Justen H. Passwell,<br />

and Yair Reisner. "Human and Porcine Early Kidney Precursors as a New Source for<br />

Transplantation." Nature Medicine 9, no. 1 (2003): 53-60.<br />

Dennis, Carina. "Chinese Fusion Method Promises Fresh Route to Human Stem Cells." Nature<br />

424 (2003): 711.<br />

110


Derbyshire, David. Foetuses Had Three Genetic Parents Telegraph Group, October 13, 2003<br />

[cited August 2, 2005].<br />

Douglas, Mary. Risk and Blame: Essays in Cultural Theory. London: Routledge, 1992.<br />

Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. "Preconception Gender<br />

Selection for Nonmedical Reasons." Fertility and Sterility 75 (2001): 861-64.<br />

Feng, H.L, X.H. Wen, T. Amet, and S.C. Pesser. "Fertilization and Early Embryology: Effect of<br />

Different Co-Culture Systems in Early Human Embryo Development." Human<br />

Reproduction 11 (1996): 1525-28.<br />

First Frozen Egg Babies to Be Born in May Xinhuanet (Xinhua News Agency), March 30, 2004<br />

[cited August 2, 2005]. Available from http://news.xinhuanet.com/english/2004-<br />

03/30/content_1391270.htm.<br />

Fukuyama, Francis. Our Post-Human Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution.<br />

New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2002.<br />

Gearhart, John P., Rudolf Jaenisch, and David Prentice. Stem Cell Research: Recent Scientific<br />

and Clinical Developments Session 3, President's Council on Bioethics Meeting, July 24-<br />

25, 2003 [cited September 16, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/july03/session3.html.<br />

Genetics and Public Policy Center. "Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis. A Discussion of<br />

Ch<strong>all</strong>enges, Concerns, and Preliminary Policy Options Related to Genetic Testing of<br />

Human Embryos." Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center, 2003.<br />

———. "Public Awareness and Attitudes About Genetic Technology." Washington, D.C.: Johns<br />

Hopkins University, 2002.<br />

Grady, Denise. "Where Anti-Clone Collides with Pro-Baby." International Herald Tribune,<br />

October 15, 2003.<br />

Hampton, Tracy. "Panel Reviews Health Effects Data for Assisted Reproductive Technologies."<br />

Journal of the American Medical Association 292, no. 24 (2004): 2961-62.<br />

Hank, Karsten, and Hans-Peter Kohler. "Gender Preferences for Children in Europe: Empirical<br />

Results from 17 FFS Countries." Demographic Research 2, no. 1 (2000).<br />

Hansen, Michèle, Jennifer J. Kurinczuk, Carol Bower, and Sandra Webb. "The Risk of Major<br />

Birth Defects after Intracytoplasmic Sperm Injection and in Vitro Fertilization." New<br />

England Journal of Medicine 346, no. 10 (2002): 725-30.<br />

Hanson, Charles, Lars Hamberger, and Per Olof Janson. "Is Any Form of Gender Selection<br />

Ethical?" Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002): 431-32.<br />

Harmon, Amy. "Hello, I'm Your Sister. Our Father Is Donor 150." The New York Times,<br />

November 20, 2005, 1.<br />

"High Court Ban on 'Designer Babies' Overturned." The Guardian, April 8, 2003.<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA). "HFEA Annual <strong>Report</strong> 2003/04."<br />

London, 2004.<br />

Human GM Sperm Will Be Possible One Day, Researchers Indicate Medical News Today,<br />

January 28, 2004 [cited August 3, 2005].<br />

Ianzito, Christina. "Putting Your Eggs in a Different Basket." The Washington Post, September<br />

21, 2004.<br />

Kirschner, Steve. "The Ooplasm Transfer Debate." Genomics and Proteomics, November 1,<br />

2002.<br />

Kolata, Gina. "Babies Born in Experiment Have Genes from Three People." New York Times,<br />

May 5, 2001.<br />

111


Kubawara, Y., T. Okai, S. Kozuma, N. Unno, K. Akiba, Shinozuka, T. Maeda, and Mizuno M.<br />

"Long-Term Extrauterine Incubation of Isolated Goat Fetuses." Artificial Organs 13<br />

(1989): 527-31.<br />

Lanza, Robert, Malcolm A.S. Moore, Teruhiko Wakayama, Anthony C.F. Perry, Jae-Hung<br />

Shieh, Jan Hendriks, Annarosa Leri, Stefano Chimenti, Alyssa Monsen, Daria<br />

Nurzynska, Michael D. West, Jan Kajstura, and Piero Anversa. "Regeneration of the<br />

Infarcted Heart with Stem Cells Derived by Nuclear Transplantation." Circulation<br />

Research 94 (2004): 820-27.<br />

Lanza, Robert P., Ho Yun Chung, James J. Yoo, Peter J. Wetttstein, Catherine Blackwell, Nancy<br />

Borson, Erik Hofmeister, Gunter Schuch, Shay Soker, Carlos T. Moraes, Michael D.<br />

West, and Anthony Atala. "Generation of Histocompatible Tissues Using Nuclear<br />

Transplantation." Nature Biotechnology 20 (2002): 689-96.<br />

Lanza, Robert, Jae-Hung Shieh, Peter J. Wetttstein, Raymond W. Sweeney, Kaida Wu, Anat<br />

Wiesz, Nancy Borson, Boyd Henderson, Michael D. West, and Malcolm A.S. Moore.<br />

"Long-Term Bocine Hematopoietic Engraftment with Clone-Derived Stem Cells."<br />

Cloning and Stem Cells 7, no. 2 (2005): 95-106.<br />

Laurance, Jeremy. "Italian Births Raise Hopes for Egg-Freezing Treatment." The Independent,<br />

September 15, 2004.<br />

Mann, Ronald J. "Verification Institutions in Financial Transactons." Georgetown Law Journal<br />

87 (1999): 2225-72.<br />

Marsa, Linda. "Frozen Eggs Yield Promising Results." Los Angeles Times, September 20, 2004.<br />

McGee, Glenn, ed. The Human Cloning Debate. Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Hills Books, 2002.<br />

McKie, Robin. "Men Redundant? Now We Don't Need Women Either." The Guardian, February<br />

10, 2002.<br />

Meek, James. "Mice May Provide Human Sperm Bank." The Guardian, August 15, 2002.<br />

Nietro, F.S., W.B. Watkins, A. Lopata, H.W.G. baker, and D.H. Edgar. "The Effects of<br />

Cocolture with Autologous Cryopreserved Endometrial Cells on Human in Vitro<br />

Fertilization and Early Embryo Morphology: A Randomized Study." Journal of Assisted<br />

Reproduction and Genetics 13 (1996): 386-89.<br />

Nowak, Rachel. "Mice Born from Rat-Matured Eggs." New Scientist, September 28, 2002.<br />

Ooplasm Transfer as Method to Treat Female Infertility FDA’s Biological Response Modifiers<br />

Advisory Committee Meeting, May 9, 2002 [cited August 2, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.fda.gov/OHRMS/DOCKETS/ac/02/briefing/3855B1_01.pdf<br />

Pagàn Westphal, Sylvia. "Embryonic Stem Cells Turned into Eggs." New Scientist, May 1, 2003.<br />

———. "'Humanised' Organs Can Be Grown in Animals." New Scientist, December 17, 2003.<br />

———. "Stem Cells Can Become 'Normal Sperm'." New Scientist, May 7, 2003.<br />

Parens, Erik, and Eric Juengst. "Inadvertently Crossing the Germ Line." Science 292, no. 5516<br />

(2001): 397.<br />

Pearson, Helen. Egg Injection Boosts Fertility – New Mitochondria May Pep up Ageing Eggs,<br />

without Creating 'Three-Parent' Babies news@nature.com, October 20, 2004 [cited April<br />

26, 2006]. Available from http://www.nature.com/news/2004/041018/full/041018-<br />

10.html.<br />

———. "Infertility Specialists Counsel Caution over Frozen Eggs – Reproduction Techniques<br />

Not Ready for Prime Time." Nature 431, no. 7011 (2004): 886.<br />

Perrow, Charles. Normal Accidents: Living with High Risk Technologies. New York: Basic<br />

Books, 1984.<br />

112


Pilcher, Helen R. Could We Defeat the Menopause? Mouse Ovaries Offer up Secret of New Egg<br />

Cells News@nature.com, July 1, 2004 [cited April 26, 2006]. Available from<br />

http://www.nature.com/nsu/040628/040628-18.html.<br />

Posner, Eric A. "The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal Sanctions on<br />

Collective Action." University of Chicago Law Review 63 (1996): 133-97.<br />

Practice Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. "Ovarian Tissue and<br />

Oocyte Cryopreservation." Fertility and Sterility 82, no. 4 (2004): 993-98.<br />

President’s Council on Bioethics. "Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry."<br />

Washington, D.C., 2002.<br />

Radford, Tim. "Scientists Modify Sperm to Add New Fish to the Gene Pool." The Guardian,<br />

January 27, 2004.<br />

Radin, Margaret Jane. "Market-Inalienability." Harvard Law Review 100 (1987): 1849-936.<br />

Randerson, James. "Human Testicular Tissue Grown in Mice." New Scientist, October 19, 2004.<br />

———. Scientists Seek to Create 'Three-Parent' Babies New Scientist, October 19, 2004, 2004<br />

[cited August 2, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.newscientist.com/article.ns?id=dn6547.<br />

Regalado, Antonio. "Chinese Scientists <strong>Report</strong> Advance in Stem-Cell Work." W<strong>all</strong> Street<br />

Journal, August 13, 2003.<br />

Rifkin, Jeremy. "The End of Pregnancy." The Guardian, January 17, 2002.<br />

Roan, Shari. "Fertility in Reserve." Los Angeles Times, February 2, 2003.<br />

Robertson, John A. "Oocyte Cytoplasm Transfer and the Ethics of Germ-Line Intervention."<br />

Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 26 (1998): 211-17.<br />

———. "Preconception Gender Selection." American Journal of Bioethics 1, no. 1 (2001): 2-9.<br />

———. "Technology and Motherhood: Legal and Ethical Issues in Human Egg Donation." Case<br />

Western Reserve Law Review 39 (1989): 1-38.<br />

———. "Two Models of Human Cloning." Hofstra Law Review 27 (1999): 609-38.<br />

Rosenberg, Nathan. "Why Technology Forecasts Often Fail." The Futurist July 1 (1995): 16-21.<br />

Ross, Emma. "European Group Denounces Chimera Embryo." Associated Press, July 2, 2003.<br />

Saletan, William. Leave No Embryo Behind June 3, 2005 [cited March 14, 2006].<br />

———. The Organ Factory Slate, July 25, 2005 [cited September 27, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://slate.msn.com/id/2123269/entry/2123270/.<br />

Sample, Ian. "Can a Baby Have Two Mothers?" The Guardian, October 21, 2004.<br />

———. "Prospect of Babies from Unborn Mothers." The Guardian, July 1, 2003.<br />

———. "Scientists Hit out at Creator of 'She-Males'." The Guardian, July 3, 2003.<br />

'Saviour Sibling' Perfect Genetic Match for Brother BioNews, 320, August 8, 2005 [cited April<br />

26, 2006].<br />

Schenker, Joseph G. "Gender Selection: Cultural and Religious Perspectives." Journal of<br />

Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002): 400-10.<br />

Schieve, Laura A., Lynne S. Wilcox, Joyce Zeitz, Gary Jeng, David Hoffman, Robert Bryzski,<br />

James Toner, Lily Tatham, and Benjamin Younger. "Assessment of Outcomes for<br />

Assisted Reproductive Technology: Overview of Issues and the U.S. Experience in<br />

Establishing a Surveillance System." In Current Practices and Controversies in Assisted<br />

Reproduction. <strong>Report</strong> of a Meeting On "Medical Ethical and Social Aspects of Assisted<br />

Reproduction" , September 17-21 2001, edited by Effy Vayena, Patrick Rowe and David<br />

P. Griffin, 363-76. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization, 2002.<br />

113


Shamblott, Michael J., Joyce Axelman, John W. Littlefield, Paul D. Blumenthal, George R.<br />

Huggins, Yan Cui, Linzhao Cheng, and John D. Gearhart. "Human Embryonic Germ Cell<br />

Derivates Express a Broad Range of Development<strong>all</strong>y Distinct Markers and Proliferate<br />

Extensively in Vitro." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 98, no. 1 (2001):<br />

113-18.<br />

Sills, E. Scott, and Gianpiero D. Palermo. "Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis for Elective Sex<br />

Selection, the IVF Market Economy, and the Child – Another Long Day's Journey into<br />

Night?" Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 19, no. 9 (2002): 433-37.<br />

Skloot, Rebecca. "S<strong>all</strong>y Has 2 Mommies and 1 Daddy." Popular Science, March 1, 2003.<br />

Spencer, Geoff. Transgenic Animals Produced Using Cultured Sperm: Study Opens New<br />

Possibilities for Biological Research, Gene Therapy NIH News, National Institutes of<br />

Health, January 26, 2004 [cited August 3, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.nih.gov/news/pr/jan2004/nhgri-26.htm.<br />

Statham, H., J. Green, C. Snowdon, and M. France-Dawson. "Choice of Baby's Sex." Lancet<br />

341, no. 8844 (1993): 564-65.<br />

Stein, Rob. "Found on the Web, with DNA: A Boy's Father." The Washington Post, November<br />

13, 2005, 09.<br />

Steinbacher, Roberta, and Faith Gilroy. "Sex Selection Technology: A Prediction of Its Use and<br />

Effect." Journal of Psychology 124, no. 3 (1990): 283-88.<br />

Stem Cells Stimulated to Be Sperm Associated Press, September 15, 2003 [cited August 2, 2005].<br />

Available from http://www.wired.com/news/medtech/0,1286,60454,00.html.<br />

Stephen, Elizabeth Hervey. "Demographic Implications of Reproductive Technologies."<br />

Population Research and Policy Review 19, no. 4 (2000): 301-15.<br />

Strong, Carson. Ethics in Reproductive and Perinatal Medicine: A New Framework. New Haven,<br />

CT: Yale University Press, 1997.<br />

Surani, Azim. "Stem Cells: How to Make Eggs and Sperm." Nature 427 (2004): 106-07.<br />

Swetkis, Doreen, Faith Gilroy, and Roberta Steinbacher. "Firstborn Preference and Attitudes<br />

toward Using Sex Selection Technology." The Journal of Genetic Psychology 163, no. 2<br />

(2002): 28-238.<br />

Thibodeaux, J., and R. Godke. "In Vitro Enhancement of Early Stage Embryos with Coculture."<br />

Archives of Pathology and Laboratory Medicine 116 (1992): 364-72.<br />

Treatment for Infertile Women Yields Babies with Three Sets of Genes Kaiser Family<br />

Foundation, May 7, 2001 [cited August 2, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://report.kff.org/archive/repro/2001/5/kr010507.11.htm.<br />

Unno, N., Y. Kubawara, T. Okai, K. Kido, Nakayama H., Kikuchi, Y. Narumiya, S. Kozuma, Y.<br />

Taketani, and M. Tamura. "Development of an Artificial Placenta: Survival of Isolated<br />

Goat Fetuses for Three Weeks with Umbilical Arteriovenous Extracorporeal Membrane<br />

Oxygenation." Fetal Diagnosis & Therapy 5 (1990): 189-95.<br />

Vasagar, Jeevan. "Use of Foetal Eggs Grotesque, Say Campaigners." The Guardian, July 2,<br />

2003.<br />

Vogel, Gretchen. "Embryonic Stem Cells: Scientists Make Sperm in a Dish." Science 302, no.<br />

5652 (2003): 1875.<br />

Vogelstein, Bert, Bruce Alberts, and Kenneth Shine. "Please Don't C<strong>all</strong> It Cloning." Science 295<br />

(2002): 1237.<br />

Volokh, Eugene. "The Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope." Harvard Law Review 116 (2003):<br />

1026-137.<br />

114


Wade, Nicholas. "Is the World Ready for a Man-Mouse?" International Herald Tribune,<br />

November 28, 2002.<br />

———. "Pennsylvania Researchers Turn Stem Cells to Egg Cells." New York Times, May 2,<br />

2003.<br />

Wadyka, S<strong>all</strong>y. "For Women Worried About Fertility, Egg Bank Is a New Option." New York<br />

Times, September 21, 2004.<br />

Weiss, Rick. "Cloning Yields Human-Rabbit Hybrid Embryo." Washington Post, August 14,<br />

2003, A04.<br />

———. "In Laboratory, Ordinary Stem Cells Are Turned into Eggs." Washington Post, May 2,<br />

2002, A01.<br />

———. "Sperm Made from Stem Cells: Development in Mice Raises Issues for Human<br />

Reproduction." Washington Post, September 16, 2003.<br />

———. "U.S.-Banned Fertility Method Tried in China: Woman Became Pregnant through Egg<br />

Transfer Technique but Lost All Three Fetuses." Washington Post, October 14, 2003.<br />

Wertz, Dorothy C., John C. Fletcher, Nippert Irmgard, Gerhard Wolff, and Ayme Ségoléne. "Has<br />

Patient Autonomy Gone Too Far? Geneticists' Views in 36 Nations." The American<br />

Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 4 (2002): 1-25.<br />

Wiemer, K.E., D.I. Hoffman, W.S. Maxson, B. Muhlenberg, I. Fiore, and M. Cuervo.<br />

"Embryonic Morphology and Rate of Implantation of Human Embryos Following<br />

Coculture on Bovine Oviductal Epethelial Cells." Human Reproduction 8 (1993): 97-101.<br />

Y<strong>all</strong>op, Richard. "Professor Backs Use of Hybrid Embryos." The Australian, October 28, 2004.<br />

Zimmerman, Sacha. "Fetal Position: The Real Threat to Roe V. Wade." The New Republic,<br />

August 13, 2003.<br />

115


116


5 The Current Legal and Regulatory Framework<br />

In this chapter, we examine in some detail whether the current statutory and regulatory<br />

framework would provide a basis for addressing future biomedical controversies. We are<br />

certainly not the first ones to conduct this exercise. A noteworthy precedent is the President’s<br />

Council on Bioethics report “Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New<br />

Biotechnologies.” This report examined in great detail whether various federal statutes provide<br />

sufficient authority to regulate a number of specific reproductive and medical technologies. Here<br />

we take a somewhat different approach. We are less interested in the power of the federal<br />

government to bring under its control specific reproductive technologies than in the suitability of<br />

individual statutes to provide a robust platform for (a) monitoring the emergence of new<br />

reproductive and medical technologies, (b) adjudicating among conflicting societal interests<br />

pertaining to the use of these technologies, and (c) monitoring and assuring compliance.<br />

5.1 Federal Legislation<br />

5.1.1 The Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992<br />

The only existing statute at the federal level specific<strong>all</strong>y focused on reproductive medicine is<br />

the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992 (FCSRCA). FCSRCA was<br />

enacted in response to widespread concerns among patients and consumer groups about the<br />

accuracy of success rates published by fertility clinics. Success rates were and remain the most<br />

important device for fertility clinics to promote themselves and attract new patients. Fertility<br />

clinics operate in a very competitive economic environment, one that may induce some clinics to<br />

make inaccurate, misleading, or downright false statements about their success rates. High<br />

success rates, in the eyes of prospective patients, are of course of paramount importance in the<br />

selection of an ART program. Competition among ART clinics is made fiercer by the fact that in<br />

the United States, very few health insurance plans offer coverage for fertility treatments.<br />

With FCSRCA, the Congress, in cooperation with the Society for Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technology (SART) and the American Society of Reproductive Medicine, established leg<strong>all</strong>y<br />

binding standards for measuring and reporting ART success rates. It also required the CDC to<br />

devise a model program for the inspection and certification of embryo laboratories.<br />

The scope of FCSRCA is narrow: It applies exclusively to embryo laboratories, i.e., to<br />

facilities “in which human oocytes are subject to assisted reproductive technology treatment or<br />

procedures based on manipulation of oocytes or embryos which are subject to implantation.” 1<br />

Thus, the act does not reach laboratories that conduct research on human oocytes or sperm at<br />

1<br />

See 42 USC 263a-7(2).<br />

117


iotech companies or university clinics, nor does it reach privately funded laboratories<br />

conducting research on human development proper – i.e., on human embryos.<br />

The statute defines success rate as the ratio between the number of achieved pregnancies and<br />

“...the number of ovarian stimulation procedures attempted.” 2 ART treatments include only those<br />

fertility treatments that involve the handling of both eggs and sperm. As a result, assisted (or<br />

artificial) insemination (also known as intrauterine insemination, or IUI) and treatments that<br />

consist only of ovarian stimulation (without egg retrieval) are not considered ART procedures.<br />

The CDC, in cooperation with SART, now publishes success rates on a yearly basis. These<br />

reports are intended both as a decision-making tool and as an educational resource for<br />

prospective parents. 3<br />

Measuring ART success rates is only one of two FCSRCA components. The other requires<br />

the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS), through the CDC, to develop a model<br />

program for the inspection and certification of embryo laboratories. The program, to be<br />

implemented by the states, is voluntary. The delegation of the program’s implementation to the<br />

states seems to reflect Congress’ desire to respect regional and cultural differences in this very<br />

sensitive policy area. The CDC published the actual program requirements only in 1999, mainly<br />

due to lack of funding. 4 To our knowledge, no state has yet implemented it.<br />

The program is modeled after similar ones in other industrialized countries. Requirements<br />

include developing standards and procedures to ensure consistency in performing ART<br />

treatments, 5 standards for record-keeping of laboratory tests and ART treatments, 6 and standards<br />

for maintaining written records about personnel and facilities. 7 An important element of the<br />

model program is inspections, to be conducted periodic<strong>all</strong>y and unannounced by the states or by<br />

accredited professional and trade organizations. The program includes specific criteria for an<br />

organization to qualify as an accreditation organization. The performance of each accreditation<br />

organization is reviewed on an annual basis. Inadequate performance can result in the withdrawal<br />

of accreditation. The implementation of the model program can be in part or fully funded<br />

through the user fees. 8<br />

What role, if any, could FCSRCA play as a key component of a future regulatory system?<br />

The short answer to this question is that it would be a modest one. At most, the FCSRCA could<br />

provide a basic regulatory infrastructure on which additional statutory and regulatory<br />

components could be built. For example, the reporting system designed to measure success rates<br />

2<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

See 42 USC 263a-1 (b)(2).<br />

All reports are available in electronic form at http://www.cdc.gov/reproductivehealth/ART/index.htm.<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention), "Implementation of the<br />

Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992 – a Model Program for the Certification of Embryo<br />

Laboratories; Notice," Federal Register 64, no. 139 (1999).<br />

See 42 USC 263a-2 (d)(1) and (d)(2).<br />

See 42 USC 263a-2 (d)(3).<br />

See 42 USC 263a-2 (d)(4).<br />

See 42 USC 263a-6.<br />

118


on a clinic-by-clinic basis could be expanded to monitor the health and well-being of newborn<br />

children up to approximately one year of age. This is the age at which most birth and congenital<br />

defects not detectable at birth become apparent. As shown in Appendix C, there remains<br />

considerable uncertainty about the relationship between the use of ART technologies and the<br />

frequency of various birth and genetic defects. An extended system of health monitoring would<br />

go a long way to improving our limited knowledge of the possible risks associated with ART<br />

technologies. Obviously, there would be costs associated with the implementation and operation<br />

of an extended system of monitoring, costs that could be defrayed in part through user fees and<br />

in part through governmental contributions.<br />

The model program is clearly not designed to substantively regulate the practice of<br />

reproductive medicine. Its requirements reveal a ubiquitous concern for procedural matters.<br />

These requirements do not in any way impinge upon the professional autonomy and judgment of<br />

the medical profession, or for that matter restrict the options available to prospective parents. In<br />

fact, the statute explicitly prevents regulators from intervening directly in this field of medicine.<br />

FCSRA prohibits “establish[ing] any regulation, standard, or requirement which has the effect of<br />

exercising supervision or control over the practice of medicine in assisted reproductive<br />

technology programs.” 9 In this sense, the model program should be regarded as a regulatory<br />

infrastructure that could play a useful role should Congress decide to intervene more directly in<br />

the field of reproductive medicine. For example, tracking the creation, import, export, and<br />

exchange of human embryos would require only minimal changes. 10 The model program would<br />

also facilitate detecting violations of prohibited practices, such as the for-profit trade of oocytes<br />

or embryos, and the misuse or unauthorized destruction of embryos. 11<br />

It should be noted that the model program as described by the CDC is comprehensive and<br />

quite detailed. Its implementation would no doubt cause additional, and possibly significant,<br />

costs to ART clinics. Yet the program can hardly be described as a case of administrative<br />

overzealousness. The CDC has made clear that many requirements included in the model<br />

program are based on existing ART programs, such as the College of American Pathologists<br />

(CAP) certification program for embryo labs and other state, federal, and international ART<br />

programs. 12 The addendum lists several professional organizations the CDC has consulted with<br />

to develop this program. Thus the model program, comprehensive and cumbersome as it may be,<br />

simply reflects the state of the art in managing embryo labs as it has emerged in consultation<br />

with <strong>all</strong> relevant professional and trade associations.<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

12<br />

42 USC 263a-2(i).<br />

We are not suggesting that embryos currently are being bought and sold in large numbers. Should the donation<br />

of cryopreserved embryos for research become common practice, tracking embryo donation would become<br />

considerably more important.<br />

See Department of Health and Human Services (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention), "Implementation<br />

of the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992 – a Model Program for the Certification of<br />

Embryo Laboratories; Notice," Section C 39388- 91.<br />

See Ibid. Introduction and background sections.<br />

119


As an infrastructure of quality assurance and monitoring, the model program has one glaring<br />

limitation: It does not reach <strong>all</strong> laboratories involved in the use and manipulation of embryos.<br />

Laboratories that create embryos for purposes other than reproduction do not f<strong>all</strong> under FCSRCA<br />

jurisdiction. Nor is FCSRCA’s emphasis to protect the health and safety of the patients, establish<br />

appropriate personnel qualifications, or ensure consistency in the quality of medical procedures<br />

of any relevance to conducting research. Other elements of the model program, such as recordkeeping<br />

requirements for reproductive tissues, could, however, be extended to research labs at<br />

biotech companies and university hospitals.<br />

In addition to its inability to reach any of the controversial reproductive procedures or<br />

research protocols, the model program includes only weak sanctions. HHS, through the CDC,<br />

makes inspection results public and has the authority to revoke the certification of third-party<br />

inspectors. 13 This approach may be described as enforcement by disclosure, and under certain<br />

circumstances it can indeed be effective – for example, when disclosed information negatively<br />

affects an organization’s public image. Bad publicity is often associated with negative economic<br />

consequences, reason enough for an organization to stay in compliance with applicable laws and<br />

regulations. In the present case, however, neither ART clinics nor third-party inspectors are<br />

likely to suffer significant financial losses from a poor inspection record. Neither one of these<br />

types of organizations has enough public visibility to fear the negative consequences of bad<br />

publicity.<br />

5.1.2 Public Health Service Act<br />

The use and manipulation of reproductive tissues, including embryos, is not entirely beyond<br />

the reach of the FDA. Section 361 of the Public Health Service Act (PHSA) gives the FDA the<br />

authority to promulgate rules and regulations to prevent the introduction, transmission, and<br />

spread of communicable diseases between the states or from foreign countries into the United<br />

States. In this area, the FDA has exercised its authority selectively. While blood and bloodrelated<br />

products have tradition<strong>all</strong>y received considerable scrutiny, other biological products have<br />

remained essenti<strong>all</strong>y unregulated. In response to the rapid growth in the commercial trade of<br />

human tissues, the agency announced in 1997 its plans to implement a comprehensive regulatory<br />

system aimed at minimizing health risks involved in the transplantation of human tissues,<br />

improving understanding of the human tissue bank industry, monitoring new developments, and<br />

institutionalizing communication and information exchange with industry members. These plans<br />

are set out in two documents: “A Proposed Approach to the Regulation of Cellular and Tissue-<br />

Based Products” and “Reinventing the Regulation of Human Tissue.” 14 The new regulatory<br />

framework consists of three main rules: an “establishment registration and listing” rule, a “donor<br />

13<br />

14<br />

See 42 USC 263a-3(c).<br />

See http://www.fda.gov/cber/gdlns/celltissue.pdf and http://www.fda.gov/cber/tissue/rego.htm, respectively.<br />

Programmatic documents and proposed interim and final rules can be found at<br />

http://www.fda.gov/cber/tissue/docs.htm. See also Martha A. Wells, "Overview of FDA Regulation of Human<br />

Cellular and Tissue-Based Products," Food and Drug Law Journal 52 (1997).<br />

120


eligibility” rule, and a “good tissue practice” rule, 15 <strong>all</strong> of which have been finalized, pending<br />

some minor changes.<br />

Of particular interest to the present discussion are the first two rules on “establishment<br />

registration” and ”donor eligibility.” The first rule simply requires <strong>all</strong> tissue manufacturers,<br />

including ART programs and sperm and oocyte banks, to register with the FDA and to provide a<br />

listing of the human tissues produced, stored, or manipulated. Registration consists of a one-page<br />

form, to be updated twice a year. 16 Upon completion of the registration process, it will be<br />

possible for the first time to determine the exact number and type of reproductive tissue facilities<br />

in the United States. While the number of ART programs is well-known, no accurate information<br />

was available until recently on the number of sperm and oocyte banks operating in the United<br />

States. Estimates ranged from less than 100 to more than 1,000. 17 Its simplicity notwithstanding,<br />

this rule is an essential element of any regulatory infrastructure aimed at monitoring the ART<br />

industry.<br />

Donor screening and testing requirements set forth in the second rule (“donor eligibility”)<br />

are not central to the present discussion. The rule would be of considerable import if Congress<br />

decided to monitor and/or regulate the trade of reproductive tissues. As discussed in chapter 6,<br />

most countries that recently have passed regulation in the area of reproductive medicine have<br />

restricted, in some cases severely, the free and commercial trade of reproductive tissues. The<br />

“donor eligibility” rule requires not only that donors be screened and tested, but that the<br />

reproductive tissue establishments maintain documentation about <strong>all</strong> reproductive tissues. The<br />

rule has detailed provisions for the information that must be attached to reproductive tissues at<br />

<strong>all</strong> times. 18 In addition to the test results, a unique identification code associated with the donor<br />

must be included. Tissue banks must retain these records for at least 10 years.<br />

If the U.S. public, through Congress or a regulatory agency, determined that the trade of<br />

oocytes should be permitted but only as a non-commercial activity, the “donor eligibility” rule<br />

would considerably facilitate the agency’s monitoring and enforcement efforts. To this end, the<br />

labeling requirements would have to be updated to include some basic financial information<br />

about each transaction. More gener<strong>all</strong>y, this rule may also be regarded as a first important step<br />

15<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Food and Drug Administration), "21 CFR Parts 207, 807, and 1271.<br />

Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products; Establishment Registration and Listing; <strong>Final</strong><br />

Rule," Federal Register 66, no. 13 (2001).<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Food and Drug Administration), "21 CFR Parts 210, 211, 820, and<br />

1271. Eligibility Determination for Donors of Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products,"<br />

Federal Register 69, no. 101 (2004).<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Food and Drug Administration), "21 CFR Parts 16, 1270, and<br />

1271," Federal Register 69, no. 226 (2004).<br />

See http://www.fda.gov/opacom/morechoices/fdaforms/FDA-3356.doc.<br />

In 1997, Ginsberg put this number at 400, but the source was a New York Times news story whose source was<br />

unnamed. See Karen M. Ginsberg, "FDA Approved? A Critique of the Artificial Insemination Industry in the<br />

United States," University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 30 (1997), p.826.<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Food and Drug Administration), "21 CFR Parts 16, 1270, and<br />

1271," p.1271.55.<br />

121


toward implementing a comprehensive system for monitoring embryo donation and, depending<br />

on political preferences, for monitoring oocytes as well. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the rule includes specific<br />

enforcement provisions, although it has an important limitation: It does not extend to research<br />

and educational establishments. From a public health standpoint, this is perfectly reasonable, but<br />

it is a crucial limitation in terms of monitoring capabilities.<br />

In this new scheme, the FDA considers reproductive tissues (defined as eggs, sperm, and<br />

embryos) a low-risk category; they are subject to minimal manipulation, and usu<strong>all</strong>y they are<br />

exchanged between sexu<strong>all</strong>y intimate partners. In this case, the FDA merely recommends donor<br />

screening. This means that ART clinics, with certain exceptions, are not subject to the new<br />

screening, reporting, and labeling requirements. Sperm banks, however, must comply with the<br />

new FDA rules. Should cryopreservation technologies improve to the point of <strong>all</strong>owing the<br />

freezing of eggs, oocyte banks would also f<strong>all</strong> under the purview of these new rules.<br />

5.1.3 The Clinical and Laboratory Amendments of 1988<br />

The Clinical Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988 (CLIA) was designed to ensure<br />

that clinical laboratories around the country meet minimal quality and safety standards. It also<br />

imposes minimal requirements on the professional qualifications of laboratory personnel. In<br />

essence, CLIA’s mandate is to guarantee that tests performed on human tissues and materials<br />

provide accurate and reliable information “for the diagnosis, prevention, or treatment of any<br />

disease.” As this brief description already indicates, CLIA is very unlikely to reach actual<br />

practices of reproductive medicine; the statute applies exclusively to clinical tests “for the<br />

diagnosis, prevention, or treatment of any disease ... or the assessment of the health of human<br />

beings.” 19 For example, CLIA would reach testing of semen and ova, but not the actual IVF<br />

treatment. CLIA would presumably extend to PGD (the procedure of extracting and testing a cell<br />

from an early-stage embryo), but it certainly does not provide a statutory basis for crafting<br />

guidelines aimed at informing when performing PGD may or may not be appropriate. As for<br />

research laboratories, to the extent that they do not offer clinical services, they are explicitly<br />

exempt from compliance with CLIA.<br />

CLIA clearly was not designed to resolve controversies produced by new reproductive<br />

technologies or novel research protocols. Scholars seem to agree that CLIA so far has been<br />

ineffectual even in ensuring the effectiveness of genetic tests. 20 Others have noted that the Center<br />

for Medicare and Medicaid Services (CMS), which administers this statute, has been plagued<br />

with monitoring and enforcement problems. This is hardly surprising, given that according to<br />

CMS as of December of 2003, there were 184,000 laboratories in the United States. Monitoring<br />

19<br />

20<br />

See 42 U.S.C. 263a(a) (1994).<br />

Lori B. Andrews, "A Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy: Comparing the Medical, Public Health and<br />

Fundamental Rights Models," Washington University Law Quarterly 79 (2001), p.256-57; Anny Huang, "FDA<br />

Regulation of Genetic Testing: Institutional Reluctance and Public Guardianship," Food and Drug Law Journal<br />

53 (1998); Michael J. Malinowski and Robin J.R. Blatt, "Commercialization of Genetic Testing Services: The<br />

FDA, Market Forces, and Biological Tarot Cards," Tulane Law Review 71 (1997).<br />

122


and enforcement difficulties can partly be explained by the fact that CLIA merely requires labs<br />

to identify themselves for certification. It appears that many sm<strong>all</strong> labs are not aware of this<br />

requirement. Compliance rates, while improving over time, remain a concern, especi<strong>all</strong>y among<br />

physician office labs.<br />

To the extent that CLIA reaches embryology and other laboratories that perform clinical<br />

tests for ART clinics, this statute could serve as a useful tool for monitoring and quality<br />

assurance, assuming that a sufficient proportion of <strong>all</strong> embryology and andrology labs have<br />

indeed registered with the program. What makes CLIA relevant to our discussion is not the<br />

statute per se, but the administering agency. CMS, if adequately funded, could be a suitable<br />

administrative host for a newly created regulatory agency. Unlike NIH, CMS does not have<br />

strong institutional ties to the scientific community. Nor does it have strong ties to the ART<br />

sector, as the CDC does. In addition, CMS and the biotech industry do not have a history of<br />

collaboration. CMS does, however, have considerable expertise in regulating a large, dispersed<br />

and diverse population of laboratories, and it would clearly have the scientific and medical<br />

expertise to carry out this task in an efficient manner.<br />

5.1.4 Institutional Review Boards and Human Subject Protection<br />

It is no exaggeration to say that scientists, ART specialists, and biotech companies – not to<br />

mention many ethicists – tend to view institutional review boards as a panacea for resolving any<br />

and every ethical controversy. Congress often shares this assumption. Recent Congressional bills<br />

such as Senate Bill S. 303 require IRB approval for research protocols involving stem cells,<br />

probably on the assumption that an IRB review would take care of the surrounding controversies.<br />

Some reasonable prima facie arguments can indeed be offered for relying on IRBs as a<br />

means to untangle ethical controversies. IRBs are a decentralized and flexible system of<br />

decision-making. To many scientists in academia and in the private sector, they are highly<br />

preferable to a rigid and slow-moving federal bureaucracy. According to this view, IRBs are in a<br />

much better position to take into account highly contingent factors and local peculiarities that a<br />

federal system of oversight, by its very nature, would be forced to ignore. In addition, affected<br />

organizations such as research hospitals, universities, and biotech companies are <strong>all</strong> very familiar<br />

with this system of review. 21<br />

In our view, most of these arguments do not stand up to closer scrutiny. Before delving into<br />

this discussion, however, a brief discussion of the IRB review system is necessary. There are two<br />

distinct but very similar sets of FDA regulations governing experimentation on human subjects<br />

and the establishment of an IRB: The “Common Rule” has jurisdiction over feder<strong>all</strong>y funded<br />

21<br />

This view is based largely on past experience with clinical ethics consultations. See, for example, Susan B.<br />

Rubin and Laurie Zoloth, "Clinical Ethics and the Road Less Taken: Mapping the Future by Tracking the Past,"<br />

Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (2004). In the context of clinical consultations on highly private matters,<br />

this position is commendable. We are far from convinced that the same approach is viable in the context of<br />

modern-day biomedical research.<br />

123


clinical research, 22 while the FDA has its own set of regulations governing privately funded<br />

clinical trials. 23 Many of the observations in the remainder of this section apply to both sets of<br />

regulations.<br />

A first important observation is that both regulations define research in very narrow and<br />

technical terms. Consider, for example, how the Common Rule defines research: “Research<br />

means a systematic investigation, including research development, testing, and evaluation,<br />

designed to develop or contribute to generalizable knowledge.” 24 While this is certainly an<br />

acceptable definition of research, it is a very narrow one. Experimental medical procedures such<br />

as those often performed in the ART industry would not fit this definition of research, as they are<br />

not performed for the purpose of contributing to generalizable knowledge and they can hardly be<br />

described as “systematic investigations.” 25 In addition, they are gener<strong>all</strong>y not funded by the<br />

federal government. 26 As for controversial research protocols, they often do involve human<br />

subjects, but only in a marginal sense of this term. To the extent that reproductive tissues are<br />

obtained from human donors, human subjects would indeed be involved in research. For<br />

example, the donation of embryos, oocytes, and sperm would require free and informed consent,<br />

and would therefore trigger an IRB review. We certainly do not want to minimize the importance<br />

of this review, but it must be said that reviewing informed consent forms simply will not reassure<br />

the critics of experiments involving human reproductive tissues. On the other end, current<br />

regulations would be wholly inadequate to address the health, safety, and ethical concerns raised<br />

by clinical trials involving inheritable genetic modifications, as for example in the case of the<br />

genetic modification of pre-implantation embryos. 27 In sum, neither the Common Rule nor 21<br />

C.F.R. 50 and 56 are likely to reach experimental reproductive procedures nor are research<br />

protocols themselves significantly affected by these regulations.<br />

Could IRBs be reformed so as to become an effective and credible institution for the<br />

adjudication of controversial ethical disputes? Technic<strong>all</strong>y yes, but practic<strong>all</strong>y no, if one<br />

22<br />

23<br />

24<br />

25<br />

26<br />

27<br />

See 45 C.F.R. 46.<br />

See 21 C.F.R. 50 and 56.<br />

See 45 C.F.R. Sec. 46.102 (d).<br />

There is an extensive literature on the distinction between medical research and medical experimental treatments.<br />

We are certainly not arguing that innovative medical procedures should always be subject to IRB review, nor<br />

that such procedures are not legitimate. Medicine remains in many ways an art, one that often requires medical<br />

practitioners to depart from standard medical practice. Surgery provides a striking illustration. On the other end,<br />

as we discuss in more detail in chapter 13, so-c<strong>all</strong>ed innovative treatments on occasion amount to little more than<br />

experimentation on human subjects free of any of the usual checks imposed on clinical trials. See Amer S.<br />

Ahmed, "The Last Twist of the Knife: Encouraging the Regulation of Innovative Surgical Procedures,"<br />

Columbia Law Review 105 (2005); Nancy M.P. King, "The Line between Clinical Innovation and Human<br />

Experimentation," Seton H<strong>all</strong> Law Review 32 (2002); Lars Noah, "Informed Consent and the Elusive Dichotomy<br />

between Standard and Experimental Therapy," American Journal of Law and Medicine 28 (2002).<br />

Federal funding of embryo research has been prohibited since 1996. Research on eggs and sperm is not subject<br />

to this ban.<br />

For an in-depth discussion, see Rebecca Dresser, "Genetic Modification of Preimplantation Embryos: Toward<br />

Adequate Human Research Policies," Milbank Quarterly 82, no. 1 (2004).<br />

124


considers the scope and depth of the necessary changes. Consider first the central task an IRB is<br />

c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to perform – namely, the evaluation of the risk and benefits of research on human<br />

subjects. First, the legal definition of research would have to be broadened. Second, the scope of<br />

IRB review would have to be updated. For instance, the Common Rule currently limits the scope<br />

of the risks IRBs are required to consider: “The IRB should not consider possible long-range<br />

effects of applying knowledge gained in the research (for example, the possible effects of the<br />

research on public policy) as among those research risks that f<strong>all</strong> within the purview of its<br />

responsibility.” 28<br />

This qualification <strong>all</strong> but precludes IRBs from including broader societal<br />

concerns as described in <strong>chapters</strong> 2 and 4. Third, the rules governing the appointments to an IRB<br />

would have to undergo fundamental changes. IRBs consist largely of scientists and clinicians.<br />

While the regulations governing the establishment and operation of IRBs require that at least one<br />

individual with no connections to science and medicine be included, this is hardly a guarantee of<br />

a broad and balanced examination of ethical concerns.<br />

How the appointment rules could be modified so as to broaden the range and depth of<br />

ethical views represented on an IRB is not entirely clear. The inclusion of bioethicists is a first<br />

necessary but by no means sufficient step. As we show in more detail in chapter 10.2,<br />

professional bioethicists and the general public take very different approaches to evaluating<br />

controversial medical procedures. 29 These differences cannot easily be reconciled or ignored.<br />

Broadening the participation to include laypersons is probably another necessary step, but the<br />

implementation of this requirement is fraught with conceptual and practical difficulties. In sum,<br />

the scope and depth of the necessary reforms are so significant as to require a fundamental<br />

redesign of the IRB system of review.<br />

Commentators have also noted several operational problems affecting the current system. 30<br />

Decision-making procedures within IRBs are a major source of concern. IRBs do not provide a<br />

written justification for their decisions, and their meetings gener<strong>all</strong>y are not public. Individual<br />

IRB members are not required to explain their positions; assessments of risks and benefits often<br />

are impressionistic. Minutes are available, but they are rarely detailed enough to provide insight<br />

into the decision-making process. 31 Minimal procedural standards <strong>all</strong> but ensure that in similar<br />

cases, IRBs will produce inconsistent results. In sum, IRBs do not operate according to<br />

28<br />

29<br />

30<br />

31<br />

See 45 C.F.R. Sec. 46.102 (d).<br />

Susan L. Erikson, "Post-Diagnostic Abortion in Germany: Reproduction Gone Awry, Again?," Social Science &<br />

Medicine 56 (2003); Jackie Leach Sculley, Christine Rippberger, and Christoph Rehmann-Sutter, "Non-<br />

Professional Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics," Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004); Wertz et al., "Has<br />

Patient Autonomy Gone Too Far? Geneticists' Views in 36 Nations."<br />

Carl H. Coleman, "Rationalizing Risk Assessment in Human Subject Research," Arizona Law Review 46 (2004);<br />

Ezekiel J. Emanuel et al., "Oversight of Human Participants Research: Identifying Problems to Evaluate Reform<br />

Proposals," Annals of Internal Medicine 141, no. 4 (2004); General Accounting Office, "Scientific Research:<br />

Continued Vigilance Critical to Protecting Human Subjects," (Washington, D.C.: GAO/HEHS publication no.<br />

GAO/HEHS-96-72, 1996).<br />

Coleman, "Rationalizing Risk Assessment in Human Subject Research."<br />

125


principles of good governance as federal regulatory agencies or administrative law judges are<br />

required to do.<br />

5.1.5 Federal Funding of Embryo Research<br />

A major obstacle to improving the safety and effectiveness of ART treatments and to<br />

conducting advanced medical research is the Congressional ban on federal funding of embryo<br />

research. This prohibition came in the form of an amendment to the Health and Human Services<br />

Appropriation Bill of 1996, the so-c<strong>all</strong>ed Dickey-Wicker Amendment. The amendment has been<br />

reauthorized every year since its introduction, and there is no indication that Congress will lift<br />

this ban soon. 32<br />

Some commentators regard this ban as the only ethical position consistent with the<br />

government’s strong preference for the respect of nascent human life. This may seem at first a<br />

coherent attitude. On closer examination, however, this policy also has produced ethical<br />

contradictions. If respect for nascent human life is of paramount importance, it cannot be<br />

acceptable for the U.S. government to simply ignore privately funded experimentation on human<br />

embryos. The U.S. government has not legalized or otherwise endorsed privately funded<br />

research, but this lack of enthusiasm certainly has not prevented many biotech companies from<br />

conducting research on human embryos, activities that a consistent ethical position should<br />

explicitly condemn.<br />

From a practical standpoint, the ban on funding human embryo research has had some<br />

perverse consequences. In <strong>all</strong> likelihood, the Dickey-Wicker Amendment has kept medical<br />

technology from improving ART success rates, and therefore has contributed to the creation and<br />

destruction of more human embryos than absolutely necessary. It has also undermined efforts to<br />

better understand the causes of infertility, and probably hindered the development of more<br />

effective ART techniques. These unintended consequences have most likely increased rather<br />

than diminished the instrumental use of human embryos.<br />

Perhaps most importantly, with this ban, the government has lost its ability to oversee<br />

embryo research in the private sector. Elected officials may still find that the Dickey-Wicker<br />

Amendment is the only defensible ethical position in this matter, but they should come to this<br />

conclusion after taking into account both the intended and unintended consequences of this<br />

position.<br />

5.1.6 The National Organ Transplantation Act<br />

The National Organ Transplantation Act of 1984 makes it “unlawful for any person to<br />

knowingly acquire, receive, or otherwise transfer any human organ for valuable consideration for<br />

use in human transplantation if the transfer affects interstate commerce.” 33 The act defines the<br />

meaning of “human organ” in very broad terms. It includes, among other things, fetal tissues<br />

32<br />

33<br />

As, for example, in the most recent appropriation bill, S. 2810, Sec. 510.<br />

See 42 USCS 274e (2004)(a).<br />

126


and/or any organs derived from human fetuses. It also establishes substantial penalties for<br />

violating its provisions. However, legal scholars agree that this act does not reach the trade of<br />

human gametes. It appears that no judicial decision has ever construed the meaning of “human<br />

organ” to include gametes. 34<br />

Hence, for the purpose of this report, the National Organ<br />

Transplantation Act is immaterial.<br />

5.1.7 Regulation by Tort<br />

Conceivably, the practice of reproductive medicine could also be regulated through the tort<br />

system. Malpractice litigation is based on the notion that a plaintiff, in order to prevail, must<br />

demonstrate that he or she is owed a duty of care, and that the attending physician has harmed<br />

the plaintiff by violating this duty. Combined with often-draconian verdicts, this system is<br />

supposed to induce medical professionals to establish appropriate standards of care and to ensure<br />

that practitioners follow them scrupulously.<br />

An obvious limitation of this system is its focus on procedures rather than on the merits of<br />

an expected outcome. For example, whether sex selection for non-therapeutic uses is an ethic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

acceptable reproductive procedure cannot be decided through tort litigation. Litigation in this<br />

case can only determine whether a patient was harmed, and whether harm can be attributed to<br />

medical malpractice. In the case of many ethic<strong>all</strong>y controversial treatments, making these twin<br />

determinations is no easy task. For example, is it re<strong>all</strong>y possible to claim that failure to deliver a<br />

baby of the desired sex amounts to medical malpractice? Certainly the “outcome” was undesired,<br />

but can a baby of the “wrong” sex re<strong>all</strong>y produce harm? Assuming some notion of harm is<br />

recognized by the court, what standard of care has been violated in this case?<br />

One can easily imagine many variations on this scenario. Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

to screen for dreadful diseases and ooplasm transfer to treat extreme cases of infertility provide<br />

two examples. How the courts may decide these cases is an interesting question for legal scholars<br />

to ponder, but it is beyond the scope of the present discussion. Presumably, litigation in this area<br />

would prompt ART clinics to scrutinize more carefully the harm that novel reproductive<br />

technologies and innovative treatments might cause and to establish appropriate standards of<br />

care. 35<br />

This development certainly would be most welcome, but standards of care <strong>all</strong> by<br />

themselves are of little importance in adjudicating competing ethical claims.<br />

5.1.8 Regulation by the Market<br />

Regulation can occur through market mechanisms as well. There are many precedents in this<br />

area. Consumers may prefer products certified to have been produced in an environment<strong>all</strong>y<br />

34<br />

35<br />

President's Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New Biotechnologies,<br />

p.151-52.<br />

In recent times, serious doubts have emerged about the effectiveness of malpractice litigation in improving<br />

medical standards of care. An excellent introduction to this issue is Atul Gawande, Complications: Decisions<br />

and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life (London: Profile Books, 2002).<br />

127


sustainable way. Examples include chocolate, coffee, fruits, vegetables, and furniture. In other<br />

cases, the products in questions have been manufactured in accordance with broadly accepted<br />

social standards. The textile and toy industries have made significant efforts in this area. 36 A key<br />

reason for the success of these initiatives is the very active role played by international<br />

nongovernmental groups. It is also fair to say that despite unresolved questions of legitimacy, the<br />

social and environmental causes advanced by these groups are broadly in line with consumers’<br />

preferences in industrialized countries. Unfortunately, this is not the case with consumer groups<br />

associated with the ART industry. Groups like the National Infertility Association (known as<br />

RESOLVE) and the American Fertility Association (AFA) espouse what may be described as a<br />

purely self-interested perspective on many issues associated with reproductive technologies. For<br />

example, in its response to early drafts of the President’s Council on Bioethics report,<br />

“Reproduction and Responsibility,” RESOLVE made it quite clear that access to reproductive<br />

technologies and the cost of reproductive services eclipse any consideration pertaining to the<br />

health and well-being of children:<br />

[…] At the outset, it must be stated that additional reporting requirements necessarily increase the<br />

costs of providing treatment for infertility, and these costs will be borne by patients. We do not<br />

support additional reporting requirements that will further burden the medical profession, making<br />

fertility treatment more expensive for patients and less accessible to them, without providing<br />

substantial benefits for the patients.<br />

[…] While always concerned about material side effects of treatments, RESOLVE believes it is<br />

too soon to launch mandatory reporting until it is known through ongoing and proposed studies<br />

that the risks are substantial enough to justify burdening doctors and raising what may be needless<br />

concerns in patients. 37<br />

In this case at least, it is clear that public interest groups cannot be expected to advance the<br />

public interest.<br />

5.2 Recent Legislative Initiatives<br />

5.2.1 Congressional Initiatives<br />

Over the last few years, most OECD (Organisation for Economic Co-operation and<br />

Development) countries have passed legislation in the areas of new reproductive technologies<br />

and biomedical research. Many Asian countries also have crafted or are in the process of crafting<br />

new laws in this area. Only one country so far has failed to take any legislative measures – the<br />

United States. To some extent, the legislative gridlock in this area is a direct consequence of the<br />

U.S. system of divided government. According to the Center for Public Integrity in Washington,<br />

36<br />

37<br />

See, for example, Peter F<strong>all</strong>on and Zafiris Tzannatos, "Child Labor: Issues and Directions for the World Bank,"<br />

in Social Protection, Human Development Network (Washington, D.C.: The World Bank, 1998); Charles Sabel,<br />

Dara O'Rourke, and Archon Fung, "Ratcheting Labor Standards: Regulation for Continuous Improvements in the<br />

Global Workplace," (John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University, 2000).<br />

A letter dated October 2, 2003, from RESOLVE Board Chairperson Vicki Baldwin to the President’s Council on<br />

Bioethics on an early draft of the report. Letter on file with the authors.<br />

128


D.C., since 2001, the Congress has attempted more than 40 times to pass legislation related to<br />

cloning and stem cell research. 38 None of these initiatives has become law. A review of the<br />

legislation proposed since 2001 shows that the proposed bills f<strong>all</strong> in two main categories. Many<br />

legislative proposals simply aim at prohibiting any kind of cloning research, independently of its<br />

purpose. In the second category, we find bills that explicitly ban and often criminalize cloning<br />

for reproductive purposes, but legalize research cloning.<br />

We believe that none of these bills represents an adequate response to current ethical<br />

controversies. Broad legislative bans are too blunt a response in light of the need to make fine<br />

distinctions between acceptable and unacceptable applications of new reproductive technologies<br />

and medical research. On the other hand, distinguishing between reproductive and research<br />

cloning is only the first step toward addressing ethical controversies, of which many more would<br />

remain unresolved. To appreciate just how narrow the focus of legislative debates in the United<br />

States has been, one only needs to compare the scope of U.S. legislative efforts with legislative<br />

proposals in other OECD countries. As Table 16 and Table 17 in Appendix H demonstrate, most<br />

European and Asian countries have found it necessary to provide legal guidance not only for<br />

cloning research, but also for embryo research, pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (and sex<br />

selection), the creation of chimerical animals and hybrids, germ-line genetic engineering,<br />

reproductive services, and the trade of human gametes. By contract, the United States is the only<br />

country that has enacted little or no legislation in most of these areas.<br />

5.2.2 Senate Bill 303<br />

In this section, we examine in some detail Senate Bill 303, a bill that has been praised by<br />

many as a reasonable legislative answer to the current legislative gridlock over cloning research,<br />

but has been opposed in the Senate by pro-life legislators. S. 303 was passed by the House of<br />

Representatives and referred to the Senate Judiciary Committee in 2003, where it has been<br />

languishing ever since. Its official title is the “Human Cloning Ban and Stem Cell Research<br />

Protection Act of 2003.” As the name suggests, it consists of two distinct parts, Title I, the<br />

“Prohibition of Human Cloning,” and Title II, “Ethical Requirements for Nuclear<br />

Transplantation Research.”<br />

Title I is a straightforward ban on reproductive cloning. It instructs the Department of<br />

Justice to adopt measures to detect possible violations, in collaborations with state and local<br />

authorities. Penalties for performing or attempting to perform human reproductive cloning are<br />

among the most severe in the world – imprisonment for up to ten years and a fine of up to a<br />

million dollars. Section 102(a) instructs the Justice Department, among other things, to prepare<br />

and submit a report to the Senate Judiciary Committee that describes the actions taken by the<br />

Attorney General to enforce the ban on reproductive cloning.<br />

Which measures the Justice Department would have taken to ensure compliance we will<br />

never know. It could have required any individual or institution that plans to conduct research<br />

38<br />

See Appendix D for an overview.<br />

129


cloning to register with the Department, as proposed by earlier bills. Alternatively, it could have<br />

conducted random inspections, in cooperation with the states, as it does in enforcing<br />

environmental statutes. What is clear is that S. 303 does not explicitly require the Justice<br />

Department to design and implement a robust system of embryo registration and tracking. Nor is<br />

it clear that the bill would have authorized the Justice Department to implement such a system.<br />

In sum, S. 303 offers insufficient guarantees to opponents of reproductive cloning that if nuclear<br />

transplantation research were to be legalized, the Justice Department would have had both the<br />

legal authority and the administrative resources to prevent and to sanction abuses. Without a<br />

comprehensive system of oversight, the legal distinction between reproductive and research<br />

cloning is not credible.<br />

Title II establishes a legal framework for conducting research cloning, in this bill referred to<br />

as “nuclear transplantation research.” Specific<strong>all</strong>y, Section 499A(b) requires that nuclear<br />

transplantation research be reviewed by an institutional review board, and that informed consent<br />

be obtained from the human subjects involved in the research, most notably from the women<br />

donating their oocytes. Section 499A(d) limits the use of and experimentation on “unfertilized<br />

blastocysts” – i.e., on cloned embryos up to 14 days old – and prohibits their purchase or sale.<br />

IRB review and informed consent clearly are meant to reassure critics that nuclear<br />

transplantation research would be conducted in accordance with strict ethical standards.<br />

For those who believe that embryos have the same moral status as newborn infants, S. 303<br />

simply is unacceptable, whether or not the bill includes appropriate legal safeguards; it<br />

legitimizes embryo research, legalizes the destruction of embryos, and paves the way for federal<br />

funding of research in this area. As noted in the introductory chapter, this is not our position. We<br />

believe that embryos have an intermediate moral status, and that research on embryos is mor<strong>all</strong>y<br />

acceptable if appropriate legal safeguards are put in place. Unfortunately, from an administrative<br />

and regulatory standpoint, Title II f<strong>all</strong>s short of providing a legal framework capable of<br />

reassuring a skeptical public. As we have shown earlier in this chapter, IRBs are wholly<br />

unsuitable to review ethic<strong>all</strong>y controversial research proposals. In addition, Title II does not<br />

make any provisions for the establishment of an embryo tracking system, in the shape of either a<br />

reporting or a licensing scheme. One may argue that it would have been the Justice Department’s<br />

responsibility to ensure that nuclear transplantation is conducted exclusively for research<br />

purposes, but as we have shown above, Senate Bill 303 is in this regard too generic and quite<br />

possibly inadequate.<br />

In sum, far from being a reasonable compromise, S. 303 would <strong>all</strong>ow the research<br />

community to move forward with highly controversial research with only minimal legal<br />

oversight. S. 303 simply does not provide a credible institutional mechanism for resolving the<br />

inevitable controversies that any research protocol involving nuclear transplantation would<br />

generate, nor does it require the adoption of effective safeguards against possible abuses.<br />

Compare this legislative proposal with the situation in Britain. Critics on this side of the<br />

Atlantic have argued that the British approach is too permissive. The American scientific<br />

community, for its part, considers the British regulatory system too cumbersome and<br />

130


ureaucratic. As we discuss in more detail in chapter 6.4, reproductive cloning in Britain is<br />

prohibited, but research cloning is legal. Any research protocol involving nuclear transplantation<br />

must obtain a license from the Human Fertilization and Embryology Authority, which closely<br />

scrutinizes the rationale for conducting research on human embryos in general, and for research<br />

cloning in particular. This provision alone is likely to make the HFEA unacceptable to the<br />

American scientific community. Yet ironic<strong>all</strong>y, in October of 2004, the HFEA approved the first<br />

research protocol involving nuclear transplantation. The decision was far from uncontroversial.<br />

Pro-life groups voc<strong>all</strong>y denounced it, but were eventu<strong>all</strong>y forced to recognize that the HFEA had<br />

acted according to the laws of the country. As a result, a research group in Britain is now moving<br />

forward with a cloning protocol backed by the full force of the law – despite, or perhaps thanks<br />

to, a regulatory system considered by American observers to be too intrusive.<br />

5.2.3 Legislative Initiatives at the State Level<br />

Our discussion of state-level initiatives is not meant to be exhaustive. After examining<br />

various state-level legislative initiatives, we have come to the conclusion that there is little to be<br />

learned from the states either in the area of reproductive medicine or biomedical research. As<br />

several commentators have recognized, few states have passed legislation concerning<br />

reproductive technologies, and even fewer cases are relevant to the present discussion.<br />

Of some interest is the approach taken by Louisiana to regulating reproductive medicine.<br />

Louisiana, certainly, is the state that has passed the most comprehensive legislation in this area,<br />

and also the most restrictive. Noteworthy in particular is the extensive legal protection afforded<br />

to the embryo, defined as a “juridical person” enjoying most of the legal rights and protections<br />

afforded to children. 39 More pertinent to the discussion is Louisiana reliance on the American<br />

Society for Reproductive Medicine and the American College of Obstetricians and<br />

Gynecologists (ACOG) to ensure that reproductive laboratories and facilities meet suitable<br />

standards of quality and consistency. This is an important precedent: It demonstrates that, as for<br />

other policy domains, it is both possible and sensible for regulators to rely on private standarddeveloping<br />

organizations to achieve public goals. 40 The case of Pennsylvania is also worth<br />

mentioning in this context, because it is to our knowledge the only state that has adopted<br />

extensive record-keeping requirements. Both Louisiana’s and Pennsylvania’s experience in<br />

regulating reproductive medicine could prove very valuable to federal regulators tasked with<br />

implementing similar schemes at the federal level.<br />

When it comes to the regulation of biomedical research, recent state-level initiatives closely<br />

follow federal patterns. They are narrowly focused on cloning and stem cell research, and just<br />

like the numerous federal bills introduced over the last few years, they either attempt to ban any<br />

39<br />

40<br />

President's Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New Biotechnologies,<br />

p.52-53.<br />

As we show in more detail in chapter 13.6, there are some good prima facie reasons for delegating certain<br />

functions to the private sector, including economic efficiency, flexibility, and access to technical and medical<br />

expertise.<br />

131


kind of cloning or they limit the ban to reproductive human cloning but fail to provide adequate<br />

safeguards for conducting research cloning. Among the states that have banned both<br />

reproductive and research cloning are Arkansas, Iowa, North Dakota, South Dakota, and<br />

Michigan. Many states have attempted to ban both kinds of cloning but have so far failed to pass<br />

any legislation. Virginia has banned reproductive cloning, but excluded research cloning from its<br />

ban. Rhode Island has adopted a similar measure, to expire in 2010. Some states, like Missouri,<br />

have merely banned state funding of research cloning. New Jersey is the only state that has<br />

passed legislation that explicitly bans reproductive cloning but legalizes research cloning.<br />

Unfortunately, the New Jersey law, just like Senate Bill 303, while acknowledging the<br />

controversial nature of this research, only requires research protocols to receive IRB approval,<br />

and does not include any other safeguards against possible abuses. 41<br />

California deserves a separate discussion. In 2003, the state of California banned<br />

reproductive cloning but legalized research cloning and embryonic stem cell research. California<br />

did go a step further, however. The state legislature required the California Department of Health<br />

and Human Services to establish an anonymous registry of embryos available for research, and<br />

specified in considerable detail the rules for disposing of these human embryos. The state<br />

legislature, however, made the registry’s implementation dependent on the availability of private<br />

funding. It also directed the state’s Health and Human Services Department to establish an<br />

advisory board responsible for crafting guidelines for embryonic stem cell research. In the f<strong>all</strong> of<br />

2003, then-Governor Gray Davis signed both bills into law. By any measure, this legislation was<br />

by far the most sophisticated attempt at banning reproductive cloning while providing reasonable<br />

safeguards to conducting research cloning.<br />

With the 2004 passage of Proposition 71 (the “California Stem Cell Research and Cures<br />

Act”), the situation has changed dramatic<strong>all</strong>y. Proposition 71 represents a radical departure from<br />

pre-existing legislation in this area. It requires the state of California to raise $3 billion, to be<br />

administered by a newly created California Institute for Regenerative Medicine (CIRM). An<br />

“Independent Citizen’s Oversight Committee” should ensure that the research funds are spent in<br />

conformance with the statute. Its label notwithstanding, the CIRM’s oversight committee<br />

involves neither citizens nor independent individuals. Its 29 members are drawn from the<br />

research institutions and biotech companies benefiting from the funding, and from various<br />

disease advocacy groups that are strong promoters of this kind of research. The initiative goes so<br />

far as to specify that no minority opinion can be issued unless 35 percent of the board votes in<br />

favor; the likelihood that 11 of 29 members would have true independence from the scientific<br />

community and the biotech industry is negligible, thus essenti<strong>all</strong>y muting any form of dissent.<br />

Like its legislative predecessors, Proposition 71 explicitly embraces research cloning, but<br />

makes no provisions for regulatory controls that would prevent, for example, a cloned embryo<br />

from being implanted in a woman’s uterus. Disturbingly, the initiative specific<strong>all</strong>y exempts<br />

California researchers from existing rules prohibiting experiments on embryos beyond eight to<br />

41<br />

See Appendix G for an overview of state legislative initiatives.<br />

132


12 days old, as well as safeguards for obtaining informed consent in human subject research. The<br />

initiative carefully removes virtu<strong>all</strong>y <strong>all</strong> institutional constraints that would interfere with the<br />

insiders doing what they want with the funds. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the state legislature is prohibited from<br />

amending the initiative for three years, and then only by a 70 percent margin, which makes it<br />

highly unlikely that it will be able to pass any changes. 42<br />

In sum, while the legislation passed by the California legislature in the f<strong>all</strong> of 2003 took<br />

some preliminary but promising steps to create appropriate legal safeguards for conducting<br />

cloning research, Proposition 71 was written in a way that <strong>all</strong> but ensures that the scientific<br />

community will be able to conduct highly controversial research at the taxpayer expense free of<br />

virtu<strong>all</strong>y any public oversight. Perhaps because the legislation was so poorly drafted, it has<br />

already been ch<strong>all</strong>enged in the courts and faces potenti<strong>all</strong>y crippling delays as a series of litigants<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enge various aspects of the proposition.<br />

5.3 Self-Regulatory Initiatives<br />

5.3.1 Introduction<br />

There is a tendency in many policy debates to consider regulatory interventions and selfregulatory<br />

programs mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive. Typic<strong>all</strong>y, industry representatives perceive federal and<br />

state regulations as burdensome and ineffective, and advocate self-regulation as a superior<br />

alternative. Public interest groups, policy-makers, and many academics also subscribe to the<br />

view that government regulation and industry self-regulation are mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive, but<br />

interpret this observation in a diametric<strong>all</strong>y opposed way. In the view of these critics, selfregulation<br />

can be described as an elaborate public relation exercise meant to improve an<br />

industry’s public image and to prevent regulatory interventions. In the critics’ view, cases of<br />

credible self-regulation are simply too rare for self-regulation to be considered a credible<br />

regulatory option. Neither one of these characterizations is empiric<strong>all</strong>y accurate. As we show<br />

below, regulatory systems are almost always an amalgamation of legal requirements and private<br />

standards. Effective and responsive regulatory systems often are based on self-regulatory<br />

elements, an insight that will guide much of the discussion in chapter 13.6.<br />

In the remainder of this section, we first provide several examples of the hybrid nature of<br />

modern regulatory systems. We then examine in some detail the main components of the selfregulatory<br />

system as it exists in the ART industry. As it will quickly become apparent, these selfregulatory<br />

initiatives, while remarkable in their own right, <strong>all</strong> by themselves are incapable to<br />

credibly adjudicate broad societal disputes produced by new reproductive technologies. Properly<br />

integrated into a formal system of regulation, however, they could play a very important<br />

supporting role.<br />

42<br />

The Center for Genetics and Society has monitored the implementation of Proposition 71 from the start. For a<br />

detailed discussion see http://genetics-and-society.org/resources/cgs/20060118_cirm_press.html.<br />

133


The federal government has been relying on the private sector to meet its numerous public<br />

mandates in several ways. The Underwriters Laboratories (UL), for example, has long been<br />

responsible for testing and certifying the safety of electric appliances and devices. The UL plays<br />

a quasi-autonomous regulatory role, the credibility of which is ensured in part (but not<br />

exclusively) by the tort system. UL is not an exceptional case, however. Just about every sector<br />

of the economy has developed safety standards. Some of the most familiar examples include fire<br />

safety codes developed by the National Fire Protection Association, health and safety standards<br />

for cosmetics promulgated by the U.S. Pharmacopeia, and the innumerable standards developed<br />

by American Society for Testing and Materials. 43<br />

In other cases, the government sets broad public goals but <strong>all</strong>ows the private sector to<br />

determine how to achieve them. Emission trading systems are a case in point. The Environmental<br />

Protection Agency (EPA) sets an over<strong>all</strong> environmental goal – for example, the total volume of<br />

sulfur dioxide emissions produced by coal-burning electric plants – but leaves it to the market to<br />

find the most cost-effective way to achieve this goal. Another example is Project XL, launched<br />

by the EPA in 1995 as part of the Clinton administration’s efforts to improve government<br />

services. 44 Under this program, industrial plants with multiple pollution sources can apply for a<br />

single permit if they demonstrate that they can reduce their over<strong>all</strong> emission volume. More<br />

prosaic perhaps but just as relevant is the case of the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and<br />

Certification Act discussed in section 5.1.1 above. As the agency responsible for administering<br />

FCSRCA, the CDC has delegated the responsibility for gathering ART success rates to a private<br />

group, the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology.<br />

The federal government has a long record of adopting privately developed standards. One of<br />

the most spectacular examples is the Occupational Safety and Health Administration’s wholesale<br />

adoption of private health and safety standards soon after its creation. 45 Another example is the<br />

Nuclear Regulatory Commission’s incorporation of its books of safety standards developed by<br />

the Nuclear Energy Institute, an industry trade association. FCSRCA was in large part an<br />

exercise in the codification of an already existing practice, namely the annual survey of success<br />

rates conducted by SART. SART began gathering information about success rates on a voluntary<br />

basis in 1989, and has been publishing the results in the journal Fertility and Sterility ever since.<br />

FCSRCA improved the SART surveys in several ways – by providing a consistent definition of<br />

success rate, by making reporting of success rates to the CDC mandatory, and more recently, by<br />

43<br />

44<br />

45<br />

Harry S. Gerla, "Federal Antitrust Law and Trade and Professional Association Standards and Certification,"<br />

Dayton Law Review 19 (1994); Samuel Krislov, How Nations Choose Product Standards and Standards Change<br />

Nations (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1997).<br />

Dennis D. Hirsch, "Project XL and the Special Case: The EPA's Untold Success Story," Columbia Journal of<br />

Environmental Law 26 (2001); Lawrence E. Susskind and Joshua Secunda, "The Risks and the Advantages of<br />

Agency Discretion: Evidence from EPA's Project XL," UCLA Journal of Environmental Law and Policy 17<br />

(1998).<br />

That many of these standards were more effective at protecting the competitive position of their private<br />

developers than at achieving their purported goal is a sobering lesson about the pitf<strong>all</strong>s of blind trust in the<br />

virtues of the private enterprise.<br />

134


conducting targeted inspections of fertility clinics aimed at verifying the accuracy of the<br />

information provided.<br />

FCSRCA demonstrates that, far from being mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive, the credibility and<br />

effectiveness of self-regulatory programs can be improved through formal regulation. It also<br />

shows that much federal regulation is based directly on self-regulatory standards. At the same<br />

time, the preceding discussion also suggests that self-regulation, <strong>all</strong> by itself, is neither<br />

sufficiently credible nor very effective, an observation that carries over to the ART industry, to<br />

which we now turn.<br />

5.3.2 Self-Regulation in the ART Industry<br />

In this section, we describe in some detail the ART industry’s system of self-regulation. The<br />

discussion has two main purposes. We show that self-regulation in this sector cannot simply be<br />

considered a public relations scheme designed to prevent regulatory action. Self-regulation<br />

consists of an extensive network of private organizations that has promulgated numerous<br />

standards pertaining to medical practice, and has issued many ethical recommendations. To put it<br />

bluntly, self-regulation in the ART industry should be taken seriously. However, while our<br />

discussion will demonstrate that self-regulation is an incomplete system of governance, backed<br />

by the power of the state, the ART industry system of self-regulation could become both a<br />

credible and an effective system of regulation.<br />

American Society for Reproductive Medicine. The ASRM is the leading professional group<br />

representing the industry interests at the national level. ASRM has approximately 9,000<br />

members, 25 percent of which are international. Its members include not only reproductive<br />

physicians, but also scientists, nurses, and other specialists whom, taken together, cover OB-<br />

GYN, urology, psychiatry, andrology, and embryology. Each major professional specialty in the<br />

industry is organized into a separate professional society. There are three major professional<br />

groups – the Society for Reproductive Endocrinology and Infertility (SREI), the Society of<br />

Reproductive Surgeons (SRS), and the Society of Male Reproduction and Urology (SMRU).<br />

The ASRM offers services typical of any professional association: It lobbies federal and<br />

state representatives on behalf of its members; it offers professional education and certification;<br />

it has a well-established and extensive record of developing standards and guidelines pertaining<br />

to the practice of reproductive medicine; and it has developed health and safety standards and<br />

operating procedures pertaining to embryo labs. Importantly, it also has adopted consensus<br />

recommendations on numerous controversial ethical questions.<br />

The governance structure of ASRM consists of an executive committee, three standing<br />

committees, and 26 appointed committees. Two committees, the practice committee and the<br />

ethics committee, are of particular relevance to the present discussion. Both are appointed<br />

committees. According to Sandra Carson, former ASRM president, the ethics committee<br />

135


includes ethicists, scientists, mental health care providers, lawyers, and members of the general<br />

public. 46<br />

Table 2 and Table 3 illustrate the scope of the ASRM system of self-regulation. As these<br />

tables clearly demonstrate, over the years, ASRM has adopted guidelines and recommendations<br />

on many issues raised by the practice of reproductive medicine. Remarkably, these<br />

recommendations are often quite specific. For example, ASRM discourages pre-implantation<br />

genetic diagnosis for elective sex selection; it also does not recommend post-menopausal<br />

pregnancies through oocyte donation, and it is strongly opposed to reproductive cloning. On<br />

other, critical issues such as the number of embryos to be transferred during IVF, ASRM has<br />

adopted a more flexible position: It recommends transferring two embryos in favorable cases,<br />

four embryos in the case of “average” prognosis, and five embryos for women with a “poor”<br />

prognosis.<br />

Guidelines<br />

Year of publication<br />

Position Statement on West Nile Virus 2005<br />

Ovarian Tissue and Oocyte Cryopreservation 2004<br />

Position Statement on Donor Suitability of Recipients of<br />

2004<br />

Sm<strong>all</strong>pox Vaccine<br />

Estrogen and Progestogen Therapy in Postmenopausal<br />

2004<br />

Women<br />

Round Spermatid Nucleus Injection (ROSNI) 2003<br />

Clomiphene Citrate Use in Women 2003<br />

Salpingectomy for Hydrosalpinx Prior to IVF 2001 (reviewed 2003)<br />

Table 2: Recent guidelines published by ASRM/SART. 47<br />

The recommendations on the number of embryos to be transferred provide an excellent<br />

illustration of the strengths and weaknesses of self-regulation. ASRM could have adopted a rigid,<br />

universal rule as did the British legislation. For example, it could have recommended that no<br />

more than two embryos be transferred, in any case. Instead, ASRM in this case opted for<br />

flexibility. Flexibility gener<strong>all</strong>y protects the ART practitioners’ prerogative to take what is<br />

thought to be the most appropriate course of action – certainly a desirable feature. In this case,<br />

however, professional autonomy tends to operate in favor of the prospective parents and against<br />

the interests of future children. As discussed in Appendix C, a high number of simultaneously<br />

transferred embryos are responsible for most twins and higher-order pregnancies. Higher-order<br />

pregnancies are the single most important factor affecting the health of newborn babies – they<br />

are associated with serious health problems and are extremely costly. 48 For these reasons, many<br />

46<br />

47<br />

48<br />

Sandra Carson, Biotechnology and Public Policy: Professional Self-Regulation (Session 5, President's Council<br />

on Bioethics Meeting, March 7, 2003 [cited September 16, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/march03/session5.html.<br />

See Appendix E for a comprehensive list of published guidelines.<br />

L. Garceau et al., "Economic Implications of Assisted Reproductive Techniques: A Systematic Review," Human<br />

Reproduction 17, no. 12 (2002), p.3104-05; C Jones and R. Ward, "Cost-Minimization Analysis of One-, Two-,<br />

136


countries have imposed strict limits on the number of embryos that can leg<strong>all</strong>y be transferred. In<br />

this case at least, an inflexible rule that protect the health of ART children would seem preferable<br />

to a flexible approach that preserves professional autonomy and furthers the prospective parents’<br />

interests.<br />

Opinion<br />

Date of Publication<br />

Fertility treatment when the prognosis is very poor or futile 2004<br />

Child-rearing ability and the provision of fertility services 2004<br />

Informing offspring of their conception by gamete donation 2004<br />

Family members as gamete donors and surrogates 2003 (reviewed 2004)<br />

Donating spare embryos for embryonic stem-cell research 2002 (reviewed 2004)<br />

Table 3: Ethical opinions recently published by ASRM/SART. 49<br />

A crucial limitation of the ASRM system of self-regulation is the absence of any formal<br />

system of monitoring and compliance assurance. The ASRM does not monitor adherence to its<br />

recommendations, nor has it ever considered doing so. In this regard, ASRM is not unique. Most<br />

self-regulatory systems do not have formal mechanisms of oversight. There are two reasons for<br />

professional groups’ reluctance to adopt systems of compliance assurance. In the United States,<br />

trade and professional groups are very concerned that by taking enforcement action, they might<br />

violate anti-trust legislation. Judicial decisions in this area indicate that the reluctance to interfere<br />

with private business practices is indeed justified. 50 The second reason for this reluctance is<br />

organizational. Since the membership to a trade or professional group is usu<strong>all</strong>y voluntary, these<br />

groups have virtu<strong>all</strong>y no authority to ensure compliance with their guidelines; a member can<br />

easily avoid private regulatory strictures by leaving the association.<br />

American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists. Just like the ASRM, ACOG – the<br />

largest gynecology and obstetrics professional association in the United States – has issued<br />

several ethical opinions on questions ranging from surrogacy to embryo research. 51 And just like<br />

the ASRM ethical guidelines, ACOG opinions are meant to inform, not to constrain medical<br />

practice. Accordingly, ACOG does not monitor compliance assurance nor has it ever considered<br />

sanctioning violations, except for highly visible cases where inaction could seriously undermine<br />

the association’s credibility.<br />

49<br />

50<br />

51<br />

and Three-Embryo Transfers in IVF," in Triplet Pregnancies and Their Consequences, ed. Keith Louis G. and<br />

Blickstein Isaac (London: Parthenon Publishing Group, 2002).<br />

See Appendix F for a complete list of published ethical recommendations and links to the full-text articles.<br />

Jack R. Bierig, "Whatever Happened to Professional Self-Regulation?," American Bar Association Journal 69<br />

(1983); Gerla, "Federal Antitrust Law and Trade and Professional Association Standards and Certification.";<br />

Robert Heidt, "Industry Self-Regulation and the Useless Concept of 'Group Boycott'," Vanderbilt Law Review<br />

39, no. 6 (1986); Thomas A. Hemphill, "Self-Regulation Industry Behavior: Antitrust Limitations and Trade<br />

Association Codes of Conduct," Journal of Business Ethics 11 (1992); Murray S. Monroe, "Trade and<br />

Professional Associations: An Overview of Horizontal Restraints," University of Dayton Law Review 9, no. 3<br />

(1984).<br />

See http://www.acog.org/from%5Fhome/publications/ethics/.<br />

137


Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology. ASRM’s sister society, SART comprises<br />

most of the nation’s ART programs. According to the 2002 CDC report on ART success rates in<br />

the United States, there are 428 (reporting and non-reporting) ART programs. SART has a wellestablished<br />

history of self-regulation. In 1989, it started gathering data about success rates, which<br />

has been published every year since in the journal Fertility and Sterility. With the 1992 passage<br />

of FCSRCA, the CDC signed a memorandum of understanding that effectively delegated to<br />

SART the responsibility for conducting the annual survey of ART success rates. As of 1997,<br />

SART has been conducting random validation inspections to verify the accuracy of the reported<br />

data. In 2002, according to the CDC, SART inspected 30 of 391 reporting clinics. Discrepancies<br />

between reported data and medical records were quite limited, mostly below 1 percent. 52<br />

Reproductive Laboratory Accreditation Program. This program was developed by the<br />

College of American Pathologists in cooperation with ASRM and SART. The CAP has long<br />

played an important role in ensuring high standards of safety and quality at clinical laboratories<br />

around the country. Clinical laboratories are subject to the requirements of the Clinical<br />

Laboratory Improvement Amendments of 1988. The administering agency, the Center for<br />

Medicare and Medicaid Services, has contracted with third parties such as the CAP to perform<br />

tasks such as auditing and certification of clinical laboratories. The CAP does not merely<br />

perform compliance assurance; it has developed a full-fledged Laboratory Accreditation Program<br />

that meets or exceeds CLIA requirements. In 1992, in cooperation with ASRM, the CAP<br />

designed an accreditation program for embryo laboratories, the Reproductive Laboratory<br />

Accreditation Program (RLAP).<br />

A comparison of the FCSRCA model program and RLAP shows that FCSRCA has adopted<br />

and expanded most of the features of the CAP program. For example, RLAP establishes detailed<br />

professional prerequisites for the position of director and for the laboratory personnel; it also<br />

includes safety provisions, and describes the main components of a system of quality assurance<br />

and discusses the modality of certification and inspection. 53 Certification is valid for two years,<br />

and is renewable subject to inspection. Reproductive labs are required to audit themselves on a<br />

regular basis. Far less clear is whether CAP inspectors have actual enforcement authority. RLAP<br />

does not include sanctions of any kind, nor does it establish a schedule for correcting infractions<br />

or require RLAP inspectors to perform follow-up audits. In 1998, SART made RLAP<br />

accreditation mandatory for <strong>all</strong> its members. As a result, RLAP has achieved a very high level of<br />

certification. In 2002, the most recent year for which CDC data is available, 72 percent of <strong>all</strong><br />

reporting ART programs were CAP/ASRM accredited. 54<br />

52<br />

53<br />

54<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National<br />

Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," p.469-70.<br />

College of American Pathologists, "Reproductive Laboratory Accreditation Program – Standards for<br />

Accreditation," (Northfield, IL: 2004).<br />

Specific<strong>all</strong>y, of 403 reporting ART clinics in 2002, 289 were CAP/ASRM accredited. Cf. U.S. Department of<br />

Health and Human Services (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention), "2002 Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technology Success Rates. National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," (Atlanta, GA: 2004), Appendix C.<br />

138


As for other programs of self-regulation, it is extremely difficult for an external observer to<br />

determine whether RLAP is being properly implemented by ART clinics. Like any other trade<br />

association, SART does not consider itself a policing organization and does not impose fines or<br />

penalties. It emphasizes a collaborative approach to compliance; it considers violations the result<br />

of inadequate training rather than malfeasance, and encourages members with a poor compliance<br />

record to undergo additional training. 55 SART does have some authority over its members – it<br />

can exclude members found in violation of RLAP requirements. Industry officials have testified<br />

that over the last few years, SART has excluded more than 30 members, albeit mainly for failing<br />

to report to the national success rate registry. SART members have up to one year to remediate<br />

problems found during a RLAP inspection. Failure to correct problems can also trigger<br />

expulsion. 56<br />

SARS and ASRM, while certainly the most important, are not the only components of the<br />

industry system of self-governance. Several other professional and trade associations have<br />

developed their own systems of professional accreditation, and some of them have made<br />

accreditation conditional upon on-site inspection.<br />

Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO). The JCAHO<br />

may be regarded as an alternative to CAP. It is the largest accreditation organization in the health<br />

care sector and certifies nearly 16,000 health care organizations. JCAHO accredits a broad range<br />

of facilities offering laboratory services, including freestanding clinical laboratories and embryo<br />

laboratories. Its accreditation process is focused on health and quality, and covers surveillance,<br />

prevention, and control of infections, management of information and human resources,<br />

management of the laboratory environment, and quality control, among other things. 57<br />

JCAHO is governed by a 29-member board of commissioners, which is broadly<br />

representative of the health care sector and includes nurses, physicians, consumers, medical<br />

directors, administrators, providers, employers, a labor representative, health plan providers,<br />

quality experts, ethicists, a health insurance administrator, and educators. 58 The accreditation is<br />

limited to two years (for clinical laboratories), and is renewable subject to a survey. According to<br />

the 2001 CDC survey of ART success rates, 25 percent of reporting ART clinics are JCAHO<br />

certified, and many of them have both CAP and JCAHO accreditation.<br />

CAP and JCAHO provide a very similar service. Neither one of these organizations offer<br />

ethical opinions, of course, yet both could play a very important role in monitoring and ensuring<br />

compliance with government-mandated standards. In addition, they could greatly facilitate<br />

consulting with ART practitioners on controversial public policy issues. A similar mediating<br />

function could also be performed by professional organizations involved in the accreditation of<br />

various reproductive medicine professions, such as the American Association of Bioanalysts, the<br />

55<br />

56<br />

57<br />

58<br />

Carson, Biotechnology and Public Policy: Professional Self-Regulation ([cited September 16, 2005]).<br />

Ibid.([cited September 16, 2005).<br />

See http://www.jointcommission.org/AboutUs/joint_commission_facts.htm.<br />

Ibid.<br />

139


Reproductive Endocrinology Subspecialty Board of the Society for Reproductive Endocrinology<br />

and Infertility, the American Board of Obstetrics and Gynecology, and the American College of<br />

Obstetricians and Gynecologists.<br />

A promising approach to self-governance was the National Advisory Board on Ethics in<br />

Reproduction (NABER). NABER was created in 1991 by ACOG and ASRM. It then became<br />

independently incorporated. Before being disbanded in 1998 for lack of funding, it was regarded<br />

as broadly representative of various industry interests. Over the course if its existence, NABER<br />

published several highly regarded opinions on controversial biomedical developments. NABER<br />

is a perfect illustration of the precarious existence many bodies of self-governance are<br />

condemned to. Created by leading industry representatives out of concerns for the industry’s<br />

public image, it quickly became apparent that, absent a credible threat by the Congress to<br />

regulate the ART industry, NABER did not have the necessary authority to function as an<br />

impartial arbiter on ethical controversies of national import. Not surprisingly, the ART industry<br />

opposed NABER’s role as an independent regulator; in 1998, the organization simply ran out of<br />

funds. 59<br />

National Coalition for Oversight of Assisted Reproductive Technologies (NCOART). The<br />

National Coalition for Oversight of Assisted Reproductive Technologies is a little-known but<br />

potenti<strong>all</strong>y quite important institution of self-governance. Established in 1997 as a SART<br />

oversight committee, NCOART is a genuine example of a bridging institution 60 – it includes<br />

representatives of <strong>all</strong> industry interests, patient groups, and the government. NCOART has a<br />

well-defined governance structure that consists of two SART representatives (one clinical and<br />

one laboratory representative), an ASRM official, and a representative of RESOLVE, a leading<br />

national patient group. The committee chair rotates every two years between SART and<br />

RESOLVE. In addition to these voting members, NCOART includes liaison members<br />

representing the CDC, the FDA, and the Federal Trade Commission (FTC). Significantly,<br />

NCOART has the authority to spawn working groups; in addition to representatives of the<br />

aforementioned organizations, working group members can come from the American<br />

Association of Tissue Banks, the American Bar Association, and the American Fertility<br />

Association.<br />

Like other bridging institutions, NCOART does not regulate in the legal sense of the term.<br />

Rather, its main goal is to identify “issues” and to develop “recommendations” on any topic of<br />

paramount importance to the industry. While certainly not a regulatory body, NCOART could be<br />

instrumental in identifying possible sources of common concern, in promoting communication<br />

59<br />

60<br />

See Andrea Kalfoglou, "Looking Back, Looking Forward: The Legacy of the National Advisory Board on Ethics<br />

in Reproduction (NABER)," Women's Health Issues 10, no. 3 (2000). for an in-depth discussion of the NABER<br />

experience.<br />

Franco L. Furger, "Accountability and Self-Governance Systems: The Case of the Maritime Industry," Law &<br />

Policy 19, no. 4 (1997); Franco L. Furger, "Global Markets, New Games, New Rules: The Ch<strong>all</strong>enge of<br />

International Private Governance," in Rules and Networks. The Legal Culture of Global Business Transactions,<br />

ed. Richard P. Appelbaum, William L.F. Felstiner, and Volkmar Gessner (Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing,<br />

2001).<br />

140


and dialogue among <strong>all</strong> relevant industry segments, and in facilitating the development of<br />

consensual positions on many policy questions. Compared to other industry bodies of<br />

governance, such as ASRM and SART, NCOART authority seems modest. At the same time, the<br />

broad range of different interests represented within NCORT would make it an ideal candidate<br />

for advising a future regulatory agency. Regulators in turn could consider strengthening<br />

NCOART authority by delegating to it the responsibility for implementing monitoring and<br />

compliance assurance functions.<br />

5.3.3 Self-Regulation of Medical Research<br />

Scientists, just like their counterparts in the legal and medical professions, have long<br />

advocated and jealously protected their prerogative to be as free from governmental interference<br />

as possible, and the government has gener<strong>all</strong>y obliged. The rationale for granting scientists<br />

considerable latitude is straightforward: Science and technology are the engines of innovation on<br />

which the prosperity of industrialized nations is based. Excessive restrictions on the scientific<br />

enterprise could undermine both the prosperity and the competitiveness of nations. This is one of<br />

the reasons why top scientists invariably advocate self-regulation in response to c<strong>all</strong>s for direct<br />

regulatory interventions. Another is, of course, a general sense of uniqueness and even<br />

superiority toward members of the general public and political leaders. 61 What exactly scientists<br />

mean by self-regulation is often unclear, but one precedent seems to loom large in this debate –<br />

the Recombinant DNA Advisory Commission, or RAC.<br />

To many scientists, the RAC is proof that the scientific community is quite effective at<br />

regulating itself, if necessary. Unfortunately, the scientists’ faith in the RAC model is largely<br />

misplaced. The effectiveness of the RAC in dealing with the ch<strong>all</strong>enges raised by new<br />

recombinant DNA technologies can be attributed to contingent factors. As we show below,<br />

absent these highly idiosyncratic factors, the self-regulation of science is very likely to fail.<br />

As new and exciting techniques for cutting DNA molecules at specific locations and for<br />

inserting fragments from other DNA molecules were announced at the 1973 Gordon Conference<br />

– techniques that became known as recombinant DNA technologies – leading molecular<br />

biologists began to worry about possible public health risks. The spectrum of a hitherto unknown<br />

and dangerous strain of bacteria prompted leading scientists to c<strong>all</strong> for a moratorium, one the<br />

scientific community followed, albeit grudgingly so. The leaders in the field also c<strong>all</strong>ed for a<br />

conference to examine the risks associated with this new technology. The now famous Asilomar<br />

Conference in 1975 took place with the notable (though not welcomed) participation of the news<br />

media. One of the main concerns of the conference became how to ensure the safety of the newly<br />

developed recombinant DNA molecules. The conference participants crafted a set of provisional<br />

61<br />

The Workshop on “Guidelines for Conducting Embryonic Stem Cell Research,” organized the U.S. National<br />

Academies in the f<strong>all</strong> of 2004, is only the most recent illustration of the scientific community’s reluctance to<br />

accept societal restrictions. Informal conversations with leading scientists at this workshop invariably have<br />

shown that scientists are indeed quite skeptical of any federal intervention, and would much prefer a selfregulatory<br />

approach.<br />

141


safety guidelines aimed at ranking potential risks and defining appropriate safety procedures and<br />

requirements. These recommendations were to be adopted and expanded by the newly created<br />

Recombinant DNA Advisory Committee, established by the NIH in late 1974 and whose first<br />

meeting took place in early 1975, immediately after the Asilomar Conference. Producing a final<br />

version of the recommendations proved more difficult than anticipated. It took the RAC well<br />

over a year, until June of 1976, to fin<strong>all</strong>y release this document. It is a testimony to the perceived<br />

seriousness of the threats posed to public health by recombinant DNA technologies that the<br />

private sector decided to follow the RAC guidelines and to voluntarily submit to the RAC its<br />

research protocols for review.<br />

In its early days, it appears that this system of semi-voluntary oversight was indeed quite<br />

effective in reviewing research protocols involving rDNA molecules. Soon, however, the RAC<br />

found itself exposed to considerable pressure by the scientific community to take a less cautious<br />

approach in reviewing research protocols. Many scientists felt that rDNA technologies did not<br />

pose significant risks and that the RAC was burdening them with unnecessary restrictions. As<br />

recombinant DNA technology reached commercial viability, biotech companies began to express<br />

concern about the open nature of the RAC review process, a process that in their view was not<br />

sufficiently protective of their intellectual property. As the RAC played an increasingly marginal<br />

role in reviewing rDNA protocols, it began focusing on gene therapy trials. The new emphasis<br />

on human subjects prompted a revision of the guidelines and required significant changes to the<br />

composition of the commission. Medical ethicists and lawyers replaced representatives of public<br />

interest groups, mainly environmental groups. To date, the RAC remains involved mainly in the<br />

review of gene therapy trials. 62<br />

This (very much abridged) version of the RAC history seems to suggest that a selfregulatory<br />

body could indeed supervise novel and potenti<strong>all</strong>y threatening research activities.<br />

Arguably, the scientific community recognized from the beginning that rDNA technology posed<br />

a potenti<strong>all</strong>y serious treat to public health and took appropriate measures to prevent a disastrous<br />

outcome. In this sense, self-regulation as embodied by the RAC has succeeded in protecting<br />

public health without creating cumbersome and inflexible regulations. By contrast, a legislative<br />

response probably would have slowed down research considerably, with few or no additional<br />

benefits to public health and to the research community. This, in a nutshell, is the position taken<br />

in 1997 by two prominent scientists, Paul Berg and Maxine Singer, who warned against<br />

legislative overreaction after Scottish scientists announced the cloning of a sheep. 63<br />

Paul Berg’s and Maxine Singer’s concerns for unexpected negative consequences that<br />

rushed legislative initiatives could have on the research enterprise are justified. Far less<br />

62<br />

63<br />

A more detailed account of the RAC history can be found in Barry R. Furrow, "Governing Science: Public Risks<br />

and Private Remedies," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 131 (1983); Norman L. Rave, "Interagency<br />

Conflict and Administrative Accountability: Regulating the Release of Recombinant Organisms," Georgetown<br />

Law Review 77 (1989); Charles Weiner, "Is Self-Regulation Enough Today? Evaluating the Recombinant DNA<br />

Controversy," Health Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 9 (1999).<br />

Paul Berg and Maxine Singer, "Regulating Human Cloning," Science 282, no. 5388 (1998).<br />

142


justifiable is the assumption that in the case of modern biomedical research, the adoption of a<br />

system of oversight inspired by the RAC would be equ<strong>all</strong>y effective. In the 1970s, scientists’<br />

cooperative behavior was fueled in large measure by a genuine fear of a public health disaster. It<br />

was the existence of a perceived collective threat that prompted the scientific community to<br />

voluntarily accept significant constraints to their research freedom. As soon as this threat<br />

subsided, scientists began pressuring the RAC for a more expeditious and less strict review<br />

process. For its part, the biotech industry quickly lost interest in submitting rDNA research<br />

protocols to the RAC. In sum, both the RAC’s effectiveness and authority were predicated on the<br />

existence of a serious external threat. Absent this threat, the RAC quickly lost much of its moral<br />

authority.<br />

This sequence of events is by no means unique. In the late nineteenth century, it was the<br />

rapidly deteriorating public image of the legal profession in Chicago and New York that<br />

prompted these two legal communities to create local bar associations and to adopt ethical<br />

guidelines. 64 The adoption by many sectors of the chemical industry of extensive safety and<br />

environmental management programs ultimately can be attributed to the devastating impact that<br />

the disastrous gas leak in Bhopal, India, had on that industry’s public image. The efforts<br />

undertaken by the nuclear power industry to improve nuclear power plant safety above and<br />

beyond federal standards are a consequence of the Three Mile Island accident. 65<br />

The<br />

international maritime industry has an extensive system of self-regulation whose adoption was<br />

prompted in part out of concern for the industry’s deteriorating public image. 66 This body of<br />

literature demonstrates not only that trade and professional associations adopt programs of selfregulation<br />

mostly (but not exclusively) in reaction to a collective external threat; it also shows<br />

that the effectiveness of these measures cruci<strong>all</strong>y depends on the sustained presence of a threat.<br />

Absent this threat, a private body of governance quickly looses its authority.<br />

The RAC is an inadequate model of governance for another reason as well. Two core<br />

functions of a contemporary self-regulatory body are to ensure that a broad range of ethical<br />

concerns be heard and that competing ethical claims be adjudicated. Preventing ethical debates<br />

from turning into an exceedingly narrow discussion of mostly procedural questions would<br />

require broadening the participation in this deliberative body to social scientists and to<br />

representatives of the general public. During its entire history, the RAC has rarely attempted to<br />

broaden the scope of its ethical inquiries. In its early days, it was simply a body of scientists<br />

responsible for examining largely scientific issues. In its late incarnation, the RAC did include<br />

bioethicists on its gene therapy subcommittee, but the focus of its ethical inquiry remained<br />

64<br />

65<br />

66<br />

Jerome E. Carlin, Lawyers' Ethics: A Survey of the New York City Bar (New York: Sage, 1966); William T.<br />

G<strong>all</strong>agher, "Ideologies of Professionalism and the Politics of Self-Regulation in the California State Bar,"<br />

Pepperdine Law Review 22 (1995).<br />

Joseph V. Rees, Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three Mile Island<br />

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994).<br />

Furger, "Accountability and Self-Governance Systems: The Case of the Maritime Industry."<br />

143


elatively mundane. 67 For example, the RAC has always refused to explicitly condemn germ-line<br />

genetic engineering, focusing instead on traditional bioethical concerns such as informed consent<br />

and safety. In sum, a scientific body of self-governance as exemplified by the RAC is largely<br />

incompatible with a broad ethical analysis. In plain terms, the main reason why the RAC in its<br />

early days was regarded as a legitimate body of self-regulation was the absence of any<br />

significant disagreement between the scientific community and the public about the need to<br />

carefully monitor rDNA research. In the case of modern biomedical research, scientists and the<br />

public are only parti<strong>all</strong>y in agreement on what constitutes acceptable research protocols. For this<br />

reason, attempts by an RAC-like body to unilater<strong>all</strong>y resolve these controversies would not be<br />

regarded by the public as legitimate.<br />

Could the RAC be redesigned to become a credible and effective system of governance?<br />

Technic<strong>all</strong>y, yes. A redesigned RAC would have to consider a much broader range of views. The<br />

inclusion of a few representatives of public interest groups on this body is probably a necessary<br />

first step, though certainly not a sufficient one. As our discussion of public attitudes toward new<br />

biomedical technologies in chapter 8 shows, it is often incorrect to assume that public interest<br />

groups accurately reflect the views of the general public. Nor are professional ethicists always or<br />

necessarily in the best position to articulate critical ethical issues. Recent studies of patients’<br />

moral reasoning have shown that the ethical arguments for and against new medical technologies<br />

are much broader and often deeper than those offered by professional ethicists. 68<br />

Rules of representation would have to be changed as well. Currently, the RAC charter<br />

defines representation in functional terms, thus assuring that scientific and technical expertise is<br />

adequately represented on the committee. Scientific competence is certainly an important<br />

requirement, but we doubt that it should have a dominant role in the appointment process. The<br />

appointment rules would have to be revised, as well. At present, the NIH director is responsible<br />

for <strong>all</strong> appointments to the RAC. This may be acceptable for an obscure body of oversight that<br />

operates essenti<strong>all</strong>y like a club, but it would clearly be difficult to justify this rule for a decisionmaking<br />

body with broad regulatory authority. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the RAC tends to develop its<br />

recommendations in an informal way. To our knowledge, no specific rules of decision-making<br />

exist. In the past, the chair of the subcommittee on gene therapy made an effort to craft a<br />

consensus; other subcommittee may have been governed by different informal rules. 69 How<br />

conflicts on the gene therapy subcommittee were resolved when a consensus could not be crafted<br />

is unclear, but obviously this is an issue that cannot be left unresolved.<br />

An RAC redesigned according to these criteria can no longer be described as a system of<br />

self-regulation. It would certainly not be considered as such by the scientific community. But it<br />

could become a respected body of governance if it succeeded in projecting an image of fairness<br />

and impartiality.<br />

67<br />

68<br />

69<br />

Weiner, "Is Self-Regulation Enough Today? Evaluating the Recombinant DNA Controversy."<br />

Leach Sculley, Rippberger, and Rehmann-Sutter, "Non-Professional Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics."<br />

Interview with Leroy Walters, October 29, 2002.<br />

144


5.4 Bibliography<br />

Ahmed, Amer S. "The Last Twist of the Knife: Encouraging the Regulation of Innovative<br />

Surgical Procedures." Columbia Law Review 105 (2005): 1529-62.<br />

Andrews, Lori B. "A Conceptual Framework for Genetic Policy: Comparing the Medical, Public<br />

Health and Fundamental Rights Models." Washington University Law Quarterly 79<br />

(2001): 222-85.<br />

Berg, Paul, and Maxine Singer. "Regulating Human Cloning." Science 282, no. 5388 (1998):<br />

413.<br />

Bierig, Jack R. "Whatever Happened to Professional Self-Regulation?" American Bar<br />

Association Journal 69 (1983): 616-19.<br />

Carlin, Jerome E. Lawyers' Ethics: A Survey of the New York City Bar. New York: Sage, 1966.<br />

Carson, Sandra. Biotechnology and Public Policy: Professional Self-Regulation Session 5,<br />

President's Council on Bioethics Meeting, March 7, 2003 [cited September 16, 2005].<br />

Available from http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/march03/session5.html.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success<br />

Rates: National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for<br />

Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health,<br />

2004.<br />

Coleman, Carl H. "Rationalizing Risk Assessment in Human Subject Research." Arizona Law<br />

Review 46 (2004): 1-51.<br />

College of American Pathologists. "Reproductive Laboratory Accreditation Program – Standards<br />

for Accreditation." Northfield, IL, 2004.<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention).<br />

"Implementation of the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992 – a<br />

Model Program for the Certification of Embryo Laboratories; Notice." Federal Register<br />

64, no. 139 (1999): 39374-92.<br />

Department of Health and Human Services (Food and Drug Administration). "21 CFR Parts 16,<br />

1270, and 1271." Federal Register 69, no. 226 (2004): 68612-88.<br />

———. "21 CFR Parts 207, 807, and 1271. Human Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-<br />

Based Products; Establishment Registration and Listing; <strong>Final</strong> Rule." Federal Register<br />

66, no. 13 (2001): 5447-69.<br />

———. "21 CFR Parts 210, 211, 820, and 1271. Eligibility Determination for Donors of Human<br />

Cells, Tissues, and Cellular and Tissue-Based Products." Federal Register 69, no. 101<br />

(2004): 29786-834.<br />

Dresser, Rebecca. "Genetic Modification of Preimplantation Embryos: Toward Adequate Human<br />

Research Policies." Milbank Quarterly 82, no. 1 (2004): 195-214.<br />

Emanuel, Ezekiel J., Anne Wood, Alan Fleischman, Angela Bowen, Kenneth A. Getz, Christine<br />

Grady, Carol Levine, Dale E. Hammerschmidt, Ruth Faden, Lisa Eckenwiler, Carianne<br />

Tucker, and Jeremy Sugurman. "Oversight of Human Participants Research: Identifying<br />

Problems to Evaluate Reform Proposals." Annals of Internal Medicine 141, no. 4 (2004):<br />

282-92.<br />

Erikson, Susan L. "Post-Diagnostic Abortion in Germany: Reproduction Gone Awry, Again?"<br />

Social Science & Medicine 56 (2003): 1987-2001.<br />

145


F<strong>all</strong>on, Peter, and Zafiris Tzannatos. "Child Labor: Issues and Directions for the World Bank." In<br />

Social Protection, Human Development Network. Washington, D.C.: The World Bank,<br />

1998.<br />

Furger, Franco L. "Accountability and Self-Governance Systems: The Case of the Maritime<br />

Industry." Law & Policy 19, no. 4 (1997): 445-76.<br />

———. "Global Markets, New Games, New Rules: The Ch<strong>all</strong>enge of International Private<br />

Governance." In Rules and Networks. The Legal Culture of Global Business<br />

Transactions, edited by Richard P. Appelbaum, William L.F. Felstiner and Volkmar<br />

Gessner, 201-45. Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2001.<br />

Furrow, Barry R. "Governing Science: Public Risks and Private Remedies." University of<br />

Pennsylvania Law Review 131 (1983): 1403-67.<br />

G<strong>all</strong>agher, William T. "Ideologies of Professionalism and the Politics of Self-Regulation in the<br />

California State Bar." Pepperdine Law Review 22 (1995): 485-628.<br />

Garceau, L., J. Henderson, L.J. Davis, S. Petrou, L.R. Henderson, E. McVeigh, D.H. Barlow,<br />

and L.L. Davidson. "Economic Implications of Assisted Reproductive Techniques: A<br />

Systematic Review." Human Reproduction 17, no. 12 (2002): 3090-109.<br />

Gawande, Atul. Complications: Decisions and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life. London: Profile<br />

Books, 2002.<br />

General Accounting Office. "Scientific Research: Continued Vigilance Critical to Protecting<br />

Human Subjects." Washington, D.C.: GAO/HEHS publication no. GAO/HEHS-96-72,<br />

1996.<br />

Gerla, Harry S. "Federal Antitrust Law and Trade and Professional Association Standards and<br />

Certification." Dayton Law Review 19 (1994): 471-531.<br />

Ginsberg, Karen M. "FDA Approved? A Critique of the Artificial Insemination Industry in the<br />

United States." University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 30 (1997): 823-51.<br />

Heidt, Robert. "Industry Self-Regulation and the Useless Concept of 'Group Boycott'."<br />

Vanderbilt Law Review 39, no. 6 (1986): 1507-98.<br />

Hemphill, Thomas A. "Self-Regulation Industry Behavior: Antitrust Limitations and Trade<br />

Association Codes of Conduct." Journal of Business Ethics 11 (1992): 915-20.<br />

Hirsch, Dennis D. "Project XL and the Special Case: The EPA's Untold Success Story."<br />

Columbia Journal of Environmental Law 26 (2001): 219-57.<br />

Huang, Anny. "FDA Regulation of Genetic Testing: Institutional Reluctance and Public<br />

Guardianship." Food and Drug Law Journal 53 (1998): 555-91.<br />

Jones, C, and R. Ward. "Cost-Minimization Analysis of One-, Two-, and Three-Embryo<br />

Transfers in IVF." In Triplet Pregnancies and Their Consequences, edited by Keith Louis<br />

G. and Blickstein Isaac, 429-35. London: Parthenon Publishing Group, 2002.<br />

Kalfoglou, Andrea. "Looking Back, Looking Forward: The Legacy of the National Advisory<br />

Board on Ethics in Reproduction (NABER)." Women's Health Issues 10, no. 3 (2000):<br />

92-104.<br />

King, Nancy M.P. "The Line between Clinical Innovation and Human Experimentation." Seton<br />

H<strong>all</strong> Law Review 32 (2002): 573-81.<br />

Krislov, Samuel. How Nations Choose Product Standards and Standards Change Nations.<br />

Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1997.<br />

Leach Sculley, Jackie, Christine Rippberger, and Christoph Rehmann-Sutter. "Non-Professional<br />

Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics." Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004): 1415-25.<br />

146


Malinowski, Michael J., and Robin J.R. Blatt. "Commercialization of Genetic Testing Services:<br />

The FDA, Market Forces, and Biological Tarot Cards." Tulane Law Review 71 (1997):<br />

1211-312.<br />

Monroe, Murray S. "Trade and Professional Associations: An Overview of Horizontal<br />

Restraints." University of Dayton Law Review 9, no. 3 (1984): 479-501.<br />

Noah, Lars. "Informed Consent and the Elusive Dichotomy between Standard and Experimental<br />

Therapy." American Journal of Law and Medicine 28 (2002): 361-408.<br />

President's Council on Bioethics. Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New<br />

Biotechnologies. Washington, D.C., 2004.<br />

Rave, Norman L. "Interagency Conflict and Administrative Accountability: Regulating the<br />

Release of Recombinant Organisms." Georgetown Law Review 77 (1989): 1787-814.<br />

Rees, Joseph V. Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three<br />

Mile Island. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.<br />

Rubin, Susan B., and Laurie Zoloth. "Clinical Ethics and the Road Less Taken: Mapping the<br />

Future by Tracking the Past." Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (2004): 218-25.<br />

Sabel, Charles, Dara O'Rourke, and Archon Fung. "Ratcheting Labor Standards: Regulation for<br />

Continuous Improvements in the Global Workplace." John F. Kennedy School of<br />

Government, Harvard University, 2000.<br />

Susskind, Lawrence E., and Joshua Secunda. "The Risks and the Advantages of Agency<br />

Discretion: Evidence from EPA's Project XL." UCLA Journal of Environmental Law and<br />

Policy 17 (1998): 67-116.<br />

U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention).<br />

"2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates. National Summary and Fertility<br />

Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA, 2004.<br />

Weiner, Charles. "Is Self-Regulation Enough Today? Evaluating the Recombinant DNA<br />

Controversy." Health Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 9 (1999): 289-302.<br />

Wells, Martha A. "Overview of FDA Regulation of Human Cellular and Tissue-Based<br />

Products." Food and Drug Law Journal 52 (1997): 401-08.<br />

Wertz, Dorothy C., John C. Fletcher, Nippert Irmgard, Gerhard Wolff, and Ayme Ségoléne. "Has<br />

Patient Autonomy Gone Too Far? Geneticists' Views in 36 Nations." The American<br />

Journal of Bioethics 2, no. 4 (2002): 1-25.<br />

147


148


6 International Legislative and Regulatory Approaches<br />

In this chapter, we take a detailed look at legislative initiatives in four countries: Italy,<br />

Australia, Canada, and Britain. Each case provides a distinctive perspective on possible<br />

approaches to the regulation of reproductive technologies and biomedical research. Italy<br />

exemplifies a legislative approach to controversial biomedical developments that, while favored<br />

by some in the United States, in our view would be costly at best and counterproductive at worst.<br />

The Italian legislation goes well beyond simply targeting deeply troubling practices such as<br />

reproductive cloning and the creation of human embryos solely for research purposes. The scope<br />

of its prohibitions is very broad and its bans are sweeping. Not surprisingly, the Italian approach<br />

has triggered a considerable amount of controversy, and we present it here as an illustration of<br />

how not to approach controversial ethical dilemmas in the United States. Australia, by contrast,<br />

has passed legislation that seems to enjoy the support of <strong>all</strong> relevant constituencies and of the<br />

general public. Its approach to regulating controversial biomedical developments is restrictive –<br />

from an American perspective, perhaps too restrictive – but it also recognizes the importance of<br />

providing a leg<strong>all</strong>y protected space to controversial biomedical research. <strong>Final</strong>ly, Canada and<br />

Britain provide an illustration of our claim that similar regulatory infrastructures are compatible<br />

with different ethical concerns. Both countries emphasize the need to closely monitor the field of<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research through a specialized regulatory entity, yet<br />

Britain is considerably more liberal in its regulatory stance than Canada. Britain is also the only<br />

country with many years of experience in regulating controversial reproductive technologies.<br />

None of the legislative approaches examined in this chapter provides a template that could<br />

mechanic<strong>all</strong>y be used to implement a new regulatory structure in the American context. With the<br />

exception of Italy, each of these approaches does, however, provide important insights into how<br />

a U.S. system of regulation could be implemented. To facilitate this task, we have also examined<br />

legislative and regulatory approaches in 13 industrialized countries. Our analysis shows that<br />

there is virtu<strong>all</strong>y no agreement among these countries on what constitute the most appropriate<br />

legislative responses to new biomedical dilemmas, the notable exception being reproductive<br />

cloning. On the other end, there is considerable agreement on which reproductive practices and<br />

research protocols should be regulated. 1 For each of these practices, a majority of the reviewed<br />

countries has either adopted specific legislative measures or crafted regulation. Only one country<br />

– the United States – has taken little or no action. This observation underscores the need for the<br />

U.S. Congress to pay closer attention to medical and scientific developments in the area of<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research.<br />

1<br />

In Appendix H, we have identified 10 activities pertaining to reproductive medicine and biomedical research that<br />

in recent times have been targeted for legislative or regulatory intervention in 13 OECD countries.<br />

149


6.1 Italy – from the “Wild West” to “Politburo”?<br />

On February 10, 2004, the Italian Chamber of Representatives passed a comprehensive bill<br />

titled “Norme in materia di procreazione medicalmente assistita” (“Norms concerning medic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

assisted procreation”). The bill, already passed by the Italian Senate in December of 2003, is now<br />

law. 2 We have chosen to examine in some depth the Italian case for one main reason: The new<br />

legislation provides an excellent illustration of the possible negative consequences of a laissezfaire<br />

approach to reproductive medicine, followed by a late and excessive legislative reaction. To<br />

put it simply, the longer a legislative body delays crafting a response to new scientific and<br />

medical developments, the likelier it becomes that legislators will overreact.<br />

Until the passage of bill n.40, Italy exercised only minimal oversight over reproductive<br />

medicine and research. Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, among ART practitioners and ART patients, Italy<br />

was known as the “Wild West” of reproductive medicine. The new law has changed <strong>all</strong> this. In<br />

terms of access restrictions to ART technologies, the types of reproductive technologies<br />

available to patients, and the ends that justify the recourse to assisted reproductive technologies,<br />

the Italian legislation is one of if not the most restrictive legislative frameworks worldwide.<br />

Hence the term “politburo” used by an Italian columnist to describe the new approach to<br />

regulating reproductive medicine.<br />

The costs of this legislative overreaction are likely to be significant, and they are not only<br />

economic in nature. In the present case, the negative consequences of the new law will be felt by<br />

research institutions, by patients, and by ART practitioners. Scientists will find themselves<br />

incapable of conducting research that largely is considered legitimate in many other liberal<br />

democracies. Patients will be deprived of important reproductive services, and the industry likely<br />

will suffer considerable economic losses.<br />

The law, though it does not explicitly discuss guiding principles, is informed by clear ethical<br />

standards. ART technologies can be used exclusively for the treatment of medic<strong>all</strong>y diagnosed<br />

infertility, and are not a means for individuals to meet their reproductive desires. Accordingly,<br />

IVF is considered a medical technology of last resort intended to help heterosexual couples have<br />

a baby. The protection of embryos has priority over the demands of non-traditional couples,<br />

singles, research institutions, and in some cases, over the interests of the couple. In this sense, the<br />

Italian law embodies very specific views of sexuality, of the family, and of the moral status of<br />

the embryo – views that are quite close to traditional Catholic teachings on these issues.<br />

The law consists of 18 fairly straightforward articles. Unlike most other legislative<br />

approaches in the area of ART and biomedical research, the Italian statute is comprehensive. It<br />

limits access to ART technologies, it describes which ART procedures can be used and how, and<br />

it spells out the rationale for resorting to ART treatments. It also sets clear legislative boundaries<br />

to what researchers are entitled to do in this area. In addition, the legislation requires the<br />

implementation of a licensing scheme for <strong>all</strong> ART clinics, to be administered by the Italian<br />

2<br />

Legge 19 febbraio 2004, n. 40, available at http://www.parlamento.it/parlam/leggi/04040l.htm (Medic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

Assisted Reproduction Law).<br />

150


Health Ministry, and sets aside funds for conducting scientific research on the causes of<br />

infertility.<br />

Taking a closer look at the law, article 5 establishes that only stable, adult, heterosexual<br />

couples, married or otherwise, have the right to receive ART treatments. In addition, both<br />

spouses must be alive. However, the access to reproductive treatments is not unconditional.<br />

Traditional couples have access to ART treatments only after they have demonstrated that their<br />

infertility cannot be cured by any other means. Demonstration of infertility requires medical<br />

examination and appropriate documentation. 3<br />

As for the means available to couples that qualify for an ART treatment, the statute contains<br />

several provisions. Gamete donation by a third party is prohibited. 4 Since only the couple’s own<br />

gametes can be used for reproductive purpose, no provision is necessary to regulate the donation,<br />

import, or export of gametes and embryos. Performing IVF is subject to constraints. Only three<br />

embryos can be created for any one cycle, and <strong>all</strong> of them must be transferred. 5 In an effort to<br />

prevent the accumulation of excess embryos, the long-term cryopreservation of embryos is not<br />

<strong>all</strong>owed, 6<br />

nor is their destruction. Embryo cryopreservation is permitted only for medical<br />

reasons, and only for a limited period of time, in any case until the embryo is transferred. 7<br />

“Selective reduction” is prohibited, with some very limited exceptions. 8<br />

Since every in vitro embryo must be transferred and no embryo can be destroyed, any<br />

technique that leads to the destruction of an embryo is prohibited. This means that techniques of<br />

genetic screening such as pre-implantation genetic diagnosis are not <strong>all</strong>owed for any reason,<br />

including therapeutic treatments. Also banned is any eugenic application – i.e., any change in the<br />

genome of gametes or embryos not intended directly to benefit the latter. 9 Research on embryos<br />

is <strong>all</strong>owed only to benefit the health and development of the embryos themselves. 10<br />

Consistent with the narrow focus on procreation, the law leaves very little room for research<br />

involving reproductive tissues. Somatic cell nuclear transfer of any kind is prohibited. 11 Since<br />

embryos can only be created for procreative reasons and cannot be destroyed, the donation of<br />

embryos for research purposes is excluded. The law also explicitly prohibits the creation of<br />

embryos solely for research purposes. 12 The creation of human-animal chimeras or hybrids is<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

12<br />

See Article 4, Section 1.<br />

See Article 4, Section 3.<br />

See Article 14, Section 2.<br />

See Article 14, Section 1.<br />

See Article 14, Section 3.<br />

See Article 14, Section 4.<br />

See Article 13, section 3b.<br />

See Article 13, section 2.<br />

See Article 13, Section 3c.<br />

See Article 13, Section 3a.<br />

151


also prohibited. 13 The law actively supports and promotes research on the causes of infertility,<br />

including medical research on human gametes. 14<br />

As for regulatory measures, the law requires the administering agency, namely the Health<br />

Ministry, to establish a registry of <strong>all</strong> ART clinics. Also, ART programs are required to report<br />

the number of created embryos and babies born through ART on an annual basis. 15 In addition,<br />

ART clinics must provide the Health Ministry with the data necessary to monitor the health and<br />

well-being of babies born through ART. Unfortunately, this article is crafted in such general<br />

terms as to prevent an evaluation of the Italian approach to health monitoring. The law is much<br />

more specific in terms of the administrative and criminal sanctions imposed on violators. For<br />

example, an ART practitioner can be fined up to 600,000 euros (approximately $730,000) for<br />

using gametes extraneous to the couple. Trade in gametes or embryos can be punished by up to<br />

two years in prison, and attempts at reproductive cloning carry a sentence of up to 20 years in<br />

prison and fines up to a million Euros (approximately $1,218,000).<br />

The Italian approach to new reproductive technologies is an excellent example of how not to<br />

legislate the field of reproductive science and medicine. As the preceding discussion<br />

demonstrates, many legislative provisions in this law seem guided by a desire to ensure better<br />

protection for ART children and for embryos. As we have argued in chapter 3, the well-being of<br />

ART children and the respect for human embryos are both important moral goods worthy of<br />

legislative attention. However, in our view the Italian statute achieves these goals by sacrificing<br />

several other moral goods worthy of legal protection. Access to standard ART technologies, even<br />

by heterosexual couples is severely limited, and promising new lines of medical research<br />

(including but not limited to stem cell research) are sacrificed for the sake of a very specific<br />

ethical perspective – an ethical perspective that may not be shared by a majority of the Italian<br />

public. 16 The law also prevents prospective parents affected by genetic diseases from having<br />

healthy children. In other words, it does not attempt to reconcile conflicting moral goods; it<br />

simply imposes on Italian citizens what amounts to traditional Catholic precepts of morality.<br />

The Italian law is problematic for other reasons as well. Its rigid approach to controversial<br />

ethical questions makes it <strong>all</strong> but impossible to accommodate unanticipated future medical<br />

developments. For example, medical research likely will make it possible in the not-too-distant<br />

future to cryopreserve human oocytes. The cryopreservation of human eggs raises new and<br />

important ethical questions, but it is not obvious to us that this technology should simply be<br />

banned by legislative means. There may well be good medical and non-medical reasons for<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

16<br />

See Article 13, Section 3d.<br />

See Article 2 Sections 1 and 2.<br />

See Article 11.<br />

The failure of four referenda to revoke several provisions of this statute could be interpreted as an indication of<br />

broad popular support for this new statute. However, the initiators made clear that theirs was not a fundamental<br />

opposition to the regulation of reproductive medicine, per se. Rather, the referenda targeted specific prohibitions<br />

of the new law deemed too broad – the use of human embryos for research, the cryopreservation of human<br />

embryos, any form of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, and ART procedures using donated gametes and<br />

embryos – as well as the recognition of pre-embryos as legal entities with the same rights as human beings.<br />

152


<strong>all</strong>owing the cryopreservation of oocytes, at least in some cases. A sweeping ban on new medical<br />

developments in our view is an ill-informed response to biomedical developments that cannot be<br />

unambiguously condemned or uncondition<strong>all</strong>y embraced.<br />

6.2 Australia – Regulated Self-Regulation<br />

6.2.1 Regulatory Precedents<br />

A unique feature of the Australian system of government is its extensive reliance on selfregulation.<br />

In the Australian context, self-regulation is not synonymous with lax regulation. The<br />

Australian government codifies standards developed by the private sector and relies on trade<br />

associations and other accredited third parties to ensure compliance. Procedures of compliance<br />

assurance are no different from those adopted by government regulators in other countries, and<br />

include inspections and various forms of sanctions. 17 The Australian ART industry provides an<br />

excellent illustration of this approach. Australia, with approximately 20 million inhabitants, has<br />

34 ART programs – almost twice as many per million inhabitants as the United States. By <strong>all</strong><br />

accounts, the Australian ART industry is very dynamic, on both the clinical and the research<br />

fronts. The industry began regulating itself in 1987, when the Fertility Society of Australia<br />

established the Reproductive Technology Accreditation Committee (RTAC). 18 The committee<br />

produced a set of guidelines, the “Code of Practice for Centres Using Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technology” (or “Code of Practice” for short), which was revised in April of 2002 and can be<br />

regarded as a comprehensive set of binding recommendations for the operation of an ART<br />

program in Australia. Its adherence is monitored and enforced by the RTAC.<br />

In 1996, the Code of Practice was supplemented by the “Ethical Guidelines on the Use of<br />

Assisted Reproductive Technology in Clinical Practice and Research” (or “Guidelines”),<br />

published by the Australian Health Ethics Committee (AHEC) and updated in September of<br />

2004. The AHEC is a principal committee of the National Health and Medical Research Council<br />

(NHMRC), the Australian equivalent of the NIH, which was established under the NHMRC Act<br />

of 1992. The Guidelines address numerous ethical questions not specific<strong>all</strong>y discussed in the<br />

Code of Practice, and not included in two statutes to be examined below, the Prohibition of<br />

Human Cloning Act of 2002 (PHCA) and the Research Involving Human Embryos Act of 2002<br />

(RIHEA). They are reminiscent of many guidelines developed by the American Society for<br />

Reproductive Medicine, differing only in that they, unlike their American counterparts, are being<br />

enforced.<br />

The ethical standards espoused in the Australian Guidelines are indicative of a rather<br />

conservative approach to the access and use of ART technologies, but they are certainly not as<br />

rigid as their Italian counterpart. For example, the Australian Guidelines ban the use of sex-<br />

17<br />

18<br />

See, for example, Toni Makkai and John Braithwaite, "Reintegrative Shaming and Compliance with Regulatory<br />

Standards," Criminology 32 (1994).<br />

See http://www.fsa.au.com/rtac/.<br />

153


selection technologies, but only for non-therapeutic uses. They deem the commercial trade of<br />

human gametes and embryos unacceptable, but <strong>all</strong>ow the donation of such tissues. They<br />

proscribe surrogacy as a commercial service, recognize that it remains a controversial practice<br />

even for non-commercial reasons, and refer to state-level laws and regulations for additional<br />

guidance. As for pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, they proscribe its use for elective sex<br />

selection but <strong>all</strong>ow it to prevent or reduce the chance of inheriting a serious genetic condition.<br />

The Guidelines do not provide any guidance on other unconventional reproductive technologies<br />

such as ooplasm transfer, embryo splitting, or reproductive cloning. Nor do they address the<br />

creation of embryos and chimeras or genetic engineering. These issues are dealt with by the two<br />

new statutes mentioned earlier, the PHCA and the RIHEA.<br />

By the end of 2002, the Australian Parliament had passed both the PHCA and the RIHEA,<br />

and did so in less than two years, apparently without major societal traumas. The two laws<br />

complement each other: The PHCA identifies ethic<strong>all</strong>y unacceptable and therefore prohibited<br />

practices in the ART industry, whereas the RIHEA outlines a regulatory system for conducting<br />

research on human embryos, including but not limited to stem cell research. The actual<br />

regulation of the ART industry is covered by the Code of Practice and by the Guidelines.<br />

The PHCA and the RIHEA reflect a genuine effort by the Australian authority to balance<br />

ethical concerns and freedom of research. The centerpiece of this balancing act is the Embryo<br />

Research Licensing Committee (ERLC), a principal committee of the NHMRC responsible for<br />

overseeing research protocols involving human embryos. The ERLC is modeled after the British<br />

Human Fertilization and Embryology Authority, but differs from the latter in some important<br />

respects. Unlike the HFEA, the ERLC oversees exclusively research activities, not the ART<br />

industry proper. Appointment and operational rules also differ, as do the criteria for approving<br />

and rejecting research proposals.<br />

6.2.2 The Prohibition of Human Cloning Act of 2002<br />

The stated purpose of the PHCA is to identify in a clear and unambiguous fashion<br />

reproductive practices and technologies deemed unethical or otherwise unacceptable. 19 PHCA<br />

does so by distinguishing between cloning 20 and prohibited activities. 21 Cloning a human embryo<br />

for any purpose is prohibited. This means that Australia, unlike Britain but like Canada, has<br />

banned both reproductive and research cloning. PHCA speaks of the “human embryo clone” and<br />

defines this term as the “genetic copy” of another living or dead human being, excluding<br />

“copies” created by the fertilization of an egg by a sperm, thus ensuring that twins are not<br />

inadvertently declared clones.<br />

In Section 8(2), the legislators clarify the definition of “genetic copy.” For an embryo to be a<br />

genetic copy, it is sufficient for the genes in the nucleus of a cell to be copied; it is not necessary<br />

19<br />

20<br />

21<br />

See Section 3.<br />

See Division 1.<br />

See Division 2.<br />

154


that the cloned embryo have an identical copy of the genome of the original cell. This means that<br />

cloning could not leg<strong>all</strong>y be performed on the grounds that cloned embryos have different<br />

mitochondrial DNA and therefore are not genetic copies. Section 8(4) establishes that “embryo<br />

splitting” – the process by which an embryo at a very early stage is split into two embryos – does<br />

produce a human embryo clone and is therefore also banned. The PHCA prohibits the<br />

implantation of cloned embryos in a human body, 22<br />

and the import or export of cloned<br />

embryos. 23 It also preempts the argument that cloning an embryo is not punishable because the<br />

embryo in question would not have been viable, an argument that in the United States enjoys<br />

some popularity. 24 In sum, Australia has closed <strong>all</strong> doors on the creation and use of cloned<br />

human embryos.<br />

The creation of human embryos is otherwise permitted but severely restricted. Embryos can<br />

be created, but exclusively for reproductive purposes. 25 The PHCA forbids the creation of human<br />

embryos by means other than the union of a human oocyte and human sperm. 26 It also prohibits<br />

retrieving a viable human embryo from the body of a woman. 27 This procedure, known as<br />

“embryo flushing,” is common in animal husbandry, but it has yet to be used in humans. The<br />

PHCA makes it illegal to implant a human embryo in an animal, 28 and fin<strong>all</strong>y, it prohibits the<br />

import and export of human embryos, 29 as well as the trade of embryos, human eggs, and human<br />

sperm. 30 There are a few important exceptions to these prohibitions. In particular, neither embryo<br />

nor stem cell research are covered by these bans, but both are strictly regulated. Terms and<br />

conditions for conducting this type of research are laid out in RIHEA (see the next section).<br />

Furthermore, the PHCA revised explanatory memorandum clarifies that screening embryos for<br />

medical purposes, as for certain uses of PGD, remains legal.<br />

With regard to reproductive technologies in Australia, the PHCA prohibits the creation of<br />

human embryos with genetic material from more than two persons. 31 The revised explanatory<br />

memorandum makes clear that Section 15 is intended to ban reproductive techniques such as<br />

ooplasm transfer. This seems in keeping with the FDA suspension of this procedure in the United<br />

States out of concern that it may not be safe. Another preventive measure is Section 16, which<br />

bans the development of a human embryo outside the body of a woman for more than 14 days.<br />

While it may be difficult to see the need for this prohibition at this time, our discussion of new<br />

22<br />

23<br />

24<br />

25<br />

26<br />

27<br />

28<br />

29<br />

30<br />

31<br />

See Section 10.<br />

See Section 11.<br />

See Section 12.<br />

See Section 14.<br />

See Section 13.<br />

See Section 19.<br />

See Section 21.<br />

See Section 22.<br />

See Section 23.<br />

See Section 15.<br />

155


eproductive technologies in section 4.5.4 has shown that in the not too-distant future, it may<br />

indeed be possible to grow human embryos for extended periods of time outside the body of a<br />

woman.<br />

Like Canada, Britain, and most other OECD countries, the Australian legislation bans<br />

genetic engineering, defined as a heritable alteration of the human genome. 32 PHCA deals<br />

extensively with chimerism, as well, precisely defining what constitutes a chimeric animal and<br />

how chimeric animals differ from hybrids and transgenic embryos. It is worthwhile delving into<br />

some of these technicalities, as these definitional questions are of some import to our discussion.<br />

PHCA Section 8(1) defines chimeric embryos as human embryos “in which a cell, or any<br />

component of a cell, of an animal” has been introduced. 33 It appears that Australian legislators<br />

were concerned about being outpaced by scientific progress, as they empowered regulators to<br />

introduce additional definition of chimeric embryos, if necessary. The definition of a hybrid<br />

embryo consists of four distinct categories: (a) an embryo created by fertilizing a human egg<br />

with an animal sperm, (b) an embryo created by fertilizing an animal egg with human sperm, (c)<br />

a human egg in which the nucleus of an animal cell has been inserted, and (d) an animal egg in<br />

which the nucleus of a human cell has been introduced. Most importantly, the legislators have<br />

<strong>all</strong>owed the regulators to introduce new definitions of hybrid embryos as necessary. Section 20<br />

of PHCA makes it an offense punishable by up to 10 years in prison to create a chimeric embryo<br />

or a hybrid embryo, as defined above.<br />

In keeping with well-established laboratory practices, PHCA does not prohibit the creation<br />

of transgenic embryos, defined as animal embryos in which human genes or fractions thereof<br />

have been introduced, nor does it address the case of an animal embryo in which human cells<br />

have been introduced. The PHCA revised explanatory memorandum describes these embryos as<br />

instances of genetic<strong>all</strong>y manipulated organisms, a somewhat misleading terminology in our<br />

opinion. This case is dealt with in a separate Act, the Gene Technology Act of 2000, which is<br />

beyond the scope of the present report.<br />

6.2.3 The Research Involving Human Embryos Act of 2002<br />

The main purpose of the RIHEA, defined in Section 3, is to “…address concerns, including<br />

ethical concerns, about scientific developments in relation to human reproduction and the<br />

utilization of human embryos by regulating activities that involve the use of certain human<br />

embryos created by assisted reproductive technology.” If the proposed research could damage or<br />

destroy the embryo, research on human embryos is permitted only on excess embryos, and only<br />

on those created prior to April 5, 2002. 34 This clause is more flexible than President Bush’s 2001<br />

directive on human stem cell research. It <strong>all</strong>ows the creation of new stem cell lines if these are<br />

32<br />

33<br />

34<br />

See Section 18.<br />

Note that the terms “introduce” and “fertilize” are not synonymous. The former indicates a process by which an<br />

some extraneous cells are mixed to the cell of an existing embryo.<br />

See Paragraph 21(3)(b).<br />

156


derived from embryos created before the April 2002 cutoff. In addition, paragraph 21(3)(b) was<br />

repealed on April 5, 2005, thus <strong>all</strong>owing legislators to revisit the policy and update it, if<br />

necessary. The moratorium has not been extended, thus <strong>all</strong>owing Australian researchers to derive<br />

new stem cell lines using embryos created after April 5, 2002. 35<br />

As mentioned above, Australia regulates human embryo research by means of a licensing<br />

system overseen by the Embryo Research Licensing Committee, located within the NHMRC.<br />

The ERLC has the authority to grant licenses for conducting embryo research and to monitor<br />

research activities, licensed or not. In addition, it must maintain a public database of licensed<br />

research projects. Its operations must be reviewed on a regular basis, and an activity report must<br />

be submitted to both houses of the Australian Parliament.<br />

The ERLC could be described as a hybrid between the British Human Fertilisation and<br />

Embryology Authority and the U.S. Recombinant DNA Advisory Committee. Like the RAC, the<br />

ERLC operates within the NHMRC. 36 Like the HFEA, the ERLC licenses <strong>all</strong> research activities<br />

involving human embryos, not just publicly funded projects. And as with the HFEA, ERLC<br />

members include representatives of the scientific community, the general public, and other<br />

constituencies. Unlike the RAC, however, the ERLC has extensive monitoring and enforcement<br />

powers backed by administrative and criminal sanctions.<br />

The Australian approach to defining the composition of the ERLC departs significantly from<br />

the British model. While the British HFEA is an idiosyncratic mix of corporatism and direct<br />

popular representation, the Australian ERLC takes a clear corporatist approach. Sections 13<br />

through 19 govern its establishment and operation. Section 16 establishes the committee’s<br />

composition as follows:<br />

(a) A member of the Australian Health Ethics Committee<br />

(b) An expert in research ethics<br />

(c) A person with expertise in a relevant area of research<br />

(d) An ART expert<br />

(e) A legal expert<br />

(f) A representative of a consumer organization specialized in disability and disease<br />

(g) A representative of a consumer and patient group focused on assisted reproductive<br />

medicine<br />

(h) An expert in the regulation of ART<br />

(i) An embryologist<br />

35<br />

36<br />

No Need for More Stem Cell Embryos (Sydney Morning Herald, March 29, 2005 [cited September 22, 2005]);<br />

available from http://www.smh.com.au/news/National/No-need-for-more-stem-cell-embryos-<br />

MPs/2005/03/29/1111862384922.html?oneclick=true.<br />

It should be noted that in recent times, the British government has extracted the licensing of scientific projects<br />

involving human embryos from the HFEA and entrusted this activity to a new regulatory body within the<br />

National Health Service (NHS), the British equivalent of the NIH.<br />

157


Neither the RIHEA nor its explanatory memorandum shed any light on which criteria were<br />

behind this choice of experts. Most of the choices may be regarded as both obvious and<br />

necessary. Appointing an ART expert, a legal expert, an expert in research ethics, a scientist, an<br />

embryologist, and representatives of consumers and patients groups seem rather straightforward<br />

choices. On the other hand, taken together, these choices produce a committee that is unique in<br />

its structure. Unlike the HFEA, the ERLC is a committee of experts with no pretension of<br />

including and/or consulting with the general public. Public views are not excluded from this<br />

committee, but are limited to those societal groups most directly affected by research in this area<br />

– i.e., to representatives of infertility patients and advocates of disabled persons. Individuals who<br />

do not represent the medical profession or the research community and who are likely to<br />

represent the views of the public are a clear minority. Depending on how the slots are filled, they<br />

range between two and three out of nine members. Given the often rather self-interested nature<br />

of organized groups, and the gener<strong>all</strong>y sympathetic approach displayed by the bioethics<br />

profession toward the research community, this number could conceivably shrink to zero.<br />

The technocratic approach taken by the Australian legislation in establishing the<br />

composition of the ERLC can partly be explained by the committee’s charge. The ERLC is<br />

responsible exclusively for approving research protocols on human embryos, not for untangling<br />

difficult ethical dilemmas created by new reproductive technologies. In this sense, the<br />

committee’s scope is relatively narrow and may not require extensive public input as required,<br />

for example, for the promulgation of new ethical guidelines by the RTAC or the Human<br />

Research Ethics Committee (HREC), which is similar to an institutional review board.<br />

The Australian appointment process ensures that only broadly acceptable candidates will be<br />

appointed. The appointment process is not governed by rigid administrative rules, nor are<br />

appointments simply the result of an arbitrary choice made by the responsible minister. The<br />

RIHEA assigns the minister the responsibility for making the actual appointments, but viable<br />

candidates can be suggested only by a predefined list of organized interest groups and by the<br />

states (Paragraph 16(3)(a)). In addition, the minister must “consult, and have regard to the views<br />

expressed by, the States on the proposed appointment.” 37 How exactly this clause is being<br />

interpreted in practice is not entirely clear, but it appears that the purpose of this consultation<br />

process is to ensure that the appointed candidate is supported by <strong>all</strong> relevant political<br />

constituencies. In other words, the states must not only be consulted, but should also be<br />

represented. Sub-clause 16(5) requires that the committee chair only be appointed with a<br />

majority of states agreeing, while sub-clause 16(6) instructs the minister as to the “desirability of<br />

ensuring that the Committee as a whole comprises members from different States.” The<br />

combination of formal and informal appointment rules seems to be designed to produce<br />

consensus candidates. This approach can be relatively slow, but it guarantees that most<br />

constituencies will regard the committee as a whole as a credible and trustworthy institution of<br />

government.<br />

37<br />

See Paragraph 16(3)(b).<br />

158


RIHEA Sections 20 through 28 govern the issuance, change, and revocation of licenses. Of<br />

particular interest to the present discussion are the conditions for obtaining a research license. 38<br />

Some of these criteria are purely procedural; others are of a more substantive nature. The<br />

procedural requirements include obtaining informed consent from the donors of excess<br />

embryos, 39 and approval by the HREC in accordance with the NHRMC National Statement on<br />

Ethical Conduct in Research Involving Humans. 40<br />

In examining the merits of a research<br />

proposal, RIHEA Section 21(4) requires (a) the committee to examine whether the number of<br />

embryos to be used in the proposed research is commensurate to the research goals, and (b)<br />

whether the proposed research is likely to advance scientific knowledge or improve medical<br />

technologies and treatments that could not be achieved by other means. In addition, if the<br />

research protocol involves the damage or destruction of human embryos, the applicant can use<br />

only excess embryos created prior to April 5, 2002. Sub-clause 21(40(b) provides considerable<br />

room for interpretation, and it is by no means clear how the ERLC members may resolve the<br />

uncertainties that any attempt at assessing possible benefits and relative merits of different<br />

medical research protocols inevitably will produce. Neither the RIHEA nor the accompanying<br />

explanatory memorandum touches on this question. Surprisingly to us, the RIHEA does not<br />

include any guidance on how the ERLC should resolve internal disagreement, or on what the role<br />

the committee chair should play in this process.<br />

The RIHEA also addresses conflicts between demands for transparency and commercial<br />

expectations of confidentiality, conflicts that in the past have severely constrained the ability of<br />

the U.S. RAC to review research protocols submitted by private companies. 41 The act does<br />

require the ERLC to maintain a publicly accessible online database of granted licenses, but the<br />

information required to be included in this database is minimal. It includes the applicant’s name,<br />

a short description of the proposed research, the number of excess embryos whose use has been<br />

authorized by the license, and the period of time during which the license is valid, but explicitly<br />

excludes any commerci<strong>all</strong>y sensitive information. These provisions seem to suggest that the<br />

review process is not open to the public. The RIHEA does not delve into questions of<br />

transparency and public access to the review process. Whether a closed review process will<br />

undermine the public confidence in this new institution of government remains to be seen.<br />

RIHEA Sections 33 through 41 lay out the rules that govern monitoring activities. As with<br />

the Canadian legislation described below, these sections leave many implementation details<br />

unspecified. For example, the RIHEA does not state whether it is possible and/or necessary to<br />

38<br />

39<br />

40<br />

41<br />

See Section 21.<br />

See Paragraph 21(3)(i). Section 9 defines an excess embryo not only as an embryo that is not needed by the<br />

woman for whom it was created, but also as an embryo no longer needed by her spouse (if any) (Paragraph<br />

9(1)(b)).<br />

The statement is available at http://www.nhmrc.gov.au/publications/synopses/e35syn.htm. The criteria, both<br />

procedural and substantive, laid out by this document are not too different from the Common Rule or the FDA<br />

regulations governing the establishment of operation of an institutional review board.<br />

See Sections 29 and 30.<br />

159


inspect <strong>all</strong> licensees, or how often should they be inspected. Implementation questions are to be<br />

addressed in future regulations. As for administrative and criminal penalties, the penalties<br />

imposed by Australia, compared to Italy and Canada, are severe. Violating a provision of<br />

Division 1 of the PHCA is punishable by up to 15 years in prison; other violations of the PHCA<br />

c<strong>all</strong> for up to 10 years. Criminal penalties in the RIHEA are not as severe, but could still land a<br />

scientist in prison for up to five years.<br />

6.3 Canada: Groping Toward a New Regulatory Structure<br />

The Canadian response to the ethical dilemmas raised by new reproductive technologies has<br />

been more than 10 years in the making. In the early 1990s, the Royal Commission on New<br />

Reproductive Technologies on behalf of the Canadian government spearheaded a broad national<br />

conversation on the risks and benefits of new options in reproductive medicine. It organized<br />

numerous town h<strong>all</strong> meetings around the country, listened carefully to the views and opinions of<br />

the general public, and summarized this experience in a highly regarded report, “Proceed with<br />

Care,” published in 1993. The report was the basis for several legislative proposals, the last of<br />

which – Bill C-6, the Assisted Human Reproduction Act respecting assisted human reproduction<br />

and related research – was fin<strong>all</strong>y passed on February 11, 2004, by the Canadian House of<br />

Commons.<br />

An important reason for examining the Canadian statute in some detail is its regulatory<br />

stance. The Assisted Human Reproduction Act (AHRA) not only distinguishes between<br />

acceptable and unacceptable reproductive practices, it also establishes a new regulatory<br />

institution responsible for regulating reproductive medicine. The Canadian case is interesting for<br />

another reason as well: It is similar to the approach taken by Britain. The Canadian statute shares<br />

with the British approach several key features, including the adoption of a licensing scheme and<br />

the creation of a board of directors responsible for managing the new agency. But the Canadian<br />

AHRA also differs from the British legislation in that it takes a much more restrictive approach<br />

to several controversial reproductive and research techniques: It is more restrictive toward the<br />

use of sex-selection technologies, it does not <strong>all</strong>ow the creation of embryos solely for research<br />

purposes, and it bans research cloning (which the British HFEA has legalized).<br />

6.3.1 The Assisted Human Reproduction Act of 2004<br />

The AHRA expounds what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed a transitional morality, meaning a mix of ethical<br />

norms informed by traditionalist moral sensibilities and contemporary notions of individual<br />

moral autonomy. It prohibits <strong>all</strong> forms of human cloning, for research or reproductive purposes.<br />

In addition, it explicitly proscribes the commercial trade in human gametes and embryos. In this,<br />

it is quite similar to the position taken by the Australian legislators. On the other hand, it does not<br />

prohibit surrogacy or other forms of assisted reproduction that require the use of extraneous<br />

gametes. It also bans discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation and marital status, thus<br />

160


guaranteeing access to procreative technologies to gay and lesbian couples and to singles. In this<br />

sense, the AHRA seems to accurately reflect prevailing Canadian moral sensibilities. 42<br />

The AHRA takes what may be described as a principled approach to regulating reproductive<br />

technologies and biomedical research. In this, the Canadian statute stands alone; neither the<br />

British nor the Australian legislation nor any other legislative approach, to our knowledge, has<br />

attempted to infer legislative prohibitions and to distinguish between banned and regulated<br />

activities from a set of fairly general ethical principles. The seven principles enumerated in<br />

Section 2 of the AHRA are worth quoting in some detail:<br />

(a) The health and well-being of children born through the application of assisted human<br />

reproductive technologies must be given priority in <strong>all</strong> decisions respecting their use;<br />

(b) The benefits of assisted human reproductive technologies and related research for<br />

individuals, for families, and for society in general can be most effectively secured by<br />

taking appropriate measures for the protection and promotion of human health, safety,<br />

dignity, and rights in the use of these technologies and in related research;<br />

(c) While <strong>all</strong> persons are affected by these technologies, women more than men are directly<br />

and significantly affected by their application, and the health and well-being of women<br />

must be protected in the application of these technologies;<br />

(d) The principle of free and informed consent must be promoted and applied as a<br />

fundamental condition of the use of human reproductive technologies;<br />

(e) Persons who seek to undergo assisted reproduction procedures must not be discriminated<br />

against, including on the basis of their sexual orientation or marital status;<br />

(f) Trade in the reproductive capabilities of women and men and the exploitation of<br />

children, women, and men for commercial ends raise health and ethical concerns that<br />

justify their prohibition; and<br />

(g) Human individuality and diversity, and the integrity of the human genome, must be<br />

preserved and protected.<br />

These principles are remarkable for several reasons. They explicitly acknowledge the need<br />

to protect those most directly affected by reproductive procedures, namely the ART children and<br />

women who undergo these treatments (principles (a) and (c)). They subordinate the benefits of<br />

reproductive technologies and biomedical research to the protection of human health, safety,<br />

dignity, and the rights of those affected by these technologies and the public in general (principle<br />

(b)). And they resolve controversies over differential access to reproductive technologies<br />

42<br />

Not everybody would agree with this statement. For example, it has been argued that the Canadian public is<br />

actu<strong>all</strong>y not opposed to research cloning, and that by passing Bill C-6, the Parliament simply ignored the voice of<br />

the public. Cf. Timothy Caulfield, "Politics, Prohibitions and the Lost Public Perspective: A Comment on Bill C-<br />

56: The Assisted Human Reproduction Act," Alberta Law Review 40 (2002). Caulfield’s comments refer to an<br />

earlier version of the bill, but most of his arguments apply to Bill C-6 as well.<br />

161


(principle (e)). 43 Canada affords equal access to ART technologies to any (presumably adult)<br />

individual independent of sexual orientation and marital status. Accordingly, couples –<br />

heterosexual or not – as well as singles are granted equal access to ART technologies.<br />

A deductive approach to ethical controversies is not without problems however, especi<strong>all</strong>y<br />

for the regulators charged with implementing the provisions of the AHRA. For example,<br />

principle (a) is clearly intended to protect the health and well-being of children. As a matter of<br />

principle, very few would disagree that the health and well-being of children is a moral good<br />

worthy of protection, yet any attempt to give the terms “health” and “well-being” a precise<br />

operational meaning is likely to be controversial. Principle (b) identifies human dignity and<br />

human rights as two moral goods deserving protection, but leaves entirely unspecified the notion<br />

of human dignity, and does not bother to identify which human rights should be protected.<br />

Again, it would be only too easy to fault regulators for not adequately protecting human rights,<br />

or for taking too expansive a view of human dignity for that matter. Furthermore, it is quite<br />

possible that some of these principles may inspire conflicting regulatory interventions.<br />

That guiding principles leave considerable room for interpretation does not justify<br />

dismissing a deductive approach to modern ethical dilemmas as irrelevant or impracticable. It is,<br />

however, a good reason for establishing specific rules and institutions for addressing these<br />

interpretive ambiguities. In this regard, the AHRA leaves much to be desired, as it does not<br />

include any provisions as to how regulators may go about resolving the ambiguities that a<br />

principled approach inevitably will produce.<br />

The principles themselves are only in minimal part derived from a consistent ethical<br />

framework, and they seem to reflect the outcome of a political compromise. An American<br />

observer might regard them as politic<strong>all</strong>y liberal, for example, when they afford gay and lesbian<br />

couples equal access to reproductive technologies. On the other end, the principles prohibit the<br />

commercial trade of human gametes and embryos, a measure many Americans would find too<br />

restrictive. Being the result of a political compromise, these principles ignore some important<br />

issues. For example, the distinction between therapeutic and enhancing applications of new<br />

reproductive technologies has not been formalized, though it seems to inform several provisions<br />

of this act. At the same time, the fact that these principles represent a political compromise<br />

suggests that they will likely enjoy broad public support.<br />

Prohibited Activities<br />

AHRA Sections 5 through 9 enumerate proscribed reproductive procedures and research<br />

activities. Taken together, these prohibitions suggest a restrictive approach to reproductive<br />

medicine; the act prohibits many reproductive treatments now common in the United States.<br />

These prohibitions are remarkable for two main reasons. First, they apply to certain procreative<br />

ends, not to the specific technological means to achieve them. While scientific and medical<br />

43<br />

Principle (e) does not completely resolve this thorny issue. For example, it is not entirely clear whether this<br />

principle would afford a woman the right to become impregnated with the sperm of her deceased husband.<br />

162


progress over time may provide new means, they will not undermine the corresponding<br />

prohibitions. Second, the prohibitions are worded in such a way as to ensure that reproductive<br />

technologies are used exclusively for reproductive purposes narrowly defined, though as we<br />

show below, the intent to reproduce does not justify the use of each and every reproductive<br />

technology.<br />

The centerpiece of these prohibitions is Section 5. Section 5(1)(a) bans any kind of cloning,<br />

including research cloning, but does so not by specific<strong>all</strong>y prohibiting somatic cell nuclear<br />

transfer. Rather, it defines cloning in functional terms. Thus, this section simply proscribes the<br />

creation of “a human clone, by using any technique.” Consistent with its focus on human<br />

reproduction, Section 5 bans the creation of embryos for any purpose other then procreation,<br />

medical training, or the improvement of reproductive technologies. 44<br />

Medical and clinical<br />

research on human embryos remains legal, though it may be difficult, as a matter of practice, to<br />

determine whether a research protocol involving human embryos is indeed designed to improve<br />

the safety and efficacy of existing reproductive technologies. This distinction becomes<br />

particularly problematic when research protocols are designed to explore questions impinging<br />

only indirectly on actual medical practice. 45<br />

Reproductive intent alone does not justify resorting to any and every reproductive<br />

technology. Accordingly, Section 5 prohibits several reproductive procedures. For example, it<br />

bans any technique that could lead to the creation of embryos from fetuses or from embryonic<br />

stem cells. 46 This prohibition is a direct response to the announcement made in 2003 by an Israeli<br />

research group that it had successfully retrieved viable oocytes from aborted fetuses, and to other<br />

experiments in mice showing that it may be possible to derive sperm-like cells and oocytes from<br />

stem cells (see chapter 4 for details). In keeping with a narrow understanding of reproduction,<br />

Section 5 also proscribes the use of sex-selection technologies except for preventing sex-linked<br />

diseases. 47 As with other prohibitions discussed in this section, this ban does not refer to a<br />

specific sex-selection technology; it simply proscribes the use of any and <strong>all</strong> technological means<br />

for elective sex selection. Also proscribed are <strong>all</strong> forms of genetic engineering that would<br />

produce an inheritable genetic modification. 48 Presumably this prohibition extends to ooplasm<br />

transfer, as this procedure indeed produces an inheritable genetic modification by passing on<br />

mitochondrial DNA from a third party. Furthermore, innovative reproductive approaches that<br />

involve the use of animal tissues, such as co-culture, are also prohibited. 49 In keeping with<br />

44<br />

45<br />

46<br />

47<br />

48<br />

49<br />

See Section 5(1)(b).<br />

The AHRA does not ban stem cell research, however. Section 5(1)(b) only bans the creation of in vitro embryos<br />

for any purpose other than human reproduction. The act does not explicitly require the transfer of <strong>all</strong> in vitro<br />

embryos into a woman’s uterus. This introduces the possibility that existing, cryopreserved embryos can be<br />

donated for research, a solution that is reminiscent of the Australian approach to legalizing stem cell research.<br />

See Section 5(1)(c).<br />

See Section 5(1)(e).<br />

See Section 5(1)(f).<br />

See Section 5(1)(h).<br />

163


traditional views of reproduction, Sections 6 through 9 place numerous restrictions on the use of<br />

third party gametes and embryos and on surrogacy services. The commercial trade of gametes<br />

and embryos is proscribed, as are commercial offerings of surrogacy services, but gametes and<br />

embryos can be donated, and surrogacy may be provided on a non-commercial basis.<br />

Sections 5(1)(i) and 5(1)(j) ban the creation of chimeras and hybrids, respectively. Section<br />

5(1)(i) only bans the creation of a human chimera (i.e., one created by inserting non-human cells<br />

into a human embryos), but the converse procedure is legal, in keeping with common scientific<br />

practice. By contrast, Section 5(1)(j) bans any form of hybrid (i.e., fertilizing a human oocyte<br />

with non-human sperm, or fertilizing a non-human oocyte with human sperm), but also somatic<br />

cell nuclear transplantation using human and non-human cells.<br />

Surprisingly, Sections 5 through 9 do not address the legality of pre-implantation genetic<br />

diagnosis, explicitly or implicitly. Section 5(1)(b) forbids the creation of embryos for any<br />

reasons other than reproductive purposes. PGD requires the creation of several embryos for the<br />

stated purpose of selecting a few with specific characteristics. Those not meeting certain criteria<br />

are by definition not used for reproductive purposes, making PGD, in principle at least, illegal<br />

under the AHRA. However, Health Canada has made clear that under the AHRA, PGD is a<br />

regulated activity, not a prohibited one. 50<br />

Performing PGD will be controlled by a set of<br />

guidelines for which Health Canada was seeking public feedback at the time of this writing. 51<br />

Regulated Activities<br />

In AHRA terminology, regulated activities are referred to as “controlled” activities and are<br />

described in Sections 10 through 19. Sections 10 through 13 sketch the architecture of the<br />

Canadian system of licensing. Section 10(1) requires that any persons in the business of altering,<br />

manipulating, or treating human reproductive tissues for the purpose of creating an embryo be<br />

licensed. Also licensed must be any persons involved in altering, manipulating, or treating in<br />

vitro embryos, 52<br />

and any persons involved in storing, handling, transferring, importing, or<br />

exporting reproductive materials and in vitro embryos. 53<br />

A license is required to produce<br />

transgenic animals. 54 Facilities must also be licensed. 55 <strong>Final</strong>ly, reimbursement for transporting<br />

and donating gametes and embryos and for surrogacy services is also subject to regulation. 56<br />

Compared to the British licensing scheme, the Canadian approach is less demanding.<br />

Licenses are granted to perform regulated reproductive activities in toto, not for specific<br />

reproductive treatments, as is the case in Britain. At present, licenses have unlimited validity,<br />

50<br />

51<br />

52<br />

53<br />

54<br />

55<br />

56<br />

Health Canada is the Federal department responsible for protecting and improving pubic health in Canada.<br />

See http://www.hc-sc.gc.ca/ahc-asc/public-consult/col/pgd-dgp/pgd-dgp_e.html.<br />

See Section 10(2).<br />

See Section 10(3).<br />

See Section 11.<br />

See Section 13.<br />

See Section 12.<br />

164


whereas in Britain they must be renewed periodic<strong>all</strong>y. The Canadian approach to licensing,<br />

unlike its British counterpart, does not distinguish between licenses to perform ART procedures<br />

and licenses to store and distribute gametes and embryos. The Canadian approach to the<br />

licensing of reproductive medicine is of course much stricter than its U.S. counterpart, in which<br />

reproductive endocrinologists may be (but often are not required to be) specific<strong>all</strong>y licensed to<br />

perform ART procedures on a state-by-state basis, and where no such licensing requirements<br />

exist at the federal level.<br />

AHRA Sections 14 through 19 establish what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed a system of health monitoring.<br />

A key concept of this system is “health reporting information,” a term that in the act identifies<br />

what information ART practitioners must report to federal regulators. Health reporting<br />

information is a comprehensive concept that refers mainly to individuals. Individuals affected by<br />

reporting requirements f<strong>all</strong> into two categories. In the first, the AHRA includes donors of<br />

gametes and embryos, persons who have undergone an ART treatment (namely, the patients),<br />

and persons conceived through ART (i.e., the ART children proper). 57 Information regarding<br />

these individuals includes biographical, medical, and legal elements. The second category<br />

consists of individuals responsible for the custody of gametes and embryos.<br />

The AHRA stops short of requiring the implementation of a comprehensive tracking system<br />

that includes both affected individuals and reproductive tissues. The regulatory agency is<br />

required to establish and maintain a personal health information registry. However, the reporting<br />

requirements are limited to individuals directly affected by ART procedures – i.e., donors of<br />

reproductive tissues, patients, and ART children. 58 It appears that the act does not attempt to<br />

track the history of each and every in vitro embryo. Section 15(3)(1) does, however, mandate<br />

that regulators be notified when in vitro embryos are transferred between licensees. Reproductive<br />

tissues are not affected by this requirement. Section 18 defines the purposes of these reporting<br />

requirements, c<strong>all</strong>ing for regulators to use health reporting information for enforcement and for<br />

public health purposes.<br />

The AHRA specifies in some detail the rules governing the collection, access, and disclosure<br />

of health reporting information. A licensee is not <strong>all</strong>owed to accept donated gametes or embryos<br />

without obtaining the relevant health reporting information. 59 Conversely, the licensee is not<br />

<strong>all</strong>owed to disclose health reporting information without written consent of the individual whose<br />

information would be disclosed. 60 In addition, a person is entitled to obtain access to his or her<br />

own health reporting information, and to request that any corrections be made to his or her health<br />

reporting information. 61 Unfortunately, at the time of this writing, the regulations to implement<br />

these provisions have not yet been finalized. The types of information to be regarded as critical<br />

57<br />

58<br />

59<br />

60<br />

61<br />

See Section 3 – definitions.<br />

See Section 17.<br />

See Section 14.<br />

See Section 15.<br />

See Section 16.<br />

165


y the Canadian authorities and the specific data that must be reported to regulators remain to be<br />

determined.<br />

The Assisted Human Reproduction Agency of Canada<br />

Sections 21 through 39 establish a new regulatory agency, the Assisted Human<br />

Reproduction Agency of Canada (AHRAC). Section 22 sets forth two objectives for the agency<br />

– “to protect and promote the health and safety, and the human dignity and human rights, of<br />

Canadians” and to “foster the application of ethical principles” in the practice of human<br />

reproduction. The AHRAC bears some similarities to the British HFEA. It is governed by a<br />

board of directors consisting of 13 members (at the most), including the chairperson and the<br />

president. Appointments are for three-year terms and are renewable. The Canadian Governor in<br />

Council appoints both the board members and the chairperson. 62 The AHRAC is managed by a<br />

president, who is also appointed by the Governor in Council, for a term of five years, and can be<br />

reappointed.<br />

Unlike the British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act, the Canadian AHRA does not<br />

specify in any detail the rules that should inform the appointment of the board members, the<br />

chairperson, or the president. Nor does the AHRA touch on the composition of the board –<br />

whether it should be constituted as a body of specialists (as in the Australian case), or whether it<br />

should be inclusive of <strong>all</strong> societal views, above and beyond the views represented by organized<br />

interest groups (as in the British case). It only precludes individuals directly affected by AHRAC<br />

decisions from becoming board members.<br />

Canada takes a rather different approach than Britain in promulgating new rules and<br />

regulations. Technic<strong>all</strong>y, the AHRAC does not have any authority to autonomously craft new<br />

regulations; that responsibility f<strong>all</strong>s to the Canadian minister of health. Yet it would be wrong to<br />

conclude that the AHRAC is simply an administrative arm of the cabinet. Section 30(a)<br />

stipulates that one of the board’s responsibilities is to advise “the Minister on assisted human<br />

reproduction and other matters to which this Act applies, or on any matter referred to the Agency<br />

by the Minister.” So while the formal authority for promulgating new regulations and revolving<br />

controversial issues rests with the minister of health, the minister’s decisions may be heavily<br />

influenced by the AHRAC, especi<strong>all</strong>y if the agency recommendations are based on a broad<br />

process of public consultation. Thus, while from a legal standpoint the agency has very limited<br />

regulatory authority, its influence on the regulatory process is likely to be significant.<br />

The AHRA considerably restricts the authority of the executive to promulgate new<br />

regulations. Section 66 requires the minister of health to submit new regulations for approval to<br />

both houses of Parliament, a measure considered unusual by Canadian commentators. And<br />

Section 70 requires that the act be reviewed by the overseeing parliamentary committees every<br />

62<br />

In Canada, the “Governor in Council” is the governor general acting on the advice of the federal cabinet (in other<br />

words, the government executive). The cabinet is made up of the prime minister and members of parliament, and<br />

sometimes senators, chosen by the prime minister. Each member of cabinet is assigned a portfolio of<br />

responsibilities, usu<strong>all</strong>y the subject matter of a government department.<br />

166


three instead of the usual five years. Both provisions seem to reflect the highly contentious<br />

nature of the act and the Parliament’s desire to maintain a tight control over the AHRAC.<br />

The minister of health retains some administrative discretion in that he has the power to<br />

promulgate so-c<strong>all</strong>ed policy directions. The AHRA explicitly maintains that policy directions are<br />

not statutory instruments – i.e., that they are not regulations subject to parliamentary approval. 63<br />

Policy directions are meant to provide broad guidance in the implementation of the statute, and<br />

should not intrude on specific administrative decisions. The issuance of policy directions is the<br />

Canadian way of attenuating the tension between the desire to avoid politicizing administrative<br />

procedures and the need to provide guidance to regulatory agencies.<br />

In sum, compared to the HFEA, the Canadian AHRAC has a rather limited formal<br />

regulatory authority. Regulation is the province of the minister of health, and not of the agency.<br />

And unlike the U.S. Congress, which controls the administrative system mainly by indirect<br />

means, the Canadian Parliament retains direct control over the regulatory process. In this sense,<br />

the Canadian AHRAC and the British HFEA, while form<strong>all</strong>y similar, have vastly different<br />

authority. Nevertheless, the AHRAC is not entirely inconsequential, as it retains considerable<br />

(albeit indirect) influence over the regulatory process by playing a crucial mediating role<br />

between societal interests and the health ministry.<br />

Among the AHRAC’s main operational responsibilities are monitoring and evaluating<br />

clinical developments in reproductive medicine, 64<br />

gathering and analyzing health reporting<br />

information, 65 and informing and educating the public. 66 A central task for the agency is of<br />

course the licensing of individuals, organizations, and facilities. 67 Another important agency<br />

responsibility is taking measures to “prevent, reduce, or mitigate” threats to human health and<br />

safety that may result from regulated activities. 68 In spite of this deceptively simple statutory<br />

language, the implementation of this provision is likely to prove both complex and costly. Few<br />

countries have implemented a system of surveillance that meets these requirements. In the<br />

United States, surveillance is limited largely to measuring success rates on a clinic-by-clinic<br />

basis. Britain comes closest to implementing a similarly comprehensive system, but as of this<br />

writing, Health Canada has not made public any implementation details.<br />

The AHRA requires that the AHRAC not only oversee the ART industry, but also that it<br />

review research protocols involving human embryos. Since the AHRA mainly governs the use of<br />

ART technologies and deals only tangenti<strong>all</strong>y with research on human reproductive tissues, this<br />

area of medical research is regulated by a separate document, the “Human Pluripotent Stem Cell<br />

Research Guidelines.” The AHRA, however, does contain two provisions relevant to conducting<br />

63<br />

64<br />

65<br />

66<br />

67<br />

68<br />

See Section 25(3).<br />

See Section 24(1)(c).<br />

See Section 24(1)(e).<br />

See Section 24(1)(f).<br />

See Section 40.<br />

See Section 44.<br />

167


esearch on human embryos. It requires written and informed consent from the gamete or<br />

embryo donors (s. 40(3.1). And, cruci<strong>all</strong>y, Section 40(2) provides that scientists must satisfy the<br />

agency that the proposed research goals cannot be achieved by any means other than using<br />

human embryos. How this process is supposed to be implemented is an unresolved matter. In<br />

particular, it is unclear whether the review process should be conducted exclusively by members<br />

of the scientific community, or whether the review panel should also include representatives of<br />

organized interest groups or even of the general public. Also unclear is whether and to what<br />

extent proponents of rejected proposals should have access to judicial review.<br />

Some scientists may find this requirement too intrusive, or even consider it an unacceptable<br />

infringement on their scientific autonomy and professional independence. However, as a matter<br />

of practice, this approach is neither exceptional nor unreasonable. The British HFEA has been<br />

approving research protocols on human embryos in a similar fashion for many years. By<br />

distinguishing between the ends of a proposed research protocol and the means to achieve these<br />

ends, the Canadian AHRA protects a key aspect of research freedom while introducing a<br />

measure of accountability.<br />

<strong>Final</strong>ly, a significant portion of the AHRA is dedicated to inspection and enforcement<br />

procedures and to enumerating sanctions. 69 The order of magnitude of the fines imposed for<br />

many violations is similar to other cases discussed in this chapter. For example, violators of<br />

proscribed activities may be fined up to 500,000 Canadian dollars and may be imprisoned for up<br />

to 10 years.<br />

6.4 The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act – Blueprint for Action or a Case of<br />

British Peculiarity?<br />

6.4.1 Introduction<br />

Britain recognized earlier than any other OECD country that scientific developments in<br />

genetics and reproductive medicine would c<strong>all</strong> for the creation of new regulatory institutions. In<br />

1990, the British Parliament passed the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act (the HFE<br />

Act). 70 The passage of the HFE Act was the culmination of a protracted public debate initiated<br />

by the 1998 publication of the Warnock <strong>Report</strong> on the social, ethical, and legal ch<strong>all</strong>enges raised<br />

by new reproductive technologies and biomedical research. 71 The report recognized that human<br />

embryos are entitled to “some protection” under the law, consistent with the view that they are<br />

neither simply clumps of human cells nor entitled to full human status. The report acknowledged<br />

that in modern, pluralistic societies, reaching a consensus on ethical controversies is a very<br />

difficult task, and recommended the creation of a regulatory institution specific<strong>all</strong>y designed to<br />

69<br />

70<br />

71<br />

See Sections 45-59 and 60-64, respectively.<br />

The full text of the HFE Act is available at http://www.opsi.gov.uk/acts/acts1990/Ukpga_19900037_en_1.htm.<br />

<strong>Report</strong> of the Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilisation and Embryology, Cm 9314, July 1984, also known<br />

as the Warnock report.<br />

168


address ethical controversies – the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. The HFEA<br />

was charged with monitoring scientific and medical advances, and is responsible for licensing<br />

any activity that involves the in vitro creation of human embryos, the storage and donation of<br />

gametes and embryos, and medical research involving human embryos. It is also charged with<br />

enforcing the provisions of the HFE Act and its regulations.<br />

The HFE Act, based in large measure on the recommendations of the Warnock report, has<br />

stood the test of time. To date, Britain is the only country with extensive experience in the<br />

regulation of both reproductive medicine and biomedical research. The British experience in this<br />

area, therefore, is of considerable interest to any government confronted with the task of<br />

designing a regulatory structure for reproductive medicine and biomedical research.<br />

In its 15 years of existence, the HFE Act has rarely been updated. For this reason, in 2004,<br />

the British government announced that it planned to review the act and to conduct a public<br />

consultation on this matter in 2005. 72 That it has remained largely untouched for such a long<br />

period of time is itself an indication of broad public support for this approach to resolving<br />

societal controversies produced by advances in reproductive medicine. The HFEA may not be<br />

able to craft a consensus on each and every ethical controversy, and its policies have often been<br />

criticized alternatively by pro-life groups, scientists, and the ART industry, but few have<br />

questioned the legitimacy of the HFEA as a regulatory institution.<br />

The special position occupied by the HFEA in the British system of government is itself an<br />

expression of mild distrust in the ability of traditional administrative bodies to regulate<br />

biomedicine. 73 The HFEA enjoys a measure of regulatory discretion unknown to other British<br />

ministries. 74 The Parliament’s decision to shield the HFEA from traditional mechanisms of<br />

oversight can be explained partly by the desire to protect this regulatory body against the<br />

vagaries of interest group politics. It would seem only appropriate that a regulatory body charged<br />

with resolving highly controversial moral dilemmas not be perceived as being captured by the<br />

one or the other political constituency. While in other regulatory contexts the competition for<br />

power and influence among politicians and organized interest groups can be described as normal<br />

and even healthy, in the present case, the perception that the HFEA might cater to the interests of<br />

a specific political constituency would ipso facto undermine its moral authority as a regulatory<br />

body. In this sense, the partial regulatory autonomy enjoyed by the HFEA reflects the<br />

Parliament’s intention to minimize regulatory capture.<br />

72<br />

73<br />

74<br />

See http://www.dh.gov.uk/Consultations/ClosedConsultations/ClosedConsultationsArticle/fs/en?CONTENT_ID<br />

=4123863&chk=zy5dcI.<br />

Note that for brevity, we at times use the term “biomedicine” to mean reproductive medicine and biomedical<br />

research.<br />

The HFE Act delegates responsibility for promulgating the necessary regulations to the ministry of health.<br />

Regulations crafted by this ministry are subject to parliamentary review, as is the case for any other ministry.<br />

The HFEA does not have the authority to autonomously craft regulations. However, the agency does have the<br />

authority to formulate and enforce its own policies. HFEA policies, unlike regulations, are not subject to<br />

parliamentary review. In this sense, the HFEA enjoys considerably more regulatory discretion than its Canadian<br />

and Australian counterparts.<br />

169


This argument is not likely to convince American commentators of administrative law who<br />

may describe the HFEA as a classic example of an “unaccountable” regulatory institution.<br />

Form<strong>all</strong>y, the HFEA may be less accountable than other regulatory institutions, but in practice,<br />

its policies can hardly be described as “arbitrary and capricious.” The HFEA, mindful of its<br />

unique position, tradition<strong>all</strong>y has taken accountability seriously. An extensive process of public<br />

consultation always precedes the adoption of controversial new policies. Among the subjects<br />

selected by the HFEA for consultation are sex-selection and screening technologies, gamete and<br />

embryo donation, and pre-implantation genetic diagnosis. 75 Through the appointment process,<br />

the government can affect, at least in general terms, the future direction of the agency. Moreover,<br />

the HFE Act requires the HFEA to prepare an annual report for the minister of health. The<br />

reports are submitted to both houses of the Parliament for review. 76 <strong>Final</strong>ly, HFEA policies are<br />

subject to judicial review. In sum, while the HFEA enjoys more regulatory discretion than other<br />

administrative entities, it cannot be described as an unaccountable regulatory institution in the<br />

sense attributed to this term by U.S. scholars of administrative law.<br />

6.4.2 The HFE Act<br />

Any human embryo created outside the human body f<strong>all</strong>s under the jurisdiction of the HFE<br />

Act. This means that certain types of ART treatments that do not require the creation of an in<br />

vitro embryo are not subject to the act’s provisions. Artificial insemination is an example; the<br />

sale of fresh sperm is another.<br />

Like other statutes discussed in this chapter, the HFE Act distinguishes between prohibited<br />

and regulated activities. Prohibitions contemplated by the act are broadly consistent with<br />

activities banned by statutes passed in other countries. Section 3 identifies prohibited activities<br />

pertaining to the use of embryos, and Section 4 does the same for gametes. More specific<strong>all</strong>y,<br />

Section 3(2)(a) and (b) prohibits transferring a non-human embryo or any non-human gametes to<br />

a woman’s uterus. Section 3(3)(a) also prohibits storing or using an embryo after the appearance<br />

of the primitive streak, but in any case no later than 14 days. Section 3(3)(b) prohibits<br />

transferring a human embryo to an animal, and Section 3(3)(d) was intended to prohibit any form<br />

of cloning, though at the time cloning technologies did not yet exist. Section 12 prohibits, with<br />

some qualifications, the commercial trade of embryos and gametes. <strong>Final</strong>ly, Schedule 2, Section<br />

(1)(4) prohibits the genetic modification of embryos.<br />

Activities not explicitly prohibited by the HFE Act are regulated. The act regulates the<br />

artificial creation of embryos, the storage of gametes and embryos, and the use of embryos for<br />

research purposes by requiring ART practitioners and researchers to obtain a license for each of<br />

these three types of activities. 77 This means that research on human embryos, either privately or<br />

publicly funded, it legal under the act. In addition to the donation of human gametes and<br />

75<br />

76<br />

77<br />

See http://www.hfea.gov.uk/AboutHFEA/Consultations.<br />

See Sections 7(1), (2) and (3) of the Act.<br />

See Sections 3(1)(a) and (b) and Section 11.<br />

170


embryos, 78 the act regulates the creation of human-animal hybrids. 79 This is not as grotesque as it<br />

seems. Human-animal hybrids are created to test human gametes in animals, a well-established<br />

practice in reproductive medicine. The HFE Act is silent on the creation and use of chimeric<br />

embryos (embryos consisting of both human and animal cells). As part of a recently launched<br />

consultation on the revision of the HFE Act, the British department of health has solicited<br />

comments on the creation of human-animal hybrid or chimeric embryos for research purposes. 80<br />

A unique feature of the HFE Act is the absence of any reference to specific reproductive<br />

procedures, and with one exception (reproductive cloning), it has never been amended to include<br />

any such reference. For the last 15 years, it has been the HFEA’s task to craft policies designed<br />

to distinguish between permissible and impermissible uses of reproductive technologies. In part,<br />

this is due to fact that at the time the legislation was enacted, there were few if any controversial<br />

reproductive technologies. According to HFEA officials, the generic structure of the HFE Act<br />

was regarded by legislators as one if its main strengths. The act was designed to give the HFEA<br />

authority to promulgate new policies in response to new scientific and medical developments in a<br />

timely manner. This the HFEA has done with effectiveness. Among the most recent initiatives<br />

are a public consultation on the use of PGD in 2002, another public consultation in 2002-2003 on<br />

sex-selection technologies, and in 2004 a review of its policy on donated gametes and embryos. 81<br />

6.4.3 The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority<br />

The HFE Act defines the statutory functions of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology<br />

Authority as follows:<br />

• Review information about human embryos and any subsequent development of such<br />

embryos, and the provision of treatment services and activities governed by the HFE Act.<br />

The HFEA should also advise the secretary of state on relevant developments in<br />

treatments and research. 82<br />

• Promote its services and the services offered by the licensees to the public. 83<br />

• Provide relevant advice and information to patients, donors, and clinics in the UK. 84<br />

• Produce a code of practice which gives guidelines to infertility clinics about the proper<br />

conduct of licensed activities. 85<br />

78<br />

79<br />

80<br />

81<br />

82<br />

83<br />

84<br />

See Art. 4(1)(b).<br />

See Art. 4(1)(c).<br />

The consultation documents can be found at http://www.dh.gov.uk/Consultations/ClosedConsultations/ClosedCo<br />

nsultationsArticle/fs/en?CONTENT_ID=4123863&chk=zy5dcI.<br />

See http://www.hfea.gov.uk/AboutHFEA/HFEAPolicy for additional information about these consultations<br />

processes.<br />

See Art. 8(a).<br />

See Art. 8(b).<br />

See Art. 8(c).<br />

171


• Maintain a formal register of information about donors, treatments, and children born as a<br />

result of those treatments. 86<br />

To discharge these functions, the HFEA has the authority to establish additional, specialized<br />

committees. As of this writing, seven committees exist – the Regulation Committee, the<br />

Scientific and Clinical Advances Group, the Ethics and Law Committee, the Organization and<br />

Finance Committee, the Information Management Program Board, the Audit Committee, and the<br />

License Committee. 87 The first three committees discharge the core HFEA functions. Members<br />

of any of these committees are also members of the HFEA proper. Committees can establish<br />

specialized subcommittees. Participation in a subcommittee is not restricted to HFEA members.<br />

Outside members can be appointed to subcommittees, but HFEA members must remain in the<br />

majority. 88<br />

The HFE Act specifies in considerable detail the composition, responsibilities, and<br />

procedures governing the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. The HFEA, unlike its<br />

Australian counterpart, is not designed to be exclusively a technocratic body of governance. The<br />

Act tries to strike a balance between two parti<strong>all</strong>y conflicting goals, technical competence,<br />

including scientific, medical, legal and ethical expertise, and legitimacy. A regulatory body<br />

consisting exclusively of technical specialists obviously would be highly competent, but the<br />

general public may view the policies promulgated by this body with suspicion. On the other end,<br />

a regulatory body dominated by laypersons would most likely be regarded as legitimate, but its<br />

technical competence would be very limited.<br />

Currently, the HFEA has 18 members, including the chairperson and the deputy. Schedule 1<br />

of the Act (“The Authority: Supplementary Provisions”) does not specify the size of this board;<br />

that decision is left to the “Secretary of State for Health”, i.e. the health minister. It does,<br />

however, offer considerable guidance regarding its composition. Article 4(2) of Schedule 1<br />

requires that the views of both men and women be “adequately represented.” As of this writing,<br />

the HFEA consists of exactly nine women and nine men. Article 4(3) establishes that three<br />

categories of individuals are not eligible for the positions of chairperson or deputy chairperson:<br />

(a) medical practitioners, (b) individuals involved in “keeping or using gametes or embryos<br />

outside the body,” and (c) individuals with an interest in the funding of research on keeping or<br />

using gametes or embryos. The health minister must also ensure that medical and ART<br />

practitioners (categories (a) and (b)) are represented by at least one person on the board. <strong>Final</strong>ly<br />

and most importantly, the health minister must ensure that at least one-third but less than half of<br />

HFEA members represent the medical profession, the ART industry, and the research<br />

community (categories (a), (b), and (c)).<br />

85<br />

86<br />

87<br />

88<br />

See Art. 25. The sixth edition of the code is available at http://www.hfea.gov.uk/HFEAPublications/CodeofPract<br />

ice.<br />

See Art. 31.<br />

See http://www.hfea.gov.uk/AboutHFEA/OrganisationalStructure.<br />

See Sections 9(1) – 9(6).<br />

172


This provision has important consequences. It severely limits the health minister’s ability to<br />

appoint medical and scientific specialists. More specific<strong>all</strong>y, it forces the minister to select<br />

individuals who do not represent the medical profession, the ART industry, or the scientific<br />

community. In this narrow but important sense, the health minister must appoint a majority of<br />

individuals that in some sense represent the general public. This is a very unusual approach to<br />

filling important administrative positions, and as such deserves some scrutiny.<br />

It is the health minister’s responsibility to appoint a qualified individual to the HFEA.<br />

Schedule 1 does not include any appointment rules. The HFEA simply conducts a nationwide<br />

public search open to any qualified British citizen. The health minister selects new HFEA<br />

members from the pool of qualified individuals. The appointment is for a three-year term. A<br />

member of the HFEA can be reappointed, but not for consecutive terms. What constitutes a<br />

suitable candidate and what rules inform the appointment process are not entirely clear. It<br />

appears that the health minister enjoys considerable discretion in appointing new board<br />

members. In this regard, the HFEA is no exception. In the recent past, appointments to boards of<br />

“executive and advisory non-departmental public bodies” such as the HFEA have generated<br />

considerable discomfort in the general public. In response to the charge that appointments to<br />

these bodies often appear to be arbitrary and capricious, the British Government established an<br />

Office of the Commissioner for Public Appointments charged with developing a code of practice<br />

intended to increase the legitimacy and credibility of these appointments. 89 On its Web site, the<br />

HFEA states that its members are appointed in accordance with guidance from the<br />

Commissioner for Public Appointments, but the guidelines are rather generic and offer little<br />

insight into how members are actu<strong>all</strong>y selected. Conversations with HFEA officials have<br />

confirmed that the appointment process remains very much a discretionary activity of the health<br />

minister, as nominees do not need to be confirmed by the Parliament and no specific guidelines<br />

exist for the selection of suitable candidates.<br />

In our view, the appointment process remains the weakest element of the British approach to<br />

regulating reproductive medicine and medical technologies. To appreciate the limits of current<br />

appointment rules, one should try to identify those HFEA members that do not represent the<br />

fertility industry, the medical profession, or the scientific community. The HFEA Web site<br />

provides a list of current members complete with short biographical abstracts, but it does not<br />

supply any information about the slot occupied by each member. 90 There are seven members<br />

who are obviously not representing the three main constituencies – the chairperson (a consumer<br />

group advocate), a reverend, the UK’s financial Ombudsman, a broadcast journalist, a finance<br />

and business professional, a very senior career politician, and a senior editor. These are<br />

accomplished senior individuals, <strong>all</strong> of whom can be expected to appreciate the complexities<br />

involved in regulating reproductive medicine and medical research. However, they can hardly be<br />

regarded as typical representatives of the general public.<br />

89<br />

90<br />

See http://www.ocpa.gov.uk/the_code_of_practice/index.asp.<br />

See http://www.hfea.gov.uk/AboutHFEA/HFEAMembers.<br />

173


The remaining three positions reserved to laypersons are occupied by a representative of an<br />

infertility group, a professor of medical law, and a professor of philosophy and ethics. These are<br />

certainly highly qualified individuals, but one could legitimately wonder to what extent they may<br />

be viewed as representatives of the general public. An unsympathetic reading of these<br />

appointments could easily come to the conclusion that the HFEA lay members are neither lay nor<br />

representative of the general public. Infertility groups, far from playing a mediating role between<br />

the public and the ART industry, often are focused exclusively on their narrow interest. Whether<br />

a professor specialized in medical law is more likely to take a broad public view of bioethical<br />

dilemmas is an open question. As for the philosophy professor, it is difficult to imagine a profile<br />

more distant from common conceptions of a layperson.<br />

It is certainly not our intention to disparage the integrity and the professionalism of the<br />

HFEA board members. What this short discussion shows is how problematic the notion of a<br />

layperson can be. As it is now constituted, the HFEA is not too dissimilar from any other<br />

technical advisory board – impressive in terms of the scope and depth of medical and scientific<br />

expertise but hardly inclusive of lay views. These shortcomings notwithstanding, it must be<br />

emphasized that HFEA appointments have rarely been controversial. Perhaps the British are less<br />

distrustful of public officials than the American public.<br />

It would have been interesting to examine in some detail the rules governing the HFEA<br />

decision-making process. Unfortunately, we were unable to identify any. Schedule 1 leaves it to<br />

the HFEA to constitute itself as it sees fit, but the HFEA has never spelled out these rules. It is<br />

plausible to assume that the HFEA devotes a considerable amount of time to deliberating<br />

controversial ethical questions – in other words, that it operates in a deliberative fashion.<br />

Whether deliberation, on balance, leads to consensual positions or whether this regulatory body<br />

remains divided most of the time is unclear. Asked about this issue, HFEA officials have<br />

gener<strong>all</strong>y been evasive, a reaction suggesting that the decision-making process is not informed<br />

by clear and unambiguous rules, that conflicts may be common, and that their resolution may<br />

depend on a vote or on an executive decision by the chairperson.<br />

6.4.4 Licensing<br />

The HFE Act specifies both general requirements 91 and specific criteria for obtaining a<br />

treatment, 92 a storage license, 93 and a research license. 94 Additional licensing requirements are<br />

introduced in Schedules 2 and 3. Article 12 lays out the basic provisions for obtaining a license,<br />

including record-keeping requirements, the right of the HFEA to inspect a licensed facility, and<br />

the obligation of a licensed facility to provide records to the HFEA upon request.<br />

91<br />

92<br />

93<br />

94<br />

See Art. 12.<br />

See Art. 13.<br />

See Art. 14.<br />

See Art. 15.<br />

174


Schedule 2, Article 1 enumerates the activities a treatment license authorizes a licensee to<br />

conduct – creating human embryos, 95 keeping embryos, 96 using gametes, 97 testing embryos<br />

before implantation, 98 placing an embryo in a woman, 99 and mixing human sperm with animal<br />

eggs (to test the viability of the sperm). 100 The validity of a treatment license is limited to five<br />

years.<br />

Article 13 spells out the requirements for obtaining a treatment license, and specifies the<br />

record-keeping requirements 101 – it requires protecting the integrity of personal records 102 and<br />

taking into account the welfare of the prospective child when considering treatment; 103<br />

it<br />

mandates counseling for the woman and/or the couple prior to treatment; 104 and it demands that<br />

procedures be put in place for determining the identify of gametes and embryo donors. 105<br />

Of some interest to an American audience is Article 13(5). As mentioned above, this Article<br />

13 sanctions the principle that the welfare of ART children is be taken explicitly into account<br />

when considering the pros and cons of a reproductive treatment. What exactly constitutes<br />

“welfare” is defined more precisely in the code of practice discussed below. 106 For example, the<br />

HFEA considers protecting the well-being of future children incompatible with single women<br />

and lesbian couples seeking reproductive services. This policy has been very controversial from<br />

the beginning, but it has remained in place. Whether it will survive the ongoing review process<br />

remains to be seen.<br />

Licensing requirements for the storage of gametes and embryos are relatively straightforward:<br />

They simply require that storage be performed by licensed persons only, and that<br />

reproductive materials be supplied or transferred only to individuals in possession of a license for<br />

storage or treatment. Gametes can be stored for up to 10 years, embryos for five years.<br />

More interesting to the present discussion are the provisions of Schedule 2, Article 3<br />

concerning the granting of research licenses. Britain has been able to solve the conflict between<br />

the scientists’ desire to protect the freedom of research and public demands for increased<br />

accountability in controversial areas of medical research. Article 3 explicitly authorizes<br />

conducting research on human embryos, but it severely restricts the scope for conducting this<br />

95<br />

96<br />

97<br />

98<br />

99<br />

See (1)(1)(a).<br />

See (1)(1)(b).<br />

See (1)(1)(c).<br />

See (1)(1)(d).<br />

See (1)(1)(e).<br />

100<br />

See (1)(1)(f).<br />

101<br />

See Art. 13(2).<br />

102<br />

See Art. 13(4).<br />

103<br />

See Art. 13(5).<br />

104<br />

See Art. 13(6).<br />

105<br />

See Art. 13(7).<br />

106<br />

See Articles 25 and 26.<br />

175


type of research. The HFEA is required by the HFE Act to ensure that the proposed research<br />

meets any of the following criteria: 107<br />

• It promotes advances in the treatment of infertility<br />

• It increases knowledge about the causes of congenital disease<br />

• It increases knowledge about the causes of miscarriages<br />

• It aims to develop more effective methods of contraception<br />

• It aims at developing methods for detecting gene or chromosomal abnormalities in embryos<br />

• Other such purposes as may be specified in regulations<br />

In November of 2000, following the recommendations of a report by the Chief Medical<br />

Officer’s Expert Advisory Group titled “Stem Cell Research: Medical Progress with<br />

Responsibility,” 108 the Parliament passed new regulations known as the Human Fertilisation and<br />

Embryology (Research Purposes) Regulations 2001. 109 The new regulations, effective January<br />

31, 2001, <strong>all</strong>ow the HFEA the grant a research license for the following additional activities:<br />

• Research involving embryos for the purpose of increasing knowledge about the development<br />

of embryos<br />

• Increasing knowledge about the development of disease<br />

• Enabling any such knowledge to be applied in developing treatment for serious disease<br />

These regulations are meant to legalize research cloning – to <strong>all</strong>ow the creation of embryos<br />

by somatic cell nuclear transfer for research purposes. Following the passage of the Human<br />

Fertilisation and Embryology (Research Purposes) Regulations 2001, several members of<br />

Parliament grew concerned that these new regulations would open the door to reproductive<br />

cloning. To prevent this possibility, in the same year, the Parliament explicitly banned human<br />

reproductive cloning. 110<br />

Based on our conversations with HFEA staff, obtaining a license to conduct research on<br />

human embryos is no easy task. For example, the HFEA requires applicants to demonstrate that<br />

their research goals cannot be achieved without sacrificing human embryos. By imposing this<br />

requirement, the HFEA, for <strong>all</strong> intents and purposes, separates (scientific) means and ends. The<br />

HFEA does not question the ends (the research goals), but it probes whether the means are<br />

commensurate with these goals. The HFE Act also establishes specific rules for appealing a<br />

107<br />

See Art. 3(2).<br />

108<br />

See http://www.dh.gov.uk/AboutUs/MinistersAndDepartmentLeaders/ChiefMedicalOfficer/ProgressOnPolicy/P<br />

rogressBrowsableDocument/fs/en?CONTENT_ID=4108203&amp;MULTIPAGE_ID=5123869&amp;chk=JCM<br />

yhP.<br />

109<br />

See http://www.opsi.gov.uk/si/si2001/20010188.htm.<br />

110<br />

See http://www.opsi.gov.uk/acts/acts2001/20010023.htm.<br />

176


decision by the licensing committee. 111 Researchers whose applications have been turned down<br />

can first request to give an oral presentation to this committee. If the licensing committee persists<br />

in refusing to grant a license, researchers can appeal to the HFEA. <strong>Final</strong>ly, researchers can<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enge the decision by appealing to the High Court.<br />

American scientists may find the British approach to granting research licenses too<br />

restrictive. They may believe that the HFE Act excessively limits research freedom by granting<br />

too much discretion to the HFEA, leading to “capricious and arbitrary” decisions. They may also<br />

perceive this approach to be too bureaucratic and cumbersome. Others commentators may find<br />

the utilitarian orientation underlying granting research licenses unacceptable. Still others may be<br />

disturbed by the notion that the government is involved in the business of sanctioning the<br />

destruction of human embryos.<br />

To <strong>all</strong> those who oppose conducting research on human embryos, the British approach will<br />

remain unacceptable. To other critics, however, this approach also has some attractive features. It<br />

greatly reduces the need for scrutiny by universities and hospitals, a considerable burden<br />

according to some scientists. It establishes clear and consistent criteria for conducting embryo<br />

research, and it ensures equal treatment for publicly and privately funded research. Importantly,<br />

the utilitarian approach to evaluating research proposals ensures that the researchers must justify<br />

their methodological choices in some detail. In sum, the British approach to granting research<br />

licenses protects the freedom of research while satisfying public demands for holding scientists<br />

accountable.<br />

6.4.5 The Code of Practice<br />

Under the HFE Act, the HFEA has a statutory duty to prepare a Code of Practice. The Code<br />

of Practice provides considerable guidance to licensees (ART clinics, research institutions, and<br />

gametes and embryo banks) and to patients concerning the proper implementation of the act<br />

itself. It is in this area that the HFEA regulatory autonomy manifests itself. The HFEA uses the<br />

code to promulgate specific policies on a wide range of reproductive practices and ethical<br />

questions. The sixth edition of the Code of Practice, published in 2003, covers most aspects of<br />

the HFE Act. 112 New to this edition are Sections 14 (on pre-implantation genetic testing), 15 (on<br />

witnessing clinical and laboratory procedures), and 16 (on intra-cytoplasmic sperm injection).<br />

The legal status of the Code of Practice is somewhat ambiguous; its provisions do not have the<br />

force of law, but licensees are well-advised to take its recommendations seriously, as<br />

disregarding its provisions may have serious negative consequences. 113<br />

111<br />

See Articles 20 and 21.<br />

112<br />

These include staff, facilities, and administrative procedures, welfare of the child, assessing and screening<br />

potential donors, information, consent, counseling, use of gametes and embryos, storage and handling of gametes<br />

and embryos, research, records, confidentiality, complaints, pre-implantation genetic testing, witnessing clinical<br />

and laboratory procedures, and intra-cytoplasmic sperm injection.<br />

113<br />

Article 25(5) states: “A failure on the part of any person to observe any provision of the Code sh<strong>all</strong> not of itself<br />

render the person liable to any proceedings, but: (a) a License Committee sh<strong>all</strong>, in considering whether there has<br />

177


The relevance of the Code of Practice can hardly be overemphasized. It makes it much<br />

easier for licensees to comply with the HFE Act by reducing legal uncertainty. It also<br />

demonstrates how a regulatory body can promote the adoption of best practices without crafting<br />

rigid rules and regulations. The code accomplishes this through the HFEA system of monitoring<br />

and compliance assurance. Clinics are audited on a regular basis, typic<strong>all</strong>y yearly. Inspections are<br />

unannounced, and violations can lead to suspension of the license. In this regard, the HFEA’s<br />

approach to compliance assurance is no different than any other enforcement system. However,<br />

many inspections are conducted not by HFEA officials but ART professionals themselves,<br />

typic<strong>all</strong>y colleagues at other ART clinics. This measure was taken not to increase economic<br />

efficiency or to reduce personnel costs, but to promote reciprocal learning and the adoption of<br />

best practices. According to HFEA officials, this approach has proven very successful in<br />

ensuring that clinics become aware of potential areas of concern, and has indeed promoted the<br />

adoption of best practices among ART practitioners. 114 The HFEA capitalizes on this process by<br />

carefully scrutinizing audit results and by using this information to improve existing policies and<br />

practices.<br />

6.5 Summary and Conclusions<br />

Our review of legislative initiatives at the international level provides several lessons. Most<br />

industrialized countries and many developing nations have responded to the ethical dilemmas<br />

raised by reproductive medicine and biomedical research not only by appointing ethics<br />

commissions, but also by passing new legislation. As Appendix H demonstrates, there is a<br />

remarkable agreement among legislative bodies around the world on which reproductive<br />

practices and scientific developments may c<strong>all</strong> for governmental interventions. These include<br />

embryo research, reproductive cloning, research cloning, stem cell research, pre-implantation<br />

genetic diagnosis, the creation of chimeric animals, the creation of hybrids, germ-line genetic<br />

modifications, surrogacy, and the trade or sale of gametes and embryos. The United States is the<br />

exception, having refrained to adopting any specific measures for most of these developments.<br />

Among the countries included in our survey, there is little agreement on how to respond to<br />

new developments in biomedicine. Most countries have banned reproductive cloning. In other<br />

respects, however, important differences remain. Interestingly, prevailing religious and cultural<br />

orientations seem to be weak predictors of legislative choices. Spain, for example, has much<br />

more liberal stem cell research legislation than France or Italy. Important differences exist<br />

been a failure to comply with the conditions of a license and, in particular, conditions requiring anything to be<br />

“proper” or “suitable,” take account of any relevant provision of the Code, and (b) a License Committee may, in<br />

considering, where it has power to do so, whether or not to vary or revoke a license, take into account any<br />

observance or failure to observe the provisions of the Code.<br />

114<br />

This practice is not as uncommon as one might think. In many industrial sectors that have adopted voluntary<br />

environmental and safety codes, “compliance” is often ensured through an analogous mechanism. For example,<br />

in the United States, the National Paint and Coatings Association, an organization that has adopted a<br />

comprehensive and mandatory system of environmental management known as “Coating Care,” relies on<br />

reciprocal audits to monitor compliance and promote the adoption of best practices.<br />

178


among Scandinavian countries; Sweden has embraced stem cell research and research cloning,<br />

whereas Norway has adopted a much more cautious and restrictive approach. Similar differences<br />

exist among Asian countries. These diverging legislative paths suggest that it would be<br />

premature to envisage comprehensive international treaties in this area save for a ban on human<br />

reproductive cloning.<br />

Relatively few countries have adopted a regulatory approach or have created new regulatory<br />

institutions. This may reflect important differences in national administrative systems and in<br />

legal traditions, not to mention imperfect knowledge of these systems on our part. It appears that<br />

in many cases, existing ministries have been given the authority to craft regulations in the area of<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research. Switzerland is a case in point. The Australian,<br />

Canadian, and British cases demonstrate that the delegation of legislative authority is a realistic<br />

but not unproblematic legislative response. How these regulatory bodies can preserve their moral<br />

authority without being perceived as unaccountable institutions is a question that has not yet<br />

received an entirely satisfactory answer.<br />

It has also become clear that neither the British HFEA nor its Australian and Canadian<br />

cousins offer a template for building an analogous regulatory institution in the United States. The<br />

HFEA decision-making process is probably too informal and not sufficiently transparent for the<br />

U.S. public. Nor is an 18-member regulatory body likely to garner much support. The Australian<br />

approach is more considerate of regional differences and could therefore be considered a better<br />

fit, but it also reflects Australian peculiarities that would make it unsuitable to the U.S.<br />

administrative context. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the Canadian approach, though promising in many ways, is still<br />

being implemented and cannot be properly evaluated. In short, while these three countries have<br />

demonstrated the soundness and viability of a regulatory approach to reproductive medicine and<br />

biomedical research, their respective approaches cannot easily be adapted to the U.S.<br />

administrative and legal system.<br />

179


180


6.6 Bibliography<br />

Caulfield, Timothy. "Politics, Prohibitions and the Lost Public Perspective: A Comment on Bill<br />

C-56: The Assisted Human Reproduction Act." Alberta Law Review 40 (2002): 451-62.<br />

Makkai, Toni, and John Braithwaite. "Reintegrative Shaming and Compliance with Regulatory<br />

Standards." Criminology 32 (1994): 361-85.<br />

No Need for More Stem Cell Embryos Sydney Morning Herald, March 29, 2005 [cited<br />

September 22, 2005]. Available from http://www.smh.com.au/news/National/No-needfor-more-stem-cell-embryos-MPs/2005/03/29/1111862384922.html?oneclick=true.<br />

181


182


7 Constitutional Constraints?<br />

7.1 Traditional Reproductive Technologies versus Technologies of Reproductive Control<br />

Many Americans regard procreative decisions as a quintessenti<strong>all</strong>y private choice. This is<br />

especi<strong>all</strong>y true of prospective parents, advocacy groups, and ART professionals. Widely held<br />

beliefs in the area of reproductive medicine tend to translate into the presumption that<br />

procreative choices should receive constitutional protection against government interventions.<br />

Rules and regulations promulgated by a new regulatory entity are therefore likely to trigger<br />

judicial review. In light of this possibility, it is worthwhile exploring in some detail what legal<br />

reasoning may warrant granting or denying constitutional protection to procreative choices<br />

involving the use of assisted reproductive technologies.<br />

No matter what a regulatory intervention in the area of reproductive medicine is designed to<br />

achieve, one of its most likely effects is to limit the access to these technologies and in some<br />

cases to nullify some individuals’ desires to have a progeny. There is little doubt that laws and<br />

regulations are indeed likely to restrict the access to assisted reproductive technologies, at least<br />

in part, but their constitutional import varies considerably depending on the type of restriction<br />

and reproductive technology involved and the likely impact on prospective parents. Making the<br />

access to in vitro fertilization excessively difficult may be a much more problematic proposition<br />

than banning reproductive cloning, for example. How regulatory interventions may be ranked in<br />

terms of their constitutional import is the subject of this chapter.<br />

Since Louise Brown was born more than 25 years ago, the number of available reproductive<br />

technologies has expanded greatly. Assisted reproductive technologies nowadays include IVF,<br />

GIFT (gamete intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer), ZIFT (zygote intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer), IUIs (intrauterine<br />

insemination with washed sperm), intravaginal culture, oocyte and sperm donation, and<br />

micromanipulations such as ICSI (intracytoplasmic sperm injection), among others. 1<br />

The<br />

ultimate purpose of <strong>all</strong> these medical procedures is identical: They are designed to help couples<br />

and individuals to start a family. None of these technologies was designed to meet specific<br />

parental desires other than to have a child. For this reason, in the following discussion we speak<br />

of traditional assisted reproductive technologies. 2<br />

In a different category are assisted reproductive technologies designed not merely to<br />

facilitate procreation but to customize it. Customization may mean different things, ranging from<br />

selecting an embryo free of a particular genetic disease to giving birth to a baby for the purpose<br />

1<br />

2<br />

A partial discussion of these procedures can be found in Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "2002<br />

Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," p.3.<br />

We have introduced this category and discussed some of the ethical issues raised by these types of procreative<br />

technologies in chapter 4.<br />

183


of saving the life of an older sibling. Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis is commonly used in<br />

both cases. Customization may also mean fulfilling a desire for a girl or a boy, a desire whose<br />

fulfillment technologies such as MicroSort are making both possible and affordable. A more<br />

problematic illustration of customized conception has been provided by a couple of deaf<br />

individuals that wished to have a deaf child. 3<br />

This category also comprises any ART that<br />

facilitates selecting embryos for higher traits, a fairly remote possibility at this time but one that,<br />

given the speed of scientific progress, should not be underestimated. 4 In this chapter, we refer to<br />

procreative technologies that facilitate meeting specific parental desires as technologies of<br />

customization.<br />

The distinction between technologies of customization and traditional assisted reproductive<br />

technologies is crucial. 5 The former are not designed primarily to overcome a physiological<br />

condition (infertility) that impairs the procreative capacity of an individual, man or woman.<br />

Rather, these technologies expand the prospective parents’ ability to control the procreative<br />

process itself. Unlike regulatory interventions in the area of traditional ARTs, laws and<br />

regulations pertaining to technologies of reproductive control have a much more limited impact<br />

on prospective parents. They may restrict the range of available procreative options but do not<br />

constraint the ability to procreate per se. In other words, interventions in this area target specific<br />

reproductive goals, for example elective sex selection, but do not in any way question the<br />

legitimacy of an individual or a couple’s desire to start a family.<br />

Laws and regulations in the area of traditional assisted reproduction are more likely to<br />

impinge upon a basic desire to have a progeny; these interventions, in addition to making the<br />

access to traditional ARTs somewhat more difficult and costly, are also likely to limit the range<br />

of available reproductive options, possibly making it impossible for certain couples and<br />

individuals to fulfill their reproductive dreams. Consider, for example, a ban on the free trade of<br />

oocytes. Prohibiting commercial practices in this area is likely to reduce the availability of<br />

oocytes and make it impossible for some couples to have a progeny. Older women in particular<br />

may discover that the scarcity of oocytes tends to put them at a disadvantage.<br />

Marital status and the type of intimate relationships involved in a procreative project<br />

represent a second dimension of our discussion. ART services are no longer requested only by<br />

traditional families (i.e., by married heterosexual couples). Single individuals, both women and<br />

men, unmarried couples, as well as homosexual couples of both sexes are increasingly seeking<br />

out the services of the ART industry. Laws and regulations in the area of reproductive medicine<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

Spriggs, "Lesbian Couple Create a Child Who Is Deaf Like Them."<br />

In a recent review of the scientific literature in this area, the Genetics and Public Policy Institute suggests that<br />

targeted genetic modifications may become possible much earlier that anticipated just a few years ago Baruch et<br />

al., "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues and Options for Policymakers."<br />

In chapter 4, we introduced a somewhat finer classificatory grid. Consistency would require that we use the same<br />

classificatory scheme in this chapter. However, doing so would have made our discussion exceedingly lengthy<br />

and complex. To keep this chapter from becoming unwieldy, we have decided to focus on the distinction that is<br />

in our view is of fundamental importance – the distinction between therapeutic uses and technologies of<br />

reproductive customization.<br />

184


are likely to limit the number of reproductive options available to some of these couples and<br />

individuals, or to make the access to them more difficult. For example, regulations governing<br />

access to sperm banks may stifle a single woman’s desire to have a baby. Surrogacy laws may<br />

prevent a single man or a homosexual couple from having a genetic<strong>all</strong>y related child. To the<br />

extent that laws and regulations restrict access to reproductive options for certain couples and<br />

individuals, they are also likely to be reviewed by the courts.<br />

The combination of different reproductive technologies and diverse family relationships and<br />

reproductive goals gives rise to a bewildering array of distinctive situations. Examining each and<br />

every possible combination is well beyond the scope of the present discussion. Here, we limit<br />

ourselves to examining two sets of fairly homogenous cases, regulatory interventions targeted at<br />

traditional assisted reproductive technologies and regulations limiting the availability of<br />

technologies of customization. 6<br />

The distinction between regulatory interventions targeted at traditional assisted reproductive<br />

technologies and interventions limiting the access to technologies of customization is informed<br />

by the view that each type of intervention impinges on qualitatively different individual choices,<br />

and c<strong>all</strong>s upon different standards of state justifications. Government interventions in traditional<br />

forms of assisted reproduction may be more problematic than regulations designed to restrict the<br />

access to technologies of customization. Treating different procreative projects differently<br />

already suggests that a broadly defined fundamental right of procreation may not exist, if this<br />

right is supposed to protect access to ARTs independently of their purpose, of the technological<br />

means envisaged, and of the individuals involved. This is an important point worth emphasizing.<br />

It is certainly not our intention to deny individuals an opportunity to procreate. At the same time,<br />

we believe it would be wrong for the courts to discover a broad new class of fundamental rights.<br />

As we show below, neither the U.S. Constitution nor case law provides an especi<strong>all</strong>y strong<br />

justification for recognizing a broad class of new fundamental reproductive rights. The public<br />

and its elected representatives should have the opportunity to extensively debate the relative<br />

merits of protecting individual liberties vs. honoring majoritarian societal values as expressed by<br />

federal and state laws and regulations, before the Supreme Court is c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to adjudicate<br />

societal controversies. A Supreme Court ruling recognizing the existence of a broadly construed<br />

6<br />

Like any classificatory scheme, the distinction between these two classes of assisted reproductive technologies is<br />

not always unambiguous. For example, is egg donation for women in their 40s and 50s an instance of a<br />

traditional assisted reproductive treatment or a case of reproductive control? One could argue that age is not a<br />

medical condition, and therefore that egg donation in this case should be considered a technology of reproductive<br />

control. On the other end, this treatment can hardly be described as a technology of customization, so perhaps it<br />

should be considered a more or less traditional instance of assisted reproductive treatment. That it may not<br />

always be possible to unambiguously characterize each and every case as either an instance of assisted<br />

reproductive treatment or as an example of customized conception is not a specific limitation of our<br />

classificatory scheme, but simply an illustration of the conventional nature of any system of classification.<br />

Barnes, "On the Conventional Character of Knowledge and Cognition."; Barnes, Bloor, and Henry, Scientific<br />

Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis; Bloor, Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions.<br />

185


procreative right, unlikely as it is, would preclude any such debate, and would likely be regarded<br />

by the public and the Congress as undemocratic. 7<br />

7.2 Questions of Constitutional Interpretation<br />

7.2.1 Selecting a Level of Generality<br />

In deciding whether a right qualifies as fundamental, the Court applies what has become<br />

known as the “substantive due process” doctrine. The term stems from the interpretation of the<br />

due process clause of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments. The Court has long held the view<br />

that due process consists of both a procedural and a substantive component. Substantive due<br />

process is indispensable to protect certain fundamental rights from lawfully being taken by the<br />

state. The due process clause then requires not only that the state follow certain rules and<br />

procedures in taking away a “person’s life, freedom, or property,” but also that it provide a<br />

rational justification for doing so. Unfortunately, it is not entirely clear how the Court applies<br />

this doctrine.<br />

Substantive due process remains an extremely controversial legal doctrine. 8 During the soc<strong>all</strong>ed<br />

Lochner era, the Court made extensive use of substantive due process to invalidate state<br />

laws restricting economic activities. 9 With Griswold v. Connecticut (1965), the Court sanctioned<br />

a fundamental right to privacy partly on substantive due process grounds that laid the basis<br />

during the 1970s and 1980s for an expansive interpretation of privacy rights. It is not too difficult<br />

to appreciate the reasons for the controversial nature of this legal doctrine: It affords the Court an<br />

extremely powerful tool of political intervention. How the Court should go about determining<br />

whether an asserted liberty interest is fundamental is not entirely clear. Two distinctive<br />

approaches can be identified, one based mainly on case law and the other on societal traditions.<br />

We examine each in turn.<br />

Crucial to the determination whether an asserted fundamental right is consistent with early<br />

rulings is the selection of what constitutional scholars refer to as the appropriate “level of<br />

generality.” 10 This concept can best be explained with an example. Consider the case of a couple<br />

7<br />

8<br />

9<br />

10<br />

In passing, we should mention that this is not an issue of conservative versus liberal politics. To our knowledge,<br />

only the United States among modern democracies has introduced a right to terminate a pregnancy by judicial<br />

means. Every other country that has legalized abortion has done so through the legislative process.<br />

James W. Ely, "The Oxymoron Reconsidered: Myth and Reality in the Origins of Substantive Due Process,"<br />

Constitutional Commentary 16 (1999); John Harrison, "Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text,"<br />

Virginia Law Review 83 (1997); Stephen A. Newman, "Human Cloning and the Substantive Due Process<br />

Riddle," Southern California Interdisciplinary Law Journal 8 (1998).<br />

See 198 U.S. 45 (1905). The Court found a New York law limiting the number of hours a baker could work each<br />

week unconstitutional on the grounds that it was a violation of substantive due process and c<strong>all</strong>ed it an<br />

“unreasonable, unnecessary, and arbitrary interference with the right and liberty of the individual to contract.”<br />

Bruce Ackerman, "Levels of Generality in Constitutional Interpretation: Liberating Abstraction," University of<br />

Chicago Law Review 59 (1992); Frank H. Easterbrook, "Presidential Review," Case Western Reserve Law<br />

Review 40 (1990); Laurence H. Tribe and Michael C. Dorf, "Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights,"<br />

University of Chicago Law Review 57 (1990).<br />

186


that has been denied access to pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for a non-therapeutic use –<br />

elective sex selection, for example. The couple decides to ch<strong>all</strong>enge this regulation in court on<br />

the grounds that the federal statute banning elective sex selection violates its right to privacy.<br />

How is the Court to determine whether the couple has a legitimate liberty interest in this matter,<br />

and if so what criteria should inform the Court decision as to whether this interest constitutes a<br />

fundamental right? The latter question is often at the center of cases involving reproductive<br />

rights. Surprisingly (to us at least), no coherent methodology exists to determine whether an<br />

asserted right should be considered fundamental.<br />

The Court can seek guidance, first of <strong>all</strong>, in the Constitution itself. A narrow reading of the<br />

case under consideration would lead to the (obvious) conclusion that the Constitution offers no<br />

guidance whatsoever on the use of PGD for elective sex selection. Absent any guidance at this<br />

extremely low level of generality, the Court could select a somewhat higher level of generality. It<br />

could do so by scrutinizing its own judicial record. The Court could consult opinions involving<br />

the use of other reproductive technologies of customization, of which PGD for elective sex<br />

selection is an example. Once again, the Court would not be able to find any relevant precedents.<br />

The justices could select an even higher level of generality by turning to cases pertaining to the<br />

use of assisted reproductive technologies in general. Unable to find relevant precedents, the<br />

Court could simply review cases involving procreative rights narrowly defined, or even<br />

procreative rights in general (in other words, rights to procreate or not to procreate).<br />

Unsatisfied with an interpretation of case law based on reproductive rights, the Court could<br />

explore an altogether different line of reasoning involving privacy rights. These rulings, not<br />

coincident<strong>all</strong>y, include (but are not limited to) several rulings pertaining to reproduction. Should<br />

the Court determine that PGD for elective sex selection re<strong>all</strong>y revolves around privacy rights, it<br />

would explore which activities in the past have been deemed private, and whether the case under<br />

consideration may be described as another instance of a private activity the government can only<br />

infringe by meeting a strict scrutiny test. 11 But the Court could also determine that neither its<br />

rulings on reproductive rights nor those pertaining to privacy re<strong>all</strong>y shed much light on the<br />

present case and decide to explore an altogether different line of reasoning.<br />

To say that selecting the most appropriate level of generality is a task fraught with<br />

difficulties is an understatement. As our brief discussion demonstrates, it may be possible to<br />

select more than one line of Court rulings consistent with the case under review. Worse, the<br />

Court may find that cases raising seemingly analogous questions have received rather different<br />

answers. That under these circumstances the Court is far more likely to “discover” new<br />

fundamental rights is not entirely surprising. For this reason, in recent times, the Court has<br />

resorted to what a commentator has labeled “due process traditionalism.” 12 In banning physician-<br />

11<br />

12<br />

The Court applies the “strict scrutiny” test to government intervention in matters deemed fundamental. In<br />

principle at least, the government is not prevented from infringing upon a fundamental right, but the intervention<br />

in this case must be motivated by a “compelling state interest.” In addition, the state must demonstrate that the<br />

proposed intervention is a necessary and narrowly drawn means to pursue a compelling state interest.<br />

Cass Sunstein, "Is There a Constitutional Right to Clone?," Hastings Law Journal 53 (2002), p.989.<br />

187


assisted suicide, the Court has established that practices protected by substantive due process<br />

must meet two specific requirements: (a) that they be “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and<br />

tradition” and “implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,” such that “neither liberty nor justice<br />

would exist if they were sacrificed,” and (b) that there be a “careful description” of the liberty<br />

interest being asserted. 13 An asserted right, then, is deemed fundamental if there exist specific,<br />

longstanding societal traditions that uphold it.<br />

The most articulate advocate of this approach has been Antonin Scalia. In Michael v. Gerald<br />

(1989), the Court was c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to determine whether a natural father had visitation rights to a<br />

child conceived with a women married to another man. The Court found that protecting the<br />

integrity of the family trumped the father’s interest in visiting with his child. 14 Justice Brennan,<br />

dissenting, argued that the Court should have focused on “parenthood” rather than on the right of<br />

natural fathers, per se. In a now-famous footnote, Justice Scalia replied that the Court in its<br />

ruling had selected the most specific level of generality at which a relevant tradition protects or<br />

denies protection to an asserted right. 15 Had the Court majority followed Justice Brennan and<br />

selected the much broader category of parenthood, perhaps the father’s interest in maintaining<br />

and developing a close relationship with his child would have been recognized. But because a<br />

societal tradition with regard to the rights of the natural father of a child adulterously conceived<br />

existed, it was not necessary for the Court to select the much higher level of generality implied<br />

by the concept of “parenthood.”<br />

Several Court cases have been decided by invoking historical traditions at the lowest<br />

possible level of generality. For example, in Moore v. East Cleveland (1977), the Court<br />

determined that a woman had a right to live with her two grandsons in one apartment even<br />

though a local ordinance limited occupancy of a dwelling unit to members of a single family. In<br />

finding against the city of Cleveland, the Court noted that “Our decisions establish that the<br />

Constitution protects the sanctity of the family precisely because the institution of the family is<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

See 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997).<br />

Note the ambiguity built into this argument: The “family” to be protected in this case is implicitly defined in<br />

legal terms, whereas the relationship between the father and his child is reduced to a mere matter of “visitation<br />

rights.”<br />

Justice Scalia formulated his reply to Justice Brennan as follows:<br />

We do not understand why, having rejected our focus upon the societal tradition regarding the<br />

natural father’s rights vis-à-vis a child whose mother is married to another man, Justice Brennan<br />

would choose to focus instead upon “parenthood.” Why should the relevant category not be even<br />

more general – perhaps “family relationships”; or “personal relationships”; or even “emotional<br />

attachments in general”? Though the dissent has no basis for the level of generality it would select,<br />

we do: We refer to the most specific level at which a relevant tradition protecting, or denying<br />

protection to, the asserted right can be identified. If, for example, there were no societal tradition,<br />

either way, regarding the rights of the natural father of a child adulterously conceived, we would<br />

have to consult, and (if possible) reason from, the traditions regarding natural fathers in general.<br />

But there is such a more specific tradition, and it unqualifiedly denies protection to such a parent.<br />

491 U.S. 110, footnote 6, emphasis added.<br />

188


deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.” 16<br />

In Snyder v. Commonwealth of<br />

Massachusetts (1934), a case involving procedural matters in a criminal trial, the Court found<br />

that “The commonwealth of Massachusetts is free to regulate the procedure of its courts in<br />

accordance with its own conception of policy and fairness, unless in so doing it offends some<br />

principle of justice so rooted in the traditions and conscience of our people as to be ranked as<br />

fundamental.” 17 And in Washington v. Glucksberg (1997), the Court ruled that bans on assisted<br />

suicide are deeply rooted in the nation’s history. 18<br />

Due process traditionalism offers what at first may be regarded as an impartial methodology<br />

for selecting the most appropriate level of generality, a way out of interpretational ambiguity and<br />

constitutional arbitrariness. Unfortunately, specificity does not necessarily eliminate<br />

interpretative ambiguity. If in Michael v. Gerald the Court were unable to identify a specific<br />

societal tradition for the rights of fathers of children adulterously conceived, it might have tried<br />

to identify a societal tradition regarding the rights of natural parents (instead of fathers) of<br />

children adulterously conceived. Arguably, this level of generality is just as specific as Justice<br />

Scalia’s suggestion that the rights of natural fathers in general by consulted, but it is clearly<br />

distinct. 19 Justice Scalia’s proposal cannot resolve this fundamental ambiguity without appealing<br />

to rules and criteria external to the Constitution.<br />

Historical traditions have a disciplining effect on the Court; they force the justices to<br />

exercise considerable self-restraint in granting fundamental new rights not explicitly recognized<br />

by the Constitution. Does this mean that the Court should not recognize new fundamental rights<br />

absent a relevant tradition? Hardly. In Loving v. Virginia (1967), for example, the Court struck<br />

down a Virginia law that prohibited interracial marriage. It did so not by identifying a specific<br />

societal tradition, which obviously did not exist, but by invoking substantive due process. In this<br />

case at least, the absence of a specific historical tradition would have been a problematic<br />

justification for upholding a state prohibition of interracial marriage. Several other reasons exist<br />

for considering with some skepticism traditions as the sole source of constitutional legitimacy. 20<br />

Where does this discussion lead us? One obvious conclusion imposes itself. There is little<br />

hope to identify a method of constitutional interpretation that avoids injecting in the legal<br />

reasoning moral values, personal orientations, and political preferences. 21<br />

This observation<br />

should not be taken as a demonstration that constitutional law is dominated by arbitrariness and<br />

political considerations. Selecting a level of generality may not be a problem solvable by<br />

univers<strong>all</strong>y accepted rules; this does not mean that the selection process is necessarily arbitrary,<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

20<br />

21<br />

See Moore v. East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 503.<br />

See Snyder v. Commonwealth of Massachusetts, 291 U.S. 97, 105.<br />

See 521 U.S. 702, (1997).<br />

For a detailed discussed, see Tribe and Dorf, "Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights," p.1090-91.<br />

For a discussion, see Newman, "Human Cloning and the Substantive Due Process Riddle."<br />

For a classic examination of this claim, see John Hart Ely, "On Discovering Fundamental Values," Harvard Law<br />

Review 92, no. 1 (1977).<br />

189


or that there are an infinite number of possible interpretations. One simply has to recognize that<br />

in this as in many other areas of the law, professional and political judgment is inevitable.<br />

7.2.2 From Levels of Generality to Principled Interpretation<br />

The choice of the “appropriate” level of generality may also be described as the choice of a<br />

general principle of interpretation. The best-known and most general formulation of this problem<br />

has been offered by the late Ludwig Wittgenstein. In a much discussed passage of the<br />

“Philosophical Investigations,” Wittgenstein asked what is the correct continuation of the<br />

number series “1, 2, 3, 4, … ” One obvious answer is “5, 6, 7, 8, … ” but this is not the only<br />

correct answer. Arguably “4, 3, 2, 1” is also a correct continuation, and so is “1, 2, 3, 4, 1, 2, 3, 4,<br />

… .” What about “!, @, #, $, …”? At first, few would be inclined to consider this a correct<br />

continuation of the original number series. But a perceptive reader may recognize that the latter<br />

series obtains from the original one simply by hitting the “shift” key of a QWERTY keyboard, so<br />

perhaps “!, @, #, $, …” should also be considered a correct continuation of the original number<br />

series.<br />

While there may be several correct continuations of this number series, their number is not<br />

infinite and they <strong>all</strong> display internal coherence. Which continuation is considered to be the<br />

correct one depends in large measure on the societal context in which this determination is made.<br />

In a primary school class, the first answer is the one most likely to be chosen. By contrast, a<br />

group of computer geeks may find the last solution much more natural. The point here is simply<br />

that there are several correct answers to this question. Which rule is thought to generate the<br />

correct number series is a question that can be answered only in the context of prevailing norms,<br />

values, and orientations.<br />

In the next two sections, we discuss two opposite approaches to selecting a level of<br />

generality, one illustrated by the Supreme Court in Bowers v. Hardwick (1986), the other by the<br />

concept of presumptive procreative liberty as advocated by Professor John A. Robertson and<br />

other libertarians. Both provide an illustration of a principled approach to the discussion of<br />

procreative liberties. Neither one of them, in our view, provides a suitable template for<br />

adjudicating future disputes over the access to assisted reproductive technologies.<br />

7.2.3 An Idiosyncratic Approach to Constitutional Interpretation<br />

In Bowers v. Hardwick, the Court was c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to rule on the constitutionality of a<br />

Georgia statute that criminalizes sodomy. 22<br />

This case provides an excellent illustration of<br />

constitutional interpretation at an exceedingly low level of generality. The actual ruling in this<br />

case is less interesting than the methodology used by the Court to reach its conclusions. The<br />

Court asked whether “the Federal Constitution confers a fundamental right upon homosexuals to<br />

22<br />

See 478 U.S. 186 (1986). It should be mentioned that this ruling was recently reversed. In Lawrence v. Texas,<br />

the Court found that the right to privacy does indeed extend to homosexual sex.<br />

190


engage in sodomy […].” 23 By a five-to-four majority, the Court answered this question in the<br />

negative.<br />

A crucial element of the Court ruling was its interpretation of case law. After noting that<br />

Pierce v. Society of Sisters (1925) and Meyer v. Nebraska (1923) were cases dealing with “child<br />

rearing and education,” that Prince v. Massachusetts (1944) focused on “family relationship,”<br />

Skinner v. Oklahoma (1942) on “procreation,” and Loving v. Virginia on marriage, that<br />

Griswold v. Connecticut and Eisenstadt v. Baird (1972) were concerned with the use of<br />

contraceptives, and that Roe. v. Wade (1973) concerned abortion, the Court concluded that none<br />

of these opinions bore any resemblance to an asserted fundamental right to engage in acts of<br />

sodomy.<br />

The Court opinion makes clear that the justices interpreted their own record in a very<br />

narrow, almost literal way. There is no particularly compelling reason for interpreting case law<br />

liter<strong>all</strong>y other than in so doing, any continuity between earlier Court rulings and the present case<br />

vanishes. Every case appears to be unique and disconnected from other cases – including the<br />

case under consideration. At this particular level of generality, the Court was quite correct to<br />

proclaim that cases pertaining to child rearing and education, family relationships, marriage,<br />

procreation, contraceptives, and abortion bear little resemblance to homosexual sodomy. 24<br />

Absent relevant precedents, the Court turned to societal traditions as a possible source of<br />

constitutional guidance. The Court, however, concluded that homosexual sodomy is neither part<br />

of the concept of ordered liberty nor a fundamental aspect of the nation’s traditions. 25 Sodomy,<br />

in other words, cannot be considered a practice “deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and<br />

tradition.”<br />

The legal reasoning used in Bowers v. Hardwick is of some relevance to cases involving<br />

reproductive rights. At a very low level of generality, assisted reproductive technologies bear no<br />

resemblance to any other Court ruling. The only case involving positive procreative rights,<br />

Skinner v. Oklahoma, pertains to the natural ability of a man to procreate; it says nothing about<br />

the rights of a couple to access assisted reproductive technologies, or technologies of<br />

customization for that matter. 26<br />

The Court could have determined that Bowers v. Hardwick was to be decided on privacy<br />

grounds. At this (higher) level of generality, several Court rulings exist. “Marital privacy” may<br />

not be relevant in this case, but perhaps “intimate associations” are. We are not claiming that the<br />

ruling necessarily would have been different had the Court selected a higher level of generality.<br />

23<br />

24<br />

25<br />

26<br />

See 478 U.S. 186, 190.<br />

The Court acknowledged that in the past, it often has granted fundamental status to rights not explicitly<br />

contained in the Constitution by interpreting the due process clauses of the fifth and fourteenth amendments<br />

substantively rather than procedur<strong>all</strong>y, but it quickly resolved this tension by noting that deciding a case on<br />

substantive due process grounds involves much more than “the imposition of the Justices’ own choice of values<br />

on the states and the federal government. See 478 U.S. 186, 191.<br />

See 478 U.S. 186, 191-192.<br />

Nor could the Court offer any guidance on this matter, because it ruled on this case in 1942.<br />

191


What is obvious is that the Court simply decided to ignore these and other rationales offered in<br />

earlier rulings, opting instead for a literal interpretation of the case law.<br />

We believe that the approach taken by the Court in Bowers v. Hardwick does not provide a<br />

suitable template for cases involving assisted reproductive technologies. By selecting the lowest<br />

possible level of generality, the Court would make sure that no new reproductive rights could<br />

ever be recognized. We are not arguing that they should. As pointed out earlier, it seems to us<br />

that societal and political debates should precede Supreme Court rulings on matters as delicate as<br />

procreative rights. But to treat each new case pertaining to reproductive technologies as a unique<br />

situation unrelated to past Court reasoning seems to us an abdication of the Court’s<br />

responsibilities.<br />

7.2.4 Robertson’s Concept of “Presumptive Procreative Liberty”<br />

The constitutional protection that Robertson and other libertarian scholars would like to<br />

afford to ARTs is predicated on interpreting case law at a very high level of generality –<br />

precisely the opposite of the approach taken by the Court in Bowers v. Hardwick. 27 Robertson’s<br />

concept of presumptive procreative liberty is based on a key assumption: Even though the<br />

Constitution does not explicitly recognize a procreative right, the Supreme Court is likely to<br />

recognize “coital reproduction” as a fundamental right deserving constitutional protection, at<br />

least for married couples. Robertson then infers from this narrow definition of procreative liberty<br />

that access to most, if not <strong>all</strong>, kinds of assisted reproductive technologies should be considered a<br />

liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.<br />

There are two rationales for Robertson’s assumption, an early and a more recent one. In the<br />

1980s, Robertson took the absence of any Court opinion on matters concerning procreative<br />

liberty as a strong indication that this right was taken for granted. 28 More recently, Robertson has<br />

justified the presumption of a right to coital reproduction by pointing to several Court rulings.<br />

These include Meyer v. Nebraska (which affirmed the right to “marry, establish a home, and<br />

bring up children”); Skinner v. Oklahoma (which asserted procreation as among “the basic civil<br />

rights of man”); Stanley v. Illinois (1972) (that “the rights to conceive and raise one’s children<br />

have been deemed ‘essential,’ ‘basic civil rights of man’ and […] far more precious than<br />

property rights”); and the much quoted Eisenstadt v. Baird (“If the right of privacy means<br />

anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free of unwarranted<br />

governmental intrusion into matters so fundament<strong>all</strong>y affecting a person as the decision whether<br />

27<br />

28<br />

John A. Robertson, Children of Choice: Freedom and the New Reproductive Technologies (Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1994); John A. Robertson, "Embryos, Families, and Procreative Liberty: The Legal Structure<br />

of the New Reproduction," California Law Review 59 (1986); John A. Robertson, "Procreative Liberty in the Era<br />

of Genomics," American Journal of Law and Medicine 29 (2003).<br />

Robertson, "Embryos, Families, and Procreative Liberty: The Legal Structure of the New Reproduction."<br />

192


to bear or beget a child.”). 29 Legal scholars gener<strong>all</strong>y seem to agree that the Court is likely grant<br />

fundamental status to coital reproduction, at least for married persons. 30<br />

Robertson, then, distinguishes between procreative means and ends. Various ARTs, both old<br />

and new, are simply the technological means to achieve the <strong>all</strong>-important procreative end.<br />

Accordingly, presumptive procreative liberty includes both coital and “non-coital” procreative<br />

techniques, such as sperm, egg, and embryo donation and even surrogacy. ARTs ranging from<br />

traditional IVF to ICSI should also be protected, as should more recent techniques such as preimplantation<br />

genetic diagnosis and reproductive cloning, if the technique in question is the only<br />

way to achieve reproduction. Robertson goes so far as to argue that there might even be a<br />

constitution<strong>all</strong>y protected right to genetic<strong>all</strong>y engineer babies. 31<br />

How can such sweeping generalizations be justified? Robertson grounds his concept of<br />

presumptive procreative liberty on evolutionary biology. In his view, parental desires are not<br />

preferences shaped in large measure by social expectations, but biological instincts produced by<br />

evolutionary pressure. Evolutionary biology then explains not only why parents have procreative<br />

desires, but also why parents may wish to have a baby of a certain sex or with certain traits. For<br />

example, beauty is explained in terms of a desire for healthy children. Stamina and strength are<br />

key requisites for effectively protecting the familial unit. 32<br />

Assisted reproductive technologies do not simply help prospective parents fulfill their<br />

procreative dreams; they help them implement evolutionarily successful procreative strategies.<br />

Since evolutionary biology seems to provide an a posteriori rationalization of each and every<br />

procreative whim, it is not difficult for Robertson to conclude that access to both old and new<br />

reproductive technologies should be granted not only to married couples, but also to unmarried<br />

couples, single individuals, and homosexual couples – in short, to anyone.<br />

Does evolutionary biology provide an adequate account of why some parents may prefer a<br />

first-born male over a female, or why other parents would want to have a child t<strong>all</strong>er than<br />

average? More gener<strong>all</strong>y, can parental desires for children with any of what contemporary<br />

America considers desirable traits be adequately explained by evolutionary biology? The short<br />

answer to this question is no. Evolutionary biology may account for a deeply felt urge to<br />

procreate, but just as it does not explain why people may prefer one brand of toothpaste over<br />

another, it does not provide an adequate account of prospective parents’ preferences for certain<br />

physical and cognitive traits. Parental desires for a successful progeny can perhaps be described<br />

as the outcome of natural selection, but natural selection alone does not inform contemporary<br />

notions of “success” or the “good life.” Evolutionary biology is an inadequate basis for<br />

29<br />

30<br />

31<br />

32<br />

Robertson, "Procreative Liberty in the Era of Genomics," p.452-54.<br />

Carl H. Coleman, "Religious Values and Legal Dilemmas in Bioethics: Assisted Reproductive Technologies and<br />

the Constitution," Fordham Urban Law Journal 30 (2002), p.61; Ann MacLean Massie, "Regulating Choice: A<br />

Constitutional Law Response to Professor John A. Robertson's "Children of Choice"," Washington and Lee Law<br />

Review 52 (1995), p.150-51.<br />

Robertson, "Procreative Liberty in the Era of Genomics," p.453-54.<br />

Ibid., p.8-10.<br />

193


generalizing from a strong but generic urge to reproduce to specific uses of assisted reproductive<br />

technologies.<br />

7.3 A Different Perspective<br />

The Court has ruled repeatedly on matters pertaining both to reproduction and to privacy.<br />

These cases have been quoted so often by the Court itself and by commentators as to warrant a<br />

brief review. They are discussed in more detail in Appendix I. The only case specific<strong>all</strong>y dealing<br />

with a positive right to procreation is Skinner v. Oklahoma, 33 a case involving a compulsory<br />

sterilization law, not procreative liberty per se. It focused on whether it is constitutional for the<br />

state to deprive a man of his capacity to procreate. The Court found that the Oklahoma statute<br />

was unconstitutional, but it did so by virtue of equal protection, not on substantive due process<br />

grounds. In dictum, however, the Court noted, “We are dealing here with legislation which<br />

involves one of the basic civil rights of man. Marriage and procreation are fundamental to the<br />

very existence and survival of the race.” 34<br />

In Meyer v. Nebraska, the Court found that families have the right to determine what<br />

constitutes the best education for their children. Pierce v. Society of Sisters involved the parental<br />

rights to send children to a school of their choice, including a private school, a right the Court<br />

affirmed. That the education of children is considered an aspect of family life worthy of<br />

constitutional protection was reaffirmed in Prince v. Massachusetts and again in Stanley v.<br />

Illinois. 35 Also pertinent to this discussion is the right to marry, as sanctioned, for example, in<br />

Loving v. Virginia. 36<br />

Cases specific<strong>all</strong>y focused on negative reproductive rights (i.e., on the right not to<br />

reproduce) also might be relevant to the present discussion. Griswold v. Connecticut famously<br />

established the right of married couples to use contraceptives by identifying the realm of “marital<br />

privacy” as an area the state cannot enter. 37 Eisenstadt v. Baird extended this right to unmarried<br />

couples, 38 and Carey v. Population Services International (1977) afforded the same right to<br />

young adults 16 years of age and older, 39 whereas Roe v. Wade sanctioned a woman’s right to<br />

terminate a pregnancy, 40 a right reaffirmed in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania<br />

v. Casey (1992). 41<br />

33<br />

34<br />

35<br />

36<br />

37<br />

38<br />

39<br />

40<br />

41<br />

See 316 U.S. 535 (1942).<br />

See 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942).<br />

See 321 U.S. 158, 166 (1944); 405 U.S. 645 (1972).<br />

See 388 U.S. 1, 8 (1967).<br />

See 381 U.S. 479 (1965).<br />

See 405 U.S. 438 (1972).<br />

See 431 U.S. 678 (1977).<br />

See 410 U.S. 113 (1973).<br />

See 505 U.S. 833 (1992).<br />

194


The emphasis placed by the Court on matters concerning the family, the education of<br />

children, and contraception and abortion suggests that a state intervention intruding upon natural<br />

procreation may have to meet or exceed a strict scrutiny standard. Natural procreation involves<br />

several values central to Court jurisprudence, including privacy, bodily integrity, marital<br />

intimacy, and integrity of the family unit. These values would be threatened at least in part by a<br />

state intervention in this area. For this reason, some commentators believe that natural<br />

procreation is likely to f<strong>all</strong> within the realm of the constitution<strong>all</strong>y protected private sphere. 42<br />

Recognizing that the desire to procreate is central to family life does not necessarily afford<br />

constitutional protection to each and every type of assisted reproductive technology. While a<br />

state intervention in natural procreation likely would trigger strict scrutiny, regulations restricting<br />

the availability of ART services are unlikely to raise the same constitutional concerns. The Court<br />

may well recognize the centrality of reproduction to family life and personal identity, but avoid<br />

extending constitutional protection to each and every assisted reproductive technology,<br />

especi<strong>all</strong>y when the state has a “compelling interest” in regulating an ART. One such compelling<br />

interest is the health and well-being of ART children.<br />

Whether an outright ban of an ART procedure would be declared unconstitutional depends,<br />

of course, on the state interests involved, and is a question that cannot be answered in general<br />

terms. What is clear is that the Court is very unlikely to generalize broadly from a presumptive<br />

right to natural procreation. The jurisprudence of religious freedom provides a useful illustration.<br />

Religious freedom, just like freedom of speech, is explicitly recognized as a constitution<strong>all</strong>y<br />

protected liberty. Yet the Court has ruled time and again that certain practices motivated by<br />

religious beliefs do not enjoy constitutional protection. Obviously, freedom of religion requires<br />

that both freedom of belief and freedom to practice a religion be protected, but the protection<br />

afforded to religious practices is far less comprehensive than the absolute protection enjoyed by<br />

religious beliefs. The Court has recognized that state interests may override practices dictated by<br />

religious beliefs, as for example when it upheld universal immunization requirements and<br />

antipolygamy laws against religiously motivated objections. And it might do so without holding<br />

these laws to a strict scrutiny standard of review. These precedents demonstrate that the health<br />

and well-being of children can override parental desires, even if these enjoy constitutional<br />

protection.<br />

Our discussion so far has simply underscored the fact that the Court is extremely unlikely to<br />

recognize broadly defined procreative rights. We have not shown how the Court might reason in<br />

these cases. Societal traditions, at a very low level of generality, might provide some guidance.<br />

Michael v. Gerald is an example, as is Washington v. Glucksberg, a case in which the Court<br />

found that our traditions are wholly incompatible with a right to assisted suicide. Resorting to<br />

societal traditions will obviously invalidate any claims to new procreative rights. There simply<br />

42<br />

Coleman, "Religious Values and Legal Dilemmas in Bioethics: Assisted Reproductive Technologies and the<br />

Constitution."; Massie, "Regulating Choice: A Constitutional Law Response to Professor John A. Robertson's<br />

"Children of Choice"."; Radhika Rao, "Reconceiving Privacy: Relationships and Reproductive Technology,"<br />

UCLA Law Review 45 (1998).<br />

195


are not any societal traditions that may guide the Court on matters as novel as access to specific<br />

assisted reproductive technologies. More importantly, it is not entirely clear why the Court<br />

should focus on societal traditions rather than on its own record. Case law pertaining to<br />

reproductive rights and privacy rights may be just as relevant to cases involving assisted<br />

reproductive technologies as societal traditions.<br />

There is one major difficulty in defining “reproductive rights” as the most appropriate level<br />

of generality. “Reproductive rights” cases gener<strong>all</strong>y focus on the right not to reproduce – i.e.,<br />

they are cases involving the use of contraceptives or the access to abortion services. Whether<br />

negative reproductive rights can be generalized to include positive procreative rights is not<br />

entirely clear. People have a right to decide whether to interrupt a pregnancy and to use<br />

contraceptives, but that does not necessarily imply that they also have a right to choose any<br />

technological means to procreate. To put it in starker terms, the use of contraceptives and the<br />

access to abortive procedures uncouple procreative choices and recreational sex; Negative<br />

reproductive rights cases sanction a right to recreational sex. By contrast, restricting the access to<br />

assisted reproductive technologies pertains to the implementation of a positive procreative<br />

decision, so to speak.<br />

Restrictions in this area may not prevent a couple or an individual from having a baby; they<br />

may simply make the access to a suitable ART procedure more difficult and/or more costly to<br />

come by. Regulatory interventions that merely increase the burden of access to an assisted<br />

reproductive technology are less likely to raise constitutional concerns: Restrictions to the<br />

availability of ART services may be acceptable if they do not represent an undue burden for the<br />

couple. 43 In some cases, however, a banned ART treatment may well be the only realistic option<br />

to have a child. But even when a ban would prevent some couples and individuals from pursuing<br />

their reproductive projects, it is not obvious that the ban by itself would create a serious<br />

constitutional concern, especi<strong>all</strong>y if the state can offer compelling reasons for the ban. 44<br />

An alternative to procreative rights could be “freedom of intimate association.” It has been<br />

suggested that privacy-related Court cases could consistently be interpreted as extending<br />

constitutional protection to activities and choices made in the context of intimate associations. 45<br />

For example, the right to marry protects the desire of two individuals to form a family against<br />

state intrusion rather than the right of each individual to marry. Neither one of the individuals<br />

involved would be able to exercise this right without their partner’s consent. The right to raise<br />

children is a familial right – a relational right, so to speak, not an individual right. The right to<br />

use contraceptives presupposes two consenting individuals. As soon as conflicts arise between<br />

the partners to an intimate association, the state has a legitimate role to play.<br />

43<br />

44<br />

45<br />

Coleman, "Religious Values and Legal Dilemmas in Bioethics: Assisted Reproductive Technologies and the<br />

Constitution."<br />

Sunstein, "Is There a Constitutional Right to Clone?," p.993-94.<br />

Rao, "Reconceiving Privacy: Relationships and Reproductive Technology."<br />

196


Selecting “freedom of intimate association” as the most appropriate level of generality does<br />

seem to provide a fairly consistent reading of privacy-related rulings. If used to interpret ARTrelated<br />

cases, it would draw some sharp cutoff points. Reproductive technologies that involve<br />

one or more commercial transactions, as in the case of sperm, egg, and embryo donation as well<br />

as surrogacy, are unlikely to be granted constitutional protection. In these cases, procreation may<br />

involve up to three individuals external to a familial relationship – a sperm donor, an egg donor,<br />

and a gestational mother. A fertility clinic is also involved, and perhaps a sperm bank as well. In<br />

<strong>all</strong> these cases, the procreative act is not performed in the context of an intimate relationship. The<br />

fact that procreation involves several individuals external to an intimate relationship greatly<br />

undermines the intimate nature of the procreative project. A Court relying on this interpretative<br />

principle is unlikely to extend constitutional protection to these forms of assisted reproduction.<br />

Whether the concept of “intimate association” would extend to traditional ARTs, is not<br />

entirely clear. As long as a couple requires ART services merely to mix their own gametes, one<br />

could argue that procreation takes place in the context of an intimate association. In this case, the<br />

ART specialist plays merely a facilitating role in an otherwise intimate project. Obviously, the<br />

act itself is not intimate, but the Court in Paris Adult Theater I v. Slaton (1973) found that “the<br />

constitution<strong>all</strong>y protected privacy of family, marriage, motherhood, procreation, and child rearing<br />

is not just concerned with a particular place, but with a protected intimate relationship. Such<br />

protected privacy extends to the doctor’s office, the hospital, the hotel room, or as otherwise<br />

required to safeguard the right to intimacy involved.” 46 Whether the Court would be inclined to<br />

define a procreative act facilitated by an ART specialist and performed at a reproductive clinic as<br />

private is not entirely clear.<br />

Less problematic is the application of this interpretative principle to cases of customized<br />

conception. One may legitimately wonder whether technologies of customization re<strong>all</strong>y preserve<br />

the intimate nature of a reproductive project. Customization of conception changes the<br />

relationship between prospective parents and medical personnel. ART practitioners in this case<br />

no longer play a facilitating role: They are not simply in the business of removing physiological<br />

obstacles to natural procreation. One might say that they are tasked with “designing” a baby<br />

according to parental specifications. Admittedly, this statement amounts to an exaggeration, but<br />

only a slight one –moreover, one that is becoming more accurate by the day. Technologies of<br />

reproductive customization redefine the very meaning of procreation by “outsourcing,” in part or<br />

entirely, the process to ART specialists. Some may speak of a “joint venture,” but “intimate<br />

association” is certainly not the attribute that comes to mind in considering this process. Where<br />

exactly a reproductive choice stops being an intimate project and becomes a technological<br />

enterprise is not altogether clear. What seems fairly obvious is that the Court would not treat<br />

traditional ARTs and technologies of customization as equal.<br />

One may wonder whether the concept of intimate association should be further<br />

circumscribed to include activities taking place within the confines of the home, consistent with<br />

46<br />

See 413 U.S. 49 (1973) at 66 n.13.<br />

197


the First Amendment’s protection of peaceful assembly and the Fourth Amendment’s protection<br />

of the home. 47 At this relatively low level of generalization, natural reproduction is likely to be<br />

considered a fundamental right, access to traditional ARTs would be somewhat less likely to<br />

receive constitutional protection, and technologies of customization would be very unlikely to<br />

warrant protection by the Court. Roe v. Wade would present a difficulty, of course, and so would<br />

other rulings in which the Court reaffirmed certain rights to privacy as extending beyond the<br />

private home. On the other end, by this reading, Bowers v. Hardwick would deserve to be reexamined.<br />

Indeed, the Court, in Lawrence v. Texas (2003), reversed this earlier ruling.<br />

The New York State Task Force on Life and the Law has identified several additional values<br />

that are likely to affect a Court ruling on matters pertaining to assisted reproduction. Among<br />

them are bodily integrity, marital intimacy, the importance of being a parent a raising a child,<br />

genetic relatedness, religious aspects of the decision to procreate, and a woman’s interest in<br />

gestation and giving birth. The task force concluded that procreative choices involving most or<br />

<strong>all</strong> of the values listed above are more likely to be afforded constitutional protection than cases in<br />

which only one of these values is involved. 48<br />

Much depends, of course, on the justifications invoked by the government for banning or<br />

restricting access to ART treatments. One can anticipate at least some of these arguments by<br />

reviewing the legal reasoning offered for banning reproductive cloning. The arguments most<br />

likely to survive a rational review or strict review test are those centered on potential harm to<br />

ART children. Professor Robertson has argued that possible harm to ART children should not<br />

trump procreative liberties because children born through ARTs do not re<strong>all</strong>y have any other<br />

choice but to live with the limitations imposed by their parents and ARTs, the only alternative<br />

being not having been born in the first place. 49 We very much doubt that the Court would find<br />

this argument compelling. Pushed to its ultimate consequences, this reasoning would relieve the<br />

ART industry of any duty of care. Preventing human suffering, then, is an obvious argument not<br />

only against ART procedures such as human reproductive cloning, but also against other<br />

innovative reproductive treatments that have not been demonstrated to be safe and effective. In<br />

the latter cases, the evidence showing physical harm, while maybe more limited, would certainly<br />

be sufficient to meet at least a rational review standard.<br />

Technologies of reproductive customization could also undermine the individuality of the<br />

child-to-be. It has been argued that because individuals are shaped as much by their genes as by<br />

their environment, this argument is not likely to withstand a rational review, let alone strict<br />

scrutiny. This argument is not convincing. That individual experience and the social environment<br />

47<br />

48<br />

49<br />

Tribe and Dorf, "Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights," p.1108.<br />

New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, "Assisted Reproductive Technologies. Analysis and<br />

Recommendations for Public Policy," (New York, NY: 1998), p.144-46. See also Coleman, "Religious Values<br />

and Legal Dilemmas in Bioethics: Assisted Reproductive Technologies and the Constitution."<br />

Robertson, Children of Choice: Freedom and the New Reproductive Technologies, p.75. See also John A.<br />

Robertson, "Liberalism and the Limits of Procreative Liberty: A Response to My Critics," Washington and Lee<br />

Law Review 52 (1995), p.250-52.<br />

198


contribute to shaping individuality does not invalidate the argument that being born as a means<br />

to an end rather than as an end in itself could jeopardize the development of a sense of individual<br />

identity. Whether the Court would consider this argument compelling depends, of course, on the<br />

specific ART involved.<br />

Also relevant to the present discussion is the argument that a customized baby would suffer<br />

psychological harm. In the case of reproductive cloning, it may be detrimental for a child to be<br />

confronted daily with an older replica of him or herself – to be able to learn at an early stage how<br />

one is likely to develop, primarily physic<strong>all</strong>y, but to some extent psychologic<strong>all</strong>y as well. A child<br />

in this situation could easily come to the conclusion that his or her life is pre-ordained, a state of<br />

mind that certainly does not promote healthy mental development. This argument is particularly<br />

relevant in cases pertaining to reproductive customization. For example, some parents may wish<br />

to endow their children with the genetic assets of a top athlete like Michael Jordan, a Hollywood<br />

star like Julia Roberts, or a celebrated musician such as Yo-Yo Ma. 50 In <strong>all</strong> these cases, the<br />

children may be treated as means to some parental ends, and not as ends in themselves. Whether<br />

the Court would apply a rational review test or the much more demanding standard of strict<br />

scrutiny is anyone’s guess. What can be said is that the state interests invoked in the cases<br />

discussed above would most likely withstand rational review, and perhaps strict scrutiny as well.<br />

In the last section of this chapter, we turn to survey data on the relative importance of<br />

biological procreation and genetic relatedness versus adoption. This data is of considerable<br />

interest to the present discussion for two reasons. It puts in perspective many assumptions about<br />

the centrality of biological procreation and genetic relatedness. And the reduced importance of<br />

genetic relatedness to the procreative experience may induce the Court to hold state interventions<br />

to a rational test rather than to strict scrutiny.<br />

7.4 Procreative Drive or Familial Desires?<br />

The concept of presumptive reproductive freedom is predicated on the assumption that<br />

biological reproduction is a fundamental element of any person’s biography and sense of<br />

identity. This observation is probably accurate in general form, but it sheds little light on the<br />

relative importance of various forms of biological procreation compared to other forms of<br />

reproduction – non-biological reproduction such as adoption in particular. Adoption is a<br />

particularly interesting case because it is both a well-established practice in <strong>all</strong> Western countries<br />

and is heavily regulated. A recently conducted survey provides several important insights into<br />

this question.<br />

The hypothesis to be explored in this section is simply stated: If biological reproduction is as<br />

central to an individual’s sense of identity as commonly assumed, then adoption should be the<br />

50<br />

Admittedly, these are not technologies available today. But as pointed out in chapter 4, genetic engineering –<br />

defined as the ability to purposefully modify the human genome – has made considerable progress over the last<br />

few years. For a discussion, see Baruch et al., "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues and Options for<br />

Policymakers."<br />

199


least preferable among <strong>all</strong> forms of reproduction (biological as well as non-biological). More<br />

specific<strong>all</strong>y, ART treatments that afford at least partial biological relatedness should be<br />

preferable to adoption. To explore this hypothesis, we used survey data gathered by RESOLVE,<br />

a leading national advocate for infertility patients. 51 The survey was conducted in late 2002 and<br />

included three samples: 976 RESOLVE members ages 18 to 45, 231 members of the Harris<br />

Interactive Chronic Illness Panel, and a representative sample of the U.S. population consisting<br />

of 1,034 adults, also ages 18 to 45. The U.S. sample is representative for sex, age, race and<br />

ethnicity, education, region, and income. The survey was designed mainly to elicit both the<br />

interest and level of information about embryo adoption and embryo donation. It also contained<br />

several questions directly pertinent to the present discussion.<br />

A first, startling result emerging from this survey is that biological relatedness is far less<br />

important than one might assume. Respondents were asked to determine which reproductive<br />

option they would be extremely or very likely to consider if they were unable to have children.<br />

As Table 4 demonstrates, adoption is the preferred choice for infertile couples and individuals by<br />

very large margins. Adoption – i.e., non-biological reproduction – is preferable even to partial<br />

biological relatedness as provided by egg and sperm donation.<br />

% Likely to Consider<br />

U.S. Harris Chronic RESOLVE<br />

Population Illness Panel Members<br />

Adopting a child 66 71 74<br />

Using donated embryos 27 35 34<br />

Using donor egg 23 32 42<br />

Using donor sperm 19 30 39<br />

Surrogacy 13 16 20<br />

Table 4: Relative importance of biological versus non-biological parenthood.<br />

Interestingly, in <strong>all</strong> three samples, embryo donation is preferred to surrogacy by a factor of<br />

two. Considering that surrogacy could actu<strong>all</strong>y ensure complete biological relatedness, the strong<br />

preference for donated embryos suggests that the experience of giving birth is at least as<br />

important if not more so than biological relatedness. Unfortunately, no data is available on the<br />

relative importance of ART treatments that would ensure complete biological relatedness.<br />

Nevertheless, these remain rather surprising results. They suggest that the urge to reproduce<br />

biologic<strong>all</strong>y is perhaps not as consuming as industry representatives and advocates for the<br />

infertile seem to believe.<br />

One could argue that these are largely hypothetical answers produced by speculative<br />

questions, and that actual behavior would tell a different story. To test this hypothesis, we looked<br />

at actual birth rates versus adoption rates of very young children. According to the Census<br />

Bureau, in 2000 (the most recent year for which data is available), 1.3 percent of <strong>all</strong> children one<br />

51<br />

RESOLVE: The National Infertility Association, "Embryo Donation Research: Select Findings," (Bethesda,<br />

MD: 2003).<br />

200


year of age or younger living in a U.S. household, or 41,795 children, had been adopted. 52 In the<br />

same year, according the CDC National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>, 35,025 babies, or<br />

1.1 percent of <strong>all</strong> children one year of age and younger, were born through ARTs. 53 This means<br />

that in 2000, the number of very young children adopted exceeded the number of babies born<br />

through ARTs by 19.3 percent. If it had been possible to compare the number of adopted sm<strong>all</strong><br />

children to children born through one of the three ART treatments listed in Table 4, this<br />

difference would have been even larger.<br />

There may be several reasons for this difference. It is safe to assume that ART treatments<br />

that ensure full biological relatedness would be preferable to adoption, but it turns out that<br />

adoption is not a measure of last resort. Asked about the reproductive options they had actu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

considered, respondents with a history of infertility and those with a partner suffering from<br />

infertility offered answers consistent with the above findings. As Table 5, Table 6, and Table 7<br />

demonstrate, survey respondents in each panel considered adoption far more often than <strong>all</strong> other<br />

available ART treatments.<br />

Reproductive Method<br />

% that considered<br />

each step<br />

Adoption 41<br />

Embryo donation 2<br />

Surrogacy 2<br />

Donor egg 3<br />

Donor sperm 2<br />

Table 5: U.S. population.<br />

The data provides strong evidence that once a couple is incapable of reproducing natur<strong>all</strong>y,<br />

ART treatments that merely offer biological relatedness are of almost no importance compared<br />

to adoption. This is an important finding worth emphasizing. Biological reproduction seems to<br />

derive its profound meaning from the union of the parents’ egg and sperm. If, for whatever<br />

reason, either the prospective father or the prospective mother cannot contribute his or her<br />

gamete, biological relatedness loses much of its appeal. In this sense, the term “biologic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

related children” is misleading. It merges forms of reproduction that are not at <strong>all</strong><br />

commensurable.<br />

Reproductive Method<br />

% that considered<br />

each step<br />

Adoption 60<br />

Embryo donation 13<br />

52<br />

53<br />

U.S. Census Bureau, "Adopted Children and Stepchildren: 2000," (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of<br />

Commerce, 2003), p.7. The Census Bureau does not provide data about adoption rates of younger children.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "2000 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National<br />

Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," (Atlanta, GA: National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and<br />

Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health, 2002), p.11.<br />

201


Surrogacy 16<br />

Donor egg 14<br />

Donor sperm 14<br />

Table 6: Harris Interactive Chronic Illness Panel.<br />

The data also suggests that the quest for reproduction is only parti<strong>all</strong>y grounded in biology.<br />

Access to reproductive technologies that deliver only biological relatedness may well be of<br />

secondary importance compared to ART treatments that provide a reasonable chance to produce<br />

full biological descendents. Pregnancy and biological relatedness are only two and perhaps not<br />

the most important aspects of parenthood. In short, adoption is far more important than any ART<br />

treatment involving extraneous gametes or donated embryos.<br />

Reproductive Method<br />

% that considered<br />

each step<br />

Adoption 70<br />

Embryo donation 21<br />

Surrogacy 17<br />

Donor egg 30<br />

Donor sperm 13<br />

Table 7: RESOLVE members.<br />

One could argue that different levels of knowledge and information may explain the<br />

popularity of adoption over certain kinds of ART treatment. Adoption is almost as old as<br />

humanity itself, whereas embryo donation is a new option for which little information is<br />

available. The empirical evidence suggests that knowledge and information do not significantly<br />

affect reproductive preferences. The RESOLVE survey includes questions designed to determine<br />

whether members of the three samples had received adequate information about various<br />

reproductive options (Table 8). It is safe to assume that RESOLVE members are the most<br />

knowledgeable of the three samples included in the survey. Among the members of this panel, an<br />

almost identical percentage had not received sufficient information about adoption, donor egg,<br />

and donor sperm (24 percent, 26 percent, 25 percent, respectively). In other words, for each of<br />

the reproductive technologies under consideration, RESOLVE members were provided with an<br />

inadequate but very similar amount of information. This means that their preference for adoption<br />

cannot be explained in terms of information differentials. As for members of the Harris Chronic<br />

Illness Panel and the general population sample, they gener<strong>all</strong>y were better informed about<br />

adoption than about egg and sperm donation.<br />

Table 8 suggests that information does have an impact on preferences, but not a differential<br />

one. Members of the RESOLVE panel, clearly the most knowledgeable of the three samples, are<br />

much more likely than members of U.S. population sample to consider egg or sperm donation as<br />

viable reproductive options. However, they are also more likely to consider adoption – 70<br />

percent versus 41 percent of the general population. Thus, differences in knowledge and<br />

202


information do not provide an adequate explanation for the far greater popularity of adoption<br />

over egg and sperm donation.<br />

% who indicated they did not have enough information<br />

about option to make an informed decision<br />

U.S.<br />

Population<br />

Harris Chronic<br />

Illness Panel<br />

RESOLVE<br />

Members<br />

Pursued an Adoption 37 28 24<br />

Donor Egg 53 40 26<br />

Donor Sperm 55 30 25<br />

Table 8: Levels of information.<br />

If information does not explain the strong preference for adoption, perhaps cost differentials<br />

do. The costs associated with adoption can vary considerably depending on the agency and the<br />

origin of the child. According to the National Adoption Information Clearinghouse, an office<br />

within the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, a domestic public agency could<br />

charge anywhere between zero and $2,500 for foster care adoption, whereas reliance on a<br />

domestic private adoption agency could cost between $5,000 and $40,000 or more. 54<br />

By<br />

comparison, the American Society for Reproductive Medicine recommends compensating an egg<br />

donor with up to $4,000 for one egg and a sperm donor with $100. These are recommended<br />

prices; the market price for a donated egg is often much higher. The costs of ART services are<br />

charged separately and are significant; they range from $8,000 to $25,000 per cycle, depending<br />

on the reproductive services provided, the reputation of the ART program, and its location.<br />

Based on the available data, it appears that cost differences are not large enough to explain a<br />

strong preference for adoption.<br />

An additional consideration is red tape. Adopting a child in the United States is a lengthy<br />

and bureaucratic process that can last several years. By comparison, an ART treatment is a fairly<br />

straightforward, transparent, and predictable procedure. Thus, neither the relative costs of ART<br />

treatments versus adoption procedures nor differences in transaction costs explains the<br />

preference for adoption displayed by the members of the three panels.<br />

One could also argue that the strong preference for adoption documented in Table 4 through<br />

Table 7 may be explained by relative differences in the availability of these services throughout<br />

the country. A back-of-the-envelop analysis shows that availability differentials cannot account<br />

for the popularity of adoption. According to the most recent data on success rates published by<br />

the CDC, there are more than 400 fertility programs in the United States. Over the last 25 years,<br />

the number of ART programs has been increasing steadily. On the other end, an online search of<br />

the Gale Encyclopedia of Associations reveals that in 2005, there were less than 200<br />

organizations devoted to adoption issues, many of which provide lobbying rather then actual<br />

adoption services. Thus, differential availability of reproductive services would favor egg and<br />

sperm donation over adoption.<br />

54<br />

For additional information, visit http://naic.acf.hhs.gov/pubs/s_cost/s_costb.cfm (accessed April 26, 2004).<br />

203


To recap, the survey data shows a strong preference for adoption over ART treatments<br />

providing only partial genetic relatedness. It appears that in making procreative choices,<br />

biological relatedness is not as important as commonly assumed. On the other end, given the<br />

importance attached to adoption and its roots in the “history and traditions of this country,” one<br />

could argue that adoption should be considered a fundamental right deserving of constitutional<br />

protection. If this were the case, the Supreme Court would likely require any state regulation<br />

limiting access to adoption services to pass a strict scrutiny test, a test not many regulations are<br />

likely to survive. Instead, every state has laws regulating key aspects of the adoption process,<br />

including data collection, payments, and parentage. 55<br />

The data also suggests a broader point: Procreative decisions are based on several<br />

considerations, only one of which is genetic relatedness. Other values – such as the importance<br />

of being parents and raising children, the experience associated with pregnancy and childbirth,<br />

and procreation in the context of a familial unit – are central aspects of a procreative choice, and<br />

can be as important or more important than genetic relatedness. Perhaps not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, many<br />

of the Court precedents discussed in this chapter pertain precisely to these aspects. They also<br />

overlap with the considerations identified by the New York State Task Force on Life and the<br />

Law as crucial to any Court ruling pertaining to reproductive medicine. Taken together, these<br />

observations suggest that the Court is very unlikely not only to extend constitutional protection<br />

to technologies of procreative customization, but also to deny fundamental status to several,<br />

more traditional ART treatments.<br />

55<br />

Lori B. Andrews and Nanette Elster, "Adoption, Reproductive Technologies, and Genetic Information," Health<br />

Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 8 (1998).<br />

204


7.5 Bibliography<br />

Ackerman, Bruce. "Levels of Generality in Constitutional Interpretation: Liberating<br />

Abstraction." University of Chicago Law Review 59 (1992): 317-48.<br />

Andrews, Lori B., and Nanette Elster. "Adoption, Reproductive Technologies, and Genetic<br />

Information." Health Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 8 (1998): 125-51.<br />

Barnes, Barry. "On the Conventional Character of Knowledge and Cognition." In Science<br />

Observed. Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, edited by Karin Knorr-Cetina and<br />

Michael Mulkay, 19-51. London: Sage Publications, 1983.<br />

Barnes, Barry, David Bloor, and John Henry. Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis.<br />

Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

Baruch, Susannah, Audrey Huang, Daryl Pritchard, Andrea Kalfoglou, Gail Javitt, Rick<br />

Borchelt, Joan Scott, and Kathy Hudson. "Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues<br />

and Options for Policymakers." Washington, D.C.: Genetics and Public Policy Center,<br />

2005.<br />

Bloor, David. Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. London: Routledge, 1997.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. "2000 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success<br />

Rates: National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for<br />

Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health,<br />

2002.<br />

———. "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National Summary and<br />

Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention<br />

and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health, 2004.<br />

Coleman, Carl H. "Religious Values and Legal Dilemmas in Bioethics: Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technologies and the Constitution." Fordham Urban Law Journal 30 (2002): 57-70.<br />

Easterbrook, Frank H. "Presidential Review." Case Western Reserve Law Review 40 (1990):<br />

905-29.<br />

Ely, James W. "The Oxymoron Reconsidered: Myth and Reality in the Origins of Substantive<br />

Due Process." Constitutional Commentary 16 (1999): 315-45.<br />

Harrison, John. "Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text." Virginia Law Review 83<br />

(1997): 493-558.<br />

Hart Ely, John. "On Discovering Fundamental Values." Harvard Law Review 92, no. 1 (1977):<br />

1-55.<br />

Massie, Ann MacLean. "Regulating Choice: A Constitutional Law Response to Professor John<br />

A. Robertson's "Children of Choice"." Washington and Lee Law Review 52 (1995): 135-<br />

71.<br />

New York State Task Force on Life and the Law. "Assisted Reproductive Technologies.<br />

Analysis and Recommendations for Public Policy." New York, NY, 1998.<br />

Newman, Stephen A. "Human Cloning and the Substantive Due Process Riddle." Southern<br />

California Interdisciplinary Law Journal 8 (1998): 153-66.<br />

Rao, Radhika. "Reconceiving Privacy: Relationships and Reproductive Technology." UCLA Law<br />

Review 45 (1998): 1077-123.<br />

RESOLVE: The National Infertility Association. "Embryo Donation Research: Select Findings."<br />

Bethesda, MD, 2003.<br />

205


Robertson, John A. Children of Choice: Freedom and the New Reproductive Technologies.<br />

Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994.<br />

———. "Embryos, Families, and Procreative Liberty: The Legal Structure of the New<br />

Reproduction." California Law Review 59 (1986): 942-1039.<br />

———. "Liberalism and the Limits of Procreative Liberty: A Response to My Critics."<br />

Washington and Lee Law Review 52 (1995): 233-67.<br />

———. "Procreative Liberty in the Era of Genomics." American Journal of Law and Medicine<br />

29 (2003): 439-87.<br />

Spriggs, M. "Lesbian Couple Create a Child Who Is Deaf Like Them." Journal of Medical<br />

Ethics 28 (2002): 283.<br />

Sunstein, Cass. "Is There a Constitutional Right to Clone?" Hastings Law Journal 53 (2002):<br />

987-1005.<br />

Tribe, Laurence H., and Michael C. Dorf. "Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights."<br />

University of Chicago Law Review 57 (1990): 1057-108.<br />

U.S. Census Bureau. "Adopted Children and Stepchildren: 2000." Washington, D.C.: U.S.<br />

Department of Commerce, 2003.<br />

206


8 Public Sentiments Toward New Reproductive Technologies and<br />

Biomedical Research<br />

8.1 Introduction<br />

The main purpose of the following discussion is not to determine whether the public is<br />

supportive or opposed to any one of the many controversial reproductive technologies the news<br />

media have reported on in the last several years. The data does suggest some fairly general and<br />

robust conclusions, but this is not the most important result. Far more consequential is the<br />

observation that the general public is not as polarized as the heated debates between radical<br />

supporters and opponents of new biomedical technologies indicate. This finding suggests that the<br />

current political gridlock over biomedical research at the federal level does not accurately reflect<br />

attitudes and political preferences among members of the general public. Our data analysis<br />

shows that on many divisive issues, the public displays far more nuanced positions than the<br />

Congress. In other cases, the general public displays considerable ambivalence; in still other<br />

cases, we have found broad opposition. What we did not find was a strongly polarized public.<br />

There are several possible reasons for these differences; they may reflect opposing cultural<br />

and social values among Congressional representatives of different states. This, of course, is as it<br />

should be in any representative democracy. However, this explanation only accounts for political<br />

differences, not for a polarized Congress. Polarization tendencies in the House of<br />

Representatives may also reflect misguided policies of Congressional redistricting. 1<br />

These<br />

policies clearly have contributed to exacerbating political conflicts, but have not caused the<br />

current political stalemate over biomedical research. As we demonstrate in more detail in chapter<br />

10, the main culprits in Congress’ inability to craft broadly acceptable legislative proposals are<br />

interest groups. In the area of reproductive medicine and biomedical research, these groups wield<br />

excessive power over the Congress, to the detriment of an unaffiliated public that tends to<br />

display more moderate views.<br />

This chapter is organized as follows: We first explore public attitudes toward science,<br />

technology and medicine in general. We then examine in some detail public sentiments toward<br />

reproductive cloning, research cloning (referred to by news media as “therapeutic” cloning” and<br />

by scientific organizations as “somatic cell nuclear transfer”), stem cell research, and genetic<br />

engineering, in this order. These issues have received considerable attention from the news<br />

1<br />

Redistricting practices in many cases have had the intended result – to send a larger number of African-<br />

Americans to the Congress – but they have also contributed to producing an increasing number of conservative,<br />

white Congressional districts. Congressional representatives of these districts have no need to cater to a broad<br />

range of political interests. Their districts are simply too homogenous to require political moderation and the<br />

search for compromise.<br />

207


media and from polling organizations. Attitudes toward other developments such as preimplantation<br />

genetic diagnosis and sex-selection technologies have been polled less frequently,<br />

and are therefore not included in our discussion.<br />

Over<strong>all</strong>, we have gathered more than 120 survey questions. The data were obtained from<br />

four online databases, 2 gleaned from news reports and through extensive online searches. The<br />

large number of survey questions included in our discussion has forced us to organize the data in<br />

a somewhat unusual way. Given the survey responses to the wording of each question, we would<br />

have liked to include <strong>all</strong> the questions and the data directly in our discussion. However, this<br />

would have made this chapter unwieldy and excessively long. For this reason, we have grouped<br />

<strong>all</strong> the survey questions and the corresponding data in several Appendices. The survey questions<br />

used in each of the following sections have been linked to a corresponding Appendix through<br />

footnotes and a numeric index. Readers interested in scrutinizing the survey questions and<br />

answers in more detail should consult these Appendices.<br />

8.2 General Attitudes Toward Science and Technology<br />

It is a well-known fact that Americans, unlike Europeans and Canadians, are gener<strong>all</strong>y very<br />

optimistic about the role of science and technology in society. Our data clearly supports this<br />

observation. In 2002, a full 90 percent of respondents agreed strongly or somewhat strongly with<br />

the statement “Scientific research is essential for improving the quality of human life” (1). 3 In<br />

2003, the proportion of those who strongly agreed with this statement had increased from 48<br />

percent to 59 percent (1). And the percentage of respondents who agreed somewhat or strongly<br />

with this observation in 2004 remained very high (92 percent) (1).<br />

A general sense of optimism also emerges from the enthusiastic reaction in 2001, 2002,<br />

2003, and 2004 to the question of whether developments in science have helped make society<br />

better off; a whopping 86 percent of respondents shared this view, whereas less that 10 percent<br />

disagreed (2). These strongly positive attitudes toward science and scientific progress translate<br />

into significant support for public funding of research. In 2001, 41 percent of respondents to a<br />

Pew Research Center for the People and the Press survey thought that the federal government<br />

“should increase” spending on scientific research (110), and in 2002, 34 percent of the public<br />

thought that the federal government was spending “too little” on scientific research (111). Not<br />

surprisingly, the public gener<strong>all</strong>y feels quite positive about the over<strong>all</strong> impact of science on<br />

society. In 2001, 47 percent of respondents thought that on balance, the benefits strongly have<br />

outweighed the harmful effects, and another 25 percent thought that the benefits “slightly<br />

2<br />

3<br />

The four databases are Polling the Nations (http://www.orspub.com/), The G<strong>all</strong>up Organization<br />

(http://www.g<strong>all</strong>up.com/), Polling<strong>Report</strong> (http://www.pollingreport.com/), and the Kaiser Family Foundation<br />

Health Poll Search database (http://www.kaisernetwork.org/health_poll/hpoll_index.cfm).<br />

In this chapter, the numbers in parentheses refer to the corresponding questions in Appendices J through P.<br />

Questions, data, and sources used in this section are available in Appendix J: Attitudes toward Science and<br />

Medical Research.<br />

208


outweighed” the harm. By contrast, only 3 percent believed that the harmful effects strongly<br />

outweigh the benefits (112). Perhaps more telling is the response to the following question:<br />

“Even if it brings no immediate benefits, scientific research which advances the frontiers of<br />

knowledge is necessary and should be supported by the federal government. Do you strongly<br />

agree, agree, disagree, or strongly disagree?” (34). In 2001, 19 percent strongly agreed and 62<br />

percent agreed with this statement.<br />

With regard to medical technologies, the over<strong>all</strong> picture remains very positive, with 57<br />

percent of individuals strongly agreeing that “new technology used in medicine <strong>all</strong>ows people to<br />

live longer and better,” and 34 percent agreeing somewhat with this statement (4). These<br />

numbers, obtained in 2002, changed only slightly in 2003, with 60 percent agreeing very<br />

strongly and 31 percent agreeing somewhat with the same statement. Compared to other fields of<br />

scientific inquiry, medical research has the best public image, with 27 percent of the general<br />

public sharing the view that over the last 30 years, medicine has made the most positive<br />

contribution to society, followed closely by the 24 percent who thought that information<br />

technologies have made the most positive contribution (5).<br />

The picture emerging from the data is clear: In the United States, public sentiments toward<br />

science in general and medical research in particular remain very positive. However, policymakers<br />

and scientific leaders should not interpret these responses as a demonstration of<br />

unconditional support. The fact that the public gener<strong>all</strong>y is positively predisposed toward science<br />

does not prevent it from expressing some concerns. Asked whether “scientific research these<br />

days doesn’t pay enough attention to the moral values of societies,” in 2001, a surprising 28<br />

percent strongly agreed (6). This figure did not changed significantly in 2002, with 29 percent<br />

agreeing strongly with this expression of skepticism. Very similar figures emerged in 2003 (28<br />

percent) and in 2004 (25 percent). That not <strong>all</strong> is well with science is also demonstrated by<br />

reactions elicited by the statement “Scientific research has created as many problems for society<br />

as it has solutions” (7). In 2001, 2002, and 2003, a solid minority of approximately 20 percent of<br />

respondents strongly agreed, and between 36 and 40 percent somewhat agreed with this vote of<br />

no confidence. The following question produced an even stronger expression of distrust: “The<br />

temptations to make money from new technologies puts pressure on scientists to pursue research<br />

ideas that violate ethical principles. Do you strongly agree, somewhat agree, somewhat disagree,<br />

or strongly disagree?” In this case, 69 percent of respondents either strongly or somewhat agreed<br />

with this statement (95). These feelings of discomfort should not be dismissed simply because<br />

they are generic expressions of distrust. The survey data introduced below show that generic<br />

expressions of support or distrust provide a useful framework within which the public is likely to<br />

make more specific distinctions.<br />

8.3 Reproductive Cloning<br />

The general public has been polled on reproductive cloning at least since 1993. The surveys<br />

reviewed in this section were conducted in 1993, 1997, 1998, 2000, 2001, 2002, and 2003.<br />

209


Before diving into the data, the meaning of the term “reproductive cloning” should be clarified.<br />

In this section and throughout this report, “reproductive cloning” is synonymous with somatic<br />

cell nuclear transplantation for the purpose of creating a child. In other words, reproductive<br />

cloning can be described as a new kind of reproductive technology. 4 The data presented in this<br />

section is organized both chronologic<strong>all</strong>y and thematic<strong>all</strong>y. Chronologic<strong>all</strong>y, roughly three<br />

distinct phases can be distinguished: The first phase includes surveys conducted before 1997, the<br />

second period covers the years 1997 and 1998, and the third phase ranges from 1998 to 2003.<br />

(We were unable to find surveys of sufficient quality after 2003.) 1997 was of course the year the<br />

world became acquainted with the first cloned mammal, Dolly the sheep. Surveys conducted<br />

before 1997 are necessarily somewhat speculative. Public reactions during the 1997-1998 were<br />

registered against the background of a historical announcement. <strong>Final</strong>ly, surveys conducted since<br />

1998 are likely to reflect more distanced public sentiments.<br />

Thematic<strong>all</strong>y, we first examine a series of questions aimed at eliciting general sentiments<br />

toward reproductive cloning. Unlike the surveys discussed in the second part of this section,<br />

these questions do not include a specific rationale for performing reproductive cloning. They<br />

simply aim to assess the public’s reaction to the very notion of reproductive cloning. 5 One of the<br />

earliest surveys on this question dates back to 1993. A Time/CNN poll explored the public’s<br />

sentiments about reproductive cloning in several ways. It asked whether cloning is a “good or<br />

bad thing” (10); 75 percent found it is a bad thing, 14 percent thought it was a good thing. Other<br />

questions designed to elicit a generic statement of approval or disapproval produced similar<br />

results. For example, asked whether reproductive cloning is mor<strong>all</strong>y wrong, 58 percent agreed<br />

(14). A somewhat higher percentage (63 percent) believed that reproductive cloning is against<br />

God’s will (15). And very few respondents (7 percent) were interested in “cloning an embryo”<br />

for reproductive purposes (12).<br />

In the aftermath of the Dolly announcement, the percentage of respondents who rejected<br />

reproductive cloning increased. Depending on how the question was framed, opposition ranged<br />

from a relatively low 63 percent to an overwhelming 93 percent. For example, in 1997, 88<br />

percent of respondents were strongly opposed to “cloning a human being” (18). Asked whether<br />

cloning “is a good or a bad thing,” 62 percent of respondents agreed that it is indeed a bad thing,<br />

while 22 percent believed it is “a good thing” (19). 86 percent of respondents found it<br />

“unacceptable” to “make copies of humans” (17), whereas 74 percent thought it was “against<br />

God’s will” to clone a human being (131), 89 percent thought that it was “mor<strong>all</strong>y unacceptable”<br />

(110), 93 percent agreed that it was a “bad idea” (111), and 84 percent “opposed” creating an<br />

“exact copy” of a human being (20).<br />

Since 2000, generic attitudes toward reproductive cloning have remained largely unchanged.<br />

In 2000, 73 percent of respondents thought that it was “bad for society,” while only 10 percent<br />

4<br />

5<br />

Some commentators have pointed out, correctly in our view, that reproductive cloning is not as much a<br />

technology of reproduction as it is a replication technique. Cf. Annas, "Human Cloning: A Choice or an Echo?."<br />

To avoid confusion, in this report we use the former and more common interpretation.<br />

For a complete list of questions, corresponding data, and sources, see Appendix K: Reproductive Cloning.<br />

210


thought that cloning human beings would be “good for society” (23). A question framed in moral<br />

terms produced an 89 percent opposition (27). An overwhelming 85 percent rejected the notion<br />

that scientists should be <strong>all</strong>owed to try to clone human beings (26). In sum, the general public<br />

has been consistently opposed to this reproductive procedure by large or very large margins for<br />

well over a decade.<br />

One could predict that questions worded in more specific terms – i.e., questions that include<br />

various rationales for performing this procedure – would produce a dramatic<strong>all</strong>y different<br />

picture. To test this claim, we assembled several questions designed to assess the public’s<br />

sentiments on a variety of possible applications of reproductive cloning. As for the more generic<br />

formulations, the available data can be subdivided into three time periods: the pre-Dolly era, the<br />

period of time immediately following the announcement of Dolly, and surveys conducted more<br />

recently.<br />

In 1993, two out of three possible applications of reproductive cloning produced very strong<br />

opposition. For example, the notion that parents might want to have a “twin child” at a later point<br />

in time, that is to say a genetic copy of a living child, was rejected by 78 percent of respondents<br />

(11). The possibility of having a twin clone, i.e. of copying oneself, was rejected by an even<br />

bigger majority – 86 percent (13). By contrast, the suggestion that cloning may be used to<br />

produce a larger number of embryos to help a couple have a child through ART techniques was<br />

more controversial, with 45 percent approving and 46 percent disapproving of this possibility<br />

(9).<br />

In the aftermath of the Dolly announcement, the public was frequently polled on possible<br />

rationales for performing reproductive cloning. With one exception, offering specific<br />

justifications did not increase the public’s support for this technology. Asked whether they would<br />

want to clone themselves if they found out they had only one year to live, in 1997, 91 percent of<br />

respondents answered no (16). Nor is the possibility of simply cloning oneself appealing to<br />

many: 91 percent denied that they would want to clone themselves (120). In 1998, the suggestion<br />

that parents might want to clone a deceased young child was rejected by 87 percent of<br />

respondents (122). The view that reproductive cloning could be used to make babies that would<br />

provide vital organs to save the lives of others was rejected by 78 percent of surveyed individuals<br />

(123). Noteworthy in this case is that 19 percent of those surveyed actu<strong>all</strong>y approved of this<br />

suggestion – a rather discouraging result, to put it mildly. To <strong>all</strong>ow parents to have a “twin child”<br />

at a later point in time was again rejected, this time by 86 percent of respondents (124). Only the<br />

suggestion that reproductive cloning may be beneficial to infertile couples garnered slightly more<br />

positive responses: In one poll, 33 percent of respondents approved, while 63 percent<br />

disapproved (121). In another poll on the same subject, however, the rejection in 1998 compared<br />

to 1997 was considerably higher, at 80 percent (22).<br />

More recent polls on specific applications of reproductive cloning have produced a similar<br />

result. In 2001, only 10 percent of respondents supported reproductive cloning to <strong>all</strong>ow gay<br />

couples to have genetic<strong>all</strong>y related children, while 86 percent rejected this suggestion (125).<br />

Producing “genetic<strong>all</strong>y superior human beings” was rejected by 92 percent of polled individuals<br />

211


(126), and <strong>all</strong>owing parents to have a “twin child” at a later point in time was again rejected by a<br />

large margin, this time 88 percent (127). In 2001, retrieving “vital organs” from babies for<br />

therapeutic purposes was rejected by 68 percent of respondents, while an alarming 28 percent<br />

found this proposal acceptable (128). While 76 percent of respondents did not think that helping<br />

infertile couple is an acceptable use of reproductive cloning (130), 74 percent of polled<br />

individuals thought nothing of cloning a person in order to save that person’s life (129). In sum,<br />

no matter what the rationale for resorting to reproductive cloning, the public finds this procedure<br />

unacceptable by very large margins and has done so at least since 1993.<br />

Interestingly, opposition to reproductive cloning is not limited to the cloning of human<br />

beings. In 2002, the suggestion that pets could be cloned garnered strong opposition – 92 percent<br />

(25). The public seems to be opposed to cloning animals even when this procedure could keep a<br />

species from becoming extinct, with 58 percent of respondents remaining opposed to the<br />

procedure in this case (24). Even cloning farm animals, an almost common practice these days, is<br />

opposed by 42 percent of the general public (29).<br />

When it comes to imposing legal bans, the picture is more ambivalent. In 1993, 46 percent<br />

of the public thought that reproductive cloning should be regulated rather than banned outright.<br />

An identical percentage thought that it should be banned (41). A few years later, in 1998, the<br />

suggestion that reproductive cloning should be banned (“Do you favor or oppose an outright ban<br />

on the cloning of human beings?”) mustered significant (albeit not overwhelming) support – 58<br />

percent (21). Wording the question in terms of “not <strong>all</strong>owing” rather than “banning” significantly<br />

affected the response: In 2001, a much higher proportion of respondents (89 percent) believed<br />

that reproductive cloning “should not be <strong>all</strong>owed” (27). A year later, respondents thought by a<br />

very large margin (85 percent) that scientists should not be <strong>all</strong>owed to clone human beings (26).<br />

On the other end, surveys conducted by Virginia Commonwealth University (VCU) in 2001,<br />

2002, and 2003 seem to indicate that support for an outright ban is somewhat lower, at<br />

approximately 65 percent (28). This result is contradicted by a well-crafted question that in 2003<br />

elicited strong support for making reproductive cloning illegal (138). Quite possibly, this<br />

somewhat ambivalent attitude toward banning reproductive cloning reflects a deep-seated<br />

skepticism about government institutions and regulations.<br />

8.4 Research Cloning<br />

We define research cloning as somatic cell nuclear transplantation for research purposes.<br />

While from a scientific standpoint research cloning and reproductive cloning are identical,<br />

research cloning is not performed with reproductive goals in mind. With research cloning, we<br />

shift to a topic considerably more controversial than reproductive cloning. The medical and<br />

research community aggressively have promoted the view that research cloning is a crucial step<br />

in the development of cures for many diseases; opponents, for their part, have pointed to the<br />

hypothetical nature of this assertion and sharply criticized the destruction of human embryos for<br />

research purposes.<br />

212


Over the last few years, organized interest groups have often polled the general public on<br />

this subject. In the process, they have produced a considerable amount of survey data.<br />

Unfortunately, in the case of research cloning (or therapeutic cloning, as the news media and<br />

some research organizations prefer to c<strong>all</strong> this procedure), survey questions of good quality are<br />

often hard to come by. In many cases, interest groups conduct these surveys to produce data<br />

supportive of their positions rather than to elicit genuine public sentiments. To compensate for<br />

poor data quality, throughout our discussion, we take the distorting effects of certain types of<br />

wording explicitly into account.<br />

Our analysis shows that two criteria have a significant impact on public attitudes toward<br />

research cloning: Does a survey question specific<strong>all</strong>y mention that research cloning might lead to<br />

new medical treatments, and is the public being informed that conducting research cloning<br />

entails destroying human embryos? Research organizations and science advocacy groups tend to<br />

ask questions that emphasize the benefits for the patients and the public in general, but rarely<br />

mention the destruction of the embryo. Conservative and religious groups, on the other end,<br />

gener<strong>all</strong>y downplay possible medical benefits but underscore the fact that embryos must be<br />

sacrificed for the sake of medical research. A third set of questions may be considered neutral, in<br />

the sense that neither specific benefits nor drawbacks are mentioned. These questions do,<br />

however, mention that cloning is being conducted for research. A few survey questions include<br />

references both to possible benefits of medical research and to the destruction of cloned embryos<br />

for research purposes. It is this last category of questions that is most likely to produce accurate<br />

responses.<br />

We found three fairly neutral, generic questions aimed at eliciting public feelings about<br />

research cloning as a research technique (33, 37, 38). 6 Two of these questions focus on the<br />

legality of research cloning (as in, “Should researchers be <strong>all</strong>owed to clone human embryos for<br />

medical research?”), while one (33) simply measures support for or opposition to research<br />

cloning. In this baseline situation, there is no evidence that the public would support research<br />

cloning. In two cases (33, 38), respondents opposed research cloning by a two-to-one margin,<br />

and in one case (37), opponents and supporters were evenly split, with 47 percent favoring a ban<br />

and 48 percent opposing it. In short, the public has significant reservations about research<br />

cloning, even though the questions worded in generic terms are more likely to elicit responses<br />

supportive of medical research.<br />

Ten survey questions of various quality explicitly mention possible benefits of medical<br />

research but do not make any reference to the destruction of embryos (150, 45, 44, 151, 152, 35,<br />

36, 40, 153, 154). 7 One may think that emphasizing possible health benefits would produce<br />

strong and consistent support for this new field of research. To our surprise, this turned out not to<br />

be the case. In three cases (45, 44, 36), supporters and opponents were almost evenly split.<br />

Respondents to the other three questions (35, 40, 151) remained opposed or strongly opposed to<br />

6<br />

7<br />

Wording of the questions used in this section, data, and sources are available in Appendix L: Research Cloning.<br />

The order in which the questions are listed reflects their sequence in the Appendix L.<br />

213


esearch cloning. Two questions (150, 152) produced a significant but not overwhelming<br />

majority of responses in support of research cloning; fin<strong>all</strong>y, respondents to two questions (153,<br />

154) were overwhelmingly supportive of this kind of research. Based on this data, it is fair to say<br />

that the public is rather ambivalent about the wisdom of moving forward with research cloning.<br />

We found one question (43) that was designed to elicit the legitimacy of performing medical<br />

research that would destroy human embryos but that did not mention possible medical benefits:<br />

“Should scientists be <strong>all</strong>owed to use human cloning to create a supply of human embryos to be<br />

destroyed in medical research?” Not surprisingly, an overwhelming majority of respondents (80<br />

percent) found this suggestion unacceptable.<br />

What about questions forcing respondents to evaluate both the pros and cons of research<br />

cloning? We found two questions making the relevant trade-offs fairly clear (30, 155). Both<br />

questions also explained in some detail the technicalities of research cloning. One (30) explicitly<br />

juxtaposed the destruction of the embryo with possible medical breakthroughs. The other (155)<br />

did not mention the destruction of the embryo, but pointed to the risk that cloning technologies<br />

might be misused for reproductive purposes. In both cases, the public rejected research cloning<br />

by a two-to-one margin. (Both questions were asked in August 2001, and are therefore somewhat<br />

dated.)<br />

Based on this survey data, we can draw three main conclusions: First, the poor quality of<br />

some survey questions notwithstanding, it is fair to say that there remains considerable<br />

skepticism among members of the general public about the wisdom of moving forward with<br />

research cloning. Second, public attitudes toward research cloning seem quite sensitive to<br />

whether mention is made of both embryo destruction and possible medical benefits. Third, and<br />

most importantly, the general public clearly distinguishes between reproductive and research<br />

cloning. We are not suggesting that the public has a clear understanding of the medical and<br />

scientific terminology. Our claim is simply that respondents, if provided with understandable<br />

trade-offs, provided consistently different answers to questions pertaining to these two<br />

procedures: They reject reproductive cloning by large margins, and remain ambivalent about<br />

research cloning.<br />

8.5 Stem Cell Research<br />

Not surprisingly, the best survey data available is on stem cell research. Our discussion of<br />

this topic is organized as follows: We first take in in-depth look at several survey questions<br />

worded in general terms. These are questions simply aimed at measuring generic support for or<br />

opposition to stem cell research, in which no mention is made of the destruction of embryos, and<br />

possible research benefits are rarely mentioned. We then examine survey questions pertaining to<br />

the moral status of the embryo. In the final part of this section, we turn our attention to the<br />

willingness of the public to support federal funding for stem cell research.<br />

An important observation emerging from this data is that the general public holds fairly<br />

specific and differentiated views about stem cell research. The public gener<strong>all</strong>y regards stem cell<br />

214


esearch as desirable. Generic expressions of support do not translate into unconditional support,<br />

however. The donation of excess embryos is regarded as a viable option, whereas the creation of<br />

embryos solely for research purposes is rejected by significant margins.<br />

We have identified six survey questions posed between 2001 and 2004 designed to measure<br />

generic levels of approval or disapproval for stem cell research. This data suggests that the public<br />

consistently is supportive of stem cell research, although not in overwhelming numbers. Of the<br />

six questions, three produce significant support (52, 54, 60) while the public was evenly divided<br />

in three other cases (50, 51, 53). 8 Of some interest to our discussion is one poll, conducted by the<br />

Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation, which found that even religious and conservative voters<br />

show a significant degree of support for stem cell research, with 39 percent in favor of it and<br />

only 33 percent opposed (50).<br />

These preliminary results are broadly consistent with prevailing moral sentiments. We found<br />

five survey questions designed to elicit moral approval or disapproval for stem cell research,<br />

again in general terms (61, 62, 63, 66, 68). Far from eliciting more cautious responses, these<br />

questions tended to produce more consistent and somewhat stronger support for stem cell<br />

research. For example, 53 percent of respondents disagreed with the statement that “using<br />

embryos for research comes too close to <strong>all</strong>owing scientists to play God,” while 40 percent<br />

agreed (62). Less dramatic formulations, such as “<strong>all</strong>owing any medical research using stem cells<br />

from human embryos should be forbidden because it is unethical and immoral” (63), produce<br />

even stronger expressions of disagreement, with 60 percent of respondents rejecting this view<br />

and only 32 percent showing approval (63).<br />

The gener<strong>all</strong>y positive attitudes displayed by the public seem to be fuelled by very<br />

pragmatic considerations. In 2001, 34 percent of respondents thought that stem cell research is<br />

“wrong, but may be necessary.” The same percentage thought that this line of research is “not<br />

wrong, and may be necessary” (66). In the same year, 60 percent of respondents believed that<br />

“the embryo has the potential for life, but is not the same as life, because it cannot develop on its<br />

own,” whereas only 36 percent chose the statement “the embryo is a human life that should be<br />

given the same protection as <strong>all</strong> other human lives” (69). Whether supporters of stem cell<br />

research consistently hold a view of the moral status of the embryo that lies somewhere between<br />

a materialistic and a transcendental perspective is anyone’s guess, but it is fair to say that this<br />

view is entirely compatible with the 68 percent of the public that found stem cell research<br />

“necessary.” A third question provides additional, albeit indirect, evidence for the public’s<br />

pragmatic attitude: Asked whether “stem cell research is an important step forward in finding a<br />

cure or treatment for things like Parkinson’s disease and MS (multiple sclerosis)” or whether<br />

“stem cell research will take the lives of innocent unborn children,” 52 percent of respondents<br />

chose the former option, while only 30 percent selected the latter (64).<br />

Generic expressions of support consistently translate into equ<strong>all</strong>y supportive attitudes<br />

toward federal funding for stem cell research. Between 2001 and 2002, polling organizations<br />

8<br />

A complete list of survey questions used in this section is available in Appendix M: Stem Cell Research.<br />

215


asked five times whether the public would support federal funding for stem cell research. These<br />

questions were worded in general terms, with no reference to the origin of the embryos or the<br />

specific research benefits. Each of the five questions examined here produced significant support<br />

for federal funding of stem cell research. In three cases, supporters outweighed opponents by a<br />

two-to-one margin (56, 57, 46); in the other two cases, support remained significant, though a<br />

larger number of respondents were undecided (47, 55). In sum, a solid although not<br />

overwhelming majority of the public is supportive of stem cell research, does not find it mor<strong>all</strong>y<br />

objectionable, and would be favorable to federal funding for this new area of research.<br />

The two-to-one margin in favor of stem cell research should not be interpreted as an<br />

unconditional statement of support. Rather, it should be regarded as a baseline that is likely to<br />

shift depending on the specific policy proposals. As we show below, attitudes toward stem cell<br />

research change significantly if one examines whether embryos should be created solely for the<br />

purpose of conducting stem cell research (“research embryos”), or whether stem cell research<br />

should rely on excess embryos from fertility clinics.<br />

The question that by far has received the greatest attention is whether the public would<br />

support the use of donated excess embryos stored at fertility clinics. We have identified 13<br />

survey questions that speak to this issue. The results are summarized in Table 9 and Table 10.<br />

These questions, though at times worded very differently, share two attributes: They make<br />

reference to the fact that to derive new stem cell lines, the embryo would have to be destroyed,<br />

and they explicitly mention possible medical benefits from this new area of research. The<br />

vocabulary used to alert the respondents to the fact that embryos are being destroyed varies.<br />

Some questions simply state that embryos would have to be used; others point out explicitly that<br />

embryos are being destroyed.<br />

The implicit reference to the destruction of embryos could mislead some members of the<br />

public and produce distorted response patterns. To identify possible distortions, we have grouped<br />

the survey questions in two categories: In the top half of Table 9 and Table 10, we have listed<br />

questions that explicitly mention the destruction of embryos; in the bottom half, we have<br />

included formulations that merely suggest embryo destruction. Surprisingly, the data do not<br />

show any appreciable difference in the response patterns. For this reason, we have decided to<br />

ignore this issue.<br />

Poll Support Oppose Intensity<br />

CNN/USA Today/G<strong>all</strong>up 1 (Q83) 55 40 +<br />

Ipsos Reid (Q84) 75 20 ++<br />

CNN/USA Today/G<strong>all</strong>up 2 (Q86) 55 39 +<br />

Washington Post/ABC News (Q87) 63 33 ++<br />

Harris Interactive 1 (Q81) 61 21 ++<br />

Harris Interactive 2 (Q82) 72 21 ++<br />

G<strong>all</strong>up (Q88) 77 18 ++<br />

Table 9: Attitudes toward the use of excess embryos for stem cell research in 2001.<br />

216


To the extent possible, we have aggregated the original data so as to <strong>all</strong>ow a comparison<br />

across questions. The last column in Table 9 and Table 10 is a measure of the intensity of<br />

support. Intensity in this case is a somewhat subjective measure; we consider a two-to-one or<br />

higher margin an indication of strong support (++), and anything less as indicative of moderate<br />

support (+). In nine out of 13 cases, the public was very much in favor of using excess embryos<br />

for research purposes; in three cases, respondents were supportive, but by a lesser margin; and in<br />

one case, the public was almost evenly split between supporters and opponents. In sum, the<br />

general public is overwhelmingly supportive of conducting stem cell research on excess<br />

embryos.<br />

Poll Support Oppose Intensity<br />

Results for America II (Q92) 72 25 ++<br />

Results for America I (Q59) 73 24 ++<br />

Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation 2 (Q89) 56 36 +<br />

Harris Interactive 1 (Q58) 72 13 ++<br />

Harris Interactive 2 (Q96) 73 11 ++<br />

Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation 1 (Q90) 44 46 ~<br />

Table 10: Attitudes toward the use of excess embryos for stem cell research in 2004-2005.<br />

The last policy question to be examined in this section is whether the general public would<br />

support federal funding for research on embryos created exclusively for research purposes. This<br />

question may at first seem a bit speculative. According to a recently conducted study, there are<br />

currently more than 400,000 embryos frozen at fertility clinics around the country. 9 However,<br />

this same study points out that the actual number of embryos suitable for research purposes is far<br />

sm<strong>all</strong>er. If federal funding for embryonic stem cells comes through, it is quite possible that the<br />

supply of excess embryos from fertility clinics will quickly be exhausted. At that point, the<br />

question would arise as to whether it would be desirable and permissible to create embryos for<br />

the sole purpose of conducting research, and whether the federal government should fund stem<br />

cell research that relies on embryos created exclusively for research purposes. 10<br />

On this question, the general public would be far less supportive of scientists’ demands. In<br />

2001, a slight majority of respondents (53 percent) was opposed to <strong>all</strong>owing the creation of<br />

human embryos exclusively for research purposes, while only 38 percent supported this<br />

proposition (70). In 2002, the strong opposition to creating embryos for research purposes had<br />

subsided somewhat. A carefully worded G<strong>all</strong>up question on this matter found that a majority (49<br />

percent) of the public remained opposed to it, while a strong minority (46 percent) supported it<br />

(71). One survey question is insufficient to draw a firm conclusion, of course, but it appears that<br />

9<br />

10<br />

David Hoffman et al., "Cryopreserved Embryos in the United States and Their Availability for Research,"<br />

Fertility and Sterility 79, no. 5 (2003).<br />

It should be remembered that the Dickey-Wicker Amendment currently prevents the federal government from<br />

funding any kind of research on human embryos. This amendment to the Department of Health and Human<br />

Services appropriation bill has been renewed by Congress every year since its enactment in 1996.<br />

217


the creation of embryos solely for research would encounter much fiercer opposition than federal<br />

funding for stem cell research conducted on excess embryos.<br />

8.6 Genetic Engineering<br />

An area of scientific research that has received considerable attention by polling<br />

organizations is what is loosely referred to as “genetic engineering.” This term is not always<br />

well-defined, but the survey questions usu<strong>all</strong>y are worded well enough to <strong>all</strong>ow a systematic<br />

evaluation of public sentiments on this issue. Attitudes toward human genetic engineering<br />

provide an excellent opportunity to verify whether the public distinguishes between therapeutic<br />

and enhancing applications of biomedical research. In chapter 3, we suggested that this<br />

distinction should be included as one of the main guiding ethical principles in any enabling<br />

legislation. Whether the general public believes that this distinction is meaningful is therefore of<br />

considerable import to our discussion.<br />

We have identified 17 survey questions pertaining to genetic engineering for the years 1993,<br />

1994, 1997, 1998, 2002, and 2003. 11 In these questions, pollsters took this term to mean a<br />

technology that would <strong>all</strong>ow prospective parents to select specific human characteristics, usu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

higher traits such as intelligence and artistic talent but also height, hair, and eye color. Scientists<br />

in this context speak of inheritable genetic modifications. That these options today are available<br />

only in a very limited sense or not at <strong>all</strong> is rarely mentioned.<br />

An interesting result emerging from this data is that the public has begun only relatively<br />

recently to distinguish between therapeutic and enhancing applications of genetic engineering.<br />

For example, a 1993 Time/CNN poll found that 52 percent of respondents “disapproved” of<br />

screening embryos for inherited abnormalities (107). A year later, 67 percent of respondents to a<br />

CBS News poll thought that “to make a ‘test-tube’ baby that is guaranteed to be free of certain<br />

genetic diseases” was “going too far,” while only 26 percent thought it was a “good thing” (160).<br />

A few years later, in 2003, a Virginia Commonwealth University survey produced a similar<br />

result, with 54 percent of respondents believing that “changing a baby’s genetic characteristics to<br />

reduce the risk of serious diseases” is “taking medical advances to far,” while a relatively low 41<br />

percent thought that it was an “appropriate use” of this technology (105).<br />

The VCU result is somewhat of an outlier, however. It appears that the general public<br />

already had begun to distinguish between medical and enhancing applications of screening<br />

technologies. Asked by a Time/CNN poll in 1998 whether they would choose to “rule out a<br />

genetic<strong>all</strong>y transmitted fatal or crippling disease,” two-thirds of respondents declared that they<br />

would (162). The same survey found that a whopping 88 percent rejected sex selection,<br />

presumably for non-therapeutic uses (164), 86 percent would not choose height or weight (165),<br />

and 89 percent would also not choose hair or eye color (166).<br />

11<br />

All survey questions and corresponding data are available in Appendix N: Genetic Engineering.<br />

218


Therapeutic and enhancing applications of biomedical technologies trigger distinct<br />

reactions. In 2002, the Genetics and Public Policy Center tested how acceptable various forms of<br />

genetic interventions were judged to be among members of the public (167). Respondents were<br />

again strongly opposed to elective sex selection (68 percent to 28 percent), and rejected the<br />

notion that a baby should be engineered to have “desirable characteristics such as high<br />

intelligence and strength” (72 percent to 22 percent). On the other end, the same respondents<br />

were very much supportive of using genetic interventions to ensure that “their baby does not<br />

have a serious genetic disease” (74 percent to 22 percent), and that their baby “does not have a<br />

tendency to develop a disease like cancer when he or she is an adult” (60 percent to 33 percent).<br />

The participants in this survey also found, by a large margin (69 percent to 25 percent), that<br />

screening an embryo for certain tissue characteristics in order to help an older sibling in need of<br />

a transplant is acceptable.<br />

The rejection of enhancing applications of screening technologies has remained very strong.<br />

In the 2003 VCU survey, 94 percent of respondents found “changing a baby’s genetic<br />

characteristics for cosmetic purposes” to be unacceptable (104), and in a 2003 CNN/USA Today<br />

poll, 88 percent of respondents thought that the selection of traits such as intelligence or artistic<br />

talent “should not be <strong>all</strong>owed” (169). The CNN/USA Today poll also phrased the same question<br />

in personal terms, asking whether respondents themselves would actu<strong>all</strong>y make use of traitselection<br />

technologies. In this case, 91 percent of respondents thought that babies should “be<br />

born with whatever traits [they] would natur<strong>all</strong>y have” (170).<br />

Whether opposition to screening and enhancing technologies will remain high in the face of<br />

scientific and medical progress remains to be seen. One survey question seems to suggest that it<br />

might not, at least in some cases. In 2003, the VCU survey asked a representative sample of U.S.<br />

citizens whether they would likely make use of genetic technologies that “slow down the aging<br />

process” (106); 61 percent rejected this notion, but a non-trivial 37 percent stated that they would<br />

be either very likely or likely to use it. This is another compelling reason to consider adopting<br />

regulatory institutions with a mandate to structure a broad public debate on these matters.<br />

8.7 Awareness and Familiarity<br />

Critical commentators could dismiss our findings on the ground that the data from these<br />

surveys reflects superficial reactions by an uninformed public to poorly worded questions. In a<br />

general sense, this criticism may be warranted, but it is largely irrelevant in the present case for<br />

several reasons. It would certainly be misleading to draw broad generalizations from a single<br />

data point. Our conclusions, however, are not based on isolated observations but on a large<br />

number of survey questions, worded in different ways and asked at different times. Conclusions<br />

based on many survey questions are far more robust than inferences drawn from individual data<br />

points; the distorting impact of poorly worded survey questions becomes negligible, and<br />

underlying trends begin to appear. Thus, it would be very difficult to dismiss our findings for<br />

reasons of data quality.<br />

219


Our conclusions could be criticized on other grounds. It is well known that members of the<br />

general public display fairly low levels of scientific literacy. This would seem reason enough to<br />

ignore public attitudes on matters involving complex scientific controversies. This is certainly<br />

the case as far as general scientific literacy is concerned. Some of the data introduced below tend<br />

to support this observation. But as we make clear in the remainder of this section, the<br />

relationship between levels of scientific literacy and the credibility of survey answers is weak. In<br />

the case of reproductive technologies and biomedical research, comparatively low levels of<br />

scientific literacy do not undermine the credibility of our results.<br />

In light of the difficulty in assessing levels of knowledgeability, pollsters often resort to<br />

measuring “awareness.” 12 Awareness is certainly no substitute for knowledgeability, but it is not<br />

entirely unrelated to it. Individuals with no knowledge whatsoever of a topic are very unlikely to<br />

be “aware” of this topic. Conversely, respondents with a considerable interest in and knowledge<br />

of an issue are obviously aware of it. The available data suggests that the general public is quite<br />

aware of topics such as stem cell research and the cloning controversy. Moreover, the levels of<br />

awareness have increased significantly since President Bush addressed the nation on stem cell<br />

research in August of 2001. Between 2001 and 2004, the general public’s interest in medical<br />

research has remained quite high. Almost 50 percent of respondents to the annual VCU survey<br />

register a “strong interest” in medical news stories, whereas only 10 percent are “not at <strong>all</strong>” or<br />

“not much” interested in this topic (135). As for awareness of the stem cell research controversy,<br />

we found seven questions addressing this issue (76, 78, 134, 75, 132, 74, 73). Rigorous<br />

comparisons are not always possible due to different scales, but it is fair to say that a large<br />

majority of the general public has at least heard of or read something about stem cell research.<br />

With regard to levels of scientific literacy, the picture at first seems somewhat troubling. In<br />

March of 2004, the Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation asked the following question: “How<br />

well do you think you could explain this topic to a family member or friend – very well,<br />

somewhat well, not very well, or not at <strong>all</strong> well?” Only 9 percent of respondents thought they<br />

could explain this issue “very well.” A promising 37 percent thought they could at least explain<br />

these matters “somewhat well.” On the other end, 20 percent replied that they would not be able<br />

to explain the issues involved at <strong>all</strong> (77).<br />

For its part, in 2002, 2003, and 2004, Virginia Commonwealth University asked about the<br />

difference between “therapeutic” and “reproductive” cloning (139, 99, 100). The public’s<br />

responses to this question are somewhat disheartening: Responses to the question in 2002 and<br />

2003 were very similar; only a sm<strong>all</strong> minority (8 percent in 2003 and 11 percent 2002) declared<br />

to be “very clear” about this distinction, whereas a significant minority (26 percent and 31<br />

percent, respectively) was “somewhat clear.” Another 30 percent was “not very clear” (32<br />

percent and 29 percent, respectively) or “not at <strong>all</strong> clear” (33 percent and 28 percent,<br />

respectively) about the difference between reproductive and research cloning (100, 99). When<br />

this question was asked again in the f<strong>all</strong> of 2004, the number of those “somewhat clear” or “very<br />

12<br />

See Appendix O for details.<br />

220


clear” had remained at 34 percent (131). Roughly similar figures emerged when the public was<br />

quizzed about medical discoveries (“How well informed are you about medical discoveries?”).<br />

About 10 percent of respondents said that they were “very informed,” two-thirds thought they<br />

were “somewhat informed,” and 25 percent thought they were “not very informed” (133). On the<br />

other end, a 2001 Harris Interactive poll found that 78 percent of the people surveyed were able<br />

to identify genes as “the basic unit of hereditary information,” and 50 percent were aware that<br />

genes consist of DNA. About the same percentage (52 percent) knew that the genome is “an<br />

organism’s complete set of hereditary information.” 13 A year later, the Genetics and Public<br />

Policy Center discovered that the general public is not always clear on whether it was currently<br />

possible to actu<strong>all</strong>y engineer babies (136, 137).<br />

As troubling as these results may appear, they are not necessarily detrimental to the quality<br />

and credibility of the survey data. Consider the most damning piece of evidence – the general<br />

public does not seem to distinguish very well between reproductive and therapeutic cloning.<br />

Should this data be interpreted to suggest that any conclusion based on this distinction should be<br />

invalidated? We don’t think so. Consider how questions 99, 100, and 131 assess scientific<br />

literacy. These questions measure knowledge of abstract scientific concepts. The general public<br />

may not always be able to provide scholastic definitions of terms such as “reproductive cloning”<br />

and “therapeutic cloning,” but this knowledge is not necessary to answer survey questions in a<br />

coherent and informed manner. Questions designed to assess public attitudes toward various<br />

applications of cloning technology often convey a fairly good sense of what these procedures<br />

entail and of the trade-offs involved. A deep understanding of the technicalities involved is not<br />

necessary to provide an informed answer. So, while the public may not always be able to provide<br />

precise definitions of the relevant scientific concepts, it does not follow that survey questions<br />

cannot articulate the relevant trade-offs and elicit reasonably informed answers. 14<br />

Another important reason for the relative unimportance of scientific literacy is that the<br />

controversies surrounding new biomedical technologies are themselves non-scientific. 15 Is an<br />

advanced degree in genetics required to decide whether sex selection for elective purposes is<br />

desirable? Is mastery of cell biology a condition for a meaningful participation in the debate<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

Harris Interactive, The Public Is Overwhelmingly Optimistic and Supportive of Genomics Research – However,<br />

Knowledge and Understanding Remain Modest (Health Care News, June 18, 2001 [cited September 21, 2005]);<br />

available from<br />

http://www.harrisinteractive.com/news/newsletters/healthnews/HI_HealthCareNews2001Vol1_iss20.pdf.<br />

At least in the case of the distinction between therapeutic and reproductive cloning, the reason for this situation<br />

is quite clear: Pollsters have refrained from using these terms, except for assessing levels of knowledgeability.<br />

The news media, while it has reported profusely on this topic, rarely have made clear this categorical distinction.<br />

Scientific leaders, for their part, have actively tried to blur this distinction by advocating the exclusive use of the<br />

term “somatic cell nuclear transfer.” Cf. Vogelstein, Alberts, and Shine, "Please Don't C<strong>all</strong> It Cloning."<br />

Incident<strong>all</strong>y, this is not a unique feature of biomedicine. Consider for example the great outdoors. Does the<br />

general public need to absorb geomorphology and be cognizant about electrical engineering to reject a proposal<br />

aimed at flooding the Grand Canyon to produce electric energy? Certainly not. Should this rejection be<br />

dismissed by the proponents of the project as an uninformed view that Congress should ignore? Most certainly<br />

not.<br />

221


about embryonic stem cells? The answer to these questions is no. In <strong>all</strong> these cases, the public is<br />

not c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to adjudicate among competing scientific claims; rather, it is expected to make<br />

an informed ethical choice. 16 Offering thought-through answers to some of these questions may<br />

be very difficult, but scientific expertise does not necessarily facilitate this job, nor is it a<br />

requisite to accomplish it. 17<br />

8.8 The Culture Wars: A Myth?<br />

The empirical evidence discussed in this chapter suggests that the general public holds rather<br />

moderate views on new reproductive technologies and biomedical research. Reproductive<br />

cloning is rejected by large margins, research cloning generates considerable ambivalence, and<br />

stem cell research, under certain conditions, is viewed very favorably by significant majorities of<br />

the public. <strong>Final</strong>ly, genetic screening technologies such as pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

garner significant public support, but only for compelling medical reasons. These conclusions<br />

may lead those who subscribe to the view that America is deeply divided to conclude that our<br />

data must be inaccurate or that our analysis is flawed. According to this view, which is especi<strong>all</strong>y<br />

popular among political commentators, America is roughly divided into “red” and “blue” states.<br />

In a nutshell, red-state Americans are soci<strong>all</strong>y conservative and deeply religious and tend to vote<br />

republican. By contrast, in blue states live Americans with liberal social views who are of<br />

Democratic leaning and largely secular. This characterization is usu<strong>all</strong>y meant to identify a<br />

political divide along cultural rather than the traditional economic lines, hence the term “culture<br />

war.” 18<br />

If this view of contemporary America is correct and the “culture war” is indeed raging, then<br />

our survey data must be inaccurate: Deep societal divisions should certainly become apparent in<br />

matters as controversial as cloning technologies and stem cell research. The culture war<br />

hypothesis, then, would lead to the conclusion that the stalemate between scientific organizations<br />

advocating unfettered biomedical research and conservative groups staunchly defending the<br />

dignity of human life accurately reflects public sentiments on these issues, as does the legislative<br />

paralysis that has characterized the Congress in this area in the last few years.<br />

As fashionable as the concept of a culture war may be, it is seriously misleading. As some<br />

commentators convincingly have argued, most Americans continue to hold moderate, centrist<br />

views on many controversial questions. 19<br />

On the <strong>all</strong>-absorbing debate about abortion, a<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

19<br />

Jürgen Habermas, The Future of Human Nature (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 2003).<br />

Note that our claim here is not that scientific literacy is always or necessarily irrelevant. Different public<br />

controversies may c<strong>all</strong> for different levels of scientific literacy. For example, in assessing the health and<br />

environmental risks associated with genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified organisms (GMOs), scientific literacy may play a more<br />

prominent role.<br />

James Davison Hunter, Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America (New York: Basic Books, 1991).<br />

Morris P. Fiorina, Samuel J. Abrams, and Jeremy C. Pope, Culture War? The Myth of a Polarized America (New<br />

York: Pearson Education, 2005); Alan Wolfe, One Nation, after All: What Middle-Class Americans Re<strong>all</strong>y Think<br />

222


significant majority of Americans continue to support this right, but with considerable<br />

ambivalence, suggesting that abortion should stay legal but should also be closely regulated. On<br />

issues pertaining to gun control and gay marriage, the electorate is equ<strong>all</strong>y ambivalent, not<br />

polarized. The data on stem cell research discussed in the remainder of this chapter tells a similar<br />

story. Support for stem cell research is significant across political orientation, race, and gender,<br />

and in large measure across religious lines as well. The <strong>all</strong>egedly deep divisions often are simply<br />

an artifact of poorly worded survey questions rather than an expression of a culture war. The<br />

general public, presented with policy alternatives that do reflect realistic options, tend to display<br />

moderate, centrist views.<br />

In the following discussion, we included only survey questions that pose an explicit tradeoff<br />

between possible benefits from medical research on the one end and protection of human<br />

embryos on the other. We excluded several recently conducted surveys showing overwhelming<br />

support for or opposition to stem cell research that do not make this trade-off explicit. For<br />

example, a recent poll conducted by the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops that<br />

showed strong opposition to stem cell research was excluded because the questions asked in this<br />

poll barely made any mention of possible medical benefits. Analogously, we excluded a 2004<br />

National Annenberg Election Survey in which the benefits of research were explicitly mentioned<br />

but the means by which stem cell lines are derived were not. 20 Six surveys were examined: one<br />

conducted in June 2001 by ABCNews/Beliefnet (98); one conducted in August 2001 by<br />

ABCNews/Washington Post (56); two identical surveys conducted by the Pew Research Center<br />

in 2002 (49) and 2004 (109); one conducted by the Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation in<br />

2004 (89); and one conducted in 2004 by the Civil Society Institute.<br />

The two ABCNews polls found that the general public supported federal funding of stem<br />

cell research by a two-to-one margin. In these surveys, even religious and conservative voters<br />

were mostly supportive of federal funding for this kind of research. 21<br />

For example, white<br />

evangelical Protestants, arguably the most conservative group in the general population, were<br />

essenti<strong>all</strong>y split (50 percent versus 40 percent in the June poll and 47 percent versus 47 percent<br />

in the August one). Catholics were supportive by a two-to-one margin (54 percent versus 35<br />

percent in June and 65 percent versus 33 percent in August), and non-evangelical Protestants<br />

were supportive by even larger margins (68 percent versus 19 percent and 77 percent versus 19<br />

percent, respectively). Ideological orientation produced similar results: Conservative respondents<br />

20<br />

21<br />

About: God, Country, Family, Racism, Welfare, Immigration, Homosexuality, Work, the Right, the Left, and<br />

Each Other (New York: Viking, 1998).<br />

In the former case, a large majority of respondents opposed federal funding for stem cell research; in the latter,<br />

respondents supported it by large margins.<br />

It should be noted that the relevant questions as they appear in Appendix P did not make the trade-off between<br />

embryo protection and research benefit explicit. Instead, this information was provided in the preceding<br />

question: “Sometimes fertility clinics produce extra fertilized eggs, also c<strong>all</strong>ed embryos, that are not implanted in<br />

a woman’s womb. These extra embryos either are discarded, or couples can donate them for use in medical<br />

research, c<strong>all</strong>ed stem cell research. Some people support stem cell research, saying it’s an important way to find<br />

treatments for many diseases. Other people oppose stem cell research, saying it’s wrong to use any human<br />

embryos for research purposes. What about you – do you support or oppose stem cell research?”<br />

223


were essenti<strong>all</strong>y split (44 percent versus 44 percent and 53 percent versus 42 percent); moderates<br />

were supportive by a two-to-one margin (63 percent versus 26 percent and 64 percent versus 32<br />

percent); and an even larger percentage of liberal respondents (76 percent versus 14 percent and<br />

75 percent versus 23 percent) were in favor of federal funding of stem cell research. A similar<br />

but not identical pattern emerged from the two Pew Research Center polls (49, 109). In these two<br />

surveys, white evangelical Protestants were less enthusiastic about supporting stem cell research,<br />

with only 26 percent supporting it and 55 percent believing that protection of human embryos<br />

takes precedence over medical research (the 2002 Pew survey). The 2004 Pew survey produced<br />

somewhat higher support among the same group, at 33 percent. Response patterns in other<br />

population groups are comparable to those produced by the two ABCNews polls.<br />

Answers provided by white evangelical Protestants are the most sensitive to phrasing, but<br />

contrary to what might be expected, more detailed information tends to produce stronger support<br />

for medical research. The importance of providing detailed, specific information about the policy<br />

trade-offs becomes especi<strong>all</strong>y apparent in a poll conducted in 2004 by the Juvenile Diabetes<br />

Research Foundation among self-identified conservative voters (89). In this case, the actual<br />

survey questions were preceded by an extensive explanation that included, among other things,<br />

the fact that embryos would have to be destroyed and that there are more than 400,000 frozen<br />

embryos at ART clinics around the country. In this case, support for stem cell research increases<br />

to 56 percent, while opposition decreases to 36 percent. The dramatic impact of wording on<br />

conservative voters’ attitudes toward stem cell research also was documented in a 2004 survey<br />

conducted by the Civil Society Institute. 22 While the initial view of stem cell research among<br />

evangelicals is quite negative (53 percent oppose it and only 34 percent support it), after being<br />

provided with additional information, 23 negative sentiments turned positive, with 76 percent of<br />

these respondents expressing their support.<br />

The data we have just discussed provides additional support for our claim that a supposedly<br />

deep divide among contemporary Americans often is the result of poor wording rather than an<br />

expression of irreconcilable political differences. If offered adequate background information<br />

and reasonable choices, most Americans tend to pick compromise solutions and shy away from<br />

either extreme. This is true not only among self-declared moderate voters, but also among those<br />

voters who, according to the culture war thesis, should strongly object to any use of human<br />

embryos in medical research – namely, Catholics, conservative Republicans, and evangelicals.<br />

Against this background, our claim that the political gridlock in Congress reflects in large<br />

measure strongly polarized interest groups receives additional support. We discuss this issue in<br />

22<br />

23<br />

Peter D. Hart Research Associates, "Voter's Views on Stem Cell Research," (Newton Centre, MA: Civil Society<br />

Institute, 2004).<br />

“Embryonic stem cells are special cells that can develop into every type of cell in the human body. The stem<br />

cells are extracted from frozen embryos in fertility clinics, donated by couples that no longer want or need these<br />

embryos. This process destroys the embryo. These stem cells can then reproduce on their own, creating what is<br />

c<strong>all</strong>ed a “line” of stem cells that many researchers can work with. Scientists believe that there is a good chance<br />

that stem cells can be developed into cures or treatments for diseases such as cancer, Parkinson’s, Alzheimer’s,<br />

juvenile diabetes, and spinal cord injuries.” Ibid., p.5.<br />

224


some detail in chapter 10.1 Here, we simply note that support for stem cell research among the<br />

religious and conservative voters is in stark contrast to the resolute opposition expressed by<br />

advocacy groups such as the Christian Coalition, the United States Conference of Catholic<br />

Bishops, the Southern Baptist Convention, and the Family Research Council. Similarly, there is<br />

some evidence that scientific societies do not always accurately reflect the positions of their<br />

members.<br />

225


226


8.9 Bibliography<br />

Annas, George J. "Human Cloning: A Choice or an Echo?" Dayton Law Review 23 (1998): 247-<br />

75.<br />

Fiorina, Morris P., Samuel J. Abrams, and Jeremy C. Pope. Culture War? The Myth of a<br />

Polarized America. New York: Pearson Education, 2005.<br />

Habermas, Jürgen. The Future of Human Nature. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 2003.<br />

Harris Interactive. The Public Is Overwhelmingly Optimistic and Supportive of Genomics<br />

Research – However, Knowledge and Understanding Remain Modest Health Care News,<br />

June 18, 2001 [cited September 21, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.harrisinteractive.com/news/newsletters/healthnews/HI_HealthCareNews2001<br />

Vol1_iss20.pdf.<br />

Hoffman, David, Gail L. Zellman, C. Christine Fair, Jacob F. Mayer, Joyce G. Zeitz, William E.<br />

Gibbons, and Thomas G. Turner. "Cryopreserved Embryos in the United States and Their<br />

Availability for Research." Fertility and Sterility 79, no. 5 (2003): 1063-59.<br />

Hunter, James Davison. Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America. New York: Basic<br />

Books, 1991.<br />

Peter D. Hart Research Associates. "Voter's Views on Stem Cell Research." Newton Centre,<br />

MA: Civil Society Institute, 2004.<br />

Vogelstein, Bert, Bruce Alberts, and Kenneth Shine. "Please Don't C<strong>all</strong> It Cloning." Science 295<br />

(2002): 1237.<br />

Wolfe, Alan. One Nation, after All: What Middle-Class Americans Re<strong>all</strong>y Think About: God,<br />

Country, Family, Racism, Welfare, Immigration, Homosexuality, Work, the Right, the<br />

Left, and Each Other. New York: Viking, 1998.<br />

227


228


9 Possible Societal Responses<br />

In this chapter, we present an overview of the full range of regulatory responses to the<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enges posed by new biomedical technology, from doing nothing to changing the status quo to<br />

the creation of a new institution along the lines of the HFEA in Britain. In each case, we will lay<br />

out both pros and cons of each approach before presenting our recommended option. As we will<br />

show below, none of the possible options are cost-free; each involves trade-offs, and each is<br />

likely to have unforeseen consequences down the road.<br />

9.1 Maintaining the Status Quo<br />

Arguments Pro<br />

There are several serious arguments for not intervening at this time. Advocates of<br />

maintaining the status quo have argued that existing federal and state statutes combined with an<br />

extensive system of industry self-regulation provide a regulatory framework that is more than<br />

adequate to respond to whatever ch<strong>all</strong>enges might lie ahead. 1 This argument is largely based on<br />

the assumption that at the present time, we are not facing a threat serious enough to justify<br />

creating an entirely new regulatory system, whereas the establishment of a new regulatory<br />

framework would have immediate and significant costs. Should a legislative intervention become<br />

necessary, one could simply rely on existing regulatory powers. Existing statutes could be used<br />

to bolster safeguards against ethic<strong>all</strong>y questionable practices, obviating the need for new<br />

regulatory powers or new bureaucracies. For example, the FDA responded in a timely and<br />

effective manner to attempts to clone human beings: It simply declared cloned human embryos a<br />

“cellular product” subject to its statutory authority.<br />

The costs of a regulatory intervention are familiar. New statutes and regulations often have<br />

unanticipated and undesirable consequences; one consequence herein could be the moving<br />

abroad of both researchers and biotech companies seeking a more favorable regulatory climate.<br />

The United States remains the world leader in biomedical research, but adopting an extensive<br />

regulatory system could hobble its own competitive advantages, as well as deny patients access<br />

to the latest medical technologies. It is perhaps no accident that the first successful cloning of a<br />

human embryo, a procedure scientists believe is crucial to developing new cures for hitherto<br />

incurable diseases, has taken place in Korea and not in the United States. And it is no<br />

1<br />

David Adamson, "Regulation of Assisted Reproductive Technologies in the United States," Fertility and Sterility<br />

78, no. 5 (2002); Judith F. Daar, "Regulating Reproductive Technologies: Panacea or Paper Tiger?," Houston<br />

Law Review 34 (1997).<br />

229


coincidence that U.S. scientists identified the hostile political climate as one of the main reasons<br />

why this scientific breakthrough took place in Korea and not here.<br />

Cruci<strong>all</strong>y, regulatory costs include the opportunity costs of research outcomes and products<br />

that do not come into being or come into being at a slower pace as a result of regulation. In<br />

addition, regulatory intervention would reduce the range of available ART treatments and<br />

increase the costs of regulated ART services, as clinics would pass on to patients most if not <strong>all</strong><br />

their compliance costs. For example, banning reproductive cloning would make it impossible for<br />

couples unable to procreate using their own gametes to have genetic<strong>all</strong>y related children,<br />

arguably a matter of great significance for a great many people. 2 New regulations may also mean<br />

that treatments themselves would become more bureaucratic and more costly. Other costs<br />

include the direct cost to researchers and businesses of complying with new regulations, and the<br />

costs to the U.S. government of running a new regulatory agency.<br />

More gener<strong>all</strong>y, there are good reasons to protect the autonomy tradition<strong>all</strong>y enjoyed by<br />

science and medicine. The amazing scientific and technological advances witnessed over the last<br />

200 years would not have materialized had the scientific and technical community not been<br />

protected from major interferences by politics and the public. The prosperity of liberal<br />

democracies depends to a considerable extent on the ability of their economies to innovate. This<br />

ability could be compromised by unnecessary regulatory interventions.<br />

As for possible harms, advocates of the status quo reject “slippery slope” arguments – the<br />

view that the uncontrolled development of reproductive medicine and biomedical research is<br />

likely to produced undesired outcomes. This argument, in their view, is a weak foundation on<br />

which to ground public policy. Regulatory intervention is justified only when actual harm has<br />

been demonstrated. As long as “symbolic” harm is the only demonstrable harm, it is premature<br />

for the Congress to prohibit or regulate technologies that could serve a genuine public purpose. 3<br />

The widely publicized cloning experiment conducted by Korean scientists in early 2004<br />

deserves a separate discussion. It has become painfully obvious that the leading Korean scientist<br />

violated several widely accepted ethical standards and systematic<strong>all</strong>y forged scientific data. But<br />

it is also true that the peer review process was conducted in an unsatisfactory manner. What is<br />

needed in this case is a bolstering of existing safeguards, not the creation of new ones.<br />

Furthermore, the Korean experiment does not prove that we are on a slippery slope. The<br />

experiment merely has demonstrated that human embryos can indeed be cloned; it has not shown<br />

that the cloned embryos are free of the imprinting and epigenetic defects that have hampered<br />

efforts in animal husbandry. As long as safe and effective cloning techniques are not available, it<br />

is simply not possible to clone a human being, and therefore, no legislation is needed.<br />

As for attempts to clone a human being by “rogue” scientists – the Zavoses and Antinoris of<br />

the world – and by groups such as the Raelians, advocates of the status quo could point out that<br />

2<br />

3<br />

Robertson, "Two Models of Human Cloning."<br />

John A. Robertson, " 'Paying the Alligator': Precommitment in Law, Bioethics, and Constitutions," Texas Law<br />

Review 81 (2003).<br />

230


Neither Zavos and Antinori nor the Raelians have ever produced any evidence for their claims.<br />

By <strong>all</strong> accounts, these groups are not credible and can safely be ignored. It is certainly possible<br />

that at some point someone will succeed in cloning a human being or in performing a procedure<br />

regarded by the public as repugnant and objectionable. Until that time arrives, advocates of the<br />

status quo do not see a reason to intervene.<br />

Arguments Con<br />

As our discussion of the current regulatory system in chapter 5 has shown, it is very unlikely<br />

that the FDA, or any other federal agency for that matter, could rely exclusively on its current<br />

statutory powers to untangle future ethical dilemmas. 4 The FDA de facto ban on reproductive<br />

cloning, often quoted by advocates of the status quo as a demonstration that the federal<br />

government, if necessary, can prevent harm caused by new biomedical technologies, provides a<br />

clear illustration of these limits. The FDA simply asserted its authority over reproductive cloning<br />

on the basis of its powers to regulate cellular tissues. The agency explained that any attempt to<br />

create a human being through cloning techniques would require institutional review board<br />

approval and submission of an investigational new drug (IND) application. It went on to explain<br />

that it deemed reproductive cloning unsafe, and that applicants would be denied IND approval<br />

until these safety concerns had been addressed. 5 As some commentators have noted, until a court<br />

is c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to review the FDA rationale for asserting its jurisdiction over this procedure,<br />

reproductive cloning cannot leg<strong>all</strong>y be performed in the United States.<br />

The FDA’s haphazard response to attempts to clone a human being can hardly be regarded<br />

as a model of regulatory decision-making. As some legal scholars have noted, the FDA’s<br />

4<br />

5<br />

For an in-depth examination of this question, see President's Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and<br />

Responsibility: The Regulation of New Biotechnologies.<br />

The whole story is considerably more convoluted. Following the cloning of Dolly the sheep in 1997 in Britain,<br />

the U.S. news media reported that some U.S. scientists were contemplating offering cloning services to the<br />

general public. In response to these reports, the FDA, in a “Dear colleague” letter to <strong>all</strong> institutional review<br />

boards, simply asserted jurisdiction over reproductive cloning. The letter made clear that any attempt to create a<br />

human being through cloning techniques would require IRB approval and the submission of an IND application.<br />

The letter explained that the FDA deemed reproductive cloning unsafe, and that applicants would be denied IND<br />

approval until these safety concerns had been addressed. On March 28, 2001, Kathy Zoon, then-director of the<br />

FDA’s Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research (CBER), reiterated the FDA position on reproductive<br />

cloning, and addressed the jurisdictional question during a hearing before the Subcommittee on Oversight and<br />

Investigations of the House of Representatives. Zoon made clear that the FDA jurisdiction over reproductive<br />

cloning was based on its authority to regulate “cellular products.” See Center for Drug Evaluation and Research,<br />

"Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee Meeting."; Stuart L. Nightingale, Dear Colleague<br />

Letter (October 26, 1998 [cited September 18, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.fda.gov/oc/ohrt/irbs/irbletr.html; Opposition to Human Cloning Will 'Blow over,' Scientist Says<br />

(CNN, January 7, 1998 [cited September 18, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.cnn.com/TECH/9801/07/cloning.folo/; Kathryn C. Zoon, Statement before the Subcommittee on<br />

Oversight and Investigations Committee on Energy and Commerce United States House of Representatives<br />

(March 28, 2001 [cited September 18, 2005]); available from http://www.fda.gov/ola/2001/humancloning.html.<br />

231


assertion of jurisdiction in this case rests on weak legal grounds. 6 While human embryos do<br />

indeed consist of “cellular products,” we doubt that this legal argument would survive judicial<br />

scrutiny. In addition, health and safety concerns as the main rationale for regulatory interventions<br />

are of limited practical relevance. Not every new reproductive procedure is likely to raise safety<br />

concerns. MicroSort, which is designed to <strong>all</strong>ow parents to choose the sex of a baby, does not<br />

seem to raise major health and safety concerns, yet there are good reasons for regulating this new<br />

reproductive technology. And not every questionable new use of an existing reproductive<br />

treatment is unsafe. Tissue typing also seems quite safe, yet it remains a very controversial<br />

application of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis.<br />

Legal scholars might be able to show that in principle at least, the FDA statutory powers<br />

may reach beyond safety and efficacy, but the relevance of these legal constructions is bound to<br />

remain academic. Even assuming that by some obscure legal theory the FDA does have the<br />

power the adjudicate contentious ethical questions – i.e., to regulate the use of new reproductive<br />

technologies and biomedical research not exclusively in terms of safety and efficacy – it would<br />

be unsuitable for this task. Specialists in public administration have pointed out that agencies are<br />

often built around a traditional goal, and that when they are given new goals, they often have a<br />

hard time adapting. New goals often require a radical shift in an agency culture, a shift that is<br />

very unlikely to occur, tied as the agency is to dominant professional norms. 7 In the introductory<br />

chapter, we mentioned the case of the Interstate Commerce Commission being given the job of<br />

regulating trucking in addition to railroads, and how administrative law experts believe this to<br />

have been a big mistake. In chapter 2, we have shown how poorly prepared the FDA was to<br />

determine whether children of idiopathic short stature should be treated with synthetic human<br />

growth hormone, by some considered a case of an enhancing rather than a therapeutic treatment.<br />

The FDA’s ban on reproductive cloning could also be described as a usurpation of<br />

Congressional authority. The agency disguised what amounted to a political decision as a safety<br />

issue, thus depriving the Congress of its legislative prerogative on a matter of great import. In<br />

short, the FDA approach to banning reproductive cloning can be compared to saving the Apollo<br />

13 astronauts with a shoebox and duct tape – a workable but hardly generalizable approach. 8<br />

As for the criticism that regulatory interventions may cause opportunity costs in the form of<br />

slower scientific progress and forgone medical advances, this is certainly accurate, but it is an<br />

observation too generic to justify legislative restraint. Opportunity costs may or may not be too<br />

high, but there is simply no way to demonstrate that they would outweigh the benefits. While we<br />

accept the fact that regulation can indeed entail opportunity costs, we do not believe that in the<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

Richard A. Merrill, "FDA Regulation of Human Cloning: Usurpation or Statesmanship?," Harvard Journal of<br />

Law and Technology 15 (2001).<br />

James Q. Wilson, Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It (New York: Basic Books,<br />

1989), Ch.6 and p.107-09.<br />

The selective augmentation of statutory powers suffers from similar limitations. A limited expansion of the FDA,<br />

CDC, and NIH statutory authority, just to name a few likely candidates, would do nothing to change their<br />

regulatory culture or their core values, or to expand their expertise in addressing normative questions.<br />

232


present case there is any specific reason to be particularly concerned about forgone opportunities.<br />

To put it bluntly, we see no evidence that scientists’ hopes to develop new and revolutionary<br />

cures are more credible or reliable than predictions made by scientists with respect to other<br />

scientific developments.<br />

Consider, for example, gene therapy. In the early 1990s, the medical community was<br />

electrified by the prospect of developing a medical technology that would have made it possible<br />

to treat incurable diseases. The technology consists of inserting foreign genes into the DNA of<br />

diseased somatic cells in the hope that these genes would replace the diseased ones. Fifteen years<br />

later, it has become apparent that these hopes were unrealistic. To date, clinical researchers have<br />

conducted only a few trials; none of them has produced promising results, and in some cases,<br />

trials have ended with fatal consequences for the patients. 9<br />

In sum, while regulatory<br />

interventions, almost by definition, are likely to be associated with opportunity costs, absent<br />

specific evidence to the contrary, decision-makers should receive with a healthy dose of<br />

skepticism scientists’ predictions about likely medical breakthroughs. 10<br />

Opportunity costs must be weighed against known and unknown harms that regulatory<br />

interventions are designed to prevent. Just like opportunities, it is quite difficult to reliably<br />

predict the harmful consequences of any given scientific and medical development. How harm is<br />

defined is clearly an important question we cannot explore in great detail here. Suffice to say that<br />

“symbolic harm” is wholly inadequate category to convey the societal import of new biomedical<br />

technologies.<br />

Advocates of the status quo tend to forget that laissez-faire itself is bound to entail<br />

significant costs. The failure to anticipate the need for new regulatory powers often invites<br />

legislative and regulatory overreaction when the inevitable scandal, abuse, or disaster occurs.<br />

Many bureaucratic excesses since the end of World War II can aptly be described as a vicious<br />

cycle of protracted legislative inaction followed by a highly visible, catastrophic event and a<br />

period of short but intense legislative activity. 11 These interventions are usu<strong>all</strong>y quite effective in<br />

the sense that they do achieve their stated goals, but their costs rarely justify their benefits. These<br />

are draconian interventions that often produce as much harm as good.<br />

The Italian response to years of excesses in the ART industry precisely illustrates this point.<br />

Another example comes from agricultural biotechnology. During the early 1990s, the U.S.<br />

agricultural biotech industry, which had initi<strong>all</strong>y favored certain forms of regulation like the<br />

labeling of genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified foods, changed policy and argued that no new regulations were<br />

needed. After U.S. companies began marketing Bt corn and roundup-ready soybeans in Europe,<br />

the BSE (Bovine Spongiform Encephalopathy) scandal broke in the United Kingdom,<br />

convincing many European consumers that food safety regulators were not doing their job. Much<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

See http://www.ornl.gov/sci/techresources/Human_Genome/medicine/genetherapy.shtml#status.<br />

For a revealing discussion of failed scientific forecasts, see Victor S. Navasky and Christopher Cerf, The Experts<br />

Speak: The Definitive Compendium of Authoritative Misinformation (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984).<br />

Marc Eisner, Regulatory Policy in Transition (Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press, 1993).<br />

233


of the opposition to genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified organisms (GMOs) in Europe was irrational, but some<br />

was based on a view that consumers had a right to decide for themselves whether or not to eat<br />

genetic<strong>all</strong>y modified foods. By not supporting relatively modest forms of regulation like<br />

labeling, U.S. biotech firms found themselves shut out of European markets as the EU imposed<br />

its own strict safety rules on GMO products.<br />

9.2 Targeted Legislative Intervention<br />

Senate Bill 303, discussed in chapter 5.2.2, is a good example of a targeted legislative<br />

intervention. It is reactive, not anticipatory, and it is narrow in scope, addressing merely one of<br />

the many issues raised by new reproductive technologies and biomedical research. <strong>Final</strong>ly, it<br />

neither requires nor intends to delegate any legislative authority to a regulatory agency. 12 A ban<br />

on <strong>all</strong> kinds of cloning, as illustrated by Senate Bill 245, the Human Cloning Prohibition Act of<br />

2003, is another example of a targeted legislation intervention. H.R. 810, the most recent attempt<br />

by the Congress to address the stem cell controversy, is yet another example. It legalizes federal<br />

funding for donated, excess embryos, but says nothing about cloning or any other issue<br />

pertaining to reproductive medicine or biomedical research. It charges the NIH with developing<br />

appropriate guidelines, but does not delegate any real regulatory authority to this agency. When<br />

we discuss the pros and cons of targeted legislative interventions, we have regulatory<br />

interventions of this kind in mind.<br />

The reason we are focusing our discussion on targeted legislative interventions is quite<br />

simple: In the area of reproductive medicine and biomedical research this is the kind of<br />

legislative response the Congress is most likely to adopt. In the current political climate, only<br />

highly visible, persistent, and controversial issues such as stem cell research and cloning stand a<br />

chance to receive Congressional attention. These are also issues of considerable interest to<br />

influential interest groups – those groups that in the quest for Congressional re-election loom<br />

large, both in financial and electoral terms.<br />

Arguments Pro<br />

There are both conceptual and pragmatic reasons for favoring targeted legislative<br />

interventions. Advocates of targeted legislative interventions could argue that the reactive nature<br />

and narrow scope of these legislative interventions match perfectly the extent of current<br />

controversies over new reproductive technologies and medical research. They are an excellent<br />

example of legislative incrementalism designed to minimize the risks associated with grand<br />

legislative visions. Legislative incrementalism forces legislators to focus on well-defined<br />

political problems and to avoid legislating issues that have not yet risen to the top of the national<br />

political agenda. In this sense, targeted legislative interventions can be described as a<br />

12<br />

S. 303 delegates to IRBs the responsibility for approving research protocols involving the use of embryonic stem<br />

cells, but only with regard to procedural, not substantive matters.<br />

234


disciplining tool. Furthermore, by their very nature, targeted legislative interventions are costeffective;<br />

their implementation does not require the creation of costly new bureaucratic<br />

structures.<br />

One could also argue that targeted legislative interventions are in fact the only acceptable<br />

response to biomedical dilemmas. The Congress is the only political institution with both the<br />

legitimacy and the authority to settle national controversies. It is the Congress’ responsibility to<br />

provide ethical and legal guidance on issues such as stem cell research and cloning. Any<br />

delegation of legislative authority to an administrative entity in this view would amount to a<br />

violation of constitutional prerogatives.<br />

From a pragmatic point of view, one could point out that targeted legislative interventions<br />

stand a better chance of being passed by the Congress than grandiose legislative visions.<br />

Polarization tendencies in Congress further exacerbate the tendency to craft narrow legislation –<br />

bills designed to achieve precisely one goal and to do so exclusively by legislative means. 13<br />

Arguments Con<br />

The arguments in favor of legislative incrementalism are reasonable ones. One should be<br />

wary of excessively ambitious legislative projects. Experience has amply demonstrated that<br />

legislation often has unanticipated consequences that may exceed its benefits. Clearly, there is a<br />

place for incrementalism in any legislative system. The view that it is Congress’ responsibility to<br />

address ethical dilemmas of national import is also eminently sensible. We do not want unelected<br />

officials to resolve ethical dilemmas of national import. But not every ethical dilemma is equ<strong>all</strong>y<br />

important. As for other policy areas, there are many questions of implementation whose<br />

delegation to a regulatory authority is not only unproblematic but also necessary. Forcing the<br />

Congress to retain control over each and every implementation issue would produce an<br />

immediate legislative paralysis. Congress’ responsibility is to identify ethical dilemmas that need<br />

immediate legislative attention and delegate the resolution of the remaining ones to an<br />

administrative entity.<br />

The kind of targeted legislative interventions introduced in Congress over the last few years<br />

would have been unable to take into account the views and attitudes of the general public. As we<br />

have shown in chapter 8, mainstream Americans hold fairly nuanced views about biomedical<br />

technologies. They are against reproductive cloning, but they are unsure about research cloning.<br />

They do not want embryos to be created exclusively for research, but they find it acceptable to<br />

use excess embryos for this purpose. Taking these views and other distinctions documented in<br />

chapter 8 seriously would have required Congress to delegate at least some legislative authority<br />

to an administrative agency. In this context, one could also speak of legislative failure.<br />

13<br />

The logic responsible for catapulting highly visible and controversial reproductive treatments and research<br />

protocols into the political limelight is also the reason for Congressional disinterest in issues not widely<br />

perceived by the public as being of sufficient ethical import, and whose resolution would require from<br />

Congressional representatives a considerable investment of time and resources.<br />

235


More gener<strong>all</strong>y, it is shortsighted to address the ch<strong>all</strong>enges raised by the convergence of<br />

molecular biology, genetics, and reproductive medicine in a piecemeal fashion. Congress’<br />

responsibility, in our view, is not only to provide legislative guidance on the issue of the day, but<br />

also to reflect on whether it has the legislative and regulatory tools necessary to respond to<br />

present and future societal controversies.<br />

9.3 Self-Regulation<br />

Arguments Pro<br />

Representatives of the ART industry and scientific leaders have often argued that selfregulation<br />

is preferable to direct regulatory interventions. Self-regulation is certainly an<br />

important and often-overlooked element of many regulatory systems. It is neither a rare nor an<br />

uncommon or insignificant phenomenon. It has played and continues to play an important role in<br />

such disparate areas as fire safety, ocean transportation, cosmetics, electrical appliances, and<br />

nuclear power safety – and, as shown in chapter 5.3, in the ART industry as well. 14<br />

Advocates point out that self-regulation can address issues of public concern much more<br />

effectively, more rapidly, and at a fraction of the cost than a regulatory intervention would<br />

impose on the ART industry and on the scientific community. In this view, self-regulation is<br />

preferable to direct regulatory intervention for several reasons: Industry members have<br />

privileged access to crucial information not readily available to regulators, and industry members<br />

are in a better position to spot and correct violations. Federal regulators, by contrast, would be<br />

forced to implement a costly and often quite ineffective system of monitoring and compliance<br />

assurance.<br />

Contrary to common belief, self-regulatory systems do have specific mechanisms of<br />

compliance assurance. These are gener<strong>all</strong>y not formalized, and therefore are not visible to an<br />

external observer, but they can be quite effective nonetheless. The few empirical investigations<br />

available on this question seem to support this view. In one study of self-regulatory practices<br />

among lawyers in the New York metropolitan area, the author found that subtle but effective<br />

mechanisms of reciprocal monitoring create what he c<strong>all</strong>ed an “ethical climate.” 15<br />

Similar<br />

14<br />

15<br />

Furger, "Accountability and Self-Governance Systems: The Case of the Maritime Industry."; Jennifer Howard,<br />

Jennifer Nash, and John Ehrenfeld, "Standard or Smokescreen? Implementation of a Voluntary Environmental<br />

Code," California Management Review 42, no. 2 (2000); Andrew A. King and Michael J. Lenox, "Industry Self-<br />

Regulation without Sanctions: The Chemical Industry's Responsible Care Program," Academy of Management<br />

Journal 43, no. 4 (2000); Krislov, How Nations Choose Product Standards and Standards Change Nations;<br />

Rees, Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three Mile Island.<br />

Jerome E. Carlin, Lawyers on Their Own: A Study of Individual Practices (Rutgers University Press, New<br />

Jersey, 1962); Carlin, Lawyers' Ethics: A Survey of the New York City Bar. See also Hubert J. O'Gorman,<br />

Lawyers and Matrimonial Cases: A Case Study of Informal Pressures in Private Professional Practice (Glencoe,<br />

IL: Free Press, 1963).<br />

236


mechanisms of information monitoring and compliance assurance have been shown to exist<br />

among physicians at U.S. hospitals. 16<br />

As shown in chapter 5.3, the ART industry has developed an elaborate system of selfregulation<br />

over the years. Industry representatives have repeatedly pointed out that the<br />

professional and ethical standards developed by the American Society for Reproductive<br />

Medicine and other professional societies are more than adequate for the task at hand. The<br />

ASRM continues to monitor scientific developments in the field and to adopt specific<br />

recommendations as necessary. Scientific leaders, for their part, have advocated self-regulation<br />

as the best way to reassure an already wary public. How they intend to face controversial ethical<br />

questions has been described in a recent publication by the National Academy of Sciences. 17<br />

<strong>Final</strong>ly, advocates of self-regulation submit that reproductive decisions and research<br />

priorities are essenti<strong>all</strong>y private choices the government has no business regulating. In this view,<br />

prospective parents and their doctors are in an excellent position to determine what is in the best<br />

interest of the children. As for biomedical research, the argument here is simply that setting<br />

research priorities is best left to members of the scientific community. The public, ever ignorant<br />

and driven by emotional responses rather than by rational analysis, is simply not in a position to<br />

assess the rationale for viewing certain research questions as worth pursuing. Nor are politicians,<br />

for that matter.<br />

Arguments Con<br />

A measure of self-regulation is a necessary requirement of any effective and efficient<br />

regulatory system. Federal regulators, indeed <strong>all</strong> regulators, depend to some degree on the<br />

regulated community for critical knowledge and information. In some cases, monitoring and<br />

compliance assurance rely heavily on private third parties. Our discussion of the Fertility Clinic<br />

Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992 in chapter 5.1.1 makes this point. The active<br />

participation of the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology in gathering the data needed<br />

by the CDC on ART success rates contributes to generating better data at a lower cost.<br />

That self-regulation is an important ingredient of any regulatory system does not<br />

demonstrate that self-regulation, by itself, may be considered a substitute for more formal<br />

regulatory approaches. Self-regulation is a complement rather than a substitute for formal<br />

regulation. For example, in the 1990s, the National Paint and Coating Association established<br />

Coatings Care, 18 an ambitious program of environmental management. By <strong>all</strong> accounts, Coatings<br />

Care has been instrumental in improving the industry’s public image and its relationship to the<br />

EPA, and in reducing the likelihood of catastrophic accidents. The National Association of<br />

Chemical Distributors had a very similar experience with its “Responsible Distribution<br />

16<br />

17<br />

18<br />

Eliot Freidson, Profession of Medicine. A Study of the Sociology of Applied Knowledge (New York: Harper &<br />

Row, 1970), p.137-57.<br />

Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem<br />

Cell Research (Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press, 2005).<br />

See http://www.paint.org/cc/index.cfm.<br />

237


Process.” 19 According to their initiators, these programs are designed to strengthen the regulatory<br />

system, not to replace it.<br />

Contrary to industry claims, trade associations can rarely be considered impartial arbiters of<br />

societal disputes. The ART industry approach to resolving public controversies has little<br />

credibility not because it has avoided addressing these issues, but because its guidelines and<br />

recommendations tend to reflect the interests of the industry and its clients (in this case, the<br />

prospective parents) to the detriment of children and the general public. In other cases,<br />

recommendations are just that – hortatory statements of little practical significance. For example,<br />

ASRM recommends transferring no more than three embryos. ASRM also discourages the use of<br />

pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for elective sex selection. This language suggests that ART<br />

practitioners are not re<strong>all</strong>y expected to follow these recommendations if prospective parents wish<br />

otherwise.<br />

As for compliance efforts, the balance of the evidence is not encouraging. As part of its<br />

certification program, the ASRM mandates periodic audits, but violations are met with<br />

considerable leniency, as laboratories are given up to one year to correct a violation. More<br />

importantly, compliance with ethical guidelines is not part of the mandatory certification and<br />

audit program. ASRM simply does not know whether and to what extent its ethical<br />

recommendations are being followed. Industry officials believe that ethical and professional<br />

guidelines have a strong normative power. Absent any systematic assessment of compliance<br />

rates, this conviction is of little relevance.<br />

A final reason for being skeptical about the role of self-regulatory efforts in the ART<br />

industry is the absence of robust mechanisms of reciprocal learning. Twenty-five years after the<br />

first “test-tube” baby was born, this field of medicine has barely begun to take seriously the<br />

possibility that ART treatments may indeed be associated with higher health and safety risks.<br />

Often, reproductive practitioners simply believe that ART techniques are safe. Since the industry<br />

“doesn’t know what it doesn’t know,” it is unable to identify possible areas of concern and to<br />

learn from its mistakes. Considerations of cost may prevent the ART industry from<br />

implementing expensive long-term follow-up studies, but cost considerations cannot dispel the<br />

impression, occasion<strong>all</strong>y expressed by pediatricians, that the ART industry is focused<br />

exclusively on producing pregnancies, with little consideration for health consequences.<br />

9.4 Regulatory Responses<br />

Arguments Con<br />

There are several objections to a regulatory approach, of both a general and a specific<br />

nature. The general objections are well-known. Over the last 30 years, public administration<br />

researchers, economists, political scientists, and administrative law scholars have documented in<br />

excruciating detail the distortions, aberrations, hidden costs, and negative unanticipated<br />

19<br />

See http://www.nacd.com/rdp/.<br />

238


consequences brought about by ill-informed regulatory interventions. Health, safety, and<br />

environmental regulations are often singled out for achieving policy goals at exorbitant costs, or<br />

for failing to achieve their self-imposed targets. The AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory<br />

Studies has produced a long series of case studies documenting these distortions. 20<br />

Economists have also demonstrated that regulation in many cases seems to be designed to<br />

benefit or protect the competitive position of incumbent firms to the detriment of other<br />

competitors rather than to serve the public interest. Much of the literature on regulatory capture<br />

is informed by this basic observation. 21 For example, complex regulatory requirements tend to<br />

favor large companies with extensive technical and legal expertise, and with considerable<br />

financial resources, to the disadvantage of sm<strong>all</strong>er but nimbler competitors whose<br />

competitiveness is threatened by these regulations. 22<br />

One also could argue that the delegation of legislative authority to a regulatory agency is an<br />

administrative expedient with questionable constitutional legitimacy, and should be envisaged<br />

only in the most unproblematic of circumstances. For example, delegating the responsibility for<br />

implementing the Congressional prerogative to tax U.S. citizens to a specialized agency is<br />

largely unproblematic. The agency in question is simply carrying out a Congressional mandate; it<br />

lacks the authority to pass new tax laws. It is an altogether different matter to charge a federal<br />

bureaucracy with adjudicating deeply divisive, fundamental questions of life and death. In this<br />

case, delegating legislative authority to an unaccountable federal bureaucracy is unacceptable.<br />

Only the Congress has the constitutional mandate to provide legal guidance on questions of<br />

national import.<br />

One may also wonder why reproductive medicine is being singled out while other medical<br />

specialties have not received nearly as much attention. The field of reproductive medicine is just<br />

20<br />

21<br />

22<br />

A non-representative selection of these studies includes Jason K. Burnett and Robert W. Hahn, "A Costly<br />

Benefit: Economic Analysis Does Not Support EPA's New Arsenic Rule," Regulation 24, no. 3 (F<strong>all</strong> 2001);<br />

Robert W. Hahn and Jason K. Burnett, "The Epa’s Radon Rule: A Case Study in How Not to Regulate Risks,"<br />

(Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory Studies, 2001); Andrew N. Kleit, "Impacts of<br />

Long-Range Increases in the Corporate Average Fuel Economy (Cafe) Standard " (Washington, D.C.: AEI-<br />

Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory Studies, 2002); W. Kip Viscusi and James T. Hamilton, "Are Risk<br />

Regulator Rational? Evidence from Hazardous Waste Cleanup Decisions," (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings<br />

Joint Center for Regulatory Studies, 1999).<br />

Garry Becker, "A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence," Quarterly Journal of<br />

Economics 98, no. 3 (1983); Sam Peltzman, "The Economic Theory of Regulation after a Decade of<br />

Deregulation," Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. Microeconomics 1989 (1989); Sam Peltzman, "Towards<br />

a More General Theory of Regulation," Journal of Law and Economics 19 (1976); Richard A. Posner, "Taxation<br />

by Regulation," Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 2, no. 1 (1971); Richard A. Posner,<br />

"Theories of Economic Regulation," Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 5, no. 2 (1974);<br />

George J. Stigler, "Free Riders and Collective Action: An Appendix to Theories of Economic Regulation," Bell<br />

Journal of Economics and Management Science 5, no. 2 (1974); George J. Stigler, "The Theory of Economic<br />

Regulation," Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 2 (1971). An overview can be found in Robert<br />

D. Tollison and Roger D. Congleton, eds., The Economic Analysis of Rent Seeking (Hants, UK: Aldershot,<br />

1995).<br />

Note that this is not a phenomenon limited to formal regulation, however. The complexity of some systems of<br />

self-regulation can be ascribed to the same phenomenon.<br />

239


another branch of medicine. ART practitioners simply rely on a specialized body of medical<br />

knowledge to restore reproductive functions, functions necessary to fulfill a deep desire by<br />

infertile couples to have a biological offspring. Other areas of medicine are also unregulated and<br />

pose significant health and safety risks, yet they are only subject to professional oversight. For<br />

example, laser-based eye surgery is now widely practiced, yet the FDA does not regulate this<br />

activity, a surgical procedure beyond its statutory authority. 23 Nor is there a system in place to<br />

monitor the long-term consequences of this relatively new approach to eyesight correction.<br />

Arguments Pro<br />

The critique that the modern administrative state may be on shaky constitutional grounds<br />

may or may not be accurate, but this is largely a platonic question. For better or worse, the<br />

administrative state is here to stay. The contemporary United States simply could not function<br />

without regulatory agencies. The Congress itself could not fulfill its constitutional mandate<br />

without the support of the regulatory machinery. Nor is the regulatory apparatus unaccountable.<br />

Some agencies are more accountable than others, but it would be misleading to assume that<br />

unelected federal officials are accountable to no one. As we show in <strong>chapters</strong> 11 and 12, several<br />

options exist to hold a regulatory agency accountable for its action, including Congressional<br />

oversight, Presidential appointing and removal powers, and judicial review, among others.<br />

We readily acknowledge that regulation may at times be problematic. To recognize that<br />

regulation can be costly, inefficient, and ineffective is, however, no demonstration that it is<br />

unnecessary. Determining the costs and benefits of a new regulation is important, but is by no<br />

means the only consideration governing whether a proposed new rule is necessary or desirable.<br />

Economic efficiency has never been the only principle guiding the administrative state.<br />

Economists are correct to characterize the maximization of economic efficiency as a social good<br />

that should inform any rule-making process. Just as correct are political scientists and ethicists<br />

when they note that economic efficiency is not the only possible social good. An agency could<br />

determine that a proposed new rule would produce more (economic) costs than benefits and still<br />

decide to move forward with the new rule. Conversely, a regulatory agency may decide that a net<br />

benefit to society is an insufficient foundation for proposing new regulations. 24 The Nuremberg<br />

Code provides an illustration. At least since the Nuremberg process, from which the Code<br />

derives its name, the medical community has accepted the principle that an individual cannot be<br />

23<br />

The FDA does, of course, regulate the safety and efficacy of laser systems. It also provides an online information<br />

resource for prospective patients. See http://www.fda.gov/cdrh/LASIK/default.htm.<br />

24<br />

A large literature exists on this topic. For an introduction, see, for example, Matthew D. Adler and Eric A.<br />

Posner, "Rethinking Cost-Benefit Analysis," Yale Law Journal 109 (1999); Henry S. Richardson, "The Stupidity<br />

of the Cost-Benefit Standard," Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000); Amartya Sen, "The Discipline of Cost-<br />

Benefit Analysis," Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000).<br />

240


harmed for the greater good of the community. Yet cost-benefit considerations would show that<br />

on balance, experiments on individual patients produce more benefits than costs. 25<br />

We also do not dispute the well-documented empirical observation that the regulatory<br />

process may be distorted by undue political influence, and may produce outcomes that<br />

systematic<strong>all</strong>y benefit a certain societal group to the detriment of the broader public interest.<br />

Indeed, much of the discussion in <strong>chapters</strong> 8 and 5.2 shows just that. Yet this is clearly not an<br />

argument against regulation per se, as the demonstration that administrative checks and balances<br />

above and beyond the minimal requirements of the Administrative Procedure Act may be<br />

necessary. The last part of this report is devoted precisely to this question – i.e., to how undue<br />

political influence can be minimized at the regulatory level.<br />

There are also positive arguments for a regulatory approach to the resolution of normative<br />

controversies. Political and economic rationality dictates that Congressional representatives will<br />

address only the most visible and divisive political issues. Legislators do not have the time or the<br />

expertise to familiarize themselves with the scientific and ethical aspects of each and every<br />

controversy that new reproductive treatments and biomedical research are likely to produce in<br />

the future. Political logic suggests that members of Congress will prioritize their efforts, at least<br />

in part, according to electoral payoffs. Obscure technical controversies are very unlikely to<br />

produce significant benefits. 26 Absent a suitable regulatory authority, these issues are likely to<br />

remain unresolved – or to be resolved either by the market or by organized interest groups.<br />

It is also not accurate to claim that reproductive medicine is just another medical specialty.<br />

To be sure, ART specialists are in the business of curing physiological afflictions. But unlike any<br />

other medical discipline, reproductive medicine liter<strong>all</strong>y makes children. The ART field is<br />

structured around the needs and desires of prospective parents; it is less well-organized to protect<br />

the long-term interests of the children it produces. Medical practitioners argue that parents<br />

always have the best interest of their children at heart. This is undoubtedly true for the vast<br />

majority of parents. On the other hand, there are good reasons to believe that the interests of<br />

parents and their children could and occasion<strong>all</strong>y do diverge. The discussion in chapter 4<br />

provided many illustrations of possible conflicts of interest between different generations.<br />

Reproductive medicine also differs from other branches of medicine in that it can affect in a<br />

subtle but important way societal values central to our understanding of equality and of political<br />

rights. These unintended consequences have little to do with reproductive medicine, per se. They<br />

have everything to do with contemporary notions of equality and tolerance – the very values on<br />

which our democratic society is grounded. Consequences of this kind may or may not be of<br />

broader import, but this determination needs to be made by the public and its political<br />

representatives, and should not be left to the medical profession and their patients.<br />

25<br />

26<br />

This is assuming, of course, that one could solve the frustrating problems created by the comparison of<br />

interpersonal utilities.<br />

David Epstein, "Administrative Procedures, Information, and Agency Discretion," American Journal of Political<br />

Science 38, no. 3 (1994).<br />

241


242


9.5 Bibliography<br />

Adamson, David. "Regulation of Assisted Reproductive Technologies in the United States."<br />

Fertility and Sterility 78, no. 5 (2002): 932-42.<br />

Adler, Matthew D., and Eric A. Posner. "Rethinking Cost-Benefit Analysis." Yale Law Journal<br />

109 (1999): 165-247.<br />

Becker, Garry. "A Theory of Competition among Pressure Groups for Political Influence."<br />

Quarterly Journal of Economics 98, no. 3 (1983): 371-99.<br />

Burnett, Jason K., and Robert W. Hahn. "A Costly Benefit: Economic Analysis Does Not<br />

Support EPA's New Arsenic Rule." Regulation 24, no. 3 (F<strong>all</strong> 2001): 44-49.<br />

Carlin, Jerome E. Lawyers on Their Own: A Study of Individual Practices: Rutgers University<br />

Press, New Jersey, 1962.<br />

———. Lawyers' Ethics: A Survey of the New York City Bar. New York: Sage, 1966.<br />

Center for Drug Evaluation and Research, Food and Drug Administration. "Endocrinologic and<br />

Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee Meeting." edited by Food and Drug<br />

Administration Department of Health and Human Services, October 7, 2003.<br />

Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research. Guidelines for Human<br />

Embryonic Stem Cell Research. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press, 2005.<br />

Daar, Judith F. . "Regulating Reproductive Technologies: Panacea or Paper Tiger?" Houston<br />

Law Review 34 (1997): 609-64.<br />

Eisner, Marc. Regulatory Policy in Transition. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press,<br />

1993.<br />

Epstein, David. "Administrative Procedures, Information, and Agency Discretion." American<br />

Journal of Political Science 38, no. 3 (1994): 697-722.<br />

Freidson, Eliot. Profession of Medicine. A Study of the Sociology of Applied Knowledge. New<br />

York: Harper & Row, 1970.<br />

Furger, Franco L. "Accountability and Self-Governance Systems: The Case of the Maritime<br />

Industry." Law & Policy 19, no. 4 (1997): 445-76.<br />

Hahn, Robert W., and Jason K. Burnett. "The Epa’s Radon Rule: A Case Study in How Not to<br />

Regulate Risks." Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory Studies,<br />

2001.<br />

Howard, Jennifer, Jennifer Nash, and John Ehrenfeld. "Standard or Smokescreen?<br />

Implementation of a Voluntary Environmental Code." California Management Review<br />

42, no. 2 (2000): 63-82.<br />

King, Andrew A., and Michael J. Lenox. "Industry Self-Regulation without Sanctions: The<br />

Chemical Industry's Responsible Care Program." Academy of Management Journal 43,<br />

no. 4 (2000): 698-716.<br />

Kleit, Andrew N. "Impacts of Long-Range Increases in the Corporate Average Fuel Economy<br />

(Cafe) Standard ". Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Regulatory<br />

Studies, 2002.<br />

Krislov, Samuel. How Nations Choose Product Standards and Standards Change Nations.<br />

Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1997.<br />

Merrill, Richard A. "FDA Regulation of Human Cloning: Usurpation or Statesmanship?"<br />

Harvard Journal of Law and Technology 15 (2001): 85-148.<br />

243


Navasky, Victor S., and Christopher Cerf. The Experts Speak: The Definitive Compendium of<br />

Authoritative Misinformation. New York: Pantheon Books, 1984.<br />

Nightingale, Stuart L. Dear Colleague Letter October 26, 1998 [cited September 18, 2005].<br />

Available from http://www.fda.gov/oc/ohrt/irbs/irbletr.html.<br />

O'Gorman, Hubert J. Lawyers and Matrimonial Cases: A Case Study of Informal Pressures in<br />

Private Professional Practice. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1963.<br />

Opposition to Human Cloning Will 'Blow over,' Scientist Says CNN, January 7, 1998 [cited<br />

September 18, 2005]. Available from http://www.cnn.com/TECH/9801/07/cloning.folo/.<br />

Peltzman, Sam. "The Economic Theory of Regulation after a Decade of Deregulation."<br />

Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. Microeconomics 1989 (1989): 1-41.<br />

———. "Towards a More General Theory of Regulation." Journal of Law and Economics 19<br />

(1976): 211-40.<br />

Posner, Richard A. "Taxation by Regulation." Bell Journal of Economics and Management<br />

Science 2, no. 1 (1971): 22-50.<br />

———. "Theories of Economic Regulation." Bell Journal of Economics and Management<br />

Science 5, no. 2 (1974): 335-58.<br />

President's Council on Bioethics. Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New<br />

Biotechnologies. Washington, D.C., 2004.<br />

Rees, Joseph V. Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three<br />

Mile Island. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.<br />

Richardson, Henry S. "The Stupidity of the Cost-Benefit Standard." Journal of Legal Studies 29<br />

(2000): 971-1003.<br />

Robertson, John A. " 'Paying the Alligator': Precommitment in Law, Bioethics, and<br />

Constitutions." Texas Law Review 81 (2003): 1729-49.<br />

———. "Two Models of Human Cloning." Hofstra Law Review 27 (1999): 609-38.<br />

Sen, Amartya. "The Discipline of Cost-Benefit Analysis." Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2000):<br />

931-52.<br />

Stigler, George J. "Free Riders and Collective Action: An Appendix to Theories of Economic<br />

Regulation." Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 5, no. 2 (1974): 359-<br />

65.<br />

———. "The Theory of Economic Regulation." Bell Journal of Economics and Management<br />

Science 2 (1971).<br />

Tollison, Robert D., and Roger D. Congleton, eds. The Economic Analysis of Rent Seeking.<br />

Hants, UK: Aldershot, 1995.<br />

Viscusi, W. Kip, and James T. Hamilton. "Are Risk Regulator Rational? Evidence from<br />

Hazardous Waste Cleanup Decisions." Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint Center<br />

for Regulatory Studies, 1999.<br />

Wilson, James Q. Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It. New York:<br />

Basic Books, 1989.<br />

Zoon, Kathryn C. Statement before the Subcommittee on Oversight and Investigations<br />

Committee on Energy and Commerce United States House of Representatives March 28,<br />

2001 [cited September 18, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.fda.gov/ola/2001/humancloning.html.<br />

244


10 Correcting Political and Regulatory Distortions<br />

10.1 Reproductive Technologies: A case of political failure<br />

In chapter 8, we suggested that the views held by the general public on several controversial<br />

issues are at odds with the positions advocated by influential interest groups and Congressional<br />

representatives. In this chapter, we explore in some detail possible reasons for this misalignment.<br />

We argue that a sustained misalignment is a clear indication of “political failure,” a concept<br />

central to the theory of public choice. Before examining the empirical evidence in support of our<br />

claim, we briefly introduce this economic theory and discuss political failure in general terms. In<br />

the final part of this chapter, we suggest possible remedies.<br />

The term “political failure” was introduced in the early 1960s by political economists to<br />

offset the then-popular concept of market failure. 1 Public choice scholars, as they came to be<br />

known, pointed out that government interventions to correct market failures tend to make things<br />

worse, either because the costs to society are bigger than the expected benefits, or because the<br />

intervention winds up benefiting those who do not need the help of the government, or else<br />

because the government intervention is designed to benefit specific population groups to the<br />

detriment of broader societal interests. Central to the economic analysis of politics is the<br />

assumption that political actors such as Congressional representatives, administrators, lobbyists,<br />

and activists pursue their own self-interest. This view was and remains in stark contrast to the<br />

notion that political action reflects a commitment to the common good.<br />

Self-interested motives should not be narrowly construed. They may range from pursuing reelection<br />

to accumulating power and prestige to charting a professional career and increasing<br />

one’s status. Whatever form of self-interest is contemplated, the theory of public choice<br />

identifies in self-interest the ultimate motivation for a political actor’s preferred course of action.<br />

For example, Congressional representatives are mainly interested in accumulating power and<br />

influence and ensuring their re-election, and only secondarily in getting richer. Money, of course,<br />

is crucial in modern politics, but as a means to an end (for example, to get re-elected), not as an<br />

end in itself. Interest groups, for their part, gravitate toward Congress and federal bureaucracies<br />

1<br />

In its most general form, this approach is gener<strong>all</strong>y identified with the 1962 publication of James M. Buchanan<br />

and Gordon Tullock, The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy (Ann Arbor:<br />

University of Michigan Press, 1962). For a non-technical introduction in this field, see James M. Buchanan,<br />

"Public Choice: Politics without Romance," Policy 19, no. 3 (2003). A comprehensive discussion can be found<br />

in Daniel A. Farber and Philip P. Frickey, "The Jurisprudence of Public Choice," Texas Law Review 65 (1987);<br />

Dennis Mueller, Public Choice Iii (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003). For a critical<br />

examination, see Daniel A. Farber, "Democracy and Disgust: Reflections on Public Choice," Chicago-Kent Law<br />

Review 65 (1989); Jerry L. Mashaw, "The Economics of Politics and the Understanding of Public Law,"<br />

Chicago-Kent Law Review 65 (1989).<br />

245


to extract benefits for their members or to prevent or mitigate costly laws and regulations. Even<br />

positions advocated by public interest groups can be explained by selfish motives.<br />

Perhaps surprisingly, such a simplistic and cynical view of modern politics has considerable<br />

explanatory power. 2 A central finding emerging from this body of literature is that organized<br />

interest groups tend to have an influence over legislatures and regulatory agencies<br />

disproportionate to their actual political weight. Undue influence often translates into laws, rules,<br />

and regulations that directly benefit these interest groups at the expense of broader societal<br />

interests. Their influence reflects their financial support for election campaigns and their ability<br />

to deliver important blocks of votes. To some extent, they also provide Congressional<br />

representatives with valuable technical information. Administrators obviously do not depend on<br />

generous campaign contributions to do their job, but their dependency on key political<br />

constituencies is real nonetheless. Complex regulations often can only be implemented with the<br />

help and cooperation of the groups directly affected by them. Regulators may depend on<br />

obtaining technical and scientific information that is available exclusively to the regulated<br />

communities. Good professional relationships with these groups are essential to administrators<br />

operating in a charged political environment.<br />

The general public does have a role to play in this scenario, but only as a political pawn.<br />

Public choice assumes that it is rational for the public to be uninterested. Modern policy<br />

decisions are complex; for an average citizen, the costs of forming his or her opinion far<br />

outweigh the benefits. As a practical matter, it is much easier and convenient to orient one’s<br />

opinion to the recommendations expressed by the interest group or political party of choice, or<br />

simply yield to the bombardment of political messages. At the regulatory level, the public is<br />

gener<strong>all</strong>y not heard, simply because many regulations are simply too obscure and complex to be<br />

of any real interest to a broader audience. In the few instances where members of the general<br />

public submit a large number of comments to a proposed new rule, this is gener<strong>all</strong>y the result of<br />

mobilization efforts by an organized interest group rather than an expression of spontaneous<br />

political interest.<br />

From a public choice perspective, this depressing view of modern politics is no reason for<br />

pessimism. Policy-making can be described as a competitive process, as a market for political<br />

influence. And competitive markets are known for their benign effects. The operative term here<br />

2<br />

There has been a great deal of empirical analysis informed by this analytical perspective. Examples include<br />

government protection of the dairy industry to the detriment of margarine producers: Geoffrey P. Miller, "Public<br />

Choice at the Dawn of the Special Interest State: The Story of Butter and Margarine," California Law Review 77<br />

(1989). Chronic<strong>all</strong>y inadequate health standards in the meat and poultry industry: Dion Casey, "Agency Capture:<br />

The USDA's Struggle to Pass Food Safety Regulations," Kansas Journal of Law & Public Policy 7 (1998). The<br />

persistent importance of agricultural subsidies in the European Union: Matthew Elliott and Allister Heath, "The<br />

Failure of CAP Reform: A Public Choice Analysis," Economic Affairs 20, no. 2 (2000). The popularity of a<br />

losing financial proposition such as the public financing of sport stadiums: Veronica Z. Kalich, "A Public Choice<br />

Perspective on the Subsidization of Private Industry: A Case Study of Three Cities and Three Stadiums," Journal<br />

of Urban Affairs 20, no. 2 (1998). The capture of social housing programs in the UK by their beneficiaries:<br />

David Mullins, "From Regulatory Capture to Regulated Competition: An Interest Group Analysis of Housing<br />

Associations in England," Housing Studies 12, no. 3 (1997).<br />

246


is competitive – as long as the market for power and influence is competitive, there is no reason<br />

for concern. Consistent with this market metaphor, politicians trade political influence for<br />

economic and other resources. Conversely, political constituencies gain power and influence by<br />

providing politicians with the resources – financial and otherwise – needed for their re-election.<br />

The final outcome of this complex trading process is a supposedly optimal distribution of power<br />

and influence.<br />

Political markets can be assumed to be efficient only if the political “trading” process is<br />

governed by a few basic rules. A key requirement is that <strong>all</strong> interest groups are adequately<br />

represented in the political arena. To the extent that the ensemble of <strong>all</strong> views represented by<br />

interest groups is a sufficiently accurate representation of the views held by society as a whole,<br />

one could argue that it is immaterial whether the general public has had an opportunity to<br />

participate in the policy-making process. If <strong>all</strong> existing views have had a fair opportunity to be<br />

heard, the market for political influence is likely to produce an efficient outcome of sort.<br />

Conversely, a policy-making process characterized by limited political participation is a clear<br />

indication of political failure and is likely to produce a distorted outcome.<br />

Are reproductive medicine and biomedical research two policy domains characterized by<br />

significant political failures? We believe this question must be answered in the affirmative, but<br />

not in the ordinary sense. With regard to cloning and stem cell research, it appears that no key<br />

political constituency has been unable to participate or has not been heard, and there is no reason<br />

to believe that in the future any of these groups is likely be excluded from the political arena. In<br />

this sense, one cannot speak of political failure. On the other hand, these groups are clearly not<br />

representative of broader public sentiments and certainly cannot be considered a good proxy of<br />

the views expressed by the general public.<br />

There are only two main political camps in this policy domain, and <strong>all</strong> interest groups<br />

involved can unambiguously be assigned to one or the other of these camps. At the one end of<br />

the spectrum, we find scientific societies such as the American Association for the Advancement<br />

of Science, the Coalition for the Advancement of Medical Research (CAMR), the Federation of<br />

American Societies for Experimental Biology, and their <strong>all</strong>ies – mainly single-issue advocacy<br />

and patient groups like the Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation, the Parkinson’s Action<br />

Network, and Cures Now. Also in this camp we find the ART industry, represented mainly by<br />

the American Society for Reproductive Medicine and the Society for Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technology. On the other side of the political divide is an uncomfortable coalition of religious<br />

organizations, such as the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops and the Southern<br />

Baptist Convention, soci<strong>all</strong>y conservative groups like the Family Research Council, and liberal<br />

environmental groups.<br />

AAAS, the premiere U.S. scientific organization, has advocated the ban on reproductive<br />

cloning, but supports research cloning and embryonic stem cell research. AAAS favors a limited<br />

form of “federal oversight” for this kind of research, but it is unclear what this position actu<strong>all</strong>y<br />

247


entails. 3 CAMR, a very large and heterogeneous umbrella organization consisting of <strong>all</strong> major<br />

scientific societies, professional groups, and major research universities, has advocated a similar<br />

policy. 4 CAMR is more vocal in its support of biomedical research than AAAS. In 2004, it<br />

explicitly rejected any suggestion that regulatory interventions may be necessary. 5 Since then<br />

however CAMR has stopped offering specific position statements in favor of member-specific<br />

position statements. 6 FASEB, another umbrella group comprising 22 scientific societies, is also<br />

supportive of banning reproductive cloning, but supports research cloning and embryonic stem<br />

cell research subject to “strict ethical oversight.” 7 What “strict ethical oversight” means and who<br />

should promulgate these norms is unclear. At best, this statement suggests the possibility of<br />

establishing a weak form of self-regulation; at worst, it is simply an abstract recognition of the<br />

need to provide ethical guidance. Other scientific organizations, such as the Council of Scientific<br />

Societies Presidents, have expressed very similar views. In sum, leading science advocacy<br />

groups agree that reproductive cloning should be banned, but they show no or very limited<br />

support for any other form of governmental or regulatory intervention. Interest groups<br />

representing the reproductive industry, such as ASRM, RESOLVE, and the American Fertility<br />

Association have taken a similar stance, condemning reproductive cloning but voc<strong>all</strong>y rejecting<br />

any suggestion that regulatory interventions in this area of medicine may be needed.<br />

As for the organized opposition to new reproductive and biomedical research, there is<br />

considerable agreement among these groups on the need to prevent any kind of research or<br />

manipulation of human embryos that would produce their destruction. From these groups’<br />

perspective, there simply is not any justification for destroying what has been c<strong>all</strong>ed nascent<br />

human life. For example, the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops has repeatedly stated<br />

its resolute opposition to any kind of cloning and embryonic stem cell research, 8 c<strong>all</strong>ing research<br />

cloning “a sign of moral regress” and stem cell research “not […] a wise investment.” The<br />

Family Research Council also opposes any kind of research that would destroy human embryos. 9<br />

On its Web site, under “Position Statements,” the Southern Baptist Convention, for its part,<br />

summarily notes, “Procreation is a gift from God, a precious trust reserved for marriage. At the<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

9<br />

The AAAS position on human cloning is available at http://www.aaas.org/news/releases/2002/Cloning.shtml.<br />

AAAS explored various policy options at a recent workshop of research cloning. A summary can be downloaded<br />

at http://www.aaas.org/news/releases/2003/0403cloning.shtml.<br />

A complete list of <strong>all</strong> CAMR members is available at http://www.camradvocacy.org/members.aspx.<br />

The original links to these statements have been removed from the CAMR web site.<br />

See http://www.camradvocacy.org/statements.aspx.<br />

Carrie Golash, FASEB Statement on Human Somatic Cell Nuclear Transplantation (SCNT) and Embryonic Stem<br />

Cells (FASEB, February 12, 2004 [cited May 3, 2006]); available from<br />

http://opa.faseb.org/pdf/nr_2x12x4_stem.pdf.<br />

On research cloning, see, for example, http://www.usccb.org/comm/archives/2004/04-187.htm. The most recent<br />

statement on stem cell research is available at http://www.usccb.org/comm/archives/2004/04-025.htm.<br />

The Family Research Council has posted several detailed statements on this issue. See for example John C.<br />

Harvey, Distinctly Human: The When, Where and How of Life's Beginnings (Family Research Council, April 25,<br />

2002 [cited May 3, 2006]); available from http://www.frc.org/get.cfm?i=IS02D3.<br />

248


moment of conception, a new being enters the universe, a human being, a being created in God's<br />

image. This human being deserves our protection, whatever the circumstances of conception.” 10<br />

Against this background, it comes as no surprise that these groups dismiss the possibility of<br />

donating excess embryos to research, or the suggestion that there may be legitimate uses of preimplantation<br />

genetic diagnosis.<br />

These extremely polarized positions do not reflect the more nuanced sentiments expressed in<br />

survey after survey by the general public. Our discussion in chapter 8 has shown that Americans<br />

are far less polarized than the advocacy groups and their Congressional representatives. These<br />

groups either completely reject or wholly approve research cloning while the general public<br />

remains ambivalent. In the case of stem cell research, the chasm between organized interest<br />

groups and the general public is more apparent. While the public is favorable by significant<br />

margins to the federal funding of stem cell research if suitable regulatory safeguards are put in<br />

place, the president has refused to update his restrictive policy, in large measure because of the<br />

influence exercised by religious groups on Congress and the executive. The chasm between the<br />

general public and advocacy groups is particularly striking among religious voters. Catholics<br />

clearly disagree with the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops on stem cell research<br />

policy. Even conservative, white Evangelicals display ambivalence rather than downright<br />

rejection on this matter, in clear opposition to the positions taken by the Southern Baptist<br />

Convention and the Family Research Council.<br />

Gauging whether the scientists’ views on these matters are in line with scientific societies’<br />

positions is a bit of a ch<strong>all</strong>enge. Unlike the general public, scientists have rarely been surveyed.<br />

The data available shows that scientists, like their professional associations, support a ban on<br />

human reproductive cloning. According to one survey, only 9 percent of U.S. scientists and only<br />

3 percent of international scientists support reproductive cloning. By contrast, nine out of 10<br />

researchers favor research cloning. 11 With regard to these two issues, scientists’ attitudes and<br />

their societies’ positions do seem aligned. On the other end, only 59 percent of scientists in the<br />

United States support using excess embryos from fertility clinics. Considering that the public<br />

often favors this approach by higher margins, this figure seems to suggest a measure of hesitation<br />

on the part of scientific community. 12 That scientists may harbor some ambivalence about using<br />

human embryos for research purposes is confirmed by the observation that 46 percent of<br />

respondents found the destruction of human embryos “problematic,” and a whopping 73 percent<br />

is opposed to the creation of human embryos exclusively for research. 13<br />

This data suggests two distinct conclusions. The voice of the scientific community, as<br />

opposed to the positions advocated by leading scientific groups, is not sufficiently heard in<br />

contemporary debates about reproductive and biomedical technologies. A broader participation<br />

10<br />

11<br />

12<br />

13<br />

See http://www.sbc.net/aboutus/pssanctity.asp.<br />

Isaac Rabino, "Stem Cell and Cloning Controversies," Genetic Engineering News 24, no. 4 (2004), p.6.<br />

Ibid., p.7.<br />

Ibid., p.9.<br />

249


of scientists in these debates would likely put many positions advocated by scientific<br />

organizations in perspective, and may show important differences between scientists and their<br />

professional representatives. In addition, the data suggests that on several (but not <strong>all</strong>) hot-button<br />

issues, the general public and scientists are largely in agreement. It is not entirely unrealistic to<br />

imagine that a sustained dialogue between scientists and the public could actu<strong>all</strong>y produce an<br />

acceptable political compromise even in those cases, like research cloning, where the public and<br />

the scientists currently are at odds. A question that remains unanswered is whether scientists<br />

would support in significant numbers a system of regulatory oversight. Anecdotal evidence<br />

suggests that at this time, the scientific community may be very reluctant to accept additional<br />

regulations, though reluctance in this case may be dictated largely by contingent political factors<br />

and not by a fundamental rejection of societal demands.<br />

The dominance of extreme political positions and the absence of more centrist views among<br />

advocacy groups may be described as an instance of group polarization. 14 Within a group,<br />

polarization refers to the often-observed phenomenon that deliberation among individuals with<br />

similar views tends to radicalize their opinions. For example, after talking to each other,<br />

individuals with a skeptical view of the United Nations may regard this international body as a<br />

vehicle of conspiracy against the sovereignty of the United States. Environmentalists concerned<br />

about global climate change, after debating the gravity of this phenomenon, may come to believe<br />

that major environmental catastrophes are imminent. Pro-life groups are not simply concerned<br />

about possible abuses of abortion procedures. In their view, embryos are indistinguishable from<br />

full-grown individuals, and therefore abortion is tantamount to murder. Scientists, taken<br />

individu<strong>all</strong>y, may feel that they are in a better position than the public to set research priorities. A<br />

group of scientists discussing this matter may come to the conclusion that it is no one’s business<br />

but theirs to make this determination.<br />

Advocacy groups that tend to debate political priorities and weigh policy options in isolation<br />

from each other are clearly exposed to the risk of polarization. The rather homogenous<br />

membership of these groups (compared to the general public) further amplifies the tendency to<br />

polarize. Another important factor contributing to polarization is the lack of accountability<br />

typical of many advocacy groups. The group leadership rarely if ever consults with its members<br />

as a means to broaden the legitimacy of their political strategies. Paradoxic<strong>all</strong>y, this is especi<strong>all</strong>y<br />

true for public interest groups. Disgruntled members can and on occasion do vote with their<br />

w<strong>all</strong>ets – “exit” rather than “voice,” in Albert Hirschman’s terminology – but this is a rather<br />

marginal phenomenon. The opposite is actu<strong>all</strong>y more common: Public interest groups, by<br />

advocating radical agendas, manage to recruit many more members than they loose. A final<br />

14<br />

This phenomenon initi<strong>all</strong>y was documented by social psychologists. Cf. David G. Myers, "The Group<br />

Polarization Phenomenon," Psychology Bulletin 83 (1976); David G. Myers and G.D. Bishop, "Enhancement of<br />

Dominant Attitudes in Group Discussion," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 20 (1971). In the recent<br />

past, group polarization has begun to receive considerable attention by legal scholars. Cass Sunstein,<br />

"Deliberative Trouble? Why Groups Go to Extremes," Yale Law Journal 110 (2000); Cass Sunstein, Why<br />

Societies Need Dissent (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003).<br />

250


contributing factor is strategic behavior. Each interest group might be willing to make political<br />

concessions if it did not believe that its political opponents would interpret their willingness to<br />

compromise as a sign of weakness that could in turn lead to additional demands. This is a classic<br />

“slippery slope” argument whose importance has been documented in many political settings. 15<br />

Our discussion has shown that in the area of reproductive medicine and biomedical research,<br />

political distortions are significant. How to respond to these failures is a tricky question. The<br />

theory of public choice in this case has little to offer; its main recommendation, to ensure that <strong>all</strong><br />

views are being heard, both does not apply to the present situation and is operation<strong>all</strong>y empty. It<br />

does not apply because <strong>all</strong> organized interest groups are already participating in the political<br />

arena. It is operation<strong>all</strong>y empty because the general public, as such, cannot simply be organized<br />

into yet another interest group. How then could political failures and distortions in the area of<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research be corrected? In the remainder of this chapter,<br />

we discuss this question in some depth. We explore first what may be described as the<br />

professionalization of bioethical dilemmas. We find that this approach should be rejected in<br />

favor of a much broader process of decision-making. We then examine the role of administrative<br />

options such as notice-and-comment as a means to broaden public input. We also assess the<br />

experience made by federal agencies such as the EPA and the Department of Energy (DOE) in<br />

their efforts to involve the general public in highly controversial policy decisions. We conclude<br />

that while these initiatives have taught us a great deal about the pitf<strong>all</strong>s of efforts to involve the<br />

public, none provides a template for implementing a process of public consultation that meets<br />

our requirements.<br />

10.2 A Problematic Start: The Professionalization of Ethical Dilemmas<br />

It may be argued that parliaments were created at a time when political decisions were<br />

relatively simple choices and did not require an understanding of scientific facts or an<br />

appreciation of ethical questions. In this view, parliaments are not suitable institutions for sorting<br />

out some of the deepest questions afflicting modern liberal democracies. What is needed is an<br />

institutional setting in which competent and experienced individuals are given an opportunity to<br />

untangle modern ethical intricacies in a deliberate fashion free of nefarious political influences.<br />

Bioethics commissions can be described as a rough approximation of this ideal. According to<br />

this view, the members of these commissions, typic<strong>all</strong>y a mix of scientists, ethicists, theologians,<br />

and occasion<strong>all</strong>y senior politicians, are in the best position to examine in a dispassionate way<br />

contemporary bioethical dilemmas and propose broadly acceptable answers.<br />

Most industrialized countries have created ethics advisory panels, but none of them has<br />

given these bodies actual legislative powers. Britain is the only instance where a parliament,<br />

distrusting its own inclinations, has created a regulatory body, the HFEA, designed to be largely<br />

insulated from mundane political influences; but the role played by bioethicists in this body is<br />

15<br />

Volokh, "The Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope."<br />

251


elatively modest. Canada and Australia recently have established similar regulatory bodies, but<br />

their enabling legislation does not assign bioethicists a prominent role, and their composition<br />

does not reflect efforts to professionalize broad societal conflicts.<br />

It is undeniable that this strategy has a considerable appeal, most likely fueled by a deepseated<br />

mistrust in the ability of modern democracies to resist their worst temptations. Even such<br />

a fervent defender of representative democracy as Ralf Dahrendorf has come to the conclusion<br />

that parliaments are ill-suited to resolving complex ethical dilemmas, and has recommended a<br />

politic<strong>all</strong>y independent body of highly regarded individuals as a preferable alternative. 16<br />

The professionalization of modern bioethical dilemmas would be a mistake for several<br />

reasons. Bioethics, just like other disciplines in the social sciences and humanities, has seen the<br />

development of numerous and conflicting theoretical perspectives. As a discipline, bioethics is<br />

simply incapable of providing politicians with uncontroversial answers. For why should a<br />

particular ethical paradigm be preferred to another? It is fair to say that no rules exist to select<br />

one ethical paradigm from the plethora of available ethical positions. And a plethora it is. Even a<br />

cursory examination of the bioethical literature brings to the light such perspectives as<br />

principlism, specified principlism, casuistry, and narrative ethics, just to name a few. 17 The<br />

plurality of approaches in bioethics is a testimony of the richness of this relatively new academic<br />

field, but it also makes it impossible for bioethics to play a privileged role in policy-making.<br />

A genuinely pluralistic ethics advisory board could play a useful role in contemporary public<br />

debates about reproductive technologies and biomedical research provided that it does not<br />

attempt to produce consensus positions on questions for which a consensus simply does not<br />

exist. Making majority and minority recommendations available to policy-makers and ensuring<br />

that the underlying assumptions informing these positions are made transparent would be much<br />

more valuable than a thinly disguised consensus report. As we have argued in chapter 2, poor<br />

policy choices are more likely to be induced by a dearth of ethical positions rather than by a<br />

plurality thereof.<br />

A second concern is the rapid transformation of the field of bioethics from a discipline<br />

focused on broad substantive questions into a largely technical field preoccupied with<br />

fundamental principles and with procedural considerations rather than outcomes. The shift of<br />

professional bioethics toward technical, narrowly defined questions also has legitimized many<br />

hitherto controversial biomedical developments. The currently dominant bioethical perspective<br />

16<br />

17<br />

Ralf Dahrendorf, Dopo La Democrazia. Intervista a Cura Di Antonio Polito (Roma: Laterza, 2001).<br />

Tom L. Beauchamp, "Reply to Strong on Principlism and Casuistry," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25,<br />

no. 3 (2000); Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver, and K. Danner Clouser, "Common Morality Versus Specified<br />

Principlism: Reply to Richardson," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Albert R. Jonsen,<br />

"Strong on Specification," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Henry S. Richardson,<br />

"Specifying, Balancing, and Interpreting Bioethical Principles," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3<br />

(2000); Ana Smith Iltis, "Bioethics as Methodological Case Resolution: Specification, Specified Principlism and<br />

Casuistry," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Carson Strong, "Specified Principlism: What<br />

Is It, and Does It Re<strong>all</strong>y Resolve Cases Better Than Casuistry?," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3<br />

(2000).<br />

252


provides considerable ammunition to advocates of unfettered biomedical research, but is<br />

incapable of accommodating the concerns expressed by other constituencies. 18<br />

The professionalization of ethical dilemmas is reminiscent of the role played by probabilistic<br />

risk assessment in public controversies over nuclear power plant safety in the 1970s. The narrow<br />

focus on probabilities advocated by the engineering community and by the manufacturers of<br />

nuclear technology contributed to transform what were momentous societal choices into mere<br />

technical questions. In the process, probabilistic risk assessment reduced these choices to<br />

questions much easier to manage by public administrators, and made concerns expressed by the<br />

general public appear uninformed or downright irrational. 19<br />

A third and final concern is the largely benign view of controversial medical developments<br />

displayed by many bioethicists. Such an uncritic<strong>all</strong>y positive view of new biomedical research<br />

casts considerable doubts on the ability of bioethics committees to credibly mediate among<br />

conflicting societal interests. While bioethics advisory bodies do indeed understand themselves<br />

as effective and competent mediators, 20 one may wonder whether the implicit support for many<br />

controversial biomedical developments demonstrated by the discipline makes these advisory<br />

bodies a suitable institution for crafting a broad societal consensus. Recent controversies over the<br />

remuneration of bioethicists by private companies only reinforce this skepticism. 21<br />

10.3 Elements of a Solution: Notice-and-Comment<br />

Some could argue that the professionalization of ethical dilemmas is a bad idea, but that<br />

there is need for novel mechanisms of public consultation. Section 553 of the Administrative<br />

Procedure Act (APA) provides ample opportunities for anyone to comment on a proposed new<br />

rule. In a nutshell, section 553 requires federal agencies to publish a proposed new rule in the<br />

Federal Register. It then affords interested parties and the general public at least 30 days to<br />

submit comments to the agency. The agency is required to respond in writing to <strong>all</strong> comments<br />

and to take them into consideration in finalizing the proposed new rule.<br />

Section 553, better known as notice-and-comment, would seem to provide a robust<br />

mechanism for soliciting public input. As a matter of practice, however, this is not the case.<br />

There are several important limitations to using notice-and-comment as a tool of public<br />

consultation. The APA was passed short after the end of World War II in response to numerous<br />

cases of what can only be described as arbitrary and capricious agency decisions. In the period<br />

leading up to the passage of the APA, many federal agencies had a tendency to operate in a self-<br />

18<br />

19<br />

20<br />

21<br />

Evans, Playing God? Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public Bioethical Debate.<br />

Thomas Dietz and Robert W. Rycroft, The Risk Professionals (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1987).<br />

Susan E. Kelly, "Public Bioethics and Publics: Consensus, Boundaries, and Participation in Biomedical Policy,"<br />

Science, Technology and Human Values 28, no. 3 (2003); Jonathan D. Moreno, Deciding Together. Bioethics<br />

and Moral Consensus (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995).<br />

Carl Elliott, "Six Problems with Pharma-Funded Bioethics," Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological<br />

and Biomedical Sciences 35 (2004).<br />

253


ighteous manner, justifying their conduct with appeals to vacuous notions of “public interest.”<br />

Section 553 was one of the measures envisaged by Congress to curb the worst administrative<br />

excesses. 22<br />

Today, notice-and-comment in agency rule-making is no longer regarded as an effective tool<br />

to curb agency discretion, and it is certainly not considered an effective institution of public<br />

consultation, for several reasons. Notice-and-comment takes place at a point in time when <strong>all</strong><br />

controversial issues surrounding a new rule have already been sorted out. By the time a proposed<br />

new rule is announced in the Federal Register, <strong>all</strong> influential interest groups have already been<br />

consulted. Public comments at this late stage in the rule-making process are very unlikely to have<br />

a significant impact on key aspects of a proposed new rule. Nor are they likely to provide<br />

fundament<strong>all</strong>y new insights. According to practitioners, the actual importance of notice-andcomment<br />

lies in building the agency rule-making record for judicial review rather than as a tool<br />

for public consultation. 23 Indeed, if an agency were to make significant changes to a proposed<br />

new rule in response to public comments, the courts could require the agency to re-propose the<br />

rule.<br />

The reasons for this dramatic shift are complex, but they can be summarized fairly easily.<br />

Starting in the 1970s, numerous judicial decisions over agency rule-making have produced what<br />

is today known as the “hard look” doctrine. The very strict standards of judicial review embodied<br />

in the hard look doctrine force regulators to justify in excruciating detail <strong>all</strong> technical and<br />

scientific assumptions incorporated in a proposed new rule. These requirements have made rulemaking<br />

an exceedingly cumbersome and complex process. In addition to assembling a very<br />

detailed technical “preamble,” an agency will negotiate extensively but inform<strong>all</strong>y with <strong>all</strong><br />

affected parties before publishing a proposed new rule. Strict judicial review has also had a<br />

chilling effect on the willingness of many federal agencies to promulgate new rules, an effect<br />

described by some commentators as a process of “ossification.” 24 An in-depth discussion of this<br />

claim is well beyond the scope of the present discussion. What seems indisputable is that the<br />

“hard look” doctrine has forced agencies to negotiate extensively with organized interest groups,<br />

and in the process has rendered notice-and-comment as a tool of public consultation largely<br />

irrelevant.<br />

As tool of public consultation, notice-and-comment is not merely ineffectual; in some cases,<br />

it actu<strong>all</strong>y contributes to amplifying existing political distortions. While in principle anyone can<br />

22<br />

23<br />

24<br />

Robert L. Rabin, "Federal Regulation in Historical Perspective," Stanford Law Review 38 (1986).<br />

Donald E. Elliott, "Re-Inventing Rulemaking," Duke Law Journal 41 (1992), p.1492-96.<br />

William S. Jordan, "Ossification Revisited: Does Arbitrary and Capricious Review Significantly Interfere with<br />

Agency Ability to Achieve Regulatory Goals through Informal Rulemaking?," Northwestern University Law<br />

Review 94 (2000); Thomas O. McGarity, "Some Thoughts on 'Deossifying' the Rulemaking Process Duke,"<br />

Duke Law Journal 41 (1992); Thomas O. McGarity, "The Courts and the Ossification of Rulemaking: A<br />

Response to Professor Seidenfeld," Texas Law Review 75 (1997); Richard J. Pierce, "Rulemaking and the<br />

Administrative Procedure Act," Tulsa Law Journal 32 (1996); Mark Seidenfeld, "Demystifying Deossification:<br />

Rethinking Recent Proposals to Modify Judicial Review of Notice and Comment Rulemaking," Texas Law<br />

Review 75 (1997).<br />

254


submit public comments, it is usu<strong>all</strong>y well-organized groups that make the most effective use of<br />

this avenue. When members of the general public make themselves heard, it is often the result of<br />

an organized political campaign rather than a grass-roots response by concerned citizens. As a<br />

matter of regulatory practice, this may not be a serious problem, as federal regulators have<br />

become quite adept at spotting these manipulative maneuvers. But the fact remains that<br />

regulators do not use and not do consider notice-and-comment an effective tool of public<br />

involvement.<br />

Having discredited notice-and-comment as an effective institution of public consultation, it<br />

is worth noting that there have been a few instances of federal agencies making a strategic use of<br />

this administrative tool to promote broader societal interests. 25<br />

The term “broader societal<br />

interests” in this context indicates a situation in which an agency is willing and able to pursue a<br />

policy that is likely to be supported by a large majority of the general public but opposed by a<br />

few well-organized interest groups. This characterization closely resembles our description of the<br />

political landscape in the field of reproductive medicine and biomedical research, and is<br />

therefore of some interest to our discussion. The agencies involved are the EPA, the FDA and the<br />

Office of the Comptroller of the Currency (OCC), the federal agency responsible for regulating<br />

the banking industry. In 1997, the EPA managed to promulgate new air standards designed to<br />

reduce air pollution by ozone and particulate matters, against the vehement opposition of the<br />

regulated interests, including automakers, coal producers, electric utilities, and oil companies. In<br />

1996, the FDA issued a new rule governing the advertising, sale, and distribution of cigarettes<br />

and smokeless tobacco. The proposed new rule restricted access to cigarette sales by minors,<br />

limited tobacco advertising in the media, and prohibited the distribution of free tobacco samples<br />

and non-tobacco promotional items, among other things. <strong>Final</strong>ly, in the late 1990s, the OCC took<br />

numerous bold steps to expand bank securities and insurance powers, natur<strong>all</strong>y over the<br />

opposition of powerful financial interests.<br />

Common to these three federal agencies was a strategy designed to build broad public<br />

support for their proposed new regulations. To achieve this goal, the agencies began to reach out<br />

to the public at a very early stage of the rule-making process – that is, well before the proposed<br />

new rules were offici<strong>all</strong>y announced in the Federal Register. The tools used for this purpose<br />

varied somewhat from case to case; they ranged from convening public hearings, and organizing<br />

conferences and town h<strong>all</strong> meetings to making informational materials available to the public,<br />

among other things. The novelty in this case does not reside in the tools used, but in the<br />

extensive efforts made by these agencies to reach the general public at a stage of the regulatory<br />

process in which an agency usu<strong>all</strong>y negotiates exclusively with key interest groups.<br />

An important reason for mobilizing the general public was to stimulate a large number of<br />

supportive comments during the notice-and-comments phase. Extensive outreach strategies had a<br />

second, important goal: to build the best possible case in support of the proposed new rules. By<br />

25<br />

Steven P. Croley, "Public Interested Regulation," Florida State University Law Review 28 (2000); Elizabeth<br />

Garrett, "Interest Groups and Public Interested Regulation," Florida State University Law Review 28 (2000).<br />

255


eaching out to the public, the agencies hoped to obtain additional information, new insights and<br />

data that could strengthen the cases for their respective new rules, a goal that closely par<strong>all</strong>els<br />

our c<strong>all</strong> for the consideration of a much broader range of normative arguments in contemporary<br />

bioethical debates. The agencies did not expect notice-and-comment to produce exclusively<br />

supportive arguments, and organized interest groups did use notice-and-comment to register their<br />

discontent. But as hoped for by the agencies, the number of favorable comments dwarfed the<br />

negative reactions, thus strengthening the agencies’ positions.<br />

Critics could argue that these agencies manipulated the rule-making process to achieve their<br />

own bureaucratic goals, and that the process just described is a blatant case of “rogue” agency<br />

behavior, of agency “drift.” This criticism is misleading. For one thing, the goals pursued by <strong>all</strong><br />

three agencies were indeed largely in the interest of the general public. Pursuing broader<br />

objectives certainly has not benefited the leadership of these agencies. To the contrary, by<br />

deciding to fight powerful business interests and their <strong>all</strong>ies in Congress, these agencies took<br />

significant risks. The agencies simply used the room afforded to them by the APA to discharge<br />

their public mandate, and did so in the same way well-organized private groups routinely do to<br />

pursue their own interests.<br />

That the agencies succeeded in neutralizing the distorting effect of organized interest groups<br />

demonstrates that regulators genuinely committed to pursuing broader societal interests can use<br />

notice-and-comment to their advantage. Unfortunately, these are the proverbial exceptions to the<br />

rule. Mounting an effective outreach campaign is a time-consuming and costly undertaking that<br />

many agencies may not be able to undertake. The APA certainly does not mandate conducting<br />

costly and time-consuming outreach campaigns. Deciding to fight large business interests and<br />

Congress at the same time is not a decision many administrators are likely to make. Nor are<br />

senior administrators inclined to risk a conflict with the president. In sum, notice-and-comment,<br />

by itself, is of very limited value as a tool of public involvement. It can, however, become quite<br />

useful in combination with other measures of public outreach.<br />

10.4 Why Consult with the Public?<br />

In section 10.1, we argued that untangling modern bioethical dilemmas will likely require<br />

devising institutions of public consultation of a novel kind. We argued that the inclusion of the<br />

general public in policy-making would prevent political failures, or at least mitigate political<br />

distortions in a policy arena fraught with both. Another way to account for the importance of<br />

adopting robust institutions of public consultation is to note that the quality of a policy and the<br />

fairness of the decision-making process cruci<strong>all</strong>y depend on the range of views available to<br />

decision-makers. Skeptics may agree with this general observation but observe that in the case of<br />

biomedical dilemmas, the general public simply does not have the expertise to make substantial<br />

contributions to the debate. In this section, we discuss a few examples that demonstrate the<br />

opposite. Taken together, they suggest that professional views of ethical dilemmas represent only<br />

256


a fairly limited spectrum of the pool of ethical arguments policy-makers should include in their<br />

decision-making process.<br />

The case of synthetic human growth hormone discussed in chapter 2 provides a first<br />

(negative) illustration of the importance of making a broad pool of ethical arguments available to<br />

decision-makers. In that case, the Endocrinologic and Metabolic Drugs Advisory Committee<br />

decided to approve the use of human growth hormone for non-therapeutic uses based largely on<br />

testimonies offered the pharmaceutical industry and patients. A few dissenting voices were<br />

heard, but listening to critics was a formality rather than an important element of the decisionmaking<br />

process. The narrow scope of the arguments presented to the committee suggested that<br />

this advisory committee would have recommended including idiopathic shortness on the list of<br />

FDA-approved indications for the use of human growth hormone. This is exactly what the<br />

committee recommended.<br />

A case study of patients’ evaluation of somatic gene therapy provides an illustration of the<br />

discrepancy between laypersons’ and professionals’ perspectives on bioethical dilemmas. 26<br />

Among bioethicists and medical professionals, gene therapy is gener<strong>all</strong>y viewed as a benign<br />

biomedical development. Its potential benefits are substantial, while the risks are negligible;<br />

issues of patient selections, informed consent, and confidentiality of personal data do not seem to<br />

pose significant problems. The health care costs of this treatment remain very high and are<br />

clearly regarded as source of concern. This, in a nutshell, is the professional take on gene therapy<br />

trials. 27<br />

Patients with disabilities draw a much more nuanced and problematic picture of this<br />

potential cure. These patients expressed 11 distinct ethical concerns, many of which have not<br />

played a significant role in mainstream bioethical debates. Among them are the relationship<br />

between disability and personal identity and between genetic changes and personal identity.<br />

Several patients found that their disabilities, for better or worse, had become part of their<br />

identities, and that by removing these disabilities, something irreplaceable would be lost. The<br />

possible impact of somatic gene therapy on attitudes toward disabilities was a second concern.<br />

Some disabled individuals thought that society would be impoverished if certain disabilities were<br />

to disappear. This is indeed a recurrent topic, especi<strong>all</strong>y among deaf persons, who often do not<br />

consider themselves disabled but rather members of a distinctive subculture. Many prospective<br />

patients were worried that society would impose what might be c<strong>all</strong>ed eugenic pressure, a worry<br />

that is either ignored or quickly dismissed by professional bioethicists. Some patients also were<br />

concerned about the rationale offered by pharmaceutical companies and the medical<br />

establishment for developing the treatment. 28 These individuals wondered whether gene therapy<br />

26<br />

27<br />

28<br />

Leach Sculley, Rippberger, and Rehmann-Sutter, "Non-Professional Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics."<br />

LeRoy Walters and Julie Gage Palmer, The Ethics of Human Gene Therapy (Oxford: Oxford University Press,<br />

1996).<br />

Leach Sculley, Rippberger, and Rehmann-Sutter, "Non-Professional Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics,"<br />

p.1417-18.<br />

257


ultimately benefits more the patients or the pharmaceutical companies involved in its<br />

development.<br />

The researchers also surveyed a group of medical professionals. Not surprisingly, the study<br />

found several important differences in how professionals and patients evaluated somatic gene<br />

therapy. The professionals’ concerns revolved mainly around the safety and efficacy of this<br />

treatment. The study showed that for these health care professionals, the notion that some<br />

patients may not consider gene therapy a treatment at <strong>all</strong> was difficult to accept.<br />

The example just discussed is not exceptional. Time and again, non-professional<br />

assessments of bioethical dilemmas focus on substantive rather than procedural issues.<br />

Laypersons question the ends as opposed to simply examining the means. They wonder whether<br />

new cures such as gene therapy are another instance of a social problem being transformed by<br />

the medical profession and the pharmaceutical industry into a medical condition. On the other<br />

end, many of the traditional preoccupations of professional bioethicists, such as autonomy,<br />

beneficence, non-malfeasance, and justice, are not or only margin<strong>all</strong>y reflected in these patients’<br />

concerns.<br />

A third example of how professionals and laypersons may differ in their respective<br />

assessments of ethical priorities is provided by a comparative study of genetic counseling. 29 A<br />

group of citizens was assembled that was directly affected by genetic conditions, but with no<br />

prior connections to advocacy groups. Included also were genetic counselors, medical<br />

geneticists, and public health professionals. The study was designed to elicit and rank concerns<br />

from each of these groups. The results were revealing. Among patients, respect and accuracy of<br />

the information provided ranked first and second, respectively. By contrast, topics of<br />

considerable interest to bioethicists, such as privacy, non-directive counseling, and informed<br />

consent, were notably missing from the patients’ concerns.<br />

Yet another telling illustration of the differences between professionals’ and laypersons’<br />

approaches to ethical dilemmas is provided by coping strategies adopted by parents after learning<br />

that they most likely will have a disabled child. A somewhat dated but suggestive qualitative<br />

analysis of these parents’ strategies shows that parents do not decide to abort pregnancies (or to<br />

keep babies, for that matter) based on statistical probabilities. Whether parents face a 20 percent<br />

or a 70 percent chance of having a disabled child is not decisive. The prospective parents assess<br />

first how their life might change if a disabled child entered their lives, and what it would be like<br />

to care for this child. If they conclude that they will be able to cope with the ch<strong>all</strong>enge of raising<br />

a disabled child, then they are likely to have the baby. If on the other hand they come to the<br />

conclusion that they would not be able to care for the child, they are likely to interrupt the<br />

pregnancy. And when they are unable to make a positive decision, they tend to let the fate<br />

decide. 30 Compare this approach to professional norms. There is considerable anecdotal evidence<br />

29<br />

30<br />

Dorothy C. Wertz and Robin Gregg, "Genetics Services in a Social, Ethical and Policy Context: A Collaboration<br />

between Consumers and Providers," Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (2000).<br />

Abby Lippman-Hand and Clarke F. Fraser, "Genetic Counseling: Parents’ Responses to Uncertainty," Birth<br />

Defects: Original Article Series 15 (1979). A much more differentiated and more recent discussion of this issue<br />

258


that medical personnel often encourage, in subtle but no less effective ways, prospective parents<br />

to consider an abortion when an amniocentesis indicates a strong likelihood of a severe<br />

disability. 31<br />

Each of the examples discussed in this section makes a similar point: Bioethicists, medical<br />

professionals, patients, and the public differ in important ways in how they approach modern<br />

bioethical dilemmas. Moreover, these examples demonstrate that lay views widen the pool of<br />

relevant ethical arguments in important ways. We are certainly not claiming that the public<br />

always or necessarily offers superior ethical arguments. Our contention is simply that a broad<br />

process of public consultation on difficult ethical dilemmas is likely to expand in significant<br />

ways the pool of relevant ethical arguments. A large pool of ethical views is indispensable to<br />

politicians and administrators responsible for crafting broadly acceptable responses to the<br />

dilemmas created by new biomedical research. Conversely, regulatory institutions that by design<br />

limit the pool of available ethical arguments are likely to exacerbate societal divisions.<br />

10.5 Who Should Be Consulted?<br />

Simply advocating a process of broad public consultation leaves an important question open:<br />

Who exactly is “the public” in a public consultation? Administrators have often been faced with<br />

this question, either because a statute requires them to solicit public input (more on this in<br />

section 10.9), or because agency policy demands it, or else because failure in the past to include<br />

one or the other constituency has led to a protracted and acrimonious process of decisionmaking.<br />

As a matter of practice, then, many administrators operating in charged regulatory<br />

environments, the EPA and the DOE being two examples, have found ways to translate abstract<br />

demands of inclusiveness into viable administrative practices.<br />

Central to administrative notions of inclusiveness is the concept of “stakeholders.”<br />

Identifying critical stakeholders, from an administrative point of view, is far simpler than<br />

involving the public in its entirety. Administrators do not need to seek out stakeholders; these<br />

individuals and groups liter<strong>all</strong>y run into their offices to “inform” and to lobby them. These are<br />

the stakeholders the agency ignores at its own risk. The public, on the other hand, must be<br />

invited, motivated, and cajoled to participate in matters often perceived as distant and complex.<br />

In more recent times, federal agencies have adopted more elaborate strategies designed to ensure<br />

that <strong>all</strong> stakeholders, including those that tradition<strong>all</strong>y have mistrusted the federal government,<br />

participate in policy-making. These refinements, however, do not affect the view that the public,<br />

as a matter of bureaucratic practice, can be equated to a group of loosely defined key<br />

stakeholders.<br />

31<br />

can be found in Rayna Rapp, "Refusing Prenatal Diagnosis: The Meanings of Bioscience in a Multicultural<br />

World," Science, Technology and Human Values 23, no. 1 (1998); Rayna Rapp, Testing Women, Testing the<br />

Fetus: The Social Impact of Amniocentesis in America (New York: Routledge, 2000).<br />

See Erikson, "Post-Diagnostic Abortion in Germany: Reproduction Gone Awry, Again?."; Michael J.<br />

Malinowski, "Coming into Being: Law, Ethics and the Practice of Prenatal Genetic Screening," Hastings Law<br />

Journal 45 (1994).<br />

259


In many cases, these efforts are perfectly adequate. At the local level, participation by<br />

various interest groups may be considered an adequate substitute for broad public participation;<br />

participation in decision-making at the local level is less likely to suffer from political failures.<br />

The empirical evidence suggests that agencies such the DOE and the EPA have become quite<br />

adept at designing and running participatory processes. 32 Unfortunately, a pragmatic stance in<br />

identifying stakeholder groups and in involving the public makes these otherwise remarkable<br />

initiatives largely irrelevant.<br />

Stakeholders are often defined as those groups that are substanti<strong>all</strong>y and negatively affected<br />

by an agency policy. This definition is of considerable practical import, but it is far from<br />

unproblematic. Consider the following hypothetical example: Let us assume that the Yosemite<br />

V<strong>all</strong>ey has not yet been made into a national park. Political pressure is mounting to get the<br />

National Park Service to take action. The Park Service recognizes the urgency of moving<br />

forward on this matter, but is concerned about opposition expressed by select interest groups. To<br />

gauge public support for this measure, it initiates a broad process of public consultation. Central<br />

to this process are negotiations with key stakeholders. What stakeholders is the National Park<br />

Service likely to consult with? Surely, the agency would seek comments from tourist and travel<br />

operators, logging companies, hunters’ societies, local communities, and Native American tribes,<br />

among other groups. The Park Service would also want to consult with environmental and<br />

conservationist groups, both at the local and national levels. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the agency would also want<br />

to solicit public comments from the general public.<br />

Are these stakeholders <strong>all</strong> equ<strong>all</strong>y entitled to be heard? Do they <strong>all</strong> have “stakes,” and what<br />

are these stakes? The first group of individuals and organizations identified by the agency clearly<br />

meet the standard definition of stakeholder. These are societal groups who are likely to be<br />

substanti<strong>all</strong>y and negatively affected by the proposal to protect the great outdoors. Their stakes<br />

are obvious and undisputable; most of these groups would suffer economic losses; others would<br />

be dramatic<strong>all</strong>y restricted in activities they once took for granted. In other words, these groups<br />

would be harmed in the strong sense of this term.<br />

Environmental and conservationist groups, for their part, certainly consider themselves<br />

stakeholders on par with logging companies and the tourist industry. The Park Service, for its<br />

part, would share this view. These groups can be expected to provide strong support for the<br />

agency proposal to turn Yosemite V<strong>all</strong>ey into a national park. As a practical matter, few would<br />

dispute the view that conservationist groups should be considered stakeholders. By the standard<br />

definition of this concept, however, this inference is not necessarily warranted. In which sense<br />

would environmentalists and the public be negatively affected should the Park Service decide not<br />

to move forward with its proposal? What kind of damage would these groups suffer? Clearly,<br />

environmental groups would not suffer any economic losses, nor is the source of their livelihood<br />

32<br />

Thomas C. Beierle, "The Quality of Stakeholder-Based Decisions: Lessons from the Case Study Record,"<br />

(Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future, 2000); Judith A. Bradbury and Kristi M. Branch, "An Evaluation<br />

of the Effectiveness of Local Site-Specific Advisory Boards for U.S. Department of Energy Environmental<br />

Restoration Program," (Pacific Northwest National Laboratory, 1999).<br />

260


affected by a negative decision. In this sense, environmental groups do not have a stake in this<br />

decision, if “stake” is defined along the lines delineated by the Supreme Court in Lujan v.<br />

Defenders of Wildlife (1992). 33<br />

That this is not merely an academic question becomes apparent if the Park Service decided<br />

that Yosemite V<strong>all</strong>ey is not worth protecting after <strong>all</strong>. National environmental groups would<br />

certainly ch<strong>all</strong>enge this decision in court. They could do so on the grounds that some of their<br />

members have been harmed by the Park Service’s negative decision. These groups could claim<br />

that their members have visited Yosemite V<strong>all</strong>ey in the past and many of them plan to do so<br />

again in the future. If the National Park Service failed to protect Yosemite, these Americans<br />

would experience a considerable loss.<br />

The Supreme Court has repeatedly ruled on similar cases in the past. Lujan v. Defenders of<br />

Wildlife involved a decision by the Department of the Interior to provide partial funding for dam<br />

projects in Sri Lanka and Egypt. Defenders of Wildlife, a U.S. non-profit organization, claimed<br />

that the decision by the Department of the Interior would have threatened the habitat of several<br />

endangered species under the Endangered Species Act. The Court determined that the fact that<br />

an individual (in this case members of Defenders of Wildlife) had visited a pristine<br />

environmental area in the past and had a vague intention to do so again in the future did not<br />

prove that he or she would be injured by a failure to protect the area. 34 To claim standing, these<br />

individuals would have to demonstrate specific plans to visit the area again in the near future,<br />

and not merely that they have an abstract interest in the protection of the area and may visit it<br />

again sometime in the not-too-distant future.<br />

The example just discussed is far from hypothetical. The Endangered Species Act, for<br />

example, requires public input in the listing of endangered species, the designation of critical<br />

habitat, and the recovery plans for endangered species, among other things. 35 Yet exactly whose<br />

input should be solicited to implement this act? It is quite easy for the administering agency, in<br />

this case the U.S. Fish and Wildlife Service, to identify those parties that would be negatively<br />

and substanti<strong>all</strong>y affected by expanding the list of endangered species. Property owners,<br />

developers, timber companies, and sm<strong>all</strong> rural communities dependent on the timber industry for<br />

their livelihood would <strong>all</strong> be threatened in an obvious and immediate way. Yet these are not the<br />

only affected parties. The agency could determine that “interested and affected parties” should<br />

include <strong>all</strong> parties with a substantial interest in endangered species, such as national<br />

environmental groups, local activists, and biologists.<br />

33<br />

34<br />

35<br />

See 504 U.S. 555 (1992). In Lujan, the Court found that an individual has standing only if he or she can<br />

demonstrate “actual or imminent injury” (504 U.S. 555, 567).<br />

Bradford C. Mank, "Standing and Global Warming: Is Injury to All Injury to None?," Environmental Law 35<br />

(2005), p.30.<br />

Nancy Perkins Spyke, "Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking at the New Millenium:<br />

Structuring New Spheres of Public Influence," Boston College Environmental Affairs Law Review 26 (1999),<br />

p.286-87.<br />

261


The rationale for including stakeholders that are not negatively and significantly affected by<br />

the decision to list (or not to) a species as endangered is murky. Is it legitimate for national<br />

environmental organizations to intervene in what many would consider strictly local matters? Is<br />

it enough for these organizations to declare themselves interested parties by virtue of their<br />

interest and commitment to environmental causes? Good arguments can be made in favor of and<br />

against their participation, the latter by virtue of the simple fact that these organizations are<br />

intervening in highly localized political conflicts. But one could argue that the loss of a species<br />

cannot be regarded simply as another instance of a local political controversy. As we have<br />

argued earlier, the fact that the protecting Yosemite V<strong>all</strong>ey directly affects only a very narrow<br />

segment of the general public does not make protecting it a local issue. In addition, national<br />

environmental groups bring resources and expertise to the table often not available to local<br />

groups. In this sense, they contribute to enlarging the pool of possible arguments pro and con<br />

listing a species as endangered, and may contribute to correcting a political failure.<br />

The examples discussed in this section are representative of a wide range of political<br />

controversies, including those triggered by advances in reproductive medicine and biomedical<br />

research. Our “genetic heritage” and the great outdoors both are the products of billions of years<br />

of natural evolution. And just as it is utterly foolish for anyone to suggest that the Yosemite<br />

V<strong>all</strong>ey or the Grand Canyon could be “improved,” so is it equ<strong>all</strong>y foolish for scientists to claim<br />

that the human genome can be improved in more than a marginal sense. Both the magnificence<br />

of the great outdoors and the beauty of the double helix inspire respect and awe. Yet respect for<br />

the great outdoors and for our genetic heritage does not exclude enjoying these national<br />

treasures, nor does it preclude scientific research. In the case of our national parks, we have<br />

found acceptable ways to reconcile enjoying nature with the need to protect spectacular<br />

landscapes against degradation and destruction. Americans are rightly proud of their great<br />

outdoors. But it must be recognized that only national leaders inspired by an undiluted notion of<br />

public interest made the protection of these national treasures possible.<br />

Our discussion has shown that the concept of stakeholders solves as many problems as it<br />

creates. While organized interest groups are a reality that no politician or administrator can<br />

afford to ignore, reducing the concept of the public to a more or less arbitrary group of<br />

stakeholders is a pragmatic approach with clear conceptual and operational limitations. For this<br />

reason, in chapter 12, we propose mechanisms of public consultation explicitly designed to elicit<br />

input both from organized interest groups and from individual citizens.<br />

10.6 Scientific Literacy and Public Participation<br />

Given the rather modest levels of scientific literacy in the general population, it may seem<br />

implausible that modern bioethical controversies should be resolved by resorting to broad public<br />

262


consultations. 36 These doubts are understandable, but hardly justified. Many case studies have<br />

shown that citizens who are given an opportunity to examine a technological controversy<br />

develop an uncanny ability to “deconstruct” scientific claims, to uncover questionable tacit<br />

assumptions, and to thoroughly probe the empirical evidence experts rely on for their claims.<br />

They become, in other words, experts at questioning scientific authority. 37<br />

The important<br />

question is not whether the public meets some a priori, arbitrary level of scientific literacy, but if<br />

members of the general public, given the opportunity, can familiarize themselves with a complex<br />

scientific and technological controversy. The evidence suggests that this is indeed the case. 38<br />

Consider the case of stem cell research. At first, it would appear that scientific literacy<br />

would matter a great deal. Leading scientists have argued that embryos should be sacrificed for<br />

the sake of developing cures for hitherto incurable diseases. While these scientists have<br />

expressed considerable confidence that this line of research will deliver revolutionary new cures,<br />

the President’s Council on Bioethics, in a recent assessment of the state of the art, was far less<br />

sanguine about the availability of cures in the immediate future. 39 A minority of scientists is not<br />

convinced that the development of embryonic stem cells can precisely be controlled, and<br />

recommends instead focusing on the less flexible but perhaps more promising area of adult stem<br />

cells. Assessing the credibility and accuracy of competing scientific claims offered by equ<strong>all</strong>y<br />

competent and credible scientists then would seem to require precisely the kind of scientific<br />

expertise that the general public does not have.<br />

A background in science or biology would be useful but is not necessary to evaluate<br />

conflicting scientific perspectives. To adjudicate among competing scientific claims is to take on<br />

the role of an investigative reporter. What are required are general analytical skills and a<br />

reasonable, general level of education rather than expertise in cell and developmental biology.<br />

An understanding of how scientific institutions work would also be helpful. For example, no<br />

special expertise is necessary to probe scientists’ belief that the development of embryonic stem<br />

cells can actu<strong>all</strong>y be controlled. 40 The public could also question the reasons for scientists’<br />

aggressive pursuit of cloning technologies; conducting cloning research has been justified by the<br />

need to develop immunologic<strong>all</strong>y compatible organs, but a lay audience may come to the<br />

conclusion that this is a rather weak rationale, considering that clinical applications are many<br />

36<br />

37<br />

38<br />

39<br />

40<br />

The National Science Foundation (NSF) periodic<strong>all</strong>y conducts scientific literacy surveys whose results are, in the<br />

eyes of NSF officials, invariably a source of concern. See<br />

http://www.nsf.gov/statistics/showsrvy.cfm?srvy_CatID=6&srvy_Seri=17.<br />

Robert Futrell, "Technical Adversarialism and Participatory Collaboration in the U.S. Chemical Weapons<br />

Disposal Program," Science, Technology and Human Values 28, no. 4 (2003).<br />

Aaron Wildavsky, But Is It True? A Citizen's Guide to Environmental Health and Safety Issues (Cambridge,<br />

MA: Harvard University Press, 1995).<br />

President's Council on Bioethics, Applications of Human Stem Cells in Research and Medicine (2003 [cited<br />

October 3, 2005]); available from http://www.bioethics.gov/background/sc_application.html.<br />

By their own admission, and despite their best efforts, scientists so far have not been able to control how human<br />

embryonic stem cells develop. But this ability is crucial, if any clinical application should come from this line of<br />

research.<br />

263


years away. Again, no scientific background is necessary to inquire about this issue. And by<br />

asking this question, a lay audience is likely to learn a great deal about how scientists set their<br />

research priorities and about the rationales for these choices. Effectively assessing the credibility<br />

of scientific claims certainly is no easy task, but scientific literacy is unlikely to make this job<br />

easier.<br />

<strong>Final</strong>ly, it is worth pointing out that the distinction between the scientific<strong>all</strong>y illiterate public<br />

and informed scientists is itself seriously misleading. In most cases, scientists are just as illiterate<br />

about science as is the public. Knowledge production is so fragmented and specialized that<br />

anyone outside any of the innumerable and often tiny scientific communities – they are so sm<strong>all</strong><br />

that one is tempted to c<strong>all</strong> them cliques – is a scientific illiterate. For example, an average<br />

biologist, just like anyone else without an advanced degree in physics, is very unlikely to know<br />

what a Lorenz transformation is. Yet this is not an arcane piece of mathematics, but the<br />

foundation of Einstein’s special theory of relativity – formulated and published in 1905 and often<br />

taught in physics curricula at the high-school level. Lorenz transformations should not be<br />

confused with the Lorenz effect, named after Edward Lorenz. In the 1960s, Lorenz famously<br />

observed that a butterfly flapping its wings in Beijing could alter the weather in San Francisco.<br />

Among experts of chaos theory and climatology, this story is a familiar one. Yet few persons<br />

outside of these scientific communities are likely to have heard of this effect. Scientific<br />

(il)literacy is a widespread phenomenon in industrialized societies, but is of very little help in<br />

explaining opposition to scientific and technological developments.<br />

10.7 Key Features of Institutions of Public Consultation<br />

10.7.1 Deliberation: Vehicle of Consensus or Catalyst of Conflict?<br />

We suggest that mechanisms of public consultation should always include a deliberative<br />

phase. There are several good reasons for including deliberation in processes of public<br />

consultation. Deliberation ensures that the participating citizens do not simply offer improvised<br />

answers to complex questions they may never have pondered. Institutions of public consultation<br />

should be designed specific<strong>all</strong>y to elicit informed and reflected opinions. Deliberation ensures<br />

that participants acquire a much deeper and differentiated understanding of the issues involved; it<br />

is the process of familiarization that is likely to produce well-informed opinions. The outcome of<br />

this process cannot easily be dismissed on the grounds that people are in no position to express<br />

informed opinions. This is the feature that sharply distinguishes a traditional survey from a<br />

consultative process.<br />

Unlike opinion surveys, the views gathered through a process of public consultation are<br />

stable, in that they are unlikely to change significantly over time. Deliberation should <strong>all</strong> but<br />

eliminate the sensitivity of survey results to the wording of poll questions, a problem we have<br />

repeatedly encountered in our discussion of survey data in chapter 8. In sum, by ensuring that the<br />

public expresses its views only after having reflected for some time on various aspects of a<br />

264


ioethical dilemma, the credibility and robustness of a process of public consultation are<br />

considerably enhanced.<br />

By exposing <strong>all</strong> participants to a broad range of different views, beliefs, and values,<br />

deliberation fosters a better understanding of opposing views. Importantly, exposure to different<br />

opinions facilitates the crafting of political compromises. Alternatively, deliberation may help<br />

participants identify innovative solutions that they were not aware of before engaging in face-toface<br />

communication. Deliberation, in other words, can be described as a “discovery process.” 41<br />

Scholars of deliberative democracy will readily recognize these arguments. Our concept of<br />

deliberation bears some similarities with the notions of deliberation espoused by these scholars,<br />

but it also differs in important ways. Advocates of deliberative democracy and their critics seem<br />

to assume that deliberation is either disinterested or entirely self-interested. 42 Neither one of<br />

these assumptions is empiric<strong>all</strong>y accurate. Participants in a process of public consultation do not<br />

check their interests and predispositions at the door. Nor it is reasonable to assume that actual<br />

deliberations are always or exclusively informed by opportunistic, self-interested norms. More<br />

often than not, self-interest and what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed public-mindedness coexist. This means that<br />

deliberation has only a limited capacity to bring about consensus. Deliberation can move<br />

conflicting parties toward a consensus, but there is no reason to assume that this will always or<br />

necessarily be so. Some controversies may be more difficult to solve through deliberation than<br />

others. Deliberation is no substitute for other mechanisms of decision-making, such as voting. In<br />

this view, we differ from advocates of deliberative democracy, who assume, more or less<br />

explicitly, that deliberation ultimately will move participants toward finding a consensus.<br />

That deliberation does not necessarily produce consensus is demonstrated by our national<br />

conversation about new biomedical research. Since President Bush announced his policy on stem<br />

cell research in August of 2001, much has been said and written on national television and in the<br />

news media about reproductive cloning, research cloning, and stem cell research. From a<br />

quantitative perspective, the debate has been vigorous. Since we started monitoring the print<br />

media in early 2003, we have gathered almost 3,000 news stories on these and closely related<br />

topics. 43 Yet one cannot avoid the conclusion that this conversation has not contributed to<br />

bringing opposing parties closer together. To the contrary, the existing positions seem to have<br />

hardened, leaving no room for political compromise. What has been unfolding in the news media<br />

is the discursive equivalent of a bullfight: Each side has persistently but unsuccessfully tried to<br />

impose its fixed views on the other and on the nation as a whole.<br />

41<br />

42<br />

43<br />

This term is borrowed from Friedrich Hayek, who introduced it to describe market mechanisms. Friedrich A.<br />

Hayek, "Der Wettbewerb Als Entdeckungsverfahren," in Kieler Vorträge (Kiel: 1968). That in Hayek’s concept<br />

of the market face-to-face communication plays a crucial role is no coincidence.<br />

Richard A. Posner, Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003),<br />

p.131-43. See also Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict<br />

Cannot Be Avoided in Politics, What Should Be Done About It. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1996).<br />

News stories are available online at http://www.biotechgov.org.<br />

265


The view that deliberation can sharpen conflicts rather than mitigate them has a solid<br />

empirical foundation. Social psychologists have long been aware that deliberation does not<br />

always promote nuanced views, mutual understanding, and consensus among warring factions. It<br />

would be a disaster if a process of public consultation intended to facilitate reconciliation<br />

inadvertently contributed to sharpen societal divisions. In the remainder of this section, we<br />

discuss three mechanisms that can undermine deliberative efforts. They are informational<br />

cascades, reputational cascades, and a limited “arguments pool.” Taken together, they contribute<br />

to what is known as “group polarization,” a phenomenon whose significance to politics and<br />

policy-making has only recently been explored. 44<br />

Informational cascades may be described as a social mechanism of opinion-building. The<br />

need for orientation may arise with respect to widely different questions: How safe are nuclear<br />

power plants? Is busing effective? Is the minimum wage a good or bad thing? How much would<br />

it cost to send humans to Mars? In <strong>all</strong> these cases, individuals with limited knowledge and<br />

expertise tend to take their cues from opinion leaders. Opinion leaders are not always or<br />

necessarily highly reputable individuals with impeccable academic credentials. Children view<br />

their parents as their frame of reference. For teenagers, it may be their peers, much to the dismay<br />

of their parents. To political activists, it may be a charismatic leader. And if you are black, poor,<br />

and living in a dilapidated urban environment, the opinion of your church leaders on the<br />

minimum wage will carry considerable weight. Even judges and legal scholars are not immune<br />

from informational cascades. 45<br />

The more opinion leaders share a certain view of a controversial issue, the likelier it is that<br />

other, less informed or less opinionated individuals will share a particular view of a controversial<br />

question, and the more likely it becomes that even more people will hold this opinion, until the<br />

entire population or a very large fraction thereof holds the same opinion, whether this view is<br />

accurate or not. This, in a nutshell, is an informational cascade. Importantly, different population<br />

groups may be affected by different informational cascades, producing homogeneous and nonoverlapping<br />

distributions of attitudes toward controversial issues.<br />

Reputational cascades are a second important mechanism of social influence. A selfexplanatory<br />

term for this phenomenon is group conformity. Reputational cascades can play an<br />

important role in sm<strong>all</strong> group deliberations. Individuals conform to a group’s opinion out of a<br />

concern for their reputation, even though they may actu<strong>all</strong>y disagree with the group. The<br />

mechanism at work here seems to be a deeply felt need to protect one’s public image and to<br />

avoid ostracism by one’s peers or colleagues. Reputational cascades can work in the opposite<br />

direction as well: They may induce individuals to make public statements that they privately do<br />

not endorse. Reputational cascades are relevant only in those cases in which individuals are<br />

44<br />

45<br />

Myers, "The Group Polarization Phenomenon."; Sunstein, "Deliberative Trouble? Why Groups Go to<br />

Extremes."; Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent.<br />

Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent. On cascades, see also Timur Kuran and Cass Sunstein, "Availability<br />

Cascades and Risk Regulation," Stanford Law Review 51 (1999).<br />

266


concerned about their public image. Individuals only mildly or not concerned about their<br />

reputation are unlikely to feel compelled to comply with their group’s expectations.<br />

Consider for example a scientist expressing the view that research cloning currently is not<br />

critical to developing new medical treatments. This person is likely to be exposed to considerable<br />

opprobrium by his colleagues, and his career could suffer greatly. Alternatively, consider an<br />

evangelical Christian expressing some doubts about the wisdom of liter<strong>all</strong>y equating embryos to<br />

human beings. It is fair to assume that this person would no longer be welcome in his or her<br />

church. In these cases, reputational cascades shed considerable light on why we observe so much<br />

conformity among the members of a social group, even though disagreement may be widespread.<br />

Group polarization proper is the third and final phenomenon of import to institutional<br />

design. The term itself is a bit of a misnomer, since it is not meant to suggest a process by which<br />

a group breaks down into two distinct camps, or a phenomenon by which distinct groups shift<br />

toward opposite views, although as we have seen in section 10.1, this can indeed be the case. In<br />

its original meaning, group polarization identifies a rather puzzling phenomenon. After<br />

deliberation, groups whose members hold similar views shift their opinions toward a more<br />

extreme version of their initial positions. In other words, group polarization occurs when “an<br />

initial tendency of individual group members toward a given direction is enhanced following<br />

group deliberation.” 46 Group polarization is not synonymous with group radicalization. A group<br />

of cautious individuals is very likely to become ever more cautious after deliberation. The<br />

important point here is that deliberation tends to amplify the initial inclinations if a group<br />

consists of individuals with similar views. In this case, deliberation contributes to shifting<br />

individual views toward the extreme.<br />

Group polarization is well-documented and is quite common in many deliberative settings.<br />

For example, law professors sympathetic to affirmative action after deliberation are likely to<br />

express a firmer support for this policy. Citizens somewhat favorable to gun control coming<br />

together to discuss possible gun control measures in the aftermath of a nation<strong>all</strong>y televised<br />

shooting are likely to endorse stricter measures. And a group of women concerned about the<br />

growing influence of feminism can be expected to develop a very strong opposition to feminism<br />

as a result of deliberation. 47<br />

A recently conducted study of jury deliberation offers a particularly convincing example of<br />

group polarization. 48 To determine whether jury deliberation contributes to group polarization,<br />

the study authors assembled more than 500 mock juries. The individuals were provided with<br />

informational materials about a personal injury case and asked to rate the punishment on a scale<br />

between 0 (no punishment) and 8. The participants were then randomly assigned to juries of six<br />

46<br />

47<br />

48<br />

Daniel J. Isenberg, "Group Polarization: A Critical Review and Meta-Analysis," Journal of Personality and<br />

Social Psychology 50 (1986).<br />

David G. Myers, "Discussion-Induced Attitude Polarization," Human Relations 28 (1975); Myers and Bishop,<br />

"Enhancement of Dominant Attitudes in Group Discussion."<br />

David Schkade, Cass R. Sunstein, and Daniel Kahneman, "Deliberating About Dollars: The Severity Shift,"<br />

Columbia Law Journal 100 (2000).<br />

267


members and instructed to reach consensus on the punishment. Common sense suggests that the<br />

consensus rating should approximate the average of the views represented on each jury. The<br />

actual results were quite different. Juries whose median pre-deliberation punishment rating was 4<br />

or higher produced an even higher consensus rating. Conversely, juries whose pre-deliberation<br />

rating was sm<strong>all</strong>er than 4 shifted toward an even lower consensus rating. It appears that<br />

deliberation amplifies a jury’s pre-deliberation tendency, whatever that tendency may be. 49<br />

Fortunately, polarization is not an inevitable feature of group deliberation. Just as<br />

deliberative groups under certain circumstances polarize, under other circumstances, they<br />

depolarize. Producing “depolarization” is a surprisingly straightforward process. It merely<br />

requires that opposing views within a group be represented in sufficiently high numbers. If this<br />

structural condition is met, deliberation is very likely to move the participants closer to the<br />

median view. Deliberation in this case produces the expected outcome – it fosters compromise,<br />

and perhaps even a consensus. To the extent that minority views are represented in roughly equal<br />

numbers, the evidence suggests that reputational cascades (or the tendency to conform to the<br />

majority’s view) do not occur.<br />

The data discussed in chapter 8 provides some evidence, albeit indirect, that even<br />

individuals holding what seem to be unshakeable moral views may not be immune to<br />

depolarization. Even religious and conservative voters norm<strong>all</strong>y opposed to abortion rights show<br />

a measure of support for federal funding of embryonic stem cell research. Similar tendencies can<br />

be observed in Congress, where a growing number of Republican leaders, including many<br />

opposed to abortion, have expressed their support for a stronger role of the government in<br />

supporting stem cell research. Although the evidence in this case is only anecdotal, it appears<br />

that having a family member or a friend affected by a devastating disease may have prompted<br />

many conservative voters and their Congressional representatives to reconsider their firm<br />

opposition to stem cell research.<br />

In short, deliberation as understood in this report increases the credibility of a process of<br />

public consultation. It may also contribute to producing broadly acceptable political<br />

compromises, but only if the consultative process is designed to prevent group polarization and<br />

cascades. This can be accomplished by ensuring that the broadest possible range of societal<br />

positions is heard, and that these views are represented in roughly equal numbers.<br />

10.7.2 Other Features<br />

In addition to deliberation, institutions of public consultation have other distinctive features.<br />

Before diving into specifics, however, a qualification is in order. Throughout this report, we<br />

frequently use the term “consultation” instead of the more common “participation.” The term<br />

“public participation” has generated both considerable interest and considerable confusion, in<br />

large measure because its advocates often fail to specify the role public participation should play<br />

in the administrative and regulatory context. This becomes especi<strong>all</strong>y problematic at the federal<br />

49<br />

Sunstein, Why Societies Need Dissent, p.114.<br />

268


level, where bureaucratic authority and technical expertise clash against popular expectations to<br />

substanti<strong>all</strong>y affecting the decision-making process.<br />

Public consultation as understood in this report is a tool to correct political failures and to<br />

mitigate agency capture, not a means to subvert the federal system of governance. 50 Institutions<br />

of public consultations are designed to strengthen the credibility of and trust in our system of<br />

representative democracy. Views gathered through a process of public consultation should play<br />

an important role in agency decision-making, but they should not mechanic<strong>all</strong>y translate into a<br />

specific course of action. The relationship between Congress, the office of the president, the<br />

administrative state, advocacy and interest groups, and the general public is a complex one that<br />

cannot be reduced to simple normative expectations. 51<br />

Target audience: Because this report is focused on federal regulatory institutions, references<br />

to the general public always identify the entire U.S. population, i.e., a population of individual<br />

citizens endowed with certain rights and obligations, as opposed to a population of stakeholders<br />

such as trade groups, scientific societies, or religious organizations. Obviously, individual<br />

citizens may represent specific social groups; their views are likely to reflect specific social,<br />

ethnic, or racial backgrounds. But a process of public consultation is not designed to elicit groupspecific<br />

views. Rather, it affords the public as a whole a chance to be heard. Accordingly, no<br />

efforts are made to include group-specific views. This is not to say that these views are<br />

unimportant, just that there are already plenty of opportunities for them to be heard in other<br />

settings.<br />

Representativeness: As a practical matter, it is impossible to envisage a mechanism of<br />

public consultation that is liter<strong>all</strong>y inclusive of the entire U.S. population. As such, the public<br />

participating in the consultative process should be a sample large enough to be representative of<br />

the U.S. population with regard to the usual socio-demographic variables. We believe that this is<br />

not only an acceptable compromise, but that in a sense, a randomly selected sample of the U.S.<br />

population may even be superior to traditional voting. For example, a representative sample<br />

ensures that the views of social groups unlikely to go to the polls are being included. It also<br />

ensures that these views are not interpreted and misused by political entrepreneurs for their own<br />

self-interested purposes.<br />

Knowledgeability: A consultative process seeks to elicit informed opinions. This<br />

requirement sets consultative processes apart from classic polls and shields them against the<br />

common – and often justified – criticism that opinion surveys reflect uninformed views. By<br />

making sure that the participating public has an opportunity to familiarize itself with complex<br />

policy questions, an institution of public consultation takes on a role the news media are<br />

expected to play but are increasingly unlikely to meet.<br />

50<br />

51<br />

William F. Funk, "Regulatory Negotiation and the Subversion of the Public Interest," Duke Law Journal 46<br />

(1997).<br />

We discuss this question in more depth in chapter 11.<br />

269


Deliberation: This requirement has already been discussed at length, so we can keep this<br />

discussion short. An institution of public consultation is deliberative in the following sense: It<br />

encourages mutual understanding among the members of the general public, and it encourages<br />

crafting broadly acceptable political compromises (i.e., it promotes group depolarization). What<br />

deliberation is not expected to produce is consensus or unanimity.<br />

Balance: A mechanism of public consultation should be designed to facilitate the<br />

articulation of <strong>all</strong> views. This means that each view should be equ<strong>all</strong>y represented independently<br />

of its actual political weight. Balance is required to prevent deliberative groups from<br />

polarizing. 52<br />

10.8 Institutional Options<br />

Evaluating institutions of public participation presents a ch<strong>all</strong>enge. There have been some<br />

efforts in the literature to identify universal evaluative criteria, but these efforts have been<br />

hampered by a lack of attention for the administrative and legal context in which participatory<br />

initiatives take place. 53 These works have proposed both substantive and procedural criteria that<br />

would make a process of public participation effective, but since effectiveness can only be<br />

measured against a specific goal, and the goal is not always clearly defined, these criteria are of<br />

little help to our discussion. For this reason, the mechanisms of public consultation examined in<br />

the remainder of this section are evaluated largely against the constitutive attributes of an<br />

institution of public consultation as we envisage it in this report.<br />

The mechanisms of public consultation we discuss in the next two sections are the public<br />

hearing and the consensus conference. Other institutions of public consultation exist, including<br />

citizens’ panels, 54 citizens’ juries, 55 and focus groups. 56 We discuss only public hearings and<br />

consensus conferences for two main reasons. Public hearings remain by far the administrators’<br />

52<br />

53<br />

54<br />

55<br />

56<br />

A careful reader may point out that this and the first attribute are mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive. A closer examination<br />

shows that this is actu<strong>all</strong>y not the case. It is always possible, at least in principle, to assemble a representative<br />

sample of the general population in which each view is shared by an equal number of citizens.<br />

Gene Rowe and Lynn J. Frewer, "Public Participation Methods: A Framework for Evaluation," Science,<br />

Technology and Human Values 25, no. 1 (2000); Thomas Webler, " 'Right' Discourse in Citizen Participation:<br />

An Evaluative Yardstick," in Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation: Evaluating Models for<br />

Environmental Discourse, ed. Ortwin Renn, Thomas Webler, and Peter Wiedemann (Dordrecht, the Netherlands:<br />

Kluwer Academic, 1995).<br />

John S. Applegate, "Beyond the Usual Suspects: The Use of Citizens Advisory Boards in Environmental<br />

Decisionmaking," Indiana Law Journal 73 (1998); Bradbury and Branch, "An Evaluation of the Effectiveness of<br />

Local Site-Specific Advisory Boards for U.S. Department of Energy Environmental Restoration Program.";<br />

Susan L. Santos and Caron Chess, "Evaluating Citizen Advisory Boards: The Importance of Theory and<br />

Participant-Based Criteria and Practical Implications," Risk Analysis 23, no. 2 (2003).<br />

David Dunkerley and Peter Glasner, "Empowering the Public? Citizens' Juries and the New Genetic<br />

Technologies," Critical Public Health 8, no. 3 (1998); Wendy Kenyon, Ceara Nevin, and Nick Hanley,<br />

"Enhancing Environmental Decision-Making Using Citizens’ Juries," Local Environment 8, no. 2 (2003); David<br />

Price, "Choices without Reasons: Citizens' Juries and Policy Evaluation," Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (2000).<br />

Gregor Dürrenberger, Hans Kastenholz, and Jeannette Behringer, "Integrated Assessment Focus Groups:<br />

Bridging the Gap between Science and Policy?," Science and Public Policy 26, no. 5 (1999).<br />

270


method of choice at <strong>all</strong> levels of government, and as such deserve to be closely scrutinized.<br />

Consensus conferences, on the other end, are perhaps the most interesting and most promising<br />

method of public participation developed in recent times. Other methods of public participation<br />

either are not sufficiently distinct from consensus conferences to justify a separate discussion, or<br />

are less innovative.<br />

10.8.1 Public Hearings<br />

Public hearings are the oldest and most common form of public participation. Over the last<br />

40 years, administrators from the local to the federal level have routinely relied on public<br />

hearings to test the public mood on any number of issues, ranging from room-tax collection in<br />

Puerto Rico to the use of locomotive train horns at highway-rail crossings in Illinois and Ohio,<br />

from open-flame mattress flammability standards in California to inner-city Brownfield cleanup<br />

efforts by the EPA and the disposal of nuclear wastes at Yucca mountain in Nevada by the DOE.<br />

A public hearing gener<strong>all</strong>y consists of an introductory presentation by the convening agency.<br />

The presentation is meant to convey basic, factual information to the public. The presentation is<br />

followed by a question-and-answer session. The Q&A session gives the public an opportunity to<br />

ask for clarifications on technical matters, and is not intended to foster dialogue between agency<br />

officials and the public. After the Q&A session, the public has a chance to make public<br />

statements, followed by a response by the public officials. Administrative agencies often<br />

reconfigure the basic structure of a public hearing depending on the circumstances, but the<br />

elements just described are gener<strong>all</strong>y included.<br />

Judged by the criteria laid out in the preceding section, public hearings are a poor<br />

mechanism of public consultation. They do a poor job of conveying complex and controversial<br />

technical information to the general public. Nor is the goal of a public hearing to adjudicate<br />

among conflicting scientific claims. At a hearing, scientists tend to provide even prosaic<br />

scientific information in an obscure technical language. 57 Deliberation as we have defined it in<br />

this report is simply is not present. Q&A sessions are exactly what their name suggests – an<br />

opportunity to clarify details, not a forum for discussing complex technical or policy questions.<br />

Testimonies given by the public are not meant to be deliberative, and public officials do not treat<br />

them as such. Statements and rebuttals are reminiscent of a jury trial rather than a deliberative<br />

forum. The participants in a public hearing are anything but representative of the general public.<br />

At the federal level at least, but often at lower administrative levels as well, only well-organized<br />

advocacy groups have both the resources and the expertise to participate in a meaningful way.<br />

Lay participants tend to be poorly informed and overwhelmed by technicalities, and are quickly<br />

marginalized. In sum, public hearings disregard representativeness and knowledgeability, are not<br />

deliberative, and tend to exacerbate political failures – hardly a sound foundation on which to<br />

build new institutions of public consultation.<br />

57<br />

There is good reason for this: The use of scientific jargon insulates experts from public criticism and reinforces<br />

their authority vis-à-vis the general public.<br />

271


One may wonder why public hearings remain so popular among public administrators if<br />

they are such a poor institution of public consultation. There are several good reasons for this<br />

situation. Public agencies with a statutory mandate to solicit input from the public regard them as<br />

a quick and cheap way to form<strong>all</strong>y meet their administrative obligations. In addition, public<br />

hearings can be manipulated to minimize ch<strong>all</strong>enges to the agency’s preferred policy option.<br />

Since the agency controls the logistical aspects of the decision-making process, it can choose to<br />

convene a public hearing when fundamental policy choices have already been made. If an<br />

agency expects the proposed policy to trigger strong criticism, it can decide to exclude the most<br />

controversial issues from the agenda. Alternatively, it can convene the hearing on a day and at a<br />

time that is likely to make it difficult for critics to participate.<br />

Hearings are popular among administrators also because they provide an opportunity to<br />

strengthen their relationship with key political constituencies. Organized interest groups are<br />

predictable, their positions don’t change abruptly, and they master the technical and legal<br />

language necessary to communicate effectively with public administrators. By contrast,<br />

laypersons are often viewed as unpredictable, irrational, and poorly informed. In addition, the<br />

agency can credibly describe its effort to reach out to its core constituencies as an adequate<br />

approach to soliciting public input. Well-organized interest groups, for their part, welcome<br />

public hearings because they afford them an opportunity to restate their positions in a public<br />

setting. <strong>Final</strong>ly, public hearings are useful to the agency because they may warn of upcoming<br />

legal ch<strong>all</strong>enges. Against this background, it should come as no surprise that the available<br />

empirical evidence suggests that despite their popularity, public hearings have very little impact<br />

on agency behavior. 58<br />

10.8.2 Consensus Conferences<br />

Consensus conferences have been described by some commentators as a promising<br />

institutional mechanism for democratizing political choices involving controversial technological<br />

developments. 59 In this section, we briefly examine the history of this participatory instrument<br />

58<br />

59<br />

Barry Checkoway, "The Politics of Public Hearings," Journal of Applied Behavioral Science 17, no. 4 (1981);<br />

Richard L. Cole and David A. Caputo, "The Public Hearing as an Effective Citizen Participation Mechanism: A<br />

Case Study of the General Revenue Sharing Program," American Political Science Review 78, no. 2 (1984);<br />

Carol Ebdon, "Beyond the Public Hearing: Citizen Participation in the Local Government Budget Process,"<br />

Journal of Public Budgeting, Accounting and Financial Management 14, no. 2 (2002); Daniel J. Fiorino,<br />

"Citizen Participation and Environmental Risk: A Survey of Institutional Mechanisms," Science, Technology and<br />

Human Values 15, no. 2 (1990), p.230-31; Tom Lando, "The Public Hearing Process: A Tool for Citizen<br />

Participation, or a Path toward Alienation?," National Civic Review 92, no. 1 (2003); Jeanne Nelson Ratliff, "The<br />

Politics of Nuclear Waste: An Analysis of a Public Hearing on the Proposed Yucca Mountain Nuclear Waste<br />

Repository," Communication Studies 48, no. 4 (1997); Rowe and Frewer, "Public Participation Methods: A<br />

Framework for Evaluation," p.18.<br />

Edna F. Einsiedel and Deborah K. Eastlick, "Consensus Conferences as Deliberative Democracy," Science<br />

Communication 21, no. 4 (2000); David H. Guston, "Evaluating the First U.S. Consensus Conference: The<br />

Impact of the Citizens’ Panel on Telecommunications and the Future of Democracy," Science, Technology and<br />

Human Values 24, no. 4 (1999); Simon Joss, "Toward the Public Sphere – Reflections on the Development of<br />

Participatory Technology Assessment," Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 22, no. 3 (2002); Myung-Sik<br />

272


and lay out its main elements. We then discuss whether this approach can be considered a<br />

suitable mechanism of public consultation as defined in section 10.7.<br />

Consensus conferences are nothing new. NIH has been using them in their original form<br />

since the 1970s as a means to bridge the gap between medical research and clinical practice. 60 As<br />

practiced by NIH, the goal of a consensus conference is to craft a consensus among leading<br />

clinical researchers on the best available treatment for a medical condition. It is a collaborative<br />

effort by clinical researchers to resolve a professional controversy over the merits of alternative<br />

therapies. This seems an eminently sensible way to assist practitioners with no access to a<br />

university hospital. 61<br />

In the mid-1980s, the Danish Board of Technology, an institution inspired by the U.S.<br />

Office of Technology Assessment, made the consensus conference concept into a tool for<br />

consulting with the general public on new technological developments. 62 The Danish Board of<br />

Technology is an independent organization wholly funded by the Danish parliament and<br />

governed by a board of directors broadly representative of <strong>all</strong> major political constituencies. 63<br />

The board has a twofold mission: to advise the parliament on controversial policy questions and<br />

to stimulate a public debate on new technological developments. Since its creation, it has<br />

convened numerous consensus conferences on topics ranging from food irradiation to gene<br />

therapy and teleworking. The institutionalized position of the board, its independence, and its<br />

credibility ensure that the Danish parliament not only takes consensus recommendations<br />

seriously, but on occasion also adopts them. 64 The Danish example spurred numerous imitations.<br />

The Swiss government adopted a similar approach when it created the Office of Technology<br />

Assessment and gave it an advisory function. Like its Danish counterpart, this office has shown<br />

considerable interest in consensus conferences, known as “publiforums.” 65 In addition, as of this<br />

writing, Argentina, Australia, Canada, France, Germany, Israel, Japan, The Netherlands, New<br />

Zealand, Norway, South Korea, and Switzerland <strong>all</strong> have conducted at least one consensus<br />

60<br />

61<br />

62<br />

63<br />

64<br />

65<br />

Kim, "Cloning and Deliberation: Korean Consensus Conference," Developing World Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002);<br />

Derrick Purdue, "Experiments in the Governance of Biotechnology: A Case Study of the UK National<br />

Consensus Conference," New Genetics and Society 18, no. 1 (1999).<br />

A search in the New England Journal of Medicine produced more than 250 articles reporting on consensus<br />

conferences.<br />

Allan D. Sniderman, "Clinical Trials, Consensus Conferences, and Clinical Practice," Lancet 354; JoAnne<br />

Zujewski and Edison T. Liu, "The 1998 St. G<strong>all</strong>en's Consensus Conference: An Assessment," Journal of the<br />

National Cancer Institute 90 (1998).<br />

Simon Joss, "Danish Consensus Conferences as a Model of Participatory Technology Assessment: An Impact<br />

Study of Consensus Conferences on Danish Parliament and Danish Public Debate," Science and Public Policy<br />

25 (1998).<br />

See http://www.tekno.dk/subpage.php3?page=forside.php3&language=uk for more information.<br />

Joss, "Danish Consensus Conferences as a Model of Participatory Technology Assessment: An Impact Study of<br />

Consensus Conferences on Danish Parliament and Danish Public Debate."<br />

See http://www.ta-swiss.ch/framesets/projects-e.htm#publiforum for additional information.<br />

273


conference. Denmark is the clear leader among these countries, with 19 conferences organized<br />

since 1987. 66<br />

Consensus conferences have a straightforward structure: A steering committee is tasked with<br />

recruiting a panel of laypersons and selecting a group of experts representative of <strong>all</strong> societal<br />

sectors (industry, science, and consumers groups, among others). The appointment rules vary,<br />

but there is broad agreement among practitioners that the panel members should not have any<br />

ties to the industry being scrutinized, should not represent an advocacy group, and should not<br />

have strong views on the matter under consideration. In other words, they should not be<br />

prejudiced in favor of or against a given technology, and should represent only themselves. A<br />

panel gener<strong>all</strong>y consists of 12 to 20 citizens. Organizers often try to assemble a “balanced”<br />

panel, i.e., a panel that is at least somewhat representative of the general public with respect to<br />

key socio-demographic variables such as sex, age, education, and geographical origin.<br />

Operation<strong>all</strong>y, a consensus conference consists of three main stages. In the first stage, the<br />

lay participants have an opportunity to absorb basic scientific facts and uncontroversial technical<br />

details. The learning phase is followed by a deliberative phase, during which the panel has an<br />

opportunity to engage the experts and probe conflicting answers. The deliberative stage is<br />

usu<strong>all</strong>y conducted in the presence of a larger audience and representatives of the news media. In<br />

the third and final stage, the panel is charged with preparing a consensus statement. This final<br />

phase takes place behind closed doors.<br />

By <strong>all</strong> accounts, consensus conferences have a significant impact on both lay participants<br />

and the scientific experts. To lay participants, a consensus conference is a refreshing civic lesson.<br />

Without exception, the participants describe their experience as exhausting but also as a<br />

tremendous learning opportunity. For their part, experts are invariably surprised and impressed<br />

by how quickly laypersons learn to identify weak aspects of a scientific rationale and to question<br />

them in a competent way. Many of them develop a healthy respect for a lay audience’s ability to<br />

probe highly technical issues.<br />

Of more immediate interest to our discussion is the impact that deliberation may have on the<br />

participants’ views and opinions. As much of the work on consensus conferences is descriptive<br />

rather than analytical, answering this question is not entirely possible. Gener<strong>all</strong>y speaking, lay<br />

participants take participation in a consensus conference very seriously. Discussions often are<br />

informed by a genuinely disinterested perspective, while strategic behavior and self-interested<br />

motives, if not entirely absent, tend to recede into the background. In this sense, deliberation<br />

comes quite close to the Habermasian ideal of communicative action. On the other end, there is<br />

considerable anecdotal evidence that consensus conferences rarely produce a genuine consensus,<br />

and that consensus statements often are consensual only in name. Panelists have repeatedly<br />

pointed out that these statements must be regarded as a precarious compromise designed to mask<br />

sharply diverging views rather than a genuine expression of unanimity.<br />

66<br />

See http://www.loka.org/pages/worldpanels.htm for details.<br />

274


There is also some evidence that on occasion, deliberation has contributed to polarize the<br />

panelists. The first Canadian consensus conference on agricultural biotechnologies is a case in<br />

point. 67 As part of their evaluation efforts, before the conference, participants were asked to<br />

describe what images came to mind when they thought of agricultural biotechnology. According<br />

to the organizers, the lay participants had a rather negative view of agricultural biotechnologies.<br />

The skewed composition of the panel suggests that deliberation may have pushed the participants<br />

to espouse more radical views. Unfortunately, this question was not asked again after the<br />

conference, but there are some indications that the deliberative process did indeed exacerbate the<br />

panel’s negative views of agricultural biotechnologies; news reports about the conference noted<br />

that the panel consensus statement, while <strong>all</strong>owing that agricultural biotechnology could have<br />

some benefits, had identified a long litany of concerns. 68<br />

There is a simple explanation for the tendency displayed by some of these panels to polarize.<br />

The organizers of these events make considerable efforts to assemble a “balanced” panel by<br />

recruiting lay participants on the basis of the usual socio-demographic variables. For example,<br />

they will ensure that the panel consists of an equal number of women and men, and that <strong>all</strong> ages<br />

and education levels are represented. By contrast, it is not clear that pre-deliberation attitudes<br />

toward specific policy options are systematic<strong>all</strong>y taken into account, or that a panel is balanced<br />

not only with regard to key socio-demographic variables, but also with respect to predeliberation<br />

views and opinions.<br />

Their undeniable appeal notwithstanding, it is fair to say that consensus conferences have<br />

not played a major role as mechanisms of public consultation, nor have they affected important<br />

legislative or regulatory choices, perhaps with the exception of the Danish consensus<br />

conferences. There are both implementation and conceptual reasons for this state of affairs. From<br />

a practical standpoint, consensus conferences are not sufficiently focused on a specific policy<br />

questions to have an impact on politicians and senior administrators. The first United Stated<br />

consensus conference on new information technology provides an illustration. It took place just a<br />

few months after the passage of a major bill, the 1996 Telecommunications Act, and could<br />

therefore no longer affect the legislative choices. Even if it had taken place earlier, it would not<br />

have affected the legislative process, for one simple reason: The lay panelists made a conscious<br />

decision not to focus on specific policy questions, opting instead to examine a host of rather<br />

generic issues. 69 The fact that the conference took place in Boston and not in Washington, D.C.,<br />

certainly didn’t make it easier for these lay panelists to have a measurable impact on national<br />

politics.<br />

There are also more general reasons for the negligible role consensus conferences have<br />

played in policy-making. Chief among them is their uncertain and precarious place in the<br />

67<br />

68<br />

69<br />

Einsiedel and Eastlick, "Consensus Conferences as Deliberative Democracy."<br />

Ibid.<br />

Guston, "Evaluating the First U.S. Consensus Conference: The Impact of the Citizens’ Panel on<br />

Telecommunications and the Future of Democracy."<br />

275


legislative and regulatory process. Consensus conferences are not initiated by regulators or the<br />

legislative branch. Members of parliament and regulators therefore regard them with<br />

considerable skepticism, as the first British consensus conference on agricultural biotechnology<br />

demonstrated. At the end of the conference, Lord Howie of Troon, chair of the Lords Select<br />

Committee on Biotechnology, after offering the obligatory laudatory remarks went on to explain<br />

in no uncertain terms that the consensus conference report would have no influence on the<br />

parliament. 70<br />

Apparently, the organizers of the first German consensus conference on<br />

reproductive technologies received a similarly frosty reaction from members of the German<br />

parliament.<br />

That legislators and bureaucrats are not willing to relinquish their authority is not surprising.<br />

Consensus conferences may be perceived as an attempt to shift the center of political gravity<br />

from elected representatives and government bureaucracies to the general public. They also<br />

undermine well-established administrative norms. Yet it would be shortsighted to conclude that<br />

the main reason for the failure of consensus conferences to influence national politics is the<br />

(understandable) tendency of politicians and bureaucrats to protect their turf. Just as important is<br />

the naïve understanding of the public, of democracy, and of democratic participation displayed<br />

by advocates of participatory methods. One can hardly fault politicians for pointing out that that<br />

unlike a lay panel, a parliament is a far better and more legitimate representation of the general<br />

public.<br />

An important lesson to be learned from consensus conferences is that size matters.<br />

Organizers of consensus conferences often invest inordinate amounts of time and financial<br />

resources to ensure “balance,” but invariably convene exceedingly sm<strong>all</strong> panels. For example,<br />

organizers of the 2001 German consensus conference on reproductive medicine invested<br />

approximately two years recruiting a panel of only 19 members. 71 Other organizers of consensus<br />

conferences have managed to recruit panels of laypersons much faster by focusing on their<br />

regions. The U.S. consensus conference on telecommunication and the Canadian consensus<br />

conference on agricultural biotechnology took this approach. Yet promoters of consensus<br />

conferences have never attempted to broaden participation beyond the usual dozen citizens.<br />

In sum, consensus conferences can be considered deliberative as we understand this term.<br />

They can also be said to rely on knowledgeable panelists. However, consensus conferences, like<br />

most other tools of public participation, do not ensure representativeness, and while they may be<br />

balanced in terms of key socio-demographic variables, they may be unbalanced with respect to<br />

pre-deliberative views and opinions. In its present form, therefore, a consensus conference is not<br />

a viable institutional option.<br />

70<br />

71<br />

Purdue, "Experiments in the Governance of Biotechnology: A Case Study of the UK National Consensus<br />

Conference," p.92.<br />

Silke Schicktanz and Jörg Naumann, eds., Bürgerkonferenz: Streitf<strong>all</strong> Gendiagnostik. Ein Modellprojekt Der<br />

Bürgerbeteiligung Am Bioethischen Diskurs (Dresden: Deutsches Hygiene-Museum, 2003) p.57-68.<br />

276


10.9 Public Participation at the Federal Level<br />

The post-World War II era has witnessed a continuous expansion of public participation<br />

efforts in administrative decision-making. “Public participation” originates in the concept of selfgovernance,<br />

a concept that, like accountability, is at the core of many American institutions of<br />

government. Numerous instances of federal statutes include provisions for public involvement<br />

above and beyond the requirements of the Administrative Procedure Act. Among these statutes<br />

are the National Environmental Policy Act of 1969, the Resource Conservation and Recovery<br />

Act of 1994, the Comprehensive Environmental Response, Compensation, and Liability Act of<br />

1980, and the Endangered Species Act of 1973. Other statutes that mandate public participation<br />

are the Clean Water Act of 1972 72 and the Federal Advisory Committee Act of 1972. 73 The<br />

Onshore Oil and Gas Leasing Reform Act of 1987 requires public participation before issuing a<br />

lease of public lands. 74 Agencies such as the EPA and the DOE have promulgated regulations<br />

that mandate public involvement for a variety of federal statutes. For example, 40 C.F.R. 25.7<br />

(1989) requires establishing citizen advisory groups under the Clean Water Act, the Resource<br />

Conservation and Recovery Act, and the Safe Drinking Water Act.<br />

Statutes requiring broader public participation in the rule-making process reflect mainly the<br />

expectation that public involvement will increase confidence in federal agencies operating in<br />

controversial regulatory environments and prevent conflicts and reduce litigation. For this<br />

reason, federal regulators’ experience in implementing these provisions is of considerable<br />

interest to our discussion. As we show in the remainder of this chapter, these expectations often<br />

are not met, partly because Congress provides precious little guidance on how an agency should<br />

implement these provisions, but also because these statutes do not address the inherent tension<br />

between administrative prerogatives and public demands. Confronted with a host of difficult<br />

implementation questions, an unpredictable, noisy, and uninformed public, and aggressive<br />

interest groups, federal agencies have responded by adopting administrative strategies that<br />

minimize public input by restricting the scope of public comments, by soliciting public input at a<br />

late stage in the policy-making process, and by relying heavily on public hearings. In short,<br />

statutory provisions mandating public involvement have often not produced the expected results.<br />

In the next two sections, we elaborate on these themes by focusing on two statutes, the National<br />

Environmental Policy Act (NEPA) and the Comprehensive Environmental Response,<br />

Compensation, and Liability Act (CERCLA).<br />

72<br />

73<br />

74<br />

See 33 U.S.C. 1251(e) (1994).<br />

See 5 U.S.C. 1-15 (1972).<br />

See 30 U.S.C.A. 226(f) (1986).<br />

277


10.9.1 The National Environmental Policy Act of 1969<br />

NEPA is often referred to as the father of <strong>all</strong> environmental statutes, the “Magna Carta” of<br />

the environmental movement – and with good reason. 75 With NEPA, Congress enacted a very<br />

ambitious statute that, among other things, was supposed to “encourage productive and enjoyable<br />

harmony between man and his environment; to promote efforts which will prevent or eliminate<br />

damage to the environment and biosphere and stimulate the health and welfare of man […].” 76<br />

The centerpiece of these efforts is the environmental impact statement (EIS), a detailed<br />

description of possible negative impacts on the environment. Section 102(C) of the statute<br />

requires the agency to make the EIS, along with comments from other federal agencies with<br />

relevant expertise, available to the general public for comments. Following the statute’s passage,<br />

the Council on Environmental Quality (CEQ), the executive office administering NEPA,<br />

promulgated numerous regulations that translated these rather generic requirements into specific<br />

obligations.<br />

NEPA does not establish specific performance standards. It achieves its main goal<br />

procedur<strong>all</strong>y by requiring federal agencies to develop methods and techniques to study the<br />

impact of their endeavor on the natural environment and to make a “determination of<br />

significance” thereof. In this, NEPA was a visionary statute, anticipating by more than 20 years<br />

modern tools of environmental management such as the ISO14000 set of standards. NEPA also<br />

fosters what could be described as a dialogue with the public: Agencies have an obligation to<br />

inform the public about a project’s environmental impact by disseminating the EIS. The public,<br />

for its part, is given an opportunity to improve on the quality of the analysis by submitting<br />

comments.<br />

There is no doubt that NEPA has been widely successful in broadening the decision-making<br />

process beyond contractual stakeholders. Environmental groups quickly recognized that the<br />

rhetoric of “public participation” would have shifted the center of political gravity from the<br />

agencies and their closest clients to a much larger universe of advocacy groups, neighborhood<br />

associations, ad hoc citizens’ coalitions, and just plain folks. Legislators had hoped that a more<br />

inclusive process of decision-making would have increased the legitimacy of the final outcome<br />

and reduced litigation. More than 35 years after the enactment of this statute, it has become clear<br />

that NEPA, far from quelling public controversies over federal projects, has actu<strong>all</strong>y contributed<br />

to amplifying them. The end result, according to some commentators, has been both<br />

administrative paralysis and litigiousness.<br />

The fact that consulting with the public has in some cases paralyzed the bureaucratic<br />

machinery is not necessarily an indication of political failure. One could argue that injecting<br />

public views and <strong>all</strong>owing environmental groups to comment on proposed projects actu<strong>all</strong>y has<br />

contributed to correcting a political failure characterized by distorted planning processes in<br />

75<br />

76<br />

Michael C. Blumm, "The National Environmental Policy Act at Twenty: A Preface," Environmental Law 20<br />

(1990).<br />

See P.L. 91-190, Section 2.<br />

278


which only business and developers’ interests were effectively represented. Yet it is hard to<br />

avoid the conclusion that over time, this welcome correction has degenerated into unjustifiable<br />

administrative paralysis. 77<br />

To appreciate the reasons for this state of affairs, a brief discussion of the rules of public<br />

participation under NEPA is necessary. Per CEQ regulations, NEPA requires an agency to<br />

prepare an EIS for <strong>all</strong> “major actions significantly affecting the quality of the human<br />

environment.” It is the agency’s responsibility to determine whether the proposed action should<br />

be considered “major” and whether its impact on the environment is “significant.” If the<br />

proposed action is not deemed major, then it is not subject to NEPA’s provisions. If a project is<br />

thought to be major but its impact is not “significant,” then the proposing agency needs only<br />

prepare a much-less-demanding environmental statement focusing on whether the proposed<br />

action may have a significant impact on the human environment. Whether a project is considered<br />

significant is, once again, a determination made by the agency itself. 78<br />

The 1978 CEQ regulations lay out in some detail the procedural rules governing the<br />

preparation of an EIS. The first step is c<strong>all</strong>ed “scoping.” During scoping, the agency determines<br />

which issues should be considered and how they should be ranked. Scoping requires input from<br />

other agencies as well as the general public. The public may provide comments in writing or at<br />

meetings organized by the agency. Following scoping, the agency prepares a draft EIS, which it<br />

makes available to the general public for comment. Interested parties must be given a minimum<br />

of 45 days to respond.<br />

CEQ regulations are more demanding than APA requirements in that they <strong>all</strong>ow more time<br />

for response; they also require the agency not only to announce the publication of the draft EIS<br />

in the Federal Register, but also to actively solicit comments from “those persons or<br />

organizations who may be interested or affected.” 79<br />

This usu<strong>all</strong>y means announcing the<br />

publication of the draft EIS in local papers and notification by mail. In addition, CEQ regulations<br />

require the agency to hold public hearings on the draft EIS if there is “substantial environmental<br />

controversy concerning the proposed action or substantial interest in holding the hearing […].” 80<br />

After receiving comments from the public and from other agencies, the proposing agency<br />

produces the final EIS. The public again has 30 days after publication of the final EIS to<br />

comment before the agency makes it final determination, described in the “record of decision,”<br />

or ROD. The ROD must, among other things, state the agency decision and the alternatives<br />

77<br />

78<br />

79<br />

80<br />

As for example in the case of decision-making and the National Forest Service. Cf. Stark Ackerman,<br />

"Observations on the Transformation of the Forest Service: The Effects of NEPA on Forest Service Decision<br />

Making," Environmental Law 20 (1990), p.710.<br />

William Murray Tabb, "The Role of Controversy in NEPA: Reconciling Public Veto with Public Participation in<br />

Environmental Decisionmaking," William and Mary Environmental Law and Policy Review 21 (1997), p.185-92.<br />

See 40 C.F.R. 1503.1(a)(4).<br />

See 40 C.F.R. 1506.6(c).<br />

279


considered in the process, identify the preferable alternatives from an environmental standpoint,<br />

81 82<br />

and discuss the criteria used to make the final determination.<br />

This seems an eminently rational and transparent way to structure a complex decisionmaking<br />

process, one with ample opportunity for <strong>all</strong> interested and affected parties to be heard.<br />

Yet the (somewhat naïve) hope that a broader process of public involvement would produce<br />

strong public support for bureaucratic decisions rarely has materialized. A case in point is the<br />

U.S. Army Corps of Engineers, which in the late 1970s became a frequent target of<br />

environmental groups’ discontent after NEPA provided a systematic opportunity to ch<strong>all</strong>enge the<br />

Corps approach to waterway management. In a short time, the agency went from an organization<br />

proud of its engineering accomplishments to a paralyzed bureaucracy incapable of meeting its<br />

public mandate. 83<br />

That broader public involvement produced more controversy is not entirely surprising given<br />

the history of technocratic decision-making at many federal agencies. Public servants<br />

tradition<strong>all</strong>y have privileged technical expertise over processes of public consultation, in part<br />

because of dominant professional norms, but also as a means to protect their power and<br />

authority. By <strong>all</strong>owing the public to participate in a hitherto bureaucratic process of decisionmaking,<br />

the cultural clash between administrative culture and pluralist impulses became visible.<br />

Whereas agency representatives had tradition<strong>all</strong>y emphasized and cultivated technical expertise,<br />

representatives of interest groups and members of the general public espoused a pluralist view of<br />

public policy, one in which every view is equ<strong>all</strong>y legitimate.<br />

From a bureaucratic standpoint, public participation can be reduced to two basic steps: The<br />

agency “informs” the public about its plans, and the public registers with the agency its<br />

disagreement and discontent. To the extent that an agency relies on input provided by the public,<br />

it does so to ensure that it has complied with its procedural requirements. An actual dialogue,<br />

even in embryonic form, does not take place. On the one end, the agency deems the public<br />

simply incapable of appreciating the technical complexities involved in preparing an EIS; on the<br />

other, the public perceives the agency as incapable or unwilling to provide technical information<br />

in a clear and transparent way.<br />

Pluralism has profoundly affected not only how the general public and interest groups view<br />

government bureaucracies, but also how public administrators interpret their mandate to involve<br />

the public. In a sense, administrators unconsciously have absorbed the main tenets of public<br />

choice theory – that citizens, like any other individuals in the political arena, are rational<br />

individuals with fixed preferences exclusively interested in maximizing their private utility. In<br />

81<br />

82<br />

83<br />

Paul J. Culhane, "NEPA's Impacts on Federal Agencies, Anticipated and Unanticipated," Environmental Law 20<br />

(1990), p.691-93; Jonathan Poisner, "A Civic Republican Perspective on the National Environmental Policy<br />

Act's Process for Citizen Participation," Environmental Law 26 (1996), p.68-75.<br />

See 40 C.F.R. 1505.2(a)-(c) (1995).<br />

Daniel A. Mazmanian and Jeanne Nienaber, Can Organizations Change? Environmental Protection, Citizen<br />

Participation and the Corps of Engineers (Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution, 1979).<br />

280


this view of politics, there is no space for lofty concepts such as deliberation, reciprocal<br />

understanding, and the pursuit of the public good.<br />

This rather cynical view of public involvement has immediate practical consequences.<br />

Public administrators, not expecting participatory processes to produce anything even remotely<br />

resembling a consensus, are very unlikely to consider the impact of alternative institutions of<br />

public participation on the quality of the participatory process. A pluralist view of public<br />

participation is often a self-fulfilling prophecy: By assuming that participants have fixed<br />

preferences and that no room for compromise exists, it ignores institutional options that may<br />

reduce group polarization and may actu<strong>all</strong>y contribute to exacerbating the initial differences. Not<br />

coincident<strong>all</strong>y, then, many federal agencies, while superfici<strong>all</strong>y complying with CEQ regulations<br />

and court rulings, have used their administrative power to channel and restrict public<br />

participation in myriad ways, further exacerbating the pathologies of a technocratic decisionmaking<br />

process. 84<br />

10.9.2 The Comprehensive Environmental Response, Compensation, and Liability Act of 1980<br />

In 1976, recognizing the need to protect Americans from the health risks produced by<br />

hazardous waste sites, Congress passed the Resources Conservation and Recovery Act<br />

(RCRA). 85 RCRA is a prospective statute: It addresses future hazardous waste releases but<br />

ignores the health risks created by pre-existing hazardous wastes. To reduce these risks and to<br />

promote the cleanup of old industrial sites, Congress enacted the Comprehensive Environmental<br />

Response, Compensation, and Liability Act in 1980. 86 CERCLA instructs the EPA to develop<br />

plans for cleaning up the nation’s hazardous waste sites and imposes “several joint liabilities” on<br />

responsible parties. What this means exactly has been the subject of much litigation, but the<br />

original legislative intent is fairly clear: Past and present owners of a contaminated industrial site<br />

are jointly responsible for the clean-up costs.<br />

From the very beginning the relationship between the affected populations –(often poor,<br />

African-American, or Latino communities) and the agency administering the statute (the EPA)<br />

has been strained. In its original form, CERLCA provided very limited opportunities for these<br />

populations to comment on EPA clean-up plans. 87<br />

The agency’s credibility was severely<br />

undermined when several studies in the 1980s showed that the EPA was apparently much more<br />

solicitous in cleaning up hazardous waste sites located in white neighborhoods than those in the<br />

84<br />

85<br />

86<br />

87<br />

Perkins Spyke, "Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking at the New Millenium: Structuring New<br />

Spheres of Public Influence," p.277-80; Tabb, "The Role of Controversy in NEPA: Reconciling Public Veto with<br />

Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking," p.177-86.<br />

See 42 U.S.C. 6901-6999k (1988).<br />

See 42 U.S.C. 9601-9675 (1994).<br />

Adam N. Bram, "Public Participation Provisions Need Not Contribute to Environmental Injustice," Temple<br />

Political and Civil Rights Law Review 5 (1996), p.161.<br />

281


vicinity of black residential areas. 88 The preparation of the clean-up plan, a key element of the<br />

statute, quickly became a major source of concern for the affected populations and the focal<br />

point of the confrontation between the EPA and local environmental groups. One EPA official<br />

reportedly characterized the relationship between the agency and minority populations as one in<br />

which the EPA initiates remediation action with “negative trust.”<br />

The Superfund Amendments Reauthorization Act (SARA) of 1986 partly remedied this<br />

disastrous situation. 89 Under SARA, the EPA must notify the affected populations of its plans to<br />

remove hazardous wastes or remediate a site. SARA gives the EPA the authority to c<strong>all</strong> public<br />

hearings as a means to inform the public about the proposed clean-up plan. The plan must<br />

describe the clean-up alternatives considered, identify the preferred option, and provide a<br />

rationale for the agency’s choice. The EPA also must provide extensive information about the<br />

plan itself; in other words, it must attach a description of the plan in non-technical language. The<br />

public has 30 days (extensible to 60 days) to submit written comments. The EPA must respond<br />

to any “significant comment” through a “responsiveness summary” and take into account any<br />

new information it receives. The agency must then notify the public of any changes made to the<br />

original clean-up plan. The responsiveness summary becomes part of the administrative record<br />

and must also be made available to the public. To assist and facilitate the participatory process,<br />

technical assistance grants (TAGs) are available. TAGs are meant to help local organizations to<br />

educate themselves in highly complex technical matters such as analyzing technical reports and<br />

clean-up plans. The public also has the right to judicial review of any regulation promulgated<br />

under the statute. <strong>Final</strong>ly, SARA authorizes citizen suits against the EPA for failure to perform<br />

nondiscretionary duties. 90<br />

The EPA did not wait for the Superfund Amendments Reauthorization Act of 1986 to<br />

implement its own outreach measures. Its community relations program, adopted in 1981, was<br />

designed to improve communication with the affected populations. Among the activities<br />

included are the early-stage involvement of local community members in characterizing the site,<br />

the identification of key community leaders and interested parties, the establishment of a location<br />

for information depositories and public hearings, and the appointment of an EPA community<br />

coordinator. The most recent description of the EPA’s approach to community involvement is<br />

contained in two documents, the Superfund Community Involvement Handbook 91<br />

and the<br />

88<br />

89<br />

90<br />

91<br />

Vicki Been, "What's Fairness Got to Do with It? Environmental Justice and the Siting of Loc<strong>all</strong>y Undesirable<br />

Land Uses," Cornell Law Review 78 (1993); United Church of Christ Commission for Racial Justice, Toxic<br />

Waste and Race in the United States: A National <strong>Report</strong> on the Racial and Socioeconomic Characteristics of<br />

Communities with Hazardous Waste Sites (New York: Public Access, 1987).<br />

See Pub. Law. No. 99-499, 100 Stat. 1613 (1986).<br />

Bram, "Public Participation Provisions Need Not Contribute to Environmental Injustice."; Ellison Folk, "Public<br />

Participation in the Superfund Cleanup Process," Ecology Law Quarterly 18 (1991), p.193-95; Perkins Spyke,<br />

"Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking at the New Millenium: Structuring New Spheres of<br />

Public Influence," p.284-85.<br />

See http://www.epa.gov/superfund/tools/cag/ci_handbook.pdf.<br />

282


Superfund Community Involvement Toolkit. 92<br />

As even a cursory examination of these<br />

documents and the related online resources shows, the EPA has made enormous efforts to inform<br />

and involve the affected populations.<br />

There is no doubt that the EPA has become much more sophisticated and effective in<br />

dealing with what continues to be a very delicate public controversy. In other respects, however,<br />

the EPA has not been able to reconcile community demands with bureaucratic authority and<br />

expectations from former property owners. Offici<strong>all</strong>y, the EPA has moved away from a strategy<br />

based on “communication” and adopted an approach that emphasizes dialogue – what<br />

practitioners describe as “two-way communication.” The Superfund Community Involvement<br />

Handbook, published in 2002, includes among its “core values for public participation” the<br />

expectation that “People should have a say in decisions about actions that affect their lives,” and<br />

furthermore, that public participation “includes the promise that the public’s contribution will<br />

influence the decision.” The handbook also requires that “[t]he public participation process<br />

communicates the interests and meets the needs of <strong>all</strong> participants.” 93<br />

One does not need to be a public administration specialist to recognize that these generic<br />

declarations of intent, as laudable as they may be, provide precious little guidance to<br />

administrators in the trenches. What does it mean from an administrative standpoint that the<br />

community “should have a say”? Should community views simply be accepted on their face<br />

value, even if the EPA has come to the conclusion that the option advocated by the community<br />

would produce marginal health benefits whose costs could not be justified? What if the option<br />

favored by the community from a public health perspective is inferior to the agency-preferred<br />

alternative? If the EPA determines that it is politic<strong>all</strong>y preferable to endorse the community’s<br />

preferred option, even if it is the less-than-optimal choice, how should the EPA justify its<br />

decision to the responsible parties?<br />

Left without appropriate regulatory guidance, program administrators could respond in one<br />

of two ways. They could interpret their role as a purely informational one. In this role, the EPA’s<br />

primary responsibility is simply to adequately inform the general public, and secondarily to<br />

“listen” to the community’s concerns. The requirement to listen, in this case, is simply a<br />

procedural obligation, and does not entail a duty to incorporate the community’s concerns into<br />

the clean-up plan. This strategy is entirely compatible with the technocratic instincts of many<br />

federal agencies, and has been the EPA’s preferred mode of operation for many years. 94 It <strong>all</strong>ows<br />

the agency to form<strong>all</strong>y meet its statutory mandate, but also to preserve its authority.<br />

Alternatively, program administrators could envisage extending the clean-up process until a<br />

consensus among the affected population and the responsible parties is reached. This option is<br />

unlikely to garner significant administrative support, however, for several reasons. By its nature,<br />

92<br />

93<br />

94<br />

See http://www.epa.gov/superfund/tools/.<br />

See the Superfund Community Involvement Handbook, p.7.<br />

See, for example, Folk, "Public Participation in the Superfund Cleanup Process." for a detailed account of the<br />

EPA approach to public involvement.<br />

283


it significantly constraints the agency’s ability to choose the clean-up plan it deems most<br />

appropriate. In addition, a consensus solution is exposed to the risk of legal ch<strong>all</strong>enge by a<br />

disgruntled affected or responsible party. Whether this argument would stand up in a court of law<br />

depends on the details of the case. Our point here is simply that consensus solutions produced by<br />

ad hoc coalitions consisting of representatives of the public and responsible parties may not be<br />

regarded as acceptable by <strong>all</strong> parties involved.<br />

In recent times, the EPA has been experimenting with community advisory groups (CAGs).<br />

Their predecessors, community working groups, were one element of the EPA community<br />

relations program, but they were rarely used and were gener<strong>all</strong>y regarded as a conduit for<br />

efficiently conveying important information to the affected population rather than as a potenti<strong>all</strong>y<br />

viable institution of public participation. The term “advisory” suggests a more rigorous and<br />

perhaps a more dialogic approach to community relations. Convening an advisory panel is<br />

subject to the provisions of the Federal Advisory Committee Act, 95 which, while far from<br />

perfect, forces the convening agency to respect certain basic procedural rules, ensures some<br />

degree of transparency, and c<strong>all</strong>s for a broad representation. A recently conducted review of five<br />

Superfund CAGs found, among other things, that CAGs are one of the most effective means of<br />

promoting community involvement. Not surprisingly, the review also found that broadly<br />

representative CAGs enjoy the confidence of the communities they represent, and are more<br />

credible in the eyes of the EPA. The study emphasized the importance of appointing CAG<br />

members without a specific agenda, possibly an indication of the distorting political influence of<br />

interest groups at the local level. It went on to note that unlike public hearings, CAGs are wellsuited<br />

to be institutional platforms of public deliberation and consensus finding. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the<br />

study noted that CAGs increase the influence of the affected populations on the clean-up process,<br />

and contribute to establish a more constructive relationship between EPA officials and local<br />

groups. 96<br />

CAGs are certainly not the final word on institutions of public participation, but they once<br />

again demonstrate the crucial importance of institutional design in meeting statutory goals. The<br />

provisions of the Federal Advisory Committee Act are a weak protection against attempts to<br />

limit the range of views represented on these committees. And CAGs operate in a purely<br />

advisory mode. Yet nothing would prevent the EPA from strengthening the CAGs’ role by<br />

imposing more stringent eligibility criteria. The agency could mandate appointing CAG<br />

members through a local election. An election would almost guarantee that CAG members<br />

would represent much broader sections of the local population, thus mitigating the risk of group<br />

polarization. If interest group leaders were elected, they would represent the affected population<br />

and not just a sm<strong>all</strong> group of activists. Increased legitimacy, in turn, would make the CAG a<br />

much more credible partner in dealing with the EPA. Last but not least, broadly legitimate and<br />

95<br />

96<br />

See chapter 2 for a discussion.<br />

"Community Advisory Groups: Partners in Decisions at Hazardous Waste Sites, Case Studies," (Cincinnati, OH:<br />

National Service Center for Environmental Publications, 1996).<br />

284


more deliberative CAGs may produce more realistic recommendations and refrain from<br />

excessive clean-up demands, a problem that has tradition<strong>all</strong>y plagued remedial actions and has<br />

been responsible for horrendous clean-up costs. 97<br />

In this chapter, we have argued that reproductive medicine and biomedical research are<br />

fraught with political failures. This term indicates a gap between the policies advocated by<br />

organized interest groups and the attitudes displayed by the general public on key policy<br />

questions. Considerable disagreement also exists between some organized interest groups and<br />

their core constituencies. We have suggested that an institution of public consultation would<br />

greatly reduce the negative consequences of political failure. Public consultation is nothing new<br />

in the American system of government. Many statutes require the administering agencies to<br />

“consult with the public.” Its long history notwithstanding, public participation remains a<br />

precarious exercise that often produces the exact opposite of what it was designed to achieve –<br />

broad public support for an agency policy. A mechanism of public consultation that is likely to<br />

produce reliable results and prevent both political failures and regulatory capture must ensure<br />

that the participating public is representative and balanced, that it is knowledgeable, and that the<br />

process is deliberative. But a process of public consultation is only one (albeit important)<br />

element of a new regulatory system. In the next chapter, we examine in some detail which<br />

organizational forms may be suitable to regulate reproductive medicine and biomedical research.<br />

97<br />

Stephen Breyer, Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1993).<br />

285


286


10.10 Bibliography<br />

Ackerman, Stark. "Observations on the Transformation of the Forest Service: The Effects of<br />

NEPA on Forest Service Decision Making." Environmental Law 20 (1990): 703-34.<br />

Applegate, John S. "Beyond the Usual Suspects: The Use of Citizens Advisory Boards in<br />

Environmental Decisionmaking." Indiana Law Journal 73 (1998): 901-57.<br />

Beauchamp, Tom L. "Reply to Strong on Principlism and Casuistry." Journal of Medicine and<br />

Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000): 342-47.<br />

Been, Vicki. "What's Fairness Got to Do with It? Environmental Justice and the Siting of Loc<strong>all</strong>y<br />

Undesirable Land Uses." Cornell Law Review 78 (1993): 1001-83.<br />

Beierle, Thomas C. "The Quality of Stakeholder-Based Decisions: Lessons from the Case Study<br />

Record." Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future, 2000.<br />

Bioethics, President's Council on. Applications of Human Stem Cells in Research and Medicine<br />

2003 [cited October 3, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.bioethics.gov/background/sc_application.html.<br />

Blumm, Michael C. "The National Environmental Policy Act at Twenty: A Preface."<br />

Environmental Law 20 (1990): 447-83.<br />

Bradbury, Judith A., and Kristi M. Branch. "An Evaluation of the Effectiveness of Local Site-<br />

Specific Advisory Boards for U.S. Department of Energy Environmental Restoration<br />

Program." Pacific Northwest National Laboratory, 1999.<br />

Bram, Adam N. "Public Participation Provisions Need Not Contribute to Environmental<br />

Injustice." Temple Political and Civil Rights Law Review 5 (1996): 145-67.<br />

Breyer, Stephen. Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective Risk Regulation. Cambridge,<br />

MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.<br />

Buchanan, James M. "Public Choice: Politics without Romance." Policy 19, no. 3 (2003): 13-18.<br />

Buchanan, James M., and Gordon Tullock. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of<br />

Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962.<br />

Casey, Dion. "Agency Capture: The USDA's Struggle to Pass Food Safety Regulations." Kansas<br />

Journal of Law & Public Policy 7 (1998): 142-56.<br />

Checkoway, Barry. "The Politics of Public Hearings." Journal of Applied Behavioral Science 17,<br />

no. 4 (1981): 566-82.<br />

Cole, Richard L., and David A. Caputo. "The Public Hearing as an Effective Citizen<br />

Participation Mechanism: A Case Study of the General Revenue Sharing Program."<br />

American Political Science Review 78, no. 2 (1984): 404-16.<br />

"Community Advisory Groups: Partners in Decisions at Hazardous Waste Sites, Case Studies."<br />

Cincinnati, OH: National Service Center for Environmental Publications, 1996.<br />

Croley, Steven P. "Public Interested Regulation." Florida State University Law Review 28<br />

(2000): 7-107.<br />

Culhane, Paul J. "NEPA's Impacts on Federal Agencies, Anticipated and Unanticipated."<br />

Environmental Law 20 (1990): 681-702.<br />

Dahrendorf, Ralf. Dopo La Democrazia. Intervista a Cura Di Antonio Polito. Roma: Laterza,<br />

2001.<br />

Dietz, Thomas, and Robert W. Rycroft. The Risk Professionals. New York: Russell Sage<br />

Foundation, 1987.<br />

287


Dunkerley, David, and Peter Glasner. "Empowering the Public? Citizens' Juries and the New<br />

Genetic Technologies." Critical Public Health 8, no. 3 (1998): 181-92.<br />

Dürrenberger, Gregor, Hans Kastenholz, and Jeannette Behringer. "Integrated Assessment Focus<br />

Groups: Bridging the Gap between Science and Policy?" Science and Public Policy 26,<br />

no. 5 (1999): 341-49.<br />

Ebdon, Carol. "Beyond the Public Hearing: Citizen Participation in the Local Government<br />

Budget Process." Journal of Public Budgeting, Accounting and Financial Management<br />

14, no. 2 (2002): 273-94.<br />

Einsiedel, Edna F., and Deborah K. Eastlick. "Consensus Conferences as Deliberative<br />

Democracy." Science Communication 21, no. 4 (2000): 323-43.<br />

Elliott, Carl. "Six Problems with Pharma-Funded Bioethics." Studies in the History and<br />

Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35 (2004): 125-29.<br />

Elliott, Donald E. "Re-Inventing Rulemaking." Duke Law Journal 41 (1992): 1490-96.<br />

Elliott, Matthew, and Allister Heath. "The Failure of CAP Reform: A Public Choice Analysis."<br />

Economic Affairs 20, no. 2 (2000): 42-48.<br />

Erikson, Susan L. "Post-Diagnostic Abortion in Germany: Reproduction Gone Awry, Again?"<br />

Social Science & Medicine 56 (2003): 1987-2001.<br />

Evans, John H. Playing God? Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public<br />

Bioethical Debate. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2002.<br />

Farber, Daniel A. "Democracy and Disgust: Reflections on Public Choice." Chicago-Kent Law<br />

Review 65 (1989): 161-76.<br />

Farber, Daniel A., and Philip P. Frickey. "The Jurisprudence of Public Choice." Texas Law<br />

Review 65 (1987): 873-927.<br />

Fiorino, Daniel J. "Citizen Participation and Environmental Risk: A Survey of Institutional<br />

Mechanisms." Science, Technology and Human Values 15, no. 2 (1990): 226-43.<br />

Folk, Ellison. "Public Participation in the Superfund Cleanup Process." Ecology Law Quarterly<br />

18 (1991): 173- 221.<br />

Funk, William F. "Regulatory Negotiation and the Subversion of the Public Interest." Duke Law<br />

Journal 46 (1997): 1351-88.<br />

Futrell, Robert. "Technical Adversarialism and Participatory Collaboration in the U.S. Chemical<br />

Weapons Disposal Program." Science, Technology and Human Values 28, no. 4 (2003):<br />

451-82.<br />

Garrett, Elizabeth. "Interest Groups and Public Interested Regulation." Florida State University<br />

Law Review 28 (2000): 137-54.<br />

Gert, Bernard, Charles M. Culver, and K. Danner Clouser. "Common Morality Versus<br />

Specified Principlism: Reply to Richardson." Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no.<br />

3 (2000): 308-22.<br />

Golash, Carrie. FASEB Statement on Human Somatic Cell Nuclear Transplantation (SCNT) and<br />

Embryonic Stem Cells FASEB, February 12, 2004 [cited May 3, 2006]. Available from<br />

http://opa.faseb.org/pdf/nr_2x12x4_stem.pdf.<br />

Guston, David H. "Evaluating the First U.S. Consensus Conference: The Impact of the Citizens’<br />

Panel on Telecommunications and the Future of Democracy." Science, Technology and<br />

Human Values 24, no. 4 (1999): 451-82.<br />

Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. Democracy and Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict<br />

Cannot Be Avoided in Politics, What Should Be Done About It. Cambridge, MA: Belknap<br />

Press, 1996.<br />

288


Harvey, John C. Distinctly Human: The When, Where and How of Life's Beginnings Family<br />

Research Council, April 25, 2002 [cited May 3, 2006]. Available from<br />

http://www.frc.org/get.cfm?i=IS02D3.<br />

Hayek, Friedrich A. "Der Wettbewerb Als Entdeckungsverfahren." In Kieler Vorträge. Kiel,<br />

1968.<br />

Isenberg, Daniel J. "Group Polarization: A Critical Review and Meta-Analysis." Journal of<br />

Personality and Social Psychology 50 (1986): 1141-51.<br />

Jonsen, Albert R. "Strong on Specification." Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3<br />

(2000): 348-60.<br />

Jordan, William S. "Ossification Revisited: Does Arbitrary and Capricious Review Significantly<br />

Interfere with Agency Ability to Achieve Regulatory Goals through Informal<br />

Rulemaking?" Northwestern University Law Review 94 (2000): 393-449.<br />

Joss, Simon. "Danish Consensus Conferences as a Model of Participatory Technology<br />

Assessment: An Impact Study of Consensus Conferences on Danish Parliament and<br />

Danish Public Debate." Science and Public Policy 25 (1998): 2-22.<br />

———. "Toward the Public Sphere – Reflections on the Development of Participatory<br />

Technology Assessment." Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 22, no. 3 (2002):<br />

220-31.<br />

Kalich, Veronica Z. "A Public Choice Perspective on the Subsidization of Private Industry: A<br />

Case Study of Three Cities and Three Stadiums." Journal of Urban Affairs 20, no. 2<br />

(1998): 199-219.<br />

Kelly, Susan E. "Public Bioethics and Publics: Consensus, Boundaries, and Participation in<br />

Biomedical Policy." Science, Technology and Human Values 28, no. 3 (2003): 339-64.<br />

Kenyon, Wendy, Ceara Nevin, and Nick Hanley. "Enhancing Environmental Decision-Making<br />

Using Citizens’ Juries." Local Environment 8, no. 2 (2003): 221-32.<br />

Kim, Myung-Sik. "Cloning and Deliberation: Korean Consensus Conference." Developing<br />

World Bioethics 2, no. 2 (2002): 159-72.<br />

Kuran, Timur, and Cass Sunstein. "Availability Cascades and Risk Regulation." Stanford Law<br />

Review 51 (1999): 683-768.<br />

Lando, Tom. "The Public Hearing Process: A Tool for Citizen Participation, or a Path toward<br />

Alienation?" National Civic Review 92, no. 1 (2003): 73-82.<br />

Leach Sculley, Jackie, Christine Rippberger, and Christoph Rehmann-Sutter. "Non-Professional<br />

Evaluation of Gene Therapy Ethics." Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004): 1415-25.<br />

Lippman-Hand, Abby, and Clarke F. Fraser. "Genetic Counseling: Parents’ Responses to<br />

Uncertainty." Birth Defects: Original Article Series 15 (1979): 325-39.<br />

Malinowski, Michael J. "Coming into Being: Law, Ethics and the Practice of Prenatal Genetic<br />

Screening." Hastings Law Journal 45 (1994): 1435-526.<br />

Mank, Bradford C. "Standing and Global Warming: Is Injury to All Injury to None?"<br />

Environmental Law 35 (2005): 1-84.<br />

Mashaw, Jerry L. "The Economics of Politics and the Understanding of Public Law." Chicago-<br />

Kent Law Review 65 (1989): 123-60.<br />

Mazmanian, Daniel A., and Jeanne Nienaber. Can Organizations Change? Environmental<br />

Protection, Citizen Participation and the Corps of Engineers. Washington, D.C.:<br />

Brookings Institution, 1979.<br />

McGarity, Thomas O. "Some Thoughts on 'Deossifying' the Rulemaking Process Duke." Duke<br />

Law Journal 41 (1992): 1385-462.<br />

289


———. "The Courts and the Ossification of Rulemaking: A Response to Professor Seidenfeld."<br />

Texas Law Review 75 (1997): 525-58.<br />

Miller, Geoffrey P. "Public Choice at the Dawn of the Special Interest State: The Story of Butter<br />

and Margarine." California Law Review 77 (1989): 83-129.<br />

Moreno, Jonathan D. Deciding Together. Bioethics and Moral Consensus. New York: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1995.<br />

Mueller, Dennis. Public Choice Iii. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003.<br />

Mullins, David. "From Regulatory Capture to Regulated Competition: An Interest Group<br />

Analysis of Housing Associations in England." Housing Studies 12, no. 3 (1997): 301-19.<br />

Myers, David G. "Discussion-Induced Attitude Polarization." Human Relations 28 (1975): 699-<br />

714.<br />

———. "The Group Polarization Phenomenon." Psychology Bulletin 83 (1976): 602-62.<br />

Myers, David G., and G.D. Bishop. "Enhancement of Dominant Attitudes in Group Discussion."<br />

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 20 (1971): 386-91.<br />

Nelson Ratliff, Jeanne. "The Politics of Nuclear Waste: An Analysis of a Public Hearing on the<br />

Proposed Yucca Mountain Nuclear Waste Repository." Communication Studies 48, no. 4<br />

(1997): 359-80.<br />

Perkins Spyke, Nancy. "Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking at the New<br />

Millenium: Structuring New Spheres of Public Influence." Boston College Environmental<br />

Affairs Law Review 26 (1999): 263-313.<br />

Pierce, Richard J. "Rulemaking and the Administrative Procedure Act." Tulsa Law Journal 32<br />

(1996): 185-201.<br />

Poisner, Jonathan. "A Civic Republican Perspective on the National Environmental Policy Act's<br />

Process for Citizen Participation." Environmental Law 26 (1996): 53-94.<br />

Posner, Richard A. Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 2003.<br />

Price, David. "Choices without Reasons: Citizens' Juries and Policy Evaluation." Journal of<br />

Medical Ethics 26 (2000): 272-76.<br />

Purdue, Derrick. "Experiments in the Governance of Biotechnology: A Case Study of the UK<br />

National Consensus Conference." New Genetics and Society 18, no. 1 (1999): 79-99.<br />

Rabin, Robert L. "Federal Regulation in Historical Perspective." Stanford Law Review 38<br />

(1986): 1189-326.<br />

Rabino, Isaac. "Stem Cell and Cloning Controversies." Genetic Engineering News 24, no. 4<br />

(2004): 6-9.<br />

Rapp, Rayna. "Refusing Prenatal Diagnosis: The Meanings of Bioscience in a Multicultural<br />

World." Science, Technology and Human Values 23, no. 1 (1998): 45-70.<br />

———. Testing Women, Testing the Fetus: The Social Impact of Amniocentesis in America.<br />

New York: Routledge, 2000.<br />

Richardson, Henry S. "Specifying, Balancing, and Interpreting Bioethical Principles." Journal of<br />

Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000): 285-307.<br />

Rowe, Gene, and Lynn J. Frewer. "Public Participation Methods: A Framework for Evaluation."<br />

Science, Technology and Human Values 25, no. 1 (2000): 3-29.<br />

Santos, Susan L., and Caron Chess. "Evaluating Citizen Advisory Boards: The Importance of<br />

Theory and Participant-Based Criteria and Practical Implications." Risk Analysis 23, no. 2<br />

(2003): 269-79.<br />

290


Schicktanz, Silke, and Jörg Naumann, eds. Bürgerkonferenz: Streitf<strong>all</strong> Gendiagnostik. Ein<br />

Modellprojekt Der Bürgerbeteiligung Am Bioethischen Diskurs. Dresden: Deutsches<br />

Hygiene-Museum, 2003.<br />

Schkade, David, Cass R. Sunstein, and Daniel Kahneman. "Deliberating About Dollars: The<br />

Severity Shift." Columbia Law Journal 100 (2000): 1139-75.<br />

Seidenfeld, Mark. "Demystifying Deossification: Rethinking Recent Proposals to Modify<br />

Judicial Review of Notice and Comment Rulemaking." Texas Law Review 75 (1997):<br />

483-524.<br />

Smith Iltis, Ana. "Bioethics as Methodological Case Resolution: Specification, Specified<br />

Principlism and Casuistry." Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000): 271-<br />

84.<br />

Sniderman, Allan D. "Clinical Trials, Consensus Conferences, and Clinical Practice." Lancet<br />

354: 327-30.<br />

Strong, Carson. "Specified Principlism: What Is It, and Does It Re<strong>all</strong>y Resolve Cases Better<br />

Than Casuistry?" Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000): 323-41.<br />

Sunstein, Cass. "Deliberative Trouble? Why Groups Go to Extremes." Yale Law Journal 110<br />

(2000): 71-119.<br />

———. Why Societies Need Dissent. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003.<br />

Tabb, William Murray. "The Role of Controversy in NEPA: Reconciling Public Veto with<br />

Public Participation in Environmental Decisionmaking." William and Mary<br />

Environmental Law and Policy Review 21 (1997): 175-231.<br />

United Church of Christ Commission for Racial Justice. Toxic Waste and Race in the United<br />

States: A National <strong>Report</strong> on the Racial and Socioeconomic Characteristics of<br />

Communities with Hazardous Waste Sites. New York: Public Access, 1987.<br />

Volokh, Eugene. "The Mechanisms of the Slippery Slope." Harvard Law Review 116 (2003):<br />

1026-137.<br />

Walters, LeRoy, and Julie Gage Palmer. The Ethics of Human Gene Therapy. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1996.<br />

Webler, Thomas. " 'Right' Discourse in Citizen Participation: An Evaluative Yardstick." In<br />

Fairness and Competence in Citizen Participation: Evaluating Models for Environmental<br />

Discourse, edited by Ortwin Renn, Thomas Webler and Peter Wiedemann, 35-86.<br />

Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer Academic, 1995.<br />

Wertz, Dorothy C., and Robin Gregg. "Genetics Services in a Social, Ethical and Policy Context:<br />

A Collaboration between Consumers and Providers." Journal of Medical Ethics 26<br />

(2000): 261-65.<br />

Wildavsky, Aaron. But Is It True? A Citizen's Guide to Environmental Health and Safety Issues.<br />

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995.<br />

Zujewski, JoAnne, and Edison T. Liu. "The 1998 St. G<strong>all</strong>en's Consensus Conference: An<br />

Assessment." Journal of the National Cancer Institute 90 (1998): 1587-89.<br />

291


292


11 Independent Agencies<br />

11.1 Why an Independent Agency?<br />

Any proposal to create a new regulatory institution for biomedical technologies must ensure<br />

that regulators remain independent. Only a proposal for a genuinely independent agency stands a<br />

chance to be supported by organized interest groups and by a majority in Congress. What exactly<br />

“independence” means will be discussed in some detail below, but the basic gist of the argument<br />

can easily be summarized: we consider an agency independent if none of the affected interest<br />

groups believes that other interest groups exercise undue influence over the agency decisionmaking.<br />

Agency independence as understood in this report is related to but distinct from the<br />

concept of independent agency familiar to legal scholars and public administrators. As we will<br />

show in more detail below, independent agencies as they exist throughout the federal<br />

government are not adequately protected against regulatory capture and political manipulations<br />

by Congress or the office of the president. They are, however, an important means to ensure<br />

genuine independence.<br />

A quick look at the current political landscape demonstrates the crucial importance of<br />

agency independence. It is no exaggeration to say that in recent times, the scientific community<br />

has been terrified by the prospect that research freedom could be encroached upon by<br />

ideologues, religious zealots, and radical environmental groups advancing a deeply skeptical<br />

view of modern science. On the opposite side, an <strong>all</strong>iance of religious and conservative<br />

organizations is deeply concerned about unbridled reproductive medicine and what they see as<br />

growing scientific arrogance. In this political climate, the science camp has come to view any<br />

attempt to provide legal guidance in this area as the first step toward bigotry and intolerance.<br />

Conservative and religious groups, for their part, resist a regulatory approach on the grounds that<br />

it would provide a governmental stamp of approval to murderous procedures. Against this<br />

background, a proposal that does not include appropriate measures to prevent undue political<br />

interference would simply be ignored.<br />

Supporters of unconstrained scientific research may find the concept of agency<br />

independence very attractive; in the current political environment, an independent agency would<br />

provide an effective protection against attempts by conservative and religious groups to unduly<br />

interfere with science and medicine. Protecting science is, however, not what agency<br />

independence is designed to achieve. The concept of an independent agency is neutral. One<br />

could just as well imagine a future administration very supportive of biomedical research being<br />

unable to significantly affect an independent agency constrained by a statute deemed too<br />

restrictive. In this scenario, it is the scientific community that threatens to unduly influence the<br />

regulatory independence. The concept of independence, if it means anything, denotes an<br />

293


agency’s ability to implement Congressional intent in accordance with broad public sentiments,<br />

possibly against the wishes of organized interest groups of any kind.<br />

The relevance of agency independence is not limited to the U.S. context. As shown in<br />

chapter 6, countries such as Britain, Canada, and Australia have, to different extents and in<br />

different ways, endorsed this general principle. The British experience certainly suggests that<br />

agency independence as envisaged by the British Parliament is a feasible and effective<br />

proposition. In the course of its relatively short history, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology<br />

Authority has faced numerous ch<strong>all</strong>enges and the wisdom of its rules and policies has often been<br />

contested, yet until very recently, its legitimacy as the premiere regulatory authority in matters<br />

pertaining to reproductive medicine has not been ch<strong>all</strong>enged. 1 The much more recently created<br />

Australian Embryo Research Licensing Committee has received its fair share of criticisms, but to<br />

our knowledge its existence is not in danger.<br />

Independent agencies are nothing new in our own administrative system. Since the<br />

establishment of the first independent agency in 1887, the Interstate Commerce Commission,<br />

Congress has created numerous independent agencies, including the Securities and Exchange<br />

Commission and the National Labor Relations Board (both established during the New Deal),<br />

and more recently the Consumer Product Safety Commission, the Nuclear Regulatory<br />

Commission, the Commodity Futures Trading Commission, and the Federal Communications<br />

Commission. This list is by no means exhaustive. The May 2005 Unified Agenda lists 17<br />

independent agencies, but many more are likely to exist. 2<br />

But what is an independent agency in the U.S. system of government? Surprisingly, no<br />

universal legal definition of this term is available. Independent agencies can differ from each<br />

other in significant ways. Legal scholars have identified several attributes shared by most<br />

independent agencies. 3<br />

Appointing the head of an independent agency is a presidential<br />

prerogative. Appointments require confirmation by the Senate – the president appoints with the<br />

“advice and consent” of the Senate. Unlike other heads of agency, however, the head of an<br />

independent agency does not serve “at the pleasure of the President” – the president can only<br />

remove him or her for “cause.” In the case of the Federal Trade Commission (FTC), for example,<br />

the removal clause maintains that “any commissioner may be removed by the President for<br />

1<br />

2<br />

3<br />

This may be about to change however, as in early 2005, the House of Commons Science and Technology<br />

Committee has initiated a broad review of the HFEA’s mandate. See Susan Bartlett Foote, "Independent<br />

Agencies under Attack: A Skeptical View of the Importance of the Debate," Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988);<br />

Science and Technology Committee House of Commons, "Inquiry into Human Reproductive Technologies and<br />

the Law: Eighth Special <strong>Report</strong> of Session 2004-05," (London: The Stationary Office, 2005); James C. Miller,<br />

"A Reflection on the Independence of Independent Agencies," Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988); Alan B.<br />

Morrison, "How Independent Are Independent Regulatory Agencies?," Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988); Aulana<br />

L. Peters, "Independent Agencies: Government's Scourge or Salvation?," Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988); Glen<br />

O. Robinson, "Independent Agencies: Form and Substance in Executive Prerogative," Duke Law Journal 288<br />

(1988).<br />

See http://www.gpoaccess.gov/ua/browse0505.html.<br />

For an in-depth discussion of independent agencies and their position in the U.S. system of government, see Paul<br />

R. Verkuil, "The Purposes and Limits of Independent Agencies," Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988).<br />

294


inefficiency, neglect of duty, or malfeasance in office.” 4 Thus, in the U.S. system of government,<br />

agency independence has a very narrow meaning: An agency enjoys a measure of independence<br />

from the executive branch, and from the executive branch only. Congressional oversight, in its<br />

various forms, is fully preserved.<br />

Most independent agencies are constituted as commissions of various sizes, though in<br />

principle at least, an independent agency could be governed by a single individual. To our<br />

knowledge, currently no such agency exists. Most commissions, including the Federal Trade<br />

Commission, the Nuclear Regulatory Commission, and the Securities and Exchange<br />

Commission, have a five-member board; a few operate with only three commissioners, and one,<br />

the Federal Reserve Board, is governed by seven board members.<br />

Another typical attribute of independent agencies is stacked appointments for a fixed term of<br />

office. Stacked appointments ensure that new commissioners are replaced at a slow pace, and<br />

that the turnover remains low. The terms of office are often set so as not to coincide with the<br />

presidential term. FTC commissioners, for example, serve for a five-year term. Members of the<br />

Federal Reserve Board serve for an exception<strong>all</strong>y long 14-year term. Other commissions operate<br />

on a three-year basis. By limiting the appointment to only one term, commissioners have greater<br />

room for maneuver; their reappointment obviously is not a consideration in their daily work.<br />

Independent commissions are constituted as bipartisan administrative units. Neither party can be<br />

represented by a clear majority – another indication of the Congressional will to insulate<br />

independent agencies from excessive political influence.<br />

Independent commissions tend to operate in a consensual way. Commissioners debate the<br />

pros and cons of alternative courses of action, listen to expert testimony, and try to make<br />

decisions by consensus rather than by majority vote. Decision by consensus is norm<strong>all</strong>y the<br />

preferred option; decision by majority vote is regarded both as a recognition of the difficulty of<br />

achieving a consensus within a reasonable period of time, and of the need to avoid administrative<br />

paralysis.<br />

A final, perhaps less common but important attribute of independent agencies is their<br />

accumulation of authority in legislative, adjudicative, and prosecutorial matters. In plain text,<br />

some independent agencies make rules, preside over legal disputes pertaining to the<br />

commission’s regulatory scope, and in some cases also prosecute civil violations of the statutes<br />

they administer. Not <strong>all</strong> independent agencies perform <strong>all</strong> three tasks, and some executive<br />

agencies have been assigned at least two of these functions, so this is by no means an exclusive<br />

characteristic of independent agencies, but it seems more common for independent agencies than<br />

for executive agencies to accumulate powers. This is also the reason why some legal scholars<br />

believe that this administrative construction violates the separation of powers doctrine and is<br />

therefore unconstitutional.<br />

But what is the rationale for Congress to create an independent agency? Tradition<strong>all</strong>y,<br />

Congress has established independent agencies to oversee specific industries or policy-making<br />

4<br />

See 15 U.S.C. § 41 (1982).<br />

295


areas that were thought to require extensive technical expertise. Moreover, in Congress’ view,<br />

the exercise of technical judgment should not be hampered or distorted by political<br />

considerations. Agency independence in this case is synonymous with technocratic decisionmaking:<br />

Technical experts are in the best position to select the most appropriate course of action;<br />

they do so by relying on science-based, objective criteria. Non-technical considerations are<br />

regarded as an unacceptable distortion of the decision-making process. Examples include the<br />

regulation of nuclear power plants (by the Nuclear Regulatory Commission), of financial<br />

markets (by the Securities and Exchange Commission), or of product safety (by the Product<br />

Safety Commission).<br />

On closer examination, this rationale is anything but convincing. If technical expertise and<br />

technocratic decision-making were of such paramount importance, then it is difficult to see why<br />

the Food and Drug Administration is not an independent agency. On the other end, some would<br />

argue that the extreme independence enjoyed by the Federal Reserve Board cannot be justified<br />

on technical grounds alone. These observations suggest that the Congressional rationale for<br />

establishing independent agencies is of dubious credibility. Whatever the offici<strong>all</strong>y stated reasons<br />

for Congress to establish a new independent agency, its creation usu<strong>all</strong>y signals a Congressional<br />

desire to increase control over the agency at the expense of the president’s ability to shape<br />

agency policy. Agency independence, in this sense, is simply a (perhaps marginal) shift in the<br />

relative ability of the executive and legislative branches of government to control a regulatory<br />

body. It most definitively does not represent a significant net increase in the agency’s ability to<br />

implement a policy agenda that conflicts with presidential wishes or Congressional preferences.<br />

Furthermore, independent agencies, just like any other executive agency, are exposed to the<br />

lobbying efforts of innumerable interest groups. So it is not at <strong>all</strong> clear that the creation of an<br />

independent agency, notwithstanding many desirable attributes of this organizational form,<br />

would help create an agency that could operate in a genuinely independent manner.<br />

Some commentators have argued that independent agencies are more and not less exposed to<br />

the dangers of factionalism and capture than agencies placed under the control of the president. 5<br />

Reducing the president’s powers to shape agency policy could deprive the agency of a powerful<br />

political advocate. Independence origin<strong>all</strong>y derived from an antiquated notion of the<br />

administrative state. In this view, an agency implementation and interpretation of the law can and<br />

should be guided exclusively by technical rationality. Accordingly, an agency should be<br />

insulated from any external interventions that might distort this <strong>all</strong>egedly impartial process of<br />

decision-making. The agency is supposed to pursue the public interest, and the means for<br />

accomplishing this goal is technical rationality. This view of the administrative state was very in<br />

vogue during the New Deal, but it lost much of its appeal soon after the end of World War II.<br />

During those days, agency independence was often synonymous with regulatory capture and<br />

factionalism. Independent agencies were more exposed to the dangers of factionalism and<br />

5<br />

James F. Blumstein, "Regulatory Review by the Executive Office of the President: An Overview and Policy<br />

Analysis of Current Issues," Duke Law Journal 51 (2001); Easterbrook, "Presidential Review."; Lawrence<br />

Lessig and Cass Sunstein, "The President and the Administration," Columbia Law Review 94 (1994).<br />

296


capture than executive agencies placed under the control of the president. It is in no sm<strong>all</strong><br />

measure because of “arbitrary and capricious” decisions by both independent and executive<br />

agencies that the Congress in 1946 passed the Administrative Procedure Act.<br />

In what sense, then, is an independent agency a concept worth pursuing? First, for symbolic<br />

reasons. In the eyes of the general public, it simply would not be credible on the one end to c<strong>all</strong><br />

for strong regulatory independence and on the other to reject the creation of an independent<br />

agency. Proponents of an executive agency would find themselves in the uncomfortable position<br />

of having to explain why an executive agency is actu<strong>all</strong>y more independent than an independent<br />

agency. Establishing an independent agency is thus a first, necessary step to ensure genuine<br />

independence.<br />

Political symbolism is certainly not the only reason for favoring the creation of an<br />

independent agency. This organizational form is a far better match for what may be described as<br />

the two main tasks facing a regulatory agency responsible for overseeing reproductive medicine<br />

and biomedical research – implementing the Congressional mandate and adjudicating societal<br />

disputes – than an executive agency. Consider first how the agency would go about translating<br />

Congressional expectations into actual regulations. Let’s assume for a moment that Congress has<br />

included a set of ethical principles in the enabling statute as outlined in chapter 3. Ethical<br />

principles, by definition, provide merely a general sense of direction. In <strong>all</strong> but the most trivial<br />

cases, they are not capable of unambiguously resolving a specific ethical dilemma, in the sense<br />

that with regard to a given medical technology or research protocol, there may be several<br />

regulatory interpretations of the same ethical principle. For example, the principle that the<br />

agency should favor therapeutic over enhancing technologies, applied to pre-implantation<br />

genetic diagnosis, could produce startlingly different regulations depending on exactly how the<br />

concept of therapy is defined, and on whether the prospective parents alone should benefit from<br />

the treatment or the benefits should be extended to the blastocysts and the future child. If<br />

Congress does not ban reproductive cloning, the agency would also have to determine whether<br />

this procedure should be considered therapeutic or enhancing. Sex-selection technologies would<br />

raise analogous interpretative problems. In <strong>all</strong> these cases, the agency would be c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to<br />

perform a task typical of a judicial body. 6<br />

The agency would also be c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to adjudicate disputes over new reproductive<br />

treatments or controversial research protocols. For example, at some point regulators may be<br />

forced to offer a legal opinion on whether the creation of so-c<strong>all</strong>ed designer babies is compatible<br />

with the protection of the well-being of future children, or whether this procedure should be<br />

considered therapeutic in the first place. Some research protocols involving mixing human and<br />

animal reproductive tissues are also likely to require adjudication by the agency.<br />

6<br />

Some could argue that performing judicial tasks reflects Congress’ failure to promulgate sufficiently specific<br />

legislation. In this view, Congress should prevent this abuse of administrative power by passing more narrowly<br />

crafted legislation. As discussed in chapter 9, this view simply flies in the face of current administrative realities.<br />

In addition, requiring Congress to take on regulatory tasks would produce a rigid statutory framework incapable<br />

of responding in a timely fashion to new medical and scientific developments.<br />

297


Sm<strong>all</strong> decision-making bodies such as independent agencies are particularly well-suited to<br />

take on both interpretative and adjudicative tasks. Performing these tasks requires balanced<br />

judgment, a systematic examination of <strong>all</strong> relevant arguments, and an over<strong>all</strong> commitment to<br />

finding consensual solutions in a deliberative fashion. In other words, this independent agency<br />

would operate more like a court than a traditional executive agency. Its core task would consist –<br />

after listening to the views and positions of <strong>all</strong> affected parties and the general public – of<br />

deciding factual questions in a deliberative manner by applying the ethical principles set forth in<br />

the enabling legislation. Central to this decision-making body are not efficiency and<br />

effectiveness, as in the case of an executive agency responsible for implementing a<br />

Congressional mandate, but moral authority and procedural fairness, as expressed in the rationale<br />

offered to justify a certain finding of fact. This is not to say that this agency would not have to<br />

perform traditional executive tasks. We will discuss some of these tasks in chapter 13. Our claim<br />

here is simply that this independent agency’s core task is mainly judicial. For this particular task,<br />

a sm<strong>all</strong> deliberative body would be the organizational form of choice.<br />

The judicial nature of this regulatory body provides a prima facie argument against<br />

presidential powers of removal. It would be quite disturbing, inappropriate, and detrimental to<br />

our modern notions of democracy if a president felt compelled to intervene on behalf of specific<br />

political constituencies in an ongoing adjudicative procedure by removing commissioners<br />

deemed hostile. No quasi-judicial regulatory body would be viewed as an authoritative and<br />

independent arbiter if the president had the authority to remove a commissioner deemed hostile<br />

to the interest of one or the other presidential constituencies. Agency independence, in this case,<br />

is indeed cruci<strong>all</strong>y dependent on the president not having powers of removal.<br />

The view that adjudicatory functions within the executive branch should be removed from<br />

presidential oversight is certainly not new. As some commentators have pointed out, the<br />

Founding Fathers placed considerable value on a unitary executive, but they also made clear that<br />

other values could on occasion trump unitariness. 7 Arguably, the independence of adjudicative<br />

functions was such a value. This is not <strong>all</strong> that surprising and quite consistent with contemporary<br />

notions of the separation of powers. This is not to say that presidents would be deprived of broad<br />

policy-making authority, or that they would loose the ability to ensure that the administrative<br />

apparatus conforms to their political priorities. The president can do so effectively through the<br />

appointment process, but also through the Office of Management and Budget (OMB) regulatory<br />

review and through presidential directives. For example, Section 1 of President Clinton’s<br />

Executive Order 12866 of September 30, 1993, requires that <strong>all</strong> federal agencies, in deciding<br />

whether to regulate, take <strong>all</strong> costs and benefits into account. 8 Obviously, Executive Order 12866<br />

7<br />

8<br />

Lessig and Sunstein, "The President and the Administration."; Cass Sunstein, "The Myth of the Unitary<br />

Executive," American University Administrative Law Journal 7 (1993).<br />

Executive Order 12866, 1993, “Statement of Regulatory Philosophy and Principles” states that (a) The<br />

Regulatory Philosophy. Federal agencies should promulgate only such regulations as are required by law, are<br />

necessary to interpret the law, or are made necessary by compelling public need, such as material failures of<br />

private markets to protect or improve the health and safety of the public, the environment, or the well-being of<br />

298


does little to directly affect the outcome of rule-making. It does, however, provide a specific<br />

policy framework within which any agency of the federal government, independent or executive,<br />

involved in regulatory activities must operate. 9 Executive Order 12866 advances a view of the<br />

regulatory state strongly informed by cost-benefit considerations. It goes almost without saying<br />

that at least some of the ethical principles outlined in chapter 3 would produce rules that might<br />

not pass a cost-benefit test. Whether these rules would be incompatible with Executive Order<br />

12866 is an interesting question that we are not prepared to discuss here.<br />

Skeptics could argue that adjudicative functions should not lie with an independent agency,<br />

but rather be delegated to the judiciary. We believe that there are good reasons for keeping these<br />

functions within the executive branch. An independent commission, unlike a panel of judges,<br />

specializes in a specific and narrow aspect of the law, in this case a statute pertaining to<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research. Over time, this regulatory institution would<br />

develop considerable expertise in adjudicating difficult bioethical controversies; the quality of its<br />

rulings, measured by their perceived fairness in the eyes of <strong>all</strong> affected parties and the general<br />

public, would increase, and so would the agency’s efficiency is delivering a ruling.<br />

The emphasis we have placed on agency independence could suggest inattention on our part<br />

to questions of accountability. A judicial body should be shielded from political manipulations.<br />

On the other end, there is a very real danger that a quasi-judicial body, as outlined in this report,<br />

could quickly turn into an unaccountable bureaucracy with a tendency to produce “arbitrary and<br />

capricious” opinions. Inadequate accountability would be just as corrosive as factionalism and<br />

capture, and must be avoided. Our discussion could have suggested that there may be an<br />

unavoidable trade-off between agency independence and accountability. This impression is<br />

misleading. We believe that it is quite possible to ensure both agency independence and<br />

accountability.<br />

The president and Congress have various means at their disposal for ensuring accountability.<br />

Congress can threaten to use the power of the purse to induce the agency to change its course, a<br />

threat used quite effectively in the past. Presidents, for their part, through their power to facilitate<br />

or impede future career moves, can exercise considerable influence on commissioners taking<br />

positions incompatible with broad public sentiments. Judicial review is also a powerful check on<br />

agency drift. These are <strong>all</strong> familiar checks and balances. With the exception of judicial review,<br />

these oversight measures could themselves be regarded as “arbitrary and capricious.” For this<br />

reason, we propose to ensure accountability by other means – i.e., through mechanisms of public<br />

consultation. How a public consultation could be embedded in traditional rule-making and what<br />

its impact would be on the legislative and executive branch is the topic of chapter 12. Here, we<br />

would simply like to point out that mechanisms of public consultation are likely to obviate a<br />

long-standing problem, namely that with the ability of either branch of government to maintain<br />

9<br />

the American people. In deciding whether and how to regulate, agencies should assess <strong>all</strong> costs and benefits of<br />

available regulatory alternatives, including the alternative of not regulating. […]”<br />

Note that this directive replaced a similar one origin<strong>all</strong>y signed by President Reagan, and that the current<br />

president has left Executive Order 12866 in place.<br />

299


accountability also comes the very real risk of excessive or inappropriate interventions by the<br />

office of the president or Congress. In sum, while advocates of a unitary executive may find it<br />

disturbing that in our proposal the president would be deprived of his or her removal powers, we<br />

believe that these powers are not necessary to protect the agency against capture, and that they<br />

could actu<strong>all</strong>y threaten the credibility and authority of this quasi-judicial regulatory body.<br />

11.2 Design Considerations<br />

Having justified in some detail why an independent commission is preferable to an<br />

executive agency with a single head, in this section we proceed to discuss several additional<br />

benefits and a few possible drawbacks of the proposed organizational format, and to examine<br />

specific implementation options.<br />

A deliberative body of government is much better suited to resolving complex ethical<br />

dilemmas than a single head of agency. Deliberation is likely to produce better reasoned and<br />

therefore more legitimate rulings. A fair judgment also requires taking into account <strong>all</strong><br />

perspectives, and doing so in a balanced manner. A single head of agency is simply in no<br />

position to meet <strong>all</strong> these requirements. Another reason for preferring the commission format to a<br />

single head of agency is that the decision-making process would be more transparent. Opening<br />

the commission meetings to the public would likely increase the quality of the arguments in<br />

favor of and against any given policy. It would also shield the commissioners against the most<br />

blatant attempts to manipulate the decision-making process. 10 This is not to say that private<br />

conversations in this regulatory context have no useful role to play. To the contrary, a measure of<br />

privacy is indispensable for commissioners to establish relationships of mutual trust. How<br />

exactly conflicting demands for privacy and for public access should be reconciled is not a<br />

question with a straightforward answer.<br />

A commission, by its very nature, is less exposed to manipulative attempts by Congressional<br />

representatives. The history of the administrative state clearly demonstrates that often it is<br />

precisely Congressional representatives who advance the most parochial agendas on behalf of<br />

their constituencies. A commission format dilutes administrative authority and makes it more<br />

difficult for politicians to directly influence regulatory process. <strong>Final</strong>ly, a deliberative approach<br />

to resolving ethical dilemmas is particularly well-suited to reconciling different interests and<br />

ethical positions. It also helps in crafting broadly acceptable political compromises. As shown in<br />

chapter 10, a deliberative approach to ethical controversies does not guarantee consensus or<br />

unanimity, and under certain circumstances deliberation may even sharpen the divisions among<br />

commissioners. On the other end, it is difficult to imagine addressing any ethical dilemmas in a<br />

non-deliberative fashion.<br />

Having mentioned the benefits associated with a commission format, we should mention<br />

some potenti<strong>all</strong>y significant disadvantages. Scholars of public administration have pointed out<br />

10<br />

Making the transcripts of public meetings available to the public, as is now common across the federal<br />

government, would also have a positive educational impact on the general public.<br />

300


that independent commissions tend to attract second-rate candidates for office. An appointment<br />

to a federal regulatory commission gener<strong>all</strong>y is not a sufficient enticement to attract top<br />

administrative talent. This is especi<strong>all</strong>y the case when an independent commission’s work has<br />

become somewhat of a routine. Independent agencies are also likely to be inefficient. 11 Some<br />

commentators have pointed out that a deliberative approach to rule-making and the search for<br />

consensus solutions make for slow decision-making.<br />

These criticisms are accurate, but only in a narrow sense. The kinds of skills embodied in<br />

ambitious, top-notch administrators would be of little use in the context of a deliberative body.<br />

Making the most efficient use of bureaucratic resources to achieve a policy goal is not what the<br />

resolution of complex ethical dilemmas requires. Not only would top administrators not be<br />

attracted by this body, their appointment is unnecessary and would be counterproductive. Strong<br />

personalities with an extensive business background are a poor choice for a quasi-judicial,<br />

egalitarian, and deliberative body of government.<br />

The quality and competence of prospective commissioners is not likely to degrade over time<br />

for the simple reason that medical and scientific progress will keep the agency’s work from<br />

becoming routine. As the case of the British Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority<br />

demonstrates, in its 14 years history, that agency rarely has formulated a policy that did not<br />

generate considerable public controversy. And while it is certainly true that in certain regulatory<br />

contexts – as in the case of product safety, for example – the commission format most likely has<br />

been the primary reason for an unacceptably slow pace of decision-making, 12 one may wonder<br />

whether in the case of nuclear power safety slow decision-making is such a bad thing. Efficiency<br />

is only one of several competing goals in designing a system of governance. A head of agency<br />

most likely would resolve ethical dilemmas in a more expeditious way, but protracted judicial<br />

review would more than compensate for increased efficiency at the regulatory stage. One simply<br />

has to accept the fact that deliberative bodies are not designed to operate in an efficient manner,<br />

and that producing fair and just rules in this case takes precedence over bureaucratic efficiency.<br />

What criteria, then, should inform the design of this commission? At the international level,<br />

there seems to be a growing consensus that a regulatory body in the area of reproductive<br />

medicine and biomedical research should be composed of representatives of specific<br />

constituencies. The British have been the first to adopt this approach. As discussed in chapter 6,<br />

the HFEA governing body consists of 18 persons. In addition to representatives of the fertility<br />

industry and the medical community, this body includes a majority of what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed<br />

laypersons, i.e., individuals who do not represent a clearly identifiable interest group. This was<br />

11<br />

12<br />

Commentators seem to agree that independent agencies are an inefficient form of government, yet there is<br />

precious little evidence of actual inefficiency, if by evidence we mean a systematic, comparative analysis of<br />

decision-making within different types of government organizations. It is true that during the New Deal, the<br />

Golden Age of independent agencies, regulatory capture and organizational dysfunction were of almost Biblical<br />

proportions, as documented, for example, in James M. Landis, The Administrative Process (New Haven: Yale<br />

University Press, 1938). modern independent agencies do not bear much resemblance to their ancestors.<br />

Elliot Klayman, "Standard Setting under the Consumer Product Safety Amendments of 1981 – a Shift in<br />

Regulatory Philosophy," George Washington Law Review 51 (1982).<br />

301


and remains the British solution to the problem of capture by factional interests. Perhaps inspired<br />

by the British precedent, the Australian and Canadian governments have also established<br />

regulatory bodies structured in functional terms, though in these latter two cases, it appears that<br />

preventing regulatory capture was not of paramount importance in <strong>all</strong>ocating the available slots.<br />

We believe that an independent agency for regulating reproductive medicine and research in<br />

the United States should not be thought of and designed as a representative body of key political<br />

interests. Attempts to ensure representation would likely produce a large regulatory body<br />

consisting of many narrow and mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive interests. Affected constituencies are illdefined<br />

societal groupings with a tendency to proliferate. For example, it may not be sufficient to<br />

ensure that the interests of prospective parents are adequately represented, because at some point,<br />

lesbians and homosexual associations may feel that their constituents’ interests are sufficiently<br />

distinct from those of traditional couples as to deserve separate representation. This distinction,<br />

in turn, may encourage singles to claim their own separate seat at the regulatory table. The ART<br />

industry and the scientific communities are likely to suffer from the same fragmentation<br />

tendencies. As a general rule, the more homogeneous a political constituency becomes, the more<br />

specific and narrow its interests, and the more difficult it is for its representatives to accept<br />

political compromises, let alone produce consensual solutions. This is not to say that factional<br />

interests should be ignored, but merely that these groups should have an opportunity to be heard<br />

in a different setting. 13<br />

Independent commissions are gener<strong>all</strong>y quite sm<strong>all</strong>. With very few exceptions, U.S.<br />

independent agencies consist of only three to five commissioners (the Federal Reserve Board<br />

being a noteworthy exception). Bureaucratic efficiency would require keeping the number of<br />

commissioners sm<strong>all</strong>, but in this case, efficiency is neither the only nor the most important<br />

design consideration, nor is size as detrimental to efficiency as commentators tend to believe.<br />

The British and Australian regulatory bodies in the area of biomedicine are considerably larger.<br />

The HFEA is governed by an 18-member body, as stated above, while the Australian Embryo<br />

Research Licensing Committee consists of nine members. Whether the size of the HFEA<br />

governing committee has had a negative impact on the ability of the British regulators to oversee<br />

reproductive medicine in an efficient way is an interesting but also very difficult question to<br />

answer. Anecdotal evidence suggests that in controversial and highly visible cases, the HFEA<br />

indeed proceeded at a glacial pace. If one examines the HFEA decision-making record over its<br />

entire existence, however, it is difficult to depict this agency as a paragon of bureaucratic<br />

inefficiency. So while to U.S. commentators an 18-member independent commission may seem<br />

exceedingly large, experience demonstrates that a regulatory body of this size is quite capable of<br />

meeting its public mandate.<br />

Another reason for not attaching too much importance to the size of a regulatory body is<br />

that, in the case of the HFEA, for example, the slow pace of decision-making was not as much a<br />

13<br />

Establishing specific commission positions may also be interpreted as an unconstitutional limitation on the<br />

presidential prerogative to appoint executive officers.<br />

302


eflection of the committee size as a conscious choice by the HFEA to resolve deep divisions<br />

among its members by consensus rather than by majority vote. Conclusive evidence is not<br />

available, given the British penchant to conduct business in a rather informal manner, but<br />

anecdotal evidence suggests that the HFEA often has strived to find consensual answers to the<br />

ethical dilemmas. Taking a vote would of course make the decision-making process considerably<br />

more efficient, but efficiency would have been achieved at the cost of legitimacy.<br />

One important reason for not envisaging a large commission is that a sm<strong>all</strong>er commission<br />

has a better chance to produce a genuine consensus. Yet sm<strong>all</strong> size has its own problems. Sm<strong>all</strong><br />

bodies are exposed to the risks of individual idiosyncrasies and perverse group dynamics in a<br />

way that larger bodies are not. Some commissioners may become too influential; others may<br />

become irrelevant. By contrast, the larger the group, the less idiosyncratic it is likely to become.<br />

The influence of individual members becomes sm<strong>all</strong>er the larger the body is. In addition,<br />

members of a very sm<strong>all</strong> regulatory body may quickly become trapped in mechanical reactions<br />

and argumentative frameworks that would make it very difficult for this board ever to achieve<br />

consensus. For this reason alone, the periodic renewal of commission members may be crucial to<br />

maintaining the commission’s ability to regulate. 14<br />

Absent empiric<strong>all</strong>y validated rules for<br />

determining the optimal size of a sm<strong>all</strong> regulatory body such as the one envisaged in this chapter,<br />

we believe that a commission of seven to nine members represents a reasonable compromise<br />

between the pros and cons of large versus sm<strong>all</strong> decision-making bodies.<br />

Consensual solutions to complex ethical dilemmas contribute to increasing the legitimacy of<br />

a controversial regulatory body in a way that a majority vote does not, though it is not entirely<br />

obvious why this is so. Perhaps a consensual response to difficult ethical dilemmas reinforces the<br />

regulators’ moral authority in the eyes of the general public. To the extent that <strong>all</strong> affected parties<br />

and the public regard this regulatory body as genuinely independent, consensual solutions would<br />

certainly make controversial policies more acceptable to the loosing factions. For this reason,<br />

organizational design should privilege structures and procedures that favor consensus solutions.<br />

Very little consolidated knowledge is available on how to promote achieving a consensus.<br />

Deliberation, as often noted in this report, certainly is an important contributing factor, but its<br />

importance should not be overemphasized. Just as important in this context is the actual<br />

composition of the regulatory body with regard to the commissioners’ views and ethical<br />

inclinations. Commissioners with weak preferences are preferable to candidates with very strong<br />

views if finding consensus is indeed of paramount importance. Against this background,<br />

appointing professional bioethicists or individuals with considerable ethical expertise may be<br />

counterproductive. The appointment of what may be described as thoughtful generalists would<br />

promote a deliberative process that starts from genuine ambivalent positions and fluid<br />

preferences rather than from clearly articulated interests. The appointment of generalists <strong>all</strong> but<br />

ensures that these individuals would not have strong <strong>all</strong>egiances to any particular constituency.<br />

Just as important is ensuring that no particular view is overrepresented. In practice, this<br />

14<br />

In this regard, see Moreno, Deciding Together. Bioethics and Moral Consensus, ch.8.<br />

303


equirement is very difficult to implement, as the agency is c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to regulate disparate<br />

issues likely to produce different distributions of individual positions.<br />

An obvious way to ensure consensus is for the Congress to mandate consensual decisionmaking<br />

in the enabling legislation. This extreme measure would ensure that the agency will<br />

promulgate only broadly supported rules and regulations, but it would also mean that as a matter<br />

of practice, this regulatory agency will produce very little legal guidance. And consensus, in<br />

many cases, may simply reflect a political compromise and not a genuine common view<br />

achieved in a deliberative manner. Consensus through compromise may be an acceptable<br />

alternative to genuine consensus when the commissioners have clear and strong preferences. In<br />

this case, deliberation will contribute to clarifying the commissioners’ positions, but it is unlikely<br />

to cause the commissioners to change their ethical preferences. This outcome may not be<br />

satisfactory to advocates of deliberative democracy, but it may well be the only available option<br />

short of deciding by majority vote – an alternative that, considering its corrosive impact on the<br />

moral authority of a regulatory body, is far less attractive. 15<br />

In the world of politics, it is unrealistic to expect that even the best-intentioned and<br />

thoughtful commission would always produce a consensus. One possible alternative to making<br />

choices either by consensus or by majority voting is to invest the chairperson with the authority<br />

to decide on a case-by-case basis whether an ongoing rule-making process is likely to produce a<br />

consensus. Should he or she determine that a consensus could be achieved, he or she may decide<br />

to invest more time in deliberation; otherwise, he would simply c<strong>all</strong> for a vote. Alternatively, the<br />

enabling legislation could provide for a fixed, maximum period of deliberation, say three<br />

months, followed by a vote. Depending on the issue under consideration, a simple majority could<br />

suffice; in more divisive cases, a supermajority may be required.<br />

If designed according to the criteria discussed in this report, a regulatory commission is<br />

much more likely to promulgate consensus policies than the preceding discussion indicates. The<br />

commission’s deliberations would take place at an advanced stage of the rule-making process. At<br />

that stage, the commissioners would be able to review the range of positions advocated by a wide<br />

range of affected and interested parties, as well as to gauge the public’s response to various<br />

policy options emerging from a process of public consultation. As a practical matter, it may not<br />

always be possible to conduct public consultation, and in some cases the consultation may not<br />

produce an unambiguous outcome. But to the extent that a clear public inclination emerges, it<br />

would dramatic<strong>all</strong>y reduce the potential for gridlock.<br />

In discussing possible implementation options, we have privileged legitimacy, moral<br />

authority, and consensus over efficiency, representativeness, and ethical expertise. These choices<br />

15<br />

There is no consensus on the actual value of deliberation in the regulatory and more gener<strong>all</strong>y in the political<br />

context. In a recently published book, Judge Richard Posner has argued that deliberation is of little value to the<br />

functioning of modern representative democracies. Cf. Posner, Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy. That the role<br />

of deliberation is not as straightforward as sometimes assumed is not in dispute. But it would be difficult to<br />

argue that deliberation has no impact, even on highly opinionated individuals. The change of heart displayed by<br />

some solidly conservative Supreme Court justices seems to indicate that even highly competent and opinionated<br />

individuals in a deliberative context may re-examine their views.<br />

304


should not be taken to suggest that the latter design considerations are unimportant, but only that<br />

there are trade-offs in the design of an independent regulatory agency. In this sense, our<br />

approach departs significantly from that of the British. In our view, representativeness is not<br />

sufficiently important as to warrant explicit consideration in the design of our independent<br />

commission. Nor is efficiency so important as to warrant reducing this independent agency to a<br />

three-member body, though it is sufficiently important as to induce us to avoid recommending an<br />

18-member panel. <strong>Final</strong>ly, we believe that ensuring the legitimacy and credibility of this body<br />

should have priority over its ethical and scientific expertise. This is not to say that<br />

representativeness and ethical and scientific expertise should be neglected, but rather that<br />

organized interest groups should have a chance to be heard in a different setting, and that the<br />

commission should be granted access to ethical and scientific expertise by bureaucratic means.<br />

11.2.1 The Advisory Board<br />

Many of the limitations characterizing the British, Australian, and Canadian approaches to<br />

regulating biomedicine can be traced to organizational trade-offs. It is simply not possible to<br />

design a sm<strong>all</strong> deliberative body that is authoritative and legitimate and at the same time broadly<br />

representative of <strong>all</strong> affected parties and knowledgeable in ethical, medical, and scientific<br />

matters. For this reason, we propose to complement the independent commission with an<br />

advisory board. As its name suggests, the board would not have regulatory authority. In essence,<br />

its job would be to serve as an institutionalized communication platform between the<br />

commissioners, the regulated community, and the general public.<br />

The board would be designed to ensure representativeness and technical competence in <strong>all</strong><br />

relevant scientific fields and in bioethics. It would operate in a deliberative fashion, but would<br />

not be required to produce consensus recommendations. Majority and minority positions would<br />

not only be <strong>all</strong>owed but welcomed, for the reasons discussed in chapter 10. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the board<br />

would not be subject to size constraints to the same extent as the independent commission, and<br />

could be considerably larger.<br />

Representativeness requires elaboration. The advisory board would be representative of <strong>all</strong><br />

affected parties, but not as this term is norm<strong>all</strong>y understood. An affected party should not<br />

necessarily be equated to any existing professional or trade association. Affected parties include<br />

the ART industry, the scientific community, the biotech industry, and patients. Each sector<br />

would receive a fixed and equal number of slots. Trade and professional associations and their<br />

members would be responsible for selecting and nominating suitable candidates. For example,<br />

the scientific community may decide that it wants to be represented by the American Association<br />

for the Advancement of Science. In this case, AAAS would represent not only its own members,<br />

but also the members of other scientific societies, such as the Federation of American Societies<br />

for Experimental Biology or the American Society for Microbiology. Analogous choices would<br />

have to be made by the ART industry and its various trade and professional associations.<br />

There are good reasons for proposing such a broad concept of representativeness. As<br />

repeatedly discussed in this report, the broader the sector represented by a member of this<br />

305


advisory board, the higher the chances that the advisory board will succeed in generating broadly<br />

acceptable policy recommendations. To use the terminology developed in chapter 10, the less<br />

homogenous the sector represented, the less likely it is that the advisory board will display<br />

polarization tendencies.<br />

Some commentators have observed that advisory panels, especi<strong>all</strong>y those meant to provide<br />

scientific guidance, may have both a subtle and a disproportionate influence on regulatory<br />

agencies. 16 How an ethical dilemma is framed and what language and metaphors are used to<br />

describe the relevant ethical concerns are choices likely to affect how an independent<br />

commission will resolve a controversy. This is why it is important that <strong>all</strong> societal perspectives<br />

be represented on this panel, including those of laypersons. A layperson is an individual who<br />

does not represent the interests of the ART industry, patients, the scientific community, or the<br />

biotech industry. Furthermore, this person is not immediately or substanti<strong>all</strong>y affected by<br />

advances in reproductive medicine or biomedical research, and does not have financial interests<br />

in the sectors subject to the commission’s regulatory authority.<br />

There are at least four reasons for appointing a substantial number of laypersons to the<br />

advisory board. Laypersons are likely to advocate a notion of harm not limited to economic costs<br />

or to narrowly defined health risks. They would also prevent the advisory board from focusing<br />

exclusively on procedural matters. In addition, a significant number of laypersons would<br />

contribute to preventing or mitigating group polarization. To this end, it would not be sufficient,<br />

as is common practice on many science advisory boards, to appoint only one layperson.<br />

Depolarization can only take place if <strong>all</strong> relevant views are represented in roughly equal<br />

numbers. A fourth and final reason for including laypersons on the advisory board is their<br />

policing role. By virtue of its position between the independent commission and the affected<br />

parties, the advisory panel could accumulate considerable power and influence. As for any other<br />

broker, the role of this advisory board could be both beneficial and pernicious. On the one end, it<br />

could actively promote collaboration, consensus, and compromise. Alternatively, it could<br />

promote a political agenda of its own. 17 Absent independent board members, it is quite possible<br />

for a societal sector to obtain support for a policy in its interest in return for the promise to return<br />

the favor in the future.<br />

How many laypersons should be appointed? Our discussion of group polarization suggests<br />

that for laypersons to develop a genuinely independent voice, their weight on the commission<br />

should be comparable to that of other societal interests. For this reason, we propose to appoint at<br />

least as many laypersons as representatives of any one of the other societal sectors. If the<br />

enabling legislation does not require the advisory board to produce consensus recommendations,<br />

16<br />

17<br />

Sheila Jasanoff, The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers as Policymakers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 1990).<br />

This is a somewhat unusual illustration of what may be c<strong>all</strong>ed a “political entrepreneur.” As pointed out by<br />

Ronald Burt, an entrepreneur is an individual (or an organization) that has identified two disconnected parties<br />

who could each benefit from cooperation but are unable to do so by themselves. Ronald S. Burt, Structural<br />

Holes. The Social Structure of Competition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).<br />

306


then an equal number of representatives for <strong>all</strong> societal sectors, including the general public,<br />

would be acceptable. On the other hand, if recommendations on the advisory board are made by<br />

majority vote, then the number of appointed laypersons should be much larger – and equal that<br />

of <strong>all</strong> interested parties combined.<br />

The advisory board would also work with the commission to implement and operate a<br />

suitable system of monitoring and compliance assurance. This move has both obvious and<br />

subtler benefits. By delegating monitoring functions to the advisory board, the commission<br />

would be able to focus on its core task. Less intuitively, delegation of monitoring and<br />

compliance assurance to third parties is likely to produce higher levels of compliance and, in the<br />

long run, to increase the legitimacy of government regulation in the eyes of the regulated<br />

community. We will return to this topic in chapter 13. 18<br />

To prevent this advisory from becoming unaccountable to its constituencies, the enabling<br />

legislation could require that board members be in close contact with their constituencies. The<br />

importance of this measure can hardly be overemphasized. Absent any accountability<br />

mechanism, board members would be free to advance a political agenda that may be entirely<br />

detached from the constituencies they supposedly represent. As noted in chapter 8, little is<br />

known about the attitudes of scientists, reproductive doctors, or biotech companies on a broad<br />

range of contested policy questions. There is some evidence that these constituencies do not<br />

always endorse their association’s positions. Whether, for example, scientists share the views<br />

and positions of the AAAS or any one of the many scientific societies operating in Washington is<br />

debatable. Some scientific societies do make some efforts to consult with their members on<br />

important issues, but these are exceptional cases. It is quite possible that the associations’<br />

positions in the area of reproductive medicine and biomedical technologies are aligned with their<br />

members’ views; yet absent specific mechanisms of consultation, this question cannot be<br />

answered.<br />

This requirement would not be as unusual as it may seem. As a matter of practice, many<br />

trade and professional organizations already consult with their members on various issues of<br />

mutual interest. And one should remember that there are significant benefits to implementing this<br />

measure. By adopting a robust mechanism of internal consultation, the legitimacy of the<br />

positions represented on the advisory board would greatly be strengthened.<br />

18<br />

The delegation of monitoring and compliance assurance functions to private parties is a classic example of what<br />

is sometime referred to as “collaborative governance.” Jody Freeman, "Collaborative Governance in the<br />

Administrative State," UCLA Law Review 45 (1997); Jody Freeman, "The Private Role in Public Governance,"<br />

New York University Law Review 75 (2000); Lester M. Salamon, Partners in Public Service: Government-<br />

Nonprofit Relations in the Modern Welfare State (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995).<br />

Collaborative governance describes an approach to government in which a government agency plays a prominent<br />

role, but is by no means the only relevant actor in the implementation of public policies.<br />

307


11.2.2 The Advisory Board as a Board of Directors?<br />

The appointment of representatives of the general public to a federal advisory board is<br />

certainly unusual within government, but it would not be exceptional in the private sector. The<br />

type of advisory board envisaged in this report is not too dissimilar from a board of directors. In<br />

the United States, it is common practice to appoint independent board directors, but this<br />

corporate role is relatively new. To appreciate its importance, it is instructive to revisit the<br />

motivations for creating independent board members.<br />

In the late 1970s, a string of highly visible corporate scandals prompted the business and<br />

legal communities to reexamine the then-dominant approach to corporate governance. 19 At the<br />

time, the debate was informed by the assumption that poor corporate governance was the direct<br />

consequence of the sharp separation of ownership and control. In a nutshell, shareholders “own”<br />

the corporation, but they have very little say in how it is managed. Conversely, management is<br />

largely responsible for both strategic decisions and the day-to-day operations, but it has few if<br />

any property rights in the firm. One of the main tasks of the board of directors, then, is to ensure<br />

that the shareholders’ and senior management’s interests are aligned. This includes monitoring<br />

strategic decisions and preventing opportunistic behavior by senior management – i.e.,<br />

management choices designed primarily to benefit senior management to the detriment of the<br />

company. 20<br />

As a matter of practice, this laudable construction has been of limited effectiveness. Because<br />

senior management often appoints the board members, and because those board members used to<br />

be subordinates, their willingness to intervene in managerial decisions is limited. In other cases,<br />

top individuals in management would simply appoint themselves to the board. Not surprisingly,<br />

then, early studies found that boards of directors play a largely passive role in governing<br />

corporations and are in no position to ch<strong>all</strong>enge senior management’s decisions. 21<br />

A proposal that eventu<strong>all</strong>y garnered considerable support in both the legal and business<br />

communities was the appointment of independent or outside board members. Independent<br />

directors were meant to increase both the independence of the board of directors from top<br />

management and the board’s ability to prevent opportunistic behavior. The notion of the<br />

independent (or outside) director is itself broad, and can be interpreted in various ways.<br />

Form<strong>all</strong>y, an outside director is an individual who is not currently employed by the corporation<br />

he or she is meant to oversee. Practic<strong>all</strong>y, this may include former employees, retired executives,<br />

19<br />

20<br />

21<br />

Stephen M. Bainbridge, "Independent Directors and the ALI Corporate Governance Project," George<br />

Washington Law Review 61 (1993); Melvin A. Eisenberg, "Corporate Governance: The Board of Directors and<br />

Internal Control," Cardozo Law Review 19 (1997); Roberta S. Karmel, "The Independent Corporate Board: A<br />

Means to What End?," George Washington Law Review 52 (1984); Mark J. Loewenstein, "The SEC and the<br />

Future of Corporate Governance," Alabama Law Review 45 (1994).<br />

“Opportunistic behavior” indicates the pursuit by senior management of its own financial interests to the<br />

detriment of shareholders’ best interests.<br />

Myles L. Mace, Directors: Myth and Reality (Boston: Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard<br />

University, 1971); Lewis D. Solomon, "Restructuring the Corporate Board of Directors: Fond Hope: Faint<br />

Promise?," Michigan Law Review 76, no. 4 (1978).<br />

308


or individuals who have been selected by the CEO because of their close personal ties to top<br />

management. These individuals, while technic<strong>all</strong>y outsiders, do not meet any strong, substantive<br />

notion of independence. 22<br />

Other commentators have submitted that the outside director’s role is not simply one of<br />

monitoring senior management on behalf of the shareholders, but of representing a broad range<br />

of societal constituencies, including employees; representatives of women, minorities, and<br />

environmental groups; key corporate customers; consumer groups; representatives of the<br />

financial community; and large institutional investors. The inclusion of these stakeholders serves<br />

several purposes, including obtaining access to information, reducing coordination costs,<br />

facilitating access to capital, obtaining independent advice, providing a mechanism of early<br />

warning, and, last but not least, protecting the corporation’s public image. 23<br />

Over the last 20 years, the composition of U.S. boards of directors has shifted significantly<br />

to reflect these demands. As of 1998, corporate boards of publicly traded corporations had on<br />

average 11 directors, but only two inside directors, down from three inside directors in 1993 and<br />

five in 1973. 24 Paradoxic<strong>all</strong>y, it is not entirely clear that the inclusion of outside directors has<br />

improved corporate boards’ ability to prevent corporate misconduct. The empirical evidence in<br />

this regard is mixed. 25 There are straightforward reasons for doubting the effectiveness of outside<br />

directors, some of which we have already <strong>all</strong>uded to: Outside directors may be insiders in<br />

disguise. They may lack either the expertise or the resources (or both) to closely and competently<br />

monitor senior management. Cruci<strong>all</strong>y, they may not have access to the information necessary to<br />

accurately assess the performance of senior management. Lastly, they may not be inclined<br />

openly to ch<strong>all</strong>enge senior management and risk losing their positions on the board. 26<br />

Perhaps paradoxic<strong>all</strong>y, independent board members are much more likely to meet the<br />

expectations imposed on them in the regulatory context than in the business sector. Monitoring<br />

the independent commission is a straightforward task, and concerns regarding the competence of<br />

these board members are of secondary importance, because their responsibility would not entail<br />

assessing complex technical matters. In short, the effectiveness of independent board members is<br />

likely to be far greater in government than in the private sector.<br />

11.2.3 Appointment Rules<br />

Identifying suitable appointment criteria for independent board members presents a bit of a<br />

ch<strong>all</strong>enge. There is certainly no dearth of organizations that would feel quite comfortable<br />

22<br />

23<br />

24<br />

25<br />

26<br />

Victor Brudney, "The Independent Director: Heavenly City or Potemkin Village?," Harvard Law Review 95, no.<br />

3 (1982).<br />

Lynne L. D<strong>all</strong>as, "The Multiple Roles of Corporate Boards of Directors," San Diego Law Review 40 (2003),<br />

p.796-800.<br />

Ibid., p.787.<br />

For a discussion see, Kathleen A. Farrell and David A. Whidbee, "The Consequences of Forced CEO Succession<br />

for Outside Directors," Journal of Business 73, no. 4 (2000).<br />

Brudney, "The Independent Director: Heavenly City or Potemkin Village?."<br />

309


suggesting candidates. They include religious organizations such as United States Conference of<br />

Catholic Bishops and the Southern Baptist Convention, soci<strong>all</strong>y conservative organizations such<br />

as the Family Research Council, and secular groups such as the Center for Genetics and Society.<br />

Most of them would likely see themselves as legitimate representatives of the general public, or<br />

at least as representing views not associated with the regulated community. Each of these groups<br />

would inject a distinctive perspective into the debate and could be expected to oppose the ART<br />

industry and the scientific community on many key issues. From a pluralist perspective, this<br />

indeed would seem a natural way to select independent board members.<br />

Our analysis of the current legislative stalemate in chapter 10 suggests that this would not be<br />

a wise move. By mechanic<strong>all</strong>y appointing representatives of opposing interest groups, we would<br />

simply replicate on a sm<strong>all</strong>er scale the current political gridlock. Furthermore, including<br />

constituencies on the advisory board that are not directly and negatively affected by regulatory<br />

interventions could be problematic, if not downright arbitrary. In the current litigious climate, it<br />

would be very difficult to justify why one particular organization should be preferred to an<br />

equ<strong>all</strong>y credible group. Conceivably, one could envisage adopting the same procedure laid out<br />

for appointing the representatives of affected parties: Interested organizations are responsible for<br />

identifying broadly acceptable candidates for the available slots. In this case, however, we are<br />

not dealing with a reasonably homogeneous organizational universe, and there is little chance<br />

that these organizations would agree on common candidates. For these reasons, appointing<br />

laypersons in the narrow sense of this term is a preferable option.<br />

We propose that the head of an executive agency – for example, the head of the Department<br />

of Health and Human Services – be charged with appointing independent board members. The<br />

enabling legislation should provide considerable guidance as to what constitutes an independent<br />

commissioner. This point should not be underestimated. Even a cursory examination of an<br />

average advisory board charter would demonstrate that agency heads have a tendency to ignore<br />

the Federal Advisory Committee Act’s c<strong>all</strong>s for “fair and balanced” appointments, instead<br />

simply filling these slots with political <strong>all</strong>ies. Several desirable characteristics of an independent<br />

advisory board member have already been identified: An independent board member should not<br />

have strong ties to the ART or the biotech industries or to the scientific community. A financial<br />

interest in the ART or biotech industries would most likely be regarded as prejudicial. A<br />

biomedical scientist would also not qualify for a position as an independent board member,<br />

though perhaps other natural scientists and in particular social scientists might. An independent<br />

board member should not have close relatives affected by medical conditions that could be cured<br />

by promoting certain types of research. 27 Most importantly, perhaps, these individuals should<br />

bring with them the analytical skills and life experience necessary to navigate complex questions<br />

at the intersection of ethics, science, and medicine.<br />

27<br />

We are certainly not suggesting that the patients’ interests should be ignored. We believe that their interests are<br />

adequately represented by both patient groups and the scientific community.<br />

310


How should these individuals be identified? Standard random sampling techniques followed<br />

by a standardized interview would produce a sizeable pool of suitable candidates. We believe<br />

this approach is superior to the British approach in terms of procedural fairness, in that it would<br />

not be subject to self-selection bias, and the selection criteria would be established in advance. In<br />

order to further reduce possible sources of administrative drift, independent board members<br />

could be selected at random from the pool of suitable candidates. In turn, this suggests that in<br />

addition to the selection criteria discussed above, it may be necessary to ensure balance in terms<br />

of regional representation and socio-demographic characteristics. Alternatively, the head of<br />

agency could person<strong>all</strong>y select independent board members based on a personal conversation.<br />

Selection through a head of agency would probably identify better-suited candidates, but in the<br />

current political climate, it is unlikely to be acceptable to <strong>all</strong> affected parties. The technocratic<br />

alternative may not produce equ<strong>all</strong>y capable independent directors, but it is a practicable solution<br />

and would not be regarded as biased. 28<br />

28<br />

The novel nature of this appointment process may require Congress to periodic<strong>all</strong>y revisit the enabling<br />

legislation and update appointment rules and procedures based on past experience.<br />

311


312


11.3 Bibliography<br />

Bainbridge, Stephen M. "Independent Directors and the ALI Corporate Governance Project."<br />

George Washington Law Review 61 (1993): 1034-83.<br />

Bartlett Foote, Susan. "Independent Agencies under Attack: A Skeptical View of the Importance<br />

of the Debate." Duke Law Journal 1988 (1988): 223-37.<br />

Blumstein, James F. "Regulatory Review by the Executive Office of the President: An Overview<br />

and Policy Analysis of Current Issues." Duke Law Journal 51 (2001): 851-99.<br />

Brudney, Victor. "The Independent Director: Heavenly City or Potemkin Village?" Harvard Law<br />

Review 95, no. 3 (1982): 597-659.<br />

Burt, Ronald S. Structural Holes. The Social Structure of Competition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

D<strong>all</strong>as, Lynne L. "The Multiple Roles of Corporate Boards of Directors." San Diego Law Review<br />

40 (2003): 781-820.<br />

Easterbrook, Frank H. "Presidential Review." Case Western Reserve Law Review 40 (1990):<br />

905-29.<br />

Eisenberg, Melvin A. "Corporate Governance: The Board of Directors and Internal Control."<br />

Cardozo Law Review 19 (1997): 237-64.<br />

Farrell, Kathleen A., and David A. Whidbee. "The Consequences of Forced CEO Succession for<br />

Outside Directors." Journal of Business 73, no. 4 (2000): 597-627.<br />

Freeman, Jody. "Collaborative Governance in the Administrative State." UCLA Law Review 45<br />

(1997): 1-98.<br />

———. "The Private Role in Public Governance." New York University Law Review 75 (2000):<br />

543-675.<br />

House of Commons, Science and Technology Committee. "Inquiry into Human Reproductive<br />

Technologies and the Law: Eighth Special <strong>Report</strong> of Session 2004-05." London: The<br />

Stationary Office, 2005.<br />

Jasanoff, Sheila. The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers as Policymakers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1990.<br />

Karmel, Roberta S. "The Independent Corporate Board: A Means to What End?" George<br />

Washington Law Review 52 (1984): 534-56.<br />

Klayman, Elliot. "Standard Setting under the Consumer Product Safety Amendments of 1981 – a<br />

Shift in Regulatory Philosophy." George Washington Law Review 51 (1982): 96-112.<br />

Landis, James M. The Administrative Process. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1938.<br />

Lessig, Lawrence, and Cass Sunstein. "The President and the Administration." Columbia Law<br />

Review 94 (1994): 1-120.<br />

Loewenstein, Mark J. "The SEC and the Future of Corporate Governance." Alabama Law<br />

Review 45 (1994): 783-815.<br />

Mace, Myles L. Directors: Myth and Reality. Boston: Graduate School of Business<br />

Administration, Harvard University, 1971.<br />

Miller, James C. "A Reflection on the Independence of Independent Agencies." Duke Law<br />

Journal 1988 (1988): 297-99.<br />

Moreno, Jonathan D. Deciding Together. Bioethics and Moral Consensus. New York: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1995.<br />

313


Morrison, Alan B. "How Independent Are Independent Regulatory Agencies?" Duke Law<br />

Journal 1988 (1988): 252-56.<br />

Peters, Aulana L. "Independent Agencies: Government's Scourge or Salvation?" Duke Law<br />

Journal 1988 (1988): 286-96.<br />

Posner, Richard A. Law, Pragmatism, and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 2003.<br />

Robinson, Glen O. "Independent Agencies: Form and Substance in Executive Prerogative." Duke<br />

Law Journal 288 (1988): 238-51.<br />

Salamon, Lester M. Partners in Public Service: Government-Nonprofit Relations in the Modern<br />

Welfare State. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995.<br />

Solomon, Lewis D. "Restructuring the Corporate Board of Directors: Fond Hope: Faint<br />

Promise?" Michigan Law Review 76, no. 4 (1978): 581-610.<br />

Sunstein, Cass. "The Myth of the Unitary Executive." American University Administrative Law<br />

Journal 7 (1993): 299-308.<br />

Verkuil, Paul R. "The Purposes and Limits of Independent Agencies." Duke Law Journal 1988<br />

(1988): 257-79.<br />

314


12 Designing Mechanisms of Public Consultation<br />

A key element of our regulatory proposal is an institutionalized mechanism of public<br />

consultation. In chapter 10, we have argued that consulting with the public is necessary to<br />

mitigate the distorting impact of interest group politics, while in chapter 11, we have shown that<br />

an institution of public consultation is indispensable both to ensure agency independence and to<br />

prevent factionalism. In the following discussion, we lay out in some detail how it may be<br />

possible to implement institutions of public consultation that meet the requirements discussed in<br />

section 10.7: The agency must ensure that the consulted public is a representative sample of the<br />

general population, that the sample is balanced, that the consulted public is adequately informed,<br />

and, last but not least, that the process is deliberative.<br />

With regard to the implementation of mechanisms of public consultation, it is crucial that<br />

the enabling legislation be sufficiently specific. First, the public should be consulted on any new<br />

regulatory initiative. Second, Congress should specify in some detail what criteria a consultative<br />

mechanism should meet. Third, Congress should mandate that the consultative process be<br />

conducted at the early stages of the rule-making process, in par<strong>all</strong>el to traditional consultations<br />

with organized interest groups, and in any case well before the announcement of a proposed new<br />

rule. Fourth, the enabling statute should require that the outcomes of any process of public<br />

consultation be published as soon as the consultation has been concluded, but in any case no later<br />

than the publication of a proposed new rule. All materials related to the consultation process<br />

must be made available to the general public.<br />

In the remainder of this chapter, we explore two possible mechanisms of public consultation,<br />

deliberative panels and the consultative college. These two institutions of public consultation are<br />

reminiscent of James Fishkin’s “deliberative polls.” 1 Like Fishkin, we emphasize the role of<br />

informed public opinion in policy-making. Our approach differs from Fishkin’s in that feasibility<br />

considerations play a more prominent role in our discussion. Another important difference is the<br />

role played by consultative processes in the administrative system. In our view, institutions of<br />

public consultation should strengthen representative democracy, not be regarded as a possible<br />

substitute. Accordingly, we articulate more precisely the role of institutions of public<br />

consultation in the regulatory process.<br />

1<br />

James S. Fishkin, "Deliberative Polling and Public Consultation," in Deliberative Democracy in Theory and<br />

Practice ( Turin: European Consortium for Political Research, 2002); James S. Fishkin, "The Televised<br />

Deliberative Poll: An Experiment in Democracy," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social<br />

Science 546 (1996); James S. Fishkin and Chair Patterson-Bannister, "Virtual Democratic Possibilities:<br />

Prospects for Internet Democracy" (paper presented at the Internet, Democracy and Public Goods, Belo<br />

Horizonte, Brazil, November 6-10, 2000); Iain S. McLean, "Does Deliberation Induce Preference Structuration?<br />

Evidence from Deliberative Opinion Polls" (paper presented at the American Political Science Association<br />

Annual Meeting, Washington, D.C., August 30-September 4, 2000, 2000).<br />

315


12.1 Deliberative Panels<br />

Deliberative panels expand and refine the concepts of consensus conferences and citizens’<br />

panels discussed in chapter 10. They address three important shortcomings of the latter two<br />

institutions of public participation: The views expressed by participants in consensus conferences<br />

and citizens’ panels carry very limited political weight, the size of these groups is too sm<strong>all</strong> to be<br />

regarded as indicative of broad public sentiments, and they tend to produce polarized opinions.<br />

Increasing the political weight of deliberative panels is a straightforward process. Instead of<br />

convening just one panel, regulators should run numerous deliberative panels. As we show<br />

below, convening a significant number of deliberative panels is both logistic<strong>all</strong>y feasible and<br />

financi<strong>all</strong>y affordable. Surprisingly, proponents of participatory methods, to our knowledge, have<br />

never entertained this possibility, an indication that there is a considerable room for<br />

experimentation and innovation in this area.<br />

Deliberative panels differ from consensus conferences and other participatory tools in that<br />

they are not expected to produce a consensus. The purpose of convening a deliberative panel is<br />

to identify and evaluate ethical concerns, and – depending on the issue under consideration – to<br />

rank policy options from the most to the least desirable. This is in keeping with our conviction<br />

that deliberation can provide clarification and an appreciation of complex ethical questions, but<br />

cannot be expected to always move the participants toward consensual positions.<br />

Preventing group polarization from distorting the final outcome presents a ch<strong>all</strong>enge. A<br />

sample of the general public based on the usual socio-demographic variables is likely to produce<br />

an uneven pre-deliberation distribution of existing views. This means that it may be difficult to<br />

assemble a large number of sm<strong>all</strong> deliberative groups with an equal number of views in favor of<br />

and against a regulatory proposal. As we have repeatedly pointed out in this report, deliberation<br />

among members of an unbalanced group could reinforce a priori beliefs and induce group<br />

polarization. Obviously, this is not a desirable outcome, if indeed this shift is caused exclusively<br />

by a pre-deliberation bias. An institution of public consultation must be neutral with regard to the<br />

possible final outcomes.<br />

Fortunately, a straightforward solution to this problem exists. If we assume that the<br />

participants’ attitudes are not extremely skewed, it is relatively easy to assemble two<br />

representative samples of the general public, one consisting of individuals gener<strong>all</strong>y supportive<br />

of and the other of citizens opposed to a given policy option. If the public holds views pro and<br />

con in roughly equal proportions, or if the public has no strong opinions or else is ambivalent<br />

about a new biomedical development, assembling balanced pre-deliberation panels is a<br />

straightforward process. In these cases, it is particularly important that the consultation process<br />

does not itself turn into a source of significant distortions by exacerbating polarization<br />

tendencies.<br />

Public consultation does not become superfluous if a large fraction of the general public<br />

holds specific views. As we have argued in chapter 8, survey results often are exposed to the<br />

criticism that they merely reflect superficial views held by uninformed citizens. A mechanism of<br />

316


public consultation is immune to this criticism. In this case, ensuring balance not only is far less<br />

important, but it also could also be seen, with some justification, as an attempt by the regulators<br />

to manipulate public opinion.<br />

An alternative method to control for skewed pre-deliberation positions is to explicitly<br />

include this information in the analysis. Assuming that a sufficiently large number of panels have<br />

been convened, a statistical analysis will reveal the impact of the pre-deliberation bias on the<br />

final outcome. This approach makes a fairly complicated sampling process unnecessary and is<br />

less costly, but it may require a larger sample.<br />

12.1.1 Questions of Implementation<br />

Experience suggests that each deliberative panel should consist of no more than 10 to 12<br />

participants. Larger groups would make it difficult to sustain genuine group discussions; sm<strong>all</strong>er<br />

groups would require convening a much larger number of panels and would make the logistics<br />

too complex.<br />

Participation in deliberative panels should not require citizens to commit a weekend or even<br />

a full day, as has often been the case for consensus conferences. Depending on the complexity of<br />

the issue under consideration, a few hours to one afternoon should be sufficient. In the summer<br />

of 2004, the Genetics and Public Policy Center at Johns Hopkins University in Washington,<br />

D.C., conducted six town-h<strong>all</strong> meetings, each lasting one afternoon, on the ethical dilemmas of<br />

new reproductive technologies. Conversations with the center staff have shown that it is quite<br />

possible to tackle complex ethical and policy question in one afternoon, including an initial<br />

familiarization phase.<br />

There are several ways to familiarize the participants with the scientific aspects of<br />

reproductive medicine and biomedical research. The panelists could be required to participate in<br />

a short training session. Typic<strong>all</strong>y, this would consist of watching an introductory video or<br />

attending a presentation. Alternatively, the participants could receive print materials ahead of<br />

time. A well-structured online resource could complement both print and video materials.<br />

However, while availability of information alone is unlikely to motivate prospective participants<br />

to thoroughly familiarize themselves with complex scientific and ethical questions, this would<br />

only be a potential problem in select cases, as both the introductory session and the deliberation<br />

phase itself would serve to clarify most technicalities. To help the panelists feel comfortable with<br />

complex medical and scientific questions, a panel of experts representative of <strong>all</strong> relevant<br />

positions (industry, academic scientists, regulatory scientists, advocacy groups, and so on) would<br />

be available to answer questions about controversial scientific claims.<br />

Making expert opinions available to a large number of deliberative panels presents a<br />

logistical ch<strong>all</strong>enge. A nationwide public consultation requires that <strong>all</strong> regions of the country<br />

have an opportunity to be heard. This means that deliberative panels would have to be convened<br />

at different locations around the country. As a practical matter, it may not be possible to<br />

assemble a group of nation<strong>all</strong>y recognized experts at each location, nor is it feasible for one<br />

panel of experts to participate in every group discussion. One way to reduce the logistical<br />

317


complexity would be to convene deliberative panels at different locations at roughly the same<br />

time. Information technologies (such as e-mail, online chat, voice-over-IP, and teleconferencing)<br />

would enable deliberative panels at different locations to communicate with the experts. And<br />

while it would obviously be impossible to assemble as many expert groups as deliberative<br />

panels, it is quite reasonable to assume that the agency could at least assemble several such<br />

panels.<br />

Another distinctive attribute of deliberative panels is an Internet-based information<br />

clearinghouse, which would serve as a repository for <strong>all</strong> the educational materials (brochures,<br />

technical summaries, scientific publications, instructional videos, and so forth) and be made<br />

available to <strong>all</strong> participants and to the general public. The clearinghouse would also keep track of<br />

<strong>all</strong> questions put to the experts by the lay panelists and their answers. This feature would <strong>all</strong>ow<br />

lay participants to learn from each other, and would drastic<strong>all</strong>y reduce the volume of questions<br />

the experts could expect to receive. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the clearinghouse would serve as a repository for <strong>all</strong><br />

recorded conversations among participants in each deliberative panel. Unlike other sources of<br />

information, recordings of actual deliberations would be made available to a general audience<br />

only after the consultation process had been concluded, and only in anonymous form.<br />

12.1.2 Considerations of Feasibility<br />

Deliberative panels are not entirely new, of course. In the last 20 years, there have been<br />

various efforts, mostly involving local matters, to engage the public in policy-making. We have<br />

discussed some of these initiatives in chapter 10. The most suggestive precedent to our proposal,<br />

however, is not a proposal aimed to enhance public participation, but a project designed to study<br />

the impact of jury deliberation on monetary awards in personal injury cases. This project is<br />

remarkable, among other things, because it demonstrates that it is quite possible to convene a<br />

very large number of deliberative panels in a limited period of time. The study in question was<br />

based on 500 mock juries, each consisting of six citizens, with a total participation of more than<br />

3,000 individuals – an impressive number by any measure, and certainly more than adequate to<br />

ensure representativeness in a process of public consultation. 2<br />

Running 3,000 people through 500 mock juries turned out to be a surprisingly<br />

straightforward task, partly because the organizers limited the time for deliberation to only 30<br />

minutes. Each session lasted one-and-a-half hours. It took the study authors only five<br />

consecutive weekends (consisting of a Friday, Saturday, and Sunday) to complete the study. On<br />

each day, the group ran eight sessions, each including four simultaneous juries. Recruitment<br />

started approximately three weeks before the first weekend. Assuming recruitment costs of $35<br />

per person, financial incentives to participate in this effort of $100 per participant, and including<br />

personnel costs, convening 500 mock juries would cost approximately $450,000 dollars.<br />

These figures demonstrate that the logistics of organizing and running even a large number<br />

of deliberative panels are not overly complex, that the time required for conducting a process of<br />

2<br />

Schkade, Sunstein, and Kahneman, "Deliberating About Dollars: The Severity Shift."<br />

318


public consultation is modest, and that the cost is reasonable. In the case of a national<br />

consultative process, the convening agency would have to run things somewhat differently. The<br />

deliberative phase would have to be extended considerably. Regulators would have to budget for<br />

expert participation, for moderators, and for the implementation and maintenance of the Webbased<br />

clearinghouse. On the other end, the agency could assemble groups up to twice as large.<br />

Furthermore, to ensure representativeness, a sample of approximately 1,000 participants would<br />

suffice. Nevertheless, the over<strong>all</strong> costs for a consultative process are likely to exceed the above<br />

figure. This sum is not negligible, to be sure, but well worth it if it contributed to crafting a<br />

national consensus on highly controversial matters pertaining to reproductive medicine and<br />

biomedical research.<br />

As for the online clearinghouse, a few suggestive precedents exist. Our own Human<br />

Biotechnology Governance Forum was intended to achieve similar goals, but constraints on<br />

financial resources have prevented us from fully implementing it. 3<br />

In its present form, the<br />

Human Biotechnology Governance Forum includes almost 3,000 news stories on scientific and<br />

policy developments, as well as dozens of commentaries and editorials. It also incorporates<br />

analysis and resources sections, the former focused on scholarly analysis and the latter intended<br />

as a tool for self-study. The Center for Genetics and Society Web site is probably the single best<br />

source of information available in the area of reproductive medicine, but does not include an<br />

interactive component. 4 The Geneforum, a non-profit initiative launched in Oregon in 1998,<br />

promotes education and public dialogue on subjects broadly related to biotechnology. 5 None of<br />

these online resources fully implement the information clearinghouse concept as envisioned here,<br />

but taken together, they suggest that its implementation is within reach.<br />

12.2 Consultative College<br />

Deliberative panels are predicated on face-to-face deliberation. An emphasis on traditional<br />

forms of sm<strong>all</strong>-group deliberation both is costly and increases logistical complex. Importantly, it<br />

may force the agency to compromise on other design goals, such as the time available for<br />

deliberation or the number of experts and the quality of expert opinions. For this reason, in this<br />

section, we discuss an alternative mechanism of public consultation that retains deliberation<br />

(though not face-to-face deliberation) but tries to reduce logistical complexity and cost through<br />

the systematic use of information technologies. We c<strong>all</strong> this approach a consultative college.<br />

The consultative college is similar to deliberative panels in that it also strives to ensure<br />

representativeness. Just like deliberative panels, it begins with a familiarization phase, continues<br />

with a deliberation stage, and closes with participants ranking alternative policy options.<br />

Deliberation takes place in sm<strong>all</strong>, balanced groups, as is the case for deliberative panels. Unlike<br />

3<br />

4<br />

5<br />

See http://www.biotechgov.org.<br />

See http://www.genetics-and-society.org/index.asp.<br />

See http://www.geneforum.org/.<br />

319


deliberative panels, however, deliberation in a consultative college is mediated by information<br />

technology. In other words, the deliberation in a consultative college renounces to face-to-face<br />

communication.<br />

There are several important benefits to relying on information technologies for the<br />

deliberation phase. Geography in a country as large as the United States is no longer a<br />

constraining factor. Participants can be consulted from the comfort of their living rooms. Experts<br />

can receive and answer questions from anywhere. Public officials can monitor the entire process<br />

from one location. Travel needs are reduced to a minimum. Informational and educational<br />

materials can quickly and easily be made available to everyone.<br />

The use information technology makes it possible to overcome otherwise severe time and<br />

spatial constraints. A consultation process can be stretched over an extended period of time,<br />

several weeks and perhaps even months, with minimal disruption for participants’ daily routines.<br />

For example, college members could meet online once a week or once every other week over a<br />

period of several weeks. This approach would make it considerably easier for the regulatory<br />

agency to recruit participants. It would also make it possible to envisage a stable membership, if<br />

necessary. Repeated participation in public consultation would further reduce over<strong>all</strong> operational<br />

costs. Participants would have to receive a monetary compensation for their participation, but the<br />

savings from a dramatic<strong>all</strong>y simplified recruitment process and from relying on a stable pool of<br />

participants would more than offset these costs. Conceivably, over time, monetary rewards could<br />

be reduced as participation in a consultation process could become a source of (some) prestige.<br />

The consultation process follows a familiar plot: College members first familiarize<br />

themselves with the therapeutic and scientific and aspects of the reproductive technology under<br />

consideration. This is accomplished in the same way as for deliberative panels, i.e., by making<br />

print and video materials available to college members and by implementing an information<br />

clearinghouse. A panel of experts representing various interests and positions, convened by the<br />

agency, stands by to take and answer questions. Questions and answers are saved in the<br />

clearinghouse and made available to <strong>all</strong> members of the consultative college. In the final step, the<br />

agency gathers, evaluates, and synthesizes the range of expressed concerns and attitudes toward<br />

various policy options. This information forms the basis for crafting new rules and regulations.<br />

As for the actual deliberative stage, college members rely on voice-based technology to<br />

communicate with each other. Text-based communication is possible, but should be used as a<br />

backup or as a tool for the moderator to get in touch privately with individual participants. The<br />

popularity of Internet telephony demonstrates that it is becoming both technic<strong>all</strong>y feasible and<br />

economical to use the Internet for voice-based communication. Our approach is not too<br />

dissimilar from what survey organizations have been doing for years. As part of their business<br />

portfolio, these organizations have assembled panels representative of the general U.S.<br />

population. These panels are polled regularly by phone on any number of topics. In recent years,<br />

polling organizations have begun using the Internet to enable online discussions among panel<br />

members. In the summer of 2004, the Genetics and Public Policy Center relied on one of these<br />

survey organizations to conduct an Internet-based deliberative poll similar to what we are<br />

320


proposing here. More than 130 individuals participated in this project. Participants were assigned<br />

to groups of approximately 12 to 15 persons. Online meetings took place on a weekly basis over<br />

a period of two months. Each session lasted on average one-and-a-half hours. 6<br />

The extensive use of information technologies gives the convening agency an unprecedented<br />

ability to closely monitor the deliberative process and to quickly respond to unanticipated<br />

problems. For example, the review of online deliberation may provide cues as to an inadequate<br />

or insufficient understanding of technical and/or scientific matters among the college members.<br />

In this case, the agency would be able to provide additional information to select participants<br />

without embarrassing them in front of their colleagues. The agency would also be able to<br />

selectively foster contributions from passive participants by establishing separate discussion<br />

forums (“deliberative enclaves”) that would encourage these individuals to develop their own<br />

views privately until they feel confident enough to share them with their original audience.<br />

The enabling legislation would require the agency not only to publish the proposed new rule<br />

in the Federal Register, but also to make the consultation process itself and <strong>all</strong> related materials<br />

available to the general public. This could have an important side effect: By becoming a focal<br />

point for individuals seeking reliable information on the medical and ethical aspects of a<br />

regulatory proposal, the clearinghouse is likely trigger an informational cascade. 7 For example,<br />

Catholics may find it helpful to examine the views expressed by fellow Catholics represented on<br />

the college. Liberal voters may take a similar approach. To the extent that the views expressed by<br />

members of a reference group are more nuanced and differentiated than those expressed by<br />

corresponding organized groups, there is a chance that over time, the deliberative college would<br />

contribute to reducing societal divisions. To use the terminology developed in chapter 10, the<br />

college would contribute to depolarizing the public.<br />

Conversations with representatives of the Genetics and Public Policy Center have shown<br />

that the technical hurdles to running a process of online consultation remain significant. On the<br />

other hand, the quality and reliability of information technologies is rapidly improving. The rapid<br />

development of Internet telephony suggests that in the medium term, technology no longer will<br />

play a constraining role. It is also becoming apparent that government agencies are beginning to<br />

explore uses of information technology beyond traditional considerations of efficiency and<br />

responsiveness. For example, in July of 2001, the EPA conducted a “National Dialogue on<br />

Public Involvement in EPA Decisions,” which was intended to supplement notice-and-comment<br />

through an online public consultation process. The initiative brought together 1,166 individuals<br />

over a period of two weeks. The result was 1,261 messages posted by 320 people, with many<br />

more reading the postings and the daily summaries. According to one commentator, the initiative<br />

was a resounding success. 8 The same author also pointed out some predictable shortcomings.<br />

6<br />

7<br />

8<br />

Joan Scott, Genetics and Public Policy Center, personal communication.<br />

See chapter 10 for a discussion of informational cascades and related concepts.<br />

Thomas C. Beierle, "Democracy on-Line: An Evaluation of the National Dialogue on Public Involvement in<br />

EPA Decisions," in RFF <strong>Report</strong> (Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future, 2002). That this initiative was the<br />

first of its kind speaks volumes about the real role of information technologies on administrative processes and<br />

321


Participation suffered from considerable self-selection bias, ethnic minorities were<br />

underrepresented (in large measure due to limited access to technology), and time demands on<br />

the agency staff were considerable. There is also considerable evidence that outside the United<br />

States, especi<strong>all</strong>y in Europe, the role of information technologies is no longer seen simply as a<br />

tool to improve government efficiency and cut costs. 9 In Britain, some commentators have<br />

advocated experimenting with mechanisms of public engagement not too dissimilar from what<br />

we have proposed here. 10 The British Parliament took an interest in this matter as it published the<br />

“Sixth <strong>Report</strong> on Innovations in Citizen Participation in Government.” 11<br />

The concept of the consultative college as espoused in this chapter does suffer from some<br />

potenti<strong>all</strong>y important problems and limitations. Advocates of traditional forms of public<br />

consultation may argue that online deliberation is an inadequate substitute for face-to-face<br />

communication. 12 The evidence does not support this claim. It is certainly no secret that the<br />

quality of deliberation in online, text-based forums is indeed very low. It is also quite common<br />

for these forums to polarize in ways that can only be described as spectacular. But the poor<br />

quality of online forum discussions has everything to do with the rules governing these online<br />

forums, and very little to do with the medium itself. Carefully designed experiments to elicit<br />

possible differences between face-to-face communication and voice-based deliberation have<br />

found that online deliberation is just as valid an option as face-to-face communication. 13 Other,<br />

in-depth studies have produced similar results. In a series of facilitated online deliberations<br />

conducted in 2000 involving both randomly recruited participants and control groups,<br />

researchers found that participation in online discussions can produce greater awareness of the<br />

9<br />

10<br />

on rule-making. Federal agencies do of course rely extensively on information technologies, but technology is<br />

mostly used to increase efficiency and cut costs. They do not have a significant impact on the practices of rulemaking.<br />

Yet it is in this area, as one commentator points out, that information technologies could play a very<br />

useful role. See Beth Simone Noveck, "Designing Deliberative Democracy in Cyberspace: The Role of the<br />

Cyber-Lawyer," Boston University Journal of Science & Technology Law 9, no. 1-91 (2003); Beth Simone<br />

Noveck, "The Electronic Revolution in Rulemaking," Emory Law Journal 53 (2004).<br />

Dimitris Kyriakou, Special Issue: On E-Democracy (The IPTS <strong>Report</strong> 75, June, 2003 [cited September 6,<br />

2005]); available from http://www.jrc.es/home/report/english/articles/vol75/welcome.htm; Malcolm Peltu and<br />

Stephen Coleman, "A New Agenda for E-Democracy: Positions Papers for an Oxford Internet Institute<br />

Symposium. In Association with with University of Maryland, Cisco and BT" (paper presented at the OII<br />

Symposium, Oxford, May 7, 2004); Bart Van Oudenhove et al., "<strong>Report</strong> on Electronic Democracy Projects,<br />

Legal Issues of Internet Voting and Users (i.e. Voters and Authorities Representatives) Requirement Analysis,"<br />

(Consortium led by MATRA Systèmes & Information, 2001).<br />

Stephen Coleman and John Gøtze, "Bowling Together: Online Public Engagement in Policy Deliberation,"<br />

(London: BT Hansard Society, 2001).<br />

11<br />

The full report is available at<br />

http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm200001/cmselect/cmpubadm/373/37303.htm. The government<br />

response is available at<br />

http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm200102/cmselect/cmpubadm/334/33403.htm.<br />

12<br />

Benjamin R. Barber, "The Uncertainty of Digital Politics," Harvard International Review 23, no. 1 (2001).<br />

13<br />

S. Iyengar, R.C. Luskin, and James S. Fishkin, "Facilitating Informed Public Opinion: Evidence from Face-to-<br />

Face and on-Line Deliberation." (paper presented at the American Political Science Association Annual Meeting,<br />

Philadelphia, PA, 2003).<br />

322


underlying motives informing opposing views. Predictably, the researchers also found that<br />

deliberation can produce polarization. 14<br />

Representatives of the Genetics and Public Policy<br />

Center, for their part, have pointed out that in their experience, participants in online<br />

deliberations do engage each other in a respectful and constructive manner. They also noticed<br />

that voice-based interactions foster a more frank dialogue than traditional face-to-face<br />

communication.<br />

Some commentators are likely to criticize our proposal for not being “open and transparent.”<br />

Others may argue that ours is an elitist approach designed to exclude rather than to include the<br />

public. We freely acknowledge that a process of public consultation as envisaged in this report is<br />

not open to the general public and it is not entirely transparent; it is not supposed to be. The<br />

legitimacy and credibility of mechanisms of public consultation as proposed in this report<br />

depend cruci<strong>all</strong>y upon the regulators maintaining tight control over the process itself. “Opening”<br />

the consultation process to a larger audience would obviously undermine any claim to<br />

representativeness; it would disrupt the deliberative phase and expose the entire consultative<br />

process to manipulation by organized interest groups. The proper way for the general public and<br />

for interest groups to provide input is through notice-and-comment afforded to <strong>all</strong> citizens by the<br />

Administrative Procedure Act. As for the claim that the proposed mechanisms of public<br />

consultation exclude the public, this criticism is unfounded. No other process of public<br />

consultation, to our knowledge, would afford the general public greater influence over the<br />

regulatory process.<br />

Two other, possibly important problems are access to information technology and literacy.<br />

Extensive reliance on information technologies could prove a barrier for some, especi<strong>all</strong>y among<br />

the poor and the uneducated. The “digital divide” is shrinking, however, as the cost of personal<br />

computers has dropped significantly and continues to f<strong>all</strong>. The agency could remedy this<br />

problem by lending or renting for a nominal fee a TV computer, just as some polling<br />

organizations do. Literacy is a more serious problem. Even the best informational and<br />

educational materials require basic readings and analytical skills. It may be unrealistic to expect<br />

most participants to absorb lengthy policy briefs, even if they are designed with a lay audience in<br />

mind. Educational videos may mitigate this problem, at least in part. Conceivably, the convening<br />

agency could recruit volunteers willing to help struggling individuals overcome these barriers.<br />

We realize that our discussion of online consultative tools does not provide satisfactory<br />

answers to each and every implementation detail. Our aim here was not to offer an exhaustive<br />

description of innovative mechanisms of public consultation. Rather, we wanted to demonstrate<br />

that the time is ripe for experimenting with innovative forms of public consultation. We hope our<br />

readers will find our discussion compelling enough to explore our proposal in more depth.<br />

14<br />

V. Price and J. Cappella, "Online Deliberation and Its Influence: The Electronic Dialogue Project in Campaign<br />

2000," IT & Society 1 (2002); V. Price and J. Cappella, "Online Discussion, Civic Engagement, and Social<br />

Trust," (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 2003).<br />

323


12.3 Public Consultation and Rule-Making<br />

A question we have only peripher<strong>all</strong>y explored in this report is the relationship between<br />

consultative processes and agency discretion. In chapter 10, we have argued that a consultative<br />

process does not compromise the agency prerogative to pursue a specific regulatory agenda. At<br />

the same time, a proposed new rule flying in the face of broadly shared public sentiments would<br />

be considered by some to be strong evidence of capricious and arbitrary agency behavior. In<br />

what sense, then, does a structured process of public consultation contribute to preventing or<br />

mitigating agency capture? How does a consultative process protect the independence – i.e., the<br />

credibility – of this agency?<br />

Consider the case of an agency succumbing to pressures from an interest group, a powerful<br />

Congressional representative, or a senior White House official. Let’s assume that the agency has<br />

conducted a consultative process and that the consultation has produced a clear and unambiguous<br />

result. The agency is considering ignoring this outcome and is strongly tempted to follow the<br />

recommendations of one or the other of its closest constituencies. This is an illustration of<br />

political failure as defined in chapter 10: The agency is catering to parochial interests to the<br />

detriment of broader public sentiments.<br />

What considerations may affect the agency’s decision to ignore or to abide by the outcome<br />

produced by the consultative process? As mentioned earlier, the enabling legislation requires the<br />

agency to make the results of <strong>all</strong> consultations available to the general public well before the<br />

agency publishes its proposed new rule in the Federal Register. The agency is perfectly aware of<br />

the implications of the “hard look” doctrine for rule-making and, in particular, of the need to<br />

provide a very detailed rationale for the assumptions informing a proposed new rule. The agency<br />

is entitled to propose a policy inconsistent with the outcome of a public consultation, but it<br />

would have to provide a well-reasoned explanation for this choice. To the extent that the agency<br />

was indeed considering an alternative policy for no other reason than political expediency,<br />

justifying a different choice may be extremely difficult. For this reason, the agency is likely to<br />

resist the demands by special interest groups and their <strong>all</strong>ies in Congress even if regulators<br />

sympathize with these demands, or might have found it useful to cater to a powerful political<br />

constituency as a means to pursue other bureaucratic goals, such as ensuring future agency<br />

funding.<br />

Now let’s assume that the agency believes it can get away with a decision to ignore the<br />

outcome of a consultative process. Following the publication of the consultation results, the<br />

public has an opportunity to provide feedback through notice-and-comment. While some<br />

organized interest groups will certainly voice their support, the general public is likely to signal<br />

its disagreement to the agency in significant numbers, and point to the inconsistency between the<br />

consultation process and the proposed new rule. The Administrative Procedure Act requires the<br />

agency to acknowledge each comment and to “consider” it in drafting the final rule. The agency<br />

may try to finesse the inconsistencies brought about by its decision to overlook public<br />

sentiments, but it also knows that its responses to the received comments become part of the<br />

324


administrative record and form the basis for judicial review. Knowing this, the agency will likely<br />

resist the temptation to ignore the consultation results. 15<br />

Critics may argue that even if an agency proposes a rule inconsistent with the outcome of a<br />

consultation process, the public is unlikely voice its disagreement through notice-and-comment,<br />

either because it won’t notice the agency’s disregard for public sentiments, or simply because it<br />

won’t care. For this strategy to succeed, several fairly implausible requirements must be met.<br />

Public consultation should be a low-key affair with little or no media visibility. This is very<br />

unlikely, given the public nature of most bioethical controversies. Even if the media and the<br />

general public are not paying attention, organized interests groups are. These groups will<br />

immediately spot any inconsistency between consultation results and proposed new rule. In their<br />

comments to the agency, they would demand that the agency provide a rationale for its choice.<br />

These are also the groups most likely to ch<strong>all</strong>enge a new rule in court should they come to the<br />

conclusion that the agency has no reason to disregard the outcome of a consultative process. For<br />

these reasons, it would not be rational for the agency to assume that “bureaucratic drift” will go<br />

unnoticed. 16<br />

Our discussion so far was based on the assumption that a process of public consultation will<br />

produce a clear and unambiguous outcome. This may not always be the case, however. A divided<br />

public – i.e., a situation in which any given policy proposal is approved and disapproved by<br />

roughly 50 percent of the public – would afford the agency considerably more discretion. Should<br />

agency discretion be considered problematic? Does this amount to the breakdown of a central<br />

mechanism of accountability? Most likely not. To the extent that the public is genuinely divided<br />

and/or ambivalent about a new reproductive technology or a revolutionary line of research, the<br />

agency could choose between two strategies. It could determine that it should move ahead and<br />

propose a policy that more closely reflects the preferences of organized interest groups. This<br />

would not be a case of agency capture, but of exercise of legitimate regulatory authority<br />

constrained by the enabling statute and Congressional intent. Alternatively, the agency could<br />

decide that it would be inappropriate to deprive the public of the opportunity to debate the pros<br />

and cons of a new biomedical development, and simply propose a moratorium.<br />

As a matter of practice, it is very unlikely that the agency, after consulting with the public,<br />

will be left without guidance. It is certainly true that most people entering a consultative process<br />

are unlikely to have strong, informed views about a new biomedical development. But the<br />

empirical record suggests that citizens, if given an opportunity, are perfectly capable of<br />

developing informed opinions. And while it is certainly possible that a given policy option will<br />

15<br />

16<br />

It is worth noting that agency accountability is the result of both public consultation and notice-and-comment.<br />

Absent notice-and-comment, the agency would face fewer incentives to abide by the outcome of a consultative<br />

process. On the other hand, rule-making without public consultation would greatly diminish the effectiveness of<br />

notice-and-comment as a mechanism of accountability.<br />

The preceding discussion is based on the assumption that a rational choice model is an adequate representation<br />

of agency behavior. It would certainly be possible to analyze agency behavior from a somewhat less cynical<br />

standpoint, but a more sophisticated modeling exercise is very unlikely to affect our conclusions.<br />

325


divide the public, it is quite unlikely that the general public will be divided on each and every<br />

available choice. As our discussion in chapter 8 has shown, more often than not, a divided public<br />

reflects inadequate alternatives rather than underlying deep divisions.<br />

326


12.4 Bibliography<br />

Barber, Benjamin R. "The Uncertainty of Digital Politics." Harvard International Review 23, no.<br />

1 (2001): 42-47.<br />

Beierle, Thomas C. "Democracy on-Line: An Evaluation of the National Dialogue on Public<br />

Involvement in EPA Decisions." In RFF <strong>Report</strong>. Washington, D.C.: Resources for the<br />

Future, 2002.<br />

Coleman, Stephen, and John Gøtze. "Bowling Together: Online Public Engagement in Policy<br />

Deliberation." London: BT Hansard Society, 2001.<br />

Fishkin, James S. "Deliberative Polling and Public Consultation." In Deliberative Democracy in<br />

Theory and Practice. Turin: European Consortium for Political Research, 2002.<br />

———. "The Televised Deliberative Poll: An Experiment in Democracy." Annals of the<br />

American Academy of Political and Social Science 546 (1996): 132-40.<br />

Fishkin, James S., and Chair Patterson-Bannister. "Virtual Democratic Possibilities: Prospects<br />

for Internet Democracy." Paper presented at the Internet, Democracy and Public Goods,<br />

Belo Horizonte, Brazil, November 6-10, 2000.<br />

Iyengar, S., R.C. Luskin, and James S. Fishkin. "Facilitating Informed Public Opinion: Evidence<br />

from Face-to-Face and on-Line Deliberation." Paper presented at the American Political<br />

Science Association Annual Meeting, Philadelphia, PA 2003.<br />

Kyriakou, Dimitris. Special Issue: On E-Democracy The IPTS <strong>Report</strong> 75, June, 2003 [cited<br />

September 6, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.jrc.es/home/report/english/articles/vol75/welcome.htm.<br />

McLean, Iain S. "Does Deliberation Induce Preference Structuration? Evidence from<br />

Deliberative Opinion Polls." Paper presented at the American Political Science<br />

Association Annual Meeting, Washington, D.C., August 30-September 4, 2000, 2000.<br />

Noveck, Beth Simone. "Designing Deliberative Democracy in Cyberspace: The Role of the<br />

Cyber-Lawyer." Boston University Journal of Science & Technology Law 9, no. 1-91<br />

(2003).<br />

———. "The Electronic Revolution in Rulemaking." Emory Law Journal 53 (2004): 433-518.<br />

Peltu, Malcolm, and Stephen Coleman. "A New Agenda for E-Democracy: Positions Papers for<br />

an Oxford Internet Institute Symposium. In Association with with University of<br />

Maryland, Cisco and BT." Paper presented at the OII Symposium, Oxford, May 7, 2004.<br />

Price, V., and J. Cappella. "Online Deliberation and Its Influence: The Electronic Dialogue<br />

Project in Campaign 2000." IT & Society 1 (2002): 303-28.<br />

———. "Online Discussion, Civic Engagement, and Social Trust." Philadelphia: University of<br />

Pennsylvania, 2003.<br />

Schkade, David, Cass R. Sunstein, and Daniel Kahneman. "Deliberating About Dollars: The<br />

Severity Shift." Columbia Law Journal 100 (2000): 1139-75.<br />

Van Oudenhove, Bart, Berry Schoenmakers, Sylvie Brunessaux, Karl Schlichting, and Tomas<br />

Ohlin. "<strong>Report</strong> on Electronic Democracy Projects, Legal Issues of Internet Voting and<br />

Users (i.e. Voters and Authorities Representatives) Requirement Analysis." Consortium<br />

led by MATRA Systèmes & Information, 2001.<br />

327


328


13 Implementation Issues<br />

Consistent with the scheme developed in chapter 4, in this chapter we discuss<br />

implementation-related issues for each of the three areas of reproductive medicine (standard<br />

reproductive treatments, innovative reproductive procedures, and technologies of reproductive<br />

customization) and for biomedical research. We also discuss in some detail issues pertaining to<br />

compliance assurance, and we conclude by offering some considerations of cost.<br />

13.1 Monitoring and Information Gathering<br />

One of the first ch<strong>all</strong>enges the newly created regulatory agency would face is the design and<br />

implementation of a system of monitoring and information gathering. This system is<br />

indispensable to discharging the agency’s statutory mandate and would serve several purposes.<br />

First, it would <strong>all</strong>ow the agency to identify and evaluate health and safety risks associated with<br />

traditional ART procedures. As mentioned in chapter 4, this is possible today only in a very<br />

limited sense. Second, a tracking system would facilitate identifying and monitoring ART clinics<br />

performing innovative ART treatments, an area of reproductive medicine in need of closer<br />

scrutiny. Third, information gathered through a system of monitoring would make it possible for<br />

regulators to implement an effective mechanism of reciprocal learning within the ART industry –<br />

and in so doing, would contribute to improving the quality and reliability of ART treatments.<br />

Fourth, a comprehensive tracking system is crucial to ensuring compliance, not only in the ART<br />

sector, but also in the biotech industry and in the scientific community. <strong>Final</strong>ly, a system of<br />

monitoring and information gathering would enable regulators to provide prospective parents<br />

with up-to-date information on a wide range of infertility-related questions, and would help<br />

improve our understanding of the causes of infertility.<br />

A tracking system as proposed in this chapter would track the import, creation,<br />

manipulation, storage, trade, and export of human reproductive tissues. Reproductive tissues<br />

include human embryos, oocytes, and sperm. The term “creation” should be understood in the<br />

broadest possible sense: It includes not only traditional practices, such as the in vitro mixing of<br />

egg and sperm, but also laboratory practices that lead to the creation of viable oocytes and sperm<br />

by artificial means, such as experiments involving human embryonic stem cells, for example. 1<br />

Different reproductive tissues entail different record-keeping requirements. The import,<br />

export, creation, use, and trade of embryos would receive the greatest regulatory attention,<br />

followed by oocytes and by sperm. This ranking reflects the relative importance of ethical<br />

concerns. We discuss these differences in more detail in the following sections.<br />

1<br />

<strong>Report</strong>ing requirements in this case are limited to fully functional reproductive tissues.<br />

329


Among the parties subject to record-keeping requirements are ART programs, embryo<br />

laboratories, sperm banks, university hospitals, university labs, and research labs at biotech and<br />

pharmaceutical companies. This list is not meant to be exhaustive. Should the preservation of<br />

human oocytes become widely available, then oocytes banks would also be subject to regulatory<br />

oversight. In other words, any establishment that retrieves, produces, stores, and trades in human<br />

reproductive tissues would be subject to record-keeping and reporting requirements. The newly<br />

established registration requirements promulgated by the FDA for establishments involved in the<br />

trade, storage, and use of human tissues provide an excellent implementation basis. 2<br />

The tracking system proposed in this chapter could be implemented in various ways. The<br />

British HFEA, arguably the agency with most experience in this area, has adopted a fairly<br />

intrusive system of monitoring that consists of both a licensing and a reporting system. In the<br />

United States, it is the responsibility of the states to license the practice of medicine. For this<br />

reason, it is very unlikely that Congress would support a federal system of medical licensing,<br />

even a narrowly defined one. Furthermore, it is not entirely clear that additional licensing<br />

requirements at the federal level are necessary to meet the new agency’s public mandate. On the<br />

other end, a mandatory establishment registration coupled with specific reporting requirements<br />

would satisfy most if not <strong>all</strong> regulatory demands.<br />

A monitoring system that emphasizes the health and well-being of ART children and women<br />

would entail much more than just tracking the use of reproductive tissues. It would require<br />

gathering information concerning the ART children, their parents, the gamete donors (if the<br />

gametes were donated), and the type of ART procedure performed, among other things. These<br />

are not unreasonable requirements; Canadian regulators are in the process of implementing<br />

similar requirements. The British HFEA has been operating a comprehensive system of<br />

monitoring for years.<br />

A statutory emphasis on the health and well-being of children could also mean that the<br />

personal identity of gamete and embryo donors must be preserved. Currently, ART clinics<br />

routinely destroy records that would <strong>all</strong>ow ART children to identify gamete donors. It is a<br />

practice that protects the interests of prospective parents and donors, possibly to the detriment of<br />

ART children. Whether these children are ultimately better off knowing their biological parents<br />

is a question for others to ponder, but it can no longer be assumed that this information should<br />

simply be destroyed. That this requirement could significantly reduce the pool of available<br />

gamete donors is a risk that would have to be weighed against other benefits.<br />

Record-keeping would be subject to inspection, and violations would trigger civil and/or<br />

criminal penalties, depending on the gravity of the violation. This is in marked contrast to current<br />

practice. The CDC has no authority to enforce the reporting requirements established by the<br />

Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act. Non-reporting, however, is rather modest,<br />

roughly 10 percent or less. This figure suggests that while actual sanctions for non-compliance<br />

are necessary, they would not have to be draconian. Furthermore, the implementation of a<br />

2<br />

See chapter 5 for a discussion.<br />

330


tracking and monitoring system would in part be delegated to third parties such as trade and<br />

professional societies. We discuss compliance assurance in more depth in section 13.6.<br />

13.1.1 Embryos<br />

Procedures involving human embryos raise the most serious ethical concerns and would be<br />

subject to the most stringent record-keeping requirements. The protracted controversy over the<br />

use of human embryos for stem cell research suggests that the import, creation, storage, use,<br />

manipulation, and export of human embryos should be carefully monitored. Developing and<br />

testing innovative reproductive procedures would be far less controversial activities if they were<br />

to be conducted with the blessing of the law. The view – shared by two-thirds of the American<br />

public – that embryos are not simply just another mass of cells but cannot be equated to actual<br />

human beings 3<br />

underscores the importance of distinguishing between acceptable and<br />

unacceptable uses of human embryos.<br />

Subject to record-keeping requirements would be <strong>all</strong> establishments involved in the import,<br />

storage, creation, use, trade, and export of human embryos, including ART programs, biotech<br />

firms, and university laboratories. These categories are not meant to exhaust the variety of<br />

establishments subject to record-keeping requirements. Any establishment more than margin<strong>all</strong>y<br />

involved in these activities would be subject to the same requirements. 4<br />

The “creation” of embryos must be construed in the broadest possible way. Included in this<br />

definition are not only embryos created in vitro for ART purposes, but also embryos created<br />

through somatic cell nuclear transplantation or any other medical technology that may become<br />

available in the future.<br />

Record-keeping requirements vary considerably depending on the enabling statute.<br />

Gener<strong>all</strong>y speaking, the more specific the statutory provisions, the more detailed the reporting<br />

requirements are likely to be. For example, should reproductive cloning be banned and research<br />

cloning legalized, regulators would have to adopt a record-keeping architecture that would<br />

discourage attempts to misuse cloned embryos. Regulators may consider limiting the maximum<br />

number of embryos that can be transferred to a woman’s uterus to two or three, a limitation<br />

adopted by some European countries. They could grant researchers permission to conduct a<br />

controversial but particularly promising experiment involving the destruction of embryos, but<br />

require that only a sm<strong>all</strong> number of embryos be used. In <strong>all</strong> these cases, an architecture of recordkeeping<br />

ensures that <strong>all</strong> parties operate in accordance with applicable rules and regulations. In<br />

short, record-keeping requirements for embryos greatly facilitate monitoring and compliance<br />

assurance efforts.<br />

The nascent practice of “adopting” supernumerary embryos raises specific record-keeping<br />

issues. Among them is the question of just how much information should adopting parents be<br />

entitled to receive about a donated embryo. Many prospective parents are likely not only to<br />

3<br />

4<br />

See chapter 8 for details.<br />

The transportation of human reproductive tissue would not be subject to reporting requirements.<br />

331


demand in-depth health screening, a requirement that is now part of the new FDA human cellular<br />

and tissue-based products rules; they may also feel entitled to select an embryo based on<br />

extensive genetic testing information, and on detailed descriptions of the biological parents’<br />

physical characteristics and on their academic and personal achievements, among other things.<br />

“Informed choice” in this case would come dangerously close to private eugenics. Whether<br />

Congress is prepared to restrict the amount of information donor organizations are <strong>all</strong>owed to<br />

gather remains to be seen.<br />

13.1.2 Oocytes<br />

While the donation and manipulation of human oocytes do not raise ethical concerns as<br />

substantial as those surrounding the use of human embryos, they nevertheless must be taken<br />

seriously. The new FDA rules regulating human cellular and tissue-based products require that<br />

oocyte donors be screened for a wide range of communicable diseases. In this area, no additional<br />

requirements are necessary. Broadly speaking, oocytes are being donated for reproductive or<br />

research purposes. Each case raises a distinctive set of issues.<br />

The for-profit trade of human oocytes for reproductive purposes is gaining popularity among<br />

affluent individuals. Oocytes from young, athletic, good-looking women with impeccable<br />

academic credentials are in high demand. In a few instances, these oocytes have been sold for as<br />

much as $200,000. The average price for oocytes is much lower, ranging roughly between<br />

$5,000 and $10,000. 5 High prices correlate strongly with parental desires. Prospective parents<br />

may wish to select oocytes based on a wide range of characteristics, ranging from good health<br />

and good looks to academic achievement. Accordingly, oocytes “donated” by students with high<br />

SAT scores or by super models fetch premium prices. This is more surprising, considering that<br />

this kind of eugenic selection is very unlikely to be effective. In any case, until oocyte<br />

cryopreservation is fully developed, oocyte donation will remain a fairly limited phenomenon.<br />

Oocyte donation for reproductive purposes does not require extensive record-keeping.<br />

Preventing the spread of infectious diseases may entail preserving the identity of egg donors for<br />

an extended period of time. Donor identity may also have to be preserved if Congress decides<br />

that the well-being of ART children includes being able to meet their biological mothers.<br />

Donating oocytes for research requires closer scrutiny. Should research cloning show<br />

promise, biomedical research would become a very important “buyer” of oocytes. That in this<br />

area abuses are indeed possible has recently been illustrated by Dr. Hwang Woo-Suk, the Korean<br />

researcher who in 2004 successfully cloned several human embryos. Dr. Hwang recently<br />

resigned amid <strong>all</strong>egation that he had pressured his female staffers to “donate” their oocytes, and<br />

5<br />

The American Society for Reproductive Medicine has recognized the problematic nature of unregulated oocyte<br />

donation and has adopted guidelines that discourage the sale of oocytes but <strong>all</strong>ow reimbursement for medical and<br />

other expenses up to approximately $4,200. Cf. Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive<br />

Medicine, "Financial Incentives in Recruitment of Oocyte Donor," Fertility and Sterility 74, no. 2 (2000), p.219.<br />

332


that he had falsified some of the data used for his seminal publications. 6 At a minimum, then,<br />

investigators would have to demonstrate compliance with rules of informed consent. Ensuring<br />

traceability may also be necessary, as research could produce results directly relevant to the<br />

donor’s health. <strong>Final</strong>ly, preventing abuses in the area of somatic cell nuclear transplantation<br />

would require keeping track of the number of donated eggs and their uses.<br />

13.1.3 Sperm<br />

Practices surrounding the trade, storage, and use of human sperm raise only modest ethical<br />

concerns. Unlike embryo and oocyte donation, sperm donation has a long history in the United<br />

States. The first recorded U.S. case dates back to nineteenth century. A full-blown market for<br />

sperm emerged only in the early 1960s. Nowadays, sperm banks have become a common and<br />

profitable industry across the country. The industry is represented by the American Association<br />

of Tissue Banks, which includes among its members many other types of tissue banks.<br />

As for embryos and oocytes, the new FDA rules governing the production, trade, and use of<br />

cellular tissues (HCT/P rules) protect against the spread of communicable diseases. In this area,<br />

no additional action is necessary. 7 The FDA rules, however, do not address several important<br />

questions not directly related to preventing the spread of communicable diseases. For example,<br />

few sperm banks have policies to avoid the marriage between half-siblings, a substantial risk<br />

considering that sperm banks impose very few limitations on the maximum number of donations<br />

by an individual. Should Congress determine that this area is ripe for regulations, additional<br />

record-keeping requirements may be necessary.<br />

Also in need of scrutiny is the long-standing industry practice to jealously protect donors’<br />

anonymity. This measure makes eminently good business sense, but it is far from clear that it is<br />

also in the best interest of children born through anonymous sperm donation. Requiring that<br />

sperm banks be able to identify sperm donors is likely to greatly reduce the pool of potential<br />

donors and to negatively impact this business sector. We are not arguing that Congress should<br />

eliminate donor anonymity, but it is worth pondering whether this practice can be justified.<br />

<strong>Final</strong>ly, the HCT/P rules are not designed to resolve whether eugenic practices should be<br />

tolerated. Sperm banks compete in part by encouraging prospective parents to select a sperm<br />

donor on the basis of physical, aesthetic, and academic stereotypes. Selecting a sperm donor in<br />

many cases is reduced to a shopping act: It is simply a matter of consulting a catalogue. That<br />

6<br />

7<br />

David Cyranoski and Erika Check, "Clone Star Admits Lies over Eggs," Nature 438, no. 7068 (2005); David<br />

Cyranoski and Erika Check, "Korean Stem-Cell Crisis Deepens," Nature 438, no. 7067 (2005); Constance<br />

Holden, Gretchen Vogel, and Dennis Normile, "Korean Cloner Admits Lying About Oocyte Donations," Science<br />

310, no. 5753 (2005).<br />

Despite its importance to the ART industry, no reliable information was available until recently about the<br />

number of existing sperm banks and their mode of operation. The HCT/P registration requirements will close<br />

this gap; as of February 28, 2005, 1,579 establishments had registered with the FDA. The actual number of<br />

sperm banks is significantly sm<strong>all</strong>er, however, because this figure also includes IVF programs, embryo<br />

laboratories, and other kinds of human tissue establishments. See<br />

http://www.fda.gov/cber/tissue/hctregestabl.htm.<br />

333


many prospective parents are attracted by physical appearance and academic performance is<br />

understandable, but the question remains as to whether Congress should unintention<strong>all</strong>y<br />

contribute to reinforcing <strong>all</strong> manner of stereotypes or whether it should limit the type of<br />

information prospective parents are entitled to request.<br />

13.2 Standard Reproductive Procedures<br />

To the extent that the enabling legislation emphasizes protection of the health and wellbeing<br />

of ART children, the tracking system would require regulators systematic<strong>all</strong>y to gather<br />

data and information about a wide range of ART-related defects and malformations. The British<br />

HFEA has been collecting ART-related health data since 1994. The kind of information the<br />

HFEA gathers on a regular basis is illustrated Table 11, gleaned from the 1999-2000 HFEA<br />

annual report. 8 This data has been collected every year since 1994, <strong>all</strong>owing the HFEA to<br />

identify both absolute and relative risks of various ART treatments and to detect possible longterm<br />

public health concerns.<br />

Congenital abnormalities Total Fresh<br />

IVF<br />

Frozen<br />

IVF<br />

Donor<br />

Insemination<br />

Micromanipulation<br />

Cleft lip with cleft palate 5 2 3<br />

Anomalies of the alimentary system 5 1 1 3<br />

Cardiac murmurs 6 3 3<br />

Ventricular septal defect 5 2 1 2<br />

Other congenital cardiac anomalies 12 4 2 3 3<br />

Other anomalies of the cardiac septa 1 1<br />

Patent ductus 3 1 2<br />

Anomalies of the cardiovascular 4 1 3<br />

system<br />

Hypospadias, epispadias 2 1 1<br />

Renal anomalies 13 3 3 1 6<br />

Reduction deformities of the limbs 1 1<br />

Talipes 9 2 2 5<br />

Congenital dislocation of the hip 2 1 1<br />

Other anomalies of the limbs<br />

2 1 1<br />

or limb girdles<br />

Anomalies of the nose, face,<br />

2 1 1<br />

neck, and skull<br />

Ear anomalies 7 1 6<br />

Exomphalos 5 1 4<br />

Total number of children born 120 41 9 16 54<br />

Table 11: Congenital abnormalities in ART children in 1999 (extract).<br />

In an effort to improve its ability to detect new health risks, the HFEA has begun testing a<br />

new alert system designed to anonymously gather detailed information about new incidents. This<br />

8<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), "Ninth Annual <strong>Report</strong> and Accounts 2000," (London:<br />

2000).<br />

334


information is stored in a database and made available to <strong>all</strong> licensed facilities, thus contributing<br />

to improving the safety and efficacy of ART treatments. According to the HFEA, clinics have<br />

responded very positively to this initiative.<br />

It should be mentioned that the British tracking system f<strong>all</strong>s far short of a full-fledged<br />

longitudinal system of monitoring. While conducting a long-term longitudinal study of ART<br />

children in the United States as proposed by the President’s Council on Bioethics would certainly<br />

be very useful, systematic<strong>all</strong>y monitoring the health of ART children up to one year of age<br />

would be considerably less costly and would provide a wealth of information currently not<br />

available. Putting the threshold at one year is not an arbitrary choice. ART specialists point out<br />

that some chromosomal and congenital abnormalities do not become immediately apparent, but<br />

that most of them have surfaced by one year of age.<br />

It appears that as part of its collaboration with the Society for Assisted Reproductive<br />

Technology, the CDC has begun gathering data and information beyond success rates.<br />

Unfortunately, no details are available about these practices. Implementing a system of<br />

monitoring as outlined in this section would certainly be more costly than what is considered<br />

standard practice today, but far less costly than feared by the ART industry. Tracking the health<br />

of ART children up to one year of age does not pose insurmountable technical or legal problems.<br />

Technic<strong>all</strong>y, the system could be based on chip cards technology. This technology has been<br />

adopted by many transit systems around the country and by the credit card industry; it is<br />

considered mature and it is inexpensive. Chip card technology would <strong>all</strong>ow select individuals,<br />

such as ART practitioners, pediatricians, parents, and regulators to verify, store, and retrieve<br />

personal health data while preventing unauthorized parties from accessing sensitive information.<br />

By affording adequate protection against the misuse of personal health data, this technology<br />

should be received favorably by prospective parents. Trust in this technical solution should also<br />

ensure high levels of participation and make a mandatory adoption superfluous.<br />

13.3 Innovative Reproductive Treatments<br />

The notion of innovative reproductive treatments was discussed in some detail in chapter 4.<br />

In a nutshell, innovative reproductive procedures, unlike standard reproductive treatments, may<br />

not only expose the future child to heightened health and safety risks, but may also be<br />

unacceptable from an ethical standpoint. Regulators have no systematic way to monitor these<br />

kinds of reproductive treatments. What so far has come to regulators’ attention is sufficiently<br />

problematic as to justify adopting a robust system of monitoring and evaluation, including the<br />

possibility that regulators may impose a moratorium or ban on certain types of treatments.<br />

Any suggestion that the practice of medicine should be regulated is bound to be<br />

controversial. Critics are likely to offer a broad range of arguments against direct regulatory<br />

interventions at the federal level, of a legal nature and of other varieties as well. While legal<br />

arguments against direct regulatory interventions are weak, some of the arguments offered by the<br />

profession to protect their autonomy are important and deserve to be taken seriously.<br />

335


Tradition<strong>all</strong>y, the practice of medicine has been regulated at the state level, and Congress<br />

has been very careful to avoid any suggestion that it intends to directly regulate the practice of<br />

medicine. 9 Perhaps for this reason, it is gener<strong>all</strong>y assumed that Congress does not have the<br />

authority to regulate this profession. We believe that this assumption is unfounded. Medical<br />

autonomy is certainly a jealously protected professional prerogative, but it is neither absolute nor<br />

uncontested. Congress indirectly regulates the practice of medicine in numerous ways. The FDA<br />

regulates drugs, biologics, and medical devices. The Medicare and Medicaid programs directly<br />

affect the selection of prescription drugs. The Department of Health and Human Services<br />

regulates clinical trials through informed consent regulations. Many of the measures aimed at<br />

containing the explosion of health care costs are predicated on limiting the discretion of the<br />

medical profession in choosing medical technologies and treatments. 10<br />

Some may argue that a direct regulatory intervention may run afoul of constitutional<br />

guarantees. A detailed examination of this question is well beyond the scope of the present<br />

discussion, but this argument seems implausible. If medical doctors had a constitution<strong>all</strong>y<br />

protected right to exercise their profession, then it is difficult to see why other professions<br />

shouldn’t enjoy the same kind of constitutional protection. Shouldn’t accountants, then, also be<br />

shielded from oversight by the Securities and Exchange Commission? Perhaps the medical<br />

profession does enjoy a modicum of constitutional protection. Washington v. Glucksberg, a case<br />

involving medic<strong>all</strong>y assisted suicide, does not lend much credibility to this hypothesis. A full<br />

discussion of this issue is beyond the scope of this chapter, but it is reasonable to assume that the<br />

Supreme Court is very unlikely to discover a broad new class of fundamental rights.<br />

A more important argument against direct regulatory intervention is what may be described<br />

as asymmetrical information. Medicine remains both a science and an art. Dramatic advances in<br />

medical science and technology have not undermined the need for good professional judgment.<br />

Expert medical opinion remains indispensable to selecting the most appropriate therapy. Only<br />

the physician is in a position to select an appropriate treatment based on a set of unique clinical<br />

circumstances. 11 In its essence, this is an argument about the importance of decentralized, tacit<br />

knowledge. It is precisely because this kind of knowledge is both decentralized and tacit (i.e.,<br />

not codified) that a regulatory authority should refrain from intervening in medical practice.<br />

9<br />

10<br />

11<br />

For example, the 1997 FDA Modernization Act (FDAMA) restates a doctor’s right to prescribe drugs for offlabel<br />

uses, an issue that was highly contentious at the time FDAMA was passed. Steven R. Salbu, "Off-Label<br />

Use, Prescription, and Marketing of FDA-Approved Drugs: An Assessment of Legislative and Regulatory<br />

Policy," Florida Law Review 51 (1999).<br />

Barry R. Furrow, "Regulating the Managed Care Revolution: Private Accreditation and a New System Ethos,"<br />

Villanova Law Review 43 (1998); Alycia C. Regan, "Regulating the Business of Medicine: Models for<br />

Integrating Ethics and Managed Care," Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems 30 (1997).<br />

Not coincident<strong>all</strong>y, this is the same argument offered by advocates of the free market against excessive<br />

regulatory interventions.<br />

336


Failure to acknowledge this fact, so the argument goes, often produces ineffective, wasteful, and<br />

quite possibly counterproductive rules and regulations. 12<br />

Gener<strong>all</strong>y speaking this argument has lost nothing of its relevance. In the case of the medical<br />

profession, however, it must be qualified in two important respects. Asymmetrical information<br />

should urge regulators to be cautious when considering intervening in medical decisions, but this<br />

argument is entirely irrelevant in examining the ethical aspects of these choices. As repeatedly<br />

argued in this report, bioethical dilemmas should not be decided by the medical profession and<br />

patients alone. Just as important is the observation that the health care sector has a very poor<br />

health and safety record. Consider the following bit of information: In 2000, the National<br />

Academy of Medicine estimated that every year in the United States, between 50,000 and<br />

100,000 persons die from preventable medical errors. 13 No other sector in the United States has<br />

such a poor safety record. If the chemical or the airline industry caused 50,000 deaths per year,<br />

the federal government would immediately shut them down. Against this background, the<br />

argument that the federal government would do more harm than good in considering regulatory<br />

interventions in this sector loses much if not <strong>all</strong> plausibility.<br />

It is instructive to explore some of the reasons for this situation. To date, the health care<br />

industry’s main response to medical errors is the morbidity and mortality (M&M) conference.<br />

M&M conferences are convened on a regular basis at university hospitals around the country.<br />

Their primary purpose is to offer to doctors in residence an opportunity to discuss their mistakes<br />

with their colleagues without fear of incurring in legal liabilities. 14 M&M conferences have<br />

proven remarkably ineffective in reducing medical errors. Information about incidents and<br />

accidents is not gathered in a systematic way or widely shared. More importantly, perhaps,<br />

M&M conferences are informed by a very narrow view of safety, one that is focused exclusively<br />

on the actions taken by a medical practitioner. Broader organizational considerations that may<br />

negatively affect the performance of medical personnel are gener<strong>all</strong>y absent. Every incident is<br />

examined in isolation, and no effort is made to identify possible connections among similar<br />

incidents. Nor would it be possible to conduct a similar analysis, because, as mentioned earlier,<br />

no standardized system of data gathering exists in the health care sector. To make things worse,<br />

informal sanctions against poorly performing doctors, according to some insider reports, are<br />

largely ineffective. 15<br />

The situation in private medical practices is qualitatively different, but not much more<br />

encouraging. For example, it has been shown that randomized clinical trials often contradict<br />

12<br />

13<br />

14<br />

15<br />

Perhaps the most forceful advocate of this perspective is Friedrich Hayek. Friedrich A. Hayek, Individualism and<br />

Economic Order. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976); Friedrich A. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit: The Errors<br />

of Socialism, The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek. Vol. 1 (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1988).<br />

Institute of Medicine, To Err Is Human: Building a Safer Health System (Washington, D.C.: National Academy<br />

Press, 2000).<br />

Edgar Pierluissi et al., "Discussion of Medical Error in Morbidity and Mortality Conferences," Journal of the<br />

American Medical Association 290, no. 21 (2003).<br />

Gawande, Complications: Decisions and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life.<br />

337


eliefs firmly held by medical practitioners about the efficacy of a given medical treatment. In<br />

some cases, these treatments do not even have a discernible therapeutic effect; in others, they are<br />

actu<strong>all</strong>y counterproductive. 16 Yet it appears that many physicians remain distinctively reluctant<br />

to accept recommendations based on randomized clinical trials. Conversely, physicians are more<br />

inclined to accept as validated knowledge recommendations from colleagues, even if these are<br />

based on a sample size of one. In sum, compared to other business sectors, the health care<br />

industry’s approach to safety and quality assurance is wholly inadequate.<br />

In the case of the ART industry in general, and of innovative reproductive treatments in<br />

particular, the situation is both better and worse. It is better because these treatments (and<br />

reproductive medicine more gener<strong>all</strong>y) clearly are not as dangerous for the patients as other<br />

medical fields. It is worse because in its 30-year history, reproductive medicine has never<br />

attempted to closely monitor the health and safety of the children born through ART. 17 Yet our<br />

discussion of innovative reproductive treatments in chapter 4 has shown that there have been<br />

several instances of ART practitioners performing potenti<strong>all</strong>y unsafe and quite possibly unethical<br />

procedures. The available evidence seems to indicate that ART physicians indeed are inclined to<br />

try wholly untested procedures on their patients but, absent a robust system of monitoring, it is<br />

impossible to determine whether these stories are isolated incidents or should be regarded merely<br />

as the tip of the proverbial iceberg. To use a now (in)famous formulation: In the area of<br />

reproductive medicine, regulators simply don’t know what they don’t know. What we do know is<br />

that we should learn a lot more about the nature and scope of innovative reproductive<br />

procedures.<br />

In proposing a system of monitoring for innovative ART treatments, an important design<br />

consideration is minimizing intrusiveness. Practitioners should remain free to choose what they<br />

regard as the most promising course of action, even if this course of action may be regarded by<br />

some as an innovative but untested ART treatment. In this sense, our approach to monitoring<br />

preserves professional autonomy. However, the ART community and regulators should be able<br />

to examine the rationale for these procedures, analyze possible risks for the mother and the child,<br />

and evaluate the relevance of various ethical concerns. The concept of “information regulation”<br />

meets these requirements. This regulatory approach should not be confused with the wellestablished<br />

notion of informed consent, although the two concepts are related. By information<br />

regulation, we mean a system of mandatory information disclosure that would require ART<br />

practitioners to report to regulators every instance of an innovative ART treatment. <strong>Report</strong>ing<br />

requirements would include a statement explaining the reasons for the course of action taken, an<br />

16<br />

17<br />

John F. Burnum, "Medical Practice a La Mode. How Medical Fashions Determine Medical Care," New England<br />

Journal of Medicine 317 (1987); David A. Grimes, "Technology Follies: The Uncritical Acceptance of Medical<br />

Innovation," Journal of the American Medical Association 269 (1993).<br />

This can be attributed in part to the fact that in this field of medicine, it is considerably more costly to conduct<br />

clinical trials and to follow the patients than in other fields of medicine, and in part to the fact that one party to<br />

the doctor-patient relationship, the child-to-be, cannot give his or her consent to performing an experimental<br />

reproductive procedure.<br />

338


assessment of possible health and safety risks to the prospective mother and her child, and a<br />

discussion of possible ethical concerns. Regulators would use this information to build a record<br />

for various innovative ART procedures. The report would also form the basis for determining if<br />

the procedure poses unacceptable risks or serious ethical concerns. To this end, the regulators<br />

would solicit comments from the ART practitioners and from professional bioethicists. Note that<br />

this process would not have a suspensive effect on the proposed ART treatment unless the<br />

agency determines that it poses an obvious and immediate threat to the health and well-being of<br />

the child and/or the mother.<br />

The rationale for mandating information disclosure is straightforward: Requiring that both<br />

the rationale for performing an innovative procedure be made available to the regulators and<br />

their peers will encourage ART physicians to more carefully examine the pros and cons of<br />

performing the procedure in the first place. It is not unreasonable to assume that mandatory<br />

disclosure requirements will discourage some ART practitioners from performing questionable<br />

procedures. They are also likely to induce the ART profession to evaluate much more carefully<br />

possible dangers associated with these procedures. Furthermore, mandatory disclosure<br />

requirements will set off a debate among ART professionals about the wisdom of the course of<br />

action taken, its benefits, and possible harms. An unintended but welcome consequence of these<br />

internal debates is the identification of alternative, less problematic, or less risky procedures. In<br />

sum, information regulation not only encourages accountability among ART practitioners; it is<br />

also an institutionalized mechanism of monitoring and learning.<br />

Information regulation as proposed in this section has several precedents. It is at the core of<br />

many financial disclosure requirements mandated by the Securities and Exchange Commission;<br />

it has successfully been used to improve the safety of U.S. nuclear power plants, 18 and has found<br />

numerous applications in environmental policy. 19 Perhaps the single most successful example of<br />

information regulation is the Toxic Release Inventory (TRI) program established as part of the<br />

Emergency Planning and Community Right-to-Know Act of 1986 by the EPA. The TRI program<br />

requires industrial facilities to report to the EPA on a yearly basis the production of<br />

approximately 650 hazardous chemicals (as of 1999). It should be emphasized that the EPA does<br />

not directly regulate the production and disposal of the chemicals listed in the TRI; it only<br />

requires that chemical plants report hazardous waste production on an annual basis. According to<br />

18<br />

19<br />

Rees, Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three Mile Island.<br />

Paul R. Kleindorfer and Eric W. Orts, "Information Regulation of Environmental Risks," Risk Analysis 18, no. 2<br />

(1998). An illustration is provided by the Global <strong>Report</strong>ing Initiative, a program launched by the United Nations<br />

Environment Programme designed to improve environmental disclosure by large international corporations. See<br />

http://www.globalreporting.org/index.asp for more information. See also Thomas C. Beierle, "Environmental<br />

Information Disclosure: Three Cases of Policy and Politics," (Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future,<br />

2003). In developing countries, information disclosure has gained some popularity as a low-cost, effective<br />

regulatory tool. See for example Shakeb Afsah and Jeffrey R. Vincent, "Putting Pressure on Polluters:<br />

Indonesia's Proper Program " (Harvard Institute for International Development, 1997); Tom Tietenberg and<br />

David Wheeler, "Empowering the Community: Information Strategies for Pollution Control" (paper presented at<br />

the Frontiers of Environmental Economics Conference, Airlie House, VA, October 23-25, 1998).<br />

339


some studies, the TRI program has been spectacularly successful in reducing the volume of<br />

hazardous wastes. 20<br />

There have been some instances of information regulation in medicine as well. The state of<br />

New York, for example, makes available to the public risk-adjusted mortality rates for cardiac<br />

artery bypass surgery on hospital-by-hospital basis and for individual physicians. 21 Whether this<br />

particular form of information regulation is an effective way to reduce medical errors is doubtful.<br />

Underlying this kind of mandatory system of disclosure is the assumption that patients will select<br />

a surgeon based on his or her safety record. This assumption may be seriously flawed. Every<br />

surgeon, even the best one, in his or her career will make at least one tragic error. 22 Prospective<br />

patients may be able to make an “informed decision,” but one may wonder just how informed<br />

this decision re<strong>all</strong>y is.<br />

Implementing a system of monitoring and information disclosure as envisaged in this<br />

section requires solving several problems. Among them is defining what constitutes an<br />

innovative treatment. Distinguishing between innovative and standard treatments is not as<br />

problematic as one might assume, however. The ART industry has settled on fairly<br />

straightforward definitions of standard treatments. Their number is sm<strong>all</strong>. A list of these<br />

procedures, complete with a brief description, fits comfortably on one page. 23 Reproductive<br />

endocrinologists routinely tweak and adapt these procedures to meet specific clinical<br />

requirements, but these modifications do not warrant introducing new categories. For example,<br />

some reproductive practitioners <strong>all</strong>ow the embryo to develop in vitro for five instead of the more<br />

common three days. Tweaking the time of in vitro embryo development is just that, a marginal<br />

change that should not be construed as an innovative treatment.<br />

Innovative procedures by definition have never been tested in animal models and depart<br />

significantly from standard ART treatments. Accurately defining “significant departure” may<br />

require some trial-and-error. Initial definitions are bound to be controversial, and in some<br />

instances, the courts may be c<strong>all</strong>ed upon to resolve these controversies. It is quite possible that<br />

initi<strong>all</strong>y, regulators will cast the net too broadly. As a result, they may consider as innovative<br />

20<br />

21<br />

22<br />

23<br />

Bradley C. Karkkainen, "Information as Environmental Regulation: TRI and Performance Benchmarking,<br />

Precursor to a New Paradigm?," Georgetown Law Journal 89 (2001); King and Lenox, "Industry Self-<br />

Regulation without Sanctions: The Chemical Industry's Responsible Care Program."<br />

See http://www.health.state.ny.us/press/releases/2004/cardiac_release_05-06-2004.htm. For a general discussion,<br />

see William M. Sage, "Regulating through Information: Disclosure Laws and American Healthcare," Columbia<br />

Law Review 99 (1999). It appears that information disclosure has little impact on actual consumer choices, but it<br />

does have a measure of impact on the quality of service. See Mark R. Chassin, E. L. Hannan, and B. A.<br />

DeBuono, "Benefits and Hazards of <strong>Report</strong>ing Medical Outcomes Publicly," New England Journal of Medicine<br />

334 (1996); Edward L. Hannan et al., "Improving the Outcomes of Coronary Artery Bypass Surgery in New<br />

York State," Journal of the American Medical Association 271, no. 10 (1994); Eric C. Schneider and Arnold M.<br />

Epstein, "Influence of Cardiac-Surgery Performance <strong>Report</strong>s on Referral Practices and Access to Care," New<br />

England Journal of Medicine 335 (1996).<br />

Gawande, Complications: Decisions and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "Survey of Assisted Reproductive Technology: Embryo Laboratory<br />

Procedures and Practices," (Chamblee, GA: Public Health Practice Program Office, Division of Laboratory<br />

Systems, Laboratory Practice Assessment Branch, 1999), Appendix G, p.2.<br />

340


many procedures the industry regards merely as a form of tweaking. In time, however, a<br />

consensus between the regulators and the industry on what constitutes a “significant departure”<br />

is likely to emerge.<br />

As a general principle, reporting requirements should ensure that other ART physicians<br />

could reproduce the procedure. The rationale provided by the performing practitioner should be<br />

specific enough as to <strong>all</strong>ow other reproductive endocrinologists to debate the pros and cons of his<br />

or her decision. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the performing ART practitioner should conduct a risk-benefit analysis<br />

that includes not only the prospective parents but the future child as well. We realize that riskbenefit<br />

analysis is an exercise fraught with unknowns and questionable assumptions.<br />

Implementing this requirement may represent a considerable hurdle for many ART practitioners.<br />

To overcome these difficulties, the regulators could provide extensive scientific and medical<br />

assistance, as well as detailed guidelines. More or less sophisticated approaches can be<br />

envisaged, but the principle that performing an innovative reproductive treatment requires<br />

assessing possible health and safety risks should be retained.<br />

Performing innovative procedures will also trigger stricter standards of informed consent. A<br />

key aspect of these standards is informing the prospective parents that the reproductive<br />

procedure envisaged is indeed experimental. Whether stricter standards of informed consent will<br />

prompt prospective parents to reconsider questionable reproductive procedures is doubtful. As<br />

we have shown in chapter 4, the dividing line between parental desperation and reckless<br />

behavior is a thin one. Many parents are likely to expose future children to excessive risks even<br />

if they have received extensive and in-depth information about these risks. Nevertheless, we<br />

believe that the experimental nature of innovative reproductive procedures warrants a more<br />

rigorous approach to informed consent.<br />

Having examined an innovative reproductive protocol, its rationale, its risks, and its<br />

benefits, and having heard the ART practitioners’ views on the merits or demerits of the<br />

procedure in question, regulators can make one of several possible determinations. They may<br />

decide that the procedure in question does not raise significant concerns. Alternatively, given the<br />

uncertain nature of the risks involved, they may c<strong>all</strong> for a moratorium while more research is<br />

conducted. They may also come to the conclusion that the risks outweigh the benefits and justify<br />

a ban. <strong>Final</strong>ly, based on the feedback submitted by the ART industry, they may recommend<br />

taking a number of precautions and suggest tweaks that would mitigate the most important risks.<br />

Reproductive specialists are likely to find these requirements problematic. There is no doubt<br />

that implementing a system of monitoring as discussed in this section would increase the cost of<br />

ART treatments and may prevent some prospective parents from realizing their dream. But the<br />

system of monitoring proposed here also has several important benefits. It provides a measure of<br />

legitimacy and legal protection to reproductive endocrinologists performing innovative<br />

reproductive procedures deemed acceptable by regulators; it protects the interests of ART<br />

children in a much more effective way; it improves the quality and safety of reproductive<br />

procedures; and it expands the number of reproductive treatments available to the ART industry.<br />

These benefits are well worth their costs.<br />

341


13.4 Technologies of Reproductive Customization<br />

Technologies of reproductive customization set themselves apart from standard reproductive<br />

techniques and innovative treatments for their purpose. These technologies are not used simply<br />

to increase the prospective parents’ chances to have a family, but to meet specific parental<br />

requirements. A classic example is the use of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for elective sex<br />

selection.<br />

With regard to monitoring the use of technologies of customization or reproductive control,<br />

no additional action is needed. As for innovative reproductive treatments, ART practitioners<br />

would have to provide an assessment of possible health and safety risks and a discussion of<br />

possible ethical concerns, if the contemplated procedure is not already regulated. The notion of<br />

risk in this case should be construed broadly to include harm to the well-being of the child, and<br />

not simply health threats in the narrow sense of this term. Consistent with the view that<br />

technologies of reproductive customization should be more closely scrutinized, the review<br />

process would have a suspensive effect. The proposed procedure may not be performed until the<br />

agency has evaluated the documentation and has received feedback from the ART industry and<br />

the bioethics community.<br />

Depending on the type of procedure and the concerns expressed, the agency could proceed<br />

as in the case of innovative reproductive treatments – i.e., offer a specific opinion on the pros and<br />

cons of the proposed treatment, or determine that the procedure at issue deserves broader public<br />

scrutiny. In the latter case, it would propose a new rule and initiate a process of public<br />

consultation.<br />

Initi<strong>all</strong>y, the legal definition of a technology of reproductive customization could create<br />

some difficulties. It may not always be clear whether a certain treatment should be regarded as<br />

an instance of a traditional ART treatment, as an innovative technique, or rather as a technology<br />

of reproductive customization. Nor is determining what harm the child may experience a trivial<br />

matter. The debate over reproductive cloning has shown that it may be surprisingly difficult (but<br />

certainly not impossible) to demonstrate harm for the children involved. This is also the reason<br />

why we have suggested establishing an independent agency with quasi-judicial powers.<br />

13.5 Biomedical Research<br />

Of the four policy domains identified in this report, biomedical research poses perhaps the<br />

greatest ch<strong>all</strong>enge. Science and scientific institutions enjoy a special position in modern<br />

America. The public continues to regard science and technology as crucial to the future of our<br />

country. The libertarian ethos that is one of the constitutive elements of American<br />

exceptionalism is particularly strong among scientists. 24 Representatives of this profession often<br />

consider scientific freedom sacrosanct. Attempts by Congress to restrict freedom of research are<br />

24<br />

See, for example, Lipset, American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword.<br />

342


likely to meet with fierce resistance, more so perhaps than the suggestion that the practice of<br />

reproductive medicine should be regulated.<br />

In select areas, the scientific community has recognized the importance of conducting<br />

research in a manner that is regarded by the public as ethical. The “Guidelines for Human<br />

Embryonic Stem Cells,” a report published by the National Academy of Sciences (NAS) in early<br />

2005, provides an illustration. Unlike most legislative proposals introduced in Congress over the<br />

last few years, the NAS report, in addition to recommending the usual procedural safeguards,<br />

proposes the creation of an infrastructure of evaluation and monitoring. The proposal is by far<br />

the most sophisticated and serious effort to establish a regulatory framework for a field of<br />

biomedical research. For this reason, we examine its main elements in some detail.<br />

The NAS report establishes the principle that research proposals should be evaluated not<br />

merely on procedural but also on substantive grounds. Cruci<strong>all</strong>y, the report distinguishes<br />

between research that is “permissible” (i.e., that does not require additional review), research that<br />

is permissible only after additional review, and research that “should not be permitted at this<br />

time.”<br />

The derivation of new stem cell lines, either from donated embryos or created through<br />

somatic cell nuclear transfer, would trigger additional review. Additional scrutiny would also be<br />

necessary for introducing human embryonic stem cells into non-human animals at any stage of<br />

embryonic, fetal, or postnatal development. 25 Among the activities that should not be permitted<br />

are (a) the in vitro culture of human embryos for longer than 14 days or until the formation of the<br />

primitive streak, whichever occurs first; (b) research in which human embryonic stem cells are<br />

introduced into non-human primate blastocysts, or in which any embryonic stem cells are<br />

introduced into human blastocysts; and (c) the breeding of animals in which human embryonic<br />

stem cells have been introduced at any stage of development. 26<br />

Taken together, these provisions suggest that the scientific community is beginning to<br />

recognize the need to distinguish between research that is largely unproblematic, research that<br />

warrants additional scrutiny, and research that should not be conducted. In our view, this<br />

recognition is more important than where exactly the specific ethical lines should be drawn. The<br />

NAS recommendations are noteworthy for another reason as well: They implicitly acknowledge<br />

the need to create a regulatory institution that can operate in a contingent, quasi-adjudicative way<br />

rather than suggesting the creation of a system based on the seriously misleading assumption that<br />

ethical controversies can be resolved in an abstract, a priori fashion.<br />

Chiefly responsible for the evaluation of research proposals would be an Embryonic Stem<br />

Cell Research Oversight (ESCRO) committee. ESCROs would be established at each research<br />

institution at which human embryonic stem cell research is being conducted, but they would not<br />

duplicate the functions of institutional review boards. The report recommends that<br />

25<br />

26<br />

Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem<br />

Cell Research, p.87.<br />

Ibid., p.87-88.<br />

343


epresentatives of the general public as well as professional bioethicists and legal scholars be<br />

represented on each ESCRO. 27<br />

It also recognizes the crucial importance of compliance<br />

assurance, and proposes what at first seems a practicable approach to compliance assurance –<br />

identifying in private institutions such as funding agencies, professional societies, publishers, and<br />

institutional review panels entities that can provide “valuable community pressure” and “impose<br />

appropriate sanctions to ensure compliance.” 28 More specific<strong>all</strong>y, the report recommends that<br />

compliance be ensured through three private institutions – review committees such as ESCROs<br />

and IRBs, funding agencies, and journals. 29<br />

Having emphasized several commendable aspects of the NAS report, three major<br />

shortcomings should mentioned. First, the role of the general public remains unspecified.<br />

Presumably, this requirement is inspired by the now fairly common practice to include a<br />

“community representative” on IRBs and ethics committees. This approach may be reasonable in<br />

the case of medical ethics committees, but it is hard to see how a few representatives of a local<br />

community may contribute to defuse anxieties, concerns, and opposition to controversial<br />

research proposals. Should a research protocol be prevented from moving forward if the local<br />

community is opposed to it? In which way are the community representatives accountable to the<br />

community? Should they be elected or simply selected by the research institution to participate?<br />

The credibility of ESCRO committees as moral authorities and independent bodies of evaluation<br />

and oversight depends cruci<strong>all</strong>y on how these issues are resolved.<br />

One may also wonder why the report suggests implementing a decentralized system of<br />

oversight. Quite possibly, the preference for a decentralized over a federal system of oversight<br />

resides in a deep-seated distrust of the G.W. Bush administration, often regarded by the scientific<br />

community as being captured by religious interests inimical to medical science and to the<br />

scientific enterprise more gener<strong>all</strong>y. This argument ignores the simple fact that a decentralized<br />

system of oversight is not better protected against skeptical views than a federal system of<br />

oversight would be, and has some shortcomings of its own. As shown in chapter 10, citizen<br />

advisory boards can quickly become a platform for skeptical groups to voice their opposition.<br />

ESCRO committees, too, could become the focus of heated, protracted, and ultimately sterile<br />

political controversies between a research institution and the local community. A federal system<br />

27<br />

28<br />

29<br />

Ibid., p.44-46.<br />

Ibid., p.12. There is ample empirical evidence that private systems of reciprocal monitoring can produce<br />

surprisingly high levels of compliance with privately enacted rules and norms. See, for example, Lisa Bernstein,<br />

"Opting out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry," Journal of Legal<br />

Studies 21, no. 1 (1992); Lisa Bernstein, "Private Commercial Law in the Cotton Industry: Creating Cooperation<br />

through Rules, Norms and Institutions," Michigan Law Review 99 (2001); Robert D. Cooter, "Decentralized Law<br />

for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to Adjudicating the New Law Merchant," University of<br />

Pennsylvania Law Review 144, no. 5 (1996); Avery Katz, "Taking Private Ordering Seriously," University of<br />

Pennsylvania Law Review 144, no. 5 (1996); Mark D. West, "Private Ordering at the World’s First Futures<br />

Exchange," Michigan Law Review 98 (2000).<br />

Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem<br />

Cell Research, p.12.<br />

344


of oversight as laid out in this report would provide both legal protection and legitimacy to the<br />

research community independently of idiosyncratic political landscapes at the local level.<br />

The system of compliance assurance proposed by the NAS report has the merit of focusing<br />

on private organizations such as funding agencies and publishers that by virtue of their position<br />

could ensure high levels of compliance. These organizations could require sufficient and credible<br />

evidence of compliance with the NAS guidelines as a condition for funding or publication. In<br />

select areas, mainly with regard to compliance with procedures of informed consent, this<br />

approach could prove workable. In this case, the task of reviewing compliance records may be<br />

manageable, and the reviewing institutions could be expected to have the necessary<br />

administrative expertise to perform this task. Certainly, the leading funding institutions and<br />

highly reputable journals could perform this task. Sm<strong>all</strong>er organizations, such as foundations and<br />

second-tier journals, may not have the necessary expertise and may be far less inclined to assume<br />

these responsibilities. Importantly, the system of compliance assurance proposed by the NAS<br />

guidelines does not explicitly contemplate a system of inspection, nor does it include any kind of<br />

sanctions for non-compliance. <strong>Final</strong>ly, the report does not elaborate on how the integrity of a<br />

private system of compliance assurance could be protected.<br />

<strong>Final</strong>ly, as laid out in this report, the responsibility for determining the acceptability of new<br />

research protocols resides with the scientific community and with it alone. Local communities<br />

have an opportunity to be heard, but they certainly do not have the authority to prevent new<br />

research from moving forward. This is precisely the opposite of what we have proposed in this<br />

report: Scientists and the general public must be given ample opportunities to be heard, but the<br />

authority to decide what may or may not move forward must reside with an administrative entity<br />

created by Congress. It should be the responsibility of the regulatory advisory board (see chapter<br />

11) to examine new research protocols and to make recommendations for the regulatory<br />

commission. For these reasons, we believe that the guidelines proposed by the National<br />

Academy of Sciences do not form the basis for a robust and trustworthy regulatory<br />

infrastructure.<br />

13.6 Designing a System of Compliance Assurance<br />

Implementing an efficient and effective system of compliance assurance is no easy task. In<br />

this regard, the British experience is only of limited help. As of August 31, 2004, the HFEA had<br />

exercised its oversight over 108 ART programs and ART laboratories. 30<br />

Inspecting these<br />

facilities on a regular basis is a manageable task, considering the modest number of facilities and<br />

the limited travel distances involved. A U.S. regulatory agency would face a much more<br />

complex organizational landscape that includes more than 400 ART clinics, countless embryo<br />

labs, more than 900 biotech companies, several large pharmaceutical companies, and a<br />

potenti<strong>all</strong>y significant number of university laboratories. Furthermore, this very diverse<br />

30<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA), "HFEA Annual <strong>Report</strong> 2003/04," p.8.<br />

345


population of firms, clinics, laboratories, and universities is scattered over a very large territory,<br />

making it difficult for any administrative agency to implement a credible and effective system of<br />

compliance assurance.<br />

Regulatory agencies facing a ch<strong>all</strong>enge of this magnitude routinely delegate some<br />

monitoring and enforcement authority to third parties, such as trade and professional<br />

organizations. Obvious candidates for surveying ART programs are the American Society for<br />

Reproductive Medicine and the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technologies. The<br />

Biotechnology Industry Organization could monitor the biotech sector, and leading scientific<br />

societies such as the American Association for the Advancement of Science and the Federation<br />

of American Societies for Experimental Biology could audit academic laboratories.<br />

Delegating monitoring and enforcement authority to third parties – referred to as<br />

intermediary organizations in the remainder of this section – has a crucial limitation: Trade and<br />

professional associations would have a very limited authority to ensure compliance; members<br />

could easily avoid compliance by simply leaving the association, while non-members would be<br />

exempt from oversight in the first place. This is not, however, an insurmountable problem. While<br />

limited, an intermediary organization’s authority is not negligible; it varies depending on the<br />

nature of the benefits it provides to its members. 31<br />

Intermediary organizations providing<br />

valuable, exclusive benefits to their members make it more difficult for a member to leave. The<br />

more valuable the exclusive benefits, the more difficult it is for a member to leave, and the more<br />

powerful an intermediary organization becomes. 32<br />

Regulators could bolster these embryonic systems of private governance either by making<br />

membership in intermediary organizations more attractive or by increasing the cost of leaving an<br />

intermediary group. For example, regulators could decide that the members of an intermediary<br />

organization would be inspected less frequently, and that the inspection process should be<br />

collaborative and should emphasize the correction of violations and the adoption of best<br />

practices over punishment, fines, and prosecution. The agency could also determine that serious<br />

violations by a member of an intermediary organization should be treated more leniently. By<br />

contrast, non-members would be inspected more frequently, their inspection process would be<br />

antagonistic, and violations would trigger severe penalties. Importantly, members of an<br />

intermediary organization would be inspected by their peers or by representatives of their<br />

intermediary organization, while non-members would be inspected by the regulators.<br />

In this architecture of compliance, the regulator’s main role shifts from compliance<br />

assurance to ensuring the integrity of a decentralized system of monitoring and inspection, i.e., to<br />

monitoring the monitors. Assuring the credibility and integrity of this system entails addressing<br />

several concerns. Chief among them are ensuring consistency of inspection and preventing<br />

31<br />

32<br />

Typic<strong>all</strong>y, national trade associations advocate vigorously for their members, to avoid or mitigate regulations or<br />

to obtain specific benefits. They also offer a wide range of training and educational opportunities.<br />

Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (Cambridge, MA:<br />

Harvard University Press, 1965); Posner, "The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal<br />

Sanctions on Collective Action."<br />

346


collusion between inspectors and inspected parties. To achieve these goals, regulators would<br />

adopt a certification scheme. Only certified intermediary organizations would be delegated the<br />

authority to conduct inspections. Maintaining the certification would require intermediary<br />

organizations to periodic<strong>all</strong>y undergo extensive audits, for example, every three to five years.<br />

Serious irregularities could trigger monetary and other penalties for both the auditing and the<br />

audited organization. For the most egregious violations, the regulators could revoke the<br />

certification. The consequences of this measure would be severe, because in this case, both the<br />

intermediary organization and its members would be punished. 33<br />

Revoking certification is perhaps the most extreme illustration of a collective sanction. The<br />

threat of collective sanctions, if properly designed, could have several unintended but welcome<br />

consequences. It could trigger collaborative efforts to identify best practices and promote their<br />

adoption throughout the group. It could also encourage the members of an intermediary group to<br />

exercise pressure on violators to comply with <strong>all</strong> applicable laws and regulations. Failure to<br />

demonstrate improvement on the part of violators could prompt some members to file a report<br />

with the intermediary group. <strong>Final</strong>ly, individual members would have an incentive to report<br />

cases of collusion between an audited organization and the auditor to the regulators. 34<br />

Collective sanctions are neither new nor unusual. In the early 1970s, the scientific<br />

community effectively faced a collective threat when its leaders at the Asilomar Conference<br />

proposed to establish a system of self-regulation. In this case, the threat originated not with<br />

regulators but with the general public. Scientific leaders recognized that even a single accident<br />

associated with recombinant DNA technology would have damaged the reputation of this<br />

nascent field of research beyond repair. This is by no means an exceptional pattern. Over the last<br />

20 years, many industries that experienced a highly visible, catastrophic incident reacted by<br />

establishing elaborate systems of self-governance. 35<br />

This somewhat simplistic analysis of the impact of collective sanctions on intermediary<br />

organizations and their members masks a subtle but very important phenomenon: the gradual<br />

emergence among these organizations of civic norms and attitudes, i.e., the recognition of the<br />

crucial importance of obtaining a “public license” for conducting ethic<strong>all</strong>y controversial medical<br />

research. Key to initiating this learning process is a new professional role: a person charged by<br />

33<br />

34<br />

35<br />

The threat of revoking certification is credible only if the intermediary organization being audited is not too large<br />

compared to other intermediary organizations. Should a large intermediary organization loose its certification, it<br />

may be difficult for regulators to find a replacement. In turn, this would make the threat of decertification less<br />

credible.<br />

Note that whistle-blowing as outlined in this passage provides an additional incentive to intermediary<br />

organizations to properly audit their members.<br />

The classic example is the Responsible Care Program established by the American Chemistry Council (formerly<br />

the Chemical Manufacturers Association) in the aftermath of the Bhopal accident. Cf. Howard, Nash, and<br />

Ehrenfeld, "Standard or Smokescreen? Implementation of a Voluntary Environmental Code."; King and Lenox,<br />

"Industry Self-Regulation without Sanctions: The Chemical Industry's Responsible Care Program." Other<br />

chemical sub-sectors have followed suit, adopting their own programs of safety and environmental management.<br />

A similar approach has been taken by the nuclear power industry in the wake of Three Mile Island. Rees,<br />

Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three Mile Island.<br />

347


an ART program, a biotech company, or a university to ensure compliance with applicable laws<br />

and regulations – a compliance assurance officer, so to speak. This person’s job would be not<br />

only to make sure that researchers and ART practitioners follow procedures and maintain proper<br />

documentation, but also to determine whether a certain ART treatments should be considered<br />

traditional, innovative, or technologies of customization, and what ethical concerns they may<br />

raise. In the case of biomedical research, this person would help determine whether a given<br />

research proposal might raise special ethical concerns. Cruci<strong>all</strong>y, the compliance officer would<br />

cooperate with compliance officers at other ART programs or research institutions to resolve<br />

complex ethical problems created by new research protocols, and to identify possible harms<br />

involved in novel reproductive treatments. These patterns of collaboration eventu<strong>all</strong>y will morph<br />

into a horizontal network of personal and professional relations, and lead to the emergence of a<br />

professional culture that will find itself at the intersection of public virtues and private interests.<br />

From a regulatory standpoint, the emergence of this network would have several important<br />

benefits: It would reduce the risks of collusion between member organizations and auditors. It<br />

would spur the ethical analysis of novel ART treatments and biomedical research protocols. It<br />

would contribute to developing new techniques of risk assessment. Importantly, it would also<br />

become an effective promoter of civic values among biomedical researchers and medical<br />

professionals. 36<br />

Admittedly, creating the position of compliance assurance officer, by itself, is unlikely to<br />

produce the kind of cultural change envisaged here. No one should be under the illusion that<br />

civic norms would quickly emerge. That compliance assurance could initiate a process of<br />

societal change is, however, both surprising and encouraging. This alone would justify its<br />

implementation costs, as discussed in the next section.<br />

13.7 Operating Costs<br />

In this section, we provide a rough estimate of the costs of operating a new regulatory entity<br />

as outlined in this report. This discussion is not meant to provide precise cost estimates. It is<br />

simply a back-of-the-envelope calculation that should demonstrate how modest the over<strong>all</strong> costs<br />

of operating a new regulatory agency would be. Our calculations are based on data derived from<br />

the British regulatory system, one of the most intrusive systems of ART regulation worldwide.<br />

The data is derived from the 2001, 2002, and 2003 annual HFEA reports, available on the HFEA<br />

Web site. 37 Each of them includes a financial statement and other operational data. They also<br />

describe in some detail the scope of the HFEA’s regulatory activities.<br />

36<br />

37<br />

An important precedent to this professional role is the environmental and safety (ES) manager common at large<br />

industrial firms. Several trade groups in the chemical sectors that in recent times have adopted extensive systems<br />

of self-regulation have learned that ES managers play a crucial role in resolving complex questions of<br />

implementation and in promoting high levels of compliance.<br />

See http://www.hfea.gov.uk.<br />

348


Consider first the scope of the HFEA’s regulatory activities. In 2003, the agency was<br />

responsible for overseeing 110 facilities. Most of them (80) offer both treatment and storage<br />

services; 15 had received <strong>all</strong> three kinds of license (treatment, storage, and research); the<br />

remaining ones are specialized in just one type of licensed activity. (See Table 12.)<br />

Type of HFEA-licensed center Number of centers<br />

Treatment only 2<br />

Storage only 8<br />

Treatment and storage 80<br />

Treatment with storage and research 15<br />

Research only 5<br />

Total 110<br />

Table 12: The ART industry in Britain, 2002-2003, p.8.<br />

Another measure of the size of the British ART industry is the number of licensed<br />

treatments granted by the HFEA on a clinic-by-clinic basis. As Table 13 shows, not every clinic<br />

is licensed to perform <strong>all</strong> ART treatments, but most perform donor insemination, in vitro<br />

fertilization, and intracytoplasmic sperm injection. They also offer the storage of embryos and<br />

sperm.<br />

HFEA-licensed treatments<br />

Number of centers<br />

Storage of eggs (including ovarian tissue) 20<br />

Storage of sperm (including testicular tissue) 103<br />

Storage of embryos 76<br />

Donor insemination 96<br />

In vitro fertilization 75<br />

Intracytoplasmic sperm injection 74<br />

Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis 8<br />

Pre-implantation genetic screening for aneuploidy 5<br />

Table 13: Licensed treatments in Britain, 2002-2003, p.8.<br />

Clinics are gener<strong>all</strong>y inspected on a yearly basis, although facilities in good standing are<br />

fully inspected only once every three years. Table 14 provides another indication of the tight<br />

control exercised by the HFEA over the ART industry, in the form of the total number of<br />

inspections conducted in 1999, 2000, 2002, and 2003.<br />

Inspection 1998-1999 1999-2000 2001-2002 2002-2003<br />

Number of inspection visits 106 109 115 121<br />

Number of audits 28 25 106 93<br />

Number of ICSI practitioners inspected 35 22 18<br />

30<br />

Number of PGD practitioners inspected 0 1<br />

n/a<br />

Table 14: Inspection visits and audits, 1999-2003.<br />

349


By <strong>all</strong> accounts, the British regulatory system can only be described as comprehensive and<br />

fairly intrusive. And while the British ART industry is considerably sm<strong>all</strong>er than its U.S.<br />

counterpart, it is large and complex enough to serve as a basis for assessing the operational costs<br />

of a domestic regulatory program.<br />

Just how expensive is it to operate the HFEA licensing and inspecting scheme? Actual<br />

financial information about these two operational aspects is not available, but total operating<br />

expenses are a good substitute. Information about total expenditures is readily available and is<br />

reported in Table 15.<br />

Year 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004<br />

Total expenditures 1,552,909 1,706,657 1,772,910 2,743,558 1,716,845 5,629,560 7,444,580<br />

Staff costs 848,288 932,093 969,503 1,363,038 1,263,038 2,523,912 3,665,204<br />

Table 15: HFEA operating costs, 1998-2004 (in pounds).<br />

Until 2000, total expenditures remained largely unchanged. In response to the rapid growth<br />

of the ART industry in 2001, the HFEA budget and its staff expanded considerably. Section 16<br />

of the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act requires the HFEA to recover 70 percent of its<br />

expenditures. The HFEA recoups its operating expenses through licensing fees (for first-time and<br />

for renewal applications) and through an annual fee based on the number of ART cycles<br />

performed. In 2000, the fee for performing an IVF cycle was reduced from £40 to £36, whereas<br />

fees for donor insemination were raised from £10 to £18. The HFEA has been quite good at<br />

achieving a 70 percent level of self-funding. In the fiscal year 2000-2001, its self-funding level<br />

was 67 percent. In 1999-2000, it reached 101 percent of its cash limit.<br />

The U.S. ART industry is approximately four times larger than its British counterpart, not<br />

counting the sperm and embryo banks already regulated by the new FDA human cellular and<br />

tissue-based products rules. 38<br />

The 2002 CDC report on ART success rates lists 391 ART<br />

programs, up from 384 a year before. 39 These programs gener<strong>all</strong>y do not conduct basic research<br />

on human embryos. On the other hand, according to news media reports, restrictions on federal<br />

funding for embryonic stem cell research have prompted private foundations to fill this gap, so it<br />

is quite possible that a fair number of universities are now receiving human embryos, though<br />

how many is anyone’s guess. 40<br />

38<br />

39<br />

40<br />

See chapter 5 for a discussion of these rules.<br />

These are the reporting programs. Appendix C of the report lists 37 non-reporting programs. Cf. Centers for<br />

Disease Control and Prevention, "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National Summary<br />

and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s."<br />

Anne Harding, Harvard Has Human Cloning Plans. Institute Seeks Nod to Create Embryos Using Genes from<br />

Patients with Diabetes, Parkinson's (The Scientist, October 15, 2004 [cited September 20, 2005]); available from<br />

http://www.biomedcentral.com/news/20041015/03; Nancy Touchette, New Stem Cells Created for Research:<br />

Harvard Scientist Will Make 17 New Lines Available (Genome News Network, March 3, 2004 [cited September<br />

20, 2005]); available from http://www.genomenewsnetwork.org/articles/2004/03/03/stem_cells.php.<br />

350


There is some evidence that the biotech industry does conduct research in this area, but just<br />

how much research is unknown. A fairly recent survey conducted by the Department of<br />

Commerce in cooperation with BIO, the leading biotech industry trade association, shows that of<br />

776 surveyed firms, 41 percent did perform “culturing/manipulation of cells, tissues,,<br />

embryos.” 41 However, the survey does not provide any information on the relative importance of<br />

embryo research proper, or the significance of this research area in the industry research<br />

portfolio.<br />

For the purpose of this discussion, we assume that the newly created regulatory agency<br />

would have to fund itself through user fees. (This is a worst-case scenario, as Congress is likely<br />

to fund this agency at least in part.) The regulators, then, would have to adopt a fee system<br />

similar to the one operated by the British HFEA. A simple way to assess the burden imposed on<br />

the ART industry and patients by this fee system is to compare fee levels to the cost of ART<br />

services to patients. Assessing the cost of ART services in the United Sates is no easy task.<br />

Prices vary considerably depending on the type of service rendered and the clinic’s reputation<br />

and location. ASRM does not provide reliable cost information, nor does the CDC gather this<br />

kind of data. A rough estimate of the cost of various ART services can be gleaned from Web<br />

resources offering information to prospective parents and from fertility clinics’ own published<br />

information. For example, www.babycenter.com provides the following price estimates per<br />

cycle:<br />

• Artificial insemination: $300 to $700<br />

• In vitro fertilization: $8,000 to $15,000<br />

• Gamete intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer: $8,000 to $15,000<br />

• Zygote intraf<strong>all</strong>opian transfer: $8,000 to $15,000<br />

• Intracytoplasmic sperm injection: $10,000 to $17,000 42<br />

Note that these categories are not mutu<strong>all</strong>y exclusive. An individual cycle may require<br />

performing ICSI followed by traditional IVF. Other cycle-related services such as testing of<br />

reproductive tissues are charged separately. In the United States, by far the most common<br />

procedure remains IVF. According to the CDC, in 2001, 107,587 ART cycles were performed. 43<br />

Assuming that the U.S. regulatory counterpart would charge the same fee as the British HFEA<br />

(i.e. £36, or $64), 44 and given the average price of $12,000 per cycle, a U.S. regulatory system<br />

41<br />

42<br />

43<br />

44<br />

U.S. Department of Commerce, "A Survey of the Use of Biotechnology in the U.S. Industry," (Washington,<br />

D.C.: Technology Administration, Bureau of Industry and Security, 2003).<br />

See http://www.babycenter.com/refcap/preconception/fertilityproblems/1228997.html, page visited on July 20,<br />

2005.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, "2001 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National<br />

Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s," (Atlanta, GA: National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and<br />

Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health, 2003), p.6.<br />

Exchange rate as of April 26, 2006.<br />

351


would add roughly 0.56 percent to the cost of this ART service. This figure must be regarded as<br />

a rough estimate; it does not include the one-time costs to ART programs to implement the new<br />

record-keeping and reporting requirements, and it does not include the additional operating<br />

expenses ART programs would incur in complying with reporting and other regulatory<br />

requirements. On the other end, it is quite possible that a U.S. regulatory agency would be less<br />

costly to operate and could charge lower user fees.<br />

The new record-keeping requirements are likely to increase the operational costs of ART<br />

programs, though it is unclear by just how much. If we assume that ART programs depend on<br />

effective systems of record-keeping for their daily operations, and that in cooperation with SART<br />

and the CDC they have already adopted an IT-based reporting system, compliance with new<br />

reporting requirements is likely to cause only modest additional costs.<br />

352


13.8 Bibliography<br />

Afsah, Shakeb, and Jeffrey R. Vincent. "Putting Pressure on Polluters: Indonesia's Proper<br />

Program ": Harvard Institute for International Development, 1997.<br />

Beierle, Thomas C. "Environmental Information Disclosure: Three Cases of Policy and Politics."<br />

Washington, D.C.: Resources for the Future, 2003.<br />

Bernstein, Lisa. "Opting out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the<br />

Diamond Industry." Journal of Legal Studies 21, no. 1 (1992): 115-57.<br />

———. "Private Commercial Law in the Cotton Industry: Creating Cooperation through Rules,<br />

Norms and Institutions." Michigan Law Review 99 (2001): 1724-88.<br />

Burnum, John F. "Medical Practice a La Mode. How Medical Fashions Determine Medical<br />

Care." New England Journal of Medicine 317 (1987): 1220-22.<br />

Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. "2001 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success<br />

Rates: National Summary and Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for<br />

Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health,<br />

2003.<br />

———. "2002 Assisted Reproductive Technology Success Rates: National Summary and<br />

Fertility Clinic <strong>Report</strong>s." Atlanta, GA: National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention<br />

and Health Promotion, Division of Reproductive Health, 2004.<br />

———. "Survey of Assisted Reproductive Technology: Embryo Laboratory Procedures and<br />

Practices." Chamblee, GA: Public Health Practice Program Office, Division of<br />

Laboratory Systems, Laboratory Practice Assessment Branch, 1999.<br />

Chassin, Mark R., E. L. Hannan, and B. A. DeBuono. "Benefits and Hazards of <strong>Report</strong>ing<br />

Medical Outcomes Publicly." New England Journal of Medicine 334 (1996).<br />

Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research. Guidelines for Human<br />

Embryonic Stem Cell Research. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press, 2005.<br />

Cooter, Robert D. "Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach to<br />

Adjudicating the New Law Merchant." University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144, no.<br />

5 (1996): 1643-96.<br />

Cyranoski, David, and Erika Check. "Clone Star Admits Lies over Eggs." Nature 438, no. 7068<br />

(2005): 536-37.<br />

———. "Korean Stem-Cell Crisis Deepens." Nature 438, no. 7067 (2005): 405.<br />

Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. "Financial Incentives in<br />

Recruitment of Oocyte Donor." Fertility and Sterility 74, no. 2 (2000): 216-20.<br />

Furrow, Barry R. "Regulating the Managed Care Revolution: Private Accreditation and a New<br />

System Ethos." Villanova Law Review 43 (1998): 361-407.<br />

Gawande, Atul. Complications: Decisions and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life. London: Profile<br />

Books, 2002.<br />

Grimes, David A. "Technology Follies: The Uncritical Acceptance of Medical Innovation."<br />

Journal of the American Medical Association 269 (1993): 3030-33.<br />

Hannan, Edward L., H. Jr. Kilburn, M. Racz, E. Schields, and Mark R. Chassin. "Improving the<br />

Outcomes of Coronary Artery Bypass Surgery in New York State." Journal of the<br />

American Medical Association 271, no. 10 (1994): 761-66.<br />

Harding, Anne. Harvard Has Human Cloning Plans. Institute Seeks Nod to Create Embryos<br />

Using Genes from Patients with Diabetes, Parkinson's The Scientist, October 15, 2004<br />

353


[cited September 20, 2005]. Available from<br />

http://www.biomedcentral.com/news/20041015/03.<br />

Hayek, Friedrich A. Individualism and Economic Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,<br />

1976.<br />

———. The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism, The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek. Vol. 1.<br />

London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1988.<br />

Holden, Constance, Gretchen Vogel, and Dennis Normile. "Korean Cloner Admits Lying About<br />

Oocyte Donations." Science 310, no. 5753 (2005): 1402-03.<br />

Howard, Jennifer, Jennifer Nash, and John Ehrenfeld. "Standard or Smokescreen?<br />

Implementation of a Voluntary Environmental Code." California Management Review<br />

42, no. 2 (2000): 63-82.<br />

Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA). "HFEA Annual <strong>Report</strong> 2003/04."<br />

London, 2004.<br />

———. "Ninth Annual <strong>Report</strong> and Accounts 2000." London, 2000.<br />

Institute of Medicine. To Err Is Human: Building a Safer Health System. Washington, D.C.:<br />

National Academy Press, 2000.<br />

Karkkainen, Bradley C. "Information as Environmental Regulation: TRI and Performance<br />

Benchmarking, Precursor to a New Paradigm?" Georgetown Law Journal 89 (2001):<br />

257-370.<br />

Katz, Avery. "Taking Private Ordering Seriously." University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144,<br />

no. 5 (1996): 1745-63.<br />

King, Andrew A., and Michael J. Lenox. "Industry Self-Regulation without Sanctions: The<br />

Chemical Industry's Responsible Care Program." Academy of Management Journal 43,<br />

no. 4 (2000): 698-716.<br />

Kleindorfer, Paul R., and Eric W. Orts. "Information Regulation of Environmental Risks." Risk<br />

Analysis 18, no. 2 (1998): 155-69.<br />

Lipset, Seymour Martin. American Exceptionalism: A Double-Edged Sword. New York: W.W.<br />

Norton & Company, 1996.<br />

Olson, Mancur. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups.<br />

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965.<br />

Pierluissi, Edgar, Melissa A. Fischer, Andre R. Campbell, and C. Seth Landenfeld. "Discussion<br />

of Medical Error in Morbidity and Mortality Conferences." Journal of the American<br />

Medical Association 290, no. 21 (2003): 2838-42.<br />

Posner, Eric A. "The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Nonlegal Sanctions on<br />

Collective Action." University of Chicago Law Review 63 (1996): 133-97.<br />

Rees, Joseph V. Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety since Three<br />

Mile Island. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994.<br />

Regan, Alycia C. "Regulating the Business of Medicine: Models for Integrating Ethics and<br />

Managed Care." Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems 30 (1997): 635-83.<br />

Sage, William M. "Regulating through Information: Disclosure Laws and American Healthcare."<br />

Columbia Law Review 99 (1999): 1701-829.<br />

Salbu, Steven R. "Off-Label Use, Prescription, and Marketing of FDA-Approved Drugs: An<br />

Assessment of Legislative and Regulatory Policy." Florida Law Review 51 (1999): 181-<br />

227.<br />

354


Schneider, Eric C., and Arnold M. Epstein. "Influence of Cardiac-Surgery Performance <strong>Report</strong>s<br />

on Referral Practices and Access to Care." New England Journal of Medicine 335 (1996):<br />

251.<br />

Tietenberg, Tom, and David Wheeler. "Empowering the Community: Information Strategies for<br />

Pollution Control." Paper presented at the Frontiers of Environmental Economics<br />

Conference, Airlie House, VA, October 23-25, 1998.<br />

Touchette, Nancy. New Stem Cells Created for Research: Harvard Scientist Will Make 17 New<br />

Lines Available Genome News Network, March 3, 2004 [cited September 20, 2005].<br />

Available from http://www.genomenewsnetwork.org/articles/2004/03/03/stem_cells.php.<br />

U.S. Department of Commerce. "A Survey of the Use of Biotechnology in the U.S. Industry."<br />

Washington, D.C.: Technology Administration, Bureau of Industry and Security, 2003.<br />

West, Mark D. "Private Ordering at the World’s First Futures Exchange." Michigan Law Review<br />

98 (2000): 2574-615.<br />

355

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!