16.11.2012 Views

Sebastian Neubauer (Free University Berlin, Germany ... - jusmenacu

Sebastian Neubauer (Free University Berlin, Germany ... - jusmenacu

Sebastian Neubauer (Free University Berlin, Germany ... - jusmenacu

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Congreso Internacional<br />

“PODER SER DIFERENTE SIN TEMOR”:<br />

ANTISEMITISMO Y EXCLUSIÓN,<br />

AYER Y HOY<br />

7-9 marzo 2012<br />

Proyecto de Investigación<br />

«Filosofía después del Holocausto:<br />

Vigencia de sus lógicas perversas»<br />

Centro de Ciencias Humanas y Sociales-CSIC<br />

(Madrid)<br />

<strong>Sebastian</strong> <strong>Neubauer</strong><br />

(<strong>Free</strong> <strong>University</strong> <strong>Berlin</strong>,<br />

<strong>Germany</strong>)<br />

sneu@zedat.fu-berlin.de<br />

International Congress<br />

“BEING DIFFERENT WITHOUT FEAR”:<br />

ANTISEMITISM AND EXCLUSION,<br />

THEN AND NOW<br />

March 7 to 9, 2012<br />

Research Project<br />

“Philosophy after the Holocaust:<br />

Validity of its Perverse Logics”<br />

Center for Human and Social Sciences-CSIC<br />

(Madrid)<br />

Elements of a Critical<br />

Theory of Zionism. The<br />

Jewish State, the<br />

disastrous history and the<br />

changing functionality of<br />

Antisemitism in the<br />

thought of Max<br />

Horkheimer<br />

Max Horkheimer‟s theory of Antisemitism, most notably expressed in the „Elements of a theory<br />

of Antisemitism‟ section of the „Dialectic of Enlightenment‟ (Horkheimer/Adorno 1988), has well<br />

made its way into academic discourse. The same is true for Horkheimer‟s - whose thought has<br />

often been understood as particularly Jewish Political Thought [Barboza 2009; Rosen 2009] -<br />

connected and constant attempt to analyze the role of Jews and Judaism in Continental<br />

Philosophy and History (Reichmann 1974). However, I intend to open up a radically different<br />

perspective on Horkheimer‟s Theory of Judaism and thereby on - the Functionality of - Anti-<br />

Semitism. My approach specifically grounds in Horkheimer‟s scattered, fragmentary and<br />

unfortunately often disregarded so called „Spätwerk’ - his later, mostly posthumously published<br />

writings from the period after his return to Frankfurt. In the following, I intend to show that<br />

Horkheimer‟s thought of this period is essentially guided by an implicit theory of Zionism - or<br />

rather, to speak in Horkheimer‟s own language, by „Elements of a Critical Theory of Zionism‟. I<br />

argue, that precisely Horkheimer‟s account of Zionism provides us with worthy and innovative<br />

insights into the internal dynamics of his late thought. Building on this, I further argue, that<br />

Horkheimer thereby provides us with an implicit theoretical approach to - the Functionality of -<br />

„Anti-Semitism‟ in socio-political modernity. Although there is a broad textual basis in the work of<br />

Horkheimer (Horkheimer 1960; 1967; 1968a; 1968b; 1969b; 1969c; 1970b; 1974; 1988a;


1988b; 1988c), the significance of the issue of Zionism and the Jewish State for the latter‟s<br />

thought has so far neither been acknowledged - let alone analyzed - by academic work on<br />

Horkheimer, nor is his voice to be encountered in contemporary critical discourses on Zionism<br />

(Brumlik 2007).<br />

In the following, I aim, first, to approach the late Horkheimer as a Jewish Political Thinker,<br />

thereby elaborating his „Elements of a Critical Theory of Zionism‟. Building on this, I intend,<br />

second, to highlight the significance and over-arching character of the account of Zionism for the<br />

internal dynamics of the late Horkheimer‟s thought. My goal is to show, how these „Elements‟ are<br />

essentially interwoven with Horkheimer‟s Philosophy of History, his analysis of the (back then)<br />

contemporary socio-political world and of utmost importance his conception of Critical Theory as<br />

such. Thereby I argue, Horkheimer‟s so far disregarded account of Zionism can serve as a foil, a<br />

prism, for re-sorting and re-understanding his late thought. By following this line of argument, I<br />

finally argue, that in the last instance Horkheimer‟s account of Zionism bridges into a significantly<br />

re-shaped theory of „Anti-Semitism‟. Thereby, I hope to demonstrate that in the advent of Zionism<br />

the notion of „Functionality‟ radically changes, as Horkheimer leaves the Jews behind. Thus, we<br />

can understand from Horkheimer‟s argument that the „anti-Semitic‟ logic of identity and violence<br />

becomes the sole and entire logic of the perpetuated „disastrous history‟ itself.<br />

First: Horkheimer’s Elements of a Critical Theory of Zionism<br />

It is well known, that Horkheimer‟s life and thought was highly influenced by his personal and<br />

philosophical background in Judaism (Altwickler 2009; Baboza 2009; Ehrlich 2009: Reichmann<br />

2004). A fact that is, of course, more true for his last two decades, than for his previous life. Max<br />

Horkheimer conceived his particularly Jewish identity throughout his entire life as crucial<br />

(Horkheimer 1970b). Accordingly, his biographer Zvi Rosen has shown that Horkheimer‟s<br />

philosophical work in general has been influenced by two major sources: The „German tradition‟<br />

on the one hand and the „Jewish tradition‟ on the other hand (Rosen 2006: 36ff.).<br />

For Horkheimer himself, being Jewish essentially meant to live „in der Erwartung, dass es<br />

einmal in der Welt noch gut wird“ 1 (Horkheimer 1968a: 210). This expectation, which he himself<br />

traced back to his own personal and philosophical Jewish background, is - of course - deeply<br />

reflected throughout his Philosophy. Since Critical Theory - being decisively understood as the<br />

critique of the existing conditions of life - gains, in the last instance, its validity from the<br />

imagination that one day the world could change towards the better, that there might be<br />

something radically „other to-come‟. Therefore, this „other‟, Horkheimer used to call it „das ganz<br />

Andere” 2 (1977b), has to be understood as the utmost core of Horkheimer‟s over-all thought.<br />

This „other‟ is conceived by Horkheimer as being expressed by a number of traits of the Jewish<br />

tradition, which he therefore describes as a “geistige Realität” (Horkheimer 1988c: 331), a<br />

“spiritual reality”. Of particular importance among these traits is the Jewish focus on this world<br />

only as well as the connected Jewish concept of Messianism. Since Judaism does, as Horkheimer<br />

argues, „not know an afterlife“ (Horkheimer 1968a: 210), it aims solely to improve this life,<br />

meaning the life of the entire Jewry and of the generations to-come (1988c: 401/402). This focus<br />

on this world gains, in Horkheimer‟s thought, its particular importance in its connection with the<br />

Jewish conception of Messianism. Horkheimer interprets the latter as expressing the general<br />

quality of „the other to-come‟, which should be, according to the Jewish logic, not be restricted to<br />

1 In the expectation, that the world might one day change towards the better.<br />

2 The radical other.


the Jewish people, but expanded to the entire humanity itself: „Ihr Messias soll nicht nur Israel,<br />

sondern alle Völker erlösen.“ 3 (1988c: 410)<br />

Interestingly enough, Horkheimer conceives this fundamental imagination of the „other‟, the<br />

„spirtiual reality‟ of Judaism as being socially sublated and materialized in the Jewish diaspora.<br />

This „other‟ is, according to Horkheimer, real, since it has its social and historical space in the<br />

material existence of the Jewish diaspora. This interconnection grounds, for Horkheimer, in the<br />

very special social situation of the European Jewry. Horkheimer argues that the eternal suffering<br />

und the never-ending threat the European Jews were exposed to, resulted in a social maintenance<br />

of this „other‟, which itself derives from the Jewish tradition as such:<br />

“Durch Jahrtausende haben die Juden in den Verfolgungen um der Gerechtigkeit willen<br />

zusammengehalten. Ihre Riten [...] waren Momente des Zusammenhalts, der Kontinuität.<br />

Kein Machtstaat, sondern die Hoffnung auf Gerechtigkeit am Ende der Welt hieß<br />

Judentum. Sie waren ein Volk und das Gegenteil, der Vorwurf aller Völker.“ 4 (1974: 369)<br />

This notion of the Jewish diaspora gains, according to Horkheimer, its crucial historical<br />

momentum, after the international workers movement, which had also aimed such a change<br />

towards the „other‟, has been fallen apart. After the historical defeat of the international workers<br />

movement, in Horkheimer‟s view, the Jewish diaspora appears as the last remnant of the „other‟<br />

within the disastrous history. Thus, the diaspora occupies, in Horkheimer‟s thought, the historical<br />

space of the last weak and vulnerable but nevertheless remaining anti-dote to the disastrous<br />

dialectic of history: „Selbst die Vorstellung der Möglichkeit dieses ‚Anderen„ verschwindet 5 “<br />

(1970b: 433).<br />

In the given context it is of particular interest, that Horkheimer blames the historic defeat of<br />

the workers movement on a fact, which he calls „Marx hat die Juden verraten“ 6 (1988b: 351).<br />

Thereby, Horkheimer argues, that Marx‟ Philosophy had failed to expand the ‚spiritual reality„ of<br />

Judaism on the entire society, since it narrowed the general solidarity on the particularity of the<br />

proletariat, subsequently causing the historic defeat of the workers movement.<br />

At this point it should be clear that Judaism conceived as a „spiritual reality‟ sublating „the<br />

other to-come‟ is truly essential for the thought of the late Horkheimer. However, regarding the<br />

fact that Horkheimer connects, as I indicated, this notion of Judaism very strongly to the material<br />

existence of the diaspora, the question opens up, how the advent of Zionism and the Creation of<br />

the State of Israel, which aims per definition for the negation of the diaspora, intervenes into this<br />

line of thought?<br />

First of all, it is very noteworthy that Horkheimer, who has been very much engaged for the<br />

sake of diasporic Judaism, both in the US and in post-war <strong>Germany</strong>, has been, from the very<br />

beginnings on, somewhat distanced towards Zionism and Zionist Organizations. Despite their<br />

high influence in pre-war <strong>Germany</strong>, Horkheimer has, as far as we know, never been in touch with<br />

Zionist youth movements. Furthermore, Horkheimer‟s focus on the diaspora is demonstrated by<br />

the fact, that as early as in 1944 Horkheimer started to worry that within the American Public,<br />

Judaism could become identified with Zionism. This, of course was the Zionists political goal,<br />

whereas Horkheimer feared that precisely these Zionist Politics could contribute to „anti-Semitic‟<br />

resentments within the American Public and weakening the position of the diaspora (Jay 1976:<br />

3 The Jewish Messiah shall redeem not only the people of Israel, but all people of the world.<br />

4 Throughout millennia, the Jews have resisted their persecution for the sake of Justice. Their religious rites […]<br />

were moments of community, of continuity. Not a nation-state based on power, but the desire for justice at the end of<br />

the world was called Judaism. They were a people and its opposite, the accusation of all people.<br />

5 Even the mere imagination of the possibility of this other tends to disappear.<br />

6 Marx betrayed the Jews.


393). This issue was apparently of such crucial importance for Horkheimer, that he intended to<br />

conduct broad sociological research on it. However, the planned project, never materialized due to<br />

a lack of financial means and the changing political situation after the end of the World War<br />

(Rabinbach 2009: 253).<br />

This Horkheimerian particular focus on the diaspora is underlined by the fact that within his<br />

broad correspondence, Horkheimer does not devote a single word to the foundation of the State of<br />

Israel in 1948. However, from the 1950s on we can observe a radical change in Horkheimer‟s<br />

attention. This shift grounds, for my understanding, first, on the fact that Horkheimer started to<br />

realize that the Zionist enterprise succeeds and that it will therefore have a significant impact on<br />

the crucial diaspora, and, second, on the fact that the young state of Israel appeared to be<br />

vulnerably caught in a very precarious political situation. Thus, we can find from this point on,<br />

within the work of Horkheimer, a very strong publicly displayed political solidarity with Israel as<br />

well as a highly critical theorization of the Zionist enterprise, which he kept for the very same<br />

political reasons privately.<br />

Starting with Horkheimer‟s political solidarity, we can conclude that Horkheimer, who himself<br />

never travelled to Israel, displayed this strong political solidarity since the Jewish state provided a<br />

safe haven for endangered Jewish individuals. For instance, Horkheimer himself told in a late<br />

interview: „Man hat daher Israel zu bejahen. Für mich ist entscheidend: Israel ist das Asyl für viele<br />

Menschen.“ 7 (1970b: 398) Horkheimer‟s political solidarity with Israel was further bolstered, since<br />

the Jewish State was a very small and, thus, powerless political entity, which could, as Horkheimer<br />

apparently thought, easily sink in the modern „ocean of violence“ (1968c: 19).<br />

However, underneath this publicly displayed political solidarity, Horkheimer developed from<br />

the 1950s on a very unique and powerful dialectical criticism of the Zionist enterprise, which<br />

should, as I argue, finally essentially re-shape his entire thought. These „Elements of a Critical<br />

Theory of Zionism‟ are very much connected to the core position, outlined above, which<br />

Horkheimer attributes to diasporic Judaism conceived as a „spiritual reality‟ sublating the historical<br />

possibility for „the other to-come‟. Therefore, at the bottom-line of Horkheimer‟s critique of<br />

Zionism appears the argument, that the success of the Zionist movement equals the autoliquidation<br />

of the diaspora and, thus, of the „spiritual reality‟ Judaism:<br />

„Das Symbol der Krise, in der das Judentum heute sich befindet, ist die durch<br />

Verfolgungen bedingte Entstehung Israels, die Rettung jüdischer Menschen, die, nicht<br />

unwahrscheinlich, das Ende des Judentums im geistigen Sinn vorhersehen läßt. Eine<br />

schlechte, aber für die Gegenwart kennzeichnende Dialektik.“ (1985-1996, Band 18:<br />

643) 8<br />

In this line of argument, Horkheimer stresses that the dissolution of Judaism into a Nation<br />

equals the transformation of the power-less into competitors on power. However, according to<br />

Horkheimer, the „spiritual reality‟ materialized in the diaspora, precisely since the Jews were<br />

power-less. Thus, the diasporic Jews could be the historical representatives of „the other to-come‟.<br />

However, by the advent of Zionism, this social position and thus the historical possibility of the<br />

„other‟ appears as being destructed forever:<br />

„Das jüdische Volk war nicht nationalistisch, es trug seine Leiden für die Menschheit. Israel<br />

hingegen ist eine Nation geworden, im Grunde strukturiert wie jede andere, und der<br />

7 We do have to support Israel. For me personally it is crucial, that Israel provides asylum for many individuals.<br />

8 The creation of Israel, which took place due to the persecution and in order to rescue Jewish individuals, is the<br />

symbol of the current crisis of Judaism. However, this crisis points towards the end of the „spiritual reality‟ of Judaism.<br />

It is a worse dialectic, nevertheless characteristic for our age


ursprüngliche messianische Gedanke hat der Selbsterhaltung der eigenen nationalen<br />

Existenz weichen müssen.“ 9 (1988c: 326)<br />

In a note entitled ‚Staat Israel„ Horkheimer further states:<br />

„Jetzt beansprucht ein Staat, fürs Judentum zu sprechen, das Judentum zu sein. Das<br />

jüdische Volk, an dem das Unrecht aller Völker zur Anklage geworden, ist […] nun selber<br />

positiv geworden. Nation unter Nationen, Soldaten, Führer, money-raisers für sich selbst.<br />

[...] Wie hat es [das Judentum] doch im Triumph seines zeitlichen Erfolges im Grunde<br />

resigniert! Es bezahlt sein Fortbestehen mit dem Tribut ans Gesetz der Welt, wie sie ist.<br />

Wenn es auch Hebräisch zur Sprache hat, es ist die des Erfolges, nicht die der Propheten.<br />

Es hat sich dem Zustand der Welt assimiliert. Wer von Schuld sich frei weiß, werfe den<br />

ersten Stein. Nur - es ist schade, durch solchen Verzicht kommt eben das aus der Welt,<br />

was sich durch ihn erhalten sollte.“ 10 (1974: 369)<br />

According, to this harsh critique of Zionism, Horkheimer polemically writes about modern<br />

Jewry: „Die modernen Juden haben das Höhere aufgegeben, um das Niedere zu akzeptieren.“ 11<br />

(1988c: 332). The force of Horkheimer‟s critique of Zionism is probably most noteworthy<br />

displayed in the following passage of an early draft of ‚Zur Ergreifung Eichmanns„, which was later<br />

removed from the final version due to Adorno‟s intervention:<br />

„Was immer Eichmann in Israel geschehen wird, beweist die Ohnmacht, nicht die Macht<br />

der ihrer selbst und ihres Rechts bewussten Juden, die Anmaßung, nicht die Gewohnheit<br />

der staatlichen Autorität in Israel. Jeder weiß, dass man die totalitären Allüren, die an<br />

Benito und die Russen gemahnen, den Israelis im Hinblick auf New York noch einmal<br />

hingehen ließ.“ 12 (1974: 348)<br />

From these words, explicitly comparing the State of Israel with Stalin‟s totalitarian Sowjet<br />

Union and Mussolini‟s Italy, we can understand, that Horkheimer was truly and deeply concerned<br />

with the Zionist enterprise and its success.<br />

Before I go on to examine these concerns, it has to be added, that Horkheimer, of course,<br />

thinks the issue of Zionism dialectically. In his view, not the Jews are to be blamed for the fatal<br />

transformation of the diaspora, which sublated the „other‟, into a Nation-State which becomes like<br />

everything else and thus annihilates the last remaining historical possibility of the „other‟. To the<br />

contrary, Horkheimer perceives the creation of the Jewish State as a result of the disastrous history<br />

itself, as being without alternative in order to provide a safe haven for persecuted Jewish<br />

individuals:<br />

9 The Jewish people were not nationalistic at all, they were suffering for the sake of all Humanity. Israel, to the<br />

contrary, is a nation-state, at its basis structured like all others. Thus, the original messianic thought had to vanish for<br />

the sake of national existence.<br />

10 In nowadays a State claims to speak for Judaism, to be itself Judaism. The Jewish people, who used to be the<br />

accusation of all people, have themselves become positive. Nation among nations, soliders, leaders, money-raisers for<br />

themselves. […] How has Judaism, in fact, resigned in the face of its temporal triumph! Judaism pays for its ongoing<br />

existence by accommodating to the world as it is. Although Hebrew is the language of Israel, it is the language of<br />

success and not the language of the prophets. Judaism has itself assimilated to the existing state of the world. The one<br />

who is free of guilt, shall throw the first rock. Just, it is sad, since by means of this sacrifice, the other vanishes from<br />

the world, which actually should be preserved through it.<br />

11 The modern Jews gave up the better, the other, in order to accept the existing, the worse.<br />

12 Whatever will happen to Eichmann in Israel, it demonstrates the lack of power and not the power of the selfconscious<br />

Jews. It demonstrates the pretension and not the practice of the authority of the State of Israel. Everyone<br />

knows that Israel‟s totalitarian affectations, which recall Benito and the Russians, were tolerated this time only with<br />

respect to New York.


„Um sich zu retten hatten sie die Alternative, ihren Gott zu verleugnen oder sich als Staat<br />

zu konstituieren. Beides bedeutet den Untergang des Judentums: das erste das<br />

Verschwinden aus der Welt, das zweite den Umschlag in den unvermeidlichen<br />

Nationalismus der anderen: Israel.“ 13 (1988b: 314)<br />

Second: The account of Zionism as a prism for understanding the thought of the late<br />

Horkheimer<br />

Building on the outlined Horkheimerian view, that the success of the Zionist enterprise equals<br />

the liquidation of Judaism as „spiritual reality‟ and thus of the last remnant of the „other‟ in the<br />

disastrous history, I would like to explore in the following the far-reaching consequences of this<br />

argument for Horkheimer‟s over-all thought, before focusing in the last section of my presentation<br />

on the issue of „Anti-Semitism‟.<br />

Very basically, Horkheimer conceived the fatal but nevertheless alternative-less success of the<br />

Zionist enterprise as the disastrous history coming to itself, as the closing point for the possibility<br />

to transform the ever-ongoing pre-history into real history. Thus, the materialization of Zionism in<br />

the shape of the Jewish State necessarily appears, in Horkheimer, as the eternal perpetuation of the<br />

„disastrous history‟, and is therefore characterized as the “darkest aspect of all history”: „Es ist der<br />

trübste Aspekt der Geschichte, […] der trübste sowohl für das Judentum wie für Europa, dass der<br />

Zionismus recht behielt.“ 14 (1961a: 166/167)<br />

This tragic but unavoidable loss of the social and historical possibility of the „other‟, the better,<br />

has, in Horkheimer‟s view, far reaching consequences for the possibility of Philosophy and of<br />

Critical Theory in general. If we recall, that Horkheimer conceives the imagination of the „other‟,<br />

the better as the core of all Philosophy, as providing, in the last instance, validity to the entire<br />

project, we can imagine the consequences that he perceives in facing this fatal tragedy, called the<br />

success of Zionism. In a note entitled „Ausgeträumt„, Horkheimer expresses in a very condensed<br />

way his view on the interconnection of Judaism, the disastrous history, the success of Zionism and<br />

the consequences of this entire historical development for the possibility of Critical Theory, of<br />

Philosophy as such:<br />

„Der Traum vom Messias, des Anbruchs der Gerechtigkeit auf Erden, der in der Diaspora<br />

die Juden zusammenhält, ist ausgeträumt. Er hat unendlich viele Märtyrer gefunden,<br />

unendliches Leid verursacht und Hoffnung gewährt. Jetzt sind die Verfolgten ohne Messias<br />

nach Zion gezogen, haben wie andere Völker ihre Nation und ihren Nationalismus<br />

etabliert, und das Judentum wurde zur bloßen Religion. Die in der Diaspora verbleiben,<br />

können sich entscheiden; sei es für Israel, für die Auflösung in der Nation […] oder sie<br />

müssen als Juden provinziell werden, romantische Sektierer ohne geschichtliche Substanz.<br />

Die Diaspora ist eine Hinterwelt. Die Juden sind Überbleibsel. [...] Wer an die kritische<br />

Theorie sich hält, kann für eine […] Form des Nationalismus sich entscheiden, den<br />

sogenannten kommunistischen […], oder provinziell werden, romantischer Sektierer. Das<br />

Reich der Freiheit ist eine Hinterwelt. Die zur Theorie halten, sind Überbleibsel wie die<br />

Getreuen des Talmud und des messianischen Vertrauens.“ 15 (1974: 392)<br />

13 In order to rescue themselves, they had the alternative either to repudiate their God or to become a Nationstate.<br />

Both means the decay of Judaism: The former vanishing from the world, the latter the unavoidable<br />

transformation into Nationalism: Israel.<br />

14 It is the darkest aspect of all history, the darkest for both Judaism and Europe, that Zionism was proven to be<br />

right.<br />

15 The dream of the Messiah, of eternal justice on earth, which had given community to the Jews in the diaspora,<br />

has come to an end. This dream has led to uncounted numbers of martyrs, it had caused eternal suffering and at the<br />

same time given eternal hope. Now the persecuted went to Zion without Messiah. They have established their Nation<br />

and their Nationalism like all other people, whereas Judaism itself degraded to be a mere religion. The ones, who


If we pay close attention to these few sentences, we may recognize something truly remarkable.<br />

Horkheimer argues that in the Zionist age, of course, promoted by the disastrous history itself,<br />

Critical Theory, Philosophy in general becomes “backwardness”, loses its connection to History, its<br />

social space, and therefore its over-all social meaning. For Horkheimer, in the Zionist age, the<br />

Critical Theorists become ‚romantic sectarians„. Their time has forever passed, since with the<br />

diaspora also the social space, the historical sublation of the imagination and thus the historical<br />

possibility of the „other‟ has forever vanished.<br />

Facing this general loss of possibility, of social meaning, Horkheimer‟s critique of Zionism<br />

transforms itself into a critique of mourning, which again transforms the position of Critical<br />

Theorists in the light of the inevitable triumph of Zionism into a position of, speaking polemically,<br />

professional mourning:<br />

„Dem kann ich nicht widersprechen, aber auch der Trauer mich nicht erwehren, dass es der<br />

Wiederholung des Zugs ins Heilige Land ohne den Anbruch der richtigen Zeit bedurfte.“ 16<br />

(Horkheimer 1974: 380/381)<br />

Third: A theory of the (Functionality) of Anti-Semitism in the Zionist Age<br />

So far, I have highlighted the over-arching position of the issue of Zionism for the thought of<br />

late Horkheimer as well as Zionism‟s manifold implications for understanding core topics of his<br />

work. Although, this field is still open for further research, I indicated that Horkheimer‟s<br />

reflections on Zionism may serve as a prism for reading and re-acquiring his scattered and,<br />

unfortunately, often disregarded „Spätwerk‟. However, in the given context the implications of<br />

Horkheimer‟s account of Zionism are particularly striking regarding the theory of Anti-Semitism<br />

and the latter‟s functionality. Accordingly, I would like to, first, explore what, according to<br />

Horkheimer, „Anti-Semitism‟ could mean after the historical disappearance of Judaism and,<br />

second, I would like to outline a Horkheimerian theory of „Anti-Semitism‟ in the Zionist age.<br />

Of course, also in Horkheimer‟s thought, „Anti-Semitism‟ is not necessarily connected to the<br />

meaning of Judaism as such. However, in a late note entitled „Zum Antisemitismus‟, Horkheimer<br />

argues that the Jews of the diaspora became the object of hate and persecution, since they were the<br />

physical representatives of the „other‟, the „better‟. He writes, that the Jews„ mere existance is “ein<br />

Stein des Anstoßes [weil] sie sich dem Absoluten nicht in toto unterwerfen.“ 17 While being<br />

exposed to all this persecution, the Jews - recurring to their tradition - reacted without power by<br />

preserving the „other‟, the better, among their own threatened community. This Horkheimerian<br />

view may rightly be called romantic. Nevertheless, in Horkheimer‟s thought, the outlined<br />

„dialectic‟ maintained throughout history the social and historical possibility of the „other to-come‟.<br />

From this argument it is possible to deduce a double-fold „functionality‟ of „Anti-Semitism‟. On<br />

the one hand, its function appears to be as giving way to violent regression since Anti-Semitism is<br />

conceived as the „inverted‟ wish of the repressed individuals for change towards the „other‟. On the<br />

other hand, somewhat cynically, „Anti-Semitism‟ appears to be historically functional, since it,<br />

despite all involved cruelty, maintained a „dialectic‟ sublating and preserving the „other‟ within<br />

history and society.<br />

remain in the diaspora, can decide either for Israel, which means the dissolution into a nation, or they can maintain<br />

Judaism, which means becoming provincial, becoming romantic sectarians that lack historical substance. Today, the<br />

diaspora is backwardness. The Jews are remnants. The one who remains faithful in Critical Theory can opt for a way of<br />

nationalism, the so called communism or he can become provincial, a romantic sectarian. The realm of freedom has<br />

become backwardness. The ones, who remain faithful in Critical Theory, are last, out-dated, remnants like the faithful<br />

Jews.<br />

16 I have nothing to oppose, but I do have to mourn, that the repetition of the return to the holy land had taken<br />

place before its time had come.<br />

17 The thorn in our side, since they refuse to completely subjugate to the absolute.


However, in Horkheimer‟s view, precisely this „dialectic‟ comes with the advent of Zionism to a<br />

tragic end; by the destruction of the „diaspora‟ and its transformation into a power seeking<br />

Nationalism, this entire „dialectic‟ vanisehs forever. First of all, this historical movement comes<br />

down to the fact, that „conventional‟ Anti-Semitism, understood in the sense outlined above,<br />

vanishes, too. Since the „other‟ is no longer sublated within Judaism, Jews couldn‟t be hated any<br />

more for representing precisely this „other‟. However, social repression, the individuals „inverted‟<br />

wish for changing towards the „other‟, their hate on this „other‟, does not vanish with its historical<br />

possibility. To the contrary, if Zionism - the specific Jewish response to Anti-Semitism - appears as<br />

the „auto-liquidation‟ of Judaism and thereby as the eternal perpetuation of the disastrous history,<br />

the social hate on the „other‟, now including Jews as well, seems to be eternally perpetuated, too.<br />

Thus, I finally argue, that we can - if we pay attention to Horkheimer‟s „Elements of a Critical<br />

Theory of Zionism‟ - gain hold on the corner-stone of a theory of socio-political Modernity. We<br />

find here a theory of socio-political Modernity, in which „Anti-Semitism‟, the hate of the „other‟<br />

understood as the inverted wish to achieve it, is no longer functional. To the contrary, the entire<br />

world functions in the light of this - rather pessimistic - argument, so to speak, purely „anti-<br />

Semitic‟ - it is not only guided by logics of identity and violence, but in which the logics of identity<br />

and violence have become universal and, thus, reality itself. As late Horkheimer writes: „Der Gang<br />

der Geschichte tendiert auf automatische Reaktion, auf Uniformität, die über terroristische<br />

Perioden sich durchsetzen muss.“ 18 (1988a: 139)<br />

Bibliography<br />

Altwicker, Norbert 2009: Loeb-Lectures. Gastvorlesungen über Geschichte, Philosophie und<br />

Religion des Judentums an der Universität Frankfurt am Main 1956-1957, in: Boll/Gross<br />

2009: 158-161.<br />

Bayer, Oswald 1995: Die Furcht, dass es Gott nicht gebe. Zum Judentum in der Philosophie Max<br />

Horkheimers, in: Lucas, Franz D. (Hg): Geschichte und Geist. Fünf Essays zum<br />

Verständnis des Judentums. <strong>Berlin</strong>: Duncker und Humblot: 35-54.<br />

Barboza, Amalia 2009: Die ‚Jüdische Identität„ der Frankfurter Schule, in: Boll/Gross 2009: 162 -<br />

169<br />

Boll, Monika / Gross, Ralph 2009: Die Frankfurter Schule und Frankfurt. Eine Rückkehr nach<br />

Deutschland, Frankfurt am Main: Wallenstein.<br />

Brumlik, Micha 2007: Kritik des Zionismus, Hamburg: Europäische Verlagsanstalt.<br />

Ehrlich, Ernst Ludwig 2009: Von Hiob zu Horkheimer. Gesammelte Schriften zum Judentum und<br />

seiner Umwelt, <strong>Berlin</strong>: De Gruyter.<br />

Freimüller, Tobias 2009: Max Horkheimer und die jüdische Gemeinde Frankfurt am Main nach<br />

1945, in: Boll/Gross 2009: 150 - 157.<br />

Grigat, Stephan 2006a: Feindaufklärung und Reeducation. Kritische Theorie gegen Postnazismus<br />

und Islamismus, Freiburg: ca-ira.<br />

Grigat, Stephan 2006b: Befreite Gesellschaft und Israel. Zum Verhältnis von Kritischer Theorie<br />

und Zionismus, in Grigat 2006a: 115-129.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1917: Jochai, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 1: 264-272.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1935: Gedanke zur Religion, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 3: 326-<br />

328.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1939a: Die Juden und Europa, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 4: 308-<br />

331.<br />

18 The path of history tends towards automatic reaction, uniformity, which has to materialize through despotic<br />

periods.


Horkheimer, Max 1939b: Jüdischer Charakter, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 12: 263-<br />

264.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1944: Antisemitismus: Der soziologische Hintergrund des psychoanalytischen<br />

Forschungsansatzes, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 5: 364-372.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1945a: Zur Klassifikation jüdischer Einwanderer, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-<br />

1996, Band 5: 373-376.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1945b: Die Juden und der Eid, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 12:<br />

303-305.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1960: Zur Ergreifung Eichmanns, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 8:<br />

156-159.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1961a: Über die deutschen Juden, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 8:<br />

160-174.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1961b: Nachwort [zu Porträts deutsch-jüdischer Geistesgeschichte], in:<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 8: 175-193.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1967: „Liebe deinen Nächsten“ [Nach Gesprächen mit Dagobert Lindlau], in:<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 13: 183-187.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1968c: Vorwort, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985: 7-10.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1968a: Psalm 91, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 207-212.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1968b: Wahrheit im Denken. Aus einer theologischen Diskussion, in:<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 13: 101-107.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1968c: Vorwort zur Neupublikation, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 3:<br />

14-19.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1969a: Über den Zweifel, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 213-223.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1969b: „Himmel, Ewigkeit und Schönheit.“ Interview zum Tode Theodor W.<br />

Adornos, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 291-296.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1969c: Dokumente - Stationen [Gespräch mit Otmar Hersche], in:<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 317- 344.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1970: „Was wir ‚Sinn„ nennen, wird verschwinden.“ [Gespräch mit Georg<br />

Wolff und Helmut Gumnior], in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 345-357.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1970b: Die Sehnsucht nach dem ganz Anderen [Gespräch mit Helmut<br />

Gumnior], in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 7: 385-404.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1974: Notizen 1949 - 1969, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996, Band 6: 189-<br />

424.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996: Gesammelte Schriften, 19 Bände, Frankfurt a. Main: Fischer.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1988a: Nachgelassene Notizen 1949 - 1969, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-1996,<br />

Band 14: 33-144.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1988b: Verstreute Aufzeichnungen 1950 - 1971, in: Horkheimer, Max 1985-<br />

1996, Band 14: 145-170.<br />

Horkheimer, Max 1988c: Späne. Notizen über Gespräche mit Max Horkheimer, in<br />

unverbindlicher Formulierung aufgeschrieben von Friedrich Pollock, in: Horkheimer, Max<br />

1985-1996, Band 14: 172-548.<br />

Horkheimer, Max / Adorno, Theodor W. 1988: Dialektik der Aufklärung. Philosophische<br />

Fragmente, Frankfurt a. Main: Fischer.<br />

Horkheimer, Max / Adorno, Theodor W.2006: Briefwechsel 1927 - 1969, Band IV: 1950-1969,<br />

Frankfurt a. Main: Suhrkamp.<br />

Jay, Martin 1976: Dialektische Phantasie. Die Geschichte der Frankfurter Schule und des Instituts<br />

für Sozialforschung 1923 1950. Frankfurt a. Main: Fischer.<br />

Löwenthal, Leo 1980: Mitmachen wollte ich nie. Ein autobiographisches Gespräch mit Helmut<br />

Dubiel, Frankfurt a. Main: Suhrkamp.<br />

Maier, Joseph 1986: Jüdisches Erbe aus deutschem Geist, In: Schmidt / Altwickler 1986: 146 -<br />

162.


Maor, Maimon 1981: Max Horkheimer, <strong>Berlin</strong>: Colloquium.<br />

Marcus, Judith / Tar, Zoltan 1986: The Judaic Element in the Teachings of the Frankfurt School,<br />

In: The Leo Baeck Institute Yearbook 31(1): 339-353.<br />

Pangritz, Andreas 1992: Vom kleiner- und unischtbarwerden der Theologie. Ein Versuch über das<br />

Projekt einer ‚impliziten Theologie‟ bei Barth, Tillich, Bonhoeffer, Benjamin, Horkheimer<br />

und Adorno. <strong>Berlin</strong>: Freie Universität, Habilitationsschrift.<br />

Rabinbach, Anson: Israel, die Diaspora und das Bilderverbot in der kritischen Theorie, in:<br />

Boll/Gross 2009: 251-263.<br />

Reichmann, Eva G. 1974: Max Horkheimer the Jew: Critical Theory and Beyond, In: The Leo<br />

Baeck Institute Yearbook 19(1): 181-195<br />

Rosen, Zvi 1995: Max Horkheimer, München: Beck.<br />

Rosen, Zvi 2006: Interkulturalität im Denken Max Horkheimers, Nordhausen: Traugott Bautz.<br />

Rosen, Zvi 2009: Über die gesellschaftliche Rolle des Judentums, in: Boll / Gross 2009: 128 - 135.<br />

Schmidt, Alfred / Altwickler, Norbert (Hrsg.) 1986: Max Horkheimer heute: Werk und Wirkung.<br />

Frankfurt a. Main: Fischer.<br />

Schmidt, Alfred 2009: Fortschritt, Skepsis und Hoffnung. Kategorien in der<br />

Geschichtsphilosophie Max Horkheimers, In: Boll / Gross 2009: 96-107<br />

Wegerich, Ulrich 1994: Dialektische Theorie und historische Erfahrung. Zur<br />

Geschichtsphilosophie in der frühen kritischen Theorie Max Horkheimers, Würzburg:<br />

Königshausen & Neumann.<br />

Wiggershaus, Rolf 1988: Die Frankfurter Schule. Geschichte, Theoretische Entwicklung,<br />

Politische Bedeutung, München: DTV.<br />

Wiggershaus, Rolf 1998: Max Horkheimer. Zur Einführung, Hamburg: Junius.<br />

Zuckermann, Moshe (Hg.) 2000a: Theodor W. Adorno - Philosoph des beschädigten Lebens,<br />

Göttingen: Wallstein.<br />

Zuckermann, Moshe 2000b: Kritische Theorie in Israel. Analyse einer Nichtrezeption. In:<br />

Zuckermann 2000a: 9 - 24.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!