26.06.2015 Views

A Uniform Theory of Conditionals: Beyond Stalnaker - Will Starr

A Uniform Theory of Conditionals: Beyond Stalnaker - Will Starr

A Uniform Theory of Conditionals: Beyond Stalnaker - Will Starr

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Outline<br />

A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> and <strong>Beyond</strong><br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong><br />

03.05.12<br />

1 <strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument<br />

2 Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

3 <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis<br />

4 A New Analysis<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 1/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 2/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The Direct Argument<br />

Conditional to Disjunction<br />

The Direct Argument (DA)<br />

Yet:<br />

1 It is uncontroversial that (2) follows from (1)<br />

(1) If the butler didn’t do it, the gardener did<br />

(2) Either the butler or the gardener did it<br />

2 But, (1) also seems to follow from (2)<br />

3 Then if A then B and not A or B are equivalent<br />

4 So indicative conditionals are material conditionals<br />

• Material conditional analysis <strong>of</strong> indicatives is terrible!<br />

• ¬φ φ ⊃ φ, ¬(φ ⊃ ψ) φ<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1975)<br />

<strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> and Response to Direct Argument<br />

• <strong>Stalnaker</strong>: the similarity analysis <strong>of</strong> subjunctive<br />

conditionals works for indicatives too<br />

• To make it work, he relies on some ideas about how<br />

context and inference work<br />

• Context: a set <strong>of</strong> possible worlds<br />

• Inference: needn’t always be captured semantically,<br />

sometimes it makes use <strong>of</strong> context<br />

• Call these reasonable inferences<br />

• Using these ideas he makes the similarity analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

indicative plausible<br />

• But he also responds to the direct argument:<br />

disjunctions do not entail indicative conditionals<br />

• Yet, it is <strong>of</strong>ten reasonable to infer one from the other<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 4/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 5/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on Context<br />

A Set <strong>of</strong> Possible Worlds c<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on Context and Assertion<br />

Shinking c<br />

• Context: the common assumptions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

conversational participants<br />

• This is information the speaker can expect her<br />

interlocutors to use to interpret her utterances<br />

• These assumptions needn’t be true, nor actual beliefs<br />

• This common information can be thought <strong>of</strong> as a set <strong>of</strong><br />

possible worlds<br />

• The set <strong>of</strong> worlds not ruled out by the common<br />

assumptions<br />

• The conversationally ‘live’ possibilities<br />

• Successful assertions change the shared assumptions <strong>of</strong><br />

the conversationalists<br />

• Therefore, they must change c too<br />

• How should we change c to reflect that a new<br />

proposition p has been accepted?<br />

• Eliminate all the worlds in c that incompatible with p:<br />

• c ′ = c ∩ p<br />

• This shrinks the set <strong>of</strong> live possibilities<br />

• <strong>Stalnaker</strong> calls this the context set c<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 6/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 7/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on Reasonable Inference<br />

Context Changes During an Inference<br />

• For A to semantically entail B:<br />

• Every world in which A is true, B must be true<br />

• But on <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s model <strong>of</strong> context, sometimes we<br />

ignore certain worlds<br />

• Worlds outside c<br />

• Sometimes A may not entail B but it may be<br />

reasonable to infer B from A in c<br />

Reasonable Inference<br />

The inference from A to B is reasonable in c iff<br />

c ′ = A c ∩ c, and c ′ ⊆ B c ′<br />

• The proposition expressed by A in c, together with c<br />

entails the proposition expressed by B in c ∩ A c<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

Overview and Semantics<br />

• <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s tact: give a semantics for (if φ) ψ that is<br />

plausible for both indicatives and subjunctives<br />

• Maintain that indicatives and subjunctives have<br />

identical semantics, but differ pragmatically<br />

Semantics for Both Varieties (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1968, 1975)<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true at w if and only if ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

φ-worlds most similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ f = {w | f(w, φ f ) ⊆ ψ f }<br />

• f(w, φ f ): the set <strong>of</strong> φ-worlds most similar to w<br />

• f obeys three constraints, e.g. f(w, p) ⊆ p<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 8/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 9/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

The Pragmatics <strong>of</strong> Indicatives<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on Disjunction<br />

Appropriateness Conditions<br />

Pragmatics for Indicatives (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1975: 69)<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true in c at w ∈ c iff:<br />

• ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds in c most similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ c,f = {w ∈ c | f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f }<br />

Appropriateness <strong>of</strong> Disjunctions (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1975: 71)<br />

• Disjunctive assertions appropriate only in a context<br />

where either disjunct to be true without the other<br />

• An assertion <strong>of</strong> A ∨ B is appropriate if<br />

• There is a A ∧ ¬B-world in c<br />

• There is a ¬A ∧ B-world in c<br />

• Suppose we’ve ruled out the possibility that the Butler<br />

did it and the gardener didn’t.<br />

(3) ?? Either the Butler did it, or the gardener did it.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 10/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 11/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The Direct Argument is Reasonable<br />

From Or to If<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reasonable Inference<br />

Further Applications<br />

• Suppose B ∨ G is felicitously asserted in c 0<br />

• Then there are B ∧ ¬G and ¬B ∧ G-worlds in c 0<br />

• All ¬B ∧ ¬G-worlds are eliminated in<br />

c 1 = c 0 ∩ B ∨ G c<br />

• The inference to (if ¬B) G will be reasonable if<br />

(4) c 1 ⊆ (if ¬B) G c1 ,f<br />

• (if ¬B) G c1 ,f = {w ∈ c 1 | f(w, ¬B c1 ,f ∩ c 1 ) ⊆ G c1 ,f}<br />

• By Success ∀w : f(w, ¬B c1 ,f ∩ c 1 ) ⊆ (¬B c1 ,f ∩ c 1 )<br />

• Since all <strong>of</strong> the ¬B-worlds in c 1 are G-worlds, this<br />

means that f(w, ¬B c1 ,f ∩ c 1 ) ⊆ G c1 ,f<br />

• So (if ¬B) G c1 ,f = c 1 !<br />

• Condition (4) holds so, the inference is reasonable!<br />

• <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s indicative semantics invalidates:<br />

Antecedent Strengthening A → B (A ∧ B) → C<br />

Disjunctive Antecedents<br />

(A ∨ B) → C (A → C) ∧ (B → C)<br />

Transitivity A → B, B → C A → C<br />

Contraposition A → B ¬B → ¬A<br />

• Yet they <strong>of</strong>ten sound plausible!<br />

• As it turns out, these are also reasonable inferences<br />

(w/a little tweaking)<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 12/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 13/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

Indicative and Subjunctive<br />

‘Indicative’ <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

(5) a. If Bob danced, Leland danced<br />

b. If Bob is dancing, Leland is dancing<br />

‘Subjunctive’ <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

Past (looking) antecedent + modal consequent<br />

(6) a. If Bob had danced, Leland would have danced<br />

b. If Bob had danced, Leland might have danced<br />

c. If Bob had danced, Leland could have danced<br />

d. If Bob danced, Leland would dance<br />

e. If Bob were to dance, Leland would dance<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

Felicitous After Denying Antecedent?<br />

(7) a. # Bob never danced. If Bob danced, Leland<br />

danced.<br />

b. # Bob isn’t dancing. If Bob is dancing, Leland is<br />

dancing.<br />

(8) a. Bob never danced. If Bob had danced, Leland<br />

would have danced.<br />

b. Bob never danced. If Bob had danced, Leland<br />

might have danced.<br />

Felicitous After Denying Antecedent?<br />

1 Indicative conditionals? ×<br />

2 Subjunctive conditionals? ̌<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 15/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 16/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

The Subjunctive Suggestion<br />

The Subjunctive Suggestion<br />

Assertions <strong>of</strong> if Bob had danced, Leland would have danced<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten suggest that Bob didn’t dance.<br />

• Evidence for the suggestion?<br />

• Infelicity <strong>of</strong> asserting that Bob did dance and then<br />

asserting the subjunctive conditional<br />

(9) # Bob definitely danced. If Bob had danced, Leland<br />

would have danced.<br />

• As discussed earlier in semester, this suggestion isn’t<br />

an entailment or presupposition<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

Ingredients <strong>of</strong> a Subjunctive Antecedent<br />

(10) a. If Bob had danced, Leland would have danced<br />

b. If Bob were to dance, Leland would dance<br />

c. If Bob danced, Leland would dance<br />

• Antecedents: past tense look, not past meaning<br />

(11) Bob died yesterday. If he had died tomorrow instead,<br />

he would have been 98 years old.<br />

• Not possible w/genuine past tense had died<br />

(12) Yesterday I went to the Black Lodge. By the time I<br />

got there, Bob had died, but Cooper hadn’t.<br />

(13) # I will go to the Black Lodge tomorrow. By the time<br />

I get there, Bob had died, but Cooper hadn’t.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 17/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 18/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

Ingredients <strong>of</strong> a Subjunctive Antecedent<br />

• Past tense does not contribute its normal meaning in<br />

subjunctive antecedents<br />

• This is not true for indicative antecedents<br />

(11) Bob died yesterday. If he had died tomorrow instead,<br />

he would have been 98 years old.<br />

{ }<br />

was<br />

(14) # If Bob died tomorrow, he<br />

98 years old<br />

will be<br />

• So we have one more difference between the two kinds<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

The Data So Far<br />

Felicitous After Denying Antecedent?<br />

1 Indicative conditionals? ×<br />

2 Subjunctive conditionals? ̌<br />

The Subjunctive Suggestion<br />

Assertions <strong>of</strong> if Bob had danced, Leland would have danced<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten suggest that Bob didn’t dance.<br />

• Suggestion not asserted, presupposed or entailed<br />

Subjunctive Antecedents and Past Tense<br />

Unlike indicative antecedents, subjunctive ones have past<br />

tense morphology that does not have past tense meaning.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 19/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 20/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction: in pictures<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1975: §3)<br />

1 Indicative conditionals concern only antecedent worlds<br />

within the live possibilities c, which represent what’s<br />

being taken for granted in the discourse.<br />

2 Subjunctive conditionals concern antecedent worlds<br />

that may not be among c, that is they may be<br />

counterfactual from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the discourse.<br />

As <strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1975: 69) puts it “the idea [for indicative<br />

conditionals] is that when a speaker says if A, then<br />

everything he is presupposing to hold in the actual<br />

situation is presupposed to hold in the hypothetical<br />

situation in which A is true.”<br />

Indicatives<br />

c<br />

antecedent<br />

Subjunctives<br />

c<br />

antecedent<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 21/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 22/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction and the Data<br />

Felicitous After Denying Antecedent?<br />

1 Indicative conditionals? ×<br />

2 Subjunctive conditionals? ̌<br />

• Since an indicative conditional says something about<br />

antecedent worlds in c, it makes sense for it to<br />

presuppose that there is at least one such world<br />

• After denying antecedent: no antecedent worlds in c<br />

• So indicative should be infelicitous<br />

• Subjunctive may reach outside c, so same reasoning<br />

does not apply to them<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction and the Data<br />

The Subjunctive Suggestion<br />

Assertions <strong>of</strong> if Bob had danced, Leland would have danced<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten suggest that Bob didn’t dance.<br />

• Suggestion not asserted, presupposed or entailed<br />

• Subjunctive allows antecedent worlds outside c, but<br />

indicative does not<br />

• Choosing the subjunctive over the indicative indicates<br />

that it is important that there are antecedent worlds<br />

outside c<br />

• One reason it may be important: antecedent is false<br />

• Suggestion results from strategic reasoning<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 23/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 24/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction and the Data<br />

Subjunctive Antecedents and Past Tense<br />

Unlike indicative antecedents, subjunctive ones have past<br />

tense morphology that does not have past tense meaning.<br />

Modal Hypothesis (Isard 1974; Lyons 1977; Iatridou 2000)<br />

1 Past tense in subjunctive antecedents serves a modal<br />

function rather than a temporal one: locates<br />

antecedent event among a set <strong>of</strong> possibilities that may<br />

contain counterfactual ones.<br />

2 Past tense morphology serves purely temporal function<br />

in indicative antecedents, so they remain concerned<br />

with the live contextual possibilities.<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Towards an Explanation<br />

Linguistic Encoding <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction<br />

• The Modal Hypothesis explains:<br />

1 Why fake past tense behavior correlates w/indicative<br />

vs. subjunctive<br />

2 How <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction is linguistically encoded<br />

• Suppose we follow the Modal Hypothesis<br />

• Then we should be able to take our indicative<br />

semantics for q if p and add modal operator to<br />

antecedent to get our semantics for subjunctives<br />

• Indicative: (if φ) ψ<br />

• Subjunctive: (if ✁φ) ψ<br />

• Bittner (2010: 2): subjunctives and indicatives in<br />

Kalaallisut are identical except that the former contain<br />

a modal particle in their antecedents and consequents<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 25/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 26/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

Overview and Semantics<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

The Pragmatics <strong>of</strong> Indicatives<br />

• <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s tact: give a semantics for (if φ) ψ that is<br />

plausible for both indicatives and subjunctives<br />

• Maintain that indicatives and subjunctives have<br />

identical semantics, but differ pragmatically<br />

Semantics for Both Varieties (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1968, 1975)<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true at w if and only if ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

φ-worlds most similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ f = {w | f(w, φ f ) ⊆ ψ f }<br />

• f(w, φ f ): the set <strong>of</strong> φ-worlds most similar to w<br />

• f obeys three constraints, e.g. f(w, p) ⊆ p<br />

Pragmatics for Indicatives (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 1975: 69)<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true in c at w iff:<br />

• If w ∈ c, ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds in c most<br />

similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ c,f = {w ∈ c | f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f }<br />

• Antecedent worlds f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) are all within c!<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 28/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 29/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Problem 1<br />

Worlds Outside c<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

The Pragmatics <strong>of</strong> Indicatives, Take 2<br />

(if φ) ψ c,f = {w ∈ c | f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f }<br />

• This analysis predicts that what we assert with<br />

indicative conditionals is false at every world outside c<br />

• So, suppose you rightly assert if the light in the next<br />

room is on, then it isn’t <strong>of</strong>f<br />

• But it turns out we were falsely assuming for the<br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> our conversation that time is absolute<br />

• Then the actual world isn’t in c<br />

• Then what you said is actually false!<br />

Pragmatics for Indicatives: a second chance?<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true in c at w iff:<br />

• ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds in c most similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ c,f = {w | f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f }<br />

• We’ve eliminated the restriction to worlds in c<br />

• Antecedent worlds f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) are all within c!<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 30/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 31/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Another Problem<br />

With Modus Ponens<br />

Problem: Modus Ponens for Indicative Assertions Goes Invalid<br />

• Let w /∈ c be a φ ∧ ¬ψ-world.<br />

• Let ψ be true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds in c most similar to<br />

w: f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f .<br />

• So the conditional proposition expressed is true at w,<br />

but w is a world where φ ∧ ¬ψ!<br />

• So the consequent doesn’t follow from the conditional<br />

and its antecedent.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 32/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

The Pragmatics <strong>of</strong> Indicatives<br />

Pragmatics for Indicatives: a third chance?<br />

1 (if φ) ψ is true in c at w iff:<br />

(i) If w ∈ c, ψ is true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds in c most<br />

similar to w<br />

(ii) If w /∈ c, ψ is simply true at all <strong>of</strong> the φ-worlds which<br />

are most similar to w<br />

2 (if φ) ψ c,f = {w | f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ⊆ ψ c,f if w ∈ c<br />

& f(w, φ c,f ) ⊆ ψ c,f if w /∈ c}<br />

• Antecedent worlds: f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ∪ f(w, φ c,f )<br />

• Maybe what <strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1975: 69) intended?<br />

• But: It would allow c (if φ) ψ c,f , but we needed<br />

this fact in <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s reply to the Direct Argument<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 33/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

More Definitions, More Problems<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction Violated<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction<br />

1 Indicative conditionals concern only antecedent worlds<br />

within the live possibilities c, which represent what’s<br />

being taken for granted in the discourse.<br />

Modified <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s (1975: 69) semantics and pragmatics:<br />

• Antecedent worlds: f(w, φ c,f ∩ c) ∪ f(w, φ c,f )<br />

• Not a subset <strong>of</strong> c! Only those in the left set are!<br />

• But then we have no account <strong>of</strong> the contrasts<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s distinction was supposed to explain!<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Another Problem for <strong>Stalnaker</strong> Analysis<br />

Incompatible with the Modal Hypothesis<br />

• The Modal Hypothesis explains:<br />

1 Why fake past tense parallels indicative/subjunctive<br />

2 How <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction is linguistically encoded<br />

• To get subjunctive semantics, take indicative semantics<br />

for q if p and add modal operator to antecedent<br />

• Indicative: (if φ) ψ, Subjunctive: (if ✁φ) ψ<br />

• (if φ) ψ limited to φ worlds in c<br />

• Semantics <strong>of</strong> ✁φ: allow φ worlds outside c<br />

• Not possible w/<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s semantics:<br />

• (if φ) ψ already allows φ worlds outside c, so that<br />

can’t be what ✁ is doing<br />

• So <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s analysis cannot enjoy the benefits <strong>of</strong><br />

endorsing the Modal Hypothesis<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 34/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 35/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

What is the Analysis Anyway?<br />

The Pragmatic Constraint? (<strong>Stalnaker</strong> 2005: n.13)<br />

Both kinds <strong>of</strong> conditionals. . . have the same abstract semantics, but a<br />

context-dependent parameter <strong>of</strong> the interpretation — the selection function — is<br />

differently constrained by the different grammatical constructions. So, on this<br />

theory, the difference between the two kinds <strong>of</strong> conditionals is a semantic<br />

difference in two different senses, but a purely pragmatic difference in a third<br />

sense. The difference is semantic, first in the sense that there will normally be a<br />

difference in the proposition expressed by the contrasting conditional sentences,<br />

even when uttered in similar situations. And it is semantic also in the sense that<br />

the difference is marked by a conventional linguistic device (the<br />

tense/aspect/mood difference). But the distinction is pragmatic in that the device<br />

works by the way it constrains features <strong>of</strong> the context. The semantic rule that<br />

gives the truth conditions <strong>of</strong> the conditional as a function <strong>of</strong> the contextual<br />

parameter will be the same for both kinds <strong>of</strong> conditionals.<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s <strong>Uniform</strong> Analysis<br />

Summary<br />

1 Either gives bad truth-conditions, invalidates modus<br />

ponens or doesn’t embody <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction<br />

• But we would like a theory that does embody that<br />

distinction!<br />

2 When modified to embody <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction, MP<br />

is violated<br />

3 Incompatible with attractive hypothesis about how<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction is linguistically encoded<br />

• Fails entirely to explain correlation between fake past<br />

tense and indicative/subjunctive behavior<br />

4 Way forward: (if φ) ψ limited to φ worlds in c, but ✁φ<br />

allows φ worlds outside c in (if ✁φ) ψ<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 36/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 37/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Information Change and Semantics<br />

Two Views<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Information<br />

The Convenient Model Meets a Different Kind <strong>of</strong> Semantics<br />

• Everybody agrees that conversation takes place against<br />

an ever-changing background <strong>of</strong> information<br />

• Call it c for the contextual possibilities/info<br />

• Classic models: <strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1978), Lewis (1979)<br />

Classical Picture Semantics delivers propositions and<br />

pragmatics provides rules for changing<br />

background information (<strong>Stalnaker</strong>)<br />

Dynamic Picture Semantics operates directly on background<br />

information<br />

In Short: meaning is information vs. meaning is<br />

information change potential<br />

Informational Dynamic Semantics<br />

1 Assign each φ a function [φ] characterizing how it<br />

changes the information embodied by c: c[φ] = c ′<br />

2 Think <strong>of</strong> this information as a way <strong>of</strong> tracking the<br />

agent’s current state <strong>of</strong> mind<br />

3 [φ] is the characteristic role that φ plays in changing<br />

an agent’s mental states<br />

Formal Inspirations: Pratt (1976); Heim (1982); Veltman (1996)<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 39/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 41/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Informational Dynamic Semantics<br />

For Epistemic Might (Veltman 1996)<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Informational Dynamic Semantics<br />

For Epistemic Might (Veltman 1996)<br />

• c[Might(Cube)] = {w ∈ c | c[Cube] ≠ ∅} ‘Test’<br />

= c or ∅<br />

• c = {w 1 , w 4 }[Might(Cube)] = ?<br />

• {w 1 , w 4 }[Cube] =<br />

• c[Might(Cube)] = {w ∈ c | c[Cube] ≠ ∅}<br />

• c = {w 1 , w 4 }[Might(Cube)] = ?<br />

• {w 1 , w 4 }[Cube] = {w 1 } ≠ ∅<br />

w 1 w 4<br />

w 1<br />

c<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 42/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 43/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Informational Dynamic Semantics<br />

For Epistemic Might (Veltman 1996)<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Informational Dynamic Semantics<br />

Semantic Concepts<br />

• c[Might(Cube)] = {w ∈ c | c[Cube] ≠ ∅}<br />

• c = {w 1 , w 4 }[Might(Cube)] = c<br />

• {w 1 , w 4 }[Cube] = {w 1 } ≠ ∅<br />

Support<br />

c φ ⇐⇒ c[φ] = c<br />

Entailment<br />

φ 1 , . . . , φ n ψ ⇐⇒ c[φ 1 ] · · · [φ n ] ψ<br />

Truth in w (<strong>Starr</strong> 2010: Ch.1)<br />

w φ ⇐⇒ {w}[φ] = {w}<br />

w 1 w 4<br />

c ′ = c<br />

Propositions<br />

φ = {w | w φ}<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 44/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 45/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

The Semantics <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong><br />

• Dynamic semantics: c[φ] = c ′ (Veltman 1996)<br />

• c[A] = {w ∈ c | w(A) = 1}, c[A ∧ B] = c[A][B],<br />

c[A ∨ B] = c[A] ∪ c[B], c[¬A] = c − c[A]<br />

The Basic Analysis (Gillies 2009; <strong>Starr</strong> 2010: Ch.2)<br />

• Test that all φ-worlds in c are ψ worlds: c[φ][ψ] = c[φ]<br />

• If yes, return c; if not, return ∅<br />

• Presuppose that φ is consistent with c: c[φ] ≠ ∅<br />

{ {w ∈ c | c[φ][ψ] = c[φ]} if c[φ] ≠ ∅<br />

c[(if φ) ψ] =<br />

Undefined<br />

otherwise<br />

• Note: test concerns only antecedent worlds within c<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Motivating The Basic Analysis<br />

• This provides an improved logic for indicative<br />

conditionals (<strong>Starr</strong> 2010: Ch.2); <strong>Stalnaker</strong> invalidates:<br />

Import-Export A → (B → C)<br />

<br />

(A ∧ B) → C<br />

Antecedent Strengthening A → B (A ∧ B) → C<br />

Disjunctive Antecedents (A ∨ B) → C (A → C) ∧ (B → C)<br />

Transitivity A → B, B → C A → C<br />

Contraposition A → B ¬B → ¬A<br />

Entailment (Dynamic Strawson Entailment)<br />

φ 1 , . . . , φ n ψ ⇔ ∀c : c[φ 1 ] · · · [φ n ] ψ<br />

if c[φ 1 ] · · · [φ n ][ψ] is defined<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 46/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 47/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Extending the Basic Analysis: give a semantics for ✁φ<br />

What ✁φ Should Do<br />

Given c, ✁φ delivers a set c ′ <strong>of</strong> φ-worlds that may not be<br />

included in c. Under a Lewis-<strong>Stalnaker</strong> analysis, this set is<br />

calculated as follows. Look at each world w in c. If w is an<br />

φ-world it is allowed into c ′ . If w is not a φ-world, the<br />

φ-worlds most similar to w are placed into c ′ instead <strong>of</strong> w.<br />

These worlds need not come from c.<br />

Semantics for ✁φ<br />

Let f be a selection function::<br />

c f [✁φ] = {w ′ | ∃w ∈ c : w ′ ∈ f(w, φ)} f<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Picturing Semantics for ✁α<br />

α<br />

c f [⊳α]<br />

Figure: Relationship between α, c f and c f [✁α]<br />

• Since ✁ has same syntax as tense, it shouldn’t be<br />

scoping over logically complex sentences; so α is atomic<br />

• In general, the expanded worlds may come from<br />

outside c, ∃f: c f [✁α] c f ; <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction ̌<br />

c f<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 48/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 49/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Contrast When Antecedent is Denied: Indicatives<br />

(7) # Bob never danced. If Bob danced, Leland danced.<br />

(7 ′ ) # ¬B. (if B) L<br />

{ {w ∈ c | c[¬B][B][L] = c[¬B][B]} if c[¬B][B] ≠ ∅<br />

c[¬B][(if B) L] =<br />

Undefined<br />

otherwise<br />

• This update is undefined, since the presupposition fails<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Contrast When Antecedent is Denied: Subjunctives<br />

(8) Bob never danced. If Bob had danced, Leland would<br />

have danced.<br />

(8 ′ ) ¬B. (if ✁B) L<br />

⎧<br />

⎨ {w ∈ c f | c f [¬B][✁B][L] = c f [¬B][✁B]} if c f [¬B][✁B] ≠ ∅<br />

c f [¬B][(if ✁B) L] =<br />

⎩<br />

Undefined<br />

otherwise<br />

• This update will (probably) be defined<br />

• ✁ can reach outside c, so presupposition is weakened<br />

by subjunctive antecedent<br />

• Weakened but not eliminated: requires antecedent to<br />

be f-visible, i.e. f must find some φ world<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 50/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 51/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

A New Analysis<br />

Summary<br />

1 A uniform semantics for two kinds <strong>of</strong> conditionals<br />

• Same semantics for (if φ) ψ<br />

• Difference resides in subjunctive antecedent: ✁α<br />

2 Embodies <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction:<br />

• And so explains subjunctive suggestion and contrast<br />

w/denying antecedent<br />

3 Embodies <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Distinction by pursuing the<br />

Modal Hypothesis<br />

• This explains the correlation between fake past and<br />

subjunctive/indicative<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The New Analysis<br />

Import-Export<br />

(15) a. If Adam had come, then there would have been a<br />

fight if Bob had come<br />

b. (if ✁A) ((if ✁B) F)<br />

(16) a. If Adam had come and Bob had come, there<br />

would have been a fight<br />

a. (if ✁A ∧ ✁B) F<br />

Import-Export<br />

(if ✁α 1 ) ((if ✁α 2 ) ψ)<br />

<br />

(if ✁α 1 ∧ ✁α 2 ) ψ<br />

• Invalid on Lewis-<strong>Stalnaker</strong> semantics<br />

• Valid on present analysis<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 52/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 53/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The New Analysis<br />

Disjunctive Antecedents<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The New Analysis<br />

Towards Another Phenomena<br />

(17) a. If Bob had danced or Sarah had sang, Andy<br />

would have cried<br />

b. So, if Bob had danced, Andy would have cried,<br />

and if Sarah had sang, Andy would have cried<br />

(18) a. (if (✁B ∨ ✁S)) C<br />

b. (if ✁B) C ∧ (if ✁S) C<br />

Disjunctive Antecedents<br />

(if (✁α ∨ ✁β)) ψ ((if ✁α) ψ) ∧ ((if ✁β) ψ)<br />

• Invalid on Lewis-<strong>Stalnaker</strong> semantics<br />

• Valid on present analysis<br />

• Conditional semantics from <strong>Starr</strong> (2010: Ch.2) has<br />

more bells and whistles<br />

• One <strong>of</strong> them is relevant here: stacks <strong>of</strong> contexts, rather<br />

than just contexts<br />

• <strong>Starr</strong> (2010: Ch.2) uses this allows to give a uniform<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> interrogative and conditional if<br />

• Here, it will allow me to analyze various phenomena<br />

involving sequences <strong>of</strong> conditionals<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 54/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 55/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Hypothetical Additions<br />

Logical Tourism<br />

• Information is not only taken for granted in<br />

conversation and inquiry<br />

• Agents routinely entertain certain enrichments <strong>of</strong> the<br />

information they are taking for granted<br />

• Acts like supposition introduce these enrichments; the<br />

speech acts which follow may exploit what’s<br />

entertained in addition to what’s taken for granted<br />

• Real virtuosity comes in the ways that what’s<br />

entertained can be related to what’s accepted<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

States <strong>of</strong> Inquiry<br />

States <strong>of</strong> Inquiry and Hypothetical Change<br />

Proposal: represent hypothetical change via states <strong>of</strong> inquiry<br />

Let s be a state <strong>of</strong> inquiry — state for short<br />

s<br />

c<br />

−−→<br />

state<br />

change<br />

−−−−→<br />

s ↓ p<br />

c<br />

c[p]<br />

Figure: Supposing p<br />

1 s = 〈c〉 — nothing<br />

entertained<br />

2 s ↓ p = 〈c, 〈c[p]〉〉 — c[p] is<br />

entertained<br />

3 Call s ↓ p Subordination<br />

(Related proposal: Kaufmann 2000)<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 56/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 57/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Another Operation<br />

For Suppositional Discourse and Reasoning<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Decomposing the Conditional Further<br />

A Sequence <strong>of</strong> Stack Updates<br />

s[(if ✁α) ψ] = (s ↓ ✁α) ↑ ψ<br />

Conclusion: s ↑ q<br />

Relates what’s entertained to what’s accepted via an<br />

entailment test. Let s = 〈 c, 〈c[p]〉 〉:<br />

• If c[p] (what’s entertained) entails q, c remains as is<br />

• Otherwise, something actually contradictory has been<br />

proposed, i.e. we are brought to: 〈∅, 〈c〉〉<br />

s<br />

c<br />

↓ ✁α<br />

c f<br />

c f [⊳α]<br />

c f [⊳α][ψ]<br />

↑ ψ<br />

c ′ f<br />

s ↑ q = 〈{w ∈ c | c[p] q}〉, 〈c[p][q]〉<br />

c ′ f<br />

= {w ∈ c f | c f [✁α] ψ}<br />

= c f or ∅<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 58/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 59/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Successful Updates<br />

Create Subordinate Contexts<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reverse Sobel Sequences<br />

Another Application<br />

c f<br />

c f [⊳α][ψ]<br />

Modal Subordination: Roberts (1989)<br />

(19) a. Your cabin wasn’t raided by a<br />

coyote.<br />

b. But if a coyote had raided your<br />

cabin, it would’ve eaten your<br />

dinner.<br />

c. It would’ve eaten your meat first.<br />

• (19) is interpreted against subordinate context<br />

• Specifically: 〈c f [✁R][E]〉 ↑ F<br />

• Which context sentences are interpreted against is<br />

determined by discourse connections like anaphora<br />

von Fintel (2001); Gillies (2007)<br />

(20) a. If Sophie had gone to the parade, she would have<br />

seen Pedro dance<br />

b. But <strong>of</strong> course, if Sophie had gone to the parade<br />

and been stuck behind someone tall, she would<br />

not have seen Pedro dance<br />

(21) a. If Sophie had gone to the parade and been stuck<br />

behind someone tall, she would not have seen<br />

Pedro dance<br />

b. # But <strong>of</strong> course, if Sophie had gone to the parade,<br />

she would have seen Pedro dance<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 60/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 61/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reverse Sobel Sequences<br />

The Explanation in Symbols<br />

(22) a. (if ✁S) P<br />

b. (if ✁S ∧ ✁T) ¬P<br />

(23) a. (if ✁S ∧ ✁T) ¬P<br />

b. # (if ✁S) P<br />

• Both s[(22a)][(22b)] and s[(22a)] ↑ (22b) are identical<br />

• By contrast s[(23a)][(23b)] and s[(23a)] ↑ (23b) are not<br />

• First tests: c f [✁S] P<br />

• Second tests: c f [✁S][✁T][¬P][✁S] P<br />

• This test fails!<br />

• There is a strong bias towards the second, inconsistent<br />

discourse structure; hard to defeat, not impossible<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reverse Sobel Sequences<br />

Are Sometimes Good (Moss to appear: §4)<br />

(Context: speaker wants to indirectly convey the<br />

information that Mary would have turned down a marriage<br />

proposal from John.)<br />

(24) a. If John had proposed to Mary and she had said<br />

yes, he would have been really happy<br />

b. But if John had proposed to Mary, he would have<br />

been really unhappy<br />

• This discourse structure: s[(24a)][(24b)]<br />

• Not: s[(24a)] ↑ (24b)<br />

• This an issue for strict semantic accounts (von Fintel<br />

2001; Gillies 2007), but not mine<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 62/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 63/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reverse Sobel Sequences<br />

Anaphora Correlates w/Inconsistency<br />

(25) Although John was seriously considering a proposal to<br />

Mary, he didn’t end up proposing. He never even<br />

bought a ring.<br />

(26) a. If John had <strong>of</strong>fered Mary an engagement ring and<br />

she had said yes, he would have been really happy<br />

b. # But if John had <strong>of</strong>fered it to Mary, he would<br />

have been really unhappy<br />

• Parallel to Moss’s case, but w/anaphora from from<br />

first conditional to second<br />

• Anaphora forces second conditional to be interpreted<br />

against the subordinate state created by the first<br />

• Hence inconsistency<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

Reverse Sobel Sequences<br />

Summary<br />

1 Independently motivated apparatus explains<br />

inconsistency <strong>of</strong> reverse Sobel sequences<br />

• Needed for analysis <strong>of</strong> interrogative/conditional if<br />

• Needed for modal subordination<br />

2 More flexible than von Fintel (2001); Gillies (2007)<br />

3 But explains correlation with anaphoric dependence<br />

unlike Moss (to appear)<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 64/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 65/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

The <strong>Theory</strong><br />

Summary<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

1 Unlike <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s, this theory gives a unified<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong>:<br />

• The contrast with denied antecedents<br />

• The subjunctive suggestion<br />

• Correlation between fake past and<br />

subjunctive/indicative<br />

2 This theory delivers a better logic <strong>of</strong> indicatives &<br />

subjunctives than <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s<br />

• Import-Export, Disjunctive Antecedents<br />

3 It also <strong>of</strong>fers a competitive analysis <strong>of</strong> reverse Sobel<br />

sequences that links them to anaphoricity<br />

Thanks!<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 66/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 67/69<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

References I<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

References II<br />

Bittner, M (2010). ‘<strong>Conditionals</strong> as Attitude Reports.’ Ms. Rutgers University,<br />

URL http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~mbittner/pdf%20files%20for%20web/<br />

bittner10_jos.pdf.<br />

von Fintel, K (2001). ‘Counterfactuals in a Dynamic Context.’ In<br />

M Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: a Life in Language, 123–152. Cambridge,<br />

Massachusetts: The MIT Press. URL<br />

http://mit.edu/fintel/www/conditional.pdf.<br />

Gillies, A (2007). ‘Counterfactual Scorekeeping.’ Linguistics & Philosophy,<br />

30(3): 329–360. URL<br />

http://rci.rutgers.edu/~thony/counterfactualscorekeeping_landp.pdf.<br />

Gillies, A (2009). ‘On Truth-Conditions for If (but Not Quite Only If ).’<br />

Philosophical Review, 118(3): 325–349. URL http:<br />

//rci.rutgers.edu/~thony/truth-conditions-if-phil-review-2009.pdf.<br />

Heim, I (1982). The Semantics <strong>of</strong> Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. Ph.D.<br />

thesis, Linguistics Department, University <strong>of</strong> Massachusetts, Amherst,<br />

Massachusetts.<br />

Iatridou, S (2000). ‘The Grammatical Ingredients <strong>of</strong> Counterfactuality.’<br />

Linguistic Inquiry, 31(2): 231–270.<br />

Isard, S (1974). ‘What Would You Have Done If...’ Theoretical Linguistics, 1:<br />

233–55.<br />

Kaufmann, S (2000). ‘Dynamic Context Management.’ In M Faller,<br />

S Kaufmann & M Pauly (eds.), Formalizing the Dynamics <strong>of</strong> Conversation,<br />

171–188. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Lewis, DK (1979). ‘Scorekeeping in a Language Game.’ Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophical<br />

Logic, 8(3): 339–359.<br />

Lyons, J (1977). Semantics, vol. 2. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Moss, S (to appear). ‘On the Pragmatics <strong>of</strong> Counterfactuals.’ Noûs. URL<br />

http://www-personal.umich.edu/~ssmoss/counterfactuals.pdf.<br />

Pratt, VR (1976). ‘Semantical Considerations on Floyd-Hoare Logic.’ In<br />

Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the 17th IEEE Symposium on Foundations <strong>of</strong> Computer<br />

Science, 109–121.<br />

Roberts, C (1989). ‘Modal Subordination and Pronominal Anaphora in<br />

Discourse.’ Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(6): 683–721.<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>, RC (1968). ‘A <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong>.’ In N Rescher (ed.), Studies<br />

in Logical <strong>Theory</strong>, 98–112. Oxford: Basil Blackwell Publishers.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 68/69<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 69/69


<strong>Stalnaker</strong> on the Direct Argument Two Kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> <strong>Stalnaker</strong>’s Analysis A New Analysis References<br />

References III<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>, RC (1975). ‘Indicative <strong>Conditionals</strong>.’ Philosophia, 5: 269–286. Page<br />

references to reprint in <strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1999).<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>, RC (1978). ‘Assertion.’ In P Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics 9:<br />

Pragmatics, 315–332. New York: Academic Press. References to reprint in<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong> (1999).<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>, RC (1999). Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech<br />

and Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

<strong>Stalnaker</strong>, RC (2005). ‘Conditional Propositions and Conditional Assertions.’ In<br />

J Gajewski, V Hacquard, B Nickel & S Yalcin (eds.), New Work on<br />

Modality, vol. 51 <strong>of</strong> MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Cambridge, MA:<br />

MITWPL.<br />

<strong>Starr</strong>, WB (2010). <strong>Conditionals</strong>, Meaning and Mood. Ph.D. thesis, Rutgers<br />

University, New Brunswick, NJ. URL<br />

http://williamstarr.net/research/dissertation.pdf.<br />

Veltman, F (1996). ‘Defaults in Update Semantics.’ Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophical<br />

Logic, 25(3): 221–261. URL<br />

http://www.pgrim.org/philosophersannual/xix/velt/index.htm.<br />

<strong>Will</strong>iam <strong>Starr</strong> | A <strong>Uniform</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Conditionals</strong> | Modality Seminar | Cornell University 70/69

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!