10.07.2015 Views

New Directions in Austrian Economics

New Directions in Austrian Economics

New Directions in Austrian Economics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>


Other titles <strong>in</strong> Studies <strong>in</strong> Economic TheoryLaurence S. Moss, Series ConsultantAmerica's Great Depression, Murray N. Rothbard _1975)The Economic Po<strong>in</strong>t of View, Israel M. Kirzner (1976)The <strong>Economics</strong> of Ludwig von Mises: Toward a Critical Reappraisal,ed. Laurence S. Moss (1976)The Foundations of Modern <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>,ed. Edw<strong>in</strong> G. Dolan(1976)Capital, Interest, and Rent: Essays <strong>in</strong> the Theory of Distribuffon, byFrank A. Fetter; ed. Murray N. Rothbard (1977)<strong>Economics</strong> asa Coord<strong>in</strong>ation Problem: The Contributions of FriedrichA. Hayek, Gerald P. O'Dñscoll, Jr. (1977)Capital, Expectations, and the Market Process:Essays on the Theory ofthe Market Economy, by Ludwig M. Lachmann; ed. Walter E.Gr<strong>in</strong>der (1977)The UltimateFoundation of Economic Science:Ah Essay onMethod, byLudwig von Mises, Foreword to Second Edition by Israel M.Kirzner (1978)


<strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Edited by Louis M. SpadaroSHEED ANDREWS AND MCMEEL, INC.Subsidiary of Universal Press Syndi¢ateKansas City


This edition is published <strong>in</strong> cooperation with the programsof the Institute for Humane Studies, Inc.,Menlo Park, California; and Cato Institute, San Francisco,California.<strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>Copyñght © 1978 by the Institute for Humane Smdies.Jacket and cover design copyright © 1978 Cato Institute,San Francisco, California.AH rights reserved. Pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> the United States ofAmerica. No part of this book may be used or reproduced<strong>in</strong> any manner whatsoever without writtenpermission except <strong>in</strong> the case of repr<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> the contextof reviews. For <strong>in</strong>formation write Sheed Andrews andMcMeel, Inc., Subsidiary of Universal Press Syndicate,6700 Squibb Road, Mission, Kansas 66202.Library of Congress Catalog<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Publication DataMa<strong>in</strong> entry under rifle:<strong>New</strong> directions <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> economics.(Studies <strong>in</strong> economic theory)Includes bibliographical references.Papers sponsored by the Instimte for -Humane Studiesand presented ata symposium held at W<strong>in</strong>dsor CastleSept. 1976.1. <strong>Austrian</strong> school of economists--Congresses.I. Spadaro, Louis M. II. Institute for HumaneSmdies. III. Series.HB98.N48 880.15'7 77-28611ISBN 0-8362-5104-0ISB,N 0-8362-5103-2 pbk.


CONTENTSEDITOR'SPREFACEvi]An <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g: Unsettled Questionsand Tentative Answers 1Ludwig M. LachmannThe <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 19John B. EggerPraxeology and Econometrics: A Cñtiqueof Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 40Mario J. Riz_<strong>Economics</strong> and Error 57Israel M. KirznerThe Problem of Social Cost 77S. C. LittlechildA Critique of Neoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong>Monopoly Theory 94D. T. ArmentanoSpontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ationof Economic AcÜvities 111Gerald P. O'DriscoU,Jr.Austñan Def'mitions of the Supply of Money 143Murray N. Rothbard


The Emergence of Interest <strong>in</strong> a PureExchange Economy: Notes on a TheoremAttributed to Ludwig ron Mises 157Laurence S. Moss<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 167Roger W. GarrisonToward a Program of Research and Developmentfor <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong> 205Louis M. SpadaroIndex 229


EDITOR'SPREFACEBecause the approach of the bicentennial of both the AmeñcanRevolution and the publication of Adam Smith's famousWealthofNations tended to overshadow another mílestone--thepass<strong>in</strong>g of a hundred years s<strong>in</strong>ce the occurrence of the "marg<strong>in</strong>alist"revoluon <strong>in</strong> economic theorymthe observance of thelatter has been left mostly to economísts.Even among this relatively small company, whatever celebrationthere wastended to be further subdivided ow<strong>in</strong>g to the factthat the economic revoluon of the 1870sarose <strong>in</strong>dependently<strong>in</strong> three different places and took implicitly different forms.Two of themwthe English and the French variants--soonmerged either with pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g analysis or with subsequentformulaons and so have lost some of their specificity and identy.The thirdwthe <strong>Austrian</strong>_branch not only represented, fromthe outset, a more dar<strong>in</strong>g departure from received doctñne, butrema<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g century, more <strong>in</strong>dependent anddistimxive<strong>in</strong> its essenUal imights, its analytical method, and itsimplicationsfor economic and sodal policy.Thus it was thatearly <strong>in</strong> September of 1976, a small group of<strong>Austrian</strong>economists (mostofthem return<strong>in</strong>gfrom a sentimentaljoumey to Smith's birthplace) met for a few days <strong>in</strong> historicW<strong>in</strong>dsor Castle to celebrate their own special anniversary. Anumber of papers prepared for the occasion were presentedthere and arehere offered to a wider audience. The partidpantsat the Symposium also engaged <strong>in</strong> a great deal of formal and<strong>in</strong>form__!discussion of the papers, which it was not possible to<strong>in</strong>dude <strong>in</strong> the present volume.The arrangement of the artides here follows the order andpurpose of their presentaUon at the symposium. The first andvii


viiiEditor's Prefacelast are, respectively, a retrospective anda prospectíve for <strong>Austrian</strong>economic theory; the test deal <strong>in</strong> their various wayswith anumber of significant po<strong>in</strong>ts at the lead<strong>in</strong>g edge of <strong>Austrian</strong>analysis, where it <strong>in</strong>terfaces or takes issue with contemporaryeconomic th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g.Thus, ProfessorLachmann's paper is a thoughfful assessmentof the present state of <strong>Austrian</strong> theory anda lucid statement ofits essential disnnguish<strong>in</strong>g features. This provides the basisforaprovocative criUcalexam<strong>in</strong>ation of some of the implications ofthat theory and fora number of imag<strong>in</strong>aáve suggestions for itsfuture extension.Professor Egger attempts to locate and expla<strong>in</strong> some of thecritical po<strong>in</strong>ts on which <strong>Austrian</strong> theory differs significanflyfrom currenfly received doctr<strong>in</strong>es. His discussion of these "differentia"offers a valuable bridg<strong>in</strong>g serviceto a potenfially wideaudience who would otherwise f<strong>in</strong>d it difficult to perceive andevaluate important <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>in</strong>sights on substance and method.The methodological divergence between currently prevail<strong>in</strong>geconomic analysis and <strong>Austrian</strong>ism is explored <strong>in</strong> depth <strong>in</strong> thepaper by Mario Rizzo. By juxtapos<strong>in</strong>g econometric andpraxeological approaches, Dr. Rizzo provides a usefulframework for critical exam<strong>in</strong>aon of the claims and validity ofthe positivism that implicitly pervades so much contemporarytheoriz<strong>in</strong>g.The contribution by Kirzner complements and extends thedist<strong>in</strong>ctively <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the role of <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> theeconomic process to which Hayek called attention <strong>in</strong> a wellknownarticle some forty years algo.In the present article, ProfessorKirzner analyzes the function of error <strong>in</strong> economicdecision-mak<strong>in</strong>g as well as its relaonship to <strong>in</strong>formation and tothe nature of entrepreneurship.ProfessorLittlechild addresses himself to the problem of socíalcost--a concept that not only pervades much of moderowelfare economics, but also constitutes a major po<strong>in</strong>t of contentionbetween Austñans and conventional theorists. Littlechñdexam<strong>in</strong>es the validity of the concept itself as well as some attemptsto deal with social cost from a subjectivist perspective.


Editor'sPrefaceixStillanother focus ofdisagreement between <strong>Austrian</strong>s and theprevail<strong>in</strong>g orthodoxy is monopoly theory and the concept ofcompetition on which it rests, whether explicitly or not. ProfessorArmentano's paper is a critical exam<strong>in</strong>ation of the conventionalapproach as well as of several variants of the <strong>Austrian</strong>view.The essay byProfessor O'Driscolltakes upa question that hasdivided economists for a verylong time: whether there exists <strong>in</strong> amarket economy an ordernot externally imposed upon it. In thecourse of his analysis, O'Driscollargues that a number of problems<strong>in</strong> economic analysis that appear to be separate from thisquestion as well as from one another are ultimately reducible toit.ProfessorRothbard exam<strong>in</strong>es the conventional def<strong>in</strong>itions ofthe money supply and argues that the consistent application ofan <strong>Austrian</strong> approach requires expansion of the mean<strong>in</strong>g of thesupply of money to <strong>in</strong>dude a number of important componentscurrently excluded. Rothbard po<strong>in</strong>ts out, moreover, that differentcomponents of the money-supply may have very differentbus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle effects--a source of error that is systematicaUyoverlooked by the usual aggregative treatments of the subject.Professor Moss caUs<strong>in</strong>to question the claim made by someAustñan economists that the subjective concept of time preferenceas developed by Misesimplies that a positive rate of'pure<strong>in</strong>terest would necessarily appear even <strong>in</strong> a pure exchangeeconomy (i.e., one with no productioñ). Moss attempts a pureexchange model <strong>in</strong> which the emergence of such <strong>in</strong>terest wouldnecessarily depend on the presence of certaín objective conditions.Professor Garrisonundertakes the considerabletaskof dep_ct<strong>in</strong>gmacro-economic relationships diagrammatically and <strong>in</strong> amanner consistent with the <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>in</strong>sistence that valíd explanationsof economic relationships must ultimately refer to <strong>in</strong>dividualchoices rather than rest on the facile assumption thataggregates <strong>in</strong>teract directly. His graphics are applied to production,exchange, and other relationships <strong>in</strong> an attempt to establisha better and wider appreciation of Austñan analysis.


xEditor's PrefaceThe last paper, by this writer, attempts to discern, <strong>in</strong> the lightof the successes and failures of the past and present, somegeneral guidel<strong>in</strong>es for the future development of <strong>Austrian</strong>economícs. It tentatively concludes that suela development willmost probably need to <strong>in</strong>volve a much wider range of methods,discipl<strong>in</strong>es, and professions.F<strong>in</strong>aUy, ir is the editor's pleasant duty to express a few acknowledgementson behalf of all the participants. We ate gratefulto Professor Arthur Shenfield for agree<strong>in</strong>g to actas chairmanfor the conference meet<strong>in</strong>gs and for his patience and wit <strong>in</strong> thedischarge of a sometimes diffícult task. The presence of ProlessorFriedrich von Hayek at the meet<strong>in</strong>gs was impir<strong>in</strong>g to thescholars participat<strong>in</strong>g, and bis contributions to the discussionsadded <strong>in</strong>sight and wísdom. S<strong>in</strong>cere thanks ate also due AdmiralD. H. Mason and the staffof St. George's House, W<strong>in</strong>dsor Casfle,for all their hospitality and help. Lasfly, a very special word ofthanks is extended to the Uníversity College at Buck<strong>in</strong>gham andto the Institute for Humane Studies for sponsor<strong>in</strong>g theSymposium_and to Koch Industñes, Inc. without whose moraland material support neither the conference nor this bookwould have been possible.Louis M. SpadaroFord_m Universityjuly, 1977


2 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>tal2 was largely, if not solely, prompted by the latter's disregardof all those economica]ly relevant aspects of time that do not fallunder the head<strong>in</strong>gs "Üme preference" and "period of producnon."To Menger, time was, <strong>in</strong> the first place, the dimension <strong>in</strong>which the complex network of <strong>in</strong>ter<strong>in</strong>dividual relations presentsitself to us. <strong>Austrian</strong> economics has reta<strong>in</strong>ed and cultivated thisMengerian perspective. Time is the dimension ofall change. Irisimpossible for time to elapse without the constellation of knowledgechang<strong>in</strong>g. But knowledge shapes actíon, and acUon shapesthe observable human world. Hence ir is impossible for us topredict any future state of this world.The third feature of<strong>Austrian</strong> economics, a coroUary ofsubjec-Üvism and awareness of the protean character of time, is adistrust of all those formalizaUons of economic expeñence thatdo not llave an identifiable source <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d of an economicactor. Such distrust naturally engenders skepticism about macroeconomicaggregates. To <strong>Austrian</strong>s, MIeconomic thought isthought with<strong>in</strong> the context of means and ends imply<strong>in</strong>g choice.Austrían economics is certa<strong>in</strong>ly more than "a pure logic ofchoice." At some stage, we have to <strong>in</strong>troduce"subsidiary assumptions."Expectaons area good example, the grant<strong>in</strong>g of credit isanother. But <strong>Austrian</strong>s wiU not accept formalizations ofeconomic experience that altogether defy the category "meansand ends," concepts that ale noth<strong>in</strong>g but formalizations of recordsof statistical observations <strong>in</strong> which the events recordedappear devoid of their histoñcal character and mean<strong>in</strong>g.In what follows, the impfications of these three feamres will beexplored by apply<strong>in</strong>g them to a number of problems with which<strong>Austrian</strong> economists have good reason to concern themselves.But, quite apart from the three features, the <strong>Austrian</strong>s, be<strong>in</strong>gsuch stout defenders of the market economy, are namrídly <strong>in</strong>volved<strong>in</strong> every attack on ir. An argument currently <strong>in</strong> fashionamong the would-be sopbísticated says that the existence of sofew forward markets <strong>in</strong> the real world proves that the effectivenessof the market process <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g economic plans andactíon is gravely hampered. In the climate of our time, theímplication that here is a promis<strong>in</strong>g f'_.ld of government <strong>in</strong>ter-


4 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>(e.g., <strong>in</strong> the markets for agricultural products and for fashiongoods), expectations play a prom<strong>in</strong>ent part. But it ís of somesignificance that whatever scope there is for the expression ofexpectations <strong>in</strong> suda markets is <strong>in</strong> general commensurate withwhat scope there isfor the hold<strong>in</strong>g and variability of comrnoditystocks. In a pure flow market, <strong>in</strong> which no stocks can be held,expectations can f<strong>in</strong>d little expression, except <strong>in</strong> consumers'decisions to defer purchases. In product markets <strong>in</strong> general, <strong>in</strong>which boda flowsand stocksare traded, the <strong>in</strong>fluence ofexpectafionsis proportionate to the share of stock transactions <strong>in</strong> totaltransactíons.It isthus by no means surpris<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong> asset markets, suciaasthe Stock Exchange, beíng pure "stock markets," expectationsate paramount. Without divergent expectations, vdthout"buUs"and "bears,"such markets evidently could not exist. It is importantto understand that the notorious volatility of Stock Exchangeprices is, <strong>in</strong> the first place, due to the ease with which <strong>in</strong> apure stock market it is possible to more from one side of themarket to the other, to be a buyer <strong>in</strong> the morn<strong>in</strong>g anda seller <strong>in</strong>the afternoon, or vice versa ir one holds stock. In the potatomarket, by contrast, most participants are firmlywedded to oneside, be<strong>in</strong>g either producers or consumers, while only the merchants,hold<strong>in</strong>g stocks, are able to change sides.In the second place, short-run stability of the potato markethas to be susta<strong>in</strong>ed by "a given taste for potatoes" on the onehand and stability of agricultura1 technology, area of acreage,and wage rates on the other, while the markets for securitiesatesusta<strong>in</strong>ed byno suda forcess<strong>in</strong>ce there isno cost ofproduction orconsumer demand for them. Here stabilityis not <strong>in</strong>conceivable.But it is impossible for expectations about a certa<strong>in</strong> evént at afuture date to rema<strong>in</strong> constant while this date is mov<strong>in</strong>g nearer.The daily flow of the news wiUaffect some of the divergentexpectations. Some bulls wiUturn bears of vice versa. This, asProfessor Shaclde has shown with suda vigour, is the majorreason for the wen-known volatility of asset markets.<strong>Austrian</strong> economists, face to face with these facts, llave to askwhat they imply. Their first implication, <strong>in</strong> our view, is that we


6 <strong>New</strong> Directiom <strong>in</strong> ,dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>market economy, mean capital ga<strong>in</strong>s and losses to asset holdersand cause a daily redistribution of wealth. In fact, it is hardly anexaggeration to say that the mode of distribution of wealth <strong>in</strong> amarket economy is largely, though not solely, the cumulaáveeffect of the capital ga<strong>in</strong>s made and losses suffered <strong>in</strong> the past.This should be a sobeñng thought to aU those who contemplateother forms of the redistribution of wealth, e.g., by taxation, and<strong>in</strong> particular to those who ate ready "to accept the marketeconomy but only after a redistñbution of the exist<strong>in</strong>g wealth."As long as asset markets ate open, the process of redistribuonofwealth must cont<strong>in</strong>ue. Ifthe govemment redistñbutes wealthat the end of September, the mode ofits distribution <strong>in</strong> Octoberwill not last. By November, the market wíll have modified it, byDecember even more so. This process is a prom<strong>in</strong>ent feature ofthe market economy, an <strong>in</strong>evitable concomitant of the marketprocess, and ultimately a consequence of the divergence of expectations.IIITo act<strong>in</strong>g man time is no cont<strong>in</strong>uum. The future is uncerta<strong>in</strong>,the past alone known, or at least knowable. "We cannot haveexpeñence ofactuality at two dist<strong>in</strong>ct'moments'. The moment ofactuality, the moment <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g, 'the present', is solitary. Extendedtime, beyond the moment, appears <strong>in</strong> th_is light, asafigment, a product of thought. "8As time is cont<strong>in</strong>uously flow<strong>in</strong>gacross the threshold of the present, itis undergo<strong>in</strong>g a change ofquality. With regard to our knowledge, then, time isheterogeneous, compñs<strong>in</strong>g the unknowable and the knowable.Hence Amtrian economists, compened by their commitment tosubjectivism to view aU problems <strong>in</strong> the perspective of the actor,cannot but look askance at aUtheoñes employ<strong>in</strong>g the mathematicalnoÜon of time asa cont<strong>in</strong>uum and will cast a suspicious eyeon expressions such as dY/dL To acf<strong>in</strong>g man, time mear___s someth<strong>in</strong>gdifferent.All our knowledge belongs to the past. It is therefore, <strong>in</strong>prínciple, possible to dassify all items of knowl¢dge by a time


dn <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g 7<strong>in</strong>dex of their acquisiÜon, and this, of course, is what historiansof science are do<strong>in</strong>g. But the relaÜonships among various itemsof knowledge ma), assume vañous forros, and mete dat<strong>in</strong>g maytell us little about what we want to know.To simple m<strong>in</strong>ds, all knowledge presently acquired is additíveto prior knowledge. Mank<strong>in</strong>d is pil<strong>in</strong>g up an ever-grow<strong>in</strong>g storeof knowledge, a veritable treasure house of the m<strong>in</strong>d from which= not a s<strong>in</strong>gle ítem is ever removed. Austrían economists, put ontheir guard by their experience <strong>in</strong> the theory of capital, knowthat ir may not be so: some old knowledge is rendered obsoleteby new knowledge. The <strong>in</strong>tertemporal relationship betweenítems of knowledge may be subsÚtutive, not addiÚve. Of ir maybe complementary, where the new knowledge enhances thecompass of the old and opens new fields for the comb<strong>in</strong>edapplication of both.In our "kaleidic" society, the obsolescence of old knowledge isa fact of fundamental importance. Its consequences are ubiquitous.Even where technical progress is slow, our knowledge ofthe market, i.e., other actors, is soon out of date. Time cannotelapse without changes <strong>in</strong> the constellaUon of knowledge accompaniedby capital ga<strong>in</strong>s and losses.<strong>Austrian</strong> economists, lay<strong>in</strong>g stress on the coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g functionof the market, face a problem here: If the market coord<strong>in</strong>atesexistíng knowledge, what happens when knowledgechanges while the process is tak<strong>in</strong>g place, when people acquireknowledge of which it is possible that tomorrow it may havebecome obsolete? Leav<strong>in</strong>g this question open, we must now tumto look<strong>in</strong>g at the problem of time and knowledge <strong>in</strong> a differentperspective.Similarly, as is the case with B6hm-Bawerk's structure of production,we may look at the relationship between various itemsof kJmwledge either diachronically or synchronically. The firstwe llave already done, and conduded that the <strong>in</strong>tertemporalrelation between items of knowledge ma), be additive, substitutire,or complementary. But the same, of course, applies synchronically.In a market economy, the plans of compet<strong>in</strong>g firms may be


8 <strong>New</strong> Directiom <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong>consistent. The sarne applíes to the <strong>in</strong>novations <strong>in</strong>troduced toserve the implementation of the plans. Where these are additive,however, timas will soon learn them from each other. Wherethey ate complementary, profitable arrangements for theirjo<strong>in</strong>texploitaUon will be made <strong>in</strong> the usual way. But where they aresubstimdve, the plato of compet<strong>in</strong>g timas derive additionaldoses of <strong>in</strong>consistency from this very fact. The market as thef<strong>in</strong>al arbiter wiU determ<strong>in</strong>e which of these <strong>in</strong>novatiom survíveand become part of the social body of technical knowledge.From the <strong>Austrian</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of view, the 6me aspect as well as therelevance of consumers' wants to the economíc significance ofnew lmowledge need emphasis. Not aUtechnical change is technicalprogress. At the moment at which new knowledge becomt_available, nobody can tell ex ante which of the itetm of which it bcomposed will expost make for economic success. Only years ofexperience <strong>in</strong> the workshops and <strong>in</strong> the market can tea that. Wemust not treat as social fact what, at the moment at which therelevant decisions llave to be taken, carmot be more than subjectireop<strong>in</strong>ion.The relevance of all this to current discussions on the "socialtate of return to <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>formafion," alleged to be <strong>in</strong>excess of the "private tate," is obvious enough. We might addthat our argument wiUalso cast new iight on "product differenation,"so often described asa monopolistic device ptacUsed bywily producers on ah unmspect<strong>in</strong>g public. Can anybody imag<strong>in</strong>ehow the ah-planes, gtamophones, or founta<strong>in</strong> pero of 60 yearsago could have evolved hato their present-day tdaapes withoutcont<strong>in</strong>uom product differenUation? Time has more aspects ofeconomic relevance than ate dreamt of <strong>in</strong> neoda_ical theory./VThe last SOyears saw the ascent of macroeconomics and atempotary ecpse of <strong>Austrian</strong> though¿ What attitude should<strong>Austrian</strong> economists adopt toda), towards macroecono_m_i_¢aggregates? We spoke above of skeptiásm engendered by a


An <strong>Austrian</strong> Stoclrtak<strong>in</strong>g 9distrust of aUformalizations of economic experience which donot havean identifiable source <strong>in</strong> the mínd of aneconomic actor.] But a more positive attitude is called for. <strong>Austrian</strong> economistsmust attempt, wherever possible, to impart a measure of subjectivismto the products of macroeconomic thought.We may note that <strong>Austrian</strong> aversion does not perta<strong>in</strong> to theseaggregates as such. <strong>Austrian</strong> economists, after aH,di'ddiscussthebalance of payments of the Habsburg Empire. It perta<strong>in</strong>s to theconstruction of an economic model <strong>in</strong> which these aggregatesmove, undergo change, and <strong>in</strong>fluence each other <strong>in</strong> accordancewith lawswhich are devoid of any visiblereference to <strong>in</strong>dividualchoice. Like the bodies of a planetary system, each aggregate isaffected bychanges <strong>in</strong> other aggregates, but never, itappears, bychanges tak<strong>in</strong>g place with<strong>in</strong> itself. It is this conception of themode of relationships among aggregates, rather than the existenceof the aggregates themselves, which defies subjectivism.At fa'st sight it seems futile to attempt to change this state ofaffairs by splitt<strong>in</strong>g large aggregates <strong>in</strong>to smaHeraggregates. Butwhere it ispossible to show that movements of the smaHeraggregatesare responsive to changes which constitute effects of <strong>in</strong>dividualchoices, while the movements of the larger aggregate atenot, such ah attempt might be promis<strong>in</strong>g.In PricesandProduction, ProfessorHayek rejects the Fisheriannotion of the pñce level and substimtes the pñce levels of capitalgoods and consumption goods for it. One might th<strong>in</strong>kthatone isas macroeconomic as the other. But the whole po<strong>in</strong>t of theoperation comists <strong>in</strong> the fact that the two price levels are tied tothe sav<strong>in</strong>g-comumption decisions of <strong>in</strong>come eamers, while theFisherian price level is not.Such an evolution towards subjectivismby means of the disaggregadonof macroaggregates has actually taken place <strong>in</strong> thetheory of money over the last 60 years.It cannot surprise us thatthe textbook <strong>in</strong>dustry has ignored it. It is perhaps moreremarkablethat economic th<strong>in</strong>kers, even some who took a prom<strong>in</strong>entpart <strong>in</strong> it, appear to be unaware of it. But it is surpris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>deedthat <strong>Austrian</strong> economists, of aU people, should llave taken nonotice of"this further step <strong>in</strong> the consistent applicaáon of subjectivism."


10 Neto <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> Amtrian <strong>Economics</strong>As late as <strong>in</strong> 1911, <strong>in</strong> Fisher's Purchas<strong>in</strong>g Power of Money, theframework of monetary relations presented <strong>in</strong> the famousQuantity Equaáon consisted entirely of macroeconomic entities,either aggregates like M and T or averages of aggregates like VandP. With<strong>in</strong> this context, the Quantity Theory proper asserteda relationship between M and P.The follow<strong>in</strong>g year, Mises took the first step <strong>in</strong> the direction ofsubjectivism by stress<strong>in</strong>g the important tole of <strong>in</strong>dividual cashbalances. In Cambñdge, Pigou tried to subjeaivize the rigors ofthe Quantity Equation by means of the "Cambridge k.''4 Thediscovery of the variabilíty of bank credit played its part. Whilecommodity money "exists" <strong>in</strong> a physical form, the creation andma<strong>in</strong>tenance of a volume of credit requires acts of choice. Ajaelement of subjectivism entered <strong>in</strong>to the supply of money.In 1930 Keynes, <strong>in</strong> the Treatise,_ <strong>in</strong>troduced the díst<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween the <strong>in</strong>dustrial and the f<strong>in</strong>ancial circulation, later calledactive and idle money. We have here a alear case of a dissolutionof a macroaggregate (M) <strong>in</strong>to smaller aggregates amenable tochoice, the choice between money to use and money to hold. And<strong>in</strong> 1934, for a fleet<strong>in</strong>g moment, a few economists even becameaware of what was happen<strong>in</strong>g, viz. that night <strong>in</strong> November 1934when young Dr. Hicks read his paper, "A Suggestion forSímplify<strong>in</strong>g the Theory of Money, ''s with its emphasis on subjecfivism,to a baffled London Economic Club most of whose membersfelt that someth<strong>in</strong>g important had been said, but could notquite make out what.Even <strong>in</strong> the ranks of the Quantity theorists, subjectivism toda),makes its <strong>in</strong>fluence felt. We f<strong>in</strong>d Professor Friedman, whomnobody wou]d regard asa subjectivist, tell<strong>in</strong>g us that while theold Quantity Theory emphasized the supply of money, the newQuanfity Theory (domicíle: Chicago) prefers to put its emphasison the demand for it. Tlfis demand, as has been noted by many,has a remarkably Keynesian flavor. In the theory of moneysubjectivism appears triumphant.In the theory of capital I made ah attempt to more <strong>in</strong> thedirection of subjectivism <strong>in</strong> my book, Cap/ta/and Its Structure(London, 1956)..There I tried to dissolve the capital structure


An <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g 11<strong>in</strong>to the capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations of the various firms and to showhow these are amenable to, <strong>in</strong>deed the expression of, <strong>in</strong>dividualplans. Perhaps the attempt was premature.How lar attempts to <strong>in</strong>fuse subjectivism <strong>in</strong>to other fields ofmacroeconomics will succeed, only the future can show. It seemsfairly obvious, however, that the time for some steps <strong>in</strong> this: direction has come. <strong>Austrian</strong> economists should bf best able totake sucia steps.VFuturesmarkets?The), can reconcile,just conceivably,our PRES-ENT ideas, basedon our PRESENTknowledge. Whatof tomorrow'snew knowledge destroy<strong>in</strong>g the old or rendeñng ir obsolete, what oftomorrow'schoices and decisions, tomorrow'sdiscoveries,tomorrow's<strong>in</strong>ventions,work of imag<strong>in</strong>aon?...We are not omniscient, assured masters of known circumstance viareason, but the prisoners of time.G. L. S. ShackleJournal of EconomicLiteratureJune 1973, p. 519.The market economy has never been _without its cñtics andenemies. Those who feel threatened by the market; those who,however unwisely, feel they could do better without it;economists with little imag<strong>in</strong>ation; those, fike the devotees ofPareto optima, with only too much of ir; those who f<strong>in</strong>d mostentrepreneurs disgust<strong>in</strong>g characters; those attracted by theromantic charm ofa feudal order <strong>in</strong> which they never had to live;social th<strong>in</strong>kers offended by the raucous tone of modern advertis<strong>in</strong>g;and social thirtkers who know only too weU how to exploitenvy and greed <strong>in</strong> the service of anticapitalisc movements--allthese make a formidable array of opponents.On the other hand, the m_arketeconomy has been able to drawsupport from a 200-year-old tradition of economic thought.Here <strong>Austrian</strong> econom_¢ts, side by side with non-Austñans, havetaken a pmm<strong>in</strong>ent part <strong>in</strong> support<strong>in</strong>g it. In t_hiscenmry, out-


12 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> Auarian <strong>Economics</strong>stand<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>kers like Cassel, Hayek, Mises, and Pareto havedefended the market economy aga<strong>in</strong>st many misunderstand<strong>in</strong>gsand fallacies.But of late the w<strong>in</strong>d appears to have turned, and the heirs ofCassel and Pareto have changed sides. Lead<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>kers of theneoclassical school have launched an attack on the mai'keteconomy, charg<strong>in</strong>g it with <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>in</strong> a field <strong>in</strong> which, manyof us would have thought, some of its most impressive achievementsare to be found: <strong>in</strong> the provision of facílities for <strong>in</strong>tertemporaltradíng.To our knowledge, Professor Koopmam first launched theattack <strong>in</strong> 1957, criticis<strong>in</strong>g what he caUed "the overextended beliefof the liberalist school of economic thought <strong>in</strong> tl_e efficiency ofcompeddve markets asa meam ofallocat<strong>in</strong>g resources <strong>in</strong> a worldfuUof uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty." He conf<strong>in</strong>ued, "To my knowledge no formalmodel of resource allocafion through competitive markets hasbeen developed, which recognizes ignorante about aH decisionmakers' future actions, preferences, or states of technological<strong>in</strong>formation as the ma<strong>in</strong> source of uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty confront<strong>in</strong>g each<strong>in</strong>dividual decision maker, and which at the same time acknowledgesthe fact that forward markets on which anticipatiom and<strong>in</strong>tentions couM be tested and adjusted do not exist <strong>in</strong> sufficientvariety and with a sufficient span of foresight to make presenflydeveloped theoty regard<strong>in</strong>g the efficiency of competitive marketsapplicable .... In particular, the economics profession is notready to speak with anyth<strong>in</strong>g approach<strong>in</strong>g scientific authority onthe economic aspects of the issue of <strong>in</strong>dividual versus coUectiveenterprise which divides manldnd <strong>in</strong> our time."*In a similar ve<strong>in</strong> Professor #a'mw, <strong>in</strong> a recent PresidenfialAddress to the A.E.A., told his listeners, "Even asa graduatestudent I was somewhat surprised at the emphasis on staticaUocative effidency by __rket socialists, when the nonexistenceof markets for future goods under capitalism seemed to me amuch more obvious targeL"sIn February1973,ProfessorHahn, <strong>in</strong>bisweU-known IrmuguralLecture <strong>in</strong> Cambridge, ° employed the _me argument toshow that general equilibrium theory has its pracfical uses <strong>in</strong>


Illl IllllIIn <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g 13provid<strong>in</strong>g a sophisticated critique of the market economy. "The= argument will here turn on the absence of futures markets andcont<strong>in</strong>gent futures markets and on the <strong>in</strong>adequate treatment oftime and uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty." He cont<strong>in</strong>ued, "Pracfical men and iUtra<strong>in</strong>edtheorists everywhere <strong>in</strong> the world do not understandwhat they are claim<strong>in</strong>g to be the case when they claim a beneficentand coherent tole for the <strong>in</strong>visible hand" (p. 14).This critique of the market economy caUsfor an answer. In thefirst place, it is perhaps obvious that no exist<strong>in</strong>g st.ateof affairscan be effectively criticised by compañng ir with a purely imag<strong>in</strong>aryone, such as the general equilibrium model <strong>in</strong> its mostup-to-date and sophisticated forro. The critics rail to teU us how awofld with peffect <strong>in</strong>tertemporal markets for everyth<strong>in</strong>g is to bebrought <strong>in</strong>to existence. Nor ate we given any h<strong>in</strong>t as to how asocialist economy would of could provide a substitute for it.Second, the critics appear to share ah altogether exaggeratednotion of what forward markets can achieve. The), can provide"cover" aga<strong>in</strong>st some cont<strong>in</strong>gencies, they coord<strong>in</strong>ate expectafions,"buUish" and "bearish." But they cannot make the uncerta<strong>in</strong>fumre certa<strong>in</strong>, they carmot prevent plans from be<strong>in</strong>g upsetby events nobody could have foreseen, they cannot elim<strong>in</strong>ate thedifference between exante and expost. Shaclde has expressed thisso well <strong>in</strong> the quotation at the top of this section that no furthercomment seems called for.Third, this entire argument rests upon a confusion betweenactua/and potent/zd markets. No practical conclusions can bedrawn from the mere fact that certa<strong>in</strong> transactions which arepossible do not actually take place. There are toda), no marketsfor ostrich feathers or top hats, but there probably would be iffashion were to mm.Our <strong>in</strong>ability to observe certa<strong>in</strong> transactions does not permitus to <strong>in</strong>fer that they are impossible. The), ma), not be profitable<strong>in</strong> given circumsta.rtces. In a society full of risk-averters, riskcapitalmay be so u_rce that ir can be provided for only a fewmarkets. Many potentiai markets never become actual becausetransaction cos_ are too higlt, and all transaction costs are,certa<strong>in</strong>ly to <strong>Austrian</strong>$, oppormnity costs. I-Laveour critics ever


14 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>considered what immense precautionary (and variable) moneybalances would have to be carried agaimt forward commitments<strong>in</strong> the world they are envisag<strong>in</strong>g?Arrow actually goes <strong>in</strong>to "the causes for the absence of marketsfor future goods" (p. 7). "It seems to me there are two basiccausal factors. One is that contracts are not enforceable withoutcost and forward contracts are more cosfly to enforce than contemporaneouscontracts; the other is that because of the manyuncerta<strong>in</strong>ties about the fumre, neither buyers nor sellers arewiU<strong>in</strong>g to make commitments which completely def<strong>in</strong>e theirfumre actiom" (p. 8).It is doubtful whether either of these can provide a genera/reason. The cost of enforc<strong>in</strong>g contracts is low <strong>in</strong> law-abid<strong>in</strong>gsocieties, high <strong>in</strong> others. Moreover, as Arrow admits, the marketma), provide its own sanction by exdud<strong>in</strong>g defaulters fromfurther trad<strong>in</strong>g. The second reason should lead to a generaldiscussion of the limits of forward markets <strong>in</strong> the spirit ofShackle's remarks, but it does not. We are told <strong>in</strong>stead, "As Hicksshowed a long time ago, complementarity and substimon canoccur over time as well as simultaneously. If... uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty cantend to destroy m_rkets, then we can condude that the absenceofsome markets for future goods may cause others to fañ" (p. 9).As far as one can judge, this means that we are fac<strong>in</strong>g an"extemality" here, accord<strong>in</strong>g to modero welfare economics asource of "market failure." If so, the answer is that externaleconomies <strong>in</strong>vite jo<strong>in</strong>t exploitation by potential, beneñciaries.The second reason seems no better than the first.F<strong>in</strong>aUy, and for us most important, this criticism of the marketeconomy <strong>in</strong>um<strong>in</strong>ates the limitations of the neoclassical m<strong>in</strong>drather than the shortcom<strong>in</strong>gs of the market. This m<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>in</strong>capableof conceiv<strong>in</strong>g of "the market" otherwise than <strong>in</strong> terms of asystem of markets <strong>in</strong> general equilibrium, is helpless when confrontedwith a real world <strong>in</strong> which not aHpotential markets areactually <strong>in</strong> operaon. Not know<strong>in</strong>g that those whose view of themarket the), criticise conceive of ir<strong>in</strong> terms ver), dífferent fromtheir own, our critics tacifly assume that everybody, like theirwell-tra<strong>in</strong>ed disciples, identifies the market economy with their


Ah <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g 15general equilibrium model. To <strong>Austrian</strong>s, by contrast, the market,as Hayek taught, is a process rather than a state of affairs, aprocess which comes to an end when equilibrium is reached.Dur<strong>in</strong>g the course of this process it happens aH the time thatsome potential markets become actual and some actual marketspotential, though nobody, of course, could say for how long.Some economists who are critics of the market appear to sufferfrom a lack of imag<strong>in</strong>ation.Needless to say, the circumstances <strong>in</strong> which <strong>in</strong>tertemporalmarkets come <strong>in</strong>to existence provide an important subject forempirical study, a most significant aspect of the market process.It is to be hoped that <strong>Austrian</strong> economists will take their fullshare <strong>in</strong> its pursuit. It is not obvious why a model <strong>in</strong> which aUobstacles to the birth of<strong>in</strong>tertemporal markets are assumed awayshould be of much help to us <strong>in</strong> pursu<strong>in</strong>g such a study.V/In the recent development of economics, there is much <strong>Austrian</strong>economists cannot but disapprove of. We already mentionedmacroaggregates and what might be done with them. Butwhat positive contñbutions do they have to offer for the futureof economic science?FoUow<strong>in</strong>g what was said above, we have to dist<strong>in</strong>guish betweenthe unknowable future and the knowable past. In neodassicalthought this problem does not añse, s<strong>in</strong>ce one is ostensiblyengaged <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g "laws" apply<strong>in</strong>g as muda to the one as to theother. But there are the welbknown puzzles among which theproblem of ceterispar/has, our <strong>in</strong>ability to specify all the conditionsunder which the laws ale to hold, takes prom<strong>in</strong>ence. <strong>Austrian</strong>ssimply have to face the fact that the autonomy of the m<strong>in</strong>dprecludes determ<strong>in</strong>ism: If knowledge shapes action and actionshapes the human world, the fumre is unpredictable. "But iftheory pretends only to gire an account of particular, peculiarand speci'a! moments (sucia as may be scarcely ever atta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>fact) and repudiates any hope of connecUng them by any <strong>in</strong>telli-


16 " <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>gible, permanent mechanism allow<strong>in</strong>g prognosis, then thetheory ought explicitly to be a dassificatory one, putt<strong>in</strong>g situations<strong>in</strong> this box of that accord<strong>in</strong>g to what can happen asa sequelto it. Theories which tell us what will happen ate c!aim<strong>in</strong>g toomuch."10In other words, <strong>in</strong>solar as the future is concerned, economicswill have to become far more a descriptive díscipl<strong>in</strong>e than it is atpresent, giv<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>telligible account of a number of futurepossibilities <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> present situations, unable to rely on thestrict necessity of determ<strong>in</strong>ism or even of numerical probability.Economists will have to acquire new skills, the skills required fordescriptíon and comparison of large numbers of possible simations.Remember<strong>in</strong>g how much time and effort have of late been<strong>in</strong>vested <strong>in</strong> mathematical skilLs,the skills of symbolic precisionreflect<strong>in</strong>g necessity and determ<strong>in</strong>ism, we cannot but feel uneasyabout the concomitant circumstances of such a change ofparadigm.What promise does the knowable past hold f_r the fumre ofeconomics? Here we encounter the problem of the relationshipsbetween economics and history. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to a view widely heldtoday, it is the task of the analytical social sciences to produce"cover<strong>in</strong>g laws" which the historians wiUthen apply to concretecases. But the economist can offer the historian only laws validceterisparibus, unlikely to be of much use to the latter withoutspecification.Yet it rema<strong>in</strong>s true that the past is the great storehouse of facts,offer<strong>in</strong>g us a vast stock of material for empiñcal generalizations,<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> themselves provided we do not pretend that theyate universal laws. Here we ate able to compare ex ante with expost s<strong>in</strong>ce we know, or <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple are able to know, what happenedto plans. We might f<strong>in</strong>d out how muda capital was'mal<strong>in</strong>vested<strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> decade. We can ascerta<strong>in</strong> economic growthpatterns of the past without hav<strong>in</strong>g to rely on "steady state"models. We might even trace the multiple source$ from whichtechnical progress flowed <strong>in</strong> the past. The fact that mostgeneralizations we might draw from this material wiUbe limited<strong>in</strong> time need not, after aUwe said, discourage us. Nor need we be


Ah <strong>Austrian</strong> Stocktak<strong>in</strong>g 17afraid lest we trespass on the field of: the historians who maywelcome such help as we ate able to offer. Whenever a complexof relationships persista for a period of time, it constitutes bothan analytical and a historical subject. The f<strong>in</strong>ances of theHabsburg Empire under B6hm-Bawerk or the political structureof the Republic of Venice are obvious examples. They atehistorical and analytical subjects.Above all, <strong>Austrian</strong> economista will want to trace market processesof the past. To identify economic history with the evolutionof the market economy is a bold idea at the application ofwhich Sir John Hicks tried his hand a few years ago.lt A gooddeal might be done with<strong>in</strong> this framework.As the heirs of Menger, <strong>Austrian</strong> economists will take a particular<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> how the market evolves those "organic <strong>in</strong>stitutions"it needs? 2 But the degeneration of these <strong>in</strong>stitutions is asubject that no less deserves our attention. It míght be worth ourwhile to attempt to f<strong>in</strong>d out when exactly, and <strong>in</strong> what circumstances,the downward <strong>in</strong>flexibility of money wage ratesbecame the prom<strong>in</strong>ent feature of the Western world it todayunfortunately is. It would be even more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to l<strong>in</strong>k it tothe evolution of the imtitutions of coUective barga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g. Historyoffers many <strong>in</strong>stances of <strong>in</strong>stimtions which, created for onepurpose, carne to serve another. The parallel with mal<strong>in</strong>vestmentis obvious.Statistical time series are records of the past. Impossible as it isto derive empirical laws by correlat<strong>in</strong>g them, such correlationsmay nevertheless cast some light on the events of the time oftheir orig<strong>in</strong>. How much <strong>in</strong>formation these time series will disclosedepends on our ability to ask mean<strong>in</strong>gful questions ofthem. Subjectivism asserts itself here <strong>in</strong> that different socialscientists wiUask different questions. How large the proportionof persons <strong>in</strong> "tertiary occupations" was <strong>in</strong> a given society dur<strong>in</strong>ga certa<strong>in</strong> period may be of <strong>in</strong>terest to one social scientist. <strong>Austrian</strong>economists, by contrast, might prefer to know how many ofthem were <strong>in</strong>dependent agents, active middlemen and dealers,s<strong>in</strong>ce the operation of imperfect markets depends so largely on


18 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>agents of this type. Ask<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gful questions is a skill that has !to be acquired. ]It is to be hoped that economic science will <strong>in</strong> the future, as ithas done <strong>in</strong> the past, though not <strong>in</strong> the recent past, offer scopefor many diverse skiHs and talents. At the moment, this mustseem a sangu<strong>in</strong>e hope. <strong>Austrian</strong> economists are perhaps <strong>in</strong> abetter position than anybody else to make a contñbudon towardsthis end.REFERENCES1. F.A. Hayek, The Counter-Revolution ofScience (Glencoe, 1952), p.31.2. J. A. Schumpeter, History of Economic dna/ys/s (1954), p. 847,footnote 8.3. G. L. S. ShacHe, Ep/stem/cs and<strong>Economics</strong> (Cambridge, 1972), p.245.4. A. C. Pigou, "The Value of Money," Quarterly Journal of<strong>Economics</strong> (November 1917), pp. 42-43.5. J. M. Keynes, A Treatise onMoney (1930), Volume I, Chapter 15.6. John Hicks, Crá/ca/Essays <strong>in</strong>Monetar) Theory (Oxford, 1967), pp.61-82.7. Tjall<strong>in</strong>g C. Koopmans, Three Essayson theState ofEconomic Science(McGraw-Hill, 1957), pp. 146--47.8. K. J. Arrow, "Limited Knowledge and Economic Analysis,"American Economic Review (March 1974), pp. 1-10.9. F.H. Hahn, On theNotion ofEquilibrium <strong>in</strong><strong>Economics</strong> (Cambridge,1973).10. Shackle, op. c/t., p. 72.li. John Hicks, A Theorj ofEconomicHistory (Oxford, 1969).12. Carl Menger, Problems of<strong>Economics</strong> and Sociology(Urbana, 1963),pp. 151-59.


The <strong>Austrian</strong>MethodJohn B. EggerGoucherCollegeThere has been a renewal of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> School ofeconomics <strong>in</strong> recent years. Good public relations deserve part ofthe credit: the 1974 Nobel award to F. A. Hayek and the series ofsem<strong>in</strong>ars sponsored by the Institute for Humane Studies havehad some effect. But beneath these lies the substance:economists are learn<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong>formation has a great deal to dowith human behavior--and they are learn<strong>in</strong>g that the <strong>Austrian</strong>School long has focused on the broad and narrow behavioralimplications of fragmented <strong>in</strong>formation.Recogníz<strong>in</strong>gthatthe<strong>Austrian</strong>Schoolisdifferentornoveloreven better is easier than recogniz<strong>in</strong>g exacfly what makes itdifferent. Sometimes the span between the recognition and theidentification of the difference is long and difficult. Mak<strong>in</strong>g itshorter and easier is the goal of this paper. It does not particularlyadvance the frontiers of <strong>Austrian</strong> methodology, but airas atpresent<strong>in</strong>g the basic differences between the <strong>Austrian</strong> Schooland the neoclassical orthodoxy _ <strong>in</strong> terms likely to be clear tostudents of the latter. The paper's target reader is perhaps thegraduate smdent who studies to the po<strong>in</strong>t of memoriz<strong>in</strong>g statementslike "The <strong>Austrian</strong> School studies purposive human action"and yet is sfill unable to see how this relates to what he f<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>in</strong> bis microtheory course, zDOES A PRIORISM DIFFERENTIATE AUSTRIANISM?Murray Rothbard and Ludwig von Mises, two of the great19


20 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>Austrian</strong> School economists, strongly defend the propositionthat economics is apr/or/, s The primary question for my thesis is:does this position differentiate the <strong>Austrian</strong> writers from othereconomists? While argu<strong>in</strong>g that the laws of economics are <strong>in</strong>dependentof the specifics of human experience, Mises stood opposedto historical and <strong>in</strong>stitutional approaches which held eventhe very theory of economics valid only <strong>in</strong> particular historical or<strong>in</strong>stitutional sett<strong>in</strong>gs. Of course a theory whose most basic pr<strong>in</strong>cipleschange over time is no theory at all; Mises was thus defend<strong>in</strong>gthe very possibility of a science of economics.But it was never bis <strong>in</strong>tent, <strong>in</strong> Iris statements ofa pr/0r/sm, todifferentiate his and his followers' method from that of theneoclassical economists. Their "constra<strong>in</strong>ed maximization"technique is every bit as <strong>in</strong>dependent of historical circumstanceas is the technique of sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g out implications from the "actionaxJom."4 Because a pr/or/sm does not differentiate the <strong>Austrian</strong>School, ir is nota def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic of the School.EQUILIBRIA, STATIC AND DYNAMICOne of the avenues by which the nature of the "<strong>Austrian</strong>differentia" can be approached is an exam<strong>in</strong>aUon of two mean<strong>in</strong>gsof"equilibrium. ''sIn the convenonal sense (which I te,m "static'), "equilibrium"refers simply to a state <strong>in</strong> which prices of the various goodsresult <strong>in</strong> zero excess demand for each of them. The term "static"is often taken to mean "tirneless" and is <strong>in</strong>clicated by the absehceof time parameters <strong>in</strong> the supply and demand functions, but theessenUally static nature of this conception of equiUbrium is notviolat_l even if some of the goods among which the <strong>in</strong>dividualschoose are "future goods."Consideras a typical example the <strong>in</strong>teraaions among three<strong>in</strong>dividuals, each with ah endowment of goods and a specificutility function. Under certa<strong>in</strong> reasonable assumptions about theforros of these utility functions, some set of relative prices amongthese goods wiU be consistent with the preferences and <strong>in</strong>itial


The <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 21endowment_ of the three <strong>in</strong>dividuals. The market's, and each<strong>in</strong>dividual's, excess demand for each good will be zero at this setof relative prices. The nature of this equilibrium is not at aHchanged if some of the goods are promises of future delivery ofother_---based upon knowledge, let us say, of a regular Sundaynight manna delivery. Each <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>dependently considershis present and future preferences, and the <strong>in</strong>dividuals' <strong>in</strong>teractiondetei c,_<strong>in</strong>es a mumally consistent (present and future) pricevector.This is certa<strong>in</strong>ly ah equilibrium. In the context of the particularmoment's valuations and expectations, any further changes<strong>in</strong> any of the prices would cause some net excess demands tobecome nonzero. But ir is as¿at/c equilibrium <strong>in</strong> this sense: ir doesnot differentiate between future expectations which ate consistentamong the <strong>in</strong>dividuals and those which ate <strong>in</strong>consistent, sEven though a unique price vector of "future goods" is determ<strong>in</strong>ed,we have no assurance that the plans on which the <strong>in</strong>dividualsbased their future valuations ate consistent. In thesimplest case--that of divergent expectations about physicaldata---an equilibrium relative price between beach umbrellasand ra<strong>in</strong> umbrellas may be determ<strong>in</strong>ed under circumstances <strong>in</strong>which one <strong>in</strong>dividual th<strong>in</strong>ks it wñl ra<strong>in</strong> tomorrow while the othertwo believe ir will be a pleasant day for swimm<strong>in</strong>g. But even ifexpectations about physical data co<strong>in</strong>cide, expectations abouteach other's action plans may be contradictory: each <strong>in</strong>dividualmay base his demand for, say, "tomorrow's automobile services"on the expectadon that he alone platas +to drive on a certa<strong>in</strong>narrow, dusty mounta<strong>in</strong> road. In either of these cases, a uniquestatic equilibrium price vector may be determ<strong>in</strong>ed, but the passageof time wiU reveal the <strong>in</strong>consistency of the <strong>in</strong>dividuals'expectations and hence require the determ<strong>in</strong>ation of a new pricevector. This equilibrium is static because it is built upon <strong>in</strong>consistenciesof which the <strong>in</strong>dividuals wiU learn <strong>in</strong> attempt<strong>in</strong>g to followtheir plans. Only a dynamic equilibrium <strong>in</strong>corporates consistentfumre plans, and hence is not disturbed "endogenously"--bythe very act of follow<strong>in</strong>g one's plans.The Hayekian dynamic equilibñum, 7 <strong>in</strong> short, consists of a


22 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>market-clear<strong>in</strong>g price rector based upon <strong>in</strong>terpersonally consistentexpectations; the stafic equifibrium discussed above consistsof a rector of market-clear<strong>in</strong>g prices based upon plans which the<strong>in</strong>dividuals mayor may not be able to carry out.Two quite different perspectives on the economic problem areimplied by these two viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts on the nature of"equilibrium." Iclaimed at the start of this section that these perspectives williUum<strong>in</strong>ate the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the <strong>Austrian</strong> School and theneoclassical microapproach. There is just a bit more igroundwork.The analysis characterized above as static concentrates uponthe existence of a price rector consistent with the momentaryrelative valuations of the índividuals. The conditions of the1world expected by these <strong>in</strong>dividuals--which <strong>in</strong>clude the actionsof other índividuals--rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the shadows; the only relevantissue is the subjective rate of substitution among the commodities,and there is no way tojudge whether or not the subjectirerates of substituáon determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the different <strong>in</strong>dividualsare based upon contradictory future expectations. Static analysisbeg<strong>in</strong>s at a po<strong>in</strong>t at which expectations and marg<strong>in</strong>al utilities (orpreference order<strong>in</strong>gs) have already been formed and allows usto determ<strong>in</strong>e the existence and uniqueness of a price rector(which may <strong>in</strong>clude future goods) consistent with these preferences.Whether the preferences themselves are based upon consistentexpectations is simply beyond the pale of this approach. Ihave thus come to believe that ir is not quite accurate to arguethat the (static) analysis of equilibrium conditions "assumesaway" the problem of <strong>in</strong>consistent expectations: s it simply hasñoth<strong>in</strong>g to say on that issue.Such an approach may be considered "timeless," <strong>in</strong> a sense,whether or not there are "future goods" <strong>in</strong> the commodity bundles.For the passage of time would reveal whether the <strong>in</strong>dividuals'expectations were <strong>in</strong>terpersonally consistent or not, and thiswould transform the problem <strong>in</strong>to someth<strong>in</strong>g quite differentfrom that with which static analysis deals. It would, to be specific,shift us <strong>in</strong>to the realm of the dynamic equilibrium or disequilibriumnature of the stafic conditions we have derived.


The ,4ustrian Method 23The difference between a market-clear<strong>in</strong>g price vector correspond<strong>in</strong>gto a static and one relat<strong>in</strong>g to a dynamic equilibriumis that the latter necessarily <strong>in</strong>corporates <strong>in</strong>terpersonally consistentexpectations. The process of deñv<strong>in</strong>g, by logical deduction,the distribution of goods and relative pñces under th/s sort ofequilibñum presupposes that the premises on which the deducdonis based--the preferences andplans of the <strong>in</strong>dividuals--are,themselves, logically consistent. Thus the application of ourstatic tools to dynamic questions requires a great deal more <strong>in</strong> theway of assumption: that each <strong>in</strong>dividual foresee exactly thoseactions which the others plan to take3 This <strong>in</strong>terpersonal consistencyof expectatíons must be presupposed before the specificpattern of prices and distribution can be logically deduced.THE "/IUSTRI,4N DIFFERENTIA"In his sem<strong>in</strong>al "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge" Hayek made astatement which for some time I found puzzl<strong>in</strong>g:... s<strong>in</strong>ceequilibriumis a relationship between acfions, and s<strong>in</strong>ce theactions ofone per-.anmust necessañly take place successively<strong>in</strong> time,itis obvious that the passage of time is essential to gire the concept ofequilibrium any mean<strong>in</strong>g. This deserves mention, s<strong>in</strong>ce manyeconomists appear to have been unable to f<strong>in</strong>d a place for time <strong>in</strong>equilibriumanalysis and consequenfly have suggested that equilibriummust be conceived as timeless. This seems to-me m be a mean<strong>in</strong>glessstatement,leWhy could.not this great economist understand what I knew:that all we had to do was leave t out of our equations?The answer is provided <strong>in</strong> the above section. Whether or notthere are "fumre goods" (or t's <strong>in</strong> the demand functions), 11thesearch for a logically consistent set of preferences (i.e., amarket-dear<strong>in</strong>g pñce rector) does not necessañly present uswith a logically consistent set of p/ans, n Although the pñcevector determ<strong>in</strong>ation completes the job of the auctioneer, thematter of <strong>in</strong>terest to the <strong>in</strong>dividuals participat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the mar-


24 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>ketplace is whether of not their actions wiUachieve the expectedresults---which most assuredly will not be the case if their expectationsare logically <strong>in</strong>consistent.Questiom concern<strong>in</strong>g the existente, uniquene_, and stabilityofa price vector which is mutually consistent with thepreferencesof many different <strong>in</strong>dividuals ate, <strong>in</strong> short, ofan entirely differentcharacter from the questions and problen_ which arise whenone <strong>in</strong>vesgates the existence, uniqueness, and stabiñty of the setof expectafions or p/ans which is <strong>in</strong>terpersonally comistent.Concentration upon this latter set of issues constutes the<strong>Austrian</strong> differentia. The disnction cannot be appreciated froma simple statement removed from the context of the above remarks,but it appears correct to argue that: whereas most contemporarymicrotheory focuses upon the abstract logic of preferences,the <strong>Austrian</strong> Sc.hool focuses upon act/on._sM/IN, THE ENTREPRENEURThe above comments may help to clarify some of the ¢lnimsmade by the <strong>Austrian</strong> School writers: 14although the "abstractlogic of preferences" can employ the technique of mutual determ<strong>in</strong>aÜonvía the soluÜon ofsets ofsimultaneous equaom, ananalysis of the plans underly<strong>in</strong>g these preferences and how plansare modified must <strong>in</strong>corporate the concepts of purpose andlearn<strong>in</strong>g. "Purpose" <strong>in</strong> this sense cannot refer simply to the apr/or/st/c universal goal of "utUity maximization"; ir refers tosome 5pecific goal the <strong>in</strong>dividual wishes to achieve and consequentlyto how bis actions and plans are Ukely to be modifiedwhen he learns that the economic environment is go<strong>in</strong>g to bedifferent from that which he anticipated when he developed bis<strong>in</strong>itial plans. Simuhaneous determ<strong>in</strong>ation ma), govern the logicalanalysis of preferences, but the "older concept of causeoandeffect"_5is the only technique appropríate to the smdy of learn<strong>in</strong>gand the modificaon of <strong>in</strong>consistent plans. The "cause," ofcourse, is the <strong>in</strong>dividual's subjective perception of an opportunityto improve bis simation, and the "effect" is a change <strong>in</strong> hisway of act<strong>in</strong>g, of <strong>in</strong> bis plans.


The <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 25This process of the revision of <strong>in</strong>consistent plans requires thatthe <strong>in</strong>dividual be able to recognize those feamres of his orig<strong>in</strong>alplans which caused the <strong>in</strong>consistency and that he recognize alsothe changes <strong>in</strong> his plato which tend to elim<strong>in</strong>ate that <strong>in</strong>consistency.Such abilities constitute at least part of what economistscall "entrepreneurship." (The popular notion of"creat<strong>in</strong>g a newproductor service" is simply a special case <strong>in</strong> which abus<strong>in</strong>essman th<strong>in</strong>ks he perceives the desirability of a change <strong>in</strong>his own plans and hopes that the result<strong>in</strong>g plan <strong>in</strong>consistency [heplans to get rich but potential customers have yet to leam of hisnew product, so they don't plan to buy any] will be resolved by asubsequent revision ofhis potential customers' plans rather thanof his own.) It is precisely the relation among entrepreneurship,plan revision, and action which expla<strong>in</strong>s the irrelevance of entrepreneurshipto neoclassical microeconomic theory whichtakes preferences as axiomatic and does not concern itself withthe possibility of carry<strong>in</strong>g out their underly<strong>in</strong>g plans.Professor Kirzner's important work refers to the "alertness to<strong>in</strong>formation" as entrepreneurship, ls But the importance of the<strong>Austrian</strong> viewpo<strong>in</strong>t is more clear if we realize that this ability isprecisely what differentiates man from other liv<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs, that"entrepreneurship" <strong>in</strong> general is <strong>in</strong>disnguishable from use ofthe raonal faculty, from the ability to concepmalize, fromth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. 17Concept formation requires differentiation and <strong>in</strong>tegration:differentiaon among the <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite variety of attributes of certa<strong>in</strong>items of situations, isolation ofa specific attribute common to theitems, and <strong>in</strong>tegration of the different items or situations <strong>in</strong>to aconcept accord<strong>in</strong>g to whether or not the), possess the chosencommon attribute. The process is one of group<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to dasses,or dassif'maUon, and is common to all thought. A dedsion is adassificaon, and decision is the goal of all thought.How is this process of dassification related to action? An<strong>in</strong>dividuars action h<strong>in</strong>ges upon the comparison: "What wiHth<strong>in</strong>gs be like if I don't act," versus "What will they be like if Ido?" To make sucia a decision the <strong>in</strong>dividual must constructhypothefical states of the future, one conditional on the <strong>in</strong>di-


26 Neto<strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong><strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>viduars act and the other on its absence. Once the concretes ofthe situation are perceived, the process of conceptualizationconsists of the isolaUonof certa<strong>in</strong> characteristicscommon to thisand to other situations. These other situations may be historical<strong>in</strong>stances the <strong>in</strong>dividual remembers oran imag<strong>in</strong>ary case <strong>in</strong>which he envisions himself <strong>in</strong> the role of another person andconsiders how he would behave <strong>in</strong> that role. In either case thefunction of the isolation of certa<strong>in</strong> features is to elim<strong>in</strong>ate unessentialdutter: specific details of the scene which are not thoughtto be "important." It is the ability to isolate correctly therelevant--causal---aspects of a simation oran ongo<strong>in</strong>g process,and hence to accuratelypredict its fumre <strong>in</strong> both the absence andpresence of one's own action, which constitutes successful entrepreneurship.And it is the attempt to do so which constimtesentrepreneurship, successful or not.But aUthought isexactlyof this forro.Whether one is try<strong>in</strong>g toth<strong>in</strong>k through the causal forcesbeh<strong>in</strong>d the IndustrialRevolutionor to analyze a Frost poem, the technique is to hypothesizealtemaves and to isolate particular causal elements, characteristicswhich appear to make the crucial difference betweenwhat/s and what might have been. The only difference betweensuch contemplative thought and the popular view of entrepreneurshipis that the historian or poet has at his command thedata needed to test his hypothesis, while the fledgl<strong>in</strong>gbus<strong>in</strong>essman must wait and see whether customers come. Butdur<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terval of time between the development of thecounterfactual hypothesis and its test (e.g., "perhaps X causedthe Industrial Revolution... but that would imply a certa<strong>in</strong>pattem of relative prices which did not, <strong>in</strong> fact, occur," or "whydidn't Frostwrite 'The woods are owned by MayorJones, whosewife sells pickled cabbage at the fair' <strong>in</strong>stead of 'whose woodsthese are I th<strong>in</strong>k I know'?.., but that would elim<strong>in</strong>ate the degreeof generality Frost is try<strong>in</strong>g to convey <strong>in</strong> the rest of thepoem .... "), the test liesas much <strong>in</strong> the future as that fac<strong>in</strong>g thebus<strong>in</strong>essman.To be able to speak of'entrepreneurship" and "thought" asdifferent concepts is useful, to be sure. But this analDis suggests


The/iustrian Method 27that the entrepreneur is anyone act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> accordance with hisspecifically human nature. A school ofeconomics which, becauseof its focus and method, can accord a central role to the entrepreneuris simply respect<strong>in</strong>g the nature of man. Surely this is animportant aspect of the <strong>Austrian</strong> differentia.METHOD: M/ITHEMATICS /IS /IN AN/ILYTIC/IL TOOLIN ECONOMICSIfwe are to analyze the function of mathematical term<strong>in</strong>ology<strong>in</strong> economics, we must analyze it at its best. The difficultiesassociated with the use of differential and <strong>in</strong>tegral calculus arewell-known (e.g., the requirements that products and factors be<strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely divisible, that <strong>in</strong>dividuals consider <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itesimalchanges relevant, that all preference order<strong>in</strong>gs be representableby a total utility function and production relations by a totalproduct funcUon), so analyses us<strong>in</strong>g differentiable and <strong>in</strong>tegrableobjective functions are no longer at the frontiers ofmathematical economics, except perhaps <strong>in</strong> the smdy of uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty.The more general approach of set theory has been developedlargely s<strong>in</strong>ce Debreu (1959), ls and it is a real and significantimprovement over differentia! calculus <strong>in</strong> economics.Those who wish to criticize mathematical economics must takeon its best.Bertrand Russell contends that"pure mathematics is the dassof all propositions of the forro í_ implies q:...,,ls The daim ofequivalence between pure logic and pure mathematics is sometimesattributed to Russell and Whitehead's Pr<strong>in</strong>cipiaMathemat/ca (1910-13), but the same idea is presented forcefully<strong>in</strong> the first few pages of Russelrs 1903 work. Russell was led tothis condusion by the discovery that numbers are sets, t° thatord<strong>in</strong>ary algebra is therefore aja application of set theory, andthat any statement of implication can be rewñtten <strong>in</strong> settheoreticterms: e.g., "p implies q" is identical to "q is a subset ofp." Venta diagrams even give us pictures. 11Jevom felt that economics was by nature mathematical be-


28 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>cause it deals with numbers. 2"Modern mathematicians prefer toidentify the roots of their subject with the theory of sets. Aset is acollection of undef<strong>in</strong>ed "elements," which may represent anyproperty we wish to attribute to them, and the theory of setsconsists of the logical relaUons among them. Because of thecompletely general nature of these sets and elements, we canembrace a much wider view of the namre of mathematics thancan those who restrict themselves to, say, functional notation;James R. <strong>New</strong>man's cursory sampl<strong>in</strong>g of a few modernmathematicians' viewsof their own subject <strong>in</strong>deed suggests thatthe boundary between Iogic and mathematics is becom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>glyblurred."Furthermore, either logical relations or mathematics--whatever the dist<strong>in</strong>ction may be---is capable of expression <strong>in</strong>either verbal of abstract symbofic temas. Jevons was correct <strong>in</strong>this regard: one cannot identífy the basically mathematical ornonmathemadcal nature of a discipl<strong>in</strong>e accord<strong>in</strong>g to whether or_ot it is expressed verbally.24From this viewpo<strong>in</strong>t it appears as ir <strong>Austrian</strong> School writers'criticisms of mathematics <strong>in</strong> general--rather than of crudemathematics, or of symbolicmathematic_ _-are,<strong>in</strong> essence, criticismsofpure logic, which is not always(sometimes, perhaps, butnot always)what they <strong>in</strong>tend. The real issue is: are there advantagesto be ga<strong>in</strong>ed from the substituon of symbo/sfox"words<strong>in</strong>economics?"The advantages claimed for this substitution <strong>in</strong>cludeeconomy, precision, and rigor." The economy arises simplyfrom the fact that a symbol (e.g., x) is more bñef than the set ofwords it denotes (e.g., "the number of oranges he buys perweek"). The precision and ñgor follow from the abstract natureof symbols: once a set of symbols is appropriately def<strong>in</strong>ed (i.e.,related verbally to the problem of <strong>in</strong>terest) the entire corpus ofthe formal theory of relations among these symbols becomesapplicable to one's problem. The ability to draw on the pure,abstract theory of logic (or mathematics) provides the rigor, andthe exactness required <strong>in</strong> the defmition of symbols forces thepre_.Lsion.


The <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 29It is clear enough that representati0n with symbols is alwayspossible: by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gf0 and x approprhtely we can represent"absence makes the heart grow fonder" by '_(x)>0. ''2_ Thequestion is, why bother? What advantages might such symbolismoffer? There will be advantages---economy, precision, rigormonly if the symbols wiUbe used repeatedly <strong>in</strong> the course of somelogical analysis.The economy is achieved by omitt<strong>in</strong>g repeated verbal identificationof the symbols. The forro <strong>in</strong> which this generally occurs is:verbal def<strong>in</strong>ifion of symbols, a (perhaps long) process of deductionfrom the <strong>in</strong>itial posmlates with a symbofic conclusion, andastatement <strong>in</strong> words of the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the conclusion (obta<strong>in</strong>edby reference to the symbols' <strong>in</strong>itial def<strong>in</strong>itions). Mathemaficalsymbolism is <strong>in</strong>deed economical <strong>in</strong> this case, ir only the f<strong>in</strong>aldeduced proposition is held to be important. If the problemwere analyzed <strong>in</strong> verbal temas, muela unnecessary and redundantrestatement of the symbols' def<strong>in</strong>ions would occur. Manyacademicjournal articles are precisely of this lo, cc_:a few wordsat the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g and end, pages of symbolic mathemacs <strong>in</strong> themiddle.To evaluate the process of symbolic analysis outl<strong>in</strong>ed above,we must consider the epistemological significance of language.Words are concrete audiovisual representations of the abstraconscalled concepts, <strong>in</strong> which form al1knowledge is reta<strong>in</strong>ed, ssAsa consequence, any mathematicaUy derived symbolic proposbtions which are to be mean<strong>in</strong>gful must be translated <strong>in</strong>to words.(If they are merely translatable then they are merely potentiaUymean<strong>in</strong>gful.) Thus, the long sequence of <strong>in</strong>termediate steps <strong>in</strong> alogical deñvaon must be expressed verbally if it is to be relatedto human experience. But without subsidiary hypotheses abouthow people learn, these <strong>in</strong>termediate steps ate not mean<strong>in</strong>gful asguides to the comprehension of behavior and cannot be relateddirectly to human experience. Only the conclusion can, <strong>in</strong> thesense that it describes an "equilibrium" state toward which actionsare headed. Equilibrium theorists who make extensive useof mathematical symbolism ate, <strong>in</strong> fact, sav<strong>in</strong>g a great deal ofpaper and time. The fact that causality is lost is irrelevant to one


30 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>concerned only with descriptions of equilibria.Those who perceive economic theory asa set of propositionswhich are logically implied by <strong>in</strong>itially hypothesized preferencesets and production possibifities understandably f<strong>in</strong>d symboliclogic and mathematics a powerful tool: economical, precise,rigorous. But the analysis of the condiUons specific to an equilibriumpresupposes that the conditions necessary for equilibñumexist. This is hardly much to ask if one restricts his viewpo<strong>in</strong>t tostat/c conditions, <strong>in</strong> the sense discussed earlier <strong>in</strong> this paper_thatis, to search for a price rector logically consistent with the <strong>in</strong>dividuals'preferences at a spedfic moment. Ifone sees the centralpurpose of economics as the analysis of action, however, therelevant equilibrium is the dynam/c one, and its preconditions--<strong>in</strong>terpersonally consistent future plans or expectation: eannotbe merely hypothesized. One must attempt to exam<strong>in</strong>e the ways<strong>in</strong> which this <strong>in</strong>terpersonal consistency of expectations can bebrought about. This requires the <strong>in</strong>troduction <strong>in</strong>to one's analysisof empiñcal (nondeduced) statements about what reacfions <strong>in</strong>dividualsare likely to have when confronted with unexpecteddevelopments, zs If these reactions were implícit <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ifia!propositions and therefore could be logically derived from themus<strong>in</strong>g their symbolism, they would not be reactions to unexpecteddevelopments at aU: they would simply be preprogrammedbehavioral changes <strong>in</strong> accordance with perfectly foreseenchanges <strong>in</strong> data and would be empty of learn<strong>in</strong>g.The <strong>in</strong>troduction amidstream of unexpected developmentsthus requires the use of words. Symbolism is economical onlywhen one can draw on it for a long time. Process analysis,however, by requir<strong>in</strong>g the cont<strong>in</strong>ual specification of nondeducedempirical hypotheses about learn<strong>in</strong>g and expectationrevisíon, and hence about causality, can make little use of thiseconomy.Of course, if one looks upon the process of plan revision andmovement toward a dynamic equilibrium_ as a series of discretejumps, one can associate a static equilibrium price vector witheach discrete set of preferences as they emerge throughwat theprocess. This would seem to enhance the role of pure logical


The <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 31deduction and symbolic technique, ratfier than to m<strong>in</strong>imize it.But the mean<strong>in</strong>g of these sets of price vectors is not clear. Theyare still unrelated to the consistency of the expectations on whichthe preferences support<strong>in</strong>g them are based.Those who are firmly wedded to the symbolic analysis characteristicof so much of modero economics may pref_r to contendthat their work alone is theory, that the <strong>in</strong>troduction of nondeducedhypotheses about reactions to unexpected changesconverts one's study <strong>in</strong>to applied work. But I should po<strong>in</strong>t outthat logic is common to all fields of study, and ir is only the<strong>in</strong>troduction of specific empirical characteristics that makes aneng<strong>in</strong>eer's analysis of a nonl<strong>in</strong>ear control system at all differentfrom an economist's study of bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles. The logic used byphysicists is the same as that used by biologists and byeconomists. What differentiates physics from biology fromeconomics is the namre of the empifical l<strong>in</strong>ks between the objectsstudied and the abstract logical rules the analyst employs.UNCERTAINTY AND MATHEMATICSIN ECONOMIC ANALYSISI cannot undertake here a systematic exam<strong>in</strong>ation of recenttrends <strong>in</strong> "the economics of uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty." It deserves mention,however, because it may seem to reconcile the "imperfect <strong>in</strong>formation"of the dynamic disequilibrium and the use of mathematicalsymbolism. In what sense does "uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty economics" <strong>in</strong>corporateimperfect <strong>in</strong>formation and learn<strong>in</strong>g?The relative-frequency concept of probability3ois not applicableto human action with its unique events, u For discussion I willsimply assume here someth<strong>in</strong>g which I am by no meam conv<strong>in</strong>cedis legitimate: that there is ah appropriate subjective probabilityconcept accord<strong>in</strong>g to which fumre states can be orderedby cardi_nal degrees of belief.Modern analyses us<strong>in</strong>g this approach are, like their deterrn<strong>in</strong>isticcou_nterparts, <strong>in</strong>evitably stat/¢. Even the most sophisticatedof the techniques, th_t of"stochastic dom<strong>in</strong>ance," which


32 " <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economics</strong>permits the entire subjective distribuUon (rather than only itsmean and vañance) to be considered,8snecessarily<strong>in</strong>volves thereduction oran akernativeto a"certa<strong>in</strong>ty equivalent,"anord<strong>in</strong>alwhich can be value ranked aga<strong>in</strong>st other alternatives. Essentially,a hypothetical and certa<strong>in</strong> alternative is manufactured--one ]which has the same valueas the uncerta<strong>in</strong> state---and preferences _are constructed on the basis of this hypothetical alternative. Forexample, aman may be <strong>in</strong>different to the choice between $40and a 50-50 chance at $100 or noth<strong>in</strong>g. In determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g preferenceshe willactas if $40 were actually the alternaUve; marketpñces of lottery tickets, for example, willbe determ<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> thismarmer.When we consider the <strong>in</strong>dividu_!'splans, rather than bis preferences,we see at once that the state of w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g $40 with ce::ta<strong>in</strong>ty cannot have been expected and planned for. It is simplynot one of the possible outcomes. Asa consequence, the uncerta<strong>in</strong>tymodels are by their nature static: perfectly sufficient forthe analysis of market-dear<strong>in</strong>g prices, but no'more capable of<strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g learn<strong>in</strong>g and the removal of plan <strong>in</strong>consistencythan the determ<strong>in</strong>istic static analyses. When the <strong>in</strong>dividual discoversthathe has--or has not--won the $100, he no longer actsand plans as ii"he were certa<strong>in</strong> to receive$40. Static uncerta<strong>in</strong>tyanalysis has contributed to our understand<strong>in</strong>g of pñce detei __<strong>in</strong>ationunder uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, but it does not permit us to analyze aprocess of action and learn<strong>in</strong>g.THE AUSTRIAN METHODWhat implications do the forego<strong>in</strong>g comments have formethodology? How are propositions about economics to be developed?The formal study of patterns of consistentpreferences--which I have called the "abstract logic ofpreference_---may employ the techniques of formal logic andmathematics, particularly set theory. The study of consistentplans, and how <strong>in</strong>consistencies <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpersonal expectatiom areelim<strong>in</strong>ated through learn<strong>in</strong>g, requires atechnique (ifit may be so


The Amtrian Method 33called) different from the abstract syml_lism of mathemaÚcs. Itrequires that specific nondeduced hypotheses be advancedabout how an <strong>in</strong>dividual's plans and preferences change whenhe ís confronted with unexpected events. The fact that theseproposions about learn<strong>in</strong>g cannot be logically derived fromother accepted statements may make the analysis appear unscientific,because of course it renders the conclusions dependentupon the accuracy of the empirical hypotheses. But if one acceptsPopper's term<strong>in</strong>ology, ss the possibility of falsification isprecisely that which makes a proposition scientific rather thanunscientific.In fact, it may not be the empiri¢al elements themselves whichgire <strong>Austrian</strong> work an "unsdentific" appearance, but <strong>in</strong>stead theway <strong>in</strong> which they ate <strong>in</strong>troduced. Rather than be<strong>in</strong>g simplyempirical assertions presented as part of the statement of aproblem from which logical implications ate then deduced (e.g.,"such-and-such ah elastidty is greater than one"), these propositionsabout learn<strong>in</strong>g must be <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> the middle of theanalytical process. One is not allowed to follow through with hislogic: the smooth work<strong>in</strong>gs of the logical deñvation ate <strong>in</strong>terruptedby the discovery and revision of <strong>in</strong>consistent plans.But this <strong>in</strong>troducdon of nondeduced hypotheses does notimply that "anyth<strong>in</strong>g goes"; the nature of these hypotheses isgoverned by the <strong>in</strong>trospecÜve and experiential evidence thatpeople learn from experience; that when confronted with planínconsistencies they tend to revise their plans <strong>in</strong> the direcfion ofconsistency, s4 The development of an "A.ustrian processanalysis" consists largely of ah exam<strong>in</strong>ation of how <strong>in</strong>dividualsare likely to <strong>in</strong>terpret market or nonmarket changes as evidencethat their own expectations must be revised. If different <strong>in</strong>consistendesare brought to light when they proceed to act on theserevised expectations, some further changes <strong>in</strong> plans (perhaps,this time, the plans of the other people) will be required. It isalways possible to advance some reasonable hypothesis about thenature of the plan changes.The role of symbolic mathematical analysis consists of thedeterm<strong>in</strong>ation of the spedfi_: condidons which would exist


34 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> Au_trian <strong>Economics</strong>under plan consistency. Whether there "really are" such consistentplans implicit <strong>in</strong> current expectaons but somehow unrecognized,deep below the level of awareness, 3s or whether (as isfar more likely) current expectations are fundamentally <strong>in</strong>consistentso that some hypothesis must be <strong>in</strong>vented about what planswould be like if they were consistent, this state of plan consistencyis the benchmark, the goal provid<strong>in</strong>g a general direction toentrepreneurial activity. But the process by which it is approachedmust be analyzed with unfaif<strong>in</strong>g sensivity to what theact<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong> the course of his actions and how he islikely to revise his expectations when he learns these th<strong>in</strong>gs.As an example of what difference all this makes, we couldconsider literally any process <strong>in</strong> time, especially a process wecould consider evolutionary. The monetary theor/of Mengerand Mises 3e provides an excellent example because Mises'conclusion--the regression theorem provides the solution tothe so-caUed monetary-value theory dichotomy stiU challeng<strong>in</strong>gtoday's monetary theorists.Start<strong>in</strong>g with a set of preferences based upon use values alone(although of course it is irrelevant to the mathematics what theyare based upon), we can logically derive a consistent static set ofrelative prices. Now suppose one <strong>in</strong>dividual learns or guessesthat he can use a certa<strong>in</strong> good asa trad<strong>in</strong>g medium and therebyacquire goods he could not otherwíse have obta<strong>in</strong>ed. His preferencefor this "trad<strong>in</strong>g good" rises above its pure use value. Onceaga<strong>in</strong> we can logically derive a new static price rector, based t_histime on his higher valuation (the cause of which, once aga<strong>in</strong>, isirrelevant). Now we can hypothesize that others observe this<strong>in</strong>termediate trad<strong>in</strong>g, or get the same idea <strong>in</strong>dependently, orobservethat our <strong>in</strong>ial <strong>in</strong>dividualis nowmorewil_l<strong>in</strong>gto acceptthe trade good than before, so their valuations of it rise for thisreason. Once aga<strong>in</strong>, we can deñve a new static price rector, thisone reveal<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong> the higher relative price of the traded good.As the leam<strong>in</strong>g process proceeds, the good becomes m0a_. Itsrelative pñce ("the price level') is tied by the gradual process oflearn<strong>in</strong>g to the barter relative price of the good from which itdeveloped.


The/lustrian Method 35The whole approach, which provides such fruitful <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>tomonetary evolution, is rooted <strong>in</strong> the question: why do <strong>in</strong>dividualspay more for a good than its use value? The answer is: theyhave learned, through observation and experience, of its acceptability<strong>in</strong> trade. However rigorous symbolic logical deductionmay be, it can tell us very little about such everyday evolutionaryprocesses.CONCLUSIONSThe differentia of the <strong>Austrian</strong> School is its focus upon theplans the action-relevant plans--of the <strong>in</strong>dividual rather thanupon his preferences. Preferences can be treated <strong>in</strong> an abstractfashion, as the preponderance of contemporary economictheory demonstrates, and such analyses make correct and beneficialuse of mathematical symbolism. But the study of plans andhow they are brought <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>terpersonal consistency requires amuch more sensitive read<strong>in</strong>g of the nature of human thoughtand action. Hypotheses about learn<strong>in</strong>g and changes <strong>in</strong> expectationscan be based only upon such <strong>in</strong>trospective philosophiz<strong>in</strong>gas the attribut<strong>in</strong>g of one's own thought processes to others andguess<strong>in</strong>g, aga<strong>in</strong> based upon one's own personal experiences andhypothetical behavior <strong>in</strong> similar circumstances, about thespecific purpose of the other's behavior) 7What of the big issues on which the School seems to offerspecial <strong>in</strong>sight? It ís tempt<strong>in</strong>g, at first, to try to "def<strong>in</strong>e" theSchool by simply list<strong>in</strong>g them: time preference, opportunitycost, bus<strong>in</strong>ess-cycle theory, monetary theory, imperfect <strong>in</strong>formation,entrepreneurship, capital theory, the role of time,analysis without symbolic mathematics. Time preferencé andopportunity cost are now part of conventional economics? s Butthe others are still special to Austñans, and the particular <strong>Austrian</strong>outlook arise: <strong>in</strong> each of these cases from the approachI have outl<strong>in</strong>ed here: emphasis upon action (not preferences),recognition that action takes time and that because plans may be<strong>in</strong>consistent the results of acfions are uncerta<strong>in</strong>, and will<strong>in</strong>gness


36 _ <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> ,4ustrian <strong>Economics</strong>to adopt a method appropriate to this ouflook.A pnce is paid for all of these <strong>in</strong>sights, and that pric.e is thepurely deductive method. This technique, the approach of today'smathematical economists, is superbly suited to analysis ofthe conditions under which known, given preferences ateconsistent--my static equilibriummbut only to that. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>Austrian</strong>sare not will<strong>in</strong>g to restrict their viewpo<strong>in</strong>t to the abstractlogic of preferences, they must be will<strong>in</strong>g to admit nondeducedhypotheses about plan revision <strong>in</strong>to their analyses.So which is better--neoclassical and mathematical economictheory, or <strong>Austrian</strong>ism? It is simply not true that all of theadvantages ate on one side: mathematical symbolism offers decidedadvantages when the problem is one of pure and complexlogical deduction, but the <strong>Austrian</strong> approach must be used whenthe problems are not of thís sort. And the), never are, <strong>in</strong> any realapplication J bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles, plann<strong>in</strong>g, monetary policy, theyare aU dynamic issues, swept under a rug ir_ contemporaryeconomics by a methodological bias íor pure deduction andaga<strong>in</strong>st any hypotheses hav<strong>in</strong>g to do with th<strong>in</strong>ldng.Hayek p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>ted the differences <strong>in</strong> 1942 when he noted that:... the most markedtendencyof the development ofscientifu: thought<strong>in</strong> modern times.... has been correctlydescribed as one toward theprogressiveelim<strong>in</strong>aUonof aU"anthropomorphic" explanations fromthe physicalsciences.Does this reallymean that we must refraín fromtreat<strong>in</strong>g man "anthropomorphically"--or is it not rather obvious, assoon as we put it<strong>in</strong> this way,that such ah extrapolationof past tendendesis absurd?ssThe differencebetweenphysicaland socialsciencesis not thattheformeris"<strong>in</strong>ducve" andthe latter"declucve." Ir ístl_t thephysicalsciencescanuse pure deductionbecausetheir objectscannot plan and learn. Neoclassical and mathematicaleconomistsuse the samemethodbyrestrict<strong>in</strong>gtheiranalysesto"men"whocannotplanor learnanymorethancanafriconlessplane, whereas the <strong>Austrian</strong> School builds its enfire _stem andmethod around thesedist<strong>in</strong>cvely human potential: :h<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g,plann<strong>in</strong>g, learn<strong>in</strong>g. Which is better? Each of us must answer. But


The Austr/an Method 37we must answer first: to what extent is economics a smdy ofman?NOTES1. By "neoclassical orthodoxy," I refer to the approach taken <strong>in</strong>C. E. Ferguson, The Neodassical Theory of Production and Dtribuñon(London: Cambñdge University Press, 1969) and dozens of <strong>in</strong>termediatemicroeconomic theory texthooks.2. Works taken to represent the <strong>Austrian</strong> School <strong>in</strong>clude especially:F. A. Hayek, lnd/v/dua//sm andEconomic Order (Chicago: Univ. ofChicago Press, 1948); Ludwig von Mises, HumanAction (Chicago: Regnery,1966); Israel M. Kirzner, Competition and Entrepreneurship(Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1973); Ludwig M.Lachmann, capitaland Its Structurt (London: LSE, 1956); Murray N. Rothbard, Man,Economy, and Stat¢ (Los Angeles: Nash, 1962).3. Mises, op. c/t., pp. 32-36; Rothbard, op. ctt., pp. 63-66; also,Mises, Epistemological Probl¢msof<strong>Economics</strong> (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton: Van Nostrand,1962), pp. 12-13.4. Rothbard, op. c/t., pp. 1, 63.5. On the many ways <strong>in</strong> which this word has been used, see FritzMachlup, "Equilibrium and Disequilibrium: Misplaced Concretenessand Disguised Polidcs," <strong>in</strong> Essays <strong>in</strong> Economic Sonantics (<strong>New</strong> York:Norton, 1967).6. On this issue, see F. A. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge,"repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Individualista and Economic Order, p. 40, pa.u/m.7. "The state of equilibrium as here understood is a state of completecompatibility of exante plans..." (F. A. Hayek, The Purs TluoU ofCapital [Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1941], p. 23).8. I do not know if this has ever been saidof my stadc conception,but ir certa<strong>in</strong>ly (and rightly) has been said of the dynamic equilibrium.It is important that we appreciate the dist<strong>in</strong>ction.9. F. A. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," p. 45; also bis "TheUse of Knowledge <strong>in</strong> Society," <strong>in</strong> lndividualim and Economic Order, p.91.10. "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," pp. 36-7.11. _The <strong>in</strong>troduction of time parameters <strong>in</strong>to the equations is nosolufion" 12. In a(Mises, comment Human on an .,la/on, earlierp. draft 356). of this paper, Professor Israe1M.Kirzner observed that the very clear<strong>in</strong>g of a market implies that theparticipants'short-run plans are brought <strong>in</strong>to consistency even while theoutcome permits mconsistencies <strong>in</strong>/ong-run plans (which I simply call


38 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>"plans') to rema<strong>in</strong>. I accept Kirzner's po<strong>in</strong>t, but it does not seem to<strong>in</strong>validate what follows.13. My phrase "abstract logic of preference" is obviously modeUedafter Hayek's "Pure Logic of Ghoice," but fits my purpose better.14. See especially: Mises, Human Action, pp. 350-57; Rothbard,Man, Economy, and State, pp. 277--80.15. George Stigler, Production and Distri_aztionTheories (<strong>New</strong> York:Macmillan, 1946), p. 181.16. Kirzner, Competition and Entrepreneurship, p. 68.17. Some of the follow<strong>in</strong>g is based upon Ayn Rand, "Introducfion toObjectivist Epistemology," which appeared <strong>in</strong> various issues of TheObjectivist between July 1966 and February 1967.18. Gerard Debreu, Theory of Va/ue (<strong>New</strong> York: Wiley, 1959).19. Bertrand Russell, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples ofMathemati_ (<strong>New</strong> York: Norton,n.c.d.), p. 3. Orig<strong>in</strong>ally published <strong>in</strong> 1903.20. Morris R. Cohen, A Preface to Logic (<strong>New</strong> York: Holt, 1944), pp.9-11.21. I have been <strong>in</strong>formed both by a philosopher and by amathematician that Russell failed <strong>in</strong> his lifelong attempt to prove theidentity between logic and mathematics.22. W. Stanley Jevons, The Theory ofPoli_al Ecoñomy, 5th ed. (<strong>New</strong>York: Kelley & Millman, Inc., 1957), p. 3.23. James R. <strong>New</strong>man, The Wor/d ofMathemat/cs, 4 vols. (<strong>New</strong> York:Simon and Schuster, 1956), III, p. 1830.24. Jevons, op. c/t., pp. 4-5.25. Several critics of this paper have po<strong>in</strong>ted out that words aresyrnbols which represent concepts. Of course I accept this, and urgethat my "symbols" <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as "second-ordersymbols," stand<strong>in</strong>g for words.26. One of more of these advantages have been daimed by manyeconomists. For one example, see Josef Hadar, Mathematical Theoo ofEconomi¢ Behavior (Read<strong>in</strong>g, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1971), pp. 5-7.27. Mr. Roger Garrison po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the verbal phrase expressescausality whil¢ the symbolic expression does not. His observation isabsolutely correct, and ir strengthens all of my subsequent po<strong>in</strong>ts aboutthe relatíve natures of mathematical and verbal analyses.28. Rand,op.di., pass/_.29. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," p. 33, pasdm.30. Richard von Mises, Probab///q 8tat/st/cs and Tr'_h (London:George Allen and Unw<strong>in</strong> Ltd., 1961), fwst published <strong>in</strong> 1928.31. See Mises, Human dct/on, op. dg., pp. 105-18; also, G. L. S.Shackle, Expectat/on/n <strong>Economics</strong> (Cambridge: University Presa, 1952),pp. 5, 109-27.32. See, for example, J. Hadar and W. IL Russell, URulesfor Order-


The <strong>Austrian</strong> Method 39<strong>in</strong>g Uncerta<strong>in</strong> Prospects," American EconomicRev/ew, LIX, No. 1(1969),pp. 25--34.33. Karl Popper, The Logic ofScientific Discovery(<strong>New</strong> York: Harperand Row, 1968), p. 40.34. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," p. 44, pass/m.35. It seems to me as ir those who argue that entrepreneurship isalways mov<strong>in</strong>g toward and never away from an equilibrium must adoptthis viewpo<strong>in</strong>t.36. Carl Menger, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of<strong>Economics</strong> (Glencoe: The Free Press,1950), pp. 25%71; Ludwig ron Mises, The Theory ofMoney and Credit(Irv<strong>in</strong>gton-on-Hudson, NY: Foundation for Economic Education,1971), pp. 97-123. See also Philip H. Wicksteed, The Common Sense ofPoli_al Economy, 2 vols. (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1967), I,pp. 136-37.37. See F. A. Hayek, "The Facts of the Social Sciences," <strong>in</strong> lnd/-vidualism and Economic Order, p. 66.38. It has been po<strong>in</strong>ted out to me that although these temas are now<strong>in</strong> common use, the}' are often not applied <strong>in</strong> the consistently subjectivist<strong>Austrian</strong> manner.39. Hayek, "The Facts of the Social Sciences," pp. 64-65.


Praxeologyand Econometñcs:A Critiqueof Positivist <strong>Economics</strong>Mario J. Rizzo<strong>New</strong> York UniversityThe ultimategoalofa positivescienceisthedevelopmentof a"theory"or "hypothesis" that yields valid and mean<strong>in</strong>gful (i.e., not truisc)predicfionsabout phenomena not yet observed._Although written a quarter of a cenmry ago, Milton Friedman's"The Methodology of Positive <strong>Economics</strong>" rema<strong>in</strong>s theimmediate philosophical justification for much of the contemporaryapproach to economics research. Nevertheless, the genera1po<strong>in</strong>tsraised <strong>in</strong> that essay were not new even at the time, butwere an <strong>in</strong>genious adaptation of some of the positivist argumentsof the 1930s, and the somewhat revisionist work of SirK,_I Popper. 2 Today, thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g positivism is clearly <strong>in</strong>retreat, ir not already defeated, <strong>in</strong> philosophical cirdes, but avariant of it rema<strong>in</strong>s quite vibrant <strong>in</strong> many of the social sciences,particularly economics. It is the task of this essay to presentacritique of"positive economics" and, at least, some <strong>in</strong>dications ofa viable alternative.40


Praxeology and Econometrics: A Critique of Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 41L PREDICTIONAS THE GOALFrom the posivist epistemological viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, is the open<strong>in</strong>gquotaUon to be taken as ah a pr/or/of ah empirical statement?Ira pr/or/, then it is a statement about how we shall use the terna"posive science" and is merely a l<strong>in</strong>guisUc stipulaUon. As such,one might equally weUchoose to stipulate some other mearñng.Ir empirical (/.e., a statement about what people have <strong>in</strong> factconsidered positive science), then, of course, it does not express anecessary truth and c0u/d be otherwise. But then for a long timethe Darw<strong>in</strong>ian theory of evolution yielded no predicons and yetwas considered scientifically acceptable, sFurthermore, Friedman makes no attempt to survey what hasbeen considered economic science to f<strong>in</strong>d out whether "predicon"has <strong>in</strong>deed been the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic. In fact, thereare many theoretical frameworks which generate no testablepredictions but are, nonetheless, considered part of economics.For example, it is frequenfly unclear what (predictive) relevancediscussions on the existence and stability of equilibrium undermany special assumpons (the empirical significance of which isunknown) have fora world which is never actually <strong>in</strong> equilibrium.Of course, one might claim that this is bad economics, andso the demarcaon is really between "good" and "bad" science.There is, however, no escape here, for it merely leaves unansweredthe queson: Why is nonpredictive economics badscience?Another possible escape might be to cláim that, while nonpredictivetheories ma}, be scienfific, they do not qualify as positivescience. To this we ate justified <strong>in</strong> merely reply<strong>in</strong>g: "So what?"What advantage is be<strong>in</strong>g claimed for positive science except thatits ultimate goal is prediction? In that case, we are back where westarted: Why must prediction be our goal?The goal of prediction might well obscure what has <strong>in</strong> factbeen considered a worthwhile airo of science: the explicaon andapprehension of necessary connections. Purely predictive"theory" is little more than a mnemonic device designed to relate


42 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dus_an <strong>Economics</strong>x to y. But the narre of that relafion may be unknown. TheBabylonian astronomical forecast<strong>in</strong>g techniques, which weremerely trial-and-error arithmetic calculations, are an example ofthis k<strong>in</strong>d of"black box" framework. 4 The pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of explanationrema<strong>in</strong>s unknown <strong>in</strong> the sense that the connection betweenthe <strong>in</strong>ifial and marg<strong>in</strong>al conditions (x_,x2, xs, etc.) and the consequence_) is not apprehended as necessary. The relation ischaracterized by an arbitrary givenness.But while it may be true that predíction cannot be considered asuffwient attribute for "scientific" theory, it still might be a necessaryone. However, we have already implicifly refuted this assertionby showíng that with<strong>in</strong> a positivist epistemologicalframework such necessity can be derived ordy from an essentiallyarbitrary prior stipulation.II. FdLSIFIABILITY AS THE CRITERION OF MEANING iThe emphasis on prediction asthe airo ofscience has its roots <strong>in</strong>a positivist criterion for the mean<strong>in</strong>gfulness of a statement. Tobe mean<strong>in</strong>gful, it has been said, a statement must be <strong>in</strong> a forrosuch that ir is <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple falsifiable by any observer. 5For example, let us take "the hypothesis that a substantial<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quantíty of money with<strong>in</strong> a relatively short periodis accompanied by a substantial <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> prices. ''eAside fromproblems concern<strong>in</strong>g data availability and the skills of the particular<strong>in</strong>vestigator, is this hypothesis falsifiable? For now, let us.my it is. Hence, the positivist would claim that this is a genu<strong>in</strong>elysdentific statement. In fact, the mean<strong>in</strong>g ofa hypothesis is idenfiedwith the relevant test ofits veracity. As Moritz Schlick tellsus, "the mean<strong>in</strong>g of a statement can be given only by <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>gthe way <strong>in</strong> which the truth of the statement is to be tested. "7 Ofcourse, thís cannot be literally true. If mean<strong>in</strong>g is idenfied withthe test, then what is be<strong>in</strong>g tested? But, ir there is a mean<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dependent of the test, then the posivist criterion falls <strong>in</strong> onitself, and unfals[fiable statements can be mean<strong>in</strong>gful. If we arenot to take Schlíck's statement literally, then it seems difficult to


Praxeolog3 and Econometrics:A Critique of Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 43f<strong>in</strong>d any coherent <strong>in</strong>terpretation of ir.But, of course, the whole concept of a unitary criterion formean<strong>in</strong>g is somewhat strange when viewed from with<strong>in</strong> apositivist framework. Once aga<strong>in</strong>: Is the proposition a pr/or/orempirical? A stipulated def<strong>in</strong>ition of "mean<strong>in</strong>g" to <strong>in</strong>clude falsifiabilityis not <strong>in</strong> itself impressive: One could have stipulatedotherwise. Viewed empirically, the criterion is immediately refutedby two thousand years of Western philosophy which claimsthat metaphysics and ontology are mean<strong>in</strong>gful pursuits.Aside from these issues, the falsifiability criterion loses muchof its <strong>in</strong>itial plausibility when the contradictory of a falsifiablestatement is exam<strong>in</strong>ed. 8 If we admitas falsifiable that aH<strong>in</strong>flationsare caused by <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> the money supply, then thecontradictory, 9some <strong>in</strong>flations are not caused by <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> themoney supply, is not falsifiable. If the latter hypothesis is meantto apply to the future aswell as to the past, one could alwaysclaimthat the <strong>in</strong>flation not caused by money supply <strong>in</strong>creases willappear if youjust search long and hard enough. No example ofmoney-supply-<strong>in</strong>duced <strong>in</strong>flation refutes the proposition, andwith a future, as well asa past, time horizon one has an <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itepool of <strong>in</strong>flations with<strong>in</strong> which to search for the complete absenceof nonmonetary <strong>in</strong>flations.Consequently, the falsifiability criterion <strong>in</strong>volves a majortransformation <strong>in</strong> our system of logic: Although a given statementmay be mean<strong>in</strong>gful (or scientific), the negation of thatstatement is mean<strong>in</strong>gless (or unscientific). 10A possible route of escape from this argment might appear tobe the claim that while, stricfly speak<strong>in</strong>g, the statement that some<strong>in</strong>flations are not caused by <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> the money supply is notfalsifiable, evidence could be accumulated which would render irmore or less "probable." Alas, this is no escape either. The truthor falsity ofany statement is nota random variable like tosses of aco<strong>in</strong>, and hence a frequential <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the "probability"concept is impossible here. So the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the term "probable"canonly <strong>in</strong>volve asubjective degree of belief. This amounts toa radical transformation of the whole positivist framework. Thecñteñon now becomes: Any statement which could be rendered


44 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>more or less "probable" by reference to empirical evidence is amean<strong>in</strong>gful statement. But then this is a psychological--ratherthan a logical--cñterion. Any proposition for which our subjectiredegree of belief could be <strong>in</strong>creased or decreased by _evidence"is mean<strong>in</strong>gful. Worse still, what k<strong>in</strong>ds of statements doesthis criterion exclude? Probably none. It would seem that humanbe<strong>in</strong>gs are not imag<strong>in</strong>ative enough to conceive of propositionsthat have no relafionship at aU to the world. Hence, for anynontautologous (<strong>in</strong> the narrowest sense) statement, it is possibleto f<strong>in</strong>d empirical "evidence" that has s0me bear<strong>in</strong>g on its truth orfalsity. Hence, aU statements are mean<strong>in</strong>gful. If this is so, thenthe orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>tent of the positivist criterion crumbles.Any statement of degree-of-belief probability does not fitcomfortably with<strong>in</strong> the positivist framework. Statements such as"that some <strong>in</strong>flations are not monetarily <strong>in</strong>duced is 'probable'"are, of course, neither verifiable nor falsifiable <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.More importantly, they do not carry with them any element of<strong>in</strong>tersubjective testability (which was such an important goal). Astipulation that certaln k<strong>in</strong>ds of evidence wiU be <strong>in</strong>terpreted asmak<strong>in</strong>g a statement "probable" is no real solu6on. This makesthe criterion of mean<strong>in</strong>gfulness (or the demarcafion betweenscience and non-science) purely conventional.III. CRITIQUE OF ECONOMETRICS 11Ceteris paribus predicfion is prediction of "stylized facts": xleads toy/f other factors are held constant. But s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> general,they aren't, we are not predict<strong>in</strong>g a "real-world" event. Rather,we are predict<strong>in</strong>g a hypothetical consequence.To subject the hypothesis to potential falsification, we mustcontrol for the other relevant variables. Suppose we try to do thisby us<strong>in</strong>g multiple regression analysis. Then:1. How do we know when we have adequately controlled forextra-economic factors? (There is no a pr/or/assurance thateconomic factors are the only ones that matter <strong>in</strong> a givensimation.) This would require a theory of the <strong>in</strong>teraction


Praxeology and Econometrics: A Critique oOf Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 45between economic and non-economic variables. How dowe go about subject<strong>in</strong>g this to falsify<strong>in</strong>g tests?2. How do we test the theory which enables us to determ<strong>in</strong>ethe other economic factors that must be held constant <strong>in</strong>order to isolate the effect of x?From the positivist framework the problem is crucial. Howcould we ever know that the (auxiliary) hypothesis, i.e., all otherrelevant factors have been held constant, has been falsified? Weobviously cannot claim that it has been refuted ifx does not result<strong>in</strong> y because it is that very relationship which is undergo<strong>in</strong>gtesUng <strong>in</strong> the first place. It is clear that, unless we have additionalhypotheses about the effects of each of the to-be-held-constantvafiables on y, we shall not be able to subject the crucial ceterisparibus clause to refutation. Furthermore, these auxiliaryhypotheses (or perhaps a s<strong>in</strong>gle hypothesis s<strong>in</strong>ce it is their totaleffect with which we are concerned) must be <strong>in</strong>dependent of thecentral one <strong>in</strong> the sense that the falsification of the former mustbe <strong>in</strong>dependent of the falsification of the latter. Now, ifwe claimthat we really don't care if the ceteris paribus clause is "true"because all that counts is the predictive ability of the centralhypothesis, then we have gotten ourselves <strong>in</strong>to a new quagmire.First, why have ceterisparibus clauses at all? Second, what are wefalsify<strong>in</strong>g if, <strong>in</strong> fact, x does not result <strong>in</strong> y? Certa<strong>in</strong>ly not thehypothesis as stated. Suppose the "evidence" fails to refute ourhypothesis; then what have we corroborated? Aga<strong>in</strong>, not theoñg<strong>in</strong>al hypothesis because the apparent-consistency of the datawith the framework may be illusory, be<strong>in</strong>g entirely due to the"proper" variation of the factors which were supposed to beconstant. Third, this whole viewpo<strong>in</strong>t re<strong>in</strong>states the "black box"approach to science and hence vitiates the airo of rational explanation.Ir is quite possible to claim that, although the centralhypothesis must be falsif'mble <strong>in</strong> order to be mean<strong>in</strong>gful orscienUfic, the ceterisparibus dause need not be. All that is needed<strong>in</strong> the latter case--it might be asserted--is a k<strong>in</strong>d of educatedjudgment or verstehen. While this might be permissible with<strong>in</strong>other epistemological frameworks, ir will not be adequate to


46 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>support the daims of positivism. If we can say that "all otherrelevant factors have been held constant" without falsifiabilityand still can be mak<strong>in</strong>g a mean<strong>in</strong>gful empirical statement, whycan't we do the same <strong>in</strong> the case of "x causes y," the centralhypothesis? If we can (which seems likely given the <strong>in</strong>itial admission),then once aga<strong>in</strong> the criterion of positive science crumbles.IV. MAXIMIZATIONUnder the <strong>in</strong>fluence of the "marg<strong>in</strong>alist revolution,"economics has become a discipl<strong>in</strong>e devoted <strong>in</strong> major part to thef'md<strong>in</strong>g of functional maxima and m<strong>in</strong>ima. The <strong>in</strong>dividual consumeror producer is assumed to maximize or m<strong>in</strong>imize someth<strong>in</strong>gand, from this postulated behavior, testable implicationsare drawn. It is important to keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that the maximizationbehavior itself is not subject to falsification, because it serves notasa substantive hypothesis but as a superstructure which givesrational coherence to the falsifiable implications.Any particular <strong>in</strong>stance of concrete behavior may be"expla<strong>in</strong>ed" or rationalized <strong>in</strong> terms of maximization (orm<strong>in</strong>imization) of some appropriate quantity (e.g., utility, wealth,etc.). S<strong>in</strong>ce maximization is fundamentaUy a characteristic of<strong>in</strong>tention (this the positivists won't admit), any concrete behaviormay be viewed as/f it were the maximization of someth<strong>in</strong>g. Thishas serious implications.Suppose we wish to test not the applicability of a spedficeconomic hypothesis to a given area of human behavior (say,marriage), but, rather, the validity of view<strong>in</strong>g this k<strong>in</strong>d of behavioras an <strong>in</strong>stance of economic or maximiz<strong>in</strong>g acfivityperse. Inother words, we don't care whether a particular maximiz<strong>in</strong>gmodel is appropriate, but we ask whether this is an example ofmaximiz<strong>in</strong>g behavior at all.It might be claimed that this formulation of the problemmakes no sense. After all, we are never test<strong>in</strong>g economics ormaximiz<strong>in</strong>g behavior as sucia, but only specific hypotheses ofwhatever k<strong>in</strong>d. This, of course, misses the crucial po<strong>in</strong>t of the


Praxeology and Econometrics:A Critique of Pos_ivist <strong>Economics</strong> 47need to decide upon a research framework <strong>in</strong> advance of specific_5.Is the statement "this is ah example or <strong>in</strong>stance of maximiz<strong>in</strong>gbehavior" a mean<strong>in</strong>gful and scientific one? Clearly not. S<strong>in</strong>ce theset of possible falsifiers is empty, any behavior can be"expla<strong>in</strong>ed" <strong>in</strong> terms of maximiz<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g. TM But thehypothesis, "this is an <strong>in</strong>stance of maximiz<strong>in</strong>g sales," can berefuted by appropriate behavior, and so is a mean<strong>in</strong>gful statement.This produces a curious paradox. The more generalstatement about maximization is mean<strong>in</strong>gless (or unscientific),but the more particularized ver$ion of it constitutes a positivescienfic hypothesis.Some authors have tried to escape t.his problem by claim<strong>in</strong>gthat the (maximiz<strong>in</strong>g) framework can be refuted by compañsonto an empirically richer and more general alternativeframework. Indeed, Lakatos has gone so lar as to say, "There isno falsificafion before the emergence of a better theory. ''13Thismeans, <strong>in</strong> effect, that if two hypothese: one maximiz<strong>in</strong>g andthe other non-maximiz<strong>in</strong>g--both equaHy weH "expla<strong>in</strong>" a particularcase of economic behavior, then the one which is part of amore general approach, the specific applications of which havebeen corroborated <strong>in</strong> other cases, is to be preferred. This, however,<strong>in</strong>troduces a subtle and important change <strong>in</strong> the falsifiabilitycriterion. No longer is a statement mean<strong>in</strong>gful or scientific byvirtue ofás empirical content but, rather, by the overall corroboratedempirical content ofother statements to which it is <strong>in</strong> somesense related. It is hard to recognize this as an epistemologicalcriterion rather than as an aesthetic one. 14Nevertheless, by some<strong>in</strong>explicable tra<strong>in</strong> of thought, a statement becomes mean<strong>in</strong>gfulbecause ofits relation to other similar statements which, hav<strong>in</strong>gbeen corroborated, are themselves mean<strong>in</strong>gful by virtue of theirrelation to, say, the former hypothesis. (Apparently, there issome k<strong>in</strong>d of "simultaneous determ<strong>in</strong>ation of mean<strong>in</strong>g" argumentunderly<strong>in</strong>g all of this.)Let us look at this problem <strong>in</strong> a slightly different manner. Themaximh<strong>in</strong>g framework "proves" its worth, we might say, bypredict<strong>in</strong>g everytlf<strong>in</strong>g that the alternative framework does, plus


48 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> Economi¢s ia little more. 15Hence, ir acts, <strong>in</strong> a sense, asa falsifier of the Jahernative perspective.This formulation does not seem very conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g. Ineconomics, at least, it would be surpris<strong>in</strong>g ir, my, the maximiz<strong>in</strong>gframework predicted literaUy all of the facts predicted by thealternative. Normally, I suspect, the "better" framework wouldpredict some of these facts, and some addional ones. Furthermore,compet<strong>in</strong>g frameworks frequently do not even ask thesame questions. Why, then, should they be judged on whetherthey gire the same amwers (plus a little more)?AU this aside, ir is hard to see why, from a purely positivistepistemological perspective, consideraons of the framework'ssuccess <strong>in</strong> other particular <strong>in</strong>stances should affect the mean<strong>in</strong>gfulnessor scientific chamcter of a hypothesis <strong>in</strong> any givenspecific case.!IV. EVIDENCEUntil this po<strong>in</strong>t, we llave implidtly considered as self-evidentthe answer to the quesáon: "What shall count as evidence for andaga<strong>in</strong>st a hypothesis?" How do we recognize a falsify<strong>in</strong>g or corroborat<strong>in</strong>gresult? The answer is, <strong>in</strong>deed, far from self-evident.In fact, this issue poses some crucial problems for the posiUvistapproach, which, we shall contend, it is <strong>in</strong>capable of handng.A hypothesis relates a vañable x to a vañabley, cet¢risparibus.Let us assume that the ceterispa_us dause has been corrob_rated adequately; then what would amount to falsification of thehypothesis? To be more specific, hypothesize "that a substantial<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quanty of money.., is accompanied by a substantial<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> prices. "ls In order to test this statement, wemust have some cñteria by which we can relate the theoreticalterms "money" and "prices" with their empiñcal counterparts.This is the crux of the problem, t7Someth<strong>in</strong>g must po<strong>in</strong>t the way from theory to the relevant"facts"; we need what shall be called "referennal statements." In


Praxeology and Econometrics:A Critique of Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 49our iUustration, examples of referential statements might be:"The empiñcal counterpart of theoretical 'money' isM¿'; or, "by'prices' is rneant the consumer pñce <strong>in</strong>dex." The need for referentia!statements <strong>in</strong> applied economics is not restricted to theposivist variant of the science. What is peculiar to posifivisteconomics, however, is a problem aris<strong>in</strong>g out of the epistemologicalstatus ofsuch statements. Ifthey ale to be considered apr/or/,then (from a posivist viewpo<strong>in</strong>t) we are merely talk<strong>in</strong>g abouthow we use words, and no l<strong>in</strong>k between the theoretical constructsand "empiñcal reality" is established. Then it must be establishedvia falsifiable hypotheses. Yet this is ah impossibility. (Referenalstatements make no predictions; they do not say, for exampie,that an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> x results <strong>in</strong> ah <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> y. Hence nopredictions can be falsified.)Now it is possible to recast the referential statements <strong>in</strong> such away that the), will be refutable: "If the criteria of apply<strong>in</strong>g thetheoretical construct'money' are, <strong>in</strong> fact, applied, thenM_ will befound to be the appropriate empirical counterpart." Clearly, thiswon't work because ir requires that we know the criteriapr/0r tothe test<strong>in</strong>g procedure which was to establish (orat least corroborate)these criteria <strong>in</strong> the first place.Test<strong>in</strong>g the referential statements is impossible unless we alreadyknow the criteria of apply<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical terms. If wealready know these (<strong>in</strong> any mean<strong>in</strong>gful way), then test<strong>in</strong>g isurmecessary. But, from a positivist perspective, it is clearly impossibleto have any mean<strong>in</strong>gful knowledge about the real wofldwhich is given a pr/on.One might attempt to obviate these difficulties by choos<strong>in</strong>gempirical variables so as to present the particular hypothesis <strong>in</strong>its best light. (Choos<strong>in</strong>g a def<strong>in</strong>ition of the money supply so as tobest predict GNP ís an example of this.) Unless one is attempngto <strong>in</strong>sulate a hypothesis from refutation, there seems to be nodear reason for do<strong>in</strong>g this. If empiñcal variables were chosen soas to present the hypothesis <strong>in</strong> its worst light, and ir stiUrema<strong>in</strong>edunrefuted, would we not then have more fuUy corroborated it?In any event, the outcome of a potential test should not be thedeterm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g factor <strong>in</strong> whether ir is performed.


50 - <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>VI. THE LOGICAL CHAtL,ICTER OF PR/IXEOLOGYThe epistemological status of praxeology (which is identical toeconomics very broadly conceived) is a subject of considerablemisunderstand<strong>in</strong>g and confusion. With<strong>in</strong> a positivist frameworkthe d airns of praxeology make no sense. Knowledge is either apr/or/and certa<strong>in</strong> but not perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to "reality," or it is empiricaland uncerta<strong>in</strong> but dearly embedded <strong>in</strong> the "real" world. Anexam<strong>in</strong>ation of the logical character of praxeology reveals thesecategories to be totally <strong>in</strong>appropriate. Praxeology daims to presentknowledge which is at once both absolutely certa<strong>in</strong> andempifical. This is the paradox which we shall have to expla<strong>in</strong>.Praxeological theorems or deduaions are based upon thefundamental self-evident axiom, i.e., man acts or, what is thesame, engages <strong>in</strong> purposeful behavior. The question at issue,then, is: In what precise sense is this axiom "self-evident," andwhat does it say about the world?The aaion axiom is empirical <strong>in</strong> the sense fhat it is derivedfrom <strong>in</strong>ner experience or immediate <strong>in</strong>trospeaion. It is sc/ent/ficallyempirical because it passes the <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity test: Theexperience is universal and hence, <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, can be assentedto by the observers and the observed alike. Hence, the fact thatthe axiom is based on <strong>in</strong>trospection cannot open the praxeologistto the charge that bis deduaions are of a purely personal andunscientific character. We are deal<strong>in</strong>g here with"universal <strong>in</strong>nerexperience. "18An attempt to deny the action axiom <strong>in</strong>volves us <strong>in</strong> blatantself-contradicfion. Denial consists of the use of means (argu-• ments) to achieve ends (condusiom) and, hence, purposefulbehavior. In addition, the assumption that men act is a necessaryprerequisite for the e,,Astence of a scientífic community. Arguments,attempts to conv<strong>in</strong>ce other researchers of a differentview, etc., are all fundamem_!!y based on a conception of scientiststhemselves as engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> purpmeful behavior. To separateout the scientists, and say that while the observers engage <strong>in</strong>acfion and the observed do not, would seem to be an arti_ficialityfor whic_ no supportcould be adduced.


Praxeology and Econometrics:A Critique of Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 51While the action axiom is empirical and self-evident, it is, <strong>in</strong> asense, also a pr/o_ 19 That man acts is logically pñor to anyconcrete manifestation of action. In fact, one must have a conceptof action before one can even recognize action <strong>in</strong> the so-calledreal world. The action axiom is derived from absolutely certa<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ner experience but is a pr/or/to historical phenomena. History,asa complex of human behavior, is analyzed and <strong>in</strong>terpreted byuse of praxeological theorems which are, <strong>in</strong> tum, derived fromrelatively simple expeñence.Praxeology concems theforro of acon qua acUon.Just becauseit is not about this specific action or that specific action does notmean that it concerns itself only with words. The category ofaction is about every action that has and wiUtake place empti_dof its specific means-ends content. As sucia, it is no less about"reality" than any generally recognized empiñcal statement. Al1statements about the wofld <strong>in</strong>volve some degree of abstraction,so itis not the abstraction of praxeological deductions which is atíssue. What may be of concern is that they are <strong>in</strong>capable offalsification. In pr<strong>in</strong>ciple the statement "man acts" cannot befalsified s<strong>in</strong>ce we cannot conceive of the contrary. This is notbecause we are simply deaf<strong>in</strong>g with an arbitrary stipulated def<strong>in</strong>itionof "man" as an act<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g. Rather, it is because ouracqua<strong>in</strong>tance with empirical manas act<strong>in</strong>g is both so <strong>in</strong>timateanŒnecessary that a purely react<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g would not be human<strong>in</strong> the only sense we can conceive. The concepts of purposefulbehavior and man are l<strong>in</strong>ked so tighfly not because of arbitrar),def<strong>in</strong>ition, but because they are necessariIy l<strong>in</strong>ked <strong>in</strong> empiñcalreality. Our language reflects someth<strong>in</strong>g real, yet necessary.Praxeology as applied to history (broadly viewed as to <strong>in</strong>dudecurrent history) does not depend merely on deductions from theaction axiom. It requires subsidiary assumptíons deñved empirically<strong>in</strong> order to delimit the scope of a praxeological system. 2oFor e___mple, we do not want to develop monetary theory <strong>in</strong> aworld without money. Now, the subsidiary empirical assumptionsate not seff-evident or necessañly true like the actionaxiom. These assumptiom could conceivably be otherwise, althoughthey may be virtually certa<strong>in</strong> (e.g., the existence of <strong>in</strong>di-


52 " <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>rect exchange). Insolar as they are uncerta<strong>in</strong>, so too is theapplicabRity of the praxeological _tatements we can make us<strong>in</strong>gthem.To <strong>in</strong>crease the quantitative def<strong>in</strong>iteness of relationships <strong>in</strong>applied praxeology (economic history), we require <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gspedfidty of the subsidiary assumpáons: These assumptionsmust become both more numerous and more precise. This, ofcolarse, results <strong>in</strong> condusions which ate no 1onge_"apodicticaUycerta<strong>in</strong>. In our term<strong>in</strong>ology, we refer to applied praxeologicaltheory as hypotheses (to <strong>in</strong>dicate their tentative nature). Hence,while economíc theory is immutable and necessary, economichypothesesate changeable and could be otherwise. The view thateconomic theoryis a body of tentative statements about the world(subject to refutation) is implicitly the position that knowledge ofsocial reality is conf<strong>in</strong>ed solely to historical knowledge."VIL THE ROLE OF ECONOMETRICSWhile ir might appear as if econometrics has no role <strong>in</strong> theadvancement of economic theory (def<strong>in</strong>ed as deductiom fromthe action axiom), this is not quite accurate (although ir mayserve asa tolerable first approximaUon of the truth). StatisUcalregulariUes can be the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for a purely theoretical<strong>in</strong>vestigation, <strong>in</strong>solar as they raise questions to which thepraxeologist addresses himself. But the connecfion here is moresuggestivethan logical.The central tole of econometrics is <strong>in</strong> the application ofeconomic theory to the complex phenomena of history (currentor pasO. There ate two quesons on which econometric workcan shed light:1. To what extent is a given (historical) <strong>in</strong>stance of humanbehavior explicable by reference to purposeful activity, i.e.,how much does a praxeological hypothesis expla<strong>in</strong>?2. What is the magnitude of the effect of x on the wholecomplexphenomenon,y, at somespecificpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time?


Praxeologyand Econometrics:.4 Critiqueof Positivist<strong>Economics</strong> 53With regard to the first question, it isimportant to understandthat while man necessarily acts, it does not follow that he alwaysacts,i.e.,that he neverengages <strong>in</strong> automatic response to stímuli orsome other ldnd of nonpurposive behavior. To what extent is agiven histoñcaJ phenomenon the restflt of some bl<strong>in</strong>d emotionaim<strong>in</strong>g at noth<strong>in</strong>g? The answer to this cannot be givenapr/or/.__On the second quesfion, it is important to keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d thatpraxeological reason<strong>in</strong>g per se cannot reveal quantave relaons(or even qualitative ones, when many conflict<strong>in</strong>g forcesateoperave) <strong>in</strong> economic history. Forthis, stastical <strong>in</strong>vestigaonsare our only recourse. However, it is important not to <strong>in</strong>terpreteconometrically derived relations as great constants applicableto aUsituaons at all times. These relaons are not theoreticalbut merely historicaL To extrapolate the latter to the formerrequires ah <strong>in</strong>ductíve leap that we ate not prepared to take.In answer<strong>in</strong>g both of these questions, econometric evidencecannot, of course, gire us the same certa<strong>in</strong>ty as praxeologicalreason<strong>in</strong>g. Answers <strong>in</strong> economic history must always be uncerta<strong>in</strong>.Nevertheless, this is not the uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty of economictheory; rather, it is the uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> the application ofa structure (<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the forra of action) upon historicotemporalactionswith specific content. The application of theoryto history is not ah exercise <strong>in</strong> deduction; it necessitates the use ofjudgment or understand<strong>in</strong>g (verstehen)<strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the relevantvariables and the appropriate means of measur<strong>in</strong>g them.A carearis, however, <strong>in</strong> order. Econometrics ought to be onlyone tool <strong>in</strong> the apprehension of historical phenomena. Clearly,not all issues of <strong>in</strong>terest are quantifiable. If we try to expla<strong>in</strong>complex phenomena only by reference to quantifiable variables,then we are likely to be throw<strong>in</strong>g away some <strong>in</strong>formation that wedo, <strong>in</strong>deed, have. Another danger is that we shall beg<strong>in</strong> to identifyrealitywith statistical data when, <strong>in</strong> fact, it isjust one aspect ofreality, a particular transformation of more elementary experience.There is no reason whatever why a specific wayof víew<strong>in</strong>ghistory ought to be identified with history itself or, what isworse,with the whole of soc_h]reality.


54 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> Austrían <strong>Economics</strong>VIIL CONCLUSIONS __ND UNRESOLVED QUESTIONSThe purpose of thís paper is primarily to presenta criticalanalysis of"positive economics" and only secondarily to exam<strong>in</strong>ethe praxeologíc alternative. It is <strong>in</strong> the latter area that a great dealof work needs to be done. At this po<strong>in</strong>t, however, a number ofcondud<strong>in</strong>g observatíons might be made:1. A thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g positivist approach to economics cannotbe consistently pursued. The positivist framework createscerta<strong>in</strong> problems that ate <strong>in</strong>soluble from with<strong>in</strong> thatframework.2. Although praxeology is concerned with action qua action,/.e., ahistorical and emptied of specific means-ends content,it is still about reality. The forro of action is no less real thanany of the other abstractions necessary <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g generallyrecognized empirical judgments.3. A crucial problem <strong>in</strong> praxeology is the epistemologicalnature of applied praxeology (economic history). How isthe transition from theoretical constructs to empiricalcounterparts to be made? Verstehen is too vague an answer.4. Does a praxeologist do economic history differently from aposiUve economíst? If so, <strong>in</strong> what way?In discuss<strong>in</strong>g some of the more philosophical issues ofeconomics, it has been our <strong>in</strong>tention to show that the day-to-dayissues of explanation, hypothesiz<strong>in</strong>g, and testir_g do not go on <strong>in</strong>a philosophical vacuum. We do not have a choice as to whetherwe shall make methodological decisions. Our choice, rather, íswhether we shall make them explicitly, exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the variousimplicaáons and subtleties of mean<strong>in</strong>g, or whether we shallmake themimplicifly, bl<strong>in</strong>d to ever'fih<strong>in</strong>g but technique.REFERENCES1. Milton Friedman, "The Methodology of PosiUve<strong>Economics</strong>,"Essays<strong>in</strong> Positive<strong>Economics</strong>(Chicago, 195S), p. 7.


Praxeology and Econometrics: d Critiq_ of Positivist <strong>Economics</strong> 552. See especially Karl Popper, Log/k der Forschung (Vienna, 1935).The English translation is Karl Popper, The Logic ofScientific Discovery(London, 1962). Other relevant works ate Rudolf Camap, Philosophyand Logical Syntax (London, 1935) and A. J. Ayer, Language, T_h andLog/c, 2nd edition (London, 1946).3. Stephen Toulm<strong>in</strong>,Foresight and Understand<strong>in</strong>g: AnEnquiry <strong>in</strong>to theAiras ofScience (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton, 1961), p. 28.4. op._., p.28.5. Some philosophers, such as Popper, make this the criterion ofscience, and not mean<strong>in</strong>gfulness. However, such a shift does not affectthe ma<strong>in</strong> argument sínce we then must return to the question ofwhy wedef<strong>in</strong>e "science" the way we do. See section I above.6. Friedman, p. 11.7. Moritz Schlick, GesammelteAufs_tze, 1926-1936 (Vienna, 1938),p. 179 as cited <strong>in</strong> Brand Blanshard, Reason and Analysis (LaSalle, IIl<strong>in</strong>ois,1964), p. 224.8. Blanshard, p. 229.9. The word "contradictory" is here used <strong>in</strong> its technical sense.Hence, the statement "no <strong>in</strong>flations are caused by <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> themoney supply" is not the contradictory of the statement <strong>in</strong> the text. This,is because if"no <strong>in</strong>flations are caused by <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> the money supply'isla/se, then e/ther "some <strong>in</strong>flaUons ate (not) caused .... "is true or "all<strong>in</strong>flaUons are caused .... "is true. "A and O are mumal contradictories,or negaUom:A is true ifand only ifO ís false." On this see W. V. Qu<strong>in</strong>e,Methods ofL0g/c, 3rd edition (<strong>New</strong> York, 1972), p. 84.10. Blanshard, p. 229.11. The general coneeption of this and the next section is drawnfrom Mart<strong>in</strong> Hollis and Edward Nell, RañonM E¢onomic Man (Carobridge,England, 1975), pass/m. However, <strong>in</strong> many cases the tra<strong>in</strong> ofreason<strong>in</strong>g is different (the reader should beware of assum<strong>in</strong>g that thesame po<strong>in</strong>t is be<strong>in</strong>g made), while <strong>in</strong> others the árgument is expanded.12. In a somewhat different context, Friedman says, "Ifthere is onehypothesis that is consistent with the available evidence, there arealways an <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite number that are." Friedman, p. 9.13. Imre Lakatos, "Falsificadon and the Methodology of S.ci'endficResearch Programmes," Criticism and the C,rowth of Knowledge, ImreLakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds. (Cambridge, England, 1970), p. 119.14. Friedman, pp. 10, 20.15. Lakatos, p. 118.16. Friedman, p. 11.17. Much of what follows <strong>in</strong> this section is from Hollis and NeU,chapter 4. However, the reader should note that our referent/al statementsare not the "criterial statements" of Hollis and NelL


56 " <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>18. Murray N. Rothbard, "In Defense of 'Extreme Apriorism',"$outhern EconomicJournal (January 1957), p. 318.19. Ludwig ron Mises, Human Act/on, 3rd edition (Chicago, 1966),chapter II.20. Op. cit., pp. 64-66.21. For some ver), prelim<strong>in</strong>ary observations on these issues, seeMurray N. Rothbard, "Praxeology: Reply to Mr. Schuller," AmericanEconomic.Review (December 1951), p. 945.


R<strong>Economics</strong> and ErrorIsrael M. Kirzner<strong>New</strong> York UniversityThe rifle of this paper, it may correctly be surmised, owessometh<strong>in</strong>g to the rifle of the famous 1937 paper of ProfessorHayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge. ''_ There lies, Hayekacknowledged, ah <strong>in</strong>tentional ambiguity <strong>in</strong> the title of thatpaper: we are <strong>in</strong> fact to learn <strong>in</strong> his paper that the knowledgewhich economic analysís conveys depends crucially upon propositionsabout the knowledge possessed by the different membersof society. The not dissimilar ambiguity <strong>in</strong> the rifle of thepresent paper may, one ventures to hope, suggest that a gooddeal of erroneous thought <strong>in</strong> economics has its source <strong>in</strong> confusionconcern<strong>in</strong>g the nature and role of error<strong>in</strong> the actions of thedifferent members of society. It is the purpose of this paper todispel at least some portion of this confusion. If, <strong>in</strong> the course ofthis attempt, some <strong>in</strong>cidental light can be thrown, as well,on theproblems raised by Hayek <strong>in</strong> his '37 paper, this will be seen toreflect (once aga<strong>in</strong> not accidentally) the symmetrical ambiguitiesembedded <strong>in</strong> the titles of the two papers.EFFICIENCY, WASTE, AND ERROREconomists have traditionally been concerned with issues relatedto effidency. Ineffident action occurs when one places.oneself <strong>in</strong> a position which one views as less desirable than anequany available alternative state of affairs. Inefficiency cantherefore not be thought of except as the result of ah error, a57


58 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>mistake, an <strong>in</strong>correct and wrong move. Much of the work of themodern economist has, <strong>in</strong> fact, the declared aim of avoid<strong>in</strong>gerrors, of achiev<strong>in</strong>g efficiency. At the same time, however, as hedirects his energies toward the obviation of error, the contemporaryeconomist is frequently to be found pursu<strong>in</strong>g his analysison the assumption that men do not, and will not, ever faU <strong>in</strong>toerror. "Waste," declares Stigler <strong>in</strong> a recent note, "is error with<strong>in</strong>the framework of modern economic analysis, and ir wiU notbecome a useful concept until we have a theory of error."2Modern economic analysis, we are to understand, lack<strong>in</strong>g atheory of error, can and does proceed only by assum<strong>in</strong>g it away:error and waste simply have no place <strong>in</strong> the world of economictheory. It is this position that we wish to exam<strong>in</strong>e cñUcally. Is itreally the case, we must ask, that economic theory requires us toabstract completely from the phenomenon of error? Asa prelim<strong>in</strong>arystep toward the consideration of this question, it isnecessary first to review a number of discussiomto be found <strong>in</strong>the economic literature <strong>in</strong> which the possibility of error has beenseriously canvassed.MISES, MARKSMEN,AND MISTAKESIn a passage <strong>in</strong> which he is concerned to expla<strong>in</strong> that humanaction is always rational (<strong>in</strong> the sense of be<strong>in</strong>g designed to atta<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite ends), Mises considers the objection that men makemistakes. This does not, Mises po<strong>in</strong>ts out, constimte irrationalíty."To make mistakes <strong>in</strong> pursu<strong>in</strong>g one's ends is a widespreadhuman weakness .... Error, <strong>in</strong>efficiency, and failure must not beconfused with irrationality. He who shoots wants, asa rule, to hitthe mark. If he misses it, he is not 'irratio, ar; he is a poormarksman. The doctor who chooses the wrong method to treat apatient is not irrational; he may be an <strong>in</strong>competent physician....-s The impfication here is that the <strong>in</strong>competent physician andthe poor marksman may <strong>in</strong>deed make mistakes and errors.RaUonal Misesian human actors ate human enough to err. But itis alear that these errors are not <strong>in</strong>comistent with the positíon


<strong>Economics</strong>and Error 59(exclud<strong>in</strong>gerrors) cited earlier as taken by SUgler. In fact thereason why these are not errors <strong>in</strong> the sense relevant to theStigler position, is entirely similar to the reason whythese errorsdo not, for Mises,constitute irrationality. The mistakes made bythe ill-tra<strong>in</strong>ed medic do not representa failure by hito to atta<strong>in</strong>that which ir is with<strong>in</strong> his power to atta<strong>in</strong>. His failure símplyreflects lack of the necessary quality of <strong>in</strong>put. An error (<strong>in</strong> theStigler sense) occursonly _íhen ah <strong>in</strong>put is used <strong>in</strong> a waythat failsto produce what that <strong>in</strong>put can produce. When a poormathematid_n makes a mistake <strong>in</strong> añthmetic 4 he is not, therefore,maldng an error; nor is the failure by a poor marksman tohit the markan error. Ir is notan error fora physicallyweak manto be unable to lift a heavy weight. Nor is ir an error, <strong>in</strong> therelevant sense, when one unschooled <strong>in</strong> medic<strong>in</strong>e fails to prescribetheproper treatment fora patient, (To be sure, it may bethat the <strong>in</strong>competent physicían, <strong>in</strong>different mathematician, andpoor markshaanought not to waste their time [and their patients'lives] by engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> tasks for which they are so def'mitely illsuited.But of course Mises is concerned with the mistake thephysician makes <strong>in</strong> the course of the pracfice of medic<strong>in</strong>e, notwith the possible error of his attempt<strong>in</strong>g to practice medídnealtogether.)CROCE, TECHNICAL ERROR,/INDECONOMIC ERRORIn the course of Irisfamous correspondence with Paretoat themm of the century (<strong>in</strong> the Giorna2edegliEconomisti),BenedettoCroce did f<strong>in</strong>d a def<strong>in</strong>ite place for "economic error." Such aherror, Groce expla<strong>in</strong>ed, must be sharply dist<strong>in</strong>guished from"technical error." Technical error, for Croce,consists <strong>in</strong> an errorofknowledge; it occurswhen one is ignorant of the properties ofthe materials with which one deals (such as when one places aheavy iron girder on a delicate waU too weak to support ir).Economic error, on the other hand, occurs for example when,yield<strong>in</strong>g to the temptation of the moment, one pursues a transientf_cy which is not one's true goal; it is, Croce expla<strong>in</strong>s, an


60 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>error of w//l, "the failure to airo directly at one's own object: towish this and that, i.e. not really to wish either this or that. "sAvoidance ofeconomic error requíres that one aim at one's goal;failure to airo at one's goal constitutes, therefore, a special categoryof error. This error arises out of the <strong>in</strong>correctness not of thepattern of acts taken <strong>in</strong> pursu<strong>in</strong>g one's immediate airo, s<strong>in</strong>cethese are, from the po<strong>in</strong>t of view of that airo, entirely appropriate,but of one's immediate airo itself. To pursue this airois--from the perspective of one's "u'ue" goals--an aberration.One places oneself <strong>in</strong>to contradiction with oneself, one aims atthat which one does not, <strong>in</strong> fact, seek to atta<strong>in</strong>.Croce's concept of economic error has not found favor amongeconomists. The writer has elsewhere 6 reviewed the carefulanalysis which Tagliacozzo many years ago made of Croce'spositionY Briefly the reason why economists have no place forCroce's "economic error" is that it seems impossible, from thepo<strong>in</strong>t of view of pure science, to dist<strong>in</strong>guish betwevn "true"goalsand erroneous, transient ones. Once we have accepted the possibilitythat man can discard yesterday's goals and adopt new onestowards which he wiUdirect today's purposeful actiom we havesurrendered the possibility of labell<strong>in</strong>g the pursuit of any end(no matter how fleet<strong>in</strong>g the "temptation" toward ir may be, andno matter how permanent remorse over hav<strong>in</strong>g "yielded" to itmay turn out to become) as, on scientific grounds, an erroneousone. Croce's economic error, it then mrns out, emerges only asaresult of <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g (unspechíed) judgments of value <strong>in</strong> terms ofwhich to classify, from a m_n's own po<strong>in</strong>t of view, those goals ofbis which it is "correct" to pursue and those the pursuit of_vhichhe must consider ah error.It seems worthwhile to digress bñefly lo note that Mises--<strong>in</strong>wl_ose writ<strong>in</strong>gs one f<strong>in</strong>ds no room at aUfor the type of "economicerror" identified by Croce.--seems to have consistent scientificgrounds for bis unwill<strong>in</strong>gness to recognize such error. It is wellknown that Míses denied the <strong>in</strong>dependent existence ofa scale ofvalues (actuat<strong>in</strong>g human choices) apart from the acta of cho/cethemse/ves ("the scale of values.., manifests itself only <strong>in</strong> therealit'/of action')Y The notion of a given scale of values, Mises is


Economh:sand Err_ : 61at pa<strong>in</strong>s to expla<strong>in</strong>, can therefore not be used to pronounce a realacfion (at variance with that scale) as "irrational." The logicalconsistency which human action necessarily displays, by nomeans entails com'tancy<strong>in</strong> the rank<strong>in</strong>g of ends3 Mises' <strong>in</strong>sistenceon the possibility of changes <strong>in</strong> adopted preference rank<strong>in</strong>gs isclosely related to his understand<strong>in</strong>g of choice as undetermíned.Man does not choose as area¢tion to given drcumstance_ on thebasis ofa previously adopted scale ofvalues; he chooses freely atthe time he acts, between different ends and different ways ofreach<strong>in</strong>g these ends. It foUows that the notion of economic erroras perceived by Croce has no place <strong>in</strong> economic scien¢e.ERRONEOUS tICTION AND IMPERFECT KNOWLEDGEThat men frequently act on the basis of imperfect knowledgeis of course not disputed by writers for whom error <strong>in</strong> economictheory is exduded. In the passage (dted above) where Misesdefends the "rationality" of erroneous actions, he menons anexample which we have not yet cited. '_Fhe farmer who <strong>in</strong> earlierages tried to <strong>in</strong>crease his crop by resort<strong>in</strong>g to magic rites aaed noless rationally than the modern farmer who applies more fertilizer."1°Men certa<strong>in</strong>ly engage <strong>in</strong> actions which they ma), regretwhen they discover the true facts of the simation. Croce, we haveseen, termed this k<strong>in</strong>d of mistake a te¢hnical error. Erroneousaction aHs<strong>in</strong>g from ignorance is not, however, generally seen asaserious threat to an economics which excludes error. With respectto thepercdved framework of ends and means, error-freedecidon mak<strong>in</strong>g can still be postulated. The very notion of ahends-means framework, of preferences and constra<strong>in</strong>ts, of <strong>in</strong>differencecurves and budget f<strong>in</strong>es, enables the economist toconf<strong>in</strong>e his analysis to choice udth/n the given framework. Thesource of error <strong>in</strong> such choices, be<strong>in</strong>g out.ddethat framework, isthus, by the very scope of the analysis, <strong>in</strong> effect excluded fromconsideration.To be sure ir is precisely this aspect of modern economicsaga<strong>in</strong>st which Professors Lachmann and ShacHe have, among


62 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>other matters, so vigorously rebelled. S<strong>in</strong>ce aU action is fumreoriented,necessarily <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g ah unknown and unknowablefuture, men's acÜons are <strong>in</strong>evitably attended by what Knightcalled error <strong>in</strong> the exercise ofjudgment, lI Such error may, ifonechooses, be subsumed under Croce's technical error, but theall-pervasive and <strong>in</strong>escapable character of such errors <strong>in</strong> judgmentdoes, <strong>in</strong> the view of these dist<strong>in</strong>guished critics, seriouslycompromise the usefulness of abstractions depend<strong>in</strong>g on given,known, ends-means frameworks. In this paper, we will not pursuefurther the profound consequences with respect to moderneconomics which the Lachmann-Shackle critiques imply. Ourdiscussion proceeds, <strong>in</strong>stead, <strong>in</strong> the context of modes of discoursewhich do perceive cont<strong>in</strong>ued relevance <strong>in</strong> theories ofchoice dependent on supposedly given, known frameworks ofpreferences and constra<strong>in</strong>ts.It should be po<strong>in</strong>ted out that a good deal of modero theoriz<strong>in</strong>gproceeds along a path on which actions based on mistakenknowledge appear not to be errors, <strong>in</strong> a sense deeper than that sofar discussed <strong>in</strong> this paper. Ir is not merely that an action is seenas "correct" with<strong>in</strong> the framework of the percewed---but <strong>in</strong> factthe quite wrongly perceived---ends-means framework. The act.ionís frequenfly seen as correct also <strong>in</strong> that the ignorance, onwhich the mistaken perceptions ate to be blamed, may/tself beviewed as hav<strong>in</strong>g beendeliberately (and quite correctly) cultivated.Economists have long recognized that men must deliberatelychoose what <strong>in</strong>formation they wish to acquire at given prices.One who on a deliberate gamble refra<strong>in</strong>s from acquir<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong>piece ofcosfly knowledge, and who then, <strong>in</strong> consequence ofbis ignorance, makes a "mistake," may <strong>in</strong>deed regret bis lack ofgood fortune <strong>in</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g lost as a result of bis gamble, but maynonetheless quite possibly still feel that the chances which heorig<strong>in</strong>ally confronted (when deliberat<strong>in</strong>g on whether or not toacquire the cosfly <strong>in</strong>formation) rendered bis orig<strong>in</strong>al decisionthe correct one. The relevant ends-means framework, witb<strong>in</strong>which actions llave been pronounced consistenfly errorles$, hasnow been broadened to embrace the situation with<strong>in</strong> wbich thechoice was made not to buy improved Lrtformafion. If Mises'


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error ,. 63"<strong>in</strong>competent" physician had taken a calculated risk <strong>in</strong> deliberatelynot study<strong>in</strong>g with sufficient care the treatment of a raredisease, his subsequent errors may <strong>in</strong>deed be seen as "technicalerrors"; (they may also, as we have seen earlier, be seen simply asthe entirely-to-be-expected shortcom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> output quality consequenton the less-than-perfect quality of medical <strong>in</strong>put). Butthe ignorance responsible for the technical error <strong>in</strong> medicaltreatment (or, irone prefers, for the less-than-perfect quality ofmedical experfise available for deployment) may itself be theconsistent result of a correct, deliberate, choice. This way ofsee<strong>in</strong>g imperfect knowledge--as the correctly planned limitationon <strong>in</strong>put qualitywpermits one to subsume errors aris<strong>in</strong>g outofimperfect knowledge under the general class oferrors treatedabove <strong>in</strong> the section "Mises, Marksmen, and Mistakes," that is, asnot constitut<strong>in</strong>g errors at all (<strong>in</strong> the sense of somehow fail<strong>in</strong>g toachieve an available preferred state of affairs). This way oflook<strong>in</strong>g at th<strong>in</strong>gs has ga<strong>in</strong>ed plausibility asa result of the developmentdur<strong>in</strong>g the last 15 years by Stigler and others, of the<strong>Economics</strong> of Information (<strong>in</strong> which detailed analysis isundertaken of decisions concern<strong>in</strong>g the optimum degree ofignorance to be preserved under different conditions, and of themarket consequences of such decisions).LEIBENSTEINtlND THE LdCK OF MOTIE4TIONHarvey Leibenste<strong>in</strong> has written an extensive series of papersdevelop<strong>in</strong>g the concept ofX-<strong>in</strong>efficiency and explor<strong>in</strong>g the extentto which this type of <strong>in</strong>efficiency has yet to be <strong>in</strong>corporated<strong>in</strong>to standard economic theory. Iz In this paper we consider onlythose aspects of his work that bear directly on the possibility oferror with<strong>in</strong> the scope of economic analysis. In the presentsection we briefly take note of some of the objections raisedrecentlyby Stigleraga<strong>in</strong>st certa<strong>in</strong> aspectsof Leibensteín'scontribution.For Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, X-<strong>in</strong>efficiency (as contrasted with the moreconventíonal aUocative <strong>in</strong>efficiency) is equivalent to what for


64 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> Economícsothers is called technical efficiency, TMthe failure of producers toachieve, with the <strong>in</strong>puts they use, the highest technically possiblelevel of output. Among the sources of this k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>efficiency, <strong>in</strong>Leibenste<strong>in</strong>'s view, is <strong>in</strong>adequacy of movation and of effort."The simple fact is that neither <strong>in</strong>dividuals nor firms work ashard, nor do they search for <strong>in</strong>formaon as effectívely, as theycould. TM Sgler has severely cricized Leibenste<strong>in</strong> on his use oflanguage._5 For the purposes of our discussion of the possibilityof error <strong>in</strong> economics, Stigler's objections can be stated as follows.It is certa<strong>in</strong>ly true that greater output could frequently beachieved by greater effort and stronger movation. But this doesnot <strong>in</strong>dicate error, <strong>in</strong> the sense of fail<strong>in</strong>g to achieve an availablestate of affairs more desirable than that actually achieved. If<strong>in</strong>dividuals are not sufficiently movated to work harder, thispresumably reflects, deliberately and "correctly," their preferencefor leisure. If, aga<strong>in</strong>, firms have not succeeded <strong>in</strong> organiz<strong>in</strong>gproducon so as to enhance worker motivaon, this constutesthe firm's choice of one "technology" of production, asaga<strong>in</strong>st the possibility of alternativ_" (more productivityconscious)technologies. Choice of one technology, yield<strong>in</strong>glower physical output per week than another available technology,does not, without our know<strong>in</strong>g all the relevant costs, warrantour assert<strong>in</strong>g the presence of error <strong>in</strong> the choice oftechnologies. Stigler's objections are completely conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g.Leibenste<strong>in</strong> has not, <strong>in</strong> his exploraon of motivaonal <strong>in</strong>efficiency,discovered cases of genu<strong>in</strong>e error, <strong>in</strong> the sense relevant toour discussion. (We will return later <strong>in</strong> this paper to considerother aspects of Leibenste<strong>in</strong>'s X-<strong>in</strong>efficiency as more promis<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> this respect.)ECONOMICS WITHOUT ERROR?Let us stand back and observe the position to which we havebeen led. This posiáon might appear to co<strong>in</strong>cide completely withthat <strong>in</strong> which no place for error exists <strong>in</strong> economic analysis--ffbyerror one means deliberately plac<strong>in</strong>g oneself<strong>in</strong> a situation which


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error ; 65one prefers less than another equally available situation of whichone is aware. We have refused to accept Croce's term<strong>in</strong>ology (<strong>in</strong>which economic error can occur when one has been temporarilyseduced to airo deliberately at a goal which one <strong>in</strong> fact prefersless than another "true" goal). We have, with Stígler, refused toaccept Leíbenste<strong>in</strong>'s apparent perception of <strong>in</strong>adequately motivatedpersons, persons not try<strong>in</strong>g as hard as they really could, asones who are <strong>in</strong> fact plac<strong>in</strong>g themselves <strong>in</strong> less preferred situa-Uons. We have po<strong>in</strong>ted out that errors made by agents whoselack of competence or sldll renders such mistakes <strong>in</strong>evitable,clearly do not <strong>in</strong>volve failure to achieve any atta<strong>in</strong>able preferredposiUon (s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>adequate quality of available ínputs placessuch preferred posiUons out of reach). And where, asa result ofimperfect knowledge, ah agent achieves a position less preferredthan an equally available alternative position, we have seen thathe too cannot, with<strong>in</strong> the framework of the <strong>in</strong>formation hebelieved to be relevant, be convicted of error. Moreover we haveseen that <strong>in</strong>solar as this agent deliberately refra<strong>in</strong>ed from acquir<strong>in</strong>gmore complete or more accurate knowledge, he cannot evenbe descríbed as hav<strong>in</strong>g placed himself <strong>in</strong> a less preferred situationat aU (s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> his view the cost of acquif<strong>in</strong>g the moreaccurate knowledge made ignorance the preferred risk).It should be observed that our apparent conclusion that errorhas no place <strong>in</strong> economics does not depend on any artificialassumption, as does, for example, appear to be implied <strong>in</strong> Stigler.For Stigler, it appears, error is delibei'ately (and artificially)excluded by the economist from his purview, on the groundsthat we lack a theory of error. TMBut for us as <strong>Austrian</strong>s, it shouldbe alear, our conclusions follow strictly from the ínsight that menare purposeful (or "rational," as Mises uses the word). Ir menpursue purposes, it foUows that ofcourse they do not consciouslyact to place themselves <strong>in</strong> situations that are any but the mostpreferred of those equally available alternatives of which the),are aware. If men turn out to have failed to achieve the mostpreferred situations it must be either that those situations were<strong>in</strong> fact not available, or that (possibly as a result of deliberate,purposeful earlier decisions) these agents were not aware of the


66 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>full range of altematives. Not only, that is, have we apparendybeen led to Stigler's conclusion that there is no place for error <strong>in</strong>economics, we have been led to this conclusion as implied di.rectly <strong>in</strong> the ver), assumption of purposefulness from which wetake our po<strong>in</strong>t of departure, a7<strong>Economics</strong>, it thus seems to turn out, is peopled by be<strong>in</strong>gswhose purposefulness ensures that they can never, <strong>in</strong> retrospect,reproach themselves for hav<strong>in</strong>g acted <strong>in</strong> error. They may, <strong>in</strong>retrospect, <strong>in</strong>deed wish that they had been more skillful, or hadcommanded more <strong>in</strong>puts, or had been better <strong>in</strong>formed. But theycan never upbraid themselves for hav<strong>in</strong>g acted erroneously <strong>in</strong>fail<strong>in</strong>g to command those superior skills or to acquire moreaccurate <strong>in</strong>formation. They must, at every stage concede thatthey had, <strong>in</strong> the past, acted with flawless precision (<strong>in</strong>sofar asthey were able). Any reproaches which they may validly wish todirect at themselves--for example for not hav<strong>in</strong>g tried hardenough or for hav<strong>in</strong>g succumbed to temptation:-arise out oflaterjudgments of value (concem<strong>in</strong>g the significance of leisureor of the goal represented by the fleet<strong>in</strong>g temptaon) with whichthey had, at earlier dates, disagreed. Such self-reproach, we nowunderstand, is not for hav<strong>in</strong>g acted <strong>in</strong> error, <strong>in</strong> the seme relevantto the present discussion, t8Indeed the reader might reasonably daLm cause for irritationat the tr/v/a//ty of our condusion. Given the pammountcy accordedto purposefulness, and given a def<strong>in</strong>ition of error whichexdudes "wrong" judgments of value as well as failures ascribableto ignorance or <strong>in</strong>adequacy (whether due to causes beyondthe control of the agent or to Iris past purposeful choices)---surely the conclusion that error is exduded is so obviously implicit<strong>in</strong> our def<strong>in</strong>idons as to be completely un<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g.But, as the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g pages of this paper will attempt to show,the condusiom to which we have apparendy been led by ourdiscussion thus far, are not trivial at alt--<strong>in</strong> fact they are not eventrue. Not only is there noth<strong>in</strong>g, as we shall see, <strong>in</strong> the assumptionsand def<strong>in</strong>itions on which economic analysis is built, whichrules out erroruit can be shown that economic analysis canhardly proceed at all without mak<strong>in</strong>g very important use of the


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error _, 67concept of error (as well as of the discovery and correctionerror). Let us see how aU this can possibly be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed.ofIGNORANCEAND ERRORMuch weight was placed, <strong>in</strong> earlier pages, on our recognitionthat mistakes made as a result of ignorance do not qualify aserrors (<strong>in</strong> the sense relevant to our discussion). A man who actedwith complete precision, given the knowledge he thought hepossessed, could not, we ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed, be reproached with hav<strong>in</strong>gacted <strong>in</strong> error. (And where the limits to his stock of knowledgehad been deliberately selected, we certa<strong>in</strong>ly understood hito tohave acted, at all times, beyond reproach.) That is, the man at notime refra<strong>in</strong>ed from exploit<strong>in</strong>g any known opportunity forachiev<strong>in</strong>g the most desirable situation possible. Yet surely wemust recognize that, valid though these statements are, with<strong>in</strong>their own framework, they may not fully exhaust our <strong>in</strong>terpretationof the situations to which they refer.Aman walks along a street, sees a store with signs offer<strong>in</strong>g toser apples for $1 but, perhaps th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g of other th<strong>in</strong>gs, enters asecond store where he pays $2 for identical apples. He may have"seen" the signs <strong>in</strong> the first store, but his perception ofthem wasso weak as to mean that, when he paid $2 <strong>in</strong> the second store hedid not, <strong>in</strong> fact, "know" that he was reject<strong>in</strong>g a preferred opportunityfor one less preferred. With<strong>in</strong> the framework of his"knowledge," the $2 apples were <strong>in</strong>deed his best opportunity; hemade no error. Yet, surely, <strong>in</strong> an ímportant sense he will (whenhe realizes bis mistake) reproach himself for hav<strong>in</strong>g been soabsentm<strong>in</strong>ded as to pass by the barga<strong>in</strong> whichhe saw, for the moreexpensive purchase. In this sense he d/d commit an error, theerror of not act<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>formation available to hito, of notperceivíng fully the opportunity before bis very nose. He did(without the excuse of not hav<strong>in</strong>g the necessary <strong>in</strong>formationavailable to him) consciously place him_lf <strong>in</strong> a less preferredposition than that available to him. It is true that he was not"aware" of the superior alternative. But, because the necessary


68 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong>formation was available to hito, it was surely an error on hispart to have failedto actupon ir(i.e.,to have rema<strong>in</strong>ed unawareof the superior opportunity). His "unawareness"cannotbe "excused"(from convictionof error) on the grounds of <strong>in</strong>adequacyof <strong>in</strong>puts (s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>puts were at hand). It cannotbe excused on the grounds of anearlierdecision to refra<strong>in</strong> fromacquir<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation (s<strong>in</strong>ce no such decision was made). Thisunawarenesscannotbe flatlyexduded asimpossible(becauseof<strong>in</strong>consistency with purposeful action) because there/s noth<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>purposefulactionwhichbyitselfguaranteesthateveryavailableopportunitymust be <strong>in</strong>stantaneouslyperceived?9In the discussion <strong>in</strong> the first portion of this paper knowledgewastreated as someth<strong>in</strong>g like ah <strong>in</strong>put, a"tool." Someone lacldngthis needed <strong>in</strong>put could not be reproached with error for notsucceed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> achiev<strong>in</strong>g that for which this <strong>in</strong>put was needed.(And where this <strong>in</strong>put had deliberately and correctly not beenacquired because of its cost, this exemption fróm reproach becarneeven more justified.) But we now see that ignorance maymean someth<strong>in</strong>g other than lack of command over a neededtool--it may be sheer failure to utilice a resource available andready at hand. Such failure, moreover, is not <strong>in</strong>consistent withpurposefulness, s<strong>in</strong>ce an available resource ready at hand maynot be noticed; purposefulness is not necessarily <strong>in</strong>comistentwith tunnel-vision. (Of course one might <strong>in</strong>sist that an agent notblessedwith the alermess needed to notice resourcesavailableathand, simply lacks, through no "fault" of his own, another"resource_[i.e.,"alermess"]necessary to take advantage of the otherresources with which he has been blessed. We cannot set downsuch a use of terms as wrong. We simply po<strong>in</strong>t out that whiledecisiom can <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be madé by a person to acquire aresource which he lacks, we can n0t conceive of one lack<strong>in</strong>g"alermess,"mak<strong>in</strong>g a decision to acquire it. This is so because,amongother reasons,_obefore a decision to acquireanyth<strong>in</strong>gcanbe considered, one must alreadyassume the alermess necessaryfor the perception that such ajaacquisitionis needed and possibleat all. Or, to put it somewhat differently, alermess cannot betreated asa resource with respect to whichdecisiom ate made on


<strong>Economics</strong>and Error ; 69how to use it, s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> order to make such a dedsion with respectto a resource, one must alreadyhave been alert to its availabílity."Alertness" thus appears to possess a primordial role <strong>in</strong> decisionmak<strong>in</strong>g which makes it unhelpful for it to be treated, <strong>in</strong> theanalysis of decisions, "as any other resource." We claim, therefore,justificationfora term<strong>in</strong>ology which ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that whereignorance consists, not <strong>in</strong> lack of available <strong>in</strong>formaon, but <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>explicably fail<strong>in</strong>g to see facts stañng one <strong>in</strong> the face, it representsgenu<strong>in</strong>e error, and genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>efficiency.)_1IGNOtL4NCE, ERROR, dND ENTREPRENEURIALOPPORTUNITIESWe have shown that genu<strong>in</strong>e error isnot <strong>in</strong>consistent with thefundamental postulates of economics. It rema<strong>in</strong>s to show thateconomic analysis dependson the presence of this k<strong>in</strong>d of errorfor its most elementary and far-reach<strong>in</strong>g theorems. Let us considerthe theorem whichJevons correctlycalled"a general law ofthe utmost importance <strong>in</strong> economics," which asserts that"<strong>in</strong> thesame open market, at any one moment, there cannot be twopñces for the same k<strong>in</strong>d of article.''2_NowJevons presented thisLaw of Indifference as valid only where no imperfection ofknowledge exists. Yet surely economists ever s<strong>in</strong>ceJevons haveunderstood the law as assert<strong>in</strong>g a tendencyat all times for divergentprices ofidencal goods to converge,ceterisparibus, towarda s<strong>in</strong>gle price. That is, the law asserts a tendency for imperfectknowledge to be replaced bymore perfect knowledge,z3Now theexistence of sucia a tendency requires some explanaon. If theímperfection of knowledge (responsible for the <strong>in</strong>ial multiplicityof prices) reflected the lack of some "resource" (as wheremeam ofcommunication are absent between different parts of amarket), then it isdifficult, without additionaljustification, to seehow we can postulate universally a process of spontaneous discovery.Ir, say, imperfection <strong>in</strong> knowledge resulted from deliberateunwiil<strong>in</strong>gness to <strong>in</strong>cur the costs of search, itis not alearhowwe can be confident that, <strong>in</strong> the course of the market process


70 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>such unwiU<strong>in</strong>gnesswill<strong>in</strong>variablydissipate, or that the necessarycosts of search wiU<strong>in</strong>variably faU.(Of course one can constructmodels <strong>in</strong> which these costsmaybe supposed to rail. One type oftheoriz<strong>in</strong>g concern<strong>in</strong>g the nature of the market process has,follow<strong>in</strong>g on the l<strong>in</strong>e of the economics of <strong>in</strong>formation, <strong>in</strong> effecttaken this approach.)Surely our justification for assert<strong>in</strong>g the existence of a tendencyfor the pñces of identical articles to converge rests on ourunderstand<strong>in</strong>g that the imperfection of knowledge (on whichone must rely <strong>in</strong> order to account for the <strong>in</strong>itial multiplicity ofpñces) reflected, at least <strong>in</strong> part, sheer error. We understand,that is, that the <strong>in</strong>itial imperfection <strong>in</strong> knowledge is to be attñbuted,not to lack ofsome needed resource,but to failure to noticeopportunitíes ready at hand. The multiplidty of prices representedopportunities for pure entrepreneurial profit; thatsuch multiplicity existed, means that many market partidpants(those who sold at the lower pñces and those who bought at thehigher pñces) simply overlooked these opportunities. S<strong>in</strong>cethese opportunities were left unexploited, not because of unavailableneeded resources, but because they were simply notnoticed, we understand that, as time passes, the lure of availablepure profits can be counted upon to alert at least some marketparticipants to the existence of these opportunities. The law of<strong>in</strong>difference follows from our recognition that error exists, thatit consists <strong>in</strong> available opportunities be<strong>in</strong>g overlooked, and thatthe market process is a process of the systematic discovery andcorrection of true error. The hypothetical state of equilibñum, itemerges, consists not so much <strong>in</strong> the perfecfion of knowledge(s<strong>in</strong>ce costs of acquir<strong>in</strong>g knowledge may welljustify an eq,fi!ibriumstate of ignorance) as <strong>in</strong> the hypothetical absence of error.AIIthis permits us to concur (<strong>in</strong> general temas,ir not <strong>in</strong> mattersof detail) with that aspect of Leibenste<strong>in</strong>'s concept ofX-<strong>in</strong>efficiency which he identifies with the scope for entrepreneurship..4 Scope for entrepreneurship, we have discovered,is present whenever error occurs. Pure profit opportunitiesexist whenever error occurs. Whenever error occurs <strong>in</strong>the context of producon, <strong>in</strong>puts are be<strong>in</strong>g used to achieve iess


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error _ 7 lthan the optimum quantity and quality of outputs; the produceris operat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>side the "outer-bound production possibility surfaceconsistent with [bis] resources. ":sX-<strong>in</strong>efficiency/s possible,it reflects error, and is necessarily reflected <strong>in</strong> the availabílity ofentrepreneuñal profit opportunities and scope for entrepreneurialdiscovery and improvement. That our conclusionwith respect to this aspect of Leibenste<strong>in</strong>'s contribution apparentlydiffers from that of Stigler (who rejects the notion ofX-<strong>in</strong>efficiency entirely) is fully consistent with our refusal toaccompany Stigler <strong>in</strong> his <strong>in</strong>sistence on exclud<strong>in</strong>g error fromeconomics.MARSHALL, ROBBINS, .4ND THE REPRESENTATIVE FIRMIn the course of bis critique of Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, Sgler has valuablyrecalled our attention to an old issue <strong>in</strong> the economic literature,the ratíonale underly<strong>in</strong>g Marshall's concept of the representavefirm. It was Lionel (now Lord) Robb<strong>in</strong>s who <strong>in</strong> 19282eexpla<strong>in</strong>ed Marshall's move <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g the rather troublesomenoÜon of the representaÚve firm, and who showed, withthe most effective logic, that there is <strong>in</strong> fact no need for thisawkward construct at aH. Our discussion thus far enables us tomake several comments on the issue.Bas<strong>in</strong>g his <strong>in</strong>terpretation on the authoritative op<strong>in</strong>ion of DennisRobertson, RobbLnsexplaíns that Marshall devised the representativefirm "to meet the difficulties occur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the analysisof supply when there is a disparity of effidency as betweendifferent producers. "j7 This disparity means that part of thetotal supply of each product (the magnitude of which helpsdeterm<strong>in</strong>e price) is produced by producen mak<strong>in</strong>g zero of negatireprofits. Consequendy it would appear that "the magnitudeof net profits is irrelevant to the determ<strong>in</strong>ation of... price." Forthis rea.son Marshall expla<strong>in</strong>ed that pñce is to be understood <strong>in</strong>terms of the normal costs (<strong>in</strong>dud<strong>in</strong>g gross earn<strong>in</strong>gs of management)associated with the representative firm? sRobbim went to great paim to show that, <strong>in</strong>sofar as concerns


72 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>these disparities of effióency between firms that would not disappear<strong>in</strong> equilibrium,there is no need at allto <strong>in</strong>voke the notionof a representative firm. Such dispañties <strong>in</strong> effidency are to betraced to the presence of entrepreneurs of vary<strong>in</strong>g ability. "Justas units of a given supply may be produced on lands of vary<strong>in</strong>geffidency, so their production may be supervised by bus<strong>in</strong>essmen of vary<strong>in</strong>g ability.What is normal profit for one willnot benormal profit for another, that is all.''2' As StigIer put it, it is<strong>in</strong>appropriate to use variations <strong>in</strong> entrepreneurial ability to accountfor varíations <strong>in</strong> costs among firms:"... differences <strong>in</strong> thequality of an <strong>in</strong>put do not lead to differences <strong>in</strong> outputs fromgiven <strong>in</strong>puts.... [When] costs of firms differed because ofquality of entrepreneurs (or other <strong>in</strong>puts), the differences <strong>in</strong>producvity would be reflected <strong>in</strong> differences <strong>in</strong> profits (orother <strong>in</strong>put prices)."8°In other words, differences <strong>in</strong> costsof producfionaris<strong>in</strong>gfromdifferences <strong>in</strong> entrepreneurialabilitymean thatthe equilibrium•pricesfor the vañous entrepreneuñal <strong>in</strong>putswillbe correspond<strong>in</strong>glydifferent. When account is taken of the costs of theseentrepreneurial <strong>in</strong>puts it willbe seen that, <strong>in</strong> equilibrium,thereexistno costvariatiombetweenentrepreneurs. Stiglerappearstocondude that Robbim'sdiscussionjustifies the neoclassicalpracriceof view<strong>in</strong>g each producer as always at a production frontier.If asa result of vary<strong>in</strong>g quality of entrepreneurial <strong>in</strong>puts, thereoccursoutput vañaon, this is simply because, asa result of thevariance <strong>in</strong> entrepreneurial quality, each producer may llave aproduction frontier above or belowthat of others,st There is noroom, <strong>in</strong> this scheme of th<strong>in</strong>gs, for Leibenste<strong>in</strong>'s X-<strong>in</strong>effidency(which implies the possibility that differences <strong>in</strong> output are aresult of genu<strong>in</strong>e differences <strong>in</strong> sheer efficier/cy,not attributableto differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>put quality).For our purposes it is useful to po<strong>in</strong>t out that the porfion ofRobb<strong>in</strong>s's crique of Marshallupon which Stigler draws,is conf<strong>in</strong>edexplicitly to the state of equilibrium,u Under condions ofequilibrium we mu_ <strong>in</strong>deed reject the possibility of genu<strong>in</strong>edisparities <strong>in</strong> effider/cy among firms that cannot be traced todifferences <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>put qualities. In equih'brium such disparities


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error 73cannot be traced to sheer error. But under condifions of disequilibrium,when scope exists for entrepreneurial activity,there is no reason why genu<strong>in</strong>e disparities ma), not exist amongdifferent producers, traceable (not to differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>putqualíties--s<strong>in</strong>ce we do not view alertness as an <strong>in</strong>put_but) todifferences <strong>in</strong> the degree to which producers have succumbed toerror. Robb<strong>in</strong>s's critique of Marshall does not, therefore, implyah), need to reject Leibemte<strong>in</strong>'s X-<strong>in</strong>efficiency (<strong>in</strong>sofar, as wellave seen, sucia <strong>in</strong>efficieno/co<strong>in</strong>cides with the existence of ascope for entrepreneurship).ERROR IN ECONOMIC$:SOME NORM/ITIVE APPLICATIONSOur concern <strong>in</strong> this pape r to defend the possibility of genu<strong>in</strong>eerror <strong>in</strong> economics is based on more than our wish to show howpositive economic theory cannot proceed without such possibiliD'.Our concem rests, <strong>in</strong> addifion, upon important normaUvegrounds. Allocative <strong>in</strong>efficiency <strong>in</strong> a society of errorless <strong>in</strong>dividualmaximizers must, it appears on reflectio_, be accountedfor only by the existence of prohibitive transaction costs) 3 Improvement<strong>in</strong> social well-be<strong>in</strong>g must, <strong>in</strong> such a world, appear tobe possible only asa result of unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed technological breakthroughs.Surely such a picture of the world, a picture <strong>in</strong> which nogenu<strong>in</strong>e opportunities for improvement are permitted to exist,is wholly unsatisfy<strong>in</strong>g. Surely ,,ve are conv<strong>in</strong>ced that enormousscope exists at ídl times for genu<strong>in</strong>e economic improvement andthat the world is chock-full of <strong>in</strong>efficiencies. It is most embarrím<strong>in</strong>gto have to grapple with the grossly <strong>in</strong>efficient world weknow, with economic tools which assume away the essence of theproblem with which we wish to deal.On the other hand, as soon as we admit genu<strong>in</strong>e error <strong>in</strong>to ourpurview, our embarrassment fades away. Our world/s a grossly<strong>in</strong>efficient world. What is <strong>in</strong>effícient about the world is surelythat, at each <strong>in</strong>stant, enormous scope for improvements exista, is


74 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong> one way or another ready at hand, and is yet simply notnoticed. At each <strong>in</strong>stant, because the market is <strong>in</strong> a state ofdisequilibrium, genu<strong>in</strong>e allocative <strong>in</strong>efficiendes rema<strong>in</strong> yet to beremoved simply because entrepreneurs have not yet noticed theprofit opportunities represented by these <strong>in</strong>efficiencies. At each<strong>in</strong>stant available technological improvements (<strong>in</strong> some sense alreadyready at hand) rema<strong>in</strong> to be exploited; they rema<strong>in</strong> untappedbecause entrepreneurs have not yet noticed the profitopportunities embedded <strong>in</strong> these possibilities. It is genu<strong>in</strong>e errorto which we can ascribe much of the world's iUs,and ,,veneed aneconomics that can recognize this.Fortunately, <strong>Austrian</strong> economics, with its emphasis on disequilibriumand on the entrepreneuñal role, is richly suited tofdl our need <strong>in</strong> this respect. Only an economics which recognizeshow the profit motive (by which we mean the lure of pureentrepreneurial profits) can harness entrepreneurial activitytoward the systematic elim<strong>in</strong>ation of error can be of service <strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g the way to those ínstitutional structures necessary forthe steady improvement of the lot of mank<strong>in</strong>d.NOTES1. F.A. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong>and Knowledge,"Economiza,N.S. Vol.IV, No. 13 (February 1937).2. G.J. Stigler, "The Xistence of X-Efficiency,"Amor/canEconom/cRev/ew, March 1976, p. 216.3. L. Mises,Theoryana[H/story(<strong>New</strong> Haven: Yale UniversityPress,1957), p. 268.4. See Stigler, op. cá. p. 215.5. B. Croce, "On the Economic Pr<strong>in</strong>dple," translated <strong>in</strong> IntemationalEconami¢Papers,No. 3, p. 177.6. I. M. Kirzner, T_ Econom/cPmnt of V/eu,(Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton: Van Nostrand,1960), pp. 169-72.7. G. Tagliacozzo, "Croceand the Nature of Economic Science,"QUa_sYJournal of<strong>Economics</strong>,Vol. HX, No. $ (May 1945).• L. Mises,Human Action (<strong>New</strong> Haven: Yale University Press,1949),p. 95.


<strong>Economics</strong> and Error ; 759. Ib/d. pp. 102f.10. Ib/d.11. F. H. Knight, Risk, Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty and Profit, (1921), pp. 225--26.12. H. Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, "Allocafive Efficiency vs. 'X-Efficiency'," Amer/-can Economic Review, Vol. 56 (June 1966); "Entrepreneurship andDevelopment," American Economic Review, Vol. 58 (May 1968); "Competitionand X-Efficiency: Reply,"Journal ofPolitical Economy, Vol. 81,No. 3 (May/June 1973); "Aspects of the X-Efficiency Theory of theFirm," BellJournal of<strong>Economics</strong>, Vol. 6 (Autumn 1975).13. H. Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, "Competition andX-Efficiency: Reply," p. 766.14. H. Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, "AUocative Efficiency vs. 'X-Efficiency'," p. 407.15. G.J. Sfigler, op. cit.16. lb/d. p. 216.17. Put differently, our perception of the impossibility of error doesnot depend on any "arbitrary" assumption of utility° or profitmaximiz<strong>in</strong>gbehavior. Error is impossible because it is <strong>in</strong>consistent withthe postulate of purposeful action.18. The possibility for social "<strong>in</strong>efficiency" of any k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>in</strong> such anerrorless world, would, it must appear, then rest either on the possibilitythat high transaction costs make the "correction" <strong>in</strong> fact uneconomic,or, on the highly dubious nofion of an omniscient observerfrom whose perspective the errorless (but imperfecfly omniscient)members of society are overlook<strong>in</strong>g valuable opportunifies for improv<strong>in</strong>gtheir positions. On all this see further, I. M. Kirzner, CompetitionandEntrepreneurship (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973), Ch. 6.See also the f<strong>in</strong>al secuon of the present paper.19. Although, as argued by the writer elsewhe_, the extent to whichavailable opportunities are perceived is not at all unrelated to theconcept of purposeful acUon.20. The other reasons <strong>in</strong>clude the circumstance that, were one todiscover someone whose superior alertness to profitable opportunitiesone wishes to hire, we would expect that other ("alert one") to havealready taken advantage of those opportunitíes (or at least that he willanyway do so very shortly) on bis own account.21. For further discussion of some of the issues raised <strong>in</strong> this and thefollow<strong>in</strong>g secfions, see the writer's Competition and Entrepreneurship,Chapters 2, 3.22. W. S. Jevons, The Theory ofPoli_alEconomy, 4th Edition, 1911(Pecan Books, 1970), p. 137.23. On all this see Hayek's pioneer<strong>in</strong>g contribuon <strong>in</strong> his 1937paper (see footnote 1). See also the writer's unpublished paper,"Hayek, Knowledge, and Market Processes."24. H. Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, "Entrepreneurship and Development"; and


76 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Kirzner, Competition and Entrepreneurship, p. 46n.25. H. Leibenste<strong>in</strong>, "Allocative Efficiency vs. 'X-Efficiency'," p. 413.26. L. Robb<strong>in</strong>s, "The Representave Firrn," EconomicJournal, Volume38 (September 1928).27. Robb<strong>in</strong>s, op. vit. p. 391.28. $ee A. Marshall, Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of<strong>Economics</strong> (Sth Edition,342f.1920), pp.29. Robb<strong>in</strong>s, p. 393.30. Sgler, "The Xistence ofX-Efficiency", pp. 214f.31. Sgler, p. 215.32. Robb<strong>in</strong>s, pp. 392-396.33. See e.g.G. Calbresi, "Transacfion Costs, Resource Allocaonand Liability Rules: A Comment,"Journa/ofLaw and <strong>Economics</strong>, Vol. 11(April 1968), p. 68.


The Problem of Social CostS. C. LittlechildThe University of Birm<strong>in</strong>gham (United K<strong>in</strong>gdom)INTRODUCTIONIt is difficult to overestimate the role which socialcost plays <strong>in</strong>modern welfare economics. The ideas of socialcost and productlie beh<strong>in</strong>d the surplus-maximisaUon criterion frequently urgedupon public utñities, the consequent computaon and comparisonof sociallates of return on road and rail <strong>in</strong>vestments, and thephílosophy of marg<strong>in</strong>al cost pric<strong>in</strong>g. FoUow<strong>in</strong>gPigou, the possibílityofdivergencies between private and social cost or productprovides a basis for peak-hour congestion taxes or prices onroads, airports, and telephone systems; for subsidised entrance<strong>in</strong>to the telephone network on the grounds that other subscribersthereby benefit; for regional <strong>in</strong>vestment and subsidies oftaxes on labour to counter hidden unemployment of socialcostsof urban growth not reflected <strong>in</strong> the private calculus; for reducedprices of educaonal and health services; for subsidiesto<strong>in</strong>vention, research and development, and so on.The criticismof Pigou provided <strong>in</strong> Coase's article, "The Problemof Social Cost," and the reformulation provided there, haveto some extent directed attention away from dívergencies betweenprivate and social cost towards the possibility of solv<strong>in</strong>gsocial problems through the market by means of ah improveddef<strong>in</strong>ition of reaUocationof property rights. Despite this change<strong>in</strong> approach, the concept of value of socialproduct is retaíned byboth Coase and Pigou, and <strong>in</strong>deed bythe majority ofpresent-dayeconomists, as the basic críteríon for compar<strong>in</strong>g alternave socialsystems. The purpose of the present paper is to exam<strong>in</strong>e77


78 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>these notions of social cost and social product from a "subjectivist"or "<strong>Austrian</strong>" po<strong>in</strong>t of view. Apart from its <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic importance,the concept of social cost is of particular <strong>in</strong>terest to subjectivists,for Buchanan has suggested that Coase's own work on thistopic is the major success story of the L.S.E. subjectivist school.Perhaps the most significant L.S.E. impact on modern economics hascome through an <strong>in</strong>direct application of opportunity-cost theoryrather than through an underm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g of basiccost conceptions. "Marg<strong>in</strong>alsocial cost," enthroned by Pigou as a cornerstone of appliedwelfare economics, was successfully challenged by R. H. Coase aquarter-century after his <strong>in</strong>itial work on cost. Hisnow classicpaper onsocialcost, which reflects the same cost theory held earlier, succeededwhere the more straightforward earlier attacks on the marg<strong>in</strong>al-costpric<strong>in</strong>g norm--attacks by Coase himself, by Thirlby and byWiseman---apparently failed (I, pp. 11-12).However, we shall discover <strong>in</strong> the present paper that ProfessorCoase's work, whatever may be its other substantial merits <strong>in</strong>correct<strong>in</strong>g Pigou and <strong>in</strong> reorient<strong>in</strong>g the economics profession,does not present ah approach to cost which is any more satisfactory,from a subjectivist standpo<strong>in</strong>t, than did Pigou. Indeed,once it ís recognised (a) that social value and social cost aresubjective, rather than objective concepts and (b) that they bearonly a tenuous relationship to the true costs of decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g,then it becomes questionable whether the notion of social cost isthe most useful way of approach<strong>in</strong>g the problem.We shall beg<strong>in</strong> with summaries of the social cost argument andof the subjectivist approach to economics.THE NOTIONSOF SOCIAL V.4LUE AND SOCI/IL COSTThe concept of social cost is remarkably elusive. Economistsunhesitat<strong>in</strong>gly attñbute the concept to Pigou, as expounded <strong>in</strong>hisEconomies ofWelfare, but <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>in</strong> none of the four ediUons ofthat book, nor <strong>in</strong> his earlier Weal_ and Wdfare, is there anymention of the term social cost itself. It is perhaps not entirelyco<strong>in</strong>cidental, then, that Coase's own paper, "The Problem of


The Problem of Social Cost " 79Social Cost," conta<strong>in</strong>s no mention either of the term social cost.The analyses of both authors ate, <strong>in</strong> fact, conducted almostentírely <strong>in</strong> terms of social product. (I have not yet been able todiscover the orig<strong>in</strong> of the term social cost. Knight (VI) used it <strong>in</strong>his criticism of Pigou without any suggestion that it was orig<strong>in</strong>al.A. A. Young (XIV), <strong>in</strong> review<strong>in</strong>g Wealth and Welfare, referred to asocial view ofcost. Perhaps this odd situation lends some supportto Coase's suggestion that the Pigovian doctr<strong>in</strong>e on these matterswas largely the product of an oral tradition.)Pigou admitted that the elements of welfare were ukimatelystates of consciousness, but <strong>in</strong> order to achieve someth<strong>in</strong>g practicablehe feh it necessary to limit his subject matter to "thatposition of the field <strong>in</strong> which the methods of science seem likelyto work at best advantage," namely, "... to that part of socialwelfare that can be brought directly or <strong>in</strong>directly <strong>in</strong>to relationwith the measur<strong>in</strong>g-rod of money. This part of welfare ma), becalled economic welfare (VII, p. 11).The "objective counterpart of economic welfare whicheconomists call the national dividend or nafional <strong>in</strong>come" was"composed <strong>in</strong> the last resort of a number of objecUve services,some of which are embodied <strong>in</strong> commodities." In order to preservethe measuñng rod of money, Pigou decided to <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong>the national dividend only those goods and services acmally soldfor money, and for the same reason he rejected consumersurplus as a measure of a change <strong>in</strong> the national dividend.Pigou's ma<strong>in</strong> ínstrument of analysis was marg<strong>in</strong>al product,def<strong>in</strong>ed as follows:The marg<strong>in</strong>al so¢i'a!net product is the total net produa of physicalth<strong>in</strong>gs or objectiveservicesdue to the marg<strong>in</strong>al<strong>in</strong>crement of resources<strong>in</strong> any given use of place, no matter to whom any part of this productmay acabe .... The marg<strong>in</strong>al pñvate net product is that part of thetotal net product.., which accrues<strong>in</strong> the first <strong>in</strong>stance---ge., prior tosale--to the person responsible for <strong>in</strong>vest<strong>in</strong>g resources there .... Thevalue of the marg<strong>in</strong>al socJ'a![and pñvate] net product ofany quantity ofresources employed <strong>in</strong> any use of place is simply the sum of moneywhich the marg<strong>in</strong>al social net product is worth <strong>in</strong> the market (VII, pp.


80 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>If pñvate and social net products co<strong>in</strong>cide, then "the free playof seff-<strong>in</strong>terest, so lar as it is not hampered by ignorance, willtend to bf<strong>in</strong>g about such a distñbution of resources.., as wiUraise the national dividend and, with it, the sum of economicwelfare to a maximum" (VII, p. 143). But if there is a divergentebetween private and social products (i.e., ir there ate externalities),then "specific acts of <strong>in</strong>terference with normaleconomic processes," by means of bounties and taxes, will removethe divergence and <strong>in</strong>crease the dividend (VII, p. 172).We need not be concemed here with Knight's observation thatdivergencies between private and social cost depend uponwhether or not the road (or other means of production) isprivately owned, nor with Coase's suggeson that Pigou wasignorant of the legal posion and <strong>in</strong> any case failed to take <strong>in</strong>toaccount the response of the party affected by extemalies.There are, however, two aspects of Coase's analysis which deservemention. First, he observed that Pigou's measurement ofnational dividend <strong>in</strong> terms of goods and services actua//y s0/d"means that the value of social product has no social significancewhatsoever" (III, p. 40). Coase preferred to value production atits market value regardless of whether payment actually tookplace. Second, he recommended thatWhen ah economist is compar<strong>in</strong>g alternave social arrangements, theproper procedure is to compare the total social product yielded bythese different arrangements. The comparison ofprivate and socialproducts is neither here nor there (III, p. 34).He later compares this to the opportunity cost approach used <strong>in</strong>the analysis of the firm. Ir seems .reasonable to <strong>in</strong>fer that thesocial (opportunity) cost of choos<strong>in</strong>g one Social arrangementwould- be def'med as the market value of total product correspond<strong>in</strong>gto the best alternative arrangement not chosen.THE SUBJECTIVISTAPPROACHFor those who are not familiar with the writ<strong>in</strong>gs of the Aus-


The Problem of Social Cost 81'trian school or the L.S.E. subjectivist school, it will be useful tosummarise the relevant parts of this approach, beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g withHayek's work <strong>in</strong> the 1930s and 1940s, which Buchanan (I, p. 24)has descríbed as la_ng down the central features of the subjectivistmethodolog 7.In the papers repñnted as Part One of The Counter Revolutionof Science, Hayek emphasised that the "facts" of the social sciencesate human perceptions of the world, beliefs held by people"irrespective of whether they are true or false, and whichmoreover, we cannot directly observe <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>ds of the peoplebut which one can recognise from what they do and say merelybecause we have ourselves a m<strong>in</strong>d similar to theirs." The objectsof human acfion are not "objective facts" and cannot be def<strong>in</strong>ed<strong>in</strong> purely physical temas. "So far as human actions are concemed,the th<strong>in</strong>gs are what the act<strong>in</strong>g people th<strong>in</strong>k they are."Moreover, "the knowledge and beliefs of different people, whilepossess<strong>in</strong>g that common structure which makes communicationpossíble, wiU yet be different and often conflict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> manyrespects." The term "subjective" thus reflects the idea that actionsdepend upon perceptions and also the idea that differentpeople wiU generally have different perceptions.For present purposes, two implications of this basic <strong>in</strong>sight areof particular relevance. First, as Kirzner (V) has argued, itis nolonger appropriate to restrict def<strong>in</strong>ition of the "economic problem"to that of allocat<strong>in</strong>g scarce resources between compet<strong>in</strong>gends, <strong>in</strong> the way that Robb<strong>in</strong>s (VIII) had proposed. It is necessaryto <strong>in</strong>dude the perception of ends and means, rather than totake these as given. Hence we are led to the concept of"entrepreneurship,"or alertness to advantageous changes <strong>in</strong> means orends, and to Mises' "act<strong>in</strong>g man" rather than to Robb<strong>in</strong>s's"economis<strong>in</strong>g man." In mm, the entrepreneurial element <strong>in</strong>human acUon can be identified as that which generates a processof change, and <strong>in</strong>deed the emphasis of the whole <strong>Austrian</strong> approachis on the market process rather than upon the state ofequih%rium.Ki__rznerhimself has used this notion of perception <strong>in</strong> comment<strong>in</strong>gupon Coase's analysis of property rights <strong>in</strong> the social-


82 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>cost paper already referred to. Coase had argued that, <strong>in</strong> theabsence oftransactions costs, market transactions would transferproperty rights and allocate resources so as to maximise thevalue of production, <strong>in</strong>dependent of the legal position. Kirzner(V, p. 227) objected that zero transactions costs were neithernecessary nor sufficient to ensure that all participants wouldnot/ce the mutually profitable contracts which could be enteredhato.The second implication of the subjectivist approach is that costmust be thought of asa subjective, rather than objective, concept,because the elements of <strong>in</strong>dividual choice evidently dependupon the alternatives imag<strong>in</strong>ed and thought worthy of¢onsiderationby the decision-maker, and the choice actually made dependsupon his preferences. Buchanan has argued thateconomists at the L.S.E. (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Coase) have played ah importantrole <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g this subjective theory of cost, and hesummarises the theory as follows:Cost is that which the decision-maker sacrifices of gives up when heselects one alternative rather than another. Cost consists therefore <strong>in</strong>hisown evaluation of the enjoyment or utilitythat he anticipateshav<strong>in</strong>gto forgo asa result ofchoice itself. There are specificimplications to bedrawn from this choice-bound def<strong>in</strong>ition of opportunity cost:1. Cost must be borne exclusively by the person who makes decisions;it is not possible for this cost to be shifted to or imposed onothers.2. Costis subjective;it exists only <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d of thedecision-makeror chooser.3. Cost is based on anticipations; it is necessañly a forward-look<strong>in</strong>gor ex ante concept.4. Costcan never be realised becauseof the fact that choice is made;the alternative which is rejected can never itself be enjoyed.5. Cost cannot be measured by someone other than the choosers<strong>in</strong>ce there is no way that subjective mental expeñence can bedirectly observed.


The Problem of Social Cost 836. Cost can be dated at the moment of f<strong>in</strong>al dedsion or choice.In any general theory of choice ¢ost must be reckoned ín a ulityrather t.han<strong>in</strong> a commodity dímension. From this it follows that theopportunity cost<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong>choice cannotbe observedand objectifiedand, more importantly,it cannot be measured<strong>in</strong> such a way asto allowcomparisonsover wholly different ¢hoice sett<strong>in</strong>gs (I, pp. 14-15).Thirlby (1946, 1960) and Wiseman (1953, 1957) have po<strong>in</strong>tedout some of the difficulties of supervision which now arise.I Suppose a manager is <strong>in</strong>structed to maximise net revenue. (Wer must not say "revenue less cost," s<strong>in</strong>ce these two concepts are<strong>in</strong>commensurate: Revenue is measured <strong>in</strong> terms of money andcost <strong>in</strong> terms of utility.) S<strong>in</strong>ce it is not possible to know withcerta<strong>in</strong>ty the outcomes of all possible courses of action, it is notpossible to make a direct check on the efficiency of the manager.One may make <strong>in</strong>direct checks by ascerta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g which alternativeshe considered (i.e., by exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g his "plan"), by assess<strong>in</strong>g theactual outcome (i.e., by examín<strong>in</strong>g his "account"), and by check<strong>in</strong>gthe accuracy of his forecast<strong>in</strong>g (i.e., by compar<strong>in</strong>g his planwith his account). But it is never possible to know whether therewere better alternatives which should have been considered orwhether the outcomes of alternatives not chosen were correctlyforecast. Moreover, when <strong>in</strong>direct checks of this k<strong>in</strong>d are used,the manager is led to modify his actions to take account of them,for the simple reason that the cost, to him, of taldng one decisionis necessañly his own evaluation of the alternative outcomeforegone. It is not net revenue itself, but thesignificance to hito ofnet revenue, which determ<strong>in</strong>es bis actions.Let us now apply some of these ideas to the concepts of socialvahe and cost.SOCIAL COST AND PRODUCT--ARECONSIDEtMTIONFor both Pígou and Coase, social product and social cost ateevidently objective concepts. Social product is def<strong>in</strong>ed asa stockOr flow of spedfied physical services. The question of what


84 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>constitutes a good or service,i.e.,who perceivesit and how, is notraised. There is no uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty about the goods and servicesassociated with each possible decision, hence there are no conflict<strong>in</strong>gexpectations. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the question of whose valuation isto be used isavoided byreference to the "market value."In thesecircumstances, the optimal choice is simplya matter of computationand social (opportunity) cost is objective.Ir might be conceded that, <strong>in</strong> practice, the likely outcomes ofany particular measure are unsure, as are the likely marketprices, but ir isnecessary to make a "best guess." This element ofsubjectivityof course raises the difficules referred to <strong>in</strong> the lastsecUon. Whose guess is appropriate for policy purposes, andhow is the efficiency of the guess<strong>in</strong>g procedure to be ascerta<strong>in</strong>ed?Moreover, there is a crucial difference between thissituation and that of the private firm <strong>in</strong> that no ulu'mateobjectivecheck on efficiency is available: Ir the decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g procedureis <strong>in</strong>efficient, there isno direct feedback comparable to thatof f<strong>in</strong>ancial loss and bankruptcy.But now suppose that werecognise the full degree of subjecUvityofbeliefsabout simations and no longer assume an objectivelyspecified set of physical products ora market pñce for these. Inthis general case, what becomes of the notion of value of socialproduct? Is it possible to reconcile socialproduct and social costwith the subjecáve theory of cost and choice?Take first the Pigovian approach. A decisíon by one personmay also affect other people. It is conventional to describethis asa collection of changes <strong>in</strong> utility levels. The value of (marg<strong>in</strong>al)social product is, then, <strong>in</strong> some sense, the net change <strong>in</strong> totalutility, but this raises the obvious well-known objections thatutilities are ord<strong>in</strong>al and cannot be aggregated. One thereforeattempts to derive a card<strong>in</strong>al measure byask<strong>in</strong>g what the change<strong>in</strong> utility is worth <strong>in</strong> money terms. This isdone byconstruct<strong>in</strong>g acoUection of artificial choice simations, one for each personaffected, and ask<strong>in</strong>goneselfwhat this person would be preparedto pay for the decision <strong>in</strong> question to be taken or not to be taken.The optimal decision depends upon the total sums of moneythereby calculated.


The Problem of Social Cost 85Evidently the sítuation envisaged by Coase does not differsignificantly from this. Attention is not focused on a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividualdedsion°taker, but rather all persons ate aHowed to respondto each social arrangement (say, legal position) underconsideratíon, with correspond<strong>in</strong>g changes <strong>in</strong> utility levels whichare to be valued <strong>in</strong> money terms. The optimal choice of socialarrangement then depends upon the sum of money values thusobta<strong>in</strong>ed.To what extent is this arfifidal choice <strong>in</strong>terpretafion just describedcompatible with the subjectivist approach? In effect, weare ask<strong>in</strong>g whether iris possible to attach a mean<strong>in</strong>g to the notionof damage or benefit as valued by the person damaged or benefitedby the action of another person. Ifthis action had been theresult of a contract between the two persons, then we could, <strong>in</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, have measured the effect (more precisely, the expectedeffect) with respect to the alternative choices available,i.e., to the cost of the contract. In the case where no contract ismade, we are consider<strong>in</strong>g a hypothetical choice and ask<strong>in</strong>g howattracfive a hypothetical alternative would need to have been <strong>in</strong>order to be preferred (or how unattractive it could have beenand stiU have been preferred).The first po<strong>in</strong>t to emphasíse is that the proposed proceduredoes not <strong>in</strong>volve choices, albeit hypothetical, by the person <strong>in</strong>question but rather by an outside observ<strong>in</strong>g economist, governmentoffid_!,judge, of politidan. As argued earlier, the costs ofhis choice <strong>in</strong>volve the significance to hito of the differentanswer: for example, whether the answers seem plausible toIris peers and supervisors. The valuation put on damage toanother person is thus nota cost to that person at all. Moreover,even ffthe artificial choice were made by the person <strong>in</strong> question,his costs would <strong>in</strong>volve the benefits of choos<strong>in</strong>g a higher of lowerfigure <strong>in</strong> a laboratory situation, and would not measure the costs<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tended choice situation (cf., IX).Second, s<strong>in</strong>ce this evaluation is nota choice actually made <strong>in</strong>the market, there is room for considerable uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty as to whatvalue would be appropriate. To use the standard term<strong>in</strong>ology,one is simply guess<strong>in</strong>g where the relevant <strong>in</strong>difference curves líe


86 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>(I, p. 72). Different observers could come up with differentevaluations, norte ofwhich could be proved objective!y correa or<strong>in</strong>correct.Third, the <strong>in</strong>tention of the hypothetical choice scheme is toevaluate a person's response to a situation while tak<strong>in</strong>g as givenhis perceived opportunities and objectives. But we have mentionedthat, <strong>in</strong> the subjecvist approach, economics is not simplya matter of known meam and ends, but also <strong>in</strong>volves the perceptionof new possibiliUes, which <strong>in</strong> general change one's evaluationof previously perceived opportunities. Suppose that thealternative under consideraUon by thé policymaker had notbeen conceived by the person whose evaluation ir is required toesfimate. Then an evaluation can only be obta<strong>in</strong>ed by (conceptually)chang<strong>in</strong>ghis exist<strong>in</strong>g perceptions. This, of course, raises twoproblems: how the new alternative should (aga<strong>in</strong> concepmally)be presented to the person, and what bis reacfion would be. Theproblem applies more generally: Even if he is aware of thepossibility of the decision under consideration, he will generallyhave a different impression of its namre, implications, andlikelihood than another person will have. Should the observer/economist take as given his <strong>in</strong>itial, perhaps "<strong>in</strong>correa," percel>tionsor should he (concepmally) modify them? What is a "correa"perception of the consequences of any act?Even ifit were possible to specify the <strong>in</strong>itial reactions of peoplem a proposed action, what position should be taken concern<strong>in</strong>gsubsequent changes <strong>in</strong> their perceptions and plans? Coase isevidently aware of this difficulty. He refers to the use ofbluff<strong>in</strong>order to <strong>in</strong>duce the other party to make a larger payment, butcomments "such manoeuvres are prelim<strong>in</strong>aries to an agreementand do not affect the long run equilibrium position" (III, p. 8).Evidently, he takes the view that ir is not the immediate responseto a situaon which is relevant, but the "equilibrium" response,after appropriate <strong>in</strong>formation has been acquired. The diff'_-ultywith this position is the precariousness of the notion of equilibriumonceeconomicactivityisviewedasaprocessrather than astate.


The Probleraof Social Cost 87CONCLUSIONLet us attempt to summarise the argument of this paper.It was found that the concept of social cost itself, althoughwidely used, was not used by Pigou and Coase, who preferred towork <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>in</strong> terms of social product. Despite differences <strong>in</strong>their usage of this concept, they essentially proposed to use valueof social product as a cfiterion for choos<strong>in</strong>g between alternativesituations. This notion depended upon "physical product" composedof specified objective goods and services, to which objecdvelydefmed pñces were or could be attached.This approach was shown to lead to certa<strong>in</strong> difficulties.Bñefly,1. The basic assumptions are <strong>in</strong>consistent with a subjectivistapproach. Goods and prices are def<strong>in</strong>ed objectively, so thatthe optimal choice is simply a matter of computation andcost is objective.2. Ir uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty of future quantities and prices is admitted,then there is no objectively "ñght" calculation, there aredifficulties <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g the efficiency of those required tomaxímise social product, and there is no ultimate test comparableto net revenue <strong>in</strong> a private firm.3. The attempt to use artificial choice situations <strong>in</strong> order toobta<strong>in</strong> a monetary figure of change <strong>in</strong> utility means thatcosts of choice to the observer are not costs which would beexpeñenced<strong>in</strong> a real choice situation.4. Some persons may not have perceived the altemativeunder consideration as relevant, so that an answer to thehypothefical question can only be obta<strong>in</strong>ed by (conceptually)chang<strong>in</strong>g that person's perceptions. More generaHy,s<strong>in</strong>ce different <strong>in</strong>dividuals may view altematives differently,they will not necessarily be apprais<strong>in</strong>g the "same"


88 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>alternative. How then should the situation be (conceptually)presented?5. If economic activity is viewed, notas ah equilibrium state,but asa process <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g chang<strong>in</strong>g perceptions and values,then it is not dear at what time, or after what period ofreflection, it is appropriate to calculate the value of product.In this discussion I have tried to show that social cost andproduct are not objective concepts. This does not mean to saythat any particular observer cannot make ah estimate of thedamage or benefits accru<strong>in</strong>g from any action, but rather that thisestimate wiUnecessarily embody elements of bis own evaluationand wiU depend upon his own perceptions and assumptious ofwhat is appropriate. Different <strong>in</strong>dividuals wiU,therefore, makedifferent estimates, and no objective check on efficiency is possible.This raises the question ofwhether social product as traditionallyconceived is the best concept for use <strong>in</strong> govemment decisions.We may, <strong>in</strong> fact, use Coase's argument agaimt himself.The proper question to ask is not whether _ or that socialarrangement maximises value of social product, but ratherwhether us<strong>in</strong>g social product as a criterion is preferable to us<strong>in</strong>gsome other approach. In order to answer this question, it isnecessary to know more about how those who have been urgedor required to use this criteñon have behaved <strong>in</strong> the past. Herewe might exam<strong>in</strong>e the decisions of nation_lised <strong>in</strong>dustries <strong>in</strong>Brita<strong>in</strong>, and government response, to cost-benefit analyses ofroads, railways, and airports. Second, iris necessary to know howeffective other objective controls have been, such as breakevenrequirements or specific constra<strong>in</strong>ts on spend<strong>in</strong>g or provision ofservices. F<strong>in</strong>aUy, it is necessary to compare government controlsof any k<strong>in</strong>d with those imposed by the market. A fruifful start onthese problems has been made by Alchian, Stigler, Posner, andothers, and one would expect th_t Coase would r/mpathise withsuch ah approach.


The Problem of Social Cost 89However, it would seem that social product cannot be used asthe f<strong>in</strong>al criterion of evaluation, for the reasons given. Whatother criterion is available? I simply menUon here Kirzner'ssuggeson (V, pp. 216 ff.) that alternative <strong>in</strong>sfituons or arrangementscan be evaluated <strong>in</strong> terms of their success <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>gabout mutually beneficial contracts. The effectiveness ofsucia a criterion rema<strong>in</strong>s to be explored.POSTSCRIPTI wish to add a bñefcomment on the def<strong>in</strong>ition of social cost <strong>in</strong>the literature anda more extensive discussion of social cost as thecriterion £or action by a public organisaon.Coase implicitly def<strong>in</strong>es the cost of any social arrangement asthe market value forgone under an alternative arrangement.This is <strong>in</strong>deed a cost, <strong>in</strong> the sense def<strong>in</strong>ed by Buchanan, ff weth<strong>in</strong>k of society as an entity choos<strong>in</strong>g alternative arrangementswith the airo of maximis<strong>in</strong>g market value (though how thesealternafives are generated and evaluated is not specified). However,not all economists adopt this def<strong>in</strong>ion. Stigler, for exampie,discusses a chemical plant which discharges waste <strong>in</strong>to astream, and says that "the sum of costs to eve_one is called thesocial cost of waste disposal" (Theo_ of Price, 1966). Such aconcept is nota cost <strong>in</strong> Buchanan's sense----<strong>in</strong>deed, an action byone person cannot impose costs on others. This is not to say thatthe one def<strong>in</strong>ition is supeñor to the other, ofcourse, but ratherthat one is (or can more easily be made) consistent with the L.S.E.tradition.Several of the parficipants at the W'mdsor Conference, whilebroadly sympathetic to the argument of the paper, neverthelessfelt uneasy on two counts.(a) Sínce the procedure for calculat<strong>in</strong>g social costs and benefitsappears to be similar to that for pñvate costs and benefits,why is the latter legitimate, but the former iUegimate?(b) If public organisations are not required to base decisionson social cost, what other <strong>in</strong>structions should be given


90 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>them? In this Postscript I shall attempt to answer these questionsmore directly.Consider first two ideal types: the bus<strong>in</strong>essman <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>maximis<strong>in</strong>g net private revenue and the benevolent dictator<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> maximis<strong>in</strong>g net social benefit. The problems theyhave to face are identical, although the criteria they use aredifferent. In neither case is there any dist<strong>in</strong>ction m be madebetween subjectiveand objectiveconcepts, because <strong>in</strong> both casesthe worldistaken to be as the decision-maker perceives it. Thosegoods are relevant which the decision-maker believes to be relevant;those future prices, future responses, and future valuesare appropriate which the decision-maker believes to be appropriate.In pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, to calculate net social benefit is no moredifficult than to calculate net private revenue.Putt<strong>in</strong>g plans <strong>in</strong>to aaion generates new <strong>in</strong>formation which <strong>in</strong>turn makes it appropriate, sooner or later, to revisethe previousplans. Investments or other commitments may have been made,yet other previous commitments may have expired, and newopportunities may have añsen. The pattern of costs and benefits,and hence the optimal actions, will generaHybe differentfrom those planned earlier. Revision of plans <strong>in</strong> this way isnecessary regardless of whether the objectiveis net private revenueor net social benefit, and there is no reason to suppose it isany easier <strong>in</strong> the one case than <strong>in</strong> the other.F<strong>in</strong>aHy, suppose that the bus<strong>in</strong>essman and the benevolentdictator do not carry out all the actions themselves, but rather<strong>in</strong>struct subord<strong>in</strong>ates to maximise the respective objectives ontheir behalf. In each case, it may be assumed that the subord<strong>in</strong>ateshave objecáves and preferences of their own which theywill attempt to saásfy <strong>in</strong>solar as they are not prevented or discouragedfrom do<strong>in</strong>g so. The problem of control arises: how toemure that the subord<strong>in</strong>ates are carry<strong>in</strong>g out their duties efficienfly?In neither case is it possible to ascerta<strong>in</strong> directlywhat isthe optimal policy, so it is necessary to develop <strong>in</strong>direct checks byexam<strong>in</strong>m"g the process of plan preparation, the outcomes of theactions taken, and the accuracy of the forecasf<strong>in</strong>g.


The Problem of Social Cost 91Where<strong>in</strong>, then, lies the difference between the objectives ofnet social benefit and net private revenue? It lies, I th<strong>in</strong>k, <strong>in</strong> thedegree of difficulty <strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g the outcomes of any series ofactions. Both concepts are measured <strong>in</strong> money terms, butwhereas the liquid assets of an organisation at any time can beascerta<strong>in</strong>ed reasonably easily and objectively, this is not true ofnet social benefit. The whole po<strong>in</strong>t of a social cost-benefitanalysis is to impute to people values which they 1:1onot <strong>in</strong> factexpress <strong>in</strong> the market. There is no"correct" value, there are onlydifferent views about values, which may be more or less plausibleto others. The problem of control is <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely more difficultwhen the outcome of any action is not immediately apparent.In order to maximise net social benefit it may, paradoxically,be more efficient not to set this as a direct objective, simplybecause of the difficulty of check<strong>in</strong>g performance. As arguedelsewhere, the market mechanism, the profit moáve, and thepossibility of competition provide <strong>in</strong>cenves to discover andmeet the wishes of consumers, with monetary success for thosewho succeed and replacement for those who rail. It is certa<strong>in</strong>lynot guaranteed that the market mechanism will ensure that the"correct" decisions are always taken, s<strong>in</strong>ce these cannot beknown, but there are reasons to believe the market is more likely,<strong>in</strong> the long run, to maximise net social benefit.It may be objected that competition is not always possible and,<strong>in</strong>deed, that this is a major reason for replac<strong>in</strong>g the marketmechanism with some form of government organisation. Asregards the first po<strong>in</strong>t, the work of Hayek, Coase, Kirzner,Alchian, Demsetz, and others has gradually provided a betterunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of the namre of competition and market failure.It is now recognised that the effidency of the market may beenhanced (e.g., by develop<strong>in</strong>g property rights) irthere is a will todo so. On the second po<strong>in</strong>t, whether market failure is the reasonfor government <strong>in</strong>tervention is debatable. By <strong>in</strong>tervention, thegovernment is, <strong>in</strong> effect, deliberately isolat<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>dustry frommarket forces and subject<strong>in</strong>g it, <strong>in</strong>stead, to political forces. It ísexpress<strong>in</strong>g the view that the <strong>in</strong>dustry should not maximise netsocial benefit, as expressed <strong>in</strong> market values, but rather should


92 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>give greater weight to some particular consumers or producers.It is not surpris<strong>in</strong>g to f<strong>in</strong>d, then, that those government organisaonsresponsible for monitor<strong>in</strong>g the performance of 0thergovernment organisaUons charged with maximis<strong>in</strong>g net socialbenefit show little enthusiasm for their task. Unlike net pñvaterevenue, net social benefit is ah artificial concept of direct <strong>in</strong>terestonly to economists.This suggests that operang rules for controll<strong>in</strong>g public organisationsshould sasfy two criteña. First, they should relate toconcepts and enties of direct relevance to the people of organisationsconcerned. Second, the rules should be couched <strong>in</strong> objectiveoperaonal terms: It should be possible to check whether ornot they have been obeyed.To iUustrate bñefly, it is currenfly Brish policy to rcquirenationalised <strong>in</strong>dustñes to assess proposed <strong>in</strong>_,estments aga<strong>in</strong>st a"test discount tate." S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> practice it is impossible for anoutsider to teU whether the assumpons and forecasts embodied_n the appraisal are reasonable (of even what they ate!), this ruleprovides no effecUve che& on effidency <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment. It wouldbe preferable to replace ir by, e.g., a realisc charge for borrow<strong>in</strong>gfunds plus a specified tate of return on the borrow<strong>in</strong>g of the<strong>in</strong>dustry asa whole. Requiñng the <strong>in</strong>dustry to <strong>in</strong>vest so as tomaximise net social benefit provides not control but only theillusion of control.tBIBLIOGRAPHYI. Buchanan,J. M.Costand Choice.Chicago: MarkhamPublish<strong>in</strong>gCo., 1969.II. Buchanan,J. M., and Thirlby, G. F., eds. L.S£. Es.uz3son Cost.Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 1973.III. Coue, IL H. "The Problem of SocialCost,'Jouma/ofLaw£conm/r.s3 (1960): 1-44.andIV. Hayek,Ir.A.T_ Count,,r-lh,vohaionof $c<strong>in</strong>_e. Glencoe,In.: TheFree Press, 1952.V. Kirzner, L M. C_ and £ntreprmeursh/p. Chicago andLondon: Universityof Chicago Press, 1973.


The Problem of Social Cost 93VI. Knight, F. H. "Some Fallacies <strong>in</strong> the Interpretation of SocialCost." QuarterlyJournal of <strong>Economics</strong> 38 (1924): 582-606.VII. Pigou, A. C. The<strong>Economics</strong> ofWelfare. 4th ed. London: Macmillan,1932.VIII. Robb<strong>in</strong>s, L. Ah Essay on the Nature and Significance of EconomicScience. 2nd ed. London: MacmiUan, 1935.IX. Rothbard, M. N. "Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare<strong>Economics</strong>." On Freedomand FreeEnte_prise. Edited by M.Sennholz. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, N.J.: Van Nostrand, 1956.X. Thirlby, G. F. "The Ruler." South AfricanJournal of<strong>Economics</strong> 14(1946). Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Buchanan and Thirlby (1973).XI. Thirlby, G. F. "Economists' Cost Rules and EquilibriumTheory." Economica (1960). Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Buchanan andThirlby (1973).XII. Wisernan, J. "Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, Costs and Collective EconomicPlann<strong>in</strong>g." Economica (1953). Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Buchanan andThirlby (1973).XIII. Wiseman, J. "The Theory of Public Utility Price--an EmptyBox." Oxford Economic Papers 9 (1957). Repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Buc.hartanand Thirlby (1973).XIV. Young, A. A. "Pigou's Wealth and Welfare." QuarterlyJournal of<strong>Economics</strong> 27 (1913): 672--86.


A Critiqueof Neoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong>MonopolyTheoryD. T. ArmentanoUniversity of HartfordOne of the most controversial areas <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> economics,and one where even long-established <strong>Austrian</strong> theorists differsharply, is monopoly theory. Indeed, as we shall see below, thedifferences are not merely semantic, nor are they conf<strong>in</strong>ed todetail or some m<strong>in</strong>or theoretical implication. Rather, there aremajor and fundamental disagreements between some of thelead<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Austrian</strong>s, and these disagreements are created bywholly different theories concern<strong>in</strong>g the def<strong>in</strong>/t/on of monopoly,the or/g/ns of monopoly, and the supposed effectsof monopoly onconsumer sovereignty and efficient resource allocaUon.NEOCLASSICAL MONOPOLY THEORYBy way ofcontrast, and <strong>in</strong> order to place the <strong>Austrian</strong> theoriesofmonopoly <strong>in</strong> perspective, it is perhaps necessary to review andcriticize the traditional (neodassícal) theory of monopoly?A monopolist <strong>in</strong> neoclassical analysis is a tirm that faces theentire demand for the product under consideration. In order toma_ímize its profits, it produces ah output where the marg<strong>in</strong>alrevenue associated with the last unit sold is jmt equal to the94


A Critique of Neoclassicaland <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 95marg<strong>in</strong>al costs associated with produc<strong>in</strong>g and sell<strong>in</strong>g that f<strong>in</strong>alunit. But s<strong>in</strong>ce the demand function fac<strong>in</strong>g the monopolist isnecessarily sloped downward (perhaps even steeply downward),the price charged for the output is greater than both marg<strong>in</strong>alrevenue and marg<strong>in</strong>al cost.This situation, it is argued, compares "unfavorably" with priceand output (and cost) under competitive conditions. Undercompetitive conditions, s<strong>in</strong>ce price and marg<strong>in</strong>al revenue ateequal, price is always identical with marg<strong>in</strong>al cost when profitsare maximized. Further, under competitive equilibrium conditions,price is always driven down to the m<strong>in</strong>imum po<strong>in</strong>t of theaverage cost function, so that production tends to take place at itsmost "efficient" po<strong>in</strong>t. Therefore, monopoly prices ate higherthan competitive prices, outputs are less, and average costsgreater than under comparable competitive (cost) conditions.But, importantly, how is a firm able to obta<strong>in</strong> a monopolyposition <strong>in</strong> the market and, thus, "misallocate" economic resources?In the first place the monopoly could simply be due togovernmental prohibition of competitive entry, and there iscerta<strong>in</strong>ly a recognition of this source of monopoly <strong>in</strong> the neoclassicalliterature. However, more recently it has been popular tostress certa<strong>in</strong> non/ega/"barriers to entry" that, allegedly, preservemonopoly and resource misallocation, s These barriers would<strong>in</strong>dude any difficulty or impediment'that a new firm might haveto overcome <strong>in</strong> order to compete successfully with an exist<strong>in</strong>gfirm (monopolist). Thus, scale economies enjoyed by an exist<strong>in</strong>gfirm, or commercially successful product differentiationemployed by such a firm, becomes, <strong>in</strong> the newjargon, a barrier toentry that limits competition and reduces society's "welfare."CONTEMPORARY MONOPOLY THEORY: A CRITIQUEThere are two avenues of criticism that one might take withrespect to neodassical monopoly theory. In the first place, onemight criticize the purely competitive model which is employedasa benchmark andas a basis of comparison with monopolistic


96 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>situations. And secondly, one might criticize the whole conceptof nonlegal barriers to entry, argu<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>stead, that it iS simplyconsumer preference that "limits competition" and that consequentlyno misallocatíon of resources occurs.Most economists would agree that pure competition is notactually possible. Some would agree, perhaps reluctantly, that itmight not even be desirable of optimal ir it cou/d exist. (Ir theyagree to this, of course, then they must also agree that mov<strong>in</strong>gtoward pure competition is not necessarily desirable, either.) Butfew economists have noced of emphasized thefundaraental flawof the purely competitive model, namely, that it is not a descriptionof competition at all.a Pure competition ís a static, equilibriumcondition whose very assumptions ate such that competitiveprocess is ruled out by def<strong>in</strong>ition. Or to put the matter morecharitably, while pure competition may describe the f<strong>in</strong>al outcomeof a particular compefitive situation, the ultimate endresult, it does not describe the competitiveprocess that produce.dthat particular outcome. The purely competitíve theory is notatheory of competition as such.The neoclassical habit of confus<strong>in</strong>g competitive process with af<strong>in</strong>al, stac equilibríum condition makes for gross errors <strong>in</strong>economic analysis. For <strong>in</strong>stance, product differentiation, advertis<strong>in</strong>g,price competition (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g price discrim<strong>in</strong>ation), and<strong>in</strong>novation ate rather rout<strong>in</strong>ely condemned as "monopolistic"and, thus, as resource misallocat<strong>in</strong>g and socially undesirable. Thiscondemnation follows "logically" s<strong>in</strong>ce not one of these activitiesis possible under purely competitive conditions. Hence everyth<strong>in</strong>gthat is truly competitive <strong>in</strong> the real world, truly rivalrous,gets labeled as "monopolistic" and resource misallocat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> theAlice-<strong>in</strong>-Wonderland, purely competitive world. The analyticalcondusions one is forced to come to, employ<strong>in</strong>g the purelycompetitive perspectíve, are notjust wrong, notjust unrealistic,but the very opposite of the truth. Far from be<strong>in</strong>g able to "predict,"of tell us anyth<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gful concern<strong>in</strong>g competitivebehavior, pure competition can only describe what th<strong>in</strong>gs wouldbe like if the world conta<strong>in</strong>ed zombie-like conmmers withhomogeneoustastes, atomistically structured firm$ idenfical <strong>in</strong>


A Critique ofNeodassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 97every important respect, with no locational advantages, no advertis<strong>in</strong>g,no entrepreneurship, and no rivalry whatever. Surelythis is the aajor flaw and absurdity <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> the purely competitiveperspective. 4BARRIERS TO ENTRY: A CRITIQUEDiscussions about the nonlegal barriers to entry suffer froathe saae difficulUes. The two aost popular and ímportant"barriersto entry" areproduct differentiation and scale economies.Productdifferentiation liaits coapetifion s<strong>in</strong>ce it aakes coapefiUveentry more cos@. To use a favorite neodassical example, thefact that the aajor autoaobile coapanies change styles everyyear <strong>in</strong>creases the costs of coapet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>dustry. Would-becoapetitors must be will<strong>in</strong>g and able to undergo the same orsimilar procedures, else they siaply cannot coapete. Evenworse, once coapetition is "liaited," the auto coapaniesrout<strong>in</strong>ely pass along the higher costs <strong>in</strong> the forro ofhigher príces,which contributes, ir is alleged, to a real reduction <strong>in</strong> consuaerwelfare.On the other hand--<strong>in</strong>deed, on the opposite handmscaleeconoaies also limit coapetition. The fact that certa<strong>in</strong> timasrealize lower costs per unit because of large volumes gives thesetimas the "power" to exclude smaUer timas, or smaller potentialentrants, froa the market. Ergo, we are supposed to regret thereduced coapetition and consequent resource misanocations<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong>effident timas cannot compete with efficient ones.Actually, of course, the neoclassical theoñsts have gotten theaatter coapletely and predsely backward. It is because, and onlybecause, consuaers f<strong>in</strong>d resources satisfactorily allocated thatwould-be coapetitors f<strong>in</strong>d entry difficult or impossible. Productdifferentiation, especially differentiaon that does raise prices,can only actas a barñer to entry ir consumersprefer that differentiation,and pay the presuaably higher pñces associated with,sa),, new armual auto styles. Ir consumen do not prefer suchdifferentiation and, <strong>in</strong>stead, reward the fi,,iis that change styles


98 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>/ess often, or not at all, then product differentiation could hardlyact asa barrier to competitive entry. Indeed, <strong>in</strong> the case justpostulated, product differentiation would be an open <strong>in</strong>vitationto entry and to competition.To condemn commercially successful product differentiafionasa misallocation of scarce resources, therefore, is to condemnthe very "resource allocations" that consumers apparenfly prefer.It is the neoclassical economist's allegedly "optimar' allocationof resources under purely competitive conditions that productdifferentiation upsets, and not any allocation that can be associatedwith free consumer choice.The same sort of argument can be made---and even moreobviously--with respect to scale economies. Consumers do notregret the economies nor the consequent reduction <strong>in</strong> competition.Consumers could "<strong>in</strong>crease competifion" arjy time theychoose to by <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g their will<strong>in</strong>gness to pay higher prices tocover the higher costs of the smaller firms. That they do notusually do thís <strong>in</strong>dicates the resources are correctly allocated sofar as they are concerned. Aga<strong>in</strong>, it is the economist's vision ofthe purely competitive wonderland that is upset by the large,efficient firm, and not aHocative efficiency from a conmmerperspective.The fmal absurdity <strong>in</strong> this area is to observe where such<strong>in</strong>correct theories of competition are likely to lead. Ir productdifferentiation limits competition, i.e., limits the number ofcompetitors, then more competition can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed by limit<strong>in</strong>gproduct differentiation---by law. If efficient techniques of producáonor scale economies limit competition, i.e., the number ofcompetitors, then more competition can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed by rais<strong>in</strong>geither costs or pñces for the effident companies--6y law. Thus,to take the barriers-to-entry theory señously is to end up propos<strong>in</strong>gas rational public policy--<strong>in</strong> the name of consumerwelfare--the very procedures that consumers would likely f<strong>in</strong>dmost harmful. The only th<strong>in</strong>g sadder than all of this is that mc_ideas have actually been taken seriously <strong>in</strong> some antitrust drdesand by the courts, and we llave had some real world legal dedsionsthat reflect such theoretical nonseme, s


.4 Critique of Neoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 99As should be quite clear from the above review and criUque,there is much dissatisfacUon with the traditional notions ofmonopoly and competition, and with the simplisfic antitrustpolicies (antimerger policy, for <strong>in</strong>stance) founded on such assumptions.But if the neoclassical approach to monopoly andcompetition is defective, what is the correct approach <strong>in</strong> thísarea? Indeed,/s there a logical and rational theory of monopolyand, accord<strong>in</strong>gly, an appropriate public policy to complementthat theoretical approach? In the sections below we will turn to acritical exam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>Austrian</strong> monopoly theory <strong>in</strong> an attemptto answer these questions. The views of von Mises, Kirzner, andRothbard will be taken as representative of various <strong>Austrian</strong>positions concern<strong>in</strong>g monopoly.MISES' MONOPOLYTHEORYMonopoly exists for Ludwig von Mises when "... the wholesupply of the commodity is controlled by a s<strong>in</strong>gle seller or agroup of sellers act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> concert. "e This condítion puts themonopolist (or cartel) <strong>in</strong> the position of be<strong>in</strong>g able to restfictsupply <strong>in</strong> order to raise market price without hav<strong>in</strong>g to"fear thathis plans wiU be frustrated by <strong>in</strong>terference on the part of theother sellers of the same commodity. "vMises holds, however, thatmonopoly pr/ces do not result unless the restricUon <strong>in</strong> supplyproduces prices that actually <strong>in</strong>crease the monopolist's "total netproceeds." Only if the demand for the product is <strong>in</strong>elas.tic <strong>in</strong> theprice range under discussion could "monopoly pfices emerge asdifferentiated from competitive prices." Hence, ir is not"monopoly" as such that is catallactically relevant for ML*es,butonly the "configuration" of the demand function and theemergence of monopoly prices, sImpormntly ff suela monopoly prices do exist, then they are an"<strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>gement of the supremacy of the consumers and thedemocracy of the market."9 Mises even goes further:Monopolypricesare consequentialonly becausethey ate the outcome


100 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>of a conduct of bus<strong>in</strong>ess defy<strong>in</strong>g the supremacy of the consumers andsubstitut<strong>in</strong>g the pñvate <strong>in</strong>terests of the monopolist for those of thepublic. They ate the only <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>in</strong> the operaUon of a marketeconomy <strong>in</strong> which the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between production for profit andproducfion for use could to some extent be made.... loAnd aga<strong>in</strong>:The characteristic feature of monopoly pñces is the monopolist's defianceof the wishes of the consumers? 1Mises also argues that although most monopolies andmonopoly prices ate made possible by government <strong>in</strong>tervention<strong>in</strong> the free market (tariffs, licenses, etc.), there ate certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stances<strong>in</strong> which monopoly (and monopoly prices) arise <strong>in</strong> theunhampered market. He specifically mentions natural resourcemonopoly, TM geographic monopoly, TM Iimited-spacemonopoly, TMand monopoly that might arise because consumersplace a "special confidence.., on the <strong>in</strong>dividual or firm concernedon account of previous experience, "15 as with certa<strong>in</strong>trademarked drugs.KIRZNER'S MONOPOLY THEORYProfessor Kirzner's theory of monopoly can be derived logicallyfrom bis well-articulated theory of the competitive process._°Kírzner views the market process as one <strong>in</strong> which marketseUers are conánually attempt<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>ch ahead of rivals byoffer<strong>in</strong>g moreattracUveopportunides to potential buyers. Andhe views this process as <strong>in</strong>herently competitive s<strong>in</strong>ce the key <strong>in</strong>gredientthat makes the process function---entrepreneurship--can never be monopolized. For Kírzner, pure entrepreneurshiprequires no resources whatsoever; hence the freedom to enterthe market is absolute s<strong>in</strong>ce no obstacles to entry can ever exist <strong>in</strong>a free market.However, the exercise of entrepreneurship is quite anothermatter. Here the exclusive ownership or control of "a//thecurrent endowment of a certa<strong>in</strong> resouree" is defmed by Kirzner


A Critique ofNeoclassicaI and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 101to be monopoly, can <strong>in</strong>deed block entry <strong>in</strong>to the production ofsome specific good, and can hamper competition and "impedethe course of the market process." A monopoly producer forKirzner is one whose "exclusive <strong>in</strong>put blocks competitive entry<strong>in</strong>to the production of his products. ''17 To employ Kirzner'sexample, without access to oranges, "producUon of orange juiceis blocked. ''18Kirzner notes that monopoly should not refer to a producerwho--<strong>in</strong> the absence of resource monopoly--is the s<strong>in</strong>glesupplier ofsome product <strong>in</strong> the market. That firm, he reasons, isstill fully subject to the market process s<strong>in</strong>ce entry <strong>in</strong>to competitiveproduction is always possible. On the other hand, when"needed resources" ate restñcted because of monopoly ownershipor control of a certa<strong>in</strong> resource, the very possibility ofcompetition--and the benefits to consumers that ate the consequencesof competition--are elim<strong>in</strong>ated. 19Here, accord<strong>in</strong>g toKirzner, the monopolist is completely "immune from the competitionof other entrepreneurs who might, <strong>in</strong> other circumstances,enter bis field of activity. ''2°Kirzner is quick to note, however, that the monopolist is notimmune from the competitive process itself. Although entry <strong>in</strong>tosome specific activity is by def<strong>in</strong>ition blockaded, entry <strong>in</strong>tos/m//aractivities is not. Monopoly control over a resource simply divertsthe competitive, entrepreneurial process <strong>in</strong>to other similar activities,employ<strong>in</strong>g other resources which create a "turbulence"that surrounds and imp<strong>in</strong>ges upon the monopolist's oñg<strong>in</strong>alactivity.Importan@, Kirzner h<strong>in</strong>ts that the equilibrium tendency of amarket conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g resource monopoly is to produce a higherthan "competitive-equilibrium price" for the resources and alsoa higher"surplus" for the product produced with that resource.This surplus can be accomplished by withdraw<strong>in</strong>g some of thestock from the market and "forc<strong>in</strong>g" up the market price. _1Thus, consumers raight be harmed by such activity s<strong>in</strong>ce scarcemonopolized resources are not be<strong>in</strong>g employed to the "fullestextent compatiblemarket."2zwith the pattern of consumer tastes <strong>in</strong> the


102 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>ROTHBARD'S MONOPOLY THEORYProfessor Rothbard's analysis of monopoly, monopoly pñce,and the welfare implications of such economic conditions differsradically from that of both Mises and Kirzner. Indeed, <strong>in</strong> hisdiscussion of monopoly, Rothbard is sharply critical not only ofthe neoclassícal monopoly theories, but also implicitly critical(and occasionally explicifly critical) of víews held by his fellow<strong>Austrian</strong> theorists as well.2aAs far as Rothbard is concerned, there are three possibledef<strong>in</strong>iUons ofmonopoly: one, the s<strong>in</strong>gle seller ofany given good;two, a grant of special privilege by the state, reserv<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong>area of production to one particular <strong>in</strong>dividual or group; and ithree, "a person who has achieved a monopoly price. "2_ iAlthough Rothbard admits that the first def<strong>in</strong>ition (s<strong>in</strong>gle jseller) is a coherent and even a "legitimate" one, he wjects it asimpractical because it is too broad and all-<strong>in</strong>dusive. The impracti- ical nature of this def<strong>in</strong>ition can be iUustrated, Rothbard argues,by not<strong>in</strong>g that any difference (differentiaUon) <strong>in</strong> any two goodsor resources and, more importanfly, any consumer-percdved difference<strong>in</strong> any two commodities or resources will make themunique (specific) goods and thus, by def<strong>in</strong>ition, "monopoly."Hence, "the s<strong>in</strong>gle seller of any given good" could always reduceto the notion that everyone is a monopolist s<strong>in</strong>ce each person <strong>in</strong> amarket system is presumed to have exdusive ownership of h/sown (unique) property. But a def<strong>in</strong>ion that makes everyth<strong>in</strong>gmonopoly and everyone a monopolist is barren, "confus<strong>in</strong>g,"and "absurd" accord<strong>in</strong>g to Rothbard. "sRothbard clearly prefers the second def<strong>in</strong>ition ofmonopoly--i.e., a grant of pñvilege from the state restrict<strong>in</strong>gcompetitive production or sale. This is a monopoly s<strong>in</strong>ce entry<strong>in</strong>to the privileged actívity is prohibited by the state; logically, nosuch monopoly could ever exist <strong>in</strong> a free market. This def<strong>in</strong>itionwill be adopted as the "proper" one should the f<strong>in</strong>al alternativedef<strong>in</strong>ition prove nonsemical or iUegitimate, uRothbard's criticism of the theory of"monopoly pñce" (as wellas his criticism of the theory of"competitive price") is certa<strong>in</strong>ly a


A Critique ofNeoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 103controversial contribution to the literature on monopoly. Forhere he argues that <strong>in</strong> a free market there is simply no way ofconceptually dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g "monopoly price" from a freemarketcompetitive price.On the free market there is no way of dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g a "monopolyprice" ora "subcompetitive price" or of establish<strong>in</strong>g any changes asmovements from one to the other. No criteria can be found formaiángsuch dist<strong>in</strong>ctions. The concept of monopoly price as dist<strong>in</strong>guishedfrom competitive price is therefore untenable. We can speak only ofthe free market price,z7It has been common, of course, to speak of monopoly price asthat price accomplished when output is restricted under conditionsof <strong>in</strong>elastic demand, thus <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g the net <strong>in</strong>come of thesupplier. Even Mises, it will be recalled, employed the term <strong>in</strong>this manner and drew some fairly dismal welfare implicationsfrom the "restriction."Rothbard argues, however, that there is no objective way todeterm<strong>in</strong>e that such a price is a monopoly pñce or that such a"restricon" is antisocial. AII we can know, accord<strong>in</strong>g toRothbard, is that a//firms attempt to produce a stock of goodsthat maximizes their net <strong>in</strong>come given their estimation of demand.They attempt to price (other th<strong>in</strong>gs be<strong>in</strong>g equal) such thatthe range of demand above the ask<strong>in</strong>g pñce is elastic. If theydiscover that they can <strong>in</strong>crease their monetary <strong>in</strong>come by produc<strong>in</strong>gless--or even destroy<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g stock_<strong>in</strong> the next seU<strong>in</strong>gperiod, then they do so.Rothbard ma<strong>in</strong>taim that to speak of the <strong>in</strong>itial price as the"competitive" price, and the second-period price as the"monopoly" price makes no objective seme. How, he asks, is it tobe objectively determ<strong>in</strong>ed that the first price is really the "competitive"price? Gould it, <strong>in</strong> fact llave been a "subcompetitive"price? Indeed, the entire discussion is absurd for Rothbard s<strong>in</strong>cethere are no <strong>in</strong>depende_ cñteña t,hat would allow either determ<strong>in</strong>ation.AII that can be lmown for sure, he argues, is that thepñces both before and after the supply change are free-marketprices.


104 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Rothbard also argues that "monopoly" prices cannot be <strong>in</strong>ferredby compar<strong>in</strong>g such prices to prices charged for similarfactors. So long as the factors ate not perfectly idenfical <strong>in</strong> theeyes of buyers, the differences <strong>in</strong> price (of profits) ate simplyfree-market determ<strong>in</strong>ations of value for different goods. Andany talk of monopoly price of monopoly "ga<strong>in</strong>" when two d/fferentfactors or goods ate be<strong>in</strong>g compared is analytically <strong>in</strong>.COITeCt. _8F<strong>in</strong>ally, the welfare implications concern<strong>in</strong>g alleged monopolyprices would not fo[low even ir such prices could exist. S<strong>in</strong>ce the<strong>in</strong>elasticity of demand for Rothbard is "purely the result ofvo|untary demands" of the consumers, and s<strong>in</strong>ce the exchange(at the higher prices) is completely "voluntary" anyway, there isno way to conclude that consumers of their"welfare" have been<strong>in</strong>jured. 2e Thus, for Rothbard there ís no social "problem" associatedwith monopoly <strong>in</strong> a free market. Monopoly príces cannotbe def<strong>in</strong>ed logically, let alone established <strong>in</strong> a free market.CRITICAL REVIEW OF dUSTRIAN MONOPOLY THEORYThe views of Kirzner and Mises that monopoly consists ofexclusive control over the whole supply ofsome specific resourcecreates a number of familiar difficulties. In the first place, there iwould appear to be no objective way to def<strong>in</strong>e beforehand some I"homogeneous" stock of resources that might be monopolízed.All <strong>in</strong>dividua[ly owned stocks of a resource could be differentiatedIat least with respect to location; <strong>in</strong> addition, the private-property system itself necessarily imparts a "differentiation" toall privately owned stocks. Further, even identical units ofsomegiven stock might be regarded differenfly by potential users, andthere would be no way to determ<strong>in</strong>e this beforehand. Hence, thisview of monopoly could reduce logically to the notion that eachand every unit of everyone's property stock is owned "monopolistically."Rothbard, it will be recalled, was critical of this def<strong>in</strong>ition ofmonopoly because its all-<strong>in</strong>dusiveness made ir "impractical,"


A Critique ofNeoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 105confus<strong>in</strong>g, and, ultimately, "absurd." But we can be critical of iton different grounds, employ<strong>in</strong>g Professor Kirzner's own (correct)view of the competitive market process. It will be recalledthat Kirzner had argued that the key to competition was freedoroof entry and that entry was impossible if potential entrepreneurscould not ga<strong>in</strong> access to monopolized resources, s°Yet,as has been noted above, ifall <strong>in</strong>dividual stocks of resources ate,<strong>in</strong> fact, monopolized, it would seem to follow that Kirzner's def<strong>in</strong>itionof monopoly would completely negate his own views oncompetition and market process. Indeed, it is difficult to understandhow any competition or market process would even bepossible with this def<strong>in</strong>itional approach. How could any competitionoccur if aU resources are monopolized?Even if it were to be assumed for the moment that resourcesare not uniquely specific and are, <strong>in</strong>stead, completelyhomogeneous, additional difficulties rema<strong>in</strong>. Why, for <strong>in</strong>stance,ought monopoly ownership to preclude thepossibility ofcompetitionfrom potentially rivalrous entrepreneurs that purchaseneeded resources? Indeed, Kirzner himself has already statedthat the market process is "always" competitive so long as there isfreedom to buy and sell <strong>in</strong> the market. 31Even monopoly ownershipdoes not erase the freedom to buy and seu s<strong>in</strong>ce it is possiblethat access to resources could be obta<strong>in</strong>ed, say, through purchase.Yet Kirzner argues that the "voy possibilitíesthemselves" ofcompetition may be elim<strong>in</strong>ated by monopoly ownership of aresource, s*Another difficulty with Professor Kirzner's approach is his useof the qualify<strong>in</strong>g terna, "current endowment of a certa<strong>in</strong> resource.''SsObviously, noth<strong>in</strong>g prevents potentially ñvalrous entrepreneursfrom explor<strong>in</strong>g for and exploit<strong>in</strong>g new supplies of aspecific resource. Indeed, "current endowment" of a resource isan ambiguous phrase s<strong>in</strong>ce supplies of resources ate normallyclassified as "proved," "probable," and "possible."If Kirzner means to imply that a monopoly over the currentproved endowment of a particular resource precludes thepossibilofcompetitionand allows the resource owner to be "immunefrom entrepreneurial competition, ''_4 he would be argu<strong>in</strong>g a


106 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>tenuous po<strong>in</strong>t at best. Clearly such a "monopoly" allows no suchth<strong>in</strong>g. In this example, future 35 entry is clearly possible andcannot be precluded a pr/or/. And s<strong>in</strong>ce the enre <strong>Austrian</strong>tradifion <strong>in</strong> this area is to treat the competifive process as one thatunfolds through t/me anyway, how ate the potential entrepreneurseffectively blocked from "díscover<strong>in</strong>g unexploited opportuniaesfor profit"?Asa f<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>t, monopoly over a resource would appear tomake rational economic calculadon difficult (if not impossible)s<strong>in</strong>ce no "market" would then exist for the resource, s6Withoutmarkets economic calculaUon is impossible s<strong>in</strong>ce objective pricescannot be determ<strong>in</strong>ed. A firm that monopolized "oranges" for<strong>in</strong>stance, would have no objective way of know<strong>in</strong>g, subsequendy,whether it was employ<strong>in</strong>g its resources efficiently <strong>in</strong> the productionof"orangejuice," or even whether it ought to be produc<strong>in</strong>gorange juice at all. This "def<strong>in</strong>ition" of monopol)_, therefore,would appear to be operationally self-destructive. Themonopoly posítion would tend to generate <strong>in</strong>evitable irrationalities<strong>in</strong> production s<strong>in</strong>ce entrepreneurs would have noobjective way to calculate "costs."Mises, it will be recaUed, realized the <strong>in</strong>herent difficulfies ofdef<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g monopoly, and so he moved on to the catallactíc significanceof monopoly: obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the monopoly price and, thus,frustraf<strong>in</strong>g "the wishes of the consumen." Professor Kirzner,although he denies that the elasUdty of the demand funcfion hasany bear<strong>in</strong>g whatever on whether a monopoly exists or not,nonetheless does argue that resource monopoly is likely to result<strong>in</strong> a restricted employment of such resources, higher prices, and ilarger surpluses for the producer employ<strong>in</strong>g the resource, a7 iImportantly, such ownership (at least <strong>in</strong> the short run) has!"harmful effects" s<strong>in</strong>ce it creates an <strong>in</strong>centive "for not us<strong>in</strong>g a ,scarce resource to the fullest extent compatible with the patternof consumer's tastes <strong>in</strong> the market."seIt is really difficult to see, however, why any of this argumentnecessarily follows. The "pattern ofconsumer tastes <strong>in</strong> the market"would appear to be, simply, consumer demand. C,omumerdemand is the vañable amount of some homogeneous stock that


A Critique ofNeodassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 107consumers would be will<strong>in</strong>g and able to purchase at variousprices. The important po<strong>in</strong>t to be made here is that <strong>in</strong> a freemarket such "demand" determ<strong>in</strong>ations by consumers are completelyvolunta d on their part, and all price-output comb<strong>in</strong>aonson that hypothetical function faithfuUy reflect that choice andrelate those "wishes" to the producers. Consequently, consumersare at all times <strong>in</strong> complete control of (fully sovereign over) theirown property at any given pñce-output comb<strong>in</strong>ation.It appears completely arbitrary to argue that only "low" prices,or "lower" prices <strong>in</strong>duced by "supply <strong>in</strong>creases," or only the"elastic" porfions of a consumer's demand function ate compablewith consumer sovereignty. Why are not consumers fully"sovereign" throughout the entire price-output range of their0wn demand function? After all it is they who determ<strong>in</strong>e, <strong>in</strong>certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stances, that they will trade greater volumes of dollarsfor fewer units of some good. Indeed, to prevent them fromengag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> such exchanges would more accurately <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>geupon their "sovereignty." If and when consumers become dissatisfiedwith such comb<strong>in</strong>ations, they are perfectly free tochange the "elasticity" oftheir own demand to comb<strong>in</strong>ations thatthe), do prefer.Ifthe above analysis is correct, it follows that resource ownersor producers that voluntarily "restrict" their supplies to obta<strong>in</strong>higher prices (not "force" them up as Professor Kirzner asserts)39have committed no sociaUy harmful act. Restrictedsupplies and higher prices rdative to what? All suppliers <strong>in</strong> freemarketsrestrictthdr supplies <strong>in</strong> the sen_ that theyonly supplyasmuch ofa good or resource as they determ<strong>in</strong>e u_ maximize their numetary orphysic <strong>in</strong>come. But, importantly, this is preciselywhat the "monopolist"does. Ifhis acUon is"harmful," then so is the economic activity ofall other suppliers <strong>in</strong> the market.Alternatively, it cannot be argued that what dist<strong>in</strong>guishes"monopoly" supply from "competitive" supply is the consequenfl),higher prices. In the first place we have already arguedthat the new price-output comb<strong>in</strong>ation is perfecfly compatiblewith expressed consumer demand and, therefore, with consumersovereignty. Secondly, prices are always "high" relative to


I108 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>lower prices that cou/dexist, but do not. Indeed, any price at all is"high," "frustrates" consumers, and reduces their ulñmate utilityfrom consumption. But surely the ability to charge a lowerprice than the prevail<strong>in</strong>g market price, or no pñce at all, canhardly be a correct criterion for judgíng whether a supply iscompetitive or monopolistic. Indeed, s<strong>in</strong>ce producers are a/s0sovereign under free-market conditions, we must conclude thatany supply is competitive and any price is "compatible" withconsumer sovereignty and consumer satisfaction.ROTHBARD'S MONOPOLY THEORY RECONSIDEREDRothbard it willbe recalled had def<strong>in</strong>ed monopoly as "a grantof special privilege from the State reserv<strong>in</strong>g a certa<strong>in</strong> area ofproduaion to one particular <strong>in</strong>dividual or group." This def<strong>in</strong>itionof monopoly would appear to be immune from the sort ofcriticism employed above aga<strong>in</strong>st both the neodassical andMises-Kii-znertheories of monopoly. In the first place, wecan beconfident that competition is "lessened" by this sort ofmonopoly, and that resources are nonoptimally allocated so faras consumers ate concerned, s<strong>in</strong>ce governmental monopoly restrictsby/aw both competitive entry and, consequently, freeconsumer choice.Legal barriersto entry restrict entry bydefmition.Areas of production that are truly"namrall3t' monopolisticwould hardly require governmental entry restrictions. Consequenfly,consumer choice must be distorted, and the subsequentresource allocations mustbe "<strong>in</strong>effident," s<strong>in</strong>ce consumenare prevented by law from mak<strong>in</strong>g choices that differ fromthose already made for them by the political authoñty. Hence,we condude that governmental monopoly dways restñcts compeUáon,always violates consumer (and producer) sovereignty,and a/ways"<strong>in</strong>jures" consumer welfare.Ir would be tempt<strong>in</strong>g to argue that these "restrictiom" and"<strong>in</strong>juries"are, perhaps, m<strong>in</strong>or <strong>in</strong> the case of"m<strong>in</strong>or" legal impedimentsto either production or exchange. Yet, there is nosatisfactory way to card/nally measure either "competition" orif_


A Critique ofNeoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong> Monopoly Theory 109consumer"utility." S<strong>in</strong>ce uUlity is a completely subjecUve noUon,and s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong>terpersonal comparisons of utility are not possible,there is no objective way to determ<strong>in</strong>e how severe even "m<strong>in</strong>or"state impediments to entry and competition actually are. It iscompletely possible, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that what rnay appear to be ahextremely <strong>in</strong>offensive governmental regulation, i.e., sett<strong>in</strong>gmínimum safety standards for sellers, may <strong>in</strong> fact be harmful <strong>in</strong>the extreme with respect to certa<strong>in</strong> potenal bus<strong>in</strong>essmen andspecific classes of consumers.We conclude, therefore, that any and o2/state restrictions are"monopolisc," compeon reduc<strong>in</strong>g, and destructive of consumersatisfaction vis-ñ-vis alternave free-market situations.We also conclude, <strong>in</strong> summary, that this particular theory ofmonopoly is the only theory that meets all the standard cfiticalobjections and rema<strong>in</strong>s entirely consistent with the general <strong>Austrian</strong>methodology.NOTES1. For a review ofthis position see, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Edw<strong>in</strong>Mansfield,M/croe.conom/_,Second Edition (Norton, 1975), Chapters 9 & 10.2. WiUardF. Mueller,A Primeron Monopolyand c0mpet/t/on(RandoroHouse, 1970), Chapter 2.3. hrael M. Kirzner,CompetitionandEntr¿,prenna'ship(UniversityofChicago Press, 1973).4. D. T. Armentano,TheMy0isofAnt/tn_: Econom/cTheoryand Lega/Coses(Arl<strong>in</strong>gton house, 1972), Chapter 2.5. Ibig, pp. 212--15, 246, 267-68.6. Ludwig ron Mises,Human Action (YaleUniversityPress, 1963),p. 358.7. Ib/d.8. Ib/d., pp. 358-60.9. Ibid., p. 358.10. lb/d., p 371.11. Ib/d., 1.,1373.12. Ib/d., p. $71.15. Ib/d., p. 373.14. Ib/d., p. $75.


110 <strong>New</strong> D:'rections <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>15. Ib/d., p. 364.16. Kirzner, op. c/t., Chapter I.17. Ib/d., p. 21.18. Ib/d., p. 103.19. Ib/d.20. 1/ñd., p. 105.21. Ibíd., p. 110.22. Ibíd., p. 111.23. Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and $tate, Volume II (D.Van Nostrand Company, Inc., 1962), pp. 561-66. See alsoJoumal ofEconom_ Lit_ature, September-October, 1974, pp. 902-3.24. Rothbard, op. c/t., pp. 590-93.25. I/r/d., p. 591.26. lb/d., p. 593.27. Ib/d., p. 614.28. Ib/d., pp. 608-9.29. Ib/d., p. 564.30. Kirzner, op. c/t., p. 103.31. Ibid., p. 20. This statement would seem to refute Kirzner's enreposition on monopoly. If markets are a/tttays competitive so long asthere isfreedom to buy and sell, then <strong>in</strong> a free market there is alwayscompetition and nevtr any monopoly.32. Ib/d., p. 103.33. Ib/d., p. 21.34. lb/d., p. 110.35. And "future" <strong>in</strong> an entrepreneurial sense can mean the n_moment competitive supply appears or threatens to appear.36. See Rothbard's discussion of similar problems for cartels <strong>in</strong>Man,Economy, and State.37. Kirzner, op. r/t., p. 110.38. Ib/d., p. 111.39. lb/d., p. 110.


Spontaneous Orderand the Coord<strong>in</strong>ationof Economic Activifies*Gerald P. O'Driscoll, Jr.Iowa State UniversityThis paper is an essay on the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activities.It is exploratory and speculative, connect<strong>in</strong>g argumentsthat I have made <strong>in</strong> several other places. The essay is an attemptto give a coherent picture ofsome of the theoretical and practicalproblems fac<strong>in</strong>g economists, as well as society <strong>in</strong> general. Writtenfor a conference on <strong>Austrian</strong> economics, this paper deals withquesfions specifically from that disUnctive víewpo<strong>in</strong>t. It is notthat I propose to defend the proposition that economists of thisschool possess a uniquely correct perspective of the issues, butmerely that they have much to say on the particular questionswith which I wiU deal. I trust that my references to economistsnot normally considered to be members of the Austñan SchoolwiUdemonstrate the universality of the problems discussed here.Those economists who view a system of free exchange---AdamSmith's "obvious and simple system of natural liberty"_---as thesolution of the coord<strong>in</strong>ation problem <strong>in</strong> economics face <strong>in</strong>tellecmalchallenges from at least four sources: first, the conánuíngcha_Uengeof the Keynesian legacy; second, the cha_enge fromwhat James Buchanan has termed the "modero Ricardians";*This essay appeared <strong>in</strong> The Journal of L/herrar/ahStud/es 1 (Spr<strong>in</strong>g1977): 137--51.Copyright © 1977 Pergamon Press Ltd.111


112 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>third, the challenge from the new movement for national plann<strong>in</strong>g;and f<strong>in</strong>ally, the challenge from certa<strong>in</strong> economists <strong>in</strong> the<strong>Austrian</strong> School.In previous papers, I have dealt with the <strong>Austrian</strong> analysis ofmonetary theory (or macroeconomics) as it is concerned with thecoord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activities. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, I wiU beg<strong>in</strong>with this general problem.THE KEYNESIANLEGACYIr has become clear <strong>in</strong> recent years that Keynes's General Theoryis a very confused work, so much that it is virtually ah <strong>in</strong>k-blot testfor economists: ah economist's perception of its conter, ts tellsmore about the beliefs of the reader than the _ontents of thatbook. s Indeed, Keynes's sympathetic critics are compelled topo<strong>in</strong>t out these confusions <strong>in</strong> their attempts to argue that hemade a significant contribution to our understand<strong>in</strong>g of theeconomic system. The best example of this is Axel Leijonhufvud'sOn Keynesian <strong>Economics</strong> and the <strong>Economics</strong> of Keynes. sLeijonhufvud argues there that Keynes had important <strong>in</strong>sights<strong>in</strong>to coord<strong>in</strong>ation failures <strong>in</strong> market systems. Specifically,Leijonhufvud's Keynes argued that bank<strong>in</strong>g and fmancial systemscan operate so as to impede rather than to facilitate theadjustment to a change <strong>in</strong> the equilibrium rate of <strong>in</strong>terest. Secuñesmarkets ate <strong>in</strong>capable of mov<strong>in</strong>g from a higher to alower equilibrium tate of <strong>in</strong>terest, without attendant fluctuaons<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>come and employment. This is true whether the assumeddismrbance consists of a downward shift <strong>in</strong> the marg<strong>in</strong>alefficiency of <strong>in</strong>vestment (Keynes's marg<strong>in</strong>al effidency of capital),of an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the savíngs schedule (a decreased marg<strong>in</strong>alpropensity to consume out of current <strong>in</strong>come). The existence ofbearish speculators <strong>in</strong> securies markets impedes smooth adjustmentof those markets. Keynes's bears do this by speculangaga<strong>in</strong>st any rise <strong>in</strong> the prices of long-lived assets, real or f<strong>in</strong>ancial.'Keynesian bears speculate on the basis of the historicalpercepon that the), possess of a "normal" long run tate of


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 113<strong>in</strong>terest. If this normal long-rate could be taken as summariz<strong>in</strong>gthe real forces determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the equilibrium rate of<strong>in</strong>terest, thenit is quite reasonable, from a profit-maximiz<strong>in</strong>g viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, forspeculators to treat deviaUons from the rateas temporary fluctuations.5 Indeed, Keynes's speculators behave precisely the waytextbook examples suggest, <strong>in</strong> that they act so as to basten thereturn to theperceived equilibñum position (though this effect isnot part of their <strong>in</strong>tention, of course). But <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>stance,speculaUve activity, follow<strong>in</strong>g a guide that normally proves reliable,proves to be disequilibraUng <strong>in</strong> its effects. Speculators aremisled <strong>in</strong>to identify<strong>in</strong>g as but a transitory fluctuation what <strong>in</strong> factis the consequence of a shift <strong>in</strong> parameters.In microtheory ir is customary to po<strong>in</strong>t out that speculatorswho misidentify an equilibrium position wiUsuffer capital losses,and that, <strong>in</strong> any case, market forces wiUrestore equilibrium. ButKeynes raised ah important issue: bearish speculators, <strong>in</strong> exhibit<strong>in</strong>gliquidity preference, can <strong>in</strong>itiate deflaUonary pressures. 6Unless we assume that wage and price changes occur <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itelyfast, then price deflation will be accompanied by quanUtyadjustments.7 In effect, the result<strong>in</strong>g speculative losses becomesocialized. To puta Keynesian proposition <strong>in</strong> Hayekian terms,the un<strong>in</strong>tended consequences of a speculative search for liquiditygenerate fall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>come and general iUiquidity. Ifone adoptsthe posiUonmas do most <strong>Austrian</strong>s--that-the marketprocess is acont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g search for opportunities, one cannot dismiss out ofhand the possibility that speculation of the .Keynesian varietycould <strong>in</strong>hibit the equih'braUng market forces. And unless oneadopts the view that prices ate always correct, which no <strong>Austrian</strong>would do, then one must confront this Keynesian <strong>in</strong>formationproblem.Several po<strong>in</strong>ts need to be made here. I have been talk<strong>in</strong>g of"Leijonhufvud's Keynes," because of the problematical namreof The General Theory. Yet my paraphrase of Leijonhufvud's<strong>in</strong>terpretaUon is a fairly straightforward argument about discoord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gmarket processes. The obvious question that comesto m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> th_iscontext is why Keynes didn't say all this explicitlyand simply ff this is what he meant? The thesis, as I have pre-


114 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> ,,lustrian <strong>Economics</strong>sented ít, can obviously be put very succ<strong>in</strong>cfly. What makesLeijonhufvud's presentation of ir so difficult is the web ofconfusionwoven by Keynes.In order to show that his <strong>in</strong>terpretation has captured theauthendc Keynes, Lei.jonhufvud not only must ¢ridcize ¢onflictíng<strong>in</strong>terpretations, but he must deal with Keynes's own imprecisionand confusion. The dearest example of these problemsoccurs <strong>in</strong> Leijonhufvud's discussion of Keynes's views on capitalBefore exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g this discussion, however, one must considerthe <strong>in</strong>tellecmal background to the treatment of capital quesdons<strong>in</strong> The General Theory.Hayek was quite cñtical of Keynes's earlíer book, the Treati_eon Money, when he reviewed that work. The general tenor of biscridcísm is that Keynes, at the ume he wrote that book, waslargely ignorant of capital theory. Hayek recognized that Keyneshad developed a neo-Wicksellian theory, but without the necessarytheoretícal foundations, s And he observed that:Ir is a pr/or/unlikely that an attempt to utilise the conclusionsdrawnfrom a certa<strong>in</strong> theory without accepdng that theory itself should besu¢cessful. But, <strong>in</strong> the case of ah author of Mr. Keynes' <strong>in</strong>teUectualcalibre,the attempt produces results which are truly remarkable,tIn ah amaz<strong>in</strong>g piece of candor, Keynes all but admitted thelegitimacy of Hayek's cridsm; after defend<strong>in</strong>g himself by observ<strong>in</strong>gthat there was no "satisfactory theory" of capital <strong>in</strong>"completed forro," Keynes stated:Nevertheless, substantiallyI concede Dr. Hayek's po<strong>in</strong>t. I agree withhim that a alear accountof the factorsdeterm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the naturalrateof<strong>in</strong>terestought tohave a place<strong>in</strong> a completed TreatiseonMomy, and thatít is lack<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> re<strong>in</strong>e: and I can only plead that I had much to say forwhichsuch a theory isnot requiredand thatmyown ideasaboutitwerestill too much <strong>in</strong> embryo to deserve publicafion. Later on, I wiUendeavorto make good this defidency? °Did Keynes ever"make good this ddiciency"? I do not believeso, and I offer the foUow<strong>in</strong>g observadora <strong>in</strong> support of thisjudgment. Much of the confusion surround<strong>in</strong>g the namre of


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of EconomicActivities 115Keynes's message can be accounted for if one accepts the thesisthat Keynes rema<strong>in</strong>ed largely ignorant of capital theory. He haddifficulty, then, <strong>in</strong> present<strong>in</strong>g his message because he did notpossess the requisite technical knowledge. Of course, one couldalso <strong>in</strong>fer that Keynes was not sure of the message that he wishedto present. There is evidence for this <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> the recentobservafion of one of his close associates at Cambñdge, JoanRob<strong>in</strong>son, who noted that certa<strong>in</strong> of Keynes's putaUve followers"... had some trouble <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g Maynard to see what the po<strong>in</strong>tof his revolution really was .... -11But I would offer asa f<strong>in</strong>aljudgment of Keynes the observationof his recent <strong>in</strong>terpreter, Axel Leijonhufvud. By far themost difficult chapter of the latter's book is the fourth, "TheGeneral Theory of Liquidity Preference," <strong>in</strong> which both the stateof capital theory <strong>in</strong> the thirdes and Keynes's own views on thesubject are presented. Of this complexity, Leijonhufvud remarks:"This chapter will be a lengthy affair, partly beca.use ofthe <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic difficulty of capital theory, partly because Keynesdid not work out his ideas on the subject <strong>in</strong> much detail so that weare left with only what amounts to an unf<strong>in</strong>ished sketch. ''I_ Inshort, Keynes never made up the self-admitted deficiency of theTreatise. Moreover, it is only by hav<strong>in</strong>g thus demonstratedKeynes's lack of knowledge and clarity that Leijonhufvud canmake it at aU plausible that Keynes hada comparatively simplepo<strong>in</strong>t to make (i.e., stick<strong>in</strong>ess of <strong>in</strong>terest rates), though this po<strong>in</strong>tis not the one commonly attributed to him (i.e., stick<strong>in</strong>ess ofmoney wage rates).There are several approaches that one can take to Keynes'schallenge. Conceptual errors abound <strong>in</strong> The GeneralThe0ry; and Ihave suggested that <strong>in</strong> the area of capital theory, Keynes is quiteconfused. One can fairly easily engage <strong>in</strong> piecemeal criticism ofKeynes's ideas. I do not believe that the Keynesian system canstand up to such a criticism. But I am not sure that this is afruitful approach, though I myself have adopted it on previousoccasions, ls The reasons are several-fold. First, no one, I believe,can get beyond the exegetical problem--I refer the reader aga<strong>in</strong>to my <strong>in</strong>k-blot analogy. No matter which Keynes one criticizes, a


116 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>new Keynes is proffered <strong>in</strong> its stead. More to the po<strong>in</strong>t, one m stconsider the possibility that the most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g recent <strong>in</strong>terpretationbears scant resemblance to Keynes's ideas. Yeager hasargued, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that Leijonhufvud and Clower both seemprepared to credit Keynes with their own, orig<strong>in</strong>al contribu-Uons. 14Perhaps, then Keynes is the wrong target of any criticism.Nonetheless, the Keynesian debate does raise importanttheoretical issues that <strong>Austrian</strong>s must confront, regardless ofwho is adjudged the author of particular views. And I believethat there is one unify<strong>in</strong>g theme runn<strong>in</strong>g through most, ifnot all,versions of Keynesian economics: the self-correct<strong>in</strong>g forces ofthe market economy cannot be relied upon to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> fullemploymentand reasonable price stability. In its .t most extremeversion, this criticism would even deny the existence of selfcorrect<strong>in</strong>gmarket forces. Itis to the issue of the strength of thesemarket forces that <strong>Austrian</strong>s should address themselves, for-it isnow becom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly accepted that macroeconomics is <strong>in</strong>fact concerned with the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activities.Leijonhufvud has stated the problemas foUows:•.. The central issue <strong>in</strong> macroeconomic theory ís--_nce aga<strong>in</strong>--theextent to which the economy, or at least its market sectors, may properlybe regarded as a self-regulat<strong>in</strong>g system.... How wellor badly, doits "automaác" mechanisms perform?_=Before cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g,<strong>in</strong> detail.it would be well to consider this latter issueTHE PRINCIPLE OF SPONTANEOUS ORDERThe pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneous order--or of "undesigned order,"as it might more properly be called--can be viewed as thefirst pr<strong>in</strong>dple of economics. Indeed, James Buchanan has recentlygone so far as to suggest that it is the on/y pr<strong>in</strong>ciple ofeconomics. The pr<strong>in</strong>dple is, <strong>in</strong> any case, a comerstone of moderneconomics, whet.her we trace modern (Le., pog-mercanfilisO


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 117economics back to Adam Smith and the other Scottish moralphilosophers, or to the Physiocrats. With this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, scholarsfor the first time could see economic phenomena as <strong>in</strong>terdependentevents. Indeed, this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple made it possible to reasonsystematically and coherently about economic phenomena.Much of n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century economics can be seen as consist<strong>in</strong>gof developments of this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple (along with m<strong>in</strong>ority criticismsof the pr<strong>in</strong>cíple and the systems of thought deduced therefrom).On the other hand, most of twentieth century economics hasconsisted of reactions aga<strong>in</strong>st systems <strong>in</strong> which this pr<strong>in</strong>cipleplays a central role. In this, Keynesian economics is but oneamong a family of theories that deny the existence of a spontaneousor undesigned market order <strong>in</strong> which plans are coord<strong>in</strong>ated.The reaction has been so complete that what was taken byearlier economists to be an empirical law_the existence of aspontaneous market order--is now frequently viewed as theproduct of ideological bias or prejudice. If anyth<strong>in</strong>g, moderoeconomic discussiom presuppose the absence of the very orderwhose existence was the cornerstone of much of n<strong>in</strong>eteenthcentury economics. In this sense, modern economics is fundamentally<strong>in</strong>consistent, lsIt is apparent now that the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple was not firmly enoughestablished <strong>in</strong> economics to withstand the criticisms that werelevied aga<strong>in</strong>st it. Yet the question of the existence of a spontaneouslygenerated order rema<strong>in</strong>s the central question ofeconomics and of social theory generally--even though it isseldom recognized as sucia. Theories of the <strong>in</strong>stability of <strong>in</strong>vestment,of sav<strong>in</strong>g, and of aggregate demand ate aUvariants of thegeneral proposition that the economy lacks strong forces lead<strong>in</strong>gto an undesigned order. These are not simply disputes of technicaleconomics, narrowly def<strong>in</strong>ed, though they too long havebeen treated as such. The question of the necessary amount ofgovernmental stab'flizaon policy wiUnot ge decided by runn<strong>in</strong>gyet another money-demand equation through a computer.Nonetheless, it is imperative that the question be addresseddirectly once aga<strong>in</strong>? 7As <strong>in</strong>teUectual descendants of Carl Menger, most <strong>Austrian</strong>


118 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> duarian <strong>Economics</strong>economists have defended the proposition that spontaneousmarket forces are capable of produc<strong>in</strong>g an overall order <strong>in</strong>society. Hayek, for one, is well-known for his emphasis on therole of nonpurposive social organizations <strong>in</strong> this process. TM Indeed,the persistence of members of this school <strong>in</strong> their views <strong>in</strong>the face of the contrary op<strong>in</strong>ion of much of the profession hascontributed to their <strong>in</strong>tellectual isolation. In this sense, and aloneamong the neoclassical schools, the <strong>Austrian</strong>s can today lay claimto be<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>heritors of the Smithian system. In this, thebicentenary of the publication of The Wealth ofNations, it wouldbe well for <strong>Austrian</strong> economists to seize the opportunity to reestablishthe importance of the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneousorder_an order that, though designed by no one, emerges fromthe <strong>in</strong>dividual and <strong>in</strong>dependent plann<strong>in</strong>g of market transactors.THE NEW RICMRDIANS I_There is yet another tradition <strong>in</strong> the history of economics,dist<strong>in</strong>ct from both the <strong>Austrian</strong> and Smithian traditions, andfrom those that are overtly hosUle to these traditions. It is atradition epitomized by David Ricardo's general approach toeconomic questions. In the Ricardian tradition, attenUon is focusedon the long run, <strong>in</strong> which full adjustment to all disturbanceshas occurred. Peñods of transition are abstracted from. 2oIt would be anachronistic to credit Ricardo with a theory ofperfect <strong>in</strong>formation, but he wrote as though the laborers,capitalists, and rentiers of his system had full access to futureevents. The difference between the Smithian and Ricardiantraditions is a subtle, though important one; and it separatestheorists even today.In Smith's world, changes are constantly occurr<strong>in</strong>g, and adaptaUonsto these changes are never complete. These changes maybe of comparatively simple variety, such as variations <strong>in</strong> the comharvest from year to year (with attendant effects on real wagerates),s_ More importantly, Smith was concemed with the cont<strong>in</strong>uousprocess of market adaptation to LnvenUon and further


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 119extensions of the division of labor. Changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions andthe legal structure are of prime concern. 22It is not, of course,that Smith had noth<strong>in</strong>g to say about the long run. His valuetheory is a long-run theory, though I f<strong>in</strong>d it one of the leastdeveloped parts of Iris system. _3 Nonetheless, the emphasis <strong>in</strong>The Wealth of Nations is on change. Moreover, Smith's actorssuffer various illusions and misunderstand<strong>in</strong>gs about futureevents, and, <strong>in</strong>deed, about their own seff-<strong>in</strong>terest. None of thiswould make sense <strong>in</strong> a Rícardian world.Whether ir is a quesUon of monetary economics or of fiscalpolicy, Ricardo generally treats all disturbances as though theywere fully and completely anticipated. 24In the Ricardian world,then, the problem of coord<strong>in</strong>ation disappears. It is not thatRicardo denied the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneous order. Rather hedid not treat the emergence of coord<strong>in</strong>ated behavior on themarket asa problem. He <strong>in</strong> effect assumed that economic behaviorwill be coord<strong>in</strong>ated. Most importantly, and unlike Smith,Ricardo generally ignored the question of what <strong>in</strong>stitutionalarrangements are necessary for the emergence of that orderupon which the soundness of his arguments depends.The imtitutional sett<strong>in</strong>g and the allocation mechanism matter<strong>in</strong> economics precisely because behavior <strong>in</strong> a chang<strong>in</strong>g world isnot automatically coord<strong>in</strong>ated. Laws and imtitutions have a significantimpact on human behavior precSsely because somefacilitate and some <strong>in</strong>hibit the flow of <strong>in</strong>fo_l_lation that is necessaryfor adaptation <strong>in</strong> a chang<strong>in</strong>g world. This realization isceRdmly conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> The Wealth of Nat/ons--Smith's emphasison the importance of these matters suffuses that work. Not sowith Ricardo's Pr/n__.th'ofessor Lachmann has recently rem<strong>in</strong>ded us that the problemof eommm__ coord<strong>in</strong>ation is <strong>in</strong>timately <strong>in</strong>volved with thetw<strong>in</strong> problems of acquisition and diffusion of knowledge amongtransactors. In deal<strong>in</strong>g with the characterisdc assumption thatthe state of Lnowledge is among the data of the system, hequeries:Do weassume thatall marketactorsknowall thetastesandresources<strong>in</strong>


120 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>all markets <strong>in</strong> which they, actuallyor potentially, do or might operate?But if so, equilibrium should at once be atta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> ah markets. If wewere to make this assumption, there could be no disequilibñum, nodeal<strong>in</strong>gs at "false prices." Walras's "auctioneer" would become superfluous.If, on the other hand, we do not make it, how do we delimit the•extent of each actor's knowledge ateach po<strong>in</strong>t of time, and how do wedeal with the flow of knowledge between actor s over ume?" _sDiscussion about the importance of <strong>in</strong>formation may seemprosaic to economists at this po<strong>in</strong>t. But the radical implicaons ofimperfect knowledge have simply not been generany absorbed<strong>in</strong> economic theory. For, <strong>in</strong>ter a//a, imperfecon of knowledgemeam that prices do not necessarily coord<strong>in</strong>ate economic behavior,as those prices are <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the <strong>in</strong>consistent expectaonson the basis of"false" price signals. Tojustify one's faith<strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g function of markets, one cannot simplyassume that prices are coord<strong>in</strong>ang, or at their equiñbrium level.Rather, one must be concerned with the imfimtional environmentof economic systems and with the appropriateness of these<strong>in</strong>stimfions for the emergence of a spontaneous market order.One must be concemed, then, with specify<strong>in</strong>g the simations <strong>in</strong>which prices will coord<strong>in</strong>ate, and those situaons <strong>in</strong> which pñcesw<strong>in</strong> not coord<strong>in</strong>ate, economic acvity. By his attention to thelong run, <strong>in</strong> which, ex hyp0ther/, all such problems disappearbecause full adjustment to ah changes has occurred, Ricardo(and his followers) ignored these difficules.The problem of economic coord<strong>in</strong>aon is a theoretical andpractical issue not merely because decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g is decentralized,though this is an important aspect of the problem. Ofeven more importance is the fact that we live <strong>in</strong> a world ofconstant change. Were there decentralized decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g, butan unchang<strong>in</strong>g environment, it might be reasonable to supposethat economic acávity could be coord<strong>in</strong>ated under a wide varietyof <strong>in</strong>su'tuUonal and allocational arrangements. Learn<strong>in</strong>g wouldoccur due to the repetítion of events, with adjustments made aspast errors were revealed, s' A price system and appropriatemarket <strong>in</strong>sfitutiom are of praccal signi_ficance precisely becauseof the need to register the effects of cont<strong>in</strong>uous changes <strong>in</strong> the


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 121data, changes which ate given to no one <strong>in</strong> their entirety. On theother hand, it is doubtful whether money, prices, or the marketsystem would exist <strong>in</strong> the stationary state. Those who ignore thisaspect of imperfect <strong>in</strong>formation are caught <strong>in</strong> the dilemma ofdeal<strong>in</strong>g with phenomena, most of which would not exkst <strong>in</strong> theworld as the), assume that world to exist--a world of perfectlycoord<strong>in</strong>ated plato. 2TRicardo and bis epigones thus obscured the basic quesfions ofsocial order that Smith had raised. They shifted the emphasisaway from these questiom to the theorems and lemmas of valuetheory. Their legacy is still with us today. Walras and theLau_nne _hool <strong>in</strong>troduced the concept of general equilibrium<strong>in</strong>to economics. But <strong>in</strong> other respects the Walrasian system isquite similar to the Ricardian: both are perfectly coord<strong>in</strong>atedsystems. By the sheer logic of these systems, neither is obviouslyconcerned with the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activitie: =thiscoord<strong>in</strong>ation is implicifly assumed to take place. In such systemslaws and <strong>in</strong>stitutions do not matter. Monetary dismrbances canhave no significant effects--for the tramition periods <strong>in</strong> whichmoney dearly matters are de-emphasized or ignored <strong>in</strong> theRicardian system, n In such systems, the market would not beviewed asa process <strong>in</strong> which cont<strong>in</strong>ual adjustment to cont<strong>in</strong>ualchange occurs, but a state of affairs <strong>in</strong> whie.hthis process was atan end.The Ghicago School can be fairly described as the modernRicardians. In Kirzner's term<strong>in</strong>ology, th_ transactors <strong>in</strong> theChicago world are noth<strong>in</strong>g but Robb<strong>in</strong>sian maximizers. 2sChicago economists are Ricardian <strong>in</strong> their approach to questionsof tax and expenditure policy and monetary policy, to cite twoexamples previously mentioned for Ricardo. The Ricardianbent of the Chicago School is important to the <strong>Austrian</strong> Schoolfor at least two reasons.Fi1_t, the time has passed when members of the ChicagoSchool .werearticulate, but m<strong>in</strong>ority members of the profession.Increas<strong>in</strong>gb/, economic discussions and debates are <strong>in</strong>fluencedby their approach. Second, on issues <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>aUonquestiom, their Ricardian lean<strong>in</strong>gs re-enforce the Walrasian ap-


122 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economics</strong>proach of the dom<strong>in</strong>ant mathematical, general equilibriumtheorists. This is an important po<strong>in</strong>t because economists arebeg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to recognize the dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness of the Marshallianapproach (v/s¿ v/s the Walrasianapproach) of Chicago Schooleconomists. And the differences between Chicago Schooleconomists and the rest of the profession are important for awide variety of issues, such as the role of empiñcal research,partial vs. general equilibrium analysis,etc. But as regards thecoord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activities, the new Ricardiansand theneo-Walrasiam are more of one m<strong>in</strong>d. They tend to take forgranted that markets coord<strong>in</strong>ate economic activities. By do<strong>in</strong>gso, they ignore the complex questions of economic coord<strong>in</strong>ation,upon the solution of which depends the degree of economiccoord<strong>in</strong>ation. This approach is objectionable because of the conclusionsit engenders when markets demonstrably are not coord<strong>in</strong>a6ngeconomic activity. The "market failure" mentality is aneffea of this approach? ° "The market system"is adjudged afailure <strong>in</strong> such cases, with scant recognition that "the market" is ametaphor fora complex of <strong>in</strong>terrelatiomhips and <strong>in</strong>stitutiom,any one of which may be the source of the problem. Thatmembers of the Chicago School are generally more sangu<strong>in</strong>eabout the efficacy of this system hardly mitigates themethodological po<strong>in</strong>t be<strong>in</strong>g made here.<strong>Austrian</strong> economists and other adherents to the pr<strong>in</strong>dple ofspontaneous order willreceive little support and should generallyexpect overt hostility from the Chicago School on a widerange ofeconomic questions. 81<strong>Austrian</strong> economists tend to viewmost economic questions as issues <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the pñnciple ofspontaneous order. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, they take characteristic positiomon these quesons. Two of the areas where disagreementbetween the two schools is particularly <strong>in</strong>tense are monetary andcapital theory. Quite apart from their differences over the determ<strong>in</strong>ationof the equ/br/um values of <strong>in</strong>terest rates, the twoschools are sharply divided over the approach to questions ofcapital and <strong>in</strong>terest theory, as weUas those of monetary theory.Be<strong>in</strong>g Ricardians, members of the Chicago School naturallykeep questions of monetary theory and capital theory quite


SpontaneousOrderand the Coord<strong>in</strong>ationof EconomicActivities 123disdnct, s<strong>in</strong>ce these are dist<strong>in</strong>ct problems <strong>in</strong> long-run equilibriumanalysis. As did Ricardo, they treat deviations from theequilibrium rate of <strong>in</strong>terest as temporary fluctuaons. Thetransitional periods <strong>in</strong> which monetary disturbances <strong>in</strong>fluencethe accumulation of capital and the level of rate of <strong>in</strong>terest aretypicaUyignored or at least de-emphasized.On the other hand, many of the twenUeth century membersofthe <strong>Austrian</strong> School have dealt with the <strong>in</strong>terface betweenmonetary and capital theory. Misesand Hayek weremost persistent<strong>in</strong> their analysis of the <strong>in</strong>terrelation between monetary andcapital quesons, precisely because of their <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> adjustmentproblems. Hayek, for <strong>in</strong>stance, has been consistent <strong>in</strong> treat<strong>in</strong>geconomic fluctuations as manífestaons of economic discoord<strong>in</strong>aon,brought on by monetary disturbances? 2 ForHayek, monetary disturbances change entrepreneuñal expectaonsand lead to capital accumulation that, expost, is revealedtohave been mal<strong>in</strong>vestment. These mal<strong>in</strong>vestments cause realscarcities,whose existence becomes manifest <strong>in</strong> subsequent pricechanges. The price changes compel entrepreneurs--because ofthe capital losses that they eventually <strong>in</strong>cur--to revise their <strong>in</strong>vestmentplans. It is <strong>in</strong> this sense that modern <strong>Austrian</strong>s viewcydical expansions brought about by monetary and credit <strong>in</strong>flaonas self-revers<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>herendy unstable.3"_Hayek and Misesthus dealt with phenomena virtuallyignoredby monetary theorists of the Chicago School--the transitionpeñod between a monetary disturbance and complete adjustmentto its effects,s4To the extent that ProfessorFriedman, forimtance, deals with the transition peñod, it is only <strong>in</strong> terms ofone, comparatively narrow problem---anticipation of futureprice levels,ss Asa praccal matter, monetarists generally view<strong>in</strong>flaUon as synchronized <strong>in</strong>flation, with all pñces ris<strong>in</strong>g par/pa.m_.For Hayek and Mises, synchronized <strong>in</strong>flation is a fantasy,so long as monetary disturbances imp<strong>in</strong>ge at specific po<strong>in</strong>ts,ssAnd fuUadjustment to <strong>in</strong>flation would be all but <strong>in</strong>conceivable,as it would <strong>in</strong>volve each actor's antidpat<strong>in</strong>g correctlythe precisechanges <strong>in</strong> each relative pñce that wiUoccur <strong>in</strong> each futureperiod, due to the assumed monetary dismrbances.37


124 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Once aga<strong>in</strong>, the Ricardian approach to monetary questionsbl<strong>in</strong>ds its users to the issues considered paramount by the <strong>Austrian</strong>s.In so do<strong>in</strong>g, this approach,<strong>in</strong>hibits ah understandíng ofimportant issues confront<strong>in</strong>g market economists. For the Ricardian,quantity theory approach is one <strong>in</strong> which prices contínuetheir coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g function even <strong>in</strong> ah <strong>in</strong>flation. Yet, the po<strong>in</strong>t atissue is whether spontaneous market forces operate as usual <strong>in</strong>an <strong>in</strong>flation. If monetary disturbances not only generate pureprice <strong>in</strong>flation, but also <strong>in</strong>terfere with the coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gmechanisms <strong>in</strong> ah economy, then the quantity theory approachignores an important research programme <strong>in</strong> economic_ thestudy of the monetary framework necessary for pñces to fulfiUtheir coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g function? s In the words of one expositor ofHayek's ideas:[Hayek] regarded pñces.., as empirical reflectors of spedfic circumstancesand price changes as ah <strong>in</strong>ter-rdated señes of changes <strong>in</strong>these "signals," which produced a gradual adaptaon <strong>in</strong> the entireprice structure (and hence <strong>in</strong> the outputs of different commodiUesandservices) to the constant, unpredictable changes <strong>in</strong> the real world.Pric<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> short, is seen asa cont<strong>in</strong>uous <strong>in</strong>formation-collect<strong>in</strong>g anddissem<strong>in</strong>aUng process, but it is the <strong>in</strong>sUmtional framework that determ<strong>in</strong>esboth the extem to which and the degree of success with which,f rices are enabled to perform this potential signall<strong>in</strong>g or allocativencUon.89PLANNING4oThat nonpurposive social organizations will namrally evolveand that an undesigned order can be the product of selfregard<strong>in</strong>gacts are radical ideas <strong>in</strong> Western thought. These ideasrun counter to the dom<strong>in</strong>ant approach to social questions andwere <strong>in</strong> ascendency for only a brief peñod <strong>in</strong> Western <strong>in</strong>tellec- [mal history. It is not, then, enUrely surpris<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong> economics !these ideas have not ga<strong>in</strong>ed complete acceptance; and thatamong the general public, even the so-called educated public,they are scarcely understood at aH. But there is danger that !because of essenfially reactionary developments <strong>in</strong> social


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 125thought, the <strong>in</strong>sights that were the product of the Enlightenmentwill be all but lost <strong>in</strong> practice. Adam Smith has apflycharacterized the lar older conception of social order:The man of system.... seems to imag<strong>in</strong>e that he can arrange thedifferent members of a great society with as much easeas the handarranges the different pieces upona chess-board;he does not considerthat the pieces upon the chess-board have no other pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of motionbesidesthat which the hand impresses upon them; but that, <strong>in</strong> the greatchess-board of human society, every s<strong>in</strong>gle piece has a pñnciple ofmotion of its own, altogether different from that which the legislaturemight choose to impress upon it. If those two pr<strong>in</strong>ciples co<strong>in</strong>cide andact <strong>in</strong> the same direction, the game of human society will go on easilyand harmoniously, and isverylikelyto be happy and successful. Ir theyareopposite or different, the game willgo on miserably,and the societymust be at al1ames <strong>in</strong> the highest degree of disorder.41The liberal conception of society of Adam Smith and theclassical economists stands <strong>in</strong> sharp contrast with this older view.Yet once aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the United States, we see evidence of this olderconception's becom<strong>in</strong>g prom<strong>in</strong>ent, under the guise of nationaleconomic plann<strong>in</strong>g. Proposals for plann<strong>in</strong>g ate embodiments ofthe chess-game conception of social affairs, adapted to the problemof economic allocation. These pro posals implicitly orexplicifly deny that market forces guide decision mak<strong>in</strong>g, so as toproduce an overall, yet undesigned order; and they virtually_gnore the function and tole of nonpurposive economic organizaUons.It is not that the arguments for national (i.e., central) economicplann<strong>in</strong>g constitute a direct <strong>in</strong>tdlectual challenge to opponents ofsuch plann<strong>in</strong>g. As Professor Hayek has recently demonstrated <strong>in</strong>a devastat<strong>in</strong>g rebuttal of these proposals, modern exponents of"plann<strong>in</strong>g" possess as naive and ill-thought-out an approach tothe problem as did the Bolsheviks and European socialists <strong>in</strong> theimmediate post-World War I period. As he notes:The concepon [coUectivisteconomic plann<strong>in</strong>g], oñg<strong>in</strong>ally developedby some of the orgarAzersof the C,erman wareconomy duñng World-- • " " ' dWar I, was thoroughly discussed by economlsts <strong>in</strong> the 19,20s an


126 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>1930's; and aH those familiar with that discussion will agree that itgreaflycontributedto the darificationof concepts and thatone oughttodayto be entifled to assume that no competenteconomist who livedthrough thatdiscussionwouldever aga<strong>in</strong>talkabouttheissues <strong>in</strong> temasof the vague and confused concepts <strong>in</strong>itiallybandied about.4sIndeed, if this debate were be<strong>in</strong>g carried out <strong>in</strong> the scholarlyarena, I doubt that the proposals put forth by those <strong>in</strong> favor ofcentral plann<strong>in</strong>g would survive Hayek's recent criticisms. Unfortunately,the debate is not be<strong>in</strong>g carried forth <strong>in</strong> learned journals,or, generally, by learned men; rather, the proposals atebe<strong>in</strong>g developed <strong>in</strong> the pages of the Neto York Times, and arebe<strong>in</strong>g presented by politicians, bus<strong>in</strong>essmen, and labor unionleaders. This is an <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>in</strong> which those who accept the Smithian<strong>in</strong>sights have won the <strong>in</strong>tellectual battle, but are <strong>in</strong> danger ofsee<strong>in</strong>g their arguments lose out <strong>in</strong> practice. This situation surelyrepresents a dilemma for economists. Economists generaUy disoda<strong>in</strong> polemics, but they now face a situation <strong>in</strong>_which <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>gimportant political questions depends on their ability to presenteconomic ideas <strong>in</strong> a polemical fashion. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly thoseeconomists who have chosen, for whatever reasons, 43 to allythemselves with the mislead<strong>in</strong>g arguments of the "planners"have not eschewed polemics. 44Hayek has done an admirable job of marshall<strong>in</strong>g the chiefarguments aga<strong>in</strong>st central plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> his recent arUcle. I do not<strong>in</strong>tend to repeat these arguments here. But it is worth rem<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gourselves of the central confusion of the early advocates ofcentral planníng, as ir is the central confusion of the currentadvocates. The confusion concems the very concept of"plann<strong>in</strong>g."If noth<strong>in</strong>g else developed from the earlier debates overthe question, it was the realization that a market economy ischaracterized by cor_nua/plann<strong>in</strong>g and plan-revision, albeit on adecentralized level. 4_As Hayek put it over thirty years ago, andrecenfly repeated:The dispute between the modern plan_nersand their oppon..ents,is,therefore, nota dispute on whether we ought m cl-mose<strong>in</strong>teUi_,enflybetween the various possibleorganizations ofsociety; ir is nota dispute


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 127on whether we ought to employ foresight and systematic th<strong>in</strong>ldng <strong>in</strong>plann<strong>in</strong>g our common affairs. It is a dispute about what is the best wayof sodo<strong>in</strong>g. The question is whether for this purpose it isbetter that theholder of coercive power should conf<strong>in</strong>e himseff<strong>in</strong> general to creat<strong>in</strong>gconditionsunder whichthe knowledgeand <strong>in</strong>itiativeof<strong>in</strong>dividuals aregiventhe bestscopesothattheycan planmost successfully;or whetherarationalutilizationof our resources requirescentra/direction and organizationof all our activities accord<strong>in</strong>g to some consciously constructed"bluepñnt."The socialistsof aHpartieshave appropriatedtheterm"plann<strong>in</strong>g"for plann<strong>in</strong>g of the lattertype, anditis now generallyaccepted<strong>in</strong>thissense. But though thisis meantto suggestthatthisis theonly raonal wayof handl<strong>in</strong>g our affairs, it does not, of course, provethis. It rema<strong>in</strong>s the po<strong>in</strong>t on which the plannersand the liberalsdisagree.4eThe challenge of"plann<strong>in</strong>g" confronts liberal economists withboth the necessity and the opportunity of once aga<strong>in</strong> enter<strong>in</strong>gthe popular debate over the trend of society that we will shapefor the fumre. For it must be remembered that <strong>in</strong> construct<strong>in</strong>geconomics upon the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneous order, earliereconomists were ultimately <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> the problem of socialand political organization. In part, then, I am propos<strong>in</strong>g a returnto an earlier concepUon of our task as engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> policaleconomy, though we now recognize a specifically scientific partof this field, v/z., economics. If economist_ do not conceive oftheir task thusly, it is doubtful whether there will be any practicalopportunity <strong>in</strong> the fumre for the sc/ent/fu: pursuit of the implicationsof the pr<strong>in</strong>dple of spontaneous order.In order to pursue this goal, however, <strong>Austrian</strong> economists <strong>in</strong>particular must setfle among themselves certa<strong>in</strong> theoretical andseem<strong>in</strong>gly purely scientific issues. I have argued above thatamong the neoclassical economists, the <strong>Austrian</strong>s have mostconsistently adhered to Adam Smith's conception of theeconomic problem. Ironica!!y, recent debates <strong>in</strong>dicate anyth<strong>in</strong>g.butagreement among liv<strong>in</strong>g members of this school. The positionsof some could be construed as an implicit attack on the ideathat there is a spontaneous market order <strong>in</strong> the economy. It isthus that I ana led hato a f<strong>in</strong>al section, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a discussion ofthe <strong>Austrian</strong> approach to the queson of the operation of spon-


128 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> Econoraicstaneously generated forces <strong>in</strong> a market economy.THE AUSTRI/IN SCHOOL /IND SPONTANEOUSORDERING FORCESIn a recent paper, Professor Kirzner speculates about theexact status of the proposion that profitable opportunities havea tendency to be exploited? 7He condudes that the propensity todiscover opportunities is "<strong>in</strong>separable from our <strong>in</strong>sight thathuman be<strong>in</strong>gs act purposefully. "'s In fact, he even suggests asympathetic re<strong>in</strong>terpretaon of the perfect knowledge assumptionof neodassical price theory. Though orthodox use of theassumpon is "carefree, ''49 it does reflect a ieal <strong>in</strong>sight: our"<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct" is seen as assur<strong>in</strong>g us that profitable opportunities wiUbe discovered. He then condudes that: "The perfect knowledgeassumption of neo-dassical economics carried this <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctiveassurance to altogether unjustified lengths. In reject<strong>in</strong>g thisdangerous assumption, we must take care not to expunge theentirely heahhy <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct on which it rested. "soKirzner's approach to the issue of profit exploitation <strong>in</strong> amarket economy differs markedly from Lachmann's. Nonetheless,this proposition is not easily demonstrated, for two, <strong>in</strong>terrelatedreasons. First, Lachmann to my knowledge nowhereexp//c/t/y asserts the contrary proposition, v/z., that we have nogrounds for believ<strong>in</strong>g that market participants will discover andexploit profitable oppormnifies. Second, though the figure ofProfessor Lachmann lurks <strong>in</strong> the background throughout thesecond hall of Kirzner's paper, the latter never br<strong>in</strong>gs thís figure<strong>in</strong>to the foreground.The best way of eluddat<strong>in</strong>g this issue is to turn to Lachmann'sown recent paper. Toward the end of Iris paper, Lachmannnotes that:... Skepticismaboutequilibriumneed not deter us from apprais<strong>in</strong>g therelative strengt.hand weaknem of the equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g fortes <strong>in</strong> variomsituatiom. In fach it mug encourage us todo m. To makeconfident me


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 129of the notion of equilibrium means to imply that the equilibrat<strong>in</strong>gforces willalwaysbe ofsufficient strength to triumph over all obstacles.A skepticmight readily admit that such situations may exist, but he wiUprobably doubt whether they occur with sufficient frequency to warrantor treat<strong>in</strong>g them as the norm. The more skepficalwe are aboutgeneral equilibrium as the central notion of economic analysis, themore <strong>in</strong>cumbent on us ir becomes to exam<strong>in</strong>e each situation <strong>in</strong>dividuallywith respect to the balance of strength of equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g and disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>gforces? 1Ir must be noted here that Kirzner's position is not that weshould admire neoclassácal price theory for its treatment ofgeneral equilibrium as "the central notion of economic analysis"of as"the norm." Rather, he suggests that we accept the propositionthat equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g tendencies are strong. Ifthe propensity todiscover opportunities is "<strong>in</strong>separable from our <strong>in</strong>sight thathuman be<strong>in</strong>gs act purposefully," then we must likewise acknowledgea tendency toward equilibrium <strong>in</strong> all markets.Afort/o_, thereexist strong tendencies toward ah overall or general equilibriumat each moment. Individuals are, then, constantly revis<strong>in</strong>g theirplans <strong>in</strong> a way that br<strong>in</strong>gs them <strong>in</strong>to greater uniformity. This"latter proposion, when thus phrased <strong>in</strong> dynamic terms, doesembody the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of an undesigned order. It rema<strong>in</strong>s questionable,however, whether Lachmann wishes to embrace thispr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Thus he argues that:Experience shows that <strong>in</strong> the real world of disequilibriumdifferentpersonswilltypically hold different expectaons about the same futureevent. Ir so, at best one person's expectanon can be confirmed and aHotherexpectations willbe disappo_ted. Hence the "assumpon that allother expectations are confirmed cannot possiblyhold. Nobody cantake hisequilibriumbear<strong>in</strong>gsir he does not l_aowhow others willact. Insuda a simation, which we llave every reason to regard as normal, hisequilibrium, as Hayek admits, cannot serve asa source of a "feedbackmechanism."TAe&ac.ont)_ had beendesignedto keepentrepreneurs from_,_ be_ d;.,,n.s--_rm makes much of "the autonomyof the humanm<strong>in</strong>d" (as must all <strong>Austrian</strong>s):


130 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>This source of... new knowledge may wellbe past experience, but thelatter requires <strong>in</strong>terpretation by a discern<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>d, and optimists wiU<strong>in</strong>terpret it differently from pessimists. The human m<strong>in</strong>d is a filter ofexperience, but each <strong>in</strong>dividuars filter is different from every otherfflter. Divergent expectations are thus as "natural," a feature of theso,:i_!landscape as are divergent tastes. Changes <strong>in</strong> the consteUationofknowledge are an <strong>in</strong>evitable concomitant of the pass<strong>in</strong>g of time, andchanges <strong>in</strong> the constellation of expectations are bound to followthem.s8There is no deny<strong>in</strong>g the autonomy of the human m<strong>in</strong>d, butone is reluctant to follow Lachmann <strong>in</strong> his apparent conclusionthat we can say noth<strong>in</strong>g about the likelihood that <strong>in</strong>dividuals willmake consistent and coord<strong>in</strong>ated decisions <strong>in</strong> the face of newknowledge. Ir anyth<strong>in</strong>g, he seems to be say<strong>in</strong>g that they wiUnotcoord<strong>in</strong>ate plans. Yet, one always supposed it was an Hayekian<strong>in</strong>sight that prices facilitate the diffusion of<strong>in</strong>formation and thecoord<strong>in</strong>ation of plans, s_We are faced here with an important question: Do differentand disparate Lndividuals have a common reacfion to sharedexperience? We certa<strong>in</strong>ly would not want to say they always do,or there would be little sense <strong>in</strong> referr<strong>in</strong>g to "<strong>in</strong>dividuals." Yet,there are obvious cases <strong>in</strong> which people do react to sharedexpeñences <strong>in</strong> the same or similar ways: the perception of a tire<strong>in</strong> an endosed room w<strong>in</strong> lead to virtually everyone's mak<strong>in</strong>g foran exit. Each person could forma reasonable expectaon aboutwhat the others wiU do.Moreover, many events are implidt demonstraUons of thedegree to which expectaons do co<strong>in</strong>dde. Changes <strong>in</strong> cloth<strong>in</strong>gfashion might be cited as an example. The "agreement" amongseparate manufacturers of apparel can be amaz<strong>in</strong>g, thoughdearly retail customers do not register their preferences for newfashion <strong>in</strong> a doth<strong>in</strong>g futures market. Apparenfly <strong>in</strong>dividual entrepreneurs,experienc<strong>in</strong>g the same signah and trends, willoften form similar expectations.Norte of these considerations is decisive, of course, but theyare suggeuive. Lachmann has dearly done a great service <strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out forcefuUy the absurdity of an appmach <strong>in</strong> which


SpontaneousOrderand theCoord<strong>in</strong>ationof EconomicActivities 131expectations alwaysprove consistent. Ir is an essential feature ofmarkets that not everyone reacts equally quickly to the cont<strong>in</strong>ualchanges <strong>in</strong> the data? s But it is true of at least some changes thatthey occur only because actors share a unanimous op<strong>in</strong>ion aboutthe future course of events.Hav<strong>in</strong>g eschewed the approach of assum<strong>in</strong>g consistencyamong expectations at all Umes, one is not j ustified, withoutfurther argument, <strong>in</strong> argu<strong>in</strong>g that economists can make no assumptionsabout a tendency toward suelauniformity, where thistendency is based on a universally recognized "propensity todiscover opportunities." To do so would <strong>in</strong>volve a non sequitur.Aga<strong>in</strong>, to assume that all opportunities are at any moment fullyexploited (and thus do not really existas opportunities) wouldbe, to paraphrase Kirzner, a "carefree" use of concepts. But wemust surely accept the existence of the propensity, or forsake thepr<strong>in</strong>cipleof spontaneous order. This po<strong>in</strong>t can be elaborated byrecount<strong>in</strong>g an event that happened at a December, 1975, conferenceon <strong>Austrian</strong> economics.ProfessorLerner argued that without the concept of generalequilibrium,defenders of the marketsystemllave no basisfromwhichto carryon their defense. His criticismwas <strong>in</strong> responsemLachmann'sapproach to the queson of general equilibñum. Iconfess that I rose to the latter's defense at_e time, bypo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gout that we need only assume that there is market-day equilibrium.If pricesclear exist<strong>in</strong>g supplies, then markets can operatesuccessfully.'q'hat is all we need." I ananow not sure that i didnot err. Lerner may have been rais<strong>in</strong>g ah important issue forAustñans.We must dist<strong>in</strong>guish two functions of markets.The firstconsistssimply <strong>in</strong> a method of allocat<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g su.ppliespeacefully.Wkhoutpricesand free markets, societyreqmresgunsanddictatorship. Examples of the latter type of socialaUocationofresour¢esase numerous. But Iam not sure that defenders of themarket system can be satisfied with demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g that freeUade is ma aiterna_ve to the "warof all aga<strong>in</strong>st all," howeverimportant this imight may be. For ir supplies, of goods areautonomous, if not gramitous, it is dubious <strong>in</strong> w at sense_tcan


132 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>be said that prices coord<strong>in</strong>ate activity. Indeed, I suspect thatthere is no coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> the conventional sense <strong>in</strong> Lachmann'ssystem. For hito apparently, ex ante plans bear no relation to expost reality. There is not even reason to believe that actors willmore <strong>in</strong> the right direction <strong>in</strong> correct<strong>in</strong>g past errors.Lachmann does feel that the market "cannot make bulls andbears change their expectations, but it neverthele_ can coord<strong>in</strong>atethese." He cont<strong>in</strong>ues:To coord<strong>in</strong>ate bullish and bearish expectations is, as Keynes _owed,the economic function of the Stock Exchange and of asset markets <strong>in</strong>general. This is achieved because <strong>in</strong> such markets the price will moreuntil the wholemarket isdivided <strong>in</strong>toequal halvesof bulBand bears. Inthis way dívergent expectations are cast hato a coherent pattern andameasure of coord<strong>in</strong>ation is accomplished,se"Coord<strong>in</strong>ation" is be<strong>in</strong>g used here <strong>in</strong> a híghly ambiguoussense. As Lachmann notes subsequently, he is talk<strong>in</strong>g not about_x ante consistency, but about a Marsh_lian ex post, market-dayequilibrium, s_This usage ofcoord<strong>in</strong>ation is <strong>in</strong> sharp contrast tothe more conventional one, and the usage that <strong>Austrian</strong>s havetraditionaUy employed, ss "Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of plans" <strong>in</strong> traditionalusage means there is ex ante consistency among transactors'plans. It is certa<strong>in</strong>ly scant comfort for one <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> thisproblem to be <strong>in</strong>formed that there w:dlbe "coord<strong>in</strong>aUon" expoa.Though related, ex ante and expost "coord<strong>in</strong>ation" are conceptuallydist<strong>in</strong>ct issues. To conflate the two issues is scarcely to contributeto the solution of either problem, ssIt is certa<strong>in</strong>ly not the case that <strong>Austrian</strong> economista ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>that there ever exista ex ante consistency among all tro_nmctors'plans. But they have traditionally ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed, as Lachmannhimself notes, that there is a strong tendency toward dLffusion ofknowledge and <strong>in</strong>creased consistency of plans. In other words,<strong>Austrian</strong> economists have always víewed the problem ofeconomic coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> dynamic terms. Do plana becomemore consistent over time? Lachmarm apparently sloughs overthe dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween two verydifferentpropositions:1. Economicaaivities ale coord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> the sense that all


SpontaneousOrderand theCoord<strong>in</strong>ationof EconomicActivities 133plato are successfully executed ("general equilibrium").2. Economic activities are coord<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> the sense that amechanism exists (i.e., the price system) that facilitatesrational plan revision and leads to greater consistency ofplato over time.Lachmann switches back and forth between discussions of"the relative strength and weakness of the equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g forces,"and "general equilibrium as the central notion of economicanalysis" asthough he were talldng about the same problem (seep. 129). Surely, the statement that "the market produces strongequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g forces" is fundamentally different than the assertionthat "the market is always <strong>in</strong> (general) equilibrium." DoesProfessor Lachmann acknowledge the difference? Ir is certa<strong>in</strong>lynot clear that bis arguments agaimt the first class of statementsaretell<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st the second. It istrue that elsewhere Lachmannapparenfly acknowledges the existente of a tendency towardequilibrium <strong>in</strong> some arcas: "A tendency toward the <strong>in</strong>tegrationof the [capital] structure does exist.''e°But even there, he seem<strong>in</strong>glytakes back what he has just granted.6_ I ana afraid hisoccasional concessions to the existence of a tendency to greaterconsistency of plans <strong>in</strong> markets only confuses matters.What I fmd most disturb<strong>in</strong>g about Lachmann's position is thathe criticizes a stat/c general eq-ilibñum model, but concludesthat the modern <strong>Austrian</strong> approach to coord<strong>in</strong>aUon,<strong>in</strong> a dynara/csense,is thereby called <strong>in</strong>to question. I aro not at aUalearwhat heth<strong>in</strong>ks "the general equilibrium perspective" is. The reader istold that Hayek's"early work was dearly under the <strong>in</strong>fluence ofthe general equilibrium model."s2 Elsewhere the reader is rem<strong>in</strong>dedthat as early as 1933 (<strong>in</strong> "Price Expectations, MonetaryDismrbances and Mal<strong>in</strong>vestments") Hayek dealt with expectations.It was <strong>in</strong> 1936 ("<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge") that Hayeklaunched his attack on the static, general equilibrium models ofmathematical economics. From this, one must condude thatLachmann is critical even of theories espous<strong>in</strong>g a tendency towardoveraUequilibrium (i.e., he denies the pñnciple of spontaneousorder). I can draw no other condusion.It alto _,ems that what Kirzner treats as the "equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g


134 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economics</strong>market process," Lachmann treats asa "disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g" process.At first, I thought there was a mere semantic confusion. Inow believe the apparent semantic confusion ís mask<strong>in</strong>g realconceptual differences. Kirznerseesany disturbance as develop<strong>in</strong>gequilibraung market forces. Lachmann sees change as disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g,e3 The only reason that I can adduce is thatLachmann does not see market forces as be<strong>in</strong>g equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nature. If this is his position for markets asa whole, then he isgeneraliz<strong>in</strong>g the position taken by Keynesabout securities marketsto markets asa whole, v/z., that we cannot relyon spontaneousmarket forces to br<strong>in</strong>g us to an equilibrium position after adisturbance. And ir this be the case, then Lachmann's viewsrepresenta radicalchaHengenot only to his fellow<strong>Austrian</strong>s, butto all those who accept the existence of an undesígned marketorder. Forít certa<strong>in</strong>ly seems that the only effective answer to thechallenges with which I have been concerned lies <strong>in</strong> Kirzner'scharacterization of the entrepreneurial role.Asa f<strong>in</strong>al note, ifI have misreadLachmann, I hope this sectionwillat least serveto dañfy issues and develop implications of thepr<strong>in</strong>ciple ofspontaneous order. Ir the paper succeeded <strong>in</strong> noth<strong>in</strong>gelse, it would have served its purpose.CONCLUSIONSI would like to rem<strong>in</strong>d the reader that my orig<strong>in</strong>al task was todemonstrate that seem<strong>in</strong>gly diverse and particular problems arereally<strong>in</strong>stances of a more general theoretical disagreement. Forit is only by directly address<strong>in</strong>g this general theoreticaldisagreement--disagreement that I have identified as devolv<strong>in</strong>garound the existence of an undesigned market order--that afruitful search toward solutions of these <strong>in</strong>dividual problems canbe begun. It is <strong>in</strong> the nature of ah endeavor to demonstrate the<strong>in</strong>terconnecfions between such seem<strong>in</strong>gly disparate (but reallyconnected) issues that no one of them is ad_uately treated. Irthe reader feels that each section calls for a separate paper on itstopic, the author can only agree and express the hope that more


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of Economic Activities 135papers on these subjects will be forthcom<strong>in</strong>g, albeit papers <strong>in</strong>formedby the realization of the overall problem be<strong>in</strong>g studied.NOTES1. Adam Smith, The Wealth ofNations, ed. by Edw<strong>in</strong> Cannan (<strong>New</strong>York: The Modern Library, 1937), p. 651.It is frequenfly forgotten that Smith's defense of a relatively unhamperedmarket is partly based on considerations ofjustice. See Smith,.pp. 141,308 and 497. The ethical basis of Smith's system is emphasizedm a paper byJoseph Cropsey,"The Invisible Hand: Moral and PoliticalConsideration," delivered as part of the Harry Girvetz Memorial LectureSeries at the University of Califomia, Santa Barbara. Also seeJames M. Buchanan, "The Jusrice of Natural Liberty," TheJournal ofLegal Studies, V (January, 1976): 1-16.2. My colleague, Roy Adams, first suggested this very apt analogyto me. Also: "... You can f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> Keynes, as <strong>in</strong> Marx, almost an'yth<strong>in</strong>g..." F. A. Hayek, "No Escape: Unemployment Must Follow Inflation,"<strong>in</strong>FullEmpltryment atAnyPrice? (London: Institute of Economic Affairs,1975), p. 43.3. <strong>New</strong> York: Oxford University Press, 1968; hereafter, Keynes/anEcorunnics. Leijonhufvud's "Keynes and the Classics" (London: Instituteof Economic Affairs, 1969) is also of importance here.4. Leijonhufvud has argued that, contrary to contemporary pracrice,Keynes aggregated assets accord<strong>in</strong>g to their term to maturity, andnot accord<strong>in</strong>g to whether they are real or f<strong>in</strong>ancial. Cf. Leijonhufvud,Keynesian <strong>Economics</strong>, pp. 130-57.5. SirJohn Hicks has demonstrated the remarkable stability of theretum on British consols <strong>in</strong> the n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century. If the yield ofconsols can be taken as proxy for the long-rate, then his f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs giresome empirical basis to Keynes's hypothesis. See John R. Hicks, "TheYield on Consols," <strong>in</strong> Critical Essays on Monetary Theory (Oxford: TheClarendon Press, 1967), pp. 83-102.6. It would be well to recall why speculators seek liquidity <strong>in</strong> thishypothetical situaUon; or, more precisely, why they attempt to shifttheir hold<strong>in</strong>gs from lonlz-lived to short-lived assets. If long-rates arefall<strong>in</strong>g, but are expected'_o rise once aga<strong>in</strong>, then wealth-holders have adouble <strong>in</strong>centive to sell long assets and purchase short assets. By sell<strong>in</strong>gat the long end of the yield spectrum, the), can capture capital ga<strong>in</strong>s. By"go<strong>in</strong>g short" <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terim, they can purchase these assets ba_ atlower prices and higher yields, once <strong>in</strong>terest rates have risen agam.


136 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>All this assumes, of course, that <strong>in</strong> the aggregate, transactors seek toavoid capital uncertaínty. On this po<strong>in</strong>t, cf. Leijonhufvud, Keynesian<strong>Economics</strong>, pp. 45-46; 282-314.7. Cf. ibid., pp. 49-109.8. See F. A. ron Hayek, "Reflections on the Pure Theory of Moneyof Mr. J. M. Keynes, Part I," Economica, XI (August,9. Ibid.1931): 279.10. J. M. Keynes, "The Pure Theory of Money. A Reply to Dr.Hayek," Economica, XI (November, 1931): 394-95. Of course, thequestion of whether the issues with which Keynes dealt could be treatedwithout reference to capital theory was one of the chief po<strong>in</strong>ts ofdispute.11. Joan Rob<strong>in</strong>son, "What has become of the Keynesian Revolu-Uon?" <strong>in</strong> Milo Keynes (ed.),Essays onJohn Maynard Keynes (Cambñdge:Cambñdge University Press, 1975), p. 125; quoted <strong>in</strong> F. A. Hayek, "NoEscape: Unemployment Must Follow Inflation," p. 43.12. Leijonhufvud, Keynesian Econom/cs, p. 43.13. Cf. "Hayek and Keynes: A RetrospecUve Assessment," IowaState University DepartmentIowa: Photocopy, 1975).of <strong>Economics</strong> Staff Paper No. 20 (Ames,14. See Leland Yeager, "The Keynesian Diversion," WesternEconomicJournal, XI (June, 1973): 150-63.It should be noted that what Clower and Leijonhufvud have done isto present an <strong>in</strong>terpretation of Keynes that rationalizes his doubtsconcern<strong>in</strong>g the strength of the spontaneous forces operat<strong>in</strong>g to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>or restore full employment. This <strong>in</strong> no way <strong>in</strong>dicates that these twoauthors share these doubts. Nonetheless, it is frequenfly assumed,without any tima basis, that because Leijonhufvud and Clower haveattempted to explicate Keynes's views, they agree with them <strong>in</strong> theirentiretyl15. Axel Leijonhufvud, "Effective Demand Failures," SwedishJournalof<strong>Economics</strong>, 75 (1973): 28. Leijonhufvud cont<strong>in</strong>ues, not<strong>in</strong>g that thisissue"lies at the heart of two of the most prom<strong>in</strong>ent controversies <strong>in</strong> thefield over the last decade: the Fiscalist vs. Monetarist controversy...and the controversy over the long-run stability of the Phlips-curve.The volume of writ<strong>in</strong>gs on each of these cont<strong>in</strong>ues to mount steadilywith no dear-cut resolution <strong>in</strong> sight--ín large measure becaqse thiscentral issue is not be<strong>in</strong>g effecávely addressed."16. Discussions about the energy problem area prime example ofthis. They almost never even consider what spontaneous market forcesht exist tb_t would lead to the discovery of a new, coord<strong>in</strong>ateduon to the aUocation of energy resources. One very probablesolution--perhaps the most probable if market forces were permitted


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>atior_ of Economic Activities 137to operate unfettered--would <strong>in</strong>volve the destruction of the <strong>in</strong>ternationaloil cartel, whose existence makes a reallocation of energy resourcesappear necessary. And it is not merely noneconomists who areguilty of ignor<strong>in</strong>g these market forces.On a more sophisticated level, modern welfare economics is virtuallypredicated on the absence of a spontaneous order <strong>in</strong> society, thoughpart of the problem here is the static quality of welfare analysis.On the general, 20th century reaction aga<strong>in</strong>st the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneousorder, cf. Leijonhufvud, "Effective Demand Failures," 31-82.Though the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of spontaneous order cont<strong>in</strong>ues asa cornerstoneof economics---particularly of microeconomics--this only shows the<strong>in</strong>consistency of current micro and macro economics---a po<strong>in</strong>tLeijonhufvud develops at length. Ibid., 28-33.17. The reader is referred to footnote 15 and the relevant portion ofthe text footnoted there<strong>in</strong>.18. As but one example, see F. A. Hayek, The Counter-Revolution of$dence (<strong>New</strong> York: The Free Press of Glencoe, 1955), pp. 25-35.19. I adopt here James Buchanan's term<strong>in</strong>ology to describe theChicago SchooL Professor Lachmann has proposed the terna "Neo-Ricardian" to refer to the dist<strong>in</strong>ct foibles of yet another school oftheorists, the Cambfidge (U.K.) School.20. As one example of this Ricardian tendency, see the discussion ofthe general glut controversy <strong>in</strong> Thomas Sowell, Classical <strong>Economics</strong>Reconsid_ed (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press, 1974), pp. 46ff.21. See Smith, pp. 35-36.22. On this po<strong>in</strong>t, cf. James M. Buchanan, "Public Goods andNatural Liberty" (Blacksburg, Virg<strong>in</strong>ia: Photocopy, 1976), especially3--I0.23. Thus, theorists disagree over whether Smith held a labor costtheory of value, an entrepreneurial cost theory, or merely a labormeasure theory. Smith may also have been unwitt<strong>in</strong>gly articulat<strong>in</strong>g afactor-exhaustion theorem for the long run. Nor could he seem<strong>in</strong>glydist<strong>in</strong>guish between quasi-historical observations about the role oflabor <strong>in</strong> production and theoretical statements of labor's contribution.This latter difficulty reflects Smith's "speculative" or "theoreticar' approachto history. On this, cf. A. Sk<strong>in</strong>ner, "<strong>Economics</strong> and History--The Scottish Enlightenment," $cottishJournal ofPolitical E¢onomy(February,1965): 1-22.24. Ah example of Ricardo s approach is his tr_atment of the effectsof ah <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the money supply. On this, see Gerald P. O'Driscoll,Jr., <strong>Economics</strong> as a Coord<strong>in</strong>ation Problem: The Contributions of Friedrich A.Hayek (Kansas City: Sheed Andrews and McMeel, Inc., 1977), pp.37--43.


138 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Ricardo is also famous for bis so-called "Equivalence Theorem" fortaxation and public debt. But though this ma), be the most famous caseof the Ricardian vice, it is the one case where Ricardo was not a Ricardian!See The Works and Correspondenceof David Ricardo, Vol. I: On thePr<strong>in</strong>ciples of Political Economy and Taxation, ed. by Piero Sraffa (Cambñdge:Carnbridge University Press, 1951), pp. 247-48; Ibid., Vol. VI:Pamphlet_ and Papers, 1815-1823, pp. 185--87; Sowell, pp. 67-68; andGerald P. O'Driscoll, Jr., The Ricardian Nonequivalence Theorem,JournalofPolitical Economy, 85 (February, 1977): 207-10.25. Ludwig M. Lachmann, "From Mises to Shaclde: An Essay on<strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong> and the Kaleidic Society," Journal of EconomicLiterature, XIV (March, 1976): 55. Cf. Hayek, The Counter-Revolution ofScience, pp. 29-30.26. Cf. Hayek, "The Mean<strong>in</strong>g ofCompetition," <strong>in</strong>lnd/v/dua//sm andEconomic Order (Chicago:97-98.University of Chicago Press, 1948), pp.27. Ah example of this dilemma is the role of money <strong>in</strong> a generalequilibrium model. On this, see Hayek, The Pure Theory of Capital(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1941), p. 31. Also see Ludwigron Mises, Human Action, 3rd ed. (Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1966),pp. 416-19.28. Cf. Sowell, pp. 58-59.29. Cf. Israel M. Kirzner, Competition andEntrepreneurship (Chicago:University of Chicago Press, 1973), pp. 32-37.30. Ignor<strong>in</strong>g the factors that govern the emergence of a spontaneousorder is <strong>in</strong> some sense more objectionable (from the viewpo<strong>in</strong>t ofone who accepts the pr<strong>in</strong>dple) than deny<strong>in</strong>g its relevante. Fallure to discussthe conditions under which a spontaneous order would emerge <strong>in</strong>an economic system prejudices the case aga<strong>in</strong>st unhampered, decentralizeddecision-maldng. Thus, when obvious misallocations and"marketdirectedfailures" develop <strong>in</strong> ah. economy, su..g_íesti°r_ that. polio/betowardfreer markets will be met wlth mcreduhty.In a letter to me (dated February 2, 1977), Professor RichardWagner argued permasively that <strong>in</strong> the Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples Marshall was moreaware of these problems than those daim<strong>in</strong>g to be <strong>in</strong>fluenced by him,espeáally ir we look to the Marshall of the text rather than of thefootnotes. I _ <strong>in</strong>clíned to agree with Professor Wagner.On Walras s assumpfion that markets will clear so as to produce anoverall order, cf. O'Driscoll, £conomics _ a C_ Prob/na, pp.18--19 and Note 16 on pp. 30-31.31. The hostility of the Chicago School to the approach of the<strong>Austrian</strong> Sc.hool is a fact. What _!!s for explanation is the reason, which<strong>in</strong>volves lar more than a "family" squabble. The divisions between thetwo schools antedate each <strong>in</strong> the history of economic thought.


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ation af Economic Activities 139For a recent example of the Chicago attitude toward the <strong>Austrian</strong>conception ofeconomics, see the Rev/ew ofCompeñtion andEntrepreneurshipby Benjam<strong>in</strong> Kle<strong>in</strong>, Journal of Political Economy, 83 (December,1975): 1305-09. For an earlier example of similar treatment, see theReview of Capital and lts Structure by Mart<strong>in</strong>J. Bailey,Journal ofPoliticalEconomy, LXV (]une, 1957): 265--66.32. For <strong>in</strong>stance, see the discussion <strong>in</strong> Hayek,Monetary Theoryand theTrade Cycle, translated by N. Kaldor and H. M. Croome (<strong>New</strong> York:Augustus M. Kelley, 1966), pp. 45--45.In what follows, I will draw on my paper, "Friedrich Hayek and theSdence of Choice," Iowa State University Staff Paper <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economics</strong> No.24 (Ames, Iowa: Photocopy, 1975).33. Cf. Friedrich A. Hayek, The Pure Theory of Capital, pp. 33-34.34. "Ofcourse, it is one th<strong>in</strong>g to assert that monetary changes are thekey to major movements <strong>in</strong> money <strong>in</strong>come; iris quite a different th<strong>in</strong>gto know <strong>in</strong> any detail what is the mechanism that l<strong>in</strong>ks monetary changeto economic change; how the <strong>in</strong>fluence of the one is transmitted to theother; what sectors of the economy will be affected first; what the timePthatternof the impacts will be, and so on. We have great confidence <strong>in</strong>e first assertion. We have little confidence <strong>in</strong> our knowledge of thetransmission mechanism, except <strong>in</strong> such broad and vague terms as toconstitute litfle more than an impressionistic representaUon ratherthan an eng<strong>in</strong>eeñng bluepñnt." Milton Friedman and Anna J.Schwartz, "Money and Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cydes,"<strong>in</strong>Friedman, The O_t/mumQuant/ty ofMoney (Chicago: Ald<strong>in</strong>e Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1969), p. 222.CommenÜng on Ricardo's <strong>in</strong>attention to transitional periods,Schumpeter has remarked: %.. In matters of monetary as of generaltheory, Ricardian teach<strong>in</strong>g is a detour and.., it slowed up the advanceof analysis, which would have been much quicker and smoother had[Henry] Thornton's lead been followed---had Ricardo's force not prevailedover Thornton's <strong>in</strong>sight." Joseph A.'Schumpeter, H./st0_ ofEconomicAnalyais (<strong>New</strong> York: Oxford University Press, 1954), p. 704n.35. Cf. Gerald P. O'Driscoll, Jr. and Sudha R. Shenoy, "Inflation,Recession and Stagflaon," <strong>in</strong> Edw<strong>in</strong> G. Dolan, ed., The Founda6ons ofM0dern Austr/an Econom/¢s (Kansas City: Sheed & Ward, 1976), pp.190-93.For recent statements of Friedman's position, see "A TheoreticalFramework for Monetary Analysis," Journal of Poli_al Economy, 78M.a__ April, 1970): 193--238; and _A Monetary Theory of Nationalncome, JoumalofPolilf_E ,79 (March/April, 1971)"323-37. *. •$6. I ana referr<strong>in</strong>g here to the problem of distrtbuuonal, orCa__tillon-effects, which have been so long ignored <strong>in</strong> monetary theory."Pah gap <strong>in</strong> monetary theory is not accidental, for most theories ofmoney <strong>in</strong>corporate neutrality assumpons. If money is neutral, then


140 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong>deed there are no distribuon effects. Itis not remarkable, then, thatnaonetary economists generally ignore the problem of distributioneffects. What is remarkable is that the almost fantasc assumpon ofneutrality of naoney generally does not gire economists pause. While itwould be beyond the scope of this paper to denaonstrate this proposition,it does seem that an economy <strong>in</strong> which naoney could be neutral isone <strong>in</strong> which there would be no demand for money. For, where eLsebut<strong>in</strong> a world of correct expectations and perfect coord<strong>in</strong>aon wouldchanges <strong>in</strong> the supply-demand relaon of money be neutral <strong>in</strong> theireffects?The issue of the neutrality of naoney and distribution effects isconsidered <strong>in</strong> Friedrich A. Lutz, "On Neutral Money," <strong>in</strong> Erich Streissler,Gottfried Haberler, Friedrich A. Lutz and Fritz Machlup, Roads toFreedom (<strong>New</strong> York: Augustus M. Kelley, 1969), pp. 105-16.37. Cf. O'Driscoll, <strong>Economics</strong> asa Coord<strong>in</strong>atm Problem, pp. 106-08.38. I ana quite aware that to some extent Friedman has deah with thegeneral <strong>in</strong>stitutional framework necessary for economic stability. And,<strong>in</strong>deed, I f<strong>in</strong>d his earlier work of maore<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> this regard. I wouldpo<strong>in</strong>t out that even <strong>in</strong> that he focused on price/e_e/s, and did notdevelop the problem of coord/natm at length. Cf. Milton Friedman, dProgramfor Monetary Stabili_ (<strong>New</strong> York: Fordham University Press,1960).39. From the editorial <strong>in</strong>troduction by Sudha R. Shenoy, ed.,d Tig¿,r/'3 the Tai/(London: Instimte of Economic Affairs, 1972), p. 8.40. The argument appear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of this section wasstrongly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by a talk, "Adam Smith <strong>in</strong> Theory and Pracce,"delivered by Thomas Sowell <strong>in</strong> the Harry Girvetz Memorial LecmreSeries at the University of California,Santa Barbara.41. Adam Smith, Theorj of Mora/Snaba¢nts (London: Henry G.Bohn, 1853), pp. 342--43.42. Hayek, The Morgan C,uaranty Suroey (January, 1976): 4.43. For one re&son that might attract economists to this movement,see Hayek, The Morgan Guaranty Survey: 11.44. See Wassily- Leontief, "For a NaÜonal Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>gBoard," The N¿,w York Tim_ (March 14, 1974): 37.45. "The modern <strong>Austrian</strong>s have specifically emphasized this po<strong>in</strong>t.The work of Mises, Hayek, Lachmann and Kirzner are notable na thisrespect. For a recent example of a work wñtten <strong>in</strong> the Aus.trian traditionthat empb.___Testhe role of decentralized plann<strong>in</strong>g na a marketeconomy, see Kirzner's C_ and Ent_r¿,pr¿__urs/I/p.46. This quotaUon appears <strong>in</strong> Chapter III of Hayek, The R.mít mSerfdom (Chicago: Universirt of Chícago Press, 1944), pp. 35--36, it iscited <strong>in</strong> Hayek, The Morgan Guarant3 Surv_ (January,1976): 5-6.


Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>atiow of Economic Activities 141The word "liberar' refers here, of course, to classical Englishliberalism, and not to twentieth century American liberalism.47. Israel M. Kirzner, "Hayek, Knowledge and Market Processes,"Paper Delivered at the Allied Social Science Association MeeUngs <strong>in</strong>Dallas, Texas (<strong>New</strong> York: Photocopy, 1975); especially 28-29.48. KitTmer, "Hayek, Knowledge and Market Processes," p. 29.49. Kirzner, "Hayek, Knowledge and Market Processes," p. 32.50. Kirzner, "Hayek, Knowledge and Market Processes," p. 33.51. L. M. Lachmann, "Reflections on Hayekian Capital Theory,"Paper Delivered at the Allied Social Science Associaon Meet<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>Dallas, Texas (<strong>New</strong> York: Photocopy, 1975): 13.52. Lachmann, "Reflections .... " 8-9. Emphasis added. Also, cf.Lachmann, "From Mises to Shaclde," 59-61.53. Lachmann, "Reflections... ," 9. "The Future is unknowable,though not unimag<strong>in</strong>able. Future knowledge cannot be had now, but itcan cast its shadow ahead. In each m<strong>in</strong>d, however, the shadow assumesa different shape, hence the divergence of expectations. The formationof expectations is an act of our m<strong>in</strong>ds by meam of which we try tocatch a glimpse of the unknown. Each one of us catches a differentglimpse." Lachmann, "From Mises to Shackle .... " 59.54. In his most recent work, Lachmann notes that Mises, Hayek andKirzner have emphasized the diffusion of knowledge <strong>in</strong> the marketprocess. But he denies that the market can diffuse expectations <strong>in</strong> thesame way. Cf. Lachmann, "From Mises to Shackle," 59. I believe thedisf<strong>in</strong>ction between knowledge and expectations is a spurious one.55. Cf. Kirzner, 'Hayek, Knowledge and Market Processes," 30-31.56. Lachmann, "From Mises to Shackle," 59.57. Ibid., p. 61.58. Cf. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," <strong>in</strong> lnd/v/dua//sm andEconomic Order, pp. 39-45.59. It is true that one can f<strong>in</strong>d recent <strong>in</strong>stánces <strong>in</strong> which prom<strong>in</strong>enteconomists imply "coord<strong>in</strong>aÜon" <strong>in</strong> the ex post sense. For <strong>in</strong>stance, cf.Leijonhufvud, "Effective Demand Failures," 29. But there Leijonhufvudis deal<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>ter a//a, with the quesdon of whether markets alear atall. But the general issue with which Lachmann is deal<strong>in</strong>g is surely theproblem of exan_ coord<strong>in</strong>aÜon. If not, one must ask "why all the fuss?'Generally it is not denied by non-Marxista that at least output marketsclear.60. Ludwig M. Lachmann, "On <strong>Austrian</strong> Capital Theory," <strong>in</strong> Dolan,ed., The Foundations of Modern <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>, p. 149.61. "... Expectations of early change <strong>in</strong> the present situafion mayimpede the process of adjustment, and even when this does not happen,the forces of adjustment themselves may be overtaken by other


142 <strong>New</strong> Directms <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> Econom_forces." Lachmann, "On <strong>Austrian</strong> Capital Theory," pp. 149--50.62. Lachmann, "From Mises to Shackle," 60; also see 58n of thatarticle.63. In any event, this is what I make of his public statements on theissue, made at various times. Also, note the last sentence of the firstquotation appear<strong>in</strong>g on p. 20. Lachmann juxtaposes "the forces ofequilibrium" and "the forces of change." Lachmann, "From Mises toShackle," 61.


Austñan Def<strong>in</strong>iUons of theSupply of MoneyMurray N. RothbardPolytechnic Institute of <strong>New</strong> YorkL THE DEFINITIONOF THE SUPPLY OF MONEYThe concept of the supply of money plays a vitally importantrole, <strong>in</strong> differ<strong>in</strong>g ways, <strong>in</strong> both the <strong>Austrian</strong> and the Chicagoschools of economics. Yet, neither school has def<strong>in</strong>ed the concept<strong>in</strong> a fuU or satisfactory manner; asa result, we are never sureto which of the numerous alternative def<strong>in</strong>itions of the moneysupply either school is referr<strong>in</strong>g.The Chicago School def<strong>in</strong>ition is hopeless from the start. For,<strong>in</strong> a question-begg<strong>in</strong>g attempt to reacia the condusion that themoney supply is the major determ<strong>in</strong>ant of national <strong>in</strong>come, andto reach it by statistical rather than theoretical means, theChicago School def<strong>in</strong>es the money supply as that entity whichcorrelates most closely with national <strong>in</strong>come. This is one of themost flagrant examples of the Chicagoite desire to avoid essentialistconcepts, and to"test" theory by statistical correlaUon; withthe result that the supply of money is not really def<strong>in</strong>ed at all.Furthermore, the approach overlooks the fact that stafisticalcorrelation cannot establish causal connections; this can only bedone by a genu<strong>in</strong>e theory that works with def<strong>in</strong>able and def<strong>in</strong>edconcepts. 1In<strong>Austrian</strong>economics,Ludwig von Mise setforththecssentíalsoftheconceptofthemoney supply<strong>in</strong>hisT/_oryofMoneyand143


144 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>CredO, but no <strong>Austrian</strong> has developed the concept s<strong>in</strong>ce then,and unsettled quesUons rema<strong>in</strong> (e.g., ate sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposita properlyto be <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong> the money supply?). 2 And s<strong>in</strong>ce the conceptof the supply of money is vital both for the theory and forapplied historical analysis of sucia consequences as <strong>in</strong>flaUon andbus<strong>in</strong>ess cycles, it becomes vitally important to try to settle thesequesdons, and to demarcate the supply of money <strong>in</strong> the modernworld. In The Theory of Money and Credit, Mises set down thecorrect guidel<strong>in</strong>es: money is the general medium of exchange,the th<strong>in</strong>g that aU other goods and services are traded for, the• f<strong>in</strong>al Payment for such goods on the market.In contemporary economics, def<strong>in</strong>iUons of the money supplyrange widely from cash + demand deposita (Mt) up to the<strong>in</strong>clusion of virtually aUliquid assets (a stratospheñcally high M).No contemporary economist exdudes demand deposita from bisdef<strong>in</strong>ition of money. But it is useful to consider e_acfly why thisshould be so. When Mises wrote The Theory ofMoney and Credit <strong>in</strong>1912, the <strong>in</strong>clusion of demand deposita <strong>in</strong> the money supply wasnot yet a settled quesUon <strong>in</strong> economic thought. Indeed, a controversyover the precise role of demand deposita had ragedthroughout the n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century. And when Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisherwrote his Purchas<strong>in</strong>g Power of Money <strong>in</strong> 1913, he sfill felt it necessaryto disdnguish between M (the supply of standard c_sh) andM I, the total of demand deposits, s Why then did Mises, thedeveloper of the <strong>Austrian</strong> theory of money, argue for <strong>in</strong>dud<strong>in</strong>gdemand deposita as Part of the money supply "<strong>in</strong> the broadersense"? Because, as he po<strong>in</strong>ted out, bank demand deposita werenot other goods and services, other assets exchangeable for cash;they were, <strong>in</strong>stead, redeemable for cash at par on demand. S<strong>in</strong>cethey were so redeemable, they functioned, notas a good ofservice exchang<strong>in</strong>g for cash, but rather asa warehouse receiptfor cash, redeemable on demand at par as <strong>in</strong> the case ofany otherwarehouse. Demand deposits were therefore "moneysubstitutes"and functioned as equivalent to money <strong>in</strong> the market.Instead of exchang<strong>in</strong>g cash fora good, the owner of ademand deposit and the seller of the good would both treat thedepositas _it were cash, a surrogate for money. Hence, receipt


<strong>Austrian</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions of the Supply of MoffL7 145of the demand deposit was accepted by the seller as f<strong>in</strong>al paymentfor his product. And so long o3 demand deposita ate acceptedas equivalent to standard money, they will function aspart of the money supply.It is important to recognize that demand deposits are notautomatically part of the money supply by virtue of their veryexistence; they cont<strong>in</strong>ue as equivalent to money only so long asthe subjective estimates of the sellers of goods on the marketth<strong>in</strong>k that they are so equivalent and accept them as such <strong>in</strong>exchange. Let us hark back, for example, to the good old daysbefore federal deposit imurance, when banks were liable to bankruns at any time. Suppose that the Jonesville Bank has outstand<strong>in</strong>gdemand deposita of$1 million; that million dollars is then itacontñbution to the aggregate money supply of the country. Butsuppose that suddenly the soundness of the Jonesville Bank isseverely called <strong>in</strong>to question; antl Jonesville demand deposita areaccepted only ata discount, or even not at all. In that case, as arun on the bank develops, ita demand deposita no longer functionas part of the money supply, certa<strong>in</strong>ly not at par. So that abank's demand deposit only functions as part of the moneysupply so long as it is treated as an equivalent substitute for cash.4It might weU be objected that s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> the era of fractionalreserve bank<strong>in</strong>g, demand deposita are not really redeemable atpar on demand, that then only standard cash (whether gold orfmt paper, depend<strong>in</strong>g upon the standard) can be consideredpart of the money supply. This contrasta with 100 percent reservebank<strong>in</strong>g, when demand deposita are genu<strong>in</strong>ely redeemable<strong>in</strong> cash, and function as genu<strong>in</strong>e, rather than pseudo, warehousereceipts to money. Such an objection would be plausible, butwould overlook the <strong>Austrian</strong> emphasis on the central importance<strong>in</strong> the market of subjective estimates of importance andvalue. Deposita are not <strong>in</strong>fact all redeemable <strong>in</strong> cash <strong>in</strong> a systemof fractional reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g; but so long as <strong>in</strong>dividuals on themarket th/nk that the), ate so redeemable, the)' cont<strong>in</strong>ue to functionas part of the money supply. Indeed, it is precisely theexpansion of bank demand deposita beyond their reserves thataccounta for the phenomena of <strong>in</strong>flation and bus<strong>in</strong>ess cydes. As


146 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>noted above, demand deposits must be <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the conceptof the money supply so long as the market treats them as equivailent; that is, so long as <strong>in</strong>dividuals th<strong>in</strong>k that they ale redeemable<strong>in</strong> cash. In the current era of federal deposit <strong>in</strong>surance, added tothe existente of a central bank that pr<strong>in</strong>ts standard money andfunctíons asa lender of last resort, it is doubfful that this confidente<strong>in</strong> redeemability can ever be shaken.AU economists, of course, <strong>in</strong>clude standard money <strong>in</strong> their¢oncept of the money supply. The justification for ínclud<strong>in</strong>gdemand deposits, as we have seen, is that people believe thatthese deposits are redeemable <strong>in</strong> standard money on demand,and therefore treat them as equivalent, accept<strong>in</strong>g the payment ofdemand deposits asa surrogate for the payment of cash. But ffdemand deposits ate to be <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong> the money supply for thís -reason, then it follows that any other enttities that follow the samerules must also be <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the supply of money.Let us consider the case of sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits. There are severalcommon arguments for not <strong>in</strong>dud<strong>in</strong>g sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits <strong>in</strong> themoney supply: (1) they are not redeemable on demand, the bankbe<strong>in</strong>g legally able to force the deposítors to wait a certa<strong>in</strong> amountof time (usually 30 days) before pay<strong>in</strong>g cash; (2) the), cannot beused direcfly for payment. Checks can be drawn on demanddeposits, but sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits must first be redeemed <strong>in</strong> cashupon presentation of a passbook; (3)demand deposíts atepyramided upon a base of total reserves asa multiple of reserves,whereas sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits (at least <strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks and sav<strong>in</strong>gsand loan associations) can only pyramid on a one-to-one basis ontop of demand deposits (sínce such deposits will rapidly "leakout" of sav<strong>in</strong>gs and <strong>in</strong>to demand deposits).Objection (1), however, fails from focus<strong>in</strong>g on the legalitiesrather than on the economic reafities of the simation; <strong>in</strong> particular,the objection fails to focus on the subject/ve estimates of thesituation on the part of the depositors. In reality, the power toenforce a thirty-day notice on sav<strong>in</strong>gs depositors is never enforced;hence, the depositor <strong>in</strong>variably th<strong>in</strong>ks of his sav<strong>in</strong>gsaccount as redeemable <strong>in</strong> cash on demand. Indeed, when, <strong>in</strong> the1929 depression, banks tñed to enforce this forgotten provision


A_t,_nDef<strong>in</strong>i_o,uoft_ s__zyofMo_ 147<strong>in</strong> their sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits, bank runs promptly ensued. 5Objection (2) fañs as well, when we consider that, even with<strong>in</strong>the stock of standard money, some part of one's cash will betraded more actively or directly than others. Thus, supposesomeone holds part of his supply of cash <strong>in</strong> his wallet, andanother part buñed under the fioorboards. The cash <strong>in</strong> thewallet will be exchanged and turned over rapidly; the floorboardmoney might not be used for decades. But surely no one woulddeny that the person's floorboard hoard isjust as much part ofhis money stock as the cash <strong>in</strong> his wanet. So that mere lack ofactivity of part of the money stock <strong>in</strong> no way negates its <strong>in</strong>dusionas part of his supply of money. Similarly, the fact that passbooksmust'be presented before a sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposit can be used <strong>in</strong> exchangeshould not negate its <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>in</strong> the money supply. As Ihave written elsewhere, suppose that for some cultural quirk--say widespread revulsion aga<strong>in</strong>st the number "5"---no seller willaccept a five-dollar bill <strong>in</strong> exchange, but only ones or tens. Inorder to use five-dollar bilis, then, their owner would first haveto go to a bank to exchange them for ones or tens, and then usethose ones or tens <strong>in</strong> exchange. But surely, such a necessitywould not mean that someone's stock of five-donar bilis was notpart of his money supply, eNeither is Objection (3) persuasive. For whñe ir is true thatdemand deposits area mulple pyramíd on reserves, whereassav<strong>in</strong>gs bank deposits are only a one-to-one pyramid on demanddeposits, this dist<strong>in</strong>guishes the sources or volatility of differentforros of money, but should not exdude sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits fromthe supply of money. For demand deposits, <strong>in</strong> mm, pyramid ontop of cash, and yet, whíle each of these forros of money isgenerated quite differently, so long as they exist each forros partof the total supply of money <strong>in</strong> the country. The same shouldthen be true of sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits, whether they be deposits <strong>in</strong>commercial or <strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks.A fourth objecfion, based on the third, holds that sav<strong>in</strong>gsdeposits should not be considered as part of the money supplybecause they are efficiently if <strong>in</strong>direcfiy controllable by the FederalReserve through its control of commer_al bank total re-


148 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economics</strong>serves and reserve requirements for demand deposits. Sudacontrol is <strong>in</strong>deed a fact, but the argument proves lar too muda;for, after all, demand deposits are themselves and <strong>in</strong> turn <strong>in</strong>directlybut efficiently controllable by the Fed through its controlof total reserves and reserve requirements. In fact, control ofsav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits is not nearly as efficient as of demand deposits;ir, for example, sav<strong>in</strong>gs depositors would keep their money andactivepayments <strong>in</strong> the sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks, <strong>in</strong>stead of<strong>in</strong>vanably "leak<strong>in</strong>g"back to check<strong>in</strong>g accounts, sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks w0u/d be able topyramid new sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits on top of commercial bank demanddeposits by a large multiple/Not only, then, should sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits be <strong>in</strong>duded as part ofthe money supply, but our argument leads to the conclusion thatno valíd dist<strong>in</strong>ction can be made between sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits <strong>in</strong>commercial banks (<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> M_) and <strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks ofsav<strong>in</strong>gsand loan associations (also<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> M3).8Once sav<strong>in</strong>gsdeposits are conceded to be part of the money supply, _here isnosound reason for balk<strong>in</strong>g at the <strong>in</strong>clusion of deposits of the latterbanks.On the other hand, agenu<strong>in</strong>e time deposit--a bank deposit thatwould <strong>in</strong>deed only be redeemable at a certa<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t of time <strong>in</strong> thefuture, would merit very different treatment. Suciaa time deposit,not be<strong>in</strong>g redeemable on demand, would <strong>in</strong>stead be acredit <strong>in</strong>strument rather than a form of warehouse receipt. Itwould be the result of a credit transaction rather than awarehouse claim on cash; it would therefore not function <strong>in</strong> themarket as a surrogate for cash.Ludwig von Misesdist<strong>in</strong>guished carefully between a credáanda da/m transaction: a credit transacfion is ah exchange of apresent good (e.g., money which can be used <strong>in</strong> exchange at anypresent moment) for a future good (e.g., ah IOU for money thatwill only be available <strong>in</strong> the future). In this seme, a demanddeposít, while legally designated as credit, is actually a presentgood--a warehouse claim to a present good that is similar to abailment transacñon, <strong>in</strong> which the warehouse pledges to redeemthe ticket at any time on demand.Thus, Mises mote:


<strong>Austrian</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions of the Supply of Money _ 140It is usual to reckon the acceptance of a deposit which can be drawnupon at any time by means of notes or cheques asa type of credittransaction andjuristically this viewis, ofcourse,justified; but economically,thecaseis not one ofa credittransacUon. Ifcredit<strong>in</strong> the economicsense means the exchange ofa present good ora present serviceaga<strong>in</strong>sta future good ora future servace,then it is hardlypossibleto <strong>in</strong>dude thetransactions <strong>in</strong> question under the conception of credit.A depositor ofa sum of money who acquires <strong>in</strong> exchange for it a claimconvertible<strong>in</strong>tomoney at any time whichwiUperform exactly the same servicefor himas the sum ir refers to has exchanged no present good fora futuregood. The claím that he has acquired by his deposit is also a presentgood for him. The deposit<strong>in</strong>g of the money <strong>in</strong> no waymeans that he hasrenounced immediate disposal over the utility it commands2It might be, and has been, objected that credit <strong>in</strong>struments,such as bilis of exchange or Treasury bilis, can often be soldeasily on credit market: either by the rediscount<strong>in</strong>g of bilis or<strong>in</strong> sell<strong>in</strong>g old bonds on the bond market; and that therefore theyshould be considered as money. But many assets are "liquid,"i.e., can easily be sold for money. Blue-chip stocks, for example,can be easily sold for money, yet no one would <strong>in</strong>clude suchstocks as part of'the money supply. The operative difference,then, ís not whether an asset is liquid or not (s<strong>in</strong>ce stocks ate nomore part of the money supply than, say, real estate) but whetherthe asset is redeemable at a fixed rate, at par, <strong>in</strong> money. Credit<strong>in</strong>struments, similarly to the case of shares of stock, are soldformoney on the market at fluctuat<strong>in</strong>g rates. The current tendencyof some economists to <strong>in</strong>clude assets as money purely because oftheir liquidity must be rejected; after all, <strong>in</strong> some cases, <strong>in</strong>ventoriesof retail goods might be as liquidas stocks or bonds, andyet surely no one would list these <strong>in</strong>ventories as part of themoney supply. They are other goods sold for money on themarket, loOne of the most non<strong>in</strong>flationary developments <strong>in</strong> recentAmeñcan bank<strong>in</strong>g has been the emergence ofcertificates ofdeposit(CDs), which are genu<strong>in</strong>e time and credit tra_nsactions. Thepurchaser of the CD, or at least the large-demon<strong>in</strong>ation CD,knows that he has loaned money to the bank which the bank isonly bound to repay at a specific date <strong>in</strong> the future; hence,


150 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>large-scale CDs are properly not <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the M2 and M3def'mitions of the supply ofmoney. The same might be said to betrue of various programs of time deposits which sav<strong>in</strong>gs banksand commercial banks have been develop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> recent years: <strong>in</strong>which the depositor agrees to reta<strong>in</strong> his money <strong>in</strong> the bank for aspecified peñod of years <strong>in</strong> exchange for a higher <strong>in</strong>terest return.There are worñsome problems, however, that are attached tothe latter programs, as well as to sma¿¿-denom<strong>in</strong>ationCDs; for <strong>in</strong>these cases, the deposits ate redeemable before the date of redemptionat fixed rates, but at penalty discounts rather than atpar. Let us assume a hypothetical time deposit, due <strong>in</strong> five years'time at $10,000, but redeemable at presentat a penalty discountof $9,000. We have seen that such a time deposit should certa<strong>in</strong>lynot be <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the money supply <strong>in</strong> the amount of $10,000.But should it be <strong>in</strong>cluded at the f'Lxedthough penalty rate of$9,000, or not be <strong>in</strong>cluded at all? Unfortunately, tñere is noguidance on this problem <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> literature. Our <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>aonis to <strong>in</strong>dude these imtruments <strong>in</strong> the money supply at thepenalty level (e.g., $9,000), s<strong>in</strong>ce the operative dist<strong>in</strong>ction, <strong>in</strong> ourview, is not so much the par redemption as the ever-readypossibility of redemption at some fLxed rate. If this is true, thenwe must also <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>in</strong> the concept of the money supply federalsav<strong>in</strong>gs bonds, whích are redeemable at fixed, though penahyrates, until the date of official maturation.Another entity which should be <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong> the total moneysupply on our def<strong>in</strong>ition is ca_hsurrmuttr valuea of life <strong>in</strong>surancepolicies; these values represent the <strong>in</strong>vestment rather than the<strong>in</strong>surance part of life imurance and are redeemable <strong>in</strong> cash (orrather <strong>in</strong> bank demand deposits) at any time on demand. (Thereare, ofcourse, no possibilities ofcash surrender <strong>in</strong> other forros ofimurance, such as term life, tire, accident, or medical.) StatiscaUy,cash surrender values may be gauged by the total of policyreserves less polio/loíms outstand<strong>in</strong>g, s<strong>in</strong>ce policies on whichmoney has been borrowed from the <strong>in</strong>surance company by thepolicyholder are not subject to immediate withdrawal. Aga<strong>in</strong>,the objection that poficyholders are reluctant to cash <strong>in</strong> their


<strong>Austrian</strong> De.f<strong>in</strong>ions of the Supply of Money _, 151surrender values does not negate their <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>in</strong> the supply ofmoney; such reluctance simply means that this part of ah <strong>in</strong>dividuíd'smoney stock is relatively <strong>in</strong>active. 1_One caveat on the <strong>in</strong>dusion of noncommercial bank depositsand other fixed liabilities <strong>in</strong>to the money supply:just as the cashand other reserves of the commercial banks are not <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong>the money supply, s<strong>in</strong>ce that would be double _ount<strong>in</strong>g oncedemand deposits are <strong>in</strong>duded; <strong>in</strong> the same way, the demanddeposíts owned by these noncommercial bank creators of themoney supply (sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks, sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan companies, life<strong>in</strong>surance companíes, etc.) should be deducted from the totaldemand deposits that are <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong> the supply of money. Inshort, if a commerdal bank has demand deposit liabilities of $1million, of which $100,000 ate owned by a sav<strong>in</strong>gs bank as areserve for its outstand<strong>in</strong>g sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits of $2 million, thenthe total money supply to be attributed to these two banks wouldbe $2.9 million, deduct<strong>in</strong>g the sav<strong>in</strong>gs bank reserve that is thebase for its own liabilitíes.One anomaly <strong>in</strong> American monetary statisfics should also bedeared up: for a reason that rema<strong>in</strong>s obscure, demand deposits<strong>in</strong> commerdíd banks or <strong>in</strong> the Federal Reserve Banks owned bythe Treasury are exduded from the total money supply. If, forexample, the Treasury taxes dtizem by $1 billion, and theirdemand deposits ate shifted from public accounts to the Treasur),account, the total supply of money is considered to havefallen by $1 billion, when what has really háppened is that $1billion worth of money has (temporarily) shifted from private togovemmental hands. Clearly, Treasury deposits should be <strong>in</strong>duded<strong>in</strong> the national total of the money supply.Thus, we propose that the money supply should be defmed asall entities which are redeemable on demand <strong>in</strong> standard cash ata fLxed rate, and that, <strong>in</strong> the United States at the present time,this criterion tra_nslates <strong>in</strong>to:Mo(a ffi<strong>Austrian</strong>) ffitotal supply ofcash-cash held <strong>in</strong> the banks+ total demand dep_its + total sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits <strong>in</strong> commerd_!and sav<strong>in</strong>gs total banks shares <strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan associations


152 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong>/lustrian <strong>Economics</strong>total polio/reserves of life <strong>in</strong>surance companies--policy loansoutstand<strong>in</strong>g--demand deposits owned by sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks, sav<strong>in</strong>gand loan assodations, and life <strong>in</strong>surance companies + sav<strong>in</strong>gsbonds, at current rates of redempÜon.Ma hews to the <strong>Austrian</strong> theory of money, and, <strong>in</strong> so do<strong>in</strong>g,broadens the def<strong>in</strong>iÜon of the money supply far beyond thenarrowMt, and yet avoids the path ofthose who would broadenthe def<strong>in</strong>iÜon to the virtual <strong>in</strong>dusion ofaU liquid _ssets, and whothus would obliterate the uniqueness of the money phenonemonas the f<strong>in</strong>al means of payment for all other goods and services.II.THE MONEY SUPPLY AND CREDIT E_ANSIONTO BUSINESSIn contrast to the Chicago School, the <strong>Austrian</strong> economistcannot rest content with arriv<strong>in</strong>g at the proper concept of thesupply of money. For while the supply of money (Ma) is thevitany important supply side ofthe"money relation" (the supplyof and demand for money) that determ<strong>in</strong>es the array of prices,and is therefore the relevant concept for analyz<strong>in</strong>g price <strong>in</strong>flation,different parts of the money supply play very differentroles <strong>in</strong> affect<strong>in</strong>g the bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde. For the <strong>Austrian</strong> theory ofthe trade cyde reveals that only the <strong>in</strong>flationary bank creditexpansion that enters the market through new bus<strong>in</strong>ess Ioans (ofthrough purchase of bus<strong>in</strong>ess bonds) generates the over<strong>in</strong>vestment<strong>in</strong> higher-order capital goods that leads to theboom-bust cyde. Inflafionary bank credit that enters the marketthrough f'manc<strong>in</strong>g government defidts does not generate thebus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle; for, <strong>in</strong>stead of caus<strong>in</strong>g over<strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong>higher-order capital goods, it simply reallocates resources fromthe private to the public sector, and also tends to dñve up price$.Thus, Mises dist<strong>in</strong>guished between "simple <strong>in</strong>flation," <strong>in</strong> whichthe banks create more deposits through purchase of governmentbonds, and genu<strong>in</strong>e "credit expansion," which enters thebus<strong>in</strong>ess loan market and generates the bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde. As Miseswrites:


<strong>Austrian</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions of the SuI_plyof Money 153In deal<strong>in</strong>gwiththe[bus<strong>in</strong>esscyde] weassumedthat the totalamountofadditionalfiduciarymedia enters the market system viathe loan marketas advancesto bus<strong>in</strong>ess....There are, however, ínstances <strong>in</strong> which the legal and technicalmethods of credit expansion are used for a procedure catallacticallyutterly different from genu<strong>in</strong>e credit expansion. Politicaland <strong>in</strong>stitutionalconveniencesometimesmakes it expedient fora government totake advantage of the facilities of bank<strong>in</strong>g asa substitute for issu<strong>in</strong>ggovernment fiat money. The treasuryborrowsfrom the bank,and thebank provides the funds needed by issu<strong>in</strong>g addifional banknotes orcredit<strong>in</strong>g the government on a deposit account. Legallythe bankbecomesthetreasury'screditor. In fact the whole transactionamounts tofiatmoney <strong>in</strong>flation. The additionalfiduciary mediaenter the marketby way of the treasuryas payment for vañous items of governmentexpenditure.... They affect the loan market andthe grossmarketrateof<strong>in</strong>terest, apartfrom the emergence of a positivepricepremium, onlyira partof them reaches the loan market at a time at whichtheir effectsupon ¢ommodity prices and wage rates have not yet been consummated?zMises did not deal with the relatively new post-World War IIphenomenon of large-scale bank loans to consumers, but thesetoo cannot be said to generate a bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde. Inflationary bankloans to cons_1_ers will arfificially deflect social resources toconsumption rather than <strong>in</strong>vestment, as compared to the unhampereddesires and preferences of the consumers. But theywillnot generate a boom-bust cyde, because they will not result <strong>in</strong>"over" <strong>in</strong>vestment, which must be liquidated <strong>in</strong> a recession. Notenough <strong>in</strong>vestments will be made, but at least there wiU be noflood of <strong>in</strong>vestments which wiU later have to be liquidated.Hence, the effects of divert<strong>in</strong>g consumptíon <strong>in</strong>vestment proportionsaway from consumer time preferences will be asymmetrical,wíth the over<strong>in</strong>vestment-bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde effects only result<strong>in</strong>gfrom <strong>in</strong>flationary bank loans to bus<strong>in</strong>ess. Indeed, the reason whybank fmanc<strong>in</strong>g of government deficits may be called simplerather than cyclical <strong>in</strong>flation is because government demandsare "consumption" uses as decided by the preferences of therul<strong>in</strong>g government offidals.In addition to Ma, then, <strong>Austrian</strong> economists should be <strong>in</strong>-


154 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .4ustrian <strong>Economics</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> how much of a new supply of bank money enters themarket through new loans to bus<strong>in</strong>ess. We might call the portionof new Ma that is created <strong>in</strong> the course of bus<strong>in</strong>ess lend<strong>in</strong>g, Mb(stand<strong>in</strong>g for either bus<strong>in</strong>ess loans or busíness cycle). Ir, forexample, a bank creates $1 million of deposits <strong>in</strong> a given timeperiod, and $400,000 goes <strong>in</strong>to consumer loans and governmentbonds, while $600,000 goes <strong>in</strong>to bus<strong>in</strong>ess loans and <strong>in</strong>vestments,then Mb will have <strong>in</strong>creased by $600,000 <strong>in</strong> that period.In exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Mb on the American f<strong>in</strong>ancial scene, we canignore sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks and sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan associations, whoseassets ate almost exclusively <strong>in</strong>vested <strong>in</strong> residential mortgages.Sav<strong>in</strong>gs bonds, of course, simply help f<strong>in</strong>ance government acdvity.We ate left, then, wíth commercial banks (as well as life<strong>in</strong>surance <strong>in</strong>vestments). Commercial bank assets are comprisedof reserves, government bonds, consumer loans, and bus<strong>in</strong>essloans and <strong>in</strong>vestments (corporate bonds). Their liabilities consistof demand deposits, time deposits (omitt<strong>in</strong>g large CDs), largeCDs, and capital. In try<strong>in</strong>g to discover movements ofMb with anyprecision, we founder on the difficulty that ir is impossible <strong>in</strong>practice to decide to what extent any <strong>in</strong>creases of bus<strong>in</strong>ess loansand <strong>in</strong>vestments have been f<strong>in</strong>anced by an <strong>in</strong>crease of deposits,thus <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g Mó, and how much the), have been f<strong>in</strong>anced by<strong>in</strong>creases of capital and large CDs. Look<strong>in</strong>g at the problemanother way, it is impossible to determ<strong>in</strong>e how much of an<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> deposits (<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> Ma) went to f<strong>in</strong>ance bus<strong>in</strong>essloans and <strong>in</strong>vestments, and how much went: <strong>in</strong>to reserves orconsumer loans. In tryíng to determ<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> Mb for anygiven peñod, then, it is impossible to be scientifically precise, andthe economic historian must actas an "artist" rather than as anapodictic scientíst. In practice, s<strong>in</strong>ce bank capital is relavelysmall, as are bank <strong>in</strong>vestments <strong>in</strong> corporate bonds, the figure forcommercial bank loans to bus<strong>in</strong>ess can provide a rough estimateof movements <strong>in</strong> Mb.With the development of the concepts of M,, (total supply ofmoney) and MI, (total new money supply go<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to bus<strong>in</strong>esscrediO, we have attempted to gire more precision to the Austñan


<strong>Austrian</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>itions of the SuppTy of Money 155theory of money, and to the theoretical as well as historical<strong>Austrian</strong> analysis of monetary and bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle phenomena.NOTES1. In a critique of the Chicago approach, Leland Yeager writes:"But irwould be awkward ifthe def<strong>in</strong>ition of money accord<strong>in</strong>gly had tochange from time to time and country to country. Furthermore, even ifmoney def<strong>in</strong>ed to <strong>in</strong>dude certa<strong>in</strong> near-moneys does correlate somewhatmore dosely with <strong>in</strong>come than money narrowly def<strong>in</strong>ed, that factdoes not necessañly impose the broad def<strong>in</strong>ition. Perhaps the amountof these near-moneys depends on the level of money-<strong>in</strong>come and <strong>in</strong>turn on the amount of medium of exchange .... More generally, it isnot obvious why the magnitude with which some other magnitudecorrelates most closely deserves overrid<strong>in</strong>g attention .... The numberof bathers ata beach ma), correlate more dosely with the number ofcars parked there than with either the temperature or the price ofadmission, yet the former correlation may be less <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g or usefulthan either of the latter" (Leland B. Yeager, "Essenñal Properties of theMedium of Exchange," Kyklos [ 1968], repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Monetary Theory,ed.R. W. Clower [London: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, 1969], p. 38). Also see, MurrayN. Rothbard, "The <strong>Austrian</strong> Theory of Money," <strong>in</strong> E. Dolan, ed., TheFoundations ofModern <strong>Austrian</strong> E¢onomics (Kansas City, Kansas: Sheed 8:Ward, 1976), pp. 179--82.2. Ludwig von Mises, The Theory ofMoney and Credit, 3rd ed. (<strong>New</strong>Haven: Yale University Press, 1953).3. Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher, The Purchas<strong>in</strong>g Power ofMoney (<strong>New</strong> York: Macmlan,1913).4. Even now, <strong>in</strong> the goldén days of federal deposit <strong>in</strong>surance, ademand deposit is not always equivalent to cash, as anyone who is toldthat it will take 15 bank<strong>in</strong>g days to alear a check from California to <strong>New</strong>York can attest.5. On the equivalence ofdemand and sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits dur<strong>in</strong>g theGreat Depression, and on the bank runs resultihg from attempts toenforce the 50-da}, wait for redemption, see Murray N. Rothbard,America's Grm/Deprex6_, 3rd ed. (Kansas City, Kansas: Sheed &Ward,1975), pp. 84, 316. Also see L<strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>, "Are Time Deposits Money?/lmetic.an E¢onamic Review (March 1937), pp. 76--86..6. Rothbard, "The <strong>Austrian</strong> Theory ofMoney, p. 181.7. In the Uni_redStates, the latter is beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to be the case, as


156 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly be<strong>in</strong>g aUowed "toissue checks on theirsav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits. Ir that became the rule, moreover, Objection (2)would then fall on this ground alone.8. Regardless of the legal forro, the "shares" of formal ownership<strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan associations are economically precisely equivalentto the new deposits <strong>in</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks, an equivalence that is universallyacknowledged by economists.9. Mises, Theory of Money and Credit, p. 268.10. For Míses' critique of the view that endorsed bilis ofexchange <strong>in</strong>early n<strong>in</strong>eteenth-cenmry Europe were really part of the money supply,see/b/d., pp. 284-86.11. For h<strong>in</strong>ts on the possible <strong>in</strong>clusion oflife <strong>in</strong>surance cash surrendervalues <strong>in</strong> the supply of money, see Gordon W. McK<strong>in</strong>ley, "Effectsof Federal Reserve Policy on Nonmonetary F<strong>in</strong>ancia] InstimUons," <strong>in</strong>Herbert V. Prochnow, ed., The Federal Reseroe System (<strong>New</strong> York:Harper & Bros., 1960), p. 217n; and Arthur F. Burns, Prospe_ withoutInflation (Buffalo: Economica Books, 1958), p. 50.12. Ludwig von Mises, Human A¢tion, 3rd rey. ed. (Chicago: HenryRegnery, 1966), p. 570.


The Emergence of Interest<strong>in</strong> a Pure Exchange Economy:Notes on a TheoremAttributed to Ludwig von MisesLaurence S. MossBabson College1. Individuals faced with alternatives equally attractive <strong>in</strong> allrespects except their position <strong>in</strong> time prefer proximate enjoymentsto those more remote. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Ludwig von Mises,this preference for earlier rather than later enjoyments is <strong>in</strong>herent<strong>in</strong> aUacts of <strong>in</strong>dividual choice and is termed "time preference.''1 It has been claimed that Misesian time preferenceguarantees the emergence of a positive rate of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> a pureexchange economy, that is,where there is no production and theeconomic fumre is known with certa<strong>in</strong>ty.2 Furthermore, the<strong>in</strong>terest rate that "<strong>in</strong>variably" emerges results entirely from the<strong>in</strong>teraction of valu<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ds and is therefore a subjectivephenomenon, not be<strong>in</strong>g dependent on the technology of productionor the productivity of capital. Interest is nota paymentfora monopolized agent of production, nor does it reflect aparticular distribution of the means of production that can bedone away with by reorganiz<strong>in</strong>g the social order <strong>in</strong> a mannerprescribed by Socialist visionañes, sThe dairathat a positive rate of<strong>in</strong>terest willemerge <strong>in</strong> a pureexchange economy seems fundamental to, and consistent with,157


158 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Mises' entire theoretical system. While <strong>in</strong> bis early economicwrit<strong>in</strong>gs Mises embraced Eugen von B6hm-Bawerk's theory thatthe height of the <strong>in</strong>terest tate is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the technologicalsuperiority of roundabout methods of production, his later writ<strong>in</strong>gsrepudiated the productivity theory of <strong>in</strong>terest rate determ<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>in</strong> favor of the pure time-preference theory advanced <strong>in</strong>the United States by Frank A. Fetter at the turn of this century. 4As has been claimed by recent <strong>Austrian</strong> economists, Mises' adoptionof the so-called pure time-preference concept <strong>in</strong>dicates ahabandonment of B6hm-Bawerkian theory and a return to themore thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g subjectivism characteristic of CarlMenger's thought. 5 In fact, a fundamental theoretical differencebetween Mises and Friedrich A. Hayek may well turn on theissue of the <strong>in</strong>fluence the material structure of the world exertson the <strong>in</strong>dividual's personal valuation of goods now as opposedto goods later, e To the extent that the payment of <strong>in</strong>terest isnecessitated by the material conditions surround<strong>in</strong>g the productionand distribution of commodities rather than by man's subjectiveestimate of future enjoyments, then to that extent thecapitalist system (i.e., the market economy) seems less permanentand more dependent on a historical stage <strong>in</strong> the evolutionof these material conditions. Thus, modern <strong>Austrian</strong> economistswho view capi_!ism as the only social system compatible with thenature of man attach great importance to their <strong>in</strong>terest theoryand to the theorem I shall discuss <strong>in</strong> this paperYWhat I offer here is a model ofa pure exchange economy withah analysis of the circumstances under which a positive marketrate of <strong>in</strong>terest will emerge. I shall show that much of the misunderstand<strong>in</strong>gregard<strong>in</strong>g Mises' <strong>in</strong>terest theory has to do with thespecial mean<strong>in</strong>g Mises attached m the term t/me preferenc4. StiU,when Mises' theorem is correctly stated and understood, it will beseen that the emergence of <strong>in</strong>terest is not <strong>in</strong>evitable but depends<strong>in</strong> part on the existence of certa<strong>in</strong> objective conditions thatprevent the <strong>in</strong>dividual from "<strong>in</strong>ternally f<strong>in</strong>anc<strong>in</strong>g" an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong>present consumption even when he can afford m do so. Andthese objective conditions that make possible the emergence of<strong>in</strong>terest ale hardly the sort that can be efim<strong>in</strong>ated by a reorgani-


The Emergence of Interest <strong>in</strong> a Pute Exchange Economy 159zation of the social order along the l<strong>in</strong>es advocated by antimarketreformers.2. Consider an economy consist<strong>in</strong>g of a number of <strong>in</strong>dividualseach fac<strong>in</strong>g a time horizon made up of n consumption periods.Also, assume that each <strong>in</strong>dividual is guaranteed an endowmentof a s<strong>in</strong>gle consumption good (apples) and knows how manyunits of this s<strong>in</strong>gle consumption good will be made available tohito at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of each of the n consumption peñods. Weassume the <strong>in</strong>dividual is able to rank this particular time allocationamong all other conceivable time allocations, and we writethe <strong>in</strong>dividual's utility funcfion as follows:UT = f (ti, C|, ti .... CD (1)where U represents, for <strong>in</strong>dividual I, the uUlity level associatedwith the time pattern of consumpUon offered by his orig<strong>in</strong>alendowment, and C represents the number of units of a consumpongood available to the <strong>in</strong>dividual at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of the¡thperiod of consumption (where i ranges over the n peñods).It ma)' be useful to th<strong>in</strong>k ofa prisoner ofwar camp where eachof the prisoners is told <strong>in</strong> advance how many apples he will begiven at each ofn successive dates <strong>in</strong> the future. Each <strong>in</strong>dividualis absolutely certa<strong>in</strong> that he will obta<strong>in</strong> that number of apples onschedule as promised. 8 Now suppose that after this <strong>in</strong>formationis disclosed, each prisoner is given the option of transferr<strong>in</strong>gsome of the apples promised <strong>in</strong> remoter consumption per[ods toperiods more proximate. For example, an <strong>in</strong>dividual may requestthat an apple promised <strong>in</strong> period number 10 be supplied <strong>in</strong>peñod number 3. Also, ifwe assume that storage costs are zero,<strong>in</strong>dividuals can always move apples from earlier periods to laterperiods simply by hold<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>in</strong> the form of <strong>in</strong>ventory? Insuch a world each <strong>in</strong>dividual will redistribute his consumptionstream over time so that he can achieve a preferred level ofsatisfaction over the whole plann<strong>in</strong>g period. Let us represent thispreferred allocaUon as foUows:U,_,ffif (C_, C|, C|,... Cea), (2)


160 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .4ustrian <strong>Economics</strong>where U_ represents thedesired level of satisfaction of <strong>in</strong>dividualI and C represents the desired number of apples to be consumed<strong>in</strong> the ithpeñod. As should be clear from the description of theproblem, the arithmetic sum ofapples consumed over the entireplann<strong>in</strong>g horizon must be equal to the sum of apples promised <strong>in</strong>die orig<strong>in</strong>al situation, that is,nnx c_ = X cL (s)i=li=lStated another way, ifwe def<strong>in</strong>e net borrow<strong>in</strong>g between any twoperiods asc_ - cL (4)then the sum of net borrow<strong>in</strong>g over the enUre plann<strong>in</strong>g horizonmust be zero, ofnXi=1[cid - CTl= 0. (5)3. It is alear that, if the <strong>in</strong>dividual chooses to <strong>in</strong>crease his appleconsumption <strong>in</strong> some periods, he must decrease it <strong>in</strong> otherperiods by an exact amount. _oThe utility maximiz<strong>in</strong>g allocationhas the property that the marg<strong>in</strong>al utility of apple consumptionís roughly equal <strong>in</strong> each period, or the marg<strong>in</strong>al rate of substitutionbetween apples <strong>in</strong> any two peñods is equal to unity and is thesan_e for all <strong>in</strong>dividuals. __It may at first seem that the marg<strong>in</strong>alutility of an apple scheduled to be received x periods <strong>in</strong> thefuture must be perceived as be<strong>in</strong>g ofsmaller <strong>in</strong>tensity than it willactually turn out to be when that period of comumption isreached. TMIt may be realistic to assume this <strong>in</strong> actual life situationswhere <strong>in</strong>dividuals often fail to provide adequately for theirold age, but <strong>in</strong> our model the assumptionof perfectlmowledgeassures us that no such shortsighted valuation takes place. The<strong>in</strong>dividual is equipped with the power to project his feel<strong>in</strong>gs (or


The Emergence of Interest _n a Pure Exchange Economy 161value order<strong>in</strong>gs) forward <strong>in</strong> time and anticipate quite accuratelywhat his future requirements wiUbe.It is apparent that <strong>in</strong>dividuals start<strong>in</strong>g out with identical appleendowments will not necessarily arrive at identical consumptionplans. Economists such as Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher and more recently GaryBecker tried to say someth<strong>in</strong>g more def<strong>in</strong>ite about the relationshipbetween <strong>in</strong>dividual tastes and f<strong>in</strong>al consumption patterns.For this purpose the), dist<strong>in</strong>guished among positive, negative,and zero (or neutral) time preference. 13 An <strong>in</strong>dividual whopossesses positive time preference will, when given an equalendowment of apples <strong>in</strong> two adjacent peñods, trade more thanone future apple for one present apple. On the other hand the<strong>in</strong>dividual who is will<strong>in</strong>g to give up more than one present applefor a future apple when his endowment of apples is the same <strong>in</strong>the two adjacent periods is said to possess negative time preference(though we would not observe such a trade, as I shall arguebelow). F<strong>in</strong>ally, an <strong>in</strong>dividual satisfied with an equal number ofapples <strong>in</strong> each time period is said to display neutral or zero timepreference. S<strong>in</strong>ce any one of these three situations is evidencefor what Mises called "time preference," he must have meant bythe terna someth<strong>in</strong>g different from what has become standardterm<strong>in</strong>ology among neoclassical economists.In Mises' víew an <strong>in</strong>dividual demonstrates time preference <strong>in</strong>any period simply by consum<strong>in</strong>g some apples <strong>in</strong> that periodrather than none at all. If (<strong>in</strong> temas of our n-period model) an<strong>in</strong>dividual reallocated his apple endowment so that he consumednoth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the first n- 1 periods and everyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the last peñod,we would have a situation close to what Mises described as theabsence of time preference, a4Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises, the ver,/act ofconsum<strong>in</strong>g duñng the plann<strong>in</strong>g period demonstrates (positive)time preference. In Mises' writ<strong>in</strong>gs this concept might better betermed t/me allocation than t/me preference.I do not wish to enter <strong>in</strong>to a discussion of which def<strong>in</strong>ition oftime preference is best for modern economics. I do wish to po<strong>in</strong>tout, however, that (1) the Misesian notion of time preference(that is, time allocation) does not make use of the notion of"choice at the marg<strong>in</strong>," or at least it is obscure as to what and


162 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>where the notion of the marg<strong>in</strong> might enter <strong>in</strong>to such a def'mition;"and (2) when semantic considerations are put aside, thereis no fundamental issue separat<strong>in</strong>g Mises from the rema<strong>in</strong>der ofthe economícs profession. A great deal ofconfusion has resultedfrom Mises' frequent use of the expression t/me preference tomean time allocation without <strong>in</strong>dicatíng that his special use of theterna was different from that of those whom he credited withorig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g the concept? 64. We may now ask whether Mises was correa when he <strong>in</strong>sistedthat time allocation gives rise to a market for claims to futureconsumption (that is, a bond market) with a positive rate of<strong>in</strong>terest. Obviously, we would not observe a negative <strong>in</strong>terest rate<strong>in</strong> our model of a pure exchange economy where storage costsate assumed to be zero. No one would trade a present apple fofaclaim to/ess than 0he future apple when he could obta<strong>in</strong> a wholefuture apple simply by stoñng the present app]e until that laterdate. li"consumption goods could be transferred not on]y fromthe present to the future but also from the future to the present,no one wou]d f<strong>in</strong>d it economical to trade a claim for more thanone unir of future consumpt/on goods for a unit of presentgoods when that same present good could be obta<strong>in</strong>ed morecheaply by transferr<strong>in</strong>g goods back through time. In a worldwith this type of symmetrícal me transfer, ah <strong>in</strong>dívidual timeallocator would trade onIy with himself, and there would be noeconomic <strong>in</strong>centive to create a market <strong>in</strong> which daims on futuregoods are exchanged.It is only when we drop the assumption that apples can betransferred from the future to the present (though presentapples can stíll be held i'or future consumption) that a (bond)market will merge <strong>in</strong> which claims to future apples ate exchanged.Here <strong>in</strong>dividuals who want more than one futureapple fora present apple and ale unable to acquire that applefrom their future endowment <strong>in</strong>duce others by means of aja<strong>in</strong>terest payment to gire up some of their current stock ofapples.The actual market rate of <strong>in</strong>terest will more to equate the supplyof, and demand for, goods. Furthermore, the equilibñum <strong>in</strong>-


The Emergence of Interest <strong>in</strong> a Pffre Exchange Economy 163terest rate can never fall below zero, because <strong>in</strong>dividuals canalways hold present goods until a later period at zero cost.The existence of ah organized market <strong>in</strong> which claims tofuture consumption are traded now makes it possible fora s<strong>in</strong>gle<strong>in</strong>dividual's totaln-peñod consumption to be greater or less thanhis total aggregate apple endowment. Whether it will be greateror less depends, of course, on whether over the n periods he wasa net <strong>in</strong>terest payer or receiver. Ir rema<strong>in</strong>s true, however, thattotal apple consumption for the entire society must equal totalapple endowment when both totals are summed over all <strong>in</strong>dividualsand all periods. That is,nk2 Y_(Ca - Cti) = 0, (6)i=l j=lwhere all symbols are def<strong>in</strong>ed as before andj ranges over all kmembers of society. Itis <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to po<strong>in</strong>t out the majordifference between a pure exchange economy and an economywith production and exchange: Production removes the constra<strong>in</strong>ton societal consurnption represented by equation (6).With production it is possible for all members of society simultaneouslyto reduce present consumption and have future consumptionrise by an even greater amount. It was this phenomenonB6hm-Bawerk had <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when he wrote of the productivityof roundabout methods ofproducfion? _It is not my purposehere to explore any further the <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g dynamics of theproduction economy.5. In conclusion, we say that <strong>in</strong> a pure exchange economy amarket wiU emerge <strong>in</strong> which daims to future consumer goodsare sold at posítive pñces. Ir it were technologically possible toorder up future goods ahead of time (and storage costs werezero), then no economiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual would pay more than oneunit of a present good for a claim to a future good. In such aworld, there would be no economic <strong>in</strong>centive to create a bondmarket, anda zero rate of <strong>in</strong>terest would prevail. It is only


164 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>because of the asymmetry <strong>in</strong> the time market, namely, thatpresent goods can be costlessly transferred to the future butfuture goods cannot be conjured to the present, that we haveevery reason to expect the emergence of a market for daims tofuture goods along with a posiáve <strong>in</strong>terest tate.Thus, <strong>in</strong>terest will emerge <strong>in</strong> a Socialist economy as ir does <strong>in</strong> amarket economy because time allocation proceeds <strong>in</strong> a worldwhere the present graduaUy unfolds <strong>in</strong>to the future rather thanthe other way around. Mises' attempt to presenta purely subjecotire time preference (read "time allocation') theory of <strong>in</strong>terestmust at the very least admit the empirical or broadly technologicalassumption that the transfer of goods through time is <strong>in</strong>deeda one-way street."" NOTESI. Ludwig von Mises, Human Action: A Treatise on Economic$(Chicago:Henry Regnery Co., 1966), pp. 479-90; idem, "A Cñtique ofB6hm-Bawerk's Reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Support of His Time PreferenceTheory," <strong>in</strong> Percy L. Greaves, Jr., MisesMade Easier:A Glossa,jforLudwig ronMises'Human Action(<strong>New</strong> York: Free MarketBooks, 1974),pp. 150-57.2. See Israel M. Kirzner, "Ludwig von Mises and the Theory ofCapital and Interest," <strong>in</strong> The Economic$of Lu.d.wig ron Mises: TowardaCriticalReappraisal,ed. Laurence S. Moss!KansasCity:Sheed & Ward,1976), pp. 61-65. Kirzner wrote, "Mises views on capital and on <strong>in</strong>terestmaybeconvenientlysummarized as follows.., <strong>in</strong>terest expressesthe universal.., phenomenon of time preference and will thereforeínevitably emerge also <strong>in</strong> a pure exchange economy without production"(p. 53).Weate try<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong> what Mísescalled"orig<strong>in</strong>ary<strong>in</strong>terest," whichis the market rate of <strong>in</strong>terest less a premíum for uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty (or risk)and less the anticipated tate of price <strong>in</strong>flation.3. Mises,Hu__n Action, pp. 458, 528, 532.4. On Fetters contribution, see the <strong>in</strong>troductionto FrankA. Fetter,Capital,Interest, avalRent: Essays<strong>in</strong> the Theoryof _, ed.Murray N. Rothbard (Kansas City: Sheed Andrews and McMeel,1977), pp. 1-24. On Mises' adoption and subsequent dissatis-


The Emergence of Interest <strong>in</strong> a Pure Exchange Economy 165faction with B6hm-Bawerk's theory_see Ludwig von Mises, The TheoryofMoney and Credit (<strong>New</strong> Haven: Ya_e University Press, 1959), p. 24;Kirzner, "Mises and the Theory of Capital," p. 52; and Mises, "ACñtique of B6hm-Bawerk's Reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Support of His Time PreferenceTheory," <strong>in</strong> Pero/L. Greaves, Jr., Mises Made Easier (<strong>New</strong> York:Free Market Book, 1974), pp. 150-57.5. See Ludwig M. Lachmann, "On <strong>Austrian</strong> Capital Theory," <strong>in</strong>The Foundations ofModern <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>, ed. Edw<strong>in</strong> G. Dolan (KansasCity: Sheed & Ward, 1976), pp. 145--51.6. Cf. Friedrich A. Hayek, "Time Preferente and Productivity: AReconsideration," Economiza 12 (February 1945): 22-25.7. Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, 2 vols. (<strong>New</strong>York: D. Van Nostrand, 1962), 1:350-56.8. CL R. A. Radford, "The Economic Organization of a P.O.W.Camp," Economiza 12 (November 1945): 189-201.9. I ana also assum<strong>in</strong>g that the apples do not spoil and thatthere is no possibility of theft or accidental destruction.10. There ate no fraudulent traders <strong>in</strong> our model economy; accord<strong>in</strong>gly,without production one cannot promise to pay more than one'sassets wiU atlow.11. If the marg<strong>in</strong>al utilky of an apple <strong>in</strong> period mis significantlygreater than the marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>in</strong> period n, then the <strong>in</strong>dividual woulddo better m reallocate his apples out of period-n consumption and <strong>in</strong>topeñod-m consumption. By the familiar law of dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g returns themarg<strong>in</strong>al utity of apples <strong>in</strong> pefiod m falls and rises <strong>in</strong> period n. Thiswill cont<strong>in</strong>ue so long as the marg<strong>in</strong>al utilities <strong>in</strong> any two periods arelarger than some vídue say _, í.e.,When (MU..-MU.) > _ then apples ate transferredfrom period n to pefiod m.The size of _ depends on the perceived opportunity costs of mak<strong>in</strong>gsuch a transfer. This last value will differ among <strong>in</strong>dividuals. When 4, issmall and the same for all consumers, then reallocation will cont<strong>in</strong>ueuntilMUro = MU..Multiply<strong>in</strong>gyields,both sides of this equality by Ad and divid<strong>in</strong>g by MUnMUm/MUa = AA/AANow the left-hand side is the marg<strong>in</strong>al rate of substitution for any


166 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual and the right-hand side the"terms of trade" between periodm and n which is 1 by the assumptions of this model.12. This is ah important po<strong>in</strong>t. B6hm-Bawerk and other writerstried to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest by postulat<strong>in</strong>g a psychological tendency for<strong>in</strong>dividuals to systematically underva/ue their future needs. Besidesbe<strong>in</strong>g bad psychology, <strong>in</strong> that it disregards at the very least the paranoidmiser who does quite the opposite, such misvaluation is ruled out by myassumption of certa<strong>in</strong>ty about future conditions and needs. Cf. Mises,"A Critique of B6hm-Bawerk's Reason<strong>in</strong>g," pp. 150-55.13. Irv<strong>in</strong>g Fisher, The Theory of lnterest as Determ<strong>in</strong>_ byImpa.6erwetoSpend Inco_w and Opportunity to InveJt Ir (<strong>New</strong> York: Macmillan Co.,1930), pp. 61-68; see also, for example, Gilbert R. Ghez and Gary S.Becker, The AUocation of Time ami Goods over the Life Cycle (<strong>New</strong> York:National Bureau of Economic Research, 1975), pp. 8-14.14. This is how I <strong>in</strong>terpret the follow<strong>in</strong>g passage by Mises <strong>in</strong> thecontext of ah n-peñod model: "Whoever eats and consumes anyth<strong>in</strong>gismak<strong>in</strong>g a choice between a satisfaction <strong>in</strong> the immediate future and one<strong>in</strong> the more distant future. Ifhe were to decide differenfly, that is, ifhewere not to prefer the earlier to the later satisfacUon, he would never beable to consume at aU. He could not even eat and consume tomorrow,because when tomorrow became today; and the day after tomorrowbecame tomorrow, the dedsion to consume would still call for valu<strong>in</strong>gan earlier satisfaction more than a later satisfaction. Otherwise, consumpUonwould have to be delayed still further" (Mises, "ACritique ofB6hm-Bawerk's Rcason<strong>in</strong>g," p. 157).15. See Roge r W. Garñson, "Reflections on Misesian Time lh'eference"(paper presented at Sem<strong>in</strong>ar <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>, Universítyof Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, April 1975), pp. 4-5.16. Mises, Human Act/on, p. 489; see also Garrison, "Reflections,"pp.9--13.17. EugenvonB6hm-Bawerk, PositiveTheoryofCapital,'<strong>in</strong>Cap/-talandlnterest, trans. C,eorge D. Hunche and Hans F. Sennhoh (SouthHolland, IU.: Ia'bertarian Press; 1959), pp. 10-12.


<strong>Austrian</strong>Macroeconomics:A DiagrammaticalExpositionRoger W. GarrisonUniversityof Virg<strong>in</strong>iaINTRODUCTIONThe object of this paper is the development ofa diagrammaticmodel represent<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Austrian</strong> view of macroeconomic relationships.More explicitly, the model will be designed to faithfullyreflect the macroeconomic relationships found <strong>in</strong> the wñt<strong>in</strong>gsof Mises,1 Hayek, 2 and Rothbard. s At this stage <strong>in</strong> its developmentthe model is little more than a skeletal outl<strong>in</strong>e. It is aframework that can facilitate a fuUer discussion of the actualadjustment mechanism: ".heprocesses by which the economy ismoved toward ah equilibrium posidon. Because of the brevity ofsuch discussions <strong>in</strong> this paper, the model may appear to beunfaithful to the <strong>Austrian</strong> view <strong>in</strong> one respect: It focuses onaggregates rather than on processes. Hopefully, this unfaithfulnessis only apparent. Although the model is constructed withaggregate quantities and deals with the relationships betweenthese quantities, no attempt is made to "expla<strong>in</strong>" one aggregate<strong>in</strong> temas of another. It is fully recognized that, ultimately, eachaggregate must be expla<strong>in</strong>ed or accounted for <strong>in</strong> terms of theGraphks by Cheryl L Mallory167


168 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economics</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual choicesand actionsof market participants.It is<strong>in</strong> thissense that the model is consistent with the methodological <strong>in</strong>di-Vidualista so characterisficof <strong>Austrian</strong> theory.Before we beg<strong>in</strong> the actual construction of the model, a previewof some ofits prímarycharacteristicsmay be <strong>in</strong> order. Thepurpose of the preview is twofold. Firstly,it willsuggest that themodel is <strong>in</strong> factworth develop<strong>in</strong>g. Manyof the follow<strong>in</strong>g characteristicsate desirableones and gire the <strong>Austrian</strong> modelan edgeover the more orthodox models. Secondly, it should help thosereaders un<strong>in</strong>itiated <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomics to follow thedevelopment of the model more easily.1. The capital stock <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> theory is made up ofheterogeneous capital. The relationship between the variouspieces of capital can be one of substitutability or complementarity.The <strong>in</strong>dividual pieces of capital (both fixed and circulat<strong>in</strong>g)are <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong>to a "structure of production." (Although thenature of capital is obscured by simplify<strong>in</strong>g assumptions <strong>in</strong> thefirst section of this paper, it is taken <strong>in</strong>to account more fully <strong>in</strong>subsequent sections.)2. The size of the capital stock is treated asa variable <strong>in</strong> themodel. The usual assumption is that even though <strong>in</strong>vestment ofsome positive amount is realizedeach peñod, the stock of capitalrema<strong>in</strong>s constant. 4 With the <strong>Austrian</strong> model this assumpon isunnecessary. This has the important consequence of<strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>gmacroeconomic theory, growth theory, and bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyclethe0ry. Explanatiom of both growth and cyclicadactivity atebased on the same macroeconomic modeL$. The <strong>Austrian</strong> model is not a full-employment model <strong>in</strong> thesense that it ass,mes full employment. The analysis does beg<strong>in</strong>,however, with an economy that is fully employed: "[W]e have tostart where general economic theory stops; that is to say at acondition of equih'briumwhen no unused resources exist. Theexistence of unused resources is itself a fact which needs expianation."6The model does <strong>in</strong> fact expla<strong>in</strong> the almorm_11yhigh


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 169levels of unemployment that accompany the contraction phaseof the bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde.4. The <strong>Austrian</strong> model takes explicit account of the time element<strong>in</strong> the production process. It does not simply add "lags" asan afterthought to an otherwise timeless model. It accounts forthe fact that production takes time and that more productiontakes more time.5. <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomic theory is not a theory of real <strong>in</strong>comedeterm<strong>in</strong>ation. Ultimately, it is a theory of coord<strong>in</strong>atione---ofhowthe production process is co-ord<strong>in</strong>ated withthe tastes of <strong>in</strong>dividuals (their time and liquidity preferences),and how monetary disturbances affect this co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation. Becauseofits focus on the co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation problem, there is no sharpdist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomics and Austñanmicroeconomics.THE STRUCTUREOF PRODUCTIONOne of the most dist<strong>in</strong>ctive features of <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomictheory is its use of the concept of a "structure ofproduaion. "7 This concept was formulated to give explicit recognitionto the notion that capital (and the capital structure) hastwo dimensions. It has a value dimension which can be expressed<strong>in</strong> monetary temas, and it has a time dimension which is anexpression of the time that elapses between the application of the"oñg<strong>in</strong>al means of produaion "a(labor and land) and the eventualemergence of the consumption goods associated with them.The development of the notion of two-dimensional capital hasits roots, of course, <strong>in</strong> the writ<strong>in</strong>gs ofJevons, g It can be tracedfrom Jevons to Cassel lg and B6hm-Bawerk 1_ and then toMisa, ls and from Mises to Hayek, ls Rothbard, _4 and othercontemporary <strong>Austrian</strong> theorists. This view of capital, then, isneither new nor is ir strictly <strong>Austrian</strong>, yet the notion of two-


170 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>dimensional capital is by no means readily a¢cepted by capitaltheorists <strong>in</strong> general.A third though not <strong>in</strong>dependent dimension of capital can beenvisaged which represents a composite of the two dimensionsdescribed above. Aga<strong>in</strong>, Jevons was the first to synthesize thisthird dimension. He made the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the "quantityof capital" and the "length of me duñng which it rema<strong>in</strong>s<strong>in</strong>vested." He then devised the third dimension of capital by"...multiply<strong>in</strong>g each portion of capital <strong>in</strong>vested at any moment bythe length of time for whích it rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>vested. 'q6 The compound<strong>in</strong>gof<strong>in</strong>terest was ignored for the sake of simplicíty. Theresulng composite dimension was shown to have the units of"dollar-years." (The units are Americanized here. Jevons, ofcourse, used "pound-yearsY) _sCassel foUowed thirty years later with a similar formulation:"... <strong>in</strong>terest is paid <strong>in</strong> proportion to the capital lent and <strong>in</strong>proportion to the duration of the loan, i.e., <strong>in</strong> proportion to thepr0duct of value and time" (emphasis added). _7Cass;el'sproductand Jevons's composite dimension measure the _me th<strong>in</strong>g.They are <strong>in</strong>dic.ations of the extent to which capital is "tied-up" <strong>in</strong>the production process. No chito is made here that this productcan be calculated dírectly, but ff we can conceive of <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>come and of the rate of <strong>in</strong>terest_ then we can conceive of thiscomposite dimension of capital--the amount of "wait<strong>in</strong>g" orpostponement ofconsumption brought about by the payment of<strong>in</strong>terest.This compositedimermionwill be referred to as "aggregateproduction time"_sor simply as "production time." For sure,there ate problems<strong>in</strong> aggregat<strong>in</strong>g(evenconceptually)the productiontime associatedwith different piecesof capitaljustasthere ate problems with all macroec_nomic aggregates. Much_mbiguity will be avoided, however, by us<strong>in</strong>g the concept ofag_gat_ produoion time rather than amrage produaion timeor average peñod of produaion. These latter concepts were usedby both Jevom lp and B6hm-Bawerk, n but were rejected byMi,__,sI Hayek, n and Rothbard. n Many of the problems ofl_hm-Bawerk's capit_l theory had their roots <strong>in</strong> his use of the


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:Á Diagrammatical Exposition 171average period of production: Because the denom<strong>in</strong>ator of hisaverage was the value dimension of the structure of production(value reckoned <strong>in</strong> labor units), and because changes <strong>in</strong> thenumerator of his average are typically accompanied by changes<strong>in</strong> the denom<strong>in</strong>ator <strong>in</strong> the same direction, the direction ofchange <strong>in</strong> the average period of production is generally ambiguous.Further problems derive from B6hm-Bawerk's <strong>in</strong>cautiousgeneralizations about changes <strong>in</strong> the average peñod of productionthat were based on the analysis of ah oversimplified model.With a full awareness of the difficulties of work<strong>in</strong>g with aggregates<strong>in</strong> general and of work<strong>in</strong>g with aggregate production time<strong>in</strong> particular, the structure of production wiUbe def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> termsof the value of the capital at each stage <strong>in</strong> the producfion processand the aggregate production time associated with the process.The difficulties encountered by B6hm-Bawerk will be avoidedby rely<strong>in</strong>g on a somewhat less rigorous <strong>in</strong>terpretation of"changes <strong>in</strong> aggregate producfion ame," but discussion of this<strong>in</strong>terpretation will be deferred to a later section of the paper.The actual model<strong>in</strong>g can beg<strong>in</strong> with an exam<strong>in</strong>ation of earliertreatments of the structure of production.The first graphical representation of the structure of production<strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> literamre is found <strong>in</strong> Prices and Production <strong>in</strong>the forro of the famous Hayekian triangles. 24Such a triangle hasbeen reproduced <strong>in</strong> Figure 1. (The axes have been reversed forconvenience of exposition.).Hayek envisaged a vertically <strong>in</strong>tegratedproduction process <strong>in</strong> which the "... orig<strong>in</strong>al means ofproduction are expended cont<strong>in</strong>uously duñng the whole processof production."25 Aga<strong>in</strong>, "orig<strong>in</strong>al means" refers to thenon-produced (or non-reproducible) means of produaion, i.e.,to labor and land. (In our discussion we will associate the orig<strong>in</strong>almeans with "laborers" and the produced means with"capitalista." The terms laborers and capitalists, of colarse, areused <strong>in</strong> a functional sense and do not refer to particular <strong>in</strong>dividuah.)The produaion process beg<strong>in</strong>s at po<strong>in</strong>t T <strong>in</strong> Figure 1and proceeds leftward. At the conclusion of the process consumptiongoods with a dollar value ofOY emerge. At po<strong>in</strong>t T nocapital exists. At po<strong>in</strong>t D, one of the <strong>in</strong>termediate stages of


172 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>production, there exists capital with a dollar value ofDD'. Thiscapital can be viewed as simply the unf<strong>in</strong>ished consumpdongoods that will be valued at OY when the producon process iscomplete&#Y0 D _ tzt.e TFigure 1iInThe Hayekian triangle has two mutually re-enfordng <strong>in</strong>terpretations."On the one hand, it can depict the flow of capital<strong>in</strong> real time from its <strong>in</strong>cepon at po<strong>in</strong>t T through the numerousstages of produaion until it emerges as comumption goodsvalued at OF. This is the <strong>in</strong>terpretation adopted <strong>in</strong> the preced<strong>in</strong>gparagraph. On the other hand, ir the produaion proce, is <strong>in</strong>eq_ñlibrium, or to be more vivid, ffit is <strong>in</strong> the state referred to by


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics: ,4 DiagrammaticalExposition 173Mises as the "evenly rotat<strong>in</strong>g economy,''27then the triangle representsall of the various stages of production that co-exist ateach and every po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time. At any given po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time, for<strong>in</strong>stance, consumption goods OY wiUbe emerg<strong>in</strong>g from theproduction process, and at the same time the unf<strong>in</strong>ished goodsDD' wiUbe <strong>in</strong> existence dest<strong>in</strong>ed to emerge ata later date asconsumption goods.The dollar amount represented by DD' is less than that representedby OY for two reasons. Firstly, addifional quantities ofthe orig<strong>in</strong>al means (i.e., labor) are yet to be applied to the unf<strong>in</strong>ishedproduct that exists at po<strong>in</strong>t D. Secondly, OF and DD'represent consumption goods available at different po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong>time. If OF is available now, DD' willbe available for consumpfiononly at some future date. DD', then, is discounted withrespect to OF. To separate these two <strong>in</strong>fluences on the value ofDD' with respect to OF, the model wiUbe modified. Instead ofconceiv<strong>in</strong>g, as Hayek did, of a process <strong>in</strong> which the orig<strong>in</strong>almeans of production are applied cont<strong>in</strong>uously, wewillconceiveof a production process <strong>in</strong> which the orig<strong>in</strong>al means are appliedonly at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of the process. The Hayekian triangle isabandoned <strong>in</strong> favor of a trapezoid. In Figure 2, the productionprocess beg<strong>in</strong>s at po<strong>in</strong>t T with the application of labor serviceshav<strong>in</strong>g a dollar value ofTF. These orig<strong>in</strong>al means grow <strong>in</strong> valueas the), pass through the numerous stages of production, f<strong>in</strong>allyemerg<strong>in</strong>g as consumption goods valued at OY doUars.A second modification has been made <strong>in</strong> Figure 2. The horizontalaxis now represents the aggregate production time (APT)associated with the structure of production. This allows therelaxation of the assumption that the structure is characterizedby complete vertical <strong>in</strong>tegration. The slope of l<strong>in</strong>e b3", then,represents the rate of <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> value per urt of time per dollar<strong>in</strong>vested at po<strong>in</strong>t T. That is, the slope of l<strong>in</strong>e FY is the (simple)rate of <strong>in</strong>terest (profit) when the economy is <strong>in</strong> equilibrium.Of course, this is a highly stylized representation of the actualstructure of production. The development of the <strong>Austrian</strong>model, however, willbe accompanied by discussionsof the actualprocesses that take place <strong>in</strong> the real-world structure of produc-


174 Neto <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>tion. These discussions will recognize that capital and laborservices are applied <strong>in</strong> each of the stages of production. Changes<strong>in</strong> the structure, for <strong>in</strong>stance, will be couched <strong>in</strong> terms of laborYFO............ APTTFigure 2and capital be<strong>in</strong>g moved out of the stages relaÚvely dose to thef<strong>in</strong>al (consumption) stage and <strong>in</strong>to stages relatively remote fromthe consumpon stage (or v/ce versa) <strong>in</strong> response to (<strong>in</strong>tertemporal)pñce changes and profit opporturdes. This correspondsto a lengthen<strong>in</strong>g (or shorten<strong>in</strong>g) of the structure. Changes <strong>in</strong> theshape of the stylized representation of the structure of productionw_dlbe an <strong>in</strong>dication of the nature of the changes <strong>in</strong> thereal-world structure.


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:_ Diagrammatical Exposition 175INTERTEMPORALEXCHANGEIntertemporal exchange is the exchange of present consumptiongoods for future consumption goods and v/ce versa. Thistype of market transaction is generally <strong>in</strong>troduced by first allow<strong>in</strong>gfor pure consumption loans only. Investment loans arebrought <strong>in</strong>to view only after consumption loans have establishedsome <strong>in</strong>itial terms of trade <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tertemporal market. The<strong>Austrian</strong> model, though, will account for <strong>in</strong>tertemporal exchangeby <strong>in</strong>itially abstract<strong>in</strong>g from the pure consumption loan.This will allow us to focus on the type of <strong>in</strong>tertemporal exchangethat is <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> the production process. The <strong>in</strong>tertemporalmarket, then, can be thought of as deal<strong>in</strong>g with direct purchasesof <strong>in</strong>vest_ment goods as well aswith loans made for the purpose ofpurchas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>vestment goods.In the context of the present model <strong>in</strong>tertemporal exchan'gecan be accounted for <strong>in</strong> terms of the orig<strong>in</strong>al means of production,i.e., <strong>in</strong> terms of the market for labor services. The laborservices represent future consumption goods, which is to say thatthey can be converted <strong>in</strong>to consumpon goods only by allow<strong>in</strong>gthem to pass through the time-consum<strong>in</strong>g production process.Laborers sell their services (future consumption goods) receiv<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> exchange dollars that can be used to purchase presenflyexist<strong>in</strong>g consumpon goods. The sale of labor services, then,consmtes the demand for present goods (and the supply offuture goods). Look<strong>in</strong>g at the other side of the market for<strong>in</strong>tertemporal exchange, the labor services are purchased by thecapitalists. The capitalists exchange dollars for labor servicesand, ipsofacto, register a demand for future goods. At the sametime they constitute the supply of present goods. (Of coune, thisis an "excess" supply: At the end of the production process thecapitalists own OY of consumption goods. They consume OY-TF and supply the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g TF to the laborers.)The supply and demand for present goods are representeddiagrammacally <strong>in</strong> Figure 3. This market for <strong>in</strong>tertemporalexchange is equilibrated by adjustments <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tertemporalpñce ratio-4he rate of <strong>in</strong>terest. The particular shape and posi-


176 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> .dustrian <strong>Economics</strong>tion<strong>in</strong>g of these curves is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the <strong>in</strong>dividuals' (laborels'and capitalists') relative evaluations of presentas opposed tofumre goods, i.e., by their time preferences. The technical aspectsof transform<strong>in</strong>g the labor services <strong>in</strong>to consumption goods, asmight be represented by a technical transformation function,ate kept <strong>in</strong> the background here. The Austñan model focusesnot on the technical considerations per se but rather on thealternafive comb<strong>in</strong>afions of present and future goods that <strong>in</strong>di-||||O|AFigure 3viduals perceive to be possible. Of course, when the economy is<strong>in</strong> equilibrium (the Misesianevenly rotat<strong>in</strong>geconomy),<strong>in</strong>dividuals/mozowhat alternatives arepossiblesothatthetransformationsthat are perceived to be possible and the actual trans-


,4ustrian Macroeconomics:,4 Diagrammatical Exposition 177formations are one and the same. When the economy is out ofequilibrium, however, <strong>in</strong>dividuals will act on the basis of whatthey perceive the possibilities to be and not on the basis of whatthe possibilities actually ate <strong>in</strong> some technological sense. This(fundamentally <strong>Austrian</strong>) dist<strong>in</strong>ction is an important one andwill come hato play <strong>in</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g the work<strong>in</strong>gs of the Austñanmodel under disequilibrium conditions.Rothbard makes use of a diagram essentially identical to theone <strong>in</strong> Figure 3.28 He po<strong>in</strong>ts out that the <strong>in</strong>tersection of the twocurves determ<strong>in</strong>es the equilibrium tate of <strong>in</strong>terest and theequilibrium amount of (gross) sav<strong>in</strong>gs. (Net sav<strong>in</strong>gs are zero.)Given the stylized structure of production of the present model,these (gross) sav<strong>in</strong>gs manifest themselves as payments for laborservices. When the economy is <strong>in</strong> equilibñum, the tate of <strong>in</strong>terestis given by OB; the total payment for labor services by OA.OTFigure 4q_q íIt should be noted at this po<strong>in</strong>t that OA <strong>in</strong> Figure 3 measuresthe same payment that is measured by TF <strong>in</strong> Figure 2. In recognitionof this connection between the market for <strong>in</strong>tertemporalex¢hange and the structure of production, Figure 3 can be• mverted, rotated, and juxtaposed with Figure 2 to yield thesummary diagram shown <strong>in</strong> Figure 4. There ís a second connec-


178 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong>/lustrian <strong>Economics</strong>tion between the two panels of Figure 4. The rate of <strong>in</strong>terest isrepresented by OB <strong>in</strong> the ñght-hand panel and by the slope ofthe l<strong>in</strong>e FY <strong>in</strong> the left-hand panel. In equilibrium, of course,these two representations must reflect the same tate of<strong>in</strong>terest.It may be helpful at this po<strong>in</strong>t to show the relationship betweenthis simple <strong>Austrian</strong> model and the correspond<strong>in</strong>g Keynesianmodel. The po<strong>in</strong>t of commonality is the maguitude OY whichrepresents the equílibñum dollar value of consumption goods.In the simple Keynesian model po<strong>in</strong>t Y is the íntersection of theconsumption function and the 45°reference l<strong>in</strong>e. OY is thedistance from that <strong>in</strong>tersection to the horizontal (or vertical) axis.Figure 5 shows the two models drawn on vertical planes perpendicularto one another and <strong>in</strong>tersect<strong>in</strong>g along OF. O"his compañsonmay do some violence to the Keynesían model <strong>in</strong> that aUmagnitudes are expressed <strong>in</strong> doUar terms rather than realtemas.)r,cl Ị_71__"__.......- ._1,,,,- ..c_¢vI¢E_'/VE'sIAN MODff LFigure 5


lgstrian Macroeconomics:d Diagrammatical Exposition 179INVESTMENTIn order to deal with (net) <strong>in</strong>vestment an addionalrelationshipmust be <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong>to the model, namely the relationshipbetween the quanty of capital (dollar value) <strong>in</strong> the structure ofproducon and the production time associated with ir. ("Quantityof capital" here refers to a/l the capital <strong>in</strong> the structure ofproduction. In Figure 2 it referred to the quanty that exists ateach stage of the structure of production.) Although these twodimensions of the structure of production (quanty of capitaland production time) are def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>dependently ofone another,there is, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Austñan theory, a relationship betweenthem. Aga<strong>in</strong>, this relatiomhip has its genesis <strong>in</strong> the wrif<strong>in</strong>gs ofJevons: "Capital simply allows us to expend labor <strong>in</strong> advance. ''z°More capital, Jevons went on to show, allows us to expend laborfurther Unadvance, s°The positive relationship between capital and production timehas suffered several set-backs dur<strong>in</strong>g its development. B6hm-Bawerk, for <strong>in</strong>stance, couched it <strong>in</strong> terms of the "average periodof production," <strong>in</strong>advertently caus<strong>in</strong>g the formulation to be ambiguous.But Mises and the contemporary Aus'tñan theofists(e.g., Hayek and Rothbard) fully recognize the errors <strong>in</strong> B6hm-Bawerk's formulation, s_ The), stiU accept, however, the basicnotion that there is a positive relatiomhip between the quantityof capital and the production time associated with it. Mises, for<strong>in</strong>stance, argues that".., every <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the supply of capitalgoods available results <strong>in</strong> a lengthen<strong>in</strong>g of the period of production,and of wait<strong>in</strong>gtime,..." and conversely that "... [ala<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quantity of capital goods available is a necessarycondition for the adoption of processes <strong>in</strong> which the peñod ofproduction and therefore wait<strong>in</strong>g time are longer. "3s Similarstatements can be found <strong>in</strong> Rothbard's formulation: "Any <strong>in</strong>crease<strong>in</strong> capital goods can serve only to lengthen the structure,i.e., to enable the adopon of longer.., processes. "34Hayek po<strong>in</strong>ts out the difficules of talk<strong>in</strong>g about "changes <strong>in</strong>the period of produaion" when the term refers to the actual


180 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>aggregation of <strong>in</strong>vestment periods. He goes on, though, to saythat.., s<strong>in</strong>cetheuseoftheexpression"changes<strong>in</strong>thelengthof theprocess"is a convenientway of describ<strong>in</strong>gthe type of changes<strong>in</strong> the wholeprocesswhere the changes <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>vestmentperíodsare predom<strong>in</strong>antly<strong>in</strong> one direction,there is probablysometh<strong>in</strong>g to be said forreta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>git, providedthat it is usedcautiously.... ssWith this somewhat less rigorous view "changes <strong>in</strong> productiontime" is more of a "shorthand" for the type of changes be<strong>in</strong>gmade to the structure of production than a change <strong>in</strong> a genu<strong>in</strong>eaggregate.The relationship between the quantity of capital and productiontime has been caUed <strong>in</strong>to question <strong>in</strong> recent years by theso-called "double-switch<strong>in</strong>g and capital-revers<strong>in</strong>g debates."s'The possibilityof capital revers<strong>in</strong>g (vhich <strong>in</strong>volves an apparentviolation of the Austrían relationship) has been the source ofmuch controversy <strong>in</strong> Cambridge capital theory. Although thereis good reason to believe that the problems created by doubleswitch<strong>in</strong>g and capital reversíng are conf<strong>in</strong>ed to the Cambñdgeparadigm itself, the Austñan model wl eventually have to bedefended aga<strong>in</strong>st the Cambridge charges. But this task willnotbe undertaken here. Rather, our concern with the problem willend with the observation that even those who th<strong>in</strong>k that capitalrevers<strong>in</strong>g is possible consider it extremely unlikely: "[Capitalrevers<strong>in</strong>g] could happen, but it looks like be<strong>in</strong>g on the edge ofth<strong>in</strong>gs that could happen. "sT(I)The positive relationship between the quantity of capital (d'ollarvídue) and production time is<strong>in</strong>troduced diagrammatically<strong>in</strong>the upper panel of Figure 6. The "wavy" shape of the curve issimpl_ a way of<strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that no cl_imsare made about the rateof change <strong>in</strong> the slope of the curve. The only figuificant featureof the curve is that its slope is positive. That the curve shouldbeg<strong>in</strong> at the oñg<strong>in</strong> seems obviom enough: There can be noproduaion time if there is no capital. The orig<strong>in</strong>, then, mayrepresent the hand-to-mouth existence of a Rob<strong>in</strong>son Crusoe,


<strong>Austrian</strong> Mazroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 181K.l"K ............................ .Ko/AAPTOINE-APTY K°i Z_APTOTFigure 6_T


182 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> .4ustrian<strong>Economics</strong>but for purposes of develop<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>Austrian</strong> model, this is atrivial aspect of the diagram.The "<strong>in</strong>itial" produaion time is OT as <strong>in</strong>dicated <strong>in</strong> the lowerpanel of Figure 6. This panel, of course, is the now-famil_arstructure of production. (The word "<strong>in</strong>itiar' is used here <strong>in</strong> anarbitrary sense: It does not refer to the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t of theproduction process but rather to the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t of ouranalysis.) The <strong>in</strong>iti_! dollar value of capital correspond<strong>in</strong>g toproduction time OT is represented by OK <strong>in</strong> the upper panel.Ir the orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the upper panel is shifted from O to Ko, thenthe portion of the curve extend<strong>in</strong>g northeastward from Ko willrepresent the relationship between/nv_tment and changes <strong>in</strong>production time. This is the relevant portion of the curve. Thetei:a_"<strong>in</strong>vestment" <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> model is def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a slighflyunorthodox manner. It is not the tate of <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quantityof capital, but rather the addition of a quantity of capital measuredwith respect to the <strong>in</strong>itial quantity Ko. It is measured <strong>in</strong>dollars rather than dollars per year.At this stage <strong>in</strong> the constructíon of the model, <strong>in</strong>vestment cancome about only at the expense of consumption. (Investmentmade possible by the creation of new credit willbe dealt with <strong>in</strong>the follow<strong>in</strong>g section.) The relationship between <strong>in</strong>vestment andconsumption can be shown by<strong>in</strong>vert<strong>in</strong>g the northeast portion ofthe upper panel and lower<strong>in</strong>g it until the horizontal axis isaligned with po<strong>in</strong>t Y of the struaure of production. Ifan <strong>in</strong>vestmentofK,/is made, for <strong>in</strong>stance, it is made at the expense ofconsumption lq'_. In view of the faa that <strong>in</strong>vestment is to be ahendogenous variable<strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> model, it is probably preferableto state the relationship <strong>in</strong> another way. If a change <strong>in</strong> ahexogenous variable br<strong>in</strong>gs about an <strong>in</strong>vestment of Ko/, it, ipsofacto, br<strong>in</strong>gs about a decrease <strong>in</strong> consumption of Irg,.The diagrammatics developed to this po<strong>in</strong>t ate shown <strong>in</strong> Figure7. This model allows us to determ<strong>in</strong>e the changes <strong>in</strong> thestructure of production that are brought about by shifts <strong>in</strong> thesupply and demand curves of the <strong>in</strong>tertemporal market. Theseshifts can be thought of as result<strong>in</strong>g from changes <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuaAs'relative evaluation of pre'_nt as opposed to future goods, i.e.,


.4ustrian Macroeconomics:.4 Diagrarnmatical Exposition 183_¿g: , . i./"i _i I; I| oIsi i 'i ii• 7-


184 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> Austñan <strong>Economics</strong>changes <strong>in</strong> their time preferences. A decrease <strong>in</strong> the time pret_rencesof laborers, for example, can be represented by a shift <strong>in</strong>the demand for present goods from DpgtoD'pg, which <strong>in</strong>tersectsthe orig<strong>in</strong>al supply-of-present-goods curve at coord<strong>in</strong>ates 0,4'and OB '. (To this po<strong>in</strong>t the magnitude 0,4 has been taken torepresent both the amount paid for labor services and the dorarvalue of present goods consumed by laborers. For this equality tohold requires the tacit assumption that laborers are neither<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g nor decreas<strong>in</strong>g their cash hold<strong>in</strong>gs. However, ff thedemand for present goods shifts without causíng a correspond<strong>in</strong>gshift <strong>in</strong> the supply of present goods (demand for futuregoods), then there must be a change <strong>in</strong> the cash hold<strong>in</strong>gs oflaborers (from Walras's Law). That is, a shift <strong>in</strong> just one of thetwo curves, Dpg and Spg, must correspond to a change <strong>in</strong> bothtime and liquidity preferences. OA, then, represents the dollarvalue ofpresent goods consumed by laborer: which equals theamount paid to laborers m<strong>in</strong>us the change <strong>in</strong> their cash hold<strong>in</strong>gs.(For our immediate purposes, though, this change <strong>in</strong> cash hold<strong>in</strong>gswiU be kept <strong>in</strong> the background.)The diagrammatic representation of the structure of produconis uniquely determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the shift <strong>in</strong> the demand forpresent goods. The amount of present goods advanced to laborersis now T_F'(=OA _),and the new equilibrium rate of<strong>in</strong>terest isOB_(


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 185creates profit opportunities that cause the capitalists to bid capitaland labor services away from the stages of production relativelyclose to the f<strong>in</strong>al (consumption) stage and <strong>in</strong>to stagesrelavely remote from the consumption stage. They are also<strong>in</strong>duced by the lower<strong>in</strong>g of the <strong>in</strong>terest rate to create additionalstages that had previously been unprofitable. 38Although the dollar expenditure on consumption goods decreasesfrom OY to OY', consumption <strong>in</strong> real terms decreasesonly temporarily and then rises to a new high once the additional<strong>in</strong>vestment comes to fruition. It is this additional quantity ofconsumption goods com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the market, of course, thatallows the prices of consumption goods to be bid down to a levelconsistent with OY'.The above description of changes <strong>in</strong> the structure of produconbrought about by a decrease <strong>in</strong> time preferences is verysimilar to the discussion found <strong>in</strong> Prices and Production of thechange <strong>in</strong> the shape of a Hayel6an triangle brought about byvoluntary sav<strong>in</strong>gs:If wecomparethetwodiagrams[represent<strong>in</strong>g the structureof productionbefore and after the change <strong>in</strong> voluntary sav<strong>in</strong>gs]we see at oncethat the nature of the change consists<strong>in</strong> a stretch<strong>in</strong>g [of the structure].... Its[height at the f<strong>in</strong>alstage], whichmeasure,sthe amountof moneyspent dur<strong>in</strong>g the period of timeon consumers goods.... has permanentlydecreased.... This meansthat the priceof a unitof consumen'goods, the output of whichhas<strong>in</strong>creasedasa consequenceof themorecapitalistícmethods of production,will fall.... The amount of moneyspent <strong>in</strong> each of the laterstagesof productionhasalsodecreased,whilethe amount used <strong>in</strong> the earlierstageshas<strong>in</strong>creased,and the totalspenton <strong>in</strong>termediate productshas <strong>in</strong>creasedalso becauseof the additionot•.. new stage[s] of production,sgAlthough the price level and the real level of consumption areaccounted for <strong>in</strong> the discussion of the work<strong>in</strong>gs of the <strong>Austrian</strong>model, they do not appear <strong>in</strong> the diagrammatical representation<strong>in</strong> any explicit form. <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomics has never beenconcerned direcdy with the general price level, but has beenconcerned <strong>in</strong>stead with the rdative price of consumpfion goodsas opposed to <strong>in</strong>vestment goods---or, <strong>in</strong> terms of the present


186 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>model, the relative amounts paid for consumption goods as opposedto labor services. This is a fundamental aspectof <strong>Austrian</strong>theory that sets it apart from the more orthodox macroeconomictheory. Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, for <strong>in</strong>stance, lumps "consumer commodities"and "<strong>in</strong>vestment commodities" <strong>in</strong>to a s<strong>in</strong>gle aggregate and thentells us that"... [t]he pñces of these two categories ate assumedto change <strong>in</strong> the same proportion. "_° By disallow<strong>in</strong>g relativeprice changes between these two categories of commodities,Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong> puts the structure of production <strong>in</strong> a straightjacket.This throws the entire burden of mov<strong>in</strong>g the economy from oneequilibrium position to another on the real cash balance effect? aA shift <strong>in</strong> the supply of present goods from S_ toSpg" could bethe result oía decrease <strong>in</strong> the time preferences ofcapitalists. Theeffects of this shift on the structure of production can beanalyzed <strong>in</strong> the same manner and with similar results. The newequílibrium (associated with Dpg° and Sp_') is shown withdouble-prime notation. The only _ignificant difference is thatthe amount of present goods consumed by laborers has <strong>in</strong>creasedwhen before it decreased. But this difference was to beexpected: A decrease <strong>in</strong> the time preferences of/aborers meansthat they are will<strong>in</strong>g to consume fewo" present goods now <strong>in</strong>order to enjoy greater (real) consumption later; a decrease <strong>in</strong> thetime preferences of cap/ta//sts means that they are will<strong>in</strong>g toadvance more present goods to laborers now <strong>in</strong> order to erijo),more (real) consumptíon later.A change <strong>in</strong> time preferences is not the ordy change <strong>in</strong> tastesthat can cause a shift <strong>in</strong> the supply and demand for presentgoods, although it seems to be the one that the <strong>Austrian</strong> theoristsare most concerned with. But shifts of the curves can also resultfrom changes <strong>in</strong> the demand for money, e.g., from <strong>in</strong>creases ordecreases <strong>in</strong> liquidity preferences. (Hayek was aware <strong>in</strong> his earlywrit<strong>in</strong>gs of the need to <strong>in</strong>corporate the analysis of liquiditypreferences <strong>in</strong>to <strong>Austrian</strong> macroeconomic theory.) ° To accommodatethe analysis of liquidity preferences the structureof-producUondiagram must be <strong>in</strong>terpreted so as to <strong>in</strong>clude cashbalances. In other words, OY must <strong>in</strong>dude the quantity of cashbalances "consumed." Where a change <strong>in</strong> tLrae preferences


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconoraics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 187(laborers' and capitalists') will cause both curves of the <strong>in</strong>tertemporalmarket to shift either east or west, a change <strong>in</strong> liquiditypreferences (laborers' and capitalists') will cause both curves toshift either north or south. A neutral change <strong>in</strong> liquidity preferentewould be one <strong>in</strong> which both curves shiftedjn such a way asto leave the rate of <strong>in</strong>terest unchanged. The effects of a change<strong>in</strong> liquidity preferences can be analyzed <strong>in</strong> temas of the <strong>Austrian</strong>model of Figure 7, but the details will not be described here. Itcan be said, however, that the results of such ah analysis, whetherthe change <strong>in</strong> liquidity preferences is neutral or non-neutral,confront us with no surprises.cKo_.....,_P 'P_'R_FN_S IAN MODELFigure 8In conclud<strong>in</strong>g this section it ma), be helpful to follow up on thecomparison of the <strong>Austrian</strong> model and the correspond<strong>in</strong>gKeynesian model. The two models are shown <strong>in</strong> Figure 8 <strong>in</strong> thesame formar aswas used <strong>in</strong> Figure 5. There are now two po<strong>in</strong>ts ofcommonalit 7. In addidon to the common dollar value of consumpfiongoods, the amount of (exogenous) <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> theKeynesian model corresponds <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> model to the


188 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong>/lustrian Econoraicsamount of (endogenous) <strong>in</strong>vestment brought about by a shift <strong>in</strong>the demand for present goods. Aga<strong>in</strong>, the problems created byexpress<strong>in</strong>g the Keynesian model <strong>in</strong> dollar temas rather than realterms ate overlooked.MONETARYDISTURBANCE$To this po<strong>in</strong>t it has been implicitly assumed that the economyis free from monemry disturbances. Clmnges <strong>in</strong> the endogenousvariables were brought about only by actual changes <strong>in</strong> thepreferences of laborers and capitalists, by shifts <strong>in</strong> the supplyand demand for present goods reflect<strong>in</strong>g changes <strong>in</strong> time (orliquidity) preferences. In this section the supply ofmoney will be<strong>in</strong>troduced as an exogenous variable <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> model, andits effects on the <strong>in</strong>tertemporal market and the structure ofproduction will be analyzed. To fácilitate this analysis the actualtime and liquidity preferences will be assumed to rema<strong>in</strong> unchanged.The supply and demand for present goods as represented<strong>in</strong> Figure 3 will be fixed <strong>in</strong> place throughout the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gdiscussion.In analyz<strong>in</strong>g the effects of monetary dismrbances <strong>Austrian</strong>macroeconomics is not concerned with <strong>in</strong>creases <strong>in</strong> the quantityof money per se, but rather with the process by which the newmoney enters the economy. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Hayek: "[E]veryth<strong>in</strong>gdepends on the po<strong>in</strong>t where the additional money is <strong>in</strong>jected <strong>in</strong>toárculation. ''4sThus, when Hayek beg<strong>in</strong>s his <strong>in</strong>vestigation of the"... effects of a change <strong>in</strong> the amount of money <strong>in</strong> circulation...", he immediately turns bis attention to the" ... case mostfrequently encountered <strong>in</strong> practice: the case of ah <strong>in</strong>crease ofmoney <strong>in</strong> the form of credits granted to producers. "44 Theprimary effect of a monetary expansion <strong>in</strong> the Austñan viewstems from the fact that newly created money (credit) tends tofall disproporÜonately <strong>in</strong>to the hands of producers.By way of contrast the analysis of a monetary expansion <strong>in</strong>orthodox macroeconomics is generally begun by assum<strong>in</strong>g thatthe new money is <strong>in</strong>jected uniformly throughout the economy. A


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A 1)iagrammaticalExposition 189familiar assumption, for <strong>in</strong>stance, is that a helicopter dispensesthe newly created money and that <strong>in</strong>dividuals dash out <strong>in</strong>to thestreets gather<strong>in</strong>g up the new money <strong>in</strong> direct proporUon to theamount the}' already had. 45 In this sort of highly artificialscenatio it can easily be shown that money is neutral. No realmagnimdes ate changedmapart from a temporary <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong>cash hold<strong>in</strong>gs that causes all prices to be bid up. The only consequenceof an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the monetary stock, then, is ah equiproportional<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the general pñce level. Consequencesof a nonuniform <strong>in</strong>jection of newly created money, that is, of thefact that some <strong>in</strong>dividuals receive a greater share of the newmoney than others, ate categorized as "distribution effects."These effects ate considered to be of second-order (ornth order)importance and ate generally assumed away <strong>in</strong> order to get atthe "more fundamental" aspects of an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the stock ofmoney.4eBut money <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Austrian</strong> view should not be assumed to beneutral and cannot be shown to be neutral <strong>in</strong> any relevant sense."The notion of neutral money," accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises, is a contradicUon<strong>in</strong> terms: "Money without a driv<strong>in</strong>g force of its ownwould not, as People assume, be a perfect money; it would not bemoney al_all.''7 The relevant question, then, is not whether amonetary expansion is neutral of non-neutral, but rather howthe non-neutrah'ty manifests itself <strong>in</strong> a market economy. The<strong>Austrian</strong> theorists have focused their attention on this questionand have been critical of other monetary theorists for ignor<strong>in</strong>g it.Ha),ek, for imtance, criticized them for focus<strong>in</strong>g" ... eitherexdusively of predom<strong>in</strong>anfly [on] the superficial phenomenonof changes <strong>in</strong> the value of money, while fail<strong>in</strong>g to pursue the farmore profound and fundamental effects of the process bywhichmoney is <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong>to the economic system, as dist<strong>in</strong>ct fromits effects on pñces <strong>in</strong> general. "4sA "neutral" monetary expansion is represented diagrammatically<strong>in</strong> Figure 9. The vertical axis represents the nom<strong>in</strong>al magnitudeof the orig<strong>in</strong>al stock of money (Mo), i.e., the stock <strong>in</strong>existence prior to the monetary expansion. The horizontal axisrepresents the nomirml magnitude of the expanded stock of


190 <strong>New</strong> Direaiom <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>money (M_), i.e., the stock <strong>in</strong> existence after the expansion hasoccurred. The 45 °líne, represent<strong>in</strong>g the equalityM0 -Me, servesas a reference. A neutral expansíon can be shown, then, byrotang a l<strong>in</strong>e clockwise from the reference l<strong>in</strong>e.But if the expansion is achieved by extend<strong>in</strong>g newly createdcredit to producers, ir is not a neutral expansion. In the term<strong>in</strong>ologyof the present model the newly created money f_llsdisproporUonately ínto the hands o£ capitalists (as opposed tolaborers). This can be represented diagrammaticaUy by show<strong>in</strong>gseparately the <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quanty of money <strong>in</strong> the hands ofcapitalists and the <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the quantity of money <strong>in</strong> the handsof laborers. In Figure 10 it is assumed for the sake of simplicitythat a//of the newly created money takes the form of creditextended to capitalists. Initi_lly, then, the laborers are completelyunaffected by the monetary expansion. This is representedín Figure 10 by M_r, which is co<strong>in</strong>cident with the 45 °reference líne. Capitalists, on the other hand, experience an<strong>in</strong>ifially amplífied monetary expansion as <strong>in</strong>dicated by M)_. ButMoMoFigure 9 Figure 10as the capitalists purchase addiÜonal quanties of labor services,the new money fdters through the economy such that eventmdlythe expansion experienced by the laborers ís approximately thesame as the expansion experienced by the capitalists. This is<strong>in</strong>dicated by the expansion l<strong>in</strong>eM)_ _ M=L. The arrows <strong>in</strong>dicatethe dynamics of the expansionas irappears to the capit_lkts andto the laborer_This non-neutral monetary expamion manifests itself asa


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:_ Diagrammatical Exposition 191temporary distortion <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tertemporal market. In terms ofthe <strong>Austrian</strong> model the expansion experienced by the capitalistsaffects the supplyoof-present-goods curve, while the expansionexperienced by the laborers affects the demand-for-presentgoodscurve. These two asymmetrical effects can be traced out bythe apparams of Figure 11. The upper panels represent thet_c"Mo , _o,I L_'__/ "-_l'"l___ ..............-!-:....;......................I _J'_L__. .: 7o i i!'_'oo. i! _: tI_2..........f' , S ......._o;. ...... í.....o # o ¿Figure 11monetaryexpansionofFigure]0 andthe<strong>in</strong>tertemporal marketof Figure $. The southeast panel is a dummy diagram thatfacilitates the construcfion of the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g panel. The southwestpanel, then, shows the effect of the monetary expansion onthe supply and demand for present goods. The supply curve,reflect<strong>in</strong>g the behavior of capitalists, <strong>in</strong>itially rotates clockwisefrom$ to $%while the demand curve, reflect<strong>in</strong>g the behavior oflaborers, <strong>in</strong>itially rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> place (D = D'). EventuaUy, though,as the new money becomes more evenly distributed, the supply


192 <strong>New</strong> Dírections <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>curve retracts to S" and the demandcurve rotates out to D".These f<strong>in</strong>al positions of the two curves correspond to the expansionl<strong>in</strong>e labeled M ", _ M"L <strong>in</strong> the northwest panel.Figure 11 illustrates that the rate of<strong>in</strong>terest associated with the"real" parameters rema<strong>in</strong>s unchanged, i.e., that the supply anddemand curves <strong>in</strong> the northeast panel rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> place throughoutthe monetary expansion, while the apparent rate of<strong>in</strong>terestnthe rate determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the southwest p_ne! does not.The <strong>in</strong>jection of newly created money causes the apparent rateof <strong>in</strong>terest to fall from i to ir and then to rise back to a levelapproximat<strong>in</strong>g the orig<strong>in</strong>al rate (i" _ i). This effect oran expansionon the rate of<strong>in</strong>terest is, ofcourse, neither new nor uniquely<strong>Austrian</strong>. The notion that a monetary expausion causes theínterest rate <strong>in</strong> the loan market to fall temporarily below the"natural" rate is commonly associated with the wr<strong>in</strong>gs ofWicksell. 4g(It might be added here that the <strong>Austrian</strong> model doesnot deny the existence of the Fisher effect. Ah anticipated <strong>in</strong>crease<strong>in</strong> the price level would cause a price premium to be built<strong>in</strong>to the nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>terest rate. But the present model abstractafrom this price premium justas it abstracts from the pfice levelitself. It focuses <strong>in</strong>stead on relative prices. That the Físher effectcould completelyoffset the other movements <strong>in</strong> the tate of<strong>in</strong>terestwould, of course, llave to be denied.)The <strong>in</strong>tertemporal market, together with the monetary expansionmechanísm, can now be reunited with the rest of the<strong>Austrian</strong> modelas shown <strong>in</strong> Figure 12. AIIpanels are numberedto facilitate the discussion. The only new one is panel VI whichsimply shows the monetary expansion <strong>in</strong>dependent of the processby which the newly created money is <strong>in</strong>jected hato theeconomy. This allows us to express the changes that occur <strong>in</strong>panels II and III <strong>in</strong> temas consistent with the orig<strong>in</strong>al monetarystock, that is, it allows us to focus on relative rather than absolutechanges.The monetary expansion shown <strong>in</strong> F'_,ure 12 is a neutralone---at least neutral with respect to capi_"_ts and laborers--as<strong>in</strong>dicated by the s<strong>in</strong>gle expansion l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> panel IV. As might beexpected this neutral expamion has no effect on the structure of


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 193!io'O. Q./_,,__


194 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>production (panel II). Such an "expansion" could be achieved byrenam<strong>in</strong>g the monetary unit: From this day on "one Dollar" willbe known as "ten Burlas." No real changes would result. The onlyconsequence would be the fundamentally un<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g one (noteven shown <strong>in</strong> Figure 12) that the price level would <strong>in</strong>creasetenfold. The expansion could be achieved <strong>in</strong>stead by us<strong>in</strong>g thenotoñous monetary helicopter. There seems to be no reason tobelieve that the capitalists would gather upa disproportionateshare of the new money. And so, as before, the primary consequencewould be an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the price level reflect<strong>in</strong>g theextent of the monetary expansion. Two differences, however, imake this expansiona little less sterile than the previous one. !IFirstly, the price level <strong>in</strong>creases notas a matter of def<strong>in</strong>ition butas the result of a market process. Prices are bid up to the new ilevel as <strong>in</strong>dividuals attempt to draw down their newly acquired icash hold<strong>in</strong>gs3 ° Secondly, distribution effects among capitalists iand among laborers are not ruled out. Thus, the consumption 1goods are valued at OF both before and after the expansion, butthey are likely to be different consumption goods and to be !consumed by different <strong>in</strong>dividuals asa result of these distributioneffects. That this is the only change <strong>in</strong> panel II rests on theheroic assumption that the real-world structure of production is<strong>in</strong> fact suitable for produdng these different consumptiongoods.Ir the <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the stock of money is achieved by the expansionof credit, there will be a systematic distribution effect thatcan be accounted for <strong>in</strong> the Austrían model. The expansion willbe experienced first by the capitalists and only later by thelaborers. This is illustrated <strong>in</strong> Figure 13. Unlike the monetaryexpansion of Figure 12, credit expansion has real effects on thestructure of production. Diagramma_I_ly, this is shown by theprime and double-prime notation <strong>in</strong> panel II. As the apparentrate of<strong>in</strong>terest falls from i to i', the capitalists beg<strong>in</strong> constructionof a structure of production that is to llave the configuraÜonOIOF'T'. But as the newly created money becomes more evenlydistributed among capitalists and laborers, the rate of <strong>in</strong>terestrises toi" (_). The beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs of the longer structure are then


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Dia_rammatical Exposition 195ii.............. °.......... . ........ ] ........................_'- 3.. _II


196 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>liquidated or abandoned <strong>in</strong> favor of the configuration OY"F"T"whichapproximates the orig<strong>in</strong>alstructure.The <strong>in</strong>vestment (andsubsequent dis-<strong>in</strong>vestment) represented <strong>in</strong> panel III by Ko/' isnot the result ofvoluntary sav<strong>in</strong>g(and voluntarydissav<strong>in</strong>g)but is ithe result of the monetary disturbance. This is what Mises itermed mañnvestment51 and what Hayek called forced sav<strong>in</strong>gs.5_The changes <strong>in</strong> the real-worldstructureof production can be ,described <strong>in</strong> temasof the relative profitabilityof short-term andlong-term projects. The economy is assumed to be <strong>in</strong> equilib- _.rium priorto the monetary expansion sothat allprojects (shorttermand long-term) are equally profitableat the marg<strong>in</strong>. Whenthe <strong>in</strong>terest rate falls, due to the expansion of credit, the long- Lterna projects, which by def<strong>in</strong>ifion <strong>in</strong>volve disproportionatelyhigh <strong>in</strong>terest expenditures, appear to become more profitable.Thus, the capitalists <strong>in</strong> their entrepreneurial roles bid labor andnon-specific capital away from the later stages ofproduction _nd<strong>in</strong>to the earlier stages and beg<strong>in</strong> construction of whateverspecific capital is needed to take advantage of the (apparent)profitability of these long-term projects. But <strong>in</strong> the very processof construct<strong>in</strong>g the new structure of production the newlycreated money flows from the capitalists to the laborers, and thedistribution of money comes to approximate the old, preexpansion,distribution. The laborers, whose tastes have rema<strong>in</strong>edunchanged, and who now have their fuU share of thenew money, wiUbid for consumption goods <strong>in</strong> an amount consistentwith the old, pre-expansion, structure of production. Thatis, the), are unwill<strong>in</strong>g to forgo current consumpon and to wait<strong>in</strong>stead for the consumption goods associated with the newlong-term projects. Their me preferences have not changed.With their bidd<strong>in</strong>g for consumption goods the rate of <strong>in</strong>terestríses back to somewhere near its orig<strong>in</strong>al level. The long-termprojects that appeared to be profitable dur<strong>in</strong>g the expansion arerevealed to be unprofitable. The capitalists must act now to cuttheir losses. The m<strong>in</strong>imiz<strong>in</strong>g of losses may require that some ofthe new long-term projects be completed. Others, however, wiHhave to be liquidated. The specific capital associated with them


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics: A Diagrammatical Exposition 197will have to be abandoned. The laborers and non-specific capitalcan eventually be reabsorbed <strong>in</strong> the reconstruction of the orig<strong>in</strong>alstructure of production. But the transition back to the oldstructure is bound to <strong>in</strong>volve abnormally high levels of unemployedlabor and capital. 53The two phases of the process that are <strong>in</strong>itiated by a monetaryexpansion (the first phase correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the prime notation;the second phase to the double-prime notation) should be recognizedas the expansion and contraction phases of the bus<strong>in</strong>esscycle. The above discussion and the diagrammatics of Figure 13ate faithful to Rothbard's capsulization of the cyclical boom andbust:The "boom"... is actually a period of wasteful mis<strong>in</strong>vestment. Ir is thetime when errors ate made, due to the bank credit's tamper<strong>in</strong>g with thefree market. The "crisis" arrives when the consumers come to reestablishtheir desired proportions. The "depression" is actually the pro¢essby which the economy adjusts to the wastes and errors of the boom, andreestablishes efficient service of consumer desires. The adjustmentprocess consista <strong>in</strong> the.., liquidation of wasteful <strong>in</strong>vestments. Some ofthese will be abandoned altogether...; others will be shifted to otheruses ....In sum, the free market tends to satisfy voluntarily-expressed consumerdesires with maximum e£ficíency, and this <strong>in</strong>cludes the pub]ic'srelative desire for present and future consumption. The <strong>in</strong>flationaryboom hobbles this efficiency, and distorts the structure 0£production,which no Ionger serves consumers properly. The crisis signals the endof the <strong>in</strong>flationary distortion, and the depression is the process bywhich the economy returns to the efficient service of consumers, s4And f<strong>in</strong>al]y, it should be menfioned that to the extent that themal<strong>in</strong>vestment cannot be recovered there has been a net decrease<strong>in</strong> the economy's wealth. This can cause real changes <strong>in</strong>time and ]iquidity preferences (capitalists' and ]aborers') result<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> shifts <strong>in</strong> the supply and demand curves Di"panel I. To thisextent a monetary expansion is not neutral even <strong>in</strong> the long run.The <strong>Austrian</strong> model can be summarized <strong>in</strong> terms of the diagrammaticsof Figure 13. Panels I, II, and fil are the basiccomponents of the model. Panel I describes the tastes that aterelevant to the macroeconomic variab]es, i.e., the time and


198 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>liquidity preferences of capitafists and laborers. Panel II depictsthe structure of production that is consistent with the tastesdescribed <strong>in</strong> panel I. Changes <strong>in</strong> these tastes will cause thestructure of production to undergo a correspond<strong>in</strong>g changesubject to the relationship between capital and production timeas <strong>in</strong>dicated <strong>in</strong> panel III. The rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g panels deal with themonetary l<strong>in</strong>kages that translate the <strong>in</strong>dividuals' tastes <strong>in</strong>to acorrespond<strong>in</strong>g structure of production. In the absence ofmonetary disturbances the structure of production can be expectedto accurately reflect the tastes descríbed <strong>in</strong> panel I. Thepresence of a monetary disturbance, however, will prevent thesetastes from be<strong>in</strong>g accurately reflected <strong>in</strong> the structure ofproduc- ition. More specifically, an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the monetary stock by imeans of credit expansion will mislead the capit_a!istshato mak<strong>in</strong>gan (ultimately unsuccessful) attempt to lengthen the structureof production.FURTHERSTUDYFurther development of the <strong>Austrian</strong> model outl<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> thispaper could take any of several directions. The effects of various<strong>in</strong>stitutional ñgidities could be analyzed <strong>in</strong> terms of the model,for <strong>in</strong>stance, or the model could be modified to take explicitaccount of expectations ofone sort or another. Discussion will beconf<strong>in</strong>ed here, however, to one particular direction that appearsto be potentially fruifful. At the condusions ofearlier sections ofthis paper the <strong>Austrian</strong> model was contrasted diagrammaticallywith the Keynesian model, but no sucia contrast has been mades<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>troducfion of monetary considerations. The appropriatecomparison, then, is one between Figure 13 and someversion of the 18.¿34 model. A few comments are <strong>in</strong> order abouthow such a comparison might be made.The key to the comparison of the two models is panel V ofFigure 13. The movements of the curves <strong>in</strong> this panel are suspiciouslysimilar to the movements of thelS andLM curves. Theaxes <strong>in</strong> panel V and <strong>in</strong> the I$-LM ¢Uagram measure the same or


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics:A Diagrammatical Exposition 199similar magnitudes, and the concepmalizationthe two models bears a certa<strong>in</strong> resemblance.of the curves <strong>in</strong>In both models the vertical axis measures virtually the samemagnitude: IS-LM is concerned with the <strong>in</strong>terest rate <strong>in</strong> the loanmarket, while panel V measures the apparent rate of <strong>in</strong>terest,which encompasses the loan rate. Where the IS-LM diagrammeasures (real) total <strong>in</strong>come on the horizontal axis, panel Vmeasures (nom<strong>in</strong>al) <strong>in</strong>come of laborers, that is, it exdudes <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>come. (It is not altogether clear, though, that <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>come is acmaUy <strong>in</strong>duded <strong>in</strong> the IS-LM diagram <strong>in</strong> that theKeynesian full-employment <strong>in</strong>come Y is the <strong>in</strong>come ofN workersreckoned <strong>in</strong> "wage units.")Further, <strong>in</strong> elementary form-lations of the IS-LM model theIS curve is frequently conceptualized <strong>in</strong> a manner consistent withthe conceptualization of the correspond<strong>in</strong>g curve <strong>in</strong> panel V.Dernburg and McDougal, for <strong>in</strong>stance, teU us that "... ,,vemay... <strong>in</strong>terpret the IS schedule as the schedule of aggregate demandfor goods and services with respect to the <strong>in</strong>terest rate. "ssThe rate of <strong>in</strong>terest referred to is clearly the tate <strong>in</strong> the loanmarket. It is somewhat less clear, though, whether "goods andservices" refers to present (consumption) goods or to all (consumptionand <strong>in</strong>vestment) goods. If the former <strong>in</strong>terpretation isadopted, the correspond<strong>in</strong>g curves <strong>in</strong> the two models are verysimilar <strong>in</strong>deed. Ir the latter <strong>in</strong>terpretation is adopted, the actualmean<strong>in</strong>g of the concept-ali_ationis called <strong>in</strong>to question: IfthelScurve is the demand for all goóds, who are the suppliers of aUgoods, and what are they receiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> exchange for the qu.antitysupplied? (I) The less-elementary macroeconomics texts do notclear up the problem. They usually avoid it by absta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g fromany,attempt to concept-ali_e theI$-LM curves. They are viewed<strong>in</strong>stead as simply an outgrowth of the graphics that describe thereal and monetary sectors of the economy. In a prelude to bisdiscussion of the IS-LM diagram Ackley tells us that _[w]emustnow throw aU these elements <strong>in</strong>to a s<strong>in</strong>gle pot, stir well, and tastethe result<strong>in</strong>g stew."ssView<strong>in</strong>g the supply and demand curves of panel Vas LM and18, respectively, a number of familiar movements of the curves


200 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>can be described. A (non-neutral) <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> liquidity preferentes,for <strong>in</strong>stante, can shift the LM curve up and to the left,caus<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terest tate to rise; of a (non-neutral) <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> thewfll<strong>in</strong>gness to save (decrease <strong>in</strong> time preference) can shift thelScurve down and to the left, caus<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terest to rail. Changes<strong>in</strong> taste will cause real and last<strong>in</strong>g changes ín the IS and LMcurves, but changes <strong>in</strong> the nom<strong>in</strong>al stock of money wiU not. Amonetary expansion will shift theLM curve to the right, driv<strong>in</strong>gthe rate of<strong>in</strong>terest down, but the monetary stimulation will onlyhave a temporary effect because the real sector will soon adjust tothe larger monetary stock. ThelS curve will also shíft rightward, :return<strong>in</strong>g the tate of<strong>in</strong>terest to its orig<strong>in</strong>al level. A change <strong>in</strong> thenom<strong>in</strong>al monetary stock does not cause a real and last<strong>in</strong>g change<strong>in</strong> the tate of <strong>in</strong>terest.This is not to say that the <strong>Austrian</strong> model and thelS-1.51 modelyield the same or similar conclusions or have the same or similarimplications. Quite to the contrary. Equilibrium conditions cannotbe def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> temas of panel V of the <strong>Austrian</strong> model. Thispanel shows the movements of the apparent rate of<strong>in</strong>terest andof the nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>come to laborers dur<strong>in</strong>g the period that theeconomy is expeñenc<strong>in</strong>g a monetary dismrbance. Equilibriummust be def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms of panels I and II, i.e., <strong>in</strong> terms of therelevant tastes (time and liquidity preferences) and the structureof production correspond<strong>in</strong>g to those tastes. It cannot be defmed<strong>in</strong> terms of IS.LM stew. Panel V does open the door,however, to a thorough comparison of the two models and theirimplications.NOTES1. Ludwig ron Mises,Human Ac&m:d Treatiseon Economi¢s,Srdrevised ed. (Chicago:Henry Regnery Co., 1966), pp. 538-86. AlsoseeMises, The Theory of Mon_ and Cr_d/t, trans, by H. E. Bat__, (<strong>New</strong>Haven: Yale UniversityPress, 1953), pp. 339-66. And Mises, Money,IpílaÜon and the Trade Cycle: Three Theoretical Studies,"trans, byBett<strong>in</strong>a Bien Greaves,ed. by Pero/T. GreavesJr. (Unpublished papers,1923, 1928, and 1931).2. Friedrich A. von Hayek, Pr/_ and Produce/on(<strong>New</strong> York: AugustusM.Keney,1967).A1soseeHayeL M_Ty _ aad _ Tra_


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics: A Diagrammatical Exposition 201Cycb, tratas,by N. Kaldor and H. M. Croome (<strong>New</strong> York: Augustus M.KeUey, 1966).3. Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State: A Treatise on<strong>Economics</strong>, 2 vols. (Los Angeles: Nash Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1970), pp. 273--501, 850-81. Also see Rothbard, America's Great Depression (LosAngeles: Nash Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1972), pp. 11-38.4. See, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Don Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Money, Interest, and Prices, 2nded. (<strong>New</strong> York: Harper and Row, Inc., 1965), p. 200.5. Hayek, Prices and Production, p. 34.6. Gerald P. 0 DriscoU,Jr.,<strong>Economics</strong> asa Coord<strong>in</strong>ationProblem:TheContributions ofFriedri¢h A. Hayek (Kansas City: Sheed Andrews andMcMeel, Inc., 1977).7. Hayek, Prices and Production, p. 38.8. Ib/d., p. 36.9. W. Stanley Jevons, The Theory ofPolitical Economy, ed. by R. D.Collhon Black (Middlesex: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, Inc., 1970), pp. 225-53.10. Gustav Cassel, The Nature and NecessityofInterest (London: Mac-Millan and Co., Ltd., 1903), pp. 96-157.11. Eugen ron B6hm-Bawerk, Capital and Interest, trans, by GeorgeD. Huncke and Hans F. Sennholz, 3 vols. (South HoUand, IU.:LibertarianPress, 1959), vol. 2., pp. 10-15 and pass/m.12. Mises, Human Action, pp. 493-503 and passim.13. Hayek, Prices and Production, pp. 36-68. Also, see Hayek, ThePri_ Theoryof Capital (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1941), pp.193-201 and pass/m.14. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, pp. 486-92 and pass/m.15. Jevons, Theory ofPolitical Economy, pp. 229-30.16. Ib/d., p. 230.17. Cassel, Nature and Necessity of lnterest, p. 54.18. Rothbard refers to this concept us<strong>in</strong>g the terna "aggregate productionstructure." Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, p. 491.19. Jevons, Theory ofPolitical Economy, p. 231.20. B6hm-Bawerk, Capital and Interest, p. 312ff.21. Mises, Human Action, pp. 488--89.22. Hayek, Pure Theory ofCapital, p. 140ff. Hayek rejected the notionof aggregate as well as average production time except as the ternamight be used <strong>in</strong> a very loose sense. See lb/d., p. 70.23. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, p. 412.24. Hayek, Prices and Production, p. 39.25. Ib/d., p. 40.26. Hayek, Pure Theory of Capital, p. 113ff.27. Mies, Human Artrn, p. 244ff.28. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, p. 332.29. Jevons, Theor3 of Politi¢al Economy, p. 227.


202 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>30. lb/., p. 229.31. See footnotes 20 through 23.32. Mises, Human Action, p. 495.33. Ib/d.34. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, p. 487.35. Hayek, Pure Theory of Capital, p. 70. !36. G. C. Harcourt and N. F. La<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Capital and Growth(Middlesex: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books Ltd., 1971), p. 211. Also see G. C. Harcourt,Some Cambridge Controversies<strong>in</strong> the Themy of Capital (Cambridge,England: The Cambridge University Press, 1972), pp. 118-76.I37. John R. Hicks, Capital and Time (Oxford: The Clarendon Preas, !1973), p. 44.38. Hayek, Prices and Production, pp. 49-54.t39. Ibid., p. 53. Also see Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State, pp. !470-79 where similar diagrammatics are used to depict changes <strong>in</strong> thestructure ofproducfion brought about by changes <strong>in</strong> time preferences.40. Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Money, Interest, and Pr/ces, p. 205.41. l/ñd., pp. 17-21 and pass/m.42. Fñedrich A. von Hayek, ProJ'Oa,I_terest and lnvestment (London:George Routledge and Solas, Ltd., 1939), p. 177.43. Hayek, Prices and Production, p. 11. Hayek reaffirmed this position<strong>in</strong> hís Nobel lecture. See Hayek, Full Employment al Any Price?(London: Institute for Economic Affairs, 1975), pp. 23ff. and 37.44. Hayek, Pr/ces andProduct/on, p. 54. See also Mises, HumanAc6on,p. 556 and Rotñbard, Man, Econo_, and State, p. 885.45. Milton Friedman, The Optimum Quantity ofMono and OtlJ¿_'Essays(Chicago: Ald<strong>in</strong>e Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1969), p. 4ff.46. Paf<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Money, Int¢rest, and Pric_s, p. 200 and pa.uim.47. Mises, Human dct/on, p. 418.48. Hayek, Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle, p. 46.49. It should be po<strong>in</strong>ted out, however, that the Wicksellian"naturaltate is the rate correspond<strong>in</strong>g to a constant price level, while the<strong>Austrian</strong> "natural" rate is the rate correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the absence ofmoney creation vía credit expansion. See Hayek, Mosu__ T_ andTrade C_le, pp. 109-16. Also see Rothbard,Man, Ewnowq, and Sta_,p. 940.50. This is the market proceu that captures Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>'s attenfion.Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Money, Interest, and Prices, pp. 236-44.51. Mises, Human dct/on, pp. 559-61.52. Hayek, Pr/ces and Product/on, pp. 18-81, and Hayek, Profi,Interest and Inve#ment, pp. 183-97.53. Hayek accounts for this unsuccessful attempt to lengthen thestructure of production <strong>in</strong> terms of the Ricardo effect. See Hayek,Profita, lntereatandl_a__tt, pp. 8--15. Als0 see Hayek, "The Ricardo


<strong>Austrian</strong> Macroeconomics: A Diagrammatical Exposition 203Effect," Econm_a, IX, No. 34 (new ser.; Ma), 1942): pp. 127-52 repr<strong>in</strong>ted<strong>in</strong> Hayek, Individualista and Economic Order (Chicago: HenryRegnery Co., 1972) pp. 220-54, and Hayek,"Three Elucidations of theRicardo Effect,"Journa/ofPoli_alEconoray, 77 (March/Apñ11969): pp.274-85.54. Rothbard,dmer/ca's GreatDepression, p. 19. Also see Lionel Robb<strong>in</strong>s,The GreatDepression (London: The MacMillan Co., Ltd., 1934), pp.30-54.55. Thomas F. Dernburg and Duncan M. McDougal, Macroeconomi¢s(<strong>New</strong>York: McGraw-Hill Book Co., 1968), p. 161.56. Gardner Acidey, Macroeconomic Theory (Toronto: The MacmillanCo., 1969), p. 347.BIBLIOGRAPHYAckley,Gardner.Macroeconomic Theory.Toronto:The MacMillanCo.,1969.B6hm-Bawcrk,Eugen ron.Capital andInterest. TranslatcdbyGeorgcD. Huncke and Hans F.Sennholz.3 vols.SouthHolland,Ill.:Libcrtarian Prcss,1959.Cassel,Gusmv.TheNaturea__lNece£sity ofInt_est. London:MacMillanand Co.,Ltd.,1903.Dcrnburg,Thomas F.and McDougal,Duncan M.Mac_economics. <strong>New</strong>York:McGraw-HiU Book Co.,1968.Fñedman, Milton. The Optimum Quantity of Money and Other Essays.Chicago: Ald<strong>in</strong>e Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1969.Harcourt, G. C. and La<strong>in</strong>g, N. F., editors. Capital and Growth.Middlesex: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books Ltd., 1971.Harcourt, G. C. Some Cambridge Controversies <strong>in</strong> the Theory of Capital.Cambridge, England: The Cambñdge University Press, 1972.Hayek, Friedrich A. von. FuU Employment at Any Price? London: Instituteof Economic Affairs, 1975.Hayek, Fñedrich A. von. Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle. Translatedby N. Kaldor and H. M. Croome. <strong>New</strong> York: Augustus M.Kelley, 1966. (First published <strong>in</strong> 1933.)Hayek, Fñedrich A. von.Prices andProduction. <strong>New</strong> York: Augustus M.Kelley, 1967. (First published <strong>in</strong> 1935.)Hayek, Fñedñch A. von. Profas, lnterest and lnvestment. London:George Routledge and Sons, Ltd., 1939.Hayek, Friedrich A. von. The Price Theoryof Capital. Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press, 1941.Hayek, Friedrich A. von. "The Ricardo Effect," Economica, IX, No. 34


204 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>(new ser.; May, 1942) 127-52 repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Individualista andEconomic Order. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1972.Hayek, Friedrich A. ven. "Three Eluddations of the Ricardo Effect,"Journal of Political Economy, 77 (March/April, 1969): 274-85.Hicks, John R. Capital and Time. The C]arendon Press, 1973.íJevons, w. Stanley. The Theory of Political E¢onomy. Edited by R.D. !Collison Black. Middlesex: Pengu<strong>in</strong> Books, Inc., 1970.IMises, Ludwig von. Human Action:.4 Treatise on <strong>Economics</strong>, 3rd rey. ed. JChicago: Henry RegneryCo., 1966.Mises, Ludwig von. "Money, Inflation, and the Trade Cyde: ThreeThcoretical Studies." Translated by Betf<strong>in</strong>a Bien Gr_aves, editedby Percy L. Greaves, Jr., unpublished papers, 1923, 1928, and1931.Mises, Ludwig von. The Theory ofMoney and Cred/t. Translated by H. E.Batson. <strong>New</strong> Haven: Yale Universky Press, 1953. (First published<strong>in</strong> 1911.)O'Dríscoll, Gerald P., Jr. Economi¢s _ a Coord<strong>in</strong>ation Problem: TheCont6butions of Friedrich A. Hayek. Kansas City: Sheed Andrewsand McMeel, Inc., 1977.Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don. Money, Interest, and Prices. 2nd ed. <strong>New</strong> York: Harperand Row, Inc., 1965.Robbíns, Lionel. The Great Depression. London: The MacMiUan Co.,Ltd., 1934.Rothbard, Murray N. Anwrica's Great Depression. Los Angeles: NashPublísh<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1972. (First published <strong>in</strong> 1963.)Rothbard, Murray N. Man, Economy, and Stabe: A Trw_e on EconomicPr<strong>in</strong>ciples. 2 vols. Los Angeles: Nash Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co., 1970. (Firstpublished <strong>in</strong> 1962.)


Toward a Programof Research and Developmentfor <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Louis M. SpadaroFordham UniversityI.Now that <strong>Austrian</strong> economics has entered its second century,it is both natural and useful--as the subject of the present conferenceimplies to look to the future and to tryto discern,aslaras is possible, the most promis<strong>in</strong>g directions along which ourdiscipl<strong>in</strong>e might develop further. Of course, the anniversarycustomarily also <strong>in</strong>vites review and evaluation of past experience;itis, <strong>in</strong> fact, as the resultofsome reflection on the latterthatI venmre to make the s<strong>in</strong>gle underly<strong>in</strong>g suggestíon whích willbeseen to be the po<strong>in</strong>t of the present paper.While the centenary we are celebrat<strong>in</strong>g will be thought bymany to be that of the start of the "marg<strong>in</strong>alist revolution," thefact is that the truly sem<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>sight was not the marg<strong>in</strong>alanalysis--valuable as that analytical device admittedly was, andcont<strong>in</strong>ues to be--but, rather, the strangely belated recognitionof the subjective namre of economic value and even of humanaction <strong>in</strong> general Ir is the special merit of <strong>Austrian</strong> economicsthat, wh_e it shares the concept of the marg<strong>in</strong> with its simultaneous_co-discovererselsewhere,its dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveand characteristiccontribution has been its <strong>in</strong>sistence on the explanatory power ofsubjectivism.For one th<strong>in</strong>g, unlike either of the other branches of mar-2O5


206 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>g<strong>in</strong>alísm, the <strong>Austrian</strong>s put forward a complete altemative to thecost-of-production concept ofeconomic value which permeated iclassical analysis (and also íts derivatives, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Marxista) iand not just the second half of a dualistic explanation,iMoreover, it was precisely this role ofsubjectivism that caused !the early, and subsequently widen<strong>in</strong>g, divergences <strong>in</strong> boththeory and policy among the"marg<strong>in</strong>alisms." The failure on thepart of the non-<strong>Austrian</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alists to perceive the fullexplanatory power of the subjective theory of value is, I believe,What led them--each <strong>in</strong> its own way---away from economic realityand <strong>in</strong>to an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly vacuous formalism. On the onehand, English marg<strong>in</strong>alism, perhaps because it was unable totum its back on its own Classical heritage, chose to supplementrather than supplant it. The result was a "neo-classical synthesis"2of supply and demand---best illustrated by the Marshallian"scissors" and progressively ref<strong>in</strong>.ed by an almost obsessivepreoccupation with the geometry of <strong>in</strong>tersectiom, which cont<strong>in</strong>uesunabatedw<strong>in</strong> class and textbook--to the present time.The French marg<strong>in</strong>alists, on the other hand, misled by boththe pretensions of the Enlightenment and their own mathematicalprowes.í, and also lack<strong>in</strong>g the corrective force of a fuHysubjectivist view--were led to conceive of the economic processasa general equilibrium system (expressible by the algebra ofsímultaneous equations)--grander, more <strong>in</strong>clusive (and, alas,more illusory) than the "partíar' equilibrium of the Englisheconomists. Both have spawned a numerous progeny who havelabored mightily, ir s<strong>in</strong>gle-m<strong>in</strong>dedly, <strong>in</strong> explor<strong>in</strong>g the theoreticaland policy implications of their respective paradigms; andthough their results have shown more elegance than usefulness,they have given only cursorymand often contemptuous--attention to the <strong>Austrian</strong> tradition.<strong>Austrian</strong>s, on the contrary, llave spent an <strong>in</strong>ord<strong>in</strong>ately largepart of their talents and resources <strong>in</strong> efforts to deid with theerrors of others, <strong>in</strong>dud<strong>in</strong>g some frivolous and some highly repetiveones, and correspond<strong>in</strong>gly less on the development andextension oftheir special <strong>in</strong>sight. Ir is to this misallocation ofour


Toward a Programof Researchand Development 207resources that my central suggestion is addressed, as we shaUpresently see.Before proceed<strong>in</strong>g, let me hasten to saythat there is,ofcourse,no deny<strong>in</strong>g the fact that <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>Austrian</strong> economists havecont<strong>in</strong>ued to make contñbutions of great power, clañty, anddepth--and this is <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly recognized outside their ownmembership. But those of us who area little oldermust, I th<strong>in</strong>k,also be sadder to realize how much of the efforts of so many ofour people---never a numerous company--has gone <strong>in</strong>to enocounters with an endless seriesofegregious errors,and to speculateon what might have been accomplished had aUthis <strong>in</strong>vestmentbeen directed, <strong>in</strong>stead, to ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and extend<strong>in</strong>g our ownanalysis.For, we have allowed ourselves, time and aga<strong>in</strong>, to becomeembroiled <strong>in</strong> time-consum<strong>in</strong>g and largely <strong>in</strong>conclusive controversies:with Marxism, macroeconomícs, mathematicaleconomics, and monetary medic<strong>in</strong>e men--just to name an alliterativefew. And the end is nowhere <strong>in</strong> sight, s<strong>in</strong>ce most ofthese exhibit the sort of imperviousness that led the scholasticphilosophers to co<strong>in</strong> the term "<strong>in</strong>v<strong>in</strong>cible error."Out of many, let us consider briefly two examples, which notonly iUustratethis resource rnisallocation,but also serveas referencepo<strong>in</strong>ts later on <strong>in</strong> our discussion,a The first concerm theimportant <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>in</strong>sight that a centrally directed economycannot, of itself, provide the. data necessary for effectivedecision-mak<strong>in</strong>g (/.e., consistent with the preferences of consumers).Immediately after Mises had caUed attention to thisdefect, socialistsand other <strong>in</strong>terventionists tra<strong>in</strong>ed their heaviestanalytical artillery on the idea. There ensued a very long and<strong>in</strong>voluted discussion of"shadow-pric<strong>in</strong>g" and other devices,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gnota few mathematical models, which would allegedlyenable the m<strong>in</strong>istry of production <strong>in</strong> a socialist economy to allocateresources eff'_ently.It is fair to say, I believe, that all the strenuous rebutmtqfailedto bhnt the force of the orig<strong>in</strong>al criticismof d/r/g/steplann<strong>in</strong>g,though they may have served to obfuscate it somewhat <strong>in</strong> the


208 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>m<strong>in</strong>ds of the faithful and of the unwary. But the debate engageda good deal of time and effort by the then relatively few, highlycompetent advocates of the market system--time and effort iwhich doubtless would have been better spent on ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and iextend<strong>in</strong>g their own analysis.4In short, <strong>in</strong>stead oftry<strong>in</strong>g to show jthe <strong>in</strong>adequacies of every surrogate for calculation that the ad- lvocates of central plann<strong>in</strong>g saw fit to come up with, our peoplemight have been better advised to stop after one or two of themand devote the time saved to explor<strong>in</strong>g the agencies, channels,and forms through which a market system conveys and utilizes<strong>in</strong>formation--and thus how it doescalculate. There is reason tobelieve that ir this had been done successfully, some of ourpresent tasks (e.g.,the "rehabilitation" of the entrepreneur as anactive, motive force) could have advanced earlier and further.The second <strong>in</strong>stance is the latest--most certa<strong>in</strong>ly not thelast--resurgence of the advocacyofnational economic plann<strong>in</strong>g,one of those imperishable errors we mentioned a little earlier.Although Hayek and others had long ago carefuIly and def<strong>in</strong>itivelyshown that the real issue is not plann<strong>in</strong>g versus chaos, butrather who is to plan and for whom, the current proposal seemsto be proceed<strong>in</strong>g as ff the earlier correctiveworkhad never beendone at all. Already, Hayek has found it necessary to write <strong>in</strong>reply,5repeat<strong>in</strong>g the dist<strong>in</strong>ction, though with a shade less of the"politeness to a fault" noted bySchumpeter and characteristicofthis civilized man.Though it is undoubtedly presumptuous, one cannot resistexpress<strong>in</strong>g the hope that no further time be taken from other,more deserv<strong>in</strong>g tasks, <strong>in</strong> order to beat this recyded dead horse. Ifeel certa<strong>in</strong> that Profenor Hayek would be forgiven--evenapplauded by many--ff he decided to limit himself, on thisquestion, to send<strong>in</strong>g to two senators and to a select group ofacademiefi'_nsand others simply a card<strong>in</strong>scribed with the Frenchsay<strong>in</strong>g: "On ne dit pas la Messe deux fois pour les sourds,"together with ah order blank for The R0ad to Serfdom.If there ís a lesson <strong>in</strong> all this, it ís that we ought to scale downver), sharply the extent to which our future efforts--and especiallythoseof our best young people--are devoted to the refuta-


Toward a Program of Research and Development 209tion of any and every fallacy which others choose to propose.Instead, <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>in</strong>vestment should be made <strong>in</strong> efforts to workout further the implications of subjectivism--the disnctivelyAustñan contribufion--and to <strong>in</strong>crease its impact on contemporarythought and action. It wiUbe the task of much of the restof the present paper to show that a good deal of this work is sllto be done.There is, then, much more than a simple anniversary occasionto counsel the value of pursu<strong>in</strong>g our own analysis. Furthermore,political and economic developments dur<strong>in</strong>g the last decadehave created a climate <strong>in</strong> which subjecvist analysis can expect--temporarily, at least--to get a wider and fairer hear<strong>in</strong>g thanbefore. Though one is tempted to th<strong>in</strong>k otherwise, the presenttemper, and opportunity, ma), be attributable more to the manifestfailure of policies based on non-Austñan economic reason<strong>in</strong>gthan to any sudden persuasiveness ofour own. In any event,the <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g number of talented young scholars attracted tothe <strong>Austrian</strong> approach deserve, and probably prefer, a morechaUeng<strong>in</strong>g and productive objective than putt<strong>in</strong>g out small andrecurrent brush tires.By now, the central suggestion of this paper--that we concentrateour resources on perfect<strong>in</strong>g and extend<strong>in</strong>g subjectivism--hardly needs to be stated explicifly. But its implementation isvery lar from be<strong>in</strong>g obvious. Along what l<strong>in</strong>es is further research<strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> economics needed? In which of these is there moreurgency? Ale any of these most effectively pursued by enlist<strong>in</strong>gparticipation and contribution from specialists or practitioners<strong>in</strong> other discipl<strong>in</strong>es or activities? Answers to sucia quesUonsprobably can emerge only from a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g, frank, and criUcaldiscussion of po<strong>in</strong>ts of obscurity, difticulty, or controversyamong <strong>Austrian</strong> economists. The present conference promisesto give significant Lnitial impems <strong>in</strong> this direction.The contribution of this paper, if any, is the modest one ofsett<strong>in</strong>g out a few of the possibiliUe.- asa tentative frame ofreference---and thus gett<strong>in</strong>g the discussion under way. It is expectedthat some (or all) of these wiUbe rejected and that otherswiUbe proposed. These possible "new direcUons" will be listed


iI210 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong> :and discussed very briefly under two head<strong>in</strong>gs: The next sectionwill offer a small sampl<strong>in</strong>g of theoretical (i.e., analytical,methodological) questions. The f<strong>in</strong>al section presents ah even ,.smaller sample of <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>Austrian</strong> economics andoperations-oriented and other "outside" fields. These two types !are treated separately largely for conveniente and clarity; it wiUbe obvious that they are ultimately <strong>in</strong>terdependent and mutuallyr¢<strong>in</strong>forcmg./LAs new implications of subjecávism unfold, the conceptualanalytical-methodologicalframework of Austñan theory mayrequire extensiom, and even revisions, for purposes of consistencyand coord<strong>in</strong>ation. While the bulk of such changes willalmost certa<strong>in</strong>ly be made by <strong>Austrian</strong> economists themselves,others may properly come from people not now considered to be<strong>Austrian</strong> economist:, or even economists at all.Inasmuch as attempts at discovery are mere grop<strong>in</strong>gs, andtherefore always run high risk of failure, it is perhaps worthpaus<strong>in</strong>g to reflect that ¢ven when they fa _xploratiom mayhave useful residue <strong>in</strong> the fo_m of fresh <strong>in</strong>sights, or <strong>in</strong> otherways. In the present case, it is highly probable that suciaeffortswill produce--at the very least.--a deeper understand<strong>in</strong>g on thepart of more people as to just what human acfion is (and, especially,what it is not).1. The most obvious and urgent areas need<strong>in</strong>g our attention arethose which are caus<strong>in</strong>g some disagreement among competent<strong>Austrian</strong>s themselves or those <strong>in</strong> which theorists, <strong>in</strong>dividually or<strong>in</strong> consensus, feel t,hereis a need for additional analytical support.S<strong>in</strong>ce each of us is doubfless aware of a number of suchproblem areas, a s<strong>in</strong>gle illustration will suffic.e.Some time ago, notice began to be taken of the fact that stan-,dard economic analysis tended to make, of the entrepreneurialfunction, someth<strong>in</strong>g bloodles: rigíd, automatic, and unreal.The present writer, for <strong>in</strong>stance, found Rneceuary to deplore


Toward a Program of Research and Development 211the fact while received theory had gradually relieved everyoneelse from the despicable role of "economic man," the technicalrequirements of its own equilibrium paradigm led to impos<strong>in</strong>gprecisely this role on the entrepreneur, eS<strong>in</strong>ce then, <strong>in</strong> one of the more excit<strong>in</strong>g recent developments of<strong>Austrian</strong> analysis---notably <strong>in</strong> work done by KirznerL--the funct.ionof the enterpriser <strong>in</strong> a market system is be<strong>in</strong>g reformulatedand ref<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a manner that is both more reali_'tic and moreconsistent with <strong>in</strong>dividual freedom of choice than ever before.The present case is also useful <strong>in</strong> demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g how, typically,answer<strong>in</strong>g one question raises others that need to be dealtwith next. There is some difference of op<strong>in</strong>ion as to whether--given uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty--this new, much more active concept of entrepreneurshipis stabiliz<strong>in</strong>g or not. This queson, which wiil beseen as an aspect of the more general problem of convergence 8<strong>in</strong> a free market system, has already begun to be discussedamong a group of <strong>Austrian</strong> economists from the <strong>New</strong> Yorkmetropolitan area who now meet regularly.Once the specificaon of the new entrepreneurial concept hasbeen completed, and its implicaons worked out, there will sllrema<strong>in</strong> the task of getng non-<strong>Austrian</strong> theorists to take it <strong>in</strong>toaccount. This will, ofcourse, be difficult; resistance will be all thegreater because, as ,,ve noted earlier, the new formulaon removesan important element <strong>in</strong> the neatness and automacity oftheir models. But any success at all <strong>in</strong> this direction may ultimatelylead to wider recognition of the power and potenUal of afree market to operate without outside direcon.Accumulat<strong>in</strong>g e-ddence of the failure of recent <strong>in</strong>terventionsmay, <strong>in</strong> any event, make others a bit more receptive. Samuelson,for example, <strong>in</strong> a recent piece ° devoted to Adam Smith on theoccasion of the bicentennial of the Weal_ ofNations, after quot<strong>in</strong>gtwo of its hest-known passages (one on the self-<strong>in</strong>terest of"... butcher, the brewer .... "; the other the passage menon<strong>in</strong>gthe "<strong>in</strong>visible hand"), says, <strong>in</strong> condusion:To imow the truth-.-and the limitationsl--ofa/_aa Tka/e of econom_ wisdom.these passages is the


212 N.ew<strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>There is reason to hope thatour efforts, together with the forceof events, may eventually persuade hito to reduce the quu]ification.2. Admittedly, the class of further explorations <strong>in</strong> subjectivisttheory just illustrated have a legitimate first cluirn<strong>in</strong> any systematicreallocation of our resources. Beyond these, however,there is another group of needs, whose immediacy is less apparent,but whose ultimate contributions to subjective economictheory might prove to be of considerable importance. Asagroup, these are <strong>in</strong>direct--theoretic goods of"higher order," soto speak--and <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>in</strong>puts from a wide variety of discipl<strong>in</strong>esdifferent from, but often border<strong>in</strong>g on, economic theory itself.• Let us consider, briefly, a small _mple of these possibiliUes.(a) Statistical<strong>in</strong>ference, <strong>in</strong> the forra it eventuaUytook andascurrently understood and applied, is fundamentally <strong>in</strong>congruentwith subjectivity and therefore of little, ff any, use <strong>in</strong> thetreatment of most of the phenomena with which <strong>Austrian</strong>economics is concerned. The conceptual (even the axiomatic)basisof contemporary statisticaltheory--and, deñvatively, of allof its calcuhom ksadmittedly that of "objective" probability(/.e.,the observed, or observable, frequency of<strong>in</strong>dependent andrandom events). It is therefore really <strong>in</strong>applicable to anyphenomena that are unique, or <strong>in</strong>teractive, of subjective.-and<strong>in</strong>applicableafortiori to those that are all three, asis the case withhuman acfion, <strong>in</strong> the sense understood by <strong>Austrian</strong> analysis.Imtead of refra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gfrom such phenomena, objectivelyderivedstatistical analysis and irfferenceale applied to them widely.--atavery high cost <strong>in</strong> both realista and vañdity--on the OargelyimpliciOassumption that such events are somehow amenable tothe same "law of large numbers" applicable to <strong>in</strong>dependent,ru_ndomevents.To tl-_ writer's knowledge, there has been virmally no systematiceffort to develop alternative <strong>in</strong>ferential systems moreconsistent with the <strong>in</strong>escapable subjecfivity of human events,despite the fact that the clear <strong>in</strong>adequacy of received statistical


Toward a Programof Researchand Development 213theory <strong>in</strong> this connection has been recognized for some time? °Itis the more puzzl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> that the possibility and feasibility--if notthe primacy--of subjective probability were discussed veryearlyu <strong>in</strong> the development of statistical thought and have cont<strong>in</strong>uedto be mentioned, tsDespite these and other <strong>in</strong>sights concern<strong>in</strong>g the essentially$ubjective element <strong>in</strong> probability statements, _3 the almostirresistibleurge to assign card<strong>in</strong>al numbers to degrees of beliefhas led to the arbitraryrestatement (and distortion)of subjectiveprobability <strong>in</strong> objective terms--to the consequent neglect of theneed to search for a viable alternaUve.What iscurrently referredto as "subjective probability"is thus noth<strong>in</strong>g morethan the usualobjective probability analysis broken down <strong>in</strong>to segments: ahantecedent (of "prior") probability anda consequent ("posterior")onel_--a process for which subjective is a manifest misnomer;it is more properly designated as "conditional" of "sequentiar'probability.Even here, the crudal problem--and the subject of cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gcontroversy--is the assignment ofsome weight to the antecedent(prior) probability segment <strong>in</strong> the many <strong>in</strong>stances where occurrencesare too few tojustify reliance on the law oflarge numbers,which underlies the usual statistical apparatus. The faciledevicefor skirdng this difficulty--that of arbitrarily assign<strong>in</strong>g equalprobabilities to such events---is disputed, as one might easilyguess. Some alternative approaches, _5<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the concept oflearn<strong>in</strong>g by experience, should be of some <strong>in</strong>terest to subjecdvetheorists <strong>in</strong> a number of respects, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation theory(to be mentioned briefly below) and the analysis of entrepreneurialdecision-mak<strong>in</strong>g.(b) The advocacy ofa free-market system (as dearly superiorto one run bycentral direction) relies, to an important degree, onthe asserUon that decentralized (i.e., <strong>in</strong>dividual) decisions aremade on the basisof much more reañstic and accurate <strong>in</strong>formaflotaavailableat the source ofhuman decisions:<strong>in</strong>dividual valuationsand preferences. But <strong>in</strong> any complex economy, these elemental(e.g.,consumer) choices triggerlong sequences of deriva-


214 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>tive decisions by producers and by suppliers of attendant services(e.g., f<strong>in</strong>ancial, distributive, etc.) at every level and stage ofproduction. The capability of the market process to transmithighly reliable <strong>in</strong>formaÚon along networks of such bewilder<strong>in</strong>gcomplexity--and to do so without undue distortion or loss of<strong>in</strong>formatiorb-is impressíve anda stand<strong>in</strong>g rebuke to the aspirationsof central planners. That the process works is evident; butprecisely how is only dirnly and <strong>in</strong>tuitively understood, thoughthe importance of <strong>in</strong>formaÚon <strong>in</strong> the economic process is recognized,le More detailed understand<strong>in</strong>g of its operaÜon (e.g., thelocation and role of l<strong>in</strong>kages, the localization [decentralization]of decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g through subnetworks of <strong>in</strong>formation flow,etc.) could help substantially <strong>in</strong> validaÜng and extend<strong>in</strong>g ourtheoríes---and might even cause some reth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>in</strong>terventionists.It happens that--<strong>in</strong> connection with problems different from,but ultimately not unrelated to, economics---the technicalanalysis of <strong>in</strong>formation process<strong>in</strong>g has m_adesignhícant strides<strong>in</strong> the last quarter century. 17The results of studies <strong>in</strong> "communicationstheory" (or "<strong>in</strong>formation theory') have proven value <strong>in</strong>the communicaÜons <strong>in</strong>dustry and <strong>in</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess management <strong>in</strong>general. And it is not unlikely that this field may have contributionsto make to market theory. For one th<strong>in</strong>g, ir may help usunderstand and expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a much more precise way how thetra_nsmission of <strong>in</strong>formation facilitates the convergence of theplans and decisions of large numbers of <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>dividualsand firms. For another, the basíc concepts of this analyfm--e.g.,the m<strong>in</strong>imum amount of <strong>in</strong>formation (a b<strong>in</strong>ary unit or "bit")needed to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between two alternatives (b<strong>in</strong>arychoice)--might prove to be as suggesUve for the development ofnew approaches to subjecfive-choice analysis as they were <strong>in</strong> theearly design of electronic computers? sAga<strong>in</strong>, it seems unfortunate that no serious attempt has beenmade to <strong>in</strong>vite the attention--and contribution---of thesespecialists <strong>in</strong> the explication of the market system. Althoughthese are primarily eng<strong>in</strong>eers, there is reason to believe thatmore than a fcw of them would respond to the challenge ofí


Toward a Program of Research and Development 215adapt<strong>in</strong>g portions of their analysis to the needs of economíctheory. At the very least, some dialogue with them would notleave the field open for advocates of a contrary economicphilosophy to bend communication theory to their purposes. TM(c) One aspect of the above--the concept of entropy--deserves brief, separate mention for at least two reasons. Thefirst is related to the special (technical) use made of this concept<strong>in</strong> communication theory. "Entropy" <strong>in</strong> this adaptation is verydifferent from the concept of entropy as employed <strong>in</strong> physics(though possibly ultimately reducible to it). Here, the term isused to mean a measure of the amount of <strong>in</strong>formation that atheory provides and is understood to vary directly with thedegree of freedom of choice (or "uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty") on the part ofrecipients of ínformationS°--aga<strong>in</strong>, there may be <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>sights and implications here for subjective theory.The second po<strong>in</strong>t "_that entropy <strong>in</strong> its more general sense.(i.e.,the one more directly consistent with its traditional use <strong>in</strong>physics) seems to offer a viable alternative to the equilibrium•paradigm so pervasive <strong>in</strong> contemporary economic theory--andone seem<strong>in</strong>gly more adaptive to the analysis of economic activitiesas processes. It also touches conceptually on a number ofquestions which should be of some heuristic <strong>in</strong>terest to ourtheorists. Space here will not permit more than the mere mentionof some of these: purposive activity, order and probability,partial processes, irreversibility, etc. 21 Some <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong>exploñng the potentialities, possibly <strong>in</strong> consultation withspecialists <strong>in</strong> that field, would appear to be worthwhile.(d) It is apparent that some explorations of the sort touchedupon <strong>in</strong> this section imply that at least some ofour students have,or acquire, the ability to follow mathematical argument--perhaps even to <strong>in</strong>itiate it. Many of us who have been <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong>the theoretical wars for some time will---quite understandably-.¿eskeptical of any such <strong>in</strong>volvement. For, weare all tofamiliar with mathematical models of high eleganceand small economic content; and with countless <strong>in</strong>stances of the


216 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>Procrustean tortur<strong>in</strong>g of economic reality to make it fit themathematical bed. It is, moreover, notoriously true thatmathematical formulation is often made the end, rather than ameans, of economic reason<strong>in</strong>g; and that (especially graduate)students are coerced <strong>in</strong>to this mode of argument by a labor<strong>in</strong>tensiveroute which tends to render them the locked-<strong>in</strong> victimsof their over-<strong>in</strong>vestment.But all these are, after all, outrageous abuses of ah essentiallyformal disdpf<strong>in</strong>e which, fike logic, cannot be presumed <strong>in</strong> advanceto be either wrong or useless. Each of the abuses mentionedcan easily be avoided; <strong>in</strong>deed, all of them are attributableto dilettantes rather t.han to competent mathematácians and iris to the latter that reference is made here.Several considerations deserve attention <strong>in</strong> this connection.First, the summary rejection of mathematics--root andbranch--acts to exclude aU mathematicians from our company.Yet, it should be possible fora mathematician to be a libertarian,too--and without schizophrenia. Secondly, it is a fact, howeverregrettable, that arguments <strong>in</strong> symbolic form--even when<strong>in</strong>valid--are held <strong>in</strong> awe by many. There is no good reason forthose who have someth<strong>in</strong>g valid to say to cede this advantage totheir opponents. Thirdly, and more important, the scope ofmathematics---as understood by its most able practitioner: kslar broader, more humane, and more flexible than it appears tobe to others. What Bould<strong>in</strong>g sz calls "the puritanism ofmathematics" is likely to be merely <strong>in</strong> the eye of the casualobserver.This br<strong>in</strong>gs us at last to the suggestion of this subsection: thatwe explore the usefulness, for our purposes, of less numericaland more purely relational branches of mathematics, ss One ofthese---topology--which seems to have special applicability todiscont<strong>in</strong>uous phenomena (and should therefore "have <strong>in</strong>terestedus long ago), is currendy be<strong>in</strong>g utilized by a differentgroup, <strong>in</strong> conjuncfion with so.caUed "catastrophe theory. _4 It isalso <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to note that this banch of mathemacs, which isrelatively neglect.._l <strong>in</strong> our general treatis_, is given more space<strong>in</strong> the Soviet texts, n


Toward a Program of Research and Development 2173. The f<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>t of this section is a suggestion for the implementationof our central recommendation on the allocationof our resources with respect to controversies like those mentionedearlier as examples of"mal<strong>in</strong>vestment" on our part. It isunrealisticmand perhaps unwise--to expect that we shall be ableto avoid any <strong>in</strong>volvement at all <strong>in</strong> recurrent and provocativefallacies. But we can--and should--.-determ<strong>in</strong>e to deal with themon our terms rather than on those of others.This implies not only sett<strong>in</strong>g quantitative limits on our engagement<strong>in</strong> controversies of high (and <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g) marg<strong>in</strong>alfutilíty, but also on two qualitative ones. The first is that we act toset the conditions and the form of the discourse <strong>in</strong> which weconsent to participate, for the purpose of elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g both sheerrepetition and all the small-m<strong>in</strong>ded, often demagogic,stratagems and postur<strong>in</strong>gs that one would expect, if at all, ofsecondary school debates and not of mature academic discourse.The second is that we <strong>in</strong>sist on a faírly frank and clear specificationof the context (usually a complex of tacit assumptions andesoteric defmitions) of the discussion, s<strong>in</strong>ce the failure to do sooften artificiaUy restricts the full scope of the discussion orotherwise puts one group of discussants, from the start, underunfair burden. It is only prudent to ensure that the terms ofdiscourse, like the terms of trade, are not always unfavorable tothe same people.Let us try to iIlustrate, briefly, with reference to several of thecontroversial perennials. The issues of economic plann<strong>in</strong>g andmathematical economics have already been discussed and will bepassed over here, except to say that we ought to <strong>in</strong>sist at theoutset ofany further discussion of these that (I) it be recognizedthat,,ve ate not opposed to plann<strong>in</strong>g, but only to a special form ofir; (2),,ve reject not mathematics per se, but its irrelevant ordistortive application to economic analysis; and (3) we shall notcont<strong>in</strong>ue <strong>in</strong> any dh_=ussion which does not accept these dist<strong>in</strong>ctions.(a) Although discussion of socialism and capitalism as alternatireeconomic systems long ago ran <strong>in</strong>to dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g retums,


218 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>very litfle has been done about chang<strong>in</strong>g the context. From thestart, Marxista restricted itself to a detailed exposition of the<strong>in</strong>ner stresses expected to emerge with<strong>in</strong> capitalist systems,which would eventually br<strong>in</strong>g about theír collapse and replacementby socialist regimes. Now, over a century later, the latterhall of which has seen one major such state <strong>in</strong> actual operation,together with a number of satellites, expositions of the contradictionsof capitalista cont<strong>in</strong>ue, :e while those of socialista are eithervery fighfly touched upon or ate allowed to be buried withobfuscation.Despite the fact that many crucial predictions of Marxista havefailed (e.g., the theory of immíserization, the <strong>in</strong>dustrial reservearmy, the absorption of the middle class, the wither<strong>in</strong>g of thestate, etc.), we ale stiU largely defend<strong>in</strong>g (or criticiz<strong>in</strong>g) theoperation of capitali.qm only. On a more theoretical level, boththe "transformation problem" and the calculation critique wiUillustrate clearly the obfuscation mentioned above.We should therefore cease acced<strong>in</strong>g to discussions of the problemsof one system only, or those which compare the actualoperation of one with only putative weaknesses <strong>in</strong> the other.Instead, there ought to be some <strong>in</strong>sistence on the use of somecommon denom<strong>in</strong>ator for comparison---preferably a set of performancestandards capable of empirical verification. The design<strong>in</strong>gof such standards admittedly would be difficult--giventhe <strong>in</strong>commensurabilifies of economic organization and, <strong>in</strong> par-Ücular, the differ<strong>in</strong>g degrees of coyness with which data aremade available---but the task is far from an impossible one withwhich to challenge young scholars.In fme, the burden of proof should shift <strong>in</strong> part, so thatsocialists, too, would llave to defend their system aga<strong>in</strong>st thecharge that it is fail<strong>in</strong>g. Nor should an ideological "détente" bepermitted to take the place of the rapidly evanesc<strong>in</strong>g politicalmilitaryone; their "drift" toward capitalism is not on the sameroad as ours toward socialista---so we may never meet. They areback<strong>in</strong>g slíghtly away from sociali_t arrangements which did notwork; while <strong>in</strong> the West we never really got m try<strong>in</strong>g a really freemarket system.


Toward a Program of Research and Development 219(b) In our differences with macroeconomic analysis, we havebeen once aga<strong>in</strong> too accommodat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> our will<strong>in</strong>gness to acceptits context and def<strong>in</strong>itions. By this context, macroeconomics istaken to be a system of causal and other relationships amongaggregative economic entities and consequently ah alternative tomicroeconomic_ and, <strong>in</strong>deed, often <strong>in</strong> sharp conflict with it. Assuch, it has been vigorously resisted and opposed by free-marketeconomists. But suppose this conceptíon of macroeconomics isneither the only---or correct----one?Ir is by now virmally forgotten that it was the <strong>in</strong>tention of thepioneers of national <strong>in</strong>come estimates to set up the equivalent ofa profit-and-loss statement for the whole economywlike its prototype,ex post and evaluative. Indeed, Kuznets (a founder andlead<strong>in</strong>g architect of national <strong>in</strong>come statistics) states this factunequivocally: 27... national <strong>in</strong>come is the end product of a country's economicactivity,reflect<strong>in</strong>g the comb<strong>in</strong>ed play of economic forces and serv<strong>in</strong>g to appraisethe prevail<strong>in</strong>g economic organization <strong>in</strong> terms of its returns.Be<strong>in</strong>g thus a summaryand appraisalnotionratherthanan analytical_enS_.,national <strong>in</strong>come demands statistical measurement. [Emphasisaddexl.lIn this case, as before, ,,vecan <strong>in</strong>sist on the recogrñtion of thedist<strong>in</strong>ction between macroeconomics asa set ofexpost data on theoutcomes <strong>in</strong> the economy andas a dist<strong>in</strong>ct explanatory theory--emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g that taken <strong>in</strong> the lo¿roer sense we accept, and evenwelcome, ir asa valuable supplement to any explanatiorj of thework<strong>in</strong>g of the market economy. Ifthis is done, we may be able toavoid becom<strong>in</strong>g enmeshed <strong>in</strong> a host of wasteful efforts of whichthe follow<strong>in</strong>g are illustrations.One is the frequenfly-heard wish that some way be sought tocoord<strong>in</strong>ate macro- and micro-models of analysis--presumablyas separate parts oran even grander, more <strong>in</strong>clusive explanatorymodel. This appears to be at least.improbable, given their mutuallycontradictory explanadons, and would comprise an <strong>in</strong>excusablewaste of time and talent ff the correct disposiUon of theconflict turro out to be not the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of the two, but the


220 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>subord<strong>in</strong>ation of one to the other as serv<strong>in</strong>g very different butcomplementary functions,z8Another is the h_terest<strong>in</strong>g--and generom---offer recentlyvoiced by Lachmann:29that we undertake to "subjecfivize"themacro-enfities by some process of disaggregafion unfil they areconsistent with subjectivechoice. One suspects that this arduouseffort willmerely lead us backout of the look<strong>in</strong>g glassand <strong>in</strong>tothe familiarmicro-economicworld. Fortunately, this travailwillprove unnecessary ff the subord<strong>in</strong>ation we have menfionedturns out to be the correct relaon between micro- and macroeconomics.III.Ifit is to be taken seriously, any body of theories about the realworld must eventually take its own measure aga<strong>in</strong>st that reality.To rail to do somay avoid, fora time, the risk of disconfirmaon,but also forgoes the opportunity for potent re<strong>in</strong>forcement.It is often daimed, <strong>in</strong> defense of delay, that the particular andaccidental forros <strong>in</strong> which actual events present themselves aredifferent and <strong>in</strong>congruent with those of abstract, systemacthought--and this, of course, is true <strong>in</strong> part. But, while the mostgeneral proposions of a theory may not lend themselves todirect observaon, the deducve work<strong>in</strong>g out of their implicaonsshould tend to produce subsidiary statements whose forroand content lend themselves to some forro of comparison Mthempiñcal reality--if not bythe structured methods of posivisc"scietace,"then by <strong>in</strong>formed subjectivejudgment Cverstehen").The need for some sort of outside confirmaon is especiallyimportant for those theoretical systems whích, like <strong>Austrian</strong>economics, make the claim that the), ate axiomatic and apodicUcallytrue--and are therefore open to the facile criticism thatthey ate purely formal (Le., devoid of real content) and alemerely <strong>in</strong>ternMly comistent circulañties.When, <strong>in</strong> addition to all this, the central proposions of atheory have great generality <strong>in</strong> their frame of reference, they


Toward a Program of Research and Development 291"vector" out to touch hands with other areas of analysis of ofactivity not normally subsumed with<strong>in</strong> the doma<strong>in</strong> of the theoryitself. This certa<strong>in</strong>ly appears to be the case with <strong>Austrian</strong>economics on at least two grounds: (1) it purports to deal with allhuman action and notjust one aspect or subset (economic activity);and (2) it <strong>in</strong>sists on the categorical primacy of <strong>in</strong>dividualchoice.In tuna, this generality of <strong>Austrian</strong> theory implies both anobligation and an opportunity; the obligation, on the one hand,to make whatever contributions it can to other areas to whích itspr<strong>in</strong>ciples apply, and, on the other, the opportunity to <strong>in</strong>vite andreceive contributions from people with special competence <strong>in</strong>such areas.The "field" for such mutuality of <strong>in</strong>terest extends not only toother theoretical discipl<strong>in</strong>es, but also to "applied" areas. Severalexamples of the former have already been mentioned <strong>in</strong> anotherconnection (i.e., statistics and mathematics); others will readilyoccur to the reader (consider, for example, the cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> theory on the part of philosophers, politicaltheorists, legal scholars, et al.) and will not be discussed here.The specific task of the f<strong>in</strong>al section of this paper wiU be tooffer illustrations of more practical, operational areas whichbear this sort of <strong>in</strong>terface with <strong>Austrian</strong> analysis. Spaie--and thepatience of the reader--will permit only a ver), small sampl<strong>in</strong>g ofthese; their selection should not be taken to <strong>in</strong>dicate their importancerelative to the many omitted, but merely as an attempt toshow range and diversity.A. Bus<strong>in</strong>ess operations and management should be the mostobviom and easiest---of the applied areas with which to establíshthe sort of two-way communication we are discuss<strong>in</strong>g. Yet,the exchange between economists and bus<strong>in</strong>essmen cont<strong>in</strong>ues tobe very disappo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g both <strong>in</strong> extent and quality. (The manyhistorical,imtitutional,and other factorsbeh<strong>in</strong>dthis puzzl<strong>in</strong>gand complex state of affairs---and the possibilities for chang<strong>in</strong>git--are clearly beyond the scope of this paper.) s° Nevertheless,the relatively realistic nature of its concept of the economic


!22_ <strong>New</strong> Direc_rns <strong>in</strong> duran <strong>Economics</strong> !process, together wi_ i¿s emphasis on the power of <strong>in</strong>dividualaction, gives <strong>Austrian</strong> economics a special opportunity toexplore some proxima_ and straighfforward possíbili6es for "_mutual comribuons.(1) Bus<strong>in</strong>ess o_fions offer a vast theater for _sf<strong>in</strong>g theadvanmges of reliance on the mofivafion and responsibilit 7 of<strong>in</strong>dividuals. Indeed, management _eorists s_ have presented acompellíng case for mov<strong>in</strong>g away from traditional centralizedand authoñtañan organi_zational designs of decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g responsibility("Theory X") and toward more reliance on decentralized,<strong>in</strong>dividually oriented <strong>in</strong>itiatives ("Theory Y"). Experimentationwith changes along these l<strong>in</strong>es has had to becautious and marg<strong>in</strong>al (s<strong>in</strong>ce firms must operate with<strong>in</strong> the constra<strong>in</strong>tsof the cost-recoup<strong>in</strong>g"imperative'), and the results thuslar have not been uniformly condusive. Detailed and frankanalysis of <strong>in</strong>stances of success and f_ure <strong>in</strong> such experimentswould appear to offer <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g opportunities for practitionersto confer with theorists, to the benefit of both.(2) Regular consultation with bus<strong>in</strong>essmen would not onlyacqua<strong>in</strong>t the latter wíth the often esóteñc language and conceptsof economic theory, ir would also tend to reduce the risks thattheorists run when they depart from realism. To use one of thepo<strong>in</strong>ts already familiar to the reader as illustration: It is <strong>in</strong>conceivablethat the prevail<strong>in</strong>g conception of the enLrepreneurialfuncáon <strong>in</strong> traditional economic theory would app_ar to actualentrepreneurs as accurate. If this conception is <strong>in</strong> serious error, avery long sequence of theoriz<strong>in</strong>g--as well as costly policies deriv<strong>in</strong>gfrom it---could have been averted by the simple process ofidentify<strong>in</strong>g the picture of the entrepreneur which was implicit <strong>in</strong>the early analysis and mak<strong>in</strong>g it explicit so that experiencedpractitioners could evaluate it.Even now, it would be useful to do this. For any revision of therole of the enterpriser wiU <strong>in</strong>volve radical changes <strong>in</strong> the traditionalmodels of the operation of the economy and wiUthereforenot be embraced immediately or with enthusiasm. The cooperationof bus<strong>in</strong>essmen will not only help confirm that the revision isrealistic, but they can help flesh it out further.


Toward a Program of Research and Development 223(3) The subjective view of human action necessarily puts agreat deal of reliance on the concept of"verstehen"---a compositeof experience, <strong>in</strong>tuition, and other qualities not adequatelyconveyed by the word "understand<strong>in</strong>g." The prevail<strong>in</strong>gpositivist temper ofour age is apt to dismiss so subjective a notionas be<strong>in</strong>g simply vague (if not worse) unless it is buttressed bypractical and highly realistic examples. These are best and most<strong>in</strong>fluentially to be provided by those experienced <strong>in</strong> a variety ofmanagement decisions <strong>in</strong> which the "objective" data had to beevaluated and supplemented by human judgment.(4) F<strong>in</strong>ally, this very subjectivity has important implicationsfor the proper tole of present managers <strong>in</strong> the education ofthose who wiUfollow them. 8_For, ifthe essence ofwhat they do issubjective, ir cannot be conveyed adequately either by rigid setsof rules or by abstract models devised largely without referenceto the realities of actual performance. There is reason to th<strong>in</strong>kthat just sucia a deficiency now exists and is be<strong>in</strong>g dealt with byon-the-job remedial action. The prevalence and extent of managementtra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g programs <strong>in</strong> so many ofour large corporationsma), thus be a tadt_and very cosfly--cñUcism of the adequacyof programs <strong>in</strong> the formal education of young bus<strong>in</strong>ess managers.B. This bñngs us to the second illustrative area---and one veryclose to home. Quite apart from its content--one aspect ofwhichwe havejust now touched on--the organization of formal educationon the collegiate and even on the graduate level is deeply<strong>in</strong>consistent with subjecfivism. In this respect, we <strong>in</strong> educationhave lagged far beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong>dustry, where, as we saw a little earlier,there has been at least some attempt to give greater scope to<strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>itiative and provision. But where, <strong>in</strong> our own house,is the application of the same "Theory Y" which we have beenurg<strong>in</strong>g on others? The fact is that education rema<strong>in</strong>s---as it haslong been essentially patemalistic and authoritarian. Persist<strong>in</strong>gpatterm of sanctions and rewards are hardly conduciveto-.or even tolerant of--the exercise of<strong>in</strong>dependentjudgmentsand valuations by the <strong>in</strong>dividual student. True academic free-


224 Neto <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>dom (that is, <strong>in</strong> its orig<strong>in</strong>al mean<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>tent) has more theappearance of a class privilege reserved to the faculty than an<strong>in</strong>tellectual right that extends to students--or even to applicantsfor faculty positions.A litfle reflection by anyone who has attended coUege, andesped_lly graduate school, will suggest many examples of thisperverse state of academic affairs--and the po<strong>in</strong>t will not bepursued here. But it should be obvious that subjective theoristshave herea special obligatíon to establish a dialogue with educafionaladm<strong>in</strong>istrators and others and to seek ways <strong>in</strong> which smdentscan be encouraged--certa<strong>in</strong>ly not discouraged--<strong>in</strong> theexercise of <strong>in</strong>dependent judgment.C. The third and f<strong>in</strong>al example, literature, is illustrative of alarge class of pursuits or professiom whose essence and pracácedepend sígnificantly on <strong>in</strong>dividual effort and on subjeaive values.The history of literatures from Milton to Solzhenitsynexhibits real concern for <strong>in</strong>dividual freedom of expression andof actionS3--often defended courageously and at great personalcost. Moreover, as the case of the Fabian Society illustrates all toowell, it is possible for people of great literary talent to become<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> social and economic issues and to present these tothe read<strong>in</strong>g public with great potency and effect. Here, aga<strong>in</strong>,<strong>Austrian</strong> theorists would seem to have the opportunity and theobligation to establish and ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> communication with aHthosemhowever distant from strict economy theorymwho sharetheir <strong>in</strong>sight on the nature and significance of human action.REFERENCESI. Although itwas pjablishedthree yearsafter the others, the workof Ix,on Walras (E/ímnUsd'í_ono_ po//t/quspuf,, 1874) is now generallyaccepted as <strong>in</strong>dependently developed.2. Unforumately, th_lterm is currently be<strong>in</strong>g used for th<strong>in</strong>gs verydifferent from this, its orig<strong>in</strong>al mean<strong>in</strong>g, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> unnecessaryconfuaon. Cf.,e.g., P.A. Samuelson,Ec_: da Introduetorydnalysis,


Toward a Program of Research and Development 2257th ed. (<strong>New</strong> York, 1967), pp. 351-52; and also, <strong>New</strong>sweek, Ma}, 12,1975.3. Were it not for this double purpose and the related need to savespace, maexcellent example would be provided by the extended discussionby so many Marxists and their opponents of the so-called "transformationproblem" s<strong>in</strong>ce B6hm-Bawerk (Karl Marx and theCloseof HisSystem, London, 1898).4. This may also apply to extended discussions with less antagonisticcriti_. For example, as Ludwig Lachmann observed at a recentconference on <strong>Austrian</strong> economics (Milwaukee, March 1976), the longdiscussions follow<strong>in</strong>g Knight's criticism of Austrían capital theory tooktime whida was needed eBewhere.5. F. A. Hayek, "The <strong>New</strong> Confusion about Plann<strong>in</strong>g," MorganGuaranty Survey, January 1976.6. L. M. Spadaro, The Present State of Profa Theory: Asset orLiability?(Philadelphia, 1963).7. I. M. Kirzner, Competition and Entrepreneurship (Chicago, 1973).8. See Gerald O'Driscoll, "Spontaneous Order and the Coord<strong>in</strong>ationof Eeonomic Activities," elsewhere <strong>in</strong> this volume.9. <strong>New</strong>sweek, March 15, 1976.10. Gr., e.g., L. J. Savage, The Foundañons ofStatistics (<strong>New</strong> York,1954); also, L. M. Spadaro, "Averages and Aggregates <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>,"<strong>in</strong> M. Sennholz, ed., On Freedom and Free Enterprise (Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, 1956).11. Both Laplace (Théor/e analytique desprobabilités, París, 1814) andDe Morgan (/In Essay on Probability, London, 1838) regarded probabilityas the degree of belief <strong>in</strong> a proposition andas referr<strong>in</strong>g to a state ofm<strong>in</strong>d.12. Cf., e.g., E. Nagel, "The Mean<strong>in</strong>g of Probability," <strong>in</strong> J. R. <strong>New</strong>man,ed., The World ofMathematics (<strong>New</strong> York, 1956), rol. 2, pp. 1398-1414; F. J. Anscombe and R. J. Aumann, A Def<strong>in</strong>ition of SubjectiveProbability," Annals ofMath. Stat., rol. 34 (196B), pp. 199-205. It is<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g, too, to note that J. M. Keynes, <strong>in</strong> an early work on thissubject (d Treatise on Probability, London, 1921), treats probability asadirectly íntuitable relation which, while capable of vary<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> degree, isnot analyzable by the calculus of probability.1£. One of the earliest and most able of tnose <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>itially <strong>in</strong>the truly subjective aspect of probability, Thomas Bayes, also em.-phasized its relation to degrees of belief (cf., his two memolrs mpidlo_hical Transactions, 1763 and 1764). Nowadays, however, bisname ls almost exclusively associated--because of a theorem of his(Bayes's Theorem)--with conditional probability. . - .14. E._., S. B. Richmond, O/_eratíonsResearchfor Managemem uec_-s/ons (Ne_ York, 1968),pass/m, _spec. pp. 129-33, 148--52,and 541-47.


226 <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>15. Cf., e.g., R. Carnap, "What is Probability," Sc/ent/fg ,4rn¢dcan(September 1953), pp. 128-36.16. Cf. F. A. Hayek, "<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," <strong>in</strong> IndividualistaandEconomic Order (Chicago, 1948), pp. 33-56; also, G.J. SÜgler, "The<strong>Economics</strong> of Information,'Jour. Pol. Econ. (June 1961), pp. 213-25.17. The modero resurgence of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> the analysis of <strong>in</strong>formationbeg<strong>in</strong>s with a sem<strong>in</strong>aIpaper by Claude Shannon (C. E. Shannon,"A MathemaÜcal Theory of CommunicaÜon," Bell Syst. Tech. Jour.[1948]. For more general implicafions, see N. Wiener, Cyhernet/cs[<strong>New</strong>York, 1948]).18. For comprehension of various aspects of this atea, see: C.Cherry, On Human Communication, 2nd ed. (Cambñdge, Mass., 1966);J. 1L Pierce, Symbo/s, Signals and Noise: The Nature and Proce.ssof Commun/cat/on(<strong>New</strong> York, 1961); and espec. H. Theil, Econom/csand InformatmTheor_ (Chicago, 1967).19. One mteresf<strong>in</strong>g example is an attempt to use communícationtheory to buttress what is essentially a variant of many <strong>in</strong>flationistschemes: S. Bagno, The ,4ngd and the Wheat: Coramunication Theoryand<strong>Economics</strong> (<strong>New</strong> York, 1963). UnfortunateLy, space does not permitanextended analysis of the <strong>in</strong>flationism <strong>in</strong>volved, but its dedication isreveal<strong>in</strong>g:"Dedicated toClaude Shannon and Norbert WienerWhose Theorems ate the Fcmndationsof a ConsistentEamomic Doctñneand toJohn LawWhose Methods Enabled Us to Learn Our True Potential"20. Cf., e.g., Pierce, op. di., chap. 5.2I. For a detailed exposition, see N. Georgescu-Roegen, TheEntr0pyLaw and the E_onomi¢ Process (Cambridge, Mass., 1971).22. K.E. Bould<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>Economics</strong>AsaSdence (<strong>New</strong> York, 1970), p. I01.23. The writer had occasion to make this same suggeson some timeago <strong>in</strong> another context: L. M. Spadaro, "The Heuristic VaIue of Simulation<strong>in</strong> Bus<strong>in</strong>ess and Economic Research," Pro¢ml<strong>in</strong>gs, ,4wwr. Sta_Assoc., 1966, pp. 73-79.24. <strong>New</strong>sweei_,January 19, 1976.25. Cf., e.g., A. D. Aleksandrov, A. N. Kolmogorov, and M. A.Lavrent ev, eds., M_: lts Content, Methods, and Mmn<strong>in</strong>g, Eng.transL, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass., 1969), espec, vol. 3, chap. 18.26. The most recent example known to the writer is D. P. Bell, TheCultural Contradictionso_ Capitalm (<strong>New</strong> York, 1975).27. S. S. Kuznets, National Income," Eno)d. Soc. Sd. (1933) andrepr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Amer. Econ. Asso_, _/n t/_ T/u_ 7 oflncom D/s-


Toward a Program of Research and Development 227tr/but/on (Philadelphia, 1949), pp. 3--43. The quotation here is fromp. 3.28. For discussion of some of the difficulties and errors result<strong>in</strong>gfrom attempts to establish causal relationships among macro-quantitiesdirectly, cf., H. Theil, "Alternative Approaches to the AggregationProblem," <strong>in</strong> E. Nagle, P. Suppes, and A. Tarski, eds.,Log/c, Methodology,and Philosophy of $cience (Stanford, 1962).99. Also <strong>in</strong> Iris remarks at the Milwaukee conference cited <strong>in</strong> note 4.30. The writer is plann<strong>in</strong>g a monograph which is expected to <strong>in</strong>dudea detailed analysis of this situation.31. Cf., e.g., D. McGregor, The Human Side ofEnterprise (<strong>New</strong> York,1960); A. H. Maslow, Eupsychian Manageraent (Homewood, I11.,1965);and P. F. Drucker, Management: Tasks, Responsibiliti_, Practices (<strong>New</strong>York, 1973).32. For a literate and cogent discussion of this role, cf., H. M. Boet-Unger, "Is Management Really ah Art?" Harvard Bus. Reo., (January-February 1975), pp. 54--63.33. For one suggestive example from literary criUcism, cf., L. Trill<strong>in</strong>g,The L/bera/Imag/nat/on (<strong>New</strong> York, 1950).


INDEXAckley, Gardner, Macroeconomic Ayer, A.J.,Language, Truth, andLogic,T/m_, 203 n56 55 n2Action: <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> theory, 24; axiomof, 50-52; conceptualization and, Bagno, S.,TheAngdandtheWheat,22625--36; erroneous, 61--63; praxeol- n19ogy and, 50, 54; probabity <strong>in</strong>, Bíáley, Mart<strong>in</strong> J., "Review of Cap/ta/51-32 and Its Structure," 139 n31Alchian, Armen A., 88, 91 Barriers to entry, 97-99; legal, 10"2,Alek$androv, A. D., et al., eds., 108-109; monopoly and, 95, 9fiMath¢ma6_, 226 n25 Bayes, Thomas, 225 n12Alertness, ó8-89Becker, Gary S.: on time preference,Amcombe, F. J., and IL J. Aumann, 161; a/so su Ghez, Gilbert"A Def<strong>in</strong>ion of Subjecve Proba- Bell, D. P., The Cu/tura/Contrad/consbility," 225 n12of Capitalista, 226 n26Antitrust approaches, erroneom, 98 Blanshar d, Brand, Reason andApplication of theory, 220--224 Ana/y_, 55 nn7,8A priorí'sm, 19-20, 49-52 Boett<strong>in</strong>ger, H. M., uIs ManagementArmentano, D. T., ix, 94--110; The ReaUy ah Art?" 227 n32MythJ of An6trust, 109 nn4,5 B6hm-Bawerk, Eugen ron: capitalArrow, K. J.: "Limited Knowledge dimensions, 169; Capital and InandEconom_AnalDh," 18nS;on retes¿ 166n17, 201 nnll,19, 202market economy, 12-15 n31; on capital/produaion time,Asset markets, 3--4; volaÚlity of, 4--6 179; capital theory, 1-2; <strong>in</strong>terestAumann, 1LJ.,see Anscombe, F. J. theory, 158;KarlMarxandtl_Close<strong>Austrian</strong> differentia, 23--24 of His System, 225 n3; "PositiveAum'ianeconomics, vii-x, 1 etptm/_" Theory of Capital," 166 n17; onfuture development, x, 205-227 production time, 170-171Amwm method, $2-.S5 Bond market, 162-163<strong>Austrian</strong> School: Chicago School and, Bould<strong>in</strong>g, K. E.,Econom/csasa Sdence,122-124; ¢oord<strong>in</strong>ation and, 128- 226 n22155; on equilibrium, 129-.134; Buchanan, James M.: on the Chicagomoney-suppl F def<strong>in</strong>itions, 143-- School, 137 nl9;CostandChoice, 92156; plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>, 127, 128-154; ni; '_'he Justice of Natural Libqxmtanemuorderand,128-154 erty," 135nl; on the London"Autonomy of the human m<strong>in</strong>d," School of <strong>Economics</strong>, 81-82; "Pub-129-150 lic Goods and Natural Liberty," 137229


230 I___:n222; on social cost, 78, 89; on Clower, Robert W., 116; Monaaryspontaneous order, 116Theor/, 155 nlBuchanan, J. M., and G. F. Thirlby: Coase, R. H.: on competidon andL. S. E. Es.uzyson C_JZ,92 market failure, 91; Pigou and,Burns, ArthurF.,Prospe_withoutln- 77-87; "The Problem of Socialf/at/on, 156 nll Cost," 77-79, 80, 86; on socialBus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle/s, 35-36; monetary ex- cost/pr_iuct, 77-92pansio_ and, 197; money supply Cohen, Morris 11.,.4 Prf_ace to Logic,and, ix, 152-154; Rothbard on, 197 38 n20Bus<strong>in</strong>essmen, economists' dialog Communications theory, 213-215with, 221-223 Compeddon, ix, 94-110; <strong>in</strong>correcttheories of, 97-99; plato <strong>in</strong>, 7--8;Calbr__i, G., '_rranmction Costs," 76 pure, 96-97; social cost and, 90-92n33 CompetiÜve condions, monopolyCambridge School, as Neo- vs., 95Ricardiam, 137 ni9 Competive process, monopoly and,Cantillon-effects, 139 n36 101Capital: dimensions of, 169; quantity Concept, prioHty of, 51of, and <strong>in</strong>vestment, 179--188 Conceptualization: action and,Capital theory, 1-2, 35,179-180; _b- 25-36; plato and, 25-36jeávism <strong>in</strong>, 10-11 Consumpdon, <strong>in</strong>vestment relation-Capitalism, _ontroveres concern<strong>in</strong>g, ship, 182217-218 Controveres, dcal<strong>in</strong>g with, 217Carnap, Rudolf:P_0sop/tyandL0¿,/ca/ Coord<strong>in</strong>ation of economic activiti_Syntax, 55 n2; "What ii Probabil- 111-142; <strong>Austrian</strong> school and,ity?" 226 n15 128-135, 169; knowledge and,Cartmls, 106 n._ 119-120; Lachmann on, 119-120;Cassel, Gustar: capital dimensions, <strong>in</strong> macroeconomics, 169169-170; on the market economy, Cmt/s: calculat<strong>in</strong>g, 89-92; pñvate vs.12; T_ Nature and Nueu/ty ofln- social, 77, 80; social, viii, 77-93;tereJ¿ 201 nnl0,11 mbjective theory of, 82-83Catastxophe theory, 216 Credit expamion, 192-198; moneyCerficates of depmit (CDs), money supply and, 152-155suppiy and, 149-150 Credit <strong>in</strong>struments, money supplyChange, <strong>in</strong> Smithian economics, and, 149I 18-I 19Croce, Benedetto: "On the F.xxmomicCherry, C.,OnHtma_Cotmmmim6o_ Pñndple7 74n5; on error, 59-61,226 n18 61-65, 65ChicagoSchool: Aum'ianSchooland, Cropsey, Joseph, "The Invisible122-124; Marshalliím approach, Hand," 155 ni122; money-mpply def<strong>in</strong>ition, 145;as new Rkardiam, 118--124 De Breu, Getmd, 7_y of Va/ue038Choice: error and, 62-63; pure Iosic n18of, 2; _ cmtand,8$-86 Demanddeposita:u money,144-


Index 231146; not money, 151 Error, 57-76; choice and, 62-63; <strong>in</strong>De Morgan, Augustus, dn Essay on decision mak<strong>in</strong>g, viii, 57-76;Probab////y, 225 ni I economic, 59-61, 61-63; econom-Demsetz, Harold, on competitionand ics without, 64-67; <strong>in</strong> exercise ofmarket failure, 91 judgment, 62; ignorance and,Dernburg, Thomas F., and Duncan 67-69, 69-71; impossibility of,McDougai, Macroe¢onomics, 203 65--67; normative applications of,n55 73-74; technical, 59--61, 61-63;Determ<strong>in</strong>ism, 15-18 theory of, 57-58Distñbutional effects, 139 n36 Evidence, 48--49Doctr<strong>in</strong>al differences, viii, 19-39, Exchange, <strong>in</strong>tertemporal, 175-178118, 122-124 Exchange economy, <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>, ix,Dolan, Edward G., The Foundat/ons of 157-166ModtmA_<strong>Economics</strong>, 139 n35, Expectations: of speculators, 131-141 n60, 155 nl, 165 n5 132; subjectivism and, 1, 3-óDrucker, P. F., Management, 227 nS1Falsifiability, mean<strong>in</strong>g and, 42--44Econometrics: criUque of, 44-46; Iris- Federal sav<strong>in</strong>gs bonds, money supplytory and, 52-53, 54; praxeology and, 150and, 40-56; role <strong>in</strong> economic Ferguson, C. E,, The Neoclassicaltheory, 52-53Theoryof Production and Dtribution,Economic acfivities, coord<strong>in</strong>aon of, 37 nl111-142, 169 Fetter, Frank A., Capital, Interest, andEconomic man, entrepreneur as, 211 Rtnt, 164 n4Economists, dialog with others, 214- Fisher, Irv<strong>in</strong>g: price-level concepts,215, 221-223 9-10; The Purchas<strong>in</strong>g Power ofEducaUon, <strong>in</strong> subjectivism, 223-224; Money, I0, 144; The Theory of ln-Efficiency/Inefficiency, 57-58, 75 ttrest, 166 n13; on time preference,ni8; Leibemte<strong>in</strong> on, 63-64, 70-71 161Egger, John B., viii, 19-39 Fisher effect, 192Energy problem, market forre and, Free market system, 218; entre-136 ni6 preneurial funcÜon <strong>in</strong>, 210-212Eng<strong>in</strong>eers, dialog with economists, Friedman, Milton, 55 n12; on214-215 methodology, 40, 41; The Meth0do/-Entrepreneurial __nction, lms<strong>in</strong>ess- og? of Positive Econoraics, 54 ni,men'sviewson,222;<strong>in</strong>freemarket 55nn6,12,16; monetary theory,sy=_em,210--212 10; "A Monetary Theory of Na-Entrepreneurship, 24-27, 35; tional Income," 139 nS; The Opmonopolyand, 100-101 _rnum Quanti_ of Mono and OtherEntropy, 215 Essays, 202 n45; A Program forEquilibria, 5; <strong>Austrian</strong> approach, Monetary Stability, 140 n38; "A21-23, 129-134; dy_namic, Hayek- Theoretical Framework forian, 21-25; neoclassical approach, Monetary Analysis," 139 n3522--25; static, 20-23 Friedman, Milton, and Anna J.


=232 IndexSchwartz,"Moneyand the Bus<strong>in</strong>ess vidualism and the Economic Order,Cycle,"139 n34 37 nn2,6,9,10, 138 n26, 203 n53,Future markets, 11, 13 226 n16; on <strong>in</strong>formation, viii; <strong>in</strong>teresttheory, 158; Keynes con-Garrison, Roger W., ix, 166-204; on troversies, 114-116; marketmathemadcs, 38 n27; "Reflections economy and, 12; on mathematics,on Misesian Time Preference," 166 38 n29; '_The Mean<strong>in</strong>g of Compet<strong>in</strong>nl5,16tion," 138 n26; Monetar3 Theor3 andGeorgescu-Roegen, N., The Entropy the Trade Cycle, 129 n32, 200 n2,Law and the Economic Process, 226 202 nn48,49; <strong>in</strong> The Morgann21 Guaranty Survey, 140 nn42,43,46,Ghez, Gilbert, and Gary S. Becker, 225 nS; "The <strong>New</strong> ConfusionTheAllocationofTimeandGood._over about Plann<strong>in</strong>g," 225 n5; Nobelthe Life Cycle, 166 n13award, 19; <strong>in</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>gcontroversy,Greaves, Percy L.,MisesMadeEasier, 208; "Price Expectations," 133;164 nl, 165 n4 price-level concepts, 9; The Pr/reTheoryof Capital, 201 n13; on pricesHaberler, Gottfried, see Streissler, and price changes, 124; PricesErich, et al. andProduction, 9, 179, 200 n2, 201Hadar, J., and W. R. RusseU, "Rules nn5, 7, 8, 24, 25, 202 nn38, 43,forOrder<strong>in</strong>gUncerta<strong>in</strong>Prospects," 44, 52; Prole, Inttrest and Invest-38n32 ment, 202 nn 42, 52, 53; TheHahn, F. H.: on market economy, Pure Theory of Capital, 37 n7,12-13; On the Notion of Equilibrium 138n27, 139n33, 201 nn22,26,<strong>in</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>, 18 n9202 n35; "Reflections on the PureHarcourt, G. C., Some Cambridge Con- Theory of Money of Mr. J. M.trovtrsits on the Theoryof Capita¿ 202 Keynes," 136 n8; "The Ricardo Efn36fect," 202-203 n53; The Road toHarcourt, G. C., and N. F. La<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Strfdom, 140 n46, 208; on scientificCapital and Growth, 202 n36thought, 36; on spontaneous order,Hayek, Friedrich A. ron: capital di- 118; on structure of production,mensions, 169; on capital/ 171-174; subjectivhm, 81; '`Threeproduction time, 179-181; on ElucidationsoftheRicardoEffect,"compefition and market failure, 203 n53; "Time Preference and91;TheCounterRevolutionofScitnce, I_'oductivity: A Reconsideration,"1, 81, 137n18, 158n25; on 165 n6; _I'he Use of Knowledge <strong>in</strong>economic plann<strong>in</strong>g, 125-127; Society," 37 n9; at W<strong>in</strong>chor Casfle"<strong>Economics</strong> and Knowledge," 21, sympodum, x$7 nng,10, 38 n29, 57, 74nl, Hayekian triangles, 171-174, 18575 n23, 155, 141 n58, 226 n16; on Hicks, John R.: Cat_t_daro/T/tot, 202equilibrium, 21-23; on expecta- n$7; Critical Essays on Moneta,)tions, 133; "The Facts of the Social Theory, 18 n6; on market economy,Sciences,"$9nn$7,$9;Fu//Emp/oy- 17; monetary theory, 10; "Amentat Any Príce? 5, 202 n45; lad/- Suggestion for Simplify<strong>in</strong>g the


Index 233Theory of Money," 10; .4 Theory of Jevons, w. Stanley: capital dimen-Economic History, 18 nl 1; "The sions, 169-170; capitaltheory, 179;Yield on Consols," 135 n5 on mathematics <strong>in</strong> economics,Historians: "cover<strong>in</strong>g laws," 16--18; 27-28; on production time, 170;econometrics and, 52-53, 54 The Theory of Political Economy, 38HoUis, Mart<strong>in</strong>, and Edward Nell, Ra- nn22,24, 75 n22, 201 nn9,15,19,29tional Economic Man, 55 rml 1,17Keynes, John Maynard: economicIgnorance: error and, 67-71 legacy, 112-116; The General TheoryIndifference, Law of, 69 of Employment, lnterest, and Mon 0,Inefficiency, see Efficiency/Inef- 112, 113, 114, 115; Hayek's criUficiencycisms of, 114-116; monetaryInferential systems, 212-213 theory, 10; "The Pure Theory ofInflaÜon, 123-124, 152-155 Money. A Reply to Dr. Hayek,"Information: <strong>in</strong> the economic pro- 136 nl0;A TreatiseonMoney, 18 n5,cess, viñ, 57-76; <strong>in</strong> economics, 19; 114-116; .4 Treatise on Probability,imperfect, 35; <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong>, 8; 213Lachmann on, 119-120; a/so see Keynes, Milo, ed., Essays of JohnKnowledge Maynard Keynes, 136 nl 1Information theory, 213--215 Kirzner, Israel M., viii, 57-76; on theInstitute for Humane Studies, x; Chicago School, 121; Competitionsem<strong>in</strong>ars, 19 and Entrepreneurship, 37 n2, 75Interest: <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> macro- nn18,21, 81, 82, 89, 109n3, I10economics, 170; "orig<strong>in</strong>ary" nn16--22,32-34,37-39, 138n29,(Mises), 164 n2; <strong>in</strong> a pure exchange 140 n45, 225 n7; on competitioneconomy, ix, 157-166;<strong>in</strong>asocialist and market failure, 91; Theeconomy, 164; time allocation and, EconomicPo<strong>in</strong>t of View, 74 n6; on the164;Ümepreferenceand, 157, 166 entrepreneurial function, 211;Interest rate: with expansion ofcred- "Hayek, Knowledge and Marketir, 194-195; <strong>in</strong>tertemporal ex- Processes," 75 n23, 141 nn47-change and, 175--176; monetary 50,55; "Ludwig von Mises and thedisturbancesand, 192; <strong>in</strong> Rothbard Theory of Capital and Interest,"diagram, 177; structure of produc- 164 n2; "Mises and the Theory oftion and, 185Capital," 165 n4; monopoly theory,Intertemporal exchange, 175-178; 100-101, 104-108; on plans, 37-<strong>Austrian</strong> and Keynelian models, 38 n12; on spontaneous order<strong>in</strong>g178-179 forces, 128-129Intertemporal markets, 13-13 Kle<strong>in</strong>, Benjam<strong>in</strong>, "Review of Compea-Inve_nent, 179-188; <strong>Austrian</strong> and tion and Entrepreneurship," 139 n3Keynesian models, 187; consump- Knight, F. H.: on error, 62; on Pigou,don relationship, 182; <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>forma- 79; "Some Fallacies," 79, 80don, 8 Knowledge: coord<strong>in</strong>ation and, 119-Irrationality, error and, 58-59 120; imperfect, 61-63, 68-69;


234 IndexLachmann on, 119-120;limited, X-Efficiency Theory of theFirm,"12; perfect, 69; time and, 6-8; a/ro 75 n12; "Competition and X-_e Information Efficiency: Reply," 75 nn 12,13;Koch Industries, x "Entrepreneurship and Develop-Kolmogorov, A. N.,_e Aleksandrov, ment," 75 nn12,24; on error,A.D., et al. 64-66; on <strong>in</strong>efficiency, 63--64,Koopmans, Tjall<strong>in</strong>g C.: Three Essays 70-71on the State of Economic Science, 18 Leijonhufvud, Axeh "Effective Den7;on market economy, 12 mand Failures," 136 nlS, 137 ni6,Kuznets, S., 219; "National Income," 141 n59; <strong>in</strong> Keynesian controversy,226 n27 112-116; On Keynesian Economcsand the Economic_ofK¿,3nes,112, 136nn6,12Leontief, Wassily, "For a NationalLabor, orig<strong>in</strong>al means ofproducfion, Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g Board," 140169, 171 n44Lachmann, LudwigM.,viii, 1-18,225 Lerner, Abba P., 131n4; "On Amtrian Capital Theory," Life <strong>in</strong>surance poficies, __ surren-141 n60, 165 n5; Capital and Its der values, 150-151Structure, 10-11, 37n2; on error, L<strong>in</strong>, I_<strong>in</strong>, "Are Time Deposits61-62; on knowledge, 119-120; on Money?" 155 n5macroeconomics, 220; "From Mises Liquidity, money supply and, 149to Shaclde," 138 n25, 14l nn52-54, Literature, 224142 nn62,63; on Neo-Ricardians, Littlechiki, S. C., viñ, 77-93157 n19; "Reflections on Hayekian London Economic Club, lOCapital Theory," 141 nnS1, 52; on London School of <strong>Economics</strong>, on sospontaneousorder<strong>in</strong>g forces, cial cost, 78, 81, 89128-134 Lutz, Frederick A.: "On NeutralLa<strong>in</strong>g, N. F., see Harcourt, G.C. Money," 140 n36;a/sosee Streissler,Lakatm, Imre, "FahificaÚon and the Eñch, _ o_Methodology ofScientific ResearchProgranm,"55 nn13,15Lakatos, Imre, and Alan Musgrave, McDougal, Duncan M.,see Dernburg,ed$., C_ and CheGrow¢h of Thomas F.Know/_, 55 nl$ McGregor, D., The Human S/de 0fEn-Land, orig<strong>in</strong>al meam of producfion, terpr/se, 227 n31169, 171 Machlup, Fritz: "Equilibrium andLaplace, Pierre Simon de, Thíor/e Disequilibrium," 37 nS; also see_ da pro_ 225 nll Streissler, Erich, eta/.Lamanne School, 121 McK<strong>in</strong>ley, Gordon W., "F.ffects ofLavrent'ev, M. A., _ Alehandrov, Federal Reserve Polio/," 156 ni IA. D., et al. Macroeconomic relafionships, ix,Leibemte<strong>in</strong>, H.: "Aliocative Effi- 166-204ciency v$. X-Efficiency," 75 Macroeconomics: aggregates andnnl2,14, 76n25; "Aspects of the <strong>Austrian</strong> economics, 8-11; Aus-


Index 235trian, 167-204; controversies con- Menger, Carl, 117; capital theory, 1,cern<strong>in</strong>g, 207, 219--220; further 2; on market evolution, 17; monestudy<strong>in</strong>,198-200;microeconomics tary theory, 34; Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples ofand, 219-220; subjectivism and, <strong>Economics</strong>, 39 n36; Problems of8--11 <strong>Economics</strong> and Sociology,18 ni2Malínvestment, 196-198 Methodological divergences, viii,Man, <strong>in</strong> economics, 36-37 40-56Management, 83; subjecÜvity and, Methodology, 32-35; positivism and,223 40-54Management theory, 222 Microeconomics, 219--220Mansfield, Edwín, Microeconomics, Misallocation of resources, <strong>in</strong>109 ni monopoly, 95, 96Marg<strong>in</strong>alism, 205--210; varieties of, Mises, Ludwig ron: on act<strong>in</strong>g man,206 81; on action, 51; a priorism,Marg<strong>in</strong>alist revolution, vil, 205 19-20; on capital dimensions, 169;Market economy, 2-3; criÜcsand de- on capital/production time, 179; "Afenders, 11-15; general equilib- Critique of B6hm-Bawerk'srium model, 14-15; <strong>in</strong> Keynesian Reason<strong>in</strong>g," 164 n3, 165 n4,economics, 116; plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>, 126; 166 nn12,14; Epistemological Probspontaneousorder <strong>in</strong>, ix, 111-142 lems of <strong>Economics</strong>, 37 n3; on errone-Market process, effectiveness <strong>in</strong> ousactions,61-63;onerror,58-63;coord<strong>in</strong>aon, 2-3 "evenly rotat<strong>in</strong>g economy,"Market system, 218; entrepreneurial 173,176; Human Action, 24-27,function<strong>in</strong>,210-212;<strong>in</strong>terventions 37nn2,3,11, 38n31, 56nn19,20,<strong>in</strong>, 207, 211 74 nS, 109 nn6-14, 110 n15,138Market theory, <strong>in</strong>formation and n27, 156 n12, 164 nnl,3, 166communications<strong>in</strong>, 213-215 n16, 200 nl, 201 nn12,21,27,Market value, social cost and, 89 202 nn31,32,33,47,51; on <strong>in</strong>flationMarshall, Alfred, 71-73; Pr/nc/p/es of with credit expansion, 152-155; <strong>in</strong>-<strong>Economics</strong>, 76 n28, 138 n30terest theory, ix, 157-166; marketMarxism, controversies concern<strong>in</strong>g, economy and, 12; on mistakes and207, 217-218 error, 58-59, 60--61; on monetary/Maslow, A. H., Eupsychian Manage- capital questions, 123; monetarymen¿ 227 n31 theory, 10, 34; "Money, Inflation,Mason, D. H., xand the Trade Cycle," 200 nl; onMathematicaleconomics, controversy money supply, 143-144; onover, 207 monopoly price, 103-104;Mathematics: analysis without _/'m- monopoly theory, 99--100, 104-bolic, 35; as an analytical tool, 108; Probab//y StaK¢ks and Truth,27-31; argument via, 215-216; 38n30; on rationality, 61--63, 65;plancomistencyand, 33-34; uncer- on socialist economy, 207-208;ta<strong>in</strong>ty ar.d, 81-32Theoff andH£¢0ry, 74 n3; The ThemyMaximizafion, 46-48 of Money and Cred/t, 39 n36, 143--Mean<strong>in</strong>g:._asthecriterion 144, 156nn9,10, 165n4, 200nl;of, 42--44; probability and, 43-44 on time depmits, 148=149; time


2S6I_¿_preference concept, ix, 157-166 National <strong>in</strong>come, 219--220Mistakes, 58--59Nell, Edward, ses Hollis, MarnMonetary disturbances, <strong>in</strong> Austñan Neocla_cal orthodoxy, 19macroeconomics, 188-198 NeoclasdcaI synthesis, 206Monetary policy, 36 Neo-Ricardians, 137 ni9Monetary theory, I0-II, 34-35; <strong>New</strong>man, James R., The World ofChicago S.chool, 123-124, 189; M_, _8 n23, 225 n12quantity, I0-II; subjectivism <strong>in</strong>, N¢wsweek, 225 nn2,99-11Money: evolution of, 34-38; neutral, O'Driscon, Gera]d P.,Jr., ix, I I 1-142,189--194; quanÜty theory of, 10--11 225 n8; <strong>Economics</strong> oz a Coord<strong>in</strong>atianMoney supply, ix, 143-156; <strong>in</strong> Aus- Problem, 137 n24, 138 n29,trian macroeconomics, 188-198; 140 n37, 201 n6; "Friedrich Hayek<strong>Austrian</strong> def<strong>in</strong>iÜons of, 143-156; and the <strong>Economics</strong> of Choice,"Chicago deFmiÜon of, 144; compo- 139 n32; "Hayek and Keynes: Anents of, 151-152; Fisher quanÜty Retrospective Assessment,"theory, 10 IS6n13; The Ricardian Nan-Monopoly: compeÜÚve process and, Equivalence Theorem, 138 n24101; entrepreneurship and, 100- O'Drigoll, Gerald P.,Jr., and Sudha101; government <strong>in</strong>tervendon and, R. Shenoy, "InflaÜon, Recesdon,I00, 102, 108-109; Kirzner def'mi- and StagflaÜon," lS9 n35Úon of, 101; neocla_cal def'miUon OpportuniÚes, entrepreneurial,of, 94-95; price and, 101-104, 69-71106-108; Rothbard's defmiÜon of, Opportunity cost, $5102, 108; sourcesof, 100; <strong>in</strong> un- Order, spontaneous, 111-142hampered markets, 100Monopoly theory, ix, 94-110; Aus- Pareto, Vilfredo, market economytrian, criUcal review of, 104-108; and, 12contemporary, 95-97; Kirzner's, Pat<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>, Don, 186100-101, 104-108; Mi__an, 99- Money, lnteres¿andPrir_, 201 n4,202100, 104-108; neodassical, 94-95, nn40,5096-97; Rothbard's, 102-104, 104- Physiocrats, 117109 Pierce, J. 1L, Symbols, $i¿mals, andMou, Laurence S., ix, 157-166; ed., Na/se, 226 nnl8_0The Ec_ of Ludwíg ven M/_, Pigou, A. C.: Coa_ and, 77-87; The164 n2 Ecenamirz of Wdfart, 78, 79, 80;Motivation, lackof, 63--64 monetary theory, 10; on socialMueller, Willard F., ,4 Pr/mer on cost/product, 77-93; '*The Value ofMonopo/y and Compet/t/on, 109 n2 Money," 18 n4; Wmlth and We_an,78, 79Nagel, E., _ Mean<strong>in</strong>gofProbabil- Plann<strong>in</strong>g, economic, $6, 124-128,ity," 225 ni2 207-208Nagel. E.. d aL. edL. Log/c. Met_,_do/- Piara: as the <strong>Austrian</strong> differentia. 2S.ogy. and Phau_ of Sdence, 227 24-87; of compef<strong>in</strong>g fn-ms. 7-8;n28 constencies and market. 23n;


Index 237modífication of, 24-25; prefer- ReferenÜal statements, 48-49ences and, 24-37 Research, future, 205--227Popper, Karh on falsif'uability,55 n5; Ricardians, new, 118-124The Log/c of Sc/en6fic D/scoveTy, 39 Ricardo, David, 118-124; On theP_<strong>in</strong>n33,55 n2; Log/k der Forschung, 55 dples of Political Economy and Taxn2;on scientific method, 33 at/on, 138 n24; The Works and Cor-Positivist economics, 40-56respondence of, 138 n24Posner, Richard A., 88Richmond, S. B., OperationsResearchPraxeology: action and, 50, 54; forManagementDecisions, 225n14econometñcs and, 40-56; logical Rizzo, Mario J.', vi, 40-5ócharacter of, 50-52Robb<strong>in</strong>s, Lioneh on the economis<strong>in</strong>gPrediction: ceter par/bus, 4_._.5; as man, 8l;AnEssayontheNatureandthe goal of science, 42-43 Significance ofEconomic Science, 81;Preference/s: "abstract logic of," 24; The Great Depression, 203 n54; onplans and, 24-37; $ubjectivism the representative firm, 71-73;and, 1 "The Representative Firm," 76Price/s: monopoly, 99--100; monop- nn26,27_29,32oly and, 101-104, 106-108 Robertson, Dennis, 71Probability: <strong>in</strong> action, 31-32; Rob<strong>in</strong>son, Joan,"Whathasbecomeofdegree-of-belief, 43-44; mean<strong>in</strong>g the Keynesian RevoluÜon?" 115and, 43-44; subjectivity and, 212- Rothbard, Murray N., ix, 14._-156;213 ,4merica'sGreatDepression,2, 155 nS,Prochnow, Herbert V., ed., The Fed- 201 n3; a priorism, 19-20; _f'heeral Reserve System, 156 ni 1 <strong>Austrian</strong> Theory of Money," 155Product differentiaon, 8, 97 nnl,6; on the bus<strong>in</strong>ess cyde, 197;Product markets, 3-4on capital dimensions, 169; Capital,ProducÜon:periodof,2;structureof, Interest, and Rent, 164n4; on169-174 capital/production time, 179; onProduction time, 170-174; <strong>in</strong>vest- cartels, I10 n36; "In Defense ofment and, 179-188 'Extreme Apriorism'," 56 n18;PubIicorganisations, 89-92 Man, Economy, and the State,Public utilies, social cost and, 77 37 nn2,3, 38 n14, 110 nn23-29,36,Pure exchange economy, <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>, 165 n7, 201 nn3,14,18,23,28,157-186 202 nn39,49; monopoly theory,102-109; "Praxeology: Reply toQu<strong>in</strong>e, W.V.,Met/w¿ofLo¿,/¢, 55 n19 Mr. Schuller," 56 n21; "Toward aReconstruction of Utility and Wel-Radford, R. A., "The Economic Or- fare <strong>Economics</strong>," 85ganization ofa P.O.W. Camp, _ 165 Russell, Bertrand: on mathemacs asn8a tool, 27; P_nciples of Mathematics,Rand, Ayn, _Introduction to Objec- 38 ni9tivist Epistemology," 38 nn 17,27 Russell, W. 1L,see Hadar, J.Reality,theoryand,220-224Redistribution of wealth, market as a, St. George's House, W<strong>in</strong>dsorCastle, x6 Samuelson, P. A., <strong>Economics</strong>, 224 n2


238 IndexSavage, L J., The Foundat/on of Stat- Social product: defmed, 83--84; diftics,225 nl0 ficulties <strong>in</strong> approach, 87-88; socialSav<strong>in</strong>gs, forced, 196 cost and, 83--87Sav<strong>in</strong>gs banks, check<strong>in</strong>g operations, Social value, 78-80156 n7 Socialism, controversies concern<strong>in</strong>g,Sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits, <strong>in</strong> the money sup- 208, 217-218ply, 146-148 Socialist economy, <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>, 164Sav<strong>in</strong>gs and loan shares, money sup- Sowell, Thomas: "Adam Smith <strong>in</strong>ply and, 148 Theory and Practice," 140 n40;Scale economies, 97-99 Classical<strong>Economics</strong> Reconsidered, 137Schlick, Moñtz, on falsifiability, 42; n20, 138 nn24_28Gesamme/_`4ufs_ze, 55 n7 Spadaro, Louis M., x, 205-227; "Av-Schumpeter, Joseph A., 208; Ht0ry erages and Aggregates <strong>in</strong>of Economic dnalysis, 18 n2, <strong>Economics</strong>," 225 nl0; "The139 n34; on Ricardo, 139 n34 HeurisÜc Value of Simulation,"Schwartz, Arma J.,see Friedman, Mil- 226 n23; The Present State of ProfitronTheor3, 225 n6Sennholz, M.,ed.,OnFreedomandFree Speculators: expectations, 131-132;Enterpr/se, 93, 225 nl0 <strong>in</strong> Keynesian orientaÜon, 112-114Shackle, G. L. S.: on determ<strong>in</strong>ism, Spontan¿ousorder, ix, 111-142; Aus-15-16;Epistemicsand<strong>Economics</strong>, 18 trian School and, 128-134; as esnn3,10;on error, 61-62; Expecta- sential economic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, 116-fían <strong>in</strong> Ecanomics, 38n51; on fu- 118tures, 12; on stability, 4 Stability, market, 4Shannon, Claude E., 226 nlg; "A Statiscal <strong>in</strong>ference, misapplication,Mathematical Theory of Com- 212-213municaÜon, n 226 ni8 StatisÜcal time series, 17-18Shenfield, Arthur, xStigler, G.J.: on the economics of <strong>in</strong>.Shenoy, Sudha IL, ed.,,4 Tiger by t_e formation, 63; on efficiency/Ta//, 140 n39; a/so see O'Driscoll, <strong>in</strong>efficiency, 58, 59, 63-65, 71-73;Gerald P., Jr. on entrepreneurial ability, 72; onSk<strong>in</strong>ner, A., "<strong>Economics</strong> and His- error, 58, 59, 63-65, 71; on motivatory--TheScottish Enlighten- tion, 63--64, 65; on social cost, 88,ment," 137 n23 89; Thany of Price, 89; "The Xis-Smith, Adam, 121; The W¢alth of Na- tence of X-Efficiency," 74 n2, 756ans, vil, 111, 118, 119, 211-212; nnlS,16, 76n30Thearj of Mora/St, n6mengs, 125 Streissler, Erich, ¢t al., Roads to Free-Social cost, viii, 77-93; calculat<strong>in</strong>g, doro, 140 n3689--92;choiceand,83--86;competi- Structure of production, 169-174;tion and, 90--92; concept of, 78--80; <strong>in</strong>vestment and, 178--188difficultie$ <strong>in</strong> approach, 87--88; Subjectivism/Subjectivity: <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong>market value and, 89; social prod- economics, 1; education <strong>in</strong>, 223--uct and, 83--87; subjectívist ap- 224; fumre development of, 209;proach to, 80-_, 85-86 management and, 223; <strong>in</strong> mar-


Index 239g<strong>in</strong>alism, 205--206; probability and, Unsettle¿i questions, 1-18212-213; social cost and, 80-86;value ímd, 3 Value: classical economic concept, 3;Suppes, P., see Nagel, E., et al. subjectivism and, 3Supply of money, see Money supply Value dimension, of capital, 169-170Value theory, 206Tagliacozzo, G., "Croce and the Na- Venn diagrams, 27ture of Economic Science," 60 Verstehen, 45--46, 54; history and, 53;Tarski, A., see Nagel, E., et o£.<strong>in</strong> practical evaluation of theory,Theil, H.: "Alternative Approaches to 220, 223the Aggregation Problem," 227n28; <strong>Economics</strong> and Information Wagner, Richard, 122nTheory, 226 n18Walras, Léon,121,138 n30; É/émentsTheory, economic, application of, d'économiepolitiquepure, 224 nl220--224 Walras's Law, 184Thirlby. G. F.: "Economísts'Cost Waste, 57-58Rules and Equili_Jum Theory," 83; Welfare economics, 77-92; social cmton management, 83; The Ruler, 83; <strong>in</strong>, 77set Buchanan, J.M.Wicksell, Knut, on <strong>in</strong>terest rate andTime: <strong>in</strong> Amtrian economics, 1-2; monetary expamion, 192knowledge and, 6-8; role of, 35 Wicksteed, Philip H., The CommonTime allocation, 161-162; <strong>in</strong>terest Sense ofPolitical Economy, 39 n36and, 164Wiener, Norbert, 226 nn17,19Time depmits, money supply and, W<strong>in</strong>dsor Casfle Symposium, v, x, 89148-149 Wiseman, J.: on management, 83;T'maedimendon, ofcapital, 169-170 "The Theory of Public UtilityTime preference, 2, 35; <strong>in</strong>terest and, Price--an Empty Box,"83; "Uncerix,157-166 ta<strong>in</strong>ty, Costs, and CollectiveTopology, 216 Economic Plann<strong>in</strong>g," 83Toulm<strong>in</strong>, Stephen, For_gg/g and Un-_g, 55 nn$,4 Yeager, I_land: "Essential Prol2ertiesTñll<strong>in</strong>g, L., The L/óem/Imag/nat/on, of the Medium of Exchange," 155227 n$$ ni; "The Keynesian Diversion,"116, 136 n14Unc_rm<strong>in</strong>ty, mathemaÜcsand,$1-32 Young, A. A., "Pigou's Wealth andUniversity College, at Buck<strong>in</strong>gham, x Welfare," 79


Louis M. Spadaro was born <strong>in</strong> <strong>New</strong> York City <strong>in</strong> 1913 and holdsthe A.B. and M.S. degrees from the City University of <strong>New</strong> York.He received bis doctorate <strong>in</strong> economics from <strong>New</strong> York University<strong>in</strong> 1955.A member of the faculty of Fordham University s<strong>in</strong>ce 1938,Spadaro has also served <strong>in</strong> various adm<strong>in</strong>istrative posts, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gDean of the Graduate School of Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Adm<strong>in</strong>istrationand Chairman of the Department of <strong>Economics</strong>.He is the author of numerous articles <strong>in</strong> economics and thetextbook <strong>Economics</strong>:An Introductory View (<strong>New</strong> York: Macmillan,1969).Spadaro is Prcsident of the Institutc for Humane Studies. Heis a member of and has held office <strong>in</strong> both Beta Gamma Sigmaand Omicron Delta Epsilon. His other memberships <strong>in</strong>clude theMont Pcler<strong>in</strong> Society, the American Economic Association, andthe American Statistical Association.


With the expand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence of <strong>Austrian</strong> thought <strong>in</strong> economicdebate, scholarly discussion has p[oduced major <strong>in</strong>sights<strong>in</strong>to theoretical questions. <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>collects contributions by scholars currently explor<strong>in</strong>g, ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,or extend<strong>in</strong>g the f'rontiers of economic analysis.Each paper <strong>in</strong> this volume advances significant po<strong>in</strong>ts andreveals the creative diversity of Austnan economic thought.In the course of this collection, traditional economic approachesare closely evaluated and often challenged. Among thecontributions are found:• D. T. Armentano's critique of neoclassical and <strong>Austrian</strong>monopoly theory• Roger Garrison's <strong>in</strong>tegration of macroeconomic relationships<strong>in</strong> capital theory with microeconomic decision-mak<strong>in</strong>g• Israel Kirzner on the economics of <strong>in</strong>formation andentrepreneurship• Steven Littlechild's exam<strong>in</strong>ation of subjective social cost andwelfare economics• Gerald O'Driscoll evaluat<strong>in</strong>g the nature and stability of marketprocesses• Mario Rizzo's reassessment of positivism and praxeologyas economic methodology• Murray Rothbard on conventional and <strong>Austrian</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itionsof the money stockIn open<strong>in</strong>g and clos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>New</strong> <strong>Directions</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economics</strong>,Professors Lachmann and Spadaro provide a retrospectiveand prospective survey for <strong>Austrian</strong> economic research.This dist<strong>in</strong>guished volume presents <strong>in</strong>valuable explorations <strong>in</strong>tomany of the most crucial issues fac<strong>in</strong>g modern economics.In U.$.A,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!