10.07.2015 Views

who's afraid of legal pluralism?

who's afraid of legal pluralism?

who's afraid of legal pluralism?

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

WHO'S AFRAID OF LEGAL PLURALlSM?Franz von Benda-BeckmannJOURNAL OF LEGAL PLURALlSM2002 - nr. 47in relation to feelings <strong>of</strong> justice <strong>of</strong> a majority <strong>of</strong> the population, is an empíricalquestion.4. Law and {he stateMost <strong>of</strong> these consíderalions are relevant, whelher or nOl one defines law inconneclion with the slale. But they reappear in the discussions on whether lhe linkwith the slale should be buill into the concept as a conslant crilerion or beregarded as one variation. In the following, J shall try lo capture the differemargumemations.EvoLuTionis/ assumpTionsMany anthropological, soeiological and <strong>legal</strong> science underslandings <strong>of</strong> theevolution <strong>of</strong> social and political organisalion saw law and <strong>legal</strong> systems as themost advanced and civilised form <strong>of</strong> normative ordering and ralional rule guideddecision making. Regarding social and political organisation discovered in the 19'hand 20'h centuries which had no clear hierarchically organised (state-like) politicalsystems, where no courts or clearly recognisable lhird party instilutions wereclearly institutionalised, which had no wrillen rule syslems,' and in whichnormative knowledge was not sharply differentiated, lhe queslion <strong>of</strong> whether suchsocieties had 'Iaw' presented problems to many European observers.In much evolulionisl <strong>legal</strong> anthropology around the turn <strong>of</strong> the 19,h century, thedislinction law - non-Iaw was a non-issue. Maine (1861) spoke <strong>of</strong> Ancien! Law,Bach<strong>of</strong>en (1861) <strong>of</strong> MutterrechT,and also the German scholars like POSl andKohler did nol find it difficult lo use law in relation lO lhe normalive systems <strong>of</strong>lhe socielies discovered in Afriea and Asia (see also Schott 1982 for Germanelhnological jurisprudence). Differences belween types <strong>of</strong> law in their view couldbe marked by adjectives (ancienl, tribal, and primilive) that characterised lhespecific nalure <strong>of</strong> lhese laws. These aUlhors saw dramatic changes and evolution<strong>of</strong> <strong>legal</strong> systems within the overall category <strong>of</strong> law, aware <strong>of</strong> a wide range <strong>of</strong>variable empirical manifeslalions <strong>of</strong> law though time and space.Later evolutionist wrilers adopled a different approach. They held lhat thesesocieties had nol yet reached the state <strong>of</strong> political and normative organisation thalcould be called state anq law. They developed evolulionist typologies <strong>of</strong> normsand decision making processes. The crucial crilerion used for making thedislinctions between such law and earlier forms <strong>of</strong> norrnalive ordering was lhedifferemiation and instilutionalisalion <strong>of</strong> rule making and sanctioning inslilUtions.- 52 ­We then see an evolution from unsanctioned custom, to diffuscly sanctioned socialnorms, early forms <strong>of</strong> near-law to the state <strong>legal</strong> systems as they had developed inEurope (see Diamond 1935; Von Trotha 2000).Many later anthropological ~nd sociological wntmgs about law retained theevolutionist assumptions, but in a watered·down fashion. Functional equivalentswere sufficient, for instance for L1ewellyn and Hoebel (1941), Hoebel (1954) andPospisil (1971). Law remains directly tied to political organisation, but th.ispolitical organisalion need not necessarily have tlle character <strong>of</strong> a state. No~ dldthe 'pro tanto <strong>of</strong>ficials' need to have the character <strong>of</strong> a state court. BUI the loglc <strong>of</strong>definilion,lhe dependence <strong>of</strong> law or the <strong>legal</strong> on organised sanctioning, was lhe~same (see F. von Benda-Beckmann 1986; see also Tamanaha 1993, 2000). 11should be noted, though, thal, perhaps with the exception <strong>of</strong> Pospisil, lheseauthors did not consider eonditions <strong>of</strong> overl <strong>legal</strong> <strong>pluralism</strong>. It is uncertain whatlhey would have concluded when 'real' stale instilutions co-existed with the type<strong>of</strong> third parties whicll otherwise would have fulfilled lheir crileria for <strong>legal</strong>ness. Jam therefore not eertain lhat Malinowski and olher early <strong>legal</strong> anthropologistswho accepte'd 'primitive law' as law should be regarded as the intellectualanceslors <strong>of</strong> the concepl <strong>legal</strong> <strong>pluralism</strong> (Tamanaha 1993). In my view, the lrueintelleclual ancestors are ralher lhose wrilers such as Weber 1U and Ehrlich (1913)who did nol take lhe normative claims to lhe <strong>legal</strong> monopoly <strong>of</strong> the state forgranted in theorelieal principie (see also J. Griffilhs 1986).EthnocentricityAnolher, yel relaled, argument againsl defining law withoul a conneclion to lhe state,or against developing law into an analytical comparative calegory, is theelhnocentricilY argumento According to Roberts (1979, 1998) using the concept <strong>of</strong>law for comparative purposes "means remaining implicated in the parochial scene.19 11 is characteristic for lhe writings <strong>of</strong> Austin or Hart. On Austin, see alreadyMaine 1883. See also Galloway 1976, F. von Benda-Beckmarm 1986.lO A good case eould be made, for instance, for Max Weber, rarely quoted in thisCOnlext (bUI see Kidder 1983). Weber conceptualised law through sanctioningrnechanisms, a slaff acting for the larger social whole. But his law was notnecessarily connected to the state, and it was not necessarily exclusive.."lt doesnot constilule a problem for sociology", Weber wrole (1956:23) "to recognize[acknowledge the possibility <strong>of</strong>] the co-existence <strong>of</strong> differem, mutuallycontradiclory, valid orders". For him there was no conceptual exclusivity <strong>of</strong> l~wfor slate-Iínked and -supported normalive order (1956:25).- 53 ­

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!