10.07.2015 Views

G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer

G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer

G. A. Cohen on Self-Ownership, Property, and ... - Tom G. Palmer

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Tom</strong> G. <strong>Palmer</strong>G. A. COHEN ON SELF-OWNERSHIP,PROPERTY, AND’EQUALITY,ABSTRACT: G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has produced an influential criticism of libertarianisrirthat posits joint ownershk of everydiing in the world other than labov,with each joint owner having a veto r&$t over any potential use of the world.According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in that world rati<strong>on</strong>ality would require that wealth be dividedequally, with no d@erential accorded to talent, abilitn or eJort. A closerexaminati<strong>on</strong> shows flint Colterr’s argument rests <strong>on</strong> two central errors of reas<strong>on</strong>ing<strong>and</strong> does not support his egalhrian c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s, even granting his assumpti<strong>on</strong>of joint ownership. That assumpti<strong>on</strong> was rejected by Locke,Pufendotf <strong>and</strong> other writers <strong>on</strong> property for reas<strong>on</strong>s thnt <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> does notrebut.In a number of articles, G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has set out an intricate set of argumentsrebutting attempts to derive property claims in alienable objects(“world ownership”) <strong>and</strong> n<strong>on</strong>-patterned distributi<strong>on</strong>s of income(“capitalist inequality”) from property claims in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> (“selfownership”).’As <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995, 14) describes his enterprise in SeE<strong>Ownership</strong>, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Equality, “I entertained an alternative to Nozick’s‘up for grabs’ hypothesis about the external world, to wit, that itis jointly owned by every<strong>on</strong>e, with each having a veto over itsprospective use. And I showed that final equality of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is as-Critical Revieill 12, no. 3 (Summer 1998). ISSN 0891-3811. Q 1998 Critical Review Foulidati<strong>on</strong>.<strong>Tom</strong> G. <strong>Palmer</strong>, Senior Fellow in Moral <strong>and</strong> Political Thought, Cat0 Institute, 1000 MassachusettsAvenue NW, Washingt<strong>on</strong>, DC ZOOOI, teleph<strong>on</strong>e (202) 769-5299, telefax (202) 842-3490. e-mail tpalmer@cato.org, thanks G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Ch<strong>and</strong>ran Kukathas, John Gray, Raym<strong>on</strong>dPlant, <strong>and</strong> odicr readers for comments <strong>on</strong> carlicr versi<strong>on</strong>s of this paper.22.5


226 Critical Review Vol. fa, No. 3sured when that egalitarian hypo thesis about ownership of externalresources is c<strong>on</strong>joined with the thesis of self-ownership.” <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>cludesthat “equality had indeed been derived with no breach of therules of self-ownership” (ibid.), a result that, when c<strong>on</strong>joined withadditi<strong>on</strong>al arguments, “succeeded in exploding the libertarian posi-*ti<strong>on</strong>” (ibid., IS).The argumene<strong>on</strong>ce <strong>on</strong>e gets past <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s strange assumpti<strong>on</strong>s-isingenious <strong>and</strong> has been extraordinarily influential. Wil Kymlicka(1990, II~), for example, asks, in his C<strong>on</strong>temporary Polirical Philosophy:An Introducti<strong>on</strong>, “What would happen if the world was [sic] jointlyowned, <strong>and</strong> hence not subject to unilateral privatizati<strong>on</strong>? There are avariety of possible outcomes, but in general they will negate the inegalitarianimplicati<strong>on</strong>s of self-ownership.”2 Kymlicka cites, withoutrehearsing his argument, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s authority in support of this str<strong>on</strong>gclaim. More recently, Justin Weinberg (1997, 324) has reproducedparts of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s argument in an article in Critical Review, c<strong>on</strong>cludingthat “<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> shows that libertarianism cannot be defended in the waythat most libertarian philosophers want to defend it.”3The c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> reaches <strong>and</strong> that has been so iduentidis, however, based <strong>on</strong> errors in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s reas<strong>on</strong>ing. There are numeroussteps in the argument that may be open to objecti<strong>on</strong>, but evengranting all of his assumpti<strong>on</strong>s, the logic of the argument fails.I shall first outline <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s aims <strong>and</strong> general procedure. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, Ishall identify two crucial moves in his influential argument. Third, Ishall show that the fvst move is insupportable. Fourth, I shall showthat the sec<strong>on</strong>d move is based <strong>on</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>. I examine <strong>on</strong>ly twosteps of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s argument, but they are vitally important to his c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s<strong>and</strong>, if they are wr<strong>on</strong>g, his polemic against property in <strong>on</strong>e’spers<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> against attempts to ground several property <strong>on</strong> this foundati<strong>on</strong>,is severely weakened.Finally, I will c<strong>on</strong>clude with some general remarks about wherethis leaves <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>and</strong> the issue of property rights. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> asserts thatlibertarianism is unjustified if we grant his assumpti<strong>on</strong>-offered withoutany argument whatsoever-that communism is justified. I c<strong>on</strong>cludeby rebutting this strange positi<strong>on</strong>.Before turning directly to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s case, I should offer a justificati<strong>on</strong>for plunging the reader into an often complicated <strong>and</strong> technicalargument, so much so that few readers have bothered to read it carefully.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s mistakes, although fatal to his enterprise of undermininglibertarianism, are instructive. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> does not succeed in “ex-


3238 Critical Review VoL 12, No. 3quires close scrutiny.’’ I shall set to the side questi<strong>on</strong>s about whether<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has fairly characterized Nozick’s proviso as c<strong>on</strong>stituting hisprinciple of appropriati<strong>on</strong>: <strong>and</strong> will merely reproduce the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>of his treatment, as prolegomen<strong>on</strong> to his central argument that“self-ownership” can be so c<strong>on</strong>strued or integrated with otherarrangements as to necessitate completely equal distributi<strong>on</strong> of wealth<strong>and</strong>income. .<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995,90) insists that any appropriati<strong>on</strong> will make some<strong>on</strong>eworse off,for no other reas<strong>on</strong> than that some<strong>on</strong>e will no l<strong>on</strong>ger beable to appropriate the now-appropriated item: “It is clear bey<strong>on</strong>ddoubt that an appropriati<strong>on</strong> of private property can c<strong>on</strong>tradict an individual’swill just as much as levying a tax <strong>on</strong> him can.” If c<strong>on</strong>tradicting<strong>on</strong>e’s will is the criteri<strong>on</strong> for a theory that is supposed to bebased <strong>on</strong> liberty, then, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, no private appropriati<strong>on</strong>could meet the requirements of a suitably formulated Nozickian proviso,for, even if a latecomer finding no unappropriated resources lefrto appropriate were to be compensated by greater material wealth,this compensati<strong>on</strong> could not undo the fact that the latecomer’s willhas been overruled. As <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (ibid., 89) argues, “Nozick disallowsobjectively paternalist use of people’s private property. But he permitsobjectively paternalist treatment of people in ocher ways. For, sincehe permits appropriati<strong>on</strong>s that satisfy nothing but his proviso, he allowsA to appropriate against B’s will when B benefits as a result, or,rather, as l<strong>on</strong>g as B does not lose.” If some<strong>on</strong>e were to chop off myarm, even if he later made me better off, we would still say that myrights had been violated.In the process of making this move, allegedly showing that Nozick’sapproach cannot justifi appropriati<strong>on</strong> by individuals (or groups)&om an unowned comm<strong>on</strong>s, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> suggests that Nozick‘s baselineof comparis<strong>on</strong>-what <strong>on</strong>e could get in a c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of no appropriati<strong>on</strong>or ownership at all-is arbitrary, <strong>and</strong> that a variety of collectiveownership arrangements should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered as c<strong>and</strong>idates for thebaseline, as well.6 There are, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995, 78), “otherintuitively relevant counterfactuals, <strong>and</strong> . . . they show that Nozick’sproviso is too lax, that he has arbitrarily narrowed the class of alternativeswith which we are to compare what happens when an appropriati<strong>on</strong>occurs with a view to determining whether any<strong>on</strong>e. is harmedby it.” The alternative rhat he singles out as “intuitively relevant” isthat ofjoint ownership, according to which a resource


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Eqrcaliiy 229is owned, by all together, <strong>and</strong> what each may do with it is subject tocollective decisi<strong>on</strong>. The appropriate procedure €or reaching that decisi<strong>on</strong>may be hard to define, but it wil certainly not be open to any<strong>on</strong>e of the joint owners to privatize all or part of the asset unilaterally,no matter what compensati<strong>on</strong> he offers to the rest. . .. . So if jointownership rather than no ownership is, mody speaking, the initialpositi<strong>on</strong>, then B has the right to forbid A to appropriate, even if Bwould benefit by what he thereby forbids. (Ibid., 83)In setting up the problem, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995, 92) strives to “rec<strong>on</strong>cileself-ownership with equality (or not too much inequality) of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>,by c<strong>on</strong>structing an ec<strong>on</strong>omic c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> which combines selfownershipwith an egalitarian approach to raw worldly resources.’’(<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> never makes clear what “not too much inequality” can orshould mean, or how <strong>on</strong>e might know how much was too much.)The principle of joint ownership, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, when combinedwith strict “self-ownership,” would: I) preclude individual ‘orsubgroup property rights (or property in severalty through subdivisi<strong>on</strong>)through fkee agreement, <strong>and</strong> 2) generate completely equal distributi<strong>on</strong>sof income (or, if any inequalities were to be allowed, theywould not reflect differences in c<strong>on</strong>trol over productive powers, i.e.,they would not be due to <strong>on</strong>e’s property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>). <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>tries to base both of those c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the rati<strong>on</strong>ality of the parties.The point of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s exerti<strong>on</strong>s is to attempt to show that selfownershipwould not entail rights to several property, or world-ownership,under c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of initial joint ownership of resources otherthan labor. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> claims that no individual or subgroup appropriati<strong>on</strong>can meet a properly formulated Nozickian proviso against harm,so there can be no legitimate individual or subgroup appropriati<strong>on</strong>&om a c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of no-ownership. His next two steps are to arguethat rati<strong>on</strong>ality would preclude mutually agreeable individual or subgroupdivisi<strong>on</strong> of the jointly owned assets, <strong>and</strong> that it would be irrati<strong>on</strong>alforjoint owners to agree to unequal distributi<strong>on</strong> of their jointproduct. These are the steps I will now c<strong>on</strong>test.Is Unequal Divisi<strong>on</strong> ofjointly Owned Resources Irrati<strong>on</strong>al?The first of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s two rati<strong>on</strong>ality-based arguments c<strong>on</strong>cerns thedivisi<strong>on</strong> of assets (“appropriati<strong>on</strong>”). He rejects individual or subgmup


230 Critical Review Vol. J2, No. 3divisi<strong>on</strong> or appropriati<strong>on</strong> of jointly owned assets <strong>on</strong> the grounds that“B might have good reas<strong>on</strong> to exercise his right to forbid an appropriati<strong>on</strong>by A fiom which B himself would benefit. For, if he forbidsA to appropriate, he can then bargain with A about the share of outputhe will get if he relents <strong>and</strong> allows A to appropriate. B is then.likely to improve his take by an amaunt greater than what A wouldotherwise have offered him” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1995, 84). According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>,B does not seek a more equal distributi<strong>on</strong> of assets, but the improvementof his “share of output” of the jointly owned asset.It is not at all clear fkom the text how B’s veto threat would “improvehis take” unless B might later relent <strong>and</strong> allow A to appropriate,in which case the output would no l<strong>on</strong>ger be jointly owned <strong>and</strong> subjectto distributi<strong>on</strong>. The argument that B might forbid A’s appropriati<strong>on</strong>in order to hold out for a larger share of output is thus incoherent,for if A were to be allowed to appropriate, there would be nojoint product to share.Setting aside the above c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>, it bears noting that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> iscareful to indicate that an agent “might” have good reas<strong>on</strong> to refhean appropriati<strong>on</strong>, for the agent ako might very well have good reas<strong>on</strong>sto agree to such an appropriati<strong>on</strong>. There are many observable cases,afiter all, in which jointly owned resources (e.g., in business partnerships<strong>and</strong> in marriage partnerships) are divided <strong>on</strong> the basis offieeagreement. These occasi<strong>on</strong>s happen when some <strong>on</strong>e or more of thefollowing situati<strong>on</strong>s obtain:(A) The parties no l<strong>on</strong>ger wish to cooperate, because of differencesunrelated to the physical productivity of cooperati<strong>on</strong>. (They may, forexample, mutually prefer not to be subject to the veto powers of jointowners over the dispositi<strong>on</strong> of jointly owned assets.)(B) The size or compositi<strong>on</strong> of the group of joint owners entailstransacti<strong>on</strong> costs, in corning to agreement over the dispositi<strong>on</strong> of thejointly owned asset, that are greater than the sum of the losses thatwould be suffered by even the worst off under a loss of the right toan aliquot porti<strong>on</strong> of the income stream generated by a jointlyowned asset. This would entail that those who would fare worstunder divisi<strong>on</strong> could still be compensated for their losses from the resourcesfieed up by the eliminati<strong>on</strong> of the high transacti<strong>on</strong> costs attributableto joint ownership. Under such c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> assumingthat the transacti<strong>on</strong> costs of a <strong>on</strong>e-time negotiati<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> arrangementof a divisi<strong>on</strong> were not prohibitively high, then it would be rati<strong>on</strong>alfor the joint owners to agree to divisi<strong>on</strong> of their jointly owned assets.


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> EquaZity23 I(C) One or more of the parties believe that she or they couldmanage a subdivided porti<strong>on</strong> of the currently jointly owned resourcebetter than the collectivity could, thereby generating a surplus. Fromthis surplus she or they could offer the other joint owners compensati<strong>on</strong>for the lost aliquot porti<strong>on</strong> of the income stream they wouldhave received h m the asset were it to remain jointly owned.@) The joint owners differ in their discounting of future incomestreams, <strong>and</strong> have corresp<strong>on</strong>dingly different preferences for savingsversus c<strong>on</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>, such that a divisi<strong>on</strong> into several property wouldallow them to allocate income between investment <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>differently For example, if A prefers a policy of “Eat, drink, <strong>and</strong> bemerry, for tomorrow we may die,” whereas B prefers a policy of “Apenny saved is a penny earned” (or if A simply has a shorter timehoriz<strong>on</strong> than B, due to advanced age or impending death, for example),then they may find it impossible to agree <strong>on</strong> whether to sacrificecurrent c<strong>on</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> for future satisfacti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> if so, what would bethe best tradeofE whereas with divisi<strong>on</strong>, each would be able to satisfj.her own preference, even if it were to come at the cost of a lower aggregatephysical product.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s arguments attempt to show that, under c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of jointownership, divisi<strong>on</strong> (appropriati<strong>on</strong>) resulting in some inequality of assetswould be irrati<strong>on</strong>al, but his arguments fail to justif+ that c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> is not clear <strong>on</strong> whether it is appropriati<strong>on</strong> per se or appropriati<strong>on</strong>that would result in unequal distributi<strong>on</strong> of “output” thatmatters to him. Whichever it is, though, the argument fails.7<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> does allow for the possibility, at least under c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s ofunanimity, of a precisely equal divisi<strong>on</strong> of initial assets, in the mannerfavored by Hillel SreinerS8 Joint ownership, unlike equal divisi<strong>on</strong>,“forbids a Nozickian formati<strong>on</strong> of unequal private property by placingalI resources under collective c<strong>on</strong>trol” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> Iggs,~oz). <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>(ibid., 10s) admits that, under c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of unanimity, joint ownership<strong>and</strong> equal divisi<strong>on</strong> “may readily be c<strong>on</strong>verted into the other.“But arrangements other than strict equality, <strong>and</strong> not including the entiretyof the human race, or of all rati<strong>on</strong>d agents, seem to be ruledout tout court?Of course, if property resources were to be divided <strong>and</strong> severalproperty established, joint ownership could be voluntarily reestablishedby the several owners agreeing jointly to recombine their assetsinto jointly owned assets.1° But <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s insistence that joint owners


232 Critical Review Vol. 12, No. 3would not-or would be irrati<strong>on</strong>al to-agree to divisi<strong>on</strong> is unsupported.Before proceeding to the next serious error in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s argument, ashort digressi<strong>on</strong> about <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing of Nozick is inorder, although this correcti<strong>on</strong> is not necessary to show the errors in<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s reas<strong>on</strong>ing. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995, 84) claims that,”Nozick must supposethat the world’s resources are, morally speaking, nothing likejointly owned, but very much up for grabs, yet, far tiom establishingthat premiss, he does not even bother to state it, or show any awarenessthat he needs it:’ This is untrue; Nozick (1974, 178) clearly statesthat he believes that any ownership claim must be justified, whethercollective or individual or mixed: “It is not <strong>on</strong>ly pers<strong>on</strong>s favoring pivateproperty who need a theory of how property rights legitimatelyoriginate. Those believing in collective property, for example thosebelieving that a group of pers<strong>on</strong>s living in an area jointly own the territory,or its mineral resources, also must provide a theory of how suchproperty rights arise; they must show why the pers<strong>on</strong>s living therehave rights to determine what is d<strong>on</strong>e with the l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> resourcesthere that pers<strong>on</strong>s living elsewhere d<strong>on</strong>’t have (with regard to the samel<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> resources).” Rather than Nozick being guilty of “not evenbothering to state , . . or show any awareness that he needs” such atheory, it is <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> who fails to provide a theory of how or why jointownership might be, or might have been, justified, bey<strong>on</strong>d assertingthat it is “intuitively relevant!’Again, however, this clarificati<strong>on</strong> is not essential to showing theerror in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s argument. Even granting <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s assumpti<strong>on</strong> of initialjoint ownership, he has failed to show that it would be irrati<strong>on</strong>alto agree to divide ownership of assets.Is Unequal Divisi<strong>on</strong> of/ointly Produced Output Ivvati<strong>on</strong>al?<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s sec<strong>on</strong>d <strong>and</strong> more complex argument is an attempt to showthat, assuming inescapably joint ownership (i.e., insisting that, c<strong>on</strong>traryto historical experience <strong>and</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s listed above, itwould be irrati<strong>on</strong>al to agree to divisi<strong>on</strong>),’unequal c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to ajointly produced product (i.e., a product to which all factor inputssave <strong>on</strong>e-labor-are jointly owned) will result in precisely equal distributi<strong>on</strong>of the joint product (“final equality of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>”). (Thisc<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> further assumes equal preference for leisure over labor;


<strong>Palmer</strong> - <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 233what <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> is c<strong>on</strong>cerned to show is that unequal marginal productivity,under such c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, will not result in an unequal distributi<strong>on</strong>of the joint product.) <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> assumes, like Rawls, that all incomeis jointly produced <strong>and</strong> that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the joint product is tobe the result of some sort of agreement am<strong>on</strong>g the joint owners.Where <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> differs fiom Rawls is in granting, for ihe sake of his attemptedrefutati<strong>on</strong> of Nozick, that the parties to the agreement knowwhat their productive abilities are <strong>and</strong> have property in those naturaltalents. Joint ownership of external resources means that each ownerhas a full veto right over any proposed distributi<strong>on</strong> of the joint product,because each has a veto right over the dispositi<strong>on</strong> of the factorinputs, other than labor, that c<strong>on</strong>tribute to the producti<strong>on</strong> of the jointproduct. Thus, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> writes that “I entertained an alternative toNozick’s ‘up for grabs’ hypothesis about the external world, to wit,that it is jointly owned by every<strong>on</strong>e, with each having a veto over itsprospective use. And I showed that final equality of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is assuredwhen that egalitarian hypothesis about ownership of externalresources is c<strong>on</strong>joined with the thesis of self-ownership” (14). Carehlexaminati<strong>on</strong> dem<strong>on</strong>strates, however, that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s arguments do notshow that “final equality of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is assured!’Cohet) (1995, 94) proposes that we c<strong>on</strong>sider a two-pers<strong>on</strong> world,populated by “Able” <strong>and</strong> ‘‘hfirrn,” in which there is an asymmetry inthe productive capabilities of the. two parties, who are jointly owners ofall available external resources. In this situati<strong>on</strong>, “Each owns himself <strong>and</strong>both jointly own everything else.” <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (ibid., 95) then describesbetween the two parties is impossible:I three cases in which b.ar@g.i. Able cannot pmduce.per day what% needed for <strong>on</strong>e pers<strong>on</strong> for aday, so Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm both die.ii. Able can produce enough or more than enough for <strong>on</strong>e pers<strong>on</strong>, butnot enough for two, Infirm lets Able produce what he can, since <strong>on</strong>lyspite or envy would lead him nor to. Able lives <strong>and</strong> Infirm dies.iii. Able can produce just enough to sustain both himself <strong>and</strong> Infirm.So Infirm forbids him to produce unless he produces that much. Ablec<strong>on</strong>sequently does, <strong>and</strong> both live at subsistence.In these three cases there is no surplus over which to bargain. Thetwo cases in which bargaining over a surplus might take place are describedas follows:


234 Critical Review Vol.12, No. 3iv. If Able produces at all, then the amount he produces is determinedindependently of his choice, <strong>and</strong> it exceeds what is needed to sustainboth Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm. They therefore bargain over the distributi<strong>on</strong> ofa fixed surplus. The price of failure to agree (the ‘threat point’) is noproducti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong>, therefore, death for both.v. Again, Able can produce a surplus, but now, more realistically, he canvary its size, so that Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm will bargain not <strong>on</strong>ly, as in (iv),over who gets how much, but also over how much will be produced.(<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> rg9s. 9s)<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1ggs,96) acknowledges that Able <strong>and</strong> Infrrm may differ intheir preferences for leisure or labor (which he rather oddly characterizesas “the disutility of labour for Able <strong>and</strong> the disutility of infirmityfor Infirm”),11 <strong>and</strong> that this asymmetry may be a factor in thebargaining process, presumably allowing divergences from completeequality of product. Such differences in preferences, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> asserts,are unrelated to abilities. Thus, “the crucial point is that Able’s talentwill nor, just as such, affect how much he gets. If the exercise ofahistalent is irksome to him, then he will indeed get additi<strong>on</strong>al compensati<strong>on</strong>,but <strong>on</strong>ly because he is irked, not because it is his labour whichirks him” (ibid.).<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> thus tries to establish that under c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s ofjoint ownershipof assets, the more productive would never receive a share ofoutput proporti<strong>on</strong>al to productivity or otherwise unequal to purelyegalitarian divisi<strong>on</strong>, i,esI simple divisi<strong>on</strong> of the total product by thenumber of joint owners. If Able works 10 hours <strong>and</strong> picks IOObushels of apples <strong>and</strong> Infirm works 3 hours <strong>and</strong> picks 10 bushels ofapples, their mutual rati<strong>on</strong>ality dem<strong>and</strong>s that at the end of the dayAble will receive 5s bushels <strong>and</strong> Infirm will receive 5s bushels. Perhapsbecause this is so wildly implausible, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> tries to suggest areas<strong>on</strong> why Able might get more than $5 bushels after all, to wit, thatpicking apples is unpleasant (it “irks” her). This may be the strangestpart of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s expositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> simply heaps c<strong>on</strong>fiasi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>,as he tries to make a distincti<strong>on</strong> without a difference. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>juresup the distincti<strong>on</strong> between <strong>on</strong>e’s abilities <strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>e’s preferences inorder to justiQ, <strong>on</strong> the basis of pure rati<strong>on</strong>ality, divergences &om strictegalitarianism. In effect, he argues that if joint owners were to agreeto unequal divisi<strong>on</strong>, it could <strong>on</strong>ly be because of different preferencesfor leisure (the irksomeness of labor) <strong>and</strong> never because of unequaltalenrs or abilities.


<strong>Palmer</strong> * <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 337pen& not <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> Able’s preferences for leisure over labor, but also<strong>on</strong> the expectati<strong>on</strong>s of the parties, <strong>and</strong> this involvement of expectati<strong>on</strong>sby itself entails a radical indeterminacy of result, for, as ThomasSchelling (1960,~) points out, such situati<strong>on</strong>s “ultimately involve anelement of pure bargaining-bargaining in which. each party isguided mainIy by his expectati<strong>on</strong>s of what the other Will accept. Butwith each guided by expectati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> knowing that the other is too,expectati<strong>on</strong>s become compounded.”In a case of the sort that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> describes, in bargaining over a surplusthe bargainer who can precommit credibly will get the share sheprefers, so l<strong>on</strong>g as the other party has not precommitted simultane-~usly.*~ What <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s remarks tell us is that G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has com-mitted himself, through the vehicle of his published writings, to acertain strategy (fully equal divisi<strong>on</strong>) in the sorts of cases that he describes(as it would, presumably, entail a loss of face or of academicreputati<strong>on</strong> if he were to practice other than he preaches). Any<strong>on</strong>ewho finds herselfin a pure bargaining situati<strong>on</strong> with G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>. may expect that the <strong>on</strong>ly viable move will be to dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>e-half ofwhatever is at stake-no more <strong>and</strong> no less-which is the complementaryequilibrium strategy to an irrevocably committed strategy ofdem<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>on</strong>e half.14 But that strategy may not work with bargainersother than G. A. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>. Strict egalitarianism is not the uniquelyrati<strong>on</strong>al bargaining strategy that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> claims it is.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> believes that his example of the $100 <strong>and</strong> the $I necessaryjointly to purchase a good proves that “there will be no . . . inequality,or its source will not be Able’s ownership of his own powers, butthe influence of the parties’ utility functi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the outcome of thebargaining process.” This c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> has not, however, been supportedby <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s arguments.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> proceeds to c<strong>on</strong>sider what he calls “a relatively minor objecti<strong>on</strong>to the argument” which is, however, fatal to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s claimthat “self-ownership” c<strong>on</strong>joined with joint ownership of everythingelse will necessarily result in equal income.The objezti<strong>on</strong> is that an owner of a factor of producti<strong>on</strong> couldthreaten to destroy the factor or, what amounts to the same thing (allrelevant effects being relative here), to allow it to decay in value or tofail to augment its productivity, Able, in the cases c<strong>on</strong>sidered above(iv <strong>and</strong> v), “has it in his power to let (part of) his talent decay”(<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1ggs,97). However, according to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (ibid., 97), ‘What isunclear, because of difficulties in the c<strong>on</strong>cept of rati<strong>on</strong>ality is whether


.238 Crltical Review Vol. 12, No. 3such a Schellingian threat would be credible, <strong>and</strong>, therefore, effective,under the assumpti<strong>on</strong> hat every<strong>on</strong>e is rati<strong>on</strong>al. If it would be, then thosewith greater power to produce could get more in a jointly ownedworld for reas<strong>on</strong>s which go bey<strong>on</strong>d the c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> that their labourmight be irksome to them” (emphasis orginal). (In an earlier publishedversi<strong>on</strong> of the essay <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 11986, 821 had written,“What I do notknow how to assess, because of my uncertain grasp %f bargaining theory,is whether such a Schellingian threat would be credible. . . !’)<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (1995. 97) dismisses this objecti<strong>on</strong> as “minor” because “itachieves purchase <strong>on</strong>ly in the rather peculiar case in which Able canindeed diminish his own productive power.” <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> implies that Ablewould threaten to diminish her own present powers, perhaps by cuttingoff her feet or blinding herselt <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> seems to believe thatsuch a strategy may be less than credible. But let us look at the cases<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> describes in which such a threat might be made. Such a strategywould be pointless in cases i <strong>and</strong> ii, <strong>and</strong> would not be credible incase iii, since the maximum product is stipulated to be <strong>on</strong>ly enoughto sustain Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm, with no surplus available for bargaining,so that the outcome is clear: Infirm wil insist that Able work <strong>and</strong>produce the maximum possible, which is precisely enough to sustainthem both (regardless of whether it is distributed equally), but no surplusis available for distributi<strong>on</strong> above survival level. Such a strategymay or may not be credible in case iv, in which labor inputs cannotvary but there is a surplus available for distributi<strong>on</strong>; the credibility isentirely a matter of Able’s ability to commit herself <strong>and</strong> to c<strong>on</strong>vinceInfirm that she will abide by the threat, which may be difficult to doin the absence of a third party with whom to c<strong>on</strong>tract for enforcement,or some other way to limit Able’s post-agreement opti<strong>on</strong>s. (It’ bears noting that Infirm could also precommit to dem<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>on</strong>ehalf‘,or a greater-than-<strong>on</strong>e-half‘ share, as well; nothing in case iv stopsInfirm from precommitting to exercise her veto in order to extract agreater-than-equal share of the surplus potentially available for bargaining.)But <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> cannot c<strong>on</strong>clude fiom the unavailability of sucha strategy in case iii, <strong>and</strong> the questi<strong>on</strong>able credibility of such a strategyin case iv, that it is not credible in the much-more-realistic scenarioof case v, in which labor inputs can vary over the amount necessaryto ensure that both Able <strong>and</strong> Infiim are sustained <strong>and</strong> that a corresp<strong>on</strong>dinglyvariable surplus can be generated by Able’s labor; all thatAble has to do in case v is exercise her claim rights <strong>and</strong> liberty righanot to work, i.e., to withdraw her labor &om the productive process.,


Paher <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 239Given the disutility of labor that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> presupposes, ie., that eachunit of disvalued labor can be c<strong>on</strong>verted into a unit of valued leisure,<strong>and</strong> the fact that <strong>on</strong>ly Able has the power <strong>and</strong> the right to decline towork, Able’s threatened refusal to work is a highly credible strategy,indeed. Thus, it is not incredible that Able would refuse to work bey<strong>on</strong>dthe labor necessary for both Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm to subsist withoutbeing compensated in accordance with, say, her marginal product.To clarify matters further, we can distinguish two cases. In the first,<strong>on</strong>e allows <strong>on</strong>e’s ability to decay by eliminating <strong>on</strong>e’s own opti<strong>on</strong>s.(Burning <strong>on</strong>e’s bridges can increase <strong>on</strong>e’s bargaining power, <strong>and</strong> suchmoves are neither irrati<strong>on</strong>al nor otherwise objecti<strong>on</strong>able; they arequite comm<strong>on</strong> to bargaining situati<strong>on</strong>s,) In the sec<strong>on</strong>d case, <strong>on</strong> whichI have focused, <strong>on</strong>e simply withdraws <strong>on</strong>e’s labor, but without diminishing<strong>on</strong>e’s productive capacity or otherwise limiting <strong>on</strong>e’s opti<strong>on</strong>s.Either is a credible strategy, although the latter is certainly more comm<strong>on</strong>lyobserved. It is precisely the strategy of “going <strong>on</strong> strike” that<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (xgg5,zso) c<strong>on</strong>demns-c<strong>on</strong>sistendy for a socialist “saddened”by what looked, at the time <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> wrote <strong>on</strong>e of the essays in thebook, “to be the impending final ab<strong>and</strong><strong>on</strong>ment of the Bolshevik experiment.”Strikes, after all, were not allowed in the Soviet Uni<strong>on</strong>. Inresp<strong>on</strong>se to the libertarian challenge, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> seeks to root out of socialisttheory the idea that <strong>on</strong>e has a right to property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>,in <strong>on</strong>e’s labor, or in <strong>on</strong>e’s product.The Reality of Socialist Practice<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> writes as if his experiment has never in fact been carried outin practice <strong>and</strong> that we have <strong>on</strong>ly his a priori speculati<strong>on</strong> as the basisfor thinking rati<strong>on</strong>ally about the joint-ownership scenario that he describes.But: there is ample experience of joint ownership being imposed<strong>on</strong> people, <strong>and</strong> it does not bear out <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s in anyway. The Engsh col<strong>on</strong>y at Jamestown offers a clear example of whathappens when joint ownership is imposed <strong>on</strong> those living <strong>on</strong> l<strong>and</strong>that was “good <strong>and</strong> fiuitfull.” As <strong>on</strong>e eyewitness wrote:So great was our famine, that a Savage we slew <strong>and</strong> buried, the poorersorte tooke him up agine <strong>and</strong> eat him; <strong>and</strong> so did divers <strong>on</strong>e anotherboyled <strong>and</strong> stewed with roots <strong>and</strong> herbs. It were too vile to say, <strong>and</strong>scarce to be beleeved, what we endured but the occasi<strong>on</strong> was our


240 Critical Review Vol. 12, No. 3own, for want of providence, industrie <strong>and</strong> government, <strong>and</strong> not thebarrennesse <strong>and</strong> defect of the Country, as is generally supposed. (InBethell 1998,34)Sir Thomas Dale, up<strong>on</strong> his arrival in Virginia in May of 1611, notedthat the col<strong>on</strong>ists were bowling in the streets rather than working. Itwas the introducti<strong>on</strong> of several property that put an end to the “starvinghime” that resulted f%om joint ownership of assets <strong>and</strong> egalitari<strong>and</strong>istributi<strong>on</strong> of the joint product.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s experiment was also tried at Plymouth Col<strong>on</strong>y a few yearslater. As Governor William Bradford noted:The experience that was had in this comm<strong>on</strong> come <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>,tried sundry years <strong>and</strong> that am<strong>on</strong>g godly <strong>and</strong> sober men, may wellevince the vanity of that c<strong>on</strong>ceit of Plato’s <strong>and</strong> other ancients applaudedby some of later times: that the taking away of property <strong>and</strong>bringing in community into a comm<strong>on</strong>wealth would make themhappy <strong>and</strong> flourishing; as if they were wiser than God. For this community(so far as it was) was found to breed much c<strong>on</strong>fksi<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> disc<strong>on</strong>tent<strong>and</strong> retard much employment that would have been to theirbenefit <strong>and</strong> comfort. For the young men, that were most fit <strong>and</strong> ablefor labour <strong>and</strong> service, did repine that they should spend their time<strong>and</strong> strength to work for other men’s wives <strong>and</strong> children without anyrecompense. The str<strong>on</strong>g, or man of parts, had no more in divisi<strong>on</strong> ofvictuals <strong>and</strong> clothes than he that was weak <strong>and</strong> not able to do a quarterthe other could; this was thought injustice. The aged <strong>and</strong> graver mento be ranked <strong>and</strong> equalized in labours <strong>and</strong> victuals, clothes, etc., withthe meaner <strong>and</strong> younger sort, thought it some indignity <strong>and</strong> disrespectunto them. And for men’s wives to be comm<strong>and</strong>ed to do service forother men, as dressing their meat, washing their clothes, etc., theydeemed it a kind of slavery, neither could many husb<strong>and</strong>s well brookit. Up<strong>on</strong> the point all being to have alike, <strong>and</strong> all to do alike, theythought themselves in the like c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>e as good as another;<strong>and</strong> so, if it did not cut ob those relati<strong>on</strong>s that God hath set am<strong>on</strong>gmen, yet it did at least much diminish <strong>and</strong> take off the mutual respectsthat should have been preserved am<strong>on</strong>gst them. And would have beenworse if they had been men of another c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>. Let n<strong>on</strong>e object thisis men’s corrupti<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> nothing to the course itsell: I answer, seeingall men have this corrupti<strong>on</strong> in them, God in His wisdom saw anothercourse fitter for them. (In Bethell 1998,~~)When <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s thought experiment has been run in reality, it turnsout that Able (“the str<strong>on</strong>g, or man of parts”) does not agree to work


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Pyoperty <strong>and</strong> Equality 241hard <strong>and</strong> then share equally with Infirm (“he that was weak <strong>and</strong> notable to do a quarter the other could“), but simply refuses to work, resultingin starvati<strong>on</strong> for all.The extreme egalitarian typically blames the moral failings of theparties involved, rather than the aboliti<strong>on</strong> or attenuati<strong>on</strong> of severalproperty for the failures of such collectivist schemes. Thus, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>(rggsa, 396) has criticized the reliance <strong>on</strong> incentives, in the form ofthe possibility of unequal holdings or unequal divisi<strong>on</strong>, with whichRawls amends pureIy equal divisi<strong>on</strong> of assets <strong>and</strong> income, <strong>on</strong> thegrounds that it effectively instituti<strong>on</strong>alizes immorality:My principal cot&enti<strong>on</strong> about Rawls is that (potential) high flierswould forgo incentives properly so-called in a fd compliance societygoverned by the difference principle <strong>and</strong> characterized by fraternity<strong>and</strong> universal dignity. I have not rejected the Mereme principle in itslax reading as a principle of public policy: I do not doubt that thereare c<strong>on</strong>texts where it is right to apply it, What I have questi<strong>on</strong>ed is itsdescripti<strong>on</strong> as a principle of (basic) justice, <strong>and</strong> I have deplored Rawls’swillingness to describe those at the top end of a society governed by itas undergoing the fullest possible realizati<strong>on</strong> of their mod natures.Recall, however, Governor Bradford’s observati<strong>on</strong> that joint ownership<strong>and</strong> enforced equal divisi<strong>on</strong> failed miserably “am<strong>on</strong>gst godly <strong>and</strong>sober men” <strong>and</strong> “would have been worse if they had been men of anotherc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>.” To what, then, are we to attribute the fact that suchschemes result, not in harm<strong>on</strong>y <strong>and</strong> prosperity, but in famine <strong>and</strong> cannibalism?Who or what bears the blame? The questi<strong>on</strong> was never putmore directly than by Vasily Grossman (1986, 164), a witness to theimpositi<strong>on</strong> of joint ownership <strong>on</strong> the peasant farmers in Ukraine:Some went insane. They never did become completely still. Onecould tell from their eyehecause their eyes sh<strong>on</strong>e. These were thepeople who cut up <strong>and</strong> cooked corpses, who killed their own children<strong>and</strong> ate them. In them the beast rose to the top as the human beingdied. 5 saw <strong>on</strong>e. She had been brought to the district center underc<strong>on</strong>voy. Her face was human, but her eyes were those of a wolf. Theseare cannibals, they said, <strong>and</strong> must all be shot. But they themselves, who. drove the mother to the madness of eating her own children, are evidentlynot guilty at all! For that matter, can you really find any<strong>on</strong>ewho is guilty? Just go <strong>and</strong> ask, <strong>and</strong> they will all tell you that they did itfor the sake of virtue, for everybody’s good. That’s why they drovemothers to cannibalism!


242 Critical Review Y,l. 12, No. 3It would require too l<strong>on</strong>g a digressi<strong>on</strong> to offer a full critique ofwhat is wr<strong>on</strong>g with blaming the victims of communism for failing tolive up to its “high” moral st<strong>and</strong>ards. I will merely suggest an hypoth-esis that seems simpler <strong>and</strong> more straightforward than the claim thathuman beings have not yet proven good enough for socialism: social-. ism is not good enough for human beings. .<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> errs in thinking that rati<strong>on</strong>al parties would never refuse towork or bargain or allow their abilities to decay if they were notcompensated unequally. He simply dismisses the possibility: “Nolibertarian would want to defeat the Ablehfirm argument (for thec<strong>on</strong>sistency of equality <strong>and</strong> self-ownership) <strong>on</strong> so adventitious abasis” (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> r995,97). According to <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (ibid., 97-98), the libertarian“would want, instead, to overcome it by pressing . , , [a]more fundamental objecti<strong>on</strong> , . . that to affirm joint ownership ofthe world is, as the story of Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm might be thought toshow, inc<strong>on</strong>sistent with achieving the purpose <strong>and</strong> expected effectof self-ownership.” But <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s hypothetical opp<strong>on</strong>ent need notchoose <strong>on</strong> which basis to refute <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s arguments, for theAble/Infirm story does not show what <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> claims that it shows,<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has not dem<strong>on</strong>strated that joint owners would not or shouldnot agree to divisi<strong>on</strong> of their assets; nor that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of asurplus over what is necessary to sustain both Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm mustbe evenly divided; nor that Able couId not bargain for a greatershare <strong>on</strong> the basis of a threat to diminish her productivity or herproductive effort. Finally, real-world experience with joint ownershipc<strong>on</strong>tradicts <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s rosy egalitarian descripti<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> raises theissue of why joint ownership should ever be seriously c<strong>on</strong>sidered inthe first place.*. 1’:.*t :z .:.i...!. r: .i’I?.i-


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 243may be, but why must or should they be? Classical liberals <strong>and</strong> libertariansare open <strong>on</strong> the questi<strong>on</strong> of whether particular bits of l<strong>and</strong> orother resources should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered jointly or individually owned.15What is unatgued for by <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (aside fiom asserting that it is “intuitivelyrelevant”), but is of dubious plausibility, is the idea that everyresource other than our own pers<strong>on</strong>s should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered the jointproperty of all human beings, or perhaps of all rati<strong>on</strong>al agents. If rati<strong>on</strong>alagents were to be discovered <strong>on</strong> Mars, would the joint ownersof Earth be required to obtain the permissi<strong>on</strong> of every rati<strong>on</strong>al Martianbefore any terrestrial resource might be used, <strong>and</strong> would theagreement have to be unanimous across species? This would be astrange basis <strong>on</strong> which to build a theory of jurisdicti<strong>on</strong> over scarceresources. As almost all previous writers <strong>on</strong> property have emphasized,requiring the permissi<strong>on</strong> of every<strong>on</strong>e before any<strong>on</strong>e could pickan apple would result in the extincti<strong>on</strong> of humanity. Joint ownership. requiring unanimous approval to every act of transformati<strong>on</strong> of resourcesis ultimately rejected by <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, <strong>on</strong> the ground that it interfereswith any reas<strong>on</strong>able sense of aut<strong>on</strong>omy, but it is not clear why itshould even be entertained in the first place.There may be good reas<strong>on</strong>s to believe that very early in its actualhistory, property took <strong>on</strong>e of various forms of positive community,principally familial, as Fustel de Coulanges (1864), Maine (1888), <strong>and</strong>other anthropologists <strong>and</strong> historians of property have shown; but thatis not <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s argument. Nor are the forms of positive communitydescribed by legal historians c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the egalitarian ownershipdescribed by <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> as “joint ownership,” for they did not encompassall humans or all rati<strong>on</strong>al agena, but were always forms of communitythat established rights against all n<strong>on</strong>members ofthe owning communities.As Locke noted of comm<strong>on</strong> property, “And though it be comm<strong>on</strong>,in respect of some Men, it is not so to all Mankind, but is thejoint property of this Country, or this Parish” (Zuo nedises, 11.35). Inthis respect, “negative community~’ i.e., the idea that all have a rightto appropriabe unowned objects, is a far more egalitarian startingpoint than any form of “positive community,”which in every formever observed was a n<strong>on</strong>universal, group-limited right. This issue wascarefully c<strong>on</strong>sidered by the modern natural-law writers <strong>on</strong> property,who distinguished between negative community <strong>and</strong> positive community,the latter corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the joint ownership that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>proposes as the pmper baseline.16It is remarkable that figures such as <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> persistently overlook


244 Critical Review Vol. 12, No. 3the distincti<strong>on</strong> between negative <strong>and</strong> positive community when c<strong>on</strong>sideringclaims, by Locke <strong>and</strong> other writers <strong>on</strong> several property, that,prior to appropriati<strong>on</strong>, the world was open to mankind in comm<strong>on</strong>.As Pufendorf (1994,178) noted quite explicitly,It is plain that before all human agreements there was a=communi<strong>on</strong> ofall things. Not a positive communi<strong>on</strong>, of course, but a negative <strong>on</strong>e;that is, all things were available to all <strong>and</strong> bel<strong>on</strong>ged no more to <strong>on</strong>e pers<strong>on</strong>than to another. But since things are not use&l to men unless atleast their fmits are laid hold of, <strong>and</strong> indeed, since this is d<strong>on</strong>e in vain ifothers are in turn allowed to seize what we have already actively intendedfor our own use, the first agreement am<strong>on</strong>g mortals c<strong>on</strong>cerningthings is understood to have been this: Whatever any<strong>on</strong>e had taken forhimself from the comm<strong>on</strong> stock or its fruits, with the intenti<strong>on</strong> of usingit for himself, would not be seized from him by another.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> reproduces the argument against liberal property put forthby Sir Robert Pilmer (1991,234), an apologist for royal absolutism:Certainly it is a rare felicity that all the men in the world at <strong>on</strong>e instantof time should agree together in <strong>on</strong>e mind to change the natural communityof things into private domini<strong>on</strong>. For without such an unani- .mous c<strong>on</strong>sent it was not possible for community to be altered. For ifbut <strong>on</strong>e man in the world had dissented, the alterati<strong>on</strong> had been unjust,because that man by the law of nature had a right to the comm<strong>on</strong>use of all things in the world, so that to have given a property of any<strong>on</strong>e thing to any other had been to have robbed him of his right tothe comm<strong>on</strong> use of all things.Locke, who was replying to Filmer, rejected joint ownership of thissort (in which each joint owner has a veto right, requiring unanimityfor anything to be appropriated <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sumed) as a baseline: “If sucha c<strong>on</strong>sent as that was necessary, Mankind had starved, notwithst<strong>and</strong>ingthe Plenty God had given him” (flu0 neutises, 11.28). By assertingproperty in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>, Locke managed to avoid the trap set byFilmer, forThough the Earth, <strong>and</strong> all inferior Creatures be comm<strong>on</strong> to all Men,yet every Man has a <strong>Property</strong> in his own Pers<strong>on</strong>. This no Body has anyRight to but himself. The Labour of his Body, <strong>and</strong> the Work of hisH<strong>and</strong>s, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes outof the State that Naturehaih provided, <strong>and</strong> left it in, he hath mixed his’


Pulmer * <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 245Labour with, <strong>and</strong> joyned to it something that is his own, <strong>and</strong> therebymakes it his Properfy. (Ibid., 11.27)’’It is property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> that justifies the appropriati<strong>on</strong> of that towhich every<strong>on</strong>e earlier had a right. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s attempted. rebuttal doesnot shake this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>; <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s case against libertariatlism rests <strong>on</strong>basic errors of reas<strong>on</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> fails <strong>on</strong> its own terms.There are certainly many observable scenarios in which <strong>on</strong>e oranother form of joint ownership is highly desirable, such as partnerships,co-ops, various sorts of clubs <strong>and</strong> religious instituti<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>and</strong>marriages, but there is no reas<strong>on</strong> to posit that joint ownership is the<strong>on</strong>ly rati<strong>on</strong>al or desirable arrangement, nor that property in severaltyis irrati<strong>on</strong>al or immoral. Nor does <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> even offer any goodreas<strong>on</strong> as to why joint ownership should be seriously entertained atall; the <strong>on</strong>ly justificati<strong>on</strong> that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> offers for attempting to workthrough the logic of joint ownership is that joint ownership is “intuitivelyplausible.” To say that <strong>on</strong>e’s intuiti<strong>on</strong> tells <strong>on</strong>e that a claimis reas<strong>on</strong>able or probable is hardly to offer an argument <strong>on</strong> its behalf’,<strong>and</strong>, in any case, ‘‘joint ownership” or “positive community” hascertainly been c<strong>on</strong>sidered by defenders of several property <strong>and</strong> decisivelyrejected for very good reas<strong>on</strong>s, as opposed to mere intuiti<strong>on</strong>.Finally, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has failed to dem<strong>on</strong>strate that the unequal divisi<strong>on</strong>of joint products is irrati<strong>on</strong>al (much less. that it is immoral).The central pillars of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s polemic against c<strong>on</strong>joining propertyin <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> with several property rest <strong>on</strong> errors of reas<strong>on</strong>ing; hisargument against the c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong> of property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> withseveral property will have to proceed without his often-cited but err<strong>on</strong>eousclaims about the bargaining situati<strong>on</strong> of self-owners whoown the world jointly. His bare asserti<strong>on</strong> of the “plausibility” of positivecommunity is not an argument for a policy that has been rejectedfor clear <strong>and</strong> compelling reas<strong>on</strong>s by many other writers <strong>on</strong> the topic.It may be that libertarian claims about the c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong> of propertyin <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> property in the world are false, but, if so, it is notfor the reaso‘ls that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> has advanced.I ’NOTESr. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s criticisms have appeared in numerous forms <strong>and</strong> publicati<strong>on</strong>s, notably<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1985, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> r986a, <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1986b, <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1989, <strong>and</strong> havebeen revised <strong>and</strong> collected together in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> 1995.


246 Critical Review Val. 12, No. 32.3.4.5.6.7.Other recent works that have cited without criticism or have incorporatedat least some of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s basic claims into their critique of several propertyinclude Waldr<strong>on</strong> 1988, Munzer 1990, Ingram 1994, Haworth 1.994, Christ-man 1gg4a <strong>and</strong> ~ggbb, <strong>and</strong> Sreenivasan 1995. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s approach has beencriticized by David Gord<strong>on</strong> (1990) <strong>and</strong> by Jan Narves<strong>on</strong> (~ggo), althoughwithout raising the problems I point out in this critique. Unlike the criticismsof Gord<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> Narves<strong>on</strong>, my rehtati<strong>on</strong> of <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s central argumentsis immanent.Part of Weinberg’s claim is that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s critique of libertarian views <strong>on</strong> libertyis a decisive refutati<strong>on</strong> of libertarians’ claims to be defenders of fieedom.I deal with that issue in my separate reply to Friedman in this issue of CriticalReview, in resp<strong>on</strong>se to his claim that “<strong>on</strong>e stipulative definiti<strong>on</strong> is as good asanother” (Friedman 1997,432)~ so I will instead focus my criticism here <strong>on</strong><str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s critique of “self-ownership,” which Weinberg (1997,324) c<strong>on</strong>sidersto be, if anything, “too sympathetic an analysis of libertarian c<strong>on</strong>cepts.”Weinberg cites in support of this claim a particularly outl<strong>and</strong>ish attack <strong>on</strong><str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> by Brian Barry for even bothering to address classical liberalism at all.I :!’(See Barry 1996 <strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s resp<strong>on</strong>se [1gg6].)<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> quite oddly proceeds to define each pers<strong>on</strong>’s property in herself interms of its very negati<strong>on</strong>, viz., “According to the thesis of self-ownership,each pers<strong>on</strong> possesses over himself, as a matter of moral right, all those rightsthat a slaveholder has over a complete chattel slave as a matter of legal right,<strong>and</strong> he is entitled, morally speaking, to dispose over himself in the way that aslaveholder is entitled, legally speaking, to dispose over his slave” (68). This isa strange way of underst<strong>and</strong>ing “selCownership,” <strong>on</strong>e that would not gener- :ally be endorsed by defenders of property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>, but which hasbeen taken up as paradigmatic by many who have recently followed in<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s footsteps. The possibility of the inalienability of certain rights is aclear case in which the (illegitimate) property claimed by a slaveholder in herslaves is misleading, rather than illuminating, as a paradigm of property in<strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>, Although misleading in other respects, the definiti<strong>on</strong> need notbe disputed to show that <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s do not follow from hispremises.See for a correcti<strong>on</strong> Gord<strong>on</strong> 1990, 78-80. Gord<strong>on</strong> (1990. 83) also takes<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> to task for “seizing <strong>on</strong> the exact words while ignoring their sense” inmisunderst<strong>and</strong>ing Nozick‘s point c<strong>on</strong>cerning redistributi<strong>on</strong> of wealth gainedunder a determinate system of rights-namely, that “things come into theworJd already attached to people having entitlements over them” (Nozick1974, x6o)as a claim about inifid appropriati<strong>on</strong>.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> is dem<strong>and</strong>ing, in effect, that it be shown not merely that appropriati<strong>on</strong>may be permissible, but that it must be optimal as well. See the discussi<strong>on</strong>of the two kinds ofjustificati<strong>on</strong> in Simm<strong>on</strong>s 1994.It is worth noting that even “indivisible” goods can be divided <strong>on</strong> the basisof agreement, <strong>and</strong> quite comm<strong>on</strong>ly are. H. Peyt<strong>on</strong> Young describes “eightfI.:.$:g.*g?%i$@.$gi,


<strong>Palmer</strong>. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 247Ifairly universal techniques for defining ex ante property rights in an indivisiblegood” (Young 1996,373).8, See, for example, Steiner 1994, especially the epilogue <strong>on</strong> just redistributi<strong>on</strong>s.9. It is worth pointing out that, in many actual cases, joint-ownership arrangementshave generated voluntary divisi<strong>on</strong>s of l<strong>and</strong> (as also of other resources),<strong>and</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> offers no evidence that the joint owners who. have agreed to divisi<strong>on</strong>were suffering kom irrati<strong>on</strong>al delusi<strong>on</strong>s. For some of the relevant literature<strong>and</strong> case studies, see Ellicks<strong>on</strong> 1993. especially 1388-92, <strong>and</strong> Libecap1989. For a historical study of voluntary divisi<strong>on</strong> of jointly held comm<strong>on</strong>property, see Norberg 1988. Norberg (1988, a68) notes, of popular votes <strong>on</strong>divisi<strong>on</strong> of comm<strong>on</strong> l<strong>and</strong>s in Revoluti<strong>on</strong>ary France, that “whether the peasantsvoted €or or against partiti<strong>on</strong>, they generally did so by very large mar-. gins, often unanimously.” Of communities with comm<strong>on</strong>s, 71 .gs percentvoted for partiti<strong>on</strong> in the 1793 referenda (ibid., 271).10. The c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s under which such arrangements prove mutually beneficialare set out <strong>and</strong> used to illuminate case studies in Lueck 1993.11. It is not clear how Infirm’s infirmity can be a source of disutility for her inthe way that Able’s labor is a source of disutility for her, as Infirm cannot, byhypothesis, vary her infirmity in the way that Able can vary her labor effort.Whether it was <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>’s intenti<strong>on</strong> or not, such remarks color the situati<strong>on</strong> hedescribes by engaging natural feelings of sympathy for the unfortunate,thereby introducing elements that are not explicitly acknowledged in the descripti<strong>on</strong>of the bargaining situati<strong>on</strong>. Such feelings of sympathy are alsobrought to the fore by the specificati<strong>on</strong> of the bargaining situati<strong>on</strong> as <strong>on</strong>e ofIWO pers<strong>on</strong>s dealing with <strong>on</strong>e another face to face, <strong>and</strong> therefore probably <strong>on</strong>an intimate, <strong>and</strong> not <strong>on</strong> an an<strong>on</strong>ymous, basis, rather than the situati<strong>on</strong> ofan<strong>on</strong>ymous interacti<strong>on</strong> am<strong>on</strong>g strangers who do not meet each other face toface. Thus, although <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> (19gs,gs) stipulates that Able <strong>and</strong> Infirm are “ra-ti<strong>on</strong>al, self-interested, <strong>and</strong> mutually disinterested,” the situati<strong>on</strong> he describes isnot the sort in which such motivati<strong>on</strong>s are comm<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> his descripti<strong>on</strong>evokes sentiments that are comm<strong>on</strong> to small-group, face-to-face, <strong>and</strong> intimatesettings. The importance of distinguishing between the two kinds ofsettings has been highlighted by E A. Hayek (1988, IS), who points out that“the structures of the extended order are made up not <strong>on</strong>ly of individualsbut also of many, often overlapping, sub-orders within which old instinctualresp<strong>on</strong>ses, such as solidarity <strong>and</strong> altruism, c<strong>on</strong>tinue to retain some importanceby assisting voluntary collaborati<strong>on</strong>, even though they are incapable, bythemsehres, of creating a basis for the extended order. Part of our present difficultyis that we must c<strong>on</strong>stantly adjust our lives, our thoughts <strong>and</strong> our emoti<strong>on</strong>s,in order to live simultaneously within different kinds of orders accordingto different rules. , . . So we must learn to live in two sorts of worlds at<strong>on</strong>ce!’12. A nail is driven into the “preference vs. productivity” coflin by Alex<strong>and</strong>erRosenberg (1988, IS), who notes that “the ec<strong>on</strong>omic effects of a talent or adisability may be exactly the same as those of a preference or taste,” using the


248 Critical Review Yo(. 12, No. 3example of acrophobia or acrophilia <strong>and</strong> the talent for tree climbing am<strong>on</strong>gcoc<strong>on</strong>ut harvesters; the preference for high places would generate an ec<strong>on</strong>omic“rent” (or profit) indistinguishable tiom the “rent” or profit generatedby a talent for climbing, <strong>and</strong> thus preferences <strong>and</strong> talents are difficult, if notimpossible, to distinguish.r3. The party who can make an “irrevocable comqitment” will be able to“squeeze the range of indeterminacy down to the point most favorable tohim“ (Schelling 1960,24).14. For a treatment of complementary strategies, see Sugden 1986.6749.IS. For an informed discussi<strong>on</strong> of the variety of l<strong>and</strong> regimes possible <strong>and</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sistentwith classical liberal views, see Bllicks<strong>on</strong> 1993.16. The issue is usefully canvassed in Buckle rg91, especially 36, 93, 104-5,16447, <strong>and</strong> 183-87. See also the careful discussi<strong>on</strong> of the issue in Pufendorf1994, especially 176-8s.17. Alan Ryan (1994) criticizes the noti<strong>on</strong> of “property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong>,’’ but hedoes not c<strong>on</strong>sider the advantages to the c<strong>on</strong>cept of “property in” objects.C<strong>on</strong>temporary imprecise English usage identifies property <strong>and</strong> object; thus, I .might say that “this l<strong>and</strong> [watch, book, etcJ is my property? The older usageof speaking of having “a property in a thing” is far more precise <strong>and</strong> resectsthe complex multiplicity of property arrangements that are possible <strong>and</strong> thatare fully compatible with the libertarian defense of several property Thus, itmay be that each of many different pers<strong>on</strong>s has “a property” in a piece ofl<strong>and</strong>; <strong>on</strong>e has the right to live <strong>on</strong> it, another has the right to walk across it,yet another has the right to the rental income from it, <strong>and</strong> so <strong>on</strong>. As theRoman lawyers <strong>and</strong> the modern law-<strong>and</strong>-ec<strong>on</strong>omics scholars realize, “ownership”normally represents a bundle of such rights. Presenting the rights that<strong>on</strong>e has over <strong>on</strong>eself (not to be raped, not to be killed, not to be beaten, toexpress <strong>on</strong>e’s opini<strong>on</strong>s, to c<strong>on</strong>sent to <strong>on</strong>e’s marriage, <strong>and</strong> pthcr bourgeois indulgences)as property in <strong>on</strong>e’s pers<strong>on</strong> allows the legal system to rest <strong>on</strong> a coherent<strong>and</strong> integrated foundati<strong>on</strong>. The transiti<strong>on</strong> fiom the classical formulati<strong>on</strong>(“pers<strong>on</strong> X has a propercy in object Y”) to the modern <strong>and</strong> less preciseformulati<strong>on</strong> (“object Y is X’s property”) has made legal discussi<strong>on</strong> less clear<strong>and</strong> has led-in the attempt to focus attenti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the right rather than theobject-to the formati<strong>on</strong> of such c<strong>on</strong>cepts as “property rights,’’ which means“right rights.”James Madir<strong>on</strong> (1983,266) made a valiant attempt to retain theprecisi<strong>on</strong> of the classical formulati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong> to relate the righo to keedom ofspeech <strong>and</strong> religi<strong>on</strong> to the rights to domini<strong>on</strong> over l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> other objects, inhis essay “<strong>Property</strong>”:This term in its particulat applicati<strong>on</strong> means ‘that domini<strong>on</strong> which <strong>on</strong>eman claims <strong>and</strong> exercises over the external things of the world, in exclusi<strong>on</strong>of every other individual.’ In its larger <strong>and</strong> juster meaning, itembraces every thing to which a man may attach a value <strong>and</strong> have aright; <strong>and</strong> which leaves to euey <strong>on</strong>e else the like adwntage. In the formersense, a man’s l<strong>and</strong>, or merch<strong>and</strong>ise, or m<strong>on</strong>ey is called his property Inthe latrer sense, a man has a property in his opini<strong>on</strong>s <strong>and</strong> the free com-


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Equality 249municati<strong>on</strong> of them. He has a property of particular value in his religiousopini<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> in the professi<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> practice dictated by them. Hehas a property very dear to him in the safety <strong>and</strong> liberty of his pers<strong>on</strong>.He has an equal property in the free use of his faculties <strong>and</strong> free choiceof the objects <strong>on</strong> which to employ them. In a word, as a man is said tohave a right to his property, he may be equally said t6. have a propertyin his rights.REFERENCESBarry, Brian. 1996. “You have to be crazy to believe it!’ Times Literary Supplement,October 25.Bethell, <strong>Tom</strong>. 1998. rite Noblest 7Eumpli: <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> Prosperify Through the Ages.New York St. Martin’s Press.Buckle, Stephen. 1991. Natural Law <strong>and</strong> die TIIeory of Properly. Oxford Clarend<strong>on</strong>Press.Christman, John. rgg4a. “Distributive Justice <strong>and</strong> the Complex Structure of<strong>Ownership</strong>.” PliNosophy <strong>and</strong> Public Ajairs 23: aaj-so.Christman, John. 1994b. The Myth of <strong>Property</strong>: Toward an Egalitarian Theory of<strong>Ownership</strong>. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. 1985. “Nozick <strong>on</strong> Appropriati<strong>on</strong>.” New L.e? Review no. 150: 89-105.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. 1986a. “<strong>Self</strong>-<strong>Ownership</strong>, World-<strong>Ownership</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Equality’’ In Justice<strong>and</strong> EquaNty Here <strong>and</strong> Now, ed. Frank S. Lucash. lthaca: Cornell UniversityPress.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. 1986b. “<strong>Self</strong>-<strong>Ownership</strong>, World <strong>Ownership</strong>. <strong>and</strong> Equality: Part 11.”Social Philosophy &.Policy 3(2): 77-96.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. r989. “Are Freedom <strong>and</strong> Equality Compatible?” In Alternafiues foCapitalism, ed. J<strong>on</strong> Elster <strong>and</strong> Karl Ove Moene. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. IggSa. “Incentives, Inequalityl <strong>and</strong> Community” In Equal Freedom:Selected Tanner Lectures <strong>on</strong> Human Yaues, ed. Stephen Darwall. Ann Arbor:University of Michigan Press.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>, G. A. rggsb. Seljownetsh@, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Equality. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.<str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g>. G. A. 1996. “<strong>Self</strong>-ownership <strong>and</strong> the libertarian challenge:“ Times Literarysupplement, November 8.de Coul&ges, Numa Denis Fustel. [IS&] 1956. The Ancient City:A Study <strong>on</strong> dieReligi<strong>on</strong>, Laws, <strong>and</strong> Instituri<strong>on</strong>s of Greece <strong>and</strong> Rome. Garden City, N.Y.: DoubledayAnchor.Ellicks<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. 1993. “<strong>Property</strong> in L<strong>and</strong>.” Yale Lawjournal 102: 1315-1440.Filmer, Sir Robert. 1991, “Observati<strong>on</strong>s C<strong>on</strong>cerning the Originall of Government,up<strong>on</strong> Mr. Hobs ‘Leviathan,’ Mr. Milt<strong>on</strong> against Salmasius, H. Grotius‘De Jure Bell?!’ In idem, Patriarcha <strong>and</strong> Other Writings, ed. Johann P. Sommerville.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


as0 Critical Review Vol. la, No. 3..-.Priedman, Jeffrey. 1997. “What’s Wr<strong>on</strong>g with Libertarianism.” Critical ReviewlI(3): 407-67.Gord<strong>on</strong>, David. 1990. Resurrecting Maw: The Analytical Mamists <strong>on</strong> Freedom, Ex- \;2;pfoitati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>and</strong>lustice, New Brunswick, N.J.: Transacti<strong>on</strong> Books.i’:IGrossman,Vassily 1986. Forever Flowing. New York: Harper & Row.i;Haworth, Alan. 1994. Anti-libertarianism: Markets, Philosophy <strong>and</strong> Myth. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>:Routledge.ii.IHayek. E A. 1988. 77te Fatal C<strong>on</strong>ceit:77ie Erma dSocialism, ed. W W. Bartley, 111.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge.Ingram, Attracta. 1994. A Political Tlreory of Rights. Oxford: Oxford Universityf.Press. F. .Kymlicka, Will. 1990. C<strong>on</strong>tempomry PoWal Philosophy: An Introductj<strong>on</strong>, Oxford:1:Clarend<strong>on</strong> Press. !Libecap, Gary D. 1989. “Distributi<strong>on</strong>al Issues in C<strong>on</strong>tracting for <strong>Property</strong>i’I.I.Rights!’Journal of Instituti<strong>on</strong>al <strong>and</strong> Theoretical Ec<strong>on</strong>omics 145: 6-24. I..Lueck, Dean, 1993. “C<strong>on</strong>tracting into the Comm<strong>on</strong>s!’ In The Political &c<strong>on</strong>omy1.;:.Customs <strong>and</strong> Culture: informal Soluti<strong>on</strong>s to the Comm<strong>on</strong>s Problem, ed. Terry L.Anders<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>y T. Simm<strong>on</strong>s. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Lidefield.iMadis<strong>on</strong>, James. 1983. “<strong>Property</strong>? In The Papm ofJames Madis<strong>on</strong>, vol. 14: 6 April2781-26 Match 2799. Charl<strong>on</strong>esville: University Press of Virginia.Maine, Sir Henry Sumner. 1888. ‘hcturec <strong>on</strong> the Early Hisfory qfhstituti<strong>on</strong>s. New . .. iYork Henry Holt.Muneer, Stephen R. 1990. A Theory OJ <strong>Property</strong>. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.Narves<strong>on</strong>, Jan. 1990. Tlre U&ertudun Idea, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.:tNorbeq, Kathryn. 1988. “Dividing Up the Comm<strong>on</strong>s: Instituti<strong>on</strong>al Change inRural France, 1789-1799.“ Polltiu <strong>and</strong> Socfety 16265-86.Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, <strong>and</strong> Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Pufendorf, Samuel. 1994. The Politlcal Writings of Samuel Pufendotj ed. Craig L.Carr, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Rosenberg, Alex<strong>and</strong>er. 1988. “The Political Philosophy of Biological Endowments.”Social Phfhophy <strong>and</strong> Polity 5 (I): 1-31.Ryan, Alan. 1994. “<strong>Self</strong>-<strong>Ownership</strong>, Aut<strong>on</strong>omy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Property</strong> Rights,‘‘ In <strong>Property</strong>Rights, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, <strong>and</strong> JeEey Paul. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Schelling, Thomas. 1960. The Strategy ofCot@cf. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UniversityPress.Simm<strong>on</strong>s, A. John. 1994. “Original-Acquisiti<strong>on</strong> Justificati<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>Property</strong>,’’ In<strong>Property</strong> Rights, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., <strong>and</strong> Je&y Paul.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Sreenivasan, Gopal. 1995, The Limits ofbckean Rights in <strong>Property</strong>. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.Steiner, Hillel. 1994. An Essay <strong>on</strong> Rights. Oxfotd: Blackwell.Sugden, Robert. 1986. The Ec<strong>on</strong>omiu qf mghts, Co-operati<strong>on</strong> <strong>and</strong> Wehre. OxfordBad Blackwell.


<strong>Palmer</strong> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Cohen</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Property</strong> <strong>and</strong> EqualityZSIWaldr<strong>on</strong>, Jeremy, 1988. The Right to Private <strong>Property</strong>. Oxford Oxford UniversityPress.Weinberg, Justin. 1997. “Freedom, <strong>Self</strong>-<strong>Ownership</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Libertarian PhilosophicalDiaspora.” Critical Review 11 (3): 323-44,Young, H. Peyt<strong>on</strong>. 1996. “Dividing the Indivisible:’ In Wise Choices: Dedsi<strong>on</strong>s,Gamec, <strong>and</strong> Negoriafi<strong>on</strong>s, ed. Richard 3. Zeckhauaer, Ralph L. Keeney, <strong>and</strong>James K. Sebenius. Bost<strong>on</strong>: Harvard Business School Press.’

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!