11.07.2015 Views

Bell's theorem : experimental tests and implications - Physics at ...

Bell's theorem : experimental tests and implications - Physics at ...

Bell's theorem : experimental tests and implications - Physics at ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1882 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyContents1. Introduction .2. The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen argument ,3. Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> .3.2. Foreword to the non-idealised case .3.3. Generalis<strong>at</strong>ion of the locality concept .3.4. Bell’s 1971 proof .3.5. The proof by Clauser <strong>and</strong> Horne .3.6. Symmetry consider<strong>at</strong>ions .3.7. The proof by Wigner, Belinfante <strong>and</strong> Holt .3.8, Stapp’s proof .3.1. Deterministic local hidden-variables theories <strong>and</strong> Bell (1965)3.9. Other versions of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> .4. Consider<strong>at</strong>ions regarding a general <strong>experimental</strong> test .4.1. Requirements for a general <strong>experimental</strong> test .4.2. Three important <strong>experimental</strong> cases .5. Cascade-photon experiments .5.1. Predictions by local realistic theories ,5.2. Quantum-mechanical predictions for a J =0+1 -to two-photon correl<strong>at</strong>ion.5.3. Description of experiments5.4. Are the auxiliary assumptions for cascade-photon experiments necessary<strong>and</strong> reasonable? .6. Positronium annihil<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> proton-proton sc<strong>at</strong>tering experiments6.1. Historical background6.2. The experiment by Kasday, Ullman <strong>and</strong> Wu6.3. The experiments by Faraci et al, Wilson et al <strong>and</strong> Bruno et a16.4. Proton-proton sc<strong>at</strong>tering experiment by Lamehi-Rachti <strong>and</strong> Mittig .7. Evalu<strong>at</strong>ion of the <strong>experimental</strong> results <strong>and</strong> prospects for future experiments7.1. Two problems .7.2. Experiments without auxiliary assumptions about detector efficiencies7.3. Preventing communic<strong>at</strong>ion between the analysers7.4. Conclusion .Appendix 1. Criticism of EPR argument by Bohr, Furry <strong>and</strong> SchrodingerAppendix 2. Hidden-variables theories .Acknowledgments .References ...Page1883188518861887188918911892189418961897189819001900190119021903190419061908191219141914191519171917191819181919192019211921192219261926


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 18831. IntroductionRealism is a philosophical view, according to which external reality is assumed toexist <strong>and</strong> have definite properties, whether or not they are observed by someone. Soentrenched is this viewpoint in modern thinking th<strong>at</strong> many scientists <strong>and</strong> philosophershave sought to devise conceptual found<strong>at</strong>ions for quantum mechanics th<strong>at</strong> are clearlyconsistent with it. One possibility, it has been hoped, is to reinterpret quantummechanics in terms of a st<strong>at</strong>istical account of an underlying hidden-variables theoryin order to bring it within the general framework of classical physics. However, Bell’s<strong>theorem</strong> has recently shown th<strong>at</strong> this cannot be done. The <strong>theorem</strong> proves th<strong>at</strong> allrealistic theories, s<strong>at</strong>isfying a very simple <strong>and</strong> n<strong>at</strong>ural condition called locality, may betested with a single experiment against quantum mechanics. These two altern<strong>at</strong>ivesnecessarily lead to significantly different predictions. The <strong>theorem</strong> has thus inspiredvarious experiments, most of which have yielded results in excellent agreement withquantum mechanics, but in disagreement with the family of local realistic theories.Consequently, it can now be asserted with reasonable confidence th<strong>at</strong> either the thesisof realism or th<strong>at</strong> of locality must be ab<strong>and</strong>oned. Either choice will drastically changeour concepts of reality <strong>and</strong> of space-time.The historical background for this result is interesting, <strong>and</strong> represents an extremeirony for Einstein’s steadfastly realistic position, coupled with his desire th<strong>at</strong> physicsbe expressable solely in simple geometric terms. Within the realistic framework,Einstein et aZ(l935, hereafter referred to as EPR) presented a classic argument. As astarting point, they assumed the non-existence of action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong> someof the st<strong>at</strong>istical predictions of quantum mechanics are correct. They considered asystem consisting of two sp<strong>at</strong>ially separ<strong>at</strong>ed but quantum-mechanically correl<strong>at</strong>edparticles. For this system, they showed th<strong>at</strong> the results of various experiments arepredetermined, but th<strong>at</strong> this fact is not part of the quantum-mechanical descriptionof the associ<strong>at</strong>ed systems. Hence th<strong>at</strong> description is an incomplete one. To completethe description, it is thus necessary to postul<strong>at</strong>e additional ‘hidden variables’, whichpresumably will then restore completeness, determinism <strong>and</strong> causality to thetheory.Many in the physics community rejected their argument, preferring to follow acounter-argument by Bohr (1935), who believed th<strong>at</strong> the whole realistic viewpoint isinapplicable. Many others, however, felt th<strong>at</strong> since both viewpoints lead to the sameobservable phenomenology, a commitment to either one is only a m<strong>at</strong>ter of taste.Hence, the discussion, for the gre<strong>at</strong>er part of the subsequent 30 years, was pursuedperhaps more <strong>at</strong> physicists’ cocktail parties than in the mainstream of modernresearch.Starting in 1965, however, the situ<strong>at</strong>ion changed dram<strong>at</strong>ically. Using essentiallythe same postul<strong>at</strong>es as those of EPR, JS Bell showed for a Gedankenexperiment ofBohm (a variant of th<strong>at</strong> of EPR) th<strong>at</strong> no deterministic local hidden-variables theorycan reproduce all of the st<strong>at</strong>istical predictions by quantum mechanics. Inspired by th<strong>at</strong>work, Clauser et aZ(l969, hereafter referred to as CHSH) added three contributions.First, they showed th<strong>at</strong> his analysis can be extended to cover actual systems, <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong><strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> of this broad class of theories can be performed. Second, theyintroduced a very reasonable auxiliary assumption which allows <strong>tests</strong> to be performed


1886 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonysomehow in a singlet st<strong>at</strong>e, for example, by dissoci<strong>at</strong>ion of the spin-0 system. Variousspin components of each of these particles may then be measured independently <strong>at</strong> theoption of the experimenter. The spin part of the st<strong>at</strong>e vector is given by:Here Q .Auh*( 1) = f u~*( l), so th<strong>at</strong> US( 1) quantum mechanically describes a st<strong>at</strong>e inwhich particle 1 has spin ‘up’ or ‘down’, respectively, along the direction R; uli*(2)has an analogous meaning concerning particle 2. Since the singlet st<strong>at</strong>e Y is sphericallysymmetric, A can specify any direction. Suppose th<strong>at</strong> one measures the spin ofparticle 1 along the 4 axis. The outcome is not predetermined by the description Y.But from it, one can predict th<strong>at</strong> if particle 1 is found to have its spin parallel to the4 axis, then particle 2 will be found to have its spin antiparallel to the 4 axis if the4 component of its spin is also measured. Thus, the experimenter can arrange hisappar<strong>at</strong>us in such a way th<strong>at</strong> he can predict the value of the f component of spin ofparticle 2 presumably without interacting with it (if there is no action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance).Likewise, he can arrange the appar<strong>at</strong>us so th<strong>at</strong> he can predict any other componentof the spin of particle 2. The conclusion of the argument is th<strong>at</strong> all components ofspin of each particle are definite, which of course is not so in the quantum-mechanicaldescription. Hence, a hidden-variables theory seems to be required.Some comments are in order concerning EPR’s premises in the light of Bell’s<strong>theorem</strong>. If premise (i) is taken to assert th<strong>at</strong> all of the quantum-mechanical predictionsare correct, then Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> has shown it to be inconsistent with premises(ii) <strong>and</strong> (iii). Actually, in the body of their argument EPR used only a few predictionswith probability one, which are <strong>at</strong>ypical in quantum mechanics, whereas the discrepancieswhich Bell exhibited between local realistic theories <strong>and</strong> quantum mechanicsinvolved st<strong>at</strong>istical predictions. If it was EPR’s intention to aim <strong>at</strong> a hiddenvariablestheory which is local <strong>and</strong> realistic, <strong>and</strong> which agrees with all the st<strong>at</strong>isticalpredictions of quantum mechanics-as many readers have understood them-then,of course, Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> shows m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ically th<strong>at</strong> this aim cannot be achieved. Weshall not try to answer the historical question of their intent. Two st<strong>at</strong>ements, however,can be made with confidence. First, the argument from their premises is valid, oncethe above-mentioned ambiguity is cleared up. Second, the physical situ<strong>at</strong>ion whichthey envisaged is of immense value for examining the philosophical <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> ofquantum mechanics <strong>and</strong> (via Bell’s work) for exploring the limit<strong>at</strong>ions of the family oflocal realistic physical theories.3. Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>There is a vast liter<strong>at</strong>ure concerning the consistency of hidden-variables theorieswith the algebraic structure of the observables of quantum mechanics. The majorresults of this liter<strong>at</strong>ure are summarised in appendix 2, but they are not indispensablefor underst<strong>and</strong>ing the content <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>. Heuristically,however, this liter<strong>at</strong>ure was very important for Bell’s work. In the course of preparinga review article on ‘impossibility’ proofs of hidden-variables interpret<strong>at</strong>ions ofquantum mechanics, Bell studied the theories proposed by de Broglie (1928) <strong>and</strong>Bohm (1952). He noticed, as Bohm had already realised, th<strong>at</strong> in order to reproducethe quantum-theoretic predictions for a system of EPR type, they postul<strong>at</strong>ed the


Bell’s theovem : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1887existence of non-local interactions between sp<strong>at</strong>ially separ<strong>at</strong>ed particles. Bell was thusled to ask whether the peculiar non-locality exhibited by these models is a genericcharacteristic of hidden-variables theories th<strong>at</strong> agree with the st<strong>at</strong>istical predictionsby quantum mechanics. He proved (Bell 1965) th<strong>at</strong> the answer is positive for thewhole class of deterministic hidden-variables theories in the domain of ideal appar<strong>at</strong>us<strong>and</strong> systems. Stronger versions of this <strong>theorem</strong>, which also constrain actual systems,were l<strong>at</strong>er proved by Bell himself <strong>and</strong> by others. These versions st<strong>at</strong>e th<strong>at</strong> essentiallyall realistic local theories of n<strong>at</strong>ural phenomena may be tested in a single <strong>experimental</strong>arrangement against quantum mechanics, <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong> these two altern<strong>at</strong>ives necessarilylead to observably different predictions.In this section we review some of these deriv<strong>at</strong>ions, which we shall refer tocollectively as ‘Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>’. Our purpose here is to arrive <strong>at</strong> versions of Bell’s<strong>theorem</strong> which s<strong>at</strong>isfy the following criteria. (i) The hypotheses seem to be inescapablefor anyone who is committed to physical realism <strong>and</strong> to the non-existence of action-<strong>at</strong>a-distance.(ii) Discrepancies with the predictions by quantum mechanics occur in <strong>at</strong>least one situ<strong>at</strong>ion which is <strong>experimental</strong>ly realisable. Criterion (i) is, in our opinion,very close to having been achieved, although the hypotheses are viol<strong>at</strong>ed by somep<strong>at</strong>hological instances of local realistic theories. Criterion (ii) has essentially beenachieved; however, the experiment which it specifies is difficult, <strong>and</strong> has not yet beenperformed. Additional assumptions, not implicit in locality <strong>and</strong> realism, have beenrelied upon to allow easier experiments to be considered. (The assumptions <strong>and</strong>experiments are discussed in 445 <strong>and</strong> 6.) Unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely, this fact leaves open variousloopholes (discussed in ss5-7). It must be stressed, however, th<strong>at</strong> the existence ofthese loopholes in no way diminishes the m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical validity of the versions ofBell’s <strong>theorem</strong> presented in this section.3.1. Detennizistic local hidden-variables theories <strong>and</strong> Bell (1 965)In his paper of 1965 Bell considered Bohm’s Gedankenexperiment, described abovein $2, Th<strong>at</strong> system consists of two spin-Q particles, prepared in the quantum-mechanicalsinglet st<strong>at</strong>e Y given by equ<strong>at</strong>ion (2.1). Let Ab be the result of a measurement ofthe spin component of particle 1 of the pair along the direction d, <strong>and</strong> let Bfi be th<strong>at</strong>of particle 2 along direction 6. We take the unit of spin as A/2; hence, Ab, Bs= k 1.The product A,.Bfi is a single observable of the two-particle system (even thoughtwo distinct oper<strong>at</strong>ions are needed in order to measure it). It is represented quantummechanically by a self-adjoint oper<strong>at</strong>or on the Hilbert space associ<strong>at</strong>ed with thesystem. For this Gedankenexperiment one can readily calcul<strong>at</strong>e the quantum-mechanicalprediction for the expect<strong>at</strong>ion value of this observable-f :[E(&, 6)l.p = (Y I a1 .doz. 6 I Y) = - d. 6. (3 * 1)A special case of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.1) contains the determinism implicit in this idealisedsystem. When the analysers are parallel, we have:[E(ri, d)]y”= - 1 (3.2)for all &. Thus, one can predict with certainty the result B, by previously obtainingf The not<strong>at</strong>ion of this review is to use the wavefunction or the letters QM as a subscriptto denote the quantum-mechanical prediction. We omit the subscript for predictions by theclass of theories included by the postul<strong>at</strong>es of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>, when this convention does notcause confusion.


1888 F Clausw <strong>and</strong> A Shimonythe result A (EPR’s premise (ii)). Since the quantum-mechanical st<strong>at</strong>e Y does notdetermine the result of an individual measurement, this fact (via EPRs argument)suggests th<strong>at</strong> there exists a more complete specific<strong>at</strong>ion of the st<strong>at</strong>e in which thisdeterminism is manifest. We denote this st<strong>at</strong>e by the single symbol A, although itmay well have many dimensions, discrete <strong>and</strong>/or continuous parts, <strong>and</strong> different partsof it interacting with either appar<strong>at</strong>us, etc. Presumably the quantum st<strong>at</strong>e Y is arel<strong>at</strong>ed partial specific<strong>at</strong>ion of this st<strong>at</strong>e. We thus define a deterministic hiddenvariablestheory as any physical theory which postul<strong>at</strong>es the existence of st<strong>at</strong>es of asystem, for which the observables of quantum mechanics always have definite values.Let A be the space of the st<strong>at</strong>es X for an ensemble comprised of a very large numberof the observed systems. We make no restrictions as to wh<strong>at</strong> type of space this is,nor to its dimensionality, nor do we require linearity for oper<strong>at</strong>ions with it, but ofcourse we require th<strong>at</strong> a set of Bore1 subsets of A be defined, so th<strong>at</strong> probabilitymeasures can be defined upon it. We represent the distribution function for the st<strong>at</strong>esA on the space A by the symbol p. For this ensemble we take p to have norm one:JA dp= 1. (3.3)In a deterministic hidden-variables theory the observable Ai. B6 has a definitevalue (Ad. Ba) (A) for the st<strong>at</strong>e A. For these theories Bell defined locality as follows:a deterministic hidden-variables theory is local if for all d <strong>and</strong> 6 <strong>and</strong> all A E A we have:(AL.Ba) (A)=A,(X).Bs(X). (3 *4)Th<strong>at</strong> is, once the st<strong>at</strong>e X is specified <strong>and</strong> the particles have separ<strong>at</strong>ed, measurements ofA can depend only upon X <strong>and</strong> d but not 6. Likewise measurements of B depend onlyupon h <strong>and</strong> 6, Any reasonable physical theory th<strong>at</strong> is realistic <strong>and</strong> deterministic <strong>and</strong>th<strong>at</strong> denies the existence of action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance is local in this sense. (More generaldefinitions of ‘local’ will be considered in 93.3.) For such theories the expect<strong>at</strong>ionvalue of Ai.Ba is then given byE(a, b)= JA Aa(A)Bs(X) dp. (3.5)Bell’s (1965) proof of the <strong>theorem</strong> consists of showing th<strong>at</strong> if the locality condition (3.4)<strong>and</strong> the condition (3.2) for partial agreement with quantum mechanics are boths<strong>at</strong>isfied, then the expect<strong>at</strong>ion values s<strong>at</strong>isfy a simple inequality. This inequality isthen an altern<strong>at</strong>ive prediction to th<strong>at</strong> by quantum mechanics for the expect<strong>at</strong>ion valueof A,.Bs. The predictions made by this inequality are quantit<strong>at</strong>ively different fromthose of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.1).The demonstr<strong>at</strong>ion is straightforward. Equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.2) can hold if <strong>and</strong> only ifAd( A) = - Bi( A) (3.6)holds for all h E A. Using equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.6) we calcul<strong>at</strong>e the following function, whichinvolves three different possible orient<strong>at</strong>ions of the analysers :E(d, &)-E(d, e)= - JA [A;(h)As(h)-A,(X)A,(X)] dp= - JA Aa(h)As(h)[l -&(h)&(A)]dp.Since A, B = F 1, this last expression can be written :


1892 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyAnalyser 2 Analyser 1IXDetector- -2SourceDetector 1Appar<strong>at</strong>us 2Appar<strong>at</strong>us 1Figure 2. Appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion used in the proofs by CHSH <strong>and</strong> by CH. A sourceemitting particle pairs is viewed by two appar<strong>at</strong>uses. Each appar<strong>at</strong>us consists of ananalyser <strong>and</strong> an associ<strong>at</strong>ed detector. The analysers have parameters a <strong>and</strong> b respectively,which are externally adjustable. In the above example a <strong>and</strong> b representthe angles between the analyser axes <strong>and</strong> a fixed reference axis.measuring the associ<strong>at</strong>ed spin components. However, in general, a <strong>and</strong> b may representany associ<strong>at</strong>ed appar<strong>at</strong>us parameters under control by the experimenter. Asbefore, Aa <strong>and</strong> Bb represent the measurement outcomes <strong>at</strong> appar<strong>at</strong>uses 1 <strong>and</strong> 2,respectively. Appropri<strong>at</strong>e values will be assigned to these outcomes, as necessary.The preceding definition of locality will now be generalised to include systemswhose evolution is inherently stochastic, as well as to include deterministic systemswith additional r<strong>and</strong>om variables associ<strong>at</strong>ed with either appar<strong>at</strong>us, <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong> may locallyaffect their <strong>experimental</strong> outcomes. Suppose a pair of correl<strong>at</strong>ed systems, which havea joint st<strong>at</strong>e A, separ<strong>at</strong>e. They then continue to evolve perhaps in an inherentlystochastic way, <strong>and</strong> given A, a <strong>and</strong> b, one can define probabilities for any particularoutcome <strong>at</strong> either appar<strong>at</strong>us. We allow th<strong>at</strong>, given A, these two probabilities may eachdepend upon the associ<strong>at</strong>ed (local) appar<strong>at</strong>us parameter, a or 6 respectively, <strong>and</strong> ofcourse upon A, but we assume th<strong>at</strong> these probabilities are otherwise independent ofeach other.This definition of locality seems very common-sensical. It says th<strong>at</strong> the outcome(or the probability of outcomes) of a measurement performed on one part of a compositesystem is independent of wh<strong>at</strong> aspects of the other component the experimenterchooses to measure. It by no means excludes the possibility of obtaining knowledgeconcerning system 2 from an examin<strong>at</strong>ion of system 1. The st<strong>at</strong>e A contains inform<strong>at</strong>ioncommon to both systems, <strong>and</strong> a measurement on one of these presumably revealssome of this. Nor does it prevent a measurement performed on one component of acomposite system from locally disturbing th<strong>at</strong> component. Wh<strong>at</strong> it does prescribe,in essence, is th<strong>at</strong> the measured value of a quantity on one system is not causallyaffected by wh<strong>at</strong> one chooses to measure on the other system, since the two systemsare well separ<strong>at</strong>ed (e.g. space-like separ<strong>at</strong>ed) when the measurements are performed.3.4. Bell’s 1971 proofWe now describe Bell’s (1971) proof, using this generalised locality definition.The appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion appropri<strong>at</strong>e to this proof was discussed in $3.2 <strong>and</strong> isshown in figure 1. Given th<strong>at</strong> a particle pair was emitted into the associ<strong>at</strong>ed appar<strong>at</strong>uses,the results of either measurement can have one of three possible outcomes, to


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1893which the following values were assigned by Bell :I+ 1, ‘spin-up’ detector triggered by particle 1Aa( A) = - 1, ‘spin-down’ detector triggered by particle 1 (3.9(a))0, particle 1 not detected<strong>and</strong>I+ 1, ‘spin-up’ detector triggered by particle 2Bb( A) = - 1, ‘spin-down’ detector triggered by particle 2 (3.9(b))0, particle 2 not detected.For a given st<strong>at</strong>e A of the emitted composite system, we denote the expect<strong>at</strong>ion valuesfor these quantities by the symbols Aa( A) <strong>and</strong> Bb( A). In the general case these averagevalues will differ from the values assigned by equ<strong>at</strong>ions (3.9). Since the values for A<strong>and</strong> B are bounded by 1, it follows th<strong>at</strong>:IAa(A)I < 1 IBb(A)I < 1. (3.10)Using the general definition of locality of $3.3, we can write the expect<strong>at</strong>ion value forthe product AaBb as:E(a, b) = jA &( A)Bb( A) dp* (3.11)Since we are including in our ensemble only those particles which have previouslytriggered the ‘event-ready’ detectors, we are assured th<strong>at</strong> the distribution p <strong>and</strong> therange of integr<strong>at</strong>ion A are independent of a <strong>and</strong> b. Now consider the expression:E(a, b)-E(a, b‘)= JA [Aa(h)Bb(X)-Aa(X)Bb.(X)I dpwhere we take a‘ <strong>and</strong> b’ to be altern<strong>at</strong>ive settings for analysers 1 <strong>and</strong> 2, respectively.This can be rewritten as:E(a, b)-E(a, b’)=JA Aa(h)Bb(A)[l *&?(A)Bb’(A)] dp-JAUsing inequalities (3.10), we then have:orHence :IE(a, b)-E(a, b’)( < SA [I *Aaf(A)&(A)]Aa(A)Bb’(A)[l &A<strong>at</strong>(X)Bb(A)] dp.IE(a, b)-E(a, b’)l < rt [E(a’, b’)+E(a‘, b)]-1-2dpf SA [I kAa‘(A)&(A)] dp- 2 < E(a, b) - E(a, b‘) + E(a’, b) + E(a’, b’) < 2. (3 * 12)By re-definition of the parameters a, a‘, b <strong>and</strong> b’ in the central expression of (3.12),the minus sign may be permuted to any one of the four terms. Inequality (3.12) <strong>and</strong>its permut<strong>at</strong>ions are one form of Bell’s inequality, <strong>and</strong> represent a general predictionfor the theories covered by the above assumptions.In order to complete the proof of the <strong>theorem</strong>, it is sufficient to show th<strong>at</strong> in <strong>at</strong>least one situ<strong>at</strong>ion the predictions by quantum mechanics contradict inequality (3.12).The quantum-mechanical prediction [E(&, b)]QM for the two spin-4 particle example,when due account is taken of imperfections in the analysers, detectors <strong>and</strong> st<strong>at</strong>eprepar<strong>at</strong>ion, will be of the form:dp.[E(&, ~)]QM= Cri.6 (3.13)


1894 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonywhere the coefficient C is bounded by one for actual systems, <strong>and</strong> is equal to plus orminus one only in the idealised case. Suppose we take 6, d’, 6 <strong>and</strong> 6‘ to be coplanarvectors as shown in figure 3 with (b = n/4, <strong>and</strong> calcul<strong>at</strong>e:There is a wide range of values for C for which the prediction by inequality (3.12)disagrees with th<strong>at</strong> by equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.13). Hence the proof is complete.3.5. The proof by Clauser <strong>and</strong> HomeClauser <strong>and</strong> Horne (1974) also proved Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> for general local realistictheories, including inherently stochastic theories. Their proof is noteworthy in th<strong>at</strong> itaFigure 3. Optimal orient<strong>at</strong>ions for a, a’, 6 <strong>and</strong> 6’. If the correl<strong>at</strong>ion is of the form C1+ Czcos n+, then the maximum viol<strong>at</strong>ion of the inequalities occurs <strong>at</strong> n+ = n/4.defines an experiment which might actually be performed <strong>and</strong> which does not requireth<strong>at</strong> auxiliary assumptions be made. The appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion which they usedfor the proof was introduced by Clauser et al(1969) <strong>and</strong> is shown schem<strong>at</strong>ically infigure 2. In contrast to the configur<strong>at</strong>ion of figure 1, theirs has only one detector ineach arm <strong>and</strong> no ‘event-ready’ detectors. For each analyser/detector assembly thereare only two possible outcomes: ‘count’ <strong>and</strong> ‘no-count’. The results are thus formul<strong>at</strong>edin terms of probabilities for single <strong>and</strong> coincidence counts, r<strong>at</strong>her than theexpect<strong>at</strong>ion values considered in Ss3.1 <strong>and</strong> 3.4.Suppose th<strong>at</strong> during a period of time, while the adjustable parameters have thevalues a <strong>and</strong> b, the source emits, say, N of the two-component systems of interest.For this period, denote by Nl(a) <strong>and</strong> Nz(b) the number of counts <strong>at</strong> detectors 1 <strong>and</strong> 2,respectively, <strong>and</strong> by N~z(a, b) the number of simultaneous counts from the twodetectors (coincidence counts). When N is sufficiently large, the probabilities for these


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>: <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1895results for the whole ensemble (with due allowance for r<strong>and</strong>om errors) are given by:(3.14)CH derive an inequality which constrains r<strong>at</strong>ios of the probabilities in equ<strong>at</strong>ions(3.14) r<strong>at</strong>her than their absolute magnitudes. Thereby, the influence of the quantityN vanishes, so th<strong>at</strong> it does not have to be measured.Their deriv<strong>at</strong>ion is straightforward. Following the discussion of 93.3, we expecta well-defined probability pl(A, a) of detecting component 1, given the st<strong>at</strong>e A of thecomposite system <strong>and</strong> the parameter a of the first analyser; a probability $4 A, b) ofdetecting component 2, given A <strong>and</strong> b; <strong>and</strong> a probability p14 A, a, b) of detecting bothcomponents, given A, a <strong>and</strong> b. Following our discussion of 53.3, we assume th<strong>at</strong>,given A, a <strong>and</strong> b, the probabilities pl(A, a) <strong>and</strong> pz(A, b) are independent. Thus wewrite the probability of detecting both components asPlZ(X, a, b)=p1(A, .)pz(A, b). (3.15)The ensemble average probabilities of equ<strong>at</strong>ions (3.14) are then given by:jApl(h a> dpSA$z(A, b) dp (3.16)P12(a, b)= j*Pl(A, a)Pz(A, b) dp.To proceed, CH introduce the following lemma, the proof of which may be found intheir paper: if x, x’, y,y’, X, Y are real numbers such th<strong>at</strong> O


1896 7 F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonythe r<strong>at</strong>e of single-particle detections by either appar<strong>at</strong>us, inequality (3 .20(a)) can berewritten directly in terms of a r<strong>at</strong>io of observable count r<strong>at</strong>es:R(a, b) - R(a, b’) + R(d, b) + R(a’, b’)< 1. (3*2O(b))n(a‘) + r2(b)Inequalities (3.20) are thus a general prediction for any local realistic theory of n<strong>at</strong>uralphenomena.In order to complete the proof of the <strong>theorem</strong> it suffices to exhibit an instance inwhich the quantum-mechanical counterpart to inequalities (3.20) fails. This is donein 94, when we discuss the <strong>experimental</strong> requirements for a valid test of these theories.3.6. Symmetry consider<strong>at</strong>ionsAlmost all of the experiments which have been proposed for testing the predictionsby Bell’s inequalities involve pairs of polarised particles (either photons or massiveparticles). In these experiments the parameters a <strong>and</strong> b, considered abstractly in993.4 <strong>and</strong> 3.5, are taken to be orient<strong>at</strong>ion angles rel<strong>at</strong>ive to some reference axis in afixed plane. In most of these experiments, the method of preparing the pairs ofpolarised particles <strong>at</strong>tempts to achieve cylindrical symmetry about a normal to thefixed plane <strong>and</strong> reflection symmetry with respect to planes through this normal. Thissymmetry is exhibited in the quantum-mechanical predictions for detection r<strong>at</strong>es<strong>and</strong> correl<strong>at</strong>ions :[Pl(a)]QM <strong>and</strong> [rl(a)]QM are independent of a.[&(b)]QM <strong>and</strong> [r2(b)]QM are independent of b.@JIZ(~)]QM, [R(a, b)]QM <strong>and</strong> [E(a, b)]QM are functions only of I a - b 1 .We now assume th<strong>at</strong> the corresponding predictions for local realistic theories exhibitthe same symmetries:pl(a) =*I <strong>and</strong> rl(a) 3 rl are independent of bp2(b) 3p2 <strong>and</strong> r4b) 12 are independent of b (3.21)p12(a, b)=p12(la-bl), R(a, b)rR(la-bl) <strong>and</strong> E(a, b)=E(la-bl).We must emphasise two points concerning equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.21). First, these symmetryrel<strong>at</strong>ions do not simply follow from the corresponding quantum-mechanical symmetryrel<strong>at</strong>ions or from the symmetry of the <strong>experimental</strong> arrangement, for one does notknow wh<strong>at</strong> symmetry-breaking factors may lurk <strong>at</strong> the level of the hidden variables.Second, no harm is done in assuming equ<strong>at</strong>ions (3.21), since they are susceptible to<strong>experimental</strong> verific<strong>at</strong>ion.Now suppose th<strong>at</strong> we take a, a’, b <strong>and</strong> b’ so th<strong>at</strong>:Ia-bI = la’-bl= Ia’-b’I =&Ia-b‘I =$as in figure 3. With the use of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.21), inequalities (3.12) <strong>and</strong> (3.20) simplifytoI 3E(4) - E(34) I 2 (3.22)<strong>and</strong>S(4) 1 (3 .23)


where we have defined :Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong>in terms of probabilities, or equivalently in terms of count r<strong>at</strong>es:3.7. The proof by Wigner, Belinfante <strong>and</strong> HoltA simple method of proving Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> for deterministic local hidden-variablestheories was invented independently by Wigner (1970) <strong>and</strong> Belinfante (1973), <strong>and</strong>extended by Holt (1973). The method consists of subdividing the space A of st<strong>at</strong>esof a two-component system into subspaces corresponding to various possible valuesof the observables of interest, <strong>and</strong> then performing some easy calcul<strong>at</strong>ions on themeasures of these subspaces. R<strong>at</strong>her than duplic<strong>at</strong>e their proofs, which are readilyavailable, we show how their method can be used to derive the inequality of CH.Consider the appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion of figure 2. Assume th<strong>at</strong> the detection or nondetectionof component 1 is completely determined by the parameter a of the firstanalyser <strong>and</strong> the st<strong>at</strong>e of the composite system, but is independent of the parameter bof the other analyser, <strong>and</strong> so forth for component 2. As such, the discussion is for therestricted situ<strong>at</strong>ion in which determinism applies. Under this assumption, we canexhaustively subdivide the space A into 16 mutually disjoint subspaces A (ij; kl),where each letter can take on the value 0 or 1, with 1 denoting detection <strong>and</strong> 0 nondetection;with i <strong>and</strong>j referring to the results if the parameter of the first analyser ischosen respectively to be a or a’; <strong>and</strong> with h <strong>and</strong> 1 referring to the results if the parameterof the second analyser is chosen respectively to be b or b’. For example,A (10; 01) is the subspace in which component 1 will be detected if its associ<strong>at</strong>ed parameteris chosen to be a but will not if the parameter is chosen to be a’, while component2 will not be detected if its associ<strong>at</strong>ed parameter is chosen to be b but will be detectedif th<strong>at</strong> parameter is chosen to be b’. (Note th<strong>at</strong> there is no question of simultaneouslyexamining detection or non-detection for two different values of a parameter. Indeed,such observ<strong>at</strong>ions are mutually exclusive. R<strong>at</strong>her, the subspace is defined in terms ofwh<strong>at</strong> will happen if any one of the various experiments is performed. Since thetheories are assumed to be deterministic, these values are all determined once a, b, X<strong>and</strong> the appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion are specified.) If a probability measure p is assumedto be given on A (determined presumably by the way in which the composite systemis prepared), then p(Y; kl) is defined to be the probability th<strong>at</strong> the composite st<strong>at</strong>e is inA(ij; kl). Clearly, all p(ij; kl) are non-neg<strong>at</strong>ive. Because the 16 subspaces are disjoint<strong>and</strong> exhaustive, we have :(3.25)We now define pl(a) to be the Probability th<strong>at</strong> component 1 will be detected if itsparameter is chosen to be a;p2(b) to be the probability th<strong>at</strong> component 2 will bedetected if its parameter is chosen to be b; <strong>and</strong> pl2(a, b) to be the probability of jointdetection of both components if the two parameters are chosen respectively to be a<strong>and</strong> b. Analogous definitions are given for the other values of the parameters. Then


1898 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonywe have :It follows th<strong>at</strong>:p12(a, b) -p12(a, b‘) +~12(a’, b) +~12(a’, b’) -pi(a’>-P@)= -p(11; 01)-p(l1; 00)-p(10; 11)-p(l0; Ol)-p(01; 10)-p(OI; 00)-p(O0; 11)-p(OO; 10). (3.27)Consequently, we recover inequality (3.19) derived by Clauser <strong>and</strong> Horne forthe more general stochastic case:- 1


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1899of ‘counterfactual definiteness’, th<strong>at</strong> raj(&, 6), raj(ci, I?), etc, are all definite numbers.In addition, he made an assumption of individual locality, th<strong>at</strong>:rlj(d, 6)=r1,(d, 61)?lj(cil, 6)=rlj(d’, a’)(3.28(a))(3 * 2W))rag(d, 6) = r23(d’, 6) (3* 2W)rzj(ci, 6’) = r2j(d1, Q.(3*28(d))Stapp then showed th<strong>at</strong> the 8N numbers rap(&, a), etc, must disagree with some of thest<strong>at</strong>istical predictions of quantum mechanics. Some critics of Stapp have argued th<strong>at</strong>his assumption of counterfactual definiteness is underst<strong>and</strong>able only from the st<strong>and</strong>pointof a deterministic local hidden-variables theory. Stapp (1978, $4) has replied,however, th<strong>at</strong> his assumption requires no commitment to determinism, but only tothe possibility of speaking (as is commonly done in the sciences) of possible worlds aswell as the actual one. He makes the explicit assumption th<strong>at</strong> each of the four choices(d, 6), (d, 6’), (d’, 6) <strong>and</strong> (d’, 6‘) is made in some possible world. It may neverthelessbe objected th<strong>at</strong> Stapp has not given a reason for dem<strong>and</strong>ing the existence of a quadrupleof possible worlds which mesh together as in equ<strong>at</strong>ions (3.28(a)-(d)). Thecombin<strong>at</strong>ion of no action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance with the idea of possible worlds only seems torequire four pairs of possible worlds, one pair meshing as in equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.28(a)), oneas in equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.28(b)), etc. It is not obvious why these four rel<strong>at</strong>ions need to governa cluster of four possible worlds unless determinism is supposed. An answer to thisobjection is provided by Stapp (1978), in which the following equivalence <strong>theorem</strong> isproved.Let I be the set of individual outcomes raj(c, d), where c is d or d’, d is 6 or 6’,01 is 1 or 2, <strong>and</strong>j is 1, . . . , N. Let P(I) be the set of probabilitiesp= ({rl I d}, {r2 I S}, {Tl, y2 I ci, 6))determined by the appropri<strong>at</strong>e frequencies in I:{Tl I d}= N(r1, d)/N(where N(r1, ci) is the number of j such th<strong>at</strong> rl =rlj(d, 6)=qj(d, 6’) by individuallocality),{ri, r2 I d, 6) = ~ (ri, r2, d, 6)(where N(r1, r2, d, 6) is the number of j such th<strong>at</strong> r1= rlj(d, 6) <strong>and</strong> r2 = 1.44 s)), etc.Let LP be the set of P which s<strong>at</strong>isfy the following probabilistic locality conditions:there exists a discrete set of A, a probability weight function p defined on this set, <strong>and</strong>probabilities p1( A, d, TI), p4 A, 6, r2) for the outcomes rl <strong>and</strong> r2 respectively (givenA <strong>and</strong> given d or 6), such th<strong>at</strong>:{n, r214 6>=C P(AlPl(A, 4 r1lp2(A, 6, y2)1{rl I ci> = C P(4Pl( A, ci, r1) (3.29)A{r21~)=CP(A)Pl(A, 6, r2).Finally, let L be the set of I which s<strong>at</strong>isfy the individual locality conditions (3 .28(a)-(d)). Then the equivalence <strong>theorem</strong> asserts (i) if I E L, then P(I) E Lp, (ii) if P E LP,then there is an I E L such th<strong>at</strong> P(I) is approxim<strong>at</strong>ely equal to P.


1900 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyNote th<strong>at</strong> (3.29) is essentially the CH probabilistic locality condition, except th<strong>at</strong>a sum over discrete values of h is used instead of an integral over the space A; butsince the integral can always be approxim<strong>at</strong>ed by a sum, this difference is not crucial.Because of this equivalence <strong>theorem</strong>, the <strong>theorem</strong> of CH <strong>and</strong> of Bell th<strong>at</strong> no P whichbelongs to L p can agree st<strong>at</strong>istically with quantum mechanics entails th<strong>at</strong> no I whichbelongs to L can agree st<strong>at</strong>istically with quantum mechanics <strong>and</strong>, conversely, the<strong>theorem</strong> of Stapp th<strong>at</strong> no 1 belonging to L can agree st<strong>at</strong>istically with quantummechanics implies the <strong>theorem</strong> of CH <strong>and</strong> Bell. Stapp’s equivalence <strong>theorem</strong>, therefore,shows th<strong>at</strong>, contrary to appearances, his proof of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> <strong>and</strong> those of CH<strong>and</strong> Bell (1971) are of equal strength. J S Bell (personal communic<strong>at</strong>ion) has remarkedth<strong>at</strong> part (ii) of Stapp’s equivalence <strong>theorem</strong> is an example of the possibility of simul<strong>at</strong>inga stochastic process with a deterministic one.3.9. Other versions of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>Several other versions of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> have been discovered. The proofs arem<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ically correct, but with hypotheses in some respects problem<strong>at</strong>ic, eitherfrom a philosophical point of view or from their inherent restriction to idealisedsystems.A very general deriv<strong>at</strong>ion of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> has been presented by Bell (1976). Itwas critically evalu<strong>at</strong>ed by Shimony et aZ(1976), who challenged one of the premises.Bell (1977) replied to this criticism. If we retain the not<strong>at</strong>ion of $3.8, we can expressthe essential assumption of Bell (1976) in the following way: the complete st<strong>at</strong>e ofregion SI is independent of the choice between 6 <strong>and</strong> 6’ in S2, <strong>and</strong> likewise the completest<strong>at</strong>e of S2 is independent of the choice between d <strong>and</strong> d’ in SI. Shimony et a1(1976) criticised this assumption on the ground th<strong>at</strong> the backward light cones of SI<strong>and</strong> S2 overlap in a region S, <strong>and</strong> it is possible th<strong>at</strong> a factor in S affecting the choicebetween 6 <strong>and</strong> 6’ leaves some trace in SI. Bell’s reply (1977) to this objection stressesthe spontaneity of the experimenter’s choice between 6 <strong>and</strong> 6‘ <strong>and</strong> between d <strong>and</strong> d’,but this answer seems to us to depend upon too strong a commitment to indeterminismfor his argument to be fully general (see also Shimony 1978).The proof by d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (1975) has the virtue of staying quite close to the originalideas of EPR by reasoning in terms of the intrinsic properties of the system. We shallnot try to summarise his argument, partly because of its length <strong>and</strong> partly because of apremise which is impossible to be realised <strong>experimental</strong>ly. D’Espagn<strong>at</strong> assumes (asBell did in 1965) th<strong>at</strong> one has a system like a pair of spin-4 particles in the singletst<strong>at</strong>e, such th<strong>at</strong> one can measure an observable of one of the pair <strong>and</strong> then infer withabsolute certainty the value of a corresponding observable of the other pair (equ<strong>at</strong>ion(3.2)). The same criticism can also be made of the arguments of Gutkowski <strong>and</strong>Masotto (1974), Selleri (1978) <strong>and</strong> Schiavulli (1977) but it should be noted th<strong>at</strong> theyderive a number of generalis<strong>at</strong>ions of Bell’s inequalities which have not been obtainedelsewhere.4. Consider<strong>at</strong>ions regarding a general <strong>experimental</strong> testFollowing Bell’s (1965) results, many readers believed th<strong>at</strong> local realistic theorieswere ipso facto discredited, because quantum mechanics has been so abundantlyconfirmed in a variety of <strong>experimental</strong> situ<strong>at</strong>ions. Indeed, some of the most striking


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>: <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1901confirm<strong>at</strong>ions of quantum mechanics, such as the spectrum of helium, concernedcorrel<strong>at</strong>ed pairs of particles. However, upon careful examin<strong>at</strong>ion, one finds th<strong>at</strong>situ<strong>at</strong>ions exhibiting the disagreement discovered by Bell are r<strong>at</strong>her rare, <strong>and</strong> nonehad ever been <strong>experimental</strong>ly realised. Moreover, the reasoning of the previoussections indic<strong>at</strong>es th<strong>at</strong> the tre<strong>at</strong>ment of correl<strong>at</strong>ed but sp<strong>at</strong>ially separ<strong>at</strong>ed systems maywell be the point of gre<strong>at</strong>est vulnerability of quantum mechanics. In view of theconsequences of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> it is thus important to design experiments to testexplicitly the predictions made for local realistic theories via Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>.Starting with the simple configur<strong>at</strong>ions specified in $3, the first problem is to finda suitable system whose quantum-mechanical predictions directly viol<strong>at</strong>e the predictionsin the <strong>theorem</strong>, but additionally one th<strong>at</strong> is accessible with available technology.In fact, this has not yet been done! (Possible avenues in this direction are discussedin $7.) In the present section we examine the requirements for a fully general test,<strong>and</strong> see why the problem is difficult. Since the presence of auxiliary counters isrequired by the appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion of figure 1, <strong>and</strong> usually these depolarise ordestroy the emissions, we will confine our discussion to the appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion offigure 2.We thus compare the quantum-mechanical predictions for this configur<strong>at</strong>ion withthose by inequality (3.23). The left-h<strong>and</strong> side of inequality (3.19) is not consideredhere, since it cannot be expressed in terms of r<strong>at</strong>ios of observable probabilities. It will,however, become useful for the discussion of $5.4.1. Requirements for a general <strong>experimental</strong> testConsider an experiment, with a configur<strong>at</strong>ion similar to th<strong>at</strong> of figure 2, whosequantum-mechanical predictions take the following form:[$12($)]QM=$171y2f1g[c+lc+~ fF COS (n$)][pl]QM=& ylflc+l (4.1)[pZ]QM=& r/2f2e+2-This general form is characteristic of the quantum-mechanical predictions for theactual experiments of interest (see, for example, equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.15)). In these expressionsq represents the effective quantum efficiency of detector i(i= 1,2), <strong>and</strong>€+i = €Mi + €,t E-’ E €Mi - €mi. (4.2)The terms EM^ <strong>and</strong> c,Z are the maximum <strong>and</strong> minimum transmissions of the analysersrel<strong>at</strong>ive to the pertinent orthogonal basis. The functions f1 <strong>and</strong> fi are the collim<strong>at</strong>orefficiencies, i.e. the probability th<strong>at</strong> an appropri<strong>at</strong>e emission enters appar<strong>at</strong>us 1 or 2.Typically, these are simply proportional to the collim<strong>at</strong>or acceptance solid angles.The function g is the conditional probability th<strong>at</strong>, given emission 1 enters appar<strong>at</strong>us1, then emission 2 will enter appar<strong>at</strong>us 2. The function F is a measure of the initialst<strong>at</strong>epurity <strong>and</strong> the inherent quantum-mechanical correl<strong>at</strong>ion of the two emissions.For the actual cascade-photon experiments (see $5), these functions depend on thecollim<strong>at</strong>or solid angles. The values of n are 1 or 2 depending upon whether theexperiment is performed with fermions or bosons.Inserting equ<strong>at</strong>ion (4.1) into the definition of S($), equ<strong>at</strong>ion (3.24(a)), we findthe quantum-mechanical prediction for this function to be given by :SQM($) = yg (2c++ [3 cos (n+)- cos (3n$)] F(E-~/E+). (4.3)


1902 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyHere for simplicity we have taken r 771 = 772, fi = f2, E+ = ~+1= ~+2 <strong>and</strong> E- 5 e-1 = E-2.Selecting the optimum value y5= .rr/4n, one finds th<strong>at</strong> the condition for a viol<strong>at</strong>ion ofinequality (3.23) is given by :vg€+[d2 (€-/E+)2 Ff 11 > 2. (4.4)Thus, a correl<strong>at</strong>ion experiment with values in the domain specified by inequality (4.4)is capable of distinguishing between the prediction, inequality (3.23), <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong> ofquantum theory, equ<strong>at</strong>ion (4.3). Although such experiments are apparently possible,there is <strong>at</strong> present no existing <strong>experimental</strong> result in this domain, <strong>and</strong> thus none inviol<strong>at</strong>ion of any inequality which does not require additional assumptions for itsderiv<strong>at</strong>ion.For a direct test of inequality (4.4) the requirements are stringent, which accountsfor the fact th<strong>at</strong>, so far, no such experiment has been <strong>at</strong>tempted.(i) A source must emit pairs of discrete-st<strong>at</strong>e systems, which can be detected withhigh efficiency.(ii) Quantum mechanics must predict strong correl<strong>at</strong>ions of the relevant observablesof each pair (polaris<strong>at</strong>ions in the experiments so far). Correspondingly, theensemble of pairs must have high quantum-mechanical purity.(iii) The analysers must be capable of allowing systems in certain st<strong>at</strong>es to passwith gre<strong>at</strong> efficiency, while simultaneously rejecting nearly all of those in orthogonalst<strong>at</strong>es.(iv) The collim<strong>at</strong>ors (<strong>and</strong> filters if these are necessary to remove unwanted emissions,etc) must have very high transmittances <strong>and</strong> not depolarise the emissions.(v) The source must produce the systems via a two-body decay. A three- (ormore) body decay cannot be used, because the resulting angular correl<strong>at</strong>ion willmakeg41.(vi) Another requirement should be added in order to achieve an airtight argumentagainst locality: the parameters a <strong>and</strong> b must be rapidly changed while the emissionsare in flight. A detection event should be space-like separ<strong>at</strong>ed from the correspondingparameter change event <strong>at</strong> the far appar<strong>at</strong>us (see $7). This suggestion was first madeby Bohm <strong>and</strong> Aharonov (1957).For a practical experiment, it is of course also necessary for the counting r<strong>at</strong>e tobe sufficiently high to make the required integr<strong>at</strong>ion time reasonable.4.2. Three important <strong>experimental</strong> casesLet us examine how the failure of any of these parameters to approxim<strong>at</strong>e theideal case prevents a viol<strong>at</strong>ion of inequality (3.23) from arising. Figure 4 shows theprediction by equ<strong>at</strong>ion (4.3) for three important cases of interest, along with theprediction by inequality (3.23).Case I, nearly ideal. In the domain of nearly ideal appar<strong>at</strong>us, we have g z e+z E-=qz 1. For these conditions we find a viol<strong>at</strong>ion of inequality (3.23) for a wide range of4, with a maximum viol<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>at</strong> n4 = ~14.Case II, poor detector eficiencies or eo-focusing. When g < 1 holds, because of imperfectcollim<strong>at</strong>or alignment <strong>and</strong>/or a weak angular correl<strong>at</strong>ion inherent in a three-bodydecay, or when 274 1 holds, because the detector efficiencies are low, then the amplitudeof S(4) contracts in amplitude about a value close to zero. The quantummechanicalpredictions enter a domain where no viol<strong>at</strong>ion of inequality (3.23) occurs.


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1903I I I I1.5 Case I 4-0.5Case III I I Ini 2I1 9Figure 4. Typical dependence of S(4) upon nd, for cases 1-111. Upper bound for S(q5) setby inequality (3.23) is + 1. Case I experiments (nearly ideal) have ~ M~MFME+%E- M 1. Case I1 experiments have nearly ideal parameters F M E- M E+ M 1, but haveq < 1 <strong>and</strong>/or g < 1. Case I11 experiments have nearly ideal parameters q Mg M 1, buthave Fe1 <strong>and</strong>/or E-/E+


1904 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonyquantum-mechanical predictions directly viol<strong>at</strong>e <strong>Bell's</strong> inequalities. In 94 we showedth<strong>at</strong> to do so with available appar<strong>at</strong>us is difficult. The situ<strong>at</strong>ion is not hopeless,however. Clauser et a1 (1969) showed th<strong>at</strong> with a mild supplementary assumption,actual experiments are predicted by quantum mechanics to yield a viol<strong>at</strong>ion of <strong>Bell's</strong>inequality, <strong>and</strong> they proposed such an experiment.Their suggestion is to measure the correl<strong>at</strong>ion in linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion of photonpairs emitted in an <strong>at</strong>omic cascade. Figure 5 shows a schem<strong>at</strong>ic diagram of a typicalappar<strong>at</strong>us for doing this, th<strong>at</strong> of Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser (1972)) who reported the firstsuch test. The photons were emitted in a J = O-tJ = 1 4 = 0 <strong>at</strong>omic cascade. Thedecaying <strong>at</strong>oms were viewed by two symmetrically placed optical systems, eachconsisting of two lenses, a wavelength filter, a rot<strong>at</strong>able <strong>and</strong> removable polariser, <strong>and</strong>a single-photon detector. The following quantities were measured: R(y3), the coincidencer<strong>at</strong>e for two-photon detection as a function of the angle between the planes oflinear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion, defined by the orient<strong>at</strong>ions of the inserted polarisers; RI, theFigure 5. Schem<strong>at</strong>ic diagram of appar<strong>at</strong>us <strong>and</strong> associ<strong>at</strong>ed electronics of the experiment byFreedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser. Scalers (not shown) monitored the outputs of the discrimin<strong>at</strong>ors<strong>and</strong> coincidence circuits (figure after Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser).coincidence r<strong>at</strong>e with polariser 2 removed; Rz, the coincidence r<strong>at</strong>e with polariser 1removed; Ro, the coincidence r<strong>at</strong>e with both polarisers removed.The details of this experiment along with other similar ones will be discussed in$5.3. First, however, we describe the auxiliary assumption(s) which render this areasonable test, <strong>and</strong> present the resulting inequalities. Then we describe the quantummechanicalpredictions for this <strong>and</strong> similar arrangements.5.1. Predictions by local realistic theories5.1 .l. Assumptions for cascade-photon experiments. The initial assumption by CHSHis, given th<strong>at</strong> a pair of photons emerges from the polarisers, the probability of theirjoint detection is independent of the polariser orient<strong>at</strong>ions a <strong>and</strong> b. Clauser <strong>and</strong> Horne(1974) showed th<strong>at</strong> an altern<strong>at</strong>ive assumption leads to the same results. Their assumptionis th<strong>at</strong> for every pair of emissions (i.e. for each value of A), the probability of acount with a polariser in place is less than or equal to the corresponding probabilitywith the polariser removed. The assumption of CH is stronger than th<strong>at</strong> of CHSHin so far as it is st<strong>at</strong>ed for each value of A, whereas CHSFI make an assertion only for


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1905the total sub-ensemble of photons which pass through the polarisers. On the otherh<strong>and</strong>, the assumption of CH is more general, in th<strong>at</strong> the processes ‘passage’ <strong>and</strong> ‘nonpassage’through a polariser (which are not observable, <strong>and</strong> which are inappropri<strong>at</strong>efor many possible theories) are not considered primitive. Furthermore, CH onlyassume an inequality, which is weaker than the equality of CHSH. Both assumptions,in our opinion, are physically plausible, but each gives a certain loophole to those whowish to defend local hidden-variables theories in spite of the <strong>experimental</strong> evidencewhich will be presented below.Let us discuss the consequences of the CH assumption. We denote by the symbol00 an appar<strong>at</strong>us configur<strong>at</strong>ion in which the analyser is absent. Let pl(A, 00) denotethe probability of a count from detector 1 when analyser 1 is absent <strong>and</strong> the st<strong>at</strong>e ofthe emission is A. A similar probability pz(A, 00) may be defined for appar<strong>at</strong>us 2.Thus, the assumption is th<strong>at</strong>:for every A, <strong>and</strong> for all values of a <strong>and</strong> b. Inequalities (5.1) <strong>and</strong> (3.17) <strong>and</strong> argumentssimilar to those which led from (3.16) to (3.19) yield immedi<strong>at</strong>ely the result:-p12(00, m)


1906 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonyin most cases monitored by an auxiliary appar<strong>at</strong>us, we can write the r<strong>at</strong>ios of probabilitiesas r<strong>at</strong>ios of count r<strong>at</strong>es:m(+>ip12(a t a) = R(+)/Rop12(a, @3)/p12(a, a)=R1/Ro (5*4)p12(a, b)/Pl2(@3, @3)=R2IRo.Inserting equ<strong>at</strong>ions (5.4) into inequality (5.3), we can write this form of <strong>Bell's</strong> inequalityin terms of coincidence r<strong>at</strong>es :-Ro


<strong>Bell's</strong> <strong>theorem</strong>: <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1907axis, lying in the xy plane <strong>and</strong> making an angle 0 with the f axis is:cos20 cos8 sin0 0Q( 8) = cos8 sin8 sin28I1(5 * 8)[o 0as one can check by noting th<strong>at</strong> the vector (F!), which represents linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ionin this direction, is an eigenvector of Q( 0) with eigenvalue 1. Similarly the vector(-;A:) , representing linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion perpendicular to this direction, is an eigen-vector of Q( 8) with eigenvalue 0, as is (i) which represents polaris<strong>at</strong>ion along thex axis (which of course is excluded by transversality). Consequently, the quantummechanicalprediction for this case is:[R(4)/Ro1Yo= W O I Q(a)@Q(b) IYO) = B(1 +cos 24) (5.9)where, as before, we have taken 4 = I a - b I. From this result we find th<strong>at</strong> the quantum-mechanicalpredictions[~(+>/RO- R(3n/8)/Ro1Yo = B d2 (5.10)viol<strong>at</strong>e inequality (5.5).5.2.2. Quantum-mechanical predictions for J= O+l -+0 cascade, ideal analysers, <strong>and</strong>Jinite solid-angle detectors. Consider a J = O-+J = 1 -+J = 0 <strong>at</strong>omic cascade in which noangular momentum is exchanged with the nucleus, <strong>and</strong> in which both transitions areelectric dipole. Since the <strong>at</strong>om is both initially <strong>and</strong> finally in st<strong>at</strong>es with zero totalangular momentum, <strong>and</strong> since there is a parity change in each transition, the emittedphoton pair has zero total angular momentum <strong>and</strong> even parity. We can thereforeexactly write the angular wavefunction of the photon pair as:1Y= - I: Y1,11(41) Y1,-11(42) - Yl,01(41) Y1,01(42) + ~1,--1~(~1)~1,1~(~2)] (5 * 11)d3where q1 <strong>and</strong> 42 are variable directions of propag<strong>at</strong>ion of the first <strong>and</strong> second photons,<strong>and</strong> where Yjml is the spherical vector function for total angular momentum j,magnetic quantum number m, <strong>and</strong> parity - 1 (see, for example, Akhiezer <strong>and</strong> Beretstetskii(1965) for not<strong>at</strong>ion). Now suppose th<strong>at</strong> the lenses which make the photonsimpinge normally upon the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers collect light in cones of half-angle 6,The wavefunction of a photon pair which emerges from the pair of lenses can berepresented as D([)Y, where D(6) is an oper<strong>at</strong>or which is exhibited in the appendix toShimony (1971). An argument is outlined in th<strong>at</strong> paper th<strong>at</strong> if 8 is infinitesimal, thenD(8)Y' is equal (except for normalis<strong>at</strong>ion) to the ideal two-photon polaris<strong>at</strong>ion vectorYo of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.7). This is a reasonable result, since there is no orbital angularmomentum if the two photons propag<strong>at</strong>e along a straight 1ine.Therefore the fact th<strong>at</strong>the photon pair has total angular momentum 0 implies th<strong>at</strong> it has zero spin angularmomentum, as in the st<strong>at</strong>e YO. Of course, a finite value of 6 is essential in an actualexperiment in order to obtain a non-vanishing count r<strong>at</strong>e. The quantum-mechanicalprediction for the coincidence r<strong>at</strong>es with the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>e D(f)Y is then:[R(4>PoIucpr = (W)Y I Q(a>osQ(b) I D(6)V = ;I + Pl(0 cos (24) (5 * 12)125


1908 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimmywhere F1([) is a monotonically decreasing function, has the value 1 for [=O, <strong>and</strong>diminishes to 0.9876 <strong>at</strong> [= 30". Equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.12) shows a somewh<strong>at</strong> weaker polaris<strong>at</strong>ioncorrel<strong>at</strong>ion than one finds in equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5,9), as a result of the admixture of orbitalangular momentum st<strong>at</strong>es when light is collected in a non-zero solid angle. However,the diminution of correl<strong>at</strong>ion is small, even for fairly large values of E, <strong>and</strong> it is evidentth<strong>at</strong> inequality (5.5) will be viol<strong>at</strong>ed by the probabilities of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.12), with[= 30".5.2.3. Quantum-mechanical correl<strong>at</strong>ion for J = O-t 1 -+O cascade in an actual experiment.In an actual experiment one does not have ideal linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers, <strong>and</strong>equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.12) must be corrected in order to take into account the inefficiency ofactual analysers. We let EM$ be the maximum transmittance of the jth analyser(j= 1,2) <strong>and</strong> emj be the minimum transmittance. (The former is 1 <strong>and</strong> the l<strong>at</strong>ter is 0for an ideal analyser, but values for the analysers will be given in the summaries belowof the experiments which have actually been performed.) Then equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.9) mustbe replaced by the following:(see Clauser et a1 1969, Horne 1970, Shimony 1971). Again, the quantum-mechanicalcounterpart of inequality (5.5) is viol<strong>at</strong>ed, if suitable values of the transmittances areused.5.2.4. Other cascades. If the photon pair is obtained from a J= l+J= 1+J= 0cascade with equal popul<strong>at</strong>ions in the initial Zeeman sublevels <strong>and</strong> no coherenceamong them (so th<strong>at</strong> the density m<strong>at</strong>rix of the initial level is Q I), but the preceding<strong>experimental</strong> arrangement is otherwise unchanged, then the quantum-mechanicalprediction for the probability of joint detection is the same as the right-h<strong>and</strong> side ofequ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.15), except th<strong>at</strong> F1([) is replaced by -F2([), where F2(0)= 1. The functionF2([) decreases monotonically more rapidly than F1([) (Clauser et a1 1969,Horne 1970, Holt 1973). A system<strong>at</strong>ic survey of other possible cascades has beenmade by Fry (1973).5.3. Description of experimentsSo far, there have been four experiments of the type just described. Three ofthese have agreed with the quantum-mechanical predictions, <strong>and</strong> one has agreed withthe predictions by local realistic theories via <strong>Bell's</strong> <strong>theorem</strong>.


<strong>Bell's</strong> <strong>theorem</strong>: <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 19095.3.1. Experiment by Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser (1972). Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser (1972, seealso Freedman 1972) observed the 5513 a <strong>and</strong> 4227 A pairs produced by the4p2 1So+4p4s 1P1+4sz IS0 cascade in calcium. Their arrangement is shown schem<strong>at</strong>icallyin figure 5. Calcium <strong>at</strong>oms in a beam from an oven were excited by resonanceabsorption to the 3d4p 1P1 level, from which a considerable fraction decayed to the4p2 WO st<strong>at</strong>e <strong>at</strong> the top of the cascade. No precaution was necessary for elimin<strong>at</strong>ingisotopes with non-zero nuclear spin, since 99.855% of n<strong>at</strong>urally occurring calcium haszero nuclear spin. Pile-of-pl<strong>at</strong>es polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers were used, with transmittances~~1=0.97 k 0.01, ~~1=0*038 & 0.004, €$=Om96 k 0.01, ~,2=0*037 f 0.004. Eachanalyser could be rot<strong>at</strong>ed by angular increments of n/8, <strong>and</strong> the pl<strong>at</strong>es could be foldedout of the optical p<strong>at</strong>h on hinged frames. The half-angle 6 subtended by the primarylenses was 30". Coincidence counting was done for 100 s periods; periods duringwhich all pl<strong>at</strong>es were removed altern<strong>at</strong>ed with periods during which all were inserted.In each run the r<strong>at</strong>ios R(n/S)/Ro <strong>and</strong> R(3n/8)/& were determined. Corrections weremade for accidental coincidences, but even without this correction, the results stillsignificantly viol<strong>at</strong>ed inequality (5.6). The average r<strong>at</strong>ios for roughly 200 h of runningtime are:[R(n/S)/Ro]expt= 0.400 & 0.007[R(3~/8)/Ro]expt= 0.100 f 0.003<strong>and</strong> therefore:[R(n/8)/Ro - R(3~/8)/Ro]expt= 0.300 f 0.008in clear disagreement with inequality (5.6). The quantum-mechanical predictionsare obtained from equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.15) (with allowances for uncertainties in the measurementof the transmittances <strong>and</strong> the subtended angle) :[R(n/8)/Ro-R(3n/8)/Ro]QM=(0'401 & 0*005)- (0.100 & 0*005)=0*301 f 0,007.The agreement between the <strong>experimental</strong> results with the quantum-mechanicalpredictions is excellent. Agreement is also found for other values of the angle $, aswell as for measurements made with only one or the other polariser removed.5.3.2. Experiment by Holt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin (1973). Holt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin (1973, see also Holt1973) observed 5676 A <strong>and</strong> 4047 A photon pairs produced by the 91P1-+73S1+63Pocascade in the zero nuclear-spin isotope 198Hg (see figure 6 for a partial level diagramof mercury). Atoms were excited to the glP1 level by a 100 eV electron beam. Thedensity m<strong>at</strong>rix of the glP1 level was found to be approxim<strong>at</strong>ely Q I by measurementsof the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion of the 5676 A photons, so th<strong>at</strong> equ<strong>at</strong>ion (5.15) with Fl(6) replacedby - F2(f) is used to calcul<strong>at</strong>e the quantum-mechanical predictions for the coincidencecounting r<strong>at</strong>es. Calcite prisms were employed as polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers, withmeasured transmittances :~~1=0*910 2 0.001 €M2=0*880 & 0.001< 10-4 10-4.The half-angle f was taken to be 13 O (F413") = 0.9509). The quantum-mechanicalprediction is :[R(3n/8)/RO- R(n/8)/Ro]QM=0*333 - 0*067= 0.266which only marginally exceeds the value & allowed by inequality (5.6). The <strong>experimental</strong>result in 154.5 h of coincidence counting, however, is:[R(3n/8)/Ro-R(.rr/8)/Ro],xpt=0.316 5 0.011 -0.099 & 0*009=0.216+ 0.013


1910J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimony3-xOILU Cw1;-8-6-L-2-5676 8A73 SI 5161 fi63 P2IpL358a 1017 fi2537 fiFigure 6.in good agreement with inequality (5.6) but in sharp disagreement with the quantummechanicalprediction. Since this result is very surprising, Holt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin tookgre<strong>at</strong> care to check possible sources of system<strong>at</strong>ic error: the contamin<strong>at</strong>ion of the sourceby isotopes with non-zero nuclear spin, perturb<strong>at</strong>ion by external magnetic or electricfields, coherent multiple sc<strong>at</strong>tering of the photons (radi<strong>at</strong>ion trapping), polaris<strong>at</strong>ionsensitivity of the photomultipliers, <strong>and</strong> spurious counts from residual radioactivity<strong>and</strong>/or cosmic rays, etc.One such system<strong>at</strong>ic error was found in the form of stresses in the walls of thePyrex bulb used to contain the electron gun <strong>and</strong> mercury vapour. Estim<strong>at</strong>es of theoptical activity of these walls were then made, <strong>and</strong> the results were corrected correspondingly.(The values presented above include this correction.) It is noteworthy,however, th<strong>at</strong> only the retard<strong>at</strong>ion sum for both windows was measured, for lightentering the cell from one side <strong>and</strong> exiting through the opposite side. On the otherh<strong>and</strong>, in the present experiment in which light exits from both windows, the relevantquantitj is the retard<strong>at</strong>ion difference.It is also noteworthy th<strong>at</strong> in the subsequent experiment by Clauser (95.3.3), acorrel<strong>at</strong>ion was first measured which agreed with the results of Ilolt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin.Stresses were then found in one lens which were due to an improper mounting.(These were too feeble to be detected by a simple visual check using crossed Polaroids.)The stresses were removed, the experiment was re-performed, <strong>and</strong> excellent agreementwith quantum mechanics was then obtained. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, IIolt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin didnot repe<strong>at</strong> their experiment when they discovered the stresses in their bulb.


<strong>Bell's</strong> <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 191 1A second criticism is th<strong>at</strong> Holt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin took the solid-angle limit to be th<strong>at</strong>imposed by a field stop placed outside the collim<strong>at</strong>ing lenses. It is possible th<strong>at</strong> lensaberr<strong>at</strong>ions may have allowed a larger solid angle than they recognised. A ray-tracingcalcul<strong>at</strong>ion was in fact performed to assure th<strong>at</strong> this was not the case. However, a solidstop ahead of the lens would have given one gre<strong>at</strong>er confidence th<strong>at</strong> this did not, infact, occur.5.3.3. Experiment by Clauser (1976). Clauser (1976) repe<strong>at</strong>ed the experiment of Holt<strong>and</strong> Pipkin, using the same cascade <strong>and</strong> same excit<strong>at</strong>ion mechanism, though with asource consisting mainly of the zero-spin isotope 202Hg. (The depolaris<strong>at</strong>ion effectdue to some residual non-zero nuclear spin isotopes was calcul<strong>at</strong>ed, using some resultsof Fry (1973)) Pile-of-pl<strong>at</strong>es polarisers were used with transmittances := 0.965 €ml= 0.011 = 0.972 = 0.008<strong>and</strong> the half-angle 6 taken to be 18.6". The quantum-mechanical prediction is:[R(3~/8)/Ro -R(T/8)/&]QM= 0.2841.The <strong>experimental</strong> result, from 412 h of integr<strong>at</strong>ion, is :[R(3~/8)/& - R(~/8)/Ro]expt = 0,2885 & 0.0093in excellent agreement with the quantum-mechanical prediction, but in sharp disagreementwith inequality (5.6).5.3.4. Experiment by Fry <strong>and</strong> Thompson (1976). Fry <strong>and</strong> Thompson (1976) observedthe 4358 A <strong>and</strong> 2537 A photon pairs emitted by the 73S1+63P1+61So cascade in thezero nuclear-spin isotope ZOOHg. Their experiment is shown schem<strong>at</strong>ically in figure 7.Figure 7. Schem<strong>at</strong>ic diagram of the <strong>experimental</strong> arrangement of Fry <strong>and</strong> Thompson.Polariser pl<strong>at</strong>e arrangement is also indic<strong>at</strong>ed. Actual polarisers have 14 pl<strong>at</strong>es.A, Hg oven; B, solenoid electron gun; C, RCA 8575; D, 4358 A filter; E, 5461 Alaser beam; F, Amperex 56 DUVP/03; G, 2537 A filter; H, focusing lens; I, pileof-pl<strong>at</strong>espolariser; J, laser beam trap; K, <strong>at</strong>omic beam defining slit; L, lightcollecting lens; M, crystal polariser; N, RCA 8850 (figure after Fry <strong>and</strong> Thompson).


1912 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyAn <strong>at</strong>omic beam consisting of n<strong>at</strong>ural mercury was used as a source of ground-st<strong>at</strong>e(61So) <strong>at</strong>oms. The excit<strong>at</strong>ion of these to the 73s1 level occurred in two steps <strong>at</strong>different loc<strong>at</strong>ions along the beam. First, the <strong>at</strong>oms were excited by electron bombardmentto the metastable 63P2 level. Downstream, where all rapidly decayingst<strong>at</strong>es had vanished, a single isotope was excited to the 73s1 level by resonant absorptionof 5461 A radi<strong>at</strong>ion from a narrow-b<strong>and</strong>width tunable dye laser. The techniqueprovided a high d<strong>at</strong>a accumul<strong>at</strong>ion r<strong>at</strong>e, since only the cascade of interest was excited.Photons were collected over a half-angle f of 19.9" .t 0.3", <strong>and</strong> pile-of-pl<strong>at</strong>es analyserswere used, with transmittances:EM'= 0.98 f 0.01 0.02 F 0.005 CM' = 0.97 i. 0.01 = 0.02 F 0.005.The density m<strong>at</strong>rix of the 73s1 level was ascertained by polaris<strong>at</strong>ion measurementsof the 4358 A photons; it was found to be diagonal even though the Zeeman sublevelswere not equally popul<strong>at</strong>ed. The quantum-mechanical prediction is :The <strong>experimental</strong> result is:[R(37/8)/Ro- R(7/8)/.??o]~M= 0.294 & 0.007.[R(37/8)/Ro - R(~/8)/Ro]expt= 0.296 5 0.014in excellent agreement with the quantum-mechanical prediction, but again in sharpdisagreement with inequality (5.5). Because of the high pumping r<strong>at</strong>e <strong>at</strong>tainable withthe dye laser, it was possible to g<strong>at</strong>her the d<strong>at</strong>a in a remarkably short period of 80 minwhich, of course, diminished the probability of errors due to vari<strong>at</strong>ions in the oper<strong>at</strong>ionof the appar<strong>at</strong>us, <strong>and</strong> facilit<strong>at</strong>ed checking for system<strong>at</strong>ic errors.5.4. Are the auxiliary assumptions for cascade-photon experiments necessary <strong>and</strong>reasonable?We have seen th<strong>at</strong> the d<strong>at</strong>a from the cascade-photon experiments are suficientto refute the whole family of local realistic theories, if either the CHSH or the CHauxiliary assumption is accepted. Both assumptions are very reasonable. Yet bothare conceivably false. One may ask the question: are the <strong>experimental</strong> d<strong>at</strong>a, by themselves,sufficient to refute the theories? Altern<strong>at</strong>ively, is <strong>at</strong> least some auxiliaryassumption necessary? The answer was given by CH, who contrived a local hiddenvariablesmodel, the predictions of which agree exactly with those of quantummechanics.One may then ask how reasonable are these assumptions. In particular do theydisagree with any known <strong>experimental</strong> d<strong>at</strong>a? A similar question may also be askedabout the counter-example. It seems highly artificial, but are any of its <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong><strong>experimental</strong>ly testable?5.4.1. Critique of the CH <strong>and</strong> CHSH assumptions. The CHSH assumption (45.1) is,given th<strong>at</strong> a pair of photons emerges from the polarisers, the probability of their jointdetection is independent of the polariser orient<strong>at</strong>ion a <strong>and</strong> b. It may appear th<strong>at</strong> theassumption can be established <strong>experimental</strong>ly by measuring detection r<strong>at</strong>es when acontrolled flux of photons of known polaris<strong>at</strong>ion impinges on each detector. From thest<strong>and</strong>point of local realistic theories, however, these measurements are irrelevant,since the distribution p when the fluxes are thus controlled is almost certain to bedifferent from th<strong>at</strong> governing the ensemble in the correl<strong>at</strong>ion experiments. We thus


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1913see no way of directly testing this assumption, <strong>and</strong> thus no experiments with which itdisagrees.It is noteworthy, however, th<strong>at</strong> there exists an important hidden-variables theorythesemiclassical radi<strong>at</strong>ion theory-which correctly predicts a large body of <strong>at</strong>omicphysics d<strong>at</strong>a, but which denies both the CHSH assumption as well as a presuppositionof it. The presupposition is th<strong>at</strong> one can speak unequivocally of a photon’s passageor non-passage through the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers. In the semiclassical radi<strong>at</strong>iontheory, however, a photon partially passes its respective polariser <strong>and</strong> departswith a reduced (classical) amplitude. Furthermore, this amplitude depends uponthe polariser’s orient<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> thereby determines the probability of the photon’ssubsequent detection (in viol<strong>at</strong>ion of the CHSH assumption th<strong>at</strong> all photons have thesame detection probability, independent of either polariser’s orient<strong>at</strong>ion). Nonetheless,the predictions for this theory are consistent with those by inequality (5.2), <strong>and</strong> thetheory is refuted by the cascade-photon experiments (Clauser 1972). Evidently analtern<strong>at</strong>ive assumption is possible which allows inequality (5.2) to constrain theoriesdenying this presupposition.Such an assumption was provided by CH. This assumption ($5.1) is th<strong>at</strong> for everypair of emissions, the probability of a count with the polariser in place is less than orequal to the corresponding probability with the polariser removed. This assumptionappears reasonable because the insertion of a polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analyser imposes an obstaclebetween the source of the emissions <strong>and</strong> the detector, <strong>and</strong> it is n<strong>at</strong>ural to believe th<strong>at</strong>an obstacle cannot increase the probability of detection. To be sure, we know ofsitu<strong>at</strong>ions in which the insertion of an additional optical element (apparently anobstacle) does increase the probability of detection, e.g. the insertion of a diagonallyoriented linear polariser between two crossed polarisers. However, the situ<strong>at</strong>ionappropri<strong>at</strong>e to the CH assumption is quite different from the one just mentioned,since no polarising elements follow the inserted polarisers. Moreover, if the thirdpolariser is a two-channel device, such as a Wollaston prism, the increased detectionr<strong>at</strong>e observed in one channel occurs <strong>at</strong> the expense of the detection r<strong>at</strong>e in the orthogonalchannel. The sum of the r<strong>at</strong>es from both channels actually decreases when thesecond polariser is inserted. Correspondingly, if the third polariser is replaced by apolaris<strong>at</strong>ion-insensitive detector, in a closer parallel to the situ<strong>at</strong>ion of the cascadephotonexperiments, then the detection r<strong>at</strong>e is always reduced when a polariser isinserted ahead of this detector.These consider<strong>at</strong>ions, unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely, are by no means sufficient to prove the CHassumption, since these observ<strong>at</strong>ions concern ensemble-average probabilities. TheCH assumption requires th<strong>at</strong> the probability be diminished upon the insertion of apolariserfor all A.5.4.2. The counter-example by Clauser <strong>and</strong> Home. Clauser <strong>and</strong> Horne (1974) produceda local hidden-variables model whose predictions agree exactly with those by quantummechanics. In their model the r<strong>at</strong>e <strong>at</strong> which photons jointly pass through the polaris<strong>at</strong>ionanalysers is in agreement with Bell’s inequalities, but the joint detection r<strong>at</strong>eagrees with the quantum-mechanical predictions. The model requires th<strong>at</strong> thedetected photon pairs be selected in a very special manner from among those whichpass through the analysers, <strong>and</strong> th<strong>at</strong> those which have not passed through a polariserhave a different detection probability from those which have. Although the selectionis done entirely locally, it does have the appearance of being highly artificial <strong>and</strong>,indeed, almost conspir<strong>at</strong>orial against the experimenter.


1914 J F Clausev <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyThe model applies only as long as the net detector efficiencies are smaller than acertain maximum value pax which depends on the analyser efficiencies E+ <strong>and</strong> E-:th<strong>at</strong> is (using the not<strong>at</strong>ion of $4) when:(5.16)With the conditions holding for the experiment by Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser, thesevalues are [vflexpt 0.004 <strong>and</strong> pmax E 0.4. This comparison can be improved somewh<strong>at</strong>by reference to some <strong>experimental</strong> results by Clauser?. Inequality (5.16) thenbecomes TexptGpWx. For the experiment by Freedman <strong>and</strong> Clauser the valuevexpt z 0.06 holds.Despite our caution concerning the CHSH <strong>and</strong> CH assumptions, we regard the<strong>experimental</strong> refut<strong>at</strong>ion which relies upon them to be compelling. It is striking th<strong>at</strong>only a highly artificial model has so far been found which is local <strong>and</strong> yet yieldsquantum-mechanical detection r<strong>at</strong>es in the cascade-photon experiments, <strong>and</strong> even thismodel can be excluded by r<strong>at</strong>her modest improvements in the appar<strong>at</strong>us. There isalso some hope for a <strong>theorem</strong> to the effect th<strong>at</strong> any model consistent with the <strong>experimental</strong>d<strong>at</strong>a will have anomalous fe<strong>at</strong>ures as does the CH model.6. Positronium annihil<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> proton-proton sc<strong>at</strong>tering experiments6.1. Historical backgroundTwo experiments testing predictions based on <strong>Bell's</strong> <strong>theorem</strong> have been performedusing the high-energy photons produced by positronium annihil<strong>at</strong>ion. The historicalbackground of these experiments is interesting. Wu <strong>and</strong> Shaknov (1950) determinedthe parity of the ground st<strong>at</strong>e of positronium by a method suggested by Wheeler th<strong>at</strong>consisted of measuring the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion correl<strong>at</strong>ion of y rays produced by positroniumannihil<strong>at</strong>ion. The photons Compton-sc<strong>at</strong>tered, <strong>and</strong> two-photon coincidences wereobserved as a function of azimuthal sc<strong>at</strong>tering angles, a <strong>and</strong> 6. Two rel<strong>at</strong>ive angles 0<strong>and</strong> ~ / were 2 employed. From the r<strong>at</strong>io of these two coincidence r<strong>at</strong>es they were ableto infer th<strong>at</strong> the parity of the ground st<strong>at</strong>e is neg<strong>at</strong>ive. Bohm <strong>and</strong> Aharonov (1957),with different motiv<strong>at</strong>ions, showed th<strong>at</strong> these d<strong>at</strong>a are explained by quantum mechanicsif the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>e of the photon pair is assumed to be:t Clauser (1974) noticed th<strong>at</strong> the parameters of existing <strong>experimental</strong> results were inappropri<strong>at</strong>eto determine whether or not transmission <strong>and</strong> reflection of a photon <strong>at</strong> a dielectric surface(similar to one of the surfaces in a pile-of-pl<strong>at</strong>es polariser) are, in fact, mutually exclusivepossibilities. He thus performed an experiment which confirmed th<strong>at</strong> they are. This behaviouris in marked contrast to th<strong>at</strong> of the semiclassical radi<strong>at</strong>ion theory, in which a photon is simultaneouslytransmitted <strong>and</strong> reflected by the surface. He also performed a vari<strong>at</strong>ion of thisexperiment (unpublished) in which the dielectric surface was replaced by a fine mesh mirror( M 50% transmission), <strong>and</strong> again photons were observed to be either transmitted or reflectedbut not both simultaneously. One can conclude from this result th<strong>at</strong>, <strong>at</strong> least for the purposesof local realistic theories, the simultaneous emission of a photon into any two different solidangleelements does not occur. Since the probabilities relevant to the CH counter-example areconditional upon the photons actually entering the collim<strong>at</strong>or, it follows th<strong>at</strong> the solid-angleparameter f can be dropped for the purposes of inequality (5.16).


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1915but are incomp<strong>at</strong>ible with the assumption th<strong>at</strong> the ensemble of photon pairs can bedescribed by a mixture of st<strong>at</strong>es, each of which is a product of two single-photonpolaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>es. They therefore concluded th<strong>at</strong> the d<strong>at</strong>a of Wu <strong>and</strong> Shaknovconfirm the existence of st<strong>at</strong>es of two-particle systems which are ‘non-separable’, eventhough the particles are sp<strong>at</strong>ially remote from each other (see appendix 1).Clauser et a1 (1969) investig<strong>at</strong>ed the possibility of using the arrangement of Wu<strong>and</strong> Shaknov, perhaps with some vari<strong>at</strong>ion, for the further purpose of checkingwhether the observed frequencies can viol<strong>at</strong>e Bell’s inequalities. It is, indeed, easyto show th<strong>at</strong> if efficient linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers existed for 0.5 MeV photons(with transmittances EM - Em gre<strong>at</strong>er than N 0.83), then the quantum-mechanicalvalues for the coincidence r<strong>at</strong>es, with the joint polaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>e given by equ<strong>at</strong>ion(6. l), can viol<strong>at</strong>e the inequalities (3.12) or (3.20). Unfortun<strong>at</strong>ely no such analysersexist, <strong>and</strong> Compton sc<strong>at</strong>tering does no more than give a sc<strong>at</strong>tering distribution,described by the Klein-Nishina formula, th<strong>at</strong> is dependent upon the direction oflinear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion. They concluded th<strong>at</strong> no variant of the Wu-Shaknov experimentcan provide a test of the predictions based on Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> (see Horne 1970).6.2. The experiment by Kasday, Ullman <strong>and</strong> WuIt was argued by Kasday et a1 (1970, 1975, hereafter referred to as KUW; seealso Kasday 1971) th<strong>at</strong> such photon pairs can be used to test the predictions based onBell’s <strong>theorem</strong> if one accepts two auxiliary assumptions: (i) in principle, ideal linearpolarisers can be constructed for high-energy photons; (ii) the results, which would beobtained in an experiment using ideal analysers, <strong>and</strong> those obtained in a Comptonsc<strong>at</strong>tering experiment, are correctly rel<strong>at</strong>ed by quantum theory.Their <strong>experimental</strong> arrangement (a variant of th<strong>at</strong> of Wu <strong>and</strong> Shaknov) is shownschem<strong>at</strong>ically in figure 8. Positrons were emitted by a 64Cu source, stopped <strong>and</strong>UD, IFigure 8.la Iih ISchem<strong>at</strong>ic diagram of the <strong>experimental</strong> arrangement of KUW. The lead collim<strong>at</strong>oris not shown. (a) Four-fold coincidence event; (b) (c), three-fold coincidenceevents; (d) detail of sc<strong>at</strong>terer. a, b are the azimuthal angles of the sc<strong>at</strong>tered photons.(1) Sc<strong>at</strong>tered y with energy E, absorbed by DI, (2) annihil<strong>at</strong>ion y, (3) positron source<strong>and</strong> absorber, (4) light pipe, (5) plastic sc<strong>at</strong>terer, (6) MgO-co<strong>at</strong>ed aluminium lightreflector (figure after Kasday et al).


1916 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonyannihil<strong>at</strong>ed in copper <strong>at</strong> the place labelled by 0. The annihil<strong>at</strong>ion y-rays were emittedin all directions; the vertical direction was selected by a lead collim<strong>at</strong>or. The sc<strong>at</strong>tererswere plastic scintill<strong>at</strong>ors. Lead slits selected a narrow range of acceptanceazimuthal angle about the angles a <strong>and</strong> b. The top slit-detector assembly was thenrot<strong>at</strong>ed to vary the rel<strong>at</strong>ive azimuthal angle. Accepted coincidence events had a fourfoldcoincidence among the two sc<strong>at</strong>terers <strong>and</strong> two detectors, as well as a sum-energyrequirement th<strong>at</strong> the total energy deposited in each sc<strong>at</strong>terer plus detector equals theannihil<strong>at</strong>ion energy. It is noteworthy th<strong>at</strong> this is the only experiment which employsthe arrangement of figure 1. (Here the ensemble consists of the pairs jointly sc<strong>at</strong>teredby the scintill<strong>at</strong>ors.)KUW applied assumptions (i) <strong>and</strong> (ii) as follows. Imagine two ideal linearpolaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers in the plane perpendicular to the direction of propag<strong>at</strong>ion of theselected annihil<strong>at</strong>ion photons (the vertical direction in figure S), which are respectivelyoriented in the directions a <strong>and</strong> b of the two slits. If the st<strong>at</strong>e h of the photon pair isgiven, a deterministic hidden-variables theory will determine whether each photonwill pass through its respective analyser. This is their use of assumption (i), If photon1 will pass its ideal analyser, then linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion in the a direction is assigned to it;<strong>and</strong> if photon 2 will correspondingly pass its analyser, then it is assigned linearpolaris<strong>at</strong>ion in the direction b. KUW then use assumption (ii) to assert th<strong>at</strong> the angularsc<strong>at</strong>tering distribution of each respective photon is given by the Klein-Nishinaformula (a distribution which is dependent upon the photon’s initial linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion).With the Klein-Nishina formula one can calcul<strong>at</strong>e the probability th<strong>at</strong> thesc<strong>at</strong>tered photons will enter the respective acceptance slits. Quantum mechanicsmakes a definite prediction for this joint probability. Deterministic local hiddenvariablestheories together with assumptions (i) <strong>and</strong> (ii) also imply an inequalitygoverning this probability which will disagree with the quantum-mechanical predictions.The <strong>experimental</strong> d<strong>at</strong>a of KUW are in good quantit<strong>at</strong>ive agreement with thequantum-mechanical predictions.This experiment is less decisive, in our opinion, as a refut<strong>at</strong>ion of the family of localrealistic theories than are the cascade-photon experiments discussed in $5, because itrelies upon assumptions which are considerably stronger than the assumption neededby the l<strong>at</strong>ter. If assumptions (i) <strong>and</strong> (ii) are not made, then a local hidden-variablesmodel can be constructed (Horne 1970, Bell 1971 (see Kasday 1971)) which yields thesame predictions for the experiment as those by quantum mechanics. This consider<strong>at</strong>ion,by itself, is not a fully sufficient reason to prefer the cascade-photonexperiments, since a local hidden-variables model, albeit a much more artificial one, alsoexists which yields quantum-mechanical predictions for those experiments (see $5.4).The rel<strong>at</strong>ive strengths of the supplementary assumptions provides a better reasonfor preference. There is one respect in which assumption (ii) of KUW is quiteunconvincing. The only definite polaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>es acknowledged by quantum theoryare the various modes of elliptic polaris<strong>at</strong>ion (circular <strong>and</strong> linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion beingspecial cases of these). Since quantum theory can be used to calcul<strong>at</strong>e the rel<strong>at</strong>ionshiprequired for assumption (ii) between ideal <strong>and</strong> Compton polarimeters only when thest<strong>at</strong>e of a photon is one recognised by quantum theory itself, this assumption presupposesth<strong>at</strong> photons which enter the Compton polarimeters are in a quantummechanicallydescribable st<strong>at</strong>e. Such a supposition is strongly in conflict with thepostul<strong>at</strong>es of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>. The st<strong>at</strong>e X presumably is not such a st<strong>at</strong>e, <strong>and</strong> moreoverthere is no prescription within quantum theory for calcul<strong>at</strong>ing the results of an experimentfor these more general st<strong>at</strong>es.


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1917In a general hidden-variables scheme, the st<strong>at</strong>e X of the photons clearly cannotbe represented as one of definite linear polaris<strong>at</strong>ion (the special case in which it canis the hypothesis studied by Furry). KUW’s decomposition of the st<strong>at</strong>e X of a photoninto linear <strong>and</strong>/or circular polaris<strong>at</strong>ion basis st<strong>at</strong>es is undoubtedly not possible ingeneral.Indeed, even in a quantum-mechanical tre<strong>at</strong>ment of the problem, the photons areacknowledged not to be in a st<strong>at</strong>e of definite polaris<strong>at</strong>ion. Quantum mechanically,neither photon’s polaris<strong>at</strong>ion is in a definite st<strong>at</strong>e, but each is in wh<strong>at</strong> is known as an‘improper mixture’ of such st<strong>at</strong>es (see d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (1976) for a discussion of impropermixtures). In quantum theory, the only correct procedure for h<strong>and</strong>ling such systemsis to perform calcul<strong>at</strong>ions for the composite two-photon st<strong>at</strong>e. Thus we see th<strong>at</strong> the‘marriage’ between quantum mechanics <strong>and</strong> a general local realistic theory required byassumption (ii) results in a f<strong>at</strong>ally incorrect h<strong>and</strong>ling of both theories.6.3. The experiments by Faraci et al, Wilson et a1 <strong>and</strong> Bruno et a1An experiment very similar to th<strong>at</strong> of KUW (but with 22Na as a source) wasperformed by Faraci et a1 (1974) with very different results. Their d<strong>at</strong>a disagreesharply with the quantum-mechanical predictions based upon the polaris<strong>at</strong>ion st<strong>at</strong>eof equ<strong>at</strong>ion (6.1)) <strong>and</strong> are <strong>at</strong> the extreme limit permitted by Bell’s inequalities(given the assumptions of KUW). Their d<strong>at</strong>a also showed a vari<strong>at</strong>ion in correl<strong>at</strong>ionstrength which depends upon the source-to-sc<strong>at</strong>terer distances. Since their paper isquite condensed, it is difficult to conjecture whether or not a system<strong>at</strong>ic error isresponsible for these results. KUW, however, present various criticisms of this workas well as a clarific<strong>at</strong>ion of various misinterpret<strong>at</strong>ions of their own work by theseauthors.Wilson et a1 (1976) repe<strong>at</strong>ed the experiment using 64Cu as a source. In contrastwith the results of Faraci et al, they found complete agreement with the quantummechanicalpredictions, <strong>and</strong> no significant vari<strong>at</strong>ion of the correl<strong>at</strong>ion strength whenthe sc<strong>at</strong>terer positions were changed.Bruno et a1 (1977) also repe<strong>at</strong>ed the experiment using 22Na as a source, but usedaltern<strong>at</strong>ively Cu <strong>and</strong> Plexiglass as the annihil<strong>at</strong>or. To discrimin<strong>at</strong>e against multiplesc<strong>at</strong>tering events they imposed a sum-energy restriction as did KUW <strong>and</strong> Wilson et a1(but not Faraci et al), <strong>and</strong> also varied the sc<strong>at</strong>terer sizes. Residual triplet-positroniumcontribution was ascertained by the use of the different annihil<strong>at</strong>or m<strong>at</strong>erials. Again,no viol<strong>at</strong>ion of the quantum-mechanical prediction was observed, for any of varioussource-sc<strong>at</strong>terer distances.6.4. Proton-proton sc<strong>at</strong>tering experiment by Lamehi-Rachti <strong>and</strong> Mitt@The only test of the predictions in Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> which has been performed sofar not using photons is th<strong>at</strong> of Lamehi-Rachti <strong>and</strong> Mittig (1976). They measured thespin correl<strong>at</strong>ions in proton pairs prepared by low-energy S-wave sc<strong>at</strong>tering. Thesc<strong>at</strong>tering geometry is shown in figure 9. Protons from the Saclay t<strong>and</strong>em acceler<strong>at</strong>orwere sc<strong>at</strong>tered by a target containing hydrogen. The incident <strong>and</strong> recoil protons eachentered analysers <strong>at</strong> 0lsb=45’ (OCm=9O0). The protons were sc<strong>at</strong>tered by a carbonfoil, <strong>and</strong> detected <strong>at</strong> positions labelled L1 or RI, <strong>and</strong> L2 or R2 in the figure. Coincidenceswere sought between detectors on opposite arms, as they varied the azimuthalangle of the detector pair of one arm.


1918 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyDetector RIFigure 9.Proton-proton sc<strong>at</strong>tering geometry for the experiment by Lamehi-RachtiMittig (after Lamehi-Rachti <strong>and</strong> Mittig 1976).<strong>and</strong>Auxiliary assumptions similar to those required for the positronium experimentsallow them to compare the d<strong>at</strong>a with the predictions for local realistic theories. Itshould be noted th<strong>at</strong> their geometry requires an additional assumption not necessaryfor the positronium experiments. Since the analysers are only sensitive to the transversecomponents of the spin, <strong>and</strong> since &, = 90°, the correl<strong>at</strong>ion is of the form :E(a, b) = C cos a cos b<strong>and</strong> cannot viol<strong>at</strong>e inequalities (3.12) or (3.19) no m<strong>at</strong>ter wh<strong>at</strong> value C< 1 has. Theythus assume th<strong>at</strong> the quantum-mechanically predicted rot<strong>at</strong>ional invariance of the§-wave sc<strong>at</strong>tering (supposing negligible triplet contribution) allows them to decomposethe correl<strong>at</strong>ion into a rot<strong>at</strong>ionally invariant part (singlet) <strong>and</strong> a non-rot<strong>at</strong>ionallyinvariant part (triplet). They then extrapol<strong>at</strong>e the results back to a form whichviol<strong>at</strong>es Bell’s inequalities, <strong>and</strong> rely upon other <strong>experimental</strong> evidence to set an upperlimit to the triplet sc<strong>at</strong>tering contribution. An arrangement in which one of theprotons is electrost<strong>at</strong>ically deflected through 90°, or magnetically precessed through90°, would have elimin<strong>at</strong>ed the need for this last assumption.They obtain good agreement with the quantum-mechanical predictions. If oneaccepts their assumptions, then Bell’s inequalities are viol<strong>at</strong>ed. However, even morereliance on quantum mechanics is needed than for the positronium experiments, <strong>and</strong>the criticisms of those experiments apply here more acutely.7. Evalu<strong>at</strong>ion of the <strong>experimental</strong> results <strong>and</strong> prospects for future experiments7.1. Two problemsThere are two very different problems involved in evalu<strong>at</strong>ing the experiments sofar performed for testing the predictions in Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>. The first is to determinethe significance of the anomalous results of Holt <strong>and</strong> Pipkin <strong>and</strong> Faraci et al. Thesecond is to determine wh<strong>at</strong> possibilities remain open if only the experiments which


1920 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonyassumptions are not required. It was shown in 54 th<strong>at</strong> the requirements for such ascheme are dem<strong>and</strong>ing. Experiments using photons for this purpose do not appear tobe feasible in the foreseeable future, since there seems to be no way of resolving thedilemma th<strong>at</strong> highly efficient polaris<strong>at</strong>ion analysers can be achieved only for lowenergyphotons, while highly efficient detectors can be made only for high-energyphotons. Furthermore, the two-body decay requirement is problem<strong>at</strong>ic with lowenergyphotons. Charged particles are evidently unusable, since an elegant argumentby Bohr (see Mott <strong>and</strong> Massey 1965) indic<strong>at</strong>es th<strong>at</strong> magnetic st<strong>at</strong>e selection of theirspin components viol<strong>at</strong>es the uncertainty principle. Hence, most schemes underconsider<strong>at</strong>ion involve using either neutral particles <strong>and</strong>/or discrete st<strong>at</strong>es other thanthose associ<strong>at</strong>ed with spin components. For example, Bell (1971) <strong>and</strong> Clauser et a1(see Fehrs 1973) were inspired by a paper of Inglis (1961) to consider the chargeconjug<strong>at</strong>ioncorrel<strong>at</strong>ions shown in the decay of neutral kaon pairs produced by protonantiprotonannihil<strong>at</strong>ion. It was concluded th<strong>at</strong> the exponentially decaying envelopeof the correl<strong>at</strong>ions precludes the observ<strong>at</strong>ion of a direct viol<strong>at</strong>ion of Bell’s inequalitiesin this system.There is hope th<strong>at</strong> the requirements for efficient analysis <strong>and</strong> detection can beachieved by observing the dissoci<strong>at</strong>ion fragments of a metastable molecule, with apair of Stern-Gerlach magnets as analysers. The l<strong>at</strong>ter have virtually lOOyo transmission,<strong>and</strong> proper design of the magnetic fields can minimise spurious spin-flips(Majorana transitions) during propag<strong>at</strong>ion of the decay fragments. Alkali metal <strong>and</strong>halogen <strong>at</strong>oms, if used as the decay fragments, can be detected individually byionis<strong>at</strong>ion or electron <strong>at</strong>tachment <strong>at</strong> a hot surface with nearly 1OOyo efficiency. Theparameters a <strong>and</strong> b can be taken to be the amplitudes of suitable resonant radiofrequencyfields, applied in such a way as to coherently rot<strong>at</strong>e the particle spins. Suchan experiment holds promise of testing local realistic theories without any auxiliaryassumptions, <strong>and</strong> with no loopholes other than the possibility of communic<strong>at</strong>ionbetween the analysers (see 57.3).7.3. Preventing communic<strong>at</strong>ion between the analysersBoth the special <strong>and</strong> general theories of rel<strong>at</strong>ivity preclude the existence of action<strong>at</strong>-a-distance.This fact is, of course, the primary motiv<strong>at</strong>ion for the various localitypostul<strong>at</strong>es considered above. However, in all of the experiments described so far,action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance in the rel<strong>at</strong>ivistic sense is not precluded, since the analysers arealways kept <strong>at</strong> fixed orient<strong>at</strong>ions for periods of several seconds. Thus, there is ampletime for inform<strong>at</strong>ion about the orient<strong>at</strong>ion of one analyser to be transmitted by someunknown mechanism (consistent with rel<strong>at</strong>ivity theory) to the other appar<strong>at</strong>us (<strong>and</strong>/orother particle) thereby influencing its results. It is thus conceivable th<strong>at</strong> such a mechanismis instrumental in producing quantum-mechanical coincidence counting r<strong>at</strong>esin the above experiments. To test this possibility requires an experiment in which theparameters a <strong>and</strong> b are adjusted with gre<strong>at</strong> rapidity while the correl<strong>at</strong>ed particles arein flight. If the event consisting of the adjustment of the parameter a of the firstanalyser is wholly space-like separ<strong>at</strong>ed from the detection event of particle 2, <strong>and</strong>similarly concerning adjustment of parameter b <strong>and</strong> the detection of particle 1, thenno signal with subluminal speed can convey inform<strong>at</strong>ion about the orient<strong>at</strong>ion of oneanalyser to the other appar<strong>at</strong>us in time to affect the probability of detecting therespective particles. In other words, if the parameters a <strong>and</strong> b are adjusted with sufficientrapidity, then the non-occurrence of action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance implies locality. For


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1921photons the required rapid adjustment of the analyser orient<strong>at</strong>ions can be accomplished,for example, by using modern electro-optical devices such as high-speed Pockell’scells. Aspect (1976) proposed the use of acousto-optical devices for basically thesame purpose.However, even with such devices it is impossible to block the loophole completely.Since the backward light cones of the detection <strong>and</strong> adjustment events overlap, it maybe claimed th<strong>at</strong> events in the overlap region are responsible for determining thechoices of the parameters a <strong>and</strong> b as well as the observed results. In this way thequantum-mechanical coincidence counting r<strong>at</strong>es can still be accounted for withoutany direct causal connection between opposite sides of the experiment, <strong>and</strong> hencewithout introducing action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance. Such an argument, however, seems unacceptableon methodological grounds, for it could be used to justify an ad hoc dismissalof any disagreeable d<strong>at</strong>a in almost any conceivable scientific experiment.7.4. ConclusionAlthough further <strong>experimental</strong> investig<strong>at</strong>ions of the family of theories governedby Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> are desirable, we are tent<strong>at</strong>ively convinced th<strong>at</strong> no theory of thiskind can correctly describe the physical world, Nonetheless, we find this conclusiondisturbing, since the philosophical point of view which most working scientists havefound n<strong>at</strong>ural, <strong>at</strong> least until quite recently, requires a local realistic theory. Becauseof the evidence in favour of quantum mechanics from the experiments based uponBell’s <strong>theorem</strong>, we are forced either to ab<strong>and</strong>on the strong version of EPR’s criterionof reality-which is tantamount to ab<strong>and</strong>oning a realistic view of the physical world(perhaps an unheard tree falling in the forest makes no sound after all)-or else toaccept some kind of action-<strong>at</strong>-a-distance. Either option is radical, <strong>and</strong> a comprehensivestudy of their philosophical consequences remains to be made.Appendix 1. Criticism of EPR argument by Bohr, Furry <strong>and</strong> SchrodingerThe argument of EPR is powerful, since their conclusion surely follows from theirplausible premises. Most of the community of physicists rejected EPR’s conclusion,however, because of a reply by Bohr (1935), which essentially consisted of a subtleanalysis of their premise (ii). His argument is th<strong>at</strong> when the phrase ‘without in anyway disturbing the system’ is properly understood it is incorrect to say th<strong>at</strong> system 2is not disturbed by the <strong>experimental</strong>ist’s option to measure a r<strong>at</strong>her than a’ on system 1.‘Of course there is, in a case like th<strong>at</strong> just considered, no question of a mechanicaldisturbance of the system under investig<strong>at</strong>ion during the last critical stage of themeasuring procedure. But even <strong>at</strong> this stage there is essentially the question of aninfluence on the very conditions which dejine the possible types of predictions regardingthe future behaviour of the system. Since these conditions constitute an inherentelement of the description of any phenomenon to which the term “physical reality’’can be properly <strong>at</strong>tached, we see th<strong>at</strong> the argument<strong>at</strong>ion of the mentioned authors doesnot justify their conclusion th<strong>at</strong> quantum-mechanical description is essentiallyincomplete.’It is beyond the scope of the present review to analyse Bohr’s claim th<strong>at</strong> the term‘reality’ can be used unambiguously in microphysics only when the <strong>experimental</strong>arrangement is specified. We are not convinced th<strong>at</strong> Bohr ever succeeded in giving a


1922 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonycoherent st<strong>at</strong>ement of his philosophical position (see, for example, Shimony 1971,Stein 1972, Hooker 1972). We must admit, however, in consider<strong>at</strong>ion of the <strong>experimental</strong>evidence presented in this review against EPR’s conclusion, th<strong>at</strong> Bohr’sposition remains as one of the few feasible options concerning the found<strong>at</strong>ions ofquantum mechanics.An early important reaction to the argument by EPR was to question premise (i),Furry (1936) <strong>and</strong> Schrodinger (1935) independently considered the possibility th<strong>at</strong>,after systems 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 become sp<strong>at</strong>ially separ<strong>at</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> cease effectively to interact, theirjoint wavefunction no longer has the form (2.1)’ but r<strong>at</strong>her becomes a mixture ofsimple product st<strong>at</strong>es, each having the form:Y8=Ufj*(l)@Usq2). (Al. 1)For each element of the mixture, both 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 are then in definite quantum st<strong>at</strong>es.This possibility is sometimes called ‘Furry’s hypothesis’, but th<strong>at</strong> nomencl<strong>at</strong>ure isinappropri<strong>at</strong>e. Wh<strong>at</strong> Furry did was to show th<strong>at</strong> for any choice of u;(l) <strong>and</strong> U,@),there exist in principle pairs of observables, M of 1 <strong>and</strong> S of 2, such th<strong>at</strong> the st<strong>at</strong>isticalpredictions for joint measurements of M <strong>and</strong> S based upon mixtures of the Yfi aredifferent from those based upon equ<strong>at</strong>ion (2.1). Since Furry believed quantummechanics to be correct, he concluded th<strong>at</strong> a st<strong>at</strong>e like th<strong>at</strong> of equ<strong>at</strong>ion (2.1) does notautom<strong>at</strong>ically evolve into a mixture of the Yfi when 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 separ<strong>at</strong>e from each other(see the conclusion of 54 of his paper). It is more appropri<strong>at</strong>e to call this scheme‘Schrodinger’s hypothesis’, since he explicitly st<strong>at</strong>ed th<strong>at</strong> it may be true. Strongevidence against this hypothesis was presented in 1957 by Bohm <strong>and</strong> Aharonov (see$6.1). More recent <strong>experimental</strong> evidence confirming their conclusions has beendiscussed by Kasday (1971) <strong>and</strong> Clauser (1972, 1977). It is noteworthy th<strong>at</strong> thishypothesis is such a n<strong>at</strong>ural one th<strong>at</strong> many physicists apparently believe it to be aresolution of the EPR ‘paradox’ without recognising the theoretical <strong>and</strong> <strong>experimental</strong>evidence against it.Appendix 2. Hidden-variables theoriesA theory which asserts th<strong>at</strong> the quantum-mechanical description of a physicalsystem is incomplete <strong>and</strong> requires supplement<strong>at</strong>ion in order to specify completely thest<strong>at</strong>e of the system is commonly called a hidden-variables theory?. Those propertiesof the system which are proposed as supplements to the quantum-mechanical descriptionare commonly called hidden variables or sometimes hidden parameters. Thehistory of hidden-variables theories is quite intric<strong>at</strong>e, because the various proponents<strong>and</strong> opponents have made different assumptions about the conditions of adequacywhich a hidden-variables theory should s<strong>at</strong>isfy. We shall review here only as much ofthis history as is needed to provide the background for Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>. Other reviewsof this subject (some including discussions of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong>) may be found in Bell(1966)’ Capasso et a1 (1970), Belinfante (1973), Jammer (1974) <strong>and</strong> d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (1976).In 1926-7 deBroglie wrote several papers proposing an interpret<strong>at</strong>ion of the wavefunctionvery different from th<strong>at</strong> of Bohr. He supposed th<strong>at</strong> the wavefunctionThe liter<strong>at</strong>ure is not always consistent on this point, <strong>and</strong> many authors have included ahypothesis of determinism in their definition of a hidden-variables theory. In this reviewhidden-variables theories for which determinism holds are referred to as deterministic hiddenvariablestheories.


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1923associ<strong>at</strong>ed with a particle is a physically real field propag<strong>at</strong>ing in physical space inaccordance with the Schrodinger equ<strong>at</strong>ion. He also supposed th<strong>at</strong> the particle alwayshas a definite position <strong>and</strong> a definite momentum. Thus his interpret<strong>at</strong>ion was actuallya hidden-variables theory. Finally, he assumed an intim<strong>at</strong>e coupling between theparticle <strong>and</strong> the field described by the function Y, so th<strong>at</strong> the l<strong>at</strong>ter can be considereda ‘guiding wave’ or ‘pilot wave’ for the particle. This coupling then accounts forinterference <strong>and</strong> diffraction phenomena. Several serious difficulties were found indeBroglie’s theory (see deBroglie 1960), especially concerning many-particle systems<strong>and</strong> the S-wave st<strong>at</strong>e of a particle. As a result, deBroglie set aside his investig<strong>at</strong>ionsof this kind until he was re-encouraged by the work of Bohm in 1952.We shall not discuss in detail the various other models considered so far (see, forexample, Madeliing 1926, deBroglie 1953, Bohm <strong>and</strong> Vigier 1954, Freistadt 1957,Andrade e Silva <strong>and</strong> Lochak 1969). Some of these models assume th<strong>at</strong> in addition tothe potential recognised in classical mechanics the particle is subject to a ‘quantumpotential’ hVR/2mR, where R is the amplitude of the wavefunction. Other modelsassume th<strong>at</strong> the wavefunction describes an averaged or smoothed st<strong>at</strong>e of a fluidmedium, subject to r<strong>and</strong>om fluctu<strong>at</strong>ions which are not taken into account by the wavefunction,but which are nevertheless important for underst<strong>and</strong>ing the st<strong>at</strong>isticalbehaviour of particles moving in the medium. For the most part, the advoc<strong>at</strong>es ofthese models do not claim th<strong>at</strong> they are anything but tent<strong>at</strong>ive descriptions of thesubquantum level of the physical world. Their significance lies in providing existenceproofs th<strong>at</strong> a theory can be deterministic in character, <strong>and</strong> nevertheless agree withmany of the st<strong>at</strong>istical predictions by quantum mechanics. We have found, in ourdiscussion of Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> in $3, th<strong>at</strong> a theory can achieve complete agreement withquantum mechanics only if it is non-local.Leaving aside the locality problem, we may ask how is it possible th<strong>at</strong> so manym<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ically consistent hidden-variables theories have been devised when various<strong>theorem</strong>s have claimed th<strong>at</strong> the structure of the class of quantum-mechanical observablesprecludes such theories? We now discuss two such <strong>theorem</strong>s.A2.1. Von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong>The most famous <strong>theorem</strong> of this type is due to von Neumann (1932). Let U bethe class of observables, <strong>and</strong> suppose th<strong>at</strong> every self-adjoint oper<strong>at</strong>or on a Hilbertspace 2 of dimension gre<strong>at</strong>er than 1 represents a member of U (but it is not excludedth<strong>at</strong> 0 has other members). A st<strong>at</strong>e is specified by defining an expect<strong>at</strong>ion valueExp(A) on every A E U, <strong>and</strong> it is assumed th<strong>at</strong> Exp s<strong>at</strong>isfies the following conditions.(i) Exp(l)= 1, where 1 is the observable which, by definition, always has the valueunity.(ii) For each A E 8 <strong>and</strong> each real number r, Exp(rA)=rExp(A).(iii) If A is non-neg<strong>at</strong>ive, then Exp(A) 2 0.(iv) If A, B, C, . . . , are arbitrary observables, then there is an observableA + B + C+ . . . (which does not depend upon the choice Exp) such th<strong>at</strong>:Exp(A+B+C+ . . .)=Exp(A)+Exp(B)+Exp(C)+. . . .The <strong>theorem</strong> asserts th<strong>at</strong> there exists a self-adjoint oper<strong>at</strong>or A on 2 such th<strong>at</strong>Exp(A2) #[Exp(A)]2, i.e. the st<strong>at</strong>e defined by Exp is not dispersion-free over thequantum-mechanical observables.The intuitive meaning of the conclusion of von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong> is th<strong>at</strong> no st<strong>at</strong>e126


1924 J- F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A Shimonyof the system-not even a st<strong>at</strong>e different from those recognised by quantum mechanics-can assign definite values simultaneously to all quantum-mechanical observables.Von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong> is m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ically correct, but its physical significance isdoubtful. The fact th<strong>at</strong> it was often cited over three decades as a proof for the completenessof quantum mechanics is a kind of historical aberr<strong>at</strong>ion, <strong>and</strong> has wroughtmuch confusion. Its crucial weakness is the supposition th<strong>at</strong> any possible st<strong>at</strong>e of thesystem must s<strong>at</strong>isfy condition (iv), even when A, B, C, . . . , are non-commutingoper<strong>at</strong>ors <strong>and</strong> therefore represent observables which, according to quantum mechanics,cannot be simultaneously measured. The actual procedure for measuring A + B,when A <strong>and</strong> B do not commute, is different from the procedures for measuring A <strong>and</strong>B separ<strong>at</strong>ely <strong>and</strong> does not presuppose any inform<strong>at</strong>ion about the value of either A or B.Consequently, the fact th<strong>at</strong> the additivity of condition (iv) is s<strong>at</strong>isfied by quantummechanicalst<strong>at</strong>es is a peculiarity of quantum mechanics, <strong>and</strong> there is no reason tosuppose th<strong>at</strong> it is s<strong>at</strong>isfied by non-quantum-mechanical st<strong>at</strong>es. This criticism of thephysical significance of von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong> was made by Siege1 (1966) <strong>and</strong> Bell(1966). (In the two-dimensional Hilbert space of a spin-6 particle, Bell also constructeda family of dispersion-free st<strong>at</strong>es which are physically reasonable, even though theyviol<strong>at</strong>e condition (iv). Pearle (1965) <strong>and</strong> Kochen <strong>and</strong> Specker (1967) independentlyconstructed similar models.) There is evidence+ th<strong>at</strong> Einstein was critical of condition(iv) as early as 1938 <strong>and</strong> therefore did not consider von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong> to be anobstacle to the ‘completion’ of quantum mechanics as dem<strong>and</strong>ed by the argumentof EPR. An interesting survey by Jammer (1974, pp272-7) shows th<strong>at</strong> others werecritical of condition (iv), but not with complete clarity.A2.2. Gleason’s <strong>theorem</strong>In 1957 Gleason proved a <strong>theorem</strong> which is free from the unphysical condition (iv)of von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong>, <strong>and</strong> which has frequently been considered to be a decisiveproof of the impossibility of any consistent hidden-variables theory. We shall notst<strong>at</strong>e the <strong>theorem</strong> itself but r<strong>at</strong>her shall st<strong>at</strong>e a corollaryf which can be compareddirectly with von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong>.Let 0 be a class of observables containing all those represented by the self-adjointoper<strong>at</strong>ors on a Hilbert space of dimension gre<strong>at</strong>er than 2, <strong>and</strong> let Exp be a real-valuedfunction over U, which s<strong>at</strong>isfies the following conditions :1, 2, 3, as in von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong>.4’. If A, B, C, , . , , are commuting self-adjoint oper<strong>at</strong>ors on S, thenExp(A+B+C+. . .)=Exp(A)+Exp(B)+Exp(C)+. . . ,Then Exp is not dispersion-free.This corollary is weaker than von Neumann’s <strong>theorem</strong> in one respect: it does notapply to a Hilbert space of dimension 2, <strong>and</strong> therefore it permits the models of Bell,Kochen <strong>and</strong> Specker, <strong>and</strong> Pearle. But it is much stronger in one crucial respect: itrequires additivity only over commuting oper<strong>at</strong>ors, for which the values of A + B + C+.I. Professor P G Bergmann was an assistant to Einstein <strong>at</strong> th<strong>at</strong> time, <strong>and</strong> he reportedEinstein’s criticism to one of us. We regret th<strong>at</strong> we have no evidence concerning Einstein’sopinion of von Neumann’s argument in 1935, when the paper of EPR was written.1 There are several direct proofs of essentially this corollary which do not rely upon themain <strong>theorem</strong> of Gleason: Bell (1966), Kochen <strong>and</strong> Specker (1967) <strong>and</strong> Belinfante (1973).The proof given by Jammer (1974, pp298-9) is the same as th<strong>at</strong> of Bell, who is not credited.


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1925, . . can in principle be determined by summing the results of simultaneous measurementsof A, B, C, . . . ,.The conditions for this corollary are physically plausible, <strong>and</strong> its conclusion seemsto be strong enough to preclude all non-trivial hidden-variables theories (i.e. all whichapply to a system which is quantum-mechanically represented by a Hilbert space ofdimension gre<strong>at</strong>er than 2). However, Bell (1966) pointed out the possibility of afamily of non-trivial hidden-variables theories which do not s<strong>at</strong>isfy all the conditionsof the corollary <strong>and</strong> therefore are not bound by its conclusion. Suppose A, B <strong>and</strong> Care self-adjoint oper<strong>at</strong>ors such th<strong>at</strong> A commutes with both B <strong>and</strong> C, but B <strong>and</strong> Cdo not commute with each other. Therefore A can in principle be measured simultaneouslywith B, or it can be measured simultaneously with C, <strong>and</strong> different <strong>experimental</strong>arrangements are required for the two measurements. In the corollary it wasassumed th<strong>at</strong> when the st<strong>at</strong>e of the system is fully specified, the function Exp(X) hasa definite value for each observable X, however Xis measured. ‘It was tacitly assumedth<strong>at</strong> measurement of an observable must yield the same value independently of wh<strong>at</strong>other measurements may be made simultaneously’ (Bell 1966, p451). But there is noa priori reason th<strong>at</strong> this assumption should be true. ‘The result of an observ<strong>at</strong>ionmay reasonably depend not only on the st<strong>at</strong>e of the system (including hidden variables)but also on the complete description of the appar<strong>at</strong>us’ (Bell 1966, p451). It is physicallyreasonable, therefore, to consider hidden-variables theories in which the expect<strong>at</strong>ionvalues have the form Exp(X; V), where Q indic<strong>at</strong>es the ‘context’ of the measurementof X, i.e. all the quantities measured simultaneously with X. Gleason’s <strong>theorem</strong><strong>and</strong> its corollary do not preclude the possibility th<strong>at</strong> such a ‘contextual’ hiddenvariablestheory can be dispersion-free, so th<strong>at</strong> the result of measuring any observableis precisely determined by the st<strong>at</strong>e of the system (including hidden variables) togetherwith the ‘context’ of the measurement.Bell’s proposal of a new family of hidden-variables theories sheds light on modelslike the one given by Bohm in 1952. This model anted<strong>at</strong>ed Gleason’s work, butBohm (1952, p187) defended it against von Neumann’s impossibility <strong>theorem</strong> in thefollowing way :‘the so-called “observables” are . . , not properties belonging to the observed systemalone, but instead potentialities whose precise development depends just as much onthe observing appar<strong>at</strong>us as on the observed system. In fact, when we measure themomentum “observable”, the final result is determined by hidden parameters in themomentum-measuring device as well as by hidden parameters in the observedelectron.’This passage does not propose the consider<strong>at</strong>ion of contextual hidden-variablestheories as explicitly as Bell does, but it can be construed retrospectively as implicitlyagreeing with Bell.The next step in the history of hidden-variables theories was taken by Bell, oncehe was convinced th<strong>at</strong> impossibility <strong>theorem</strong>s like th<strong>at</strong> of Gleason do not establisha priori the inconsistency of hidden-variables models. By taking these modelsseriously, he was free to examine whether they shared any physically unreasonableproperties in spite of their m<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical consistency, <strong>and</strong> to inquire whether suchproperties are inevitable in any hidden-variables theory which agrees with the predictionsby quantum mechanics. In this way he was heuristically led to the study oflocality.


~ 19741926 J F Clauser <strong>and</strong> A ShimonyAcknowledgmentsWe wish to thank Professor Michael A Horne for many valuable suggestions forthis review. One of us (AS) wishes to thank the Department of Theoretical <strong>Physics</strong>of the University of Geneva for its hospitality.ReferencesAkhiezer A I <strong>and</strong> Berestetskii V B 1965 Quantum Electrodynamics (New York: Interscience)Andrade e Silva J L <strong>and</strong> Lochak G 1969 Quanta (New York: McGraw-Hill)Aspect A 1976 Phys. Rev. D I4 1944-51Belinfante F J 1973 A Survey of Hidden-Variables Theories (Oxford: Pergamon)Bell J S 1965 <strong>Physics</strong> 1 195-2001966 Rev. Mod. Phys. 38 447-52- 1971 Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics ed B d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (New York: Academic)pp171-811972 Science 177 880-11976 Communic<strong>at</strong>ion <strong>at</strong> the 6th Gift Conf,, Jaca, June 1975 Res. Th 2053-CERN- 1977 Epistemological Lett. 15 79-84Bohm D 1951 Quantum Theory (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall) pp614-22- 1952 Phys. Rev. 85 169-93Bohm D <strong>and</strong> Aharonov Y 1957 Phys. Rev. 188 1070-6Bohm D <strong>and</strong> Vigier JP 1954 Phys. Rev. 96 208-16Bohr N 1935 Phys. Rev. 48 696-702de Broglie L 1926 C. R. Acad. Sci., Paris 183 447-81927 C. R. Acad. Sci., Paris 184 273- 1928 J. Phys. Radium 8 225-411953 La Physique Quantique: Restera-t-elle Indeterministe? (Paris : Gauthier Villars)- 1960 Non-Linear Waue Mechanics (Amsterdam : Elsevier)Bruno M, d‘Agostino M <strong>and</strong> Maroni C 1977 Nuobo Cim. 40 B142-52Capasso V, Fortun<strong>at</strong>o D <strong>and</strong> Selleri F 1970 Riv. Nuovo Cim. 2 149-99Clauser J F 1972 Phys. Rev. A 6 49-54Phys. Rev. D 9 853-60- 1976 Phys. Rev. Lett. 36 1223-6- 1977 Nuovo Cim. 33 740-6Clauser J F <strong>and</strong> Horne MA 1974 Phys. Rev. D 10 526-35Clauser J F, Horne MA, Shimony A <strong>and</strong> Holt RA 1969 Phys. Rev. Lett. 23 880-4Colodny R G (ed) 1972 Paradigms <strong>and</strong> Paradoxes (Pittsburgh, Pa. : University of PittsburghPress)Eberhard P 1977 Nuovo Cim. 38 B75Einstein A, Podolsky B <strong>and</strong> Rosen N 1935 Phys. Rev. 47 777-80d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> B (ed) 1971 Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics. Proceedings of the Intern<strong>at</strong>ionalSchool of <strong>Physics</strong> ‘Enrico Fermi’ Course XLIX (New York: Academic)- 1975 Phys. Rev. D 11 1424-35- 1976 Conceptual Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics (Reading, Mass. : Benjamin) 2nd ednFaraci G, Gutkowski S, Notarrigo S <strong>and</strong> Pennisi AR 1974 Lett. Nuovo Cim. 9 607-11Fehrs M H 1973 PhD Thesis Boston UniversityFreedman S J 1972 Lawrence Berkeley Lab. Rep. No LBL 391Freedman S J <strong>and</strong> Clauser J F 1972 Phys. Rev. Lett. 28 938-41Freistadt H 1957 Nuovo Cim. Suppl. 5 1-70Fry ES 1973 Phys. Rev. A 8 1219-32Fry E S <strong>and</strong> Thompson R C 1976 Phys. Rev. Lett. 37 465-8Furry W H 1936 Phys. Rev. 49 393-9Gleason AM 1957J. M<strong>at</strong>h. Mech. 6 885-93Gutkowski D <strong>and</strong> Masotto G 1974 Nuovo Cim. 22 B121-9Holt RA 1973 PhD Thesis Harvard University


Bell’s <strong>theorem</strong> : <strong>experimental</strong> <strong>tests</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>implic<strong>at</strong>ions</strong> 1927Holt RA <strong>and</strong> Pipkin FM 1973 Preprint Harvard UniversityHooker CA 1972 Paradigms <strong>and</strong> Paradoxes ed RG Colodny (Pittsburgh, Pa.: University ofPittsburgh Press) pp67-302Horne MA 1970 PhD Thesis Boston UniversityInglis DR 1961 Rev. Mod. Phys. 33 1-7Jammer M 1974 The PhiZosophy of Quantum Mechanics (New York: Wiley)Kasday LR 1971 Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics ed B d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (New York: Academic)ppl95-210Kasday LR, Ullman JD <strong>and</strong> Wu CS 1970 Bull. Am. Phys. Soc. 15 586- 1975 Nuovo Cim. 25 B633-61Kochen S ‘<strong>and</strong> Specker E 1967 J. M<strong>at</strong>h. Mech. 17 59-87Lamehi-Rachti M <strong>and</strong> Mittig W 1976 Phys. Rev. 14 2543-55Madelung E 1926 Z. Phys. 40 322-6Mott N F <strong>and</strong> Massey H S W 1965 The Theory of Atomic Collisions (Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress) pp214-9von Neumann J 1932 M<strong>at</strong>hemtische Grundlagen der Quantenmechnnik (Berlin: Springer-Verlag) (Engl. trans. 1955 M<strong>at</strong>hem<strong>at</strong>ical Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics (Princeton,NJ : Princeton University Press) pp307-25)Pearle P 1965 Preprint Harvard University- 1970 Phys. Rev. D 2 1418-25Schiavulli L 1977 Preprint UniversitA di BariSchrodinger E 1935 Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc. 31 555-63Selleri F 1978 Found<strong>at</strong>ions of <strong>Physics</strong> 8 103-16Shimony A 1971 Found<strong>at</strong>ions of Quantum Mechanics ed B d’Espagn<strong>at</strong> (New York: Academic)pp182-94,470-80- 1978 Epistemological Lett. 18 1-3Shimony A, Horne MA <strong>and</strong> Clauser J F 1976 Epistemological Lett. 13 1-8Siegel A 1966 Differential Space, Quantum Systems, <strong>and</strong> Prediction ed N Wiener, A Siegel,B Rankin <strong>and</strong> W T Martin (Cambridge, Mass. : MIT Press)Stapp HP 1971 Phys. Rev. D 3 1303-20- 1978 Whiteheadian Approach to Quantum Theory <strong>and</strong> the Generalised Bell’s TheoremFound<strong>at</strong>ions of <strong>Physics</strong> to be publishedStein H 1972 Paradigms <strong>and</strong> Paradoxes ed R G Colodny (Pittsburgh, Pa.: University of PittsburghPress) pp367-438Wigner EP 1970 Am. J. Phys. 38 1005-9Wilson AR, Lowe J <strong>and</strong> Butt D K 1976 J. Phys. G: Nucl. Phys. 2 613-24Wu CS <strong>and</strong> Shaknov I 1950 Phys. Rev. 77 136

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!