11.07.2015 Views

Bodily mimesis as “the missing link” in human cognitive ... - CiteSeerX

Bodily mimesis as “the missing link” in human cognitive ... - CiteSeerX

Bodily mimesis as “the missing link” in human cognitive ... - CiteSeerX

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong><strong>as</strong><strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong><strong>in</strong><strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionJordan Zlatev, Tom<strong>as</strong> Persson and Peter GärdenforsLund University Cognitive Studies 121,2005


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 3F<strong>in</strong>ally, the units of language stand <strong>in</strong> complex<strong>in</strong>ternal semantic relations <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g e.g.complementarity (Deacon 1997) and grammaticalrelations <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g hierarchical structure andrecursivity (Hauser, Chomsky and Fitch 2002;Givón 2002). Noth<strong>in</strong>g of the k<strong>in</strong>d h<strong>as</strong> beenshown to exist <strong>in</strong> natural animal communication,though <strong>as</strong>pects of both semantic relations andgrammatical patterns are not beyond the gr<strong>as</strong>pof language-taught apes (Savage-Rumbaugh andLew<strong>in</strong> 1994).We may conclude that the six general differencesbetween language and animal communicationdiscussed <strong>in</strong> this section and summarized <strong>in</strong>Table 1 def<strong>in</strong>e two very different types of semioticsystems. Even though one may argue thatfor each of the <strong>in</strong>dividual features there may besome forms of animal communication thatwould appear to be “<strong>in</strong>termediary”, e.g. theflexible <strong>in</strong>terpretations of chimpanzee alarm callsby Diana monkeys (Zuberbühler 2000), no animal<strong>in</strong> the wild h<strong>as</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g approach<strong>in</strong>g the socially transmitted,voluntarily controlled, contextually flexible, triadicsemiotic system that is language.As po<strong>in</strong>ted out <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>troduction, the difficultquestion is to account why and how such adist<strong>in</strong>ctively “odd” (from a biological perspective)communication system emerged <strong>in</strong> the firstplace. Proposals <strong>in</strong> the currently explod<strong>in</strong>g literatureon language orig<strong>in</strong>s vary widely on whatthey f<strong>in</strong>d to be the crucial feature of <strong>human</strong>cognition that could “bridge the gap” to language:process<strong>in</strong>g of recursivity (Hauser, Chomskyand Fitch 2002; Bickerton 2003), enhancements<strong>in</strong> social cognition (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1999;Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. <strong>in</strong> press), mechanisms support<strong>in</strong>gthe learn<strong>in</strong>g and use of symbolic relations(Deacon 1997, 2003). In the present quest forthe Holy Grail of expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>human</strong> uniquenessthat tends to focus on the orig<strong>in</strong> of languagedifferent researchers tend to offer their favoritecandidate for <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> and do theirbest to support their hypothesis, often at theprice of disregard<strong>in</strong>g a good deal of evidence(see Johansson 2005). Our overall project similarlyaims to resolve the puzzle of what makes<strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>cognitive</strong>ly and communicativelyspecial, but differs from the majority <strong>in</strong> (a) notfocus<strong>in</strong>g on language but on a skill that we argueis a prerequisite for language and (b) draw<strong>in</strong>g<strong>cognitive</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations and toward more low-levelmechanisms l<strong>in</strong>ked to the particular stimulus featuresof the environment.” (Hauser 1996: 59)from a large number of empirical and theoreticalstudies.Table 1. Six characteristics of animal communicationand <strong>human</strong> language1. Degree oflearn<strong>in</strong>g2. Consciouscontrol3. Contextuality4. Interpretation5. Communicativerelations6. Systematicity(<strong>in</strong>ternal relationsandcomb<strong>in</strong>atorics)Animal communication(<strong>in</strong>the wild)None (“<strong>in</strong>nate”)orhighly limitedNone orhighly limitedTied to aparticularcontext(stimulussett<strong>in</strong>g)(Relatively)fixed responseDyadic:- Cue (environment,subject)- Signal (subject,recipient)None, orvery limitedHuman languageExtensiveHighFlexible, relatively<strong>in</strong>dependent fromspecific contextFlexible, “negotiable”Triadic:Speaker-addresseereferentHighAnimals and <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs differ not only <strong>in</strong>their means of communication, but <strong>in</strong> (apparently)non-communicative <strong>as</strong>pects of cognitionsuch <strong>as</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g, symbolic thought, <strong>“the</strong>ory ofm<strong>in</strong>d”, etc. In other words, there is a parallelbetween the “communicative gap” and the“<strong>cognitive</strong> gap”. What is the source of this parallelism?When it comes to ontogeny, a possibleexplanation for the source of the “higher functions”of <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs is the cl<strong>as</strong>sical proposallaid out by Vygotsky (1978) that the latter can beseen <strong>as</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g from the <strong>in</strong>ternalization of <strong>in</strong>terpersonalrelations and representations, or <strong>as</strong> expressed byVygotsky <strong>in</strong> an often quoted p<strong>as</strong>sage:Every function <strong>in</strong> the child’s cultural developmentappears twice: first, on the sociallevel, and later, on the <strong>in</strong>dividual level; firstbetween people (<strong>in</strong>terpsychological), and then<strong>in</strong>side the child (<strong>in</strong>trapsychological). This appliesequally to voluntary attention, to logicalmemory, and to the formation of concepts.


4<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionAll the higher functions orig<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>as</strong> actual relationsbetween <strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals. (Vygotsky1978: 57)We wish to suggest that an evolutionary analogto this process, i.e. a process of hom<strong>in</strong>id selfenculturation<strong>in</strong> which more complex forms ofcommunication created selection pressures formore complex forms of cognition, can help usunderstand the close connections between thetwo “gaps”. Such a socio-cultural perspective on<strong>human</strong> cognition and its evolutionary orig<strong>in</strong>sdoes not conflict with, but rather presupposesthe crucial underly<strong>in</strong>g role of our general primatecognition (Donald 1991; Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1999; Zlatev2003). In this article we will adopt such a bioculturalperspective <strong>as</strong> a general “work<strong>in</strong>g hypothesis”,without thereby argu<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st more<strong>in</strong>dividual-b<strong>as</strong>ed alternatives (e.g. Gärdenfors2003). Ultimately, we will need a synthesis of thesocial and the <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>as</strong>pects of <strong>human</strong> cognition<strong>in</strong> order to make sense of the nature ofour major theoretical concept that is both <strong>in</strong>terand<strong>in</strong>tra-personal, <strong>as</strong> we show below.3. <strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong>The concept of <strong>mimesis</strong> goes back at le<strong>as</strong>t to Aristoteles,but <strong>as</strong> far <strong>as</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionis concerned, we take our departure from the<strong>mimesis</strong> hypothesis of <strong>human</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>s presented byDonald (1991, 1998, 2001). This hypothesisstates that a specific form of communication andcognition (and correspond<strong>in</strong>g culture) mediatedbetween those of the common ape-ancestor andmodern <strong>human</strong>s b<strong>as</strong>ed on <strong>“the</strong> ability to produceconscious, self-<strong>in</strong>itiated, representationalacts that are <strong>in</strong>tentional but not l<strong>in</strong>guistic.”(Donald 1991: 168) In brief, Donald proposesthat while ape culture is b<strong>as</strong>ed on “episodic cognition”and <strong>as</strong>sociational learn<strong>in</strong>g, early Homo –most likely Homo erectus/erg<strong>as</strong>ter consider<strong>in</strong>g therelative jump <strong>in</strong> bra<strong>in</strong> size and material culturewitnessed at this stage of hom<strong>in</strong>id evolution –evolved a new form of cognition. What supportedthis w<strong>as</strong> the fact that the body could beused volitionally to do what somebody else isdo<strong>in</strong>g (imitation), to represent external eventsfor the purpose of communication or thought(mime, gesture) and to rehearse a given skill bymatch<strong>in</strong>g performance to a goal.The most important features that Donald attributesto <strong>mimesis</strong> are: (a) reference: mimetic representationsstand for someth<strong>in</strong>g (for someone);(b) <strong>in</strong>tentionality: this referential relationship isgr<strong>as</strong>ped both by the “mimer” and the <strong>in</strong>terpreter;(c) communicativity: the relationship <strong>in</strong> (b)can be used for the purpose of convey<strong>in</strong>gthoughts; (d) autocu<strong>in</strong>g: production is voluntary <strong>as</strong>opposed to <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctive; and (e) generativity: the“ability to “parse” one’s own motor actions <strong>in</strong>tocomponents and then recomb<strong>in</strong>e these components<strong>in</strong> various ways” (Donald 1991: 171).It can be observed that features (a)-(e) def<strong>in</strong>ea system of communication that is <strong>in</strong>termediatebetween animal communication and language, <strong>as</strong>characterized <strong>in</strong> Section 2 and Table 1. Like thelatter it is learned, flexible and possibly triadic.At the same time, it lacks the follow<strong>in</strong>g criticalfeatures of <strong>human</strong> language:• Conventionality: not just shared, but knownto be shared and thus a part of mutualknowledge (Itkonen 1978; Clark 1996); Notthat this is not the same <strong>as</strong> arbitrar<strong>in</strong>ess (seebelow), even though to notions are oftenmistakenly conflated. 2• Arbitrar<strong>in</strong>ess: the semiotic ground for theexpression-content relation requires neithersimilarity, nor contiguity (Peirce 1931-1935;Sonesson <strong>in</strong> press)• Extensive systematicity of the <strong>in</strong>ternal relationsamong signs (Deacon 1997; Zlatev2003).Thus the hypothesis that <strong>mimesis</strong> plays the roleof a “<strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> (<strong>in</strong> the words of Donaldhimself) <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolution is a prioriattractive. Furthermore, it h<strong>as</strong> been backed upby evidence from archeology, neurobiology,<strong>cognitive</strong> psychology and developmental psychology,such <strong>as</strong> the presence of a “mimeticstage” <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> ontogeny and the presence ofmimetic thought <strong>in</strong> patients with total aph<strong>as</strong>ia,the homology between “mirror neuron” systems<strong>in</strong> monkeys used for action recognition, andstructures for the control of imitation, mentaliz<strong>in</strong>gand language <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs (e.g. Donald1991, 2001; Nelson 1996; Zlatev 2002, 2005;Corballis 2002).2 It is also completely dist<strong>in</strong>ct from the so-calledconventionalization of behaviors discussed <strong>in</strong> theethological literature, for which we reserve the termritualization (see Section 6).


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 5Nevertheless, the <strong>mimesis</strong> hypothesis h<strong>as</strong>been met with much resistance and criticism(Mitchell and Miles 1993; Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1993; etc)that can be summarized <strong>as</strong> follows: On the onehand, Donald’s theory underestimates the cognitionof non-<strong>human</strong> primates with respect totool-mak<strong>in</strong>g and cultural traditions (Boesch2003) and their ability to understand others’<strong>in</strong>tentions (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, Call and Hare 2003). Onthe other hand, features (a)-(e) attribute so muchrepresentational complexity to <strong>mimesis</strong>, that thisobviates the need for a second <strong>cognitive</strong> transitionto language (Laakso 1993). If this criticismis correct, then <strong>mimesis</strong> can hardly “bridge thegap” <strong>as</strong> required, s<strong>in</strong>ce it, so to speak, both givestoo little to the apes and too much to Homo erectus,thus effectively creat<strong>in</strong>g a second gap: betweenapes and Homo erectus, without any <strong>in</strong>dicationsof how it w<strong>as</strong> bridged <strong>in</strong> evolution. F<strong>in</strong>ally,Donald’s theory does not address the questionwhy <strong>mimesis</strong> evolved <strong>in</strong> the first place, and whyit later became superseded by language.Apart from these issues, Donald’s def<strong>in</strong>itionof <strong>mimesis</strong> is unclear with respect to at le<strong>as</strong>t thefollow<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts: Are the features (a)-(e) mentionedabove necessary and jo<strong>in</strong>tly sufficient orare some more central than others? Is there apriority for the communicative or the noncommunicativeforms of <strong>mimesis</strong>? In which wayshould one <strong>in</strong>terpret the notoriously ambiguousterms “reference” and “<strong>in</strong>tentionality”? Furthermore,if <strong>mimesis</strong> possesses all the features oflanguage except for phonetic realization <strong>as</strong>claimed by Laakso (1993), it rema<strong>in</strong>s unclearwhat exactly makes it “not l<strong>in</strong>guistic” <strong>in</strong> thewords of Donald quoted earlier. Hence, our firststep <strong>in</strong> elaborat<strong>in</strong>g the mimetic hypothesis of<strong>human</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>s is to offer a more specific(re)def<strong>in</strong>ition of the concept, which we refer to<strong>as</strong> bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>in</strong> order to dist<strong>in</strong>guish it fromthe broader concept with Aristotelian roots:(Def) <strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong>: A particular act ofcognition or communication is an act of bodily<strong>mimesis</strong> if and only if:1. It <strong>in</strong>volves a cross-modal mapp<strong>in</strong>g betweenproprioception (k<strong>in</strong>aesthetic experience) andexteroception (normally dom<strong>in</strong>ated by vision),unless proprioception is compromised.(Cross-modality)2. It is realized by bodily motion that is, or canbe, under conscious control. (Volition)3. The body (part) and its motion correspondto – either iconically or <strong>in</strong>dexically – some action,object or event, but at the same time aredifferentiated from it by the subject. (Representation)4. The subject <strong>in</strong>tends for the act to stand forsome action, object or event for an addressee,and for the addressee to appreciate this(Communicative sign function)But it is not an act of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> if:5. The act is fully conventional, i.e. a part ofmutual knowledge, and breaks up(semi)compositionally <strong>in</strong>to mean<strong>in</strong>gful subactsthat relate systematically to each otherand to other similar acts. (Symbolicity)This def<strong>in</strong>ition resolves some of the problemsmentioned earlier. By stat<strong>in</strong>g that bodily <strong>mimesis</strong><strong>in</strong>volves a mapp<strong>in</strong>g between proprioception, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gk<strong>in</strong>esthetic sense and the <strong>in</strong>put from sk<strong>in</strong>receptors and serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>as</strong> our b<strong>as</strong>ic form of selfknowledge(e.g. Edelman 1992; Gallagher 1995,2005) and exteroception (above all vision, butalso hear<strong>in</strong>g and touch), this expla<strong>in</strong>s the sense<strong>in</strong> which bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>in</strong>volves the body, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gspecific organs such <strong>as</strong> the vocal tract –to the extent that they are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> proprioceptive-exteroceptivemapp<strong>in</strong>g. S<strong>in</strong>ce speechproduction, and possibly even speech comprehensionaccord<strong>in</strong>g to the “motor theory ofspeech perception” (Liberman and Matt<strong>in</strong>gly1985) <strong>in</strong>volve such a mapp<strong>in</strong>g, this implies thateven speech <strong>in</strong>volves bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>, at thesame time <strong>as</strong> it transcends it due to symbolicity.By focus<strong>in</strong>g on full conventionality and systematicity<strong>as</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g language from bodily<strong>mimesis</strong>, it becomes clear <strong>in</strong> which sense <strong>mimesis</strong>is “not l<strong>in</strong>guistic”. Most importantly, however,the five criteria <strong>in</strong> the def<strong>in</strong>ition of bodily<strong>mimesis</strong> presented above allow us to cl<strong>as</strong>sify<strong>human</strong> and ape socio-<strong>cognitive</strong> skills along <strong>as</strong>cale consist<strong>in</strong>g of at le<strong>as</strong>t four dist<strong>in</strong>ct stages.We refer to this <strong>as</strong> the <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy (see Table2).Acts which only fulfill the first condition, butnot the others can be def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>as</strong> proto-mimetic.Neonatal face-mirror<strong>in</strong>g and cross-modal match<strong>in</strong>g(Meltzoff and Moore 1977, 1983, 1994) canbe regarded <strong>as</strong> such, and these have been witnessed<strong>in</strong> newborn chimpanzees <strong>as</strong> well (Myowa-Yamakoshi et al. 2004). On the other hand, bothdeferred imitation and mirror self-recognition fulfillconditions (1)-(3) and thus show a full form ofbodily <strong>mimesis</strong>. Skills such <strong>as</strong> these presupposethat the subject can both differentiate betweenhis own (felt) bodily representation, and the


6<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionentity that this representation corresponds to,and to see the first <strong>as</strong> stand<strong>in</strong>g for the latter. Thisis what Piaget (1945) called ‘the symbolic function’and argued that it appears at the end of thesensorimotor period of the child’s development.Sonesson (1989, <strong>in</strong> press) uses differentiation <strong>as</strong> thecrucial criterion to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between truesigns, which display it, and pre-sign mean<strong>in</strong>gs,which do not. Note, however, that such representation,<strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> Piaget’s example of the childmodel<strong>in</strong>g the open<strong>in</strong>g and clos<strong>in</strong>g of a matchboxwith his mouth, is not <strong>in</strong>tentionally communicative.Therefore, if condition (4) is not fulfilled itis bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> only of a dyadic sort. If it isfulfilled, then we have triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, such <strong>as</strong> that<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> pantomime or declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. F<strong>in</strong>ally,condition (5) dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between <strong>in</strong>tentionalgestural communication, and signed language,which also possesses the properties ofconventionality and systematicity (S<strong>in</strong>gleton,Goldw<strong>in</strong>-Meadow and McNeill 1995).Table 2. The <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy. Def<strong>in</strong>itions of the fourevolutionary stages (for terms <strong>in</strong> italics, see the def<strong>in</strong>itionof bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>in</strong> the text) and examples ofcorrespond<strong>in</strong>g types of acts.Stage Def<strong>in</strong>ition ExamplesProto<strong>mimesis</strong>Dyadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Triadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Jo<strong>in</strong>t attention,declarativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, pantomimePost<strong>mimesis</strong>A bodily act <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gCross-modality withproprioception, butlack<strong>in</strong>g Volition orRepresentation (or both)An <strong>in</strong>terpersonal or<strong>in</strong>trapersonal bodilyact display<strong>in</strong>g Volitionand Representation, butnot Communicative signfunctionAs dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> butalso <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g Communicativesign functionAs triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>,but also <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gSymbolicityFacial expressions,bodilysynchronizationShared attention,imperativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, mirrorself-recognition,do-<strong>as</strong>-I-doimitationSigned languageIn the rema<strong>in</strong>der of this article we shall apply theproposed <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy to the evolution(and to a lesser degree, the ontogeny) of three<strong>cognitive</strong>-communicative capabilities: imitation(Section 4), <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity (Section 5), and gestures(Section 6). By analyz<strong>in</strong>g evidence from primatology,and to a smaller extent child development,we will identify levels with<strong>in</strong> these doma<strong>in</strong>sthat correspond to the levels of the <strong>mimesis</strong>hierarchy. In other words, we considerwhether there are simple forms of these capacitiesthat are <strong>in</strong> essence proto-mimetic; whetherthere are forms that are dyadic mimetic; whetherthere is furthermore evidence for communicative<strong>in</strong>tentions, and thus for triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>.F<strong>in</strong>ally we <strong>as</strong>k whether there are specific formsof imitation, <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and gesture thatdepend on the acquisition of a conventionalsymbolic system, i.e. language, and are thus postmimetic.We will show that the progression protomimetic> dyadic-mimetic > triadic-mimetic > postmimetic,<strong>in</strong>stead of the dichotomy animal signal<strong>in</strong>gvs. <strong>human</strong> language outl<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Section 2,and <strong>in</strong> particular by dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g between dyadicand triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, h<strong>as</strong> implications for atheory of the orig<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong>uniqueness. It may seem that such a theory goesaga<strong>in</strong>st the stream of much current theoriz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>evolutionary science s<strong>in</strong>ce it <strong>in</strong>vokes relativelydiscrete “stages” requir<strong>in</strong>g qualitative transitions,while both the nature of evolutionary processes<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g many small mutations and the availablefissile evidence seem to speak <strong>in</strong> favor of aprolonged gradual process (Johansson 2005).However, we h<strong>as</strong>ten to note that there is nocontradiction between the stage-like theory thatwe will pursue and the evolutionary evidence.Firstly, it is completely possible to have relativelydiscrete transitions, or “punctuated equilibria”(Eldredge and Gould 1972) with<strong>in</strong> a b<strong>as</strong>icallygradual framework, i.e. without this imply<strong>in</strong>g anyform of “saltations” or sudden “macromutations”(Dessalles 2004). The likelihood forfairly rapid and abrupt changes is even higherwhen biological and cultural evolution <strong>in</strong>teract,<strong>as</strong> h<strong>as</strong> most likely been the c<strong>as</strong>e with <strong>human</strong><strong>cognitive</strong> evolution <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g language (Deacon1997). Secondly, our notion of a <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy,<strong>as</strong> other similar constructs (Dennett 1996;Zlatev 2003), is meant to serve primarily <strong>as</strong> aconceptual role <strong>in</strong> help<strong>in</strong>g us relate and compareprimate skills <strong>in</strong> somewhat different doma<strong>in</strong>s: itis not an evolutionary ladder for cl<strong>as</strong>sify<strong>in</strong>g differentspecies, which may very well have differentdegrees of the mimetic skills under discussion,and thus form much more of a cl<strong>in</strong>e. Withthese caveats we proceed with our analysis.


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 74. Mimesis and imitationChimpanzees, bonobos, gorill<strong>as</strong> and orangutanscan copy behavior to some extent and <strong>in</strong> seem<strong>in</strong>glyvarious ways. The literature on ape imitation<strong>in</strong> the broad sense of the term (see Whitenet al. 2004 for a recent review) can for our purposesbe grouped <strong>in</strong>to the follow<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong> experimentalparadigms: Neonatal mimick<strong>in</strong>g Instrumental tool-use Experiments with “artificial fruits” (puzzleboxes) “Do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do” t<strong>as</strong>ks- <strong>in</strong> respect to body movements (“Simonsays”)- <strong>in</strong> manipulation of objects Ethological methods (i.e. field observationsof food process<strong>in</strong>g techniques or <strong>in</strong>directevidence from local traditions)Most obviously relevant for our discussion ofstages of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> are those types of observationallearn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which an observer copiessometh<strong>in</strong>g of a model’s bodily actions, may it be <strong>in</strong> alaboratory tool-us<strong>in</strong>g situation, natural forag<strong>in</strong>gsituation or mimick<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do game.Other forms of observational or social learn<strong>in</strong>g,like emulation, available <strong>in</strong> several versions (Byrne1998; Custance, Whiten and Fredman 1999),response facilitation (see Byrne 1999), and stimulusandlocal enhancement (see Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1996), can<strong>in</strong>form observers about properties of the environmentand objects, or the connection betweencerta<strong>in</strong> manipulations and outcomes, but do not<strong>in</strong>volve copy<strong>in</strong>g bodily actions per se and thus itis not clear if they <strong>in</strong>volve bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>.For our purposes, the collective term imitationperta<strong>in</strong>s most clearly to the copy<strong>in</strong>g of bodilymotions (the do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do experimental paradigm)<strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> to imitation on the action level <strong>in</strong> objectmanipulation. The notion of action level imitationw<strong>as</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>ally contr<strong>as</strong>ted to that of programlevel (Byrne and Russon 1998), the latter be<strong>in</strong>gthe hierarchical organization of a series of actionsand the former the execution of an <strong>in</strong>dividualcomponent action. Note that imitation onthe program level can take place without imitationon action level. The program level h<strong>as</strong> beenfurther divided by Whiten (1998) <strong>in</strong>to be<strong>in</strong>geither of a sequential or a hierarchical k<strong>in</strong>d. Anexample of sequence imitation from the artificialfruitexperiments would be to manipulate obstacleA before obstacle B, while an example ofimitation on the action level would be pok<strong>in</strong>g vs.pull<strong>in</strong>g to remove a plug. If the subject copiesthe manual movement of the model, it is regarded<strong>as</strong> an <strong>in</strong>stance of action-level imitation,but if the ape <strong>in</strong>stead copies the movement ofthe plug, it is categorized by Custance et al.(1999) <strong>as</strong> object movement re-enactment. The latter isusually regarded <strong>as</strong> a form of emulation, wherethe end state of an event is achieved (or copied)but the subject <strong>in</strong>vents his or her own way toachieve this end and the model is <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciplesuperfluous. However, s<strong>in</strong>ce object movementre-enactment is a special k<strong>in</strong>d of emulationwhere at le<strong>as</strong>t the direction of the movement ofthe object is copied, <strong>in</strong> our analysis it wouldqualify <strong>as</strong> a form of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>.There is also the hypothetical c<strong>as</strong>e where thesubject only learns that the plug can be movedand then proceeds to br<strong>in</strong>g about that effect <strong>in</strong>whatever way he or she prefers. To determ<strong>in</strong>ewhat is what, however, is a tricky bus<strong>in</strong>ess. Inthe latter c<strong>as</strong>e the subject might happen to br<strong>in</strong>gabout by chance the same movement of the plug<strong>as</strong> the model showed, and thus give the impressionof object movement re-enactment. Furthermore,<strong>in</strong> both a false and <strong>in</strong> a true c<strong>as</strong>e ofobject movement re-enactment, the subject canalso happen to perform the same manual actions<strong>as</strong> the model by chance and give the impressionof bodily imitation on the action level. At le<strong>as</strong>tthree forms of observational learn<strong>in</strong>g can thusyield the same expression: simple emulation,object movement re-enactment and action levelimitation. The experiments with artificial fruits,some of which we will review below, are designedto te<strong>as</strong>e apart these copy<strong>in</strong>g strategies.The failures of great apes to fully copy behavior<strong>in</strong> several early studies led Tom<strong>as</strong>ello,Kruger and Ratner (1993) to conclude that apesemulate, but cannot imitate, s<strong>in</strong>ce imitation <strong>in</strong>their view entails copy<strong>in</strong>g both of the goal andthe method to br<strong>in</strong>g about that goal. ForTom<strong>as</strong>ello and his collaborators imitation thush<strong>as</strong> a <strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” component by def<strong>in</strong>ition,and on the b<strong>as</strong>is of the imitation data, the grouph<strong>as</strong> argued that apes lack an understand<strong>in</strong>g ofothers <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional agents (e.g. Tom<strong>as</strong>ello1999). S<strong>in</strong>ce then both the field of primate imitationstudies h<strong>as</strong> expanded and the MPI Leipziggroup h<strong>as</strong> modified their views on apes’ abilitiesto understand <strong>in</strong>tentional agency (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello etal. <strong>in</strong> press, see Section 5 for more discussion).


8<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionDonald’s def<strong>in</strong>ition of <strong>mimesis</strong> (presented <strong>in</strong>Section 3), compris<strong>in</strong>g reference, <strong>in</strong>tentionality, communicativity,autocu<strong>in</strong>g and generativity, is difficult toapply to non-<strong>human</strong> primate imitation becauseobservational learn<strong>in</strong>g through copy<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>as</strong> beenstudied <strong>in</strong> non-communicative tool us<strong>in</strong>g andpuzzle box situations, with few exceptions such<strong>as</strong> the study by Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (1994) on chimpanzeegestures <strong>in</strong> which the authors did notf<strong>in</strong>d any observational learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> functionalgesture acquisition. However, us<strong>in</strong>g ourdef<strong>in</strong>ition (see Section 3), it is possible to applythe concept of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> to f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> thefield of ape imitation. As we will show <strong>in</strong> thissection, these f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>as</strong>evidence that apes are capable of at le<strong>as</strong>t protomimeticand dyadic mimetic imitation, and possiblyeven triadic mimetic imitation when a communicativesign function is added.4.1 Proto-mimetic imitationIn what we call proto-mimetic imitation there is(iconic) resemblance between the copy and thecopied, which is probably b<strong>as</strong>ed on a b<strong>as</strong>ic formof identification with the model (see Section5.1). For this to be cl<strong>as</strong>sified <strong>as</strong> proto-mimeticrather than dyadic-mimetic, there should be noclear evidence for volition or for differentiationbetween oneself and the model.The prime candidate for proto-mimetic imitationis neonatal facial mirror<strong>in</strong>g. In the c<strong>as</strong>e of<strong>human</strong> neonatal mirror<strong>in</strong>g, the field is dividedbetween those who prefer a m<strong>in</strong>imalist <strong>in</strong>terpretationand those who argue for a more mentalisticone. For example, Anisfeld (1996) <strong>in</strong> a metaanalysisof experiments by Meltzoff and Mooreand Heimann argues that the <strong>in</strong>fant’s response islimited to one facial movement, tongue protrusion,and not several. If so, it would be a largelyreflexive form of mirror<strong>in</strong>g unlikely to requirevolition on the part of the <strong>in</strong>fant, and thus wouldbe proto-mimetic. On the other hand Meltzoffand Moore (1977, 1983, 1994) have argued thatthe <strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>fant not only displays volition (i.e.choice on whether to imitate or not, and abilityto mirror more than tongue protrusion), but thathe/she differentiates between him/herself and themodel. Meltzoff and Moore (1994) argue thatthere is evidence for deferred imitation <strong>in</strong> 6-week-old <strong>in</strong>fants who imitated the action whensee<strong>in</strong>g the model aga<strong>in</strong> after a delay of 24 hours.While differentiation <strong>in</strong> itself does not requirethe k<strong>in</strong>d of displacement that is witnessed <strong>in</strong>deferred imitation (see Sonesson <strong>in</strong> press), weagree with Piaget (1945) that the capacity fordeferred imitation rests on at le<strong>as</strong>t a simple formof representational activity. Thus, if the Meltzoff-Moore<strong>in</strong>terpretation of neonatal imitationis correct, we must conclude that <strong>human</strong> childrenperform dyadic imitation (see below) froma very early age.In the c<strong>as</strong>e of apes, newborn chimpanzeeshave been shown to have a period of <strong>in</strong>natemirror<strong>in</strong>g responsiveness to <strong>human</strong> facial stimuli(mouth open<strong>in</strong>g and tongue protrusion) that ispresent to 11 (Myowa-Yamakoshi 2001) or 9(Myowa-Yamakoshi et al. 2004) weeks of age.This shows that neonate chimpanzees have (atle<strong>as</strong>t) the capacity for proto-<strong>mimesis</strong> with respectto faces. It is to our knowledge not yettested whether this capacity also <strong>in</strong>volves differentiationor volition. But different sources forhighly similar responses <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> and ape newbornsseem unlikely.4.2 Dyadic-mimetic imitationIn what we call dyadic-mimetic imitation, thesubject differentiates between self and modeland understands that a bodily posture or motioncan correspond to someth<strong>in</strong>g else, like an objector action. However, there is no attempt tocommunicate this “someth<strong>in</strong>g else” to another<strong>in</strong>dividual by means of the bodily motion.In a non-communicative sett<strong>in</strong>g, like <strong>in</strong> theexperiments on social learn<strong>in</strong>g studied with non<strong>human</strong>primates the “someth<strong>in</strong>g else” mentionedabove would be to understand the mean<strong>in</strong>gof a model’s actions: what the model is try<strong>in</strong>gto achieve. As mentioned above, imitat<strong>in</strong>g thegoal <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> the means to br<strong>in</strong>g about that goalis the hallmark of (true) imitation accord<strong>in</strong>g toTom<strong>as</strong>ello, Kruger and Ratner (1993), and <strong>in</strong>volvescerta<strong>in</strong> levels of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>tentions.When try<strong>in</strong>g to implement the imitation ofgoals <strong>in</strong> an experimental sett<strong>in</strong>g the goal is oftento get hold of a food item, and these experimentshave tended to either foster <strong>in</strong>novation oruse of old reliable methods. This is not surpris<strong>in</strong>g.If you truly want to get hold of a food item,and apes clearly do so, the most effective means


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 9one can come up with is used, and that is notnecessarily the one witnessed.The well-known rake experiment of Nagell etal. (1993) is an example of imitation studies us<strong>in</strong>gan <strong>in</strong>strumental tool. If there is any learn<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the c<strong>as</strong>e of apes it is generally consideredto be <strong>in</strong> the form of emulation: the subjectslearn someth<strong>in</strong>g new about tools, theirmovements or the environment, but not aboutthe bodily actions the model is us<strong>in</strong>g to br<strong>in</strong>gabout the <strong>in</strong>tended goal.Better imitation results have been obta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>experiments with so called “artificial fruits”, i.e.boxes with obstacles that the subject h<strong>as</strong> to workaround <strong>in</strong> order to get to the food content.These experiments address the question: Whatdo apes spontaneously copy when they get anopportunity to observe a model? Which strategiesand mechanisms of social learn<strong>in</strong>g are <strong>in</strong>volved?The artificial fruit experimental paradigmh<strong>as</strong> yielded mixed results, <strong>as</strong> strategies ofresult emulation, object movement reenactment,action-level imitation and sequenceimitation have been recorded (Whiten et al.2004). The results seem to vary over fruit usedand species tested and/or age of subjects (Sto<strong>in</strong>skiand Whiten 2003; Custance et al. 2001; Sto<strong>in</strong>skiet al. 2001; Whiten et al. 1996). Action-levelimitation implies that the subject can represent amodel’s manual movements and re-enact thesefrom memory. Perform<strong>in</strong>g sequence imitationmeans that the subjects are also able to parse <strong>as</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>g of component actions and later re<strong>as</strong>semblethese <strong>in</strong> the same f<strong>as</strong>hion from memory,which aga<strong>in</strong> show their ability to re-enact detachedrepresentations voluntarily.Apes have demonstrated some skills of action-leveland sequence imitation, but at thesame time they experience some difficulties withthem <strong>as</strong> evident by their lack of full copy<strong>in</strong>g.Imitat<strong>in</strong>g the use of familiar motor actions <strong>in</strong>novel situations seem to come about more e<strong>as</strong>ily<strong>in</strong> apes than copy<strong>in</strong>g new motor actions altogether(Myowa-Yamakoshi and Matsuzawa1999). Especially for young <strong>in</strong>dividuals actionsare more likely to be copied if they are close tothe ones already <strong>in</strong> the subjects’ repertoire(Bjorklund et al. 2002). It is not yet settledwhether apes’ relatively poor performance ondetailed imitation of bodily actions is due tomotor-perceptual <strong>as</strong>pects or skills <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity.However, s<strong>in</strong>ce recent studies have shownthat at le<strong>as</strong>t chimpanzees have a degree of understand<strong>in</strong>gof the mentality of others (see belowand Section 5.2), the motor-perceptual explanationshould not be underestimated.Goal directedness is lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the most bodilymimetic paradigm, the “do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do” experiments,where part of mak<strong>in</strong>g sure that the copyis acquired through observation is to performnever-before seen, or at le<strong>as</strong>t unusual, movementswithout any practical function. There isno food item to get to at the end of the actionsequence. The subject is verbally <strong>as</strong>ked to do thesame <strong>as</strong> the model on cue. The do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do paradigmis an example of studies that <strong>as</strong>k the question:Can apes copy behavior? The answer ispositive. Both cross-fostered (or “enculturated”)apes, e.g. the orangutan Chantek (Miles et al.1996) and the chimpanzee Viki (Custance et al.1995), and chimpanzees with more moderate<strong>human</strong> upbr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g (Custance et al. 1995) canp<strong>as</strong>s these tests. Once they understand themean<strong>in</strong>g of the “do the same” command, anyfaults <strong>in</strong> the copy is bound to be motorperceptualand not due to <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity issues.The do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do experiments prove thatapes are capable of both volition and representation(they represent the model’s body), which qualifythem <strong>as</strong> dyadic-mimetic imitators. However,learn<strong>in</strong>g the concept of SAMENESS may <strong>in</strong>fluencethe performance of apes profoundly. Thompson,Boysen and Oden (1997) found that language-naïvechimpanzees learned to judge relationsbetween relations (A is to A <strong>as</strong> B is to B,and not <strong>as</strong> C is to D) <strong>in</strong> a match<strong>in</strong>g-to-samplet<strong>as</strong>k only if the subjects had previously learned atoken for the concept SAME. Ord<strong>in</strong>ary match<strong>in</strong>gto-sampletra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g could not yield the same result.Experiments that h<strong>in</strong>ge on the subject “gett<strong>in</strong>gthe po<strong>in</strong>t of the game”, so to speak, haveimplications for ecological validity s<strong>in</strong>ce theexperimenter h<strong>as</strong> to plant certa<strong>in</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong>the subject that it might not have stumbled uponnaturally. This is especially problematic for evolutionaryre<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g around comparative experimentalpsychology, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not clear whatcircumstances would have “planted” suchknowledge <strong>in</strong> the hom<strong>in</strong>id l<strong>in</strong>e.Deferred imitation on objects, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g do<strong>as</strong>-I-doimitation, is perhaps the most promis<strong>in</strong>gevidence for dyadic mimetic capacities <strong>in</strong> apes.In these experiments the subject is shown actionson objects and is then either <strong>as</strong>ked to “dothe same th<strong>in</strong>g” (if the verbal command islearned) or (if not) the spontaneous handl<strong>in</strong>g of


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 11tak<strong>in</strong>g have shown that chimpanzees know theimportance of others’ visual attention, both <strong>in</strong>communicative contexts (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. 1994;Krause and Fouts 1997; Pika, Liebal andTom<strong>as</strong>ello 2003, 2005) e.g. use of attentiongett<strong>in</strong>ggestures and competitive contexts (Hareet al. 2000; Hare, Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 2001).Apes also seem to be able to dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>in</strong>tentionalfrom accidental acts (Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello1998) and to judge an experimenter <strong>as</strong> eitherunwill<strong>in</strong>g or unable to give them a treat (Call etal. 2004). The conclusion is therefore that apesdo understand second-order mentality, at le<strong>as</strong>t <strong>in</strong>the form of second-order attention and (possibly)second-order <strong>in</strong>tentions. However, understand<strong>in</strong>gthe communicative sign function, andthus triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, requires third-order mentality– <strong>as</strong> we will argue <strong>in</strong> Section 5 – and there isyet no clear evidence that (non-enculturated)apes are capable of this.Possible <strong>in</strong>stances of triadic mimetic imitation<strong>in</strong> non-<strong>human</strong> primates would be copy<strong>in</strong>gof referential signs <strong>in</strong> language-taught apes.However, most of the learn<strong>in</strong>g of signs by apesthat have been taught a signed language, such <strong>as</strong>the gorill<strong>as</strong> Koko and Michael (Bonvillan andPatterson 1993, 1999), the chimpanzee W<strong>as</strong>hoe(Fouts 1972) and the orangutan Chantek (Miles1990) takes place by gett<strong>in</strong>g the hands molded<strong>in</strong>to the signs and therefore does not qualify <strong>as</strong>either imitation or bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>. Still, Gardnerand Gardner (1969) also used the “do-<strong>as</strong>-I-do”paradigm to teach new signs to W<strong>as</strong>hoe withsome success. A more general problem, however,is that it is difficult to dist<strong>in</strong>guish the imitativelearn<strong>in</strong>g of such signs from post-<strong>mimesis</strong>s<strong>in</strong>ce these apes were taught a simplified form ofAmerican Sign Language (ASL), and that impliesthat they were exposed to, and possibly evenacquired at le<strong>as</strong>t a degree of symbolicity (<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gconventionality and systematicity). In a studyof the functions of the repetition of lexigrams bylanguage-tra<strong>in</strong>ed chimpanzees and bonbobosGreenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh (1993) reportat le<strong>as</strong>t some clear c<strong>as</strong>es of the acquisition oflexigrams through imitation. At the same timeSavage-Rumbaugh and Lew<strong>in</strong> (1994) emph<strong>as</strong>izethat only when the chimpanzees Sherman andAust<strong>in</strong> acquired the referential mean<strong>in</strong>g of thelexigrams, after a prolonged and laborious processof tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, could they match lexigrams tosamples.Perhaps the most conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g evidence fortriadic-mimetic imitation <strong>in</strong> apes <strong>in</strong>volves the<strong>in</strong>vention of iconic signs by Koko (Patterson1980) and Chantek (Miles 1990). Such sign areexamples of representation (the ape representssometh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the environment) and communicativesign function (the ape addresses this to his or hercaregivers). S<strong>in</strong>ce the imitation is creative, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gthe resemblance (iconicity) between thesign and the way the referent is typically used, itcannot be solely a product of be<strong>in</strong>g taught <strong>as</strong>ymbolic code. The fact that Koko’s and Chantek’ssign <strong>in</strong>ventions build on iconicity suggestthat they are c<strong>as</strong>es of triadic-mimetic rather thanpost-mimetic imitation. We return to these c<strong>as</strong>es<strong>in</strong> Section 6.4.4 Post-mimetic imitationWhile speech may be regarded <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> part postmimetic(see Section 3), the paradigm exampleof post-<strong>mimesis</strong> is signed language: it is b<strong>as</strong>ed oncross-modal mapp<strong>in</strong>g between proprioceptionand vision, and possesses the other features of<strong>mimesis</strong>: volition, representation and communicativefunction. Furthermore, it is symbolic, not <strong>in</strong>the Peircian sense of lack<strong>in</strong>g any motivationalrelationship between the expression and contentpoles of its signs – over 50% of the signs of ASLare judged to be iconic (Woll and Kyle 2004) –but <strong>in</strong> the sense of consist<strong>in</strong>g of conventional signs(presuppos<strong>in</strong>g third-order mentality, see Section5) and systematicity (i.e. <strong>in</strong>ternal relations betweenthe signs). Other <strong>in</strong>stances of post<strong>mimesis</strong>would be emblems like the thumbs-up“OK” sign, or nodd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stead of say<strong>in</strong>g “yes”,which fulfill the property of conventionality, andat le<strong>as</strong>t a limited form of systematicity.Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, post-mimetic imitation wouldconsist of skills <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the learn<strong>in</strong>g of suchsigns. As po<strong>in</strong>ted out above, some apes thathave been taught a signed language did acquiresome of their signs <strong>in</strong> this manner, though themajority of signs were acquired through mold<strong>in</strong>gof the hands. Even for those that were acquiredby imitation, there may be doubt concern<strong>in</strong>g thedegree of their conventionality and systematicity,e.g. deaf native signers have difficulties <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>gapes’ sign<strong>in</strong>g (P<strong>in</strong>ker 1994).One form of imitation that is clearly symbolic(and hence post-mimetic) is what Tom<strong>as</strong>ello(1999) calls role-reversal imitation: imitation of sign


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 13of language, it is not so much the syntax of imitationthat is difficlt for apes, but its semantics. It isconceivable how ape copy<strong>in</strong>g ability, coupledwith a motivation to share one’s mental states(which can, of course, also mean attempt<strong>in</strong>g toimpose one’s view on others), can give rise tomimetic-communicatory <strong>in</strong>teractions, <strong>in</strong> whichlevels of <strong>mimesis</strong> and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity are closelyconnected, <strong>as</strong> we will argue <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>gsection.5. Mimesis and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityWe understand the notion of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitybroadly (and rather literally) <strong>as</strong> the shar<strong>in</strong>g andunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of others’ mentality. The term “mentality”is taken here to <strong>in</strong>volve not only beliefs andother forms of conceptual knowledge, but allforms of consciousness, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g emotions,desires, attentional foci and <strong>in</strong>tentions (seeGärdenfors 2003). Not all of these need to beunderstood conceptually, but may <strong>in</strong>volve preconceptual,non-reflective understand<strong>in</strong>g.While the close connection between bodily<strong>mimesis</strong> and imitation discussed above, andgesture (to be analyzed <strong>in</strong> Section 6) is fairlystraightforward, this may not be the c<strong>as</strong>e withrespect to <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. The re<strong>as</strong>on for thislies, we believe, <strong>in</strong> the dom<strong>in</strong>ant cognitivist viewof mentality <strong>as</strong> consist<strong>in</strong>g entirely (or at le<strong>as</strong>tpredom<strong>in</strong>antly) of propositional representations.In this view, to understand another’s m<strong>in</strong>dwould imply hav<strong>in</strong>g beliefs concern<strong>in</strong>g theirbeliefs. This conception can e<strong>as</strong>ily be framed <strong>as</strong>hav<strong>in</strong>g some sort of <strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” and, <strong>in</strong>deed,this h<strong>as</strong> been the dom<strong>in</strong>ant conception <strong>in</strong>the field (e.g. Baron-Cohen 1995).A great deal of the debate about the <strong>cognitive</strong>abilities of apes h<strong>as</strong> concerned whether or not theyhave a <strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” (Woodruff andPremack 1979; Byrne 1995; Gómez 1994; Heyes1998; Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1999). Also <strong>in</strong> the discussion of<strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> development, the question whenand how children develop one h<strong>as</strong> been a centralfocus of content (Perner et al. 1987; Gopnik andAst<strong>in</strong>gton 1988; Gopnik and Meltzoff 1997;Mitchell 1997).But regard<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity <strong>as</strong> a <strong>“the</strong>ory”<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g (primarily) beliefs h<strong>as</strong> had some negativeimplications for understand<strong>in</strong>g this fundamentalsuite of socio-<strong>cognitive</strong> capacities: (a) thequestion is typically posed <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a discrete,all-or-noth<strong>in</strong>g property: either the child oranimal “h<strong>as</strong> a theory of m<strong>in</strong>d” or doesn’t; (b) therole of one’s own body and actions – and those ofthe other – is m<strong>in</strong>imized, and (c) <strong>“the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g”about the m<strong>in</strong>ds of others (or even oneself) isconsidered prior to act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> consort with them,giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity a rather static, detachedquality.Recently, however, these implications havebeen seriously questioned on the b<strong>as</strong>is of bothnew empirical evidence from child developmentand primatology and older philosophical, aboveall phenomenological, <strong>in</strong>sights. With respect to(a) it h<strong>as</strong> become clear that <strong>“the</strong> generic term‘theory of m<strong>in</strong>d’ actually covers a wide range ofprocesses of social cognition” (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, Calland Hare 2003: 239). Consequently one mustdist<strong>in</strong>guish between these different processes <strong>in</strong>order to understand the <strong>cognitive</strong> capabilities ofanimals, <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> children of different ages. Forexample, Gärdenfors (2003) splits the so-called<strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” <strong>in</strong>to six levels, where the middlefour clearly correspond to different socio<strong>cognitive</strong>capabilities: understand<strong>in</strong>g others’emotions, attention, <strong>in</strong>tentions and beliefs, respectively.Such a division can be complementedwith the hypothesis that the different capabilitiescorrespond to different phylogenetic and ontogeneticstages <strong>in</strong> evolution and development, and<strong>in</strong>deed Gärdenfors (2003) makes this proposal.The criticism concern<strong>in</strong>g (b) and (c) w<strong>as</strong> developedfirst with<strong>in</strong> the phenomenology ofHusserl some one hundred years ago and targetedthe <strong>in</strong>tellectualist perspective on the “understand<strong>in</strong>gof other m<strong>in</strong>ds” (the usual term for<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity <strong>in</strong> philosophy) <strong>as</strong> a matter of<strong>in</strong>ference or analogy from the knowledge ofone’s own m<strong>in</strong>d. As summarized by a modern<strong>in</strong>terpreter: “For Husserl, understand<strong>in</strong>g anotherperson is not a matter of <strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>in</strong>ference,but a matter of sensory activations that are unified<strong>in</strong> or by the animate organism or lived bodythat is perceiv<strong>in</strong>g another animate organism.”(Gallagher <strong>in</strong> press).This perspective on <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity w<strong>as</strong> furtherdeveloped by Merleau-Ponty (1962), <strong>in</strong>particular through the notion of the “corporealschema” which serves <strong>as</strong> “a normal means ofknow<strong>in</strong>g other bodies” (Merleau-Ponty 2003:218). More recently, Gallagher (1995, 2005, <strong>in</strong>press) h<strong>as</strong> elaborated the dist<strong>in</strong>ction betweenbody schema and body image where the first is preconsciousand serves <strong>as</strong> a precondition and


14<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionbackdrop for <strong>in</strong>tentionality (cf. Searle’s (1992)notion of the Background), while the latter is “a(sometimes conscious) system of perceptions,attitudes, beliefs and dispositions perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g toone’s own body” (Gallagher 2005: 37). Empiricalneuroscience h<strong>as</strong> recently given support for therole of the body <strong>in</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g others throughmechanisms <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g “mirror neurons” (Rizzolattiet al. 1996; Gallese, Keysers and Rizzolati2004; Arbib <strong>in</strong> press), that mediate between theperception of another and the subject’s ownproprioception and action.With<strong>in</strong> this “embodied” and action-orientedperspective on the understand<strong>in</strong>g of otherm<strong>in</strong>ds, unlike <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tellectualist cognitivistone, bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> becomes clearly relevant.With respect to dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g different levels of<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, we can apply the <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchydef<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> Section 3 to yield a possibleevolutionary and developmental hierarchy of<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitity.It should be noted that this way of “splitt<strong>in</strong>gthe theory of m<strong>in</strong>d” is different from that proposedby Gärdenfors (2003) s<strong>in</strong>ce the differentcapabilities dist<strong>in</strong>guished by the Gärdenfors(understand<strong>in</strong>g emotion, attention, <strong>in</strong>tention andbelief) are <strong>in</strong> a sense orthogonal to the <strong>mimesis</strong>hierarchy. For example, the understand<strong>in</strong>g ofothers’ emotions occurs on each one of the levelsof the <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy, with <strong>in</strong>cre<strong>as</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>cognitive</strong> complexity. However, if we considerwhat may be regarded <strong>as</strong> a typical manifestation ofthe respective capability (emotion, attention and<strong>in</strong>tention), there turns out to be considerableoverlap between the levels of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitydef<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> this article and those of Gärdenfors(2003): Emotion can be shared on a protomimeticlevel, shar<strong>in</strong>g attention <strong>in</strong>volves (atle<strong>as</strong>t) dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, understand<strong>in</strong>g communicative<strong>in</strong>tentions is centrally implicated <strong>in</strong> triadic<strong>mimesis</strong> (but “simple” <strong>in</strong>tentions are understooddyadically), and understand<strong>in</strong>g beliefs appears torequire explicit symbolic skills, which can beargued to be post-mimetic s<strong>in</strong>ce they depend onlanguage (see Section 5.4).A central question <strong>in</strong> relat<strong>in</strong>g the proposed<strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity iswhether the respective <strong>mimesis</strong> level serves <strong>as</strong> aprecondition and a causal factor for the developmentof correspond<strong>in</strong>g skills of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. Or isit rather that <strong>in</strong>dependently reached <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>tothe m<strong>in</strong>d of others makes <strong>in</strong>cre<strong>as</strong><strong>in</strong>gly complexforms of <strong>mimesis</strong> possible? Our general Vygotskyanapproach suggests the first scenario:bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> is a fundamentally <strong>in</strong>terpersonalactivity that exercises (<strong>in</strong> ontogeny) and providesselection pressures (<strong>in</strong> phylogeny) for develop<strong>in</strong>gmore ref<strong>in</strong>ed skills <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d read<strong>in</strong>g. Thus, ourpredom<strong>in</strong>ant take is that <strong>mimesis</strong> drives <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityrather than the other way around.At the same time we acknowledge that the “driv<strong>in</strong>g”metaphor is not completely adequate s<strong>in</strong>cethe causality runs <strong>in</strong> both ways and is possiblybest described <strong>in</strong> terms of co-evolution. We willreturn to this issue <strong>in</strong> the summary at the end ofthis section.5.1 Proto-mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityGiven our def<strong>in</strong>ition of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> we canregard some of the most b<strong>as</strong>ic forms of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity<strong>as</strong> “proto-mimetic” to the extentthat they (a) consist of forms of <strong>in</strong>terpersonal<strong>in</strong>teraction that <strong>in</strong>volve cross-modal mapp<strong>in</strong>gbetween proprioception and the (visual) perceptionof others, (b) do not fulfill either one of thecharacteristics volition and representation. This canbe made more precise us<strong>in</strong>g the dist<strong>in</strong>ction madeby Gallagher (1995, 2005) between body schemaand body image. The first is characterized <strong>as</strong> “<strong>as</strong>ystem of sensory-motor processes that constantlyregulate posture and movement – processesthat function without reflective awarenessor the necessity of perceptual monitor<strong>in</strong>g” (Gallagher2005: 37-38). The second is, <strong>as</strong> po<strong>in</strong>tedout, “a (sometimes conscious) system of perceptions,attitudes, beliefs and dispositions perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gto one’s own body” (Gallagher 2005: 37).Given these def<strong>in</strong>itions, we can state that acts ofproto-<strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>in</strong>volve (above all) the body schema,which is largely <strong>in</strong>nate (<strong>in</strong> the sense of be<strong>in</strong>gpresent at birth) and pre-conscious, rather thanthe body image, which is gradually constructedwith experience and is accessible to consciousness.Furthermore, the forms of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitydescribed here do not require a conceptual differentiationbetween self and other, which isnecessary for establish<strong>in</strong>g a correspondencerelation between them, i.e. what we refer <strong>in</strong> ourdef<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>as</strong> representation. This is not to say thatthe young <strong>in</strong>fant lives <strong>in</strong> a completely undifferentiatedworld <strong>in</strong> which there is no awareness ofself whatsoever, <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> cl<strong>as</strong>sical accounts of <strong>in</strong>fantcognition (e.g. James 1890). Nevertheless, even a


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 15modern developmental psychologist who emph<strong>as</strong>izesthe role of awareness of others’ attentionand the presence of affective selfconsciousness<strong>in</strong> the first months of life po<strong>in</strong>tsout that “older <strong>in</strong>fants reveal a greater focus onthe self and the younger ones reveal a more immersed,less detached focus on the other” (Reddy2003: 401). This “more immersed, less detached”quality of the earliest forms of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitysupports our cl<strong>as</strong>sification of them <strong>as</strong>proto-mimetic.Can this analysis be extended to the (early)<strong>in</strong>terpersonal relations among apes? As po<strong>in</strong>tedout <strong>in</strong> Section 4.3 “neonatal mirror<strong>in</strong>g” h<strong>as</strong> alsobeen observed <strong>in</strong> apes (though this h<strong>as</strong> so faronly be attested with <strong>human</strong>, rather than apefaces <strong>as</strong> stimuli). S<strong>in</strong>ce this is typically attributedto a form of identification with the person imitated,serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>as</strong> a b<strong>as</strong>is for <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitywhen children are concerned (Meltzoff andGopnik 1993; Gallagher 2005), it can be viewed<strong>as</strong> evidence that at le<strong>as</strong>t apes, and possibly othermammals too, have such b<strong>as</strong>ic proto-mimetic<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. The function of such “mirror<strong>in</strong>g”can be related to what is possibly the mostb<strong>as</strong>ic form of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, both ontogeneticallyand phylogenetically: the ability to shareemotions, or empathy (E<strong>in</strong>fühlung). As a protomimetic,non-representational capacity, this istestified <strong>in</strong> early <strong>in</strong>fancy and sometimes referredto <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraffectivity (Stern 2001). The well-knownexperiments described by Trevarthen (1992)show that parent-<strong>in</strong>fant <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> the firstfew months take the form of a reciprocal rhythmic“dance”, and that frustration follows if this“attunement” is disrupted (notice the musicalmetaphors). The suggestion is that emotionssuch <strong>as</strong> joy and suffer<strong>in</strong>g are perceived directly,possibly <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g mirror-neuron structuressimilar to those <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> action recognitionand imitation, rather than <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ferences tounderly<strong>in</strong>g states (Gallese, Keysers and Rizzolati2004).Preston and de Waal (2002) have argued persu<strong>as</strong>ivelythat <strong>as</strong> a b<strong>as</strong>ic mechanism <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g thel<strong>in</strong>kage of perception and action, a b<strong>as</strong>ic form ofempathy is available to most if not all mammalspecies. Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g empathy <strong>as</strong> “any processwhere the attended perception of the object’sstate generates a state <strong>in</strong> the subject that is moreapplicable to the object’s state or situation thanto the subject’s own prior state or situation”(ibid: 4), they see a clear evolutionary motivationfor its emergence <strong>in</strong> the ability to recognize andunderstand the behavior of con-specifics. It is anopen question how much of such match<strong>in</strong>g betweenthe visually perceived body of the otherand the proprioceptively perceived body of oneselfis doma<strong>in</strong>-general – and thus can be expectedto be general across species – and howmuch is specialized <strong>in</strong> the form of speciesspecificcommunicative signals such <strong>as</strong> facialexpressions. It is characteristic that such signals,such <strong>as</strong> the famous “play-face” expression ofgreat apes (an evolutionary precursor to the<strong>human</strong> smile) typically carry emotional ratherthan referential mean<strong>in</strong>g.A second socio-<strong>cognitive</strong> skill that relates to<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and appears to have a protomimeticorig<strong>in</strong>, at le<strong>as</strong>t <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> children, isattention. Reddy (2001, 2003, 2005) h<strong>as</strong> arguedthat prior to awareness of the other’s attentionto an external object and much prior to jo<strong>in</strong>tattention appear<strong>in</strong>g around 12 months (see below),children “show an awareness of others <strong>as</strong>attend<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> an awareness of self<strong>as</strong> an object of others’ attention” (Reddy 2003:357), displayed <strong>in</strong> phenomena such <strong>as</strong> eyecontact,<strong>in</strong>tense smil<strong>in</strong>g, coyness, ‘call<strong>in</strong>g’ vocalizations,show<strong>in</strong>g-off etc. S<strong>in</strong>ce awareness of self(at this stage) is largely proprioceptive, whileawareness of the attention of others (<strong>in</strong> see<strong>in</strong>gchildren) is mostly b<strong>as</strong>ed on vision, this satisfiesour first criterion for bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>. Reddy’sclaim is that such dyadic (though not dyadicmimetic)<strong>in</strong>teractions underp<strong>in</strong> later developments<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. Evidence for this is the observationthat autistic children show difficultieseven with such simple <strong>in</strong>terpersonal engagements,“suggest<strong>in</strong>g that whatever is go<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>dyadic attentional engagements may <strong>in</strong>deed becritical, not just <strong>as</strong> a source of <strong>in</strong>formation andexperience about attentional behavior, or <strong>as</strong> <strong>as</strong>caffold for the subsequent development ofawareness of attention, but also <strong>as</strong> evidence ofawareness of attention” (Reddy 2005: 95).Until recently it h<strong>as</strong> not been clear whethersuch awareness of another’s attention exists <strong>in</strong>the <strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>in</strong>fant apes and theirmothers, but <strong>in</strong> a recent study, Bard et al. (<strong>in</strong>press) report that the rates of mutual gaze between<strong>in</strong>fants and their mothers are virtually thesame <strong>in</strong> 3-month old <strong>human</strong> children and 3-month old chimpanzees; 18-20 and 17 times perhour, respectively (though <strong>human</strong>s tend to engage<strong>in</strong> longer bouts of mutual gaze). Further-


16<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionmore, the authors noticed a “cultural” differencebetween the apes at Primate Research Institute,Japan and those at Yerkes National PrimateResearch Center, USA, with the ones <strong>in</strong> Japanengag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> mutual gaze at much higher rates (22vs. 12 times per hour), while the ape mothers <strong>in</strong>the USA cradled their <strong>in</strong>fants more often (71% vs.40% of the total time). Intrigu<strong>in</strong>gly, a similar<strong>in</strong>verse correlation between visual and tactilecontact h<strong>as</strong> been observed <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> societies,with traditional cultures favor<strong>in</strong>g touch andWestern ones gaze: “With reduced physical contactfound <strong>in</strong> Western societies, mutual engagementshifts to the visual system, arguably a moreevolutionarily derived pattern” (Bard et al. <strong>in</strong>press). S<strong>in</strong>ce apes do not seem to differ from<strong>human</strong>s <strong>in</strong> the capacity to perform this shift (andpossibly even transmit it culturally to their descendents),this confirms the conclusions fromneonatal imitation that there is no major differencebetween the species on the proto-mimeticlevel.5.2 Dyadic mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityIn our previous discussion, we proposed thatproto-mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, without a cleardifferentiation between self and other is b<strong>as</strong>edon the (mostly) unattended body schema andsimilarly unattended mechanisms for “bodycopy<strong>in</strong>g”. On the other hand, what we here referto <strong>as</strong> dyadic mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity is b<strong>as</strong>ed on theconscious control of the movements of one’sbody and attention to their correspondence tothe body of another, whereby one can imag<strong>in</strong>ewhat the other experiences on the b<strong>as</strong>is of one’sown experiences <strong>in</strong> similar circumstances. In theterm<strong>in</strong>ology of Gallagher (1995, 2005), we proposethat the role that bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> properplays for the development of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityimplies not the body schema but the body image.While the body schema and the body imagenormally <strong>in</strong>teract, Gallagher (2005) shows how<strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> pathologies they can be dis<strong>as</strong>sociated.The dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the dyadic form ofmimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, described here, and thetriadic one described <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g sub-sectionis that while the dyadic form <strong>in</strong>volves the propertiesof volition and representation (see Section3), e.g. <strong>in</strong> the c<strong>as</strong>e of recogniz<strong>in</strong>g oneself <strong>in</strong> amirror or <strong>in</strong> shared attention, there is no understand<strong>in</strong>gof communicative sign function. Thus thereis no b<strong>as</strong>is for <strong>in</strong>tentional communication on theb<strong>as</strong>is of shared representations. As we shall seehere and <strong>in</strong> the discussion of ape gestures <strong>in</strong>Section 6, it is the latter that appears to be mostdifficult for non-<strong>human</strong> primates. Below, webriefly describe how understand<strong>in</strong>g others’ emotions,attention and <strong>in</strong>tentions can be seen <strong>as</strong><strong>in</strong>timately related to dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>.Where<strong>as</strong> (simple) empathy is proto-mimetic,what Preston and de Waal (2002) call <strong>cognitive</strong>empathy requires a differentiation between subjectand object where <strong>“the</strong> subject is thought to useperspective-tak<strong>in</strong>g processes to imag<strong>in</strong>e or project<strong>in</strong>to the place of the object” (ibid: 18). Evidencethat this is not an isolated phenomenon,but shows a more advanced level of <strong>in</strong>tentionalityis the fact that <strong>cognitive</strong> empathy “appears toemerge developmentally and phylogeneticallywith other ‘markers of m<strong>in</strong>d’ … <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g perspectivetak<strong>in</strong>g …, mirror self-recognition …,deception, and tool-use.” (ibid: 18). Researchconcern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>cognitive</strong> empathy <strong>in</strong> apes h<strong>as</strong> focusedon their consolation behavior, which iswell attested <strong>in</strong> at le<strong>as</strong>t chimpanzees, but h<strong>as</strong> notbeen found <strong>in</strong> monkey species (de Waal andAureli 1996) or any other mammalian species.Consolation is <strong>cognitive</strong>ly more complex thansimple empathy s<strong>in</strong>ce the consol<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividualnot only feels that somebody else experiences anegative emotion, but also <strong>in</strong>tends to help relievethis, imply<strong>in</strong>g an ability to imag<strong>in</strong>e the morepositive emotional state. 3This supports the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that <strong>cognitive</strong>empathy <strong>in</strong>volves a more sophisticated representationalcapacity than what is necessary forsimple empathy. S<strong>in</strong>ce dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>in</strong>volvesboth the ability to identify with the other, and atthe same time to differentiate between self andother, our (Vygotskyan) hypothesis is that it isdyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, implicated <strong>in</strong> e.g. imitation (Section4) that scaffolds the development of suchrepresentational capacity.S<strong>in</strong>ce dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> allows to “place oneself<strong>in</strong> the shoes of others”, it also gives the oppor-3 An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g question is what goes on <strong>in</strong> them<strong>in</strong>d of an ape that is be<strong>in</strong>g consoled: If one couldidentify <strong>cognitive</strong> processes of the form “I can feelthat you feel that I feel bad”, this would be equivalentto “third order emotion”. However, given thelack of methodology for test<strong>in</strong>g the existence ofsuch a process, we feel compelled to apply Occam’srazor and <strong>as</strong>cribe only second order emotionsof the form “I feel that you feel”.


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 17tunity to understand what someone else is attend<strong>in</strong>gto. Such “second-order attention” is welltestified among great apes (Hare et al. 2000).When two <strong>in</strong>dividuals become aware that theother is attend<strong>in</strong>g to the same object, what resultsis shared attention. This comes a good dealtowards the construction of a “consensual reality”that can be communicated about, but doesnot quite reach it (cf. Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2004). To make agiven object X fully <strong>in</strong>tersubjective between youand me, I would need not only to “see that yousee X”, (second-order attention, see Figure 1a),but also “to see that you see that I see X” (thirdorderattention, see Figure 1b) and vice versa –which is our <strong>in</strong>terpretation of what it means toengage <strong>in</strong> jo<strong>in</strong>t attention.Figure 1a. Shared attention: Second-order attention: “Isee that you see X” (and vice versa)there is a close connection between communicative<strong>in</strong>tention and the emergence of jo<strong>in</strong>t attention.Concern<strong>in</strong>g the understand<strong>in</strong>g of another’s<strong>in</strong>tentions, it h<strong>as</strong> been for sometime a predom<strong>in</strong>antop<strong>in</strong>ion that apes cannot do this, and <strong>in</strong>deedthis w<strong>as</strong> one of the central claims ofTom<strong>as</strong>ello (1999). Recently, however, there h<strong>as</strong>been mount<strong>in</strong>g evidence that (at le<strong>as</strong>t)“[c]himpanzees understand psychological states– the question is which ones and to what extent”,which is the title of Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, Call andHare (2003). In the experiments beh<strong>in</strong>d thisclaim a subord<strong>in</strong>ate and a dom<strong>in</strong>ant chimpanzeecompeted for food placed on the subord<strong>in</strong>ate’sside of two barriers, so that <strong>in</strong> some c<strong>as</strong>es onlythe subord<strong>in</strong>ate, but not the dom<strong>in</strong>ant could seethe food. The subord<strong>in</strong>ates could also monitorthe visual access of their dom<strong>in</strong>ant competitor.The results showed that the subord<strong>in</strong>ates preferentiallyretrieved the food that dom<strong>in</strong>ants couldnot see, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that chimpanzees understandwhat con-specifics have and have not seen andeven have some awareness of the dom<strong>in</strong>ant’s goal(i.e. “a mental representation of a desired state”,Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. <strong>in</strong> press) of obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the food.This does not have to be done on the b<strong>as</strong>is ofexplicit re<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g or <strong>in</strong>ference, but possiblythrough the “projection” of one’s own motivationalstate <strong>in</strong> a similar situation onto the other(“I would get the food if I were <strong>in</strong> his place!”), <strong>in</strong>a dyadic mimetic f<strong>as</strong>hion. Apparently, even nonenculturatedand language-naïve apes are capableof this. 4However, it h<strong>as</strong> not been shown that (nonenculturated)apes are capable of understand<strong>in</strong>ganother’s mental states about their own mentalstates, which would <strong>in</strong>volve, aga<strong>in</strong>, third-ordermentality. 5 As suggested earlier, jo<strong>in</strong>t attentionFigure 1b. Jo<strong>in</strong>t attention: Third-order attention: “I seethat you see that I see X” (and vice versa)Full jo<strong>in</strong>t attention thus <strong>in</strong>volves third-ordermentality (cf. Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2003, 2004), and (possiblybecause of this, see below) appears to be beyondthe <strong>cognitive</strong> capacities of apes (Tom<strong>as</strong>ello1999). It also goes beyond dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, so wewill leave this capacity for the time be<strong>in</strong>g, butreturn to it <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g subsection, s<strong>in</strong>ce4 While it still not conclusively shown that apes arecapable of such mental “projection”, and it is conceivablehow the evidence can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> amore behavioristic manner <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g learn<strong>in</strong>g generalizationsover other <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ behavior <strong>in</strong>relation to food, we contend that the mental explanationis (a) ultimately more parsimonious and (b)consistent with other mental skills <strong>in</strong> apes, <strong>as</strong> well<strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> children <strong>in</strong> roughly comparable stagesof development.5 Note that when we <strong>in</strong> this section l<strong>in</strong>k triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>and third-order mentality, we do not implythat an agent capable of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> can handleall forms of third-order mentality, <strong>in</strong> particularthose which <strong>in</strong>volve beliefs.


18<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionalso requires third-order mentality, and is similarlysometh<strong>in</strong>g that apes seem to f<strong>in</strong>d difficult.In natural sett<strong>in</strong>gs, some c<strong>as</strong>es of deceptionmay be <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> a way to <strong>in</strong>volve thirdordermentality, but do not require this. Forexample de Waal (1998 [1982]) describes thechimpanzee Yeroen who h<strong>as</strong> had a fight withNikkie, and cont<strong>in</strong>ues to fake a limp only when<strong>in</strong> the presence of Nikkie, apparently <strong>in</strong> an act ofwish<strong>in</strong>g to provoke Nikkie’s empathy: “I wish tomake you see that I hurt”. The more parsimoniousexplanation, however, is that Yeroen h<strong>as</strong>learned from previous experience that he is notbothered by Nikkie when he is hurt: “He mayhave learned from <strong>in</strong>cidents <strong>in</strong> the p<strong>as</strong>t <strong>in</strong> whichhe is seriously wounded that his rival w<strong>as</strong> lesshard on him dur<strong>in</strong>g periods when he w<strong>as</strong> (ofnecessity) limp<strong>in</strong>g” (ibid: 35-36), so he mimes theappropriate behavior. Here we have a clear correspondencebetween dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> and second-order<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. Notice that Yeroen’slimp<strong>in</strong>g w<strong>as</strong> not a form of <strong>in</strong>tentional communication– he did not wish Nikkie to understandthat he w<strong>as</strong> fak<strong>in</strong>g a limp – if he did, that wouldbe a clear c<strong>as</strong>e of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>.Another possible <strong>in</strong>stance of third-ordermentality is that reported by Woodruff andPremack (1979) <strong>in</strong> which chimpanzees learned tosuppress glances and body orientation towardthe place where food w<strong>as</strong> hidden, when a tra<strong>in</strong>erwho would not share the food w<strong>as</strong> present.However, s<strong>in</strong>ce it took a long number of trialsfor the apes to learn this behavior, a simplerexplanation <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g condition<strong>in</strong>g is possible.The conclusion that we can draw from thesevarious examples is that wild apes <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong>those who are exposed to different degrees of<strong>human</strong> contact (captive, nursery-raised and laboratory-tra<strong>in</strong>edapes), but are not raised <strong>in</strong> a“someth<strong>in</strong>g like a <strong>human</strong> cultural environment”and thus enculturated (Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1996)can <strong>in</strong>deed understand second-order mentality.However, such apes do not seem able to understandthird-order mentality – neither <strong>in</strong> the doma<strong>in</strong>sof emotion, attention nor <strong>in</strong>tention – <strong>in</strong>which their own mental state needs to be either<strong>in</strong>tentionally communicated – <strong>in</strong> collaboration,or hidden – <strong>in</strong> competition. This correspondswell with the capacity of apes for dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>,but their relative difficulty with triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>,which we discuss further below.5.3 Triadic mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityIn the c<strong>as</strong>e of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, there is by def<strong>in</strong>itionnot just an understand<strong>in</strong>g of representationitself, but an understand<strong>in</strong>g that representationscan be used communicatively, or what we referto <strong>as</strong> communicative sign function. This implies anunderstand<strong>in</strong>g that the sign h<strong>as</strong> the same mean<strong>in</strong>gfor the addressee <strong>as</strong> for the sender. This <strong>in</strong>volves atle<strong>as</strong>t second-order mentality, which w<strong>as</strong> shownabove to correlate with dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>. But“hav<strong>in</strong>g the same mean<strong>in</strong>g” is a reflexive notionand this implies at le<strong>as</strong>t some degree of thirdordermentality. Consider the simple example ofwhat know<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the word cat implies:a) I know that cat means “a small furry animalthat meows”.b) I <strong>as</strong>sume you know that cat means “<strong>as</strong>mall furry animal that meows”.c) I <strong>as</strong>sume that you know that I know thatcat means “a small furry animal that meows”.While it is possible for <strong>in</strong>tentional communicationto beg<strong>in</strong> without a full realization of (c), itis practically <strong>in</strong>evitable that discursive experience(<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g failures <strong>in</strong> communication) will promotethe development of third-order mentality.Thus, it is possible that it w<strong>as</strong> sign use itself thatw<strong>as</strong> the major driv<strong>in</strong>g force beh<strong>in</strong>d the developmentof <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity <strong>in</strong> hom<strong>in</strong>id evolution.Unlike compet<strong>in</strong>g hypotheses related to“Machiavellian <strong>in</strong>telligence” (Byrne and Whiten1988), this puts the focus on cooperation ratherthan competition (see also Br<strong>in</strong>ck and Gärdenfors2003; Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. <strong>in</strong> press). A predictionfrom this hypothesis is that enculturatedapes – and these have all been taught at le<strong>as</strong>tsome communication through signs – will develophigher-level skills of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity.There is some support for this prediction. Insummariz<strong>in</strong>g some 200 studies of the role of<strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence, Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello (1996)conclude that “[t]he socio<strong>cognitive</strong> doma<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>which <strong>human</strong>s seem to have the highest effecton apes are <strong>in</strong>tentional communication and sociallearn<strong>in</strong>g” (ibid: 391).In Section 6, we will focus more specificallyon the understand<strong>in</strong>g and use of communicativegestures by apes. Here and <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g subsection,we will mostly review the evidence thatsign use <strong>in</strong> general, and the acquisition of (<strong>as</strong>pectsof) language <strong>in</strong> particular is the major fac-


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 19tor beh<strong>in</strong>d the development of higher forms of<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity that may deserve the label <strong>“the</strong>oryof m<strong>in</strong>d”.As po<strong>in</strong>ted out earlier, wild apes do not seemto be capable of engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> full, third orderjo<strong>in</strong>t attention. Furthermore, <strong>as</strong> Tom<strong>as</strong>ello(1999: 21) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, wild apes (1) do not po<strong>in</strong>tto objects; (2) do not hold up objects to showthem to others; (3) do not take someone along to aplace to show them someth<strong>in</strong>g; (4) do not activelyoffer someth<strong>in</strong>g to someone; and (5) do not<strong>in</strong>tentionally teach other <strong>in</strong>dividuals new behaviors.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello’s orig<strong>in</strong>al account of these absencesw<strong>as</strong> b<strong>as</strong>ed on the claim that apes are unableto understand other’s <strong>in</strong>tentions. Given themore recent evidence, this explanation is nolonger tenable, and <strong>in</strong>deed Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (<strong>in</strong>press), suggest <strong>in</strong>stead that the crucial differencebetween apes and <strong>human</strong>s <strong>in</strong>volves the motivationto participate <strong>in</strong> jo<strong>in</strong>t collaborative engagements,and the lack of this motivation preventsapes from construct<strong>in</strong>g “dialogical <strong>cognitive</strong>representations”.Our explanation is similar but more specific:we believe that non-enculturated apes fail todevelop the communicative sign function, andrelated to that, the ability to engage <strong>in</strong> third-ordermentality. The motivational difference betweenapes and <strong>human</strong>s appealed to by Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al.(<strong>in</strong> press) cannot be the full explanation s<strong>in</strong>ceenculturated apes such <strong>as</strong> Koko, Kanzi andChantek manage at le<strong>as</strong>t (1) and apparentlycommunicative skills (2-5) above <strong>as</strong> well (Miles1999), even if <strong>in</strong> restricted forms. This seems toimply that the <strong>human</strong> cultural environments 6 ofthe enculturated apes have taught them the b<strong>as</strong>icsof <strong>in</strong>tentional, sign-mediated communication,and thereby (the roots of) third-order mentality.How this could occur can be seen aga<strong>in</strong> withrespect to jo<strong>in</strong>t attention, which can be seen <strong>as</strong>emerg<strong>in</strong>g from second-order attention comb<strong>in</strong>edwith the recognition of another’s <strong>in</strong>tention concern<strong>in</strong>gmy attention: “I see that you see X”(second-order attention, Figure 1a), and furthermore“I realize that you want me to look atX”. In other words, jo<strong>in</strong>t attention can bebrought forth by understand<strong>in</strong>g a simple form ofcommunicative <strong>in</strong>tention, comb<strong>in</strong>ed with already6 Consist<strong>in</strong>g of what Wittgenste<strong>in</strong> (1953) called the“forms of life” that provide the necessary contextfor the emergence and function<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>tentionalcommunication and language.exist<strong>in</strong>g second-order attention (Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2003,2004). Thus, communicat<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>tention tojo<strong>in</strong>tly attend may be said to <strong>in</strong>volve the simplestk<strong>in</strong>d of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>: whatever k<strong>in</strong>d of behaviorthat is used to convey that <strong>in</strong>tention – someform of <strong>in</strong>dex (see the example <strong>in</strong> the next paragraph)– can be said to stand for that <strong>in</strong>tention forboth sender and <strong>in</strong>terpreter.Without enculturation, experiments <strong>in</strong>dicatethat apes do not understand communicative<strong>in</strong>tentions. A rather typical example is an experimentby Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, Call and Gluckman(1997), where the authors <strong>in</strong> different ways <strong>in</strong>dicatedfor both chimpanzees and two- to threeyear-oldchildren which out of three conta<strong>in</strong>ersconta<strong>in</strong>ed a reward: by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to the correctconta<strong>in</strong>er; by plac<strong>in</strong>g a marker on top of thecorrect conta<strong>in</strong>er; and hold<strong>in</strong>g up a replica of thecorrect conta<strong>in</strong>er. Tom<strong>as</strong>ello (1999: 102) summarizesthe results of the experiment <strong>as</strong> follows:Children already knew about po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, butthey did not know about us<strong>in</strong>g markers andreplic<strong>as</strong> <strong>as</strong> communicative signs. They neverthelessused these novel signs very effectivelyto f<strong>in</strong>d the reward. In contr<strong>as</strong>t, no ape w<strong>as</strong>able to do this for any of the communicative signsthat they did not know before the experiment.One explanation of these results is that theapes were not able to understand that the <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gshad <strong>in</strong>tentions toward their own attentional states.The apes thus treated the communicative attemptsof the <strong>human</strong> <strong>as</strong> discrim<strong>in</strong>ative cues onpar with all other types of discrim<strong>in</strong>ative cuesthat have to be laboriously learned over repeatedexperiences. The children, <strong>in</strong> contr<strong>as</strong>t,treated each communicative attempt <strong>as</strong> an expressionof the adult’s <strong>in</strong>tention to direct theirattention <strong>in</strong> ways relevant to the current situation.[our emph<strong>as</strong>is]In other words, while the children clearly understoodthe communicative <strong>in</strong>tentions of the experimenter,the apes did not. This <strong>in</strong>terpretationis supported by a similar experiment designed totest “false beliefs” (Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1999), <strong>in</strong>which the enculturated and language-taughtorangutan Chantek clearly performed differentlyfrom all the other apes <strong>in</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>human</strong>communicator’s signals. Even though thisw<strong>as</strong> not the goal of the experiment, and Chantekdid not score better than the other apes <strong>in</strong> thefalse beliefs t<strong>as</strong>k, his much better performancecould be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by consider<strong>in</strong>g that he understoodthe signals <strong>as</strong> communicative signs (<strong>in</strong> this


20<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionc<strong>as</strong>e <strong>in</strong>dexes), rather than <strong>as</strong> “discrim<strong>in</strong>ativecues”.F<strong>in</strong>ally, we should mention the c<strong>as</strong>e of captiveapes liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a zoo and thus <strong>in</strong>volved withat le<strong>as</strong>t some degree of <strong>in</strong>teraction with <strong>human</strong>culture. In their study of spontaneous gesturalcommunication <strong>in</strong> a group of gorill<strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> the SanFrancisco zoo, Tanner and Byrne (1996, 1999),found a wealth of gestures used by severalmembers of the group, <strong>in</strong> particular by the adultmale Kubie. We return to this is Section 6, but itsuffices here to note that the gestures seemed tobe used <strong>in</strong> a communicative way so that:[w]hether the receiv<strong>in</strong>g partner w<strong>as</strong> a <strong>human</strong>or another ape, the signal<strong>in</strong>g ape made surethat visual contact w<strong>as</strong> established (except fortactile close gestures), and seemed to understandboth the other’s potential actions and what thepartner might, <strong>in</strong> turn, understand from his (the signaler’s)performance of gestures. (Tanner and Byrne1999: 231, [our emph<strong>as</strong>is])We can conclude that a triadic from of mimetic<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g understand<strong>in</strong>g notonly con-specifics’ <strong>in</strong>tentions, but their communicative<strong>in</strong>tentions, and consequently a degree ofthird-order mentality, appears to be not completelybeyond the <strong>cognitive</strong> potential of apes. To realize thispotential, they need an environment that is rich<strong>in</strong> opportunities for develop<strong>in</strong>g the communicativesign function, i.e. a particular form of enculturation.Thus triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> may be said to bewith<strong>in</strong> apes’ “Zone of Proximal Development”(ZPD) – the notion <strong>in</strong>troduced by Vygotsky(1978) to refer to skills that children could acquirewith the help of adults, but not alone.If “enculturation” provides the ZPD for present-dayapes, it is re<strong>as</strong>onable to suppose that itdid the same for some particularly social groupof hom<strong>in</strong>ids through a form of “selfdomestication”giv<strong>in</strong>g rise to a bootstrapp<strong>in</strong>gspiral of sign use and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. In theterms of Donald (2001), triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> musthave been with<strong>in</strong> the common ancestor’s “zoneof proximal evolution”.5.4 Post-mimetic <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityWhat differentiates post-mimetic, or symbolic,cognition from <strong>mimesis</strong> is the use of fully conventionalsigns, <strong>in</strong>terrelated with<strong>in</strong> a system (Deacon1997; Zlatev 2003). The most obvious exampleof post-<strong>mimesis</strong>, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g all the previous featuresbut also symbolicity is a conventional, <strong>in</strong>stitutionalizedsigned language such <strong>as</strong> ASL (Stokoe1960) or Swedish Sign Language (Ahlgren2003). What is the relation between acquir<strong>in</strong>gsuch a system and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity?A convention (Lewis 1969; Clark 1996) or anorm (Itkonen 1978) exists <strong>as</strong> a form of mutual(or common) knowledge among the members of thegroup that share the convention. A commonexplication of mutual knowledge is that it consistsof third-order knowledge: “I know that youknow that I know X”. Translated to the capacityto understand the m<strong>in</strong>ds of others, commonknowledge amounts not only to my understand<strong>in</strong>gthe mentality of others, but also to my understand<strong>in</strong>gthat others (can) understand mymentality. This h<strong>as</strong> been expressed by Itkonen(1978: 96) <strong>as</strong> follows:[P]erson A cannot know that he is do<strong>in</strong>g orth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g X, and thus cannot do or th<strong>in</strong>k X,unless he is able to know what it is for someother person B to do and th<strong>in</strong>k X. The sameis true, <strong>in</strong> turn of B’s knowledge of his ownactions with respect to A’s (possible) actionsand thoughts. Hence it can be shown onpurely conceptual grounds that A must beable, <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, to identify B’s various mentalstates or processes, and vice versa. Thismeans that mental states and processes existonly at the level of common knowledge i.e. of acommon ability to identify them, whereverthey occur.Mutual knowledge is often stated <strong>as</strong> a form of“third-order belief”, but this is potentially mislead<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>in</strong>ce it is not necessary that the understand<strong>in</strong>gon all three orders of mentality is explicitenough to be a matter of “belief”, i.e. apropositional representation that is actively heldto be true. Consider aga<strong>in</strong> the three orders ofknow<strong>in</strong>g the conventional mean<strong>in</strong>g of cat mentionedearlier: I <strong>as</strong>sume that you know that Iknow that cat means “a small furry animal thatmeows”. The highest order, my <strong>as</strong>sumption thatyou know that I know, is not properly speak<strong>in</strong>g abelief for the 4 year old child, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is taken forgranted, without ponder<strong>in</strong>g on whether it is trueor not. At the same time, children at this agebecome (a) capable of understand<strong>in</strong>g that otherslack knowledge or have “false beliefs” (e.g.,Perner 1991; Wimmer et al. 1988; Gopnik andGraf 1988; Mitchell 1997), imply<strong>in</strong>g metarepresentationalcapacity, and (b) at le<strong>as</strong>t somewhat fluent<strong>in</strong> their first language. It appears that these twodevelopments are closely connected, and that


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 21acquir<strong>in</strong>g a language, spoken or signed, is a majorcausal factor for develop<strong>in</strong>g a fully-fledged<strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d”. Despite successes <strong>in</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>gother’s attention and even <strong>in</strong>tentions,apes, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g enculturated ones, have so farconsistently failed so-called “false belief tests”(Premack 1988; Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 1996, 1999;Pov<strong>in</strong>elli 2000). They have also failed <strong>in</strong> acquir<strong>in</strong>ga full <strong>human</strong> language – despite successes <strong>in</strong>acquir<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>as</strong>pects of it. Three differentsides to language (use) comb<strong>in</strong>e to promotemetarepresentational capacity.First, <strong>as</strong> mentioned above, language is a conventionalsymbolic system, and <strong>as</strong> such its m<strong>as</strong>teryimplies third-order knowledge, which wouldcarry with it tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the understand<strong>in</strong>g ofothers’ beliefs. Second, two specific (universal)features of <strong>human</strong> languages are (a) mentalpredicates such <strong>as</strong> “th<strong>in</strong>k”, “believe”, “know”…and (b) sentential complement constructionssuch <strong>as</strong> “say that…”. If one can mean<strong>in</strong>gfullyformulate sentences such <strong>as</strong> “I th<strong>in</strong>k that youth<strong>in</strong>k that X”, then one should be able to th<strong>in</strong>kthe correspond<strong>in</strong>g thought. Third, <strong>as</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ted outby Tom<strong>as</strong>ello (1999), not just the logical structureof language, but its use <strong>in</strong> discourse wouldpromote the understand<strong>in</strong>g of others <strong>as</strong> “mentalagents”: There are at le<strong>as</strong>t “three k<strong>in</strong>ds of discourse,each of which requires [children] to takethe perspective of another person <strong>in</strong> a way thatgoes beyond the perspective-tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong>comprehend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual l<strong>in</strong>guistic symbols andconstructions.” (ibid: 173): disagreements, repairs/explanationsand meta-discourse.Empirical evidence for the existence of <strong>as</strong>trong connection from language to the understand<strong>in</strong>gof beliefs h<strong>as</strong> been accumulat<strong>in</strong>g dur<strong>in</strong>grecent years and <strong>in</strong>volves e.g. the follow<strong>in</strong>g:• Deaf children who are not exposed to signlanguage at an early age p<strong>as</strong>s false belief t<strong>as</strong>kssignificantly later than those who are (Petersonand Siegal 1995);• There are correlations between parent use ofmental predicates <strong>in</strong> their child-directedspeech and the children’s performance <strong>in</strong>false belief t<strong>as</strong>ks (de Villiers and Pyers 1997);• Longitud<strong>in</strong>al studies <strong>in</strong>dicate that languagedevelopment predicts false belief t<strong>as</strong>k performance,but not vice versa (Ast<strong>in</strong>gton andJenk<strong>in</strong>s 1999);• Tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> (non-mental predicate) sententialcomplement constructions significantly improvesperformance on false belief t<strong>as</strong>ks(Hale and Tager-Flusberg 2003; Lohmannand Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 2003).• Tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> perspectival discourse alone(without sentential complements or mentalpredicates) contributes to performance onfalse belief t<strong>as</strong>ks (Lohmann and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello2003).Our conclusion is therefore that the understand<strong>in</strong>gof (false) beliefs is a form of post-mimetic<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, <strong>in</strong> the sense that is b<strong>as</strong>ed onlanguage, either spoken or signed. Notice thatthis does not contradict analyses by e.g. Bloom(2000) that the acquisition of language presupposes<strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” skills, s<strong>in</strong>ce we haveargued that the latter, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g jo<strong>in</strong>t attentionand communicative <strong>in</strong>tention are triadic mimeticphenomena, which also <strong>in</strong> our analysis are prerequisitesfor language.In one of the relevant studies, Call andTom<strong>as</strong>ello (1999) used a non-verbal false belieft<strong>as</strong>k with chimpanzees and orangutans <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong>with <strong>human</strong> children. The ma<strong>in</strong> results were thatthe children's performance on verbal and nonverbalfalse belief t<strong>as</strong>ks w<strong>as</strong> highly correlated,support<strong>in</strong>g the hypothesis of a possible causalconnection. At the same time, no ape could p<strong>as</strong>sthe nonverbal false belief t<strong>as</strong>k even though theysucceeded <strong>in</strong> all of the control trials <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>gm<strong>as</strong>tery of the general t<strong>as</strong>k demands. However,<strong>as</strong> mentioned <strong>in</strong> Section 5.3, <strong>in</strong> this latter experimentthe enculturated and language-taughtorangutan Chantek performed differently fromthe other apes, display<strong>in</strong>g a better understand<strong>in</strong>gof the experimenter’s signals <strong>as</strong> communicativesigns. A prediction from our analysis would bethat if Chantek, or any of the other “languageapes” that have been the subject of so muchcontroversy, could progress <strong>in</strong> their languagedevelopment to <strong>in</strong>volve more mental terms, <strong>as</strong>well <strong>as</strong> grammatical constructions <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gsentence complementation, they would also beable to p<strong>as</strong>s false belief t<strong>as</strong>ks.A counter-example to this Vygotskyan hypothesisof <strong>in</strong>terpersonal communication preced<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>trapersonal cognition would be to showthat non-enculturated apes are capable of understand<strong>in</strong>gbeliefs (or at le<strong>as</strong>t third-order mentality),even outside of communicative sett<strong>in</strong>gs. Acandidate doma<strong>in</strong> is aga<strong>in</strong> deception, but <strong>as</strong>mentioned <strong>in</strong> Section 5.2, the k<strong>in</strong>d of examples<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g deception, usually provided <strong>in</strong> supportfor theory-of-m<strong>in</strong>d skills (e.g. Yeroen’s fake


22<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionlimp) can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by simpler skills. A furthercandidate is counter-deception. In a study performedwith chimpanzees by Menzel (1973,1974), only the female Belle w<strong>as</strong> allowed to seewhere food w<strong>as</strong> hidden with<strong>in</strong> a large enclosedarea, and subsequently she led the group to thefood, and all were able to share it. When theexperiment w<strong>as</strong> repeated, however, the maleRock began to take all the food for himself.After this, Belle did not reveal where the foodw<strong>as</strong> hidden if Rock w<strong>as</strong> nearby. She sat furtherand further from the place where the food w<strong>as</strong>hidden, and it w<strong>as</strong> only when Rock w<strong>as</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> another direction that she went to the hid<strong>in</strong>gplace. Rock, however, countered this by pretend<strong>in</strong>gto go away and then turn<strong>in</strong>g just <strong>as</strong> Belle w<strong>as</strong>about to reveal where the food w<strong>as</strong>. Byrne(1995) <strong>in</strong>terprets this <strong>as</strong> imply<strong>in</strong>g that Rock h<strong>as</strong>an understand<strong>in</strong>g that Belle is try<strong>in</strong>g to deceivehim, i.e. third-order mentality. However,Tom<strong>as</strong>ello and Call (1997) note that the experimentwith all its steps l<strong>as</strong>ted several months soBelle and Rock may have successively learnedhow to predict the behavior of the other withoutunderstand<strong>in</strong>g deceptive <strong>in</strong>tentions. This hypothesisis supported by a later experiment withmangabey monkeys performed by Coussi-Korbel (1994), who replicated Menzel’s study,but performed a detailed day-to-day analysis.One of the <strong>in</strong>formed mangabeys, step by step <strong>in</strong>four days, learned the strategy of lead<strong>in</strong>g herma<strong>in</strong> competitor away from the food.5.5 SummaryIn this section we have tried to show that thereis a close connection between different levelsof <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and the different levels ofthe <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy, <strong>as</strong> summarized <strong>in</strong> Table4 below. Proto-<strong>mimesis</strong> is crucially implicated<strong>in</strong> mutual attention and the awareness of others’feel<strong>in</strong>gs, through a species-general capacityfor empathy that h<strong>as</strong> possibly been furtherdeveloped <strong>in</strong> the “ultra-social” species Homosapiens. Dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> leads to the ability tomap between one’s own body and that of others,<strong>in</strong> a more detached, differentiated way, and<strong>in</strong> this way understand others’ emotions, i.e.<strong>cognitive</strong> empathy, shared attention and even<strong>in</strong>tentions through a conscious process of “projection”:what would I see/feel/wish if I wereyou.Unlike earlier claims to the contrary, newer evidenceand analyses show that apes do not havemuch difficulties with this level and that theyhave the capacity for second-order mentality.Table 4. The <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy and <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityLevel Intersubjectivity skills Type of mentalityProto<strong>mimesis</strong>Dyadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Triadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Post<strong>mimesis</strong>(simple) empathymutual attentionCognitive empathyShared attentionUnderstand<strong>in</strong>gother’s <strong>in</strong>tention(<strong>in</strong> competitivecontexts)Jo<strong>in</strong>t attentionCommunicative<strong>in</strong>tentions(False) belief understand<strong>in</strong>g1 st order: lack ofcomplete differentiationbetween selfand other2 nd order: understand<strong>in</strong>gthe otherthrough “projection”(identification, butdifferentiation)3 rd order (attentionand <strong>in</strong>tentions)3 rd order (beliefs)The crucial step <strong>in</strong> the evolution of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity<strong>in</strong>volves triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, imply<strong>in</strong>g hav<strong>in</strong>gand understand<strong>in</strong>g others’ communicative<strong>in</strong>tentions, which requires third-order mentality:“I want you to do X (e.g. share attention on anobject) by recogniz<strong>in</strong>g my <strong>in</strong>tention that you dothis” from the sender’s perspective and “I understandthat you want me to do X” from therecipient’s.This is not someth<strong>in</strong>g that comes e<strong>as</strong>ily toapes <strong>in</strong> natural conditions, but through enculturationand especially through extensive signuse, some understand<strong>in</strong>g of communicative <strong>in</strong>tentionsseems to be with<strong>in</strong> the reach of apes’“Zone of Proximal Development”, even though<strong>in</strong> may be <strong>in</strong> its periphery. Evidence for this isthe relative m<strong>as</strong>tery of jo<strong>in</strong>t attention by enculturants,and <strong>as</strong> argued this can be seen to orig<strong>in</strong>ate<strong>in</strong> (dyadic mimetic) second-order attentioncomb<strong>in</strong>ed with the understand<strong>in</strong>g of the other’s<strong>in</strong>tention that I attend. F<strong>in</strong>ally, post-<strong>mimesis</strong>,with its features of conventionality and systematicitynecessarily br<strong>in</strong>gs with it sufficientunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of third-order mental states, and(at le<strong>as</strong>t) second-order beliefs, e.g. “I th<strong>in</strong>k thatyou know (or don’t)”. The latter have beenshown <strong>in</strong> numerous false belief t<strong>as</strong>ks, which areregularly failed by apes. On the other hand, there


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 23is mount<strong>in</strong>g evidence that the acquisition oflanguage, with its structural properties and discursiveuse significantly contributes to higherforms of <strong>“the</strong>ory of m<strong>in</strong>d” development.In summary, <strong>in</strong> this section we have arguedthat bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>, <strong>in</strong> its proto, dyadic andtriadic forms, is a major factor <strong>in</strong> the developmentof <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. Sign use itself w<strong>as</strong>suggested to be a driv<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>in</strong> the developmentof an understand<strong>in</strong>g of third-order mentality,and the performance of enculturants showsthat this achievement is with<strong>in</strong> the reach of apes.Therefore one can conclude that (mimetic) signuse w<strong>as</strong> possibly with<strong>in</strong> the “zone of proximalevolution” (Donald 2001) of the common ape<strong>human</strong>ancestor, considerably more so thanfully-fledged language, characterized by full conventionalityand systematicity.F<strong>in</strong>ally, while we have focused on the <strong>mimesis</strong>-to-<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivitydirection of causality, thisdoes not mean that there is no “feedback” l<strong>in</strong>kand thus we <strong>as</strong>sume a co-evolutionary scenario.It w<strong>as</strong> implicit <strong>in</strong> the discussion that achiev<strong>in</strong>gdifferent levels of <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity is necessaryfor mov<strong>in</strong>g to still higher levels on the <strong>mimesis</strong>hierarchy, e.g. jo<strong>in</strong>t attention for the acquisitionof language. It is also possible that <strong>in</strong> the presentanalysis we have overemph<strong>as</strong>ized the Vygotskyanpr<strong>in</strong>ciple of the “<strong>in</strong>terpsychologicalpreced<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>trapsychological” (see Section 1),but this h<strong>as</strong> come rather naturally by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g thedevelopmental levels or stages <strong>in</strong> terms of bodily<strong>mimesis</strong>, with its orig<strong>in</strong>ally <strong>in</strong>terpersonal character.6. Mimesis and gestureOf the three socio-<strong>cognitive</strong> doma<strong>in</strong>s we discuss<strong>in</strong> this article, gesture is the one most obviouslyrelated to bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>: at le<strong>as</strong>t some gesturesposses all the properties emph<strong>as</strong>ized by Donald(1991): reference, <strong>in</strong>tentionality, communicativity,autocu<strong>in</strong>g and generativity (see Section 3).However, not all bodily acts that are called “gestures”have these properties. Furthermore, <strong>in</strong> thecurrently highly active field of gesture studies (e.g.Kendon 1981; McNeil 1992; Gold<strong>in</strong>-Meadow1999; Kita and Özyürek 2003), study<strong>in</strong>g amongother th<strong>in</strong>gs the spontaneous co-speech gestur<strong>in</strong>gof <strong>human</strong> children and adults, it is oftenpo<strong>in</strong>ted out that gestures and language <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong> complex ways. Thus, not all gestures are e<strong>as</strong>ilysubsumed under the label “non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic” or“non-verbal”. In such a c<strong>as</strong>e, it becomes questionablewhether they are truly mimetic ratherthan post-mimetic.Perhaps <strong>in</strong> the most general sense gesture h<strong>as</strong>been def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>as</strong> “a functional unit, an equivalencecl<strong>as</strong>s of coord<strong>in</strong>ated movements thatachieve some end” (Armstrong, Stokoe andWilcox 1995: 46; Wilcox 2004: 44), which encomp<strong>as</strong>sescommunicative <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> noncommunicativebody movements <strong>as</strong> long <strong>as</strong> theyposses the property of goal-directedness. This ismuch too general for our purposes and we willconsider <strong>as</strong> gestures only goal-directed communicativebody movements, i.e. such that require <strong>in</strong>terpretation froman audience for achiev<strong>in</strong>g the gesturer’s goal. This <strong>in</strong>cludesa variety of acts such <strong>as</strong> attention gett<strong>in</strong>g,po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g and mim<strong>in</strong>g. At the same time, ourdef<strong>in</strong>ition excludes bodily signals such <strong>as</strong> laughter,which is not goal-directed, or acts thatachieve their ends through “mechanical causality”rather than <strong>in</strong>terpretation, e.g. pull<strong>in</strong>g someone,<strong>as</strong> opposed to beckon<strong>in</strong>g him. Notice thatwhile we focus on communication, we do notrequire all gestures to be <strong>in</strong>tentionally communicative:what is essential is that the bodily motion is<strong>in</strong>terpreted by an observer <strong>as</strong> reveal<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>gabout the state of m<strong>in</strong>d of the gesturer.There are numerous cl<strong>as</strong>sifications of gestures(see Kendon 1981 for a well-known taxonomy),but none, to our knowledge, that h<strong>as</strong> explicitlytaken an evolutionary perspective – apartfrom the analysis of the orig<strong>in</strong>s of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (e.g.Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2001). Our goal <strong>in</strong> this section is to applythe <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy to gesture, and <strong>in</strong> show<strong>in</strong>ghow different types of gestures correspond tothe different stages of the <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy,suggest such an evolutionary taxonomy. We willalso show how the four stages of the hierarchycross-cut with two b<strong>as</strong>ic semiotic dist<strong>in</strong>ctions:<strong>in</strong>dexicality and iconicity, which differ with respectto the semiotic ground (Peirce 1931-1935; Sonesson1989) for the relationship between the “signvehicle” (the expression) and the mean<strong>in</strong>g of thegesture:• Indexical gestures, where the ground is oneof spatio-temporal contiguity, the prototypicalc<strong>as</strong>e be<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.• Iconic gestures, where the ground is ofsimilarity, with the prototype pantomime.Figure 2 illustrates the two types schematically:what is essential for <strong>in</strong>dexical gestures, <strong>as</strong> with all


24<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolution<strong>in</strong>dexical signs, is that expression and contentare closely related <strong>in</strong> time-space. An iconic gesture(sign), on the other hand, requires similarity(often of a quite schematic type) but on theother hand it can be removed <strong>in</strong> time-space fromtheir mean<strong>in</strong>gs.Figure 2. Indexical signs, b<strong>as</strong>ed on contiguity vs. iconicsigns, b<strong>as</strong>ed on similarity. In both c<strong>as</strong>e expression andcontent need to be differentiated and perceived <strong>as</strong>stand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a representational relationship by an <strong>in</strong>terpreterfor there to be a (genu<strong>in</strong>e) sign. Withoutthis, there are only <strong>in</strong>dexicalities and iconicities.In agreement with Sonesson (1989, <strong>in</strong> press), wedist<strong>in</strong>guish between iconicity and <strong>in</strong>dexicality <strong>as</strong>a type of semiotic ground, and the sign function(Piaget 1945). The latter presupposes an <strong>in</strong>terpreter(signified by the “happy face” <strong>in</strong> Figure 2)who differentiates between the expression andthe content and is furthermore aware of therepresentational relationship between them:Only <strong>in</strong> this c<strong>as</strong>e do we have iconic and <strong>in</strong>dexicalsigns. In the c<strong>as</strong>e of gestures, this means that onlyif the gestur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual is aware of the expression-contentstructure of his gesture are thegestures <strong>in</strong>tentionally used <strong>as</strong> signs. If not, thegestures are only a matter of <strong>in</strong>dexicality or iconicityfor the gesturer; however, they may still beseen <strong>as</strong> signs by an <strong>in</strong>terpreter, <strong>as</strong> is the c<strong>as</strong>e withthe first types of gestures discussed below.6.1 Proto-mimetic gesturesWe have def<strong>in</strong>ed proto-<strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g across-modal mapp<strong>in</strong>g between exteroperceptionand proprioception, but lack<strong>in</strong>g (clear) differentiationand or/volition. From this perspectivethe spontaneous reach<strong>in</strong>g behavior of the childobserved soon after birth (von Hofsten 1983)and various forms of phylogenetic ritualizationmay be cl<strong>as</strong>sed <strong>as</strong> proto-mimetic (for the gesturer),<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dexicality and iconicity, respectively,but not the sign function.6.1.1 Proto-mimetic <strong>in</strong>dexicality: reach<strong>in</strong>gIn the first 6 months of life, the <strong>human</strong> childcoord<strong>in</strong>ates its hand movements and reachestowards <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g objects, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g those thatit desires but cannot gr<strong>as</strong>p because they are toofar away. At the same time there is no gaze alternationbetween the object and a third party, andno attempt to get the other’s attention – andpossibly help – <strong>in</strong> obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the object. Clearlythis is not a communicative gesture from thepo<strong>in</strong>t of view of the child. However, at le<strong>as</strong>t <strong>in</strong>typical Western caregiver-child <strong>in</strong>teractions atthis period of development, the adult often <strong>in</strong>terpretssuch reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>as</strong> communicative andoffers the desired object. This appears to havean effect on the child’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation of its ownaction through a process of <strong>in</strong>ternalization of the<strong>in</strong>terpersonal to <strong>in</strong>trapersonal (Vygotsky 1978,see Section 1). Eventually, this transforms reach<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>to (proto-) imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, which, <strong>as</strong>discussed below, is a dyadic mimetic gesture.Ape <strong>in</strong>fants reach out to objects that attracttheir attention similarly to <strong>human</strong> children, butless so to distal objects due to the fact that theybecome capable of locomotion much sooner.Furthermore, ape mothers are less “<strong>in</strong>terventionist”and less likely to oblige their <strong>in</strong>fants, evenwhen the latter do reach out to distal objects(Bard and Vauclair 1984). In general they <strong>in</strong>terfereonly when they deem that there is a risk oftheir offspr<strong>in</strong>g gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> harm’s way. Such differencesmay be the major re<strong>as</strong>on why feral apespo<strong>in</strong>t much less (if at all) than <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs,s<strong>in</strong>ce they are quite capable of acquir<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>ggestures when <strong>in</strong> contact with <strong>human</strong>s (see below).6.1.2 Proto-mimetic iconicity: phylogenetic ritualizationPhylogenetic ritualization is often proposed <strong>as</strong>the b<strong>as</strong>ic mechanism for the emergence of animalsignals, <strong>as</strong> expla<strong>in</strong>ed by e.g. Knight (2002:147):Over evolutionary time, certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>as</strong>pects ofnon-communicative behaviour <strong>as</strong>sume a signall<strong>in</strong>gfunction, becom<strong>in</strong>g correspond<strong>in</strong>glyspecialized through a process known <strong>as</strong> ‘ritualization’.Signal evolution beg<strong>in</strong>s when othersread some <strong>as</strong>pect of normal behaviour <strong>as</strong> significant.If the subject of such surveillance canbenefit from hav<strong>in</strong>g its m<strong>in</strong>d read or its behaviouranticipated, then over evolutionary


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 25time natural selection will accentuate the cues,reduc<strong>in</strong>g any ambiguity. By def<strong>in</strong>ition, suchphylogenetic ritualization entails special elaborationand added costs.Gestures such <strong>as</strong> gorilla chest beat<strong>in</strong>g (and otherforms of display) and the “submissive gesture”of apes, <strong>in</strong> which they crouch and “make themselvessmall” <strong>in</strong>volve iconicities (resemblances) tobody size – the larger the animal is, the louderthe signal – and state of agitation – the strongerthe emotion, the more beat<strong>in</strong>g. At the sametime, they are not iconic signs, s<strong>in</strong>ce the similaritybetween the signal and the non-communicativebehavior is not perceived (at le<strong>as</strong>t not necessarily)by either the gesturer or the <strong>in</strong>terpreter.Hence, while there is communication, there is norepresentation (<strong>in</strong> the sense of expressioncontentstructure, see Ikegami and Zlatev <strong>in</strong>press) <strong>in</strong>volved. That is why we can call suchphylogenetically ritualized signals proto-mimeticgestures.It is characteristic that when observed <strong>in</strong>highly enculturated apes such <strong>as</strong> the signed languagetaught gorilla Koko, gestures such <strong>as</strong>“gimme” and “pound” were the first to develop,with the le<strong>as</strong>t effort on the part of the tra<strong>in</strong>er. Aspo<strong>in</strong>ted out by Patterson (1980: 517):These were dist<strong>in</strong>ctive because they appearedwithout direct tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g at a time when thegreat majority of Koko’s signs were be<strong>in</strong>g acquiredby mold<strong>in</strong>g. Because other young gorill<strong>as</strong>reared <strong>in</strong> captive conditions who have notbeen exposed to sign language use these samegestures, they must be part of the gorilla’snatural repertoire.6.2 Dyadic mimetic gesturesIn the c<strong>as</strong>e of dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong> there is representation<strong>in</strong> the sense that there is both differentiationand correspondence between the gesture and its“mean<strong>in</strong>g”, <strong>in</strong> this c<strong>as</strong>e the action that the gesturerwishes that the addressee will perform. Inthis respect, such gestures constitute signs, <strong>in</strong> thesense of the term def<strong>in</strong>ed at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g ofthis section. However, they have two major limitations:(a) their <strong>in</strong>tended mean<strong>in</strong>g is always adesired action rather than a statement, i.e. theyare imperative rather than declarative, and (b)they <strong>in</strong>volve second-order mentality: a claim onthe attention and behavior of the addressee, butnot third-order mentality: there is no appeal onthe addressee to understand the gesturer’s ownmentality. In our term<strong>in</strong>ology, they do not <strong>in</strong>volvethe communicative sign function, unlikethe triadic gestures that we discuss <strong>in</strong> 6.3.6.2.1 Dyadic-mimetic <strong>in</strong>dexicality: imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gIn the <strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>fant literature “reach<strong>in</strong>g” is oftenused <strong>as</strong> a label for acts of <strong>in</strong>tentional communication,rather than to attempts at pretension.Similarly to Leavens and Hopk<strong>in</strong>s (1999),<strong>in</strong> their <strong>in</strong>formative review of studies of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> children and apes, we f<strong>in</strong>d that even if thechild does not shape the hand and arm <strong>in</strong> a “canonicalpo<strong>in</strong>t” (Butterworth 1998), given thatthere is evidence for gaze alternation between anobject and a third party, the act should be regarded<strong>as</strong> an <strong>in</strong>stance of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. In <strong>human</strong>children, such acts emerge spontaneously from 8months of age, and at le<strong>as</strong>t at first have an “imperative”function of attempt<strong>in</strong>g to make the addresseeperform some desired action. From this it followsthat imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g requires secondordermentality, but not necessarily jo<strong>in</strong>t attentionand third-order mentality (see Section 5.2,Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2003). Hence, imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g can becl<strong>as</strong>sified <strong>as</strong> a dyadic mimetic gesture. This conclusionis also supported by Tom<strong>as</strong>ello’s (1999)observation that <strong>in</strong> this stage of development,children can m<strong>as</strong>ter <strong>in</strong>tentional po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g withoutunderstand<strong>in</strong>g the po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g of others. Anotherk<strong>in</strong>d of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g that is perhaps even more obviouslydyadic mimetic that is also observed at thisstage is “po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g for oneself”, i.e. when thechild is us<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g gestures to direct its ownattention, rather than that of others (Bates,Camaioni and Volterra 1975).When it comes to apes, it w<strong>as</strong> earlier thoughtthat apes do not po<strong>in</strong>t (Donald 1991) or at le<strong>as</strong>tnot with the <strong>in</strong>dex f<strong>in</strong>ger (Pov<strong>in</strong>elli and Davis1994). This h<strong>as</strong> been recently shown to be untrue.Leavens and Hopk<strong>in</strong>s (1999) summarizesome of the evidence show<strong>in</strong>g that po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>as</strong>been reported for 15 captive monkeys, 83 captiveapes, and even one wild ape, a bonobo whow<strong>as</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g at a group of <strong>human</strong>s while look<strong>in</strong>gback and forth between the <strong>human</strong>s and theother bonobos (Veà and Sabater-Pi 1998). 77 If it w<strong>as</strong> not for the somewhat anecdotal characterof this piece of evidence, it would pose a problemfor our cl<strong>as</strong>sification, s<strong>in</strong>ce it appears to <strong>in</strong>volvedeclarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, which is otherwise observedonly <strong>in</strong> enculturated apes.


26<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionWhether or not feral apes really po<strong>in</strong>t, the evidencefrom captive apes (e.g. Call and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello1994; Leavens, Hopk<strong>in</strong>s and Bard 1996, Krauseand Fouts 1997; Leavens and Hopk<strong>in</strong>s 1999)clearly shows that the criteria for imperativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g are satisfied: attention gett<strong>in</strong>g, gazealternation and persistence until the goal is met.Leavens and Hopk<strong>in</strong>s calls these audience effects,and observe that captive chimpanzees engaged<strong>in</strong> imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g exhibit more audienceeffects, and above all more gaze alternation thanchildren at the correspond<strong>in</strong>g stage of development.At the same time, the children were considerablymore prone to vocalize while po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g,show<strong>in</strong>g the close <strong>as</strong>sociation between bodily<strong>mimesis</strong> and speech <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs.However, if we limit our attention to themanual gestures alone we can conclude that atle<strong>as</strong>t when exposed to <strong>human</strong> contact, apesclearly display imperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, requir<strong>in</strong>gdyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>. Similarly, there is evidence thatat le<strong>as</strong>t enculturated apes engage <strong>in</strong> dyadic, noncommunicativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g objectsfor the purpose of direct<strong>in</strong>g their own attention(Bonvillian and Patterson 1999). Interest<strong>in</strong>glysuch non-communicative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g emergedearlier than communicative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (of both theimperative and the declarative type) <strong>in</strong> the signlanguage taught gorilla Koko, similar to the c<strong>as</strong>ewith children (Bates, Camaioni and Volterra1975).6.2.2. Dyadic mimetic iconicity: ontogenetic ritualizationAs po<strong>in</strong>ted out <strong>in</strong> 6.1, most animal signals arethe result of phylogenetic ritualization, and are <strong>in</strong>this sense <strong>in</strong>nate. But monkeys and especiallygreat apes use a good number of learned gestures<strong>as</strong> well. Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (1994) dist<strong>in</strong>guishedsix functional categories of gestures <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>fant and juvenile chimpanzees <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g nurs<strong>in</strong>g,walk-rid<strong>in</strong>g, groom<strong>in</strong>g, eat<strong>in</strong>g, appe<strong>as</strong><strong>in</strong>g andplay/tickle. These were believed to have comeabout through a process called ontogenetic ritualization<strong>in</strong> which the gestures were shaped by respond<strong>in</strong>gto each other’s anticipations. Thishappens over the life of the <strong>in</strong>dividual ratherthan the species, hence the term given to thislearn<strong>in</strong>g process. Tom<strong>as</strong>ello and Zuberbühler(2002: 295) describe ontogenetic ritualization <strong>as</strong>a sequence of 4 steps:(1) Individual A performs behavior X.(2) Individual B reacts consistently with behaviorY.(3) Subsequently B anticipates A’s performance ofX, on the b<strong>as</strong>is of its <strong>in</strong>itial step by perform<strong>in</strong>g Y.(4) Subsequently A anticipates B’s anticipationand produces the <strong>in</strong>itial step <strong>in</strong> a ritualized form(wait<strong>in</strong>g for a response) <strong>in</strong> order to ellicit Y. [orig<strong>in</strong>alemph<strong>as</strong>is]This way of describ<strong>in</strong>g the emergence of suchgestures sounds rather behaviorist, imply<strong>in</strong>g thatit is only a matter of (co-)re<strong>in</strong>forcement of behavioralpatterns. However, Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al.(1994) showed that most chimpanzee gestures<strong>in</strong>volve gett<strong>in</strong>g the other’s attention and that thegestures vary with the attentional state of therecipient: non-tactile, non-vocal gestures arepredom<strong>in</strong>antly used when there is visual contactbetween the recipient and the gesturer. Furthermore,the animals clearly waited for a responseafter gestur<strong>in</strong>g. The presence of such “audienceeffects” <strong>in</strong>dicates that there w<strong>as</strong> an <strong>in</strong>tention onthe side of the gestur<strong>in</strong>g chimpanzee to producean effect on the addressee. However, this <strong>in</strong>tentionto communicate is not the same <strong>as</strong> a communicative<strong>in</strong>tention, which is an <strong>in</strong>tention that thedesired effect will be produced by the addresseerecogniz<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>tention to produce the effect(Grice 1957; Sperber and Wilson 1995). As argued<strong>in</strong> the Section 5, such forms of third-ordermentality appear to be beyond the capacity ofnon-enculturated apes.At the same time, to the extent that the gestur<strong>in</strong>gape is differentiat<strong>in</strong>g between its (ontogenticallyritualized) gesture and the desiredeffect and be<strong>in</strong>g more or less aware of the correspondencerelation between them, it is justifiedto regard the two <strong>as</strong> stand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a representationalrelationship – even without <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g acommunicative sign function. However, thisrepresentational relationship is fairly unstable.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (1994) showed that chimpanzeeshad a limited arsenal of gestures that theyapplied highly “flexibly”: different gestures wereused for the same goal, and the same gesture w<strong>as</strong>often used with different “mean<strong>in</strong>gs”. On theone hand, this speaks for these gestures be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tentional and different from species-specific


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 27signals. But on the other hand, it testifies to theirbe<strong>in</strong>g non-conventional, and non-systematic.Similar f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs have been replicated foryoung gorill<strong>as</strong> (Pika, Liebal and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 2003)and bonobos (Pika, Liebal and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello 2005).However, <strong>in</strong> these more recent (and systematic)studies, a number of gestures where found to begroup-specific, and therefore “some form ofsocial learn<strong>in</strong>g” (Pika et al. 2003: 108), besidesontogenetic ritualization w<strong>as</strong> considered to bethe mechanism beh<strong>in</strong>d their emergence. Furthermore,while Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (1994) did notobserve any social transmission of a specificbegg<strong>in</strong>g gesture learned by a chimpanzee toacquire rewards from <strong>human</strong> experimenters,Pika et al. (2005) summarize a number of differentstudies f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g evidence for the social learn<strong>in</strong>gof gestures <strong>in</strong> great apes. It is therefore notpossible to exclude some degree of imitation <strong>in</strong>apes’ learn<strong>in</strong>g of gestures. Even so, that does notimply that such gestures, e.g. the “arm shake” ofthe gorill<strong>as</strong> of Apenheul zoo (Pika et al. 2003)are more than dyadic mimetic, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is notclear that they <strong>in</strong>volve the communicative signfunction: e.g. represent someth<strong>in</strong>g for someone.Some dyadic mimetic gestures may also <strong>in</strong>volveiconicity (similarity) between the spatiotemporalprofile of the gesture and the mean<strong>in</strong>gof the gesture: the action to be performed by theaddressee. An example would be to gently rubdown someone’s back <strong>in</strong> the desired direction ofmovement <strong>in</strong>stead of forcefully push<strong>in</strong>g theother down. A purely visual version would be tomake the gesture <strong>in</strong> the air <strong>in</strong> view of the recipient.Such gestures are usually labeled iconic (Tannerand Byrne 1996, 1999) and we will followthis practice. However, we still need to <strong>as</strong>kwhether they function <strong>as</strong> iconic signs for both thesender and the receiver, i.e. the iconicity isgr<strong>as</strong>ped <strong>as</strong> the ground for the representationalrelationship. What characterizes dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>,<strong>as</strong> we stated above, is that this relationship is (a)unstable and (b) non-symmetrical: it is possiblethat only one of the communication parts perceivesthe iconicity <strong>as</strong> an iconic sign.In a study of captive bonobos by Savage-Rumbaugh et al. (1977) almost all gestures thatpreceded copulation appeared to be signs ofcopulatory positions. S<strong>in</strong>ce bonobos use manydifferent copulatory positions it is expected thatsome mutual agreement must be reached aboutwhich position to be used. Two animals couldsometimes “argue”, <strong>in</strong> the sense that one gesturedfor a ventro-ventral position while theother gestured for a dorso-ventral one. The likelihoodof unusual copulation postures <strong>in</strong>cre<strong>as</strong>edif the bout w<strong>as</strong> preceded by gestur<strong>in</strong>g. Thesegestures were grouped <strong>in</strong>to three groups: (1)position<strong>in</strong>g motions: the recipient’s limbs aremanipulated by the <strong>in</strong>itiator. The actual movementis done by the recipient but the direction isset by the <strong>in</strong>itiator; (2) touch plus iconic handmotions: a touch on the part of the body thatshould be moved, followed by an <strong>in</strong>dication withthe hand how this part should move; (3) iconichand motions: without touch<strong>in</strong>g the other <strong>in</strong>dividualthe gesturer shows what he wants theother to do; these are the most abstract ones.It is possible to <strong>in</strong>terpret this progression <strong>as</strong>the development of an understand<strong>in</strong>g of iconicityand an emergence of iconic signs (Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 1977), but it should be notedthat the gestures from the first group were themost frequent <strong>in</strong> the bonobo group, and gesturesfrom the most abstract level, the thirdgroup, w<strong>as</strong> the le<strong>as</strong>t frequent. In other studies ofbonobos (de Waal 1988; Pika et al. 2005) andgorill<strong>as</strong> (Pika et al. 2003) no gestures could bereadily <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>as</strong> iconic <strong>in</strong> nature. So even ifthe evidence seems to grant apes some understand<strong>in</strong>gof iconic signs, predom<strong>in</strong>antly emerg<strong>in</strong>gthrough ontogenetic ritualization, this understand<strong>in</strong>gdoes not seem to be reflective enoughto be systematically used <strong>in</strong> communication.6.3 Triadic mimetic gesturesAs po<strong>in</strong>ted out repeatedly above, what is lack<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> dyadic mimetic gestures is an understand<strong>in</strong>gof the communicative sign function, which impliesthat the gesturer not only wishes the addresseeto perform some desired action, but todo this by appreciat<strong>in</strong>g the representational(sign) relation between his gesture and its referentialmean<strong>in</strong>g. As we show <strong>in</strong> this section apescan achieve such an understand<strong>in</strong>g, but clearlyonly when they have been taught <strong>as</strong>pects of aconventional symbolic system, i.e. a language.This raises some doubts whether such gesturesare not actually post-mimetic.6.3.1 Triadic mimetic <strong>in</strong>dexicality: declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gThe third stage <strong>in</strong> the development of <strong>human</strong>children’s po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, m<strong>as</strong>tered around 14 months,


28<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionis usually called declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (Bates,Camaioni and Volterra 1975; Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2003). Thecrucial difference with respect to imperativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is that the child need not desire theobject po<strong>in</strong>ted, but rather the act of achiev<strong>in</strong>gjo<strong>in</strong>t attention with the addressee on the objectis the goal <strong>in</strong> itself. As argued <strong>in</strong> Section 5.3,jo<strong>in</strong>t attention <strong>in</strong>volves understand<strong>in</strong>g a simpleform of communicative <strong>in</strong>tention, and is thustriadic mimetic. In this sense declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gis also triadic mimetic.Br<strong>in</strong>ck (2003) proposes that at an early stageof a child’s use, an additional purpose of declarativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is the evaluation of the <strong>in</strong>dicatedobject, achieved by an exchange of emotional<strong>in</strong>formation about it. For example, the childpo<strong>in</strong>ts to an object <strong>in</strong> order to obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationfrom the addressee whether the object isdangerous. The ma<strong>in</strong> benefit for the child of thisk<strong>in</strong>d of exchange is that he/she can learn aboutobjects vicariously. This primary function presupposesthat the child can understand the emotionsof the addressee, and <strong>as</strong> we argued <strong>in</strong> Sections5.1 and 5.2, this is well with<strong>in</strong> thecompetence of the child at this stage of development,and similarly for apes. Thus, it is possiblethat the evaluative side of declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gw<strong>as</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al cause of its proliferationamong the hom<strong>in</strong>ids (Br<strong>in</strong>ck 2001).Enculturation h<strong>as</strong> been shown to have dramaticeffects on the po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g of apes. While feralapes almost never po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>as</strong> mentioned earlier,captive apes and monkeys readily learn to engage<strong>in</strong> imperative, though not declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g.On the other hand, at le<strong>as</strong>t three of the documentedlanguage-taught apes – Koko, Chantekand Kanzi – consistently po<strong>in</strong>t declaratively, i.e.refer to objects and locations for sake of call<strong>in</strong>gthese to the attention of someone else (Patterson1980; Miles 1990). In the mentioned review ofpo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> children and apes, Leavensand Hopk<strong>in</strong>s (1999), po<strong>in</strong>t out that languagetra<strong>in</strong>edapes were more likely to use a canonicalpo<strong>in</strong>t with the <strong>in</strong>dex f<strong>in</strong>ger than children of theage 13-18 months. In some studies, it is evensuggested that language-taught apes comb<strong>in</strong>esuch an act of declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g and anothersign to make a predication, i.e. THIS is X(Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh 1990).However, the question arises if such acts arec<strong>as</strong>es of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, rather than postmimeticskill. The close relation between declarativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g and reference makes it likelythat the process of be<strong>in</strong>g taught language itself iswhat h<strong>as</strong> simultaneously taught the significanceof declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to the apes. The follow<strong>in</strong>gepisode recorded by Savage-Rumbaugh andLev<strong>in</strong> (1994), <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g not the famous, highlyenculturated bonobo Kanzi, but the somewhatmore traditionally tra<strong>in</strong>ed Aust<strong>in</strong> and Sherman,shows how enculturation, and specifically theteach<strong>in</strong>g of communicative sign function, canaffect po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g:Upon spy<strong>in</strong>g the new food, Sherman reachedout for it and I suggested that he should <strong>as</strong>kfor it. He quickly turned, scrut<strong>in</strong>ized the keyboard,and deliberately, but with no fanfare,<strong>in</strong>dicated one of the un<strong>as</strong>signed lexigrams <strong>as</strong>the symbol for the food. Aust<strong>in</strong> watched attentivelyand subsequently used the symbolSherman had selected to <strong>in</strong>dicate that hewould like to try the new food also. This unexpectedskill encouraged us to believe thatSherman and Aust<strong>in</strong> understood that a uniquecorrespondence existed between each fooditem and a specific symbol. Moreover, theysometimes po<strong>in</strong>ted back and forth betweenthe symbol and the food item. They hadnamed new foods and apparently agreed oncoord<strong>in</strong>ated use of the selected symbols. (ibid:79)We will return to this issue <strong>in</strong> the summary below.6.3.2 Triadic-mimetic iconicity: communicative <strong>in</strong>tention?Possibly the clearest evidence for iconic triadicmimetic gestures <strong>in</strong> non-language-tra<strong>in</strong>ed apescomes from a study of zoo-liv<strong>in</strong>g gorill<strong>as</strong>, partiallyreared by <strong>human</strong> caregivers. Tanner andByrne (1996, 1999) studied a pair of westernlowland gorill<strong>as</strong>, Kubie and Zura, at the SanFrancisco Zoo, who seemed to have an unusuallyrich repertoire of gestures: audible, silent andtactile ones. The gestures were used almost exclusively<strong>in</strong> play sessions and sexual situations,and the choice of gesture differed accord<strong>in</strong>g tothe attentional state of Zura, with audible andtactile ones used when she w<strong>as</strong> not look<strong>in</strong>g,which mirrors the f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs for chimpanzees byTom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (1994).Some of Kubie’s gestures were “attentiongetters” and play <strong>in</strong>vitations. His most successfulgesture w<strong>as</strong> an armsw<strong>in</strong>g under his belly towardshis genitals. It had the highest frequency of accompany<strong>in</strong>g“play faces” and result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> physi-


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 29cal contact. It w<strong>as</strong> only performed when thegorill<strong>as</strong> had visual contact. “Armsw<strong>in</strong>g under”w<strong>as</strong> often preceded by a tap on Zura’s body.This is comparable with Savage-Rumbaugh etal.’s (1977) second group of iconic gestures:touch plus iconic hand motions. If Zura failed torespond, a gesture w<strong>as</strong> often repeated, strengthenedor more gestures were made – this alsoresembl<strong>in</strong>g the pattern found <strong>in</strong> chimpanzees(Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. 1994). Most of the gesturesended <strong>in</strong> contact between Kubie and Zurawith<strong>in</strong> 5 seconds, with Zura mak<strong>in</strong>g most of thecontact, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that she w<strong>as</strong> (correctly) <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>gKubie’s gestures. In 66% of the c<strong>as</strong>eswhen a tactile gesture w<strong>as</strong> made Zura moved herbody <strong>in</strong> the direction <strong>in</strong>dicated by Kubie. If agesture w<strong>as</strong> coupled with a “play face” the likelihoodof physical contact w<strong>as</strong> significantly higherthan for gesture alone. However, “head nod”,Kubie’s most frequent gesture, had a high degreeof play bouts without us<strong>in</strong>g “play faces”, whichshows that Zura did respond to gestures and notjust to the natural (pre-mimetic) gorilla signals.Still, the question rema<strong>in</strong>s if Zura really respondedto their (<strong>in</strong>tended) mean<strong>in</strong>g, comprehend<strong>in</strong>gthe gestures <strong>as</strong> iconic signs. Associat<strong>in</strong>gplayfulness (or sexual agend<strong>as</strong>) with particularbehaviors <strong>in</strong> another <strong>in</strong>dividual’s repertoire isnot sufficient to show that Zura understoodKubie’s gestures <strong>as</strong> communicative signs.Whether or not Kubie’s gestures had an iconicrelationship to their referents for him, they could<strong>in</strong> each c<strong>as</strong>e rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dexical to Zura, i.e. bebehavioral correlates to moods. The iconicity ofsome of Kubie’s gestures could very well havebeen abstractions from more physical manipulationsshaped through ontogenetic ritualizations(Tom<strong>as</strong>ello and Call 1997) and Zura’s appropriateresponse be derived from the context.However, over time Kubie used his gestureswith several females, and if he did not gothrough an identical abstraction ph<strong>as</strong>e with all ofthem, which of course cannot be ruled out completely,how could the receiver understand them?Tanner and Byrne (1996) suggest that comprehensionof motion depicted <strong>in</strong> gesture may bebiologically encoded for the great apes s<strong>in</strong>cetheir adaptation to brachiation requires a threedimensionalunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of space, and space isthe medium for gestures. 88 Brachiation also entails an ability that is unique toapes: that of be<strong>in</strong>g able to move the wrist, elbowIn summary, like the bonobo sexual gesturesdescribed <strong>in</strong> 6.2.2, the San Francisco gorilla gesturescould be argued to be at le<strong>as</strong>t dyadicmimetic,s<strong>in</strong>ce they correspond to actions <strong>in</strong>tendedto be performed by the recipient. Butthrough their iconicity the gestures also have apotential to be triadic-mimetic, under the conditionthat at le<strong>as</strong>t the recipient, and possibly alsothe sender understood their sign function. Triadic<strong>mimesis</strong> cannot be excluded <strong>as</strong> an alternativeto ontogenetic ritualization <strong>in</strong> the formationand use of such gestures because nonconventionalgestures could be understood notonly through the context but through the iconicityof the gestures themselves. If, and it is a big“if”, Kubie, Zura and the other females coulduse the iconic gestures effectively because ofsuch referential understand<strong>in</strong>g, Kubie’s gestureswould be an example of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>. Moreempirical research is necessary to decide thisissue.A f<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>t should be made <strong>in</strong> relation tothe differences observed between feral and enculturatedapes po<strong>in</strong>ted out earlier. The fact thatZura, the other female gorill<strong>as</strong> and Kubie all atsome po<strong>in</strong>t had been reared by <strong>human</strong>s (Tannerand Byrne 1996) might have implications for theconclusion we can draw about mimetic capacities<strong>in</strong> non-enculturated apes. Human be<strong>in</strong>gsengage readily <strong>in</strong> triadic forms of communicationand apes with extensive exposure to <strong>human</strong>language show good comprehension of otherrepresentational mediums, like words and pictures(Savage-Rumbaugh, Shanker and Taylor1998). However, it is not yet known how muchexposure to <strong>human</strong> culture is needed to yield anunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> (if at all) <strong>in</strong>hand-reared zoo animals, and if this would bereta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>to adulthood.While the presence of iconic signs <strong>in</strong> captiveapes rema<strong>in</strong>s unsure, there is solid evidence fortheir use <strong>in</strong> enculturated apes. The sign-languagetaught gorilla Koko reportedly <strong>in</strong>vented a numberof such signs herself, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g signs referr<strong>in</strong>gto actions e.g. “blow”, “tickle”, “walk-myback”,“bite”, <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> objects: “bird”, “bracelet”,“stethoscope”. These gestures clearly <strong>in</strong>volve areferential triangle <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the gesture, referentand the <strong>in</strong>terpreter, and were sometimes evenused <strong>in</strong> the absence of the referent, show<strong>in</strong>g oneof the crucial features of language: displacementand shoulder jo<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> all directions, mak<strong>in</strong>g subtlegestures possible.


30<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolution(Hockett 1960), and even “metaphorically”, e.g.us<strong>in</strong>g “bird” <strong>as</strong> an <strong>in</strong>sult.A problem for cl<strong>as</strong>sify<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>as</strong> triadicmimetic, however, is that these gestures werequite similar to the actual signed language signsthat she w<strong>as</strong> taught. In accordance with the caveatstated earlier, it is difficult to exclude the<strong>in</strong>terpretation that they are actually postmimetic,i.e. <strong>in</strong>duced by the language-teach<strong>in</strong>gsituation itself.Some support for their mimetic-iconic natureis offered by the fact that Koko produced manyso-called gestural modulations with respect to size,manner, number, etc. – all hav<strong>in</strong>g an iconic b<strong>as</strong>is.For example, the signs for a “small bird” anda “big bird” would differ <strong>in</strong> size; those for “severalbirds” would <strong>in</strong>volve repetition of the sign.Thus, gestural modulations are perhaps theclearest evidence of the presence of triadic <strong>mimesis</strong><strong>in</strong> Koko’s productions, especially s<strong>in</strong>cePatterson (1980: 539) emph<strong>as</strong>izes that they“were created by Koko herself”. Other testimonyfor the spontaneous production of triadicmimetic gestures <strong>in</strong> a language-tra<strong>in</strong>ed ape canbe found <strong>in</strong> the spontaneous gestures of thebonobo Kanzi, who unlike Koko w<strong>as</strong> not taughtsigned language but a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of visuallexigrams (<strong>in</strong> production) and spoken English (<strong>in</strong>comprehension). Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh (1990, 1991) report on Kanzi’s spontaneoususe of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g (see below), and at le<strong>as</strong>tsome gestures <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g iconicity such <strong>as</strong>“come”, “go” and “ch<strong>as</strong>e”.6.4 Post-mimetic gesturesMimesis w<strong>as</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ed by Donald (1991) to be“non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic”, and <strong>in</strong> Section 3 and <strong>in</strong> ourdef<strong>in</strong>ition of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> we clarified what wetake this to mean: lack of full conventionality(mutual knowledge) of the signs and systematicity,<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g at le<strong>as</strong>t a degree of compositionality.To the extent that the gestures of apes displaythese properties, they can be regarded <strong>as</strong>post-mimetic.Evidence from four of the most successfulprojects <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the teach<strong>in</strong>g of language togreat apes – the chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes)W<strong>as</strong>hoe (Fouts 1972, 1973), the gorill<strong>as</strong> Kokoand Michael (Patterson 1978, 1980) and thebonobos (Pan paniscus) Kanzi and Panbanisha(Savage-Rumbaugh and Lew<strong>in</strong> 1994; Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 1998) and the orangutan Chantek(Miles 1990) – h<strong>as</strong> shown that many of theessential characteristics of language are with<strong>in</strong>the gr<strong>as</strong>p of our nearest non-<strong>human</strong> relatives. Asis the c<strong>as</strong>e with children a precondition for thesuccess of these projects h<strong>as</strong> been a culturalenvironment rich with <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and avariety of activities to stimulate communication(Miles 1990). Our conclusion is similar to that ofMiles (1999: 204), namely that all great apes“have the <strong>in</strong>telligence for a rudimentary, referential,generalizable, imitative, displaceable, symbolsystem”.The re<strong>as</strong>on that this claim h<strong>as</strong> been controversial(e.g. Terrace et al. 1981) is not foremostempirical, but rather a matter of a disagreementon what the “essential characteristics” of <strong>human</strong>language are. Turn<strong>in</strong>g to the data reported <strong>in</strong> the“ape language” literature we see conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g evidencethat apes can:• comprehend the referential (representational)function of spoken words, ASL signs andvisual lexigrams, and comb<strong>in</strong>ations of these;• use the sign-tokens <strong>in</strong> the absence of theirreferents, i.e. “displacement” (Hockett 1960);• acquire a considerable vocabulary ofwords/signs, accord<strong>in</strong>g to some me<strong>as</strong>urementsextend<strong>in</strong>g 600 signs, but even accord<strong>in</strong>gto the most conservative criteria no lessthan 140 signs;• regard the acquired signs <strong>as</strong> conventionalnormative(consensual), to the po<strong>in</strong>t of correct<strong>in</strong>gtheir teachers if the latter do not usethese appropriately;• understand novel comb<strong>in</strong>ations of spoken orsigned words;• produce novel comb<strong>in</strong>ations of signs;• use language for a number of different functions(speech acts), <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g label<strong>in</strong>g, answer<strong>in</strong>g,express<strong>in</strong>g emotion, argu<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>sult<strong>in</strong>g;• use language not only for communication,but for th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g (private speech).What h<strong>as</strong> not yet been clearly demonstrated iswhether the spoken or signed utterances of apesconform to consistent pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of grammaticalorganization, though e.g. Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh (1990, 1991) describe at le<strong>as</strong>t twofairly consistent order<strong>in</strong>g rules <strong>in</strong> the two symbolcomb<strong>in</strong>ations of Kanzi, one of them <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g apo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g gesture (see below).It is thus unsurpris<strong>in</strong>g that those who have(over-)emph<strong>as</strong>ized syntax <strong>as</strong> opposed to seman-


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 31tics <strong>as</strong> the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic of language(e.g. Bickerton 1990; P<strong>in</strong>ker 1994; Hauser,Chomsky and Fitch 2002) cont<strong>in</strong>ue to deny <strong>“the</strong>proposition that language is no longer the exclusivedoma<strong>in</strong> of man” (Patterson 1978: 95). Buteven if the language of apes such <strong>as</strong> Koko andKanzi is termed “proto-language” rather thantrue language, it is still qualitatively differentfrom <strong>mimesis</strong>, s<strong>in</strong>ce it possesses at le<strong>as</strong>t rudimentsof conventionality and systematicity. Inthis sense, some, though not all, of the gesturesof the language-taught apes can be regarded <strong>as</strong>post-mimetic.6.4.1 Post-mimetic <strong>in</strong>dexicality: paral<strong>in</strong>guistic po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gAt le<strong>as</strong>t two forms of the po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g of languagetra<strong>in</strong>ed apes seem to go beyond <strong>mimesis</strong>, s<strong>in</strong>cethe po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g gesture is <strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong> the (proto-)l<strong>in</strong>guistic system acquired. First of all are thecomb<strong>in</strong>ations of a po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g gesture referr<strong>in</strong>g toan object or an <strong>in</strong>dividual with another sign express<strong>in</strong>ga predicate apply<strong>in</strong>g to the <strong>in</strong>dividual,thus form<strong>in</strong>g a predication. Furthermore, thebonobo Kanzi h<strong>as</strong> been reported to form such“predications” – with imperative <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> declarativefunctions – <strong>in</strong> a fairly systematic manner(Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh 1990,1991).A related form post-mimetic <strong>in</strong>dexicality<strong>in</strong>volves label<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> which the po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g gesturedirected at an object, or a picture of one <strong>in</strong> abook, is accompanied with the production of(gestural) sign denot<strong>in</strong>g the object. Such clearlydeclarative uses of po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g + label, some ofwhich are performed “privately”, i.e. not for thebenefit of a <strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>terlocutor (Bodamer et al.1994) are perhaps the most conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g c<strong>as</strong>e forthe presence of post-mimetic, paral<strong>in</strong>guisticpo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> enculturated apes. Kanzi h<strong>as</strong> beenshown to use po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g + lexigram, <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong>lexigram + po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g comb<strong>in</strong>ations for the sakeof label<strong>in</strong>g quite frequently: altogether therewere 249 examples <strong>in</strong> his five-month corpus oftwo-element comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>in</strong> which Kanzi <strong>in</strong>dicatedan entity gesturally and named it with alexigram (Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh1991).6.4.2 Post-mimetic iconic gestures: Signed languageHuman signed languages offer the clearest pictureof post-<strong>mimesis</strong>. Recent studies of thespontaneous emergence of Nicaraguan SignLanguage (NSL) dur<strong>in</strong>g the p<strong>as</strong>t 25 years showthat signed languages have their orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> (triadic)<strong>mimesis</strong>, but quickly acquire the propertiesof conventionality and systematicity. Sengh<strong>as</strong>,Kita and Özyürek (2004) compared the cospeechgestures of Nicaraguan speakers of Spanish,with the sign<strong>in</strong>g of three “cohorts”, or generations,of learners of NSL and could documentsome <strong>as</strong>pects of this transition <strong>in</strong> detail:The movements of the hands and body <strong>in</strong> thesign language are clearly derived from a gesturalsource. Nonetheless, the analyses reveal aqualitative difference between gestur<strong>in</strong>g andsign<strong>in</strong>g. In gesture, manner and path were <strong>in</strong>tegratedby express<strong>in</strong>g them simultaneouslyand holistically, the way they occur <strong>in</strong> the motion[event] itself. Despite this analogue, holisticnature of the gestur<strong>in</strong>g that surroundedthem, the first cohort of children, who startedbuild<strong>in</strong>g NSL <strong>in</strong> the late 1970s, evidently <strong>in</strong>troducedthe possibility of dissect<strong>in</strong>g outmanner and path and <strong>as</strong>sembl<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>in</strong>to <strong>as</strong>equence of elemental units. As second andthird cohorts learned the language <strong>in</strong> the mid1980s and 1990s, they rapidly made this segmented,sequenced construction the preferredmeans of express<strong>in</strong>g motion events. NSL thusquickly acquired the discrete, comb<strong>in</strong>atorialnature that is hallmark of language.Given their mimetic-gestural orig<strong>in</strong> signed languageshave a much greater degree of iconicitythan spoken languages and it h<strong>as</strong> been proposedthat this plays a role <strong>in</strong> their f<strong>as</strong>ter acquisition by(deaf) children (Brown 1977). Recent studieshave questioned this, however, s<strong>in</strong>ce only a m<strong>in</strong>orityof the signs of signed language havetransparent iconic mean<strong>in</strong>gs, and <strong>in</strong> a study of 22children acquir<strong>in</strong>g ASL it w<strong>as</strong> shown that “of the44 different signs produced by the children beforethe age of 13 months, 36% were cl<strong>as</strong>sified<strong>as</strong> iconic, 30% <strong>as</strong> metonymic, and 34% <strong>as</strong> arbitrary”(Bonvillian and Patterson 1999: 253). 9 In9 “Metonymic” signs are such that <strong>in</strong>volve somedegree of iconicity between the sign and the referent,but ”the tie between the sign and its mean<strong>in</strong>g isnot readily apparent – one would be unlikely toguess the mean<strong>in</strong>g of a metonymic sign simplysee<strong>in</strong>g it produced” (Bonvillian and Patterson 1999:252). In the dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong>troduced by Sonesson


32<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionthis study, the authors compared the rate andpattern of acquisition of ASL by children andthat of two gorill<strong>as</strong>, Koko and Michael. Despitecerta<strong>in</strong> differences – the children’s acquisitionw<strong>as</strong> (unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly) f<strong>as</strong>ter – it w<strong>as</strong> shown “thatthe similarities <strong>in</strong> early development across thespecies outweigh the differences” (ibid: 260).Thus, it can be concluded that gorill<strong>as</strong>, and by<strong>in</strong>ference other great apes, not only can acquirethe b<strong>as</strong>ics of a post-mimetic symbolic systemsuch <strong>as</strong> ASL, but that they do this is a similarway. Interest<strong>in</strong>gly, however, the gorill<strong>as</strong> seemedto rely somewhat more on the iconicity of thesigns <strong>in</strong> comparison with the children, so thatthe proportion of their first 46 signs w<strong>as</strong> somewhatdifferent to the one reported above: 42%iconic, 32% metonymic and 26% arbitrary, whilefor the first 10 signs this difference w<strong>as</strong> evenclearer: 60% iconic, 20% metonymic and 20%arbitrary. We <strong>in</strong>terpret this <strong>as</strong> suggest<strong>in</strong>g that theapes relied to a greater degree on their skills oftriadic <strong>mimesis</strong> than the children <strong>in</strong> their acquisitionof the sign language, which also would expla<strong>in</strong>why the children quickly progressed beyondthe <strong>in</strong>itial level of vocabulary acquisition tolearn the systematic character, i.e. the grammar,of the language, while the apes “stagnated” on <strong>as</strong>imple, “proto-language” level.6.5 SummaryIn this section we have reviewed some of theevidence on the production, and to some extentthe comprehension of gestures by great apes,and when relevant compared it to the acquisitionof gestures and sign languages by children. Apply<strong>in</strong>gthe <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy to this evidence h<strong>as</strong>resulted <strong>in</strong> the cl<strong>as</strong>sification summarized <strong>in</strong> Table5.Some of the natural signals of apes can beregarded <strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dexicality and iconicity,without these be<strong>in</strong>g perceived <strong>as</strong> signs by eitherthe sender or the receiver. On the other hand, ifan observer and, especially, a caregiver dur<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>fancy does see these <strong>as</strong> signs, this can providean impetus for mak<strong>in</strong>g these gestures mimetic, <strong>as</strong>seems to be the c<strong>as</strong>e with the orig<strong>in</strong> of imperativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. At le<strong>as</strong>t some ontogenetically ritualizedgestures appear to <strong>in</strong>volve differentiationand correlation between the gesture and mean-(2001) they <strong>in</strong>volve secondary (rather than primary)iconicity, which can be perceived first after know<strong>in</strong>gthe specific sign relationship.<strong>in</strong>g, and thus can be regarded <strong>as</strong> simple iconicsigns. S<strong>in</strong>ce these, however, can function withouthav<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g communicative <strong>in</strong>tentions,they are (at most) at the level of dyadic<strong>mimesis</strong>. Feral and even captive apes have notbeen conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>gly shown to progress beyondthis level.Table 5. The <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy and ape gesturesLevel Indexical gestures Iconic gesturesProto<strong>mimesis</strong>Dyadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Triadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Some ontogeneticallyritualized gesturesPost<strong>mimesis</strong>Reach<strong>in</strong>gPo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g foroneselfImperativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gDeclarativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gParal<strong>in</strong>guisticpo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gSome phylogenticallyritualized signalsIconic signs(Aspects of) signedlanguageEnculturation, and especially languageteach<strong>in</strong>gchanges this and consequently bothdeclarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g and iconic gestures emerge,testified <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals such <strong>as</strong> the gorilla Koko,the bonobo Kanzi and the orangutan Chantek.We <strong>in</strong>terpret this <strong>as</strong> evidence for triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>,though with some hesitation, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is likelythat be<strong>in</strong>g taught language w<strong>as</strong> necessary for theapes to acquire the communicative sign function.Even so, triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> can be shown to bewith<strong>in</strong> the gr<strong>as</strong>p of our nearest non-<strong>human</strong> relatives.In comparison, their skills <strong>in</strong> post-<strong>mimesis</strong><strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g full conventionality and systematicity,i.e. language, are more limited. The conclusion,similar to that at the end of Section 5, is thattriadic <strong>mimesis</strong> is with<strong>in</strong> the “zone or proximalevolution” of great apes, and by <strong>in</strong>ference, toour common ancestor.7. Summary and conclusionsThe goal of this study h<strong>as</strong> been to explore thepotentials of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> to provide perhapsnot <strong>“the</strong>” <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong>evolution, but at le<strong>as</strong>t one important <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong>piece <strong>in</strong> the puzzle, and thus help unravel themystery of the orig<strong>in</strong>s of language. In Section 3we def<strong>in</strong>ed the concept of bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> andthe related <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy, thereby ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g andmodify<strong>in</strong>g the concept of <strong>mimesis</strong> proposed by


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 33Donald (1991). Our method h<strong>as</strong> been to applythe <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy to evidence from primatology(and to some extent child development)<strong>in</strong> order to be able to compare ape skills <strong>in</strong> threedifferent doma<strong>in</strong>s: imitation, <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivityand gesture and to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether any generalpatterns could be discerned. Table 6 belowsummarizes our results.Beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g with proto-<strong>mimesis</strong>, we could seethat there is abundant evidence from all threedoma<strong>in</strong>s that apes excel <strong>in</strong> this. There do notappear to be any (major) cross-species differenceswith <strong>human</strong>s <strong>in</strong> this respect, and we can<strong>as</strong>sume with some confidence that the commonape-<strong>human</strong> ancestor had comparable skills <strong>in</strong>imitation, <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and communicativegestures.On the next level, that of dyadic <strong>mimesis</strong>, webeg<strong>in</strong> to discern some differences – both betweenthe levels, and between <strong>human</strong>s and apes.There is clear evidence for e.g. <strong>cognitive</strong> empathyand ontogenetically ritualized gestures <strong>in</strong>apes – and we suggested how these phenomenacan be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a dyadic-mimetic f<strong>as</strong>hion<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g both identification with and differentiationfrom the other. However, when it comesto imitation, apes appear to have difficulties <strong>in</strong>perform<strong>in</strong>g detailed imitation on the action level,which is the type of imitation where bodily <strong>mimesis</strong>is most relevant. Human children <strong>in</strong> comparisonexcel <strong>in</strong> this and even “overmimic”. Thisdifference between the species does not appearto be due to a difference <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity, i.e.understand<strong>in</strong>g of others’ <strong>in</strong>tentions, <strong>as</strong> w<strong>as</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>ally suggested by Tom<strong>as</strong>ello (1999) butrather <strong>in</strong> mimetic capacity per se. Thus, our resultsconfirm, at le<strong>as</strong>t <strong>in</strong> part, Donald’s proposalthat (bodily) <strong>mimesis</strong> constitutes the phenomenon<strong>in</strong> relation to which we should look for<strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> specificity. At the same time,the results reviewed <strong>in</strong> Section 4 showed clearlythat apes have the b<strong>as</strong>ic capacity for dyadic miF<strong>in</strong>ally, the capacity of apes for post-<strong>mimesis</strong>, rely<strong>in</strong>gon the possession of a conventional symbolicsystem, is furthest away from the potentialof <strong>human</strong> be<strong>in</strong>gs. While enculturated apes such<strong>as</strong> Kanzi may have m<strong>as</strong>tered a proto-languageafter a good deal of exposure and effort, thisrema<strong>in</strong>s limited <strong>in</strong> grammatical and semanticcomplexity, approximately to the level of a twoyearold child. Thus, even post-<strong>mimesis</strong> is notcompletely beyond the ZPD of apes, though it isfurther <strong>in</strong> the periphery than triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>.Us<strong>in</strong>g the analogy suggested by Donald (2001),we can say that both triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> and post<strong>mimesis</strong>are with<strong>in</strong> apes’ “zone of proximal evolution”,i.e the sphere <strong>in</strong> which evolutionaryadaptations are likely to occur, but s<strong>in</strong>ce post<strong>mimesis</strong>presupposes triadic <strong>mimesis</strong> (even conceptually),the latter constitutes the most likely<strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> l<strong>in</strong>k.Table 6. Compar<strong>in</strong>g ape skills <strong>in</strong> the doma<strong>in</strong>s of imitation, <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity and communicative gestures along thelevels of the <strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy: each level mentions example capacities, with “+” <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g positive evidence and “–” negative evidence. W = wild, C = captive, E = enculturated.Dyadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Triadic<strong>mimesis</strong>Level Imitation Intersubjectivity Communicative gestureProto<strong>mimesis</strong>Neonatal mirror<strong>in</strong>gC +Mutual attentionEmpathyC +Phylogenetically ritualized gesturesW/C +Post<strong>mimesis</strong>Action level imitationC + (?)Imitative signsW –C –E + (?)Role-reversal imitation–Shared attentionCognitive empathyC +Jo<strong>in</strong>t attentionW –C –E +Belief understand<strong>in</strong>g–Ontogentically ritualized gesturesImperative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gC +Declarative po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gW –C + (?)E +Proto-languageE +


Jordan Zlatev, Tom<strong>as</strong> Persson and Peter Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Studies, 121, (2005).What k<strong>in</strong>d of factors brought this about <strong>in</strong>evolution?The evidence summarized and analyzed <strong>in</strong>this article allows us to make two high-levelgeneralizations concern<strong>in</strong>g the three doma<strong>in</strong>s ofbodily <strong>mimesis</strong> analyzed:(1) Ape skills of imitation are <strong>in</strong> comparisonwith other skills le<strong>as</strong>t developed along the<strong>mimesis</strong> hierarchy;(2) Ape skills of gesture are <strong>in</strong> comparison withother skills most developed along the <strong>mimesis</strong>hierarchy.Furthermore, we could discern a possible causalrelationship <strong>in</strong> the direction from gesture (signuse) toward <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity: the only apes whosucceed <strong>in</strong> t<strong>as</strong>ks of jo<strong>in</strong>t attention, where thosewho where taught to use sign system throughenculturation. (In the c<strong>as</strong>e of imitation the relationis more of a logical sort: s<strong>in</strong>ce triadic imitationis def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>as</strong> the imitation of signs, it is impossibleto perform this without hav<strong>in</strong>g firstlearned the latter.) Thus we can conclude bysuggest<strong>in</strong>g the follow<strong>in</strong>g two (partially <strong>in</strong>dependent)hypotheses of <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolution,correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the two generalizations givenabove:(1´) The crucial adaptation that differentiatedearly hom<strong>in</strong>ids from apes <strong>in</strong>volved detailedbodily imitation, allow<strong>in</strong>g for the developmentof specific mimetic schem<strong>as</strong> which are prel<strong>in</strong>guisticrepresentational, <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivestructures, emerg<strong>in</strong>g through imitation butsubsequently <strong>in</strong>teriorized (see Piaget 1945;Zlatev 2005a; Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors<strong>in</strong> press).(2´) S<strong>in</strong>ce apes display some potential for spontaneouslydevelop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dexical and iconicgestures – e.g. <strong>in</strong> the rather unusual environmentof the San Francisco Zoo, see Tanner(2004) – it is re<strong>as</strong>onable to <strong>as</strong>sume that thecommon ape-<strong>human</strong> ancestor possessed sucha potential <strong>as</strong> well. An “ecological niche” requir<strong>in</strong>ga high degree of <strong>in</strong>tentional communication(there are various scenarios forbr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g this about; for a proposal regard<strong>in</strong>gthe role of Oldowan material culture (Osvathand Gärdenfors 2005) would have spurredthe use of iconic and <strong>in</strong>dexical gestures,which on their part would have both utilizedand further developed mimetic schematicrepresentations.In sum, our general proposal is that thesource of <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> specificity lies aboveall <strong>in</strong> two, mutually co-enforc<strong>in</strong>g factors <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gbodily <strong>mimesis</strong>: (a) the capacity to form mimeticschem<strong>as</strong>: representations deriv<strong>in</strong>g from theimitation of public events and (b) the use ofmimetic schem<strong>as</strong> for <strong>in</strong>tentional communication:triadic <strong>mimesis</strong>. The first of these factors is predom<strong>in</strong>antlyrepresentational and the second,communicative, and it is likely that <strong>in</strong> evolutionthe two have co-evolved. We submit that thisproposal is consistent with the evidence <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gthe capacities and limitations of apes, andshows the explanatory potential of the conceptof bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> “a <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> ourtheory of <strong>cognitive</strong> and l<strong>in</strong>guistic evolution.ReferencesAhlgren, I. (2003) Teckenspråk. In: Sveriges officiellam<strong>in</strong>oritetsspråk. F<strong>in</strong>ska, meänkieli, samiska, romani,jiddisch och teckenspråk. En kort presentation.Nordstedt.Anisfeld, M. (1996) Only tongue protrusion model<strong>in</strong>gis matched by neonates. Developmental Review, 16:149-161.Arbib, M. (2003) The evolv<strong>in</strong>g mirror system: Aneural b<strong>as</strong>is for language read<strong>in</strong>ess. In: LanguageEvolution, ed. M. Christiansen and S. Kirby, OxfordUniversity Press.- (<strong>in</strong> press) From monkey-like action recognition to<strong>human</strong> language: An evolutionary framework forneurol<strong>in</strong>guistics. Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences.Armstrong, D., Stokoe, W., and Wilcox, S. (1995)Gesture, and the Nature of Language. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Ast<strong>in</strong>gton, J. W. and Jenk<strong>in</strong>s, J.M. (1999) A longitud<strong>in</strong>alstudy of the relation between language andtheory-of-m<strong>in</strong>d development. Developmental Psychology,35/5: 1311-1320.Badcock, C. (2000) Evolutionary Psychology. A CriticalIntroduction. Cambridge: Polity Press.Bard K. A., Myowa-Yamakoshi, M., Tomonaga, M.,Tanaka, M., Costall, A. and Matsuzawa, T. (<strong>in</strong>press) Group differences <strong>in</strong> the mutual gaze ofchimpanzees. Developmental Psychology Vol. 41,2005.Bard, K. A. and Vauclair, J. (1984) The communicativecontext of object manipulation <strong>in</strong> ape and<strong>human</strong> adult-<strong>in</strong>fant pairs. Journal of Human Evolution,13: 181-90.Baron-Cohen, S. (1995) M<strong>in</strong>dbl<strong>in</strong>dedness: An Essay onAutism and Theory of M<strong>in</strong>d. Cambridge, MA: MITPress.Bates, E., Camaioni, L. and Volterra, V. (1975) Performativesprior to speech. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly,21: 205-226.Lund University Cognitive Studies - LUCS 121 ISSN 1101 – 8453 © 2005 by the authors


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 35Ber<strong>in</strong>g, J. M., Bjorklund, D. F. and Ragan, P. (2000)Deferred imitation of object-related actions <strong>in</strong><strong>human</strong>-reared juvenile chimpanzees and orangutans.Developmental Psychobiology, 36: 218-32.Bickerton, D. (1990) Language and Species. Chicago:University of Chicago Press.- (2003) Symbol and structure: A comprehensivestructure for language evolution. In: Christiansenand Kirby (2003), 77-93.Bjorklund D. F., Ber<strong>in</strong>g, J. M. and Ragan, P. (2000) Atwo-year longitud<strong>in</strong>al study of deferred imitationof object manipulation <strong>in</strong> a juvenile chimpanzee(Pan troglodytes) and orangutan (Pongo pygmaeus).Developmental Psychobiology, 37: 229-37.Bjorklund, D. F. and Ber<strong>in</strong>g, J. M. (2003) A note onthe development of deferred imitation <strong>in</strong> enculturatedjuvenile chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). DevelopmentalReview, 23: 389-412.Bjorklund, D. F., Yunger, J. L., Be<strong>in</strong>g, J. M. and Ragan,P. (2002) The generalization of deferred imitation<strong>in</strong> enculturated chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes).Animal Cognition, 5: 49-58.Bloom, P. (2000) How Children Learn the Mean<strong>in</strong>g ofWords. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Bodamer, M. D., Fouts, R. S., Fouts, D. H., andJensvold, K. B. (1994) Indicat<strong>in</strong>g acts dur<strong>in</strong>gcount<strong>in</strong>g by a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). Journalof Comparative Psychology, 109: 47-51.Boesch, C. (2003) Is culture a golden barrier between<strong>human</strong> and chimpanzee? Evolutionary Anthropology,12: 82-91.Boesch, C. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (1998) Chimpanzeeand <strong>human</strong> cultures. Current Anthropology, 39/5:591-614.Bonvillan, J. D. and Patterson, F. G. (1993) Early signlanguage acquisition <strong>in</strong> children and gorill<strong>as</strong>: Vocabularycontent and sign iconicity. First Language,13: 315-38.- (1999) Early sign-language acquisition: Comparisonbetween children and gorill<strong>as</strong>. In: The Mentalitiesof Gorill<strong>as</strong> and Orangutans: Comparative Perspectives,eds, S.T. Parker, R.W. Mitchell, H. L.Miles, 240-264. Cambridge University Press.Br<strong>in</strong>ck, I. (2001) Attention and the evolution of <strong>in</strong>tentionalcommunication. Pragmatics and Cognition,9/2: 255-272.- (2003) The pragmatics of imperative and declarativepo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. Cognitive Science Quarterly, 3(4): 429-446.- (2004) Jo<strong>in</strong>t attention, triangulation and radical<strong>in</strong>terpretation: A problem and its solution, Dialectica,58(2): 179-206.Br<strong>in</strong>ck, I. and Gärdenfors, P. (2003) Co-operationand communication <strong>in</strong> apes and <strong>human</strong>s. M<strong>in</strong>dand Language, 18(5): 484-501.Brown, R. (1977) Why are signed languages e<strong>as</strong>ier tolearn than spoken languages? In: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of theNational Symposium on Sign Language Research andTra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, ed. W. Stokoe, 9-24. Silver Spr<strong>in</strong>g, MD:National Association of the Deaf.Butterworth, G. (1988) What is special about po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g?In: The Development of Sensory, Motor, and CognitiveCapacities <strong>in</strong> Early Infancy: From Perception toCognition, ed. F. Simion and G. Butterworth 171-190. Hove: Psychology Press.Byrne, R. W. and Stokes, E. J. (2002) Effects of manualdisability on feed<strong>in</strong>g skills <strong>in</strong> gorill<strong>as</strong> andchimpanzees. International Journal of Primatology,23/3: 539-54.Byrne, R. W. (1995) The Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Ape: EvolutionaryOrig<strong>in</strong>s of Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.- (1998) Commentary on Boesch, C. andTom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. Chimpanzee and <strong>human</strong> culture.Current Anthropology, 39: 604-5.- (1999) Imitation without <strong>in</strong>tentionality. Us<strong>in</strong>gstr<strong>in</strong>g pars<strong>in</strong>g to copy the organization of behaviour.Animal Cognition, 2: 63-72.Byrne, R. W. and Russon, A. E. (1998) Learn<strong>in</strong>g byimitation: A hierarchical approach. Behavioral andBra<strong>in</strong> Sciences, 21: 667-21.Call, J. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (1994) Production andcomprehension of referential po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g byorangutans (Pongo pygmaeus). Journal of ComparativePsychology, 108: 307-317.- (1996) The effect of <strong>human</strong>s <strong>in</strong> the <strong>cognitive</strong>development of apes. In: Reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to Thought:The M<strong>in</strong>ds of Great Apes. ed. A. Russon, K. Bardand S. Parker. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.- (1998) Dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentional from accidentalactions <strong>in</strong> orangutans (Pongo pygmaeus), chimpanzees(Pan troglodytes), and <strong>human</strong> children (Homosapiens). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 112/2:192-206.- (1999) A nonverbal false belief t<strong>as</strong>k: The performanceof children and great apes. Child Development,70/2: 381-395.Call, J., Hare, B., Carpenter, M. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello,M. (2004) “Unwill<strong>in</strong>g” versus “unable”: chimpanzees’understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>human</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional action.Developmental Science, 7/4: 488-98.Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. (1990) How Monkeys Seethe World: Inside the M<strong>in</strong>d of Another Species. Chicago:University of Chicago Press.Christiansen, M. and Kirby, S. (2003) (eds.) LanguageEvolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Clark, H. (1996) Us<strong>in</strong>g Language. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Corballis, M. C. (2002) From Hand to Mouth: The Orig<strong>in</strong>sof Language. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton UniversityPress.Coussi-Kourbel, S. (1994) Learn<strong>in</strong>g to outwit a competitor<strong>in</strong> mangabeys (Cercocebus torquatus torquatus).Journal of Comparative Psychology, 108: 164-171.Custance, D. M., Whiten, A. and Bard, K. A. (1995)Can young chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) imitatearbitrary actions? Hayes and Hayes (1952)revisited. Behaviour, 132/11-12: 837-59.


36<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionCustance, D. M., Whiten, A., Sambrook, T. andGaldik<strong>as</strong>, B. (2001) Test<strong>in</strong>g for social learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>the “artificial fruit” process<strong>in</strong>g of wild bornorangutans (Pongo pygmaeus), Tanjung Put<strong>in</strong>g, Indonesia.Animal Cognition, 4: 305-13.Custance, D. M., Whiten, A. and Fredman, T. (1999)Social learn<strong>in</strong>g of an artificial fruit t<strong>as</strong>k <strong>in</strong> capuch<strong>in</strong>monkeys (Cebus apella). Journal of ComparativePsychology, 113/1: 13-23.de Waal, F. (1988) The communicative repertoire ofcaptive bonobos (Pan paniscus), compared to thatof chimpanzees. Behaviour, 106/3-4: 183-251.- (1996) Good Natured: The Orig<strong>in</strong>s of Right and Wrong<strong>in</strong> Humans and Other Animals. Harvard: HarvardUniversity Press.- (1998 [1982]) Chimpanzee Politics. Harper.de Waal, F. and Aureli, F. (1996) Consolation, Reconciliationand a Possible Cognitive Difference Between Macaquesand Chimpanzees. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.de Villiers, J., and Pyers, J. (1997) Complement<strong>in</strong>gcognition: The relationship between languageand theory of m<strong>in</strong>d. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 21 st AnnualBoston University Conference on Language Development.Somerville, MA: C<strong>as</strong>cadillia Press.Deacon, T. (1997) The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Bra<strong>in</strong>. New York:Norton.- (2003) Universal grammar and semiotic constra<strong>in</strong>ts.In Christiansen and Kirby (2003), 111-139.Dennett, D. (1996) K<strong>in</strong>ds of M<strong>in</strong>ds. Towards an Understand<strong>in</strong>gof Consciousness. London: Phoenix.Dessalles, J.-L. (2004) Language <strong>as</strong> an isolated niche.Presented at The Fifth Conference on the Evolution ofLanguage, Leipzig.Donald, M. (1991) Orig<strong>in</strong>s of the Modern M<strong>in</strong>d. ThreeStages <strong>in</strong> the Evolution of Culture and Cognition. Harvard:Harvard University Press.- (1998) Mimesis and the Executive Suite: Miss<strong>in</strong>gl<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> language evolution. In Approaches to theEvolution of Language, eds., J. Hurford, M. Studdert-Kennedyand C. Knight, 44-67. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.- (2001) A M<strong>in</strong>d So Rare. The Evolution of HumanConsciousness. New York: Norton.Edelman, G. (1992) Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On theMatter of the M<strong>in</strong>d. New York: B<strong>as</strong>ic Books.Eldridge, N. and Gould. S. J. (1972) Punctuatedequilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism.In: Models <strong>in</strong> Paleobiology, ed., T. Schopf. SanFrancisco: Freeman.Fouts, R. S. (1972) Use of guidance <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g signlanguage to a chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes). Journalof Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 80/3:515-22.- (1973) Acquisition and test<strong>in</strong>g of gestural signs <strong>in</strong>four young chimpanzees. Science, 180: 978-980.Gallagher, S. (1995) Body schema and <strong>in</strong>tentionality.In: The Body and the Self, ed. J. Bermúdez, N.Eilan, and A. Marcel. Cambridge, MA:MIT/Bradford Press.- (2005) How the Body Shapes the M<strong>in</strong>d. Oxford:Oxford University Press.- (<strong>in</strong> press) Phenomenological and experimentalcontributions to understand<strong>in</strong>g embodied experience.In Ziemke, Zlatev and Frank (<strong>in</strong> press).Gallese, V., C. Keyners and Rizzolatti, G. (2004) Aunify<strong>in</strong>g view of the b<strong>as</strong>is of social cognition.Trends <strong>in</strong> Cognitive Sciences, 8/9: 396 – 403.Gallup, G. (1982) Self-awareness and the emergenceof m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> primates. American Journal of Primatology,2: 237-248.Gärdenfors, P. (2003) How Homo Became Sapiens: Onthe Evolution of Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.Gardner, R. A. and Gardner B.T. (1969) Teach<strong>in</strong>gsign language to a chimpanzee. Science, 165: 664-672.Givón, T. (2002) Bio-L<strong>in</strong>guistics. The Santa BarbaraLectures. Amsterdan: Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Gold<strong>in</strong>-Meadow, S. (1999) The role of gesture <strong>in</strong>communication and th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Trends <strong>in</strong> CognitiveSciences, 3/11: 419-429.Gómez, J. C. (1994) Mutual awareness <strong>in</strong> primatecommunication: a Gricean approach, In: Selfawareness<strong>in</strong> Animals and Humans, ed. S. T. Parker,R. W. Mitchell and M. L. Boccia. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Gopnik, A. and Ast<strong>in</strong>gton, J. W. (1988) Children’sunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of representational change, and itsrelation to the understand<strong>in</strong>g of false belief andthe appearance-reality dist<strong>in</strong>ction, Child Development,59: 26-37.Gopnik, A. and Graf, P. (1988) Know<strong>in</strong>g how youknow: young children’s ability to identify andremember the sources of their beliefs. Child Development,59: 1366-1371.Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, A. N. (1997) Words,Thoughts, and Theories, Cambridge, MA: MITPress.Greenfield, P. M. and Savage-Rumbaugh. E. S. (1990)Grammatical comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Pan pamiscus:Processes of learn<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>vention <strong>in</strong> the evolutionand development of language, In: “Language”and Intelligence <strong>in</strong> Monkeys and Apes, eds. S T.Parker and K. R. Gibson, 540-578. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Greenfield, P. M. and Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S. (1991)Imitation, grammatical development, and the <strong>in</strong>ventionof protogrammar. In N. Kr<strong>as</strong>negor, D.Rumbaugh, M. Studdert-Kennedy, and R.Schiefelbusch (Eds.), Biological and behaviorial determ<strong>in</strong>antsof language development (pp. 235-258).Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Greenfield, P. M., and Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S.(1993) Compar<strong>in</strong>g communicative competence


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 37<strong>in</strong> child and chimp: The pragmatics of repetition.Journal of Child Language, 20, 1-26.Grice, P. (1957). Mean<strong>in</strong>g. Philosophical Review, 66:377-88.Hale, C. M. and Tager-Flusberg, H. (2003) The <strong>in</strong>fluenceof language on theory of m<strong>in</strong>d: A tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gstudy. Developmental Science 6/3: 346-359.Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M.(2000) Chimpanzees know what conspecifics doand do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59: 771-85.Hare, B., Call, J. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (2001) Do chimpanzeesknow what conspecifics know? AnimalBehaviour, 61: 139-51.Hauser, M. (1996) The Evolution of Communication.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Hauser, M., Chomsky, N. and Fitch, T. (2002) Thefaculty of language: What is it, who h<strong>as</strong> it andhow did it evolve? Science, 298: 1559-1569.Heyes, C. (1998) Theory of m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> non<strong>human</strong> primates.Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences, 21: 101-115.Hockett, C. F. (1960) The orig<strong>in</strong> of speech. ScientificAmerican, 23: 89-96.Itkonen, E. (1978) Grammatical Theory and Met<strong>as</strong>cience.Amsterdam: Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Ikegami, T. and Zlatev, J. (<strong>in</strong> press) From prerepresentationalcognition to language. InZiemke, Zlatev and Frank (<strong>in</strong> press).James, W. (1890) The Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of Psychology. New York:Henry Holt.Johansson, S. (2005) Orig<strong>in</strong>s of Language. Constra<strong>in</strong>ts onHypotheses. Amsterdam: Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Kendon, A. (1981) Geography of gesture. Semiotica,37: 129-163.Kita, S. and Özyürek, A. (2003) What does crossl<strong>in</strong>guisticvariation <strong>in</strong> semantic coord<strong>in</strong>ation ofspeech and gesture reveal? Evidence for an <strong>in</strong>terfacerepresentation of spatial th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g and speak<strong>in</strong>g.Journal of Memory and Language, 48: 16-32.Knight, C. (2002) Language and revolutionary consciousness.In: The Transition to Language, ed. A.Wray, 138-160. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.Krause, M and Fouts, R. (1997) Chimpanzee (Pantroglodytes) po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g: Hand shapes, accuracy andthe role of gaze. Journal of Comparative Psychology,111 (4): 330-336.Laakso, A. (1993) Language equals <strong>mimesis</strong> plusspeech. Commentary to Donald: Orig<strong>in</strong>s of M<strong>in</strong>d.Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences, 14/4: 765-766.Landau, M. (1991) Narratives of Human Evolution. NewHaven: Yale University Press.Lewis, D. K. (1969) Convention: A Philosophical Study.Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Leavens, D. A., Hopk<strong>in</strong>s, W. D. and Bard, K. (1996)Indexical and referential po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> chimpanzees(Pan troglodytes). Journal of Comparative Psychology,110: 346-353.Leavens, D. A. and Hopk<strong>in</strong>s, W. D. (1999) Thewhole-hand po<strong>in</strong>t: The structure and function ofpo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g from a comparative perspective. Journalof Comparative Psychology, 113/4: 417-425.Lohmann, H. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (2003) The role oflanguage <strong>in</strong> the development of false belief understand<strong>in</strong>g:A tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g study. Child Development74/4: 1130-1144.Liberman, A. M. and Matt<strong>in</strong>gly, I. G. (1985) Themotor theory of speech perception revised. Cognition,21: 1-36.Mandler, J. (2004) The Foundations of M<strong>in</strong>d: Orig<strong>in</strong>s ofConceptual Thought. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.Marler, P. (1985) Representational vocal signals ofprimates. In: Experimental Behavioral Ecology andSociobiology, ed. B. Hölldobler and M. L<strong>in</strong>dauer.Stuttgart: Fischer Verlag.- (1991) Difference <strong>in</strong> behavioral development <strong>in</strong>closely related species: Birdsong. In: The Developmentand Integration of Behavior, ed. P. Bateson, 41-70. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Matsuzawa, T., Biro, D., Humle, T. Inoue-Nakamura,N., Tanook, R. and Yamakoshi G. (2001) Emergenceof culture <strong>in</strong> wild chimpanzees: Educationby m<strong>as</strong>ter-apprenticeship. In: Primate Orig<strong>in</strong>s ofHuman Cognition and Behavior, ed. T. Matzuzawa.Spr<strong>in</strong>ger-Verlag.McNeill, D. (1992) Hand and M<strong>in</strong>d: What GesturesReveal about Thought. Chicago: University of ChicagoPress.Meltzoff, A. and Gopnik, A. (1993) The role of imitation<strong>in</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g other persons and develop<strong>in</strong>ga theory of m<strong>in</strong>d. In: Understand<strong>in</strong>g otherM<strong>in</strong>ds: Perspectives from Autism, ed. S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, and D. J. Cohen. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Meltzoff, A. and Moore, M. K. (1977) Imitation offacial and manual gestures by <strong>human</strong> neonates.Science 198: 75-78.- (1983) Newborn <strong>in</strong>fants imitate adult facial gestures.Child Development, 54: 702-709.- (1994) Imitation, memory, and the representationof persons. Infant Behavior and Development17: 83-99.Menzel, E. W. (1973) Chimpanzee spatial memoryorganization, Science 182: 943-945.- (1974) A group of chimpanzees <strong>in</strong> a 1-acre field:leadership and communication, In: Behavior ofNon<strong>human</strong> Primates, ed. A. M. Schrier and F.Stollnitz. Academic.Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962 [1945]) Phenomenology ofPerception. Routledge and Kegan Paul.- (2003) La Nature: Notes, Cours du College de France.Trans. Robert Vallier, Northwestern UniversityPress.Miles, H. L. (1990) The <strong>cognitive</strong> foundations forreference <strong>in</strong> a sign<strong>in</strong>g orangutan. In: “Language”and Intelligence <strong>in</strong> Monkeys and Apes, eds. S T.


38<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionParker and K. R. Gibson. Cambridge UniversityPress.- (1999) Symbolic communication with and bygreat apes. In: The Mentalities of Gorill<strong>as</strong> andOrangutans, ed. S. Taylor Parker, R. W. Mitchelland H. L. Miles. Cambridge University Press.Miles, H. L., Mitchell, R. W. and Harper, S. E. (1996)Simon says: The development of imitation <strong>in</strong> anenculturated orangutan. In: Reach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to Thought:The M<strong>in</strong>ds of the Great Apes, ed. A. E. Russon, K.A. Bard. and S. T. Parker. Cambridge UniversityPress.Mitchell, P. (1997) Introduction to Theory of M<strong>in</strong>d: Children,Autism and Apes. Arnold.Mitchell, R. and Miles, H. L. (1993) Apes have mimeticculture. Commentary to Donald: Orig<strong>in</strong>s ofM<strong>in</strong>d. Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences 14/4: 768.Myowa-Yamakoshi, M. (2001) Evolutionary foundationand development of imitation. In: PrimateOrig<strong>in</strong>s of Human Cognition and Behavior, ed. T.Matsuzawa. Spr<strong>in</strong>ger-Verlag.Myowa-Yamakoshi, M. and Matsuzawa, T. (1999)Factors <strong>in</strong>fluenc<strong>in</strong>g imitation of manipulatoryactions <strong>in</strong> chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journalof Comparative Psychology, 113/2: 128-36.Myowa-Yamakoshi, M., Tomonaga, M., Tanaka, M.and Matsuzawa, T. (2004) Imitation <strong>in</strong> neonatalchimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Developmental Science,7/4: 437-42.Nagell, K., Olgu<strong>in</strong>, R. S. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (1993)Processes of social learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the tool use ofchimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) and <strong>human</strong> children(Homo sapiens). Journal of Comparative Psychology,107/2: 174-86.Nelson, K. (1996) Language <strong>in</strong> Cognitive Development. TheEmergence of the Mediated M<strong>in</strong>d. Cambridge UniversityPress.Nelson, K. and Shaw, L. K. (2002) Develop<strong>in</strong>g <strong>as</strong>ocially shared symbolic system. In: Language,Literacy and Cognitive Development, ed. J. Byrnesand E. Amseli, Lawrence Erlbaum.Osvath, M. and Gärdenfors, P. (2005) Oldowanculture and the evolution of anticipatory cognition.Lund University Cognitive Studies 122, Lund.Patterson, F. (1978) The gestures of a gorilla: Languageacquisition <strong>in</strong> another pongid. Bra<strong>in</strong> andLanguage, 5: 72-97.- (1980) Innovative use of language <strong>in</strong> a gorilla: Ac<strong>as</strong>e study. In: Children’s Language, Vol 2, ed., K.Nelson 497-561. New York: Garnder Press.Perner, J. (1991) Understand<strong>in</strong>g the Representational M<strong>in</strong>d.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Perner, J., Leekam, S. and Wimmer, H. (1987) Threeyear-old’sdifficulty with false belief: the c<strong>as</strong>e fora conceptual deficit, British Journal of DevelopmentalPsychology, 5: 125-137.Peterson, C. C. and Siegal, M. (1995) Deafness, conversationand the theory of m<strong>in</strong>d. Journal of ChildPsychology and Psychiatry and Allied Discipl<strong>in</strong>es, 36:459-474.Piaget, J. (1945) La Formation du Symbole Chez l'enfant.Delachaux et Niestlé.- (1953) The Orig<strong>in</strong> of Intelligence <strong>in</strong> the Child. Routledge.- (1954) The Construction of Reality <strong>in</strong> the Child. B<strong>as</strong>icBooks.Pierce, C. S. (1931-35) The Collected Papers of CharlesSanders Peirce. Vols. 1-4. Cambridge, M<strong>as</strong>s.: HarvardUniversity Press.Pika, S., Liebal, K. and Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (2003) Gesturalcommunication <strong>in</strong> young gorill<strong>as</strong> (Gorilla gorilla):Gestural repertoir, learn<strong>in</strong>g, and use. AmericanJournal of Primatology, 60: 95-111.- (2005) Gestural communication <strong>in</strong> subadultbonobos (Pan paniscus): Repetoire and use. AmericanJournal of Primatology, 65: 39-61.P<strong>in</strong>ker, S. (1994) The Language Inst<strong>in</strong>ct. William Morrow.Pov<strong>in</strong>elli, D. J. (2000) Folk Physics for Apes: The Chimpanzee’sTheory of How the World Works. OxfordUniversity Press.Pov<strong>in</strong>elli, D. J. and Davis, D. R. (1994) Differencesbetween chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) and <strong>human</strong>s(Homo sapiens) <strong>in</strong> the rest<strong>in</strong>g state of the <strong>in</strong>dexf<strong>in</strong>ger: Implications for po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. Journal ofComparative Psychology, 108: 134-139.Premack, D. (1988) “Does the chimpanzee have atheory of m<strong>in</strong>d?” revisited. In Machiavellian Intelligence.Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect <strong>in</strong>Monkeys, Apes and Humans, ed. R. W. Byrne andA. Whiten, 160-179. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Preston, S. and de Waal, F. (2002) Empathy: Its ultimateand proximal b<strong>as</strong>es, Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences,25: 1-72.Reddy, V. (2001) Te<strong>as</strong><strong>in</strong>g, jok<strong>in</strong>g and muck<strong>in</strong>g about<strong>in</strong> the first year. In: Natural Theories of M<strong>in</strong>d, ed.A. Whiten. Blackwell.- (2003) On be<strong>in</strong>g an object of attention: Implicationsof self-other-consciousness. Trends <strong>in</strong> CognitiveScience, 7/9: 397-402.- (2005) Before the “third element”: Understand<strong>in</strong>gattention to self. In Naomi Kle<strong>in</strong> (ed.) Jo<strong>in</strong>t Attention,85-109. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., and Fog<strong>as</strong>si, L.(1996) Premotor cortex and the recognition ofmotor actions. Cognitive Bra<strong>in</strong> Research, 3, 131-141.Rizzolatti, G. and Arbib, M. (1998) Language with<strong>in</strong>our gr<strong>as</strong>p. Trends <strong>in</strong> Neurosciences, 21: 188-194.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, P. (1996) Consciousness, Rules and InstructedSecond Language Acquisition. Peter Lang.Russon, A. E, and Galdik<strong>as</strong>, B. M. F. (1993) Imitation<strong>in</strong> free-rang<strong>in</strong>g rehabilitant orangutans (Pongopygmaeus). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107/2 :147-61.Saussure, F. de (1916) Cours de L<strong>in</strong>guistique Générale[Course <strong>in</strong> General L<strong>in</strong>guistics]. Payot.


Zlatev, Persson and Gärdenfors, Lund University Cognitive Science 121, (2005). 39Savage-Rumbaugh, S. E., Wilkerson, B. J. and Bakeman,R. (1977) Spontaneous gestural communicationamong conspecifics <strong>in</strong> the pygmy chimpanzee(Pan paniscus). In: Progress <strong>in</strong> Ape Research,ed. G. H. Bourne. Oxford: Academic.Savage-Rumbaugh, S. and Lew<strong>in</strong>. R. (1994) Kanzi: TheApe at the Br<strong>in</strong>k of the Human M<strong>in</strong>d. New York:John Wiley.Savage-Rumbaugh, S., Shanker, S., and Taylor, T.(1998). Apes, Language and the Human M<strong>in</strong>d. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Searle, J. (1992) The Rediscovery of the M<strong>in</strong>d. MIT Press.Sengh<strong>as</strong>, A., Kita, S. and Özyürek, A. (2004) Childrencreat<strong>in</strong>g core properties of language: Evidencefrom an emerg<strong>in</strong>g sign language <strong>in</strong> Nicaragua.Science 305: 1779-1782.S<strong>in</strong>ha, C. (1988) Language and Representation. A SocionaturalisticApproach to Human Development. HarversterPress.- (2003) The evolution of language: From signalsto symbols to system. In: Evolution of Communicationsystems: A Comparative Approach, ed. K. Ollerand U. Griebel. MIT Press.Sonesson, G. (1989) Pictorial Concepts. Lund UniversityPress.- (2001) From semiosis to ecology. On the theoryof iconicity and its consequences for the ontologyof the Lifeworld. VISIO 6/2-3: 85-110.- (<strong>in</strong> press) The “Symbolic species” revisited. Considerationson the semiotic turn <strong>in</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> scienceand biology.Sperber, D. and Wilson, D. (1995) Relevance: Communicationand Cognition. Cambridge University Press.Stern, D. (2000) The Interpersonal World of the Infant: AView from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology.B<strong>as</strong>ic Books.Sto<strong>in</strong>ski, T. S. and Whiten, A. (2003) Social learn<strong>in</strong>gby orangutans (Pongo abelii and Pongo pygmaeus).Journal of Comparative Psychology, 117/3: 272-82.Sto<strong>in</strong>ski, T. S., Wrate, J. L., Ure, N. and Whiten,A. (2001) Imitative learn<strong>in</strong>g by captive westernlowland gorill<strong>as</strong> (Gorilla gorilla gorilla) <strong>in</strong> a simulatedfood-process<strong>in</strong>g t<strong>as</strong>k. Journal of ComparativePsychology, 115/3: 272-81.Stokes, E. J. and Byrne, R. W. (2001) Cognitive capacitiesfor behavioural flexibility <strong>in</strong> wild chimpanzees(Pan troglodytes): the effect of snare <strong>in</strong>juryon complex manual food process<strong>in</strong>g. AnimalCognition, 4: 11-28.Stokoe, W. (1960) Sign language structure: An outl<strong>in</strong>eof the visual communication system of theAmerican deaf. Studies <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics, Occ<strong>as</strong>ional Paper8, University of Buffalo, New York.- (2001). Language <strong>in</strong> Hand. Why Sign Came beforeSpeech. W<strong>as</strong>h<strong>in</strong>gton, D.C.: Gallaudet UniversityPress.Tanner, J. E. and Byrne, R. W. (1996) Representationof action through iconic gesture <strong>in</strong> a captive lowlandgorilla. Current Anthropology, 37/1: 162-73.- (1999) The development of spontaneous gesturalcommunication <strong>in</strong> a group of zoo-liv<strong>in</strong>g lowlandgorill<strong>as</strong>. In: The Mentalities of Gorill<strong>as</strong> and Orangutans– Comparative perspectives, ed. S. T. Parker, R.W. Mitchell and H. Lyn Miles. Cambridge UniversityPress.Tanner, J. E. (2004) Gestural phr<strong>as</strong>es and gesturalexchanges by a pair of zoo-liv<strong>in</strong>g lowland gorill<strong>as</strong>.Gesture, 4/1: 1-24.Terrace, H. S., Petitto, L. A., Sanders, R. J. and Bever,T. G. (1981) Science 211/4477: 87-88.Thompson, R. K. R., Boysen, S. T. and Oden, D. L.(1997) Language-naive chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes)judge relations between relations <strong>in</strong> a conceptualmatch<strong>in</strong>g-to-sample t<strong>as</strong>k. Journal of ExperimentalPsychology, 23/1: 31-43.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. (1992) First verbs: A C<strong>as</strong>e Study of EarlyGrammatical Development. Cambridge UniversityPress.- (1993) It’s imitation, not <strong>mimesis</strong>. Commentaryto Donald: Orig<strong>in</strong>s of M<strong>in</strong>d. Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong>Sciences 14/4: 771-772.- (1996) Do apes ape? In: Social Learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Animals:The Roots of Culture, ed. C. Heyes and B.Galef. Oxford: Academic.- (1999) The Cultural Orig<strong>in</strong>s of Human Cognition.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.- (2003) Construct<strong>in</strong>g a Language: A Usage-b<strong>as</strong>ed Theoryof Language Acquisition. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. and Call, J. (1997): Primate Cognition.Oxford University Press.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M., Call, J. and Gluckman, A. (1997)Comprehension of novel communicative signsby apes and <strong>human</strong> children. Child Development,68: 1067-1080.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M., Call, J. and Hare, B. (2003) Chimpanzeesunderstand psychological states – the questionis which ones and to what extent. Trends <strong>in</strong>Cognitive Sciences, 7/4: 153-156.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M., Call, J., Nagell, K., Olgu<strong>in</strong>, R.and Carpenter, M. (1994) The learn<strong>in</strong>g and useof gestural signals by young chimpanzees: Atrans-generational study. Primates, 35/2: 137-154.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., andMoll, H. (<strong>in</strong> press) Understand<strong>in</strong>g and shar<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentions:The orig<strong>in</strong>s of cultural cognition. Behavioraland Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M., Kruger, A. and Ratner, H. (1993)Cultural learn<strong>in</strong>g. Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences, 16,495-552.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello M., Savage-Rumbaugh S. and Kruger,A. (1993) Imitative learn<strong>in</strong>g of actions on objectsby children, chimpanzees, and enculturatedchimpanzees. Child Development, 64: 1688-1795.Tom<strong>as</strong>ello, M. and Zuberbühler, K. (2002) Primatevocal and gestural communication. In: The CognitiveAnimal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives onAnimal Cognition, ed. M. Bekoff, C. Allen and M.Burhgardt. MIT Press.


40<strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>“the</strong> <strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>human</strong> <strong>cognitive</strong> evolutionTrevarthen, C. (1992) An <strong>in</strong>fant’s motives for speak<strong>in</strong>gand th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the culture, In: The DialogicalAlternative, ed. H. Wold. Oslo: Scand<strong>in</strong>avian UniversityPress.Varela, F., Thompson, E. and Rosch, E. (1991) TheEmbodied M<strong>in</strong>d. Cognitive Science and Human Experience.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Veà, J. J. and Sabater-Pi, J. (1988) Spontaneous po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>gbehaviour <strong>in</strong> the wild pygny chimpanzee (Panpaniscus). Folia Primatologica, 69: 289-290.von Hofsten, C. (1983). Catch<strong>in</strong>g skills <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>fancy.Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perceptionand Preference, 9: 75-85.Whiten, A. (1998) Imitation of the sequential structureof actions by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes).Journal of Comparative Psychology, 112: 270-81.Whiten, A. and Byrne, R. W. (1988) Tactical deception<strong>in</strong> primates, Behavioral and Bra<strong>in</strong> Sciences, 11:233-244.Whiten, A., Custance, D. M., Gomez, J.-C., Teixidor,P. and Bard, K. A. (1996) Imitative learn<strong>in</strong>g ofartificial fruit process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> children (Homosapiens) and chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journal ofComparative Psychology, 110/1: 3-14.Whiten, A., Horner, V., Litchfield, C. A. and Marshall-Pesc<strong>in</strong>i,S. (2004) How do apes ape? Learn<strong>in</strong>gand Behaviour, 32/1: 36-52.Wilcox, S. (2004) Gesture and language: Crossl<strong>in</strong>guisticand historical data from signed languages.Gesture, 4/1: 43-73.Wimmer, H., Hogrefe, G.-J. and Perner, J. (1988)Children’s understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>formational access<strong>as</strong> a source of knowledge. Child Development, 59:386-396.Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations. B<strong>as</strong>ilBlackwell.Woll, B. and Kyle, J. (2004) Sign language. Encylopediaof Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Oxford: Elsevier.Woodruff, G. and Premack, D. (1979) Intentionalcommunication <strong>in</strong> the chimpanzee: the developmentof deception. Cognition, 7: 333-362.Vygotsky, L. S. (1962) Thought and Language. CambridgeMA: MIT Press.- (1978) M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> Society. The Development of HigherPsychological Processes. Harvard University Press.Zlatev, J. (2002) Mimesis: The “<strong>miss<strong>in</strong>g</strong> <strong>l<strong>in</strong>k”</strong> betweensignals and symbols <strong>in</strong> phylogeny and ontogeny.In: Mimesis, Sign and the Evolution of Language, ed.A. Pajunen. University of Turku Press.- (2003) Mean<strong>in</strong>g = Life (+ Culture). An outl<strong>in</strong>e ofa unified biocultural theory of mean<strong>in</strong>g. Evolutionof Communication, 4/2: 253-296.- (2005a) What’s <strong>in</strong> a schema? <strong>Bodily</strong> <strong>mimesis</strong> andthe ground<strong>in</strong>g of language. In: From Perception toMean<strong>in</strong>g: Image Schem<strong>as</strong> <strong>in</strong> Cognitive L<strong>in</strong>guistics, ed.B. Hampe and J. Grady. Mouton.- (2005b) The dependence of language on consciousness.Paper presented at the conferenceTowards a Science of Consciousness 2005, August 17-20, Copenhagen.Zlatev, J., Persson, T. and Gärdenfors, P. (<strong>in</strong> press)Triadic bodily <strong>mimesis</strong> is the difference! Commentaryto Tom<strong>as</strong>ello et al. (<strong>in</strong> press).Zuberbühler, K. (2000) Interspecies semantic communication<strong>in</strong> two forest primates. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs ofthe Royal Society of London. Series B Biological Sciences267: 713-718.


Lund University Cognitive Studies ISSN 1101-84531991 1. Torbjörn Mol<strong>in</strong>: Tractatus de Ratione Circumscripta -Rationality for F<strong>in</strong>ite Agents, LUHFDA/HFKO-3001-SE2. Agneta Gulz: The Plann<strong>in</strong>g of Action <strong>as</strong> a Cognitive andBiological Phenomenon, LUHFDA/HFKO-1001-SE3. Christian Balkenius, Peter Gärdenfors: NonmonotonicInferences <strong>in</strong> Neural Networks, LUHFDA/HFKO-5001-SE,Published <strong>in</strong> Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of Knowledge Repres-entation andRe<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the Second International Conference,J.A. Allen, R. Fikes, and E. Sandewall, eds.(MorganKaufmann: San Mateo, CA), pp. 32-39, 1991. Revisedversion.4. Tom Andersson: Metaphorical Indices-Present<strong>in</strong>g Context <strong>in</strong>Discourse through Metaphorical Expressions,LUHFDA/HFKO-5002-SE. Out of pr<strong>in</strong>t.5. Peter Gärdenfors: The Emergence of Mean<strong>in</strong>g,LUHFDA/HFKO-5003-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics andPhilosophy, 16: 285-309, 1993.1992 6. Tom Andersson: Views on Nature <strong>in</strong> Metaphorical Discourse,LUHFDA/HFKO-5004-SE Published <strong>in</strong> Views of Nature,(FRN, Solna).7. Agneta Gulz: Conceptions of Anger and Grief <strong>in</strong> the Japanese,Swedish and American Cultures: The Role of Metaphor <strong>in</strong>Conceptual Processes, LUHFDA/HFKO-5005-SE8. Tom Andersson: The Dynamics of Metaphor - Conflict<strong>in</strong>gImages of Forest <strong>in</strong> Swedish Discourse, LUHFDA/HFKO-3002-SE9. Peter Gärdenfors: Three Levels of Inductive Inference,LUHFDA/HFKO-5006-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Logic, Methodology,and Philosophy of Science IX, D. Prawitz, B. Skyrms and D.Westerståhl, eds., (Elsevier Science, Amsterdam) pp. 427-449,1994.10. Paul Hemeren: Frequency Norms for Actions <strong>in</strong> Swedish andAmerican Samples, LUHFDA/HFKO-5007-SE, Published <strong>as</strong>"Frequency, ord<strong>in</strong>al position, and semantic distance <strong>as</strong>me<strong>as</strong>ures of cross-cultural stability and hierarchies for actionverbs" <strong>in</strong> Acta Psychologica, 91, 1996.11. Peter Gärdenfors, Hans Rott: Belief Revision,LUHFDA/HFKO-5008-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Handbook of Logic<strong>in</strong> Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programm<strong>in</strong>g, Vol. 4, D.M. Gabbay, C. J. Hogger and J. A. Rob<strong>in</strong>son, eds., (OxfordUniversity Press, Oxford), 1995.12. Paul Davidsson: Concept Acquisition by Autonomous Agents:Cognitive Model<strong>in</strong>g versus the Eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g Approach,LUHFDA/HFKO-5009-SE13. Robert Pallbo: Neuronal Selectivity Without IntermediateCells, LUHFDA/HFKO-5010-SE14. Christian Balkenius: Neural Mechanisms for Self-organizationof Emergent Schemata, Dynamical Schema Process<strong>in</strong>g, andSemantic Constra<strong>in</strong>t Satisfaction, LUHFDA/HFKO-5011-SE15. Peter Gärdenfors: How Logic Emerges from the Dynamics ofInformation, LUHFDA/HFKO-5012-SE. Published <strong>in</strong> Logicand Information Flow, J. van Eijck and A.Visser, eds. (MITPress: Cambridge, MA), pp. 49-77, 1994.1993 16. Guy de Lucs: There are no Mean<strong>in</strong>gless Sentences,LUHFDA/HFKO-7001-SE17. Kenneth Holmqvist: Implement<strong>in</strong>g Cognitive Semantics:Image Schemata, Valence Accommodation and ValenceSuggestions for AI and Computational L<strong>in</strong>guistics,LUHFDA/HFKO-1002-SE18. Peter Gärdenfors, Christian Balkenius: Varför f<strong>in</strong>ns det <strong>in</strong>gariktiga robotar? LUHFDA/HFKO-7002-SE. Pub-lished <strong>in</strong>Framtider, Vol. 12, 1/93, pp. 11-14, (Institutet förFramtidsstudier, Stockholm).19. Tom Andersson: Real Forests <strong>in</strong> Our M<strong>in</strong>ds: Metaphors andPrototypes <strong>in</strong> Discourse, LUHFDA/HFKO-5013-SE20. Tom Andersson: Metaphorical Re<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g and RealPrototypes: Empirical Studies of Metaphors and Prototypes ofForest, LUHFDA/HFKO-5014-SE21. Peter Gärdenfors: The Role of Expectations <strong>in</strong> Re<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g,LUHFDA/HFKO-5015-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Knowledge;Representation and Re<strong>as</strong>on<strong>in</strong>g Under Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ity, M.M<strong>as</strong>uch and L. Pólos, eds, (Spr<strong>in</strong>ger-Verlag, Berl<strong>in</strong>), pp.1-16.22. Henrik Gedenryd: Active Perception and the "ResonanceMetaphor, LUHFDA/HFKO-5016-SE23. Henrik Gedenryd: Manag<strong>in</strong>g Complexity by Support<strong>in</strong>gKnowledge Growth <strong>in</strong> Design and Development Projects,LUHFDA/HFKO-5017-SE24. Robert Pallbo: Ontogenesis <strong>in</strong> Neural Networks,LUHFDA/HFKO-5018-SE1994 25. Peter Gärdenfors: Kategorisk perception i vetenskapen,LUHFDA/HFKO-7003-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Tidskrift förVetenskapsstudier, 7:2, pp. 17-29.26. Peter Gärdenfors, Kenneth Holmqvist: Concept Formation <strong>in</strong>Dimensional Spaces, LUHFDA/HFKO-5019-SE27. Tom Andersson: Conceptual Polemics: Dialectic Studies ofConcept Formation, LUHFDA/HFKO-1003-SE28. Kenneth Holmqvist: Conceptual Eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g I: Frommorphemes to valence relations, LUHFDA/HFKO-5020-SE29. Christian Balkenius: Natural Intelligence for AutonomousAgents, LUHFDA/HFKO-5021-SE30. Christian Balkenius: Biological Learn<strong>in</strong>g and ArtificialIntelligence, LUHFDA/HFKO-5022-SE31. Sofia Broström: The Role of Metaphor <strong>in</strong> CognitiveSemantics, LUHFDA/HFKO-3003-SE32. Lars Kopp: A Neural Network for Spatial Relations:Connect<strong>in</strong>g Visual Scenes to L<strong>in</strong>guistic Descriptions,LUHFDA/HFKO-5023-SE33. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Förväntn<strong>in</strong>gar och kognitionsforskn<strong>in</strong>g,LUHFDA/HFKO-7004-SE34. Robert Pallbo: M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>as</strong> Evolution and Evolution <strong>as</strong> Such,LUHFDA/HFKO-5024-SE35. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter, Peter Gärdenfors: L<strong>in</strong>guistic Modality <strong>as</strong>Expressions of Social Power, LUHFDA/HFKO-5025-SE,Published <strong>in</strong> Nordic Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics, 18, 1995, pp. 137-166.1995 36. Erik Olsson: Can Information Theory Help us RemoveOutdated Beliefs? LUHFDA/HFKO-5026-SE37. Christian Balkenius: Natural Intelligence <strong>in</strong> ArtificialCreatures, LUHFDA/HFKO-1004-SE38. Peter Gärdenfors: Cued and Detached Representations <strong>in</strong>Animal Cognition, LUHFDA/HFKO-5027-SE, Published <strong>in</strong>Behavioural Processes 36, 1996, pp. 263-273.39. Kenneth Holmqvist, Jaroslaw Pluciennik: Concept-ualisedDeviations from Expected Normalities: A SemanticComparison Between Lexical Items End<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> -ful and -less,LUHFDA/HFKO-5028-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Nordic Journal ofL<strong>in</strong>guistics, 19, 1996, pp. 3-3340. Peter Gärdenfors: Mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>as</strong> Conceptual Structures,LUHFDA/HFKO-5029-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> M<strong>in</strong>dscapes:Philosophy, Science and the M<strong>in</strong>d, ed. by M. Carrier and P.Machamer, Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh, 1997, pp.61-86.41. Peter Gärdenfors: Language and the Evolution of Cognition,LUHFDA/HFKO-5030-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> Penser l'esprit: Dessciences de la cognition à une philosophie <strong>cognitive</strong>, ed. by V.Rialle and D. Fisette, Presses Universitaires de Grenoble,Grenoble, 1996, pp. 151-172.42. David de Léon: The Limits of Thought and the M<strong>in</strong>d-BodyProblem, LUHFDA/HFKO-7005-SE43. Peter Gärdenfors: Human Communication: What Happens?LUHFDA/HFKO-7006-SE. <strong>in</strong> The Contrib-ution of Scienceand Technology to the Development of Human Society, ed byB. Reichert, ECSC-EC-EAEC, Brussels, abstract on p. 96


1996 44. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Anticipation and Viol<strong>in</strong> Str<strong>in</strong>gs,LUHFDA/HFKO-5031-SE45. Mikael Johannesson: Obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Psychologically MotivatedSpaces with MDS, LUHFDA/HFKO-5032-SE46. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Det självklara behöver <strong>in</strong>te säg<strong>as</strong>,LUHFDA/HFKO-7007-SE47. Christian Balkenius, Lars Kopp: The XT-1 VisionArchitecture, LUHFDA/HFKO-5033-SE, Published <strong>in</strong>Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the Symposium on Image Analysis, ed. by P.L<strong>in</strong>de and G. Sparr, Lund University, Lund, 1996, pp. 39-43.48. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Vad är pragmatik, egentligen? LUHFDA/HFKO-7008-SE49. Kenneth Holmqvist, Jana Holsánová: "Jag längtar efter svenskkvalité och tänkande...": Hur vi använder kategoriser<strong>in</strong>gar isamtalet, LUHFDA/HFKO-5034-SE50. Kenneth Holmqvist, Jana Holsánová: Focus Movements andthe Internal Images of Spoken Discourse, LUHFDA/HFKO-5035-SE, Published <strong>as</strong> "Focus Movements dur<strong>in</strong>gVisualisation of Spoken Discourse," <strong>in</strong> DiscourseConstructions, ed. W. Liebert, G. Redeker and L. Waugh,Amsterdam/ Philadelphia: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s, 1997.51. Peter Gärdenfors: När tanken lyfter, LUHFDA/HFKO-7009-SE Published <strong>in</strong> Kungliga Vitterhets- Historie- ochAntikvitets-akademiens Årsbok 1996, Stockholm, pp. 106-117.1997 52. Christian Balkenius, Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Explorations <strong>in</strong> SyntheticPragmatics, LUHFDA/HFKO-5036-SE, Published <strong>in</strong> “DoesRepresentation Need Reality?”, Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs from New Trends<strong>in</strong> Cognitive Science -97, ed. A. Riegler and M. Peschl,Vienna, ASoCS Technical Report 97-01, Austrian Society ofCognitive Science, pp. 100-107.53. Peter Gärdenfors: Att tala med m<strong>as</strong>k<strong>in</strong>erna, LUHFDA/HFKO-7010-SE, Abridged version publ-ished <strong>as</strong> "De kulturellakonsekvenserna av att tala med s<strong>in</strong> dator" <strong>in</strong> Moderna Tider,April 1997, pp. 40-42.54. Annika Wall<strong>in</strong>: Shaky Constructions, LUHFDA/ HFKO-5037-SE55. Mikael Johannesson: Modell<strong>in</strong>g Asymmetric Similarity withProm<strong>in</strong>ence, LUHFDA/HFKO-5038-SE56. Christer Garbis: Spatial Representationand Haptic MentalRotation, LUHFDA/HFKO-5039-SE57. Robert Pallbo: M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> Motion: The utilization of noise <strong>in</strong> the<strong>cognitive</strong> process, LUHFDA/HFKO-1005-SE58. David de Léon: The Qualities of Qualia, LUHFDA/ HFKO-5040-SE Communication and Cognition, 34 (1/2), pp. 121-138.59. Peter Gärdenfors: Media och berättande, LUHFDA/ HFKO-5041-SE pp. 315-336 published <strong>in</strong> Boken i tiden, SOU1997:141, Stockholm.60. David de Léon, Jana Holsánová: Reveal<strong>in</strong>g User Behaviour onthe World-Wide Web, LUHFDA/HFKO-5042-SE61. Jan Morén: Dynamic Action Sequences <strong>in</strong> Re<strong>in</strong>forcementLearn<strong>in</strong>g, LUHFDA/HFKO-5043-SE62. Christian Balkenius, Jan Morén: Computational Models ofCl<strong>as</strong>sical Condition<strong>in</strong>g: A Comparative Study LUHFDA/HFKO-5044-SE63. Ingar Br<strong>in</strong>ck, Peter Gärdenfors: Representation and selfawareness<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional agents, LUHFDA/HFKO-5045-SE <strong>in</strong>Synthese 118, pp. 89-104.1998 64. Jens Månsson: Stereovision. A Model of Human Stereopsis,LUHFDA/HFKO-5046-SE65. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Dialogue Dynamics, Viol<strong>in</strong> Str<strong>in</strong>gs, and thePragmatics-Semantics Cont<strong>in</strong>uum, LUHFDA/ HFKO-5047-SE66. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Evolution, Categorization, and ValuesLUHFDA/HFKO-5048-SE published <strong>in</strong> Evolution &Cognition, vol 4 no 2, 1998, Vienna University Press, Vienna.67. Annika Wall<strong>in</strong>: Choos<strong>in</strong>g Problems, LUHFDA/HFKO-5049-SE68. Christian Balkenius: A Neural Network Model of Cl<strong>as</strong>sicalCondition<strong>in</strong>g Part I: The Dynamics of Learn<strong>in</strong>g,LUHFDA/HFKO-5050-SE69. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter, Peter Gärdenfors: Evolv<strong>in</strong>g Social Constra<strong>in</strong>tson Individual Conceptual Representations, LUHFDA/HFKO-5051-SE70. Kenneth Holmquist, Marianne Gullberg: Focus on Gesture,LUHFDA/HFKO-5052-SE71. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Expectations and L<strong>in</strong>guistic Mean<strong>in</strong>g,LUHFDA/HFKO-1006-SE72. Bengt Carlsson: Evolutionary Models <strong>in</strong> Multi-AgentSystems, LUHFDA/HFKO-3004-SE73. Simon W<strong>in</strong>ter: Introduktion till avhandl<strong>in</strong>gen Expectationsand L<strong>in</strong>guistic Mean<strong>in</strong>g, LUHFDA/ HFKO-7011-SE74. Nils Hulth, Peter Grenholm: A Distributed Cluster<strong>in</strong>gAlgorithm, LUHFDA/HFKO-5053-SE75. Henrik Gedenryd: How Designers Work: Mak<strong>in</strong>g Sense ofAuthentic Cognitive Activities, LUHFDA/ HFKO-1007-SE76. Peter Gärdenfors: Concept Comb<strong>in</strong>ation: a Geometricalmodel, LUHFDA/HFKO-5054-SE pp. 129-146 <strong>in</strong> L. Cavedon,P. Blackburn,, N. Braisby and A. Shimojima (eds) Logiclanguage and Computation Vol 3, CSLI, Stanford, CA.77. Ingar Br<strong>in</strong>ck, Peter Gärdenfors: Representation and Selfawareness<strong>in</strong> Intentional Agents, LUHFDA/ HFKO-5055-SE78. Jana Holsánová: På Tal om Bilder, LUHFDA/HFKO-3005-SE1999 79. Jordan Zlatev: The Epigenesis of Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Human Be<strong>in</strong>gs,and Possibly <strong>in</strong> Robots, LUHFDA/HFKO-5056-SE. Published<strong>in</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ds and Mach<strong>in</strong>es Vol. 11 (2), pp. 155-195.80. Pierre Gander: Two Myths about Immersion <strong>in</strong> New Storytell<strong>in</strong>gMedia, LUHFDA/HFKO-5057-SE81. Jens Månsson: Occlud<strong>in</strong>g Contours: A Computational Modelof Suppressive Mechanisms <strong>in</strong> Human Contour PerceptionLUHFDA/HFKO-5058-SE2000 82. Ingar Br<strong>in</strong>ck: Attention and the Evolution of IntentionalCommunication. LUHFDA/HKFO-5059-SE2001 83. Jana Holsánová: Picture View<strong>in</strong>g and Picture Description:Two W<strong>in</strong>dows on the M<strong>in</strong>d. LUFDA/HFKO-1008-SE84. Philip Diderichsen: Visual Fixations, Attentional Detection,and Syntactic Perspective, LUHFDA/ HKFO-5060-SE85. Eds. Christian Balkenius et al: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the FirstInternational Workshop on Epigenetic Robotics, Model<strong>in</strong>gCognitive Development <strong>in</strong> Robotic Systems, LUHFDA/HFKO-2002-SE86. Eds. Kai Oliver Arr<strong>as</strong> et al: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the FourthEuropean Workshop on Advanced Mobile Robots(Eurobot'01), LUHFDA/HFKO-2001-SE87. Mikael Johannesson: The problem of Comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Integral andSeperable Dimensions, LUHFDA/HKFO-5061-SE88. Ingar Br<strong>in</strong>ck, Peter Gärdenfors: Co-operation and Communication<strong>in</strong> Apes and Humans, LUHFDA/ HKFO-5062-SE89. Lars Kopp, Peter Gärdenfors: Attention <strong>as</strong> a M<strong>in</strong>imalCriterion of Intent<strong>in</strong>ality <strong>in</strong> Robots, LUHFDA/HKFO-5063-SE2002 90. Mikael Johannesson: Geometric Models of Similarity.LUHFDA/HFKO-1009-SE91. Peter Gärdenfors: Cooperation and the Evolution of SymbolicCommunication, LUHFDA/HFKO-5064-SE92. Peter Gärdenfors: Att skapa gemensamma visioner: Omspråkets roll i människans utveckl<strong>in</strong>g, LUHFDA/HFKO-5065-SE93. Jan Morén: Emotion and Learn<strong>in</strong>g. A Computational Modelof the Amygdala LUHFDA/HFKO-1010-SE94. Eds. Christian Balkenius et al: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the SecondInternational Workshop on Epigenetic Robotics, Model<strong>in</strong>gCognitive Development <strong>in</strong> Robotic Systems, LUHFDA/HFKO-2003-SE


95. Lars Hall, David de Léon & Petter Johansson: The Future ofSelf-Control: Distributed Motivation and Computer-MediatedExtrospection. LUHFDA/HFKO-5066-SE96. Petter Johansson: The New Contenders: On How to Model theM<strong>in</strong>d. LUHFDA/HFKO-5067-SE97. Jens Månsson: The Uniqueness Constra<strong>in</strong>t Revisited: ASymmetric Near-Far Inhibitory Mechanism Produc<strong>in</strong>gOrdered B<strong>in</strong>ocular Matches. LUHFDA/HFKO-5068-SE2003 98. Christian Balkenius, Anders J Johansson & Anna Balkenius:Color Constancy <strong>in</strong> Visual Scene Perception.LUHFDA/HFKO-5069-SE99. Annika Wall<strong>in</strong>: Expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Everyday Problem Solv<strong>in</strong>g.LUHFDA/HFKO-1011-SE100. Lars Kopp: Natural Vision for Artificial Systems: ActiveVision and Thought. LUHFDA/HFKO-1012-SE101. Eds. Christian Balkenius et al: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the ThirdInternational Workshop on Epigenetic Robotics, LUHFDA/HFKO-2004-SE102. Agneta Gulz: Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g Styles and Socially Enriched Learn<strong>in</strong>gMaterial: Differential Effects on Motivation and MemoryPerformance. LUHFDA/HFKO-5070-SE103. David de Léon: The Cognitive Biographies of Th<strong>in</strong>gs.LUHFDA/HFKO-5071-SE104. David de Léon: Actions, Artefacts and Cognition: AnEthnography of Cook<strong>in</strong>g. LUHFDA/HFKO-5072-SE105. David de Léon: Artefactual <strong>in</strong>telligence: The devel-opmentand use of <strong>cognitive</strong>ly congenial artefacts. LUHFDA/HFKO-1013-SE.106. David Bengtsson: The Nature of Explanation <strong>in</strong> a Theory ofConsciousness. LUHFDA/HFKO-5073-SE107. Lars Hall & Petter Johansson: Introspection andExtrospection: Some Notes on the Contextual Nature of Self-Knowledge. LUHFDA/HFKO-5074-SE108. Lars Hall, & Petter Johansson: On the Role of Bra<strong>in</strong>-Imag<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> the Calibration of Mental Strategies. LUHFDA/HFKO-5075-SE109. Monica Bredefeldt Öhman: Livet som figur - Omsjälvbiografiskt m<strong>in</strong>ne. LUHFDA/HFKO-3006-SE110. Lars Hall och Petter Johansson: Neurofeedback and Metacognition.LUHFDA/HFKO-5076-SE111. Lars Hall och Petter Johansson: Self-Regulation <strong>in</strong> Education:A Ubiquitous Comput<strong>in</strong>g Perspective. LUHFDA/HFKO-5077112. Andre<strong>as</strong> Olsson: Emotion and Motivation <strong>in</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g:Current Research, Future Directions and PracticalImplications. LUHFDA/HFKO-5078-SE113. Lars Hall: Self-Knowledge/Self-Regulation/Self-Control: AUbiquitous Comput<strong>in</strong>g Perspective. LUHFDA/HFKO-1014-SE114. Anna Tebelius: Fonologiskt och semantiskt m<strong>in</strong>ne av bilderoch ord – En dyslexistudie. LUHFDA/HFKO-5079-SE2004 115. Åsa Harvard: Lek, lärande och motorik. Delrapport till ”TheLearn<strong>in</strong>g Bra<strong>in</strong>, the Learn<strong>in</strong>g Individual, the Learn<strong>in</strong>gorganisation.” LUHFDA/HFKO-5080-SE116. Anders Sandberg: Computational Memory Models.LUHFDA/HFKO-5081-SE117. Eds Luc Berthouze et al.: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 4 th InternationalWorkshop on Epigenetic Robotics, LUHFDA/HFKO-2005-SE118. Marie Gustafsson: Mak<strong>in</strong>g Agents Less Annoy<strong>in</strong>g: Towardsan Animated Agent that Responds to Social Cues.LUHFDA/HFKO-5082-SE119. Eds Yvonne Eriksson and Kenneth Holmqvist: Language andVisualisation.2005 120. Pierre Gander: Participat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a Story: Explor<strong>in</strong>g audiencecognition. LUHFDA/HFKO-1015-SE121. Jordan Zlatev, Tom<strong>as</strong> Persson and Peter Gärdenfors: <strong>Bodily</strong>Mimesis <strong>as</strong> the“Miss<strong>in</strong>g L<strong>in</strong>k” <strong>in</strong> Human Cognitive Evolution.LUHFDA/HFKO-5083-SE122. Mathi<strong>as</strong> Osvath and Peter Gärdenfors: Oldowan Culture andthe Evolution of Anticipatory Cognition. LUHFDA/HFKO-5084-SE123. Eds Luc Berthouze et al.: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 5 th InternationalWorkshop on Epigenetic Robotics, LUHFDA/HFKO-5070-SE124. Conference Abstracts: European Society for Philosophy andPsychology, LUHFDA/HFKO-8453-SE

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!