12.07.2015 Views

Economic Science and the Austrian Method_3

Economic Science and the Austrian Method_3

Economic Science and the Austrian Method_3

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ECONOMIC SCIENCEAND THEAUSTRIAN METHOD


ECONOMIC SCIENCEAND THEAUSTRIAN METHODHANS..HERMANN HOPPELu~wigvon MisesInstituteAUBURN, ALABAMA


All rights reserved. Written permission must be secured from <strong>the</strong>publisher to use or reproduce any part of this book, except for briefquotations in critical reviews or articles.Copyright © 1995 <strong>and</strong> 2007 by <strong>the</strong> Ludwig von Mises InstituteLudwig von Mises Institute, 518 West Magnolia Avenue, Auburn,Ala. 36832; www.mises.orgISBN 10 digit: 1~933550~11~2ISBN 13 digit: 978~ 1~933550~ 11~4


CONTENTSPREFACE 5PRAXEOLOGY AND ECONOMIC SCIENCE 7ON PRAXEOLOGY AND THE PRAXEOLOGICALFOUNDATION OF EPISTEMOLOGY 49RECOMMENDED READINGS 85INDEX 87ABOUT THE AUTHOR 893


PREFACEIt was a tragic day when economics, <strong>the</strong> queen of <strong>the</strong>social sciences, adopted <strong>the</strong> methods associated with<strong>the</strong> natural sciences: empiricism <strong>and</strong> positivism. In <strong>the</strong>sweep of economic thought, this change occurred-notcoincidentally-about <strong>the</strong> same time that intellectuals <strong>and</strong>politicians came to believe in <strong>the</strong> efficacy of governmentplanning. Despite <strong>the</strong>ir failures, both doctrines remain godlessfaiths of our age.In this extraordinary essa~ Hans-Hermann Hoppe extends<strong>the</strong> argument ofLudwig von Mises that <strong>the</strong> methodsassociated with natural sciences cannot be successfully appropriatedfor economic <strong>the</strong>or~ Professor Hoppe <strong>the</strong>n arguesfor <strong>the</strong> existence ofa priori knowledge, <strong>the</strong> validity ofpure <strong>the</strong>or~ <strong>the</strong> use of deductive logic, <strong>the</strong> implacability ofeconomic law, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> view that economics is but a part of<strong>the</strong> larger discipline of praxeology: <strong>the</strong> science of humanaction.If economists are to free <strong>the</strong>mselves from <strong>the</strong> failedassumptions that <strong>the</strong>y can precisely predict <strong>the</strong> future <strong>and</strong>,thus, that <strong>the</strong> state can plan <strong>the</strong> economy better than <strong>the</strong>market, <strong>the</strong>y will have to revisit more fundamental methodologicalerrors. When that happens, Professor Hoppe, <strong>the</strong>outst<strong>and</strong>ing praxeologist working toda~ will have played anindispensable role.-Llewellyn H. Rockwell, Jr.Ludwig von Mises InstituteThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 5


PRAXEOLOGY ANDECONOMIC SCIENCEIt is well-known that <strong>Austrian</strong>s disagree strongly witho<strong>the</strong>r schools of economic thought, such as <strong>the</strong>Keynesians, <strong>the</strong> Monetarists, <strong>the</strong> Public Choicers, Historicists,Institutionalists, <strong>and</strong> Marxists. 1 Disagreement ismost conspicuous, of course, when it comes to economicpolicy <strong>and</strong> economic policy proposals. At times <strong>the</strong>re alsoexists an alliance between <strong>Austrian</strong>s <strong>and</strong>, in particular, Chicagoites<strong>and</strong> Public Choicers. Ludwig von Mises, Murray N.Rothbard, Milton Friedman, <strong>and</strong> James Buchanan, to cite afew names, are often united in <strong>the</strong>ir efforts to defend <strong>the</strong> freemarket economy against its "liberal" <strong>and</strong> socialist detractors.None<strong>the</strong>less, as important as such occasional agreementsmay be for tactical or strategic reasons, <strong>the</strong>y can only besuperficial, for <strong>the</strong>y cover up some truly fundamental differencesbetween <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> school, as represented by Mises<strong>and</strong> Rothbard, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>the</strong> rest. The ultimate difference fromwhich all disagreements at <strong>the</strong> levels of economic <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>and</strong> economic policy stem-disagreements, for instance,IThe first two essays are based on two lectures delivered at <strong>the</strong> Ludwig vonMises Institute's '~dvanced Instructional Conference on <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s,"June 21-27, 1987. The third essay is reprinted from The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Ethics ofPrivate Property (Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1993), pp. 141-64.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 7


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>as regards <strong>the</strong> merit of <strong>the</strong> gold st<strong>and</strong>ard vs. fiat mone~free-banking vs. central banking, <strong>the</strong> welfare implications ofmarkets vs. state-action, capitalism vs. socialism, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oryofinterest <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> business cycle, etc.-concerns <strong>the</strong> answerto <strong>the</strong> very first question that any economist must raise:What is <strong>the</strong> subject matter ofeconomics, <strong>and</strong> what kind ofpropositions are economic <strong>the</strong>orems?Mises's answer is that economics is <strong>the</strong> science ofhumanaction. In itself, this may not sound very controversial. But<strong>the</strong>n Mises says of <strong>the</strong> science of economics:Its statements <strong>and</strong> propositions are not derived from experience.They are, like those of logic <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matics, apriori. They are not subject to verification <strong>and</strong> falsificationon <strong>the</strong> ground of experience <strong>and</strong> facts. They are bothlogically <strong>and</strong> temporally antecedent to any comprehensionof historical facts. They are a necessary requirement of anyintellectual grasp of historical events. 2In order to emphasize <strong>the</strong> status ofeconomics as a purescience, a science that has 11-10re in common with a disciplinelike applied logic than, for instance, with <strong>the</strong> empiricalnatural sciences, Mises proposes <strong>the</strong> term "praxeology" (<strong>the</strong>logic ofaction) for <strong>the</strong> branch ofknowledge exemplified byeconomics. 3It is this assessment ofeconomics as an a priori science,a science whose propositions can be given a rigorous logicaljustification, which distinguishes <strong>Austrian</strong>s, or more2Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1966), p. 32.3Mises's methodological work is contained mainly in his EpistemologicalProblems of<strong>Economic</strong>s (New York: New York University Press, 1981); Theory <strong>and</strong>History (Washington, D.C.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1985); The UltimateFoundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> (Kansas City, Kans.: Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel,1978); Human Action, part I.8 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeprecisely Misesians, from all o<strong>the</strong>r current economicschools. All <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs conceive ofeconomics as an empiricalscience, as a science like physics, which develops hypo<strong>the</strong>sesthat require continual empirical testing. And <strong>the</strong>y all regardas dogmatic <strong>and</strong> unscientific Mises's view that economic<strong>the</strong>orems-like <strong>the</strong> law of marginal utili~ or <strong>the</strong> law ofreturns, or <strong>the</strong> time-preference <strong>the</strong>ory of interest <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Austrian</strong> business cycle <strong>the</strong>ory-can be given definite proof,such that it can be shown to be plainly contradictory to deny<strong>the</strong>ir validi~The view ofMark Blaug, highly representative ofmainstreammethodological thought, illustrates this almost universalopposition to <strong>Austrian</strong>ism. Blaug says ofMises, "Hiswritings on <strong>the</strong> foundations of economic science are socranky <strong>and</strong> idiosyncratic that one can only wonder that <strong>the</strong>yhave been taken seriously by anyone.,,4Blaug does not provide one argument to substantiate hisoutrage. His chapter on <strong>Austrian</strong>ism simply ends with thatstatement. Could it be that Blaug's <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs' rejection ofMises's apriorism may have more to do with <strong>the</strong> fact that<strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>ing st<strong>and</strong>ards of argumentative rigor, whichan apriorist methodology implies, prove too much for<strong>the</strong>m?54Mark Blaug, The <strong>Method</strong>ology of<strong>Economic</strong>s (Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1980), p. 93; for a similar statement of outrage see Paul Samuelson,Collected Scientific Papers, vol. 3 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,1972), p. 761.5Ano<strong>the</strong>r prominent critic of praxeology is Terence W Hutchison, TheSignificance <strong>and</strong> Basic Postulates of<strong>Economic</strong> Theory (London: Macmillan, 1938).Hutchison, like Blaug an adherent of <strong>the</strong> Popperian variant of empiricism, hassince become much less enthusiastic about <strong>the</strong> prospects ofadvancing economicsalong empiricist lines (see, for instance, his Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Ignorance in <strong>Economic</strong>s[Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977]; <strong>and</strong> The Politics <strong>and</strong> Philosophy of<strong>Economic</strong>s [New York: New York University Press, 1981]), yet he still sees noalternative to Popper's falsificationism. A position <strong>and</strong> development quite similarThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 9


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>What led Mises to his characterization of economics asan a priori science? From <strong>the</strong> present day perspective itmight be surprising to hear that Mises did not see hisconception as out ofline with <strong>the</strong> mainstream view prevailingin <strong>the</strong> early twentieth centur~ Mises did not wish toprescribe what economists should be doing as opposed towhat <strong>the</strong>y actually were doing. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, he saw his achievementas a philosopher of economics in systematizing, <strong>and</strong>in making explicit what economics really was, <strong>and</strong> how ithad implicitly been conceived by almost everyone callinghimself an economist.And this is indeed <strong>the</strong> case. In giving a systematicexplanation ofwhat was formerly only implicit <strong>and</strong> unspokenknowledge, Mises did introduce some conceptual <strong>and</strong>terminological distinctions that had previously been unclear<strong>and</strong> unfamiliar, at least to <strong>the</strong> English-speaking world. Buthis position on <strong>the</strong> status of economics was essentially infull agreement with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>n-orthodox view on <strong>the</strong> matter.They did not employ <strong>the</strong> term "a priori," but such mainstreameconomists as Jean Baptiste Sa~ Nassau Senior, <strong>and</strong>John E. Cairnes, for instance, described economics quitesimilarl~Say writes: "A treatise on political economy will ... beconfined to <strong>the</strong> enunciation of a few general principles, notrequiring even <strong>the</strong> support ofproofs or illustrations; becauseto Hutchison's is to be found in H. Albert (see his earlier Marktsoziologie undEntscheidungslogik (Neuwied: 1967). For a critique of<strong>the</strong> empiricist position, seeHans-Hermann Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung. Unterschungenzur Grundlegung von Soziologie und Okonomie (Opladen: 1983); "IsResearch Based on Causal Scientific Principles Possible in <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s?"Ratio 25, no. 1 (1983); "In Defense ofExtreme Rationalism," Review of<strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s 3 (1988); "On Praxeology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Praxeological Foundations of Epistemology<strong>and</strong> Ethics," in Llewellyn H. Rockwell, Jr., ed., The Meaning ofLudwigvon Mises (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1989).10 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppe<strong>the</strong>se will be but <strong>the</strong> expression ofwhat every one will knO\\T,arranged in a form convenient for comprehending <strong>the</strong>m, aswell as in <strong>the</strong>ir whole scope as in <strong>the</strong>ir relation to eacho<strong>the</strong>r." And "political economy ... whenever <strong>the</strong> principleswhich constitute its basis are <strong>the</strong> rigorous deductions ofundeniable general facts, rests upon an immovable foundation.,,6.According to Nassau Senior, economic "premises consistof a few general propositions, <strong>the</strong> result ofobservations, orconsciousness, <strong>and</strong> scarcely requiring proof, or even formalstatement, which almost every man, as soon as he hears<strong>the</strong>m, admits as familiar to his thoughts, or at least asincluded in his previous knowledge; <strong>and</strong> his inferences arenearly as general, <strong>and</strong>, ifhe has reasoned correctl); as certainas his premises." And economists should be "aware that <strong>the</strong><strong>Science</strong> depends more on reasoning than on observation,<strong>and</strong> that its principal difficulty consists not in <strong>the</strong> ascertainmentof its facts, but in <strong>the</strong> use of its terms.,,7And John E. Cairnes remarks that while "mankind hasno direct knowledge ofultimate physical principles" ... "<strong>the</strong>economist starts with a knowledge of ultimate causes." ..."The economist may thus be considered at <strong>the</strong> outset ofhisresearches as already in possession ofthose ultimate principIesgoverning <strong>the</strong> phenomena which form <strong>the</strong> subject ofhis study; <strong>the</strong> discovery of which in <strong>the</strong> case of physicalinvestigation constitutes for <strong>the</strong> inquirer his most arduoustask." "Conjecture [in economics] would manifestly be outof place, inasmuch as we possess in our consciousness <strong>and</strong>6Jean-Baptiste Say, Ireatise on Political Economy (New York: Augustus Kelley,[1880] 1964), p. xx, xxvi.7Nassau Senior, An Outline of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Science</strong> of Political Economy (New York:Augustus Kelley, [1836] 1965), pp. 2-3, 5.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 11


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>in <strong>the</strong> testimony of our senses . . . direct <strong>and</strong> easy proofofthat which we desire to know: In Political Econom~ accordingl~hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is never used as a help toward <strong>the</strong> discoveryofultimate causes <strong>and</strong> laws."sThe views ofMises's predecessors, Menger, Bohm-Bawerk,<strong>and</strong> Wieser, are <strong>the</strong> same: The~ too, describe economicsas a discipline whose propositions can-in contrast to thoseof <strong>the</strong> natural sciences-be given some ultimate justification.Again, however, <strong>the</strong>y do so without using <strong>the</strong> terminologyemployed by Mises. 9And finall~ Mises's epistemological characterization ofeconomics was also considered quite orthodox-<strong>and</strong> certainlynot idiosyncratic, as Blaug would have it-after havingbeen explicitly formulated by Mises. Lionel Robbins'sbook The Nature <strong>and</strong> Significance of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>, whichfirst appeared in 1932, is nothing but a somewhat watereddownversion of Mises's description of economics aspraxeolo~ Yet itwas respected by <strong>the</strong> economics professionas <strong>the</strong> guiding methodological star for almost twenty years.In fact, Robbins, in his Preface, explicitly singles outMises as <strong>the</strong> most important source of his own methodologicalposition. And Mises <strong>and</strong> Richard von Strigl-whose8John E. Cairnes, The Character <strong>and</strong> Logical <strong>Method</strong> ofPolitical Economy (NewYork: Augustus Kelley, 1965), p. 83,87, 89-90,95-96.9See Carl Menger, Untersuchungen uber die <strong>Method</strong>en der Sozialwissenschaften(Leipzig: 1883); idem, Die Irrtumer des Historismus in der Deutschen Nationalokonomie(Wien: 1884); Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk, Schriften, E X. Weiss, ed.(Vienna: 1924); Friedrich von Wieser, Theme der gesellschaftlichen Wirtschaft(Tiibingen: 1914); idem, Gesammelte Abh<strong>and</strong>lungen (Tiibingen: 1929). ForMises's evaluation ofhis predecessors, see his Epistemological Problems of<strong>Economic</strong>s,pp. 17-22. The term "a priori" in connection with economic <strong>the</strong>orems is also usedby Frank H. Knight; his methodological writings, however, lack systematic rigor.See his "What Is Truth in <strong>Economic</strong>s," in Knight, On <strong>the</strong> History <strong>and</strong> <strong>Method</strong> of<strong>Economic</strong>s (Chicago: University ofChicago Press, 1956); <strong>and</strong> his "The Limitationsof Scientific <strong>Method</strong> in <strong>Economic</strong>s," in Knight, The Ethics ofCompetition (Chicago:University of Chicago Press, 1935).12 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppeposition is essentially indistinguishable from Mises'slo-arecited approvingly in <strong>the</strong> text more often than anyone else.IIYet, illuminating as all this may be for an assessment of<strong>the</strong> present-day situation, it is only histor~ What <strong>the</strong>n is <strong>the</strong>rationale of <strong>the</strong> classical economists for regarding <strong>the</strong>irscience as different than <strong>the</strong> natural sciences? And what isbehind Mises's explicit reconstruction ofthis difference asone between an a priori science <strong>and</strong> an aposteriori science?It was <strong>the</strong> recognition that <strong>the</strong> process of validation-<strong>the</strong>process of discovering whe<strong>the</strong>r some propositionis true or not-is different in one field ofinquirythan in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.Let us first look briefly at <strong>the</strong> natural sciences. How dowe know what <strong>the</strong> consequences will be if we subject somenature-given material to specified tests, let's sa~ if we mixit with ano<strong>the</strong>r kind ofmaterial? Obviously we do not knowbefore we actually try it <strong>and</strong> observe what happens. We canmake a prediction, of course, but our prediction is only ahypo<strong>the</strong>tical one, <strong>and</strong> observations are required to find outif we are right or wrong.Moreover, even if we have observed some definite outcome,let's say that mixing <strong>the</strong> two materials leads to anexplosion, can we <strong>the</strong>n be sure that such an outcome willlORichard von Strigl, Die okonomischen Kategorien und die Or;ganisation derWirtschaft (Jena: 1923).11It may be worth mentioning that Robbins's methodological position, muchlike Friedrich A. Hayek's, became increasingly less Misesian over time due mainlyto <strong>the</strong> influence of Karl R. Popper, <strong>the</strong>ir colleague at <strong>the</strong> London School of<strong>Economic</strong>s. See on this Lionel Robbins, An Autobiography ofan Economist (London:Macmillan, 1976); Hayek's disagreement with Mises's idea of praxeologyhas been most recently restated in his "Einleitung" to Ludwig von Mises'sErinnerungen (Stuttgart: 1978). Mises's own, entirely negative verdict on Poppercan be found in his The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>, p. 70. In supportof this verdict see also Hans H. Hoppe Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung(Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1983), pp. 48-49.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 13


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>invariably occur whenever we mix such materials? Again,<strong>the</strong> answer is no. Our predictions will still, <strong>and</strong> permanentl)',be hypo<strong>the</strong>tical. It is possible that an explosion will onlyresult ifcertain o<strong>the</strong>r conditions-A,B, <strong>and</strong> C-are fulfilled.We can only find out whe<strong>the</strong>r or not this is <strong>the</strong> case <strong>and</strong> what<strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r conditions are by engaging in a never-endingtrial <strong>and</strong> error process. This enables us to improve ourknowledge progressively about <strong>the</strong> range of application forour original hypo<strong>the</strong>tical prediction.Now let us turn to some typical economic propositions.Consider <strong>the</strong> validation process ofa proposition such as <strong>the</strong>following: Whenever two people A <strong>and</strong> B engage in avoluntary exchange, <strong>the</strong>y must both expect to profit from it.And <strong>the</strong>y must have reverse preference orders for <strong>the</strong> goods<strong>and</strong> services'exchanged so that A values what he receivesfrom B more highly than what he gives to him, <strong>and</strong> B mustevaluate.<strong>the</strong> same things <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around.Or consider this: Whenever an exchange is not voluntarybut coerced, one party profits at <strong>the</strong> expense of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.Or <strong>the</strong> law of marginal utility: Whenever <strong>the</strong> supply ofa good increases by one additional unit, provided each unitis regarded as of equal serviceability by a person, <strong>the</strong> valueattached to this unit must decrease. For this additional unitcan only be employed as a means for <strong>the</strong> attainment of agoal that is considered less valuable than <strong>the</strong> least valuedgoal satisfied by a unit of such good if <strong>the</strong> supply were oneunit shorter.Or take <strong>the</strong> Ricardian law of association: Of two producers,ifA is more productive in <strong>the</strong> production of twotypes of goods than is B, <strong>the</strong>y can still engage in a mutuallybeneficial division of labor. This is because overall physicalproductivity is higher ifA specializes in producing one good14 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppewhich he can produce most efficientl~ ra<strong>the</strong>r than both A<strong>and</strong> B producing both goods separately <strong>and</strong> autonomousl~Or as ano<strong>the</strong>r example: Whenever minimum wage lawsare enforced that require wages to be higher than existingmarket wages, involuntary unemployment will result.Or as a final example: Whenever <strong>the</strong> quantity ofmoneyis increased while <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money to be held as cashreserve on h<strong>and</strong> is unchanged, <strong>the</strong> purchasing power ofmoney will fall.Considering such propositions, is <strong>the</strong> validation processinvolved in establishing <strong>the</strong>m as true or false of <strong>the</strong> sametype as that involved in establishing a proposition in <strong>the</strong>natural sciences? Are <strong>the</strong>se propositions hypo<strong>the</strong>tical in <strong>the</strong>same sense as a proposition regarding <strong>the</strong> effects of mixingtwo types of natural materials? Do we have to test <strong>the</strong>seeconomic propositions continuously against observations·?And does it require a never-ending trial <strong>and</strong> error process inorder to find out <strong>the</strong> range of application for <strong>the</strong>se propositions<strong>and</strong> to gradually improve our knowledge, such as wehave seen to be <strong>the</strong> case in <strong>the</strong> natural sciences?It seems quite evident-except to most economists for<strong>the</strong> last forty years-that <strong>the</strong> answer to <strong>the</strong>se questions is aclear <strong>and</strong> unambiguous No. That A <strong>and</strong> B must expect toprofit <strong>and</strong> have reverse preference orders follows from ourunderst<strong>and</strong>ing ofwhat an exchange is. And <strong>the</strong> same is <strong>the</strong>case concerning <strong>the</strong> consequences ofa coerced exchange. Itis inconceivable that things could ever be different: It wasso a million years ago <strong>and</strong> it will be so a million years hence.And <strong>the</strong> range of application for <strong>the</strong>se propositions too isclear once <strong>and</strong> for all: They are true whenever something isa voluntary exchange or a coerced exchange, <strong>and</strong> that is all<strong>the</strong>re is to it.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 15


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>There is no difference with respect to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r examplesgiven. That <strong>the</strong> marginal utility ofadditional units ofsupplyof homogeneous goods must fall follows from <strong>the</strong> incontestablestatement that every acting person always preferswhat satisfies him more over what satisfies him less. It issimply -absurd to think that continuous testing would berequired to establish such a proposition.The Ricardian law ofassociation, along with a once-<strong>and</strong>for-alldelineation of its range of application, also logicallyfollows from <strong>the</strong> very existence of <strong>the</strong> situation described.IfA <strong>and</strong> B differ as described <strong>and</strong> accordingly <strong>the</strong>re exists atechnological substitution ratio for <strong>the</strong> goods produced(one such rate for A <strong>and</strong> one for B), <strong>the</strong>n if <strong>the</strong>y engage ina division of labor as characterized by <strong>the</strong> law, <strong>the</strong> physicaloutput produced must be greater than it o<strong>the</strong>rwise wouldbe. Any o<strong>the</strong>r conclusion is logically flawed.The same is true regarding <strong>the</strong> consequences of minimumwage laws or an increase in <strong>the</strong> quantity of mone~ Anincrease in unemployment <strong>and</strong> a decrease in <strong>the</strong> purchasingpower of money are consequences which are logically impliedin <strong>the</strong> very description of<strong>the</strong> initial condition as statedin <strong>the</strong> propositions at h<strong>and</strong>. As a matter offact, it is absurdto regard <strong>the</strong>se predictions as hypo<strong>the</strong>tical <strong>and</strong> to think that<strong>the</strong>ir validity could not be established independently ofobservations,i.e., o<strong>the</strong>r than by actually trying out minimum wagelaws or printing more money <strong>and</strong> observing what happens.To use an analogy; it is as ifone wanted to establish <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>orem of Pythagoras by actually measuring sides <strong>and</strong>angles of triangles. Just as anyone would have to commenton such an endeavor, mustn't we say that to think economicpropositions would have to be empirically tested is a sign ofoutright intellectual confusion?16 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeBut Mises by no means merely notices this ra<strong>the</strong>r obviousdifference between economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> empirical sciences.He makes us underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature ofthis difference<strong>and</strong> explains how <strong>and</strong> why a unique discipline like economics,which teaches something about reality without requiringobservations, can possibly exist. It is this achievementof Mises's which can hardly be overrated.In order to better underst<strong>and</strong> his explanation, we mustmake an excursion into <strong>the</strong> field of philosophy; or moreprecisely into <strong>the</strong> field of <strong>the</strong> philosophy of knowledge orepistemolog~In particular, we must examine <strong>the</strong> epistemologyofImmanuel Kant as developed most completely in hisCritique ofPure Reason. Mises's idea ofpraxeology is clearlyinfluenced by Kant. This is not to say that Mises is a plain<strong>and</strong> simple Kantian. As a matter of fact, as I will point outlater, Mises carries <strong>the</strong> Kantian epistemology beyond <strong>the</strong>point at which Kant himself left off. Mises improves <strong>the</strong>Kantian philosophy in a way that to this very day has beencompletely ignored <strong>and</strong> unappreciated by orthodox Kantianphilosophers. None<strong>the</strong>less, Mises takes from Kant his centralconceptual <strong>and</strong> terminological distinctions as well assome fundamental Kantian insights into <strong>the</strong> nature of humanknowledge. Thus we must turn to Kant.Kant, in <strong>the</strong> course ofhis critique ofclassical empiricism,in particular that of David Hume, developed <strong>the</strong> idea thatall our propositions can be classified in a two-fold way: On<strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y are ei<strong>the</strong>r analytic or syn<strong>the</strong>tic, <strong>and</strong> on<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are ei<strong>the</strong>r a priori or a posteriori. The meaningof <strong>the</strong>se distinctions is, in short, <strong>the</strong> following. Propositionsare analytic whenever <strong>the</strong> means of formal logic aresufficient in order to find out whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are true or not;o<strong>the</strong>rwise propositions are syn<strong>the</strong>tic ones. And propositionsare a posteriori whenever observations are necessary in orderThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 17


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>to establish <strong>the</strong>ir truth or at least confirm <strong>the</strong>m. Ifobservationsare not necessa~ <strong>the</strong>n propositions are a priori.The characteristic mark of Kantian philosophy is <strong>the</strong>claim that true a priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions exist-<strong>and</strong> itis because Mises subscribes to this claim that he can be calleda Kantian. Syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori propositions are those whosetruth-value can be definitely established, even though in orderto do so <strong>the</strong> means offormal logic are not sufficient (while,ofcourse, necessary) <strong>and</strong> observations are unnecessary:According to Kant, ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>and</strong> geometry provideexamples of true a priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions. Yet he alsothinks that a proposition such as <strong>the</strong> general principle ofcausality-i.e., <strong>the</strong> statement that <strong>the</strong>re are time-invariantlyoperating causes, <strong>and</strong> every event is embedded into a networkofsuch causes-is a true syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori proposition.I cannot go into great detail here to explain how Kantjustifies this vie",-12 A few remarks will have to suffice. First,how is <strong>the</strong> truth ofsuch propositions derived, ifformal logic isnot sufficient <strong>and</strong> observations are unnecessary? Kant's answeris that <strong>the</strong> truth follows from self-evident material axioms.What makes <strong>the</strong>se axioms self-evident? Kant answers, itis not because <strong>the</strong>y are evident in a psychological sense, inwhich case we would be immediately aware of<strong>the</strong>m. On <strong>the</strong>contrar~Kant insists, it is usually much more painstakingto discover such axioms than it is to discover some empiricaltruth such as that <strong>the</strong> leaves of trees are green. They areself-evident because one cannot deny <strong>the</strong>ir truth withoutself-contradiction; that is, in attempting to deny <strong>the</strong>m onewould actuall~ implicitl~ admit <strong>the</strong>ir truth.12A brilliant interpretation <strong>and</strong> justification of Kant's a prioristic epistemologyis to be found in E Kambartel, Erfahrung und Struktur. Bausteine zu einer Kritikdes Empirismus und Formalismus (Frankfurt/M.: 1968), esp. chapter 3; see alsoHans-Hermann Hoppe, H<strong>and</strong>eln und Erkennen (Bern: 1976).18 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hertnann HoppeHow do we find such axioms? Kant answers, by reflectingupon ourselves, by underst<strong>and</strong>ing ourselves as knowingsubjects. And this fact-that <strong>the</strong> truth of a priori syn<strong>the</strong>ticpropositions derives ultimately from inner, reflectively producedexperience-also explains why such propositions canpossibly have <strong>the</strong> status of being understood as necessarilytrue. Observational experience can only reveal things as <strong>the</strong>yhappen to be; <strong>the</strong>re is nothing in it that indicates why thingsmust be <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y are. Contrary to this, however, writesKant, our reason can underst<strong>and</strong> such things as being necessarily<strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y are, "which it has itself producedaccording to its own design."13In all this Mises follows Kant. Yet, as I said earlier, Misesadds one more extremely important insight that Kant hadonly vaguely glimpsed. It has been a common quarrel withKantianism that this philosophy seemed to imply some sortof idealism. For if, as Kant sees it, true syn<strong>the</strong>tic a prioripropositions are propositions about how our mind works<strong>and</strong> must of necessity work, how can it be explained thatsuch mental categories fit reality? How can it be explained,for instance, that reality conforms to <strong>the</strong> principIeofcausality ifthis principle has to be understood as oneto which <strong>the</strong> operation of our mind must conform? Don'twe have to make <strong>the</strong> absurd idealistic assumption that thisis possible only because reality was actually created by <strong>the</strong>mind? So that I am not misunderstood, I do not think thatsuch a charge against Kantianism is justified. 14 And yet,13Immanue1 Kant, Kritik der reinen Urnunft, in Kant, uerke, vol. 2, W Weischedel,ed. (Wiesbaden: 1956), p. 23.14See in particular E Kambartel's work cited in note 12; instructive is also<strong>the</strong> Kant interpretation given by <strong>the</strong> biologist-ethologist K. Lorenz, WJm ueltbilddes Urhaltensforschers (Munich: 1964); idem, Die Ruckseite des Spiegels. Ursuch einerNaturgeschichte menschlichen Erkennens (Munich: 1973). Among some followersThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 19


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>through parts of his formulations Kant has no doubt giventhis charge some plausibility:Consider, for example, this programmatic statement ofhis: "So far it has been assumed that our knowledge had toconform· to observational reality"; instead it should be assumed"thatobservational reality conform to our knowledge."15Mises provides <strong>the</strong> solution to this challenge. It is true,as Kant says, that true syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori propositions aregrounded in self-evident axioms <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>se axioms haveto be understood by reflection upon ourselves ra<strong>the</strong>r thanbeing in any meaningful sense "observable.') Yet we have togo one step fur<strong>the</strong>r. We must recognize that such necessarytruths are not simply categories of our mind, but that ourmind is one of acting persons. Our mental categories haveto be understood as ultimately grounded in categories ofaction. And as soon as this is recognized, all idealisticsuggestions immediately disappear. Instead, an epistemologyclaiming <strong>the</strong> existence oftrue syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori propositionsbecomes a realistic epistemolog)T. Since it is understoodas ultimately grounded in categories of action, <strong>the</strong> gulfbetween <strong>the</strong> mental <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real, outside, physical world isbridged. As categories ofaction, <strong>the</strong>y must be mental thingsas much as <strong>the</strong>y are characteristics ofreality: For it is throughactions that <strong>the</strong> mind <strong>and</strong> reality make contact.of <strong>Austrian</strong>ism, <strong>the</strong> Kant interpretation of Ayn R<strong>and</strong> (see, for instance, herIntroduction to Objectivist Epistemology (New York: New American Library, 1979);or For <strong>the</strong> New Intellectual (New York: R<strong>and</strong>om House, 1961) enjoys greatpopularity. Her interpretation, replete with sweeping denunciatory pronouncements,however, is characterized by a complete absence of any interpretivedocumentation whatsoever. See, on R<strong>and</strong>'s arrogant ignorance regarding Kant, B.Goldberg, '~yn R<strong>and</strong>'s 'For <strong>the</strong> New Intellectual'," New Individualist Review 1, no.3 (1961).20 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeKant had hinted at this solution. He thought ma<strong>the</strong>matics,for instance, had to be grounded in our knowledge of<strong>the</strong> meaning of repetition, of repetitive operations. And healso realized, if only somewhat vaguel~ that <strong>the</strong> principle ofcausality is implied in our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of what it is <strong>and</strong>means to act. 16Yet it is Mises who brings this insight to <strong>the</strong> foreground:Causality; he realizes, is a category of action. To act meansto interfere at some earlier point in time in order to producesome later result, <strong>and</strong> thus every actor must presuppose <strong>the</strong>existence ofconstantly operating causes. Causality is a prerequisiteof acting, as Mises puts it.But Mises is not, as is Kant, interested in epistemologyas such. With his recognition ofaction as <strong>the</strong> bridge between<strong>the</strong> mind <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outside reality; he has found a solution to<strong>the</strong> Kantian problem of how true syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori propositionscan be possible. And he has offered some extremelyvaluable insights regarding <strong>the</strong> ultimate foundation ofo<strong>the</strong>rcentral epistemological propositions besides <strong>the</strong> principle ofcausality; such as <strong>the</strong> law ofcontradiction as <strong>the</strong> cornerstone oflogic. And he has <strong>the</strong>rebyopened a path for future philosophicalresearch that, to my knowledge, has hardly been traveled.Yet Mises's subject matter is economics, <strong>and</strong> so I willhave to lay to rest <strong>the</strong> problem ofexplaining in more detail <strong>the</strong>causality principle as an a priori true proposition.I 716For Kantian interpretations ofma<strong>the</strong>matics see H. Dingler, Philosophic der LogikundMa<strong>the</strong>matik (Munich: 1931); Paul Lorenzen, Einfiihrung in die operative Logikund Ma<strong>the</strong>matik (Frankfurt/M.: 1970); Ludwig Wittgenstein, Remarks on <strong>the</strong>Foundations ofMa<strong>the</strong>matics (Cambridge, Mass.: M.Ll: Press, 1978); also Kambartel,Erfahrung und Struktur, pp. 118-22; for an unusually careful <strong>and</strong> cautiousinterpretation of Kantianism from <strong>the</strong> point ofview ofmodern physics, seeP. Mittelstaedt, Philosophische Probleme der modernen Physik (Mannheim: 1967).17For some far<strong>the</strong>r reaching considerations on <strong>the</strong>se matters, see Hoppe "InDefense ofExtreme Rationalism."The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 21


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Mises not only recognizes that epistemology indirectlyrests on our reflective knowledge of action <strong>and</strong> can <strong>the</strong>rebyclaim to state something a priori true about reality but thateconomics does so too <strong>and</strong> does so in a much more directway; <strong>Economic</strong> propositions flow directly from our reflectivelygained knowledge of action; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong>sepropositions as a priori true statements about somethingreal is derived from our underst<strong>and</strong>ing ofwhat Mises terms"<strong>the</strong> axiom of action."This axiom, <strong>the</strong> proposition that humans act, fulfills <strong>the</strong>requirements precisely for a true syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori proposition.It cannot be denied that this proposition is true, since <strong>the</strong>denial would have to be categorized as an action-<strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong>truth of <strong>the</strong> statement literally cannot be undone. And <strong>the</strong>axiom is also not derived from observation-<strong>the</strong>re are onlybodily movements to be observed but no such things asactions-but stems instead from reflective underst<strong>and</strong>ing.Moreover, as something that has to be understood ra<strong>the</strong>rthan observed, it is still knowledge about reality; This isbecause <strong>the</strong> conceptual distinctions involved in this underst<strong>and</strong>ingare nothing less than <strong>the</strong> categories employed in<strong>the</strong> mind's interaction with <strong>the</strong> physical world by means ofits own physical bodr And <strong>the</strong> axiom of action in all itsimplications is certainly not self-evident in a psychologicalsense, although once made explicit it can be understood asan undeniably true proposition about something real <strong>and</strong>existent. 18Certainl~ it is not psychologically evident nor is itobservable that with every action an actor pursues a goal;<strong>and</strong> that whatever <strong>the</strong> goal may be, <strong>the</strong> fact that it is pursued180n this <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> following see Mises, Human Action, chapters IV,V.22 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppeby an actor reveals that he places a relatively higher value onit than on any o<strong>the</strong>r goal of action he could conceive of at<strong>the</strong> start of his action.It is nei<strong>the</strong>r evident nor observable that in order toachieve his most highly valued goal an action must interfereor decide not to interfere (which, of course, is also aninterference) at an earlier point in time to produce somelater result; nor that such interferences invariably imply <strong>the</strong>employment of some scarce means (at least those of <strong>the</strong>actor's bod); its st<strong>and</strong>ing room <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> time absorbed by <strong>the</strong>interference).It is nei<strong>the</strong>r self-evident nor can it be observed that <strong>the</strong>semeans must also have value for an actor-a value derivedfrom that of <strong>the</strong> goal-because <strong>the</strong> actor must regard <strong>the</strong>iremployment as necessary in order to effectively achieve <strong>the</strong>goal; <strong>and</strong> that actions can only be performed sequentiall);always involving <strong>the</strong> making ofa choice, i.e., taking up thatone course of action which at some given point in timepromises <strong>the</strong> most highly valued result to <strong>the</strong> actor <strong>and</strong>excluding at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>the</strong> pursuit ofo<strong>the</strong>r, less highlyvalued goals.It is not automatically clear or observable that as aconsequence ofhaving to choose <strong>and</strong> give preference to onegoal over ano<strong>the</strong>r-of not being able to realize all goalssimultaneously-each <strong>and</strong> every action implies <strong>the</strong> incurrenceofcosts. For example, forsaking <strong>the</strong> value attached to<strong>the</strong> most highly valued alternative goal that cannot berealized or whose realization must be deferred because <strong>the</strong>means necessary to effect it are bound up in <strong>the</strong> productionof ano<strong>the</strong>r, even more highly valued goal.And last!); it is not plainly evident or observable that atits starting point every goal of action must be consideredThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 23


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>worth more to <strong>the</strong> actor than its cost <strong>and</strong> capable ofyieldinga profit, i.e., a result whose value is ranked higher than thatof <strong>the</strong> foregone opportunities. And yet, every action is alsoinvariably threatened by <strong>the</strong> possibility of a loss if an actorfinds, in retrospect, that <strong>the</strong> result actually achieved-contraryto previous expectations-has a lower value than <strong>the</strong>relinquished alternative would have had.All of <strong>the</strong>se categories-values, ends, means, choice,preference, cost, profit <strong>and</strong> loss, as well as time <strong>and</strong> causality-areimplied in <strong>the</strong> axiom ofaction. Yet, that one is ableto interpret observations in such categories requires that onealready knows what it means to act. No one who is not anactor could ever underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. They are not"given," readyto be observed, but observational experience is cast in <strong>the</strong>seterms as it is construed by an actor. Nor is <strong>the</strong>ir reflectivereconstruction a simple, psychologically self-evident intellectualtask, as proved by a long line ofabortive attempts along<strong>the</strong> way to <strong>the</strong> just-outlined insights into <strong>the</strong> nature ofaction.It took painstaking intellectual effort to recognize explicitlywhat, once made explicit, everybody recognizesimmediately as true <strong>and</strong> can underst<strong>and</strong> as true syn<strong>the</strong>tic apriori statements, i.e., propositions that can be validatedindependently of observations <strong>and</strong> thus cannot possibly befalsified by any observation whatsoever.The attempt to disprove <strong>the</strong> action-axiom would itselfbe an action aimed at a goal, requiring means, excludingo<strong>the</strong>r courses ofaction, incurring costs, subjecting <strong>the</strong> actorto <strong>the</strong> possibility of achieving or not achieving <strong>the</strong> desiredgoal <strong>and</strong> so leading to a profit or a loss.And <strong>the</strong> very possession of such knowledge <strong>the</strong>n cannever be disputed, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong>se concepts can24 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppenever be falsified by any contingent experience, for disputingor falsifying anything would already have presupposed<strong>the</strong>ir very existence. As a matter offact, a situation in which<strong>the</strong>se categories of action would cease to have a real existencecould itself never be observed, for making an observation,too, is an action.Mises's great insight was that economic reasoning hasits foundation in just this underst<strong>and</strong>ing ofaction; <strong>and</strong> that<strong>the</strong> status of economics as a sort of applied logic derivesfrom <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong> action-axiom as an a priori-truesyn<strong>the</strong>tic proposition. The laws of exchange, <strong>the</strong> law ofdiminishing marginal utilit~ <strong>the</strong> Ricardian law ofassociation,<strong>the</strong> law of price controls, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney-all <strong>the</strong> examples of economic propositions whichI have mentioned-can be logically derived from this axiom.And this is why it strikes one as ridiculous to think ofsuch propositions as being of<strong>the</strong> same epistemological typeas those of <strong>the</strong> natural sciences. To think that <strong>the</strong>y are, <strong>and</strong>accordingly to require testing for <strong>the</strong>ir validation, is likesupposing that we had to engage in some fact-findingprocess without knowing <strong>the</strong> possible outcome in order toestablish <strong>the</strong> fact that one is indeed an actor. In a word:It is absurd.Praxeology says that all economic propositions whichclaim to be true must be shown to be deducible by meansof formal logic from <strong>the</strong> incontestably true material knowledgeregarding <strong>the</strong> meaning of action.Specificall~all economic reasoning consists of <strong>the</strong> following:(1) an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> categories of action <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>meaning of a change occurring in such things as values,preferences, knowledge, means, costs, etc;The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 25


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>(2) a description ofa world in which <strong>the</strong> categories ofactionassume concrete meaning, where definite people are identifiedas actors with definite objects specified as <strong>the</strong>ir meansof action, with some definite goals identified as values <strong>and</strong>definite things specified as costs. Such description could beone ofa Robinson Crusoe world, or a world with more thanone actor in which interpersonal relationships are possible;of a world of barter exchange or of money <strong>and</strong> exchangesthat make use ofmoney as a common medium ofexchange;of a world of only l<strong>and</strong>, labor, <strong>and</strong> time as factors ofproduction, or a world with capital products; of a worldwith perfectly divisible or indivisible, specific or unspecificfactors of production; or of a world with diverse socialinstitutions, treating diverse actions as aggression <strong>and</strong>threatening <strong>the</strong>m with physical punishment, etc; <strong>and</strong>(3) a logical deduction of <strong>the</strong> consequences which resultfrom <strong>the</strong> performance of some specified action within thisworld, or of <strong>the</strong> consequences which result for a specificactor if this situation is changed in a specified wa~Provided <strong>the</strong>re is no flaw in <strong>the</strong> process of deduction,<strong>the</strong> conclusions that such reasoning yield must be valid apriori because <strong>the</strong>ir validity would ultimately go back tonothing but <strong>the</strong> indisputable axiom of action. If <strong>the</strong> situarion<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> changes introduced into it are fictional orassumptional (a Robinson Crusoe world, or a world with onlyindivisible or only completely specific factors ofproduction),<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> conclusions are, ofcourse, a priori true only ofsucha "possible world." If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>and</strong>changes can be identified as real, perceived <strong>and</strong> conceptualizedas such by real actors, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> conclusions are apriori true propositions about <strong>the</strong> world as it really is. 1919See also Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung, chapter3.26 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann H~peSuch is <strong>the</strong> idea of economics as praxeolog~ And such<strong>the</strong>n is <strong>the</strong> ultimate disagreement that <strong>Austrian</strong>s have with<strong>the</strong>ir colleagues: Their pronouncements cannot be deducedfrom <strong>the</strong> axiom of action or even st<strong>and</strong> in clear-cut contradictionto propositions that can be deduced from <strong>the</strong> axiomof action.And even if <strong>the</strong>re is agreement on <strong>the</strong> identification offacts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> assessment ofcertain events as being related toeach o<strong>the</strong>r as causes <strong>and</strong> consequences, this agreement issuperficial. For such economists falsely believe <strong>the</strong>ir statementsto be empirically well-tested propositions when <strong>the</strong>yare, in fact, propositions that are true a priori.IINon-praxeological schools of thought mistakenlybelieve that relationships between certain eventsare well-established empirical laws when <strong>the</strong>y arereally necessary <strong>and</strong> logical praxeological ones. And <strong>the</strong>y<strong>the</strong>reby behave as if<strong>the</strong> statement "a ball cannot be red <strong>and</strong>non-red aU· over at <strong>the</strong> same time" requires testing inEurope, America, Africa, Asia <strong>and</strong> Australia (of courserequiring a lot of funds in order to pay for such daringnonsensical research). Moreover, <strong>the</strong> non-praxeologists alsobelieve that relationships between certain events are well-establishedempirical laws (with predictive implications)when a priori reasoning can show <strong>the</strong>m to be no morethan information regarding contingent historical connectionsbetween events, which does not provide us with anyknowledge whatsoever regarding <strong>the</strong> future course ofevents.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 27


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>This illustrates ano<strong>the</strong>r fundamental confusion non­<strong>Austrian</strong> schools have: a confusion over <strong>the</strong> categoricaldifference between <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> implicationthat this difference has for <strong>the</strong> problem of social <strong>and</strong> economicforecasting.I must again begin with a description ofempiricism, <strong>the</strong>philosophy which thinks of economics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sciencesin general as following <strong>the</strong> same logic of research asthat, for instance, of physics. I will explain wh~ Accordingto empiricism-today's most widely held view of economics-<strong>the</strong>reis no categorical difference between <strong>the</strong>oretical<strong>and</strong> historical research. And I will explain what this impliesfor <strong>the</strong> idea ofsocial forecasting. The very different <strong>Austrian</strong>view will <strong>the</strong>n be developed out ofa critique <strong>and</strong> refutationof <strong>the</strong> empiricist position.Empiricism is characterized by <strong>the</strong> fact that it acceptstwo intimately related basic propositions. 2o The first <strong>and</strong>most central one is: Knowledge regarding reali~ which is calledempirical knowledge, must be verifiable or at least falsifiable byobservational experience. Observational experience can onlylead to contingent knowledge (as opposed to necessaryknowledge), because it is always of such a kind that, inprinciple, itcould have been different than it actually was. Thismeans that no one can know in advance ofexperience-that20For various representative accounts of empiricism-united in <strong>the</strong>ir oppositionagainst any form ofapriorism-see R. Carnap, Der logische AuJbau der mit(Hamburg: 1966); idem, Iestability <strong>and</strong> Meaning (New Haven, Conn.: YaleUniversity Press, 1950); Alfred ]. Ayer, Logic, Truth, <strong>and</strong> Language (New York:Dover, 1952); Karl R. Popper, Logic ofScientific Discuvery (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong>Row, 1959); idem, Conjectures <strong>and</strong> Refutations (London: Routledge <strong>and</strong> KeganPaul, 1969); C. G. Hempel,AspectsofScientiftcExplanation (New York: Free Press,1970); for accounts which also give some attention to economics, see in particularErnest Nagel, The Structure of <strong>Science</strong> (New York: Harcourt, Brace <strong>and</strong> World,1961); Felix Kaufmann, <strong>Method</strong>ology of <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s (Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s,N.].: Humanities Press, 1944).28 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppeis before actually having had some particular observationalexperience-if <strong>the</strong> consequence of some real event will beone way or ano<strong>the</strong>r. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, knowledge is notverifiable or falsifiable by observational experience, <strong>the</strong>n itis not knOWledge about anything real. It is simply knowledgeabout words, about <strong>the</strong> use of terms, about signs <strong>and</strong>transformational rules for signs. That is to say; it is analyticalknowledge, but not empirical knowledge. And it is highlydoubtful, according to this vie~ that analytical knowledgeshould be regarded as knowledge at all.The second assumption of empiricism formulates <strong>the</strong>extension <strong>and</strong> application of <strong>the</strong> first assumption to problemsof causality; causal explanation, <strong>and</strong> prediction. Accordingto empiricism, to explain causally or predict a realphenomenon is to formulate a statement of ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> type"if A, <strong>the</strong>n B" or, should <strong>the</strong> variables allow quantitativemeasurement, "if an increase (decrease) in A, <strong>the</strong>n an increase(decrease) in B."As a statement referring to reality (with A <strong>and</strong> B beingreal phenomena), its validity can never be established withcertainty; that is, by examining <strong>the</strong> proposition alone, or ofany o<strong>the</strong>r proposition from which <strong>the</strong> one in question couldbe logically deduced. The statement will always be <strong>and</strong>always remain hypo<strong>the</strong>tical, its veracity depending on <strong>the</strong>outcome of future observational experiences which cannotbe known in advance. Should experience confirm a hypo<strong>the</strong>ticalcausal explanation, this would not prove that <strong>the</strong>hypo<strong>the</strong>sis was true. Should one observe an instance whereB indeed followedA as predicted, it verifies nothing. A <strong>and</strong>B are general, abstract terms, or in philosophical terminolog~universals, which refer to events <strong>and</strong> processes ofwhich<strong>the</strong>re are (or might be, in principle) an indefinite numberof instances. Later experiences could still possibly falsify it.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 29


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>And if an experience falsified a hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, this wouldnot be decisive ei<strong>the</strong>r. For ifit was observed thatA was notfollowed by B, it would still be possible that <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ticallyrelated phenomena were causally linked. It could bethat some o<strong>the</strong>r circumstance or variable, heretofore neglected<strong>and</strong>uncontrolled, had simply prevented <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sizedrelationship from actually being observed. At <strong>the</strong>most, falsification only proves that <strong>the</strong> particular hypo<strong>the</strong>sisunder investigation was not completely correct as it stood.It needs some refinement, some specification of additionalvariables which have to be watched for <strong>and</strong> controlled sothat we might observe <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sized relationship between4<strong>and</strong>B. But, to be sure, a falsification would neverprove once <strong>and</strong> for all that a relationship between somegiven phenomena did not exist, just as a confirmation wouldnever definitively prove that it did exist. 21When we consider this position, we notice that it againimplies a denial of a priori knowledge that is at <strong>the</strong> sametime knowledge about anything real. Any proposition thatclaims to be a priori can, according to empiricism, be nomore than signs on paper that are related to each o<strong>the</strong>r bydefinition or by arbitrary stipulation, <strong>and</strong> is thus completelyvoid: it is without connection to <strong>the</strong> world of real thingswhatsoever. Such a system of signs only becomes an empiricallymeaningful <strong>the</strong>ory once an empirical interpretationis given to its symbols. Yet as soon as such aninterpretation is given to its symbols, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is nolonger a priori true but ra<strong>the</strong>r becomes <strong>and</strong> remains foreverhypo<strong>the</strong>tical.2IOn <strong>the</strong> relativistic <strong>and</strong>-on <strong>the</strong> level of politics-interventionist implicationsof empiricism, see Hans-Hermann Hoppe, "The Intellectual Cover forSocialism," The Free Market (February 1988).30 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeMoreover, according to empiricism, we cannot knowwith certainty whe<strong>the</strong>r something is a possible cause ofsomething else. If we want to explain some phenomenon,our hypo<strong>the</strong>sizing about possible causes is in no way constrainedby a priori considerations. Everything can havesome influence on anything. We must find out by experiencewhe<strong>the</strong>r it does or not; but <strong>the</strong>n experience will never giveus a definite answer to this question ei<strong>the</strong>r.The next point brings us to our central topic of thissection: <strong>the</strong> relationship between history <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>or~ Wenotice that according to empiricism <strong>the</strong>re is no principaldifference between historical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical explanations.Every explanation is of <strong>the</strong> same type. In order to explain aphenomenon we hypo<strong>the</strong>size some o<strong>the</strong>r phenomenon as itscause <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n see whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sized causeindeed preceded <strong>the</strong> effect in time. A distinction exists betweena historical <strong>and</strong> a <strong>the</strong>oretical explanation only insofar as ahistorical explanation refers to events that already happened,something that lies in <strong>the</strong> past, whereas a <strong>the</strong>oretical explanationwould be an explanation, or ra<strong>the</strong>r a prediction, of aneffect that has not yet occurred. Structurall); though, <strong>the</strong>reis no difference between such historical explanations <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong>oretical predictions. There is, however, a pragmatic differencewhich explains why empiricists in particular stress<strong>the</strong> importance of a <strong>the</strong>ory's predictive power <strong>and</strong> are notcontent with testing it only vis-It-vis historical data. 22 Thereason for this is quite evident to anyone who was everengaged in <strong>the</strong> foolish game ofdata analyses. If<strong>the</strong> phenomenonto be explained has already occurred, it is easy as cake to22Por <strong>the</strong> emphasis placed on prediction by empiricist-positivists, see inparticular Milton Friedman, "The <strong>Method</strong>ology ofPositive <strong>Economic</strong>s" in Friedman,Essays in Positive <strong>Economic</strong>s (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 31


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>find all sorts of events that preceded it in time <strong>and</strong> couldpossibly be considered its cause. Moreover, ifwe don't wantto leng<strong>the</strong>n our list of possible causes by finding morepreceding variables, we can do <strong>the</strong> following (<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> ageof computers, it's even easier): We can take anyone of <strong>the</strong>preceding variables <strong>and</strong> tryout different functional relationshipsbetween it <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> variable to be explained-linear orcurvilinear ones, recursive or non-recursive functions, additiveor multiplicative relations, etc. Then one, two, three, wefind what we were looking for: a functional relationship thatfits <strong>the</strong> data. And you will find not just one but any amountof <strong>the</strong>m that you could possibly desire.But which of all <strong>the</strong>se preceding events, or of all <strong>the</strong>types of relationships, is <strong>the</strong> cause or <strong>the</strong> causally effectiverelation? There are no a priori considerations, according toempiricism, that could help us here. And that, <strong>the</strong>n, is <strong>the</strong>reason why empiricists emphasize <strong>the</strong> importance of predictions.In order to find out which one of <strong>the</strong>se manifoldhistorical explanations is indeed correct-or at least notfalse-we are asked to try <strong>the</strong>m out by using <strong>the</strong>m inpredicting events that have not yet occurred, see how good<strong>the</strong>y are, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby weed out <strong>the</strong> wrong explanations.So much for empiricism <strong>and</strong> its ideas about <strong>the</strong>or~histor~ <strong>and</strong> forecasting. I will not go into a detailed analysisof <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r or not this emphasis on predictivesuccess changes much, if anything at all, with respect to <strong>the</strong>ra<strong>the</strong>r evident relativistic implications of empiricism. Justrecall that according to its very own doctrine, nei<strong>the</strong>r apredictive confirmation nor a predictive falsification wouldhelp us ei<strong>the</strong>r in deciding whe<strong>the</strong>r a causal relationshipbetween a pair ofvariables did or did not exist. This shouldmake it appear ra<strong>the</strong>r doubtful that anything is gained bymaking prediction <strong>the</strong> cornerstone ofone's philosoph~32 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeI would like to challenge <strong>the</strong> very starting point of <strong>the</strong>empiricists' philosoph~ There are several conclusive refutationsof empiricism. I will show <strong>the</strong> empiricist distinctionbetween empirical <strong>and</strong> analytical knowledge to be plainly false<strong>and</strong> se1f-contradictor~2~That will <strong>the</strong>n lead us to developing<strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> position on <strong>the</strong>or)) histof)) <strong>and</strong> forecasting.This is empiricism's central claim: Empirical knowledgemust be verifiable or falsifiable by experience; <strong>and</strong> analyticalknowledge, which is not so verifiable or falsifiable, thuscannot contain any empirical knowledge. Ifthis is true, <strong>the</strong>nit is fair to ask: What <strong>the</strong>n is <strong>the</strong> status ofthis fundamentalstatement of empiricism? Evidently it must be ei<strong>the</strong>r analyticalor empirical.Let us first assume it is analytical. According to <strong>the</strong>empiricist doctrine, however, an analytical proposition isnothing but scribbles on paper, hot air, entirely void of anymeaningful content. It says nothing about anything real. Andhence one would have to conclude that empiricism could noteven say <strong>and</strong> mean what it seems to say <strong>and</strong> mean. Yet if, on<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, it says <strong>and</strong> means what we thought it did allalong, <strong>the</strong>n it does inform us about something real. As amatter offact, it informs us about <strong>the</strong> fundamental structureof rea1i~ It says that <strong>the</strong>re is nothing in reality that can beknown to be one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r prior to future experienceswhich may confirm or disconfirm our hypo<strong>the</strong>sis.And if this meaningful proposition is taken to be analytical,that is, as a statement that does not allow any falsification<strong>and</strong> whose truth can be established by an analysis of230n rationalist critiques of empiricism, see Kambartel, Erfahrung undStruktur; Br<strong>and</strong> Blanshard, Reason <strong>and</strong> Analysis (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1964);A. Pap, Semantics <strong>and</strong> Necessary Truth (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press,1958); Martin Hollis <strong>and</strong> Edward Nell, RJJtional <strong>Economic</strong> Man (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1975).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 33


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>its terms alone, one has no less than a glaring contradictionat h<strong>and</strong>. Empiricism itself would prove to be nothing butself-defeating nonsense. 24So perhaps we should choose <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r available option<strong>and</strong> declare <strong>the</strong> fundamental empiricist distinction betweenempirical <strong>and</strong> analytical knowledge an empirical statement.But <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> empiricist position would no longer carry anyweight whatsoever. For ifthis were done, it would have to beadmitted that <strong>the</strong> proposition-as an empiricalone-mightwellbe wrong <strong>and</strong> that one would be entitled to hear on <strong>the</strong> basis ofwhat criterion one would have to decide whe<strong>the</strong>r ornotit was.More decisivel~ as an empirical proposition, right or wrong,it could only state a historical fact, something like "allheretofore scrutinized propositions fall indeed into <strong>the</strong> twocategories analytical <strong>and</strong> empirical." The statement wouldbe entirely irrelevant for determining whe<strong>the</strong>r it would bepossible to produce propositions that are true a priori <strong>and</strong>are still empirical ones. Indeed, ifempiricism's central claimwere declared an empirical proposition, empiricism wouldcease altoge<strong>the</strong>r to be an epistemolog~ a logic of science,<strong>and</strong> would be no more than a completely arbitrary verbalconvention ofcalling certain arbitrary ways ofdealing withcertain statements certain arbitrary names. Empiricismwould be a position void of any justification.24Writes Mises in The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>:The essence oflogical positivism is to deny <strong>the</strong> cognitive value ofa prioriknowledge by pointing out that all a priori propositions are merelyanalytic. They do not provide new information, but are merely verbalor tautological, asserting what has already been implied in <strong>the</strong> definitions<strong>and</strong> premises. Only experience can lead to syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions.There is an obvious objection against this doctrine, viz., that thisproposition that <strong>the</strong>re are no syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori propositions is in itself-as <strong>the</strong> present writer thinks, false-a syn<strong>the</strong>tic a priori proposition,for it can manifestly not be established by experience. (p. 5)34 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeWhat does this first step in our criticism of empiricismprove? It proves evidently that <strong>the</strong> empiricist idea of knowledgeis wrong, <strong>and</strong> it proves this by means of a meaningful apriori argument. And in doing this, it shows that <strong>the</strong> Kantian<strong>and</strong> Misesian idea of true a priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions iscorrect. More specifically; it proves that <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history cannot be as depicted byempiricism. There must also be a realm of<strong>the</strong>ory-<strong>the</strong>orythat is empirically meaningful-which is categorically differentfrom <strong>the</strong> only idea of <strong>the</strong>ory empiricism admits tohaving existence. There must also be a priori <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>relationship between <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history <strong>the</strong>n must be different<strong>and</strong> more complicated than empiricism would have usbelieve. How different indeed will become apparentwhen I present ano<strong>the</strong>r argument against empiricism,ano<strong>the</strong>r a priori argument, <strong>and</strong> an a priori argument against<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis implied in empiricism that <strong>the</strong> relation between<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> empirical research is <strong>the</strong> same in every field ofknowledge.However appropriate <strong>the</strong> empiricist ideas may be indealing with <strong>the</strong> natural sciences (<strong>and</strong> I think <strong>the</strong>y areinappropriate even <strong>the</strong>re, but I cannot go into this here),25it is impossible to think that <strong>the</strong> methods ofempiricism canbe applicable in <strong>the</strong> social sciences.Actions are <strong>the</strong> field of phenomena which constituteswhat we regard as <strong>the</strong> subject matter of <strong>the</strong> social sciences.Empiricism claims that actions can <strong>and</strong> must be250n this see, in addition to <strong>the</strong> works cited in note 23, in particular H.Dingler, Die Ergreifung des Wirklichen (Munich: 1955); idem, Aujbau der exaktenFundamentalwissenschaft (MUnich: 1964; Paul Lorenzen, <strong>Method</strong>isches Denken(Frankfurt/M.: 1968); E Kambartel <strong>and</strong> J. Mittelstrass, eds., Zum normativenFundament der Wissenschaft (Frankfurt/M.: 1973); also my "In Defense ofExtremeRationalism." ,The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 35


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>explained, just as any o<strong>the</strong>r phenomenon, by means ofcausalhypo<strong>the</strong>ses which can be confirmed or falsified byexperience.26Now ifthis were <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong>n empiricism would be firstforced to assume-contrary to its own doctrine that no apriori knowledge about anything real exists-that time-invariantlyoperating causes with respect to actions exist.One would not know a priori which particular eventmight be <strong>the</strong> cause ofany particular action. But empiricismwants us to relate different experiences regarding sequencesof events as ei<strong>the</strong>r confirming or falsifying each o<strong>the</strong>r. Andif <strong>the</strong>y falsify each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>n we are to respond with areformulation of <strong>the</strong> original hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Yet in order to doso, we must assume a constancy over time in <strong>the</strong> operationof causes as such-<strong>and</strong> to know that causes for actions doexist is, of course, knowledge about <strong>the</strong> reality of actions.Without such an assumption regarding <strong>the</strong> existence ofcauses as such, different experiences can never be related toeach o<strong>the</strong>r as confirming or falsifying one ano<strong>the</strong>r. They aresimply unrelated, incommensurable observations. Here isone, <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r; <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> same or similar; or <strong>the</strong>yare different. Nothing else follows. 27In addition, <strong>the</strong>re is yet ano<strong>the</strong>r contradiction, <strong>and</strong>making it evident will immediately lead us to Mises's central261n addition to <strong>the</strong> literature cited in note 20 see, for instance, suchtypical empiricist products as Arthur Goldberger <strong>and</strong> Otis D. Duncan, eds.,Structural Equation Models in <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s (San Diego, Calif.: AcademicPress, 1973); H. B. Blalock, ed., Causal Inferences in Non-Experimental Research(Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1964); Arthur L. Stinchcombe,Constructing Social Theories (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World,1968).27On this <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> following, see Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichenSozialforschung, chapter 2, <strong>and</strong> "Is Research Based on Causal Scientific PrinciplesPossible in <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s?"36 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeinsight that <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history in<strong>the</strong> field of <strong>the</strong> social sciences is of an entirely differentnature than that in <strong>the</strong> natural sciences.What is this contradiction? If actions could indeed beconceived of as governed by time-invariantly operatingcauses, <strong>the</strong>n it is certainly appropriate to ask: But what <strong>the</strong>nabout explaining <strong>the</strong> explainers? What about causally predicting<strong>the</strong>ir actions? They are, after all, <strong>the</strong> persons whocarryon <strong>the</strong> very process of creating hypo<strong>the</strong>ses <strong>and</strong> ofverification <strong>and</strong> falsification.In order to assimilate confirming or falsifying experiences-toreplace old hypo<strong>the</strong>ses with new ones-one mustassumedly be able to learn from experience. Every empiricistis, ofcourse, forced to admit this. O<strong>the</strong>rwise why engage inempirical research at all?But if one can learn from experience in as yet unknownways, <strong>the</strong>n one admittedly cannot know at any given timewhat one will know at a later time <strong>and</strong>, accordingl~ howone will act on <strong>the</strong> basis of this knowledge. One can onlyreconstruct <strong>the</strong> causes ofone's actions after <strong>the</strong> event, as onecan explain one's knowledge only after one already possessesit. Indeed, no scientific advance could ever alter <strong>the</strong> fact thatone must regard one's knowledge <strong>and</strong> actions as unpredictableon <strong>the</strong> basis of constantly operating causes. One might holdthis conception of freedom to be an illusion. And one mightwell be correct from <strong>the</strong> point of view of a scientist withcognitive powers substantially superior to any human intelligence,or from <strong>the</strong> point of view of God. But we are notGod, <strong>and</strong> even if our freedom is illusory from His st<strong>and</strong>point<strong>and</strong> our actions follow a predictable path, for usthis is a necessary <strong>and</strong> unavoidable illusion. We cannotpredict in advance, on <strong>the</strong> basis of our previous states, <strong>the</strong>future states of our knowledge or <strong>the</strong> actions manifestingThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 37


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>that knowledge. We can only reconstruct <strong>the</strong>m after <strong>the</strong>event. 28Thus, <strong>the</strong> empiricist methodology is simply contradictorywhen applied to <strong>the</strong> field of knowledge <strong>and</strong> action-whichcontains knowledge as its necessary ingredient.The empiricist-minded social scientists who formulate predictionequations regarding social phenomena are simplydoing nonsense. Their activity ofengaging in an enterprisewhose outcome <strong>the</strong>y must admit <strong>the</strong>y do not yet kno~proves that what <strong>the</strong>y pretend to do cannot be done. AsMises puts it <strong>and</strong> has emphasized repeatedly: There are noempirical causal constants in <strong>the</strong> field of human action. 29By means ofa priori reasoning <strong>the</strong>n, one has establishedthis insight: Social history; as opposed to natural history;does not yield any knowledge that can be employed forpredictive purposes. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, social <strong>and</strong> economic historyrefers exclusively to <strong>the</strong> past. The outcome of research intohow <strong>and</strong> why people acted in <strong>the</strong> past has no systematicbearing on whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y will act <strong>the</strong> same way in <strong>the</strong>future. People can learn. It is absurd to assume that onecould predict in <strong>the</strong> present what one will know tomorrow<strong>and</strong> in what way tomorrow's knowledge will or will not bedifferent from today's.A person cannot predict today his dem<strong>and</strong> for sugar inone year any more than Einstein could have predicted <strong>the</strong>28Interestingly, this argument was first advanced by Karl R. Popper in <strong>the</strong>Preface to his The Poverty ofHistoricism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1957).However, Popper entirely failed to notice that such an argument actually invalidateshis own idea ofa methodological monism (Einheitswissenschaft) <strong>and</strong> demonstrates<strong>the</strong> inapplicability of his falsificationism in <strong>the</strong> field of human action <strong>and</strong>knowledge. See on this my Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung, pp.44-49; K. O. Apel, Die Erkliiren: *rstehen Kontroverse in transzendental-pragmatischerSicht (Frankfurt/M.: 1979), pp. 44-46, footnote 19.29Mises, Human Action, pp. 55-56.38 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppe<strong>the</strong>ory of relativity before he had actually developed it. Aperson cannot know today what he will know about sugarone year from no~ And he cannot know all <strong>the</strong> goods thatwill be competing against sugar for his money in a year. Hecan make a guess, of course. But since it must be admittedthat future states of knowledge cannot be predicted on <strong>the</strong>basis of constantly operating causes, a person cannot pretendto make a prediction of <strong>the</strong> same epistemological typeas, for instance, one regarding <strong>the</strong> future behavior of <strong>the</strong>moon, <strong>the</strong> wea<strong>the</strong>r, or <strong>the</strong> tides. Those are predictions thatcould legitimately make use of <strong>the</strong> assumption of time-invariantlyoperating causes. But a prediction about futuresugar dem<strong>and</strong> would be an entirely different thing.Provided social <strong>and</strong> economic history can only come upwith reconstructive explanations <strong>and</strong> never with explanationsthat have any systematic predictive relevance, ano<strong>the</strong>r extremelyimportant insight regarding <strong>the</strong> logic of empiricalsocial research follows. And this amounts to ano<strong>the</strong>r decisivecriticism ofempiricism, at least regarding its claim of beingan appropriate methodology for social science research.Recall what I said earlier about why it is that empiricismso strongly emphasizes <strong>the</strong> predictive function of explanatory<strong>the</strong>ories. For every phenomenon to be explained <strong>the</strong>reare a multitude ofpreceding events <strong>and</strong> a multitude offunctionalrelationships with such preceding events by which <strong>the</strong>phenomenon in question could possibly be explained. Butwhich of<strong>the</strong>se rival explanations is correct <strong>and</strong> which ones arenot? The empiricist answer was: Try to predict, <strong>and</strong> yoursuccess or failure in predicting future events will tell youwhich explanation is or is not correct. Evidentl~ this advicewon't do if <strong>the</strong>re are no time-invariantly operating causeswith respect to actions. What <strong>the</strong>n? Empiricism, ofcourse,cannot have an answer to this question.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 39


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Yet even ifactions cannot be predicted in any scientific wa)',this does not imply that one reconstructive historical explanationis just as good as any o<strong>the</strong>r. It would be regarded asabsurd if someone explained <strong>the</strong> fact that I moved fromGermany to <strong>the</strong> United States by pointing out, for example,that <strong>the</strong> corn in Michigan, prior to my decision, was experiencinga growth spurt <strong>and</strong> that this had caused my decision.But why not, assuming here that <strong>the</strong> event regardingMichigan's corn indeed happened prior to my decision? Thereason is, ofcourse, that I will tell you that Michigan's cornhad no relevance for my decision. And insofar as anything isknown about me at all, it can be recognized that this is indeed<strong>the</strong> case.But how can you recognize this? The answer is byunderst<strong>and</strong>ing my motives <strong>and</strong> interests, my convictions<strong>and</strong> aspirations, my normative orientations, <strong>and</strong> my concreteperceptions resulting in this action. How do we underst<strong>and</strong>somebody <strong>and</strong>, moreover, how do we verify that ourunderst<strong>and</strong>ing is indeed correct? As regards <strong>the</strong> first part of<strong>the</strong> question-one underst<strong>and</strong>s somebody by engaging in apseudo-communication <strong>and</strong> interaction with him. I saypseudo because, evident1~ we cannot engage in an actualcommunication with Caesar in order to fmd out why hecrossed <strong>the</strong> Rubicon. But we could study his writings <strong>and</strong>compare his convictions expressed <strong>the</strong>rein with his actualdeeds; we could study <strong>the</strong> writings <strong>and</strong> actions of contemporaries<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby try to underst<strong>and</strong> Caesar's personali~his time, <strong>and</strong> his particular role <strong>and</strong> position within his. 30tIme.300n <strong>the</strong> logic ofhisto~ see Mises, Theory <strong>and</strong> History, chapter 14; The UltimateFoundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>, pp. 45-51; Human Action, pp. 47-51, 59-64.40 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann HoppeAs regards <strong>the</strong> second part of<strong>the</strong> question-<strong>the</strong> problemof verification ofhistorical explanations-one has to admitfrom <strong>the</strong> outset that <strong>the</strong>re is no absolutely clear-cut criterionthat would allow one to decide which one of two rivalexplanations, both equally based on underst<strong>and</strong>ing, is definitelycorrect <strong>and</strong> which one is not. History is not an exactscience in <strong>the</strong> same sense as <strong>the</strong> natural sciences are exactsciences or in <strong>the</strong> very different sense in which economics isan exact science.Even if two historians agree in <strong>the</strong>ir description offacts<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir assessment offactors ofinfluence for a given actionto be explained, <strong>the</strong>y might still disagree on <strong>the</strong> weight thatshould be assigned to such factors in bringing about <strong>the</strong>action. And <strong>the</strong>re would be no way to decide <strong>the</strong> matter ina completely unambiguous wa~31Yet let me not be misunderstood here. There is none<strong>the</strong>lesssome sort of truth-criterion for historical explanations.It is a criterion that does not eliminate all possible disagreementsamong historians, but that still excludes <strong>and</strong> disqualifiesa wide range of explanations. The criterion is that anytrue historical e~planation must be of such a kind that <strong>the</strong>actor whose actions are to be explained must, in principle, beable to verify <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> explanatory factors asbeing those that contributed to his acting <strong>the</strong> way he did. 32 Thekey phrase here is: in principle. N aturall~ Caesar could notpossibly verify our explanation for his crossing <strong>the</strong> Rubicon.Moreovet; he might actually have strong reasons not to verify <strong>the</strong>explanation even ifhe could, since such a verification mightconflict with some o<strong>the</strong>r objectives that he might have.31Mises, Human Action, pp. 57-58.320n <strong>the</strong> logic ofhistorical <strong>and</strong> sociological reconstruction <strong>and</strong> verification,see also Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung, pp. 33-38.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 41


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Also, to say that any true explanation must be verifiableby <strong>the</strong> actor in question is not to say that every actor isalways best qualified to be his own explainer. It may be thatEinstein.can explain better than anyone else why <strong>and</strong> howhe came up with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of relativity when he did. Butthis might not be so. As a matter of fact, it may well bepossible that a historian ofscience may underst<strong>and</strong> Einstein<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> influences leading to his discovery better than hehimself did or could. And this would be possible because<strong>the</strong> influencing factors or <strong>the</strong> rules that determined one'sactions might only be subconscious. 33 Or <strong>the</strong>y might be soobvious that one would fail to notice <strong>the</strong>m simply onaccount of this.The following analogy may be quite helpful in underst<strong>and</strong>ing<strong>the</strong> curious fact that o<strong>the</strong>rs might underst<strong>and</strong> aperson better than <strong>the</strong> person himself. Take, for example, apublic speech. Ofcourse, to a large extent <strong>the</strong> person giving<strong>the</strong> speech can probably give reasons for saying what he says<strong>and</strong> formulate <strong>the</strong> influences that led him to see things <strong>the</strong>way he does. He can probably do so better than anyone else.And yet, in saying what he says, he follows rules habitually<strong>and</strong> unconsciously that he could hardly or only with greatdifficulties make explicit. He also follows certain rules ofgrammar when he says what he says. But quite often hewould be completely unable to formulate <strong>the</strong>se rules eventhough <strong>the</strong>y clearly influence his actions. The historian whounderst<strong>and</strong>s someone's actions better than <strong>the</strong> person himselfis quite analogous to <strong>the</strong> grammarian analyzing <strong>the</strong>sentence structure of <strong>the</strong> public speaker. Both reconstruct330n <strong>the</strong> logic ofpsychoanalytic explanation <strong>and</strong> verification, see A. MacIntyre,The Unconscious (London: Duckworth, 1958); ]iirgen Habermas, Erkenntnisundlnteresse (Frankfurt/M.: 1968), chapter 2; on <strong>the</strong> relevance ofpsychoanalysisalso Mises, Human Action, p. 12.42 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppe<strong>and</strong> explicitly formulate <strong>the</strong> rules that are actually followed,but that could not, or only with extreme difficulties, beformulated by <strong>the</strong> speaker himself. 34The speaker may not be able to formulate all <strong>the</strong> rulesthat he follows <strong>and</strong> may need <strong>the</strong> professional historian orgrammarian to help him. But it is of great importance torealize that <strong>the</strong> truth criterion for <strong>the</strong> grammarian's explanationwould none<strong>the</strong>less be that <strong>the</strong> speaker would have tobe able-in principle-to verify <strong>the</strong> correctness of<strong>the</strong> explanationafter whatwas previously known implicitly was madeexplicit. In order for <strong>the</strong> grammarian's or historian's explanationsto be correct, <strong>the</strong> actor would need to be able torecognize <strong>the</strong>se rules as being those whichindeed influencedhis actions. So much for <strong>the</strong> logic of historical research asnecessarily reconstructive research based on underst<strong>and</strong>ing.35The argument establishing <strong>the</strong> impossibility of causalpredictions in <strong>the</strong> field of human knowledge <strong>and</strong> actionsnow might have left <strong>the</strong> impression that if this is so, <strong>the</strong>nforecasting can be nothing but successful or unsuccessfulguessing. This impression, however, would be just as wrong340n <strong>the</strong> logic of linguistic explanations as involving <strong>the</strong> reconstruction ofrules which require confirmation through <strong>the</strong> "intuitive knowledge" of"competentspeakers," see Noam Chomsky, Aspects of <strong>the</strong> Theory ofSyntax (Cambridge:M.I:r. Press, 1965); also K. O. Ape!, 'l:Noam Chomskys Sprach<strong>the</strong>orie und diePhilosophie der Gegenwart" in Ape!, 1ransformation der Philosophie, vol. 2 (Frankfurt/M.:1973).35For important critiques of <strong>the</strong> empiricist-positivist philosophy of <strong>the</strong>empirical social sciences, <strong>and</strong> explanations of social research as based on reconstructiveunderst<strong>and</strong>ing, see also K. O. Ape!, Iransformation der Philosophie; idem,Die Erkliiren: "'Wrstehen Kontroverse in transzendental-pragmatischer Sicht; PeterWinch, The Idea ofa Social <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> Its Relation to Philosophy (Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s,N.J.: Humanities Press, 1970); idem, Ethics <strong>and</strong> Action (London: Routledge<strong>and</strong> Kegan Paul, 1972); Jiirgen Habermas, Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften(Frankfurt/M.: 1970); G. H. von Wright, Explanation <strong>and</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong>ing (Ithaca,N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1971).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 43


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>as it would be wrong to think that one can predict humanaction in <strong>the</strong> same way as one can predict <strong>the</strong> growing stagesof apples. It is here where <strong>the</strong> unique Misesian insight into<strong>the</strong> interplay of economic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history enters <strong>the</strong>. 36pIcture.In fact, <strong>the</strong> reason why <strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic futurecannot be regarded as entirely <strong>and</strong> absolutely uncertainshould not be too hard to underst<strong>and</strong>: The impossibility ofcausal predictions in <strong>the</strong> field ofaction was proven by meansof an a priori argument. And this argument incorporated apriori true knowledge about actions as such: that <strong>the</strong>ycannot be conceived of as governed by time-invariantlyoperating causes.Thus, while economic forecasting will indeed always bea systematically unteachable art, it is at <strong>the</strong> same time truethat all economic forecasts must be thought of as beingconstrained by <strong>the</strong> existence of a priori knowledge aboutactions as such. 37Take, for example, <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory of mone~ <strong>the</strong>praxeological proposition that if you increase <strong>the</strong> quantity360n <strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history, see in particular Mises, HumanAction, pp. 51-59; <strong>and</strong> Epistemological Problems of<strong>Economic</strong>s, chapters 2-3.37The former <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>and</strong> neo-historicist-hermeneutician-nihilist LudwigLachmann, who repeats ad nauseam <strong>the</strong> unpredictability of future states ofknowledge (see his "From Mises to Shackle: An Essay on <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> Kaleidic Society," Journal of<strong>Economic</strong> Literature 54 (1976); The Market as an<strong>Economic</strong> Process (New York: Basil Blackwell, 1986), entirely misses recognizingthis latter point. In fact, his arguments are simply self-defeating. For evidently heclaims to know for certain <strong>the</strong> unknowability offuture knowledge <strong>and</strong>, by logicalextension, of actions. Yet <strong>the</strong>n he does know something about future knowledge<strong>and</strong> action. He must know something about knowledge <strong>and</strong> action as such. Andthis, precisely, is what praxeology claims to be: knowledge regarding actions assuch, <strong>and</strong> (as I have explained in my "On Praxeology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> PraxeologicalFoundations of Epistemology <strong>and</strong> Ethics," p. 49 below) knowledge about <strong>the</strong>structure which any future knowledge must have by virtue of <strong>the</strong> fact that itinvariably must be knowledge of actors.44 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeof money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money stays constant, <strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong> purchasing power of money will fall. Our a prioriknowledge about actions as such informs us that it is impossibleto predict scientifically whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> quantity ofmoney will be increased, decreased or left unchanged. Noris it possible to predict scientifically whe<strong>the</strong>r or not, regardlessof what happens to <strong>the</strong> quantity of mone~ <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> formoney to be held in cash balances will go up or down or stay<strong>the</strong> same. We cannot claim to be able to predict such thingsbecause we cannot predict future states of knowledge ofpeople. And yet <strong>the</strong>se states evidently influence what happenswith respect to <strong>the</strong> quantity of money <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> formone)!. Then, our <strong>the</strong>or~ our praxeological knowledge incorporatedin <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>or)!, has a ra<strong>the</strong>r limited usefulnessfor one's business ofpredicting <strong>the</strong> economic future.The <strong>the</strong>ory would not allow one to predict future economicevents even if, sa); it is an established fact that <strong>the</strong>quantity of money had been exp<strong>and</strong>ed. One would still beunable to predict what would happen to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> formonc)!. And though, ofcourse, concurrent events regarding<strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money do affect <strong>the</strong> shape ofthings to come(<strong>and</strong> cancel, increase, decrease, accelerate, or decelerate <strong>the</strong>effects stemming from <strong>the</strong> source of an increased moneysupply), such concurrent changes cannot in principle bepredicted or experimentally held constant. It is an outrightabsurdity to conceive ofsubjective knowledge, whose everychange has an impact on actions, as predictable on <strong>the</strong> basisof antecedent variables <strong>and</strong> as capable of being held constant.The very experimenter who wanted to hold knowledgeconstant would, in fact, have to presuppose that hisknowledge, specifically his knowledge regarding <strong>the</strong> experiment'soutcome, could not be assumed to be constant overtime.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 45


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>The quantity <strong>the</strong>ory of money <strong>the</strong>n cannot render anyspecific economic event, certain or probable, on <strong>the</strong> basis ofa formula employing prediction constants. However, <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory would none<strong>the</strong>less restrict <strong>the</strong> range of possiblycorrect predictions. And itwould do this not as an empirical<strong>the</strong>or~ but ra<strong>the</strong>r as a praxeological <strong>the</strong>or~ acting as alogical constraint on our prediction-making. 38 Predictionsthat are not in line with such knowledge (in our case: <strong>the</strong>quantity <strong>the</strong>ory) are systematically flawed <strong>and</strong> making <strong>the</strong>mleads to systematically increasing numbers of forecastingerrors,. This does not mean that someone who based hispredictions on correct praxeological reasoning would necessarilyhave to be a better predictor of future economicevents than someone who arrived at his predictions throughlogically flawed deliberations <strong>and</strong> chains of reasoning. Itmeans that in <strong>the</strong> long run <strong>the</strong> praxeologically enlightenedforecaster would average better than <strong>the</strong> unenlightenedones.It is possible to make <strong>the</strong> wrong prediction in spite of<strong>the</strong> fact that one has correctly identified <strong>the</strong> event "increasein <strong>the</strong> money supply" <strong>and</strong> in spite of one's praxeologicallycorrect reasoning that such an event is by logical necessityconnected with <strong>the</strong> event "drop in <strong>the</strong> purchasing power ofmone)!." For one might go wrong predicting what will occurto <strong>the</strong> event "dem<strong>and</strong> for mone)!." One may have predicteda constant dem<strong>and</strong> for mone~ but <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> might actuallyincrease. Thus <strong>the</strong> predicted inflation might not showup as expected. And on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, it is equally possiblethat a person could make a correct forecast, Le., <strong>the</strong>re willbe no drop in purchasing power, in spite of<strong>the</strong> fact that he380n <strong>the</strong> logic of social <strong>and</strong> economic forecasting, see also Hoppe, "InDefense ofExtreme Rationalism," sections 3, 4.46 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppewas wrongly convinced that a rise in <strong>the</strong> quantity ofmoneyhad nothing to do with money's purchasing power. For itmay be that ano<strong>the</strong>r concurrent change occurred (<strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>for money increased) which counteracted his wrongassessment of causes <strong>and</strong> consequences <strong>and</strong> accidentallyhappened to make his prediction right.However, <strong>and</strong> this brings me back to my point thatpraxeology logically constrains our predictions ofeconomicevents: What if we assume that all forecasters, includingthose with <strong>and</strong> without sound praxeological knowledge, areon <strong>the</strong> average equally well-equipped to anticipate o<strong>the</strong>rconcurrent changes? What if<strong>the</strong>y are on <strong>the</strong> average equallylucky guessers of<strong>the</strong> social <strong>and</strong> economic future? Evidentl)',we must conclude <strong>the</strong>n that forecasters making predictionsin recognition of<strong>and</strong> in accordance with praxeological lawslike <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory of money will be more successfulthan that group offorecasters which is ignorant of praxeolog~It is impossible to build a prediction formula whichemploys <strong>the</strong> assumption of time-invariantly operatingcauses that would enable us to scientifically forecast changesin <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for mone~ The dem<strong>and</strong> for money is necessarilydependent on people's future states ofknowledge, <strong>and</strong>future knowledge is unpredictable. And thus praxeologicalknowledge has very limited predictive utili~39Yet ofall forecasters who correctly forecast that a changesuch as an increase in <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> for money will take place<strong>and</strong> who equally correctly perceive that an increase in <strong>the</strong>39See also MurrayN. Rothbard,Power<strong>and</strong>Market (Kansas City, Kans.: SheedAndrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1977), pp. 256-58, on <strong>the</strong> different function ofeconomic<strong>the</strong>orizing in a free market environment vs. an environment hampered by governmentintervention.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 47


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>quantity of money has indeed happened, only those whorecognize <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney will make a correctprediction. And those whose convictions are at variancewith praxeology will necessarily go wrong.To underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic ofeconomic forecasting <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>practical function of praxeological reasoning, <strong>the</strong>n, is toview <strong>the</strong> a priori <strong>the</strong>orems ofeconomics as acting as logicalconstraints on empirical predictions <strong>and</strong> as imposing logicallimits on what can or cannot happen in <strong>the</strong> future.* * * * *48 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


ON PRAXEOLOGYAND THE PRAXEOLOGICALFOUNDATION OF EPISTEMOLOGYIAs have most great <strong>and</strong> innovative economists, Ludwigvon Mises intensively <strong>and</strong> repeatedly analyzed<strong>the</strong> problem of <strong>the</strong> logical status of economicpropositions, i.e., how we come to know <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> how wevalidate <strong>the</strong>m. Indeed, Mises ranks foremost among illose whohold that such a concern is indispensable in order to achievesystematic progress in economics. For any misconceptionregarding <strong>the</strong> answer to such fundamental questions ofone'sintellectual enterprise would naturally have to lead to intellectualdisastet; i.e., to false economic doctrines. Accordingl~ threeof Mises's books are devoted entirely to clarifying <strong>the</strong> logicalfoundations ofeconomics: His early Epistemological Problems of<strong>Economic</strong>s, published in German in 1933; his Theory <strong>and</strong>History of 1957; <strong>and</strong> his Ultimate Foundations of <strong>Economic</strong><strong>Science</strong> of 1962, Mises's last book, appearing when he wasalready well past his eightieth birthda~ And his works in <strong>the</strong>field ofeconomics proper also invariably display <strong>the</strong> importancewhich Mises attached to <strong>the</strong> analysis ofepistemologicalThis essay is from Hans-Hermann Hoppe, The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Ethics ofPripateProperty (Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1993), pp. 141-64 <strong>and</strong> it is reprintedhere with permission of Kluwer Academic Publishers.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 49


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>problems. Most characteristicall~Human Action, his masterpiece,deals in its first hundred-odd pages exclusively with suchproblems, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r nearly 800 pages of <strong>the</strong> book arepermeated with epistemological considerations.Quite in line with <strong>the</strong> tradition of Mises, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>foundations ofeconomics are also <strong>the</strong> subject ofthis chapter.I have set myself a twofold goal. First, I want to explain <strong>the</strong>solution which Mises advances regarding <strong>the</strong> problem of<strong>the</strong>ultimate foundation of economic science, i.e., his idea ofa pure <strong>the</strong>ory ofaction, or praxeolog~as he himself termsit. And secondl~ I want to demonstrate why Mises'ssolution is much more than just an incontestable insightinto <strong>the</strong> nature of economics <strong>and</strong> economic propositions.It provides an insight that also enables us to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>the</strong> foundation on which epistemology ultimately rests. Infact, as <strong>the</strong> title of<strong>the</strong> chapter suggests, I want to show thatit is praxeology which must be regarded as <strong>the</strong> very foundationof epistemolog); <strong>and</strong> hence that Mises, aside from hisgreat achievements as an economist, also contributed pathbreakinginsights regarding <strong>the</strong> justification of <strong>the</strong> entireenterprise of rationalist philosoph~40IILet me turn to Mises's solution. What is <strong>the</strong> logicalstatus of typical economic propositions such as <strong>the</strong> law ofmarginal utility (that whenever <strong>the</strong> supply ofa good whose40See on <strong>the</strong> following also my Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung.Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung von Soziologie und Okonomie; idem, "IsResearch Based on Causal Scientific Principles Possible in <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s?,"chapter 7); idem, "In Defense of Extreme Rationalism."50 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeunits are regarded as of equal serviceability by a personincreases by one additional unit, <strong>the</strong> value attached to thisunit must decrease as it can only be employed as a meansfor <strong>the</strong> attainment of a goal that is considered less valuablethan <strong>the</strong> least valuable goal previously satisfied by a unit ofthis good); or of <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney (that whenever<strong>the</strong> quantity of money is increased while <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>for money to be held in cash reserve on h<strong>and</strong> is unchanged,<strong>the</strong> purchasing power of money will fall)?In formulating his answer, Mises faced a double challenge.On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>re was <strong>the</strong> answer offered bymodern empiricism. The Vienna Ludwig von Mises knewwas in fact one of <strong>the</strong> early centers of <strong>the</strong> empiricist movement:a movement which was <strong>the</strong>n on <strong>the</strong> verge of establishingitself as <strong>the</strong> dominant academic philosophy of <strong>the</strong>Western world for several decades, <strong>and</strong> which to this veryday shapes <strong>the</strong> image that an overwhelming majority ofeconomists have of <strong>the</strong>ir own discipline. 41Empiricism considers nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural sciences asits model. According to empiricism, <strong>the</strong> aforementionedexamples of economic propositions have <strong>the</strong> same logical410n <strong>the</strong> Vienna Circle see ~ Kraft, Der Wiener Kreis (Vienna: Springer,1968); for empiricist-positivist interpretations of economics see such representativeworks as Terence W Hutchison, The Significance <strong>and</strong> Basic Postulatesof<strong>Economic</strong> Theory [Hutchison, an adherent of<strong>the</strong> Popperian variant of empiricism,has since become much less enthusiastic about <strong>the</strong> prospects of a Popperizedeconomics-see, for instance, his Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Ignorance in<strong>Economic</strong>s-yet he still sees no alternative but to cling to Popper's falsificationismanyway.]; Milton Friedman, "The <strong>Method</strong>ology of Positive <strong>Economic</strong>s," inidem, Essays in Positive <strong>Economic</strong>s; Mark Blaug, The <strong>Method</strong>ology.of<strong>Economic</strong>s; apositivist account by a participant in Mises's Privat Seminar in Vienna is EKaufmann, <strong>Method</strong>ology of <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s; <strong>the</strong> dominance of empiricism ineconomics is documented by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>re is probably not a singletextbook, which does not explicitly classify economics as-what else?-anempirical (a posteriori) science.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 51


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>status as laws of nature: Like laws of nature <strong>the</strong>y statehypo<strong>the</strong>tical relationships between two or more events,essentially in <strong>the</strong> form of if-<strong>the</strong>n statements. And likehypo<strong>the</strong>ses of <strong>the</strong> natural sciences, <strong>the</strong> propositions ofeconomics require continual testing vis-a-vis experience. Aproposition regarding <strong>the</strong> relationship between economicevents can never be validated once <strong>and</strong> for all with certain~Instead, it is forever subject to <strong>the</strong> outcome of contingent,future experiences. Such experience might confirm <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis.But this would not prove <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis to be true,since <strong>the</strong> economic proposition would have used generalterms (in philosophical terminology: universals) in its descriptionof <strong>the</strong> related events, <strong>and</strong> thus would apply to anindefinite number of cases or instances, <strong>the</strong>reby alwaysleaving room for possibly falsifying future experiences. Alla confirmation would prove is that <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis had notyet turned out wrong. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> experiencemight falsify <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. This would surely prove thatsomething was wrong with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis as it stood. Butit would not prove that <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sized relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong> specified events could never be observed. Itwould merely show that considering <strong>and</strong> controlling inone's observations only what up to now had been actuallyaccounted for <strong>and</strong> controlled, <strong>the</strong> relationship had not yetshown up. It cannot be ruled out, however, that it mightshow up as soon as some o<strong>the</strong>r circumstances have beencontrolled.The attitude that this philosophy fuels <strong>and</strong> that hasindeed become characteristic of most contemporary economists<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir way of conducting <strong>the</strong>ir business is one ofskepticism: <strong>the</strong> motto being "nothing can be known withcertainty to be impossible in <strong>the</strong> realm of economic phenomena."Even more precisel~ since empiricism conceives52 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppeof economic phenomena as objective data, extending inspace <strong>and</strong> subject to quantifiable measurement-in strictanalogy to <strong>the</strong> phenomena of <strong>the</strong> natural sciences-<strong>the</strong>peculiar skepticism of <strong>the</strong> empiricist economist may bedescribed as that ofa social engineer who will not guaranteeanyth· Ing.42The o<strong>the</strong>r challenge came from <strong>the</strong> side of<strong>the</strong> historicistschool. Indeed, during Mises's life in Austria <strong>and</strong> Switzerl<strong>and</strong>,<strong>the</strong> historicist philosophy was <strong>the</strong> prevailing ideologyof <strong>the</strong> German-speaking universities <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir establishment.With <strong>the</strong> upsurge of empiricism this formerprominence has been reduced considerabl~ But overroughly <strong>the</strong> last decade historicism has regained momentumamong <strong>the</strong> Western world's academia. Today it is with useverywhere under <strong>the</strong> names of hermeneutics, rhetoric,deconstructionism, <strong>and</strong> epistemological anarchism. 43For historicism, <strong>and</strong> most conspicuously for its contemporaryversions, <strong>the</strong> model is not nature but a literary text.<strong>Economic</strong> phenomena, according to <strong>the</strong> historicist doctrine,are not objective magnitudes that can be measured. Instead,<strong>the</strong>y are subjective expressions <strong>and</strong> interpretations unfoldingin history to be understood <strong>and</strong> interpreted by <strong>the</strong> economist420n <strong>the</strong> relativistic consequences ofempiricism-positivism see also Hoppe,A Theory ofSocialism <strong>and</strong> Capitalism (Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989),chapter 6; idem, "The Intellectual Cover for Socialism."43See Ludwig von Mises, The Historical Setting of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> School of<strong>Economic</strong>s (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1984); idem, Erinnerungen(Stuttgart: Gustav Fischer, 1978); idem, Theory <strong>and</strong> History, chapter 10; MurrayN. Rothbard, Ludwig von Mises: Schola1j Creat01; Hero (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig vonMises Institute, 1988); for a critical survey ofhistoricist ideas see also Karl Popper,The Poverty ofHistoricism; for a representative of<strong>the</strong> older version of a historicistinterpretation of economics see Werner Sombart, Die drei Nationalokonomien(Munich: Duncker & Humblot, 1930); for <strong>the</strong> modern, hermeneutical twistDonald McCloskey, The Rhetoric of<strong>Economic</strong>s (Madison: University ofWisconsinPress, 1985); Ludwig Lachmann, "From Mises to Shackle: An Essay on <strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Kaleidic Society,"Journal of<strong>Economic</strong> Literature (1976).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 53


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>just as a literary text unfolds before <strong>and</strong> is interpreted by itsreader. As subjective creations, <strong>the</strong> sequence of <strong>the</strong>ir eventsfollows no objective law. Nothing in <strong>the</strong> literary text, <strong>and</strong>nothing in <strong>the</strong> sequence of historical expressions <strong>and</strong>interpretations is governed by constant relations. Of course,certain literary texts actually exist, <strong>and</strong> so do certain sequencesofhistorical events. But this by no means implies that anythinghad to happen in <strong>the</strong> order it did. It simply occurred. In <strong>the</strong>same wa~ however, as one can always invent different literarystories, history <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sequence of historical events,too, might have happened in an entirely differentwa~ Moreover,according to historicism, <strong>and</strong> particularly visible in itsmodern hermeneutical version, <strong>the</strong> formation of<strong>the</strong>se alwayscontingently related human expressions <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir interpretationsis also not constrained by any objective la'W In literaryproduction anything can be expressed or interpreted concerningeverything; <strong>and</strong>, along <strong>the</strong> same line, historical <strong>and</strong>economic events are whatever someone expresses or interprets<strong>the</strong>m to be, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir description by <strong>the</strong> historian <strong>and</strong>economist is <strong>the</strong>n whatever he expresses or interprets <strong>the</strong>sepast subjective events to have been.The attitude that historicist philosophy generates is oneof relativism. Its motto is "everything is possible." Unconstrainedby any objective la\\; for <strong>the</strong> historicist-hermeneuticianhistory <strong>and</strong> economics, along with literary criticism,are matters of es<strong>the</strong>tics. And accordingl~ his output takeson <strong>the</strong> form of disquisitions on what someone feels aboutwhat he feels was felt by somebody else-a literary formwhich we are only too familiar with, in particular in suchfields as sociology <strong>and</strong> political science. 44440n <strong>the</strong> extreme relativism of historicism-hermeneutics see Hoppe, "In DefenseofExtreme Rationalism"; Murray N. Rothbard, "The Hermeneutical InvasionofPhilosophy <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s," Review of<strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s (1988); Henry Veatch,54 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeI trust that one senses intuitively that something isseriously amiss in both <strong>the</strong> empiricist as well as <strong>the</strong> historicistphilosophies. Their epistemological accounts do noteven seem to fit <strong>the</strong>ir own self-chosen models: nature on <strong>the</strong>one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> literary texts on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. And in any case,regarding economic propositions such as <strong>the</strong> law of marginalutility or <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney <strong>the</strong>ir accountsseem to be simply wrong. The law of marginal utilitycertainly does not strike one as a hypo<strong>the</strong>tical law subjectforever for its validation to confirming or disconfirmingexperiences popping up here or <strong>the</strong>re. And to conceive of<strong>the</strong> phenomena talked about in <strong>the</strong> law as quantifiablemagnitudes seems to be nothing but ridiculous. Nor does<strong>the</strong> historicist interpretation seem to be any better. To thinkthat <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> events referred to in <strong>the</strong>quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney can be undone ifone only wishedto do so seems absurd. And <strong>the</strong> idea appears no less absurdthat concepts such as money; dem<strong>and</strong> for money; <strong>and</strong> purchasingpower are formed without any objective constraints<strong>and</strong> refer merely to whimsical subjective creations. Instead,contrary to <strong>the</strong> empiricist doctrine, both examples of economicpropositions appear to be logically true <strong>and</strong> to referto events which are subjective in nature. And contrary tohistoricism, it would seem that what <strong>the</strong>y state, <strong>the</strong>n, couldnot possibly be undone in all ofhistory <strong>and</strong> would containconceptual distinctions which, while referring to subjectiveevents, were none<strong>the</strong>less objectively constrained, <strong>and</strong> wouldincorporate universally valid knowledge."Deconstruction in Philosophy: Has Rorty Made it <strong>the</strong> Denouement ofContemporaryAnalytical Philosophy," Review ofMetaphysics (1985); Jonathan Barnes, '~Kind of Integrity," <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s Newsletter (Summer 1987); David Gordon,Hermeneutics vs. <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s (Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig von Mises Institute,Occasional Paper Series, 1987); for a brilliant critique of contemporary sociologysee St. Andreski, Social <strong>Science</strong> as Sorcery (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1973).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 55


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Like most of <strong>the</strong> better known economists before him,Mises shares <strong>the</strong>se intuitions. 45 Yet in quest of<strong>the</strong> foundationofeconomics, Mises goes beyond intuition. He takes on <strong>the</strong>challenge posed by empiricism <strong>and</strong> historicism in order toreconstruct systematically <strong>the</strong> basis on which <strong>the</strong>se intuitionscan be understood as correct <strong>and</strong> justified. He <strong>the</strong>rebydoes not want to help bring about a new discipline ofeconomics. But in explaining what formerly had only beengrasped intuitivel~ Mises goes far beyond what had everbeen done before. In reconstructing <strong>the</strong> rational foundationsof <strong>the</strong> economists' intuitions, he assures us of <strong>the</strong>proper path for any future development in economics <strong>and</strong>safeguards us against systematic intellectual error.Empiricism <strong>and</strong> historicism, Mises notes at <strong>the</strong> outset ofhis reconstruction, are self-contradictory doctrines. 46 Theempiricist notion that all events, natural or economic, areonly hypo<strong>the</strong>tically related is contradicted by <strong>the</strong> messageof this very basic empiricist proposition itself: For if thisproposition were regarded as itselfbeing merely hypo<strong>the</strong>ticallytrue, i.e., a hypo<strong>the</strong>tically true proposition regarding hypo<strong>the</strong>ticallytrue propositions, it would not even qualify as anepistemological pronouncement. For it would <strong>the</strong>n provideno justification whatsoever for <strong>the</strong> claim that economic45Regarding <strong>the</strong> epistemological views of such predecessors as J. B. Say;Nassau W. Senior, J. E. Cairnes, John Stuart Mill, Carl Menger, <strong>and</strong> Friedrich vonWieser see Ludwig von Mises, Epistemological Problems of<strong>Economic</strong>s, pp. 17-23;also Murray N. Rothbard, "Praxeology: The <strong>Method</strong>ology of <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s,"in Edwin Dolan, ed., The Foundations ofModern <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s (KansasCity: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976).461n addition to Mises's works cited at <strong>the</strong> outset of this chapter <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>literature mentioned in note 40, see Murray N. Rothbard, Individualism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>Philosophy of<strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s (San Francisco: Cato Institute, 1979); for a splendidphilosophical critique of empiricist economics see Hollis <strong>and</strong> Nell, Rational<strong>Economic</strong> Man; as particularly valuable general defenses of rationalism as againstempiricism <strong>and</strong> relativism-without reference to economics, however,-see Blanshard,Reason <strong>and</strong> Analysis; Kambartel, Erfahrung und Struktur.56 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppepropositions are not, <strong>and</strong> cannot be, categoricall~ or a prioritrue, as our intuition informs us <strong>the</strong>y are. If, however, <strong>the</strong>basic empiricist premise were assumed to be categoricallytrue itself, i.e., if we assume that one could say somethinga priori true about <strong>the</strong> way events are related, <strong>the</strong>n thiswould belie its very own <strong>the</strong>sis that empirical knowledgemust invariably be hypo<strong>the</strong>tical knowledge, thus makingroom for a discipline such as economics claiming to producea priori valid empirical knowledge. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> empiricist<strong>the</strong>sis that economic phenomena must be conceived of asobservable <strong>and</strong> measurable magnitudes-analogous tothose of<strong>the</strong> natural sciences-is rendered inconclusive, too,on its own account: For, obviousl~ empiricism wants toprovide us with meaningful empirical knowledge when itinforms us that our economic concepts are grounded inobservations. And yet, <strong>the</strong> concepts of observation <strong>and</strong>measurement <strong>the</strong>mselves, which empiricism must employ inclaiming what it does, are both obviously not derived fromobservational experience in <strong>the</strong> sense that concepts such ashens <strong>and</strong> eggs or apples <strong>and</strong> pears are. One cannot observesomeone making an observation or measurement. Ra<strong>the</strong>r,one must first underst<strong>and</strong> what observations <strong>and</strong> measurementsare in order to <strong>the</strong>n be able to interpret certainobservable phenomena as <strong>the</strong> making of an observation or<strong>the</strong> taking of a measurement. Thus, contrary to its owndoctrine, empiricism is compelled to admit that <strong>the</strong>re isempirical knowledge which is based on underst<strong>and</strong>ing-justas according to our intuitions economic propositions claimto be based on underst<strong>and</strong>ing-ra<strong>the</strong>r than on observations.4747For an elaborate defense of epistemological dualism see also Apel, 1Yansformationdcr Philosophic) 2 vals. <strong>and</strong> Habermas, Zur Logik der Sozialwissenschaften.The Ludwig van Mises Institute • 57


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>And regarding historicism, its self-contradictions are noless manifest. For if, as historicism claims, historical <strong>and</strong>economic events-which it conceives of as sequences ofsubjectively understood ra<strong>the</strong>r than observed events-arenot governed by any constant, time-invariant relations, <strong>the</strong>nthis very proposition also cannot claim to say anythingconstantly true about history <strong>and</strong> economics. Instead, itwould be a proposition with, so to speak, a fleeting truthvalue: it may be true now; ifwe wish it so, yet possibly falsea moment later, in case we do not, with no one ever knowinganything about whe<strong>the</strong>r we do or do not. Yet, if this were<strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong> basic historicist premise, it, too, wouldobviously not qualify as an epistemolog~ Historicismwould not have given us any reason why we should believeany of it. If, however, <strong>the</strong> basic proposition of historicismwere assumed to be invari<strong>and</strong>y true, <strong>the</strong>n such a propositionabout <strong>the</strong> constant nature of historical <strong>and</strong> economic phenomenawould contradict its own doctrine denying any suchconstants. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> historicist's-<strong>and</strong> even more soits modern heir, <strong>the</strong> hermeneutician's-claim that historical<strong>and</strong> economic events are mere subjective creations, unconstrainedby any objective factors, is proven false by <strong>the</strong> verystatement making it. For evidentl~a historicist must assumethis very statement to be meaningful <strong>and</strong> true; he mustpresume to say something specific about something, ra<strong>the</strong>rthan merely uttering meaningless sounds like abracadabra.Yet if this is <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong>n, clearly; his statement must beassumed to be constrained by something outside <strong>the</strong> realmof arbitrary subjective creations. Of course, I can say what<strong>the</strong> historicist says in English, German, or Chinese, or inany o<strong>the</strong>r language I wish, in so far as historic <strong>and</strong> economicexpressions <strong>and</strong> interpretations may well be regarded asmere subjective creations. But whatever I say in whatever58 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppelanguage I choose must be assumed to be constrained by someunderlying propositional meaning of my statement, which is<strong>the</strong> same for any language, <strong>and</strong> exists completely independentofwhatever <strong>the</strong> peculiar linguistic form may be in which it isexpressed. And contrary to historicist belief, <strong>the</strong> existence ofsuch a constraint is not such that one could possibly disposeof it at will. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is objective in that we can underst<strong>and</strong>it to be <strong>the</strong> logically necessary presupposition for sayinganything meaningful at all, as opposed to merely producingmeaningless sounds. The historicist could not claim to sayanything if it were not for <strong>the</strong> fact that his expressions <strong>and</strong>interpretations are actually constrained by laws oflogic as <strong>the</strong>very presupposition ofmeaningful statements as such. 48With such a refutation of empiricism <strong>and</strong> historicism,Mises notices, <strong>the</strong> claims of rationalist philosophy are successfullyreestablished, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> case is made for <strong>the</strong> possibilityof a priori true statements, as those ofeconomics seem to be.Indeed, Mises explicitly regards his own epistemological investigationsas <strong>the</strong> continuation of<strong>the</strong> work ofwestern rationalistphilosoph~ With Leibniz <strong>and</strong> Kant he st<strong>and</strong>s opposite<strong>the</strong> tradition of Locke <strong>and</strong> Hume. 49 He sides with Leibnizwhen he answers Locke's famous dictum "nothing is in <strong>the</strong>intellect that has not previously been in <strong>the</strong> senses" with hisequally famous one "except <strong>the</strong> intellect itself." And he recognizeshis task as a philosopher of economics as strictlyanalogous to that of Kant's as a philosopher of pure reason,i.e., of epistemologr Like Kant, Mises wants to demonstrate<strong>the</strong> existence oftrue a priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions, or propositionswhose truth values can be definitely established, even48See on this in particular Hoppe, "In Defense of Extreme Rationalism."49See Mises, The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>, p. 12.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 59


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>though in order to do so <strong>the</strong> means of formal logic areinsufficient <strong>and</strong> observations are unnecessar~My criticism ofempiricism <strong>and</strong> historicism has proved<strong>the</strong> general rationalist claim. It has proved that we indeeddo possess knowledge which is not derived from observation<strong>and</strong> yet is constrained by objective laws. In fact, ourrefutation of empiricism <strong>and</strong> historicism contains such apriori syn<strong>the</strong>tic knowledge. Yet what about <strong>the</strong> constructivetask of showing that <strong>the</strong> propositions of economics-suchas <strong>the</strong> law of marginal utility <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantity <strong>the</strong>ory ofmoney-qualify as this type of knowledge? In order to doso, Mises notices in accordance with <strong>the</strong> strictures traditionallyformulated by rationalist philosophers, economicpropositions must fulfill two requirements: First, it mustbe possible to demonstrate that <strong>the</strong>y are not derived fromobservational evidence, for observational evidence can onlyreveal things as <strong>the</strong>y happen to be; <strong>the</strong>re is nothing in it thatwould indicate why things must be <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y are. Instead,economic propositions must be shown to be grounded inreflective cognition, in our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of ourselves asknowing subjects. And secondl~ this reflective underst<strong>and</strong>ingmustyield certain propositions as self-evident material axioms.Not in <strong>the</strong> sense that such axioms would have to be self-evidentin a psychological sense, that is, that on~ would have to beimmediately aware of <strong>the</strong>m or that <strong>the</strong>ir truth depends on apsychological feeling ofconviction. On <strong>the</strong> contrar~ like Kantbefore him, Mises very much stresses <strong>the</strong> fact that it is usuallymuch more painstaking to discover such axioms than it is todiscover some observational truth such as that <strong>the</strong> leaves oftrees are green or that I am 6 foot 2 inches. 50 Ra<strong>the</strong>r, what50See Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, p. 45; Mises, Human Action, p. 38.60 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppemakes <strong>the</strong>m self-evident material axioms is <strong>the</strong> fact that noone can deny <strong>the</strong>ir validity without self-contradiction, becausein attempting to deny <strong>the</strong>m one already presupposes<strong>the</strong>ir validi~Mises points out that both requirements are fulfilled bywhat he terms <strong>the</strong> axiom ofaction, Le., <strong>the</strong> proposition thathumans act, that <strong>the</strong>y display intentional behavior. 51 Obviousl~this axiom is not derived from observation-<strong>the</strong>re areonly bodily movements to be observed but no such thing asactions-but stems instead from reflective underst<strong>and</strong>ing.And this underst<strong>and</strong>ing is indeed of a self-evident proposicion.For its truth cannot be denied, since <strong>the</strong> denial woulditselfhave to be categorized as an action. But is this not justplain trivial? And what has economics got to do with this?Ofcourse, it had previously been recognized that economicconcepts such as prices, costs, production, mone~ credit,etc., had something to do with <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>re were actingpeople. But that all ofeconomics could be grounded in <strong>and</strong>reconstructed based on such a trivial proposition <strong>and</strong> ho~is certainly anything but clear. It is one of Mises's greatestachievements to have shown precisely this: that <strong>the</strong>re areinsights implied in this psychologically speaking trivial axiomof action that were not <strong>the</strong>mselves psychologicallyself-evident as well; <strong>and</strong> that it is <strong>the</strong>se insights whichprovide <strong>the</strong> foundation for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orems of economics astrue a priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions.It is certainly not psychologically evident that with everyaction an actor pursues a goal; <strong>and</strong> that whatever <strong>the</strong> goalmay be, <strong>the</strong> fact that it was pursued by an actor reveals tha<strong>the</strong> must have placed a relatively higher value on it than on anySIOn <strong>the</strong> following see in particular Mises, Human Action, chapter 4; MurrayN. Rothbard, Man, Economy, <strong>and</strong> State (Los Angeles: Nash, 1962), chapter 1.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 61


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r goal of action that he could think of at <strong>the</strong> start of hisaction. It is not evident that in order to achieve his mosthighly valued goal an actor must interfere or decide not tointerfere-which, of course, is also an intentional interference-atan earlier point in time in order to produce a laterresult; nor is it obvious that such interferences invariablyimply <strong>the</strong> employment of some scarce means-at least thoseof <strong>the</strong> actor's bod)!, its st<strong>and</strong>ing room, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> time absorbedby <strong>the</strong> action. Itis notself-evident that <strong>the</strong>se means, <strong>the</strong>n, mustalso have value for an actor-a value derived from that of<strong>the</strong>goal-because <strong>the</strong> actor must regard <strong>the</strong>ir employment asnecessary in order to effectively achieve <strong>the</strong> goal; <strong>and</strong> thatactions can only be performed sequentiall)T, always involvinga choice, i.e., taking up that one course ofaction which at somegiven time promises <strong>the</strong> most higWy valued results to <strong>the</strong> actor<strong>and</strong> excluding at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>the</strong> pursual ofo<strong>the</strong>r, less higWyvalued goals. It is not automatically clear that as a consequenceof having to choose <strong>and</strong> give preference to one goal overano<strong>the</strong>r-of not being able to realize all goals simultaneously-each<strong>and</strong> every action implies <strong>the</strong> incurrence ofcosts,i.e., forsaking <strong>the</strong> value attached to <strong>the</strong> most highly rankingalternative goal that cannot be realized or whose realizationmust be deferred, because <strong>the</strong> means necessary to attain itare bound up in <strong>the</strong> production ofano<strong>the</strong>r, even more highlyvalued goal. And lastl)!, it is not evident that at its startingpoint every goal of action must be considered worth moreto <strong>the</strong> actor than its cost <strong>and</strong> capable of yielding a profit,i.e., a result whose value is ranked higher than that of <strong>the</strong>foregone opportunit)T, <strong>and</strong> yet that every action is alsoinvariably threatened by <strong>the</strong> possibility of a loss if an actorfinds, in retrospect, that contrary to his expectations <strong>the</strong>actually achieved result in fact has a lower value than <strong>the</strong>relinquished alternative would have had.62 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann HoppeAll of<strong>the</strong>se categories which we know to be <strong>the</strong> very heartofeconomics-values, ends, means, choice, preference, cost,profit <strong>and</strong> loss-are implied in <strong>the</strong> axiom ofaction. Like <strong>the</strong>axiom itself, <strong>the</strong>y are not derived from observation. Ra<strong>the</strong>r,that one is able to interpret observations in terms of suchcategories requires that one already knows what it means toact. No one who is not an actor could ever underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>m,as <strong>the</strong>y are not"given," ready to be observed, butobservationalexperience is cast in <strong>the</strong>se terms as it is construed by an actor.And while <strong>the</strong>y <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir interrelations were not obviouslyimplied in <strong>the</strong> action axiom, once it has been made explicitthat <strong>the</strong>y are implied, <strong>and</strong> how, one no longer has anydifficulty recognizing <strong>the</strong>m as being a priori true in <strong>the</strong> samesense as <strong>the</strong> axiom itself is. For any attempt to disprove <strong>the</strong>validity ofwhat Mises has reconstructed as implied in <strong>the</strong> veryconcept ofaction would have to be aimed at a goal, requiringmeans, excluding o<strong>the</strong>r courses of action, incurring costs,subjecting <strong>the</strong> actor to <strong>the</strong> possibility of achieving or notachieving <strong>the</strong> desired goal <strong>and</strong> so leading to a profit or a loss.Thus, it is manifestly impossible to ever dispute or falsify <strong>the</strong>validity of Mises's insights. In fact, a situation in which <strong>the</strong>categories ofaction would cease to have a real existence coulditself never be observed or spoken of, since to make anobservation <strong>and</strong> to speak are <strong>the</strong>mselves actions.All true economic propositions, <strong>and</strong> this is what praxeologyis all about <strong>and</strong> what Mises's great insight consists of, canbe deduced by means offormal logic from this incontestablytrue material knowledge regarding <strong>the</strong> meaning ofaction <strong>and</strong> itscategories. More precisel); all true economic <strong>the</strong>orems consist of(a) an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> meaning ofaction, (b) a situationor situational change-assumedto be given oridentified as beinggiven-<strong>and</strong> described in terms of action-categories, <strong>and</strong> (c) alogical deduction of<strong>the</strong> consequences-again in terms ofsuchThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 63


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>categories-which are to result for an actor from this situationor situational change. The law of marginal utili~ forinstance,52 follows from our indisputable knowledge of <strong>the</strong>fact that every actor always prefers what satisfies him more overwhat satisfies him less, plus <strong>the</strong> assumption that he is faced withan increase in <strong>the</strong> supply ofa good (a scarce mean) whose unitshe regards as ofequal serviceabili~byone additional unit. Fromthis it follows with logical necessity that this additional unit can<strong>the</strong>n only be employed as a means for <strong>the</strong> removal of anuneasiness that is deemed less urgentthan <strong>the</strong> leastvaluable goalpreviously satisfied by a unit ofsuch a good. Provided <strong>the</strong>re isno flaw in <strong>the</strong> process of deduction, <strong>the</strong> conclusions whicheconomic <strong>the</strong>orizing yields, no different in <strong>the</strong> case of anyo<strong>the</strong>r economic proposition from <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> law ofmarginal utilit:}', must be valid a priori. These propositions'validity ultimately goes back to nothing but <strong>the</strong> indisputableaxiom ofaction. To think, as empiricism does, that <strong>the</strong>se propositionsrequire continual empirical testing for <strong>the</strong>ir validation isabsurd, <strong>and</strong> a sign ofoutright intellectual confusion. And it isno less absurd <strong>and</strong> confused to believe, as historicism does, thateconomics has nothing to say about constant <strong>and</strong> invariablerelations but merely deals with historically accidental events. Tosay so meaningfully is to prove such a statement wrong, assaying anything meaningful at all already presupposes acting<strong>and</strong> a knowledge of<strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong> categories of action.IIIThis will suffice here as an explanation ofMises's answerregarding <strong>the</strong> quest for <strong>the</strong> foundations ofeconomics. I shall520n <strong>the</strong> law of marginal utility see Mises, Human Action, pp. 119-27 <strong>and</strong>Rothbard, Man, Economy, <strong>and</strong> State, pp. 268-71.64 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppenow turn to my second goal: <strong>the</strong> explanation of why <strong>and</strong>how praxeology also provides <strong>the</strong> foundation for e_pistemolo~Mises had been aware ofthis <strong>and</strong> he was convinced of<strong>the</strong>great importance ofthis insight for rationalist philosophy: YetMises did not treat <strong>the</strong> matter in a systematic fashion. Thereare no more than a few briefremarks concerning this problem,interspersed throughout his massive body ofwriting.53 Thus,in <strong>the</strong> following I must try to break new ground.I shall begin my explanation by introducing a second apriori axiom <strong>and</strong> clarifying its relation to <strong>the</strong> axiom ofaction. Such an underst<strong>and</strong>ing is <strong>the</strong> key to solving ourproblem. The second axiom is <strong>the</strong> so-called "a priori ofargumentation," which states that humans are capable ofargumentation <strong>and</strong> hence know <strong>the</strong> meaning of truth <strong>and</strong>validity:54 As in <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> action axiom, this knowledgeis not derived from observation: <strong>the</strong>re is only verbal behaviorto be observed <strong>and</strong> prior reflective cognition is required inorder to interpret such behavior as meaningful arguments.And <strong>the</strong> validity of<strong>the</strong> axiom, like that of<strong>the</strong> action axiom,is indisputable. It is impossible to deny that one can argue,as <strong>the</strong> very denial would itself be an argument. In fact, one53Mises writes: "Knowledge is a tool of action. Its function is to advise manhow to proceed in his endeavor to remove uneasiness.... The category ofactionis <strong>the</strong> fundamental category of human knowledge. It implies all <strong>the</strong> categories oflogic <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> category of regularity <strong>and</strong> causality. It implies <strong>the</strong> category of time<strong>and</strong> that of value.... In acting, <strong>the</strong> mind of<strong>the</strong> individual sees itself as differentfrom its environment, <strong>the</strong> external world, <strong>and</strong> tries to study this environment inorder to influence <strong>the</strong> course ofevents happening in it" (The Ultimate Foundationof<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>, pp. 35-36). Or: "Both, apriori thinking <strong>and</strong> reasoning on <strong>the</strong>one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> human action on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, are manifestations of <strong>the</strong> mind....Reason <strong>and</strong> action are congeneric <strong>and</strong> homogeneous, two aspects of <strong>the</strong> samephenomenon" (ibid., p.42). Yet he leaves <strong>the</strong> matter more or less at this <strong>and</strong>concludes that "it is not <strong>the</strong> scope of praxeology to investigate <strong>the</strong> relation ofthinking <strong>and</strong> action" (Human Action, p. 25).540n <strong>the</strong> a priori of argumentation see also K. O. Apel, 1Yansfonnation derPhilosophie, vol. 2.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 65


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>could not even silently say to oneself "1 cannot argue"without <strong>the</strong>reby contradicting oneself. One cannot arguethat one cannot argue. Nor can one dispute knowing whatit means to make a truth or validity claim without implicitlyclaiming <strong>the</strong> negation of this proposition to be true.It is not difficult to detect that both a priori axioms-ofaction <strong>and</strong> argumentation-are intimately related. On <strong>the</strong>one h<strong>and</strong>, actions are more fundamental than argumentationswith whose existence <strong>the</strong> idea of validity emerges, asargumentation is only a subclass of action. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rh<strong>and</strong>, to recognize what has just been recognized regardingaction <strong>and</strong> argumentation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir relation to each o<strong>the</strong>rrequires argumentation, <strong>and</strong> so, in this sense, argumentationmust be considered more fundamental than action: withoutargumentation nothing could be said to be known aboutaction. But <strong>the</strong>n, as it is in argumentation that <strong>the</strong> insightis revealed that-while it might not be known to be so priorto any argumentation-in fact <strong>the</strong> possibility ofargumentationpresupposes action in that validity claims can only beexplicitly discussed in <strong>the</strong> course ofan argumentation if<strong>the</strong>individuals doing so already know what it means to act <strong>and</strong>to have knowledge implied in action-both <strong>the</strong> meaning ofaction in general <strong>and</strong> argumentation in particular must bethought of as logically necessary interwoven str<strong>and</strong>s of apriori knowledge.What this insight into <strong>the</strong> interrelation between <strong>the</strong> apriori ofaction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> a priori ofargumentation suggests is<strong>the</strong> following: Traditionall)', <strong>the</strong> task ofepistemology has beenconceived of as that of formulating what can be known tobe true a priori <strong>and</strong> also what can be known a priori not tobe <strong>the</strong> subject ofa priori knowledge. Recognizing, as we havejust done, that knowledge claims are raised <strong>and</strong> decided uponin <strong>the</strong> course of argumentation <strong>and</strong> that this is undeni~bly66 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeso, one can now reconstruct <strong>the</strong> task of epistemology moreprecisely as thatofformulating those propositions which areargumentatively indisputable in that <strong>the</strong>ir truth is alreadyimplied in <strong>the</strong> very fact of making one's atgument <strong>and</strong> socannot be denied argumentatively; <strong>and</strong> to delineate <strong>the</strong>range of such a priori knowledge from <strong>the</strong> realm of propositionswhose validity cannot be established in this way butrequire additional, contingent information for <strong>the</strong>ir validation,or that cannot be validated at all <strong>and</strong> so are meremetaphysical statements in <strong>the</strong> pejorative sense of <strong>the</strong> termmetaphysical.Yet what is implied in <strong>the</strong> very fact of arguing? It is tothis question that our insight into <strong>the</strong> inextricable interconnectionbetween <strong>the</strong> a priori of argumentation <strong>and</strong> that ofaction provides an answer: On a very general level, it cannotbe denied argumentatively that argumentation presupposesaction <strong>and</strong> that arguments, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> knowledge embodied in<strong>the</strong>m, are those of actors. And more specificall~ it cannot<strong>the</strong>n be denied that knowledge itselfis a category ofaction;that <strong>the</strong> structure of knowledge must be constrained by <strong>the</strong>peculiar function which knowledge fulfills within <strong>the</strong> frameworkof action categories; <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> existence of suchstructural constraints can never be disproved by any knowledgewhatsoever.It is in this sense that <strong>the</strong> insights contained in praxeologymust be regarded as providing <strong>the</strong> foundations ofepistemology:Knowledge is a category quite distinct from thosethat I have explained earlier-from ends <strong>and</strong> means. Theends which we strive to attain through our actions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>means which we employ in order to do so, are both scarcevalues. The values attached to our goals are subject toconsumption <strong>and</strong> are exterminated <strong>and</strong> destroyed in consumption<strong>and</strong> thus must forever be produced anew. AndThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 67


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong><strong>the</strong> means employed must be economized, too. Not so,however, with respect to knowledge-regardless ofwhe<strong>the</strong>rone considers ita means or an end in itself. Of course, <strong>the</strong>acquisition of knowledge requires scarce means-at leastone's body <strong>and</strong> time. Yet once knowledge is acquired, it isno longer scarce. It can nei<strong>the</strong>r be consumed, nor are <strong>the</strong>services that it can render as a means subject to depletion.Once <strong>the</strong>re, it is an inexhaustible resource <strong>and</strong> incorporatesan everlasting value provided that it is not simply forgotten.55 Yet knowledge is not a free good in <strong>the</strong> same sense thatair, under normal circumstances, is a free good. Instead, it is acategory of action. It is not only a mental ingredient ofeach<strong>and</strong> every action, quite unlike air, but more importantl);knowledge, <strong>and</strong> not air, is subject to validation, which is tosay that it must prove to fulfill a positive function for anactor within <strong>the</strong> invariant constraints of <strong>the</strong> categoricalframework of actions. It is <strong>the</strong> task of epistemology toclarify what <strong>the</strong>se constraints are <strong>and</strong> what one can thusknow about <strong>the</strong> structure of knowledge as such.While such recognition of <strong>the</strong> praxeological constraintson <strong>the</strong> structure ofknowledge might not immediately strikeone as in itselfofgreat significance, it does have some highlyimportant implications. For one thing, in light of this insightone recurring difficulty of rationalist philosophy findsits answer. It has been a common quarrel with rationalism in<strong>the</strong> Leibniz-Kant tradition that it seemed to imply some sortofidealism. Realizing that a priori true propositions could notpossibly be derived from observations, rationalism answered<strong>the</strong> question how a priori knowledge could <strong>the</strong>n be possibleby adopting <strong>the</strong> model of an active mind, as opposed550n this fundamental difference between economic, i.e., scarce means <strong>and</strong>knowledge, see also Mises, Human Action, pp. 128, 661.68 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppeto <strong>the</strong> empiricistmodelofa passive, mirror-like mind in <strong>the</strong>tradition of Locke <strong>and</strong> Hume. According to rationalist philosoph~a priori true propositions had <strong>the</strong>ir foundation in <strong>the</strong>operation of principles of thinking which one could not possiblyconceive ofas operating o<strong>the</strong>rwise; <strong>the</strong>y were grounded incategories ofan act;ive mind. No\\) as empiricists were only tooeager to point out, <strong>the</strong> obvious critique of such a position is,that ifthis were indeed <strong>the</strong> case, it could not be explained whysuch mental categories should fit realit¥ Ra<strong>the</strong>r, one would beforced to accept <strong>the</strong> absurd idealistic assumption that realitywould have to be conceived of as a creation of <strong>the</strong> mind, inorder to claim that a priori knowledge could incorporate anyinformation about <strong>the</strong> structure of reali~ And clearl~ such anassertion seemed to be justified when faced with programmaticstatements of rationalist philosophers such as <strong>the</strong> followingby Kant: "Sofar ithas been assumed thatourknowledgehad to conform to realit:)r," instead it should be assumed "thatobservational reality should conform to our mind."s6Recognizing knowledge as being structurally constrainedby its role in <strong>the</strong> framework of action categoriesprovides <strong>the</strong> solution to such a complaint. For as soon asthis is realized, all idealistic suggestions of rationalist phi­10sophy disappear, <strong>and</strong> an epistemology claiming that apriori true propositions exist becomes a realistic epistemologyinstead. Understood as constrained by action categories,<strong>the</strong> seemingly unbridgeable gulf between <strong>the</strong> mentalon <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real, outside physical world on <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r is bridged. So constrained, a priori knowledge must56Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen vernunft, p. 25. Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not such aninterpretation ofKant's epistemology is indeed correct is, ofcourse, a very differentmatter. Clarifying this problem is, however, of no concern here. For an activist orconstructivist interpretation ofKantian philosophy see E Kambartel, Erfahrung undStruktur, chapter 3; also Hoppe, H<strong>and</strong>eln und Erkennen (Bern: Lang, 1976).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 69


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>be as much a mental thing as a reflection of <strong>the</strong> structure ofreali~ since it is only through actions that <strong>the</strong> mind comesinto contact with reality; so to speak. Acting is a cognitivelyguided adjustment ofa physical body in physical realit)T. Andthus, <strong>the</strong>re can be no doubt that a priori knowledge, conceivedof as an insight into <strong>the</strong> structural constraints imposedon knowledge qua knowledge ofactors, must indeedcorrespond to <strong>the</strong> nature of things. The realistic characterofsuch knowledge would manifest itselfnot only in <strong>the</strong> factthat one could not think it to be o<strong>the</strong>rwise, but in <strong>the</strong> factthat one could not undo its truth.Yet <strong>the</strong>re are more specific implications involved in recognizing<strong>the</strong> praxeological foundations ofepistemology-apartfrom <strong>the</strong> general one that in substituting <strong>the</strong> model of <strong>the</strong>mind of an actor acting by means of a physical body for <strong>the</strong>traditional rationalist model ofan active mind a priori knowledgeimmediately becomes realistic knowledge (so realisticindeed that it can be understood as being literally notundoable). More specificall)T, in light of this insight decisivesupport is given to those deplorably few rationalist philosopherswho-against <strong>the</strong> empiricist Zeitgeist-stubbornlymaintain on various philosophical fronts that a priori truepropositions about <strong>the</strong> real world are possible. 57 Moreover, in571n addition to <strong>the</strong> works mentioned in note 46 see Br<strong>and</strong> Blanshard, TheNature-of Thought (London: Allen <strong>and</strong> Unwin, 1921); M. Cohen, Reason <strong>and</strong>Nature (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1931); idem, Preface to Logic (New York:Holt, 1944); A. Pap, Semantics <strong>and</strong> Necessary Jruth (New Haven: Yale UniversityPress, 1958); S. Kripke, "Naming <strong>and</strong> Necessity," in D. Davidson <strong>and</strong> G. Harman,eds., Semantics ofNatural Language (New York: Reidel, 1972); H. Dingler, DieErgreifung des Wirklichen (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1969); idem, Aufbau derexakten Fundamentalwissenschaft (Munich: Eidos, 1964); W KamIah <strong>and</strong> P. Lorenzen,Logische Propiideutik Mannheim: (Mannheim: Bibliographisches Institut,1968); P. Lorenzen, <strong>Method</strong>isches Denken (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1968); idem,Nonnative Logic <strong>and</strong> Ethics (Mannheim: Bibliographisches Institut, 1969); K. O.Apel, Transformation der Philosophie.70 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppelight of <strong>the</strong> recognition of praxeological constraints on <strong>the</strong>structure of knowledge <strong>the</strong>se various rationalist endeavorsbecome systematically integrated into one, unified body ofrationalist philosophy;In explicitly underst<strong>and</strong>ing knowledge as displayed inargumentation as a peculiar category of action, it becomesclear immediately why <strong>the</strong> perennial rationalist claim that<strong>the</strong> laws oflogic-beginning here with <strong>the</strong> most fundamentalones, i.e., ofpropositional logic <strong>and</strong> ofJunctors ("<strong>and</strong>," "or,""if-<strong>the</strong>n," "not") <strong>and</strong> Quantors ("<strong>the</strong>re is," "all," "some")-area priori true propositions about reality <strong>and</strong> not mere verbalstipulations regarding <strong>the</strong> transformation rules of arbitrarilychosen signs, as empiricist-formalists would have it, is indeedcorrect. They are as much laws of thinking as of reality;because <strong>the</strong>y are laws that have <strong>the</strong>ir ultimate foundation inaction <strong>and</strong> could not be undone by any actor. Ineach <strong>and</strong> everyaction, an actor identifies some specific situation <strong>and</strong> categorizesit one way ra<strong>the</strong>r than ano<strong>the</strong>r in order to be able to makea choice. It is this which ultimately explains <strong>the</strong> structure ofeven <strong>the</strong> most elementary propositions (like "Socrates is aman") consisting ofa proper name or some identifying expressionfor <strong>the</strong> naming or identifying ofsomething, <strong>and</strong> a predicateto assert or deny some specific property of <strong>the</strong> named oridentified object; <strong>and</strong> which explains <strong>the</strong> cornerstones oflogic:<strong>the</strong> laws of identity <strong>and</strong> contradiction. And it is this universalfeature of action <strong>and</strong> choosing which also explains our underst<strong>and</strong>ingof <strong>the</strong> categories "<strong>the</strong>re is," "all" <strong>and</strong>, by implication,"some," as well as "<strong>and</strong>," "or," "if.<strong>the</strong>n" <strong>and</strong> "not."S8 One can say,580n rationalist interpretations of logic see Blanshard, Reason <strong>and</strong> Analysis,chapters 6, 10; P. Lorenzen, Einfuhrung in die operative Logik und Ma<strong>the</strong>matik(Frankfun/M.: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, 1970); K. Lorenz, Elemente derSprachkritik (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1970); idem, "Diedialogische Rechtfertigungder effektiven Logik," in: E Kambartel <strong>and</strong> ]. Mittelstrass, eds., Zum normativenFundament der Wissenschaft (Frankfurt/M.: A<strong>the</strong>naum, 1973).The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 71


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>ofcourse, that something can be "a" <strong>and</strong> "non-a" at <strong>the</strong> sametime, or that "<strong>and</strong>" means this ra<strong>the</strong>r than something else. Butone cannot undo <strong>the</strong> law of contradiction; <strong>and</strong> one cannotundo <strong>the</strong> real definition of "<strong>and</strong>." For simply by virtue ofacting with a physical body in physical space we invariablyaffirm <strong>the</strong> law of contradiction <strong>and</strong> invariably display ourtrue constructive knowledge of <strong>the</strong> meaning of "<strong>and</strong>" <strong>and</strong>"or."Similarly; <strong>the</strong> ultimate reason for arithmetic's being ana priori <strong>and</strong> yet empirical discipline, as rationalists haveOn <strong>the</strong> propositional character oflanguage <strong>and</strong> experience, in particular, seeW KamIah <strong>and</strong> P. Lorenzen, Logische Propiideutik, chapter 1; P. Lorenzen, NormativeLogic <strong>and</strong> Ethics, chapter 1. Lorenzen writes: "I call a usage a convention if Iknow ofano<strong>the</strong>r usage which 1 could accept instead.·... However, I do not knowofano<strong>the</strong>r behavior which could replace <strong>the</strong> use ofelementary sentences. IfI didnot accept proper names <strong>and</strong> predicators, I would not know how to speak at all.. . . Each proper name is a convention ... but to use proper names at all is nota convention: it is a unique pattern oflinguistic behavior. Therefore, I am goingto call it 'logical'. The same is true with predicators. Each predicator is aconvention. This is shown by <strong>the</strong> existence of more than one natural language.But all languages use predicators" (ibid., p. 16). See also J. Mittelstrass, "DieWiederkehr des Gleichen," Ratio (1966).On <strong>the</strong> law of identity <strong>and</strong> contradiction, in particular, see B. Blanshard,Reason <strong>and</strong> Analysis, pp. 276ff, 423ff.On a critical evaluation of 3- or more-valued logics as ei<strong>the</strong>r meaninglesssymbolic formalisms or as logically presupposing an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> traditionaltwo-valued logic see W Stegmiiller, HauptstrOmungen der Gegenwartsphilosophievol. 2 (Stuttgart: Kroner, 1975), pp. 182-91; B. Blanshard, Reason <strong>and</strong> Analysis,pp. 269-75. Regarding, for instance, <strong>the</strong> many-valued or open-textured logic,proposed by E Waismann, Blanshard notes: "We can only agree with Dr. Waismann-<strong>and</strong>with Hegel-that <strong>the</strong> black-<strong>and</strong>-white distinctions offormal logic arequite inadequate to living thought. But why should one say, as Dr.Waismann does,that in adopting a more differentiated logic one is adopting an alternative systemwhich is incompatible with black-<strong>and</strong>-white logic? What he has actually done isto recognize a number of gradations within <strong>the</strong> older meaning of<strong>the</strong> word 'not'.We do not doubt that such gradations are <strong>the</strong>re, <strong>and</strong> indeed as many more as hecares to distinguish. But a refinement of<strong>the</strong> older logic is not an ab<strong>and</strong>onment ofit. It is still true that <strong>the</strong> colour I saw yesterday was ei<strong>the</strong>r a determinate shade ofyellow or not, even though <strong>the</strong> 'not' may cover a multitude of approximations,<strong>and</strong> even though I shall never know which was <strong>the</strong> shade I saw" (ibid., pp.273-74).72 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hennann Hoppealways understood it, now also becomes discernible. The prevailingempiricist-formalist orthodoxy conceives of arithmeticas <strong>the</strong> manipulation ofarbitrarily defined signs according toarbitrarily stipulated transformation rules, <strong>and</strong> thus as entirelyvoid of any empirical meaning. For this view; whichevidently makes arithmetic nothing but pIa); however skillfulit might be, <strong>the</strong> successful applicability of arithmetic inphysics is an intellectual embarrassment. Indeed, empiricistformalistswould have to explain away this fact as simplybeing a miraculous event. That it is no miracle, however,becomes apparent once <strong>the</strong> praxeological or-to use here <strong>the</strong>terminology of<strong>the</strong> most notable rationalist philosopher-ma<strong>the</strong>maticianPaul Lorenzen <strong>and</strong> his school-<strong>the</strong> operative or constructivistcharacter of arithmetic is understood. Arithmetic<strong>and</strong> its character as an a priori-syn<strong>the</strong>tic intellectual disciplineis rooted in our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of repetition, <strong>the</strong>repetition of action. More precisel); it rests on our underst<strong>and</strong>ing<strong>the</strong> meaning of"do this-<strong>and</strong> do this again, startingfrom <strong>the</strong> present result." And arithmetic <strong>the</strong>n deals withreal things: with constructed or constructively identifiedunits of something. It demonstrates what relations are tohold between such units because of <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>y areconstructed according to <strong>the</strong> rule of repetition. As PaulLorenzen has demonstrated in detail, not all of what presentlyposes as ma<strong>the</strong>matics can be constructivelyfounded-<strong>and</strong> those parts, <strong>the</strong>n, should ofcourse be recognizedfor what <strong>the</strong>y are: epistemologically worthless symbolicgames. But all of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical tools that are actuallyemployed in physics, i.e., <strong>the</strong> tools ofclassical analysis, can beconstructively derived. They are not empirically void symbolisms,but true propositions about reali~ They apply toeverything insofar as it consists of one or more distinctunits, <strong>and</strong> insofar as <strong>the</strong>se units are constructed or identifiedThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 73


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>as units by a procedure of"do it again, construct or identifyano<strong>the</strong>r unit by repeating <strong>the</strong> previous operation."S9 Again,one can say, of course, that 2 plus 2 is sometimes 4 butsometimes 2 or 5 units, <strong>and</strong> in observational reality; for lionsplus lambs or for rabbits, this may even be true,60 but in <strong>the</strong>reality of action, in identifying or constructing those unitsin repetitive operations, <strong>the</strong> truth that 2 plus 2 is neveranything but 4 could not possibly be undone.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> old rationalist claims that geometry; that is,Euclidean geometry is a priori <strong>and</strong> yet incorporates empiricalknowledge about space becomes supported, too, in viewof our insight into <strong>the</strong> praxeological constraints on knowledge.Since <strong>the</strong> discovery of non-Euclidean geometries <strong>and</strong>590n a rationalist interpretation of arithmetic see Blanshard, Rcason <strong>and</strong>Analysis~ pp. 427-31; on <strong>the</strong> constructivist foundation ofarithmetic, in particular,see Lorenzen, EinfUhrung in die operative Logik und Ma<strong>the</strong>matik; idem, <strong>Method</strong>ischesDenken, chapters 6, 7; idem, Normative Logic <strong>and</strong> Ethics~ chapter 4; on <strong>the</strong>constructivist foundation of classical analysis see P. Lorenzen, Differential undIntegral: Eine konstruktive EinfUhrung in die klassische Analysis (Frankfurt/M.:Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, 1965); for a brilliant general critique ofma<strong>the</strong>matical formalism see Kambartel, Erfahrung und Struktur, chapter 6,esp. pp. 236-42; on <strong>the</strong> irrelevance of<strong>the</strong> famous Godel-<strong>the</strong>orem for a constructivelyfounded arithmetic see P. Lorenzen,Metama<strong>the</strong>matik (Mannheim: BibliographischesInstitut, 1962); also Ch. Thiel, "Das Begrlindungsproblem derMa<strong>the</strong>matik und die Philosophie," in E Kambartel <strong>and</strong> J. Mittelstrass, eds.,Zum normativen Fundament der Wissenschaft, esp. pp. 99-101. K. Godel'sproof-which, as a proof, incidentally supports ra<strong>the</strong>r than undermines <strong>the</strong>rationalist claim of<strong>the</strong> possibility ofapriori knowledge-only demonstrates that<strong>the</strong> early formalist Hilbert program cannot be successfully carried through,because in order to demonstrate <strong>the</strong> consistency of certain axiomatic <strong>the</strong>oriesone must have a meta<strong>the</strong>ory with even stronger means than those formalizedin <strong>the</strong> object-<strong>the</strong>ory itself. Interestingly enough, <strong>the</strong> difficulties of<strong>the</strong> formalistprogram had led <strong>the</strong> old Hilbert already several years before Godel's proof of1931 to recognize <strong>the</strong> necessity ofreintroducing a substantive interpretation ofma<strong>the</strong>matics ala Kant, which would give its axioms a foundation <strong>and</strong> justificationthat was entirely independent of any formal consistency proofs. SeeKambartel, Erfahrung und Struktu1j pp. 185-87.60Examples of this kind are used by Karl Popper in order to "refute" <strong>the</strong>rationalist idea of rules of arithmetic being laws of reality. See Karl Popper,Conjectures <strong>and</strong> Refutations (London: Routledge <strong>and</strong> Kegan Paul, 1969), p. 211.74 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hernt-ann Hoppein particular since Einstein's relativistic <strong>the</strong>ory of gravitation,<strong>the</strong> prevailing position regarding geometry is onceagain empiricist <strong>and</strong> formalist. It conceives of geometry asei<strong>the</strong>r being part of empirical, aposteriori physics, or asbeing empirically meaningless formalisms. Yet thatgeometryis ei<strong>the</strong>r mere pIa)', or forever subject to empirical testingseems to be irreconcilable with <strong>the</strong> fact that Euclideangeometry is <strong>the</strong> foundation of engineering <strong>and</strong> construction,<strong>and</strong> that nobody <strong>the</strong>re ever thinks ofsuch propositionsas only hypo<strong>the</strong>tically true. 61 Recognizing knowledge aspraxeologically constrained explains why <strong>the</strong> empiricist-formalistview is incorrect <strong>and</strong> why <strong>the</strong> empirical success ofEuclidean geometry is no mere accident. Spatial knowledgeis also included in <strong>the</strong> meaning of action. Action is <strong>the</strong>employment of a physical body in space. Without acting<strong>the</strong>re could be no knowledge of spatial relations, <strong>and</strong> nomeasurement. Measuring is relating something to a st<strong>and</strong>ard.Without st<strong>and</strong>ards, <strong>the</strong>re is no measurement; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reis no measurement, <strong>the</strong>n, which could ever falsify <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard.Evidentl)', <strong>the</strong> ultimate st<strong>and</strong>ard must be provided by<strong>the</strong> norms underlying <strong>the</strong> construction ofbodily movementsin space <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> construction of measurement instrumentsby means of one's body <strong>and</strong> in accordance with <strong>the</strong> principlesof spatial constructions embodied in it. Euclidean geometr)',as again Paul Lorenzen in particular has explained,is no more <strong>and</strong> no less than <strong>the</strong> reconstruction of <strong>the</strong> idealnorms underlying our construction of such homogeneousbasic forms as points, lines, planes <strong>and</strong> distances, which arein a more or less perfect but always perfectible way incorporatedor realized in even our most primitive instrumentsofspatial measurements such as a measuring rod. Naturall)',61SeeonthisalsoMises, The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>) pp.12-14.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 75


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong><strong>the</strong>se norms <strong>and</strong> normative implications cannot be falsifiedby <strong>the</strong> result ofany empirical measurement. On <strong>the</strong> contrar~<strong>the</strong>ir cognitive validity is substantiated by <strong>the</strong> fact that it is<strong>the</strong>y which make physical measurements in space possible.Any actual measurement must already presuppose <strong>the</strong> validityof<strong>the</strong> norms leading to <strong>the</strong> construction ofone's measurementst<strong>and</strong>ards. Itis in this sense thatgeometry is an a priori science;<strong>and</strong> that itmust simultaneously be regarded as an empiricallymeaningful discipline, because it is not only <strong>the</strong> very preconditionfor any empirical spatial description, it is also <strong>the</strong>precondition for any active orientation in space. 62In view of<strong>the</strong> recognition of<strong>the</strong> praxeological characterof knowledge, <strong>the</strong>se insights regarding <strong>the</strong> nature of logic,arithmetic <strong>and</strong> geometry become integrated <strong>and</strong> embeddedinto a system of epistemological dualism. 63 The ultimate620n <strong>the</strong> aprioristic character ofEuclidean geometry see Lorenzen,<strong>Method</strong>ischesDenken, chapters 8 <strong>and</strong> 9; idem, Normatipe Logic <strong>and</strong> Ethics, chapter 5; H.Dingler, Die Grundlagen der Geometrie (Stuttgart: Enke, 1933); on Euclideangeometry as a necessary presupposition of objective, i.e., intersubjectively communicable,measurements <strong>and</strong> in particular of any empirical verification of non­Euclidean geometries (after all, <strong>the</strong> lenses of <strong>the</strong> telescopes which one uses toconfirm Einstein's <strong>the</strong>ory regarding <strong>the</strong> non-Euclidean structure ofphysical spacemust <strong>the</strong>mselves be constructed according to Euclidean principles) see Kambartel,Erfahrung und Struktur, pp. 132-33; ~ Janich, Die Protophysik der Zeit(Mannheim: Bibliographisches Institut, 1969), pp. 45-50; idem, "Eindeutigkeit,Konsistenz und methodische Ordnung," in E Kambartel <strong>and</strong> J. Mittelstrass, eds.,Zum normatipen Fundament der Wissenschaft.Following <strong>the</strong> lead ofHugo Dingler, Paul Lorenzen <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members of<strong>the</strong> so-called Erlangen school have worked out a system of protophysics, whichcontains all aprioristic presuppositions ofempirical physics, including, apart fromgeometry, also chronometry <strong>and</strong> hylometry (i.e., classical mechanics withoutgravitation, or "rational" mechanics). "Geometry, chronometry <strong>and</strong> hylometry area-priori <strong>the</strong>ories which make empirical measurements ofspace, time <strong>and</strong> materia'possible'. They have to be established before physics in <strong>the</strong> modern sense of anempirical science, with hypo<strong>the</strong>tical fields offorces, can begin. Therefore, I shouldlike to call <strong>the</strong>se disciplines by a common name: protophysics." Lorenzen, NormatiTJeLogic <strong>and</strong> Ethics, p. 60.630n <strong>the</strong> fundamental nature of epistemological dualism see also Mises,Theory <strong>and</strong> History, pp. 1-2.76 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppejustification for this dualist position, i.e., <strong>the</strong> claim that<strong>the</strong>re are two realms of intellectual inquiry that can beunderstood a priori as requiring categorically distinct methodsof treatment <strong>and</strong> analysis, also lies in <strong>the</strong> praxeologicalnature of knowledge. It explains why we must differentiatebetween a realm ofobjects which is categorized causally <strong>and</strong>a realm that is categorized teleologically instead.I have already briefly indicated during my discussioJ} ofpraxeology that causality is a category ofaction. The idea ofcausality that <strong>the</strong>re are constant, time-invariantly operatingcauses which allow one to project past observations regarding<strong>the</strong> relation ofevents into <strong>the</strong> future is something (as empiricismsince Hume has noticed) which has no observationalbasis whatsoever. One cannot observe <strong>the</strong> connecting linkbetween observations. Even if one could, such an observationwould not prove it to be a time-invariant connection.Instead, <strong>the</strong> principle of causality must be understood asimplied in our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of action as an interferencewith <strong>the</strong> observational world, made with <strong>the</strong> intent ofdiverting <strong>the</strong> "natural" course ofevents in order to producea different, prefered state of affairs, i.e., of making thingshappen that o<strong>the</strong>rwise would not happen, <strong>and</strong> thus presupposes<strong>the</strong> notion of events which are related to each o<strong>the</strong>rthrough time-invariantly operating causes. An actor mighterr with respect to his particular assumptions about whichearlier interference produced which later result. But successfulor not, any action, changed or unchanged in light of itsprevious success or failure, presupposes that <strong>the</strong>re are constantlyconnected events as such, even if no particular causefor any particular event can ever be preknown to any actor.Without such an assumption it would be impossible to evercategorize two or more observational experiences as falsifyingor confirming each o<strong>the</strong>r ra<strong>the</strong>r than interpreting <strong>the</strong>mThe Ludwig von Mises Institute • 77


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>as logically incommensurable events. Only because <strong>the</strong> existenceoftime-invariantly operating causes as such is alreadyassumed can one ever encounter particular instances of confirmingor disconfirming observational evidence, or can <strong>the</strong>reever be an actor who can learn anything from past experienceby classifying his actions as successful <strong>and</strong> confirming someprevious knowledge, or unsuccessful <strong>and</strong> disconfirming it.It is simply by virtue of acting <strong>and</strong> distinguishing betweensuccesses <strong>and</strong> failures that <strong>the</strong> a priori validity of<strong>the</strong> principIeof causality is established; even if one tried, one couldnot successfully refute its validi~64In so underst<strong>and</strong>ing causality as a necessary presuppositionof action, it is also immediately implied that its rangeof applicability must <strong>the</strong>n be delineated a priori from thatof <strong>the</strong> category of teleolog)T. Indeed, both categories arestrictly exclusive <strong>and</strong> complementar)T. Action presupposes acausally structured observational reali~ but <strong>the</strong> reality ofaction which we can underst<strong>and</strong> as requiring such structure,is not itself causally structured. Instead, it is a reality thatmust be categorized teleologicall~ as purpose-directed,meaningful behavior. In fact, one can nei<strong>the</strong>r deny nor undo640n <strong>the</strong> aprioristic character of <strong>the</strong> category of causality see Mises, HumanAction, chapter 1; Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung;idem, "Is Research Based on Causal Scientic Principles Possible in <strong>the</strong> Social<strong>Science</strong>s?"; on <strong>the</strong> causality principle as a necessary presupposition in particularalso of <strong>the</strong> indeterminacy principle of quantum physics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fundamentalmisconception involved in interpreting <strong>the</strong> Heisenberg-principle as invalidating<strong>the</strong> causality principle see Kambartel, Erfahrung und StruktuJ; pp. 138-40; alsoHoppe, "In Defense ofExtreme Rationalism," footnote 36. In fact, it is precisely<strong>the</strong> indisputable praxeological fact that separate measurement acts can only beperformed sequentially which explains <strong>the</strong> very possibility of irreducibly probabilistic-ra<strong>the</strong>rthan deterministic-predictions as <strong>the</strong>y are characteristic of quantumphysics; <strong>and</strong> yet, in order to perform any experiments in <strong>the</strong> field ofquantummechanics, a.nd in particular to repeat two or more experiments <strong>and</strong> state this tobe <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong> causality principle must evidently already bepresupposed.78 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppe<strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong>re are two categorically different realms ofphenomena, since such attempts would have to presupposecausally related events qua actions that take place withinobservational reali~ as well as <strong>the</strong> existence ofintentionallyra<strong>the</strong>r than causally related phenomena in order to interpretsuch observational events as meaning to deny something.Nei<strong>the</strong>r a causal, nor a teleological monism could be justifiedwithout running into an open contradiction: physicallystating ei<strong>the</strong>r position, <strong>and</strong> claiming to say something meaningfulin so doing, <strong>the</strong> case is in fact made for an indisputablecomplementarity of both, a realm of causal <strong>and</strong>teleological phenomena.65Everything which is not an action must necessarily becategorized causall~ There is nothing to be known a prioriabout this range of phenomena except that it is structuredcausally-<strong>and</strong> that it is structured according to <strong>the</strong> categoriesof propositional logic, arithmetic <strong>and</strong> geometry:66Everything else <strong>the</strong>re is to know about this range of phenomenamust be derived from contingent observations <strong>and</strong>thus represents aposteriori knowledge. In particular, allknowledge about two or more specific observational eventsbeing causally related or not is aposteriori knowledge. 0 b­viously; <strong>the</strong> range of phenomena described in this waycoincides (more or less) with what is usually considered tobe <strong>the</strong> field of <strong>the</strong> empirical natural sciences.650n <strong>the</strong> necessary complementarity of <strong>the</strong> categories of causality <strong>and</strong>teleology see Mises, Human Action, p. 25; idem, The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>) pp. 6-8; Hoppe, Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung;idem, "Is Research Based on Causal Scientific Principles Possible in <strong>the</strong>Social <strong>Science</strong>s?"; also G. v. Wright, Nann <strong>and</strong> Action (London: Routledge <strong>and</strong>Kegan Paul, 1963); idem, Explanation <strong>and</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong>ing (Ithaca, N.Y:: CornellUniversity Press, 1971); K. O. Apel, Die ErkJitren: ftrstehen Kontroverse in transzendental-pragmatischerSicht (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1979).66More precisely still: it is structured according to <strong>the</strong> categories of logic,arithmetic, <strong>and</strong> protophysics (including geometry). See note 62 above.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 79


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>In contrast, everything that is an action must be categorizedteleologicall~ This realm ofphenomena is constrainedby <strong>the</strong> laws of logic <strong>and</strong> arithmetic, too. But it is notconstrained by <strong>the</strong> laws of geometry as incorporated in ourinstruments of measuring spatially extending objects, becauseactions do not exist apart from subjective interpretationsof observable things; <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong>y must be identifiedby reflective underst<strong>and</strong>ing ra<strong>the</strong>r than spatial measurements.Nor are actions causally connected events, but eventsthat are connected meaningfully within a categorical frameworkofmeans <strong>and</strong> ends.One can not know a priori what <strong>the</strong> specific values,choices <strong>and</strong> costs of some actor are or will be. This wouldfall entirely into <strong>the</strong> province of empirical, aposterioriknowledge. In fact, which particular action an actor is goingto undertake would depend on his knowledge regarding <strong>the</strong>observational reality <strong>and</strong>/or <strong>the</strong> reality of o<strong>the</strong>r actors' actions.And it would be manifestly impossible to conceive ofsuch states of knowledge as predictable on <strong>the</strong> basis oftime-invariantly operating causes. A knowing actor cannotpredict his future knowledge before he has actually acquiredit, <strong>and</strong> he demonstrates, simply by virtue ofdistinguishingbetween successful <strong>and</strong> unsuccessful predictions, that hemust conceive of himself as capable of learning from unknownexperiences in as yet unknown ways. Thus, knowledgeregarding <strong>the</strong> particular course of actions is onlyaposteriori. And since such knowledge would have to include<strong>the</strong> actor's own knowledge-as a necessary ingredientof every action whose every change can have an influenceon a particular action being chosen-teleological knowledgemust also necessarily be reconstructive, or historical knowledge.It would only provide ex-post explanations whichwould have no systematic bearing on <strong>the</strong> prediction of80 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppefuture actions, because, in principle, future states ofknowledgecould never be predicted on <strong>the</strong> basis of constantlyoperating empirical causes. Obviousl~ such a delineation ofa branch of aposteriori <strong>and</strong> reconstructive science of actionfits <strong>the</strong> usual description of such disciplines as history <strong>and</strong>sociology; 67What is known to be true a priori regarding <strong>the</strong> field ofaction, <strong>and</strong> what would <strong>the</strong>n have to constrain any historicalor sociological explanation is this: For one thing, any suchexplanation, which essentially would have to reconstruct anactor's knowledge, would invariably have to be a reconstructionin terms of knowledge of ends <strong>and</strong> means, of choices<strong>and</strong> costs, of profits <strong>and</strong> losses <strong>and</strong> so on. And secondl~since <strong>the</strong>se are evidently <strong>the</strong> categories of praxeology asconceived of by Mises, any such explanation must also beconstrained by <strong>the</strong> laws of praxeolog~And since <strong>the</strong>se lawsare, as I have already explained, a priori laws, <strong>the</strong>y must alsooperate as logical constraints on any future course ofaction.They are valid independent of any specific state of knowledgethat an actor might have acquired, simply by virtue of<strong>the</strong> fact that whatever this state might be, it must be describedin terms of action categories. And as referring toactions as such, <strong>the</strong> laws of praxeology must <strong>the</strong>n be coextensivewith all <strong>the</strong> predictive knowledge <strong>the</strong>re can be in <strong>the</strong>field of <strong>the</strong> science of action. In fact, ignoring for <strong>the</strong>moment that <strong>the</strong> status of geometry as an a priori sciencewas ultimately grounded in our underst<strong>and</strong>ing ofaction <strong>and</strong>in so far praxeology would have to be regarded as <strong>the</strong> morefundamental cognitive discipline, <strong>the</strong> peculiar role of67On <strong>the</strong> logic of history <strong>and</strong> sociology as reconstructive disciplines see inaddition to <strong>the</strong> works of Mises mentioned at <strong>the</strong> outset of this chapter Hoppe,Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung, chapter 2.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 81


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>praxeology proper within <strong>the</strong> entire system ofepistemologycan be understood as somewhat analogous to thatofgeometr~Praxeology is for <strong>the</strong> field of action what Euclideangeometry is for <strong>the</strong> field of observations (non-actions). As<strong>the</strong> geometry incorporated in our measuring instrumentsconstrains <strong>the</strong> spatial structure bf observational reali~ sopraxeology constrains <strong>the</strong> range of things that can possiblybe experienced in <strong>the</strong> field ofactions. 68IVIn so establishing <strong>the</strong> place ofpraxeology proper, I havecome full circle in outlining <strong>the</strong> system of rationalistphilosophy as ultimately grounded in <strong>the</strong> action axiom. Ithas been my goal here to reaffirm Mises's claim that economicsis praxeology; that <strong>the</strong> case for praxeology is anindisputable one; <strong>and</strong> that empiricist or historicist-hermeneuticistinterpretations of economics are self-contradictorydoctrines. And it has been my objective to indicatethat <strong>the</strong> Misesian insight into <strong>the</strong> nature ofpraxeology alsoprovides <strong>the</strong> very foundation on which traditional rationalistphilosophy' can be successfully reconstructed, <strong>and</strong> systematicallyintegrated.For <strong>the</strong> rationalist philosopher this would seem to implythat he should take account of praxeolog~For it is precisely<strong>the</strong> insight into <strong>the</strong> praxeological constraints on <strong>the</strong> structureof knowledge which provides <strong>the</strong> missing link in hisintellectual defense against skepticism <strong>and</strong> relativism. For680n <strong>the</strong> categorical distinctiveness ofpraxeological <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> history <strong>and</strong>sociology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> logical constraints that praxeology imposes on historical <strong>and</strong>sociological research as well as on social <strong>and</strong> economic predictions see Mises,Human Action, pp. 51-59, 117-18; Hoppe, "In Defense ofExtreme Rationalism."82 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


Hans-Hermann Hoppe<strong>the</strong> economist in <strong>the</strong> tradition of Mises it means, I claim,that he should explicitly come to recognize his place within<strong>the</strong> wider tradition of western rationalism; <strong>and</strong> that heshould learn to incorporate <strong>the</strong> insights provided by thistradition in order to construct an even more impressive <strong>and</strong>profound case for praxeology <strong>and</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> economics than<strong>the</strong> one made by <strong>the</strong> great Mises himself.The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 83


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Recommended ReadingsBlock, Walter. "On Robert Nozick's 'On <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>ology'."Inquiry 23 (1980).Hollis, Martin, <strong>and</strong> Edward Nell. Rational <strong>Economic</strong> Man: APhilosophical Critique ofNeo-Classical <strong>Economic</strong>s. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1975.Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung.Unterschungen zur Grundlegung von Soziologie undOkonomie. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1983.-. "Is Research Based on Causal Scientific Principles Possiblein <strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s?" Ratio 25, no. 1 (1983).-. "In Defense ofExtreme Rationalism." Review of<strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s 3 (1988).-. A Theory ofSocialism <strong>and</strong> Capitalism. Kluwer AcademicPublishers, 1989.-. "On Praxeology <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Praxeological Foundations ofEpistemology <strong>and</strong> Ethics." In Llewellyn H. Rockwell, Jr., ed.,The Meaning ofLudwig von Mises. Auburn, Ala.: Ludwig vonMises Institute, 1989.-. The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Ethics ofPrivate Property. Kluwer AcademicPublishers, 1993.Kirzner, Israel M. The <strong>Economic</strong> Point ofView. Kansas City;Kans.: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976.Lavoie, Don. "From Hollis <strong>and</strong> Nell to Hollis <strong>and</strong> Mises."JournalofLibertarian Studies, I, no. 4 (1977).Mises, Ludwig von. Epistemological Problems of<strong>Economic</strong>s. NewYork: New York University Press, 1981.-. Human Action: A Treatise on <strong>Economic</strong>s. Chicago: HenryRegnery; 1966; Part 1.85 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>-. Theory <strong>and</strong> History. Washington, D.C.: Ludwig von MisesInstitute, [1969] 1985.-. The Ultimate Foundation of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>. Kansas Ci~Kans.: Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1978.Rizzo, Mario. "Praxeology <strong>and</strong> Econometrics: A Critique ofPositivist <strong>Economic</strong>s." In Louis M. Spadaro, ed., New Directionsin <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s. Kansas Cit:}r, Kans.: Sheed Andrews<strong>and</strong> McMeel, 1978.Robbins, Lionel. The Nature <strong>and</strong> Significance of<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong>.New York: New York University Press, 1984.Rothbard, Murray N. "Praxeology: Reply to Mr. Schuller."American <strong>Economic</strong> Review, December 1951.-. "In Defense ofExtreme Apriorism." Sou<strong>the</strong>rn <strong>Economic</strong>Journa123, no. 3 (January 1957)._. Man) Economy) <strong>and</strong> State. 2 Vols. Los Angeles: Nash 1970[1962]; Chapter 1.-. "Praxeology: The <strong>Method</strong>ology of<strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s." InEdwin Dolan, cd., The Foundations ofModern <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s.Kansas Cit~ Kans.: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward, 1976._. Individualism <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy of<strong>the</strong> Social <strong>Science</strong>s. SanFrancisco: Cato Institute, 1979.Selgin, George. "Praxeology <strong>and</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong>ing: An Analysis of<strong>the</strong> Controversy in <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s." Review of<strong>Austrian</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s 2 (1987).Strigl, Richard von. Die okonomischen Kategorien und die Ot;ganisationder Wirtschaft. Jena: Gustav Fischer, 1923.86 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


INDEXAlbert, H., 10Andreski, St., 54Apel, K. 0., 38, 43, 57, 65,70, 79Aposteriori propositions, 17,79,80A priori ofargumentation, 65--67A priori propositions, 17, 35A priorism, 8, 9, 10, 11,14-15,24-26,44,60,69-71,81A priori syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions,19-25, 35, 59Analytic propositions, 17, 33<strong>Austrian</strong> school, 7-8, 27Axiom of action, 21-25,61-63,67Ayer, Alfred J., 28Barnes, J., 54Blalock, H. B., 36Blanshard, Br<strong>and</strong>, 33, 56, 70,71,72,74Blaug, Mark, 9, 51Bohm-Bawerk, Eugen von, 12Cairnes, John Elliott, 10,11-12,55Carnap, R., 28Causalit~ 18, 21, 29-32,36-38, 77-79Chomsk~Noam, 43Cohen, M., 70Comparative advantage(Ricardian law of association),14, 16Data analysis, 31-32Davidson, D., 70Dingler, Hugo, 21, 35, 70, 76Dolan, Edwin, 56Duncan, 0., 36Empiricism, 13-14, 28-31,51-53.criticisms of, 33-38, 55-57Epistemolog~ 17-21, 49-50,65-83Forecasting, 31-32, 38-40,43-48, 79Friedman, Milton, 31, 51Geomet~ 18, 74-76, 80,81-82Godel, K., 74Goldberger, A., 36Gordon, David, 54Habermas, Jiirgen, 42, 43, 57Harman, G., 70Hempel, C. G., 28Hermeneutics 53-54, 58Historicism 31, 53-55criticisms of, 57-59Histo~ 31-32, 40-43Hollis, Martin, 33, 56The Ludwig von Mises Institute • 87


<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Science</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Austrian</strong> <strong>Method</strong>Hoppe, Hans-Hermann, 10,21,26,30,35,36,38,44,46,50,54,59,78,79,81Hume, David, 17, 59Hutchison, M. G., 51Hutchison, Terence W, 9Kambartel, E, 18, 19, 21, 33,35,56,74,76,78KamIah, W, 70Kant, Immanuel, 17, 18, 19,59,60Kaufmann, Felix, 28Knight, Frank H., 12Kraft, ~, 51Kripke, S., 70Lachmann, Ludwig, 44, 53Locke, John, 59Lorenz, K., 19, 71Lorenzen, Paul, 21, 35,70, 71,72, 74, 75, 76MacIntyre, A., 42Marginal utili~ 14, 16, 50, 64Ma<strong>the</strong>matics, 18, 21, 72-74McCloske)', Donald, 53Menger, Carl, 12, 55Mill, John Stuart, 55Minimum wage, 15, 16Mises, Ludwig von, 8, 10, 12,17,20-22,34,36,40,42,44,49,53,55-56,59,60,61,64,65,68,76,78,79,82Mittelstaedt, E, 21Mittelstrass, J., 35, 72, 74, 76Nagel, Ernest, 28Natural sciences, 13, 35, 79Nell, Edward, 33, 56Pap, A., 33, 70Popper, Karl, 9, 28, 38, 53, 74Praxeolog)T, 8, 25, 27, 47-48,49-83Quantity of money <strong>the</strong>or)T, 15,44-47,51R<strong>and</strong>, Ayn, 20Rationalist philosoph)', 59,68-69,82-83Ricardo, David, 14Robbins, Lionel ,12Rockwell, Llewellyn H., Jr., 10Rothbard, Murra)', 47, 53, 55,61,64Sa)', Jean Baptiste, 10-11, 55Senior, Nassau, 10, 11, 55Sombart, Werner, 53Stegmuller, W, 72Stinchcombe, Arthur L., 36Strigl, Richard von, 12Structure ofknowledge, 67-68Syn<strong>the</strong>tic propositions 17Teleolog)', 78-79Validation, 13-17Veatch, H., 54Waisman, E, 72Wieser, Friedrich von, 12, 55Winch, Peter, 43Wittgenstein, L., 21Wright, G. H. von, 43, 7988 • The Ludwig von Mises Institute


ABOUT THE AUTHORHans..Hermann Hoppe is an <strong>Austrian</strong> School econo..mist <strong>and</strong> libertarian/anarcho..capitalist philosopher.He is professor of economics at <strong>the</strong> University ofNevada, Las Vegas, a distinguished fellow with <strong>the</strong> Ludwig vonMises Institute, founder <strong>and</strong> president of <strong>the</strong> Property <strong>and</strong>Freedom Society, <strong>and</strong> editor..at..large of <strong>the</strong> Journal of LibertarianStudies.He was born on September 2, 1949, in Peine, Germany. Heattended <strong>the</strong> Universitat des Saarl<strong>and</strong>es, Saarbriicken, <strong>the</strong>Goe<strong>the</strong>..Universitat, Frankfurt/M., <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> University of Michi..gan, Ann Arbor, for studies in philosophy, sociology, history,<strong>and</strong> economics. He earned his Ph.D. (philosophy 1974) <strong>and</strong> his"Habilitation" (sociology <strong>and</strong> economics, 1981), both from <strong>the</strong>Goe<strong>the</strong>..Universitat, Frankfurt/M.Professor Hoppe is <strong>the</strong> author of H<strong>and</strong>eln und Erkennen(1976); Kritik der kausalwissenschaftlichen Sozialforschung (1983);Eigentum, Anarchie und Staat (1987); Theory of Socialism <strong>and</strong> Cap~italism (1988); The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Ethics of Private Property (1993;2nd ed. 2006); Democracy-The God That Failed (2001); The Mythof National Defense (2003); <strong>and</strong> numerous articles on philoso..phy, economics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> social scienc~s.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!