28.11.2012 Views

Datives at Large

Datives at Large

Datives at Large

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>D<strong>at</strong>ives</strong> <strong>at</strong> <strong>Large</strong><br />

by<br />

María Cristina Cuervo<br />

Licenci<strong>at</strong>ura en Letras<br />

Universidad de Buenos Aires, 1995<br />

SUBMITTED TO THE DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS AND PHILOSOPHY IN PARTIAL FULLFILMENT OF<br />

THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF<br />

DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS<br />

AT THE<br />

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY<br />

JUNE 2003<br />

© 2003 María Cristina Cuervo. All rights reserved.<br />

The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute<br />

publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part.<br />

Sign<strong>at</strong>ure of the Author: ____________________________________________________________<br />

Department of Linguistics and Philosophy<br />

May 27, 2003<br />

Certified by: ______________________________________________________________________<br />

Alec Marantz<br />

Professor of Linguistics<br />

Thesis Supervisor<br />

Accepted by:______________________________________________________________________<br />

Alec Marantz<br />

Professor of Linguistics<br />

Head, Department of Linguistics and Philosophy


ABSTRACT<br />

DATIVES AT LARGE<br />

by<br />

MARÍA CRISTINA CUERVO<br />

Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy<br />

on May 27, 2003, in partial fulfillment of the<br />

requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics<br />

This dissert<strong>at</strong>ion is a study of the syntactic and semantic properties of d<strong>at</strong>ive arguments. The<br />

main source of d<strong>at</strong>a is Spanish, where d<strong>at</strong>ive arguments can appear with all types of verbs,<br />

and can have a wide range of meanings: goal, possessor, source, experiencer, affected object,<br />

causee, loc<strong>at</strong>ion, benefactive, malefactive, ethical d<strong>at</strong>ive. The challenge for a theory of d<strong>at</strong>ive<br />

arguments, which form a n<strong>at</strong>ural class morphologically, is to explain both wh<strong>at</strong> they have in<br />

common and how they differ syntactically and semantically. I argue th<strong>at</strong> d<strong>at</strong>ive arguments<br />

have structural meanings, i.e., the meaning of a d<strong>at</strong>ive DP can be derived directly from the<br />

position in which it is licensed. To be able to predict the possible meanings of d<strong>at</strong>ive<br />

arguments, it is crucial to take into account the details of the syntactic configur<strong>at</strong>ion, which<br />

include the properties of the head th<strong>at</strong> licenses the d<strong>at</strong>ive DP and of the functional heads<br />

th<strong>at</strong> construct the event structure.<br />

D<strong>at</strong>ive arguments are not direct arguments of the verb; they are, like subjects, licensed<br />

syntactically and semantically by a specialized head. This argument introducing head, the<br />

Applic<strong>at</strong>ive, licenses the d<strong>at</strong>ive DP as its specifier and rel<strong>at</strong>es this DP to the structure it takes<br />

as a complement. The range of possible meanings of a d<strong>at</strong>ive DP is predicted from the range<br />

of possible complements an applic<strong>at</strong>ive head can take (i.e. a DP or a vP), and from the range<br />

of heads th<strong>at</strong> the applic<strong>at</strong>ive phrase can be a complement of. Applic<strong>at</strong>ive heads are also<br />

sensitive to the type of event expressed by the vP (e.g., dynamic or st<strong>at</strong>ive, activity or<br />

caus<strong>at</strong>ive). The theory provides a set of positions into which an applic<strong>at</strong>ive head can merge<br />

and license an argument DP, as well as the set of interpret<strong>at</strong>ions the argument can get in each<br />

position. The set of positions is universal, but languages can differ with respect to the<br />

positions into which an applic<strong>at</strong>ive head is allowed to merge. These predictions generalize to<br />

applied arguments in languages in which they are not marked by d<strong>at</strong>ive case (e.g., English<br />

and Bantu languages).<br />

Thesis Supervisor: Alec Marantz<br />

Title: Professor of Linguistics

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!