12.07.2015 Views

Mladen-Dolar_Whats-in-a-Name

Mladen-Dolar_Whats-in-a-Name

Mladen-Dolar_Whats-in-a-Name

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Mladen</strong> <strong>Dolar</strong>What’s <strong>in</strong> a <strong>Name</strong>?


<strong>Mladen</strong> <strong>Dolar</strong>What’s <strong>in</strong> a <strong>Name</strong>?Published by: Aksioma – Institute for Contemporary Art, Ljubljanaas part of the action FREE Janez JanšaProduced by: Aksioma, steirischer herbst, Graz and Artribune, Rome<strong>in</strong> the framework of Masters & ServersEdited by Janez JanšaProofread<strong>in</strong>g: Eric Dean ScottGraphic design: Luka UmekProducer: Marcela OkretičThis work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.Ljubljana, November 2014Contact: www.aksioma.org/contactsPr<strong>in</strong>ted and distributed by: Lulu.comwww.lulu.comISBN: 978-1-312-65543-0


“What’s <strong>in</strong> a name? That which we call a roseBy any other name would smell as sweet;So Janša would, were he not Janša call’d,Reta<strong>in</strong> that dear perfection which he owesWithout that title.”Romeo and Juliet, II, 2, 43–49


It all began with Plato. The question of nam<strong>in</strong>g,of name call<strong>in</strong>g, of the aptitude or <strong>in</strong>eptitude ofnames, their appropriate or <strong>in</strong>adequate nature,their capacity to hit the mark, their reference,their multitude, their force to evoke the th<strong>in</strong>g,the impossibility to be disentangled from theth<strong>in</strong>g, it all began with Plato, that is, with a s<strong>in</strong>gularname condens<strong>in</strong>g the orig<strong>in</strong> of so many ofour concepts and our ways of th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Thereis already a certa<strong>in</strong> paradox <strong>in</strong> this, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>gthis illustrious name, for philosophy <strong>in</strong> its endeavortowards conceptuality and universality,its striv<strong>in</strong>g for ideas, notions, theories, purethought, ultimately h<strong>in</strong>ges on a dozen, or twodozen, proper names form<strong>in</strong>g the knots, p<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gthe universal to the most s<strong>in</strong>gular. Platoprom<strong>in</strong>ently features as the found<strong>in</strong>g name towhich a long str<strong>in</strong>g of concepts can be attached,provid<strong>in</strong>g them an anchorage <strong>in</strong> a name.Plato’s dialogue Cratylus, with the subtitle ‘Onthe correctness of names’, represents the firsttime <strong>in</strong> history that the question is seriouslyraised: What’s <strong>in</strong> a name? A couple of millenniabefore Juliet, Socrates meets Cratylus and Hermogeneson a street <strong>in</strong> Athens, and Socrates iscalled upon to unravel this mystery, to <strong>in</strong>tervene6


<strong>in</strong>to the already ongo<strong>in</strong>g discussion. Hermogeneswas ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that names are based ona convention, an agreement of a community ofspeakers, and whatever the arbitrary agreementmay be, it is the sole foundation of proper nam<strong>in</strong>g.1 Cratylus, on the other hand, ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>edthat names must ultimately be based <strong>in</strong> nature,so that there would have to be a tie, an umbilicalcord that attaches the names to the th<strong>in</strong>gsnamed. Can it be that names are just arbitrary?Are some names better than others to designatethe th<strong>in</strong>g named? Can the names be true orfalse, and how is one to discrim<strong>in</strong>ate the onefrom the other? How do they refer to th<strong>in</strong>gs?The specter of Juliet on the balcony is alreadythere: Would the rose by any other name smellas sweet? Does the name affect its smell, or isit completely <strong>in</strong>different to it, or does its sweetsmell affect the name and is it propelled by it?How do names smell?Socrates, who is called <strong>in</strong> as a referee, first firmlyestablishes that there is a divide between trueand false speech, and that names, be<strong>in</strong>g parts of1 “No name belongs to a particular th<strong>in</strong>g by nature, but only becauseof the rules and usage of those who establish the usage and call it by thatname.” (384d) I am us<strong>in</strong>g Plato’s Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper,Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publish<strong>in</strong>g Company, 1997.7


speech, must also partake <strong>in</strong> this divide, that theycannot be simply <strong>in</strong>different, that there are ultimatelytrue and false names. Furthermore, theremust be an essence to th<strong>in</strong>gs which the namesmust spell out 2 – th<strong>in</strong>gs have their <strong>in</strong>dependentessence and names must <strong>in</strong> some way be dependenton this <strong>in</strong>dependent essence, althoughthis essence, be<strong>in</strong>g completely <strong>in</strong>dependent, cannotbe quite affected by the ways <strong>in</strong> which wehappen to call th<strong>in</strong>gs, but it is nevertheless notunrelated. <strong>Name</strong>s are like tools that we need toget to this essence, and there can be tools whichare more or less appropriate, and hence have avary<strong>in</strong>g degree of truth or falsity. But these toolsare not quite freely ours to choose, or to selectbetter ones from, for the names are always givenby some Other, the rule-setter, the lawgiver, thename-maker (389a), whose status escapes us.The names precede us, they are transmitted fromgeneration to generation, and if one is to surmiseabout their orig<strong>in</strong> and the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of thecha<strong>in</strong>, then one would have to imag<strong>in</strong>e some div<strong>in</strong>esource, beyond the capacity of humans simplyagree<strong>in</strong>g upon conventions – names are never2 “Th<strong>in</strong>gs have some fixed be<strong>in</strong>g or essence of their own. They are not <strong>in</strong>relation to us and are not made to fluctuate by how they appear to us. Theyare by themselves, <strong>in</strong> relation to their own be<strong>in</strong>g or essence, which is theirs bynature.” (386d–e)8


quite just a matter of consensus. The Other isthere <strong>in</strong> the name, the <strong>in</strong>stance of nom<strong>in</strong>ationbeyond our reach, an <strong>in</strong>stance which must havealways already made the foundational gesture ofnam<strong>in</strong>g back <strong>in</strong> time immemorial. When, <strong>in</strong> thebiblical myth, Adam, the first man, named theanimals, this didn’t perta<strong>in</strong> to div<strong>in</strong>e jurisdiction,but to human <strong>in</strong>vention. Yet, the foundationalWord was already there, outside of human range.The supposed div<strong>in</strong>e legislator is <strong>in</strong>scrutable,so one is always <strong>in</strong> a position to scrut<strong>in</strong>ize the<strong>in</strong>scrutable, try<strong>in</strong>g to disentangle his motivesand assess the value of the names. “It’s the workof a rule-setter, it seems, to make a name. And ifnames are to be given well, a dialectician mustsupervise him.” (390d) So we need dialectics togauge and evaluate the names, they have to beexam<strong>in</strong>ed to see their possible foundation andtheir aptitude to spell out the essence of th<strong>in</strong>gs.If names had been given by some div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>stance,by gods, where does the name for gods comefrom? Why are gods called gods, ‘theoi’? “It seemsto me that the first <strong>in</strong>habitants of Greece believedonly <strong>in</strong> those gods <strong>in</strong> which many foreigners stillbelieve today – the sun, moon, earth, stars, and9


sky. And, see<strong>in</strong>g that these were always mov<strong>in</strong>g orrunn<strong>in</strong>g, they gave them the name ‘theoi’, becauseit was their nature to run (the<strong>in</strong>).” (397b) So weare a bit bemused to learn that ‘gods’ come from‘runn<strong>in</strong>g’, on the rather flimsy evidence that thetwo words happen to sound alike. And why aremen called men, ‘anthrōpoi’? “The name ‘human’signifies that the other animals do not <strong>in</strong>vestigateor reason about anyth<strong>in</strong>g they see, nor do theyobserve anyth<strong>in</strong>g closely. But a human be<strong>in</strong>g, nosooner sees someth<strong>in</strong>g – that is to say, ‘opōpe’– than he observes it closely and reasons aboutit. Hence human be<strong>in</strong>gs alone among the animalsare correctly named ‘anthrōpos’ – one whoobserves closely what he has seen (anathrōn haopōpe).” (399c) What about the soul, ‘psuchē’? Itis what gives breath and revitalizes (anapsuchon)the body. What about the body? “Some peoplesay that the body (sōma) is the tomb (sēma) ofthe soul, on the grounds that it is entombed <strong>in</strong>its present life, while others say that it is correctlycalled ‘a sign’ (sēma) because the soul signifieswhatever it wants to signify by means of thebody.” (400c) So the body is at the crossroadsbetween the tomb and the sign. What about love?“‘Erōs’ (erotic love) is so called because it flows<strong>in</strong> from outside, that is to say, the flow doesn’t10


elong to the person who has it, but is <strong>in</strong>troduced<strong>in</strong>to him through his eyes. Because of thisit was called ‘esros’ (<strong>in</strong>flux) <strong>in</strong> ancient times …”(420a–b) What about truth? “‘Alētheia’ (truth) islike some other names be<strong>in</strong>g compressed, for thediv<strong>in</strong>e motion of be<strong>in</strong>g is called ‘alētheia’ becauseit is a compressed form of the phrase ‘a wander<strong>in</strong>gthat is div<strong>in</strong>e (alē theia)’.” (421b) So truth is likea div<strong>in</strong>e drift, a div<strong>in</strong>e stray<strong>in</strong>g – gods runn<strong>in</strong>g abit amok? And so on, and so on, for all the 130or so etymologies, one fancier than the other, allprov<strong>in</strong>g that names are founded <strong>in</strong> some way, thatthey depict the th<strong>in</strong>g they name, that they are <strong>in</strong>some manner like the th<strong>in</strong>g they refer to, show<strong>in</strong>ga certa<strong>in</strong> fidelity to some of its key features, thatthey are always evocative, that there is no suchth<strong>in</strong>g as a neutral name. 3But the suggestions that Socrates proposes (andcan he really mean all this?) are based on etymologies,the names are like compounds whoseelements are already mean<strong>in</strong>gful <strong>in</strong> themselves,3 Sometimes it’s a bit tough and one needs a lot of exertion and cunn<strong>in</strong>gto f<strong>in</strong>d the connection, e.g. for technē, art or craft: “If you remove the ‘t’ and<strong>in</strong>sert an ‘o’ between the ‘ch’ and the ‘n’ and the ‘ē’ [thus obta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g echonoē],doesn’t it signify the possession of understand<strong>in</strong>g (hexis nou)?” (414b) Hmm– does it? If you remove some letters and <strong>in</strong>sert some others, couldn’t oneprove just about anyth<strong>in</strong>g? Where does this cha<strong>in</strong> of associations stop, what isit based on, what does it prove? Is Plato pull<strong>in</strong>g our leg?11


the semantic value of a name is supported bythe semantic value of another name, so thatultimately we are mov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a circle. If gods,theoi, comes from the<strong>in</strong>, runn<strong>in</strong>g, where doesthe<strong>in</strong> come from? The orig<strong>in</strong> seems to be on therun, runn<strong>in</strong>g through the tight web of words,each one evok<strong>in</strong>g others, sound<strong>in</strong>g alike, butnot just sound<strong>in</strong>g alike, s<strong>in</strong>ce the sound echothat reverberates among words co<strong>in</strong>cides withthe semantic echo, the similar sounds evokesimilar mean<strong>in</strong>gs, they po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> the directionof mean<strong>in</strong>g which cannot be disentangled fromthe sound. Sounds are never quite arbitrary <strong>in</strong>relation to mean<strong>in</strong>g, mean<strong>in</strong>g is not <strong>in</strong>differentto the sounds that happen to carry it – it runswith them.But eventually one would have to consider theelements which are <strong>in</strong> themselves not semantic,like s<strong>in</strong>gular sounds, letters, phonemes, syllables,the components which form the build<strong>in</strong>gblocks of words and all semantic units. Wouldwe thus arrive at someth<strong>in</strong>g that is purely arbitrary?No way.12


“Don’t you th<strong>in</strong>k that just as each th<strong>in</strong>g hasa color or some of those other qualities wementioned, it also has a be<strong>in</strong>g or essence?Indeed, don’t color and sound each have abe<strong>in</strong>g or essence, just like every other th<strong>in</strong>gthat we say ‘is’? … So if someone were ableto imitate <strong>in</strong> letters and syllables this be<strong>in</strong>gor essence that each th<strong>in</strong>g has, wouldn’t heexpress what each th<strong>in</strong>g itself is?” (423e)So letters, sounds and syllables could be likecolor and sound, evok<strong>in</strong>g the th<strong>in</strong>g, but express<strong>in</strong>git better, not merely by its qualities, but byspell<strong>in</strong>g out its essence. Colors and sounds havetheir craftsmen, the pa<strong>in</strong>ter and the musician,and the craftsman that we are <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g is“the namer … the one we have been look<strong>in</strong>gfor from the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.” (424a) Can we namethe namer? The name has to have a mimeticquality, it has to be like the th<strong>in</strong>g, but also it hasto perta<strong>in</strong> to logos, to the capacity of nam<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> such a way so as to spell out and express theessence. Letters (and phonemes) are the elementsrequired for such a depiction – but why those?For <strong>in</strong>stance ‘r’ (rho):13


“The letter ‘r’ seemed to the name-giver tobe a beautiful tool for copy<strong>in</strong>g motion, atany rate he often uses it for this purpose.He first uses this letter to imitate motion <strong>in</strong>the names ‘rhe<strong>in</strong>’ (‘flow<strong>in</strong>g’) and ‘rhoē’ (‘flow’)themselves. Then <strong>in</strong> ‘tromos’ (‘trembl<strong>in</strong>g’)and ‘treche<strong>in</strong>’ (‘runn<strong>in</strong>g’), and <strong>in</strong> such verbsas ‘kroue<strong>in</strong>’ (‘strik<strong>in</strong>g’), ‘thraue<strong>in</strong>’ (‘crush<strong>in</strong>g’),‘ereike<strong>in</strong>’ (‘rend<strong>in</strong>g’), ‘thrupte<strong>in</strong>’ (‘break<strong>in</strong>g’),‘kermatize<strong>in</strong>’ (‘crumbl<strong>in</strong>g’), ‘rhumbe<strong>in</strong>’ (‘whirl<strong>in</strong>g’),it is mostly ‘r’ he uses to imitate thesemotions.” (426d–e)So there is no lack of evidence, words start flock<strong>in</strong>gand mushroom<strong>in</strong>g the moment one considersthe evocative nature of, say, ‘r’. 4 Words arelike pictures of th<strong>in</strong>gs, and if this analogy is to becarried further, then a picture depicts th<strong>in</strong>gs byus<strong>in</strong>g colors that are similar to the colors of thoseth<strong>in</strong>gs, and <strong>in</strong> the same way the elements ofspeech must bear similarity to what they depict.“Then by the same token can names ever be like4 Derrida will make a big case, <strong>in</strong> Glas (Paris: Galilée, 1974), of thecompound ‘gl’ and its particular nature of ‘glue’ (featur<strong>in</strong>g also <strong>in</strong> Glas of thetitle), tak<strong>in</strong>g cue also from Cratylus, where Socrates expounds at some lengthon the nature of ‘l’ and its smoothness and softness, comb<strong>in</strong>ed with ‘g’ (as <strong>in</strong>‘glischron’, ‘gluey’), “<strong>in</strong> which the glid<strong>in</strong>g of the tongue is stopped by the powerof the ‘g’.” (427b) Consider the case of Google, to extend Socrates’ method tomodern times, and its nature of glue.14


anyth<strong>in</strong>g unless the th<strong>in</strong>gs they’re composed outof have some k<strong>in</strong>d of likeness to the th<strong>in</strong>gs theyimitate? And aren’t they composed of letters orelements?” (434b) <strong>Name</strong>s are like imitations ofth<strong>in</strong>gs, their images, notwithstand<strong>in</strong>g their lackof imagery, and if there can be better and lessgood pictures, by the criterion of likeness andthe capacity to conjure the th<strong>in</strong>g they imitate, socan there be more or less appropriate names. Yet,there can be no perfect picture, s<strong>in</strong>ce the perfectpicture would be the double of the orig<strong>in</strong>al, onecouldn’t tell them apart.“An image cannot rema<strong>in</strong> an image if it presentsall the details of what if represents.… Would there be two th<strong>in</strong>gs – Cratylusand an image of Cratylus – <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>gcircumstances? Suppose some god didn’tjust represent your color and shape the waypa<strong>in</strong>ters do, but made all the <strong>in</strong>ner parts likeyours, with the same warmth and softness,and put motion, soul, and wisdom like yours<strong>in</strong>to them – <strong>in</strong> a word, suppose he made aduplicate of everyth<strong>in</strong>g you have and put itbeside you. Would there then be two Cratylusesor Cratylus and an image of Cratylus?”(432b–c)15


The specter of two Cratyluses appears, a pictureso perfect that one cannot tell it apart from theorig<strong>in</strong>al, the perfect double. The world <strong>in</strong>habitedby doubles would be un<strong>in</strong>habitable, the world<strong>in</strong>vaded by duplicates that one couldn’t discern<strong>in</strong> relation to the orig<strong>in</strong>al, the world of an art soperfect that it would redouble this world with itsown images. But only god could supposedly besuch an artist – or is it that even the weak humanart, with all its flaws, nevertheless has the powerof blurr<strong>in</strong>g the l<strong>in</strong>es, <strong>in</strong>fr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g upon the realworld of which it is but an image? Is this whyPlato was so apprehensive and worried aboutart, to the po<strong>in</strong>t that he wanted to expel artistsfrom the city? Once one engages on the path ofreplicas, even faulty ones, there is no stopp<strong>in</strong>g,for even the bad ones still possess the magicpower of strik<strong>in</strong>g back at the orig<strong>in</strong>al.“At any rate, Cratylus, names would have anabsurd effect on the th<strong>in</strong>gs they name, if theyresembled them <strong>in</strong> every respect, s<strong>in</strong>ce all ofthem would then be duplicated, and no onewould be able to say which was the th<strong>in</strong>g andwhich was the name.” (432d)16


Here we are. If there is a spot <strong>in</strong> classical philosophywhere the project of the three Janšas is<strong>in</strong>scribed and anticipated, then it is this one.There is this passage <strong>in</strong> Plato which has been ly<strong>in</strong>glow for 2,500 years, secretly wait<strong>in</strong>g for thisproject to emerge. We have it all there: names areimperfect images, for if they were to be perfect,then they would effectively redouble th<strong>in</strong>gs, wewould be faced with a double world where themere name would be a perfect replica, and severalentities bear<strong>in</strong>g the same name would strikeback at the orig<strong>in</strong>al bearer of the name to thepo<strong>in</strong>t that one couldn’t be sure which is which.The project comes with a twist, though: if onecannot turn the name <strong>in</strong>to the perfect replicaof the th<strong>in</strong>g, one can make the perfect replicaof the name itself, the name can be cloned, soeven if the name is an imperfect image, its tenuousand tenacious connection with the beareris such that it clones the bearer. The one andonly Janez Janša is, by the mere cunn<strong>in</strong>g of thename, multiplied by three more Janšas with thethreat of becom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable. 5 Clon<strong>in</strong>g5 If I were to try my own hand at the name Janša with the Socraticmethod of fancy etymologies, then, <strong>in</strong> the ve<strong>in</strong> of Antiquity, the most prom<strong>in</strong>entcandidate for this would no doubt be Janus, the double-faced Roman deityof beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs and transitions, the god of doors and passages, display<strong>in</strong>g adifferent face on either side. Is there a similarity by which the name Janšaresembles its bearer? Here we have it, the double-faced entity, display<strong>in</strong>g >>>17


the name blurs the l<strong>in</strong>es, there is more <strong>in</strong> thename than a mere conventional marker.Of course names are not perfect images and toimag<strong>in</strong>e the universal reduplication would bean absurdity and a nightmare, but even <strong>in</strong> theirimperfect render<strong>in</strong>g they nevertheless produceeffects on the entities they name, hence Plato’sstruggle for the correctness of names and theirproper foundation. In order to be a suitable nameit has to <strong>in</strong>volve a structural similarity to whatit names, yet this similarity also <strong>in</strong>volves a dangerand threatens with confusion. S<strong>in</strong>ce Platohimself amply uses the analogy between nam<strong>in</strong>gand pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, one can refer to the way that he<strong>in</strong>sisted on the perils of pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Book Ten ofthe Republic: pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is merely the productionof copies, actually of copies of copies, s<strong>in</strong>ce theth<strong>in</strong>gs of which one makes copies are alreadycopies of ideas, but this is nevertheless dangerous.There is a mystery perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to all this: copies ofcopies – why the fuss? Why would such a slightth<strong>in</strong>g as a copy of a copy cause so much concernon the one hand the face of an orthodox communist functionary and on theother the dissident put <strong>in</strong> prison for subversive activities by the old regime;then the face of the prime m<strong>in</strong>ister and the leader of the right w<strong>in</strong>g, and theface of the corrupt politician brought to court by the new regime; the nationalhero and the demagogic trouble monger. And above all, an entity of transition.Is this then an appropriate well-founded name <strong>in</strong> the Socratic ve<strong>in</strong>?18


and passion, even rage? Why would a doubl<strong>in</strong>gcreate peril? If copies and imitations have noproper reality, or a reality so much slimmer anddimmer than the real th<strong>in</strong>g, why worry? 6 Whylose all this time and temper over someth<strong>in</strong>g som<strong>in</strong>or, negligible and even contemptible? Thetrouble is that the copy, the imitation, has thestrange power to affect the th<strong>in</strong>g itself. Imitationstrikes back, it imp<strong>in</strong>ges on the orig<strong>in</strong>al, it has animpact on it. One makes a copy, not even that, acopy of a copy, and the world of ideas seems tobe shattered, it has to be firmly defended aga<strong>in</strong>stany such <strong>in</strong>trusion. Imitators can do more harmthan they can possibly imag<strong>in</strong>e, they can causehavoc by merely replicat<strong>in</strong>g, they can disturb theorder of eternal ideas by mak<strong>in</strong>g replicas of theirreplicas. Just as the sophists, those specialists <strong>in</strong>imitation, can underm<strong>in</strong>e the true philosophyby merely mimick<strong>in</strong>g it. Ultimately, Plato’s fearwas not that the copy, the imitation, the mimeticdouble, was but a pale and unworthy shadow of6 Lacan considers this for a moment <strong>in</strong> Sem<strong>in</strong>ar XI: “[The story ofZeuxis and Parrasios] shows us why Plato raises aga<strong>in</strong>st the illusion ofpa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g. The problem is not that pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is an illusory equivalent of theobject, although Plato seems to be say<strong>in</strong>g this. … Pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g doesn’t competewith the appearance, it competes with what Plato shows us beyond theappearance as the Idea. Precisely because pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g is the appearance whichtells that it is what creates appearances, Plato raises aga<strong>in</strong>st pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g as anactivity compet<strong>in</strong>g with his own.” (Les quatre concepts fondamentaux de lapsychanalyse, Paris: Seuil, 1973, p. 103)19


the real th<strong>in</strong>g, his fear was that it was too close tothe real th<strong>in</strong>g, not separated enough from it, tiedto it by an <strong>in</strong>visible thread that cannot be cut,the umbilical cord ty<strong>in</strong>g it to its supposed model,hence the model itself couldn’t be cut loose fromit. The danger is that they are so much alike thata supposed ‘naïve observer’ could easily mistakethe one for the other.By analogy, the same goes for names. The namemay well be an imperfect image, but it is neverthelesstoo much of an image, the peril of thereverse effect is always there, it can underm<strong>in</strong>ethe reference, sta<strong>in</strong> the entity it refers to. Andwhat the Janšas have done is quite Platonic: ifthe name is to be considered as a pale copy ofthe th<strong>in</strong>g named, they have done the copy ofthe copy, actually three copies of the copy. Andif <strong>in</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g the copy of the copy is alwaysdeficient <strong>in</strong> its render<strong>in</strong>g, then they have managedthe remarkable feat of mak<strong>in</strong>g the perfectcopies of the copy, for the name can actually befully replicated <strong>in</strong> all its facets, to the po<strong>in</strong>t ofbe<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable. Should Cratylus havea perfect name, there would be two Cratyluses,what better name could one come up with thanthe precise double of the th<strong>in</strong>g; but redoubl<strong>in</strong>g20


and multiply<strong>in</strong>g the name conversely evokes thespecter of four Janez Janšas. 7The artists’ project was Platonic <strong>in</strong> its assumptions,and so was the reaction. Janša’s party, SDS(Slovene Democratic Party) was highly disconcertedby this move, it showed a lot of annoyanceand issued a number of dismissive andrather enraged remarks. Why would they fearthe copies of the copy? No doubt they sharedPlato’s concerns, assum<strong>in</strong>g that the name <strong>in</strong>some way affects the orig<strong>in</strong>al, that it spells outits key features, so that there can be no neutralnam<strong>in</strong>g, and the multiplied names carried <strong>in</strong>themselves the features spell<strong>in</strong>g out the essence,namely the Janšeity, which was hijacked by themere multiple use of the name. Each Janez Janšawas, by the name, endowed with the unfathomableessence of Janšeity, even more, this essencecannot be quite spelled out by any positive traits,it is only attached to the name, there is no otherway of gett<strong>in</strong>g to it, so the use of the name dispossessedits orig<strong>in</strong>al bearer of his s<strong>in</strong>gularity, hisuniqueness, his <strong>in</strong>effable be<strong>in</strong>g. The unease and7 When the name change occurred <strong>in</strong> 2007, the three artists changedtheir Wikipedia entries, and the first th<strong>in</strong>g that our oracle Wikipedia came upwith was disambiguation. Cf. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Janez_Janša_(disambiguation).21


the rage witness that Platonism is alive and well<strong>in</strong> today’s Slovenia, and SDS should be praisedfor subscrib<strong>in</strong>g to the ideas of Antiquity.Let me say a few more th<strong>in</strong>gs on Cratylus.Socrates is well aware of the traps <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong>names, so his concern is ultimately not the properfoundations of nam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> etymological twists andsomersaults, but rather <strong>in</strong> gett<strong>in</strong>g to the properfoundations by bypass<strong>in</strong>g names altogether.“But s<strong>in</strong>ce there is a civil war among names,with some claim<strong>in</strong>g that they are like the truthand other claim<strong>in</strong>g that they are, how thenare we to judge between them, and what arewe to start from? We can’t start from otherdifferent names because there are none.No, it’s clear we’ll have to look for someth<strong>in</strong>gother than names, someth<strong>in</strong>g that willmake pla<strong>in</strong> to us without us<strong>in</strong>g names whichof these two k<strong>in</strong>ds of names are the trueones – that is to say, the ones that expressthe truth about the th<strong>in</strong>gs that are. … But ifthat’s right, Cratylus, then it seems it mustbe possible to learn about the th<strong>in</strong>gs that are,<strong>in</strong>dependently of names.” (438d–e)22


So this is Socrates’ dream, his ultimate aim: adirect access to th<strong>in</strong>gs without the roundaboutof names, a knowledge that could read th<strong>in</strong>gsproperly and adequately without this alwaysdeficient <strong>in</strong>strument of nam<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g distortionand bias, the <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite slide of soundsand mean<strong>in</strong>gs. Only on the basis of this clearcapture of the essence <strong>in</strong>dependently of nam<strong>in</strong>gcould we then judge what names are appropriateor not, lay down weapons and sign truce<strong>in</strong> this civil war of names. The proper knowledgewould be the direct access to the namelessth<strong>in</strong>g, without any use of names which are but<strong>in</strong>truders, the short-circuit between our m<strong>in</strong>dand the essence which would get straight to thelogos of th<strong>in</strong>gs themselves without the logosof words – but doesn’t logos essentially mean‘the word’? Can one get to the nameless wordbeyond all words without any words? And howcould one testify to it without the words withwhich we are stuck? Socrates seems to shakehands with Juliet, who strives for love as thedirect access to her beloved without the by-passof the name. “’Tis but thy name that is my enemy,”says Juliet, believ<strong>in</strong>g that one should getout of the regime of names to get to the purelove. But can one ever?23


At the background of this silent and impossibleenterprise as the ultimate goal, there is theglitter<strong>in</strong>g beauty of this dialogue, the beautyof endless punn<strong>in</strong>g, the endless wordplay, theendless poetry of words echo<strong>in</strong>g other words, ofreverberations of sounds and the concomitantreverberations of mean<strong>in</strong>gs. 8 From Cratylus toF<strong>in</strong>negans Wake, there is but a step. This all maybe fanciful and far-fetched, and there have beenmany rum<strong>in</strong>ations about the status of this longexercise – could Socrates, and Plato with him,possibly be serious? Yet, at the bottom of it thereis the <strong>in</strong>sight that this entanglement of soundsand mean<strong>in</strong>gs presents the real of the name, theway that names refer to th<strong>in</strong>gs quite apart from,and on the top of, the usual univocal designation.Synonymy, with multiple different wordsmean<strong>in</strong>g the same, presupposes the univocityand unicity of mean<strong>in</strong>g that can be expressed byvarious means. Homonymy, with the differentwords sound<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>gently alike, presupposesthe dispersal of mean<strong>in</strong>g, its dissem<strong>in</strong>ation. Theparadox of Cratylus is that it tries to p<strong>in</strong> down8 “Hesitation between sound and mean<strong>in</strong>g”, this is how Roman Jakobsondef<strong>in</strong>ed poetry, follow<strong>in</strong>g Paul Valéry. What better testimony to this def<strong>in</strong>itionthan Cratylus, despite and because of its epistemic endeavor which tries todisentangle the two, to get to the purity and univocity of mean<strong>in</strong>g by means ofthe impurity and plurivocity of sounds.24


the univocal and unitary mean<strong>in</strong>g by means ofhomonymy, by the erratic nature of languagewhich unpredictably lends itself to chance encounters.Episteme meets poetics, and the demarcationl<strong>in</strong>e is blurred. Nam<strong>in</strong>g h<strong>in</strong>ges onpuns and homonyms, the erratic side of logosthat cannot be dissociated from its clear-cut sideof straight mean<strong>in</strong>g. And if I make a long shot– so does the Freudian unconscious, always us<strong>in</strong>gpuns and homonyms to pave the way to itscom<strong>in</strong>g out and convey its erratic truth. Thereis a real of language that emerges <strong>in</strong> the midst ofthis, quite beyond its capacity to convey sense.Of course we the moderns swear by Saussure,firmly believ<strong>in</strong>g that names, as all signs, are arbitraryand that any foundation of names <strong>in</strong> similarityis complete nonsense, foment<strong>in</strong>g fantasiesthat have no l<strong>in</strong>guistic or epistemological value.Yet, can there ever be a word, a sign, an utterance,that we could simply take as arbitrary, with noother value than that? Isn’t it rather that we areall profoundly Cratylian at heart, that words cont<strong>in</strong>gentlyconnect, secretly correspond and formechoes, that they constantly produce fantasies bytheir sounds, that any sign or word, as arbitrary asit may be, ceases to be just arbitrary the moment25


we use it? And even if we officially agree withHermogenes that names are just conventions,established by usage, this is not a view that wecan ever espouse <strong>in</strong> our <strong>in</strong>ner beliefs, dreams anddesires. <strong>Name</strong>s evoke, and what they evoke is notquite what they name. If the fancy foundations ofnames seem fantastic, then it is equally fantastic toassume that we will ever be able to reduce namesto their reference. <strong>Name</strong>s have their own power,and what the Janšas’ project displays is this strangepower, suspended between reference, evocation,desire, social fabric, and by their power they havethe capacity to stir the network of power as such.Cratylus, as the story goes, was allegedlyPlato’s first teacher of philosophy, his master,before he found his second and ultimate teacher<strong>in</strong> Socrates. So <strong>in</strong> this dialogue we have, like acondensation, Plato’s two masters confront<strong>in</strong>geach other and enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to a philosophical dispute,with Socrates duly tak<strong>in</strong>g the upper hand.But this is not the last of Cratylus. It seems thatCratylus, <strong>in</strong> his own way, has followed Socrates’advice of silently gett<strong>in</strong>g to the essence of th<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>in</strong>dependent of names, giv<strong>in</strong>g up on names altogether.We can read the follow<strong>in</strong>g subsequenttestimony <strong>in</strong> Aristotle:26


“Because they saw that all this world ofnature is <strong>in</strong> movement, and that about thatwhich changes no true statement can bemade, they said that of course, regard<strong>in</strong>gthat which everywhere <strong>in</strong> every respect ischang<strong>in</strong>g, noth<strong>in</strong>g could truly be affirmed.This belief that blossomed <strong>in</strong>to the most extremeof the views … was held by Cratylus,who f<strong>in</strong>ally did not th<strong>in</strong>k it right to say anyth<strong>in</strong>gbut only moved his f<strong>in</strong>ger, and criticizedHeraclitus for say<strong>in</strong>g that it is impossible tostep twice <strong>in</strong>to the same river; for he thoughtone could not do it even once.” (Metaphysics,Book 4, 1010a) 9So there we have the extreme edge of philosophy,the sheer impossibility to say anyth<strong>in</strong>g, the reductionof philosophy to merely mov<strong>in</strong>g a f<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong> silence, the ultimate gesture beyond the trapsof logos and names. Mov<strong>in</strong>g a f<strong>in</strong>ger for merelypo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g at th<strong>in</strong>gs that one cannot name? Or is itrather the universally understandable gesture ofrais<strong>in</strong>g the middle f<strong>in</strong>ger? Perhaps, <strong>in</strong> the Janšas’project, one should comb<strong>in</strong>e the two strategies:that of replicat<strong>in</strong>g the name and thus aim<strong>in</strong>g9 I am us<strong>in</strong>g The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, NewYork: Random House, 2001.27


at virtually replicat<strong>in</strong>g the bearer, and Cratylus’silent gesture of the middle f<strong>in</strong>ger.Plato doesn’t make any difference betweenproper names and common names. For him it’sall the same whether we discuss the provenanceand the aptitude of proper names such as Athena,Apollo, Hector, Astyanax, Janša, or commonnames such as truth, man, body, soul, knowledge,etc. The problem of the proper foundation of aname is the same. But this is not how this problemhas generally been treated <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics andthe philosophy of language, ancient or modern. Itis obvious that common names can have vocabularydef<strong>in</strong>itions which expla<strong>in</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g of aword by the properties of the entity it refers to, sothat every word can be accounted for <strong>in</strong> terms ofthe traits that def<strong>in</strong>e its essential features. Everycommon name can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by a bunch ofother common names, spell<strong>in</strong>g out the characteristicsthat determ<strong>in</strong>e its mean<strong>in</strong>g. 10 It is not quiteso with proper names, or at least they present aspecial case. The first one can say is that they arenot def<strong>in</strong>ed by common properties alone, one10 A haphazard example from the net: “truth: the real facts about someth<strong>in</strong>g;the th<strong>in</strong>gs that are true; the quality or state of be<strong>in</strong>g true; a statement oridea that is true or accepted as true.” This already displays the problem of alldef<strong>in</strong>itions be<strong>in</strong>g ultimately circular.28


has to add some unique properties which s<strong>in</strong>gleout its referent <strong>in</strong> its s<strong>in</strong>gularity. Say, the date andplace of birth, profession and achievements. Yetthese s<strong>in</strong>gular features that perta<strong>in</strong> exclusively tothe bearer of the name and to no other person orentity don’t quite behave <strong>in</strong> the same way as dothe common features def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g common names.If the name ‘dog’ refers to a set of propertiesthat def<strong>in</strong>e that animal’s particular nature, dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>git from other animals, thus delimit<strong>in</strong>gthe particular essence of the dog, say its ‘dogeity’,what makes a dog a dog, then the name Fido,referr<strong>in</strong>g to this s<strong>in</strong>gular dog bear<strong>in</strong>g that name,doesn’t def<strong>in</strong>e its ‘fidoity’ – there is no essenceto this name, apart from the cont<strong>in</strong>gent act ofnom<strong>in</strong>ation performed by its owner. Nor doesthe dog Fido share any features with the host ofother animals that may carry the same name.The name is not a property like any other, 11 it isarbitrarily given, but the question is then: doesthe name function simply as shorthand for a setof properties that exhaustively describe the creaturebear<strong>in</strong>g that name?11 There is an old joke about socialism as the synthesis of the highestachievements of the whole of human history to date: from prehistoric societies ittook primitivism; from the Ancient world it took slavery; from medieval society brutaldom<strong>in</strong>ation; from capitalism exploitation; and from socialism it took the name. Thefunny st<strong>in</strong>g of this joke (used on some occasions by Slavoj Žižek) is that it takesthe name to be a property like any other.29


I don’t want to enter at all <strong>in</strong>to the long andfasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g discussion which opposed the descriptivisttheory of proper names (whose mostprom<strong>in</strong>ent proponent was Bertrand Russell),claim<strong>in</strong>g that proper names can be reducedto a cluster of descriptions, and on the otherhand the harsh critics of such a theory (mostprom<strong>in</strong>ently Saul Kripke, whose Nam<strong>in</strong>g andNecessity (1980) is the most notorious book onthe subject), claim<strong>in</strong>g that a proper name is ultimatelyalways a ‘rigid designator’, irreducibleto a set of descriptions and properties, basedsolely on the cont<strong>in</strong>gent act of nam<strong>in</strong>g rigidlydesignat<strong>in</strong>g its object. Let me take a by-pass. Ifwe take a name like ‘Slovene’, then it refers toa set of descriptions – geographical, historical,l<strong>in</strong>guistic, demographic, etc. – but also to a setof some supposed real or imag<strong>in</strong>ary properties– the Slovenes be<strong>in</strong>g diligent, discipl<strong>in</strong>ed,hard-work<strong>in</strong>g, conscientious, freedom-lov<strong>in</strong>g,friendly, god-fear<strong>in</strong>g, proud, etc. (or else pompous,arrogant, envious, conceited, self-hat<strong>in</strong>g,self-righteous, take your pick). In this way, thename ‘Slovene’ would be shorthand for thesedescriptions, the function of the name wouldbe noth<strong>in</strong>g else but wrapp<strong>in</strong>g them up <strong>in</strong> a bundleand br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g them together under the same30


head<strong>in</strong>g. The name is empty <strong>in</strong> itself, it is justa sack of elements, it refers to noth<strong>in</strong>g by itselfoutside of these traits. But is this ever the case?It is rather that the empty signifier designatessome mysterious property x which is irreducibleto any of the traits, it is rather that one isprey to an <strong>in</strong>version, a structural illusion, thatall the properties appear to be but emanationsof that enigmatic property x which is designatedmerely by the name. There is the specter of‘Sloveneness’ which cannot be quite spelled outby the properties and which is p<strong>in</strong>ned down bythe name alone, not any of the positive traits. 12‘Sloveneness’ is <strong>in</strong>effable, undef<strong>in</strong>able, unfathomable,<strong>in</strong>scrutable, immeasurable, it producesthe phantom of <strong>in</strong>describable depth just by be<strong>in</strong>ga pure effect of the empty gesture of nam<strong>in</strong>g.The name, beyond all properties, beyond thedescriptivist account of proper names, refers toan x as its proper referent, a s<strong>in</strong>gular unnamablesubstance (as opposed to common nameswhich <strong>in</strong>habit different degrees of universalityand particularity, and are <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple not s<strong>in</strong>gular).It creates an x, which is an <strong>in</strong>effable be<strong>in</strong>g12 I am borrow<strong>in</strong>g this example freely from the only book by Slavoj Žižekdevoted largely to Slovenes, Jezik, ideologija, Slovenci, Ljubljana: Delavskaenotnost, 1987.31


without properties, a noth<strong>in</strong>g which neverthelessappears as someth<strong>in</strong>g, it never goes up <strong>in</strong>smoke by reduction to descriptions, it persists<strong>in</strong> its noth<strong>in</strong>gness and provides the pure stuffof fantasies. 13It is thus with every name. No name withouta specter. Nam<strong>in</strong>g is evok<strong>in</strong>g a phantom, conjur<strong>in</strong>ga ghost. One always names more than acluster of descriptions, the s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong>effable xis there accompany<strong>in</strong>g the use of names. Thename always names the unnamable, or ratherby nam<strong>in</strong>g it always produces the unnamable,someth<strong>in</strong>g that cannot be captured by a merename as shorthand for descriptive traits. The realof the name is what escapes nam<strong>in</strong>g, yet standsat its core. 1413 All this can be most economically clarified by the Lacanian algebra ofS1/S2. S2 stands for the cha<strong>in</strong> of properties, all of which make sense, whileS1 stands for ‘the signifier without a signified’, a senseless signifier susta<strong>in</strong>edmerely by the act of nom<strong>in</strong>ation and its cont<strong>in</strong>gency. The proper referent of S1would then be precisely the object ‘a’ and its unfathomable be<strong>in</strong>g.14 A great literary testimony to this is Marcel Proust, with his ample rum<strong>in</strong>ationsabout the images evoked by the names of various places, the phantasmaticcities, their particular flavors and aura, the dreamed up countries,conjured by the mere name. And of course, once he set foot <strong>in</strong> some of thoseplaces, it all evaporated, there was a structurally necessary bitter disappo<strong>in</strong>tment,the place looked so different from what its name so vividly evoked. Thephantom <strong>in</strong>duced by the name is very central to Proust’s enterprise – considerjust the title of the third part of the first volume, Le nom de pays: le nom (The<strong>Name</strong> of the Country: The <strong>Name</strong>), correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the part of the secondvolume entitled Le nom de pays: le pays (The <strong>Name</strong> of the Country: TheCountry).32


If we try to p<strong>in</strong> down the name Janez Janša to aset of positive descriptions, one stumbles on aproblem at the outset. One could try “the manborn on 17 September 1958 <strong>in</strong> Ljubljana, twiceSlovene prime m<strong>in</strong>ister, sentenced to prison oncorruption charges, the hero of Slovene <strong>in</strong>dependence”etc., but the trouble is that this persondoesn’t bear the name Janez Janša, but IvanJanša. Everyth<strong>in</strong>g may be correct, except for thename, the prerequisite of def<strong>in</strong>ite description. Itall seems that Janša is ‘always already’ redoubled,redoubled from the outset, <strong>in</strong> himself, known bya name which is not the name of his documentsor birth certificate, mak<strong>in</strong>g a career under anassumed name, thus present<strong>in</strong>g a good conundrumfor the analytical philosophers of language(I am sure Kripke would have loved this andwould eagerly <strong>in</strong>clude this case <strong>in</strong> one of hisbooks). The s<strong>in</strong>gularity of nam<strong>in</strong>g coupled withthe s<strong>in</strong>gularity of the date and place of birth isalready <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong>to a wider social web of recognition,of ‘also known as’, ‘aka’, of an assumedand socially recognized identity, apart from therigid designator attested by documents. Paradoxically,the three Janšas didn’t replicate his nameat all, they replicated its double, and s<strong>in</strong>ce theyreally possess documents to prove that they are33


Janez Janša, they ‘really’ are the legitimate bearersof this name, while the orig<strong>in</strong>al is an impostor. 15But what is a ‘real’ name? Can a name, freely givento people by choice, be ‘real’ <strong>in</strong> the sense thatother entities are, entities named by the Other,the Platonic name-giver, the supposed div<strong>in</strong>enamer, where we have no choice and no say?Do the official attestation and the documentsvouchsafe for the reality of a name?But maybe the real of a name, apart from its irreduciblesound value, rather resides <strong>in</strong> the phantomthat is evoked by it, the s<strong>in</strong>gular namelesssubstance it po<strong>in</strong>ts to. This enigmatic feature isperhaps at the bottom of the unease producedby the name-change of the three Janšas, for if the<strong>in</strong>effable x is s<strong>in</strong>gular, perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to that nameonly <strong>in</strong> its s<strong>in</strong>gularity, then the replication ofthe name causes some havoc by <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>this s<strong>in</strong>gular substance. It is not that the s<strong>in</strong>gularperson Janez Janša (aka Ivan Janša) would beaffected by this replication – why would a politicianof some stand<strong>in</strong>g care about some crazy15 Even more: the three Janšas were issued birth certificates from whichit follows that they have been born as Janez Janša, by the effect of the namechange they have always already been Janez Janša. <strong>Name</strong> is endowed with aretroactive causality, it is not only a harb<strong>in</strong>ger of a new future career, but alsotransforms the past.34


artists chang<strong>in</strong>g their names? It is rather thatthe mysterious s<strong>in</strong>gular substance is affected themoment there are more pretenders to it. Andif this property x of Janez Janša can be referredto as Janšeity (<strong>in</strong>adequately, for it perta<strong>in</strong>s toits essence that it cannot be named), then itappears that the three new pretenders raise aclaim precisely to Janšeity and they threaten todispossess the one and true agent with a properclaim to it. They threaten to deprive him not ofhis unique name (for no name is unique), butby willfully embrac<strong>in</strong>g this name and replicat<strong>in</strong>git they threaten to divest him of his substance,the x, that what is more <strong>in</strong> him than his nameand its descriptive traits, the unnamable treasureand the aura.Let us now approach names from a verydifferent angle, that of a name-giver and therelation of names to posterity. We can all atsome po<strong>in</strong>t step <strong>in</strong>to the shoes of the Platonicname-giver and choose names of our children,and the names that we choose will stickto their fates, for better or worse, it depends onour whim how they will ‘really’ be called, wecan arbitrarily mark them, and they will haveto make do with that fateful mark, live up to35


it, revolt aga<strong>in</strong>st it, love it or hate it, but therecan be no <strong>in</strong>difference, names <strong>in</strong>spire passionsthat one cannot escape. One strik<strong>in</strong>g examplewill suffice.Freud had six children, three sons and threedaughters. To list them by the order of birth:Mathilde (1887), Jean-Mart<strong>in</strong> (1889), Oliver(1891), Ernst (1892), Sophie (1893), Anna(1895). Freud <strong>in</strong>sisted to choose the names ofthe children himself. This is how he commentedon this <strong>in</strong> The Interpretation of Dreams:“I had <strong>in</strong>sisted on their names [of my children]be<strong>in</strong>g chosen, not accord<strong>in</strong>g to the fashion ofthe moment, but <strong>in</strong> memory of people I havebeen fond of. Their names made the children<strong>in</strong>to revenants. [Ihre <strong>Name</strong>n machen die K<strong>in</strong>derzu Revenants.] And after all, I reflected,was not hav<strong>in</strong>g children our own path to immortality?”(PFL 2, p. 487; SA II, pp. 468–9) 16This is a most curious remark. To follow its logic,children would actually be like ghosts, the revenants,for their names are chosen on the model16 The Pelican Freud Library (PFL), 15 vols., London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>, 1973–86;Studienausgabe (SA), 10 vols., Frankfurt/M: Fischer, 1969–75.36


of the people we care for so that they would livetheir afterlife for them, they are by their namesdoomed to be the impersonations of the dead. 17Their life already starts as an afterlife, they areghosts with a mission. Freud, by choos<strong>in</strong>g thenames himself, fully exerted his paternal authorityon this po<strong>in</strong>t as an authority of nam<strong>in</strong>g. Thename perta<strong>in</strong>s to the father.So who were the models? First for the sons:Jean-Mart<strong>in</strong> was named after Jean-Mart<strong>in</strong> Charcot,Freud’s great teacher and master <strong>in</strong> mattersof psychiatry, with whom he spent a most formativeyear at the Salpêtrière Hospital <strong>in</strong> Paris <strong>in</strong>1885–6; Oliver was named after Oliver Cromwell,for whom Freud always harbored a greatadmiration; 18 and Ernst after Ernst Brücke,17 At the po<strong>in</strong>t of their nam<strong>in</strong>g, four out of six models were actually alive.Nevertheless, the po<strong>in</strong>t is that children are dest<strong>in</strong>ed to survive the modelsafter which they have been named, and carry on the torch for them, they arenamed as already the revenants (literally those who come back), even thoughof the liv<strong>in</strong>g.18 Freud was anyth<strong>in</strong>g but naïve, so he commented on this choice <strong>in</strong> thefollow<strong>in</strong>g manner: “… my second son, to whom I had given the first name ofa great historical figure [Oliver Cromwell] who had powerfully attracted me <strong>in</strong>my boyhood, especially s<strong>in</strong>ce my visit to England. Dur<strong>in</strong>g the year before thechild’s birth, I had made up my m<strong>in</strong>d to use this name if it were a son and Igreeted the newborn baby with a feel<strong>in</strong>g of high satisfaction. (It is easy to seehow the suppressed megalomania of fathers is transferred <strong>in</strong> their thoughtson to their children, and it seems quite probable that this is one of the ways <strong>in</strong>which the suppression of that feel<strong>in</strong>g, which becomes necessary <strong>in</strong> actual life,is carried out.)” (Quoted from http://www.freud.org.uk/education/dream/63806/garibaldi-dream/)37


Freud’s first great teacher and master <strong>in</strong> mattersof natural science who died three months beforethe son’s birth – Freud spent ‘the happiest yearsof his life’ <strong>in</strong> Brücke’s physiological laboratory <strong>in</strong>1876–81. 19 As for the daughters, Mathilde wasnamed after Mathilde Breuer (born Altmann),the wife of Josef Breuer, Freud’s closest friendand collaborator at the time; Sophie after SophieSchwab-Paneth, a close friend of the family; andAnna after Anna Hammerschlag-Lichtheim, anotherclose family friend and famously Freud’spatient – she was the notorious Irma of thedream of Irma’s <strong>in</strong>jection, Freud’s most famousspecimen dream. What the three women had <strong>in</strong>common was that they were the godmothers tothe three daughters.One cannot but be a bit perplexed: the sons aftergreat scientists and political heroes, the daughtersafter the friends of the family who eagerly assumedthe roles of godmothers. Freud, the greatrevolutionary, the great discoverer and <strong>in</strong>novator,was at the same time deeply footed <strong>in</strong> the 19thcentury with his very private web of fantasies19 Freud’s grandson, the great pa<strong>in</strong>ter Lucian Freud, was Ernst’s son,and <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with the tradition of the family he was duly named after his mother(Lucie Brasch).38


which conditioned nam<strong>in</strong>g, this short-circuitbetween the most private and the public. Anyparent who ever named his or her child knowsabout the anxiety that comes with nam<strong>in</strong>g, the<strong>in</strong>tricate mixture of private fixations and fantasies,personal fancies and fixed ideas, the imag<strong>in</strong>aryaura that surrounds various names, and onthe other hand, of the public emblem that thechild will have to carry throughout his/her life.But the <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>Freud’s remark is the connection that he makesbetween names and immortality. Hav<strong>in</strong>g childrenis our way to immortality, the cont<strong>in</strong>uationof our lives through our offspr<strong>in</strong>g. But this isnot enough, what is at stake is not merely abiological survival of an <strong>in</strong>dividual by proxy,there is the question of symbolic transmissionby names. The genus will go on and may extendthe present <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>to possible immortalitythrough his progeny, our genes may be <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itelyreplicated – an <strong>in</strong>dividual may be seen as a gene’sway to create another gene, its double – genesare <strong>in</strong>deed selfish, to follow Richard Dawk<strong>in</strong>s, 20they only care about their own reproduction, we20 Richard Dawk<strong>in</strong>s, The Selfish Gene, Oxford University Press, 1976.39


are just a means to their ends. Our biologicals<strong>in</strong>gularity, <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> the unique signature ofour DNA, may thus be <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely cont<strong>in</strong>uedand prolonged. But the name is like our culturalDNA, the unique mark of our s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong>scription<strong>in</strong>to the social, and nam<strong>in</strong>g children afterour heroes and our beloved ones is propelledby the hope that our cultural DNA may run atleast a small part of the way alongside with ourbiological DNA <strong>in</strong>to the unforeseeable future.The <strong>in</strong>dividual name may be seen as a signifier’sway to provide its replica, its cultural progeny,the <strong>in</strong>dividual is the name’s way to make anothername. Generically, this holds for family nameswhich generally bear the impr<strong>in</strong>t of the name ofthe father, the supposed head of the family andthe supposed name-giver, but this also holds forthe private trade, so to speak, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual givennames, freely chosen, but <strong>in</strong>spired by the samemission, although <strong>in</strong> far less predictable ways,prompted by personal enthusiasms, fantasies,preferences and <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations.If the name raises claims to immortality, thenJanez Janša may perhaps not be so enthusiasticabout be<strong>in</strong>g immortalized by these particularreplications of his name. Although, who knows,40


it may prove that they ultimately present a betterchance at his immortality than his politicalcareer. In the long run, art may last longer thanpolitics.There is another way that the name is connectedto immortality. Brecht speaks somewhereabout Hegel, his great Teacher <strong>in</strong> the matters ofthe Great Method, i.e. dialectics. He ascribes tohim “the abilities of one of the greatest humoristsamong philosophers”, especially s<strong>in</strong>ce he wasparticularly <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> how th<strong>in</strong>gs constantlychange <strong>in</strong>to their opposites and can never rema<strong>in</strong>the same. “He contested that one equals one,not only because everyth<strong>in</strong>g that exists <strong>in</strong>exorablyand persistently passes <strong>in</strong>to someth<strong>in</strong>g else,namely its opposite, but because noth<strong>in</strong>g at allis identical to itself. As any humorist, he wasespecially <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> what becomes of th<strong>in</strong>gs.As the Berl<strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g goes: ‘My, how you havechanged, Emil!’” 21 At this po<strong>in</strong>t the k<strong>in</strong>d publisherprovides a footnote, expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that thisis taken from a Berl<strong>in</strong> joke <strong>in</strong> which a widowvisits the grave of her late husband and addresseshis gravestone with these words. The example21 Flüchtl<strong>in</strong>gsgespräche, Gesammelte Werke, vol. 14, Frankfurt/M.:Suhrkamp, 1982, p. 1460.41


of dialectics par excellence: everyth<strong>in</strong>g changes,for example, Emil has turned <strong>in</strong>to a gravestonebear<strong>in</strong>g his name. (It was not me who came upwith the name Emil here, it was Brecht, whowrote it referr<strong>in</strong>g to Berl<strong>in</strong> folklore.)When they changed their names, the three JanezJanšas, and especially the one who dialectically‘is and is not’ Emil (‘namely’ Emil Hrvat<strong>in</strong>),kept po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out, among other th<strong>in</strong>gs, that thechange of one’s name carries the connotation ofa symbolic death. If you change your name, itis as if you’ve died, as if you’ve experienced yourown death <strong>in</strong> the (symbolic) relation to others. 22Brecht’s joke presents the flip-side of the matter:the bearer changes, even more, passes away anddisappears <strong>in</strong> the most literal way, but what rema<strong>in</strong>sis precisely his name. He has ‘really’ died,but the name symbolically survived. No matterhow drastically the state of the bearer changes <strong>in</strong>this alteration, the name rema<strong>in</strong>s the same andpersists. The name is that which will outlive us,22 Most curiously, the onl<strong>in</strong>e Glossary of Slovene Art 1945–2005 (www.pojmovnik.si) features brief entries on the three artists prior to their namechange, and it undauntedly states 2007 as the year of their death. Emil Hrvat<strong>in</strong>(1964–2007), Davide Grassi (1970–2007) and Žiga Kariž (1973–2007).The fact that the latter eventually changed his name aga<strong>in</strong> to its previous formdidn’t resurrect him from the dead <strong>in</strong> the impartial eyes of the Glossary bigOther.42


it is more endur<strong>in</strong>g than we are, it presents ourchance at immortality. It will outlive us, first <strong>in</strong>the general sense, as <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> the symbolicorder and thus serve as a reference po<strong>in</strong>t forwhat we might be remembered for, but then <strong>in</strong>a more banal and directly material sense, as writtenon a gravestone, i.e. literally carved <strong>in</strong> stone.A name is someth<strong>in</strong>g that impr<strong>in</strong>ts our identity<strong>in</strong>to stone and makes it <strong>in</strong>delible. <strong>Name</strong>s areendowed with a secret plot – the word that <strong>in</strong>English also means a family tomb (Hitchcock’slast film was entitled Family Plot and it playedprecisely on this double mean<strong>in</strong>g of the word).They have a secret mission, a dest<strong>in</strong>ation, thename be<strong>in</strong>g that part of us that will one day f<strong>in</strong>ditself on our gravestone. The name’s secret <strong>in</strong>tentis, among other th<strong>in</strong>gs, to be carved <strong>in</strong>to thegravestone, <strong>in</strong>to the endurable substance, virtuallyunchangeable, at least as far as can be foreseen.It is that part of our identity that is more last<strong>in</strong>gthan we are, written on the supposedly mostlast<strong>in</strong>g substance of stone. <strong>Name</strong>s are ‘eternal’,we are not, names last, we pass away. The freechoice of the name change has its flip-side, thenon-choice regard<strong>in</strong>g the gravestone where thename would eventually be carved, the immortalpart of our mortal selves, and the context of the43


symbolic death accompany<strong>in</strong>g the name-changehas its flip side <strong>in</strong> symbolic survival. The namesymbolically cont<strong>in</strong>ues to live its life beyondour lives, it presents the real of our lives beyondour bodily life. On the one hand, there is thepart whereby the bearer rema<strong>in</strong>s the same, unchanged,and can freely change his names at hiswhim, without this affect<strong>in</strong>g his or her substance(at least seem<strong>in</strong>gly), but on the other hand, thereis the part where the name v<strong>in</strong>dicates itself frombeyond the grave, prov<strong>in</strong>g to outlast its bearer,who may change his substance but not his name.The name proves to be more ‘substantial’ andendurable than the pass<strong>in</strong>g bearer. We are but abrief episode <strong>in</strong> the long life of our names.There is a 200-year-old French say<strong>in</strong>g: “Thereis no room for two Napoleons.” It has severalvariations, e.g. “at the top, there is not enoughspace for two Napoleons” or “France is not bigenough for two Napoleons.” If someone claimsto be Napoleon, then this is a clear case of alunatic that has to be put <strong>in</strong> an asylum – hencealso the archetypal idea of a lunatic claim<strong>in</strong>g tobe Napoleon. 23 And s<strong>in</strong>ce this particular name23 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lacan’s famous adage, the madman is not the poor wretchwho believes himself to be a k<strong>in</strong>g, but the true madman <strong>in</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>g who >>>44


change does not <strong>in</strong>volve just any name but thename of the prime m<strong>in</strong>ister, then <strong>in</strong> light ofthis adage it entails a question: is Slovenia bigenough not for two, but for four Napoleons? 24Should the three surplus Napoleons, the Napoleonextras, who zealously claim that they, too, areNapoleons and prove this with documents, beput <strong>in</strong> an asylum? Or is this an ‘art project’, thusa modern alternative to the asylum, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> art,supposedly, everyth<strong>in</strong>g is allowed and the mostpreposterous ideas can be even highly sociallyvalued? Where do they belong – <strong>in</strong> an asylumor <strong>in</strong> a gallery? Or should they be put <strong>in</strong> prison,like their model, the Slovene ex-prime m<strong>in</strong>isterwho eventually landed <strong>in</strong> prison <strong>in</strong> June 2014,convicted of corruption? What is the status of‘art’ <strong>in</strong> this immediate meddl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the structureof power and its names?The ‘art project’, if this is one, poses a most ‘real’question that relates nom<strong>in</strong>ation and dom<strong>in</strong>ation.The question is not what qualifies somebelieveshimself to be a k<strong>in</strong>g. It may be said that a considerable part of Slovenepolitical problems stems from hav<strong>in</strong>g such a case <strong>in</strong> our midst.24 On a more trivial level, the three Janšas experienced quite a fewpractical difficulties when they couldn’t travel together on a plane because thecomputer cancelled their surplus tickets, assum<strong>in</strong>g that three passengers withthe same name must be an error. So there is no room for two Napoleons evenon a plane.45


one to bear, e.g. the name Žiga Kariž, but whatqualifies someone bear<strong>in</strong>g, e.g. the name JanezJanša to occupy the position of power. What isthe <strong>in</strong>tricate connection between a name andpower? Is power without a name possible? Is aname not <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> power relations possible?Is there such a th<strong>in</strong>g as a neutral and <strong>in</strong>nocentname? A name is always the bearer of a symbolicmandate and as soon as there appear false pretenders,with the documents and all, the questionis raised about the validity and the justification ofthe symbolic mandate enabl<strong>in</strong>g power. <strong>Name</strong>s,to be sure, refer to genealogies, but through thatthey always <strong>in</strong>volve a certa<strong>in</strong> distribution of power.To arrogate a name is to arrogate power.Here is a true story, an episode from Russianhistory. The story of Boris Godunov, theRussian regent and then the Russian tsar (<strong>in</strong>the period 1598–1605), was immortalized firstby Pushk<strong>in</strong>’s drama (1831) and then most notablyby Mussorgsky’s opera (1869/72), one ofthe most impressive operas <strong>in</strong> history. It prom<strong>in</strong>entlyfeatures the episode of the false Dmitry,the pretender to the throne. The story goes thatBoris Godunov had a tsarevich Dmitry murdered<strong>in</strong> 1591 (this was the youngest son of46


Ivan the Terrible) <strong>in</strong> his lust for power (althoughmodern historians have doubts about this), andonce Godunov became the tsar there appeareda pretender (around 1600) who claimed to bethe tsarevich who escaped the assass<strong>in</strong>ation. 25The false Dmitry, seen as a threat and a nuisanceby Godunov, fled to Poland where he gatheredconsiderable support and converted to Catholicismto secure the help of Vatican. He enteredRussia with his small army <strong>in</strong> 1604, where a lotof people jo<strong>in</strong>ed him <strong>in</strong> his campaign aga<strong>in</strong>st theunpopular tsar. His army grew, he was <strong>in</strong>itiallyvictorious until his luck changed and he sufferedsome bad defeats. But when Godunov died <strong>in</strong>1605, the tides changed aga<strong>in</strong>, so eventually thesupposed Dmitry triumphantly entered Moscowsurrounded by a mass of followers and wasduly crowned as the new tsar Dmitry. The nameworked, the name was enough for the claim topower and for the successful accession, althoughthe guy was certa<strong>in</strong>ly an impostor, most probablya monk called Grigory Otrepyev. Once onthe throne, he married his beloved Polish ladyMar<strong>in</strong>a Mniszech, who’d helped him all along.25 In Russian, as <strong>in</strong> Slovene, the pretender is called samozvanec, literallysomeone who calls himself by a name, someone who gives himself a name,a self-namer. He is not called by that name by the others, but by his own whim.47


But the tides soon changed aga<strong>in</strong>, his Catholicismwas a bit too much for Russia, he was assass<strong>in</strong>ated<strong>in</strong> 1606 along with his supporters anda new tsar was appo<strong>in</strong>ted, Vassily IV. But thiswas not all: soon a second pretender turned up,the false Dmitry II, aga<strong>in</strong> gather<strong>in</strong>g considerablesupport of Poles and Cossacks, putt<strong>in</strong>g up a sizeablearmy and an armed camp at Tush<strong>in</strong>o. He,too, had some military success, he tried to seizeMoscow but didn’t quite manage – althoughthe deposed tsar<strong>in</strong>a Mar<strong>in</strong>a, the widow of thefirst Dmitry, recognized him as the genu<strong>in</strong>e re<strong>in</strong>carnationof her first husband, claim<strong>in</strong>g thatthis was the same man. He was assass<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong>his own turn <strong>in</strong> 1610. But this was not all: <strong>in</strong>1611, yet another false pretender appeared, thefalse Dmitry III, aga<strong>in</strong> secur<strong>in</strong>g some support,the Cossacks acknowledged him as the tsar, buthe soon followed the gory fate of his two predecessors<strong>in</strong> 1612. The hapless widow yet aga<strong>in</strong>miraculously recognized the third pretender asthe true one, her one and only husband. Canone be married to a name? Here is a lady whomarried the name Dmitry, she was faithfullymarried to this one name throughout her life,it just so happened that it had three differentbearers, all of them impostors. The story is fas-48


c<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, it appealed not only to the Russians(above all Pushk<strong>in</strong> and Mussorgsky, but quitea few others), but also to, say, Schiller (with hisunf<strong>in</strong>ished drama Demetrius) and Rilke (wherethe story features <strong>in</strong> his Malte Laurids Brigge).And as if all this was not enough, the story wasreenacted once more <strong>in</strong> the Russian 20th century,with the appearance <strong>in</strong> 1920 of ‘pr<strong>in</strong>cess’Anastasia, the supposed youngest daughter of theassass<strong>in</strong>ated last tsar Nicolas, the Grand Duchesswho claimed to have escaped assass<strong>in</strong>ation andthen divided the Russian exile community <strong>in</strong>toa bunch of firm believers and the majority ofskeptical opponents. The story was immortalizedby Hollywood (Ingrid Bergman got an Oscar forthis role <strong>in</strong> 1956). The lady tried hard to proveher case throughout her life, which entailed oneof the longest lawsuits <strong>in</strong> history, but she waseventually turned down <strong>in</strong> 1970 on the basisof <strong>in</strong>sufficient evidence. As it turned out, withthe DNA analysis <strong>in</strong> 1994, she was an impostor,her name was actually Anna Anderson. But ofcourse she was not the only one, some ten womenclaimed to be the Grand Duchess Anastasia. 2626 The theme of impostors looms large <strong>in</strong> Russian culture. Just rememberKhlestakov <strong>in</strong> Gogol’s amaz<strong>in</strong>g The Government Inspector (Revizor) or >>>49


The false pretenders assumed the royal name<strong>in</strong> their claim to power (or to social prestige),and it all ended <strong>in</strong> bloodshed (or <strong>in</strong> shame).What’s <strong>in</strong> a name? How come the mere namecan lead to so much blood and havoc? The leastone can say is that names are not to be takenlightly – there is always the moment of the claimto power <strong>in</strong> every name, <strong>in</strong> the assumption ofthe social role that goes along with it, <strong>in</strong> thetransmission of symbolic legacy, <strong>in</strong> the socialimpact, <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>scription <strong>in</strong>to a genealogy, andthe royal false pretenders only display this <strong>in</strong> aparticularly salient manner. But their stories alsoentail the flip-side, the moment of bemusementwhereby one has the feel<strong>in</strong>g that one is actuallyalways a false pretender, and a false pretenderto a royal name that should be v<strong>in</strong>dicated onlybr<strong>in</strong>gs forth some part of our common fate.For there is no way one could <strong>in</strong>habit a namelegitimately, naturally, with ease, by be<strong>in</strong>g fullyjustified to bear the name one bears. There is nosufficient ground to bear a name, it can neverbe substantiated, no name is ever covered by theLeibnizian pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of sufficient reason. ProperChichikov <strong>in</strong> his Dead Souls, or the notorious figure of Ostap Bender <strong>in</strong> Ilfand Petrov, the proverbial impostor who started to function as an epitome ofsometh<strong>in</strong>g deeply planted <strong>in</strong> ‘the Russian soul’.50


names, as opposed to common names, can alwaysbe other than they are, one is free to chooseand to change them, or such is the necessaryillusion (while common names are fixed by thedictionary and consensus). The feel<strong>in</strong>g of be<strong>in</strong>gan impostor, a false pretender to the name, isnot some personal sentiment or idiosyncrasy, itis a structural feel<strong>in</strong>g that accompanies namesas their shadow and effect.The three Janšas, by their name-change, maylook someth<strong>in</strong>g like a reenactment of the threefalse Dmitrys. They brought to the fore both aspects,the name as a claim to power, the tacit distributionof power that goes along with names,and on the other hand, the false pretense, theimpersonation that accompanies the function<strong>in</strong>gof names. One is always the impersonator ofone’s own name. Their name-change raised thequestion not only of them be<strong>in</strong>g false pretendersto the name of Janez Janša, but also of JanezJanša be<strong>in</strong>g a false pretender to his own nameand to its stakes <strong>in</strong> power. They never disclosedtheir motives (claim<strong>in</strong>g personal reasons and,at the most, artistic ambitions), never raised aclaim to power (as opposed to the Dmitrys),but always ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed (<strong>in</strong> accordance with51


the Dmitrys) that they were ‘real’ Janez Janšas,which they could prove with their documents,and that is more than their model can do. Butby desist<strong>in</strong>g from reasons and justifications, boththe implied web of power and the ‘structural’impersonation came all the more to the fore.In Slovene history, the memory of the timewhen people massively changed their names andassumed new ones is still very alive. These werethe so-called ‘partisan names’ dur<strong>in</strong>g the time ofthe anti-fascist struggle, the assumed names thatwere based on the tradition of us<strong>in</strong>g fictitiousnames <strong>in</strong> the circumstances of conspiratorialand illegal activities, cover<strong>in</strong>g up ‘real’ identities<strong>in</strong> order to protect their bearers. But, on theother hand, this justification does not expla<strong>in</strong>everyth<strong>in</strong>g, for beh<strong>in</strong>d the pragmatic justificationthere lurks a different desire and will, a desire anda will to found a new symbolic order, a new orderof designations and symbolic mandates wherethe ‘real’ and the symbolic impact no longer lie<strong>in</strong> the real name, but <strong>in</strong> a newly chosen and assumedpartisan name, which is dest<strong>in</strong>ed to be thebearer of the real identity, regardless of the officialdocuments. One can be rem<strong>in</strong>ded that the revolutionarywill of the French Revolution expressed52


itself <strong>in</strong>, among other th<strong>in</strong>gs, a new calendar andthe new designations of months, among whichthe best known is perhaps Brumaire (and Thermidorand Germ<strong>in</strong>al), s<strong>in</strong>ce the above-mentionedNapoleon assumed power on 18 Brumaire, whileMarx immortalized this date <strong>in</strong> the eponymousessay referr<strong>in</strong>g to the other Napoleon, Napoleon’snephew, who, <strong>in</strong> the historical farcical repetition,relied precisely on the mandate of hisname – another false pretender but bear<strong>in</strong>g the‘real’ name. For a more direct precedent, onecan evoke Vladimir Ilyich Ulyanov chang<strong>in</strong>g hisname to Len<strong>in</strong>, Lev Davidovich Bronste<strong>in</strong> toTrotsky and Iossif Vissarionovich Dzhugashvilito Stal<strong>in</strong>. And Josip Broz to Tito. The will for asymbolic cut, a radical shift <strong>in</strong> the symbolic fabricof society, manifests itself as the will to renam<strong>in</strong>g.The name change of the three Janez Janšas is, <strong>in</strong>a certa<strong>in</strong> way, <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong>to the tradition of thepartisan struggle, assum<strong>in</strong>g partisan names, s<strong>in</strong>cethese new names – three identical ones, contraryto tradition – apart from <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g a very practicalofficial change of all the documents, also hadthe effect of the foundation of a parallel symbolicspace, of a virtual new designation and thus theperspective of a different symbolic relation that53


lurs the delimitation of art, civil status andpolitical mandate. The impact was conditionedprecisely <strong>in</strong> the disregard of the delimitation ofthese areas and <strong>in</strong> their co<strong>in</strong>cidence <strong>in</strong> the samegesture.The choice of partisan names was not arbitrary;they always carry a symbolic mandate, althoughthey are seem<strong>in</strong>gly chosen only accord<strong>in</strong>g to thecriterion of hav<strong>in</strong>g no connection with the realname. It is quite astound<strong>in</strong>g that Edvard Kardeljchose Krištof for his partisan name, which afterall carries the whole connotation of St. Christopher,whose symbolic mission was to carryChrist – hence his name (carrier of Christ) andhis iconic representation <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>numerable variantswith the child Christ on his shoulders. And thiswas also what this highest Communist Partylum<strong>in</strong>ary dutifully took upon himself, be<strong>in</strong>g thesecond-<strong>in</strong>-command at Tito’s side and his firmestsupport through decades. The foundation ofassum<strong>in</strong>g a new name has biblical dimensions; itextends to the sources of nam<strong>in</strong>g, the authorityof giv<strong>in</strong>g names, back to Adam. The assumedname is now the real name, an <strong>in</strong>scription <strong>in</strong>toan alternative symbolic network, <strong>in</strong> oppositionto the arbitrar<strong>in</strong>ess of civil identity based on54


spurious authority. The virtual <strong>in</strong>scription redoublesthe ord<strong>in</strong>ary <strong>in</strong>scription and underm<strong>in</strong>esits symbolic sway.From this po<strong>in</strong>t of view, the context of a namechange is not only the context of a symbolicdeath, but at the same time the context of a newbirth. Its biblical dimension is not accidental s<strong>in</strong>cerenam<strong>in</strong>g was often connected precisely with conversion,with adopt<strong>in</strong>g a new religion, with thesudden enlightenment and the new baptism. Totake just one notorious example: Cassius Clay,the most famous boxer <strong>in</strong> history, changed hisname to Mohamed Ali and thus marked his conversionto Islam. ‘Born aga<strong>in</strong>’, as the phrase goes,and be<strong>in</strong>g born aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>to the new faith entailsa new baptism and the possibility of choos<strong>in</strong>g anew name. Thus also the partisan names markeda conversion to a new belief and entailed a newbirth, a baptism, a metamorphosis. 2727 In a strange and somewhat vertig<strong>in</strong>ous counterpart, Adolf Hitler’s storyalso <strong>in</strong>volves a name change. His father was born as Alois Schickelgruber(1837–1903), and hav<strong>in</strong>g been born out of wedlock he assumed his mother’sname. In 1876, thirteen years before Adolf’s birth, he made an official requestto change his surname to Hiedler, which was the name of his step-father (whosubsequently married his mother and might actually have been his biologicalfather, although the evidence is flimsy). When the name change was entered<strong>in</strong>to the official registry <strong>in</strong> 1877 it was changed to Hitler, for reasons unknown.The biggest stroke of luck <strong>in</strong> Hitler’s entire career thus happened a dozenyears before he was born, through the choice made not by him but by hisfather, concern<strong>in</strong>g precisely ‘the <strong>Name</strong> of the Father’ – can one imag<strong>in</strong>e masseschant<strong>in</strong>g ‘Heil Schickelgruber’? What’s <strong>in</strong> a name? There is a name which >>>55


The renam<strong>in</strong>g of the three Janez Janšas causedunease precisely because the three bearers of thenew name at no moment wanted to expla<strong>in</strong> theirdecision and provide the reason for their namechange. (But, ultimately, what would be a sufficientreason for any nam<strong>in</strong>g?) They did not substantiateor justify the name change with conversion,the adoption of a new belief, the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gof new life or by claim<strong>in</strong>g that, until then, theirlives had been misguided. And the name they hadchosen didn’t seem to embody their belief, theirpolitical allegiance, or to provide a model of whatthey wanted to be. Anyth<strong>in</strong>g but – yet even if wecan assume that it perhaps embodies precisely allthat they themselves would by no means want tobe, they kept completely quiet about it, no criticismwas ever explicitly voiced. Faced with themedia prob<strong>in</strong>g, the only reasons they kept repeat<strong>in</strong>gwere ‘personal reasons’, an <strong>in</strong>timate personaldecision, etc., that is, someth<strong>in</strong>g that functionsas a cloak beh<strong>in</strong>d which it is impolite to probe,but at the same time as a cliché excuse, s<strong>in</strong>ce ‘permostoften condenses and metaphorises a political movement, but it cannotbe any odd name, it has to possess some evocative power and the strik<strong>in</strong>gsound value. No matter how persuasive the ideas and how viable the politicalprogram, there has to be a persuasive and viable name as their figurehead.The cont<strong>in</strong>gent sound value of a name is never cont<strong>in</strong>gent, it possesses thepower to stir imag<strong>in</strong>ation and fantasies, a name is never arbitrary. Witness thecaricature name Schickelgruber, as if cut out for a character <strong>in</strong> a farce.56


sonal reasons’ are precisely another name for notwant<strong>in</strong>g to reveal the true reason. The lack of justificationfor the name change, the fact that it wasnot accompanied by a conversion to some newfaith, the clon<strong>in</strong>g of three identical names thatprecisely excludes <strong>in</strong>dividuality and uniquenessand, lastly, the choice of the name that does notborrow from any celebrated and mythical past,but po<strong>in</strong>ts to the not-so-glorious present – all thismakes it impossible to make sense of this gestureand its message <strong>in</strong> any immediate or obvious way.The gesture obviously has a strong message, but itis not quite clear what this message is supposed tobe. And lastly, if – as with partisan names – thesename changes evoke the will for a new symbolicmandate and a different foundation, the gestureof a symbolic cut, then this alleged new symbolicorder here presents itself precisely as the clon<strong>in</strong>gof the most notorious name around, that of thebearer of the rul<strong>in</strong>g order at the time, and it looksas if mere clon<strong>in</strong>g underm<strong>in</strong>es the model. Thenew is only the gap <strong>in</strong> the cont<strong>in</strong>gency of theold, the sameness of names po<strong>in</strong>ts to an arbitraryco<strong>in</strong>cidence of the bearer and the name, as if anew version of the Hegelian <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite judgmentwas at work here, which asserts a direct identityof entities that have no common measure: Janez57


Janša = Janez Janša = Janez Janša = Janez Janša.Or, <strong>in</strong> another ve<strong>in</strong>, not unlike ‘a rose is a rose isa rose … is a rose.’One cannot f<strong>in</strong>ish without evok<strong>in</strong>g the bestknownscene <strong>in</strong> the entirety of theatre history, thecanonical locus pr<strong>in</strong>ceps of the theatrical tradition,the theatre scene par excellence. Juliet stands onthe balcony and speaks <strong>in</strong>to the night, and onthis most famous spot, she says: “What’s <strong>in</strong> aname?” 28 Wouldn’t the rose by any other namesmell as sweet? “O Romeo, Romeo! Whereforeart thou Romeo? / Deny thy father and refusethy name.” This is not the question of chang<strong>in</strong>gthe name, but the question of an exit from theregime of names altogether, the departure fromthe symbolic places assigned to us by names. Butsuch a way out is not possible, hence the tragedyof the Verona lovers.The scene pits one aga<strong>in</strong>st the other: on the onehand, the absolute demand of love, and on theother hand, someth<strong>in</strong>g one could call the politicsof the name. Every name entails a politics. By28 “What’s <strong>in</strong> a name? That which we call a rose / By any other namewould smell as sweet; / So Romeo would, were he not Romeo call’d, / Reta<strong>in</strong>that dear perfection which he owes / Without that title. Romeo, doff thy name; /And for that name, which is no part of thee, / Take all myself.” (II, 2, 43–49)58


one’s name one always belongs to a certa<strong>in</strong> socialgroup, a class, a nation, a family, the names p<strong>in</strong>us down to an orig<strong>in</strong>, a genealogy, a tradition,names classify us and allot us a social place,they distribute social power. By the name, oneis always a Montague or a Capulet (“and I’ll nolonger be a Capulet,” says Juliet). By our names,we are always <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> social antagonisms,they always place us either on the Montague oron the Capulet side.A name is never <strong>in</strong>dividual, it is always generic.By the family name, we are always placed underthe banner of the father’s name, the <strong>Name</strong> ofthe Father, so with the family name we alwayscarry around psychoanalysis and all its luggage.But also the given name is never personal, it is<strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong>to a code – <strong>in</strong> our culture it is preciselythe ‘Christian name’, traditionally givenaccord<strong>in</strong>g to the date of birth and its patronsa<strong>in</strong>t, based on a ramified classification of sa<strong>in</strong>tlydistribution. Or else excluded from it – IvanCankar’s remarkable short story Polikarp, just ahundred years old, tells the story of a man whowas given this curious name, Polikarp, at hisbirth, <strong>in</strong> order to stigmatize him as a child bornout of wedlock, a bastard. He was doomed to59


carry that name as his mark of Ca<strong>in</strong>, the namedef<strong>in</strong>ed his fate from his birth to the bitter end.Although nowadays the codes of nam<strong>in</strong>g aremore relaxed, elusive and loose, seem<strong>in</strong>gly liberal,they still very much exist and cont<strong>in</strong>ue tosecretly del<strong>in</strong>eate us, although <strong>in</strong> subtle waysthat are hard to decipher.Where does the name reside? “It is nor hand,nor foot, / Nor arm, nor face, nor any otherpart / Belong<strong>in</strong>g to a man,” says Juliet, and further:“’Tis but thy name that is my enemy.” Soeveryth<strong>in</strong>g would be all right, or so it seems, ifonly he could cut off his name, the source of alltrouble, and this is what he <strong>in</strong>deed attempts todo at some po<strong>in</strong>t. “In what vile part of this anatomy/ Doth my name lodge?” asks Romeo later<strong>in</strong> the play (III/3). “Tell me that I may sack / Thehateful mansion.” And he draws his sword, asthe stage directions <strong>in</strong>dicate, prepared to cut offthat vile bodily part, to cut off his name with thesword, castrate himself of his name, the name ofthe Father, 29 but to no avail. To cut off the name29 What part of the body might he purport to cut off when he drawshis sword? Does he tacitly assume that ‘the phallic signifier’ resides <strong>in</strong> hisphallus? Is this not the spontaneous assumption that the audience <strong>in</strong>evitablymakes? This is like an almost caricature Lacanian Urszene, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g togetherthe <strong>Name</strong> of the Father, the phallic signifier, castration, and the nature of love.The fate of the Veronese lovers may actually be sealed by this assumption >>>60


<strong>in</strong> order to espouse the immediacy. “Deny thyfather and refuse thy name” – <strong>in</strong> order to fullyassume love? This is the fantasy of the Veronalovers – love beyond names and signifiers, thecommunion of immediate be<strong>in</strong>g.In the balcony scene, love appears as that whichshould entail leav<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d all these social codes.The tragedy of the Veronese lovers stems fromthe stark opposition between name and be<strong>in</strong>g,that unique human be<strong>in</strong>g which is supposed tobe beyond nam<strong>in</strong>g and which should enable establish<strong>in</strong>ga bond apart from names, the truebond of love and passion based on s<strong>in</strong>gularity.And this is at the core of their tragedy: the namehas nevertheless affected their be<strong>in</strong>g and took revenge,they couldn’t overcome the way they weremarked by their proper names, there is no wayone can cut off names as expendable additions,for names as <strong>in</strong>truders are nevertheless what givesus access to be<strong>in</strong>g, and they affect be<strong>in</strong>g.Does Emil Hrvat<strong>in</strong> by the name Janez Janša smellthe same? Will the name Janez Janša ever smellthe same?that true love resides <strong>in</strong> the immediacy, by gett<strong>in</strong>g rid of the phallic signifier ofthe name as the <strong>in</strong>truder <strong>in</strong>to the purity of heart.61


<strong>Mladen</strong> <strong>Dolar</strong> is Professor and Senior Research Fellow at theDepartment of Philosophy, University of Ljubljana. His pr<strong>in</strong>cipalareas of research are psychoanalysis, modern French philosophy,German idealism and art theory. He has lectured extensively atuniversities <strong>in</strong> the US and across Europe, he is the author of overa hundred papers <strong>in</strong> scholarly journals and volume collections.Apart from ten books <strong>in</strong> Slovene, his book publications <strong>in</strong>cludemost notably A Voice and Noth<strong>in</strong>g More (MIT 2006, translated<strong>in</strong>to six languages) and Opera’s Second Death (with Slavoj Žižek,Routledge 2001, also translated <strong>in</strong>to several languages). He is theco-founder of what has become known as ‘the Ljubljana School’.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!