12.07.2015 Views

Stoicism - College of Stoic Philosophers

Stoicism - College of Stoic Philosophers

Stoicism - College of Stoic Philosophers

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO3 1822 601 3419'^^;


^J^^n^


V -^":fCHIEF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHIES.^STOICISM.BYRev. W. W. CAPES,FELLOW OF HERTFORD COLLEGE, AND READER IN ANCIENT HISTORY,OXFORD.PUBLISHED UNDER THE DIRECTION OFTHE COMMITTEE OF GENERAL LITERATURE AND EDUCATION.APPOINTED BY THE SOCIETY FOR PROMOTINGCHRISTIAN KNOWLEDGE.LONDON.SOCIETY FOR PROMOTING CHRISTIAN KNOWLEDGE,NORTHUMBERLAND AVENUE, CHARING CROSS ;43, Ql SEN VICTORIA STREET ;AND 48, PICCADILLY.NEW YORK : POTT, YOUNG, & CO.1880.


CONTENTS.ChapterPageI. The Thought and Character <strong>of</strong> Socrates 5II. The Cynics 14III. The Rise <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> and its Relation toTHE Spirit <strong>of</strong> the Age 22IV. <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> in the Rigour <strong>of</strong> its EssentialPrinciples 37V. <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> tempered by Concessions to CommonSense 54VI. <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> at Rome under the Republic ....64VII.The Critics and Enemies <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> underVIII. The,THE Early Empire 78Social Status <strong>of</strong> the Pr<strong>of</strong>essionalMoralists at Rome 106IX. The Career <strong>of</strong> Seneca 127X. Seneca as a Moralist 143XI.Seneca and St. Paul, or the Relation <strong>of</strong><strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> to Christianity 166XII. Epictetus, or <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> in the Cottage ... 180XIII.Marcus Aurelius Antoninus, or <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>ON THE Throne 200XIV. The <strong>Stoic</strong> Creed and Temper in Relationto other Aspects <strong>of</strong> Thought 230B 2


STOICISM.CHAPTER I.THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF SOCRATES.The study <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> cannot be properly begunwithout some attempt to trace itsgerms in earlierspeculation, and to note what was the state <strong>of</strong> Greeksociety in which it first took root before it was transferredto other and perhaps to kindlier soils. Likeall the famous systems which divided the earnestthinkers <strong>of</strong> the old Greek world, its real starting-pointis to be found in the life and thought <strong>of</strong> Socrates,whose original and striking figure fills so marked aplace in the pictures <strong>of</strong> the social life at Athenstowards the close <strong>of</strong> the fifth century before our era.Not that Greek philosophy began with him. Therehad been no lack before <strong>of</strong> serious efforts to solvesome <strong>of</strong> the many problems which had forced themselvesupon men's thoughts when they looked outupon the universe around them, or tried to thinkabout their own relations to the world unseen, andto the infinities that lay before and after. But theseearlier seekers after wisdom had no chart or rulesby which to steer, had no instruments or method


6 STOICISM.<strong>of</strong> discovery, and could make therefore little progressin their course. There was a sublime audacity inthe way in which they grappled with greatquestions,constructed systems <strong>of</strong> the universe, and explainedas they thought the laws <strong>of</strong> nature, before they haddetermined the simplest rules <strong>of</strong> logic, or had anymore appliances than the experience <strong>of</strong> the untrainedsenses. They were like the early painters who aspired<strong>of</strong>ten to portray the imagery <strong>of</strong> heaven, or to dealwith lurid scenes <strong>of</strong> future judgment, before they hadlearnt even the rudiments <strong>of</strong> perspective or anatomy.They gave birth therefore to little more than guesswork,lighted up here and there with flashes <strong>of</strong> strangeinsight, that may remind us <strong>of</strong> the discoveries <strong>of</strong> laterages ;but nothing came <strong>of</strong> all their subtle thought,for they had no tests by which to disentangle truthfrom error. There was a want <strong>of</strong> balance and proportionin their hasty systems which seemed tooscillate from pole to pole. At one time they hadonly eyes to see the moods and qualities <strong>of</strong> outwardnature, and language seemed to them to bear nohigher meaning, and mind and its processes to be butsubtler forms <strong>of</strong> matter. At another time they wereso much impressed by the fleeting character <strong>of</strong> allthe knowledge gained through sense, that thoughtalone seemed sure and solid, while all experience elsewas treacherous and unreal.There was no practicalvalue in their speculations while they rested on thislevel.The love <strong>of</strong> wisdom, which the name philosophyimplied, was strong and earnest it was a natural;yearning to explain the mysteries <strong>of</strong> the world in


THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF SOCRATES. 7which men lived, but it had borne as yet no solidfruits to justify itself to sober sense. It had notfurnished men with any rule <strong>of</strong> action, with anystandard <strong>of</strong> what was right or wrong. It had nothelped to train them for the needs <strong>of</strong> social life ;for it had not fitted them to serve their country orto push their fortunes in any <strong>of</strong> the arts <strong>of</strong> peace orwar. Such had not been its aim indeed ;it neverhad aspired to do such work, but then againitmightbe urged that little else had yet been gained: no sureknowledge <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> nature, no full acquaintancewith the powers <strong>of</strong> thought. But while philosophywas dreaming on, disdaining to be man'scounseller and guide in common life, anotherpower was ready to step into the vacant place, andto meet all the demands <strong>of</strong> higher culture.In Sicily,and among the isles <strong>of</strong> Greece, a class <strong>of</strong> teachershad arisen, who had made a special study <strong>of</strong> the arts<strong>of</strong> speech and forms <strong>of</strong> language, and all the show<strong>of</strong> literary graces. They had learnt much <strong>of</strong> menand manners as they passed from land to land, andwere familiar ^vith all the topics <strong>of</strong> politics and artand morals which had roused the interest <strong>of</strong> the age.They pr<strong>of</strong>essed to educate the rising youth for publiclife, to train them for the fence <strong>of</strong> words in thenational assembly and the law courts, to stock theirmemory with graceful phrases as well as with the lessons<strong>of</strong> ripe statecraft. Old-fashioned folks, indeed, mightshake their heads and say that the so-called sophistshad the show <strong>of</strong> wisdom, not its substance ; that theydid not care for truth, but only for effect, and were quite


8 STOICISM.indifferent to the ends which knowledge should bemade to serve. They probably unsettled old convictionsby comparing the customs and the laws <strong>of</strong>different nations, and <strong>of</strong>ten ran a tilt at venerabledogmas out <strong>of</strong> mere bravado or caprice.It might seem, perhaps, to careless eyesas ifSocrates were only one <strong>of</strong> this new class <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essionalteachers. Like them he seemed to courtmen's notice, to live chiefly out <strong>of</strong> doors, and to befor ever talking to the young men he gathered roundhim, and to treat <strong>of</strong>ten too with scant respect timehonouredcustoms and beliefs. But unlike them heaffected no display, and made no pretensions tosuperior knowledge like older; thinkers, he was buta seeker after wisdom, with a deeper sense <strong>of</strong> his ownignorance than the rest the; irony^ which was somarked a feature <strong>of</strong> his style, consisted in the humilitywith which he owned his want <strong>of</strong> knowledge, in hiswillingness to hear what others had to say, and inwhat they thought the captious spirit with which heprobed and criticised their answers. But he feltstronglythat the ideas <strong>of</strong> men around him were allloose and hasty and one-sided, not based on anysure experience or careful scrutiny <strong>of</strong> facts. Theywere <strong>of</strong>ten inconsistent in themselves, or carelesslygathered from imperfect data a few\ questions or afew appeals to other cases were enough to show theneed <strong>of</strong> further thought to correct and to completesuch notions. Knowledge, he said, was true andreal only in so far as it consisted in conceptions inwhich the class qualities were duly gathered from a


THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF SOCRATES. 9wide experience amply sifted, and all the seemingquibbles <strong>of</strong> his daily talk were but infinitely variedillustrations <strong>of</strong> what we call the processes <strong>of</strong> definitionand induction.His was a method <strong>of</strong> inquiry therefore,but no system really formed ;he had no definitetheories or body <strong>of</strong> connected doctrines to be handedon by his disciples, or defended as a sacred trust.So it was that schools <strong>of</strong> widely different tenets alikeowned his influence and revered his name. Thesame principle and method were applied by all, butled them in some cases to conclusions far apart.But one feature which they mostly shared was hislarge interest in moral questions. Socrates is saidto have brought down philosophy from heaven toearth ;he certainly discouraged for awhile all theambitious speculations about the universe at largewith which the older thinkers were so busy. Theone thing <strong>of</strong> paramount importance in his eyes wasthe standard <strong>of</strong> right action ; if man is to rule hislife aright he must know what is honourable, just,and good ;all his efforts must be centred on thatknowledge, which alone will give him the virtue <strong>of</strong>true manhood. Without knowledge there is, hethought, no virtue possible, but only a blind following<strong>of</strong> custom, authority, or law, or an aimless driftingwith caprice or passion.Each, therefore, <strong>of</strong> the greatSocratic schools had its own moral system, and itsrule <strong>of</strong> life ;the votaries <strong>of</strong> wisdom were the menwho were most intent to practise virtue and as;religion spoke in heathen days in faltering and misleadingaccents on such subjects, and in the decline


lOSTOICISM.<strong>of</strong> Greece the laws and sanctions <strong>of</strong> the State haddaily less <strong>of</strong> moral force, philosophy stepped intotheir place and became the" Ductor dubitantium,"the guide for the consciences <strong>of</strong> earnest men.Another feature <strong>of</strong> Socratic thought is the highestimate it formed <strong>of</strong> the dignity <strong>of</strong> manhood, whichwas thus to be a law unto itself. A certain divineelement was lodged,it seemed, within the soul <strong>of</strong>man ;its future lifebeyond the grave was probable,though hardly capable <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> The value <strong>of</strong> itspiety transcended far the worth <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong>feringswhich it could make to God, and in some privilegedcases, as <strong>of</strong> Socrates himself, some superhuman guidancemight be vouchsafed, not from without, butfrom within.It has been said that the practical importance <strong>of</strong>these moral speculations grew larger as the purity andbinding force <strong>of</strong> the standards <strong>of</strong> the State declined,but they tended also in their turn to estrange men insome degree from publiclife. It is true that Socrateshimself spoke in the highest terms <strong>of</strong> dutyto theState and <strong>of</strong> obedience to its commands. He urgedthe competent to labour for the common weal, andendured death himself that he might not violate hiscountry's laws. But his political ideal could not agreewith the facts <strong>of</strong> the Greek republics <strong>of</strong> his day.The statesman's virtue lay in knowledge that ; alone,not popular election or haphazard, could confer theright to rule. For the well-being <strong>of</strong> all an aristocracy<strong>of</strong> intellect must hold command, but when the massesare in power the upright <strong>of</strong>ficial cannot secure right


THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF SOCRATES. 1 1and justice,and will <strong>of</strong>ten best consult his dignity byretiring into private life.Moreover, the whole tone <strong>of</strong> his teaching, and hiscritical method <strong>of</strong> inquiry, well might seem to disparagethe common code <strong>of</strong> morals and the usualrules <strong>of</strong> conduct which rested on authority or custom.The little Greek republics <strong>of</strong> old days had donegreat things by the strong glow <strong>of</strong> patriotic feeling,and by unshrinking obedience to the national codes<strong>of</strong> honour. They were troubled by no doubts, butidentified alike their interest and duty with the presentwell-being <strong>of</strong> the State. But man's virtue nowwas to consist in the knowledge <strong>of</strong> right and wrong ;his first duty was to follow his convictions ;the lawseven <strong>of</strong> his country might be called in question, andfeelings towards its enemies be merged in the largersense <strong>of</strong> human brotherhood. The martyrdom <strong>of</strong>Socrates is in itself a symbol <strong>of</strong> this conflict, a pro<strong>of</strong>that the Greek conscience claimed to direct its owncareer,State.free henceforth from all dictation from theBut the independence <strong>of</strong> character which Socratespr<strong>of</strong>essed included something more than social freedom.It was not enough to rise above the opinions<strong>of</strong> the thoughtless crowd, and to cleave at allhazftrd to the inner sense <strong>of</strong> right ;reasonable selfrespect,he thought, could only be maintained by selfcontrol,by such a mastery over the desires that noneshould assert itself too strongly, or interfere with thepursuit <strong>of</strong> truth. He did not indeed push matters toextremes, or disparage the natural pleasures <strong>of</strong> the


12 STOICISM.senses. There was no ascetic rigour in his conductsuch as later moraUsts have <strong>of</strong>ten preached and practised;but in the simpHcity <strong>of</strong> his daily life, in hischeerful abstinence from self-indulgence, in the hardihoodwith which he bore hunger and thirst and heatand cold, while yet he could truly say that he wasthoroughly happy in his moderation, he lived up tohis own sense <strong>of</strong> human dignity, and left a model <strong>of</strong>philosophic independence which has influenced thewhole tone <strong>of</strong> later thought.There was no revolt in Socrates against the standards<strong>of</strong> his age and country, but still it is <strong>of</strong> interestto note that there were features in him which werecertainly not <strong>of</strong> a Greek type. There was somethingeccentric in his outer man, an obvious want <strong>of</strong> harmonybetween his looks and character which wasalmost a matter <strong>of</strong> jest among his friends, and which<strong>of</strong>fended the cultivated taste <strong>of</strong> Athens. The commoncurrent <strong>of</strong> his talk and the nature <strong>of</strong> his illustrationshardly were in keeping with the grace and artisticbeauty <strong>of</strong> his times. He took his examples from thecommonest subjects, without much regard to prejudiceand fashion, and explained the notion <strong>of</strong> thebeautiful as consisting in mere usefulness. He wasso sunk at times in meditation as to forget the outerworld a while, and the stiffness <strong>of</strong> his posture at suchtimes was paralleled by a certain want <strong>of</strong> delicate tactand intellectual sympathy for the feelings <strong>of</strong> hishearers. This may have weakened perhaps his influencewhile he lived, but it also may explain somesides <strong>of</strong> the Socratic thought in the later forms which


THE THOUGHT AND CHARACTER OF SOCRATES. 1 3itassumed, and which were still less in harmony withthe spirit <strong>of</strong> Greece.With these remarks, then, we may pass from themethod and sentiments <strong>of</strong> Socrates himself, but thepoints which have been thus lightly touched on willmeet us <strong>of</strong>ten at a later stage. The paramount importancethus ascribed to moral questions, the highestimate <strong>of</strong> human dignity, the estrangement from thebusiness <strong>of</strong> public life or the protest at its lower rules<strong>of</strong> action, the ideal <strong>of</strong> the unruffled calm <strong>of</strong> selfcontrol,and thepartial disregard <strong>of</strong> the balance andharmony natural to Greece — these were all developedafterwards in various forms, and some <strong>of</strong> them werepushed to great extremes, but nowhere with suchextravagance as by the Cynics.


14 STOICISM.CHAPTER II.THE CYNICS.It was not many years after the death <strong>of</strong> Socratesbefore some <strong>of</strong> the tendencies which have been noticedin his teaching were carried out in their extremestforms, and paraded as a rule <strong>of</strong> Hfe before the startledeyes <strong>of</strong> an Athenian public. What we read <strong>of</strong> themmay sound almost like a grotesque parody <strong>of</strong> theSocratic thought, but they were pr<strong>of</strong>essed ip^soberearnestness at first, and lasted on with littlechange <strong>of</strong>phrase or argument for at least 500 years, reappearingeven afterwards to some extent in Christian dress, andstamping a familiar epithet on every modern language.The Cynic sect began with Antisthenes, who was<strong>of</strong> Athenian birth, but the chief champion <strong>of</strong> thatmilitant philosophy was Diogenes, <strong>of</strong> Sinope, whosestriking figure and bold epigrams filled a far largerspace in public fancy. The gymnasia or public halls<strong>of</strong> the Greek cities were used not only for athleticexercises, but also by the lecturers, rhetoricians,sophists, who found in them a willing audience or aready market for their literary wares. Antisthenesand his followers frequented one called Cynosarges,and the first half <strong>of</strong> the word may probably have givena nickname to the rising sect, for the wits <strong>of</strong> Athenswere not slow to play upon the meaning <strong>of</strong> the name,


THE CYNICS.15which meant "a dog," and found an apt referenceit to what they thought the low aims and dogged ways<strong>of</strong> the new teachers. Diogenes, especially, took therough banter in good part, recognising even itscharacteristic fitnessinby many a rude jest or symbolicact, and the Corinthians at last placed the figure <strong>of</strong> adog in Parian marble on his grave.No Greek school had so narrow an intellectualbasis, and in none was the moral type so entirely unchangedfrom age to age. It was the independence<strong>of</strong> the character <strong>of</strong> Socrates which caught the fancy<strong>of</strong> Antisthenes ;the strength <strong>of</strong> will and power <strong>of</strong> selfassertionwas what he tried to copy, but he could notunderstand the analytic subtlety, or appreciate the pregnantshrewdness <strong>of</strong> his master's thought. Indeed, allspeculation seemed to him quite idle or fantastic whichdid not bear directly upon moral questions: general conceptionswere but fictions <strong>of</strong> the fancy, for individualsalone were real, definitions dealt with verbal quibbles,and the hopes <strong>of</strong> scientific progress were delusive.But no deep researches seemed to be required to givesuch knowledge as was needful for the guidance <strong>of</strong>man's life, virtue alone could make him happy ;tosecure that he must concentrate his efforts on himself,and might safely neglect all beside. Nothingwas really good but virtue ; nothing but vice wasabsolutely bad ; all else should be indifferent. Theonly thing which he could truly call his own, whichmight be placed beyond the power <strong>of</strong> chance, wasmind ;in moral action, and in that alone, he couldbe really free ;all else depended upon some influence


1 6 STOICISM.from without, and might desert him in his hour <strong>of</strong>need. Wealth was very treacherous and blind, fataltemptation to some men, source <strong>of</strong> untold misery toothers. Honour was an empty bubble, blown by theignorant and foolish. Sensual pleasure was a form<strong>of</strong> madness, which threw the reason wholly <strong>of</strong>f itsbalance. But labour and hardship, though man inhis folly shrunk from them, were good, for they servedto keep his powers in proper training, and raised himto a healthy independence.So Hercules was the type <strong>of</strong> the true hero, for oldfables pictured him as the knight errant, doing battlewith every form <strong>of</strong> evil, and never flinching from thepath <strong>of</strong> duty. The Cynics copied even, as best theycould, the traditipnal symbols with which he was investedby Greek art, and reproduced his club andlion's skin with the philosophicstaff and mantle.Virtue, therefore, in one sense, they thought, consists<strong>of</strong> knowledge, but it is a knowledgethat all else isvanity, that common pleasures are at best treacherousand unsubstantial, and unworthy <strong>of</strong> serious pursuit.But virtue, in its positive aspect, is a course <strong>of</strong> training,an exercise <strong>of</strong> the free will, an assertion <strong>of</strong> thestrength within, an independence <strong>of</strong> all that lies without.The wise alone can gain that calm which isunruffled by the gusts <strong>of</strong> fortune, can find a homein any scene, and live a life <strong>of</strong> heaven on earth. Allelse are in a piteous plight, slaves to their passionsand unreason, living in a sort <strong>of</strong> lazar-house, wherethe Cynic can hardly find a healthy man, though hesearch with a lantern in his hand.


THE CYNICS. 17It was not enough with Socrates to practise moderation,or to control the wayward impulses <strong>of</strong> passion.Their object was to push much further their indifferenceto all that was not wholly in their power, toreduce their wants within the narrowest limits, andtrample on the pleasures they despised. The Greeklevel <strong>of</strong> requirements was moderate enough,ifjudgedby the standard <strong>of</strong> our modern comforts ;but theCynics would reduce life to its barest elements, andprune away most <strong>of</strong> the decencies <strong>of</strong> civilized societyas the mere superfluities <strong>of</strong> luxurious refinement.They gave up their property to live upon the beggar'sdole ; they were content with the scantiest clothing,and that sometimes so ragged that Antisthenes wastold his vanity might be seen through the holes <strong>of</strong> hisown coat. They could dispense with house or bed,and stretch themselves to sleep upon the stones, orlike Diogenes, in some convenient tub. The plainestdiet was thought enough;and as a return to simplenature, it was proposed even to dispense with the help<strong>of</strong> fire, and to eat all their food uncooked.While so many <strong>of</strong> the wants <strong>of</strong> civilized life werethus discouraged,it was not likely that the institutions<strong>of</strong> the State would be regarded with much favourThe sage, they thought, should feel himself a citizen<strong>of</strong> the world at large, and be indifferent to the pettypolitics <strong>of</strong> any little State, with all their much adoabout the trifles <strong>of</strong> honours or <strong>of</strong>iicial rank. None <strong>of</strong>the governments that were could satisfy his judgment,for in all <strong>of</strong> them the choice <strong>of</strong> rulers turned on theaccidents <strong>of</strong> fortune, not on the essentials <strong>of</strong> true


1 8 STOICISM.moral worth. Of what value were the laws <strong>of</strong> anyState to one who had learnt to "be law unto himself,however useful they might be to provide for knavesand fools ?the social union atWhy should he prizeall who thought meanly <strong>of</strong> all its material symbols,such as money, markets, senate-houses, law-courts;who was careless even about civil freedom on theground that he alone was the real slave who wasmastered by his passions or his fears, and that strength<strong>of</strong> will would assert itself with the more credit underdiscouraging conditions.In his "Dialogue <strong>of</strong> the Republic," Plato sketches animaginary picture <strong>of</strong> the simplest rudiments <strong>of</strong> sociallife in a supposed state <strong>of</strong> nature, but a young Athenianwho is present in the scene impatiently objectsthat such an Utopiaisonly fit for pigs. Plato is probablyreferring in this passage to the extravagances<strong>of</strong> the Cynics, and itmay seem to us perhaps that thestricture is not too harsh when we find that some<strong>of</strong> themhad no reverence even for the sanctities <strong>of</strong> the home life,were an artificial bond-but thought the ties <strong>of</strong> familyage, and could be best replaced by a community <strong>of</strong>wives, that the aspirant after virtue mightnot be distractedby material cares, or hamperedin his effortsto assert his perfect freedom.In their strange hankering for the state <strong>of</strong> nature,they pr<strong>of</strong>essed such indifference to the opinion <strong>of</strong> theworld, that they seemed to aim at the suppression <strong>of</strong>all modesty or shame. They insisted, that is, overmuchon the broad lines <strong>of</strong> distinction between conventionaldecencies and moral right.The latter was


THE CYNICS. 19done, they said, <strong>of</strong> any value, and we need only beashamed when we ignore its claims upon our reason.The former are artificial and unreal, varying as theydo from age to age and land to land. It is falsedelicacy, therefore, to regard the sentiments <strong>of</strong> otherson such points, or to refrain from any natural act inpublic, however revolting it may seem to the morbidtaste <strong>of</strong> silly worldlings.It is not to be supposed, indeed, that they couldalways act up to their principles completely, or pushto such outrageous lengths their disregard <strong>of</strong> finerfeelings. But in the stories left us <strong>of</strong> Diogenes andothers in grave writers, there is evidence enough <strong>of</strong>bold effrontery and insolent self-assertion,relieved asitmight be by homely wit or humorous eccentricity<strong>of</strong> manner, ennobled as it was moreover by the missionaryspirit <strong>of</strong> their lives, and the energy with whichthey set themselves, alike in season and out <strong>of</strong> season,to preach the Cynic creed.The satirist, Lucian, who, five centuries later,mocks at the follies <strong>of</strong> his age, includes the Cynic inhis gallery <strong>of</strong> social portraits. In the auction scene,when each <strong>of</strong> the old philosophers <strong>of</strong> Greece is put upfor auction and knocked down to the highest bidderDiogenes appears among the others on the stage, and ismade to appraise himself in the characteristic language<strong>of</strong> his sect. It is curious to note that here at least theportrait is no parody, or rather that there was nothingleft for caricature. Not a word is put into his mouththat is not ascribed to him by graver authors, andthe mad Socrates, as an ancient writerc 2called him, is


20 STOICISM.described with perfect sincerity and historic truth.Another scene <strong>of</strong> Lucian portrays a would-be sagethrusting himself uninvited on a supper party, descantingin high-flown terms on simple moderation,but disgusting all the guests with the boastful effrontery<strong>of</strong> his philosophic phrases, which contrastedstrangely with his drunken and lascivious habits.The description illustrates the fact, which we haveindeed from other sources, that many a sturdy beggarand ill-conditioned vagrant took up as a convenientdisguise the Cynic staff and mantle, bringing by hisdissolute life still more into disfavour the obnoxioustenets <strong>of</strong> the sect, somewhat as the monk's cowl, inthe later days <strong>of</strong> Christendom, was donned by manyan unworthy pretender to the spiritual life.The Cynics have <strong>of</strong>ten been comparedwith theBegging Friars <strong>of</strong> the Middle Ages, and some features<strong>of</strong> resemblance are obvious enough. Such are theself-chosen life <strong>of</strong> poverty, the austerity <strong>of</strong> dress andmanner, the missionary spirit <strong>of</strong>ten shown, the rudeuncourtly vigour <strong>of</strong> the language in which they denouncedvices in high places, while they spoke tothe people in the people's tongue.But the comparison rests mainly on the accidents<strong>of</strong> dress, and manner, and ascetic life, and the points<strong>of</strong> difference are most essential. The mendicantorders chiefly did their work among the weak, andignorant, and poor. They moved to and fro amongthe neglected masses <strong>of</strong> the towns, or among villagersin lonely hamlets, ministering alike to body and tomind.They did not, like the Cynics, foster spiritual


THE CYNICS.CIpride, and preach counsels <strong>of</strong> perfection to the strongand self-contained ; they did not loosen recklesslythe ties <strong>of</strong> social union or domestic life, but they hadwords <strong>of</strong> comfort for the sick and hopeless, whilethey enforced the claims <strong>of</strong> homely duties, and bademen walk humbly with their God. They did notstunt or deform the ideal <strong>of</strong> intellectual life, forfrom the Dominican and Franciscan orders came thegreatest <strong>of</strong> the schoolmen, the subtlest spirits <strong>of</strong> theirage, famed in the lecture-halls <strong>of</strong> Paris and <strong>of</strong> Oxfordfor their mastery <strong>of</strong> the old systems <strong>of</strong> philosophy, aswell as for their reverent handling <strong>of</strong> the mysteries <strong>of</strong>the faith.


2 2 STOICISM.CHAPTER III.THE RISE OF STOICISM AND ITS RELATION TO THESPIRITOF THE AGE.The Roman satirist Juvenal remarked that thedistinction between the Cynics and the <strong>Stoic</strong>s lay onlyin the coat they wore, and it is <strong>of</strong> interest for us tonote how the latter clung to the main principleswhich have just been described among the tenets <strong>of</strong>the former, while they tried to tone down the extravagance<strong>of</strong> their conclusions. The <strong>Stoic</strong> system, likethe rest <strong>of</strong> the great Socratic schools, took form andsubstance first at Athens, and was gradually developedby Zenon, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus in the course<strong>of</strong> the third century before our era.It was the age <strong>of</strong> Macedonian supremacy in Greece,when Alexander's empire had fallen into fragments,and the ceaseless wars, vices, and follies <strong>of</strong> his varioussuccessors filled the imagination <strong>of</strong> the world.Demosthenes, the great orator <strong>of</strong> the democracy <strong>of</strong>Athens, had spent his energies and life in the fruitlesseffort to preserve the independence <strong>of</strong> his country ;the single-hearted Phocion, who had counselled moresubmissive action, but had proudly declined the pr<strong>of</strong>feredgold <strong>of</strong> Macedon, had been flung aside at last as adishonoured tool, and had fallen as a victim to the fury<strong>of</strong> a capricious people. Demetrius Phalereus, rulingas the viceroy <strong>of</strong> a foreign despot, had been a


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 23kindly patron <strong>of</strong> the arts and liberal studies, andsecured peace and plenty to the land to compensatefor the lost self-respect and turbulent energy <strong>of</strong>freedom.There were worse times indeed to follow, when thedegradation <strong>of</strong> the State was more complete, and theindignities <strong>of</strong> her public action more pr<strong>of</strong>ound. Ifwe would know something <strong>of</strong> the social aspects <strong>of</strong>those times we shall find some striking illustrationsin Plutarch's account <strong>of</strong> Demetrius Poliorcetes, inwhose life adventurous exploits strangely contrastedwith wild extravagance and licence. What the rulers<strong>of</strong> the period <strong>of</strong>ten were we may judge from the quietwords <strong>of</strong> Plutarch " : Of the descendants <strong>of</strong> AntigonusPhilip was the only prince who put his son to death ;whereas in the families <strong>of</strong> other kings nothingis morecommon than the murder <strong>of</strong> sons, mothers, and wives.As for the killing <strong>of</strong> brothers, like a postulate ingeometry, it was considered as indisputably necessaryto the safety <strong>of</strong> the reigning prince."iRoyal insolence may be measured bythe madwhim <strong>of</strong> Demetrius, who ordered the Athenians to" raise two hundred and fifty talents in a very shorttime, and the money was exacted with the greatestrigour. When the money was brought in, and hesaw it all together, he ordered it to be given to Lamiaand his other mistresses to buy soap. Thus the disgracehurt them more than the loss,and the applicationmore than the impost." ^'Plutarch, " Demetrius," translation <strong>of</strong> Langhome. 'Ibid,


24 STOICISM.Even among the Macedonians athome he showeda haughtiness as great, <strong>of</strong>fending by his ostentatiousdress and his hixurious and dissolute habits, but most<strong>of</strong> allby the difficulty <strong>of</strong> access to him, for he eitherrefused to see the applicants, or behaved to them in aharsh and haughty manner." One day, when heseemed to come out in a more obliging temper, andto be something less inaccessible, he was presentedwith several petitions, all which he received and putthem in the skirt <strong>of</strong> his robe. The people <strong>of</strong> coursefollowed him with great joy ;but no sooner was hecome to the bridge over the Axius than he openedhis robe and shook them all into the river." iBut the Athenians were worthy <strong>of</strong> such rulers.their senile adulation they called Demetrius and hisfather gods and saviours, and abolishing the archonshipthey created special priests to do them honour,and prefixed their names to all the public acts."They consecrated the place where their patron firstalighted from his chariot, and erected an altar thereto Demetrius Catabates." They passed even a decree"that those who should be sent upon public businessto AntigonusInand Demetrius should not be calledambassadors, but Theori, a title which had been appropriatedto those who on the solemn festivalscarried the customary sacrifices to Delphi andOlympia in the name <strong>of</strong> the Grecian states." ^" These instances <strong>of</strong> adulation concluded withtheir changing the name <strong>of</strong> the month ]\Iunychion to1Plutarch, "Demetriur." « Ibid.


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 25Demetrion, with calling the last day <strong>of</strong> every monthDemetrios, and the Dionysia, or feasts <strong>of</strong> Bacchus,Demetria." ^ In Athenseus, again, we may read howthey received him when he came among them," notonly with frankincense and crowns, and libations <strong>of</strong>wine, but they even went out to meet him with hymnsand choruses." The very hymn addressed to him onthis occasion is still existing, and it may help us tounderstand how far the religion <strong>of</strong> the age could bea stay or strength to earnest minds :—" Behold, the greatest <strong>of</strong> the gods and dearestAre come to this city ;For here Demeter and Demetrius arePresent in season.She indeed comes to duly celebrateThe sacred mysteriesOf her most holy daughter— he is presentJoyful and beautiful,As a god ought to be, with smiling face,Showering his blessings round.How noble doth he look ! his friends around.Himself the centre.His friends resemble the bright lesser stars,Himself is Phoebus.Plail, ever mighty Neptune's mightier son ;Hail, son <strong>of</strong> Venus !For other gods do at a distance keep,Or have no ears,Or no existence ;and they heed us not—But you are present.Not made <strong>of</strong> wood or stone, a genuine god.We pray to thee. "" Athenasus," Yonge's Translation, vi. 62.


26 STOICISM." This," says Athenjeus," is what was sung by thenation which once fought at Marathon, and theysang it not only in pubhc but in their private houses— men who had once put a man to death for <strong>of</strong>feringadoration to the King <strong>of</strong> Persia."Finally, they changed even the times and seasonsto humour his caprices, as when he wrote to tell themthat he proposed to have himself admitted to boththe greater and the lesser mysteries, which were heldproperly in different months and far " apart. Stratoclesprocured a decree that the month Munychion shouldbe called and reputed the month Anthesterion, to giveDemetrius an opportunity for his first initiation. Afterwhich Munychion was changed again into Boedromion."iBy these means Demetrius was admitted toboth mysteries.These extravagant compliances <strong>of</strong> Athens wereproved to be no fruit <strong>of</strong> love, for we read that afterthe decisive battle, which ruined the power <strong>of</strong> Demetrius,he reckoned chiefly on their loyalty, for with"them he had left his ships, his money, and his wifeDeidamia ;and in this distress he thought he couldhave no safer asylum than their affection. He,therefore,pursued his voyage ^^^th all',possible expeditionbut ambassadors from Athens met him near theCyclades, and entreated him not to think <strong>of</strong> goingthither, because the people had declared by an edictthat they would receive no king into their city ....To be deceived beyond all his expectations by the>Plutarch, "Demetrius."


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 2^Athenians, to find by facts that their affection, sogreat in appearance, was only false and counterfeit,was a thing that cut him to the heart." ^No wonder, then, if serious minds found politicsdistasteful, and sought a refuge in the quiet studieswhich promised to make them independent <strong>of</strong> thelow standards <strong>of</strong> society around them.The history <strong>of</strong> the Greek drama also seems to illustratethis change <strong>of</strong> feeling. The early comedy <strong>of</strong>Athens reflects in every page the public movements<strong>of</strong> the times ;is full <strong>of</strong> reference to the wars, diplomacy,and themes <strong>of</strong> national debate, and so is almostmeaningless without the knowledge <strong>of</strong> contemporaryannals. The plays <strong>of</strong> Menander, on the contrary,written as they were in times <strong>of</strong> political exhaustion,betake themselves almost entirely to the scenes <strong>of</strong>private life, and find their chief interest in sentimentsand passions common to all"ages. I am a man,"says first one and then another <strong>of</strong> the characters <strong>of</strong>the new comedy in the period with which we areconcerned. The belief that men have all one natureand a common destiny seems always present to theirthoughts, and is appealed to as a ground for resignationand a motive for compassion, as well as anexcuse for tears and an argument for self-control.Philosophy came in to deepen the feeling and exploreits issues, while it substituted moral independencefor the old ideal <strong>of</strong> State rights and sovereign power.Athens, as we have seen, no longer gave the law'Plutarch, "Demetrius."


28 STOICISM,to a thousand subject-states; but she was still,withoutdispute, the intellectual centre <strong>of</strong> the civilized world.Students flocked to her, not only from the neighbouringlands <strong>of</strong> Greece and the islands <strong>of</strong> the Archipelago,but from the coasts <strong>of</strong> Asia Minor and the towns <strong>of</strong>the Phenician sea-board. It was a time <strong>of</strong> disquietand exhaustion, when the streams <strong>of</strong> national life wereflowingfeebly,and men could walk no more withoutmisgiving in the old paths <strong>of</strong> custom and religion.They turned, therefore, with eagerness to any teacherswho pr<strong>of</strong>essed to have explored the mysteries <strong>of</strong>life, and to have found a safe rule for human action.A sage's reputation <strong>of</strong>ten was enough to draw themfrom their distant homes in quest <strong>of</strong> wisdom. Notonly the young, but men, and greybeards even crossedthe seas to gather round some celebrated teacher inthe favoured home <strong>of</strong> Greek philosophy, where allthe rival systems had their eager followers and masterspirits. Sometimes they seemed to hear a suddencall to earnest thought, as in the later stories <strong>of</strong> conversionto religious life. Thus Zenon, as we readin the old story, came on other business to Athens,but while there took up in a bookseller's shop a copy<strong>of</strong> Xenophon's Socratic Memoirs, which he read longand earnestly, till he asked at " length, Where aresuch men to be found ?" The Cynic Crates, who waspassing by, was pointedout to him as one who hadthe secret <strong>of</strong> a higher life, and Zenon forthwith followedhim as a disciple, till he became himself ateacher in his turn. In that, as in the other schools<strong>of</strong> Athens, there were many votaries <strong>of</strong> Iearning,'young


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 29and old, who freely grouped themselves around arecognised leader, listening to his exposition<strong>of</strong> thetruth, and trying to reduce his lessons to the hard test<strong>of</strong> practice. Each was supposed to reproduce inauthorized form the tenets <strong>of</strong> the Plato, Aristotle, orAntisthenes, who had been the founders <strong>of</strong> the variousschools <strong>of</strong> thought. Once appointed to the post <strong>of</strong>honour, he filled itcommonlytill death closed hislabours ;but while he lived he chose another whomight step into his place when he was gone, or in hiswill put the <strong>of</strong>ifice in commission for a while,till thedisciples who were trusted most could make theirchoice. It was a purely voluntary system, for it waslong before the foremost men could be regarded aspr<strong>of</strong>essors, appointed or salaried by the State. Rather,they lived upon the footing <strong>of</strong> the Free Churches <strong>of</strong>our modern times, and the principal members actedsomewhat as the deacons, choosing at times, thoughit does not appear that they dismissed, their spiritualhead. To the credit <strong>of</strong> the philosophic sects, it shouldbe noticed that each enjoyed a rare degree <strong>of</strong> harmonywithin itself; even the most restless spiritsseldom ventured to dispute the master's claims totheir obedience, or to set up a rival oracle beside him.Many, even <strong>of</strong> the greatest name, appear to havewaited quietly for many years, till a vacancy was madeby death, or they were invited to assume the foremostplace.We hear only <strong>of</strong> one, Chrysippus, who set upfor himself while the head <strong>of</strong> his school was still alive ;'Cf. " University Life in Ancient Athens,"c. ii.


30 STOICISM.and even he owned his fault, we are told, in laterdays, and owned that the one thing which he regrettedwas undutiful behaviour to Cleanthes.In most <strong>of</strong> the Greek towns, as has been said, therewere public buildings called gymnasia, built chiefly, itis true, for bodily exercises and athletic feats, but largelyused, by the sufferance <strong>of</strong> the State, for the lecturesand discussions <strong>of</strong> the philosophers or sophists. It wasnot long before the several schools drew themselvesapart into special buildings or into various quarters<strong>of</strong> the city ;and some even took their most familiarname, such as the Academy <strong>of</strong> Plato, and the AristotelianLyceum, and the Garden <strong>of</strong> Epicurus in theouter Ceramicus, from the localities in which theymade themselves at home. There was a splendidporch or colonnade at Athens called the Stoa Poicile,from the varied paintings with which the genius <strong>of</strong>the great artist Polygnotus had adorned Memoriesit.<strong>of</strong> horror had been long associated with it as a scene<strong>of</strong> judicial murder during the reign <strong>of</strong> terror <strong>of</strong> theThirty Tyrants, when so many <strong>of</strong> the foremost citizenshad died by the executioner's hand. But there werealso memories <strong>of</strong> the patriotism and the virtue thathad perished there, and Zenon was content to connecthis teaching with such lessons <strong>of</strong> the past when hegathered his disciples round him in the open spacewhich was then left at his disposal ;here he taught publiclyfor many years, and his successors chose it also asthe scene <strong>of</strong> their debates, and hence they soon gainedthe distinctive name <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong>s, and their sentimentswere called the tenets <strong>of</strong> the Porch. In most <strong>of</strong> the


THE RISE OF STOICISM.3 1schools we find some modest traces <strong>of</strong> endowments.Thus Theophrastus in his will disposed as follows <strong>of</strong>the house and garden near the Ilissus which cameinto his hands after Aristotle'sdeath :— " My gardenand the walk, and all the buildings which adjoin theglebe, I bequeath to such <strong>of</strong> my friends herein describedas care to pass their lives in them together instudy and philosophy, on condition that no one shallalienate them or make any individual claim; butthat all shall share alike, and live in domestic peacetogether,as is natural and right."Epicurus also left his famous garden, at his death,for the members <strong>of</strong> his school, and also set apart somefunds to keep the student world together." I givemy property in trust to Amynomachus and Timocrates,on the condition that they make over the use <strong>of</strong> thegarden and all it contains to Hermarchus and thosewho join his speculations, and to such as he maychoose to take his place, that they may there givethemselves to study ; and, moreover, I beg all whotake their principles from me to do their best as asolemn trust to keep Amynomachus and Timocratesto maintain the school-buildings inmy garden, andtheir heirs after them, as also those who may be appointedto replace my own successors. And out <strong>of</strong>the funds bequeathed by me I will that my executors,in concert with Hermarchus, provide religious servicesfor my father and mother, and brothers, and myself. . . and also for the stated meeting, to be held onthe 20th <strong>of</strong> every month, byall the members <strong>of</strong> mysect."


OT,2 STOICISM.Some <strong>of</strong> the philosophers had means enough tomaintain themselves in studious easewithout endowments<strong>of</strong> this sort ; but, besides this, nearly allaccepted presents from their hearers. Socrates, indeed,had thoughtit a low and mercenary practicefor the teacher to take pay from those he taught, andhis own friends and followers shared his sentiments,and taught freely all who came to learn. But beforelong the prejudice grew weaker, and the presents sentwere readily accepted, and payment even demandedas a due.But the true Cynic cared, as we have seen,for httle more than the means <strong>of</strong> bare subsistence.Some like Crates followed so far the counsels <strong>of</strong> perfectionthat they gave up all they had as only ahindrance in their quest for wisdom. The <strong>Stoic</strong>s also,following their example, for some time discouragedall endowments, and would accept little or nothingfrom admirers or disciples. The wealthy or fastidiouswere likely to be repelled rather than attracted bytheir language; and if their enthusiasm was pro<strong>of</strong>to irk-against hard words, they were sometimes putsome tasks to prove if the novices had the true hungerand thirst after philosophy. Thus Zenon, we are told,was too sensitive to the opinion <strong>of</strong> the world to carryout in their extreme forms the Cynic doctrines. "Onwhich account," says Diogenes Laertius, "Crates wishingto cure him <strong>of</strong> this false shame, gave him a jar <strong>of</strong>lentil porridge to carry through the Ceramicus ;andwhen he saw he was ashamed, and that he endeavouredto hide it,he struck the jar with his staff and brokeit,and as Zenon fled away, and the lentil porridge


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 33ran all down his legs, Crates called after him, ' Whydo you run away my little Phoenician ; you have doneno harm ? The 'lesson seems to have been taken ingood part, and the example followed afterwards in thetreatment <strong>of</strong> his own"disciples." Once, when ahandsome and wealthy Rhodian, but one who had noother qualification, was pressing him to take him as apupil, he, as he was not inclined to receive him, first<strong>of</strong> all made him sit on the dusty seats that he mightdirt his cloak, then he put him down in the place <strong>of</strong>the poor that he might rub against their rags, and atlast the young man went away.''^It needed some toughness <strong>of</strong> moral fibre not to be<strong>of</strong>fended at such a course <strong>of</strong> treatment, and we neednot be surprised to find that among the earlier <strong>Stoic</strong>sthere were men <strong>of</strong> resolute temper, trained in the hardlife <strong>of</strong> penury and toil. Thus Cleanthes " came toAthens, having but four drachmas, as some peoplesay, and attaching himself to Zenon he devoted himselfto philosophy in a most noble manner Hewas especially eminent for his industry, so that as hewas a very poor man he was forced to undertakemercenary employment, and he used to draw water inthe gardens by night, and by day he used to exercisehimself in philosophical discussions. They also. . .say that he was on one occasion brought before acourt <strong>of</strong> justice to be compelled to give an accountwhat his sources <strong>of</strong> income were from which he maintainedhimself in such good condition and that then:^Diogenes Laertius," Zenon," translation by Yonge.D


34 STOICISM.he was acquitted, having produced as his witness thegardener in whose garden he drew the water, and awoman who was a meal-seller, in whose establishmenthe used to prepare the meal. And the judges <strong>of</strong> theAreopagus admired him, and voted that ten minseshould be given to him, but Zenon forbade him toaccept them."iBut Zenon had first practisedthe lessons <strong>of</strong> moderationwhich he enforced upon his younger friends." He was a person," says Diogenes," <strong>of</strong> great powers <strong>of</strong>abstinence and endurance and <strong>of</strong> very simple habits,living on food which required no fire to dress it, andwearing a thin cloak, so that it was said <strong>of</strong> him —The cold <strong>of</strong> winter and the ceaseless rainCome powerless against him ;weak is the dartOf the fierce summer sun, or fell disease,To bend that iron frame. He stands apart,In nought resembling the vast common crowd :But patient and unwearied, night and day.Clings to his studies and philosophy."He cared as little for the banter <strong>of</strong> the comic poets,who made him the object <strong>of</strong> their witticisms, as for thelavish compliments <strong>of</strong> King Antigonus, who used tolisten to his lectures when he came to Athens, and atlast invited him to Macedonia to instruct himself andall his subjects in the paths <strong>of</strong> virtue. Zenon returneda courteous answer, speaking in a tone <strong>of</strong> dignifiedapproval <strong>of</strong> the great man's zeal for wisdom, and<strong>of</strong>feringto send to court some <strong>of</strong> histrusted friends,^Diogenes Laertius, "Zenon.''


THE RISE OF STOICISM. 35who would undertake the journey for which he wa^himself'too old and feeble. The Athenians themselves, it seems, had such respect for the good oldman who lived so long among them that they entrustedthe keys <strong>of</strong> the city to his care ;and whenhe passed away at length in ripe old age they voteda decree <strong>of</strong> public honours in the following terms :—" Since Zenon, the son <strong>of</strong> Innaseas, the Cittisean,has passed many years in the cityin the study <strong>of</strong>philosophy, being in all other respects a good man,and also exhorting all the young men who have soughthis company to the practice <strong>of</strong> virtue, and encouragingthem in the practice <strong>of</strong> temperance, making hisown life a model to all men <strong>of</strong> the greatest excellence ;since it has in every respect corresponded to the doctrineswhich he has taught,it has been determinedby the people to praise Zenon and to present himwith a golden crown in accordance with the law onaccount <strong>of</strong> his virtue and temperance, and to buildhim a tomb in the Ceramicus at the public expense.its vote five menAnd the people has appointed by<strong>of</strong> Athens who shall see t<strong>of</strong>rom among the citizensthe making <strong>of</strong> the crown and the building <strong>of</strong> thetomb. And the scribe <strong>of</strong> the borough shall enrolthe decree and engraveit on two pillars,and he shallbe permitted to place one pillar in the Academy andone in the Lyceum." ^The ascetic side <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> was thus embodiedin the life <strong>of</strong> the first two great doctors <strong>of</strong> the^Diogenes Laertius, ' ' Zenon. "D 2


o 6STOICISM.school, which may have seemed perhaps, so fax,to careless eyes as onlyold Cynic creed. But its literarya s<strong>of</strong>tened form <strong>of</strong> theand constructiveaspect was best represented in the person <strong>of</strong> Chrysippus,who wrote more than seven hundred differenttreatises on philosophic questions, and showed suchpower <strong>of</strong> illustration and acuteness in developing thetenets <strong>of</strong> his sect that it was said, " Had there be^nno Chrysippus, there had been no Porch." Hiscritics, indeed, complained <strong>of</strong> the careless languageand the frequent repetitions <strong>of</strong> his works, and <strong>of</strong> theundue length <strong>of</strong> his quotations from the earlierauthors, and it is evident that he cared more for thematter than the artistic value <strong>of</strong> his writings.But the<strong>Stoic</strong> system as a whole was expanded and completedby him, and when he died, in 206 B.C., its characteristicfeatures were entirely defined." If the gods have any logic,"author, "it is that <strong>of</strong> Chrysippus " yetsaid an ancienthe wrote toomuch, and from too many points <strong>of</strong> view, to be alwaysquite consistent in his statements. Plutarch, therefore,refers largely to him in his treatise on the<strong>Stoic</strong> inconsistencies ; though his objections mainlyillustrate the natural contrasts between a rigid theoryand the real needs <strong>of</strong> common life, and the self-contradictionsthat arose out <strong>of</strong> the effort to becomelearned and many-sided and elastic without beinguntrue to a hard dogmatic creed.


STOICISM. 37CHAPTER IV.STOICISM IN THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIALPRINCIPLES.The strength and originality <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> system isto be found undoubtedly in the rule <strong>of</strong> life which itpr<strong>of</strong>essed, but nothing can seem more indefinite atfirst than the familiar phrase <strong>of</strong> "Hving in conformitywith Nature," in which their moral standard was expressed.It might seem to admit <strong>of</strong> almost any explanation,and to lend itself as well to the grosser forms<strong>of</strong> practical Epicureanism, which justify the fullestindulgence <strong>of</strong> the instincts, as to the finer moods <strong>of</strong>Hellenic thought which entrusted the regulation <strong>of</strong>man's life to a sort <strong>of</strong> cultivated sympathy or artistictaste for natural beauty and refinement. Its valuemust depend upon the meaning which they gave tothe word " Nature," and thatwas too full and manysidedto be included in a definition. We must first,therefore, gain a clearer notion <strong>of</strong> their views uponthis and kindred subjects.•In the order and harmony <strong>of</strong> universal nature thereare signs enough, they argued, <strong>of</strong> a First Cause andGoverning Mind. Human instinct has everywherepointed to this cardinal truth, and from this flow themultitudinous forms <strong>of</strong> worship in all lands. A litde


38 STOICISM.thought upon the matter shows us that there must bea power inherent in the world to move it as the soulcan move the body. That power must have consciousnessand reason, else how can we explain thebeing <strong>of</strong> conscious creatures like ourselves, and allthe intricate machinery <strong>of</strong> inter-connected means andends. A building can no more exist without a builderthan the order <strong>of</strong> the world without a ruling spirit.As we mount in thought along the ladder <strong>of</strong> creation,from class to higher class above it,we cannot but goon to the belief in a yet higher being w^hose moraland intellectual perfection is quite infinite, whomfolks alike call God. Of Himphilosophers and simplethe <strong>Stoic</strong>s speak in the language <strong>of</strong> devotional fervour,not only as an abstract Reason, but as a happy andbeneficent Creator. But if we ask what were thereal features <strong>of</strong> their creed we shall find to our surprisethat it was one <strong>of</strong> Pantheism undisguised. Godis the eternal substance which is always varying itsmoods, and passing into different forms as the creativework isgoing forward, and may be alike conceivedtherefore as the primary matter and the efficient forcewhich shapes the derivative materials <strong>of</strong> which allthings are made. Spoken <strong>of</strong> as active power He isGod, but as the sum <strong>of</strong> all his emanations and effectsHe is the world, for the visible universe is only apassing stage in the eternal progressin which God isdeveloping his powers. From God all things proceed,and to Him they will all return at last,when each cycle <strong>of</strong> time has run its course andthe old emanations are absorbed into the source


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 39<strong>of</strong> life, and the formation <strong>of</strong> a new world beginsafresh.This thorough-going Pantheism was expressed,,moreover, in materialistic symbols, borrowed at leastin part from a much earlier thinker, Heraclitus.God is conceived as fiery ether, or an atmosphericcurrent, passing now by condensation into the forms<strong>of</strong> water and <strong>of</strong> earth, sublimated again into the state<strong>of</strong> air and fire, producing thus by turns the primaryelements out <strong>of</strong> which the world is made. A localhabitation is assigned to the central power fromwhich all the living forces flow, though there is nogeneral agreement on the subject; some call it heaven,while others hold it to be the sun or the centre <strong>of</strong>the earth. The matter in which this primary forcehas clothed itself awhile isbeing by slow degreesconsumed, and will be exhausted at the last, wheneach cycle <strong>of</strong> time has run its destined course. Theworld and all the derivative materials which it containswill be dissolved in "fervent heat," and thedivine substance, which "is uncompounded in itsessence pure," will then alone remain.Such expressions <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>s must not be regardedonly as a picture language to assist the fancy, as thefigures and symbols used by the soaring thought,when it would strive to body forth its visions. Ratherto them it seemed that material things alone werereal, their properties and forms were allproduced bythe existence <strong>of</strong> air currents, each radiating from thecentre to which it must again return. The qualities<strong>of</strong> the soul as <strong>of</strong> the body were only varieties <strong>of</strong>


causes40 STOICISM.tension caused by atmospheric impact,and thusemotions, impulses, and judgments even might beregarded as material objects. Much <strong>of</strong> this, nodoubt, was merely awkwardness <strong>of</strong> phraseology, andthe real meaning was that the realities in questionmust depend on some material conditions. But illchosenas the language seems, it runs through alltheir logical and physical discussions, and sets astamp <strong>of</strong> rude materialism on all their speculativethought.As a natural consequence their forms <strong>of</strong> speechwere fatalistic. There may seem, they said, to behazard and caprice around us, but all things cometo the birth and grow and pass away in unconditionaldependence:on a universal lawand effectsare unchangeably connected by an absolute necessitywhich rules all being and all becoming. This fate,lor destiny, is the reason <strong>of</strong> the world, for it is thenatural law in which theexpressed,course <strong>of</strong> the world may bethe order <strong>of</strong> Providence in -which theDeity unfolds his latent possibilities <strong>of</strong> being, andpasses by development through all his stages, thesum <strong>of</strong> all the generative reasons which produceand shape the individual moods <strong>of</strong> nature.Pantheistic systems <strong>of</strong>ten find in literary treatmenta lyric fervour <strong>of</strong> expression, and may be combinedin practice with a high degree <strong>of</strong> mystic resignation,but they are not quite in harmony with the language<strong>of</strong> devotion, which implies throughout belief in thebeing <strong>of</strong> a personal God, distinct from and aboveHis creatures. Yet the phrases <strong>of</strong> simple piety are


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES.4Ito be found undoubtedly in <strong>Stoic</strong> writings, as inthe striking verses <strong>of</strong> Cleanthes' hymn :—" Thee it is lawful for all mortals to address. Forwe are Thy <strong>of</strong>fspring, and alone <strong>of</strong> living creaturespossess a voice which is the image <strong>of</strong> reason. ThereforeI will for ever sing Thee and celebrate Thypower. All this universe rolling round the earthobeys Thee, and follows willingly atThy command.Such a minister hast Thou inThy invincible hands,the two-edged, flaming, vivid, thunderbolt. O King,most High, nothingis done without Thee, neitherin heaven or on earth, nor in the sea, except whatthe wicked do in their foolishness. Thou makes:order out <strong>of</strong> disorder, and what is worthless becomesprecious in Thy sight for;Thou hast fitted togethergood and evil into one, and hast established one lawthat exists for ever. But the wicked from fl}- Thylaw, unhappy ones, and though they desire to possesswhat isgood, yet they see not, neither do they hearthe universal law <strong>of</strong> God. If they would follow itwith understanding they might have a good life. Butthey go astray, each after his own devices— somevainly striving after reputation, others turning asideafter gain excessively, others after riotous livingand wantonness. Nay, but, O Zeus, Giver <strong>of</strong> allthings, who dwellest in dark clouds and rulest overthe thunder, deliver men from their foolishness.Scatter it from their souls, and grant them to obtainwisdom, for by wisdom Thou dost rightly governallthings ; that being honoured we may repay Theewith honour, singing Thy works without ceasing, as


42 STOICISM.it is right for us to do. For there is no greaterthing than this, either for mortal men or for thegods, to sing rightly the universal law."^A theory which identifies the world with God, andbelieves Him therefore to exist alike in the evil andthe good, might be in the long run fatal to intensity<strong>of</strong> moral purpose, tending as itnaturally does to slurover and efface the broad lines <strong>of</strong> distinction betweengood and evil which the common sense <strong>of</strong> humanityhas sharply drawn. Yet the <strong>Stoic</strong> morality was sternand rigid, insisting in uncompromising tones uponthe claims <strong>of</strong> duty. It was not content with thenatural outcome <strong>of</strong> a fatalistic creed, with the reveries<strong>of</strong> calm submission absorbed in the contemplation<strong>of</strong> an infinite will, working out itsplans in all themultitudinous forms <strong>of</strong> nature, but it braced theenergies for active combat, and bade men resist andconquer evil. The existence <strong>of</strong> that evil might beexplained, they sometimes thought, as an imperfectionin detail which was necessary for the perfection<strong>of</strong> the whole, or as a supplement and counterpartto good, or as a flaw inherent in man's nature, whicheven the providence <strong>of</strong> God could not remove.These explanations, if not quite consistent with theleading principles which they pr<strong>of</strong>essed, still showhow strong was their anxiety to rescue spiritualrealities from the bondage <strong>of</strong> a materialistic creed,to assertthe dignity <strong>of</strong> God and man, and vindicatethe moral order <strong>of</strong> the world.'Sir A. Grant's translation.


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 43This, then, was their view <strong>of</strong> Nature, ruled in allits parts by universal reason, which enters into theplay <strong>of</strong> elemental forces, and ordains the preestablishedharmony <strong>of</strong> the blind machinery whichit sets in motion, while it attains to consciousness inman,—and, strange to say, leaves room if not for hispersonal freedom as commonly conceived,at leastfor his responsibility <strong>of</strong> choice, as well as for devotionalfeeling towards the God <strong>of</strong> which he ishimself a part.It is man's privilege, they said, that he alone <strong>of</strong>earthly beings has the gift <strong>of</strong> reason, can see thewisdom <strong>of</strong> the Providence which rules the world, and bein sympathy with its creative thought. He has, indeed,animal impulses and appetites like the lower creatureswhich surround him, which are left by Nature to suchguidance, but man should surely respecthis betterself and be ruled by the noblest faculty within him.By virtue <strong>of</strong> this he may claim relationshipwith theEternal Reason, and this identity will be the closerthe more he gives free play and scope to thedivine element <strong>of</strong> intellect within him. This must,indeed, one day, at the end <strong>of</strong> the world's course,be resolved into the universal substance into whichall things will then return, when all individual existencewill be lost ; but, meantime, men may last onafter death as separatesouls, be cleansed even as ina state <strong>of</strong> purgatory from the stains and pollutions<strong>of</strong> the life on earth, and mount heavenward throughthe lower air tillthey reach a purer atmospherecongenial to their own ethereal nature, while the


44 STOICISM.souls <strong>of</strong> the criminal and foolish may have been soweakened by continued contact and interminglingwith the evil as to have littlepower <strong>of</strong> vitality inherentin them when their bodies crumble to decay.All things pursue, by an unconscious instinct, whatis best suited to their nature :nothing else can havereal value for them. The essential element in man isreason, and the naturalness and well-being <strong>of</strong> his lifeconsist in rational action, or, in other words, inattuning all his thoughts and aims into perfectsympathy with the general law <strong>of</strong> reason, which isembodied in the universe around him. This, therefore,is the meaning <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> rule. It is expressed,indeed, in varying forms. Some call it a life <strong>of</strong> consistencywith self, others the harmony <strong>of</strong> life withNature ;and Nature againis now explained as the constitution<strong>of</strong> the personal agent, and now as the wholesystem <strong>of</strong> the world at large. But the real meaningalways is the same, that man can only lead a rationallifeby conforming to a general law, and thathe risesor falls in the scale <strong>of</strong> dignity and happiness as hesucceeds or fails in doing this with persistent purpose,as he has more or less, in other words, <strong>of</strong> thevirtue which consists in this willing obedience to law.The leading principle thus stated was carried outto its conclusions with an exclusive and uncompromisingrigour, and the startling paradoxes which theyheld seemed to follow naturally enough from theirone-sided treatment <strong>of</strong> great truths. Good,in itswider sense, was commonly defined in the earlierschools as that which satisfies a natural want, but the


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 45essential element, the true nature <strong>of</strong> man as distinctfrom other creatures, is his reason ;and his real goo^iHtherefore, lies in rational action, or in virtue. There Iis no good independently <strong>of</strong> virtue ;it is a popular^misnomer to distinguish various kinds or differentdegrees <strong>of</strong> good, though we may <strong>of</strong> course admit,which are themselves in-they said, that many thingsdifferent, may conduce and help to something whichis better than themselves. But bodily advantagesand gifts <strong>of</strong> fortune have no abiding character <strong>of</strong>good, satisfy no permanent want <strong>of</strong> reason, have notthat unconditional value <strong>of</strong> which alone the <strong>Stoic</strong> puriststook account. So even health and wealth must becounted as indifferent, that is, with no distinctivecharacter <strong>of</strong> good, for they may be and are sadlyabused, and we may not do such dishonour to theabsolute worth <strong>of</strong> virtue as to say that aught besideis needful to complete man's happiness. Still lessmust pleasure be the object <strong>of</strong> pursuit, as Epicurusand his followers held. Pleasure there is indeed invirtuous conduct, a cheerful serenity so sweet that wemay say that only the wise man knows true pleasure,but we must not make that our aim and objectwhich is indeed the consequence <strong>of</strong> noble action, butis itself too fleeting, sensuous, and unsubstantial, tobe a standard or a rule <strong>of</strong> life. Virtue should beitself its own reward, and cannot need extraneousconditions to complete the happiness <strong>of</strong> those whohave it. We need not say, indeed, that pleasure isunnatural and bad, though some stern moralists <strong>of</strong>the school would have it so ; enough to say, that it isj


46 STOICISM.not a real good, and must not be made an end, orthe morality <strong>of</strong> action disappears.If virtue was the only good for man,it followedthat for his true self vice alone was evil, though manyother things may seem to be so to the careless eyeswhich take account <strong>of</strong> the nature which connectshim with the lower creatures. Hardship, poverty,disgrace, pain, sickness, death, seem evils to thebeings who are content to live upon a lower level ;but to the sage who would live up to a life <strong>of</strong> reason,they are things in themselves indifferent, taking theircolour and their character from the use to which weput them.The wise man alone isfree, they said again, for hecan make himself independent <strong>of</strong> the whims <strong>of</strong> fortune,can rise superior to so-called troubles, guard himselfalike from care and fear and passionate desire, andenjoy the bliss <strong>of</strong> an unruffled calm. It is true thatin another sense he is not free, has indeed less sense<strong>of</strong> freedom than the careless crowd, for he can recognisethe general law <strong>of</strong> destiny within which all thingsrevolve. His will, he knows, is mysteriously linkedto the long chain <strong>of</strong> natural causes, but he seemsfree in that he can willingly obey the dictates <strong>of</strong> hisnature without being helplessly determined by thingsexternal to himself. He decides on that which reasonpoints to, and he acts under no sense <strong>of</strong> constraintor irksome pressure, for his will and universal intellectare one.If reason alone is a sufficient guide for man, hemust not value highly the animal impulses which also


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 47prompt to action. He stands on a higher level thanthat <strong>of</strong> instinct, which sets the lower world in motion,and makes unconscious creatures seek their good.He forfeits his privilege <strong>of</strong> manhood if he forsakesthe higher guidance for the lower. But this is notall ;and we are here brought to a distinctive feature<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> system, and to the curious psychologywhich it implies. The moods <strong>of</strong> our emotional nature,to the stronger forms <strong>of</strong> which we give the name <strong>of</strong>passions, were thought by them to have their seatwithin the reason, but to be wholly disturbing andmisleading forces. Some fault <strong>of</strong> judgment or imagination,some false notion <strong>of</strong> good or evil lies alwaysat the root <strong>of</strong> each, and makes them so dangerousand misleading. Irrational fancy as to present goodgives rise to pleasure, while desire is a wrong estimateabout the future. Unreal imaginings <strong>of</strong> evil cause uscare as tothe present, or fear <strong>of</strong> that which we thinkmust come. It was easy to carry the analysis stillfurther through the various moods <strong>of</strong> human nature,though it AVas not easy to explain why these distemperedfancies should affect the judgment, or howthe distinction between truth and falsehood couldgive rise to all the different features which distinguishreason and emotion. But their theory made shortwork <strong>of</strong> all these states <strong>of</strong> feeling, and branded them asdisturbances <strong>of</strong> mental health, which tended to upsetthe natural balance <strong>of</strong> the soul, and to imperil fatallyits self-control. The wise man will learn to measurethings at their real value, and recognise the generallaw in all the shifting incidents around him ;he will


48 STOICISM.see that the passions are not natural to man, save inso far as are the diseases which affect the body ;hewill strive to keep the mastery over such faultyfancies, and be true to the consummate virtue whichis passionless and calm. There will be nothing forhim then to fear, for unreason is the only evil ;nothing to desire beyond himself, for his happiness<strong>of</strong> intellectual balance is quite selfcontained ;nocause for anger, for others cannot really harm him,and he should not need a thrill <strong>of</strong> feeling to stirhim to defend the right.It might be thought, perhaps, that this destructivecriticism would at least deal somewhat tenderly withthe grace <strong>of</strong> mercy and the feeling <strong>of</strong> compassion,but the austere moralists <strong>of</strong> the school would notallow <strong>of</strong> any such condescension to our human weakness.Relieve the wants and succour the distresses <strong>of</strong>your fellow-men, they said, in such measure as thelaws <strong>of</strong> general well-being may ordain, but thesedelicate tasks should be entrusted to the calmermoods <strong>of</strong> reason, and not to passionate thrills <strong>of</strong>sympathy which will make you bungle in your work.Much <strong>of</strong> the seeming misery around you is unreal,for the evils <strong>of</strong> which men talk are <strong>of</strong>ten only thenightmares <strong>of</strong> their own disordered fancy ;the sagemust be careful not to come down from his serenerheights, to encourage the delusions <strong>of</strong> weak men, andthe strong ones will not want his pity, for the onlyevils that they know <strong>of</strong> for themselves are within theirpower to remove.This passionless serenity <strong>of</strong> balanced temper is


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 49what was meant by the <strong>Stoic</strong> apathy so famous in theschools <strong>of</strong> Greece and Rome ;itpostulated not onlythe absolute supremacy <strong>of</strong> reason but its rightfulclaims to be the only motive force within the soul,for itwould make a solitude <strong>of</strong> all besides and call itpeace ;but itimplied no torpor <strong>of</strong> ecstatic reveriesand mystic contemplation, such as those whichEastern ascetics have enjoyed, in iheir attempts toclose every pore and inlet <strong>of</strong> emotion, and to endalmost in pure nothingness <strong>of</strong> individual being.We have seen that in their pictures <strong>of</strong> the moral Ilife there is no place left for feeling, save in so far asits calmer moods may rank as states <strong>of</strong> reason ;whilethe emotions or the passions are regarded as a morbidbias given to the thoughts. It was far easier for themto ignore the will as a separate factor in the soul, orto see in itnothing more than knowledge in a state <strong>of</strong>action. But ifknowledgeis thus left as the onething needful in the analysis <strong>of</strong> human conduct, itwould seem to follow as by natural sequence that thedifferent virtues are only forms <strong>of</strong> partial knowledge,such as belong to our imperfect state, andthat we may all have, some more some less,<strong>of</strong> the truth which constitutes salvation. Butthey were far from allowing this conclusion.They insisted for the most it part, is true, that thevirtues were distinct in kind, accounting for theirseveral features sometimes by the variety <strong>of</strong> objectswith which they are connected, sometimes bypeculiar qualities inherent in the soul ;but all <strong>of</strong>them, they thought, have the same end in obedienceE


50 STOICISM.to the general laws <strong>of</strong> Nature— all have the samequality <strong>of</strong> tone or temper or conviction, on whichthey are all strung as on a silver thread, and whichonce broken carries with it the decay <strong>of</strong> each and all.The merit <strong>of</strong> each act consists alone in the intention,which is unconditionally good or bad. If it be theformer, virtue exists then in its entirety ; if the latter,the whole character is naught.Hence, well-known paradoxes follow, with whichthe wits <strong>of</strong> Rome afterwards made merry, and whichwere certainly <strong>of</strong> a kind to startle common sense.I St. There is no difference <strong>of</strong> degree they said betweenthe vices. The results may be widely different <strong>of</strong>course : some seem to do much harm and otherslittle, but in themselves they are alike derangements<strong>of</strong> the mental health, pro<strong>of</strong>s that the right intention isnot present, but that unreason rules the soul. Thebad man, therefore, can do nothing right, and he thatcommits one crime is guilty<strong>of</strong> all.lord <strong>of</strong>himself and master <strong>of</strong> the world.2nd. The wise man is absolutely perfect,There is no lovelinesson earth to be compared with the moral excellence<strong>of</strong> virtue, no freedom like the peace <strong>of</strong> perfectself-control, no wealth like that <strong>of</strong> wisdom, whichfits him for every form <strong>of</strong> active work, and evenmakes him ruler and king by right divine if not byuniversal suffrage, as well as priest <strong>of</strong> the mysteries <strong>of</strong>heaven and earth.3rd. The sage is a citizen <strong>of</strong> the whole world.There isnothing narrow, nothing selfish, in his views,for his whole effort is to rise above his personal and


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 51local limits to the sphere <strong>of</strong> universal law. He willnot neglect, indeed, the duties that lie readyto hishand ;he will respect the ties <strong>of</strong> family and country,though he will not let them bound his horizon <strong>of</strong>benevolence, and will <strong>of</strong>ten have to rise above theirincomplete and sordid maxims. Much <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>language on this subject may be, no doubt, explainedwith reference to the circumstances <strong>of</strong> their age,when the free commonwealths <strong>of</strong> Greece were overshadowedby the power <strong>of</strong> Macedon, and wider sympathiesand freer thought replaced the narrow intensity<strong>of</strong> the old Hellenic standards. Something wasdue, also, to the fact that the earlier <strong>Stoic</strong>s were notcommonly <strong>of</strong> Greek descent, but came from theislands or the coasts <strong>of</strong> Asia, where Semitic influencehad largely modified the bias givenin the schools <strong>of</strong>Athens. But apart from this, the leading principles<strong>of</strong> their <strong>Stoic</strong> theory must have tended to discouragethe zeal <strong>of</strong> the patriot and the efforts <strong>of</strong> the statesman.As an able and learned critic has remarked,^ " aphilosophy which attaches moral value to the culti.vation <strong>of</strong> intentions only, considering all externalcircumstances at the same time as indifferent, canhardly produce a taste or a skill for overcoming thoseoutward interests and circumstances with which apolitician is chiefly concerned. A system. which regardsthe mass <strong>of</strong> men as fools, which denies to themevery healthy endeavour and all true knowledge, canhardly bring itself unreservedly to work for a State,'Zeller. Translation by Reichel, p. 307.E 2


52 STOICISM.the course and institutions <strong>of</strong> which depend upon themajority <strong>of</strong> its members, and are planned with a viewto their needs, prejudices, and customs. Undoubtedly,there were able statesmen among the <strong>Stoic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> theRoman period, but Rome and not <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> was thecause <strong>of</strong> their statesmanship.Taken alone, <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>could form excellent men, but hardly excellent statesmen.And looking to facts, not one <strong>of</strong> the oldmasters <strong>of</strong> the<strong>of</strong>fice."school ever had or desired any public4th. Local or national ties, as we have seen, laylightly on the conscience <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> there were;occasions even, as he thought, when itmight be wellfor him to give uplife itself, if he could no longerplay his part in it with dignity or pr<strong>of</strong>it. They werevery far indeed from counselling or condoning suicidein fits <strong>of</strong> passion or despair. The fatal results <strong>of</strong> viceand folly were not to be shaken <strong>of</strong>f so easily by onerash plunge into the void, but would leave their marksupon the undying soul, and condemn it to misery stillto come. But to the wise man death was in itselfno evil, and when he was brought face to face, assome might be, with conditions in which he couldnot turn his wisdom to a good account, or whensome nobler end might be attained by death, hemight calmly and cheerfully trust to his own handto give him freedom, or to usher him to a better lifebeyond the grave. Thus Zenon in ripe old age grewweary <strong>of</strong> the burden <strong>of</strong> his years, and recognised ina fall and broken limb the summons to be gone.Cleanthes was bidden to abstain from food awhile


THE RIGOUR OF ITS ESSENTIAL PRINCIPLES. 53to cure a bodily disease, and persisted even in thesame course when the passing object was attained,saying that it was a pity to retrace his steps as hewas now so far upon the road. Cato courted deathwith his own hands when his cause was wholly lostand the commonwealth was ruined. And in the evildays <strong>of</strong> Roman tyranny the counsel fell on willingears, and many hurried from a world which seemedgiven over irredeemably to violence and lust.


54 STOICISM.CHAPTERSTOICISMTEMPERED BY CONCESSIONS TO COMMONSENSE.If <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> always had remained on the high level<strong>of</strong> the austere and rigid tenets described in the lastchapter, it might have given substance to the reveries<strong>of</strong> a few lonely thinkers here and there, but it wouldhardly have taken rank as one <strong>of</strong> the great movingforces <strong>of</strong> the earnest minds <strong>of</strong> heathendom. Ithad, indeed, already passed beyondthe narrowCynic dogmasit had abandoned the rude;protestagainst civilized life, and the discouragement <strong>of</strong>speculative thought. It had expanded on all sidesthe negative ideal at which the earlier system hadstoppedshort. But there was still too much <strong>of</strong> theCynic leaven working in its midst, in the frequentparade <strong>of</strong> paradox, the affected contempt for theopinion <strong>of</strong> the world, and ostentatious disparagement<strong>of</strong> common pleasures. It was too absolute in itsnegations, too unbending in its claims upon the conscience,to satisfy the countless souls who were cravinglight and guidance in the paths <strong>of</strong> duty, and notl<strong>of</strong>ty sentiments about the vanity <strong>of</strong> human wishes.It was not long before the attempt was made to reconcilethe claims <strong>of</strong> theory and practice, to relax


TEMPERED BY CONCESSIONS TO COMMON SENSE. 55the rigour <strong>of</strong> their definitions, to tone down andmodify the absoluteness <strong>of</strong> their maxims, and so toclothe the dry skeleton with flesh and blood as toitgive vital force to move as a real power among thehearts and consciences <strong>of</strong> men. Itmay be well,first, to briefly indicate the chief directions in whichsome change or relaxation seemed required, withoutentering at present into much detail uponThe practical mind <strong>of</strong> Rome, which had littlethe subject.taste for verbal subtlety or paradox, was most earnestin requiringa rule <strong>of</strong> life suited to the demands <strong>of</strong>common sense, and we shallhave occasion at a laterstage to quote largely from the great Roman <strong>Stoic</strong>s,and see how much was gradually done by them togive warmth and colour, and many-sided interest, towhat might seem at first unlovely and ungracious.The extravagant pretensions <strong>of</strong> the earlier members<strong>of</strong> the school to lavish all the resources <strong>of</strong> thelanguage in praise <strong>of</strong> the consummate sage sooncaught the attention <strong>of</strong> contemporary critics, whokeenly scrutinized its meaning. The wise man inwhom there is no folly— no weakness, selfishness, orsin— the king-philosopher and high-priest <strong>of</strong> huma-— nity where is he to be found, and what are thetokens <strong>of</strong> his presence ? The men and women whomwe know have their good qualities and evil blended,and few <strong>of</strong> us can seriously think that we have ever 'seen perfection embodied in an earthly shape. Callit an ideal, ifyou will, to which we may tend but notattain, but then we have a right to remind you thatyour picture is confessedly a type <strong>of</strong> unapproachable


56 STOICISM.perfection.Other systems, moral and religious, havetheir ideals, which may be <strong>of</strong> good service if theyshame us out <strong>of</strong> our languid self-content, and give us arule by which to measure the poor realities <strong>of</strong> commonlife.They too have had their doctrines <strong>of</strong> originalcorruption, have mourned over the prevaihng sinfulness<strong>of</strong> man, and have spoken sometimes harshly <strong>of</strong>the hollowness <strong>of</strong> all the seeming virtues that belongto the stillunregenerate state. But they never venturedto affirm that, with a few possible but rareexceptions, humanity was made up<strong>of</strong> fools andat all.knaves, in whom there was no good thingSuch statements outrage common sense, and give nosort <strong>of</strong> help in the rough paths <strong>of</strong> common life. Thevast majority they seem to despair <strong>of</strong> and ignore, forthere is no goodin them on which to work, no fulcrumfor the moral lever; the perfect, if such there are, standabove man's help, for they have found peace, and canenjoy a grace which is indefectible when it is once won.To meet objections <strong>of</strong> this kind, the trenchant language<strong>of</strong> the school was s<strong>of</strong>tened down by kindlierand more hopeful tones. The two extreme alternativeswere no longer regarded as exhaustive ;roomwas left for earnest seekers and toilers after virtue,who were part <strong>of</strong> their Church Militant, which wasnot as yet triumphant. Henceforth men are encouragedto go forward, there is much talk in the school<strong>of</strong> progress, the various stages and criteria <strong>of</strong> whichare reckoned up, and alike in theory and practiceengage a large share <strong>of</strong> their attention. It was aword little known as yet to heathen thought, which


TEMPERED BV CONCESSIONS TO COMMON SENSE. 57was singularly hopeless in its tone while ; Jewishbooks looked forward and spoke ever <strong>of</strong> a good timecoming, and had for the burden <strong>of</strong> their prophecythe bold, strong words " ''for ever," to the wisest even<strong>of</strong> the seers <strong>of</strong> pagandom, society seemed to revolvein fated cycles, and man's life to have little chance<strong>of</strong> being ever a gladder or a worthier thing. Butnow, one after another leading Stoir addressed himselfto the work <strong>of</strong> moral education ;the ascetic lifewas to be, as its name implies, a course <strong>of</strong> training,not an idle and contemptuous protest at the refinements<strong>of</strong> our civilized life, but a series <strong>of</strong> experimentsto test the soul's native power to resist temptationand unloose the coils <strong>of</strong> habit.In s<strong>of</strong>tening down the outlines <strong>of</strong> their picture <strong>of</strong>perfection, it was natural to relax the rigour <strong>of</strong> theapathy which had been made one <strong>of</strong> its marked features.It had been <strong>of</strong>ten urged already by Greekcritics, that Reason was not <strong>of</strong> itself an ultimatesource <strong>of</strong> action ; itsprovince was to sift and to comparethe elements <strong>of</strong> choice, and to step in withauthority among the various Desires, but not to setthe Will in motion byitself.If left to Reason's rulealone, without a motive force to stir it,the complexmachinery could never work, and apathy must shortlyend in complete stagnation <strong>of</strong> the natural system.In answer to such arguments, the <strong>Stoic</strong>s said thatthere were reasonable states <strong>of</strong> feeling which mightl-and must exist in the wise man.Nothing passionateor turbulent, indeed, could be allowed there, onlythe gentlest ripples on the current <strong>of</strong> emotion ;and


58 STOICISM.the most colourless words were appropriated by themto these serenities <strong>of</strong> feeling, high and pure, whichwere worthy <strong>of</strong> admission into the holy peacefulness<strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> apathy. The difference between themselvesand their opponents, therefore, was narrowed now toa mere verbal question, and the old elements <strong>of</strong> theemotional nature, before seemingly excluded, werereadmitted under different names.Thus we have restored to us again some <strong>of</strong> thetenderer sympathies <strong>of</strong> human nature, which wereput before under the ban, making thus a cold andmutilated manhood, to <strong>of</strong>fend us with its tones<strong>of</strong> insolent paradox. The social instinct, with itscluster <strong>of</strong> kindred sentiments, is now allowed to rankas natural, thoughitmay seem to risk that independence<strong>of</strong> the outer world which is the main condition<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> freedom. The virtue <strong>of</strong> mercy reappears,to drop its balm upon the wounds, and spare the<strong>of</strong>fender when he falls, thoughstillmisgivings areexpressed, and theory speaks with an uncertain soundon the emotional aspects <strong>of</strong> compassion. Friendshipand love too find their place, and that a large one>in the moral code, though put <strong>of</strong> course upon arational basis, and purged <strong>of</strong> all the grossness <strong>of</strong> ourcommon clay.We have seen above how narrow was the list <strong>of</strong>things admitted by the <strong>Stoic</strong>s to be really good orevil, and how broadly nearly all the objects whichmen desire or shun were labelled by them as indifferent.Insisting as it did so much on a life agreeableto Nature, their theory made light <strong>of</strong> what are


TEMPERED BY CONCESSIONS TO COMMON SENSE. 59certainly the primary instincts <strong>of</strong> our complex being,and made the naturalness consist alone in the effort<strong>of</strong> reason to maintain a balance, and show obedienffeto a higher law. Yet common sense would have itssay upon the subject, and remind them that theremust be some motive for our choice in action, andthat none such can be supplied, if Reason on its sidecan see no difference <strong>of</strong> good or evil, and emotionon the other is to be silenced or completely purgedaway. A large concession, therefore, was requiredand made to modify the absoluteness <strong>of</strong> their definition.Among the wide class <strong>of</strong> things which are notgood or evil in the highest sense, there are yet somewhich have a kind <strong>of</strong> value, as meeting a naturalwant, or conducing to a higher good, or as helping tomaintain the body's health, or allowing freer play foractive thought. For these a new class was invented<strong>of</strong> things to be preferred (TrpoTjy/LttVa), their contrarieswere to be avoided (cnrmrporjyiJiii'a),and the oldname indifferent (doia^opa) was now reserved fora much narrower class <strong>of</strong> things <strong>of</strong> neutral tint andaccidental value. The importance <strong>of</strong> the changeconsisted in the appreciable value thus assignedunder the first head to the bodily advantages andgifts <strong>of</strong> fortune, which the austerer spirits <strong>of</strong> theearlier school had contemptuously swept out <strong>of</strong> thelist <strong>of</strong> goods, as unworthy <strong>of</strong> the sage's seriousthought.In closeconnection with the compromisesand reservesdescribed above, there was one further distinctiondrawn by them which it is <strong>of</strong> interest to note.


6oSTOICISM,Their standard <strong>of</strong> right action had at first been veryabsolute in itsrequirements and trenchant in itsterms. It was virtuous conduct, dealingwith theunconditionally good, animated by a high and pureintention. But now the large class <strong>of</strong> secondarygoods, objects to be preferred or shunned, reasonablestates <strong>of</strong> calm emotion, which they had ignoredbefore, began to press upon the moralist's attention,who was bound to discuss their proper limits and thefitting modes <strong>of</strong> action in such cases, and to developfinally a code <strong>of</strong> moral rules to be applied in all theirvarying relations. These were only conditional andincomplete, falling short <strong>of</strong> the high standard <strong>of</strong> absoluteperfection (/vardp0w/ia)on which their eyes hadall been fixed before to the exclusion <strong>of</strong> these poordetails <strong>of</strong> common life, but they were seen now tohave a value for the many who were striving to makeprogress to a higher state, and who needed kindlyguidance while passing through the stages <strong>of</strong> transition.So these proprieties <strong>of</strong> conduct, these decenciesand rules <strong>of</strong> choice in worldly matters, weredefined and classified with an increasing care, attimes even with subtlety and casuistical minuteness,and it is curious to observe that the term employedto designate these lower rules (K-a0»//co)'7-a) passed firstinto the Latin word <strong>of</strong>ficia, and then into our Englishduties, thus gradually becoming more absolute insense, and more associated with ideas <strong>of</strong> law andconscience. To the <strong>Stoic</strong>, however,itimplied theworldly rules <strong>of</strong> work-day life,distinct from the counsels<strong>of</strong> perfection (/caropfluY*") addressed only to the


TEMPERED BY CONCESSIONS TO COMMON SENSE. 6 1privileged few, who could climb the philosophicheights and breathe the purer air where all sense <strong>of</strong>effort was henceforth merged in the fruition <strong>of</strong> theTruth.The distinction Hngered on in later ages, when theChristian saint stepped into the place <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> sage,and the old rules <strong>of</strong> ascetic lifepassedwith littlechange into the austerities <strong>of</strong> monk or hermit, andthose who would be perfect were bidden to renouncethe world, whose joys and sorrows, trials and temptationscould give scope only, it was thought, to ameaner and inglorious virtue, while even the sanctities<strong>of</strong> family ties and honest work were degraded tothe level almost <strong>of</strong> the things indifferent or at best <strong>of</strong>relative and imperfect value.There could not be much sympathy at first in theattitude <strong>of</strong> early <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> towards the popular religion.It was reverent and devout, indeed, developing theidea <strong>of</strong> Providence with a precision quite unknownbefore, recognising the Divine in all the many-sidedlife <strong>of</strong> Nature, but its Puritanism was <strong>of</strong> too cold andintellectual a type to be attracted by the sensuouspomp and symbolism <strong>of</strong> the people's worship ; itcould not possibly accept the fantastic immoralities<strong>of</strong> the old Greek legends, asgiving any true conception<strong>of</strong> the Godhead.It was somewhat hostile, therefore,at the first,— insisted that the Deity would notcare to dwell in buildings made with hands, thatprayers were for the most part spent upon unfittingobjects, such as goods <strong>of</strong> body or <strong>of</strong> fortune, or thatprayer was entirely a mistake, since God was good,


62 STOICISM.and knew far better than ourselves the needs to whichHe would minister in His own time. But the religiousconvictions <strong>of</strong> the people, however erring and onesidedin details, were too important to be lightlydealt with, for on them depended much <strong>of</strong> the respectfor law and order, and the most familiar sanctions <strong>of</strong>morality.Attempts were made, therefore, to reconcile thepopular and the philosophic creed. The Zeus <strong>of</strong> theGreek Pantheon was identified with the all-pervadingspirit <strong>of</strong> Divinity, <strong>of</strong> which the minds <strong>of</strong> men wereonly partial moods or emanations, and as such thereforesupernatural (^at'/xovec) ;while the universe contained,perhaps, still higher forms, on which thebounded fancy <strong>of</strong> the masses rested without mountingto their common source.As for the strange myths in the people's Bible, thefanciful descriptions <strong>of</strong> the poets, these were, perhaps,only the sensuous disguises <strong>of</strong> a picture language inwhich the thoughts <strong>of</strong> manhood had been bodiedforth for childish fancy there were; surely deepertruths below, though the symbols might seem coarseor grotesque, and a little patient study might ascertaintheir hidden meaning. By the method <strong>of</strong> allegoricalinterpretation the <strong>Stoic</strong>s were enabled to explainthe follies or indecencies that shocked theirmoral sense in the old religious creed, and find belowthem a substratum <strong>of</strong> physical and spiritual truthsuch as could content the intellectual aspirations <strong>of</strong>their age.in ingenious ways, butIt was a method largely used by them andthey were not long allowed to


TEMPERED BY CONCESSIONS TO COMMON SENSE. 63retain exclusive hold upon it ;the schools <strong>of</strong> Neoplatonismresorted to it constantly, resolving by its aidthe simplest figures <strong>of</strong> poetry and facts <strong>of</strong> history intovague abstractions <strong>of</strong> the most transcendental type.Some <strong>of</strong> the early Christian fathers, such as Origen,used it largely in their turn, and thus succeeded inextracting a series <strong>of</strong> philosophic dogmas out <strong>of</strong> theplain naturalism <strong>of</strong> the historic language <strong>of</strong> the Pentateuch.


64 STOICISM.CHAPTER VI.STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC.The principles <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>, which have been thus fardescribed, were developed chiefly in the lecture-iooms<strong>of</strong> Athens, whose world-wide reputation as a seat <strong>of</strong>learning drew earnest seekers after wisdom from everycivilized land. Students <strong>of</strong> many races there weremingled and; among them the Cilicians, Syrians, andothers <strong>of</strong> Semitic speech, seemed to have been mostattracted by the <strong>Stoic</strong> dogmas ;while the schools <strong>of</strong>Epicurus and the New Academy were more congenialperhaps to the true Hellenic nature. In the Westthese systems <strong>of</strong> philosophy were little known. TheRoman energy, now in the mid course <strong>of</strong> its career <strong>of</strong>conquest, was chiefly occupied with the stirring game<strong>of</strong> politics and war, and had scarcely begun to meditateas yet upon the mysteries <strong>of</strong> life and Nature.The time-honoured customs and ceremonial usages<strong>of</strong> public life, the rigour <strong>of</strong> domestic training with itsappeals to all the venerable associations <strong>of</strong> the past,the spirit <strong>of</strong> clanship and the fervour <strong>of</strong> patriotic zeal,these suppliedduty, which law and religionthe Roman with a definite rule <strong>of</strong>alike enforced withpotent sanctions. But at length a new era openedwhen the legions crossed the seas, and the generals


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC. 65and statesmen came into close contact with the oldercivilizations <strong>of</strong> the world.The language and thea necessary study to the governingliterature <strong>of</strong> Greece becamefamilies <strong>of</strong> theconquering State ;her poetry and art made them feelthe narro\vness and coldness <strong>of</strong> their own nationalculture ;Greek rhetoricians soon appeared at Romedazzling the inexperienced hearers with their speciouswords, ready to make any subject matter <strong>of</strong> debate,and to argue with equal readiness on every side. Theywere not accepted there, indeed, without a protest.The old spirit <strong>of</strong> conservatism found many a sturdyrepresentative among the ruling classes ;men like theolder Cato vehemently denounced the foreign brood <strong>of</strong>sciolists and sophists, who played fast and loose withevery principle <strong>of</strong> faith and reason, and seemed <strong>of</strong>very wantonness to unsettle every conviction. Morethan once the magistrates or Senate decided on strongmeasures to put down the growing evil, and banishedfrom the soil <strong>of</strong> Italy the dangerous teachers whomthey dreaded.But the age was one <strong>of</strong> rapid change, and authoritywas powerless to stay the tide. Half a century hadbeen enough to humble every rival that barred theway <strong>of</strong> Rome's ambition, and had left her undisputedmistress in the East. The spoil <strong>of</strong> the world hadpoured into her c<strong>of</strong>fers. Her capitalists and bankerswere not slow to turn their opportunities to goodaccount ;a new school <strong>of</strong> diplomatists and statesmen<strong>of</strong> wider aims and suppler policy had been trained inscenes <strong>of</strong> foreign warfare; one and all were <strong>of</strong> noF


66 STOICISM.mind to wa'ik in the old paths and be bound by theThe rude simplicity, therigid trammels <strong>of</strong> the past.narrow formalisms, the uninquiring faith <strong>of</strong> earlierdays seemed out <strong>of</strong> date the;wealth and power oithe governing race required a more artistic finish anda wider culture,such as only Greece was competentto give. It is true that the pretensions and the selfassertions<strong>of</strong> the petty Hellenic commonwealthsseemed ridiculous enough to Roman eyes, now thatthey had ceased to breed a race <strong>of</strong> soldiers to defendthem ; they soon grew weary <strong>of</strong> appeals to rights thatwere not based upon material strength, and trampledthem down at last with insolent disdain <strong>of</strong> justice.But humbled as she was beneath her conqueror'sfeet, she gained ere long a wider influence than ever,for nationaland exchanged an intellectual supremacyfreedom. Some <strong>of</strong> the foremost families <strong>of</strong> Rome,like the circle <strong>of</strong> the great Scipio, the conqueror <strong>of</strong>Carthage, set the stamp <strong>of</strong> their approval on theforeign culture, invited men <strong>of</strong> learning to theirhomes, filled their galleries with Hellenic works <strong>of</strong>art, and tried to naturaHze the liberal studies uponRoman soil.But Greek thought was a powerful solvent, whichhad spared at home none <strong>of</strong> the creeds and institutions<strong>of</strong> the past ;its merciless logic had disposed <strong>of</strong>the legendary fancies <strong>of</strong> the people's worship, hadcalled in question every local usage and every venerablephrase,till those convictions only could survivev/hich were not reasonable only, but were based onconscious reason.At Rome under the new influence


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC 67the process was repeated. In the national rehgion,as far as it was <strong>of</strong> genuine home growth, there wasfar less for the critical spirit to attack.The Italian deities were abstractions <strong>of</strong> the reason,not clothed with poetic shapes by any personifyingfancy, nor invested with the passions or caprices <strong>of</strong>our human nature. They gave rise therefore to nolegendary fictions, such as might embarrass the piety<strong>of</strong> a later and reflecting age. There was no dogmaticcreed for criticism to examine, but there were ceremonialusages to be observed, and formularies to beguarded from neglect, and time-honoured methods forinterpreting the will <strong>of</strong> heaven. There was nothingin all this, as in the mythology <strong>of</strong> Homer and <strong>of</strong>Hesiod, that conflicted with the moral instincts <strong>of</strong> alater age, but it was too soulless and mechanical around <strong>of</strong> forms to satisfy the spiritual needs, or toinform the conscience when itreally wanted Hght orhelp. For rules <strong>of</strong> duty, men had looked not toReligion but to Law. Devotion to their country hadsupplied them with an animating motive, which hadtransfigured the selfishness <strong>of</strong> private action ;theearly training, the statute book, and the opinion <strong>of</strong>the world supplied the customary rules which sufficedfor all the common wants <strong>of</strong> life. But in the later<strong>of</strong> Rome these sources and sanctions <strong>of</strong> thedaysmoral law spoke with an uncertain sound ;widerexperience and fuller thought brought manyan inconsistencyto light which had been unseen before,and where authority might be turned against itself,itremained only for reason to decide.F 2


68 STOICISM.Men naturally turned to the newly-imported theorieswhich pr<strong>of</strong>essed to give help and guidance in suchquestions,but the Roman had little taste for abstractspeculations, and turned impatiently away from everythingthat seemed like transcendental metaphysics.It was the practical side only <strong>of</strong> the systems whichattracted his attention, and <strong>of</strong> this even he absorbedonly so much as was congenial to his nature. Thegreat philosophies <strong>of</strong> Plato and <strong>of</strong> Aristotle had losttheir freshness and their power even on their nativesoil,and no serious attempt was made to carry themacross the seas ;and they remained almost to the lastunknown, except in fragmentary forms, to Romanreaders. The New Academy, with its refined scepticismand balanced state <strong>of</strong> intellectual suspense, wasacceptable enough to dilettanti students, familiarwith all the learning <strong>of</strong> the schools, and indifferentto the wants <strong>of</strong> work-day life ;but it would not beartransplanting, and it seemed for the most part heartlesstrifling to the ruder natures trained on coarserfood.The system <strong>of</strong> Epicurus had an ugly sound, andappeared like a mere apology for self-indulgence tothose who did not weighall its reserves and definitions.Its founder lived indeed a pure and blamelesslife,and the pleasure which he advocated was a gladserenity unruffled by the gusts <strong>of</strong> passion^ and onlypossible for thoughtful and well-ordered souls. Butthere was nothing earnest or manly in its creed,nothing to brace the moral energieslife's dangers or temptations, or to speakfor conflict witlito the


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC. 69irresolute conscience with the trumpet tones <strong>of</strong> duty.It had no faith in the moral government <strong>of</strong> theworld, or in a personal immortality ;and resolving asit did the powers <strong>of</strong> heaven into such stuff as dreamsare made <strong>of</strong>, it came into rude collision with thepopular worship, and awoke againstitself both thesuspicions <strong>of</strong> the governing classes and the hostility<strong>of</strong> serious minds.It was far otherwise with the stern doctrines <strong>of</strong>the Porch, which were more akin to the Romantype <strong>of</strong> character than to the Greek itself Itstheories <strong>of</strong> Order and <strong>of</strong> Providence were suited toa law-making and an organizing race ; its allegorizingmethod respected the names and attributes <strong>of</strong> thenational Pantheon, while it reconciled them with itsown conception <strong>of</strong> the great World-spirit, varyingconstantly its moods in an endless series <strong>of</strong> emanations.Its tones <strong>of</strong> paradox, indeed, and its uncompromisingtheory had a startling effect at first whenthey fell upon unaccustomed ears. We read thatwhen the famous embassy was sent from Athens inwhich the heads <strong>of</strong> the leading philosophic schoolstook part, one <strong>of</strong> the chief magistrates asked thefollowing question in the presence Senate,—<strong>of</strong> the" Is it true, Carneades, that you hold that I am nota prgetor, because I am not a sage, and that this isnot a city,and that there is no true state in it ? "Carneades in answer" said, I do not think so, butthis <strong>Stoic</strong> does," turning to Diogenes, who stood besidehim. The anecdot.^ may serve to illustrate thebewilderment which the trenchant language <strong>of</strong> the


70 STOICISM.,Porch occasioned, and the seemingboldness <strong>of</strong> itsclaims to set its wise man high above the rulers. <strong>of</strong>the earth. But by 150 b.c, the higher circles <strong>of</strong>familiar with its tenets.society at Rome had grownPantCtius <strong>of</strong> Rhodes, its most eminent pr<strong>of</strong>essor,moved among the group which surrounded the greatScipio, attending him on his travels as a companionand a friend, as in his mission to the courts <strong>of</strong> Asia.He s<strong>of</strong>tened down the harsher tones, and dwelt uponthe practical aspects <strong>of</strong> the creed, to the exclusion <strong>of</strong>all that might appear as arid dialectic or extravagantextremes. At the same time he gave his teachinga more attractive shape by his appeals to the opinionsand authority <strong>of</strong> earlier thinkers, as especially <strong>of</strong> Plato,whom he styled the very Homer <strong>of</strong> philosophers.The example <strong>of</strong> Scipio was followed by many others<strong>of</strong> the leading nobles, and it soon became a commonpractice for every great mansion to include its cultivatedGreeks, half-friends, half-clients, who as poets,moralists,or rhetoricians instructed or amused theirwealthy patrons, and gave to the social intercourseabout them a learned tone and literary finish. Tothese, perhaps, the circle <strong>of</strong> the Gracchi owed much<strong>of</strong> its wide sympathies and humanitarian aims, andsome <strong>of</strong> them at least had no wish to survive the fall<strong>of</strong> the statesmen whom they had encouraged withtheir counsels. As the times grew darker in the age<strong>of</strong> revolution, and serious minds began to broodincreasingly upon the graver themes <strong>of</strong> politics andmorals, the fashion also grew for every great house tohave its own philosopher, or moralist as we may call


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC.7 Ihim, as a sort <strong>of</strong> domestic chaplain or confessor.That the choice was <strong>of</strong>ten made with care we mayinfer from the story <strong>of</strong> the younger Cato, who is saidby Plutarch to have travelled all the way to Pergamusto invite the <strong>Stoic</strong> doctor Athenodorus to his house,where once installed he remained to end his days.Other systems, <strong>of</strong> course, found their adherents, andthe poem <strong>of</strong> Lucretius remains as a lasting monument<strong>of</strong> the hold <strong>of</strong> Epicurean tenets upon some Romanminds ;but the followers <strong>of</strong> the Porch outnumberedallthe rest, and from them the favourite legal studiessoon received a definite stamp and scientific shapewhich was <strong>of</strong> great moment in the history <strong>of</strong> laterjurisprudence.For a century and more, however, men werecontent to hear these subjects orally discussed byforeign teachers, or to read about them in Greek textbooks;till the time <strong>of</strong> Cicero, scarcely an attempt wasmade to introduce them to a wider circle in a Latindress ;and Cicero himself first formed acquaintancewith these studies as a convenient source <strong>of</strong> illustrationor an exercise <strong>of</strong> dialectic skill. In later life,when untoward conditions forced him to retireawhile from the political arena, he sought distractionin philosophy, and rapidly produced a number <strong>of</strong>treatises on the most important questions, which were<strong>of</strong>ten litde more than free translations from the Greek,though the style, selection, and illustrations were hisown. Two <strong>of</strong> these, especially, reflect the doctrines<strong>of</strong> the Porch, and are <strong>of</strong> interest to us as showingthatin the judgment <strong>of</strong> the writer, who was no <strong>Stoic</strong>


72 STOICISM.by pr<strong>of</strong>ession, but inclined by temper rather to astate <strong>of</strong> Academic doubt, no other rule <strong>of</strong> life hadsuch high claims as theirs for sterling value, and nonewas so suitable for Roman study. The work uponPropriety <strong>of</strong> Conduct (" De Officiis") is based confessedlyupon a treatise <strong>of</strong> Pangetius, while containingreferences to other doctors <strong>of</strong> the school, such asAntipater and Posidonius. In it <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> poses asa philosophy <strong>of</strong> common sense, employed in theservice <strong>of</strong> a high ideal, and droppingall its airs <strong>of</strong>paradox ; though tending somewhat to casuisticaldiscussion in its effort to be practically useful, andhinting perhaps to worldly ears that it might bepossible to combine a high degree <strong>of</strong> theoretic rigourwith some complaisant indulgence in details.The other writing, called " Tusculan Disputations,"deals with some <strong>of</strong> the great questions <strong>of</strong> the Stoa ;such as the proper attitude in face <strong>of</strong> death, and pain,and sorrow, and other emotions <strong>of</strong> the soul, but in amore meditative and abstracted vein, avoiding allextravagance <strong>of</strong> language, and tempering the tenets<strong>of</strong> the school with liberal doses <strong>of</strong> Platonic thought.to us as we readThey may seem but common placesthem in these calmer days, after centuries <strong>of</strong> moralizinghave worn the themes threadbare. But theyhad a real value for the author, who turned to thelessons <strong>of</strong> philosophy for comfort and courage inthose evil days. They were not mere empty phrases<strong>of</strong> conventional rhetoric for the republicans who readthem on the eve <strong>of</strong> the proscriptions, and who foundin them arguments and illustrations <strong>of</strong> patient resig-


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC. 73nation and heroic courage.Even Atticus, Epicureanas he was, wrote to his friend to tell him that he felta new fire and energy ashe turned over those pages.Indifference to death was in part the burden <strong>of</strong> itsteaching ;and the counsel fell in those days on willingears, for they received it <strong>of</strong>ten, not as a theme formystic meditation, but as an encouragement to withdrawfrom the scene without delay. At each crisis<strong>of</strong> the civil wars we read <strong>of</strong> a longlist <strong>of</strong> suicidesamong the champions <strong>of</strong> the fallen cause ;the facts<strong>of</strong> history thus form a melancholy comment on thepages <strong>of</strong> the moralist, and throw a lurid light uponthe words that else might seem to Christian eyes likethe mere idle sophistry <strong>of</strong> morbid rhetoric.There was one contemporary figure, the mostfamous <strong>Stoic</strong> <strong>of</strong> the age, the younger Cato, whoshows us in a striking form the strength and weakness<strong>of</strong> the standard by which he ruled his life. Noone had more than he the courageto avow hisprinciples and act up to his convictions ;in an age<strong>of</strong> political corruption there was no stain upon hishonour ;and his moral influence, when once exerted /to check the bribery <strong>of</strong> candidates for <strong>of</strong>fice, didmore, we are told, than all the laws and penal sanctionswhich enforced them. In the worst crisis <strong>of</strong>the revolution, when the spirits <strong>of</strong> other men weresoured, and the party cries grew fiercer, his temperseemed to become gentler, and to forbode the miseries<strong>of</strong> civil war. Inflexible before, he pleaded for concessionsto avert the storm ;and when they wererefused, he raised his voice still for moderate counsels,


74 STOICISM.and spoke to unwilling ears <strong>of</strong> the claims <strong>of</strong> humanityand mercy. He struggled on, while hope remained,fearlessly and consistently in what he thought thecause <strong>of</strong> right and order ;and when at last that causeseemed ruined irretrievably, he calmly prepared toleave the scene where he could no longer act withself-respect, talking as he died upon the soul's immortalhopes, and the freedom which the wise manonly can enjoy. Imperialism suffered more, perhaps,from the protest <strong>of</strong> that voluntary death than fromanything which he had done during his lifetime and;the conqueror thought it needful, while the burden<strong>of</strong> a subject world lay upon his shoulders, to penhimself a literary answer tothe praises which passedfrom mouth to mouth as well as to the more elaboratepanegyrics on the dead.^And yet, withal, the strength <strong>of</strong> the theories <strong>of</strong> lifewhich he embodied seemed to lie overmuch in theirpowers <strong>of</strong> resistance, and to lack adaptiveness tonew conditions. There were a pedantry and formalismin his adherence to the antiquated maxims whichwere wholly unsuited to the experience<strong>of</strong> his times,a blindness in his reverence for an inelastic systemwhich made him constantly the dupe <strong>of</strong> his ownhollow and pretentious phrases. The old constitutionlay a-dying,for friends and foes alike had dealt itmany a death-blow, but Cato clung to it as thoughthe wit <strong>of</strong> man could not devise a better system, orwithout il save the cause <strong>of</strong> social order. Political1The " Anti-Cato" <strong>of</strong> Julius Ccesar.


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC. 75action cannot be successful without allowance forvarieties <strong>of</strong> temper, and delicate tact innoticing theshifting currents <strong>of</strong> opinion, and some willingness togive and take in the necessary play <strong>of</strong> mutual compromisesand concessions. Cato, perhaps, was hamperedby the associations <strong>of</strong> his name, which madehim narrow his cosmopolitan ideal to the picture <strong>of</strong>the stubborn old republican who had made his familyillustrious in an earlier age. But the tenets <strong>of</strong> thePorch seem responsible in part for his failure as astatesman. They encouraged him in his contemptfor the opinion <strong>of</strong> the ignorant public, and nursedhis pride <strong>of</strong> haughty opposition. They made it seema weakness to give way on any point ;as if every rulewere alike sacred, and nothing could be yieldedwithout a sacrifice <strong>of</strong> principle or courage. Theymade him wTap himself too ostentatiously in thecloak <strong>of</strong> his own virtue, identify complacently hiscause with that <strong>of</strong> right, and pride himself on hisdefiance <strong>of</strong> the passions and unreason <strong>of</strong> weak men.Mommsen. the learned historian <strong>of</strong> Rome, afterdescribingthe introduction <strong>of</strong> the new theories <strong>of</strong>ethics a century before the end <strong>of</strong> the Republic, says,in a mocking spirit, that with all their show <strong>of</strong> popularitythe practical results were hardly more than this,that " two or three noble houses lived on poor fareto please the Stoa." He speaks again <strong>of</strong> the reactionagainst the fashionable system <strong>of</strong> philosophy duringthe long agony <strong>of</strong> the civil wars, and <strong>of</strong> the antipathyamong men <strong>of</strong> intellectual vigour to the pretentiousness<strong>of</strong> Pharisaic phrases," coupled, doubtless, with


J 6ST0IC1SI>I.the increasing disposition to take refuge from practicallife in indolent apathy or empty irony, that occasionedduring this epoch the extension <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong>Epicurus to a larger circle."^ It is probable that thehistorian somewhat underrates the moral influence <strong>of</strong>theories for which he has so littlesympathy himself;but, indeed, in that exceptional age<strong>of</strong> social dissolutionand upheaval, men would be more likely tolisten to the cry, "Let us eat and drink, for to-morrowwe die," or be prompted to parade a sceptical indifferenceor cynical despair.But the writer does not speak so lightly <strong>of</strong> theinfluence <strong>of</strong> Cato's name and character upon thefollowing generation. "The unrelenting warfare whichthe ghost <strong>of</strong> the legitimate republic waged for centuries,from Cassius and Brutus down to Thrasea and Tacitus,—nay, even far later, against the Csesarian monarchya warfare <strong>of</strong> plots and <strong>of</strong> literature— was the legacywhich the dying Cato bequeathed to his enemies.This republican opposition borrowed from Cato itswhole attitude— stately, transcendental in its rhetoric,pretentiously rigid, hopeless, and faithful to death ;and, accordingly, itbegan even immediately after hisdeath to revere as a saint the man who in his lifetimewas not unfrequentlyits laughing-stock andscandal.""But though the din <strong>of</strong> civil wars may have madeit hard for any but a Cato or a Brutus to calmlymeditate on abstract questions, there can be no doubt*Mommsen. English translation, iv. 2, p. 560.* Ibid., p. 449.


STOICISM AT ROME UNDER THE REPUBLIC. 77that the victories <strong>of</strong> Pharsalia and PhiHppi, disastrousas they were to the repubUcan traditions, favoured thespread <strong>of</strong> jDhilosophic thought. The minds that wereweary <strong>of</strong> the turbulence and strife, and could find nomore an outlet for their energies in the affairs <strong>of</strong>State, turned <strong>of</strong>ten with new interest to the theories<strong>of</strong> morals for which they had found no leisure inmore stirring times. The sentiments and standards<strong>of</strong> their class or party were fatally discredited byrecent failure, and many a serious inquirer turned toseek after a new creed or a better rule <strong>of</strong> life. Theheavier the burden <strong>of</strong> Imperial rule, and the morestifling the <strong>of</strong>ficial air in senate, law courts, or thestreets <strong>of</strong> Rome, the greater the inducement to explorethe resources <strong>of</strong> the inner life, and retire withinthe citadel <strong>of</strong> self, where alone shone the light <strong>of</strong>freedom.


78 STOICISM.CHAPTER VII.THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISJI UNDERTHE EARLY EMPIRE,As in the middle and the higher classes <strong>of</strong> societyat Rome in the first century <strong>of</strong> the Empire the moi-altone became more serious and sad, men turned, aswe have seen, with enthusiasm to the doctrines <strong>of</strong>the Porch as to a religious creed, and literature is full<strong>of</strong> the testimony both <strong>of</strong> friends and foes to the widespreadand enduring nature <strong>of</strong> the movement. Satiresoon found out the weak points <strong>of</strong> the system whichmight be assailed with most advantage, and mademerry with Varro over the pedantry <strong>of</strong> phrase andverbal quibbles, or amused itself with Horace at theparadox that all crimes were <strong>of</strong> equal dye, and thatit therefore was as great a fault to spoil a neighbour'sgarden-stuff as to commit a robbery in holy places.To the votary <strong>of</strong> moderation, trying to reduce tactand good sense to a system,it seemed a very properjest to hear the <strong>Stoic</strong>s talk in their pretentious way<strong>of</strong> the wise man who was master <strong>of</strong> all learning, highand low, and every virtue, blessing, and accomplishmentto boot. And so, perhaps, we might conceivea scholar and gentleman <strong>of</strong> Corinth who had strayedunawares into the midst <strong>of</strong> the little Christian flockwhile the letters <strong>of</strong> St. Paul were being read, finding


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 79it hard to understand the writer when he spoke in /his strange way <strong>of</strong> himself, " as unknown, and yetwell known ;as dying, and behold we live ;aschastened, and not killed ;as sorrowful, yet alwaysrejoicing; as poor, yet making many rich; as havingnothing, and yet possessing all things." For Christianmysticism has itsparadoxes many, and they are foolishnessto those who know them not.The men <strong>of</strong> the world again, who recognised theworth <strong>of</strong> everything that had a money value, but whowere seldom haunted by the thought <strong>of</strong> anythingmuch better than themselves— they were impatientat this talk <strong>of</strong> the self-sufficiency <strong>of</strong> virtue, and theindifference to the gifts <strong>of</strong> fortune, and <strong>of</strong> sublimeideals <strong>of</strong> perfection. If any one spoke in their hearing<strong>of</strong> the need <strong>of</strong> meditating more on the great themes<strong>of</strong> human destiny and duty, they were likely enoughto answer in the words which Persius puts into themouth <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the brawny centurions <strong>of</strong> common"life:— I am quite content wath what I know already;I have no mind to be like an Arcesilas or woe-begoneold Solon, to walk with head awry, and eyes fastenedon the ground, mumbling to himself or working withhis mouth in silencelike a madman, or thrusting outhis lips as though to weigh his words, pondering onsuch stuff as a dotard's dreams are made <strong>of</strong>, asthat nothing can come forth from nothing,and intonothing nothing can return. Is it to study this youlook so pale, or is this worth giving up a single meal ?"' ''Persius, " Satires," iii. 'JJ-^S-


8oSTOICISM.The seeming affectation <strong>of</strong> their dress and demeanourgave <strong>of</strong>fence, and the sight <strong>of</strong> the philosophicstaff and mantle, the close-croppedhair and studiouslook <strong>of</strong>ten was a signal for much ignorant banter <strong>of</strong>the crowd, somewhat as in Christian lands there havebeen times and places when the friar's cowl ortonsure has provoked coarse sarcasm or an outburst,even, <strong>of</strong> unreasoning hate.Yet there was some excuse perhaps for such unfavourablejudgments in the fact that gross deceivers<strong>of</strong>ten donned the cloak <strong>of</strong> the philosopher, and dealtin sanctimonious phrases, while they dragged theirhigh pr<strong>of</strong>ession through the mjre <strong>of</strong> sensuality andlicence. For hypocrisyis <strong>of</strong> all times ;and everyl<strong>of</strong>ty creed, in itsheyday <strong>of</strong> popularity and sunshine,will have its dark shadows and its unclean growth <strong>of</strong>things that cannot bear the light.No wonder ifmany an honest formula gave out a suspicious ring toundiscerning ears, and sounded painfully like Pharisaicboasting, when notorious scandals <strong>of</strong> the kind lingeredin the public memory, and became stock examplesfor the satirists' pages. No wonder if thecareless livers, whose worldliness was visibly reproachedby all austerities <strong>of</strong> practice, exaggeratedthe occasional abuses ;as grave delinquencies amongmonastic orders furnished an excuse for generaloutcries <strong>of</strong> intolerance. They mocked loudly at thewould-be sages who talked so grandly <strong>of</strong> the contemptfor riches and for glory, and <strong>of</strong> treating the greatones <strong>of</strong> the earth as equals, while yet they wanted afee for every lesson, and were ready to do homage to


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 8 1the rich. They gladlywelcomed bitter words likethose <strong>of</strong> Lucian, who speaks <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essionalmoralists as " greedy <strong>of</strong> lucre, more passionate thandogs, more cowardly than hares, more lascivious thanasses, more thievish than cats, more quarrelsomethan cocks."But there were more adverse influences to facethan such opposition <strong>of</strong> an ignorant public. Theliterary and <strong>of</strong>ficial classes looked with an evil eyeupon the speculations which set up a rival influenceto their own, and tempted men to linger in the newpaths <strong>of</strong> ascetic aims and mystic aspirations. Theold quarrel between philosophers and sophists whichdated from the days <strong>of</strong> Socrates and Plato, was renewedin new scenes and under different names, butthe principles at issue were the same. To the phrasemongersand the rhetoricians who were busy withthe graces <strong>of</strong> style and arts <strong>of</strong> culture, philosophyappeared like a sour pedant, whose narrow rules andpedagogic airs were repugnant to all true refinement.She angered them with her pretensions to sitin judgment on the moral life, and to dictate as toAvhat was and what was not men's duty. Thusto the rhetorician Fronto, his own favourite artseemed the only serious study <strong>of</strong> the age.^ "Forphilosophy," he thought, " no style was needed, nolaboured periods, nor touching peroration.Thestudent's intellect was scarcely ruffled while the lecturerwent droning on in the dull level <strong>of</strong>his tedious'"Age <strong>of</strong> the Antonines," p. 1S3.G


82 STOICISM.disquisitions. Lazy assent or a few lifeless wordsalone were needed, and the audience might be evenhalf- asleep while the firstly and secondly were leisurelyset forth, and truisms disguised in learned phrases.That done, the scholar's Avork was over ;no conningover tasks by night, no reciting or declaiming, nocareful study <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> synonymsor themethods <strong>of</strong> translation." He thoughtit mere pretension<strong>of</strong> philosophy to claim the sphere <strong>of</strong> morals forits special care. The domain <strong>of</strong> rhetoric was wideenough to cover that, as well as many another field <strong>of</strong>thought her mission was to touch the; feelings andto guide men by persuasive speech. For words weresomething infinitely sacred, too precious to be trifledwith by any bungler in the art <strong>of</strong> speaking. As forthe thoughts, they were not likely to be wantingifonly the terms <strong>of</strong> oratory were fitly chosen.Quintilian, the celebrated critic, who made thepractice and theory <strong>of</strong> rhetoric his familiar study,was quite as bitter in his antipathy as Fronto. Tohim it also seemed that moral questions belonged tohis own domain by natural right, and that it was insufferablepride on the part <strong>of</strong> any school <strong>of</strong> abstractthought to claim the monopoly <strong>of</strong> such importantsubjects. The good man was the true sage, hethought, and in a matter so intensely practical therecould be no need <strong>of</strong> fine-drawn speculations.Lucian, writing as a man <strong>of</strong> letters, takes anotherline for his attack, without however quite disdainingthe use <strong>of</strong> arguments already stated. The Hermotimus<strong>of</strong> his dialogue is a student <strong>of</strong> ripe age. who


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 83had followed for twenty years with laborious anxietythe tenets <strong>of</strong> the Stoa, and yet was but a learner still,and did not count himself already perfect. In asmany years again he hopes, perhaps, to attain to hisideal, to despise the transitory vanities <strong>of</strong> life, andrise above the sordid impulses <strong>of</strong> anger .and <strong>of</strong> grief,like the doctor whose lectures he attends. Hisfriend, Lycinus, when he hears these gushing phrases,maliciously reminds him <strong>of</strong> a scene which he hadwitnessed when the sage in question was draggingbefore a magistrate one <strong>of</strong> his slippery disciples whowould not pay his fee, and so violent was his fit <strong>of</strong>passion that he almost strangled him with his ownhands by the way.He tells Hermotimus that he need be in no hurr}^to attend the morning's lecture, for the learned doctorhad made too free the day before on the occasion<strong>of</strong> a birthday festival, and was obliged to have anotice pasted up that he could not preach as usualthat morning. Then dropping such coarse banterfor a while, he asks his friend why <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> had beenchosen out <strong>of</strong> such a multitude <strong>of</strong> rival systems, forit could not be seriously thought that popularity, orgrand pr<strong>of</strong>essions, or the solemn airs <strong>of</strong> the philosophersthemselves could weigh much with a man<strong>of</strong> sense in his choice <strong>of</strong> a spiritual guide. To illustratethe embarrassments <strong>of</strong> a decision he goes on infigurative :—" style Virtue, we will suppose, is like acity whose inhabitants enjoy unclouded happiness, asyour teacher who has reached it would describe,having attained to perfect wisdom ; brave, just, andG 2


84 STOICISM.temperate without alloy, they are almost in a worddivine. The theft and violence and greed we seearound us here are banished from that happy citywhere men live in peace and harmony together.that excites strife and rivalryinand pleasures and vain-glory that mightAllother towns, the goldstir dissensionin their midst, have been swept away as idlevanities, and life is therefore calm and happy underthe sanction <strong>of</strong> good lavv-s, and in the midst <strong>of</strong>equality and freedom. What more natural than thatevery one should wish to be a citizen <strong>of</strong> such a State,and should not heed the weariness upon the road,or be discouraged by the time the journey takes, if hecan only get a resting-place assigned him and gain thestatus <strong>of</strong> a citizen ? I remember hearing an old manlong ago describe the way to get admission there ;hewas to guide me on the road, and get me the privilege<strong>of</strong> the franchise, and find me a place even inhis own ward that I might share the general bliss.I was but fifteen years <strong>of</strong> age, but I was already inthe suburbs, almost entering on the promised land.My old friend told me, if I remember rightly, that inthat city all the inhabitants are aliens by birth whohave come to it from other lands ; they are barbarians,slaves, humpbacks, dwarfs, or paupers ; anyone who will may be enrolled without regard to fortune,birth, or dress, or shape, or looks, for thosethings do not matter. To become a citizen one needonly be intelligent, desire the good, work hard, spurnpleasure, and faint not or give way before the manyhardships on the road. He who can prove that these


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 85qualities are his, and can travel over the whole waythat leads there, has won his title to the franchise,whatever he may be in other ways, and will be placedon the same level as the rest. If the city were butfull in view and near at hand, be sure that I shouldlong since have made it myabode. But it is faraway, and the road needs careful search and guidance.A multitude <strong>of</strong> folks pr<strong>of</strong>ess to act as guides,and say they know the waythat leads there. Butthey do not point to one and the same route, butto many difierent paths which have no connectionwith each other. One seems to lead you to theWest, another to the East, this one leads South, andthat goes North. One winds over the meadows andthrough shady groves, where all is fresh and charmingand there is no hardship for the traveller ;another lies over rough and stony ground, exposedto the full glare <strong>of</strong> the sun, and they that journeythere grow faint and parched. Yet all pr<strong>of</strong>ess to leadto the same city. It bewilders me to find that atevery road I pass there is some one standingat theentrance beckoning to me with an air <strong>of</strong> certainty,and telling me to follow him with confidence, for he,and he alone, knows the right way, while all the restare blundering and will never reach the city, for theywould not follow the right guidance. If I listen tothe next, I hear only the same <strong>of</strong>fers and the samereproaches, and so on, till I cannot tell what road totake or whom to trust to show the way."Hermotimus sees, <strong>of</strong> course, the meaning <strong>of</strong> thefigure, and assures his friend that if he were to listen


86 STOICISM.to every preacher in his turn he would never find asafer or more experienced guidance than from thedoctors <strong>of</strong> the Porch, and that the only way toreach the realms <strong>of</strong> virtue was to follow Zenonand Chrysippus. But Lycinus replies," Suppose, myfriend, that I were to listen only to the prompting <strong>of</strong>affection and to follow your advice, who know nothingbut the <strong>Stoic</strong> dogmas, and have never travelled byanother route, ifany God were to recall to lifePythagoras,Plato, Aristotle and the rest, and they were tocome round and ply me with importunate questions,*What reason, or whose authority, friend Lycinus, hasmade you prefer Zenon and Chrysippus to ourselves,who are so much more venerable than they, dating asthey do from yesterday, and that without a word toWouldus, or getting any knowledge <strong>of</strong> our systems ? 'it be enough to urge that I had full confidence in theadvice <strong>of</strong> Hermotimus ? I am sure that they wouldsay in answer, We have no ' idea for our part whoyour Hermotimus is, and on his side he knows us nobetter. But you should not pass your judgment onus on the evidence <strong>of</strong> a man who knows only onepath in philosophy, and has not even thoroughly exploredthat one. Lawgivers, my friend, do not givetheir sanction to the jury if they act in that way andonly listen to one party in a trial without allowing theother side to speak. They require them to hear bothsides in turn, and weigh their words impartially thatthey may distinguish truth and falsehood."The dialogue continues for some time in this strain,with many ingenious arguments and illustrations, but


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 87the burden is the same throughout, that the widerthe experience men have <strong>of</strong> philosophic systems, themore hopeless they-will feel <strong>of</strong> attaining absolutetruth, seeing that the would-be teachers are so many,and their theories so conflicting, and their pretensionsso arrogantly exclusive.From other quarters came pretensions <strong>of</strong> a moreutilitarian nature.In the numerous schools <strong>of</strong> declamation,when the growing youth was trained in thefence <strong>of</strong> words and ail the artifices <strong>of</strong> debate, it was afavourite practice, we are told, to proposeto the ingeniousstudents the following subject for debate :— Afather had three sons, who chose for their severalWhenpr<strong>of</strong>essions philosophy, rhetoric, and medicine.he died he left the bulk <strong>of</strong> his substance to that one<strong>of</strong> his children who could prove his own pr<strong>of</strong>ession tobe the most useful to the State. The teachers whohad no love for abstract speculation gladly took theopportunity to develope all their common-placesabout the utter uselessness <strong>of</strong> what they termed suchcobwebs <strong>of</strong> airy metaphysics. And so, in a later age,we find that Marcus Aurelius Antoninus, the philosophicprince, was despised as a mere book-worm bythe hardy soldier Avidius Cassius, who at length rosein revolt against him. In a letter to his son-in-law,which is still preserved, he wrote in characteristiclanguage on the subject :—" Where is Cato, the oldcensor ? where are the strict rules <strong>of</strong> ancient times ?They are vanished long ago,and no one dreams <strong>of</strong>reviving them again, for our prince spends his time instar-gazing, in fine talk about the elements and the


88 STOICISM.human soul, in questions <strong>of</strong> justice and <strong>of</strong> honour,but neglects the interests <strong>of</strong> State meanwhile."Less prejudiced writers, though in more moderatelanguage, drew the same conclusions, and spoke likeTacitus <strong>of</strong> all such studies as suitable enough forearly youth, as a sort <strong>of</strong> intellectual gymnastic, but asquite unbecoming in maturer years; or like Pliny- theyounger, praised such <strong>of</strong> their friends as proved in theconduct <strong>of</strong> their life a piety, strength <strong>of</strong> mind, orjustice quite as great as that <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essors<strong>of</strong> philosophy, and yet did not haunt the colonnadesor lecture-rooms, to waste their time in endless disputations,but were always to be seen in their <strong>of</strong>ficialdress in close attention to the affairs <strong>of</strong> State.It wasevident that large-minded, cultivated men, who had nolack <strong>of</strong> interest in moral questions, looked with somemisgiving at the growing popularity <strong>of</strong> the doctrines<strong>of</strong> the Porch, which tended to distract men's thoughtsfrom the heat and press <strong>of</strong> active life, and led themto look for satisfaction in a sort <strong>of</strong> cloistered virtue,full <strong>of</strong> fine thoughts about their personal salvation,but <strong>of</strong> slight value to the struggling world below.The familiar arguments which have been so <strong>of</strong>tenurged in Christian lands against the spread <strong>of</strong> theconventual system find some sort <strong>of</strong> parallel in theprotests raised among the pagan society <strong>of</strong> Rome,that public duties were neglected and the responsibilities<strong>of</strong> workday life disparaged by the manyvotaries <strong>of</strong> mystic contemplation.These motives among others may probably haveinfluenced the ruling powers <strong>of</strong> Rome, which <strong>of</strong>ten


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 89looked with marked disfavour on the philosophicsects, and among them regarded with especial rancourthe chief members <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> school. But more<strong>of</strong>ten, probably, this argument was urged as an excuseto disguise less creditable motives, and it may be <strong>of</strong>interest to enter into more details upon the subject,and to illustrate the mutual relations <strong>of</strong> the Imperialgovernors towards the tenets and pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> thePorch. We have spoken already <strong>of</strong> the influence onsucceeding generations <strong>of</strong> the protest <strong>of</strong> Cato's voluntarydeath. But for some time at least it was asrepublican, rather than as philosopher, that his memorywas revered or hated, and the early Empire showedfor half a century no suspicion <strong>of</strong> free thought, anddid not realize that there was any danger in it, eitherto itself or to the institutions which it sheltered.Augustus lived himself on terms <strong>of</strong> intimacy withnoted <strong>Stoic</strong>s, and entrusted the young Claudius totheir care. Dion Cassius,it is true, in the warningwhich he puts into the mouth <strong>of</strong> his minister andconfidant Maecenas, makes him dwell upon the:— necessary limits to such toleration "Many <strong>of</strong> thosewho call themselves philosophers lead men astray todangerous innovations, it is well to be upon yourguard in dealing with them. For though Arius andAthenodorus have been proved to be men <strong>of</strong> honour,yet it must not be supposed that all who call themselvesthe same are really like them. For under thecloak <strong>of</strong> that pr<strong>of</strong>ession many knaves bring infinitemisfortune on the State, as well as on their dupes."But Dion here gives expression to the fears <strong>of</strong> later


goSTOICISM.rulers, and Augustus, like his immediate successors,looked with apparent unconcern upon the spread <strong>of</strong>the <strong>Stoic</strong>s, as <strong>of</strong> other sects.But in the days <strong>of</strong> Nero the Imperialattitude waswholly changed ;the leading <strong>Stoic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the age werestruck down by the strong hand <strong>of</strong> power, whilephilosophy in general was put under a ban, whichwas renewed from time to time, and was not finallyremoved till the tyranny <strong>of</strong> Domitian was over. Thepersecution had not in Nero's case at least the excuse<strong>of</strong> ignorant hatred, for he had been trained himselfin early years to follow the moral speculations <strong>of</strong>his teachers, till his mother stepped in to forbidthe studies as unworthy<strong>of</strong> a man <strong>of</strong> rank.His adviser,Seneca, who held the reins for him in his firstyears <strong>of</strong> government, had drunk deeply at the fountain-head<strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> thought, and it had been one <strong>of</strong>the first signs <strong>of</strong> the emperor's wanton humour thathe loved to gather round him at his table pr<strong>of</strong>essors<strong>of</strong> the various schools <strong>of</strong> thought, and to make merrywith the hot disputes <strong>of</strong> their interminable dialectic.But in the year 59 a.d. the system <strong>of</strong> persecution wasbegun. If we may believe the somewhat questionableevidence in the memoirs <strong>of</strong> Apollonius <strong>of</strong> Tyana, thecharge <strong>of</strong> sorcery and magic was brought against theseekers after wisdom, some <strong>of</strong> whom were draggedbefore the courts, while others fled away from Romebefore the storm ; yet to the honour <strong>of</strong> the thinkersit is said that most <strong>of</strong> them stayed bravely at theirand were true to their convictions. One <strong>of</strong>postthe adherents <strong>of</strong> the Porch, indeed, Egnatius Celer,


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 91basely turned against his friend and pupil BareaSoranus, and worked his ruin by his lying charges,but the indignation roused was loud and deep, andthe treachery isspoken <strong>of</strong> as quite unique in theannals <strong>of</strong> the sect. For some years the attacks weremade on the representative men <strong>of</strong> different systemsas they caught the emperor's jealous eye, or as his vilefavourite, Tigellinus, dropped the seeds <strong>of</strong> suspicion inamonghis ears, but it was speciallythe ranks <strong>of</strong> thegreat <strong>Stoic</strong>s that tyranny made havoc. RubelliusPlautus, the powerful pro-consul ; Seneca, the famousminister and moralist ;and Psetus Thrasea, one <strong>of</strong>the most commanding figures <strong>of</strong> the age, were amongthe foremost <strong>of</strong> the victims to the tyrant's hate orfear,and a crowd <strong>of</strong> less illustrious martyrs followed,among whom many a noble woman showed by wordor deed that the austere lessons <strong>of</strong> the school hadpassed out <strong>of</strong> the domain <strong>of</strong> theory, and had stampedthemselves as living truths upon her heart.At last came a general edict <strong>of</strong> proscription; whichonly heralded, however, Nero's headlong the example was a fatal one to tempt the caprice <strong>of</strong>fall. Butabsolute power. Vespasian, in his turn, sorely irritatedby the contumacious words <strong>of</strong> Helvidius Priscus,the stifthecked son-in-law <strong>of</strong> Psetus, and goaded bythe prompting <strong>of</strong> his chief adviser, Mucianus, put fora while at least the <strong>Stoic</strong> and the Cynic sects underthe ban, and made Helvidius paypenalty <strong>of</strong> his bold bearing. Vespasianwith his life thesoon ruedhis fatal weakness ;but Domitian, the moody tyrant,had less .scruple, and in his hatred <strong>of</strong> free thought


92 STOICISM.he forbade entirely the teaching <strong>of</strong> philosophy, anddrove the pr<strong>of</strong>essors forth from Rome. We may wellask what were the causes <strong>of</strong> this bitter hostility andpersecution.It might seem at first sightthat there could belittle in the <strong>Stoic</strong> creed which could bringits votariesinto rude collision with the ruling powers. It had amarked tendency, as we have seen, to wean menfrom the cares <strong>of</strong> pubhc life,and in evil days tomake them find a solace and distraction in the indulgence<strong>of</strong> a tranquil meditation. As in Christian timesthe retirement to the cloister seemed to end thedanger from a disturber <strong>of</strong> the public peace,so itmight be thought that the staff and mantle <strong>of</strong> philosophywould set at rest for ever all fears <strong>of</strong> revolutionaryaction from those who had embraced thespiritual life. The Empire posed, indeed, as thedefender <strong>of</strong> the faith, and threw its protection roundthe forms <strong>of</strong> the established Church, and as suchmight fear the insidious action <strong>of</strong> free thought. But<strong>of</strong> all systems <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> at the first could be harmonizedmost easily with the old Italian creed, andthrough its principles <strong>of</strong> allegory could explain withoutexcessive boldness even the later fancies <strong>of</strong> theHellenic myths. To this itmay be also added, thatunbelieving rulers have <strong>of</strong>ten patronized religion inthe interests <strong>of</strong> policy, as checking the passions <strong>of</strong>the vulgar through the influence <strong>of</strong> fear ;and <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>took the place to many hearts <strong>of</strong> a kind <strong>of</strong> religiouscreed, and threw all its authority into the scale <strong>of</strong>


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 93social order. As such itmight seem a natural ally,to be courted rather than regarded with an evil eyeby all good governors.There is some weight in such considerations, butwe must not insist on them too strongly. For<strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>, when it was transplanted to the soil <strong>of</strong>Rome, dropped much <strong>of</strong> its negative and transcendentallanguage, and became more practical andenergetic. The Empire <strong>of</strong> Rome was wide enoughto satisfy itscosmopolitan ideal; its business was to findor put enough <strong>of</strong> pure reason into the organization<strong>of</strong> the State to meet the aspirations <strong>of</strong> the sage, andto enable him to take his part in public life withoutany sacrifice <strong>of</strong> self-respect. The most famous namesupon its roll <strong>of</strong> martyrs were the generals and statesmenwho had not despaired <strong>of</strong> the grossness <strong>of</strong> theworld, or withdrawn their vital energies from activework.Mysticism, too, has at other times, we may remember,given umbrage to the temporal power. TheChristian Quietists <strong>of</strong> the last century were silencedharshly with all the rigour <strong>of</strong> the law, and an absoluteKing <strong>of</strong> France was urgentto condemn whatcardinals and popes would have willingly ignored.The language <strong>of</strong> disinterested love seemed fatalheresy to the defenders <strong>of</strong> the orthodox faith ;rulersand priests, who relied exclusively on the influence<strong>of</strong> constraint and fear as moral engines, would makeno terms with the enthusiasts who reliedupon affection,and who would fain mergeall their selfish


94 STOICISM.hopes and fears in the sublime ecstasies <strong>of</strong> adoration.There was extravagance, doubtless, in the language <strong>of</strong>Madame Guyon and her friends which might wellawaken grave mistrust in calmer minds there ; mightseem some disparagement <strong>of</strong> the ceremonial forms <strong>of</strong>the religious life with which a humble piety couldnot dispense ;and so, too, the language <strong>of</strong> the Roman<strong>Stoic</strong>s, with itsrhapsodies about the world-spirit andthe universal reason, and the truths which wereveiled from careless eyes by the child-like fancies <strong>of</strong>the poets, might well sound like an attack upon thepeople's faith, which was the more dangerous becauseitsspirit was intensely earnest, and not like thefrivolous indifference <strong>of</strong> dilettanti sceptics. A Neroor Domitian, indeed, are not to be compared inorthodox feeling with a Louis XIV. <strong>of</strong> France, butthe Imperial regime began with the revival <strong>of</strong> thepopular religion;the rulers were themselves thesupreme pontiffs, and favourites and ministers wereprobably not slow to turn such arguments to goodaccount when they wished to crush a rival influencetoo near the throne.Could any <strong>of</strong> the courtiers have been present atthe literary gatherings before which the young <strong>Stoic</strong>Persius read his second satire, they might have foundsome <strong>of</strong> his shafts <strong>of</strong> ridicule come home to theirown hearts, while others were aimed at the superstitions<strong>of</strong> the people. The poet has no mercy onthe hypocrites who pray with bated breath for favourswhich they dare not own to other men, and so maketheir prayers an insult to the gods they worship ;but


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 95he deals in gentler style with the ignorant fancies <strong>of</strong>the masses :^—Lo ! from his little crib the grandam hoar, /Or aunt, well-vers'd in superstitious lore,Snatches the babe ; in lustral spittle dipsHer middle finger, and anoints his lipsAnd "forehead. Charms <strong>of</strong> potency," she cries," To break the influence <strong>of</strong> evil eyes."The spell complete, she dandles high in airHer starveling hope, and breathes a humble prayer /That heaven would only tender to his handsAll Crassus's houses, all Licinus's lands !Let every gazer by his charms be won,And kings and queens aspire to call him son.He exposes the folly <strong>of</strong> believing that the favour<strong>of</strong> Heaven can be bought by costly gifts:—O grovelling souls, and void <strong>of</strong> things divine,Why bring our passions to the immortal shrine.And judge from what this carnal sense delightsOf what is pleasing in their purer sights ?At last he ends in the accents <strong>of</strong> true spiritualfaith,—No !Of great Messala, now depraved and base,let me bring the immortals, what the raceOn their huge charger cannot ; bring a mind.Where legal and where moral sense are join'dWith the pure essence ; holy thoughts, that dwellIn the soul's most retired and sacred cell ;A bosom dyed in honour's noblest grain—Deep dyed — with these let me approach the fane,And heaven will hear the humble prayer I make,Though all my <strong>of</strong>fering be a barley-cake.'Persius. Translation by Gifford, ii. 53.


96 STOICISM.But the real motives <strong>of</strong> the Imperial hatred arenot perhaps so far to seek, and were connectedwith the more superficial features <strong>of</strong> the sect.The attitude which they assumed on moral questions,their stern, uncompromising language, whichknew no respect <strong>of</strong> persons, and which seemedto make all distinctions between man and man <strong>of</strong>trifling value as compared with the momentous differencebetween the few wise and the many foolish :their unbending dogmatism and stiff-necked assertion<strong>of</strong> their spiritual freedom ;these were <strong>of</strong> themselvesenough to make them odious to vicious rulers, and tosupply the wish, though not perhaps the occasion, forattack. Their favourite phrases about the Divineright <strong>of</strong> the wise man to govern sounded like a covertsatire on the unreason <strong>of</strong> the Cassar on the throne ;they had no mind like the flatterers <strong>of</strong> the court tocanonize their ruler or condone his vices ; they weretoo proud to catch the tones and copy the fashions <strong>of</strong>the palace, so their bearing, whether that <strong>of</strong> manlyself-respect or <strong>of</strong> Pharisaic self-complacency, madethem <strong>of</strong>ten seem like Mordecai by the gate. Therewere some, moreover, who did not confine themselvesto general language, but showed a foolish pride inbraving the displeasure <strong>of</strong> the ruling powers. TheCynic leaven still was working in the <strong>Stoic</strong> sect, andthere were preachers <strong>of</strong> morality among them whoparaded their independence both in and out <strong>of</strong> season,and mistook insolence for manly freedom. We mayillustrate this practice by a story <strong>of</strong> Cornutus, whowas summoned to a sort <strong>of</strong> Privy Council called by


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 97Nero, to advise him, when he thought <strong>of</strong> writing apoetic history <strong>of</strong> Rome. They discussed thenumber <strong>of</strong> the books <strong>of</strong> which the poem should consist,and some courtiers would have it that fourhundred would not be too many for so great asubject. Cornutus remonstrated loudly, saying, thatno one would read a work <strong>of</strong> such a portentouslength." Yet Chrysippus wrote far more," was urgedby some objector." True," was the critic's answer,"but then what he wrote was at least <strong>of</strong> some use tomankind."Yet few, perhaps, carried their audacityto suchlengths as Demetrius the Cynic, who even in thebaths lately built by Nero declaimed against theluxury <strong>of</strong> which such buildings were the pro<strong>of</strong>,sparing no rank in his indiscriminate invective, andanswering the emperor'sthreats with bold defiance.He seems, however, to have been regarded as aprivileged railer, for he escaped with life, though hedid his best to irritate the ruling powers. WhenVespasian passed by as he was lying on the ground,we read, he would not rise to greet him, but onlyrecognised his presence with a gibe ;to which theemperor replied with patience, " You wish to provokeme, Demetrius, to passion, but I do not care tocrush a yelping hound."But it was not till Nero was far advanced uponthe path <strong>of</strong> tyranny and had stained his handswith his mother's blood, that hatred or fear at lastprovoked him to deeds <strong>of</strong> violence against the leading<strong>Stoic</strong>s. They were the Puritans <strong>of</strong> the society <strong>of</strong>H


98 STOICISM.Rome, who were known to frown at all his frivolouspursuits, and sternly to reprobate his cruel caprices.There were philosophic circles in the society <strong>of</strong> Rome,to which Cornutus gave the tone, and where asympathizing audience heard the young Persius readhis satires, applauding in them many a causticreference to the vices in high places and the frivolousfashions set by Nero's court. The common-places<strong>of</strong> the Porch were charged with all the bitterness <strong>of</strong>personal contempt, and informers were not slow totrace or to imagine the political allusions in many adiatribe upon the follies <strong>of</strong> the age.When cringing spirits fawned and flattered, andwhims in thehumoured or encouraged the despot'ssenate or the council chamber, the <strong>Stoic</strong>s at leastprotested by their silence or withdrawal from thescene ; they were thought, some <strong>of</strong> them, to be Republicansat heart, they were known, at least, to be thecentre <strong>of</strong> a sort <strong>of</strong> constitutional opposition, howevermild and faint its efforts ; if there were to be a cry<strong>of</strong> revolution, it would come most likely from theirranks, and among them, asthe noblest and the mostrespected, a national leader would be found, such asa Plautus or a Thrasea, to whom men turned withwondering looks to see how far their toleration wouldbe carried. It was rumoured that some <strong>of</strong> themobserved in solemn state the birthdays <strong>of</strong> Brutus or<strong>of</strong> Cassius, who had murdered the first Csesar; othersspoke <strong>of</strong> Cato as the noblest model for a Roman,and such sentiments might one day prompt them topass from theory to vigorous action. At last a wide-


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 99spread conspiracy was traced against the emperor'sthe accused were some at least <strong>of</strong> the chieflife; among<strong>Stoic</strong> circles, though as a party they had held alo<strong>of</strong>;there were other plots, too, in the air, for the murmurs<strong>of</strong> discontent were loud and deep, and it seemed to betime to strike down the prominent malcontents, andto provide for safety by a reign <strong>of</strong> terror.The most commanding figure among those martyrs<strong>of</strong> free thought was Thrasea Pastus, and a few detailsabout his life and social bearing may illustrate theinfluence <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> creed upon the practical statesmen<strong>of</strong> the age, and its relations in such cases tothe Imperial regime.His birth-place, Padua, had thereputation <strong>of</strong> preserving much <strong>of</strong> the austerer virtue<strong>of</strong> the old Italian type, which had given place commonlyto sensuality and licence, but he left it in earlylife for Rome, where he gave himself to philosophicstudies, with no wish to forsake the world, but toplay his part in it with greater credit, in the highplace to which his wealth and noble parentage entitledhim. His wife Arria was the daughter <strong>of</strong> the heroine /<strong>of</strong> the same name <strong>of</strong> whom the famous story hasbeen toldthat when her husband was condemned todeath, she would not be left to live alone, butshowed him how to die when the fatal momentcame, plunging first the dagger into her own breast,and then handingit to him with the words, "SeePaetus, it does not hurt." Thrasea lived on terms <strong>of</strong>intimacy with the notabilities <strong>of</strong> Rome, attaching tohimself especially the more earnest spirits <strong>of</strong> the age,such as Musonius Rufus and Demetrius, and the poetH 2


lOOSTOICISM.Persius. Like Cato <strong>of</strong> Utica,to whose life he devotedcareful study, he tried to turn his moral theories togood account in public life, regarding the properorganization <strong>of</strong> the State as the primary condition <strong>of</strong> allmoral progress ;while the firstduty <strong>of</strong> the citizenconsisted in helping to reform the evil, and in raisingthe tone <strong>of</strong> social thought. But he was no strictmartinet, or gloomy pedant with an intellectualhorizon bounded by a narrow range <strong>of</strong> rules. Hewas very tender and considerate in word and deed,fearing even to speak out too sternly in his moraljudgments, lest he should seem not to hate the evilonly, but the evil-doers. They were hard timesindeed in which his lot was cast, and there was littlein the constitution <strong>of</strong> the State to satisfy his highideal or to help to raise men to a better life. Theworld seemed ruled, in Nero's person, not by itshighest, but its lowest thought ; passion, not reason,took the lead ;the senate only met to register theirmaster's whims, and bespatter with fulsome praise hisvilest acts. How was the moralist <strong>of</strong> l<strong>of</strong>ty standardto act with dignity on such a scene, and use theworld as not abusing it? His demeanour in thesenate-house was watched narrowly by friend and foe,and even in the distant provinces men turned overthe <strong>of</strong>ficial journals to see how itlong would bepossible for Thrasea to take part in public life andstill be true to himself and loyal to the State. Hisattitudeunder these trying circumstances was one <strong>of</strong>studied moderation, equallyfree from the extremes<strong>of</strong> flattery or bravado. When the senate-house was


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 10 1turned into a court<strong>of</strong> criminal justice, before whichpolitical <strong>of</strong>fenders were arraigned, he threw all hisinfluence into the scale <strong>of</strong> mercy, checkingas far aspossible the licence <strong>of</strong> the false informers, and theservile truckling <strong>of</strong> the judges to what they supposedto be the will <strong>of</strong> their Imperial master. But he carefullyabstained meanwhile from the bitterness <strong>of</strong>personal attacks or needless parade <strong>of</strong> independence,while he raised the tone <strong>of</strong> senatorial self-respect byhis quiet dignity <strong>of</strong> manner, which neither courteddangernor flinched from it. In the interests <strong>of</strong>humanity he raised his voice among them againstthe cruel usages <strong>of</strong> the gladiatorial shows, whichencouraged the worst instincts <strong>of</strong> a ferocious mob.Other voices after his took up the cry, and kindliersentiments were gradually fostered, to temper thehardness <strong>of</strong> the pagan world.Another time we fiindhim defending the privileges <strong>of</strong> the House and theindependence <strong>of</strong> the provincial rulers against thecorrupt influence <strong>of</strong> powerful intriguers in theprovinces, who pretended to make or mar the <strong>of</strong>ficialcareer <strong>of</strong> any statesman, and even to determine thecourse <strong>of</strong> proceedings in the senate. His owncharacter, indeed, stood high above the whisper <strong>of</strong>suspicion. When some complained in Nero's hearing<strong>of</strong> his decision as arbitrator in a the trial, emperorreplied with bitterness, " I wish I were as sure <strong>of</strong> hisaffection for me as I am <strong>of</strong> his perfect equity as judge."But the time came at last when he could no longerhope to check the servility <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>ficial classes,who vied with each other in the demonstrations <strong>of</strong>


I02STOICISM.their joy when Poppsea bore a son to Nero, and <strong>of</strong>their grief when the young child was hurried <strong>of</strong>f bydeath. Thrasea could not sitcalmly by when thanksgivingservices, temples, priesthoods, canonizationseven, were decreed. He had already left the senatehousein silence when the news <strong>of</strong> Agrippina's death,sent by the parricide himself, became the signal forpublic curses on her memory and compliments tothe Imperial assassin. But now he withdrew altogetherfrom <strong>of</strong>ficial life, when it was idle to resist byineffectual remonstrance, and when silence might beconstrued into assent.But his was too marked a figure to escape unnoticed,and the protest <strong>of</strong> his silent absence was a theme forevery tongue. The members <strong>of</strong> the civil service in theprovinces, the military circles in the camp, read overthe longlist <strong>of</strong> decrees and votes and acclamations tosee what it was in which Thrasea would take no part ;malevolent informers whispered into Nero's ears thatsuch a policy <strong>of</strong> abstention could not be trifled withmuch longer, that society was being parted into twogreat camps, and that as Caesar and Cato were <strong>of</strong> oldthe chiefs <strong>of</strong> rival parties, so the State was nowdivided between the adherents <strong>of</strong> Thrasea and <strong>of</strong>Nero. Yet the emperor still hesitated to pushmatters to extremes. For a time he soothed hisvanity by the public slight which he put on Thraseawhen he appeared before him in a deputation fromthe senate ;he gave him time even now to bend beforethe threatening storm, and to make his peace bysome show <strong>of</strong> submission.


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICISM. 103At last the expected letter came, but Thrasea hadnothing to retract or to excuse he; simply asked toknow what were the charges laid against him, and hewould then prove that he was not guilty <strong>of</strong> disloyaltyin word or deed. The emperor would wait nolonger now the bloodhounds were let loose; uponhim in the senate, and the cringing house was madeto sentence him to death, leaving him only the poorprivilege <strong>of</strong> choosing the means and form <strong>of</strong> execution.The description which Tacitus has left us <strong>of</strong> thelast hours which he spent on earth is one <strong>of</strong> themost striking <strong>of</strong> the great historian's pages. We seehim walking in his garden while a company <strong>of</strong> histrue-hearted friends, among the noblest <strong>of</strong> Rome'sworthies, was gathering round him and his doomwas still uncertain. At last the fatal message came,as he was talking with the sage Demetrius <strong>of</strong> thenature <strong>of</strong> the soul and its relations to its earthlyhome ;he calmly bade his friends withdraw that theymight, if possible, escape his fate ; Arria, his wife, waseager, like her mother, to share her husband's death,but he begged her to live on to watch over their only:daughter and when he heard that his son-in-lawHelvidius was not condemned to die with him heseemed to forget himself entirely in his pleasure atthe tidings. The young quaestor who brought thewarrant for his death was standing by, and Thraseasaid to him with kindly air that he hopedhis turnto suffer would not come, but in such evil days itwas well to be prepared, and to learn how quietly


I04STOICISM.a clear conscience could face death. Then as hisveins were opened the current <strong>of</strong> his talk flowedcalmly on, while he sprinkled the ground with theblood which was pouring from his veins, and said, "Letthat be my libation to Jupiter, the god <strong>of</strong> freedom."It was no wonder, surely, if a character like thatimpressed so deeply the imagination <strong>of</strong> the age ; few,certainly, <strong>of</strong> the great men <strong>of</strong> the Stoa harmonizedso perfectly the claims <strong>of</strong> theory and practice, and invery few indeed was there so close a union <strong>of</strong> thes<strong>of</strong>ter and the tenderer graces with all the dignity <strong>of</strong>perfect manhood.But the pattern <strong>of</strong> his patient moderation was notfollowed by his son-in-law Helvidius Prisons, whoescaped from Nero only to suffer under one <strong>of</strong> themost prudent <strong>of</strong> emperors, Vespasian. Whether hewas provoked to impatience by the death <strong>of</strong> Thrasea,or was <strong>of</strong> more irreconcilable temper, he certainlycriticised so hotly all the policy <strong>of</strong> government,and flaunted so needlessly his republican ideals, thatat last even Vespasian's forbearance failed him, andhe allowed his judgment to be overruled by hispowerful adviser, Mucianus, who insisted on thedanger <strong>of</strong> such constant opposition, and prevailed onhim at last to sign the death-warrant <strong>of</strong> Helvidius.It is true that this account must be received withsome reserve, for Dion Cassius and Suetonius, fromwhom it comes, are writers <strong>of</strong> an Imperialist bias andreflect the prejudices <strong>of</strong> the ruling classes ; theythrow the odium <strong>of</strong> the act indeed on Mucianus,but possibly exaggerate the provocation given by the


THE CRITICS AND ENEMIES OF STOICIS-M. 105contumacious bearing <strong>of</strong> Helvidius, <strong>of</strong> whom authors<strong>of</strong> higher character, hke Tacitus and the youngerPUny, speak with reverence and admiration. Howeverthat may be, Vespasian soon regretted the irrevocableact, but the opposition between the palace and theschool stilllingered on, and under the moody Domitianit led to another ban <strong>of</strong> exile for the philosophersin general, and to the death <strong>of</strong> Junius Rusticus,whom Thrasea had spoken <strong>of</strong> as a saint.But brighter days came in with Trajanand theAntonines. Freedom <strong>of</strong> thought and speculativestudies were not tolerated only, but encouraged ;special privileges were granted to the teachers, some<strong>of</strong> whom were treated with marked honour, andinvited to the court ;endowments even were createdand salaried pr<strong>of</strong>essors named, to represent thegreat historic systems <strong>of</strong> philosophy.At last <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong>itself mounted on the throne, and in the person <strong>of</strong>Marcus Antoninus seemed to realize the high ideal <strong>of</strong>the king-philosopher which Plato had dreamed <strong>of</strong>centuries before.


I06STOICISM.CHAPTER VIILTHE SOCIAL STATUS OF THE PROFESSIONAL MORALISTSAT ROME.We have seen that in the early Empire, through evilreport and good report, in persecution or the sunshine<strong>of</strong> court favour, the influence <strong>of</strong> philosophy was ohthe increase, and that <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> most <strong>of</strong> all. Somecourse <strong>of</strong> training in it was considered in good familiesas an almost necessary part <strong>of</strong> the education <strong>of</strong> theyoung.In the earlier days <strong>of</strong> the Republic a Romanyouth <strong>of</strong> talent attached himself to one <strong>of</strong> the greatspeakers <strong>of</strong> the day, followed him about from courtto court, watching every gesture and studying hisphrases, that he might fashion his own style on thefamiliar model, and learn in later life to emulate hisoratorical successes. But under the Imperial systemthe prizes <strong>of</strong> eloquence had ceased to dazzle, theschools <strong>of</strong> declamation grewwearisome to seriousminds, and graver spirits turned to some moralist orsage as to a spiritual director who might give themthe counsels <strong>of</strong> perfection. They were told emphaticallythat they could only hopeto rule their lifearight if they sought for guidance in such quarters." As exercise and medicine provide," says Plutarch,"for the body's health and strength, so philosophy


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.loyalone can cure the weakness or the sickness <strong>of</strong> thesoul.By her help man learns to distinguish the noblefrom the base, the just from the unjust, the thingsworthy <strong>of</strong> our choice from those which we shouldshun ;she teaches him how he ought to act in all therelations <strong>of</strong> his social life, warning him to fear thegods, honour his parents, respect old age, obey thelaws, submit to governors, be loving to his friends,show self-control with w^omankind, tenderness withchildren, moderation with his slaves— above all, notto triumph overmuch in prosperous days, or to be castdown in adversity, not to be overmastered by pleasure,or brutalized by passion." ^How they acted on such principles we see fromthe example <strong>of</strong> the youthful Persius, who describes forus in touching language the early relations that wereformed between himself and the celebrated Cornutus,whom he chose to be his -guide and friend.When first I laid the purple by, and free,Yet trembling at my new-felt liberty,Approach'd the hearth, and on the Lares hungThe bulla, from my willing neck unstrung ;When gay associates sporting at my side,And the white boss display'd with conscious pride,Gave me, uncheck'd, the haunts <strong>of</strong> vice to trace,And throw my wandering eyes on eveiy face,When life's perplexing maze before me lay,And error, heedless <strong>of</strong> the better way,To straggling paths, far from the route <strong>of</strong> truth,Woo'd with blind confidence my timorous youth.'De Educ. Puer., c. lo.^Persius. Gifford, v. 49.


1 08 STOICISM.I fled to you, Cornulus, pleased to restMy hopes and fears on your Socratic breast.Nor did you, gentle sage, the charge decline ;Then, dext'rous to beguile, your steady lineReclaim'd, I know not by what winning force.My morals, warp'd from nature's straighter course ;While reason press'd incumbent on my soul,That struggled to receive the strong control,And took like wax, temper'd by plastic skill,The form your hand imposed, and bears it still.Can I forget, how many a summer's day.Spent in your converse, stole unmark'd away ?Or how, while listening with increased delight,I snatched from feasts the earlier hours <strong>of</strong> night ?One time (for to your bosom —still I grew)One time <strong>of</strong> study and <strong>of</strong> rest we knew ;One frugal board where, every care resigned.An hour <strong>of</strong> blameless mirth relaxed the mind.And SO, too, we read in the next century <strong>of</strong> MarcusAntoninus, that his studies <strong>of</strong> philosophy began at avery tender age, when he caught up with eagerness,and pushed even to excess, the lessons <strong>of</strong> hardihoodand self-control. He tried to put his principles tothe test <strong>of</strong> practice, to live simply in the midst <strong>of</strong>luxury and licence, to content himself with frugalfare, and to take the bare groundfor his bed atnight. At last, it needed all his mother's gentle influenceto curb the enthusiasm <strong>of</strong> his ascetic humour.^He gave the <strong>Stoic</strong> Rusticus the credit <strong>of</strong> his conversionto philosophy :— " It was he who made me feelhow much I needed to reform and train my character.He warned me from the treacherous paths <strong>of</strong>'"Age <strong>of</strong> the Antonines," p. 28.J


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.IO9sophistry, from formal speeches <strong>of</strong> parade, which aimat nothing higher than applause. Thanks to him Iam weaned from rhetoric and poetry, from affectedelegance <strong>of</strong> style, and can write now with simplicity.From him I have learned to concentrate my thoughtson serious study, and not to be surprised into agreeingwith all the random utterances <strong>of</strong> fluent speech."In the description which Aulus Gellius gives us <strong>of</strong>his student life at Athens we have a pleasant picture<strong>of</strong> the close relations that existed between the teachersand the pupils, in the case at least <strong>of</strong> Taurus, thephilosopher,^ who was not content with formal lectures,^but did his best to form the character <strong>of</strong> his youngfriends by personal converse, chatting with them athis bedroom door when they walked home with himfrom lecture, travelling with them sometimes in thecountry, taking long walks to see them when he heardthat they were sick, and wiling away their wearinessby pleasant talk, in which the serious mingled withthe gay. If he asked his pupils to his table, he didnot care to tempt the appetite with costly viands, butthe simple fare <strong>of</strong> pudding or <strong>of</strong> salad was seasonedwith true Attic salt, and his guests were happier andwiser when they left him. He had a way <strong>of</strong> delicatelyhinting that a fault might be mended or bad habitdropped, which served its end while it spared hishearer's self-respect. Yet Taurus was no easy-goingteacher, with a standard easily attained. He liked totell his youthful friends the story <strong>of</strong> Euclides, who'"University Life at Athens," p. 48.


noSTOICISM.^ braved death to hear Socrates, his friend and guide,when it was penal for one <strong>of</strong> Megara to enter Athens ;whereas now-a-days, he said, philosophers must <strong>of</strong>tenwait till their pupils have recovered from the wineparty<strong>of</strong> the night before.We may gather from the same old writer that thepr<strong>of</strong>essors sometimes presumed a little on the privileges<strong>of</strong> their <strong>of</strong>fice, and pushed their rights <strong>of</strong> interferencesomewhat far, even with scholars <strong>of</strong> matureryears.^ Favorinus once was discoursing to his classwhen the message came that the wife <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> hisold pupils— a man <strong>of</strong> noble birth— had been just delivered<strong>of</strong> a son." Let us go," he said," to congratulatethe father." And <strong>of</strong>f he started with his train.They were ushered in together, and gave their complimentsand made inquiries for the mother's health.That done the pr<strong>of</strong>essor said, "Of course the ladywill suckle her own child." Her mother answeredthat she was not strong enough, but must have a wetnursefor the purpose ;but Favorinus was not satisfiedwith the excuse, and then and there delivered a longlecture on the subject, insisting on the natural duty,and on the danger <strong>of</strong> such artificial habits. His remarksare sensible enough, as they appear in thenotes which Aulus Gellius wrote out from memory,and they may serve at least to illustrate the wide rangewhich the moralist <strong>of</strong> those days gave to his rights orduties <strong>of</strong> personal supervision.Often they had no need to obtrude their counsels,^Aul. Gell., xii. I.


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.Illfor they were constantly consulted in the graver passages<strong>of</strong> lifeby men who knew not how to apply theirmoral principles, or were in doubt about a case <strong>of</strong>conscience. Even the frivolous and worldly, whohad long turned away from serious thought, knockedat their doors for consolation or advice in the darkerpassages <strong>of</strong> life. " Most men," says Dion Chrysostom," shrink from philosophers as from physicians ;as they will not buy drugs till they are sick, so theyrefuse the counsels <strong>of</strong> the moralist tillthey arewretched. A man is well-to-do, suppose, with a goodincome or a large estate, in sound health himself, hiswife and children well, his credit and reputationgood. He is too happy to give philosophy a thought.But let him lose his fortune or his health, he will bemore ready to listen then ;let his wife, or son, orbrother die, then he will send for the sage to comforthim, to teach him how to bear so much misfortune."But his figure is chiefly to be seen in the picturesdrawn for us <strong>of</strong> death-bed scenes, or when friends aregathering round the man on whom a prince haslooked with evil eye, and who has to face the thought<strong>of</strong> coming doom, or to escape life's evils by a voluntaryflight. One or more are always named in thedescriptions drawn by the master-hand <strong>of</strong> Tacitus,when a Plautus, or a Thrasea, or a Seneca is makingready for the last long journey. They were notthere, indeed, to shrive the penitent and <strong>of</strong>fer absolution,like the priest-confessor <strong>of</strong> a later age, but tostrengthen the tones <strong>of</strong> manly resignation, and whisperhopes <strong>of</strong> life beyond the grave. So customary was


112 STOICISM.the practice, that in the account <strong>of</strong> the last hours <strong>of</strong>Petronius we are told especially that the fastidiousworldling passed away, as he had lived, with frivolousepigrams upon his dying lips, and would not hear aword about the faith or aspirations <strong>of</strong> the wise.^Consistently enough, in the satirical romance whichhe had probably composed, Trimalchio, the vulgarupstart, gives directions to his servants that when histime draws near no ghostly counsels are to vex hispeace <strong>of</strong> mind, and no philosopher be admitted to hisdeath-bed.The lively interest in moral questions <strong>of</strong>ten led, aswe have seen, the earnest-minded to have constantresource to spiritual guides, to attach them even totheir persons, and to keep them for years together intheir homes. The fashion spread more widely than theactual need, till it became a recognised thing thatevery great mansion must have its pr<strong>of</strong>essionalmoralist, to be ready with a word in season when theconversation took a serious tone, and to give an air <strong>of</strong>proper dignity to the domestic life. But the relationmust have <strong>of</strong>ten been a trying one. A Cato with hisenthusiasm for wisdom might treat Athenodorus asan equal or superior ; Augustus was delicate enoughto treat Arius as a friend, and confide every thoughtto his discretion ;and so, perhaps, with many a generousnature the union was very close and tender,and even gained in strength as time wore on. Butthere was a coarseness in the moral fibre <strong>of</strong> theTac. " Annales," xvi. 19.


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.II3Roman, a want <strong>of</strong> refinementin the treatment <strong>of</strong> dependents,a dulness <strong>of</strong> intellectual sympathy whichmust have <strong>of</strong>ten made him in such cases a churlishand exacting patron.The Greeks, who were most at home in speculativequestions, were by national character, in that age atleast, too complaisant and suppleto maintain adignity or claim the respect which their position <strong>of</strong>tenfailed to give them. Some, indeed, stood enough upontheir merits, as when Apollonius came from Colchisat the invitation <strong>of</strong> the prince, to teach philosophyto the young Marcus Antoninus, but declined to callupon him when he came to Rome, saying thatthepupil should wait upon the master, not the masteron the pupil. Antoninus the Elder only laughed athis pretentiousness, and said that it was easier, asit seemed, to come all the way from Colchis thanto walk across the street at Rome.The Satires <strong>of</strong> Lucian give us quite another picture,in his descriptions <strong>of</strong> the domestic philosopherin Roman houses ;the colours, doubtless, are toocoarse, but the very vehemence <strong>of</strong> the openingpages <strong>of</strong> his treatise on the subject show us howbitterly the writer, himself a Greek, resented theinsults shown to liberal studies by the purse-proudpatrons in their treatment <strong>of</strong> men <strong>of</strong> education andrefinement.! " Weigh not only the trouble, but thebaseness, dishonour, and servility <strong>of</strong> such employments.For first, from the time you are enter-'Lucian. Translation <strong>of</strong> Jasper Mayne, p. 66.I


114 STOICISM.tained, you are to forget your liberty and parentage, and are to resolve when you enter into suchrelations to leave your descent, freedom, and ancestorsat the door— for liberty cannot have admissionwith you who are received into such lowand ungenerous employment. A servant, therefore,however you are troubled at the name, a servantyou are necessarily to be, not <strong>of</strong> one, but many,and are to wait uncovered from morning to nightfor contemptible wages. Besides, not being bred <strong>of</strong>a child to service, but comingto the trade late andwell-stricken in years, you will hardly pleaseor bemuch valued by your master. . . Because you have alarge beard, and are <strong>of</strong> a venerable aspect, and weara decent Greek mantle, and all men know you tobe a grammarian, or orator, or philosopher, hethinks it is for his reputation to minglewith those who go before him, to gracesuch a oneand setout his train. And from hence he gains the opinion<strong>of</strong> a patron <strong>of</strong> the Greek arts and <strong>of</strong> a friend tolearning, so that you are not hired for excellency<strong>of</strong> parts, or discourse, but for your beard and gown,and, therefore, are always to be seen in his company,and never to be from him, but are to riseearly every morning to present yourself, and appearin your attendance. He sometimes laying his handupon you prates anything by chance, and makesshow to those he meets that in passage through thestreets he forgets not the Muses, but employs thesmall leisure <strong>of</strong> his walk in honest conferences :whilst you most wretchedly, sometimes going apace,


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.II5sometimes s<strong>of</strong>tly, sometimes up, sometimes down(for such you know are the passages <strong>of</strong> the city),sweat, and put yourself out <strong>of</strong> breath. x\t lengthhe strikes into a house, to talk with some friendwhom he wants to visit, when, for want <strong>of</strong> a place tosit down, you are fain to read a book to pass awaythe time. After this, having neither eaten nor drunkthat day, discommodiously washed, and at an unseasonablehour, about midnight, perhaps, you go tosupper, and are no longer reverenced or regarded bythe rest. But if there be a new-comer you are setbelow him, and thrust into some obscure corner,where you sit as a spectator only <strong>of</strong> what isbrought totable, and like a dog gnaw the bones which descendto you, or, out <strong>of</strong> hunger, suck some withered saladrefused by those who sit above youIf at any time a pig be cut up, or a venison pasty,you had need have the carver your friend, or you willdivide with Prometheus, and nothing but bones willcome to your shareAfter a long time, at the Feast <strong>of</strong> Saturn, perchance,or Minerva, if some threadbare cloak or moth-eatengarment be sent you, you must receive it as a greatpresent.. . .Next, your whole pension comesnot to above six crowns, which ifyou demand you arethought impudent and troublesome, and thereforebefore you can receive it you must insinuate andflatter, and court the steward, which is one step <strong>of</strong>servitude more; nor is he to be neglected, who isyour patron's friend and <strong>of</strong> his counselsPerhaps the carriage <strong>of</strong> the man is to be borne with ;I 2


1 1 6 STOICISM.but then the women affect, too, to have learned menin pay, who shall attend on their sedans, and theythink nothing conduceth so much to their otherAndbravery and pomp as to be called learned philosophersand better makers <strong>of</strong> verses than Sappho.for the raising <strong>of</strong> such an opinion they are accompaniedby pensionary rhetoricians, grammarians andphilosophers, who most ridiculously read to them,either while they are dressing themselves or curlingtheir hair, or at meal-time, for at other times they arenot at leisure. Sometimes while the philosopher isin the midst <strong>of</strong> his discourse, the chambermaid entersand delivers a letter to her lady from her lover,whereupon the sermon must break <strong>of</strong>f till she havewritten an answer and can return to her lecture. . .I'll tellyou a passage which Thesmopolia, the<strong>Stoic</strong>, told me <strong>of</strong> himself, very ridiculous but not incredible,or such as may not happen to any other.He lived with a wealthy, delicate, proud lady inthe city, who had occasion to take a journey where;he said, the firstcontemptible accident he sufferedwas, being a philosopher, to sit next in the coach toher page, whose name was Chelidonius (or Swallow).Judge you what a sight it was for a severe, grave,ancient man, with a white beard, to be placed next toan effeminate boy, whose eyeswere painted and lasciviouslyrolled in his head, and his neck wantonlybent to one side, who more deserved to be calledVulture, for his naked chin, than Swallow. Innumerable,he said, were the disturbances whichhe suffered from the page, who all the way sung


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME. 117and prattled, and if he had not restrained himwould have danced in the coach. He told me also<strong>of</strong> a certain charge laid upon him by the lady,'who calling to him, Thesmopolis,' quoth she,'ifyou love me you must not deny me a favourwhich I shall ask <strong>of</strong> you.' He, as it was fit, promisedto obey her request.'Then,' quoth she, ' I pray,because I take you to be an honest, careful, goodnaturedman, take my little bitch, Myrrhina, into thecoach and keep her for me, and see she lacks nothing,for she isvery big with puppies, and is even ready towhelp, and my other servants are such knaves thatupon the way they have neither care <strong>of</strong> her, nor, indeed,<strong>of</strong> me.' Thesmopolis, at her earnest entreaty,received the bitch. Here, then, was a spectacle mostridiculous to see. A littledog peeping under hisgown, just below his beard, and barking in a smallvoice (for such dogs are most in fashion), and lickingthe crumbs which stuck upon the philosopher's chin.The page, who sat next him, having, not unwittily,at supper played upon others <strong>of</strong> the company,broke a jest upon ThesmopoHs.'at lastAll I can say,'quoth he, ' <strong>of</strong> ThesmopoHs is only this, that <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Stoic</strong>,he is become a Cynic, for I heard when the littlebitch pupped in his gown.' These are the mockeries,or rather the affronts, which they fasten upon thosewho live with them, rendering them bylittle and littletame and patient <strong>of</strong> contemptsMany who have been cast upon that course <strong>of</strong> lifehave made descriptions to me ;some while they yetfelt the thraldom, deploring the many and great indig-


1 1 8 STOICISM.nities they endured ;others as if theyhad brokenprison, recounting with some pleasure what theyhadsuffered, much rejoicing to repeat the mischiefs theyhad escaped."An EngUsh reader <strong>of</strong> Lucian's lively satires mayrecall perhaps to memory a parallel in an age farnearer to our own." In the mansions <strong>of</strong> men <strong>of</strong> liberal sentiments andcultivated understandings," writes Macaulay, <strong>of</strong> the"end <strong>of</strong> the seventeenth century, the chaplain doubtlesswas treated with urbanity and kindness. Butthis was not the general feeling <strong>of</strong> the country gentlemen.The coarse and ignorant squire, who thoughtthat itbelonged to his dignity to have grace said everyday at his table by an ecclesiastic in full canonicals,found means to reconcile dignity with economy. Ayoung Levite — such was the phrase then in use —might be had for his board, a small garret, and tenpounds a year, and might not only perform his pr<strong>of</strong>essionalfunctions, might not only be the most patient<strong>of</strong> butts and <strong>of</strong> listeners, might not only be alwaysready in fine weather for bowls, and in rainy weatherfor shovelboard, but might also save the expense <strong>of</strong> agardener or <strong>of</strong> a groom. Sometimes the reverendman nailed up the apricots, and sometimes he curriedthe coach-horses. He cast up the farrier's bills. Hewalked ten miles with a message or a parcel. If heHewas permitted to dine with the family, he was expectedto content himself with the plainest fare.might fill himself with the corned beef and the carrots;but as soon as the tarts and cheesecakes made their


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME.I19appearance, he quitted his seat, and stood alo<strong>of</strong> tillhe was summoned to return thanks for the repast,from a great part <strong>of</strong> which he had been excluded.The nature <strong>of</strong> the matrimonial connections which theclergymen <strong>of</strong> that age were in the habit <strong>of</strong> formingisthe most certain indication <strong>of</strong> the place which theorder held in the social system. A waiting-maid wasgenerally considered as the most suitable helpmatefor a parson. During several generations the relationsbetween priests and handmaidens were a theme forendless jest; nor would it be easy to find, in thecomedy <strong>of</strong> the seventeenth century, a single instance<strong>of</strong> a clergyman who wins a spouse above the rank <strong>of</strong>a cook.iBut there is evidence enough that many <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>essionalmoralists at Rome enjoyed a reputation fartoo high to be exposed to so contumelious a treatmentas that which Lucian pictures. Such was MusoniusRufus, for example, who moved with perfect dignityin the highest social circles, won the respect <strong>of</strong> allwho heard him lecture, and left affectionate memoriesin the minds <strong>of</strong> men <strong>of</strong> different type, like Epictetusand the younger Pliny. So commanding was his influenceover the young nobles <strong>of</strong> his time, that Nero,whose jealous fears were roused, resolved to silencehis persuasive voice. As no charges <strong>of</strong> disloyaltycould be made good againsthim, after months spentin prison, he was banished to the bare rocks <strong>of</strong> Gyara,where it was thought he would at least be harmless.'Macaulay, Hist. i. 327.


I20STOICISM.But his fame brought so many a visitor from Greece,that the tyrant's fears again were stirred, and Musoniuswas himself hurried <strong>of</strong>f, Hke a convict sentenced tohard labour, to work at thecanal by which Nero hadresolved that the Isthmus <strong>of</strong> Corinth should be pierced.Demetrius found him there among the workmen, andCynic as he was, could not restrain an exclamation <strong>of</strong>surprise. Musonius only struck his spade deeper intothe ground, and asked him why he should be grievedto see him toiling for the good <strong>of</strong> Greece, and if itwas not a less painful sightemperor playing like a common piper.?than that <strong>of</strong> a RomanOnce, indeed,his moral influence and prudence seemed to fail him,overbalanced by excess <strong>of</strong> zeal. In the civil warsthat followed close on Nero's fall, when the legions <strong>of</strong>Vespasian were knocking at the gates<strong>of</strong> Rome andthe frightened senators sent envoys to the camp toplead for mercy, Musonius joined them on the mission,trusting overmuch to the eloquence <strong>of</strong> his own winningwords. But the rough soldiery was in no moodto listen to the rounded periods <strong>of</strong> the man <strong>of</strong> peace.He only met with ridicule and insult, which wouldhave soon passed on to blows if he had not hurriedfrom the camp, where the clash <strong>of</strong> arms drowned allappeals to reason.But the voice <strong>of</strong> Musonius was more persuasiveindealing with a different class. It was one <strong>of</strong> hisfavourite theses for discussion that both sexes alikeshould pr<strong>of</strong>it by the lessons <strong>of</strong> philosophy, and itwould seem that many <strong>of</strong> the women <strong>of</strong> his time werenot slow to take advantage <strong>of</strong> the invitation. This


1PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME. 121naturally leads our thoughts to one <strong>of</strong> the brightestfeatures <strong>of</strong> the age, which may rank also among thefairest fruits <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> at Rome. In the hotbed <strong>of</strong>Imperial license there had been indeed a portentousgrowth <strong>of</strong> female shamelessness and lust. Many abad woman, like Messalina, had flaunted in thepeople's sight her orgies <strong>of</strong> extravagance and crime,and with such examples in high places there wasdanger that vice would cease to pay the homage <strong>of</strong>hypocrisy to virtue. But now, as by natural reaction,and with the spread <strong>of</strong> philosophic teaching, thereappears suddenly upon the scene another and a higherstandard <strong>of</strong> true womanhood.The matrons <strong>of</strong> the early days <strong>of</strong> the Republicwere expected to be grave, decorous figures ; theystayed at home and spun their wool, as the old epitaphexpresses it,and controlled the household labours <strong>of</strong>theirhandmaids, but they could not share their husband'shigher thoughts, or enliven his leisure withrefinement.In Cicero's time they were <strong>of</strong>ten more accomplished,and took a more brilliant part in public life, but withthe freer culture there was also spreading a laxer tone<strong>of</strong> thought, and graver scandals to the moral sense.But the leaven <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> soon began to work amongthe social circles <strong>of</strong> the capital its ; principles <strong>of</strong> selfrestraintand order were congenial to the better type<strong>of</strong> Roman character, and gradually passed from thestreets and lecture-rooms to the quiet retirement <strong>of</strong>home life, where without respect <strong>of</strong> persons they struckupon the chords <strong>of</strong> deeper thoughts,and furnished


122 STOICISM.Strength and solace in the darkest hours <strong>of</strong> absoluterule.The "Annals" <strong>of</strong> Tacitus are <strong>of</strong>ten sombre and depressing,but there is many a bright and stirring pagein which we read <strong>of</strong> a long line <strong>of</strong> noble women whosememory does honour to the early Empire. Such werethe two heroines <strong>of</strong> the name <strong>of</strong> Arria, each wife to adistinguished Paetus, with Fannia the daughter <strong>of</strong> theyounger such was the domestic circle in which;Persius grew up to manhood such was the 3 youngwife <strong>of</strong> Seneca, and many another taughtin familiarintercourse to understand the theory and the practice<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> morals, who vied with their husbands inthe hardihood <strong>of</strong> patient resolution, and temperedtheir vigorous principles with s<strong>of</strong>ter graces.We have seen already that the relation betweenthe domestic moralists and those who retained theirservices could not be maintained always at itsproperlevel. The pr<strong>of</strong>essional teacher had his dangers alsoand temptations, as had the hearers who resorted tohis lectures. The former was tempted to forget thel<strong>of</strong>ty aims <strong>of</strong> the philosopher, and to sink into theSophist or the Rhetorician. He might think more,that is,<strong>of</strong> the form than the matter <strong>of</strong> his lectures ;lay too much stress on the graces <strong>of</strong> styleand themodulations <strong>of</strong> the voice and elegancies <strong>of</strong> gesture ;try to win the admiration <strong>of</strong> his audience, not keepingsteadily in view the one thing needful^ which shouldbe— to instruct and to reform.The hearers, on their side, <strong>of</strong>ten came as to a lecture<strong>of</strong> parade to criticise the speaker's skill, or wile away


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME. 1 23a vacant hour, or to gather a few fine passages forlater use, but with littlethought to take seriously toheart the lessons which they heard, and turn them togood account in the conduct <strong>of</strong> their lives. Musoniusand others dwelt, as we are told, with emphaticearnestness upon this frivolity <strong>of</strong> purpose, speakingwithauthority aspreachers <strong>of</strong> righteousness themselves,and complaining like the great religious orators <strong>of</strong> everyage that the influence <strong>of</strong> their words was evanescenton the weak and unconverted conscience. Epictetusspeaks in his own homely way <strong>of</strong> the faults whichwere so common, then as since, with both the teachersand their scholars.^" Rufus was used to say, If youhave leisure to praise me, I am speaking to no purpose.Accordingly, he used to speak in such a waythat every one <strong>of</strong> us who was sitting there supposedthat some one had accused him before Rufus ;he sotouched on what was doing, he so placed beforetheeyes every man's faults. The philosopher's school,ye men, is a surgery ; you ought not to go out <strong>of</strong> itwith pleasure, but with pain. For you are not insound health when you enter ;one has dislocated hisshoulder, another has an abscess, a third a fistula, anda fourth a head-ache. Then do I sit and utter to youlittle thoughts and exclamations that you may praiseme and go away, one with his shoulder in the samecondition in which he entered, another with hisheadstill aching, and a third with his fistula or his abscessjust as they were ? Is it for this, then, that young'Epictetus, iii. 23. Long's translation.


124 STOICISM.men shall quit home and leave their parentsfriends and kinsmen and property, thatand theirthey may sayto you, 'Wonderful!' when you are uttering yourexclamations ? Did Socrates do this, or Zenon, orCleanthes ? What then ? is there not the hortatorystyle ? Who denies it ? as there is the style<strong>of</strong> refutation,and the didactic style. Who, then, everreckoned a fourth style with these— the style <strong>of</strong> display? What is the hortatory style ? To be able toshow both to one person and to many the struggle inwhich they are engaged, and that they think moreabout anything than about what they really wish.For they wish the things that lead to happiness, butthey look for them in the wrong place.In order thatthis may be done, a thousand seats must be placed,and men must be invited to listen, and you mustascend the pulpit in a fine robe or cloak and describethe death <strong>of</strong> Achilles. Cease, I entreat you by thegods, to spoil good words and good acts as much asyou can. Nothing can have more power in exhortationthan when the speaker shows to the hearers thathe has need <strong>of</strong> them. But tell me who, when hehears you reading or discoursing, is anxious abouthimself, or turns to reflect on himself? or when hehas gone out, says, ' The philosopher hit me well ;Imust no longer do these things.' But does he not,even ifyou have a great reputation, say to someperson, He ' spoke finely about Xerxes ;'and anothersays, ' No;but about the battle <strong>of</strong> ?'Thermopylce Isthis listening to a philosopher ?"There were, however, worse abuses than the poor


PROFESSIONAL MORALISTS AT ROME. 125vanity <strong>of</strong> the public speaker who forgot awhile thegraver interests committed to his chargein the wishto dazzle those who heard him. The dialectic subtletyand the pedantry <strong>of</strong> logical parade which weresometimes encouraged in the <strong>Stoic</strong> schools had adangerous effect upon unbalanced minds, which, onthe strength <strong>of</strong> a few sophistic puzzles and sometechnicalities <strong>of</strong> mood and figure, thrust themselvesforward in the assurance <strong>of</strong> half-educated pride. Onesuch Aulus Gellius describes at length as dogmatisingmost <strong>of</strong>fensively in the cultivated circle which wasgathered in the hospitable seat <strong>of</strong> Herodes Atticus,at Cephissia. The braggart paraded his glib phrasesand pretensions <strong>of</strong> omniscience in language bristlingwith the terms <strong>of</strong> logic ;but at last, to the relief <strong>of</strong>all concerned, he was silenced by their host, who hadthe Table-talk <strong>of</strong> Epictetus brought to him, and readan appropriate passage, which distinguished in causticstyle the features <strong>of</strong> the true student and <strong>of</strong> the falsepretender to philosophy.^We have already spoken <strong>of</strong> the Cynic vagrants whodonned the sage's mantle and <strong>of</strong>ten in their coarseeffrontery dragged high pr<strong>of</strong>essions through the mud.One such we read <strong>of</strong> as pushing rudely in among thefriends who were on a visit to Herodes, demandingalms <strong>of</strong> right, and grumbling because he was not recognisedas a compeer. "A beard and staff, indeed, Isee," was the"retort ; but no philosopher."Such abuses were apparent on the surface, and'Aulus Gellius, i. 2.


126 STOICISM.there were, no doubt, false prophets and pretendedseekers after wisdom, but their existence testifies tothe wide-spread interest in moral studies, and to theunfeigned desire on the part <strong>of</strong> very many to find arule <strong>of</strong> life,and listen to any preacher who seemedto have a message for his fellow-men. Among themthere were many, doubtless, like Demonax, whomLucian, satirist as he was, described in the most enthusiasticterms, as irreproachable in private life,simple in manners, winning in his words, consummatein his knowledge, and while incliningto the <strong>Stoic</strong>system, yet so full <strong>of</strong> tenderness and sympathy as toseem to take in the whole <strong>of</strong> the human race in hisaffection.The Athenians, among whom he lived, felt so muchveneration for him that when he passed by, eventhemagistrates rose up to do him honour ;and in hislater years he made his home each night in any housewhere he happened to go in, and the inmates gladlywelcomed him as though some good genius hadhonoured them with his presence. When he died hewas buried by the Slate with every honour, and thestone seat where it had been his wont to sit wascrowned with flowers, and regarded as a holy placefor time to come.


STOICISM. 127CHAPTER IX.THE CAREER OF SENECA.The life and influence <strong>of</strong> Seneca fill so large a placein the history <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> at Rome, that we may findat someit <strong>of</strong> advantage to dwell upon these topicslength, for they will serve to bring before us and toillustrate several <strong>of</strong> the leading questions connectedwith the spread <strong>of</strong> philosophy among the highersocial circles, and the practical value <strong>of</strong> the doctrines<strong>of</strong> the Porch. We shall have before us one who wasno pr<strong>of</strong>essional moralist, but a scholar and a statesman;familiar with the world <strong>of</strong> fashion, endeavouringnot only to shape his life by the <strong>Stoic</strong> rule, but tohelp others as a sort <strong>of</strong> spiritual director, too wide inhis intellectual sympathiesto be content with therigid monotony <strong>of</strong> Zenon's paradoxes, and also it mustbe owned too weak in moral fibre to escape somecompromise <strong>of</strong> principle and honour ; straining aftera high ideal which he confesses that he is very farfrom having reached, and tempering the hard formalism<strong>of</strong> his school with tones <strong>of</strong> tenderness andsympathy, and with the language <strong>of</strong> a religious feelingwhich rises at times almost to a Christian level, thoughits real spirit is essentially cold and self-contained,and alien to the graces <strong>of</strong> the Gospel. No Roman


128 STOICISM.moralist has been so widely read, none perhaps hasbeen so variously judged, both in ancient and inmodern times. Criticism has fastened keenly on allthe seeming inconsistencies <strong>of</strong> theory and practice,and the real merits <strong>of</strong> the writer's style and thoughthave been decried because <strong>of</strong> his shortcomings as amoral agent. Some have been so struck by hisreligious phrases as to regard him, with the Latinfathers, as almost a Christian in disguise while ; others,like Diderot, with a very different bias, have pointedto the elevation <strong>of</strong> his moral standard as a pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>the powers <strong>of</strong> the unassisted reason.To many English readers Seneca isonly knownthrough the brilliant rhetoric <strong>of</strong> Macaulay, whichshowed littlemercy to his private character, while itridiculed his efforts as a moral teacher. Some <strong>of</strong> thecriticisms in question may be conveniently quotedhere:— "The ancient philosophy disdained to beuseful, and was content to be stationary. It dealtin theories <strong>of</strong> moral perfection, which were so sublimethat they never could be more than theories ;inattempts to solve insoluble enigmas ;in exhortationsto the attainment <strong>of</strong> unattainable frames <strong>of</strong> mind.It could not condescend to the humble <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong>ministering to the comfort <strong>of</strong> human beings. . . .'In my own time,' says Seneca, 'there have been inventions<strong>of</strong> this sort, transparent windows, tubes fordiffusing warmth equally through all parts <strong>of</strong> a building,shorthand which has been carried to such aperfection that a writer can keep pace with the mostrapid speaker. But the inventing <strong>of</strong> such things is


THE CAREER OF SENECA. 129drudgery for the lowest slaves, philosophy lies deeper.It is not her <strong>of</strong>fice to teach men how to use theirhands. The object <strong>of</strong> her lessons is to form thesoul. . . . We shall next be told,' exclaims Seneca,'that the first shoemaker was a philosopher.' For ourown part if we are forced to make our choice betweenthe first shoemaker and the author <strong>of</strong> the three bookson Anger, we pronounce for the shoemaker. Itmaybe worse to be angry than to be wet. But shoeshave kept millions from being wet, and we doubtwhether Seneca ever kept anybody from being angry.... It isvery reluctantly that Seneca can bebrought to confess that any philosopher had everpaid the smallest attention to anything that couldpossibly promote what vulgar people would consideras the well-being <strong>of</strong> mankind. . . . He is forced toown that such a thing might happen, and itmayalso happen, he tells us, that a philosopher may beswift <strong>of</strong> foot. But it is not in his character <strong>of</strong> philosopherthat he either wins a race or invents a machine.No, to be sure. The business <strong>of</strong> a philosopher wasto declaim in praise <strong>of</strong> poverty with two millionssterling out at usury ;to meditate epigrammaticconceits about the evils <strong>of</strong> luxury, in gardens whichmoved the envy <strong>of</strong> sovereigns ;to rant about liberty,while fawning on the insolent and pampered freedmen<strong>of</strong> a tyrant ;to celebrate the divine beauty <strong>of</strong> virtuewith the same pen which had just before written adefence <strong>of</strong> the murder <strong>of</strong> a mother by a son."iThe closing lines do little more than reproduce1Macaulay," Essay on Bacon."R


130 STOICISM.the invectives <strong>of</strong> a rancorous opponent, asuttered inthe crisis <strong>of</strong> a personal struggle. But Tacitus, whosedramatic pen records them,i speaks himself <strong>of</strong> Senecain terms <strong>of</strong> marked respect, and his authorityoutweighs that <strong>of</strong> the later writers, such as DionCassius, who have stained their pages with the foulestscandals. To estimate the justice <strong>of</strong> such chargeswe require to have before us some general sketch <strong>of</strong>his career.Seneca came <strong>of</strong> a Spanish family <strong>of</strong> ample means,but was brought in early years from Cordova to Rome.His father, a noted rhetorician in his day, had hisson trained in his favourite studies, and gave perhapsa bias to the style, which <strong>of</strong>fended the taste <strong>of</strong> latterpurists like Quintilian. But before long his mindwas deeply stirred by the grave questions <strong>of</strong> philosophywhich he heard discussed by lecturers <strong>of</strong> variousschools, and he threw himself with youthful ardour intoausterities <strong>of</strong> ascetic practice which were iUsuited tohis feeble constitution, till it needed all his father'sinfluence to make him relax the rigour <strong>of</strong> his vegetarianrule. The names and tenets <strong>of</strong> his earlyteachers constantly recur, even in his latest writings,and though among them the prevailing tone was<strong>Stoic</strong>, yet other systems found exponents, to givemore width and freedom to his thought. A fewpassages from his works may serve not only to explainthe nature <strong>of</strong> his education, but also to throw lighton the state <strong>of</strong> philosophic studies in the Romancircles <strong>of</strong> the day.^Tacitus, " Annales," xiii. 42.


THE CAREER OF SENECA.I31It was the school <strong>of</strong> Sextius which was thenand the noble Roman from whom itespeciallyin vogue,took its name seems to have aimed at giving ascientific basis, combined with a slight Eastern tinge<strong>of</strong> mysticism, to the austerer qualities <strong>of</strong> the oldnational "character. A work <strong>of</strong> Q. Sextius the fatherwas read to us," says Seneca," a great man, believe me,and a <strong>Stoic</strong>, though he would not own it. Whatvigour and spirit there were in him, and that is morethan you will always find in the philosophers. . . .After reading him you will say,' There is life, and fire,and freedom in him, he seems to rise above thehuman level, and leaves me full <strong>of</strong> high self-confidence.Whatever mood I may be in when I take up hisI own that I long to brave all hazards, I amwritings,ready to cry out, ' Why dost thou loiter, fortune, tryyour strength upon me, you will find me quiteprepared.' I long for hardships to encounter, to testmy powers <strong>of</strong> endurance. For Sextius has thisstriking merit also, that while he makes you feel howgreat the prize <strong>of</strong> a happy life must be, he does notcause you to despair <strong>of</strong> gaining it, you will be assuredthat it ishigh above you, but still within your reachifyou will have it."iBut Seneca refers more <strong>of</strong>ten to the younger Sextiuswho extended his father's influence, and laid stresson two <strong>of</strong> the Pythagorean tenets, that <strong>of</strong> frequentself-examination, and <strong>of</strong> vegetarian diet. The latterpoint was especially insisted on by Sotion <strong>of</strong> Alexandria,who took a high place among the» " Epist." 64.K 2teachers <strong>of</strong>


132 STOICISM.this school, and Seneca speaks thus from personal"<strong>of</strong> his lectures. Sotion used to explain tomemoryus the reasons which led Pythagoras to abstainfrom animal food, and why Sextius did the same inlater times. Their motives were different, but didthem equal credit. The latter thoughtcould find food enough without resortingthat manto theblood <strong>of</strong> life, and that he learnt to practise crueltyby making murder minister to his pleasures. Weought, he said moreover, to cut short all that tendsto pamper us. He argued that a varied diet isprejudicial to good health, and ill-suited to our constitution.Pythagoras maintained that all livingbeings were akin, and that their souls passed by freeinterchange from one form to another. If he is tobe trusted, no soul dies altogether, nor is its lifesuspended for more than a brief moment, while themetamorphosis is taking place. After Sotion hadexplained these views and pressed them home withfurther arguments, he said, 'Great men have heldthese sentiments, therefore suspend your judgmentand reserve the right <strong>of</strong> embracing them yourself.If they are true,a law <strong>of</strong> nature ; if not,the abstinence from animal food isit is at least a measure <strong>of</strong>economy. ... I was strongly influenced by suchlanguage and began to abstain myself, and after ayear's trial I found the practice not only easy, butagreeable. My mental powers seemed to gain invigour, and to this day I am not sure that they didnot. You may wonder why I dropped the practice.My early life fell in the years when Tiberius was


THE CAREER OF SENECA.I33prince, at the time when certain foreignrites wereput under a ban, and among the supposed evidences<strong>of</strong> their superstition was the abstinence from theflesh <strong>of</strong> certain animals. My father, who had moredishke for philosophy than actual fear <strong>of</strong> the informers,begged me to be careful, so I returned to my formerhabits as to diet." ^There was also a famous pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>school whose lectures Seneca attended, and whosecharacteristic features he"describes. For my part,as <strong>of</strong>ten as I heard Attains enlarging on the vices andmiseries <strong>of</strong> life, I felt pity for mankind, and lookedon him as a superior being raised above the commonlevel <strong>of</strong> humanity. When he began to praise poverty,and to set himself to prove that everything whichwent beyondirksome burden, I leftour actual wants was a needless andhis lecture-room with the wishthat I was poor. After he had criticised our selfindulgence,praising chastity, sobriety,pure from the taint <strong>of</strong> superfluousand a mindas well as illicitpleasures, I desired to curtail all the enjoyments <strong>of</strong>the table. Some <strong>of</strong> this influence has clung to methrough life at; first, indeed, I threw myself withardour into all his rules, but the fashion <strong>of</strong> the worlddrew me away and Ihabits."retained only a few <strong>of</strong> my goodSeneca goes on to notice some <strong>of</strong> the costlierviands and luxurious ways <strong>of</strong> common life which he hadsucceeded in renouncing to the end, such, for example,as oysters, unguents, wine, and the use <strong>of</strong> baths. ^To these teachers we may add the name <strong>of</strong> Papirius»Ep. 108, ^ Ep. 108.


134 STOICISM.Fabianus, who also denounced with energy the vices<strong>of</strong> the age, not deaHng much with abstract thought,but giving a rhetorical expression to the doctrines <strong>of</strong>the Porch. Seneca devotes a whole letter to thecriticism <strong>of</strong> his style, but lays no stress on anyspecial tenets on which he may have heard him dwell.^After some time spent in the lecture-rooms <strong>of</strong> thesephilosophers, he chose the Bar for his pr<strong>of</strong>ession, atwhich he soon made himself a name, pleading sobrilliantly on one occasion before the EmperorCaligula, that the mad despot was moved to murderousenvy, but listened happily to the suggestion that theyoung lawyer seemed far gone in a decline, and thatit was surely needless to cut short a life w^hichhung already on so frail a thread. From that timeSeneca became a marked figure in the world <strong>of</strong>fashion, but in those days <strong>of</strong> absolute rule, dangerfollowed closely on the steps <strong>of</strong> all who rose to highestate.The Imperial household was not large enough tohold in peacethe wife and sister <strong>of</strong> the dotardClaudius, but the former ere longsucceeded in destroyingthe influence and reputation <strong>of</strong> her rival,who was driven with tarnished honour from the court,while Seneca was denounced as the partner <strong>of</strong> Julia'sshame, and hurried <strong>of</strong>f to Corsica to spend eightyears in exile. The charge came with an illgracefrom the pr<strong>of</strong>ligate Messalina, who only cared tocompass the destruction <strong>of</strong> her rival, and such wasthe mockery <strong>of</strong> justice under Claudius that the'Ep. loo.


THE CAREER OF SENECA.I35emperor's sentence on the accused carries little orno presumption <strong>of</strong> their guilt.At most, perhaps,we may infer that the successful lawyer movedin the highest circles <strong>of</strong> the capital, and seemedto careless eyes to live more as a worldling than astudious ascetic. The blow was a very heavy oneto bear, and may wellhave overtasked his powers <strong>of</strong>resignation. He could find, indeed, topics <strong>of</strong> consolation,such as those he urges in his letter to hismother Helvia, but there issomething strained andartificial in the phrases, which lack the ring <strong>of</strong> genuineconviction ;he sadly owns that he is very far frombeing perfect, and the lessons <strong>of</strong> the sages had hardlypower to cheer him in the hardships and monotony<strong>of</strong> these long years <strong>of</strong> forced inaction. His spiritmust have been much broken before he penned hisletter to Polybius, the confidential minister <strong>of</strong> Claudius,in which master and servant are alike addressed interms <strong>of</strong> extravagant and cringing adulation. Of theformer he speaks as if he weare a very Solomon uponthe seat <strong>of</strong> justice, or a Titan supporting on his wearyshoulders the burden <strong>of</strong> a subject world ; yet a fewmonths later he insults his memory with savage ironyin the merciless burlesque where he describes theappearance <strong>of</strong> the late emperor among the realms<strong>of</strong> spirits, to which he was pursued with the cursesand the scorn both <strong>of</strong> the living and the dead.^Dion Cassius does not fail to notice the mean flatteryto which Seneca stooped on this occasion, but hetells us also that the letter had been lost before his^Seneca, Ludus de morte Claudii.


136 STOICISM.time, and the scholar Lipsius therefore thought itpossible, and Diderot held it to be almost certain, thatthe fragment which bears the title in his works was alater forgery <strong>of</strong> some malignant critic, who has pushedthe language <strong>of</strong> servility so far as to make it read tous like overt satire. We would gladly wish it werenot genuine, but unhappily there can be little doubtthat the letter written was unworthy, whether we havethe original or not before us.At length the fall <strong>of</strong> Messalina brought hopes <strong>of</strong>freedom to the exile. Her successor, Agrippina, soonhad him recalled, wishing, says Tacitus, to do an act<strong>of</strong> grace to one who stood so high in popular esteem,and whose gratitude might be <strong>of</strong> service to her in thefuture.She entrusted even to his care her young sonNero, though with the ominous condition that he wasnot to learn philosophy, as if its lessons could have noserious value for a future ruler. When Claudius diedsoon after and Nero stepped upon the vacant throne,Seneca became his chief adviser, or rather sharedwith Burrus, the commander <strong>of</strong> the household troops,the main moving force <strong>of</strong> the new ministry. Thefirst five years <strong>of</strong> Nero's reignwere afterwards regardedas one <strong>of</strong> the brightest epochs <strong>of</strong> Imperialrule, and the actual regents may fairly have thecredit <strong>of</strong> the good government which they secured.But Seneca's eye had soon discerned the latentferocity <strong>of</strong> Nero's temper, which was not to be charmedaway by edifying treatises like those which he addressedto him "On Anger" and "On Clemency," themoral influence <strong>of</strong> which was sadly marred by the


THE CAREER OF SENECA. 137hints which fell on willing ears about the unlimitedpowers <strong>of</strong> the Imperial ruler. The annals <strong>of</strong> thecourt became a long tragedy <strong>of</strong> shame and horror.The estrangement between the mother and the sonhad soon begun, when Agrippina claimed to rule inNero's name, for his advisers, fearing with good reasonher capricious lusts, had worked upon his jealousand stooped even to introduce a rival influencefears,by encouraging a low amour. Agrippina's fierce resentmentfound a vent in ominous threats; she wouldhurry to the camp and bid the soldiers rally roundthe son <strong>of</strong> Claudius, whose rightful claims had beenignored, and hurl the thankless Nero from the throne.The threat cost her her life. But first the haplessboy, whose name she had abused, was disposed <strong>of</strong>by a draught <strong>of</strong> poison. Then a plot was laid tosink the ship in which she sailed by night acrossthe bay <strong>of</strong> Naples, and when that failed recoursewas had to open force, and assassins were ordered todespatch her.There is no reason to believe that Seneca connivedat such atrocities, the details <strong>of</strong> which were left toconfidants <strong>of</strong> meaner stamp. But he has left a fatalstain upon his memory by the publicsanctions whichhe seemed to give to the deeds <strong>of</strong> horror when theyhad been done. It was not merely that he clung to<strong>of</strong>fice and remained at court, when a moralist <strong>of</strong>sterner stamp would have retired from a scene wherevirtue could no longer act with dignity and freedom.For this it was possible to urge the plea that heowed a duty to the Roman world to use such influence


138 STOICISM.as still remained in the interests <strong>of</strong> right and order,and not leave the government to be a carnival forthe excesses <strong>of</strong> the unprincipled courtiers <strong>of</strong> a youngdespot who would take his passions only for hisguide. While the mad caprices <strong>of</strong> Caligula, and thecriminal abuse <strong>of</strong> power by the freedmen and wives<strong>of</strong> Claudius, were still fresh in men's memories, itmight seem a paramount obligation for the statesmanto remain still at his post, if he could hope by hisauthority to avert or to delay such orgies <strong>of</strong> misrule.We cannot say how far such motives weighed, andthey are never expressly urged by Seneca himselfBut many a looker-on would have swept away suchpleas as hypocritic trifling, and sneeringly contrastedthe high pr<strong>of</strong>essions <strong>of</strong> austere philosophy with thegrowing wealth <strong>of</strong> the great minister whose broadlands and mansions might be, and were, regarded asthe price <strong>of</strong> blood. It was hard enough before t<strong>of</strong>ind an answer to such taunts, but it became almostimpossible when he had penned the famous messageto the Senate from the throne, which did not scrupleto imply that the murdered mother had failed in aplot against the emperor's life, and then died by herown hands in despair. It went on further to tramplemeanly on the memory <strong>of</strong> the fallen queen, ascribingto her all the worst atrocities <strong>of</strong> the last reign as wellas criminal ambition in the present. This is a blotupon the character <strong>of</strong> Seneca which no apology canwipe away. Decency required at least a little morerespect for the benefactress to whom he owed hisfreedom and his high estate. His gratitude, indeed.


THE CAREER OF SENECA.I39was rightly bounded by a higher duty to the State,and he had with good reason tried in earher years tothwart the influence <strong>of</strong> the proud and imperiouswoman over the court and Government <strong>of</strong> Nero.But that danger was aheadyover before the murderousdeed was done ; to pahiate its guiltwas anact <strong>of</strong> criminal weakness, and though the cringingSenate receivedthe message with applause, its writermust have forfeited the respect <strong>of</strong> honest men likeThrasea Psetus, who could not even stay in thesenate-house when it was read.As might have been expected, compromise couldnot long secure the influence for which so high aprice was paid. Real power drifted steadily awayfrom the advisers who could not honestly encourage,and dared not firmly check, the whims <strong>of</strong> theirImperial master.There were supple courtiers enoughto flatter and applaud ivhen he came forward, lyrein hand, to' sing and play before the populace <strong>of</strong>Rome ;there were boon companions to take partin the reckless fooling <strong>of</strong> his sumptuous banquets ;there were darker spirits, like Tigellinus, to whispermalignant words into his suspicious ear, and markthe victims for proscription. But Seneca, who wouldnot stoop so low, began to feel that there was noplace at court for one who would not bow or truckle ;wealth, and character, and independence were alikedangerous possessions when greedy sycophants hadcaught a despot's ear. Before long, therefore, heasked Nero's leave to retire once more into privatelife after thirteen years <strong>of</strong> public duties, and to return


140 STOICISM.all the gifts <strong>of</strong> his Imperial bounty. The flatteringanswer which was given did not blind him to hisdanger, and he withdrew thenceforth from the busyworld to spend his last days in earnest study andseclusion. Tyranny at first found other victims amongthe pr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> the<strong>Stoic</strong> creed, v/ho were regardedwith mistrust as disaffected to the ruling powers ;some, like Rubellius Plautus, were driven from publiclife in Rome, and struck down while in exile ;inothers, like Thrasea, abstention was counted as acrime, and it was felt that before long their turnwould come. At length an opportunity was found ;a wide-spread conspiracy against the emperor's lifehad been detected, and inor torture had extortedthe disclosures which fearthe innocent and guilty wereconfounded ; among them Seneca's name appearedupon the list, while his nephew, Lucan, certainly Avasactive in the plot. The evidence, indeed, was verymeagre, and in the bearing and answers <strong>of</strong> the accusedthere was no sign <strong>of</strong> guilty fear. But Nero wasresolved that he should die, and sent the fatal messageto announce his doom.The account <strong>of</strong> Seneca's last hours may be givenin the words <strong>of</strong> Tacitus :—" Seneca, quite unmoved,asked for tablets on which to inscribe his will, and onthe centurion's refusal, turned to his friends, protestingthat as he was forbidden to requite them, he bequeathedto them the onlybut still the noblestpossession yet remaining to him, the pattern <strong>of</strong> hislife, which if they remembered, they would win aname for moral worth and steadfast friendship. At


THE CAREER OF SENECA, 141the same time he called them back from theirtears to manly resolution, now with friendly talk,and now with the sterner language <strong>of</strong> rebuke.''Where,' he asked again and again, are yourmaxims <strong>of</strong> philosophy, or the preparation <strong>of</strong> so manyevils to come ? Who knew notyears' study againstNero's cruelty ? After a mother's and a brother'smurder, nothing remains but to add the destruction<strong>of</strong> a guardian and tutor.' Having spoken these andlike words, meant, so to say, for all, he embraced hiswife ;then s<strong>of</strong>tening awhile from the stern resolution<strong>of</strong> the hour, he begged and implored her to spareherself the burden <strong>of</strong> perpetual sorrow, and in thecontemplation <strong>of</strong> a life virtuously spent, to endure ahusband's loss with honourable consolations. Shedeclared, in answer, that she too had decided to die,and claimed for herself the blow <strong>of</strong> the executioner.Thereupon Seneca, not to thwart her noble ambition,from an affection which would not leave behindhim for insult one whom he dearly loved, replied:'I have shown you ways <strong>of</strong> smoothing life ; youprefer the glory <strong>of</strong> dying. I will not grudge you sucha noble example. Let the fortitude <strong>of</strong> so courageousan end be alike in both <strong>of</strong> us, but let there be morein your decease to win fame.' Then byone and thesame stroke they sundered with a dagger the arteries<strong>of</strong> their arms.Seneca, as his aged frame, attenuatedby frugal diet, allowed the blood to escape but slowly,severed also the veins <strong>of</strong> his legs and knees. Wornout by cruel anguish, afraid too that his sufferingsmight break his wife's spirit,and that as he looked on


142 STOICISMher tortures, he might himself sinK into irresolution,he persuaded her to retire into another chamber.Even at the last moment his eloquence failed himnot ;he summoned his secretaries, and dictated muchto them which, as it has been published for all readersin his own words, I forbear to paraphrase. ... Asthe tedious process <strong>of</strong> death still lingered on, hebegged Statius Annaeus to produce a poison with whichhe had some time before provided himself. It wasbrought to him, and he drank it in vain, chilled as hewas throughout his limbs and his frame closed againstthe efficacy <strong>of</strong> the poison. At last he entered a pool<strong>of</strong> heated water, from which he sprinkled the nearest<strong>of</strong> his slaves, adding the exclamation, * I <strong>of</strong>fer thisliquid as a libation to Jupiter the deliverer.' He wasthen carried into a bath, with the steam <strong>of</strong> which hewas suffocated, and he was burnt without any <strong>of</strong> theusual funeral rites. So he had directed in a codicil<strong>of</strong> his will, when even in the height <strong>of</strong> his wealth andpower he was thinking <strong>of</strong> his life's close." ^A recent writer speaks <strong>of</strong> the dislike which Tacitusseems to feel for the character <strong>of</strong> Seneca. In thispassage at least there is nothing to support thequestionable statement, nor is there in the rumour towhich he refers in the next chapter, that the conspiratorshad intended that the empireshould behanded over not to Piso, for whom they had scantesteem, but to Seneca " as a man singledsplendid virtues by all persons <strong>of</strong> integrity."out for his' " Annals," xv. 63. Translation <strong>of</strong> Church and Brodribb.


STOICISM. 143CHAPTER X.SENECA ASA MORALIST.It has been said with truth that, as an author, Senecashould be regarded rather as a spiritual director thanas a systematic moralist ;his writings are not dogmatictreatises, but moral sermons. But the sameremark applies, in a great measure, to many <strong>of</strong> thephilosophers <strong>of</strong> the later Roman world. The earlierHellenic seekers after wisdom, while speculative interestswere strong, indulged their subtlety<strong>of</strong> witand spent much <strong>of</strong> their strength in abstract questions,which had <strong>of</strong>ten a merely controversial value.The greatest <strong>of</strong> them kept to the serene heights <strong>of</strong>general theory, seldom coming down into the hotpress and conflict <strong>of</strong> real life, to deal with the details<strong>of</strong> human action.But in the first and second centuries <strong>of</strong> our era,philosophy became for the most part religious in itstone, and earnestly practical in its appealsto intellectand heart. It aspired not only to furnish strugglingmen with an authoritative standard, but to guideand help and strengthen them in their efforts toattain it. To explain this itchange, would not beenough to point to the practical temper <strong>of</strong> the Romanas compared with that <strong>of</strong> the more speculative Greek.


144 STOICISM.In a corner <strong>of</strong> the old Greek world, at Chseroneia,Plutarch held for years his conferences on moralthemes, inviting those <strong>of</strong> the audience who pleasedto stay after his lectures, to lay bare the troubles <strong>of</strong>their conscience, or enter freely into the story <strong>of</strong>their personal doubts. Dion Chrysostom travelledwidely as a sort <strong>of</strong> missionary <strong>of</strong> a moral propaganda,with no original system to propose, but withan earnest sympathy for human trials, which madehim popular alike in the palace and the street.Aristides left behind him a whole volume <strong>of</strong> sermons,and Julian impressed upon the priests <strong>of</strong>heathendom the novel duty <strong>of</strong> preaching to their coreligionistsas did the ministers <strong>of</strong> Christ. The tendencyin question was part, therefore, <strong>of</strong> a generalmovement due to the spirit <strong>of</strong> the age, influenced nodoubt in course <strong>of</strong> time by the enthusiasm <strong>of</strong> theChristian teaching, but answering also to a universalwant which the old religious and state systems failedto satisfy,now that the spirit <strong>of</strong> criticism was widelyspread, and the incoherencies <strong>of</strong> prejudice andcustom were exposed.There had been already much discussion amongthe later <strong>Stoic</strong>s as to the respective value <strong>of</strong> abstractprinciples and special precepts. Some, as Ariston,with the dogmatism <strong>of</strong> the earlier school, had heldthat the one thing needful was to sweep away themists <strong>of</strong> prejudice and error, and to implant theright convictions in the mind, which can then be leftto its own native strength and force <strong>of</strong> will, andcannot possibly be furnished with directions to meet


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 145all the infinite variety<strong>of</strong> circumstance and action.Others, like Posidonius, laid so much stress uponthe practical details, insisting at such length on thetheory <strong>of</strong> habits and description <strong>of</strong> the virtues, whichthey called by the pretentious names <strong>of</strong> ethology,characteristics, or moral imagery, as to leave the impressionon some readers that this side alone was<strong>of</strong> real value, and that principles must be whollybarren without precepts. Seneca discusses the wholesubject at some length in two important letters (94,95), deciding sensibly enough that there must be aframework <strong>of</strong> general theory to give a scientific valueto the special rules, which should depend uponthe leaves and branches draw their sustenance andvital power from the trunk <strong>of</strong> which theyit asare themembers. But he is very urgent, on the other hand,as to the usefulness <strong>of</strong> practical direction. The mass<strong>of</strong> men, he says, areweak, irresolute, passionate, andforgetful, soon blinded by sophistry, or led astray bybad example. The world in which they live is full<strong>of</strong> specious falsehoods and misleading maxims.Theyneed, therefore, the help, the sympathy, the guidance<strong>of</strong> a living rule, a voice that can speak with someauthority to heart or conscience, proverbial maximswhich embody general truth in striking forms, illustrationsto encourage or rebuke, friendly counselwhich may help the wavering forw-ard in the path <strong>of</strong>progress. We are far already from the crude paradox<strong>of</strong> the earlier school, which, beyond the circle <strong>of</strong>a few blest spirits, saw in the wide world only knavesand fools, all <strong>of</strong> whose vices seemed <strong>of</strong> equal black-L


146 STOICISM.ness. For Seneca had a large hopefulness in moralprogress ; they who felt that they were not alreadyperfect need not despair, but should push forward tothe light, clearing as they could the road for thosewho followed after, and leaving here and there asign-post for the unwary feet that else might stray.The volume <strong>of</strong> his letters to Lucilius, written probablyin his last years, brings this side <strong>of</strong> his characterand thought before us in every variety <strong>of</strong> light.He knows, we see, no royal road nor original system<strong>of</strong> salvation, and therefore is not tempted to laytoo much stress on intellectual beliefs. But he is sokeenly sensible himself <strong>of</strong> the fleeting and unsubstantialnature <strong>of</strong> the interests <strong>of</strong> common life, that hetries to wean his friend Lucilius from the vanitiesand ambition <strong>of</strong> the world, that he mayattune histhoughts to higher things, and find the true happiness<strong>of</strong> spiritual peace. He never seems to weary <strong>of</strong>the importunity <strong>of</strong> his appeals, and letter followsletter on some fresh aspect <strong>of</strong> the rule <strong>of</strong> life. Noris his interest bounded to the welfare <strong>of</strong> a single soul,for he tells <strong>of</strong> his anxiety to bringothers within thecircle <strong>of</strong> his influence, and how he uses differentmethods to suit the varieties <strong>of</strong> character and age,bearing even patiently the waywardness <strong>of</strong> youth andpetulant rebuffs, in hope to find one day a favourablean access to the s<strong>of</strong>tenedmoment when he may gainheart. Lucilius, in his turn, must do his part tospread the moral propaganda, not failing to let dropa timely hint, and win other souls if possible to listento the words <strong>of</strong> spiritual counsel There is little


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 147assumption <strong>of</strong> authority as <strong>of</strong> a sage condescendingto poor worldlings on a lower level ;rather he pointsto the experience <strong>of</strong> his own efforts to go forward,recommending the self-discipline to which he hashimself recourse, the quiet times <strong>of</strong> meditation inretreat, when the spirit communes with the worldunseen ;the hard mattress and the scanty fare, withwhich he tries to keep the body under, and riseabove the need <strong>of</strong> riches which may one day takewing and fly away the; nightly musings when thestory <strong>of</strong> the day rises before the wakeful conscience,which gives sentence on the rash word and hasty act;—such are the methods <strong>of</strong> his self-improvement, the regimenwhich he prescribes for serious minds. Hecarries perhaps sometimes too far the frank admission<strong>of</strong> his own shortcomings ;as when he tells <strong>of</strong> apleasant time which he spent in the country with afriend, when they bivouacked as they could, andshared the humblest fare, while a village bumpkindrove their rustic carriage. But while he enjoys theretrospect <strong>of</strong> all these simple pleasures, he admits thathe could not bear to be taken for the owner <strong>of</strong> thesorry vehicle in which they rode, and could not meetwithout a blush the grander carriages <strong>of</strong> people <strong>of</strong>distinction. He takes himself to task for havingmade so little progress, and caring over much for theopinion <strong>of</strong> the world, and setting a foolish value onsuperfluous wealth. ^At times he carries his confessions somewhat far,'Ep. 87.L 2


148 STOICISM.as when he tells his friend Lucilius that he has takenrooms above a public bath, that he might learn toconcentrate his thoughts, and disregard distractions<strong>of</strong> all kinds. He dwells complacently on the curiousmedley <strong>of</strong> the local noises which were forced uponhis ears— the hissing and the groaning, the leapingand the splashing, the singing and the whistling, thehue and cry after the pickpocket, and many a disturbance<strong>of</strong> the kind— as longa list as Londonerscould make <strong>of</strong> the costermongers' cries, and organgrindersand brass bands, or rumbling carriages thatallow no rest to mind or body. We read at the close<strong>of</strong> the epistle that the experiment has been successful,and the writer thinks that he may leave theunpleasant scene, and betake himself to more attractivequarters.^It has been said above, that Seneca lays littlestress on rigid adherence to an abstract system. Itis curious to notice that the quotations which occurin the earlier letters to Lucilius are rarely drawn from<strong>Stoic</strong> authors, but most frequently from Epicurus,who had given his name to the theory most markedlycontrasted with the doctrines <strong>of</strong> the Porch. Pleasureis the standard <strong>of</strong> the one, while the other speaks <strong>of</strong>right and duty. This seems to encourage a worldlyprudence, which would shun all high ambition, andchiefly aim at keeping on good terms with self, andwith mankind at large. That would nerve the willfor conflict, and live laborious days, and shun all self-'Ep. 58..


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 149indulgence as a traitor <strong>of</strong>fering a kiss. There was acardinal opposition in the leading principles o-f the twosystems ;there was a momentous difference betweenthe two types <strong>of</strong> conduct to be traced in the rank andfile in either camp. The noblest spirits <strong>of</strong> the agewere <strong>Stoic</strong>s, but very few <strong>of</strong> resolute temper and highaims pr<strong>of</strong>essed the creed <strong>of</strong> Epicurus. Yet there isless difference than might have been expected whenwe pass from abstract theory to rules <strong>of</strong> conduct.For beyond the dialectics <strong>of</strong> the schools, and thehigh-sounding dogmas which divided ancient sages,there was a philosophy <strong>of</strong> common sense, whosestore <strong>of</strong> moral maxims, and list <strong>of</strong> virtues and <strong>of</strong>vices, gradually became the common stock <strong>of</strong> all therival sects. Pleasure itself, as Epicurus painted it,became so refined and spiritualized a thing, that thehappinesswhich it secured was an ideal <strong>of</strong> calmserenity and chastened moderation,unruffled by thegusts <strong>of</strong> vicious passions, and scarcely to be distinguishedfrom the tranquil impassiveness <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>sage. In practice, as in theory, the master lived ablameless lifeupon this higher level, which many <strong>of</strong>his followers found a very slippery incline ;while hisdelicate sensibilities <strong>of</strong> taste and temper took theplace <strong>of</strong> any sterner discipline <strong>of</strong> self-denial. Thefine sentiments and wise suggestions <strong>of</strong> his works arelargely used by Seneca, the more perhaps becauseLucilius had been before attracted to the sect <strong>of</strong>Epicurus ; but, indeed, it was his constant practiceto pass freely from one school to another, and to takethe thoughts which suited him wherever he might


150 STOICISM.find them. Thus, he sometimes seems almost aPythagorean, when he recalls the Sotion whose lectureshe attended as a boy he talks like Plato on;the nature <strong>of</strong> the soul and immortality ;and speaks <strong>of</strong>" our" Demetrius as if he were a Cynic like hisfriend. No wonder if Quintilianhave remarked uponand other criticshis inconsistencies and want <strong>of</strong>rigorous method, forgetting that his aims were practical,and that he cared more to direct a consciencethan to expound a system. Many <strong>of</strong> the letters toowere written with a special object ;the advice wouldvary with the circumstances, and no rigidly consistentrule could be applied to different types <strong>of</strong> characterand age.But there can be no doubt that Seneca adheredwithout hesitation to the <strong>Stoic</strong> creed, and his reservesand compromises belong more to his heart than tohis head. We still hear more than we could wish <strong>of</strong>the extreme positions <strong>of</strong> the school, though, as a man<strong>of</strong> the world and a warm-hearted friend, he had <strong>of</strong>tento abate the rigour <strong>of</strong> its claims. We hear too much<strong>of</strong> the ideal man, whose absolute serenity is not to beclouded by any <strong>of</strong> the accidents <strong>of</strong> health or fortune,who cannot be touched by wrong or insult, never feelsanger, grief, or pity, or any <strong>of</strong> the impulses <strong>of</strong> ouremotional nature. He refuses to allow that this isan imaginary picture, though only to be realized perhapsby few, and at long intervals <strong>of</strong> time. And yet,at another time, he frankly owns that all this grandtheory leaves him unconvinced. To be faithful tothe tenets <strong>of</strong> his school he controverts the view <strong>of</strong>


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 151Aristotle that the emotions are necessary parts <strong>of</strong>human nature, to be regulated, not repressed. Buthis own reasoning on the subject isinconsequent andfeeble, and betrays his sense <strong>of</strong> the weakness <strong>of</strong> athesis which he elsewhere surrenders in detail. Heseems to feel, indeed, throughout misgivings which heputs into the mouth <strong>of</strong> an objector, and never reallymeets." These are the reasons why your teaching carriesso littleweight ; you promise much more thanwe can hope for, still less credit. Then, after yourgrand pr<strong>of</strong>essions that the sage is never poor, youadmit that he may be in want <strong>of</strong> clothing, food, andshelter. You say that the sage never can be foolish,yet allow that he may lose his senses, and utter sillywords, and go to whatever lengths his morbid violencemay force him. After denying that the wise man canever lose his freedom, you admit that he may be sold,and have to obey orders, and to do menial drudgeryto serve his master. So, after all your l<strong>of</strong>ty airs, yougo to much the same lengths as other folks, thoughyou call things by new names. So I suspect that itissomething <strong>of</strong> the kind in this case : fine and grandas the statement sounds at first that the wise mancannot receive a \vrong or insult. For it makes allthe difference whether you assert that he is beyondthe influence <strong>of</strong> resentment or <strong>of</strong> wrong. If you meanthat he will bear it patiently, he enjoys no specialprivilege, only the common grace <strong>of</strong> patience, whichwe may leam by having much to bear. If you meanthat he never will be wronged, that is, that no man


152 STOICISM.will ever try to injure him, then I will give upall elseand be at once a <strong>Stoic</strong>." 1He cites with approval the example <strong>of</strong> the resoluteDemetrius, who complained that the powers <strong>of</strong> heavenhad not deigned to tell him <strong>of</strong> their purpose, that hemight have forestalled their purpose by <strong>of</strong>fering freelywhat it was their pleasure to remove, since all that hehad was theirs to give, and theirs to take away."He speaks with admiration more than once <strong>of</strong> theconstancy <strong>of</strong> Stilbon, who seemed to lose his all,fortune, family, and home, when his city wasdestroyed, yet could say calmly that he had all hisproperty safe in his own keeping, meaning therebythe qualities <strong>of</strong> mind and temper, <strong>of</strong> which no enemycould rob him.^ He expends much idle subtlety onthe self-sufficiency <strong>of</strong> virtue, the happiness <strong>of</strong> which isnot to be impaired by any loss <strong>of</strong> friends or children ;it is but their bodies, not themselves, he says, we lose ;good cannot perish save by passing into evil; say theyare gone, yet their place is more than filled by thegood qualities which lived but lately in them ;for whatmatters it, if the waters flow away, if the fountain stillruns on.^ Still he owns that it is natural that all theoutward tokens <strong>of</strong> emotion should appear in the wiseman, the shifting colour, and the tottering limbs, andthe sudden chill <strong>of</strong> sorrow, for these are due to naturalimpulse where the mind has no control, but its resolutionwill be shown in the assurance that there isDial. ii. 3.Ibid. ii. 5.' Ibid. i. 5.*Ep. 74.


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 153no evil which can make his reason lose its healthybalance. ^Elsewhere, he says thathe has no wish to raise thesage above the common level <strong>of</strong> humanity, or treathim as a rock insensible to mortal pain, for he is madeup— <strong>of</strong> two elements the one irrational, which is full<strong>of</strong> changing sensibilities while the rational; preservesthe balance <strong>of</strong> its calm and"fixed convictions. Forfear our theory should seem to travel beyond thebounds <strong>of</strong> nature, I admit that the wise man willexperiencefear and pain and pallor, for all these arebodily sensations, but the real evil or misfortune onlybegins then when these enslave the mind, and makeit own itsdegradation or ^its shame."It is evident that most <strong>of</strong> the paradox <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>apathy is abandoned in these lines, and that it becomesfor the most part a mere question <strong>of</strong> names ifthe emotions are disapproved <strong>of</strong> only when they passbeyond control, and the term " evil " is restricted toa moral sense as distinct from physical discomfort.He is far, again, from expecting rigid self-restraintfrom his mourning friends, or from denouncing thechoking sense <strong>of</strong> "grief It would be inhuman," hesays, " not virtuous, to look on as calmly when ourkinsmen are borne out to burial as when we saw themliving at our side. . . . Let the tears flow as long asthe emotion bids them." Nor does he tolerate themonly when the griefis violent and loss is recent." There are tears to which we give free course, when'Ep. 74.2 Ibid. 7,.


f154 STOICISM.we recall to memorywhen we think over theirthe friends whomwe have lost,pleasant talk, their cheerfulintercourse, and tender <strong>of</strong>fices <strong>of</strong> friendship. Let thetears flow then as they will."^The sage himself is no impassive thing, but willshow humanity in sorrow, though without loss <strong>of</strong> selfcontrol; yet, for himself, he owns that his grief forhis friend Serenus passed all proper bounds, so completelywas he over-mastered by his sorrow.^ He hasthe good sense to see that he who would rebukegrief must rebuke love as well, and his ownheart was warm and tender, and he does not think itunphilosophical to own He it. is careful <strong>of</strong> his health,he says on one occasion, more for the sake <strong>of</strong> hisloving wife, Paulina, than for himself. He sees howmuch her happiness, her life even, is bound up withhis own, and regardsit as a duty to indulge so farour natural affections.^ He protests against thesordid view <strong>of</strong> friendship, which would make thestrength <strong>of</strong> the tie depend upon the sense <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>itfrom a friend's company or help, as though withEpicurus we desired to find a friend only to sit byour bed-side when we are ill,or to come to oursuccour when in poverty or prison. Rather,it is theexpression <strong>of</strong> a natural instinct, and not a calculation<strong>of</strong> self-interest. The best philtre or love-charm toprovoke affection is to feel love oneself The pleasureconsists in forming the friendship, not in after pr<strong>of</strong>it.should I make a friend ? To have some one" Why'Ep. 99.2 Ibid. 63.3 Ibid, 104.1


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 155to die for; to follow into banishment; to risk my ownlife to save him."i No good thing can be enjoyedwithout a friend to share it.^It is partly for this reason that he discourages allausterities <strong>of</strong> dress and manner, all Cynical disregard<strong>of</strong> common customs, as tending to isolate us from ourfellows, and to emphasize the points <strong>of</strong> difference thatdivide us, in place <strong>of</strong> fostering the kindly sympathies,the courtesy, and the gregarious instinct on which hisphilosophy, as interpreted by his own tenderness, laysso much stress.^This kindliness, he thinks, should be strong enoughto overleap the social barriers which divide us, andignore even the difference between the freeman andthe slave. No ancient moralist has spoken so feelinglyand earnestly upon this subject, or describedwith more contempt the haughty inhumanity <strong>of</strong> manya wealthy master, surrounded by a multitude <strong>of</strong> coweringmenials, in whom he saw, accordingproverb, " as many enemies as slaves."to the Roman" Not so,"says Seneca, " it is our own fault if we make themsuch ; they are <strong>of</strong> the same flesh and blood as we are,breathe the same air <strong>of</strong> heaven, are, or should be, ourfellows, companions, and our humble friends. Weneed not go abroad in quest <strong>of</strong> friendship ;we shallfind it, if we seek it,in our homes. Kindly intercoursewill bring to light their good qualitiestemper, and will gradually efface the grossertheir training or associations." *<strong>of</strong> mind orstains <strong>of</strong>»Ep. 9.=Ibid. 6.3 ^Ibid. 5. Ibid. 47.


156 STOICISM.He raised his voice also in protest against thebutchery <strong>of</strong> the gladiatorial shows, and the ferocity wi-thwhich criminals were exposed to the wild beasts whilethe populace looked on at the cruel sport. He warnshis friend Lucilius against the demoralizing influence<strong>of</strong> such a scene, reacting as it must upon the character"and temper. They are highwaymen and murderers,you say, and deserve to die. True, they meet perhapswith their deserts ;but what have you done that youshould be condemned to sitby at such a sight ?"iWe see, therefore, that in spite <strong>of</strong> all his borrowedphrases <strong>of</strong> the school, there is little in Seneca's ownteaching <strong>of</strong> the hardness and the coldness <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>creed. In place <strong>of</strong> an unattainable ideal, which wasuntrue to the conditions <strong>of</strong> our human nature, wehave a discipline <strong>of</strong> self-improvement, with constanthopes <strong>of</strong> further progress,and criteria <strong>of</strong> the variousstages <strong>of</strong> perfectibility. 2 "Let us press on andpersevere ;more remains for us to do than we havedone already ;but the wish to improve is a great steptowards improvement.conscience bearsTo this myme witness. I do wish it with all my mind."^ Thesage's calm is no unfeeling self-contentment, butis coloured and warmed with social sympathies andtender moods, in which sorrow and love and pity finda place. The seeming impassiveness (aTrddeia) consistsonly in the mental balance by which the reasoncan measure things at their true value, and refuse tobe overpowered by emotion.But philosophy alone»Ep. 7.» Ibid. 75,' Ibid. 71.


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 157can teach us the true estimate <strong>of</strong> all that can befallus here; <strong>of</strong> the wealth and honours, business andpleasure, <strong>of</strong> our mortal lot ;and therefore Senecabetakes himself with ardour, and would guide othersalso, to the Mistress whose service alone is perfectfreedom.!But there was nothing in this intellectual freedom,he insisted, which should giveumbrage to the rulingpowers. They were quite mistaken who supposedthat the devoted students <strong>of</strong> philosophy must be turbulentor stiff-necked in their self-assertion, and disrespectfultowards magistrates or princes. Far fromthat, the more they prized the blessings <strong>of</strong> theirstudious ease, the more grateful they should be towardsthe rulers whose vigilance secured their restfrom danger or disturbance.There could be no fear<strong>of</strong> rival jealousies from those who should be raisedabove the ambition <strong>of</strong> the world, and for whom thegame <strong>of</strong> politics and war had less attraction than thecare <strong>of</strong> their own souls. As their happiness was morecomplete than that <strong>of</strong> other men, so they should havemore cause to thank the rulers to whom they owedtheir peace.^ It is the jealousy <strong>of</strong> Nero to whichthis passage points, and it is one <strong>of</strong> the few placesin the Letters where we have any direct referenceto the political aspects <strong>of</strong> the times. And yet,if we look more deeply, we shall find that to a greatextent they coloured his temper and gavea bias to'Philosophias sen'ias oportet, ut tibi contingat vera libertas(Ep. 8).'Ep. 73.


158 STOICISM./ his thought. They explain the gloomy tinge whichhis meditations <strong>of</strong>ten take from the abiding thought<strong>of</strong> death, which isalways present to his fancy. Itwas, indeed, a commonplace <strong>of</strong> the ancient moraliststo insist upon this subject, as the one theme on whichwe could never speculate in vain. As he says himself," for other things our preparations may be useless.The soul may be steeled against poverty, andriches abide with us to the end. We may have armedourselves against assault <strong>of</strong> pain, and yet never haveour patience tested, thanks to the good hap <strong>of</strong> a soundand healthy body ;we may have schooled ourselvesto bear with fortitude the loss <strong>of</strong> our departedfriends, while fortune wills that all whom we love outliveus ;this is the one discipline whose use will certainlyone day be tested." ^Even in early years the mind <strong>of</strong> Seneca may have<strong>of</strong>ten dwelt upon the thought <strong>of</strong> death, for he wasalways <strong>of</strong> weak health, and almost every variety <strong>of</strong>ailment had left its mark upon him. 2 His bodilyinfirmities form a frequent subject <strong>of</strong> reference inhis letters, though there isnothing querulous orunmanly in his tone. They lead him to dwell howeveron the question, whether itmay not seemadvisable one day to make an easier exit from theworld than that which nature might provide, and hedecides that he will not be impatient to depart inpeace so long as disease leaves his nobler facultiesuntouched ;should itbegin to lay rude hands upon'Ep. 70.2 jbj^_ ^^


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 159his reason or disturb his moral hfe, while itsparesthe vital spark, then he will speed away at once " asfrom a ruinous and crumbling house." ^But in later years more probablyit was the experience<strong>of</strong> a despot'scruel capriceswhich made thevisions <strong>of</strong> death familiar to his fancy, and suicide inall its bearings an " engrossing question. Somepr<strong>of</strong>essors <strong>of</strong> "philosophy maintain," he says, that wehave no right to lay violent hands upon ourselves,but that duty calls us to await the end which naturemay assign us. In saying this they do not see thatthey bar the road to freedom." But we may rejoinperhaps that in this comment Seneca is false to hisown principles, forgetting his own analysis <strong>of</strong> freedomas the state in which the reason holds the sway overthe passions, and has might as she has already right.He concludes that no general decision can be madeupon a question which depends so much on itsdetails, but he has no doubt at any rate that he maychoose his own form <strong>of</strong> an inevitable death, as wemay select a ship in which to make a voyage, or ahouse in which to dwell. "A longer life is not alwaysthe better, but a lingering death is always worse." ^Not only, as he thinks, have the heroes <strong>of</strong> humanitylike Cato asserted this right <strong>of</strong> theirs to die whenand how they pleased, but men <strong>of</strong> low degree,the poor gladiators <strong>of</strong> the stage,the barbarians orcriminals condemned to be thrown to the wild beasts,have flung defiance inthe face <strong>of</strong> death, and left ex-'Ep. 58.« Ibid. 70.


l6oSTOICISM,amples which the subjects <strong>of</strong> tyranny mayheart.take toIt has been remarked that <strong>of</strong> the modern criticswho have occupied themselves with Seneca, Garatwas the first to understand him rightly, and thatbecause he lived under a reign <strong>of</strong> terror which<strong>of</strong> Nero. Herecalled the memory <strong>of</strong> the dark daystells us that he had the guillotine in prospect whenhe began to read afresh the works <strong>of</strong> Seneca for anew edition. He had read him in his earlier years<strong>of</strong> cheerful life before the Revolution ;he read himonce more in days <strong>of</strong> gloom, and found him quiteanother writer. The first time he had much workto keep the page still open ;the second timehe could scarcely tear himself away." His moralshad seemed before unnatural and high pitched;now they appeared hardly up to the level <strong>of</strong> ourown experience and needs." Or again," Seneca'sphilosophy was composed for those periods <strong>of</strong>lingering agony to which tyrants sometimes condemntheir people." Again, "There was need <strong>of</strong>a philosophy to teach men to give up all theyhad before it was taken from them ;to isolatethem from their fellows who could do no more forthem ;to create a personal force and greatnesswhich despots and executioners might crush, butwhich they could not cause to tremble. Such isthe philosophy <strong>of</strong> Seneca." Or again,"He dwells,it is true, on the same truth a long time, butremember that it is not with him a question only<strong>of</strong> what he ought to think <strong>of</strong> death; he has to


SENECA AS A MORALIST.l6lmake himself ready for the moment when Silvanuswill come with Nero's message 'Die.' " ^This attitude <strong>of</strong> Seneca seems to have been /neglected by Macaulay in the criticism which wasquoted at the beginning <strong>of</strong> 4his chapter. It is not ^^'fair to treat his thought as idle moralizing uponabstract questions, such as the man <strong>of</strong> action maybrush impatiently aside, for it was really earnest meditationon the experience <strong>of</strong> actual life. It is possibleindeed that the l<strong>of</strong>ty sentiments on anger and, onclemency may have been wasted on a Nero, andphrases about the vanity <strong>of</strong> wealth may have soundedas mere empty talk in the ears <strong>of</strong> many a Romannoble, but so perhaps the grandest eloquence <strong>of</strong>Christian divines, even the preaching <strong>of</strong> Prophets andApostles, may have seemed to fail entirely to touchthe conscience <strong>of</strong> some hearers, yetitmight bethought mere shallow flippancy to treat such teachingas unpractical because it did not deal with themethods <strong>of</strong> induction or contribute to the materialcomforts <strong>of</strong> the age. Meditations such as Seneca's,inadequate as they may seem, took the place <strong>of</strong>religious principles among the educated circles <strong>of</strong> theRoman Empire, were a protest <strong>of</strong> real value againstthe coarse materialism <strong>of</strong> the old heathen world, taughtthe choicer spirits how to live with dignity and diewith honour, supplied a force <strong>of</strong> public sentiment <strong>of</strong>which even despots had to take account, and didsomething to lessen the misery <strong>of</strong> the toiling masses'E. Havet, "Le Christianisme et ses Origines," ii. 256.M


l62STOICISM.by tender words <strong>of</strong> sympathy for the stranger and theslave. It is a matter <strong>of</strong> regret, no doubt, that theold philosophy <strong>of</strong> Greece and Rome busied itselfso little with the inductive method and the order <strong>of</strong>the physical world, helped so little to advance man'smastery over nature by the knowledge <strong>of</strong> its laws.This is no more true <strong>of</strong> Seneca, however, than <strong>of</strong> allthe schools <strong>of</strong> Hellenic thought. But the moralvalue <strong>of</strong> their speculations is not lessened by thefact that they neglected the fields <strong>of</strong> physical research,and it isunworthy <strong>of</strong> a serious critic thus to confusethe wants <strong>of</strong> different ages, and to treat with contemptthe ancient seekers after wisdom, who pondered onthe questions that were full <strong>of</strong> actual interest to themand theirs. In the letter which has been referred to(p. 129) Seneca distinguished, as he was warrantedin doing, the functions <strong>of</strong> the moralist and the mechanician,and it is idle to compare the usefulness <strong>of</strong>each, or to balance the increase <strong>of</strong> man's creaturecomforts against the improvement <strong>of</strong> his moral nature.If Seneca seems to underrate the value <strong>of</strong> the artist'sor inventor's v/ork, we must remember the asceticbias <strong>of</strong> his teaching, intended as it was to counteractin himself or others the sensualism and the mammonworship <strong>of</strong> the age. His tones may seem to us highpitched, his language too intense and highly coloured,but this is one <strong>of</strong> the literary features <strong>of</strong> the timesthemselves, when vice and luxury and despotic forcewere all realized in monstrous shapes, and challengedtherefore and excused some seeming extravagance <strong>of</strong>rhetoric and style.


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 1 63We have not yet done, however, with Macaulay.There is an amusing passage in which he imagines a<strong>Stoic</strong> and a follower <strong>of</strong> Bacon as fellow-travellersupon a "journey. They come to a village where thesmall-pox has begun to rage, and find houses shut up,intercourse suspended, the sick abandoned, mothersweeping in terror over their children. The <strong>Stoic</strong>assures the dismayed population that there is nothingbad inthe small-pox, and that to a wise man disease,deformity, death, the loss <strong>of</strong> friends are not evils.The Baconian takes out a lancet and begins to vaccinate.They find a body <strong>of</strong> miners in great dismay.An explosion <strong>of</strong> noisome vapours has just killed many<strong>of</strong> those who were at work; and the survivors areafraid to venture into the cavern. The <strong>Stoic</strong> assuresthem that such an accident isnothingbut a mereaTTOTrporjyfiiror.The Baconian, who has no such fineword at his command, contents himself with devisinga safety-lamp. They find a shipwrecked merchantwringing his hands on the shore. His vesselwith an inestimable cargo has just gone down,and he is reduced in a moment from opulence tobeggary. The <strong>Stoic</strong> exhorts him not to seek happinessin things which lie without himself, and repeatsthe whole chapter <strong>of</strong> Epictetus np6c tovq Tr)v cnropiavc£?otcorac. The Baconian constructs a diving-bell,goes down in it,and returns with the most preciouseffects from the wreck. It would be easy to multiplyillustrations <strong>of</strong> the difference between the philosophy<strong>of</strong> thorns and the philosophy <strong>of</strong> the fruit, philosophy<strong>of</strong> words and the philosophy <strong>of</strong> works."M 2


164 STOICISM.It has been remarked with justice that in thispassage the author " only represents the conflict <strong>of</strong>man with nature, and it is true that in confrontingnature only two alternatives are possible, action orsilence ; protest is not to be thought<strong>of</strong>. This is notso true when we have to face human injustice ;theredefiance is meritorious. What could the Baconian <strong>of</strong>Macaulay have done had he been in the place <strong>of</strong>Seneca? What was the operation possible to curethe world <strong>of</strong> Nero ? Itmay be said, that it was theinsurrection <strong>of</strong> Vindex ;and that is true, but Vindexdid not and could not act at once. It was needfulfirst that the world should be weary <strong>of</strong> the master ithad borne with so long. Physical evils are felt andrecognised directly, it is not so with that moralpoison <strong>of</strong> which nations die ; they must first be madeto feel that they are ill,and that is the first steptowards the cure. That is just what Seneca did,and his so-called declamations certainly contributedto cause that universal impatience which broughtabout deliverance." ^The opulence <strong>of</strong> Seneca, contrasted with hispraises<strong>of</strong> contented poverty, has <strong>of</strong>ten moved the spleen <strong>of</strong>critics, as among others <strong>of</strong> Macaulay. Was it, besides,then becomeill-gotten wealth, the rhetorical phrasesstill more hollow and insincere. But as to its sourcewe have no certain evidence. He came <strong>of</strong> a family<strong>of</strong> ample means ;his talents as an advocate broughthim large pr<strong>of</strong>essional gains ;but above all the favour•E. Havet, " Le Christianisme et ses Origines," ii. 254.


SENECA AS A MORALIST. 165<strong>of</strong> the court heaped its bounties lavishly upon him.It was natural enough to sneer and say that he clungto <strong>of</strong>fice for the sake <strong>of</strong> wealth and honour, butthough his position was a false one he may well havebeen unwilling on far higher grounds to let his influencepass into worse hands. If he penned themessage <strong>of</strong> Nero to the senate with its attack on thememory <strong>of</strong> the murdered Agrippina, nothing canjustify his conduct. It exposed him to the vilestimputations, which were not probably well-founded,but which could not be disproved. But after that hegains in dignity and moral courage. He stoops tono flattery <strong>of</strong> Nero's vices ;he is taunted even withuncourtly frankness. He <strong>of</strong>fers to resign all the solidfruits <strong>of</strong> the Imperial favour, and withdraws from theworld <strong>of</strong> fashion when the <strong>of</strong>fer is declined. This isthe period in which the letters that we read werewritten, and their language is almost certainly sincere.He feels his wealth a dangerous burden, for thelightning strikes the l<strong>of</strong>tiest spires. It makes him amark for jealous gossip, which he cannot alwaysleave unnoticed. Thus on one occasion he observes"our object should be to live by nature's rule, but itis unnatural to distress the body, to disfigure it bythe neglect <strong>of</strong> simple graces or by recourse to unwholesomeor repulsive fare. Philosophy requiresnot penal discipline, but moderation. He shows hisgreatness who can use earthenware like silver, nor ishe inferior who can treat his silver plate as if it werebut earthenware. It shows an abject soul not to beable to use wealth aright."


l66STOICISM.CHAPTER XLSENECA AND ST. PAUL, OR THE RELATION OFSTOICISM TO CHRISTIANITY.There are some letters which pr<strong>of</strong>essedly belong toa correspondence between St. Paul and Seneca, inwhich the latter writes like one who is a Christian atheart, and seems tobe acquainted with the style anddoctrines <strong>of</strong> the former. They are, indeed, a clumsyforgery, for their literary form and thought, and thereferences which they contain, are such as could notpossibly proceed from either writer. But they pointto a prevalent belief among the Fathers <strong>of</strong> the LatinChurch that Seneca had felt the influence <strong>of</strong> St. Paul,and they grew probably out <strong>of</strong> the attempt to clothein circumstantial shape the wide-spread fancy.Men could not but be struck with the echoes <strong>of</strong>Christian thought and feeling, which occur morefrequently in Seneca than in any heathen writer.They remembered that St. Paul lived in the samepart <strong>of</strong> the century, and was brought before Gallio,the statesman's brother, who was then provincialgovernor at Corinth that he was;lodged at Rome inthe custody <strong>of</strong> Burrus, the general <strong>of</strong> the praetoriansoldiers, who shared so long with Seneca the cares <strong>of</strong>actual government, and that he stood at last for


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 167judgment before Nero, or his council, and foundfriends or converts among those <strong>of</strong> Caesar's household.It seemed natural to suppose that in one or other <strong>of</strong>these waysSeneca's attention was called to theapostle, and that his earnest wish for self-improvementwas rewarded ere he died by a fuller measure<strong>of</strong> the truth. There is no direct evidence, indeed, <strong>of</strong>any contact, except the similarity <strong>of</strong> thought whichgrows more marked in Seneca's later writings, but thebelief must have been early spread ;and St.Jeromenot merely speaks <strong>of</strong> him as " our own," a termwhich he might possibly apply to Virgil, or toany other Latin writer, but says that he rankshim in the catalogue <strong>of</strong> the saints, on the authority<strong>of</strong> the well-known correspondence with St.Paul.In the days when Jerome lived, the ascetic spirithad taken strong hold upon the Christian Church ;multitudes were turning from the world which theydespaired <strong>of</strong> to the calm retirement <strong>of</strong> the cloister.In Seneca they found a moralist who seemed to thinkas meanly as themselves <strong>of</strong> the common interests <strong>of</strong>the life <strong>of</strong> cities ;who tried to wean himself andothers from the " lust <strong>of</strong> the flesh," and the "lust <strong>of</strong>the eyes," and the " pride <strong>of</strong> life," by stringent rules<strong>of</strong> self-denial, by the exercise<strong>of</strong> meditation, and detachmentfrom the busyworld. Here was a fund<strong>of</strong> sympathy far greater for them than for ourselves,and in their surprise and pleasure at such outwardfeatures <strong>of</strong> resemblance in the methods <strong>of</strong> selfdisciplinethey laid probably too little stress on the


1 68 STOICISM.essentials <strong>of</strong> the moral life, and on the articles <strong>of</strong> hisreligious creed.They found again in Seneca many <strong>of</strong> the specialterms adopted in their own spiritual language, andthese in the course <strong>of</strong> time had become colouredwith the associations <strong>of</strong> theology, and were full <strong>of</strong>the suggestions <strong>of</strong> its doctrines. They were naturallytempted to receive them in the sense familiar tothemselves ;to do otherwise required a serious eftbrt <strong>of</strong>critical reserve,though ttie words may have conveyedto earlier readers quite a different shade <strong>of</strong> meaning.Thus his " Saar Spiritus " sounded to them like the" Holy Spirit" <strong>of</strong> the Christian Trinity ;^^peccatiim""was the sin <strong>of</strong> which all men are guilty ; sahcs," the"salvation which should be their aim ; caro " was thebody with all its carnal passions, which can only betransfigured {transfigurari) by a spiritual grace, oneform <strong>of</strong> which they seemed to find a hint <strong>of</strong> in his" sacratnentujti"; while his influence on the moral lifewas traced in " caritas" or charitv.Some <strong>of</strong> the most striking parallels to our religiousthought belong, not to Seneca himself or to thesystem <strong>of</strong> philosophy which he embraced, but toearlier schools and different thinkers from whom hefreely borrowed.We have already called attention tothis tendency, which was natural enough in that lateage when rigid exclusiveness was out <strong>of</strong> date andeclecticism had become a ruling fashion. Thus thebeautiful expressions to be found in him about ourHeavenly Father, from whom come allgood andperfect gifts, whom we should try to imitate, that we


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 169may be perfect like our Father <strong>of</strong> the ; guardian angelswho watch over us ;<strong>of</strong> the immortality beyond thegrave, and the decrees <strong>of</strong> Divine retribution ;<strong>of</strong> theextension <strong>of</strong> the guilt <strong>of</strong> vice from the act to the intention;the picture <strong>of</strong> the just man calmly confrontingpersecution and forgiving his worst enemies ;—be found in Plato cen-these and many others mayturies before they gained a place, but not always aharmonious setting, in the letters and dialogues <strong>of</strong>Seneca. In the school <strong>of</strong> Pythagoras, which hefollowed in his youth,he may have learnt to examinehimself, as was his later practice, to listen to the voice<strong>of</strong> conscience, and to confess the wrong which he haddone. From Epicurus, as we have seen, he borrowedmuch, and among other sentiments that one, " theconsciousness <strong>of</strong> sin is the first step towards salvation,"^ on which so much stress has been laid as anevidence <strong>of</strong> Scriptural doctrine. Of manyother <strong>of</strong>his highest thoughts traces could be found in earlierwritingsdetail.if it were worth while to discuss them inYet after all these reserves it must be owned thatthe parallels between the language <strong>of</strong> Seneca andScripture are <strong>of</strong>ten very close and striking. Thesubject is examined fully in a special work by a Frenchwriter ^ ;but the most carefully selected list isgivenby Bishop Lightfoot, in an essay in his treatise on the"Epistle to the Philippians," which has leftnothing' " Initium salutus est notitia peccati " (Ep. 28).^Aubertin," Seneque et St. Paul."


lyoSTOICISM.further to be said upon the question. Itmay beenough, therefore, to transcribe a few <strong>of</strong> the mostmarked examples to illustrate the close resemblance<strong>of</strong> the thought. " The mind, unless it ispure andholy, comprehends not God."i " What will the wiseman do when he is buffeted ? He will do as Catodid when he was smitten on the mouth. He did notburst into a passion, did not avenge himself, did not^even forgive it,but denied itshaving been done."" I will be agreeable to friends, gentle and yielding to"enemies."-^ Give aid even to enemies."* "Do not,like those whose desire is not to make progress butto be seen, do anything to attract notice in your demeanouror mode <strong>of</strong> life.Avoid a rough exterior andunshorn hair, and a carelessly kept beard and pr<strong>of</strong>essedhatred <strong>of</strong> money and a bed laid on the ground, andwhatever else affects ambitious display by a perversepath Let everything within us be unlike, but let our. . .^outward appearance resemble the common people."" If you imitate the gods, confer benefits even onthe unthankful : for the sun rises even on the wicked,and the seas are open to pirates." ^" Good does not grow <strong>of</strong> evil, any more than a fig<strong>of</strong> an olive tree. The fruits correspond to theseed. "7" Let him break his bread with the hungry."^•Ep. 87;Matt. V. 8.2De Const. Sap. 14; cf. Matt. v. 39.»De Vita Beat. 20.^Ep. 5 ; cf. Matt. vi. 16.*De Otio, 28 ; cf. Matt. v. 44.^De Benef. 4; cf. Luke vi. 35.'Ep. 87 ; cf. Matt. vii. 17.^Ep. 95 cf. Isaiah Iviii. ; 7.


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 171As regards the form <strong>of</strong> Seneca's expressions wemay notice how <strong>of</strong>ten the metaphors <strong>of</strong> Scriptureseem to reappear among his writings, as for example,that <strong>of</strong> the house built upon the rock ;<strong>of</strong> life regardedas a warfare and a pilgrimage ;<strong>of</strong> the athlete'scrown <strong>of</strong> victory ;<strong>of</strong> hypocrites like whited walls ;<strong>of</strong>girding the loins <strong>of</strong> the mind ;<strong>of</strong> spending and beingspent in faithful service.We may find traces even <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the bestknown <strong>of</strong> the parables <strong>of</strong> Christ, as <strong>of</strong> the sower, andthe rich fool, and the debtor, and the talents out atusurj-.Resemblances so numerous and circumstantialseem to call for some attempt at explanation, such asthe supposed acquaintance <strong>of</strong> the moralist and theapostle. The silence <strong>of</strong> history makes this verydoubtful. Gallio and Burrus, as far as we know theircharacters, would attach too little significanceto thelanguage <strong>of</strong> St. Paul to speak or write about it totheir literary friends; and Seneca may well have failedto hear that some slaves or freemen <strong>of</strong> the palace wereattracted by a new form <strong>of</strong> devotion preached by aJewish prisoner from Asia. Yet it isprobable enough,as Bishop Lightfoot has observed, that the figures anddistinctive maxims <strong>of</strong> the Scriptures, the imageryadopted by our Lord, because already familiar tohis hearers, may have found their way by variouschannels even into the disdainful circles <strong>of</strong> philosophy.Seneca speaks, indeed, in scornful tones <strong>of</strong>the people <strong>of</strong> the Book ;he had given up in earlyyears his abstinence from animal food lest he should


172 STOICISM,be thought to share the scruples <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the despisedraces <strong>of</strong> the East ; yet the Jews were spreadthrough every land, and quartering themselves in thecentre <strong>of</strong> the Roman world, had called the notice <strong>of</strong>the curious to their peculiar customs, and wonproselytes in every circle. Tacitus might show hiscontemptuous ignorance <strong>of</strong> their history in the past,but they clung with a tenacious grasp to their oldbooks, and diffused the utterances <strong>of</strong> the Law andProphets round them.While this spiritual influence was in the air, the<strong>Stoic</strong>s above others were likely to absorb some portion<strong>of</strong> it for ; though Hellenic in its origin and logic,the moral intensity <strong>of</strong> the Stoa and its ascetic tonewere Eastern. Its most celebrated teachers were drawnchiefly from the East, from the countries nearest tothe Holy Land, where the Jews <strong>of</strong> the dispersion mostabounded. All the currents <strong>of</strong> moral thought weremeeting and mingling at that time, and it is scarcelylikely that the two most distinctive should keep themselvesentirely apart.To this it has been added that Seneca himselfassociated freely with his slaves, and may well haveheard from some <strong>of</strong> them in hours <strong>of</strong> familiar intercourseabout the spiritual leaven that was working inthe bosom <strong>of</strong> the Jewish synagogue, and that wassoon to make the name <strong>of</strong> Christ the greatest in thecivilized world.And yet we must admit that the resemblances <strong>of</strong>tone and style do not touch the essentials <strong>of</strong> themoral system, and fail to bridge over the gulf between


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 173the <strong>Stoic</strong> and the Christian creed. The former wasPantheistic still ; its God is diffused throughstages <strong>of</strong> creation its ; providenceis an inexorablefate ; itsHoly Spirit ebbs and flows like tidal wavesthrough all the multitudinous realms <strong>of</strong> Nature.The Fatherhood <strong>of</strong> God is an unmeaning phrase inall thesuch a system. Instead <strong>of</strong> filial devotion to a personalwill, we have submission to an absolute law; instead<strong>of</strong> the humbling sense <strong>of</strong> sin against a perfect goodness,we have mere errors, and mistakes from ignorance<strong>of</strong> natural conditions.Devotional language there may be, indeed, to expressthe fervour <strong>of</strong> emotion, kindled by the effort topursue in thought the Absolute Being in all its endlesschanges through the immensities <strong>of</strong> time and space.Large thoughts like these, long brooding in the mind,may make man feel his littleness at times, and fostera sort <strong>of</strong> humility <strong>of</strong> moral bearing, but they have nopower to give the tenderer saintlier gracesup the temper <strong>of</strong> true Christian meekness. And howcould it be otherwise when the same system allowedtliat makesuch boastful phrases as that " God surpasses theor thatgood man in this only that He is longer good,"^" the good man can excel God in the patience withJwhich he bears the trials <strong>of</strong> his mortal lot." -On the subject <strong>of</strong> immortality, again, the <strong>Stoic</strong> speakswith an uncertain sound. At one time he seems to soarwith Plato into clearer air, and to believe in a personalidentity remaining after death, and lasting on for end-'Ep. 73."De Prov. 6.


174 STOICISM.less ages.But how little hold it had on his convictionsis shown by some expressions in his letters to Lucilius:— " I was pleasantly engaged ininquiring aboutthe eternity <strong>of</strong> souls, or rather, I should say, in trusting.For I was ready to trust myself to the opinions<strong>of</strong> great men, who avow rather than prove so veryacceptable a thing.I was surrendering myself to thisgreat hope, I was beginning to be weary <strong>of</strong> myself, todespise the remaining fragments <strong>of</strong> a broken life, asthough I were destined to pass away into that illimitabletime, and into the possession <strong>of</strong> eternity, whenI was suddenly aroused by the receipt <strong>of</strong> your letter,and this beautiful dream vanished."^ And so we <strong>of</strong>tenfind him balancing the two alternatives <strong>of</strong> regardingdeath either as a leap into utter nothingness or asthe birthday <strong>of</strong> eternity {(zterni natalis) ; and thateven in his "Consolation," where the most reassuringthoughts that he can find are brought to bear uponthe mourning Marcia. And, indeed, however waveringmight be his tone upon the subject, there can belittle doubt that the <strong>Stoic</strong> system could admit n<strong>of</strong>aith in personal immortality. The soul's vital forcemight, it is true, outlive a while the shock <strong>of</strong> bodilydecay, nobler spirits might survive the dissolution <strong>of</strong>the grosser beings round them, yet soon or late theirturn would come to pass into new modes <strong>of</strong> life,till thewhole cycle <strong>of</strong> material changes should be complete,and a period <strong>of</strong> time be closed by the great conflagrationwhich should dissolve all combinations into chaos.However that might be, the <strong>Stoic</strong> laidEp. I02.no stress on


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 175any moral sequence between the life on earth and thehereafter; the claims <strong>of</strong> justice may be met, theythought, by the good and evil <strong>of</strong> our present lot, theaccount <strong>of</strong> which is balanced when the last debt ispaid at death.No personal Maker had brought man into being ;there was no one to call him to account for his stewardship<strong>of</strong> powers entrusted to his keeping. Instead <strong>of</strong>,the Lord giveth, the Lord hath taken away" <strong>of</strong> our*'Burial Service, we read in Seneca, " Fortune hastaken away my friend, but he was her gift."<strong>Stoic</strong> looked on suicide as hisSo theright when he seemedto risk his dignity by staying longer on the scene.It might be cowardice, indeed, or weak impatience tohurry from the common ills <strong>of</strong> life, but he trusted hisown judgment— a sadly treacherous guide— to tellhim when he might withdraw in honour from thestage. The literature <strong>of</strong> the times is full <strong>of</strong> illustrations <strong>of</strong> this state <strong>of</strong> feeling, and among others apassage <strong>of</strong> his letters may serve to bring it home :—"Tullius Marcellinus, whom you know so well, ayoung man <strong>of</strong> quiet life, but prematurely aged, wastaken ill with a disease, which, though not incurable,was lingering and troublesome as requiring constantcarej and began to think <strong>of</strong> death. He called intocouncil many <strong>of</strong> his friends. Some cautiously gavehim the advice they would have taken in like case ;the flattering and insincere suggested what theythought he would be pleased to hear ;but our <strong>Stoic</strong>friend, like a man <strong>of</strong> bold and resolute nature, to givehim his real due, seems to have <strong>of</strong>fered him the best


Do176 STOICISM.advice. For he began :— as follows 'not vex yourself,my Marcellinus, as though you were making upyour mind on a matter <strong>of</strong> great moment. Life is nogrand thing. All your slaves, all kinds <strong>of</strong> animalshave life ;the great thingis to die with honour,prudently and bravely. Think how long you havegone through the old routine <strong>of</strong> food, and sleep, andanimal desire. Not only the thoughtful and the braveand wretched, but even the faithfulmay wish todie.' "1 The teachingfell on willing ears, till at timessuicide became almost a fashion among the highersocial circles.There was much that was very noble in their moralstandard ;but the impassiveness <strong>of</strong> their ideal was afatal error which marks at every turn the contrastbetween the <strong>Stoic</strong> and the Christian ethics. Theparadox that pain and losses are not evils not onlyoutraged common sense but weakened the motiveforce which was most needed for a movement <strong>of</strong> reform.The Gospel spirit has been called in our owntimes the "enthusiasm <strong>of</strong> charity." The <strong>Stoic</strong>s, as wehave seen, had laid stress already on the duty ;theirhero, in the words <strong>of</strong> Lucan, feltthat he was born notfor himself, but for the world at large, and turnedfrom the carnage <strong>of</strong> the battle-fieldto think what theforce there wasted might have done even by materialefforts in the service <strong>of</strong> humanity. There might be<strong>of</strong> self-philanthropy there ; might be even a spiritsacrifice, such as Seneca puts forward ;but enthusiasm'Ep. 77.


SENECA AND ST. PAUL, 177there could not be in a system which discouraged allemotional fervour as the sorry weakness <strong>of</strong> our lowernature. Our moralist, indeed, himself was tender andwarm-hearted, because his philosophy had failed tospoil the good qualities which nature gave him. Inhis hands the system lost in rigorous logic whatitgained in true humanity. He traces, for example,the portrait <strong>of</strong> the sage in which, true to the definition<strong>of</strong> his school, he treats compassion as unmanly weakness." To feel pain and grief for the misfortunes <strong>of</strong>another, to weep at the sight <strong>of</strong> suffering, is aweakness unworthy <strong>of</strong> the sage, for nothing shouldcloud his serenity or shake his firmness. Yet hewill readily do everything to which compassionprompts the souls that yield to it ;he will succourthe shipwrecked, welcome the exiled, and relievethe indigent. He will restore to the distractedmother her lost son, will ransom him from bondage ;like the gods, will let no misery pass unnoticed, butwill help those who need it most. His benevolencewill reach even to those who mainly suffer theirdeserts, but he will not make much ado or be unmannedat the sight <strong>of</strong> a poor beggar's emaciatedform or dirty rags. Only weak eyes get flushed andpainful at the sight <strong>of</strong> the iophthalmia <strong>of</strong> others."We have already seen indeed that there are manypassages in his letters which are quite inconsistentwith such teaching, pointing as they do both byprecept and example to tenderer sympathies and play'Clem. ii. 6.N


178 STOICISM.<strong>of</strong> natural emotions. He can only have acceptedthese repulsive <strong>Stoic</strong> maxims by putting a forcedmeaning on the words, and condemning love, pity,and resentment, when they are only passionate moodsand deaf to the voice <strong>of</strong> reason. No sect, he says,has shown more love to mankind than the <strong>Stoic</strong> ;andhere, <strong>of</strong> course, love passes into a higher stage <strong>of</strong> rationalaction, free from such taint <strong>of</strong> undisciplined emotion.With Seneca himself it tends to be a mere question<strong>of</strong> words, for all the affections that a peremptorydefinition has proscribed are re-admitted under athin disguise as reasonable states. But the theoryitself thus stands condemned as beingeither false tonature, or a truism stated in most unnatural language.Its whole influence must have tended to repressemotion and check the free expression <strong>of</strong> thesympathies <strong>of</strong> social life. It appealed to the intellectindeed to undertake the corresponding duties, thoughwithout the assistance <strong>of</strong> its best ally, but it had littlepower to move the hearts <strong>of</strong> weak and ignorant menby terms so hard and cold, so little coloured by theloveliness <strong>of</strong> Christian graces. It spoke with forceto the strong and self-contained, who felt no need<strong>of</strong> stimulus, and could be a law unto themselves,but it could scarcely fail to foster intellectual prideby raising man to the level <strong>of</strong> his God, by leavinghim nothing to look up to, nothing to depend on,with no distrust <strong>of</strong> his own power to defy the loudeststorms <strong>of</strong> fortune. That pride must have borderedclosely on contempt for weaker natures, who had nosuch confidence in their own clearness <strong>of</strong> judgment


SENECA AND ST. PAUL. 179or strength <strong>of</strong> will. Such a ring <strong>of</strong> scorn we noticedin the tones <strong>of</strong> the early school when it describedthe helpless folly <strong>of</strong> the mass <strong>of</strong> ignorant men, andsomething like it may be still heard in the words <strong>of</strong>Seneca when he " says, You have no cause to be angrywith them ; forgive rather, for ^they are all mad."These are surely most unlike the temper <strong>of</strong> those lastwords <strong>of</strong> Christ, with which they have sometimesbeen" compared, Father, forgive them, for theynot what they do."^De Benef. v. 17.N 2


l8cSTOICISM.CHAPTER XII.EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE.In quitting Seneca for Epictetus we pass from oneextreme <strong>of</strong> social standing to another :instead <strong>of</strong> thenoble Roman, sometime favourite <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong>fashion, we enter the cell <strong>of</strong> a poor slave who hadnothing to attract attention but his homely wisdomand uncompromising steadiness <strong>of</strong> moral purpose. Ofhis personal history little has been told us. A Phrygianby birth, he was in early life a slave <strong>of</strong> Epaphroditus,who was himself a freedman high in the goodgraces <strong>of</strong> the Emperor Nero. We are told that themaster <strong>of</strong> Epictetus broke his slave's leg in wanton"frolic, at which he only said, I told you, master, youwould break it." But the story is not confirmed byother writers, and it is more likely that he was lameand feeble from his birth. He had little kindness toexpect indeed from one whose character would leadhim to oppress the weak and truckle to the strong.Thus he tells us"in one place, Epaphroditus had ashoemaker whom he sold because he was good fornothing. This fellow by some good luck was boughtby one <strong>of</strong> Caesar's men, and became Cassar's shoemaker.You should have seen what respect Epaphrodituspaid to him. 'How does the good Felicion do,


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. l8lI pray ? ' Then ifany <strong>of</strong> us asked, ' What is masterdoing?' the answer was, he isconsulting aboutsomethingwith FeHcion. Had he not sold the manas good for nothing? Who then made him wise all atonce."^There was probably no sympathy for culture,almost certainly no love for the special doctrines<strong>of</strong> the Stoa in the confidant <strong>of</strong> Nero's revels, yethe gave his poor slave a liberal education, and senthim even to the lectures <strong>of</strong> the famous MusoniusRufus, one <strong>of</strong> the first teachers <strong>of</strong> the day. Butthe household <strong>of</strong> a wealthy Roman included itslibrarians, poets, rhetoricians, and philosophers, whoministered in various ways to the pride and vanity <strong>of</strong>the great men whom they served, and the master <strong>of</strong>Epictetus doubtless aimed no higher than the rest ;yet freedom came in time, we know not how, andfame enough to make it needful for him to retirefrom Rome when Domitian put philosophy under aban. He crossed the seas, and made Nicopolis hishome henceforth, living a life <strong>of</strong> cheerful poverty,withoutparade, and winning many a hearer to listento his homely words and weighty thoughts ; leaving,however, nothing in literary shape behind him morethan the fragments <strong>of</strong> his conversation, gathered upby the loving care <strong>of</strong> his friend and pupil, Arrian.Nothing can well be simpler and more unadorned,though the speaker <strong>of</strong>ten found a telling phrase orvivid figure to give force and illustration to his'Epict. Diss. i. 19 ; Long's translation.


lS2STOICISM.thought. To the same hand we also owe theEncheiridion," or Manual, in which we have the*'substance <strong>of</strong> his familiar talk compressed into a fewterse and pregnant pages, which form a sort <strong>of</strong> wholeduty <strong>of</strong> man according to the <strong>Stoic</strong> rule <strong>of</strong> life, andwhich was afterwards received as the most authoritativeexposition <strong>of</strong> the tenets <strong>of</strong> the sect.Perhaps the most striking feature <strong>of</strong> his characterwhich is thus brought before us is his deep andearnest piety, which finds expression in such passagesas this :— " If we had understanding, ought we to doanything else both jointly and severally than to singhymns and bless the Deity and to tell <strong>of</strong> His benefits ?Ought we not when we are digging, and ploughing,and eating, to sing this hymn to God ? 'Great is God,who has given us such implements with which weshall cultivate the earth :great is God, who has givenus hands, the power <strong>of</strong> swallowing, a stomach, imperceptiblegrowth, and the power <strong>of</strong> breathing whilewe sleep.' This is what we ought to sing on everyoccasion, and to sing the greatest and most divinehymn for giving us the faculty <strong>of</strong> comprehending thesethings and using a proper way. Well, then, sincemost <strong>of</strong> you have become blind, oughtbe some man to fillthere not tothis <strong>of</strong>fice, and on behalf <strong>of</strong> allwhat else can I do, ato sing the hymn to God ? Forlame, old man, than sing hymns to God ? If then Iwere a nightingale, I would do the part <strong>of</strong>a nightingaleif I were a swan, I would do like a swan. But:now I am a rational creature, and I ought to praiseGod : this is my work, I do it,nor will I desert this


EriCTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 183post SO long as I am allowed to keep it and !exhort you to join in this same song." ^IBut <strong>of</strong> speculations on the nature <strong>of</strong> the Divine wehave no trace in Epictetus. He speaks throughoutm persona) language, as <strong>of</strong> a Being distinct from theUniverse on which he acts, though sometimes headopts the popular terms <strong>of</strong> a polytheistic creed, butin a sense stripped <strong>of</strong> all its coarser adjuncts. Thus," As to piety towards the gods you must know thatthis is the chief thing, to have right opinions aboutthem, to think that they exist, and that they administerthe All well and justly; and you must fix yourselfin this principle to obey them, and to yield to them ineverything which happens, and voluntarily to follow itas being accomplished by the wisest intelligence.For ifyou do so, youwill never either blame thegods, nor will you accuse them <strong>of</strong> neglecting you." ^To the sense <strong>of</strong> the Fatherhood <strong>of</strong> God he tracesthe due estimate <strong>of</strong> human dignity and human duty." If a man should be able to assent to the doctrine ashe ought, that we are allsprung from God in anespecial manner, and that God is the father both <strong>of</strong>men and <strong>of</strong> gods, I suppose that he would never haveany ignoble or mean thoughts about himself But ifCeesar should adopt you, no one could endure yourarrogance and if; you know that you are the son <strong>of</strong>Zeus, will you not be elated ? Yet we do not so ;but since these two things are mingled in the generation<strong>of</strong> man, body in common with the animals, and>Diss. i. 16.=Ench. 31.


184 STOICISM.reason and intelligence in common with the gods,many incline to this kinship which is miserable andmortal ;and some few to that which is divine andhappy. The few have no mean or ignoble thoughtsabout themselves ;but with the many, it is quite contrary.For they say, What am I ? a poor miserableman, with my wretched bit <strong>of</strong> flesh. AV^retched, indeedbut ; you possess something better than yourbit <strong>of</strong> flesh.Why then do you neglect that whichisbetter, and why do you attach ^yourself to this?"Again, in another place he urges us to think<strong>of</strong> theduties which follow from this fellowship :—" Zeus hasplaced by every man a guardian, to whom he hascommitted the care <strong>of</strong> the man, a guardian who neversleeps, is never deceived. For to what better or morecareful guardian could he have entrusted each <strong>of</strong> us ?When then you have shut the doors and made darknesswithin, remember never to say that you are alone,for )'ou are not ;but God is within, and your daemoniswithin, and what need have they <strong>of</strong> light to see whatyou are doing ? To this God you ought to swear anoath just as the soldiers do to C^sar. But they whoare hired for pay swear to regard the safety <strong>of</strong> C^sarbefore all things and; you who have received so manyand such great favours, w^illyou not swear, or whenyou have sworn, will you not abide by your oath ?And what shall you swear ? Never to be disobedient,never to make any charges, never to find fault withanything that He has given, and never unwillinglyto'Diss. i. 3.


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 185do or to suffer anything that is necessary.Is this oathUke the soldier's oath ? The soldiers swear not toprefer any man to Coesar in this oath men swear to;honour themselves before all." ^But he insists even more emphatically on theresignationwhich should spring from the abiding sense <strong>of</strong>kinship with the "Deity. Dare to look up to Godand say, Deal with me for the future as thou wilt; I am<strong>of</strong> the same mind as thou art ;I am thine : I refusenothing that pleases thee : lead me where thou wilt :clothe me in any dress thou choosest is it thy will that:I should hold the <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> a magistrate, that I shouldbe in the condition <strong>of</strong> a private man, stay here oran exile, be poor, be rich ? I will make thy defenceto men in behalf <strong>of</strong> allthese conditions."— Again: "You see that Caesar appearswith great peace, that there are no longer enemies norbeto furnish usbattles, nor great associations <strong>of</strong> robbers nor <strong>of</strong> pirates,but we can travel at every hour, and sail from east towest. But can Csesar give us security from fever, also,from shipwreck, from fire, from earthquake, or fromlightning ? Can he from love, from sorrow, from envy ?He cannot. But the doctrine <strong>of</strong> philosophers promisesto give us peace even against these things. And whatdoes it say ? Men, if you will attend to me, whereveryou are, whatever you are doing, youwill not feelsorrow nor anger, nor compulsion nor hindrance, butyou will pass your lime without perturbations and freefrom everything. When man has this peace, not pro-'Diss. i. 14.= Ibid. ii. 16.


'l86STOICISM.claimed by Caesar, but by God through reason, is henot content when he is alone ? when he sees andreflects, now no evil can happen to me ;for methere is no robber, no earthquake, everythingisfull <strong>of</strong> peace, full <strong>of</strong> tranquillity:every way, every city,every meeting, neighbour, companion,is harmless.One person, whose business it is, supplies me withfood ;another with raiment ;another with perceptionsand preconceptions. And if he does notsupply what is necessary, he gives the signal forretreat, opens the door and says to you, 'Go.'Go whither ? To nothing terrible, but to the placefrom whence you came, to your friends and kinsmen,to the elements."!:— Or, again " God has no need <strong>of</strong> a spectator who isnot satisfied. He wants those who join in the festival,those who take part in the chorus, that they mayrather applaud, admire, and celebrate with hymns thesolemnity. But those who can bear no trouble, andthe cowardly. He will not unwillingly see absent fromthe great assembly ;for they did not when they werepresent behave as they ought to do at a festival, norfillup their place properly, but they lamented, foundfault with the Deity, fortune, their companions ;notseeing both what they had, and their own powers,which they received for contrary purposes, the powers<strong>of</strong> magnanimity, <strong>of</strong> a generous mind, manly spirit, andwhat we are now inquiring about, freedom.For whatpurpose then have I received these things ? To useDiss. iii. i^.


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 187them. How long? So long as He Avho has lentthem chooses."^Such sentiments, he thinks, ought to be strongenough to overrule all the weariness <strong>of</strong> life which mayincline men's thoughts to suicide." You might cometo me and say, Epictetus, we can no longer endure'being bound to this poor body, and feedingit andgiving it drink and rest and cleaning it,and for thesake <strong>of</strong> the body complying with the wishes <strong>of</strong> theseand <strong>of</strong> those. Are not these things indifferent andnothing to us ;and is not death no evil ? And arewe not in a manner kinsmen <strong>of</strong> God, and did we notcome from Him ? Allow us to depart from the placefrom whence we came ;allow us to be released atlast from these bonds by which we are bound andweighed down. Here there are robbers and thievesand courts <strong>of</strong> justice, and those who are namedtyrants, and think they have some power over us bymeans <strong>of</strong> the body and its possessions. Permit us toshow them that they have no power over any man ' ;'and I on my part would say, Friends, wait for God :when He shall give the signal and release you fromthis service, then go to Him ;but for the present endureto dwell in this place where He has put you :short indeed is this time <strong>of</strong> your dwelling here, andeasy to bear for those who are so disposed, for whattyrant, or what thief, or what courts <strong>of</strong> justice, areformidable to those who have thus considered asthings <strong>of</strong> no value the body and the possessions'Diss. iv. I.


1 88 STOICISM.<strong>of</strong> the body ? Wait, then ;do not depart without areason." ^The sense <strong>of</strong> the Fatherhood <strong>of</strong> God leadshim tothe large thought <strong>of</strong> human brotherhood, <strong>of</strong> which hespeaks, like Seneca, in most emphatic language :—"When some one asked, how may a man eat acceptablyto the gods, he answered : If he can eat justly'and contentedly, and with equanimity, and temperatelyand orderly, will it not be also acceptable to thegods ? But when you have asked for warm water andthe slave has not heard, or if he did hear, has broughtonly tepid water, or he is not even found to be in thehouse, then not to be vexed or to burst with passion, isnot this acceptable to the godsman endure such persons as this slave ? Slave your-will you not bear with your own brother, who hasself,? How then shall aZeus for his progenitor, and is like a son from thesame seeds and <strong>of</strong> the same descent from above?But ifyou have been put in any such higher place,will you immediately make yourself a tyrant ? Willyou not remember who you are, and whom you rule ?that they are kinsmen, that they are brethren by'<strong>of</strong> Zeus ?' But Inature, that they are the <strong>of</strong>tspringhave purchased them, and they have not purchased'me.' Do you see in what direction you are looking,that it is towards the earth, towards the pit, that it istowards these wretched laws <strong>of</strong> dead men ? but towxrdsthe laws <strong>of</strong> the gods you are not looking." -The same thought leads him also to give a wider'Diss. i. 9.* Ibid. i. 13.


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 189—range to the conceptions <strong>of</strong> nationality and race: " Ifthe things are true which are said by the philosophersabout the kinship between God and man, what elseremains for man to do than what Socrates did ?Never, in reply to the question to what country youbelong, say that you are an Athenian or Corinthian,but that you are a citizen <strong>of</strong> the world. . . He who hasobserved with intelligence the administration <strong>of</strong> theworld, and has learned that the greatest and supremeand the most comprehensive communityis that whichiscomposed <strong>of</strong> men and God, and that from Godhave descended the seeds, not only to my father andgrandfather, but to all beings which are generated onthe earth, and particularly to rational beings — whyshould not such a man call himself a citizen <strong>of</strong> theworld, why not a son <strong>of</strong> God, and whyshould he beafraid <strong>of</strong> anything which happens among men ?kinship with Caesar enoughIsto enable us to live insafety, and above contempt and without any fear atall ? and to have God for your maker and father andguardian, shall not this release us from sorrows andfears"?!But the strength <strong>of</strong> this piety <strong>of</strong> Epictetus appearsnowhere more markedly than in the picture which hedraws <strong>of</strong> the philosopher as a missionary bound by thestrong sense <strong>of</strong> a religious duty to spread abroad theknowledge <strong>of</strong> :— God's will. It was thus Diogenes actedin old days " Did Diogenes love nobody, who wasso kind and so much a lover <strong>of</strong> all, that for mankind'Diss. i. 9.


190 STOICISM.in general he willinglyundertook so much labour andbodily suflferings.He did love mankind, but how ?As became a minister <strong>of</strong> God, at the same time caringfor men, and being also subjectto God. For thisreason all the earth was his country, and no particularplace ;and when he was taken prisoner he did notregret Athens nor his associates and friends there, buteven he became familiar with the pirates and tried toimprove them ;and being sold afterwards he lived inCorinth as before at Athens ;and he would havebehaved the same if he had gone to the country <strong>of</strong>the Perrhsebi." 1It is thus also that the true philosopher must act inlater days :—" The true Cynic must know that he issent a messenger from Zeus to men about good andbad things, to show them that they have wandered,and are seeking the substance <strong>of</strong> good and evil whereit is not, but where it isthey never think, and that heis a spy, as Diogenes was carried <strong>of</strong>f to Philip after thebattle <strong>of</strong> Chaeronea as a spy. For, in fact, the Cynicis a spy <strong>of</strong> the things which are good for men andwhich are evil, and it is his duty to examine carefullyand to come and report truly, and not to bestruck with terror, so as to point out as enemiesthose who are not enemies, nor in any other wayto be perturbed by appearances nor confounded."Or, again " The : thing is great, it is mystical, not acommon thing, nor is itgiven to every man. But noteven wisdom perhapsisenoughto enable a man to'Diss. iii. 24.


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 191take care <strong>of</strong> youths ;a man must have also a certainreadiness and fitness for this purpose, and a certainquality <strong>of</strong> body, and, above all things, he must haveGod to advise him to occupy this <strong>of</strong>fice, as God advisedSocrates to occupy the place <strong>of</strong> one who confuteserror, Diogenes the <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> royalty and repro<strong>of</strong>, and^the <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> teaching precepts."In the assurance <strong>of</strong> this commission from on highthe missionary Cynic will bear with cheerfulness thehardships <strong>of</strong> his lot, and they are many :— " Reflectmore carefully, know thyself, consult the divinity,without God attempt nothing, for if He shall adviseyou (to do this or anything) be assured that He intendsyou to become great or to receive many blows.For this very amusing quality is conjoined to a Cynic ;he must, be flogged like an ass, and when he is floggedhe must love those who flog him, as if he were thefather <strong>of</strong> all and the brother <strong>of</strong> all. . . . Do youthink that if a man comes to a Cynic and saluteshim, that he is the Cynic's friend, and that the Cynicwill think him worthy <strong>of</strong> receiving a Cynic into hishouse ? So that, ifyou please, reflect on this also,rather look round for some convenient dunghill onwhich you shall bear your fever, and which will shelteryou from the north wind, that you may not be frozen.But you seem to me to wish to go into some man'shouse and to be v/ell fed there for a time. Why, then,do you think <strong>of</strong> attempting so great a thing (as thelife <strong>of</strong> a Cynic?") 2'Diss. iii. 21.^ Ibid. iii. 22.


192 STOICISM.He will hold himself alo<strong>of</strong> from public life in theform <strong>of</strong> politics or civil duties which will seem unworthy<strong>of</strong> his interest. " If you ple.ise, ask me alsoif a Cynic shall engage in the administration <strong>of</strong> theState. Fool, do you seek a greater form <strong>of</strong> administrationthan that in which he isengaged ? Do youask if he shall appear among the Athenians and saysomething about the revenues and supplies, he whomust talk with all men, alike with Athenians, alikewith Corinthians, alike with Romans, not about supplies,nor yet about revenues, nor about peace or warbut about happiness and unhappiness, about goodfortune and bad fortune, about slavery and freedom ?When a man has undertaken the administration <strong>of</strong>such a state, do you ask me also if he shall govern ?again I will say to you. Fool, what greater governmentshall he exercise than that which he exercisesnow?"iHe will have to abstain also from the blessings <strong>of</strong>domestic life, such as other men find natural andinnocent. " Said the young man, ' Shall marriage andthe begetting <strong>of</strong> children as a chief duty be undertakenby the Cynic ? ''If you grant me a community<strong>of</strong> wise men,' Epictetus replies, ' perhapsno man willreadily apply himself to the Cynic practice. For onwhose account should he undertake this manner <strong>of</strong>life ? However, if we suppose that he does, nothingwill prevent him from marrying and begetting children,for his wife will be another like himself, and his'Diss. ili. 22.


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 193father-in-law another like himself, and his childrenwill be brought up like himself But in the presentstate <strong>of</strong> things, which is like that <strong>of</strong> an army placedin battle order, is it not fit that the Cynic should,without any distraction, be employed only on theministration <strong>of</strong> God, able to go about among men,not tied down to the common duties <strong>of</strong> mankind, norentangled in the ordinary relations <strong>of</strong> life, which ifhe neglects, he will not maintain the character <strong>of</strong> anhonourable and good man ?and if he observes them,he will lose the character <strong>of</strong> the messenger and spy*and herald <strong>of</strong> God.' Yes, but Crates took a wife.'*You are speaking <strong>of</strong> a circumstance which arose fromlove and <strong>of</strong> a woman who was another Crates. Butwe are inquiring about ordinary marriages and thosewhich are free from distractions, and making this inquirywe do not find the affair <strong>of</strong> marriage in thisstate <strong>of</strong> the world a thing which is especially suited tothe Cynic.'"!Yet these counsels are intended only for the menengaged in missionary work, for others may enjoy thesocial pleasures that they innocently can if they seethat their will is not enfeebled or entangled by them." As on a voyage when the vessel has reached a port,ifyou go out to get water it is an amusement by theway to pick up a shell-fish or some bulb, but yourthoughts ought to be directed to the ship, and youought to be constantly watching if the captain shouldcall, and then you must throw away all those things,•Diss, iii, 22.O


STOICISM.J A rM^rhed into the shipto. you may not be bound and pU^hed^^like sheep ;so in life also .f thae g ^ ^^.^^^instead <strong>of</strong> a little bulbftom taking=;"d;*^yJ,,, ",/ „ ^^ to thethere will be nothing t° .P'^'^fU). But if the cap- * f^4tt regatd toship, and leave all *°=^ '^^^^j „en go far fromthem. But if you -« f>J^„,ake default.-^the ship,lestwhen 5-°" "^^a ^'.eadyto resigntheI„ anycasewemu^be* ;^^ ^^^ ^^^^ ^^ f„,blessings which Gods «^^^^^ ,^^j „^awhile."Neversay about anyth.g^^^^, ^^but say I have restored r. Is you^^^^^ ^^^ ^^^has been'-'«^^^/;re,tatebeen taken frombeen restored, ^as your^^^^, .But,ou? Has not then thrs been a o^^^L who has takenl^^^oZ^^,,the giver de-,hat is it to you take^^^^'^^^ „,y,„o„ you,rf<strong>of</strong>Uafa^ht-g'which belongs to another, astravellers do with their mn.' - -^^ to ourBut, indeed, *-^.f;'7„t7his moralist. Nohumanweakness m*lPf;=^^,,„„trol more sternlywhere is the rigour <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> se ^^^.^.^^stated than by Epic'etus and most^^ ^^^^paradoxes <strong>of</strong> *-;^°; ^^ Jvil in his sight .vhichThose thmgs alone are goo^^ ^^^^^^Be within our power to do or shun t^ ^^^^ ^^^ .„indifferentincluesmo^^owat^mtheir common Ufe , tne wm c^ 2 Ibid. II.»Encli., 7-


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 195the happiness <strong>of</strong> any moral agent; desire, regret,complaint, or pity are only forms <strong>of</strong> misplaced weaknessin regard to all the gifts and accidents <strong>of</strong>fortune." Remember that in lifeyou ought to behave as ata banquet. Suppose that somethingis carried roundand isopposite to you. Stretch out your hand andtake a portion with decency. Suppose that itpassesby you. Do not detain it.Suppose that it is notyet come to you. Do not send your desire forwardto it,but wait till it is opposite to you. Do so withrespect to children, so with respect to a wife, so withrespect to magisterial <strong>of</strong>fices, so with respect tcwealth, and you will be some time a worthy partner<strong>of</strong> the banquets <strong>of</strong> the gods. But ifyou take none<strong>of</strong> the things which are set before you, and evendespise them, then you will be not only a fellowbanqueterwith the gods, but also a partner withthem in power. For by acting thus Diogenes andHeracleitus and those like them were deservedlydivine, and were so called."^Another passage consistently extends this absence<strong>of</strong> emotion to the losses or apparent misfortunes <strong>of</strong>our fellows :—'' When you see a person weeping insorrow either when a child goes abroad or when he isdead, or when the man has lost his property, takecare that the appearance do not hurry you away withit as if he were suffering in external things. Butstraightway make a distinction in your mind, and beEnch., 15.O 2


STOICISM196U k that which has happeneditin readhaessto say, is not t^^^ ^^.^^ ^^^^^^^^that afflicts this ^^-^^> /' thing which afflicts thebut itis the op— bout th.s g^ ^^ ^^^^.^^.^^ ^^tnan. So far as words, then a^^^ ^^_^ .^ ^^^^^^^show h- f^X C' ake care that you do notlament with him. o^^^lament internally also __^^j^^;„ hisThe leading tenets <strong>of</strong> '\'^° ;^^^„,^^ instinctsuncompromising ^^^langnagedjicAe.^^^^^^^<strong>of</strong> the heart, and are ialse ^^^^^ .^ ^^^ ^^^^^ „{mony <strong>of</strong> human nature.throughout therearrogance or "ff-'^^--^^"^ „';„ his words. Iti, a ring <strong>of</strong> genome conv c^°^^^^^ ^ S,„ecanray move our =?'«" ^^ le surrounded by alldeclaim in praise <strong>of</strong> pove.ty^^^^^ ^^^.^^^^ ^t.he signs <strong>of</strong> l-y -J^;^t fine theories about thetimes might well df "


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 197nothing like the hair-shirt, and dirt, and maceration<strong>of</strong> many a later hermit. "If a Cynic is an object otcompassion, he seems to be a beggar all ; personsturn away from him, all are <strong>of</strong>fended with him : forneither ought he to appear dirty, so that he shall notalso in this respect drive away men ;but his veryroughness ought to be clean and attractive." ^Or, again, " We ought not by the appearance <strong>of</strong>the body to deter the multitude from philosophy;but as in other things a philosopher should showhimself cheerful and tranquil, so also he should inthe things that relate to the body. See, ye men, thatI have nothing, that I want nothing ;see how I amwithout a house, and without a city,and an exile, ifithappens to be so, and without a hearth, I. live morefree from trouble and more happily than all <strong>of</strong> noblebirth, and than the rich. But look at my poor bodyalso, and observe that it is not injured by my hardway <strong>of</strong> living. But if a man says this to me whohas the appearance and face <strong>of</strong> a condemned man,what god shall persuade me to approach philosophy,if it makes men such persons ? Far from it, I wouldnot choose to do so even if I were going to become awise man. I indeed would rather that a young man,who ismaking his first movements towards philosophy,should come to me with his hair carefully trimmedthan with it dirty and rough, for there is seen in hima certain notion <strong>of</strong> beauty and a desire <strong>of</strong> that whichisbecoming ;and where he supposesit to be, therealso he strives that it shall be." -'Diss. iii. 22.^ Ibid, iv. II.


198 STOICISM.Yet there is no doubt upon the whole that EpictetusIS a Cynic rather than a <strong>Stoic</strong> he will allow;nocompromise between the rigour <strong>of</strong> theory and theclaims <strong>of</strong> common sense ;he will do nothing tos<strong>of</strong>ten the hard outlines <strong>of</strong> his airdOeia his ; teachingis an ineffectual protest against the richness andmanysidedness <strong>of</strong> civilized life. In his own caseits sternness and rigour are disguised by the modesty<strong>of</strong> his language and the beauty <strong>of</strong> his devotionalfervour ;but it was powerless to move the masses,for it had no charm to heal the wounds and soothethe sufferings <strong>of</strong> stricken manhood, while with thestrong and self-contained itmight easily feed a sort<strong>of</strong> Pharisaic pride which would thank God that itwas not as other men. The following is thedying speech which Epictetus puts into the Cynic'smouth :—"If death surprises me when I am busy aboutthese things, it isenoughmy hands to God and say : Thefor me if I can stretch outmeans which I havereceived from- thee for seeing thy administration <strong>of</strong>the world and followingit I have not neglected: Ihave not dishonoured thee by my acts : see how Ihave used my perceptions have I ever blamed thee ?:have I been discontented with anything that happens,or wished it to be otherwise ? have I wished to transgressthe relations <strong>of</strong> things ? That thou hast givenme life, I thank thee for what thou hast given: solong as I have used the things which are thine I amcontent ;take them back and place them whereverthou mayest choose ;for thine were all things, thou


EPICTETUS, OR STOICISM IN THE COTTAGE. 199gavest them to me. Is it not enough to depart mthis state <strong>of</strong> mind, and what Ufe is better and morebecoming than that <strong>of</strong> a man who is in this state <strong>of</strong>mind, and what end is more happy? " ^'Diss. iv. 10.


200 STOICISM.CHAPTER XIIIMARCUS AURELIUS ANTONINUS, OR STOICISMTHRONE.ON THEIt may seem a long step from the cottage to thethrone, from the slave-born Epictetus to MarcusAurelius, the philosophic Emperor <strong>of</strong> the great Romanworld, but there should be no respect <strong>of</strong> persons inreligion, and philosophy bythis time had becomereligious in its principles and tones. It had ceasedto care much for abstract theory or dialectic, andaspired almost exclusively to guide the consciences <strong>of</strong>earnest men. In no one is this tendency moremarked than in the gentle prince whose character,far more even thanmuster roll <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> worthies.A few hnes mayhis l<strong>of</strong>ty station, graced the longbe useful first to bring before ourmemories the course <strong>of</strong> his career and the conditions<strong>of</strong> his age. He was not born in the purple, like asovereign <strong>of</strong> modern days, nor exposed from the veryfirst to the temptations <strong>of</strong> the court, but he soon roseto high estate, and passed as an adopted son into thefamily <strong>of</strong> Antoninus, whose virtuesmade him knownto later history under the name <strong>of</strong> Pius. No painswere spared to train him worthily for the responsibilities<strong>of</strong> future greatness. Besides the watchful tenderness<strong>of</strong> his home circle, and the ripe experience <strong>of</strong>


STOICISM ON THE THRONE.20IAntoninus, he pr<strong>of</strong>ited by the intercourse and guidance<strong>of</strong> the first teachers <strong>of</strong> the day, whose lessonsfell on willing ears.But he soon passed from lighterstudies and from purely literary themes, to the graverthoughts <strong>of</strong> an inquiring spirit, anxious to drink deeplyat the sources <strong>of</strong> all heathen knowledge. The earnestwords which he pennedtowards the close <strong>of</strong> hiscareer, in the journal meant only for his personal use,may serve to show how strongly he recognised hisobligations to his early mentors, and how varied werethe influences which helped to form his character andenrich his thought." From my mother [I learned]piety and beneficence, and abstinence, not only fromevil deeds, but even from evil thoughts and; further,simplicity in my way <strong>of</strong> living, far removed from thehabits <strong>of</strong> the rich.^ From Diognetus tohave become intimate with philosophy ;and to havebeen a hearer, first <strong>of</strong> Bacchius, then <strong>of</strong> Tandasisand Marcianus ;and to have desired a plank bedand skin, and whatever else <strong>of</strong> the kind belongs tothe Grecian discipline.- From Rusticus I receivedthe impression that my character required improvementand discipline ;and from him I learnednot to be led astray to sophistic emulation, nor towriting on speculative matters. . . . nor to showingmyself <strong>of</strong>f as a man who practises much discipline, ordoes benevolent acts in order to make a display. . .;and I am indebted to him for being acquaintedwith the discourses <strong>of</strong> Epictetus, which he com-* " Tlie Thoughts <strong>of</strong> M. Aurelius Antoninus " ; translated byG. Long, i. 3.'"Thoughts,"i. 6.


202 STOICISM.municated to me out <strong>of</strong> his own collection.^ FromApollonius I learned .... to see clearly in a livingexample that the same man can be both resolute andyielding, and not peevish in giving his instruction;and to have had before my eyes a man who clearlyconsidered his experience and his skill in expoundingphilosophical principles as the smallest <strong>of</strong> his merits.^From Sextus, a benevolent disposition, and theexample <strong>of</strong> a family governed in a fatherly manner,and the idea <strong>of</strong> living conformably to nature : and•gravity without affectation and to tolerateignorant persons.^ From Fronto I learned to observewhat envy, and duplicity, and hypocrisy are in atyrant, and that generally those amongus who arecalled Patricians are rather deficient in paternalaffection.* From Severus I learned to love mykin, and to love truth, and to love justice, and throughhim I learned to know Thrasea, Helvidius, Cato, Dion,Brutus ;and from him I received the idea <strong>of</strong> a polityin which there is the same law for all, a polityadministered with regard to equal rights and equalfreedom <strong>of</strong> speech, and the idea <strong>of</strong> a kingly governmentwhich respects most <strong>of</strong> all the freedom <strong>of</strong> thegoverned ;I learned from him also consistency andundeviating steadiness in my regard for philosophy ;and a disposition to do good, and to give to othersreadily, and to cherish good hopes, and to believethat I am loved by my friends.^ From Maximus I'"Thoughts,"!. 7.3"Thoughts," i. 9.5"Thoughts," i. 14.2""Thoughts,""Thoughts,"i. 8.i. 11.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 203learned self-government, and not to be led asidr.by anything ;and cheerfulness in all circumstancesas well as in illness, and a just admixture in themoral character <strong>of</strong> sweetness and dignity, and to dowhat was set before me without complaining. Iobserved that everybody believed that he thoughtas he spoke, and that in all that he did he never hadany bad intention ;and he never showed amazementand surprise, and was never in a hurry, and never put<strong>of</strong>f doing a thing, nor was perplexed nor dejected,nor did he ever laugh to disguise his vexation,nor, on the other hand, was he ever passionateor suspicious.^ To the godsI am indebted forhaving good grandfathers, good parents, a goodsister, good teachers, good associates, good kinsmenand friends, nearly everything good. ... I am thankfulthat I was subjected to a ruler and a father whowas able to take away all pride from me, and tobring me to the knowledge that it is possible for aman to live in a palace without wanting either guardsor embroidered dresses, or torches and statues, andsuch-like show ;but that it is in such a man's powerto bring himself very near to the fashion <strong>of</strong> a privateperson, without being for this reason either meanerin thought, or more remiss in action, with respect tothe things which must be done for the public interestin a manner that befits a ruler." 2But Marcus Aurelius had little leisure to becomethe studious recluse, to which perhaps his tastesinchned him most. Marked out in early life for the>"Thoughts," i. 15.2"Thoughts,"!. 17.


204 STOICISM.succession to the throne by Antoninus, he was trainedunder his experienced eye to bear the burden <strong>of</strong> thecares <strong>of</strong> state. On the emperor's death he shared thethrone awhile with Lucius Verus, but after a few yearsbecame the sole sovereign <strong>of</strong> the Roman world, withall the onerous responsibilities <strong>of</strong> absolute power.The task that lay before him was enormous. Theefficiency <strong>of</strong> every part <strong>of</strong> the greatmachine <strong>of</strong>government depended on his watchfulness and wisdom;from him the rank and the authority <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong>ficialclasses were derived, and to him in every case <strong>of</strong> doubtthey naturally turned for sanction and for guidance.The boundaries <strong>of</strong> the Empire stretched to the furthestlimits <strong>of</strong> the civilized world, and all the lands whichitincluded looked to the Csesar on the throne as theone central source <strong>of</strong> law and order.Marcus Aureliuswas indeed no brilliant ruler, and had no high ambitionwith far-reaching plans, but he sincerely wishedto make his subjects happy, and spent in their serviceanxious and laborious years. His gentle nature wasbest suited for the quiet days <strong>of</strong> peace when he couldfind leisure among the cares <strong>of</strong> civil government forhis philanthropic schemes, could succour the poor andneedy, provide endowments for the orphaned, andsee that every class <strong>of</strong> suitors had prompt justicedone them. But untoward destiny required him tospend the best years <strong>of</strong> his life in an inglorious warfarewith enemies unknown to fame. Some passionateimpulse seemed to pass like a fiery cross along theborders, and barbarous hordes came swarming upwith fury to tlie attack, and threatened to burst the


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 20$barriers raised against them. The Parthians had beenhumbled for a time by Trajan, but were soon to showthemselves in arms once more. The Moors <strong>of</strong> Africawere on the move, and before long were sweepingover Spain with havoc and desolation in their track.The Caledonians <strong>of</strong> the far West were irritated morethan frightened by the long lines <strong>of</strong> wall and dykewhich had been built to shut them in, and their untamedfierceness was enough to make the Romantroops retire before the children <strong>of</strong> the mist. Fromthe mouth <strong>of</strong> the Dniester to where the Rhine bearsto the sea the waters <strong>of</strong> all its tributary rivers a multitude<strong>of</strong> restless tribes with uncouth names andunknown antecedents, Teutonic, Slave, Finnish, andTartar, were roaming in hostile guise along thenorthern frontiers, and ready to burst in at everyunguarded point. ^ This was not all :earlyin hisreign great floods and famine had spread desolationthrough the centre <strong>of</strong> the Empire ;later on thesoldiers who came back from the wars in Parthiabrought with them the fatal seeds <strong>of</strong> plague, andspread them rapidly through all the countries <strong>of</strong> theWest. The famous Galen was called in to try allthat medical experience and skill could do, but hisefforts failed to check the ravages <strong>of</strong> pestilence, orbring its victims back to health. The scourge passedon with steady course from land to land, leaving atrack <strong>of</strong> panic and desolation where it stalked along.To this long list <strong>of</strong> misfortunes should be added thetreasonous disloyalty which cast a cloud <strong>of</strong> suspicion'Cf." The Age <strong>of</strong> the Antonines."


206 STOICISM.and anxiety over the last years <strong>of</strong> his Ufe. One <strong>of</strong>his best generals, Avidius Cassius, was known to havelong chafed at what he thought the need <strong>of</strong> a strongerhand to grapple with abuses and misgovernment, andnow, at a false rumour <strong>of</strong> the emperor's death, herose with his army in the East and proclaimed himselfa sovereign ruler. The movement was short-livedindeed, but the danger had been very real, and therewere ugly suspicions <strong>of</strong> disloyalty in the Senate andthe <strong>of</strong>ficial circles, which did not spare even the wife<strong>of</strong> the emperor himself There was enough in theconditions <strong>of</strong> the age to task the energies <strong>of</strong> the mostresourceful and resolute <strong>of</strong> rulers, but it seemed astrange irony <strong>of</strong> fortune which set the sensitive andtender-hearted Antoninus to the roughest work <strong>of</strong>politics and war. He was perhaps too unsuspiciousand forbearing to cleanse the Augean stables <strong>of</strong>corruption in the public service ;he had too little <strong>of</strong>the soldier's tastes to make himself a name in history,like Trajan, as a great strategist or conqueror.But at least his lessons <strong>of</strong> philosophy had taught himnot to spare himself when duty called. He was notcontent to leave the distant legions to make headagainst the savage foes ;he would not depute to lessermen the post <strong>of</strong> danger when the Empire's safetyseemed at stake, but he left the court and Rome, andall the comforts which his quietmeditative natureprized, and faced the worst inclemencies <strong>of</strong> wintry warfareon the frontiers, where more than half his standingarmy was encamped for years, or was doing battlewith the swarms <strong>of</strong> multitudinous invaders. While


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 207there engaged in uncongenial duties, amid the clash<strong>of</strong> arms and the bustle <strong>of</strong> the camp, he found solaceand distraction in the quiet hours <strong>of</strong> loneliness, whenhe could muse upon the problems <strong>of</strong> life, and thehigh themes <strong>of</strong> duty, and the mysteries that lie beforeand after.We maystill read the meditations written byhim in his journal at such times ; they are simple andunaffected in their style, intended probably to meetno eye but his own, but nowhere else is the moranty<strong>of</strong> paganism couched in so pure and high and reverenta spirit.The distinctive features <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>creed have been described already at sufficient length,and among them the less pleasing qualities whichseemed to be the natural outcome <strong>of</strong> the system,though <strong>of</strong>ten toned down and disguised by writerswhose instincts perhaps were better than their logic.It must be <strong>of</strong> interest<strong>of</strong> the emperor's aspirationsto us to note how far the idealcould be freed from thedisfigurements <strong>of</strong> such unlovely tenets <strong>of</strong> the schoolwhich he pr<strong>of</strong>essed to follow.The Pantheism <strong>of</strong> the earher thinkers was expressedat times, as we have seen, with a glow <strong>of</strong>lyric and devotional fervour which reads like thelanguage <strong>of</strong> trueprayer,and the following strains <strong>of</strong>piety, enthusiastic as they are, might possibly belongto such a creed :—"Everything harmonizes with mewhich is harmonious to thee, O Universe. Nothingfor me is too early nor too late, which is in due timefor thee. Everything is fruit to me, which thy seasonsbring, O Nature : from thee are all :things in thee


2o8STOICISM.are all things : to thee all things return. The poetsays, ' Dear city <strong>of</strong> Cecrops,' and wilt thou notsay, 'Dear city <strong>of</strong> Zeus? 'i "' The earth loves theshower,' and 'the solemn tether loves;' and theuniverse loves to make whatever is about to be. Isay then to the universe, that I love as thou lovest.And is not this too said that this or that lovesto be produced? "2 The same may be said also <strong>of</strong>the striking passage in which he dwells on the richvariety <strong>of</strong> natural beauty with a delicacy and refinementwhich <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> hitherto had done little toencourage " Even the : things which follow afterthe things which are produced according to naturecontain something pleasing and attractiveFigs, when they are quite ripe, gape open ;and in theripe olives the very circumstance <strong>of</strong> their being nearto rottenness adds a peculiar beauty to the fruit.And the ears <strong>of</strong> corn bending down, and the lion'seyebrows, and the foam which flows from the mouth<strong>of</strong> wild boars, and many other things .... help toadorn them, and they please the mind ;so that if aman should have a feeling and deeper insight withrespect to the things which are produced in theuniverse, there ishardly one <strong>of</strong> those which followby way <strong>of</strong> consequence which will not seem to himto be in a manner disposed so as to give pleasure.And so he will see even the real gaping jaws <strong>of</strong> wildbeasts with no less pleasure than those which paintersand sculptors show by imitation, and in an old womanand an old man he willbe able to see a certain ma-' " Thoughts," iv. 23.2 " Thoughts," x. 21.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 209turity and comeliness, and the attractive loveliness<strong>of</strong> young persons he will be able to look on withchaste eyes ;and many such things will presentthemselves, not pleasing to every man, but to himonly who has become truly familiar with Nature andher works. "^But his child-like trust and reverence find voicemore <strong>of</strong>ten in the terms which no Pantheist couldconsistently adopt, as when he says, " To go awayfrom among men, if there are gods, is not a thing tobe afraid <strong>of</strong>, for the godswill not involve thee inevil ;but if, indeed, they do not exist, or if theyhave no concern about human affairs, what is it to meto live in a universe devoid <strong>of</strong> gods or devoid <strong>of</strong> providence? But in truth they do exist, and they docare for human things, and they have put all themeans in man's power to enable him not to fallinto real evils." ^"Whydost thou not wait intranquillity for thy end, whether it is extinction orremoval to another state ? And until that timecomes, what is sufficient ? Why, what else than tovenerate the gods and bless them, and to do good tomen, and to practise tolerance and self-restraint ;butas to everything which is beyond the limits <strong>of</strong> thy poorflesh and breath, to remember that this is neitherthine nor in thy power. "^He has no abstruse theories about the nature <strong>of</strong>the heavenly beings, but his heart and reason tellhim that they are, and that isenough for reverence»"Thoughts," iii. 2. 2"Thoughts,"" Thoughts," V. S3.ii. 11.


2IOSTOICISM.and love."To those who ask,— 'Where hast thou seenthe gods, or how dost thou comprehend that theyexist and so worshippest them ? ' I answer, in the firstplace, that they may be seen even with the eyes ;inthe second place, neither have I seen even my ownsoul, and yet I honour it. Thus then with respectto the gods, from what I constantly experience <strong>of</strong>their power, from this I comprehend that they exist,and I venerate them."iThanks to their inspiration virtuous life is possible"for man. I thank the gods .... that I receivedclear and frequent impressions about living accordingto nature, and what kind <strong>of</strong> life that is, so that, s<strong>of</strong>ar as depended on the gods, and their gifts,andhelp, and inspirations, nothing hindered me fromforthwith living according to nature, though I stillfall short <strong>of</strong> itthrough my own fault, and throughnot observing the admonitions <strong>of</strong> the gods, and, Imay almost ^say, their direct instructions."They bear even with the evil, and bless them withtheir mercies." The gods, who are immortal, are notvexed because during so long a time they must toleratecontinually men such as they are, and so many<strong>of</strong> them bad, and besides this, they also take care <strong>of</strong>them in all ways.so soon, art thou wearied <strong>of</strong> enduring the bad, andBut thou, who art destined to endthis too when thou art one <strong>of</strong> them ?"^They, or He, forhis language here as elsewhere is\mdecided, welcome the penitent with hopes <strong>of</strong> pardon.'"Thoughts," xii. 28. ^"Thoughts,"!. 17.3"Thoughts," vii. 70.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 211"If thou didst ever see a hand cut <strong>of</strong>f, or a foot,or a head, lying anywhere apart from the rest <strong>of</strong> thebody, such does a man make himself, as far as hecan, who is not content with what happens, andseparates himself from others, or does anythingunsocial. Suppose that thou hast detached thyselffrom the natural unity— for thou wast made by naturea part, but now thou hast cut thyself <strong>of</strong>f— yet herethere is this beautiful provision, that it is in thy poweragain to unite thyself. God has allowed this to noother part, after it has been separated and cutasunder, to come together again. But consider thekindness by which He has distinguished man, for Hehas putit in his power not to be separated at allfrom the universal ;and when he has been separatedHe has allowed him to return and to be united, andto resume his place as a part."^This leads him to what seems a new conception <strong>of</strong>the holiness which man may reach, something distinctfrom the self-conscious pride <strong>of</strong> heathen virtue,and more akin to saintlier ideals, as resting on a newmotive which ancient moralists had rarely urged." Reverence that which is best in the universe, andthis is that which makes use <strong>of</strong> all things and directsall things. And in like manner also reverence thatwhich is best in thyself, and this is <strong>of</strong> the same kindas that. "2Or, more "explicitly, There remains that which ispeculiar to the good man, to be pleased and contentwith what happens, and with the thread which is'"Thoughts," viii. 34.P 2^"Thoutrhts," v. 21.


212 STOICISM.spun for him, and not to defile the divinity which isplanted in his breast, nor disturb itby a crowd <strong>of</strong>images, but to preserve it tranquil, followingit obedientlyas a god, neithersaying anything contrary tothe truth, nor doing anything contrary to justice.And if all men refuse to believe that he lives a simple,modest, and contented life, he is neither angrywith any <strong>of</strong> them, nor does he deviate from the waywhich leads to the end <strong>of</strong> life, to which a man oughtto come pure, tranquil, ready to depart, and with-,out any compulsion perfectly reconciled to his lot."iYet he does not count himself " to have apprehended,or to be already perfect.""Thou wilt soondie, and thou art not yet simple, nor free from perturbations,nor without suspicion <strong>of</strong> being hurt byexternal things, nor kindly disposed towards all;nor dost thou yet place wisdom only in actingjustly. "2 " Simple and modest is the work <strong>of</strong> philosophy,"he says elsewhere "; draw me not aside toinsolence and "^ pride. This is in a different strainfrom the <strong>of</strong>fensive language <strong>of</strong> Chrysippus, who isIreported to have said that "the wise man was asnecessary to Zeus as Zeus to the wise man."The very strength <strong>of</strong> the religious convictions <strong>of</strong> thisearnest thinker leads him to deny the reality <strong>of</strong> much"that common sense calls evil. If there was anythingevil, the gods would have providedfor thisalso, that it should be altogether in a man's powernot to fall into it. Now that which does not make a1i6. ^"Thoughts," iii. 37."Thoughts," iv.3 " Thoughts," ix. 29.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 213man worse, how can it make a man's life worse ?But neither through ignorance, nor having the knowledge,but not the power to guard against or correctthese things, is itpossible that the nature <strong>of</strong> theuniverse has overlooked them ;nor is itpossiblethat it has made so great a mistake, either throughwant <strong>of</strong> power or want <strong>of</strong> skill, that good and evilshould happen indiscriminately to the good and thebad. But death, certainly, and life,honour and dishonour,pain and pleasure, all these things equallyhappen to good men and bad, being things whichmake us neither better nor worse, therefore, theyare neither good nor evil."^ The optimism mayseem indeed unnaturally strained, and to be fatallyin conflict with the experience <strong>of</strong> our common manhood,but at least we have here no arrogance <strong>of</strong> paradox,no l<strong>of</strong>ty airs <strong>of</strong> scorn for the weakness and thesuffering which cannot freely breathe in those serenerheights.He urges emphatically enough that " the kingdom<strong>of</strong> heaven is within us."" Look within," he says;"within is the fountain <strong>of</strong> good, and it will everbubble up, if thou wilt dig."- Yet it cometh notwith observation.There should be something almostunconscious and instinctive in true virtue. "Oneman, when he has done a service to another, isreadyto set it down to his account as a favour conferred.Another is not ready to do this, but still in his ownmind he thinks <strong>of</strong> the man as his debtor, and heknows what he has done. A third, in a manner, does'"Thoughts," ii. 11. ^ " Thoughts," vii. 59.


214 STOICISM.not even know what he has done, but he is like avine which has produced grapes, and seeks for nothingmore after it has once produceditsproperfruit. Asa horse when he has run, a dog when he has trackedthe game, a bee when it has made the honey, so aman, when he has done a good act, does not call outfor others to come and see, but he goes on to anotheract, as a vine goes on to produce again the grapes inseason.Must a man then be one <strong>of</strong> these, who, in amanner, act thus without observingit ? Yes— butthis very thing is necessary,a man is doing, for it may be said,otthe observation <strong>of</strong> whatit is characteristicthe social animal to perceive that he is working ina social manner, and indeed to wish that his socialpartner also should it.perceive. . . If thou wilt chooseto understand the meaning <strong>of</strong> what is said, do notfear that for this reason thou wilt omit any socialact." 1There was something <strong>of</strong> braggart ostentationalmost always in the ideal <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>, who seemedto pose himself overmuch before the eyes <strong>of</strong> men,and to wrap himself obtrusively in the cloak <strong>of</strong> hisown virtue, while he defied the gusts <strong>of</strong> angry fortune.Marcus Aurelius at least was free from any suspicion<strong>of</strong> such boastful pride. The earlier writers <strong>of</strong> theschool had given a wide range to man's social dutieswhen they made him a citizen <strong>of</strong> the world at large,bound to promote the interests <strong>of</strong> others, but theylooked to the intellect alone to prompt his action, andmistrusted all strong feeling as a saving guide. Butwith our moralist benevolence becomes enthusiastic,1"Thoughts,"V. 6.


'^STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 215and a source <strong>of</strong> keen pleasure to the agent."Justas it is with the members in those bodies which areunited in one, so it is with rational beings which existseparate, for they have been constituted for oneco-operation. And the perception <strong>of</strong> this will bemore apparent to thee, if thou <strong>of</strong>ten sayest to thyselfthat I am a member [^t'Xoe] <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong>rational beings. But if thou sayest that thou art apart [jue'poe], thou dost not yet love men from thyheart ;beneficence does not yet delight thee forits own sake ;thou still doest itbarely as a thing<strong>of</strong> propriety, and not yet as doing good to thyself."^He speaks in a new strain <strong>of</strong> the pleasures <strong>of</strong> /sympathy :—" When thou wishest to delight thyself,think <strong>of</strong> the virtues <strong>of</strong> those who live with thee ;forinstance, the activity <strong>of</strong> one, and the modesty <strong>of</strong>another, and the liberality <strong>of</strong> a third, and some othergood quality <strong>of</strong> a fourth. For nothing delights somuch as the examples <strong>of</strong> the virtues, when they areexhibited in the morals <strong>of</strong> those who live with usand present themselves m abundance, as far as ispossible."-He is not afraid even <strong>of</strong> the sentiment <strong>of</strong> pity,which sterner natures had regarded as unmanlyweakness :— "The things from the gods merit venerationfor their excellence ;and the things from menshould be dear to us by reason <strong>of</strong> kinship and;sometimes even, in a manner,they move our pity byreason <strong>of</strong> men's ignorance <strong>of</strong> good and bad ;this'"Thoughts," vii. 13."Thoughts," vi. 48.


2 I 6 STOICISM,defect being not less than that which deprives us olthe power <strong>of</strong> distinguishing things that are white andblack."!Virtue, he thinks, should give herself no airs, norlook too sternly on the vices and the follies <strong>of</strong> mankindbut wear a cheerful and engaging smile upon her face."A scowling look is altogether unnatural when it is;<strong>of</strong>ten assumed, the result is that all comeliness diesaway, and at last is so completely extinguished that itcannot be again lighted upat all.Try to concludefrom this very fact that it is contrary to reason. "^Severer <strong>Stoic</strong>s held in despite <strong>of</strong> common sensethat there were no venial errors and no degrees <strong>of</strong>heinousness in vice. Not so said Antoninus." Theophrastus in —his comparison <strong>of</strong> bad actssuch a comparison as one would make accordancewith the common notions <strong>of</strong> mankind— says, like atrue philosopher, that the <strong>of</strong>fences which are committedthrough desire are more blameable than thosewhich are committed through anger. For he who isexcited by anger seems to turn away from reason witha certain pain and unconscious contraction ;but hewho <strong>of</strong>fends through desire, being overpowered bypleasure, seems to be in a manner more intemperateand more womanish in his <strong>of</strong>fences. Rightly then,and in a manner worthy <strong>of</strong> philosophy, he said thatthe <strong>of</strong>fence which is committed with pleasure is moreblameable than that which is committed with pain ;and, on the whole, the one is more like a person whohas been firstwronged and through pain is compelled'"Thoughts," ii. 13.^ " Thoughts," vii. 24.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 217to be angry ;but the other is moved by his ownimpulse to do wrong, being carried towards doingsomething by desire." ^How gently he could act the censor's part we read /in passages like these, which show how carefully heshunned all airs <strong>of</strong> superiority or moral scorn :— " Supposeany man shall despise me. Let him look tothat himself. But I will look to this, that I be notdiscovered doing or saying anything deserving <strong>of</strong>contempt. Shall any man hate me. Let him lookto it. But I will be mild and benevolent towardsevery man, and ready to show even him his mistake,not reproachfully, nor yet as making a display <strong>of</strong> myendurance, but nobly and honestly, like the greatPhocion, unless indeed he only assumed it."^" Consider that a good disposition is invincible,if it be genuine, and not an affected smile and actinga part. For what will the most violent man do tothee, if thou continuest to be <strong>of</strong> a kind dispositiontowards him, and if as opportunity <strong>of</strong>fers, thou gentlyadmonishest him and calmly correctest his errors atthe very time when he is trying to do thee harm,saying, ' Not so, my child ;we are constituted by naturefor something else. I shall certainly not be injured,but thou art injuring thyself, my child 'and show:him with gentle tact and by general principles thatthis is so, and that even bees do not do as he does,nor any animals which are formed by nature to begregarious ?" And thou must do this neither with any double'"Thoughts," ii. 10. ^ «'Thoughts," xi. 13.


2lSSTOICISM.meaning nor in the way <strong>of</strong> reproach, but affectionatelyand without any rancour in thy soul ;and not as ifthou wert lecturing him, nor yet that any bystandermay admire. Let this truth be . . . present to theein the excitement <strong>of</strong> anger, that to be moved bypassion is not manly ;but that mildness and gentleness,as they are more agreeableto human nature, soalso are they more manly ;and he who possessesthese qualities possesses strength, nerves and courage,and not the man who is subject to fits <strong>of</strong> passion anddiscontent."!He would return good for evil, and disarm malevolencewith loving patience." Suppose that men kill thee, cut thee in pieces,curse thee.What then can these things do to preventthy mind from remaining pure, wise, sober, just?For instance, if a man should stand by a limpid purespring, and curse it,the spring never ceases sendingup potable water ;and if he should cast clay into it orfilth, it will speedily disperse them and wash themout, and will not be at all polluted. How then shaltthou possess a perpetual fountain ?By forming thyselfhourly to freedom conjoined with contentment, simplicityand modesty." ^But there is a tone <strong>of</strong> plaintive melancholy at timeswhich shows us that the emperor wearied <strong>of</strong>ten <strong>of</strong> thecares <strong>of</strong> state, and found it no easy thing to deal sogently with the follies <strong>of</strong> mankind. The very evidence<strong>of</strong> the struggle proves that his philosophy was notreserved only for his books :—' " Thoughts,"xi. i8.'^ " Thoughts," viii. 51.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE, 219" Thou wilt consider this when thou art dying, andthou wilt depart more contentedly by reflecting thus :I am going away from such a life, in which even myassociates in behalf <strong>of</strong> whom I have striven so much,prayed and cared, themselves wish me to depart,hoping perchance to get some little advantage by it.Why, then, should a man cling to a longer stay here ?Do not, however, for this reason go away less kindlydisposed to them, but preserving thy own character,and friendly and benevolent and mild, and on theother hand, not as if thou wast torn away ;but aswhen a man dies a quiet death', the poor soul is easilyseparated from the body, such also ought thy departurefrom men tobe."^Though he tries to be one in spirit with his subjects,yet he feels the loneliness <strong>of</strong> intellectual isolation." Short is the little which remains to thee <strong>of</strong> life.Live as on a mountain. For it makes no differencewhether a man lives here or there, if he lives everywherein the world as in a state. Let men see,let them know a real man who lives accordingto nature. If they cannot endure him, let themkill him. For that is better than to live thus [asmen do]."3" Soon, very soon, thou wilt be ashes, or a skeleton,and either a name or not even a name ;but name issound and echo. And the things which are muchvalued in life are empty, and rotten, and trifling, and[like] little dogs biting one another, and little childrenquarrelling, laughing, and then straightway weeping.'"Thoughts," X. 36.2"Thoughts," X. 15.


220 STOICISM.But fidelity, and modesty, and justice, and tiiithare fled"Up to Olympus from the wide-spread earth." — (Hesiod.)"What then is there which still detains theehere ? . . . To have good repute amidst such a worldas this is an empty thing. Why, then, dost thou notwait in tranquillity for thy end, whether it is extinctionor removal to another state ? And until that timecomes what is sufficient ?Why, what else than tovenerate the gods and bless them, and to do good tomen, and to practise tolerance and self-restraint;but as to everything which isbeyond the limits <strong>of</strong> thepoor flesh and breath, to remember that this is neitherthine nor in thy power." iBut if we ask what hopes he entertained <strong>of</strong> a life beyondthe grave, we shall find that his judgment waverson the subject. On the one hand he seems to be assured<strong>of</strong> a personal immortality formen <strong>of</strong> worth :— "Howcan it be that the gods after having arranged all thingswell and benevolently for mankind, have overlookedthis alone, that some men, and very good men, andmen who, as we may say, have had most communionwith the Divinity, and through pious acts and religiousobservances have been most intimate with the Divinity,when they have once died should never exist again,but should be completely extinguished ? But if thisis so, be assured that if itought to have been otherwise,the gods would have done it. For if it werejust, it would also be possible and if it were;according'"Thoughts," V. 3J.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 221to nature, nature would have had it so. But becauseit is not so, if in fact it is not so, be thou convincedthat itought not to have been so : for thou seest even<strong>of</strong> thyseU' that in this inquiry thou art disputing withthe Deity ;and we should not thus dispute withthe gods, unless they were most excellent and mostjust but if this is ; so, they would not haveallowed anything in the ordering <strong>of</strong> the universe to beneglected unjustly and irrationally." ^ But anotherpassage leaves a different impression on the mind, andis more consonant with the ordinarytenets <strong>of</strong> theschool :—" If souls continue to exist, how does the aircontain them from eternity ?But how does the earthcontain the bodies <strong>of</strong> those who have been buriedfrom time so remote ? For as here the mutation ©fthese bodies after a certain continuance, whatever itmay be, and their dissolution make room for otherdead bodies ;so the souls which are removed into theair after subsisting for some time are transmuted anddiffused, and assume a fiery nature by being receivedinto the seminal intelligence <strong>of</strong> the universe, and inthis way make room for the fresh souls which come todwell there. And this is the answer which a manmight give on the hypothesis <strong>of</strong> souls continuing toexist. "2But though there was this uncertainty about thefuture, there was none as to the duties <strong>of</strong> the presentlife, and no moody doubts had — power to cloud hispeaceful serenity <strong>of</strong> temper: "As to the animalswhich have no reason and generally all things and'"Thoughts," xii. 5.*"Thoughts,"iv. 21.


222 STOICISM.objects, do thou, since thou hast reason and they havenone, make use <strong>of</strong> them with a generous and hberalspirit.But towards human beings, as they havereason, behave in a social spirit.And on all occasionscall on the gods, and do not perplex thyself about thelength <strong>of</strong> time in which thou shalt do this ;for eventhree hours so spent are sufficient." ^ " Takecare that thou are not made into a Caesar, that thouart not dyed with this dye ;for such things happen.Keep thyself then simple, good, pure, serious, freefrom affectation, a friend <strong>of</strong> justice, a worshipper <strong>of</strong>the gods, kind, affectionate, strenuous in all properacts. Strive to continue such as philosophy wishedto make thee. Reverence the gods and help men.Short is life. There is only one fruit <strong>of</strong> this terrenelife, a pious disposition and social acts. Do everythingas a discipleconstancy in every<strong>of</strong> Antoninus. Remember hisact which was conformable toreason, and his evenness in all things, and his pietyand the serenity <strong>of</strong> his countenance, and his sweetness,and his disregard <strong>of</strong> . . .empty fame, and howhe bore with those who blamed him unjustly, withoutblaming them in return ;how he did nothing in ahurry; and how he listened not to calumnies; andhow exact an examiner <strong>of</strong> manners and actions hewas ;and not given to reproach people, nor timid,nor suspicious, nor a sophist ;. . . and how he toleratedfreedom <strong>of</strong> speech in those who opposed hisopinions ;and the pleasure which he had when anyman shovi^ed him anything better ;and how religious'"Thoughts," vi. 23.


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 223he was without superstition. Imitate all this, thatthou mayest have as good a conscience, when thylast hour comes, as he had."iTruly the man who could cultivate such graces wasnot far from the kingdom <strong>of</strong> heaven, and was in sympathymuch nearer to the Christian ideal than to thepride <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> apathy. But they cannot be regardedas the natural outcome <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>of</strong> philosophywhich he pr<strong>of</strong>essed. There is no logical connectionbetween the practical maxims and the central dogmas.The currents <strong>of</strong> Platonic thought seem largely blendedwith the special doctrines <strong>of</strong> the Porch, for moralityhad now become many-sided and eclectic, but, aboveall, the various elements were fused and coloured bythe warmth <strong>of</strong> his own delicate and noble nature whichtransfigured the coldness and the poverty <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>creed.Later ages have not ceased to marvel how anemperor so humane, who approached so nearly to theChristian graces as did Antoninus, could have sanctionedany persecution <strong>of</strong> the Christian Church. Thefact itself cannot be reasonably questioned, in spite<strong>of</strong> the well-meant efforts to discredit it.Tertullian,it is true, a few years later speaks <strong>of</strong> him as a mercifulprotector, as not, indeed, annulling the existing lawsagainst the Christians, but as weakening their forceby measures which repressed the persecuting zeal <strong>of</strong>the informers. ^Pious fancy, too, has fondly dwelt upon the story'"Thoughts," vi. 30.2 Tertullian, "Apologia," 5.


2 24 STOICISM.<strong>of</strong> the Christian soldiers whose prayers brought rainfrom heaven in the dire strait <strong>of</strong> his campaignagainst the Quadi, and on the edict in which thegrateful emperor proclaimed the entire freedom <strong>of</strong>the Church. But the document is hopelessly at variancewith undoubted facts, and even with the passage<strong>of</strong> Tertullian just referred to, though the language <strong>of</strong>both attests that the Christians <strong>of</strong> the next generationthought that the emperor had borne them no ill-will,whatever might have been the sentiment and action<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficials far away. Church history tells us <strong>of</strong> themartyrs on whom the sentence was pronounced byhis vice-regents, or whose cases were carried even byappeal before the bar <strong>of</strong> Csesar. The Christians arespoken <strong>of</strong> as obstinate fanatics in his " Meditations" ;the obstinate pr<strong>of</strong>ession <strong>of</strong> their faith was still treatedas a crime, though the civilpower made no attemptto hunt them down. A fact so strange may naturallyseem to call for comment. Rome had, indeed,its national religion as by law established, and theemperorswere defenders <strong>of</strong> the faith. But itspolytheism was many-sided and elastic, and found aniche in its Pantheon for every new form <strong>of</strong> Easternworship. The <strong>Stoic</strong> system, on its side, had alwaystreated the popular religion with forbearance and withlittle <strong>of</strong> the caustic tones <strong>of</strong> earlier free-thought.There was no tradition <strong>of</strong> intolerance, therefore,borrowed from the temple or the philosophic school,and the character <strong>of</strong> the ruler on the throne seemedwholly alien to such a temper. He was not the manto look with jealousy at a religious creed whose moral


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 2 25system was so near his own, though the foundations onwhich it stood were so unlike. Nor is there much evidence<strong>of</strong> " the narrow mahgnance <strong>of</strong> his fellow-<strong>Stoic</strong>s,"by which he isthought to have been probably incited. ^It is true that the name <strong>of</strong> Rusticus, his early teacher,does appear as that <strong>of</strong> the magistrate who tried andsentenced Justin, but the action <strong>of</strong> the judge wasmainly formal, and there is little trace <strong>of</strong> personalrancour, though his tone may sound contemptuous indealing with pr<strong>of</strong>essions which he could not understand.^Justin himself had donned the mantle <strong>of</strong> the sage,and passed throughall the schools in turn as a seekerafter wisdom, but though he spoke <strong>of</strong> the earlierphilosophers as taught by the inspiration <strong>of</strong> the Word,he may well have stirred the jealousy <strong>of</strong> those whosepartial knowledge he refuted, and who, like the Cynichave hounded onCrescens whom we read <strong>of</strong>, maythe populace against him. There is, indeed, a strangecoincidence <strong>of</strong> language which may point to someknowledge on the emperor's part <strong>of</strong> the " SecondApology " <strong>of</strong> Justin. He speaks <strong>of</strong> the soul whichshould be ready at any moment to be parted from thebody, " not from mere obstinacy, aswith the Christians,but considerately and with dignity and in a wayto persuade another, without tragic show (urpaywciwe)"-It has been thought that this contains a reference tothe wish expressed by Justin that some one would'^Sir A. Grant, "Oxford Essays," 1858, p. 119.Ruinart," Acta Martynim Selecta."Q


226 STOICISM.cry aloud with tragic voice {rpayiK^ rj) ^wr/j) anddenounce the iniquity <strong>of</strong> heathen judges.^It is, perhaps, a still more startling fancy whichascribes the emperor's course <strong>of</strong> action in this matterto the influence <strong>of</strong> Jewish prejudice and rancour.The Talmud speaks <strong>of</strong> intercourse between one <strong>of</strong>the Antonines and the greatest rabbi <strong>of</strong> the age,Jehuda-ha-Nasi, and illustrates in many ways themarked respect which the Roman ruler showed tothe great teacher <strong>of</strong> the Synagogue. A learnedtreatise has been written to prove that the Antoninus<strong>of</strong> the Talmud could be no other than the MarcusAurelius with whom we are concerned.^ Josephuscertainly had noted the general similarity betweenthe moral systems <strong>of</strong> the Pharisees and <strong>Stoic</strong>s, both<strong>of</strong> which tried to reconcile the doctrine <strong>of</strong> divinepredestination with the fact <strong>of</strong> man's free-will. Theargument itself is full <strong>of</strong> interest, but the links arefar too weak to bear the strain <strong>of</strong> any inferences fromthem, and it would be unjust alike to the saintlyJehuda and the dispassionate Antoninus to supposethat any personal influence was in this way broughtto bear against the Christians. The Jews <strong>of</strong> Smyrnamight be busy in the popular excitement which wasfatal to the life <strong>of</strong> Polycarp; Justin's death mightpossibly be due to bitter feelings stirred by controversywith the <strong>Stoic</strong>s and the Jews but we have no ;right to'"Second Apol." c. xii. ; cf. Pr<strong>of</strong>. Plumptre, " Contemp.Review," 1869, p. 83.^ Dr. Arnold Bodek, " Marcus Aurelius als Freund undZeitgenosse des Rabbi Jehuda-ha-Nasi, 1S6S."


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 227impute unworthy motives on such poor evidence asthis, or to ascribe to noble spirits the petty malignity<strong>of</strong> meaner natures. But the legal aspect <strong>of</strong> the questionhad been ruled by Trajan long ago when Plinyasked for guidance as a judge ;his answer put theChurch under the ban, and his successors acted onthe precedent so set, though like him they had nowish to encourage informers to hunt down theirvictims. The Imperial government looked withjealous eyes at all the corporate unions which mightprove the centres <strong>of</strong> conspiracy against the State;unless founded with its sanction they were treated assecret societies beyond the pale <strong>of</strong> law, and, strangeas it may seem to us, the Christian Church was <strong>of</strong>tenregarded with suspicion as a dangerous and antisocialmovement. Its dogmas roused no opposition,for they were little known to statesmen or to princes ;itshigh ideal was hidden from the wise and prudent,and revealed only unto babes ;but its little brotherhoodswere springing into life in every land, andspreading their influence men knew not how orwhere. Whatever the secret <strong>of</strong> its force, the potentleaven was working from below, while the network <strong>of</strong>its hierarchy seemed to envelope every class. Theypr<strong>of</strong>essed, indeed, obedience to the ruling powers, buttheir loyalty was not beyond suspicion. They had nolove for the soldier's life, and shrunk from all <strong>of</strong>ficialpledges and all the observances <strong>of</strong> public life onwhich the stamp <strong>of</strong> the state idolatry was set ; theywere heard to speak <strong>of</strong> a higher rule than that <strong>of</strong>Caesar, and <strong>of</strong> the blasphemy <strong>of</strong> the divine honoursQ 2


2 28 STOICISM.paid to man ; they seemed at times to push theircourage to defiance in the hot wish to win the martyr'scrown. They were thought to be churlish andmorose, for they could not take a part in the merrymakings<strong>of</strong> their neighbours, associated as these werewith the symbols and practices <strong>of</strong> a false religion.For themselves they had no image in their homesor chapels, and they were therefore branded asatheists by ignorant dislike. Wild stories spread<strong>of</strong> all the horrors <strong>of</strong> their secret meetings how; theyjoined in sensual revelry, and shed the blood <strong>of</strong>murdered innocents, till the outraged gods markedtheir displeasure by some scourge <strong>of</strong> pestilence orflood or fire.The thunderclouds <strong>of</strong> popular frenzyhere and there in fierceburst outexplosions when the peoplesrose against the Christians in wild tumult, and hurriedthem with vengeful cries before the governor orjudge. There was little to be proved, indeed, againstthem but the membership in an illegal sect and theseeming bigotry with which they clung to their pr<strong>of</strong>ession.The magistrates did not always credit thewild charges brought against them, nightmare shapesas they were <strong>of</strong> vulgar fancy, but still the Christiansociety, with its organized unity and widespreadmembers, with its notorious dislike to the institutions<strong>of</strong> the age and its prophecies <strong>of</strong> speedy change, naturallyseemed to worldly eyes like a permanent menaceto the established order. When the barbarians wereon the move, and every man was needed to defendthe frontiers, the vital forces <strong>of</strong> society were weak-


STOICISM ON THE THRONE. 229ened by the austere sectaries who stood alo<strong>of</strong> fromthe service <strong>of</strong> tlie State, and seemed to reserve theirloyalty and zeal for the spread <strong>of</strong> a mystic brotherhoodwhose homage was not paid to an earthlyCcesar, and whose New Jerusalem eclipsed the majesty<strong>of</strong> Rome. Apologists, indeed, might find it easy todisprove the calumnies <strong>of</strong> ignorant malice, mighteven in the boldness <strong>of</strong> their innocence appeal to theequity <strong>of</strong> the emperor himself, but the cares <strong>of</strong> governmenttasked all his powers, and even the wise andgentle Antonines probably accepted the currentprejudices <strong>of</strong> the ruling classes, and neglected to lookdeeper into the real doctrines <strong>of</strong> the Church withwhich they had so much unconscious sympathy <strong>of</strong>spirit. To these causes may be apparently ascribedthe startling paradox <strong>of</strong> persecution raging in the ageand with the sanction <strong>of</strong> the most tolerant and largeheartedCaesars <strong>of</strong> the Roman Empire.


230 STOICISM.CHAPTER XIV.THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER IN RELATION TOOTHER ASPECTS OF THOUGHT.The foregoing pages have been occupied almostexclusively with the moral aspect <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> system,in which all its real force and originality was centered.It only remains to gather up in a concluding chaptersome remarks on its relations to other departments<strong>of</strong> social thought and progress. It confronted theChristian Church, as we have seen, as a rival influence,appealing chiefly to the pride and self-control <strong>of</strong>resolute natures, though turning at last to preach,as Lactantius observes, even to women and toslaves,^ but with no balm for stricken consciences,or gospel <strong>of</strong> consolation for the weak. TheChurch, therefore, borrowed nothing from it atthe first, except perhaps a technical phrase or twoand illustrations, which point either to the commonplaces<strong>of</strong> the schools or to an attitude <strong>of</strong> consciousbe ascribed theopposition. To the first class maypsychological division <strong>of</strong> man's nature into body,soul, and spirit, which appears in slightly differentforms in Marcus Aurelius and St. Paul ; or, again, the'Lactantius, " Instit. Div.," iii. 23.


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 23 1quotation from Cleanthes or Aratus in the famousspeech delivered on Mars Hill at Athens.^ To the latterbelong the possible references in St. Paul's Epistles tothe ideal <strong>of</strong> the sage and the citizen <strong>of</strong> the world atlarge, which Bishop Lightfoot has suggested, andwhich may be best given in his words. The <strong>Stoic</strong>sage " alone is free, he alone ishappy ;he alone isbeautiful.He, and he alone, possesses absolute wealth.He is the true king and the true priest. Now, maywe not say that this image has suggested many expressionsto the Apostle <strong>of</strong> the Gentiles ? 'Evennow ye are full,'^he exclaims in impassioned irony tothe Corinthians ;'even now are ye rich, even now areye made kings without us ;we are fools for Christ,but ye are wise in Christ ;we are weak, but ye arestrong ; ye are glorious, but we are dishonoured.'^''All things are yours,' he says elsewhere, all thingsare yours, and ye are Christ's, and Christ is God's.' '^So, too, he describes himself and the other Apostles,'as being grieved, yet always rejoicing; as beggars,yet making many rich ; as having nothing, and yetpossessing all things.'^'In everything at every timehaving every self - sufficiency ... in everythingenriched.'*^ 'I have learnt,' he says again, 'in whatsoever circumstances I am, to be self-sufficing.I haveall strength in Him that giveth me power. I haveall things to the full and to overflowing.''''''Ek (70V yap yivoQ i<strong>of</strong>ikv (Acts xvii. 28).' I Cor. iv. 8.^* 2 Cor. vi. 10.*Ibid. iv. lO.Ibid. ix. 8, 11.* Ibid. iii. 22.^Phil. iv. il, 13, 18.


232 STOICISM." This universal dominion ... ispromised alike bythe <strong>Stoic</strong> philosopher to the wise man and by theChristian Apostle to the believer. But the one mustattain itby self-isolation, the other by incorporation.It is ep TM fvlvvaiiovvTL (inHim that giveth power) thatthe faithful becomes all-sufiicient. All things are his ;but they are only his, in so far as he is Christ's, andbecause Christ is God's. Here, and here only, theApostle found the realization <strong>of</strong> the proud ideal whichthe chief philosophers <strong>of</strong> his native Tarsus hadsketched in such bold outline and painted in thesebrilliant colours."The same writer also points to the passages whichseem to bear the traces <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> images <strong>of</strong> thegreat commonwealth <strong>of</strong> which all men are members."Our citizenship is in heaven."^ "God raised uswith Him, and seated us with Him in the heavenlyplaces in Christ "Jesus."^ Therefore ye are no morestrangers and sojourners, but fellow-citizens with thesaints and members <strong>of</strong> God's household."^ "Fulfilyour duties as citizens worthily <strong>of</strong> the Gospel <strong>of</strong>"Christ."* We being many are one body in Christ,"and members one <strong>of</strong> another."^ For as the bodyis one and hath many members, and all the members<strong>of</strong> the body being many are one body, so also isChrist ;for we all are baptized in one Spirit into onebody, whether Jews or Greeks, whether bond or free."^" There is neither Jew nor Greek ;there is neither''Phil. iii. 20.Ephes.ii. 6.' Ibid. ii. 19.* Phil. i. 27.*Rom. xii. 5.* i Cor. xii. 12.


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 233bond nor free ;there is no male and female ; for yeall are one in Christ Jesus."'With reference to this cosmopolitan :— ideal it hasbeen well said by another writer " The city <strong>of</strong> God,<strong>of</strong> which the <strong>Stoic</strong>s doubtfully and feebly spoke, wasnow set up before the eyes <strong>of</strong> men. It was no unsubstantialcity such as we fancy in the clouds, noinvisible pattern such as Plato thought might be laidup in heaven, but a visible corporation whose membersmet together to eat bread and drink wine, andinto which they were initiated by bodily immersion inwater. Here the Gentile met the Jew whom he hadbeen accustomed to regard as an enemy <strong>of</strong> the humanrace ;the Roman met the lying Greek sophist, theSyrian slave, the gladiator born beside the Danube.In brotherhood they met, the natural birth andkindred <strong>of</strong> each forgotten, the baptism alone rememberedin which they had been born again to God andto each other." ^In the next age some <strong>of</strong> the most cultivated <strong>of</strong> /the Christian converts passed into the Church throughthe portals <strong>of</strong> philosophy, and like Justin, stillput onthe <strong>Stoic</strong> mantle, holdingbecome flesh and dwelt awhile on earth, had been thethat the Word which hadsource <strong>of</strong> spiritual light in earlier ages, and thatSocrates and other earnest seekers after truth hadbeen in some sense unconscious Christians as in communionwith the Eternal Word. It was thus that'Gal. iii. 28.'"Ecce Homo," p. 136; cf. Lightfoot, St. Paul's Ep. toPhilippians.


234 STOICISM.Clemens <strong>of</strong> Alexandria maintained that God had madethree covenants with men, in heathen philosophy, andJewish law, and Christian Gospel. When the gloomand vigour <strong>of</strong> asceticism brooded over Christiansociety at the break-up <strong>of</strong> the old Roman world, itwas remembered that no system had insisted like the<strong>Stoic</strong> on the vanity <strong>of</strong> earthly pleasures, and the soul'spower to rise above the entanglements <strong>of</strong> sense tothe fruition <strong>of</strong> the absolute and the divine. Menread the doctrine <strong>of</strong> original corruption in Seneca'scomplaints <strong>of</strong> universal folly,and tempered the pride<strong>of</strong> <strong>Stoic</strong> self-restraint with the yearnings <strong>of</strong> penitenceand self-abasement.There was much to attract and little to <strong>of</strong>fend inthe Manual <strong>of</strong> Epictetus and the thoughts <strong>of</strong> Antoninus;men forgot the essential difference that laybelow the outward features <strong>of</strong> resemblance, whileapocryphal documents and letters gave a substantialshape to the floating fancies that Seneca must haveSt. Paul, and that Marcus Aureliusknown and lovedmust have publicly pr<strong>of</strong>essed his reverent regard forthe Christian Faith.But <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> as a system had by thistime passedaway;its definite outlines had been long sinces<strong>of</strong>tened or effaced, and various forms <strong>of</strong> mysticism,claiming to be sprung from the Platonic thought,were the only powers that kept the field as rivals tothe Christian Church.To science and to abstract thought the contributions <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>s were <strong>of</strong> little value. They mappedout, indeed, the world <strong>of</strong> knowledge into the three de-


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 235partments <strong>of</strong> ethic, logic, and physic, and though theycentered their interest and energy upon the first, theywere far from neglecting the two others. It is true thatAriston <strong>of</strong> Chios, Zenon'spupil, compared logic to aspider's web, which is as useless as it is curious ;andlikened those who studied it to people eating lobsters,who took much trouble for the sake <strong>of</strong> a little morselsheltered in its fence <strong>of</strong> shell. Natural science heregardedas an ambitious effort to transcend thelimits <strong>of</strong> our human powers, and likely therefore tobear little fruit. Yet others <strong>of</strong> the school were notdeterred from much intellectual activity in thesedirections, though if we looked only to the value <strong>of</strong> theresults which they obtained, we might feel inclinedto sympathize with the pessimism <strong>of</strong> Ariston. Logicthey regarded in the light <strong>of</strong> the egg's shell, or thewall <strong>of</strong> a city or a garden, because itmight help toguard the truth from rude assaults, but they couldadd nothing <strong>of</strong> solid use to the analysis <strong>of</strong> the formalprocesses <strong>of</strong> thought which Aristotle had alreadymade, and could only multiply fine-drawn distinctionsand subtleties <strong>of</strong> grammatical nomenclature.In dealing with the fundamental question <strong>of</strong> thestandard or criterion <strong>of</strong> truth, they formulated a sort<strong>of</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> common sense, which may remind us<strong>of</strong> some later systems, such as those <strong>of</strong> Locke or Reid.Sensation is the only source <strong>of</strong> all our knowledge ;the soul is a blank leaf, sensation is the hand whichcovers it with writing. From the memory<strong>of</strong> ourperceptions we pass onward to experience and generalnotions (7rpo\i)\peit:, KoivalEyyoLai), OUt <strong>of</strong> which


236 STOICISM.knowledge is built up ;but the difference betweensensation and knowledgeis one only <strong>of</strong> degree, dependingon the strength <strong>of</strong> our conviction. ForZenon compared sensation to the outstretchedfingers, assent to the closing hand, conviction to thefist,and knowledge to one fistgrasped firmly by theother. Some <strong>of</strong> our perceptions carry with them anirresistible conviction <strong>of</strong> the truth ; they not onlyrepresent external facts, but they make us grasp themas it were in immediate apprehension, and warrantour belief in their reality {KaTaXrjwTiKfj (puvTaaia), andso enable us to negative the scepticism which despairs<strong>of</strong> truth (a.KaTaXr]\pia). The simplicity andbareness <strong>of</strong> these logical positions were disguised bythe dialectical acuteness <strong>of</strong> Chrysippus, who didmost to spreadthe use <strong>of</strong> the barren subtleties andthorny quibbles which Seneca so harshly criticisesin his fellow <strong>Stoic</strong>s, though he condescends at timesto show his expertness in such weapons <strong>of</strong> debate.In connection with the theory <strong>of</strong> knowledge givenabove, they held that the only realities were bodilyobjects ;virtues and vices, thoughts, emotions, dayand night and seasons, were material beings, formatter only can be acted on or act.They went beyond this to reproduce, though notconsciously perhaps, the views <strong>of</strong> the much earlierthinker Heraclitus, in regarding a fiery ether as theprimary element which passes by successive changesinto the four elements which are known to sense ;while it is one with the universal reason, and withthe soul <strong>of</strong> man, which is his dsemoa Like him


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 237they spoke <strong>of</strong> destiny as the law <strong>of</strong> the wholeuniverse, and <strong>of</strong> alternate phases <strong>of</strong> creation and <strong>of</strong>conflagration in the eternal flux <strong>of</strong> natural causes.There is little distinctly original in these cosmicalassumptions, though with all their crudeness <strong>of</strong> materialismthey rounded <strong>of</strong>f their pantheistic system ina manner which deeply impressed the imagination<strong>of</strong> the world, and stoutly maintained the doctrine<strong>of</strong> free-will, although they seemed to sacrifice itto their theories <strong>of</strong> natural necessity and divine predestination.Nor had the <strong>Stoic</strong>s much to add to what was knownalready or believed in any <strong>of</strong> the special branches<strong>of</strong> physical inquiry. We read <strong>of</strong> treatises, indeed, byPosidonius and others on such questions, but theircontents, as far as they are known to us, seem basedon Aristotle's Physics. There is a work <strong>of</strong> Seneca'swhich deals with questions <strong>of</strong> natural philosophy, butthe treatment is rhetorical and careless, disfigured bycredulity in the supposed facts which it records, asby onesidedness and prejudice in its conclusions.But still there is a feature which may impress us aswe read his writings on such subjects, and which isstrikingly contrasted ^vith the temper <strong>of</strong> the Greeksfrom whom he mainly drew, and that is the enthusiasmwith which he dwells upon the intellectualwealth which had been already won, combined withthe large hopefulness <strong>of</strong> future progress. To Aristotleit had seemed that arts, discoveries, and knowledgewere all found and lost in turn as the cycle <strong>of</strong> theuniverse came round, but Seneca speaks in quite


238 STOICISM.another strain in passages like these which we maycomets, so rare aquote :— " Why do we wonder thatphenomenon, have not yet had their laws assigned ?That we should know so little <strong>of</strong> their beginning andtheir end, when their recurrence is at wide intervals ?It isnot yet fifteen hundred years since Greece reckonedthe stars and gave them names.There are stillmany nations which are acquainted with the heavensby sight only, which do not yet know why the moondisappears, why she is eclipsed. It is but lately thatamong us philosophy has reduced these matters to acertainty. The day shall come when the course <strong>of</strong>time and the labour <strong>of</strong> a maturer age shall bring tolight what is yet concealed. One generation, even ifit devoted itself to the skies, is not enough for researchesso extensive. How then can it be so, whenwe divide this scanty allowance <strong>of</strong> years into noequal shares between our studies and our vices ?These things then must be explained by a long succession<strong>of</strong> inquiries. We have but just begun toknow how arise the morning and evening appearances,the stations, the progressions, and the retrogradations<strong>of</strong> the fixed stars which put themselves inour way, which appearing perpetually in another andanother place compel us to be curious. Some onewill hereafter demonstrate in what region the cometswander, why they move so far asunder from the rest,<strong>of</strong> what size and nature they are. Let us be contentwith what we have discovered, let posterity contributeits share to truth, "i'"Quest. Nat." vii. 25.


VTHE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 239And again :—" Let us not wonder that what liesso deep is brought out so slowly. How manyanimals have become known for the first time in thisage And the members <strong>of</strong> future ! generations shallknow many <strong>of</strong> which we are ignorant. Many thingsare reserved for ages to come, when our memoryshall have passed away.The world would be a smallthing, indeed, if it did not contain matter <strong>of</strong> inquiryfor all the world. Eleusis reserves something for thesecond visit <strong>of</strong> the worshipper. So, too, Nature doesnot at once disclose all her mysteries. We thinkourselves initiated : we are but in the vestibule. Thearcana are not thrown open without distinction andwithout reserve. This age will see some things, thatwhich comes after us others."^With these prophecies <strong>of</strong> future progress we maynaturally connect the visions, one day to be realized,<strong>of</strong> new worlds to be discovered beyond the bounds<strong>of</strong> ocean, far remoter even from the Roman kenthan Western Thule, such as Seneca's drama <strong>of</strong>"Medea" brings before us with singular vividness andforce :—" Venient annis secula serisQnibus oceanus vincula rerumLaxet, et ingens pateat tellus,Tethysque novos deteget orbes,Nee sit terns ultima Thule."To legal studies the contributions <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong>swere far more important,but they consisted more in' " Quest. Nat." vii. 30, 31 ; cf. Whewell, '* Phil, <strong>of</strong> InductiveSciences," ii. 139.


240 STOICISM.the informing spirit, than in any definite conceptionswhich were borrowed. The schools <strong>of</strong> Greece hadlong ago insisted on a law <strong>of</strong> nature, distinct fromthe conventional usages <strong>of</strong> different lands and ages.The <strong>Stoic</strong>s took up the phrase almost as a commonplace,but laid a special emphasis upon it,and madeit the key-note <strong>of</strong> their moral system, as a guide totheory and rule for practice in all the departments <strong>of</strong>man's action. The great jurists <strong>of</strong> the Empire werefamiliar with the training <strong>of</strong> the schools, and theysaw in the law <strong>of</strong> nature an ideal <strong>of</strong> simplicity anduniversal truth for the legal student and reformer.Some rudiments <strong>of</strong> this they found already in theprinciples which lay beneath the prsetor's edicts, intendedfor the aliens to whom the strict Romanusages <strong>of</strong> family rights and property could not apply,and for whose benefit the magistrates had fallen backon general maxims, common, as it was thought, to asupposed Law <strong>of</strong> Nations {jus genimm),but needinghis sanction to be binding as a set <strong>of</strong> positiveenactments. The rules handed on from one praetorto another, expanded and systematized as time wenton, came into existence solely to supply the shortcomings<strong>of</strong> the civil law, in dealing with the casesto which that could not be with strict proprietyapplied. They were drawn from the supposed law<strong>of</strong> nations, as an element common to all humancodes ; they were thought to be based upon a law <strong>of</strong>nature rather than the accidents <strong>of</strong> race, and age,and country; they became a sort <strong>of</strong> equity, corrective<strong>of</strong> the earlier inelastic forms.The precedent so


'THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 241set was followed steadily by the great lawyers, whogave coherent and articulate expressionto the imperialcodes ;from the prevalent system <strong>of</strong> philosophythey drew, perhaps unconsciously, strongphrases about natural justice, and endeavoured bydefinition and analogy, and methods <strong>of</strong> interpretation, to infuse an animating spirit into the dry formalisms<strong>of</strong> the past, and to bring the statute law intomore and more <strong>of</strong> harmony with their ideal. Theydid not carry this so far, indeed, as might have beenexpected, and the contrasts are <strong>of</strong>ten very markedbetween the abstract principles as stated in preambles<strong>of</strong> the Digest, and the practical details whichregulate the different sides <strong>of</strong> social action. Buttheywere not theorists alone, but men <strong>of</strong> action forced totake account <strong>of</strong> the temper <strong>of</strong> the age and the forces<strong>of</strong> resistance : not philosophers dealing with imaginarybeings, but statesmen hampered by historicdata, and the prejudices <strong>of</strong> the masses and the partialenlightenment <strong>of</strong> men in power. They had,therefore, to tolerate much that was inconsistent withtheir cardinal maxims <strong>of</strong> human equality and universalbrotherhood and the commonwealth <strong>of</strong> nations." Gaius, Ulpian, Papinian, and Paulus," it has been" said, appear very timid by the side <strong>of</strong> Seneca andEpictetus."! But the influence <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> theorymight still be very real, though we must allow forthe constant force <strong>of</strong> friction. Christianity foundmuch to do in breathing a larger and humaner spiritDenis, " Idees Morales dans I'Antiquite ;"ap. Sir A. Grant,p. 121. R


242 STOICISM.into the various relations <strong>of</strong> society as defined bycivil law, but it was no slight help to it in its reformingwork that principles so true and so wide-reachinghad been uttered with authority already in theRoman codes, and held up thereby to the reverence<strong>of</strong> later ages.Among the severe comments <strong>of</strong> an eminent divinealready cited, we may read that <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> died out,having produced during its short lifetime onlyvery transient and partial effects and that; rigorousand unflinching as was the system in its principlesand heroic in its proportions, the direct results were"marvellously little. It was a staff <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essors withoutclasses. It produced, or at least attracted, a fewisolated great men, but on the life <strong>of</strong> the masses andon the policy <strong>of</strong> states it was almost wholly powerless."'A modern jurist,on the other hand, affirms that withthe single exception <strong>of</strong> Christianity no form <strong>of</strong> beliefevertookpossession <strong>of</strong> so great a number <strong>of</strong> Europeans,or held it so long ;and that it moulded human institutionsand affected human destiny to a greaterextent than allthe other philosophical systems either<strong>of</strong> the ancient or the modern world. ^ The latterseems thetruer estimate, though as the point <strong>of</strong> viewis different it may be possible to accept them bothwith some reserves. <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> had a religious philosophyindeed, but was not an organized religion, andwas too severely abstract to touch the heart and the'Bishop Lightfoot, "App. to St. Paul's Ep. to the Philipp."' " Lorimer, Institutes <strong>of</strong> Law," p. ii6.


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 243imagination <strong>of</strong> the people. Its direct influence onthe lower classes probably was very slight, thoughthe C>Tiic missionaries spread some knowledge <strong>of</strong>its principles in coarser forms. It was othenvisewith the higher and the middle classes, but even hereit is not easy to give definite pro<strong>of</strong>s or apply materialtests. In dealing with societies that have outwardsymbols <strong>of</strong> communion we may be able to count thenumbers and appraise some positive results, but howare we to measure the influence <strong>of</strong> aspiritual leavenworking in the midst <strong>of</strong> a complex social system,A^ith countless forces <strong>of</strong> attraction and repulsion allaround it. The literature, whether grave or gay, <strong>of</strong>the early Roman Empire abundantly attestsitspopularityand wide diffusion. Under the Antonines itreigned supreme as a rule <strong>of</strong> life among the highercircles. It stamped itself ineffaceably upon the language<strong>of</strong> the civil law; it gave a tone to earnestthought on moral questions ; it set an example <strong>of</strong>resolute self-control which became one at least <strong>of</strong>the moving forces <strong>of</strong> the age, and provided in thehomely talk <strong>of</strong> Epictetus a manual in constant usein serious households. What more itmight havedone we cannot say, for the Christian Church wasready by that time to take upits work from the farhigher vantage-ground <strong>of</strong> an organized society, witha personal ideal and a new spirit <strong>of</strong> enthusiasticservice. The new-comer had already all that wag<strong>of</strong> vital efficacy in the <strong>Stoic</strong> creed, together with freshelements to which heathen philosophy could not <strong>of</strong>itself attain. But <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> still lived on, though weR 2


244 STOICISM.cannot always trace its influence, or distinguish theseveral currents in their course. It lost its essentialfeatures, we are told, meantime, while itpassed awayin the dissolving view <strong>of</strong> mystic fancy. Itmay beso, but with its rigorous logic it dropped much <strong>of</strong>its pride, its hardness, and its airs <strong>of</strong> paradox and;the moral temper which survived passed into newforms, while the old system crumbled to decay.The influence <strong>of</strong> this <strong>Stoic</strong> temper may be tracedin the Jewish Philo and the School <strong>of</strong> Alexandria,deepening their scorn <strong>of</strong> sensual indulgence, whileperhaps it encouraged the pride <strong>of</strong> intellectual isolation,but providing at any rate a solid resting-point<strong>of</strong> moral propaganda amongallthe reveries <strong>of</strong> transcendentalspeculation ;and though the later philosophies<strong>of</strong> the old heathen world called themselvescommonly by other names, yet they gathered up whatwas true and vital in the lessons and examples <strong>of</strong> the<strong>Stoic</strong> system. In later times it is hard,if not impossible,to trace with certainty the interminglingcurrents which flowed from the schools and fromthe Church, but we may note that in the " Consolation" <strong>of</strong> Boethius, while there is no sure evidence<strong>of</strong> Christian thought, the <strong>Stoic</strong> elements are presentunmistakeably. The writer, in the words <strong>of</strong> Gibbon,was '• the last <strong>of</strong> the Romans whom Cato or Tullywould have acknowledged for their fellow-countryman."^The work itself was read, perhaps, morelargely in succeeding centuriesthan any other legacy'Gibbon, chap. xxix.


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 245<strong>of</strong> pagan thought, and was the starting-point <strong>of</strong> awhole literature in which the same thoughts wererepeated with countless varieties <strong>of</strong> form. The doctrines<strong>of</strong> the Porch contributed in this way probablyto the ascetic and chivalrous ideals which formed <strong>of</strong>themselves so large a part <strong>of</strong> the thought and action<strong>of</strong> the Middle Ages, and if we cannot always tracetheir presence in the sentiments <strong>of</strong> modern Europe,the reason may be that spiritual, like gaseous, forcesintermingle freely as by natural law. At the Renaissance,indeed, when enthusiastic scholars turnedback anew to the old classic models and revived thespirit <strong>of</strong> the bygone past, each <strong>of</strong> the old systems <strong>of</strong>philosophy lived once more awhile in the devotion<strong>of</strong> a few adherents, and the <strong>Stoic</strong> system, amongothers, found itschampions and exponents, such asJustus Lipsius, who carried his sympathy so far,as not only in his commentaries upon Tacitus tobreak out into rapturous admiration when the lasthours <strong>of</strong> Thrasea are recorded, but even in hisprivate letters to sanction the eiiXoyog et,ay(oyr] <strong>of</strong>the school, or the voluntary exit from the worldin face <strong>of</strong> hopelessly untoward conditions.^ Butsuch unlovely elements <strong>of</strong> the old pagan alloywere purged away, while the noble spirit lived onin other shapes, and took service in the ChristianChurch.Some measure <strong>of</strong> that temper may be surely foundin the Calvinism <strong>of</strong> the Reformation, with its austere" •J. Lipsii, Epist.Cent." ii. 26.


246 STOICISMmorality and the unbending rigour<strong>of</strong> its abstractprinciples, and high theories <strong>of</strong> divine foreknowledgecoupled with the practical insistence on the facts <strong>of</strong>man's freewill. The first essay with which its author,Calvin, began his literary labours, was a commentaryon Seneca's treatise upon " Clemency;" and Geneva,the scene <strong>of</strong> his life's work, has been called by Michelet" the spiritual city built up <strong>of</strong> <strong><strong>Stoic</strong>ism</strong> upon the rock<strong>of</strong> predestination."The same temper reappeared again in pagan dressat the close <strong>of</strong> the last century in France, whererevolutionary spirits, turning impatiently from whatthey thought the lower ideals <strong>of</strong> Catholicism, soughtfor a rule <strong>of</strong> life in heathen ethics, and nursed theirfancy with the pictures <strong>of</strong> the stern old republicans<strong>of</strong> Cato's type, or martyrs <strong>of</strong> conscience and <strong>of</strong> libertylike Thrasea Pastus. It was but a soriy parody,indeed, performed with most unlovely strut and declamation,in which the actors hardly entered intothe spirit <strong>of</strong> the system which they copied, butthought chiefly <strong>of</strong> the accidents and outward forms.To some <strong>of</strong> them, like Rousseau, the nature thatthey hankered after was a fond fiction <strong>of</strong> the fancy,a supposed ideal <strong>of</strong> man's innocence when wantswere few and instincts healthy, and the luxuries <strong>of</strong>civilized refinement all unknown.It was in a far other sense that a moralist <strong>of</strong> ourown country, Bishop Butler, reverted to the old <strong>Stoic</strong>rule <strong>of</strong> following nature ;like the doctors <strong>of</strong> thePorch he held that man should be a law unto himself,and that, as in a well-ordered state, the well-


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 247being <strong>of</strong> every part depends on the harmony andbalance <strong>of</strong> the whole.But two corrections seemed required to reconcile/the ancient standard to the claims <strong>of</strong> common sense,and both were therefore urged by Bishop Butler.The first was to eschew the paradox <strong>of</strong> apathy, whichtreated the emotions like hostile powers to be repressed,rather than natural impulses to be guidedand controlled. The next was to invert the argument<strong>of</strong> the <strong>Stoic</strong> optimists, who urged that as God's providentialgovernment must needs be perfect, andman's happiness must depend on the virtue whichlies within his power,it follows that virtue alone isa real good, while pain, privation, and disgrace,though seeming evils, are not real. But the Christiandivine maintained, that as the present life is <strong>of</strong>tennot a perfect whole which satisfies our sense <strong>of</strong>justice, it leads our faith onward to a life beyond thegrave, where the seeming inequalities <strong>of</strong> our lot maybe redressed, and a sublimer justice done to all mankind.Yet even with these cautions and reserves,the rule, so modernized, has not been safe from criticalattack. Of such we may content ourselves with twoexamples, quite different as they are in source andmeaning. The first expresses in satiric style theperplexity <strong>of</strong> common sense, that would have a simplerule to guide it,and knows not how to deal withgeneral theories and vague abstractions. Thus weread in the " Rasselas " <strong>of</strong> Dr. Johnson the philosopher's:— sonorous maxims '"The way to be happyis to live according to nature, in obedience to that


248 STOICISM.universal and unalterable law with which every heartis originally impressed He that lives according. . .to nature will suffer nothing from the delusions <strong>of</strong>hope, or importunities <strong>of</strong> desire he will receive and;reject with equability <strong>of</strong> temper and act or suffer as;the reason <strong>of</strong> things shall alternately prescribe. Othermen may amuse themselves with subtle definitions orintricate ratiocinations. Let them learn to be wiseby easier means ;let them observe the hind <strong>of</strong> theforest, and the linnet <strong>of</strong> the grove ;let them considerthe life <strong>of</strong> animals whose motions are regulated byinstinct; they obey their guide and be happy.' ....When he had spoken, he looked round him witha placid air and enjoyed the consciousness <strong>of</strong> hisown beneficence. Sir,' said the prince, with great'modesty, * as I, like all the rest <strong>of</strong> mankind, amdesirous <strong>of</strong> felicity, my closest attention has beendiscourse : I doubt not the truthfixed upon your<strong>of</strong> a position which a man so learned has so confidentlyadvanced. Let me only know what it isto live according to nature.' 'When I find youngmen so humble and so docile,' said the philosopher,'I can deny them no information which my studieshave enabled me to afford. To live according tonature is to act always with due regard to the fitnessarising from the relations and qualities <strong>of</strong> causes andeffects ;to concur with the great and unchangeablescheme <strong>of</strong> universal felicity to ; co-operate with thegeneral disposition and tendency <strong>of</strong> the present system<strong>of</strong> things.'"The prince soon found that this was one <strong>of</strong> the


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 249sages whom he should understand less as he heardhim longer. He therefore bowed and was silent ;andthe philosopher, supposing him satisfied and the restvanquished, rose up and departed with the air <strong>of</strong> aman that had co-operated with the present system." ^The criticism needs, perhaps, no serious answer, asitmight be urged with little variation <strong>of</strong> detail againstall attempts at scientific treatment, where abstractionstake the place <strong>of</strong> concrete rules.The second comes from quite another quarter—from Sir Alexander Grant, the Aristotelian scholar, whocomplains that the analysis has not been carried farenough to give the rule a definite and scientific value.The objection may be stated best in his own language:—" Into the difficulties <strong>of</strong> the question Butlerhas not entered. For instance, while he is perfectlysuccessful in establishing against the Hobbists thereality <strong>of</strong> the moral element in man's nature, he doesnot tell us whether or not he would agree with the<strong>Stoic</strong>s in ultimately giving the entire supremacy to aman's reason and conscience, so as to supplant theother instincts, or at what point he would stop. . .Is the life <strong>of</strong> the saints and martyrs to be called a lifeaccording to nature ? If not, is it better or worse ?and if better, is not man to aim at the better ? Thereisone mode <strong>of</strong> representation which describes life as aprogress, a conflict, a good fight another which;makesit the following <strong>of</strong> nature. On the one hand, there isthe spirit <strong>of</strong> aspiration and effort, the tendency to'Chap. 22.


250 STOICISM.asceticism, the victory <strong>of</strong> the will ;on the other hand,there are the genial, kindly, human feelings ;thereis the wise passivity <strong>of</strong> mind ;there is the breadth <strong>of</strong>sympathy which counterbalances an over-concentratedintensity <strong>of</strong> aim. To make the formula, " Live accordingto nature," <strong>of</strong> any value we require to havethese conflicting tendencies harmonized with eachother." 1To this train <strong>of</strong> reasoning a recent writer has givenwhat he thinks to be not only the Socratic, but theChristian answer, and with this we may be content,perhaps, to leave the subject." 'The spirit <strong>of</strong> aspirationand effort ' is not opposed to ' the genial,'the breadth <strong>of</strong>kindly, human feelings,' nor tosympathy ' '<strong>of</strong> which he speaks. The progress, theconflict, the 'good fight is an effort not by an externalpower to drive Nature from her course, or evento control her activity, but by Nature herself,as revealedto us internally and externally, to vindicateher supremacy over the denaturalizing influences,over the rebellious subjects within her own realm,which oppose her free development and harmoniousaction. When the conflict is peculiarly hard, whenthe external principle <strong>of</strong> disorder has succeeded inranging the animal and sensual against the rationaland spiritualpropensities, and when Nature herself,as a whole, is in danger <strong>of</strong> being degraded from ahuman nature into something worse than a brutenature, she calls— and in the case <strong>of</strong> saints andmartyrs calls not in vain — for aid from above.' " Oxford Essays," p. 90.


THE STOIC CREED AND TEMPER. 25 1"But it is for aid; not for her destruction, but for herpreservation and support ; it is that she may becomenot less herself, but more herself, in this her hour <strong>of</strong>trial— and that, in her triumph, she may save, not thehigher principles alone from degradation, but very'<strong>of</strong>ten, also, the lower propensities, the law in themembers,' from self-destruction by excess <strong>of</strong> presentgratification.''The whole effort <strong>of</strong> the will, when directed to therealization <strong>of</strong> the higher life, is an effort not againstNature, but in favour <strong>of</strong> Nature, in every sense thatcan be attached to that word, except the single, andeven if true, surely very narrow sense <strong>of</strong> it, in whichit is taken to mean the tendency to the unbridled indulgence<strong>of</strong> one or more <strong>of</strong> our irrational appetites.''Man,' says Kant, isunholy enough, but thehumanity inhabiting his person (his proper person)^must be holy."'Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Lorimer's " Instimtes <strong>of</strong> Law," p. 158.


( 253 )INDEX.Agrippina, 136Antipater, 72Antisthenes, 14Antoninus, M. Aurelius, 87,108, 200, 229Pius, 113, 200Apollonius <strong>of</strong> Colchis, 1 13<strong>of</strong> Tyana, 90Areopagus, 33Ariston, 144, 235Aristotle, 29, 235, 237Arius, 89Arria, 99, 103, 122Arrian, 181Athenodorus, 71, 89Attains, 133Augustus, 89Avidius Cassius, 87, 205Aulus Gellius, 109, 125Barea Soranus, 91Boethius, 244Brutus, 76Burrus, 136, 166, 1 71Butler, Bishop, 246Caligula, 134Cameades, 69Cassius, 76Cato, senior, 65junior, 53, 71, 73, 159Chrysippus, 29, 35, 212, 236Cicero, 71Claudius, 134Cleanthes, 29, 33, 41Clemens Alexandrinus, 233Cornutus, 96, 107Crates, 28, 32Demetrius the Cynic, 97, 103,120, 150Phalereus, 23Poliorcetes, 23Demonax, 126Demosthenes, 22Diderot, 135Diogenes Laertius, 34<strong>of</strong> Sinope, 14, 19, 69, 189Dion Cassius, 89, 104, 130, 135Chrysostom, ni, 144Domitian, 92, 181


254 STOICISM.Egnatius Celer, 91Epaphroditus, 180Epictetus, 125, 163, 180-199Epicurus, 30, 45, 68, 148Euclides, 109Fannia, 122Favorinus, iioFriars, The Begging, 20Fronto, 81, 202Galen, 205Gallio, 166, 171Garat, 160Gibbon, 244Gracchi, The, 70Grant, Sir Alex., 247Guyon, Madame, 94Helvia, 13sHelvidius Priscus, 91, 103, 104Heraclitus, 39, 236Hermotimus, 82Herodes Atticus, 125Horace, 78Jehuda-ha-Nasi, 226Jerome, St., 167Johnson, Dr., 247Junius Rusticus, 105, 108, 201,225Justin, 225, 233Juvenal, 22Kant, 251Lactantius, 230Lightfoot, Bishop, 1 69, 231Lipsius Justus, 135, 245Locke, 235Lucan, 140Lucian, 19, 81, I13, 126Lucilius, 146Lucretius, 71Macaulay, 118, 128, 161, 163Menander, 27Messalina, 121, 134Michelet, 246Mommsen, 75Mucianus, 91, 104Musonius Rufus, 99, II9, 123,181Nero, 90, 136New Academy, The, 64, 68Origen, 63PANiETius, 70, 72Pantheism, 39Papirius Fabianus, 133Paul, St., 166-179Paulina, 154Persius, 79, 94, 107Philo, 244Phocion, 22Plato, 18, 29Pliny, 105Plutarch, 23, 71, 106Polybius, 135Polycarp, 226Polygnotus, 30Poppsea, 102Posidonius, 72, 145Pythagoras, 131


INDEX. 255QuiETiSTS, The, 93Quintilian, 130, 150Reid, 235Rousseau, 246Rubellius Plautus, 140Rusticus, Junius, 105, 108, 201,225SCIPIO, 66, 70Seneca, 90, 136-179, 238Sextius, Q., 130junior, 131Socrates, 5-13, 31Sophists, The, 7Sotion, 131Stilbon, 152Suetonius, 104Tacitus, 88, 105, in, 122,130, 136, 140, 172Taurus, 109Tertullian, 223Theophrastus, 30Thrasea Paetus, 91, 99-104Tigellinus, 91, 139Trajan, 227Trimalchio, 112TuUius, Marcellinus, 175Varro, 78Vespasian, 91, 97Vindex, 164Zenon, 28, 30, 32, 34, 127THE END.WYMAN AND SONS, PRINTERS, GREAT QUEEN STREET, LONDON.


htuhj for lenmting Cljnsiirin JinDtolcJitjt.NON-CHRISTIAN RELIGIOUS SYSTEMS.Fcap. %vo., Cloth boards, price 2s. 6d. each.BUDDHISM.Being a Sketcli <strong>of</strong> the Life and Teachings <strong>of</strong> Gautama, theBuddha. By T. W. Rhys Davids, <strong>of</strong> the Middle Temple.With Map.CONFUCIANISM AND TAOUISM.By Robert H. Douglas, <strong>of</strong> the British Museum. WithMap.COEAN (THE): its Composition and Teaching, and the Testimonyit bears to the Holy Scriptures,By Sir William Muir, K.C.S.I., LL.D.HINDUISM.By Monier Williams, M.A., D.C.L., &c.ISLAM AND ITS FOUNDER.With Map.ByJ. W. H. Stobart, B.A., Principal, La Martiniere<strong>College</strong>, Lucknow. With Map.THE HEATHEN WORLD AND ST.PAUL.Fcap. Zvc, Cloth boards, price 2s. each, with Map.ST. PAUL IN DAMASCUS AND AEABIA.By the Rev. George Rawlinson, M.A., Camden Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<strong>of</strong> Ancient History, Oxford.ST. PAUL IN GREECE.By the Rev. G. S. Davies, M.A., Charterhouse,Godalming.ST. PAUL AT ROME.By the Very Rev. Charles Merivale, D.D., D.C.L.,Dean <strong>of</strong> Ely.ST. PAUL IN ASIA MINOR, AND AT THE SYRL&NANTIOCH.By the Rev. E. H. Plumptre, D.D., Prebendary <strong>of</strong>St. Paul's, Vicar <strong>of</strong> Bickley, Kent.


RECENTPUBLICATIONS.Africa Unveiled. By the Rev. H. Rowley.J. d.With Map, and Eight full-page Illustrations on toned paper.Crown 8vo Cloth Boards 5 oBible Places ; or, the Topography <strong>of</strong> theHoly Land :a Succinct Account <strong>of</strong> all the Places, Rivers, andMountains <strong>of</strong> the Land <strong>of</strong> Israel mentioned in the Bible, so faras they have been identified. Together with their ModernNames and Historical References. By the Rev.Canon Tkistram.A new and revised Edition, Crow7i Svo., with Map, niuneroicsWood-cuts Cloth Boards 4 oChina : TheLand and the People <strong>of</strong>. Ashort Account <strong>of</strong> the Geography, History, Religion, Social Life,Arts, Industries, and Government <strong>of</strong> China and its People. ByJ. Thomson, Esq., F.R.G.S., Author <strong>of</strong> " Illustrations <strong>of</strong> Chinaand its People," &c. With Map, and Twelve full-pageIllustrations on toned paper. Crown Svo Cloth Boards 5 oChristians under the Crescent in Asia.the Rev. E. L. Ciitts, B.A., Hon. D.D. University <strong>of</strong> the South,U.S., Author <strong>of</strong> "Turning Points <strong>of</strong> Church History," &c.With numerous Illustrations. Post Svo Cloth Boards 5 oIndia : The History <strong>of</strong>, from the EarliestTimes to the Present Day. By L. J. Trotter, Author <strong>of</strong>" Studies in Biography." Post Svo. With a Map and 23Engravings Cloth Boards 10 6Israel : The Land <strong>of</strong>. A Journal <strong>of</strong> Travelsin Palestine, undertaken with Special Reference to its PhysicalCharacter. Third Edition, revised. By the Rev.Canon Tristram.With numerous Illustrations Cloth Boards 10 6Jerusalem : TheBySiege <strong>of</strong>. By the Rev. R. S.CoPLESTON, Fellow and Tutor <strong>of</strong> St. John's <strong>College</strong>, Oxford.Post Svo.With an Illustration and Plan <strong>of</strong> the TempleLimp Cloth i 6Jewish Nation A History <strong>of</strong> the. From:the Earliest Times to the Present Day. By E. H. Palmer, Esq.,M.A., Fellow <strong>of</strong> St. John's <strong>College</strong>, and Lord Almoner'sPr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Arabic in the University <strong>of</strong> Cambridge, Author <strong>of</strong>" The Desert <strong>of</strong> the Exodus,'' &c. &c. Crown Svo. With Mapand numerous Illustrations Cloth Boards 5 o


,NaturalRECENT PUBLICATIONS— (c-c7///'/;/;uv/)s. d.Lesser Lights; or, Some <strong>of</strong> the MinorCharacters <strong>of</strong> Scripture traced, with a View to Instruction andExample in Daily Life. By the Rev. F. Bourdillon, M.A.,Author <strong>of</strong> " Bedside Readings," &c. VostZ^o. ...Cloth Boards 2 6History <strong>of</strong> the Bible, The :beinga Review <strong>of</strong> the Physical Geography, Geology, and IMeteoroldgy<strong>of</strong> the Holy Land, with a description <strong>of</strong> every Animal andPlant mentioned in Holy Scripture. By the Rev. CanonTristram. Third Edition. Crown 8vo. With numerousIllustrations Cloth Boards 7 6Narrative <strong>of</strong> a Modern PilgrimageTHROUGH Palestine on Horseback, and with Tents. Bythe Rev. Alfred Charles Smith, M.A., Christ Church,O.xford ; Rector <strong>of</strong> Yatesbury, Wilts, Author <strong>of</strong>" TheAttractions <strong>of</strong> the Nile," &c. &c. Crown 8vo. With numerousIllustrations and Four Coloured Plates Cloth Boards 5 oScenes in the East. Containing TwelveColoured Photographic Views <strong>of</strong> Places mentioned in the Bible.By the Rev. Canon Tristram, Author <strong>of</strong> " The Land <strong>of</strong>Israel," &c. 410 Cloth Boards 7Scripture Manners and Customs :being anAccount <strong>of</strong> the Domestic Habits, Arts, &c. ,<strong>of</strong> Eastern Nationsmentioned in Holy Scripture. Sixteenth Edition. Fcap. 8vo.With numerous Wood-cuts Cloth Boards 4 oSiNAi AND Jerusalem ; or, Scenes from BibleLands, consisting <strong>of</strong> Coloured Photographic Views <strong>of</strong> Placesmentioned in the Bible, including a Panoramic View <strong>of</strong>Jerusalem. With Descriptive Letterpress by the Rev. F. W.Holland, M.A Cloth, Bevelled Boards, gilt edges 7 6Cities Visited by. By theRev. Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Stanley Leathes, M.A., King's <strong>College</strong>,London. Fcap. 8vo. With Nine Wood-cuts Limp cloth i oSt. Paul : TheTurning Points <strong>of</strong> English ChurchHistory. By the Rev. Edward L. Cutts, B.A., Author<strong>of</strong> " Some Chief Truths"<strong>of</strong> Religion," St. Cedd's CroiS," &c.Crown Svo Cloth Boards 3 6Turning Points <strong>of</strong> General ChurchHistory By the Rev. E. L. Cutts, B.A., Author <strong>of</strong>"Pastoral Counsels," &c. Crown Svo Cloth Boards 5 o


•THESocictii tax Irflinoting Ckistiait Jinotok^c.ANCIENT HISTORY FROM THE MONUMENTS.Fcap, Svo., Cloth boards, price 2s. each, with Illustrations.ASSYRIA^ FROM THE EARLIEST TIMES TOFALL OF NINEVEH.By the late George Smith, Esq., <strong>of</strong> the Department <strong>of</strong>Oriental Antiquities, British Museum.BABYLONIA, THE HISTORY OF.By the late George Smith, Esq. Edited by the Rev,A. H. Sayce, Assistant Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Comparative Philology,Oxford.EGYPT, FROM THE EARLIEST TIMES TOB.C. 300.By S. Birch, LL.D., &c.GREEK CITIES AND ISLANDS OF ASIAMINOR.By W. S. W. Vaux, M.A., F.R.S.PERSIA, FROM THE EARLIEST PERIODTHE ARAB CONQUEST.By W. S. W. Vaux, M.A., F.R.S.TOSINAI, FROM THE FOURTH EGYPTIANDYNASTY TO THE PRESENT TIME.By Henry Spencer Palmer, Major, Royal Engineers,F.R.A.S.DEPOSITORIES :Northumberland Avenue, Charing Cross, S.W. ;43i Queen Victoria Street, E.C. ;and 48, Piccadilly, W.London.


University <strong>of</strong> CaliforniaSOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY305 De Neve Drive - Parking Lot 17 • Box 951388LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90095-1388Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed.


Illlllll llllll I^'"^'^^ '-'S^'^f^^ FACILITYAA 000181227

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!